Ethics of eating meat - Wikipedia Ethics of eating meat From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Jump to navigation Jump to search Food ethics topic Part of a series on Animal rights Around the world Timeline Animal cruelty Veganism Primate rights in research The Movement Advocates Vegans Groups Aspects Killing Mutilation Wild animals Consumption Dogs Horses Cats Cattle Bloodsports Bullfighting Hunting Fishing Animal testing Cosmetic Captivity Zoos Circuses Oceanariums Companion animals Puppy mills Abandonment Ideas Abolitionism Animal protectionism Carnism Personism Sentientism Sentiocentrism Speciesism Related Environmentalism  Animals portal v t e Various types of meat. v t e Worldwide laws on killing dogs for consumption    Dog killing is legal.    Dog killing is partially illegal.1    Dog killing is illegal.    Unknown 1The laws vary internally or include exceptions for ritual or religious slaughter. v t e Worldwide laws on killing cats for consumption    Cat killing is legal    Cat killing is partially illegal1    Cat killing is illegal    Unknown 1the laws vary internally and/or they include exceptions for ritual/religious slaughter v t e Worldwide laws on killing horses for consumption    Horse killing is legal    Horse killing is illegal    Unknown The question of whether it is right to eat animal flesh is among the most prominent topics in food ethics.[1] People choose not to eat meat for various reasons such as concern for animal welfare, the environmental impact of meat production (environmental vegetarianism), and health considerations.[2] Some argue that slaughtering animals solely because people enjoy the taste of meat is morally wrong or unjustifiable.[3][4] Vegans often abstain from other animal products for similar reasons. Ethical vegetarians and ethical vegans[5] may also object to the practices underlying the production of meat, or cite concerns about animal welfare, animal rights, environmental ethics, and religious reasons. In response, some proponents of meat-eating have adduced various scientific, cultural, and religious arguments in support of the practice.[citation needed] Some meat-eaters only object to rearing animals in certain ways, such as in factory farms, or killing them with cruelty; others avoid only certain meats, such as veal or foie gras. Contents 1 Overview of the argument against meat eating 2 Animal consciousness 2.1 Pain 2.2 Influences on views of animal consciousness 3 Environmental argument 4 Religious traditions of eating meat 5 Criticisms and responses 5.1 Morals 5.2 Animal welfare 5.3 Oysters 5.4 Animal and plant pain 5.5 Animals killed in crop harvesting 6 Non-meat products 7 See also 8 References 9 External links Overview of the argument against meat eating[edit] Cattle carcasses in a slaughterhouse.[6] Peter Singer—Princeton University and University of Melbourne professor and pioneer of the animal liberation movement—has long argued that, if it is possible to survive and be healthy without eating meat, fish, dairy, or eggs, one ought to choose that option instead of causing unnecessary harm to animals. In Animal Liberation, Singer argued that, because non-human animals feel, they should be treated according to utilitarian ethics. Singer's work has since been widely built upon by philosophers, both those who agree[7] and those who do not,[8] and it has been applied by animal rights advocates[9] as well as by ethical vegetarians and vegans. Ethical vegetarians say that the reasons for not hurting or killing animals are similar to the reasons for not hurting or killing humans. They argue that killing an animal, like killing a human, can only be justified in extreme circumstances; consuming a living creature just for its taste, for convenience, or out of habit is not justifiable. Some ethicists have added that humans, unlike other animals, are morally conscious of their behavior and have a choice; this is why there are laws governing human behavior, and why it is subject to moral standards.[10] Ethical vegetarian concerns have become more widespread in developed countries, particularly because of the spread of factory farming, more open and graphic documentation of what human meat-eating entails for the animal,[11] and environmental consciousness. Some proponents of meat-eating argue that the current mass demand for meat has to be satisfied with a mass-production system, regardless of the welfare of animals. Less radical proponents argue that practices like well-managed free-range rearing and the consumption of hunted animals, particularly from species whose natural predators have been significantly eliminated, could satisfy the demand for mass-produced meat.[12] Reducing the worldwide massive food waste would also contribute to reduce meat waste and therefore save animals.[13][14] According to the Food and Agriculture Organization of the United Nations, about a third of the food for human consumption is wasted globally (around 1.3 billion tons per year).[15] Some have described unequal treatment of humans and animals as a form of speciesism such as anthropocentrism or human-centeredness. Val Plumwood (1993, 1996) has argued that anthropocentrism plays a role in green theory that is analogous to androcentrism in feminist theory and ethnocentrism in anti-racist theory. Plumwood calls human-centredness "anthropocentrism" to emphasize this parallel. By analogy with racism and sexism, Melanie Joy has dubbed meat-eating "carnism". The animal rights movement seeks an end to the rigid moral and legal distinction drawn between human and non-human animals, an end to the status of animals as property, and an end to their use in the research, food, clothing, and entertainment industries.[16][17] Peter Singer, in his ethical philosophy of what it is to be a "person", argues that livestock animals feel enough to deserve better treatment than they receive. Many thinkers have questioned the morality not only of the double standard underlying speciesism but also the double standard underlying the fact that people support treatment of cows, pigs, and chickens that they would never allow with pet dogs, cats, or birds.[7] Jay Bost, agroecologist and winner of The New York Times' essay contest on the ethics of eating meat, summarized his argument in the following way: "eating meat raised in specific circumstances is ethical; eating meat raised in other circumstances is unethical" in regard to environmental usage. He proposes that if "ethical is defined as living in the most ecologically benign way, then in fairly specific circumstances, of which each eater must educate himself, eating meat is ethical." The specific circumstances he mentions include using animals to cycle nutrients and convert sun to food.[18] Ethicists like Tom Regan and Peter Singer define "ethical" in terms of suffering rather than ecology. Mark Rowlands argues that the real determinant of whether it is ethical to cause suffering is whether there is any vital need to cause it; if not, then causing it is unethical.[7] Animal consciousness[edit] See also: Animal consciousness and Emotion in animals v t e Worldwide laws regarding the formal recognition of nonhuman animal sentience and suffering    National recognition of animal sentience    Partial recognition of animal sentience1    National recognition of animal suffering    Partial recognition of animal suffering2    No official recognition of animal sentience or suffering    Unknown 1certain animals are excluded, only mental health is acknowledged, and/or the laws vary internally 2only includes domestic animals Shorthorn heifers, a typical multipurpose breed of cattle. Ethologist Jane Goodall stated in the 2009 book The Inner World of Farm Animals that "farm animals feel pleasure and sadness, excitement and resentment, depression, fear and pain. They are much more sensitive and intelligent than we ever imagined."[19] In 2012, a group of well known neuroscientists[20] stated in the "Cambridge Declaration on Consciousness in Non-Human Animals" that all mammals and birds (such as farm animals), and other animals, possess the neurological substrates that generate consciousness and are able to experience affective states.[21] Eugene Linden, author of The Parrot's Lament, suggests that many examples of animal behavior and intelligence seem to indicate both emotion and a level of consciousness that we would normally ascribe only to our own species. Philosopher Daniel Dennett counters: Consciousness requires a certain kind of informational organization that does not seem to be "hard-wired" in humans, but is instilled by human culture. Moreover, consciousness is not a black-or-white, all-or-nothing type of phenomenon, as is often assumed. The differences between humans and other species are so great that speculations about animal consciousness seem ungrounded. Many authors simply assume that an animal like a bat has a point of view, but there seems to be little interest in exploring the details involved.[22] Philosophers Peter Singer (Princeton), Jeff McMahan (Oxford) and others also counter that the issue is not one of consciousness, but of sentience.[23] Pain[edit] See also: Pain in animals and Pain in invertebrates A related argument revolves around non-human organisms' ability to feel pain. If animals could be shown to suffer, as humans do, then many of the arguments against human suffering could be extended to animals.[24] One such reaction is transmarginal inhibition, a phenomenon observed in humans and some animals akin to mental breakdown. As noted by John Webster (emeritus professor of animal husbandry at the University of Bristol): People have assumed that intelligence is linked to the ability to suffer and that because animals have smaller brains they suffer less than humans. That is a pathetic piece of logic, sentient animals have the capacity to experience pleasure and are motivated to seek it, you only have to watch how cows and lambs both seek and enjoy pleasure when they lie with their heads raised to the sun on a perfect English summer's day. Just like humans.[25] Influences on views of animal consciousness[edit] When people choose to do things about which they are ambivalent and which they would have difficulty justifying, they experience a state of cognitive dissonance, which can lead to rationalization, denial, or even self-deception. For example, a 2011 experiment found that, when the harm that their meat-eating causes animals is explicitly brought to people's attention, they tend to rate those animals as possessing fewer mental capacities compared to when the harm is not brought to their attention. This is especially evident when people expect to eat meat in the near future. Such denial makes it less uncomfortable for people to eat animals. The data suggest that people who consume meat go to great lengths to try to resolve these moral inconsistencies between their beliefs and behaviour by adjusting their beliefs about what animals are capable of feeling.[26] This perception can lead to paradoxical conclusions about the ethics and comfort involved in preferring certain types of meat over others. For example, venison or meat from a wild deer generally has a much higher nutritional quality and a much lower carbon footprint than meat from domestically-raised animals. In addition, it can be virtually assured that the deer was never bred or raised in unnatural conditions, confined to a cage, fed an unnatural diet of grain, or injected with any artificial hormones. However, since the necessary act of killing a deer to procure the venison is generally much more apparent to anyone who encounters this sort of meat, some people can be even more uncomfortable with eating this than meat from animals raised on factory farms. Many ethical vegetarians and ethical meat-eaters argue that it is behaviour rather than supporting beliefs that should be adjusted. Environmental argument[edit] Main articles: Environmental vegetarianism and Environmental impact of meat production A monocultivated potato field Some people choose to be vegetarian or vegan for environmental reasons. According to a 2006 report by LEAD Livestock's Long Shadow, "the livestock sector emerges as one of the top two or three most significant contributors to the most serious environmental problems, at every scale from local to global."[27] The livestock sector is probably the largest source of water pollution (due to animal wastes, fertilizers, and pesticides), contributing to eutrophication, human health problems, and the emergence of antibiotic resistance. It accounts also for over 8% of global human water use. Livestock production is by far the biggest user of land, as it accounts for 40% of the global land surface.[28] It is probably the leading player in biodiversity loss, as it causes deforestation, land degradation, pollution, climate change, and overfishing.[27][29][30] A 2017 study by the World Wildlife Fund found that 60% of biodiversity loss can be attributed to the vast scale of feed crop cultivation needed to rear tens of billions of farm animals.[31] Livestock is also responsible for at least 20% of the world's greenhouse gas emissions, which are the main cause of the current climate change. This is due to feed production, enteric fermentation from ruminants, manure storage and processing, and transportation of animal products.[32] The greenhouse gas emissions from livestock production greatly exceeds the greenhouse gas emissions of any other human activity. Some authors argue that by far the best thing we can do to slow climate change is a global shift towards a vegetarian or vegan diet.[33] A 2017 study published in the journal Carbon Balance and Management found animal agriculture's global methane emissions are 11% higher than previously estimated.[34] In November 2017, 15,364 world scientists signed a warning to humanity calling for, among other things, "promoting dietary shifts towards mostly plant-based foods."[35] A 2019 report in The Lancet recommended that global meat consumption be reduced by 50 percent to mitigate climate change.[36] Many developing countries, including China and India, are moving away from traditional plant-based diets to meat-intensive diets as the result of modernization and globalization, which has facilitated the spread of Western consumer cultures around the world. Over 200 billion animals are consumed by the global population of over 7 billion every year, and meat consumption is projected to more than double by 2050 as the population grows to over 9 billion.[37] A 2018 study published in Science states that meat consumption could rise by as much as 76% by 2050 as the result of human population growth and rising affluence, which will increase greenhouse gas emissions and further reduce biodiversity.[38] Animals that feed on grain or rely on grazing require more water than grain crops.[39] Producing 1 kg of meat requires up to 15,000 liters of water.[40] According to the United States Department of Agriculture (USDA), growing crops for farm animals requires nearly half of the US water supply and 80% of its agricultural land. Animals raised for food in the US consume 90% of the soy crop, 80% of the corn crop, and 70% of its grain.[41] However, where an extensive farming system (as opposed to a feedlot) is used, some water and nutrients are returned to the soil to provide a benefit to the pasture. This cycling and processing of water and nutrients is less prevalent in most plant production systems, so may bring the efficiency rate of animal production closer to the efficiency of plant based agricultural systems.[42] In tracking food animal production from the feed through to the dinner table, the inefficiencies of meat, milk, and egg production range from a 4:1 energy input to protein output ratio up to 54:1.[43] The result is that producing animal-based food is typically much less efficient than the harvesting of grains, vegetables, legumes, seeds, and fruits. There are also environmentalist arguments in favor of the morality of eating meat. One such line of argument holds that sentience and individual welfare are less important to morality than the greater ecological good. Following environmentalist Aldo Leopold's principle that the sole criterion for morality is preserving the "integrity, stability and beauty of the biotic community", this position asserts that sustainable hunting and animal agriculture are environmentally healthy and therefore good.[44][45] Religious traditions of eating meat[edit] See also: Vegetarianism and religion Cow slaughter laws in various states of India Hinduism holds vegetarianism as an ideal for three reasons: the principle of nonviolence (ahimsa) applied to animals; the intention to offer only "pure" (vegetarian) or sattvic food to a deity and then to receive it back as prasad; and the conviction that an insentient diet is beneficial for a healthy body and mind and that non-vegetarian food is detrimental for the mind and for spiritual development. Buddhist vegetarianism has similar strictures against hurting animals. The actual practices of Hindus and Buddhists vary according to their community and according to regional traditions. Jains are especially rigorous about not harming sentient organisms.[citation needed] Islamic Law and Judaism have dietary guidelines called Halal and Kashrut, respectively. In Judaism, meat that may be consumed according to halakha (Jewish law) is termed kosher; meat that is not compliant with Jewish law is called treif. Causing unnecessary pain to animals is prohibited by the principle of tza'ar ba'alei chayim. While it is neither required nor prohibited for Jews to eat meat, a number of medieval scholars of Judaism, such as Joseph Albo and Isaac Arama, regard vegetarianism as a moral ideal. In Christianity as practised by members of Eastern Orthodox Church, Roman Catholic Church, Greek Catholic Church, and others, it is prohibited to eat meat in times of fasting. Rules of fasting also vary. There are also Christian monastic orders that practice vegetarianism. Shinto has a concept of kegare, which means a state of pollution and defilement, and traditionally eating animals is thought to be one of them.[46] Eating animals having more legs is thought to be worse. (Eating mammals is worse than eating chickens or fish.) This concept leads to discrimination against slaughtermen and people who work with leather, who are called burakumin.[47][48] Shinran, the founder of the Buddhist sect Jōdo Shinshū, taught that lower class who had to kill beings could enter nirvana even though killing animals was thought to be immoral. Criticisms and responses[edit] Morals[edit] It has been argued that a moral community requires all participants to be able to make moral decisions, but animals are incapable of making moral choices (e.g., a tiger would not refrain from eating a human because it was morally wrong; it would decide whether to attack based on its survival needs, as dictated by hunger). Thus, some opponents of ethical vegetarianism argue that the analogy between killing animals and killing people is misleading.[49] For example, Hsiao (2015) compares the moral severity of harming animals to that of picking a flower or introducing malware into a computer.[49] Others have argued that humans are capable of culture, innovation, and the sublimation of instinct in order to act in an ethical manner while animals are not, and so are unequal to humans on a moral level. This does not excuse cruelty, but it implies animals are not morally equivalent to humans and do not possess the rights a human has.[50] The precise definition of a moral community is not simple, but Hsiao defines membership by the ability to know one's own good and that of other members, and to be able to grasp this in the abstract. He claims that non-human animals do not meet this standard.[49] Benjamin Franklin describes his conversion to vegetarianism in chapter one of his autobiography, but then he describes why he (periodically) ceased vegetarianism in his later life: ...in my first voyage from Boston...our people set about catching cod, and hauled up a great many. Hitherto I had stuck to my resolution of not eating animal food... But I had formerly been a great lover of fish, and, when this came hot out of the frying-pan, it smelt admirably well. I balanc'd some time between principle and inclination, till I recollected that, when the fish were opened, I saw smaller fish taken out of their stomachs; then thought I, "If you eat one another, I don't see why we mayn't eat you." So I din'd upon cod very heartily, and continued to eat with other people, returning only now and then occasionally to a vegetable diet. So convenient a thing it is to be a reasonable creature, since it enables one to find or make a reason for everything one has a mind to do.[51] One study found that approximately 60% of contemporary professional ethicists consider it "morally bad" to eat meat from mammals.[52] Writing in Current Affairs, Nathan J. Robinson describes the billions of non-human animals that suffer and die at the hands of human beings for consumption as a "holocaust" and, citing Jeremy Bentham's formulation "The question is not, Can they reason? nor, Can they talk? but, Can they suffer?" contends that it is "morally reprehensible" and "deeply wrong".[53] Conversely, Jan Narveson argues that under certain theories of utilitarianism, positive utility can be increased by having more living organisms to experience it and thus by increasing the animal population so it can later be eaten, these theories could potentially justify raising animals for the purposes of consumption.[54] Animal welfare[edit] v t e Worldwide laws regarding animal cruelty    Anti-cruelty laws meet OIE standards    Anti-cruelty laws partially meet OIE standards1    Other anti-cruelty laws exist    No anti-cruelty laws exist    Unknown 1the laws vary internally Various programs operate in the US that promote the notion that animals raised for food can be treated humanely. Some spokespeople for the factory farming industry argue that the animals are better off in total confinement. For example, according to F J "Sonny" Faison, president of Carroll's Foods: They're in state-of-the-art confinement facilities. The conditions that we keep these animals in are much more humane than when they were out in the field. Today they're in housing that is environmentally controlled in many respects. And the feed is right there for them all the time, and water, fresh water. They're looked after in some of the best conditions, because the healthier and [more] content that animal, the better it grows. So we're very interested in their well-being up to an extent.[55] In response, animal welfare advocates ask for evidence that any factory-bred animal is better off caged than free.[56] Farm Sanctuary argue that commodifying and slaughtering animals is incompatible with the definition of "humane".[57] Animal ethicists such as Gary Francione have argued that reducing animal suffering is not enough; it needs to be made illegal and abolished. Oysters[edit] Peter Singer[58] has pointed out that the ethical argument for vegetarianism may not apply to all non-vegetarian food. For example, any arguments against causing pain to animals would not apply to animals that do not feel pain. It has also often been noted that, while it takes a lot more grain to feed some animals such as cows for human consumption than it takes to feed a human directly, not all animals consume land plants (or other animals that consume land plants). For example, oysters consume underwater plankton and algae. In 2010, Christopher Cox wrote: Biologically, oysters are not in the plant kingdom, but when it comes to ethical eating, they are almost indistinguishable from plants. Oyster farms account for 95 percent of all oyster consumption and have a minimal negative impact on their ecosystems; there are even nonprofit projects devoted to cultivating oysters as a way to improve water quality. Since so many oysters are farmed, there's little danger of overfishing. No forests are cleared for oysters, no fertilizer is needed, and no grain goes to waste to feed them—they have a diet of plankton, which is about as close to the bottom of the food chain as you can get. Oyster cultivation also avoids many of the negative side effects of plant agriculture: There are no bees needed to pollinate oysters, no pesticides required to kill off other insects, and for the most part, oyster farms operate without the collateral damage of accidentally killing other animals during harvesting.[59] Cox went on to suggest that oysters would be acceptable to eat, even by strict ethical criteria, if they did not feel: "while you could give them the benefit of the doubt, you could also say that unless some new evidence of a capacity for pain emerges, the doubt is so slight that there is no good reason for avoiding eating sustainably produced oysters." Cox has added that, although he believes in some of the ethical reasons for vegetarianism, he is not strictly a vegan or even a vegetarian because he consumes oysters. Animal and plant pain[edit] Critics of ethical vegetarianism say that there is no agreement on where to draw the line between organisms that can and cannot feel. Justin Leiber, a philosophy professor at Oxford University, writes that: Montaigne is ecumenical in this respect, claiming consciousness for spiders and ants, and even writing of our duties to trees and plants. Singer and Clarke agree in denying consciousness to sponges. Singer locates the distinction somewhere between the shrimp and the oyster. He, with rather considerable convenience for one who is thundering hard accusations at others, slides by the case of insects and spiders and bacteria, they pace Montaigne, apparently and rather conveniently do not feel pain. The intrepid Midgley, on the other hand, seems willing to speculate about the subjective experience of tapeworms ...Nagel ... appears to draw the line at flounders and wasps, though more recently he speaks of the inner life of cockroaches.[60] There are also some who argue that, although only suffering animals feel anguish, plants, like all organisms, have evolved mechanisms for survival. No living organism can be described as "wanting" to die for another organism's sustenance.[61] In an article written for The New York Times, Carol Kaesuk Yoon argues that: When a plant is wounded, its body immediately kicks into protection mode. It releases a bouquet of volatile chemicals, which in some cases have been shown to induce neighboring plants to pre-emptively step up their own chemical defenses and in other cases to lure in predators of the beasts that may be causing the damage to the plants. Inside the plant, repair systems are engaged and defenses are mounted, the molecular details of which scientists are still working out, but which involve signaling molecules coursing through the body to rally the cellular troops, even the enlisting of the genome itself, which begins churning out defense-related proteins ... If you think about it, though, why would we expect any organism to lie down and die for our dinner? Organisms have evolved to do everything in their power to avoid being extinguished. How long would any lineage be likely to last if its members effectively didn't care if you killed them?[62] Animals killed in crop harvesting[edit] Steven Davis, a professor of animal science at Oregon State University, argues that the least harm principle does not require giving up all meat. Davis states that a diet containing beef from grass-fed ruminants such as cattle would kill fewer animals than a vegetarian diet, particularly when one takes into account animals killed by agriculture.[63] This conclusion has been criticized by Jason Gaverick Matheny (founder of in vitro meat organization New Harvest) because it calculates the number of animals killed per acre (instead of per consumer). Matheny says that, when the numbers are adjusted, Davis' argument shows veganism as perpetrating the least harm.[64] Davis' argument has also been criticized by Andy Lamey for being based on only two studies that may not represent commercial agricultural practices. When differentiating between animals killed by farm machinery and those killed by other animals, he says that the studies again show veganism to do the "least harm".[65] Non-meat products[edit] Egg-laying chickens in battery cages One of the main differences between a vegan and a typical vegetarian diet is the avoidance of both eggs and dairy products such as milk, cheese, butter, and yogurt. Ethical vegans do not consume dairy or eggs because they understand their production causes animal suffering or premature death[66] and because of the environmental effect of dairy production.[67][68] According to a report of the United Nations’ Food and Agriculture Organization in 2010 the dairy sector accounted for 4 percent of global man-made greenhouse gas emissions.[69][70] To produce milk from dairy cattle, most calves are separated from their mothers soon after birth and fed milk replacement in order to retain the cows' milk for human consumption.[71] Animal welfare advocates point out that this breaks the natural bond between the mother and her calf.[71] Unwanted male calves are either slaughtered at birth or sent for veal production.[71] To prolong lactation, dairy cows are almost permanently kept pregnant through artificial insemination.[71] Although cows' natural life expectancy is about twenty years,[66] after about five years the cows' milk production has dropped; they are then considered "spent" and are sent to slaughter for meat and leather.[72][73] Battery cages are the predominant form of housing for laying hens worldwide; these cages reduce aggression and cannibalism among hens, but are barren, restrict movement, and increase rates of osteoporosis.[74][75][76] In these systems and in free-range egg production, unwanted male chicks are culled and killed at birth during the process of securing a further generation of egg-laying hens.[77] It is estimated that an average consumer of eggs who eats 200 eggs per year for 70 years of his or her life is responsible for the deaths of 140 birds, and that an average consumer of milk who drinks 190 kg per year for 70 years is responsible for the deaths of 2.5 cows.[78] See also[edit] Cultured meat Devour the Earth Economic vegetarianism Ethical omnivorism Ethics of uncertain sentience Hard problem of consciousness Moral agency Non-aggression principle Psychology of eating meat Problem of other minds Sustainable diet References[edit] ^ Sandler, Ronald L. (2014). Food Ethics: The Basics. London: Taylor & Francis. p. 142. ISBN 978-1-135-04547-0. Retrieved 11 February 2018. ^ American Dietetic Association (2009). "Position Paper of the American Dietatic Association: Vegetarian Diets" (PDF). Journal of the American Dietetic Association. 109 (7): 1266–1282. doi:10.1016/j.jada.2009.05.027. PMID 19562864. ^ Harnad, Stevan (2013) Luxe, nécessité, souffrance: Pourquoi je ne suis pas carnivore Archived 6 July 2015 at the Wayback Machine. Québec humaniste 8(1): 10-13 ^ Desaulniers, Élise (30 May 2013). "I Am Ashamed to Have Been a Vegetarian for 50 Years". HuffPost Living. TheHuffingtonPost.com, Inc. Retrieved 19 May 2014. ^ Ronald L. Sandler, Food Ethics: The Basics, Routledge, 2014, p. 74. ^ "The Animal Kill Counter << ADAPTT :: Animals Deserve Absolute Protection Today and Tomorrow". adaptt.org. 24 December 2013. Retrieved 19 May 2014. ^ a b c Mark Rowlands (2013). Animal rights: All that matters. Hodder & Stoughton Archived 1 July 2014 at the Wayback Machine ^ Scruton, Roger (2006). Animal Rights and Wrongs. New York: Continuum. ISBN 9781441199157. ^ Donaldson, Sue; Kymlicka, Will (2011). Zoopolis: A Political Theory of Animal Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0199599660. OCLC 713621604. ^ Benatar, David (February 2001). "Why the Naive Argument against Moral Vegetarianism Really is Naive". Environmental Values. 10 (1): 103–112. doi:10.3197/096327101129340769. S2CID 145781996. ^ Eisnitz, G. A. (2009). Slaughterhouse: The shocking story of greed, neglect, and inhumane treatment inside the US meat industry. Prometheus Books. Chicago ^ Pluhar, E. B. (2010). "Meat and morality: Alternatives to factory farming" (PDF). Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics. 23 (5): 455–468. doi:10.1007/s10806-009-9226-x. Archived from the original (PDF) on 6 January 2014. ^ Hoffman, Beth (16 September 2013). "Food Waste: Key To Ending World Hunger". Forbes. ^ Anonymous (17 October 2016). "Food Waste". Food Safety - European Commission. Retrieved 22 November 2019. ^ "Food Loss and Food Waste". FAO. 2015. Retrieved 6 July 2015. ^ "Manifesto for the Evolution of Animals' Legal Status in the Civil Code of Quebec". animalsarenotobjects.ca. Archived from the original on 21 June 2014. Retrieved 27 March 2018. ^ Chazan, David (16 April 2014). "Pets No Longer Just Part of Furniture in France". The Telegraph. ^ Bost, Jay (3 May 2012). "Give Thanks for Meat". New York Times. Retrieved 7 April 2013. ^ Goodall J (April 2009), The Inner World of Farm Animals. Stewart, Tabori and Chang. ^ Halberstadt, Alex (3 July 2014). "Zoo Animals and their Discontents". New York Times Magazine. ^ Low P, Panksepp J, Reiss D, Edelman D, Van Swinderen B, Koch C (July 2012). "The Cambridge Declaration on Consciousness". ^ Dennett, Daniel C (1995). "Animal consciousness: what matters and why". Social Research. 62 (3). ^ McMahan, Jeff (2002). The Ethics of Killing. Oxford University Press. ^ Carter, Alan (2005). "Animals, Pain and Morality". Journal of Applied Philosophy. 22 (1): 17–22. doi:10.1111/j.1468-5930.2005.00289.x. PMID 15948329. ^ "The secret life of moody cows", John Webster. ^ Bastian, Brock; Loughnan, Steve; Haslam, Nick; Radke, Helena R. M. (2012). "Don't Mind Meat? The Denial of Mind to Animals Used for Human Consumption" (PDF). Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin. 38 (2): 247–256. doi:10.1177/0146167211424291. PMID 21980158. Retrieved 19 May 2014. ^ a b Steinfeld, Henning; Gerber, Pierre; Wassenaar, Tom; Castel, Vincent; Rosales, Mauricio; de Haan, Cees (2006), Livestock's Long Shadow: Environmental Issues and Options (PDF), Rome: FAO ^ Sutter, John D. (12 December 2016). "How to stop the sixth mass extinction". CNN. Retrieved 3 January 2018. ^ Morell, Virginia (11 August 2015). "Meat-eaters may speed worldwide species extinction, study warns". Science. Retrieved 3 January 2018. ^ Machovina, B.; Feeley, K. J.; Ripple, W. J. (2015). "Biodiversity conservation: The key is reducing meat consumption". Science of the Total Environment. 536: 419–431. Bibcode:2015ScTEn.536..419M. doi:10.1016/j.scitotenv.2015.07.022. PMID 26231772. ^ Smithers, Rebecca (5 October 2017). "Vast animal-feed crops to satisfy our meat needs are destroying planet". The Guardian. Retrieved 3 January 2018. ^ "Tackling climate change through livestock" (PDF). Retrieved 22 November 2019. ^ "Archived copy" (PDF). Archived from the original (PDF) on 17 April 2017. Retrieved 16 October 2015.CS1 maint: archived copy as title (link) ^ Wolf, Julie; Asrar, Ghassem R.; West, Tristram O. (29 September 2017). "Revised methane emissions factors and spatially distributed annual carbon fluxes for global livestock". Carbon Balance and Management. 12 (16): 16. doi:10.1186/s13021-017-0084-y. PMC 5620025. PMID 28959823. ^ Ripple WJ, Wolf C, Newsome TM, Galetti M, Alamgir M, Crist E, Mahmoud MI, Laurance WF (13 November 2017). "World Scientists' Warning to Humanity: A Second Notice". BioScience. 67 (12): 1026–1028. doi:10.1093/biosci/bix125. ^ Gibbens, Sarah (16 January 2019). "Eating meat has 'dire' consequences for the planet, says report". National Geographic. Retrieved 19 January 2019. ^ Best, Steven (2014). The Politics of Total Liberation: Revolution for the 21st Century. Palgrave Macmillan. pp. 97, 160. ISBN 978-1137471116. ^ Devlin, Hannah (19 July 2018). "Rising global meat consumption 'will devastate environment'". The Guardian. Retrieved 2 October 2019. ^ Kirby, Alex (16 August 2004). "Hungry world 'must eat less meat'". BBC News. Retrieved 19 May 2014. ^ "Managing Water under Uncertainty and Risk". unesdoc.unesco.org. Retrieved 22 November 2019. ^ "USDA ERS - Major Uses of Land in the United States, 1997". United States Department of Agriculture Economic Research Service. Archived from the original on 6 May 2014. Retrieved 19 May 2014. ^ "Allan Savory: Holistic Management: A New Framework for Decision Making." Thomas J. Elpel's Green University™--Our Mission: To Change the World. N.p., n.d. Web. 22 March 2016 ^ "U.S. could feed 800 million people with grain that livestock eat". Cornell Chronicle. Cornell University. 7 August 1997. Retrieved 19 May 2014. ^ Callicott, J. Baird (1980). "Animal Liberation: A Triangular Affair" (PDF). Environmental Ethics. 2 (4): 311–338. doi:10.5840/enviroethics19802424. Retrieved 6 July 2015. ^ Bost, Jay (3 May 2012). "The Ethicist Contest Winner: Give Thanks for Meat". The New York Times (editorial). ^ 長谷部恵理(Hasebe Eri)(2006) 江戸期における「肉」と「肉食」に関する一考察 第2章「肉食」とシンボリズム(an examination of “meat” and “eating meat” in the Edo Era, chapter Ⅱ “eating meat” and symbolism) 危機と文化 : 札幌大学文化学部文化学会紀要 8卷 ^ "Japan's hidden caste of untouchables". BBC. Retrieved 6 August 2020. ^ Harada Nobuo (1993). 歴史のなかの米と肉 食物と天皇・差別. Tokyo: 平凡社. ISBN 4-582-84147-3. ^ a b c Hsiao, Timothy (2015). "In Defense of Eating Meat". Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics. 28 (2): 277–291. doi:10.1007/s10806-015-9534-2. ^ "Animals and Ethics". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. University of Tennessee. 2 August 2013. Retrieved 19 May 2014. ^ "The Autobiography of Benjamin Franklin - Chapter 4". Earlyamerica.com. 27 February 2007. Retrieved 27 March 2011. ^ Joshua Rust; Eric Schwitzgebel (2014). "The Moral Behavior of Ethicists and the Power of Reason" (PDF). In Hagop Sarkissian, Jennifer Cole Wright (ed.). Advances in Experimental Moral Psychology. Bloomsbury Publishing. pp. 96–97. ISBN 978-1-4725-1304-5. ^ Robinson, Nathan J. (17 January 2018). "Meat and the H-Word". Current Affairs. Retrieved 18 January 2018. ^ Narveson, Jan. Moral matters. Broadview Press, 1999, page140-141 ^ Scully, Matthew. Dominion, St. Martin's Griffin, 2002, pp. 255–256. ^ Matheny, G., & Leahy, C. (2007). Farm-animal welfare, legislation, and trade. Law and contemporary problems, 325-358. ^ The Truth Behind The Labels: Farm Animal Welfare Standards and Labeling Practices Archived 6 January 2014 at the Wayback Machine Farm Sanctuary ^ Singer, Peter (1975). Animal Liberation, A New Ethics for our Treatment of Animals. New York: Random House. ^ "It's OK for vegans to eat oysters", Christopher Cox, 2010, Slate ^ Leiber, Justin (1988). "Cartesian Linguistics?". Philosophia. 118 (4): 309–46. doi:10.1007/BF02380646. ^ Natalie Angier (21 December 2009). "Sorry, Vegans: Brussels Sprouts Like to Live, Too". New York Times. Retrieved 20 February 2017. ^ "No Face, but Plants Like Life Too", Carol Kaesuk Yoon, The New York Times ^ "Should we all be vegetarians?". Time. 2 July 2002. Retrieved 14 June 2010. ^ Matheny, G (2003). "Least Harm: A Defense of Vegetarianism from Steven Davis's Omnivorous Proposal". Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics. 16 (5): 505–511. doi:10.1023/A:1026354906892. ^ Lamey, Andy (2007). "Food Fight! Davis versus Regan on the Ethics of Eating Beef". Journal of Social Philosophy. 38 (2): 331–348. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9833.2007.00382.x. SSRN 1253172. ^ a b Erik Marcus (2000). Vegan: The New Ethics of Eating. ISBN 9781590133446. ^ "Ethical Reasons to Give Up Dairy Products". dummies. Retrieved 12 May 2019. ^ Scarborough, Peter; Appleby, Paul N.; Mizdrak, Anja; Briggs, Adam D. M.; Travis, Ruth C.; Bradbury, Kathryn E.; Key, Timothy J. (2014). "Dietary greenhouse gas emissions of meat-eaters, fish-eaters, vegetarians and vegans in the UK". Climatic Change. 125 (2): 179–192. Bibcode:2014ClCh..125..179S. doi:10.1007/s10584-014-1169-1. ISSN 0165-0009. PMC 4372775. PMID 25834298. ^ "Dairy sector adds 4 percent to man-made emissions: FAO". Reuters. 20 April 2010. Retrieved 12 May 2019. ^ Moskin, Julia; Plumer, Brad; Lieberman, Rebecca; Weingart, Eden; Popovich, Nadja (30 April 2019). "Your Questions About Food and Climate Change, Answered". The New York Times. ISSN 0362-4331. Retrieved 12 May 2019. ^ a b c d Vegetarian Society. "Dairy Cows & Welfare". Archived from the original on 6 May 2013. Retrieved 18 October 2012. ^ Desaulniers, Élise (2013). Vache à lait : dix mythes de l'industrie laitière (in French). Editions Stanké, Québec. Archived from the original on 21 September 2013. Retrieved 19 May 2014. ^ Wolfson, D. J. (1996). Beyond the law: Agribusiness and the systemic abuse of animals raised for food or food production Animal L., 2, 123. [permanent dead link] ^ Horne, P.L.M. Van; Achterbosch, T.J. (2008). "Animal welfare in poultry production systems: impact of EU standards on world trade". World's Poultry Science Journal. 64 (1): 40–52. doi:10.1017/s0043933907001705. ^ Leenstra, F.; Napel, J. Ten; Visscher, J.; Sambeek, F. Van (2016). "Layer breeding programmes in changing production environments: a historic perspective". World's Poultry Science Journal. 72 (1): 21–36. doi:10.1017/s0043933915002743. ^ Meseret, S. (2016). "A review of poultry welfare in conventional production system". Livestock Research for Rural Development. 28 (12). ^ Vegetarian Society. "Egg Production & Welfare". Archived from the original on 16 March 2018. Retrieved 18 October 2012. ^ Saja, Krzysztof (11 October 2012). "The moral footprint of animal products". Agriculture and Human Values. 30 (2): 193–202. doi:10.1007/s10460-012-9402-x. ISSN 0889-048X. External links[edit] A Dissertation on the Voluntary Eating of Blood: An 18th-century justification of the eating of meat. Rare WZ 260 D626 1745. Digitized copy hosted by the UCLA Digital Library. The moral basis of vegetarianism (1959) e-book by Mahatma Gandhi The Ethics of Diet: A Catena of Authorities Deprecatory of the Practice of Flesh-Eating by Howard Williams M.A. (1837–1931) The Ethical Vegetarian v t e Ethics Normative ethics Consequentialism Utilitarianism Deontology Kantian ethics Ethics of care Existentialist ethics Particularism Pragmatic ethics Role ethics Virtue ethics Eudaimonism Applied ethics Animal ethics Bioethics Business ethics Discourse ethics Engineering ethics Environmental ethics Legal ethics Machine ethics Media ethics Medical ethics Nursing ethics Professional ethics Sexual ethics Ethics of artificial intelligence Ethics of eating meat Ethics of technology Ethics of terraforming Ethics of uncertain sentience Meta-ethics Cognitivism Moral realism Ethical naturalism Ethical non-naturalism Ethical subjectivism Ideal observer theory Divine command theory Error theory Non-cognitivism Emotivism Expressivism Quasi-realism Universal prescriptivism Moral universalism Value monism – Value pluralism Moral relativism Moral nihilism Moral rationalism Ethical intuitionism Moral skepticism Concepts Autonomy Axiology Conscience Consent Equality Free will Good and evil Good Evil Happiness Ideal Immorality Justice Liberty Morality Norm Freedom Suffering or Pain Stewardship Sympathy Trust Value Virtue Wrong full index... Philosophers Laozi Socrates Plato Aristotle Diogenes Valluvar Cicero Confucius Augustine of Hippo Mencius Mozi Xunzi Thomas Aquinas Baruch Spinoza David Hume Immanuel Kant Georg W. F. Hegel Arthur Schopenhauer Jeremy Bentham John Stuart Mill Søren Kierkegaard Henry Sidgwick Friedrich Nietzsche G. E. Moore Karl Barth Paul Tillich Dietrich Bonhoeffer Philippa Foot John Rawls John Dewey Bernard Williams J. L. Mackie G. E. M. Anscombe William Frankena Alasdair MacIntyre R. M. Hare Peter Singer Derek Parfit Thomas Nagel Robert Merrihew Adams Charles Taylor Joxe Azurmendi Christine Korsgaard Martha Nussbaum more... Related articles Casuistry Christian ethics Descriptive ethics Ethics in religion Evolutionary ethics Feminist ethics History of ethics Ideology Islamic ethics Jewish ethics Moral psychology Philosophy of law Political philosophy Population ethics Social philosophy Category v t e Veganism and vegetarianism Perspectives Veganism Animal-free agriculture Fruitarianism History Low-carbon diet Raw veganism Nutrition Vegan organic gardening Vegan studies Vegetarianism Economic vegetarianism Environmental vegetarianism History Lacto vegetarianism Orthopathy Ovo vegetarianism Ovo-lacto vegetarianism Cuisine Vegetarian Diet Pyramid Ecofeminism Nutrition By country Lists Vegetarians Vegans Fictional characters Vegetarian festivals Vegetarian organizations Vegetarian restaurants List of vegan media Ethics Secular Animal rights Animal welfare Carnism Deep ecology Environmental vegetarianism Ethics of eating meat Meat paradox Nonviolence Sentientism Speciesism Tirukkuṟaḷ Religious Buddhism Christianity (Seventh-day Adventist Church) Hinduism Sattvic Ahimsa Jainism Judaism Pythagoreanism Rastafari Sikhism Food, drink Agar Agave nectar Coconut burger Coconut milk Fruits Grains cereals legumes Meat analogue List of meat substitutes Miso Mochi Mock duck Nutritional yeast Plant cream Plant milk Quinoa Quorn Seitan Soy yogurt Tempeh Tofu Tofurkey Cheese Vegepet Vegetables Hot dog Vegetarian mark Sausage Beer Wine Veggie burger Groups and events Vegan American Vegan Society Beauty Without Cruelty Food Empowerment Project Go Vegan Movement for Compassionate Living Our Hen House Physicians Committee for Responsible Medicine Plamil Foods Nederlandse Vereniging voor Veganisme Vegan Awareness Foundation Vegan flag Vegan Ireland Vegan Outreach Vegan Prisoners Support Group Vegan school meal The Vegan Society The Good Food Institute Veganuary Veganz World Vegan Day Vegetarian Boston Vegetarian Society Christian Vegetarian Association European Vegetarian Union French Vegetarian Society Hare Krishna Food for Life International Vegetarian Union Jewish Veg Meat-free days Meatless Monday Friday Fast Order of the Golden Age ProVeg Deutschland ProVeg International ProVeg Nederland Swissveg Toronto Vegetarian Association Vegetarian Federal Union Vegetarian Society Vegetarian Society (Singapore) Veggie Pride Viva! Health World Esperantist Vegetarian Association World Vegetarian Day Companies List of vegetarian and vegan companies Books, reports An Essay on Abstinence from Animal Food, as a Moral Duty (1802) Vegetable Cookery (1812) A Vindication of Natural Diet (1813) Reasons for not Eating Animal Food (1814) Moral Inquiries on the Situation of Man and of Brutes (1824) Nature's Own Book (1835) Fruits and Farinacea (1845) What is Vegetarianism? (1886) Shelley's Vegetarianism (1891) Behind the Scenes in Slaughter-Houses (1892) Why I Am a Vegetarian (1895) Figs or Pigs? (1896) Thirty-nine Reasons Why I Am a Vegetarian (1903) The Meat Fetish (1904) A Fleshless Diet (1910) The Benefits of Vegetarianism (1927) Ten Talents (1968) Diet for a Small Planet (1971) The Farm Vegetarian Cookbook (1975) Laurel's Kitchen (1976) Moosewood Cookbook (1977) Fit for Life (1985) Diet for a New America (1987) The Sexual Politics of Meat (1990) Vegetarian Cooking for Everyone (1997) The China Study (2004) Skinny Bitch (2005) Livestock's Long Shadow (2006) The Bloodless Revolution (2006) Eating Animals (2009) Why We Love Dogs, Eat Pigs, and Wear Cows (2009) Animal (De)liberation (2016) The End of Animal Farming (2018) Meat Atlas (annual) Films Meet Your Meat (2002) Peaceable Kingdom (2004) Earthlings (2005) A Sacred Duty (2007) Fat, Sick and Nearly Dead (2010) Planeat (2010) Forks Over Knives (2011) Vegucated (2011) Live and Let Live (2013) Cowspiracy (2014) What the Health (2017) Carnage (2017) Dominion (2018) The Game Changers (2018) Magazines Naked Food Satya Vegetarian Times VegNews The Animals' Agenda Academics, physicians Contemporary Elisa Aaltola Carol J. Adams Martin Balluch Neal D. Barnard David Benatar Steven Best Yves Bonnardel T. Colin Campbell Jan Deckers Sue Donaldson Mylan Engel Gidon Eshel Caldwell Esselstyn Michael Allen Fox Gary L. Francione Joel Fuhrman Greta Gaard Valéry Giroux Michael Greger A. Breeze Harper Oscar Horta Melanie Joy Michael Klaper Aph Ko Thomas Lepeltier Andrew Linzey Clair Linzey Reed Mangels John A. McDougall James E. McWilliams Jack Norris David Olivier Dean Ornish David Pearce Tom Regan Richard H. Schwartz Peter Singer William O. Stephens David Sztybel Kim A. Williams Corey Lee Wrenn Laura Wright Historical William Alcott Thomas Allinson William Axon Horace A. Barrows George Bedborough Ernest Bell Rynn Berry Maximilian Bircher-Benner Ernest Bonnejoy Lucius Duncan Bulkley J. L. Buttner Paul Carton George Cheyne Henry S. Clubb Antonio Cocchi Charles W. Forward Narasinh Narayan Godbole Lewis Gompertz John Haddon Alexander Haig Edward Hare Philippe Hecquet Martin Luther Holbrook Isaac Jennings John Harvey Kellogg Daniel H. Kress William Lambe W. R. C. Latson Elmer McCollum Harry Willis Miller J. Howard Moore Reuben D. Mussey Francis William Newman Josiah Oldfield James Rachels Rollo Russell Henry Stephens Salt Russell Thacher Trall Howard Williams Related Vegetarian and vegan symbolism Vegetarian characters in fiction List of vegan media Juice fasting Vegetarian and vegan dog diet Vegaphobia Semi-vegetarianism Macrobiotic diet Pescetarianism Pollotarianism v t e Meat Main articles: Fish Game Insects Livestock Meat Poultry Seafood Poultry Cassowary Chicken Duck Emu Goose Grouse Ostrich Partridge Pheasant Pigeon Quail Rhea Turkey Livestock Alpaca Beef Beefalo Bison Buffalo Camel Cat Chevon (goat meat) Dog Elephant Escargot Frog Guinea pig Cuy Horse Lamb and mutton Llama Pork Veal Yak Żubroń Game Alligator Bat Bear Boar Crocodile Kangaroo Monkey Pangolin Rat Hare and rabbit Snake Turtle Venison Wolf Fish Anchovy Basa Bass Carp Catfish Cod Crappie Eel Flounder Grouper Haddock Halibut Herring Kingfish Mackerel Mahi Mahi Marlin Milkfish Orange roughy Pacific saury Perch Pike Pollock Salmon Sardine Shark Sole Swai Swordfish Tilapia Trout Tuna Walleye Shellfish and other seafood Abalone Calamari Clams Crab Crayfish Dolphin Lobster Mussel Octopus Oyster Scallop Seal meat Shrimp/prawn Sea urchin Whale Insects Black soldier fly maggots Cicada Crickets Grasshoppers (locust) Mealworm Silkworm Mopane worm Palm grub Cuts and preparation Aged Bacon Barbecued Biltong Braised Burger Charcuterie Chop Corned Cured Cutlet Dried Dum Fillet/supreme Fried Ground Ham Kebab Liver Luncheon meat Marinated Meatball Meatloaf Offal Pickled Poached Roasted Salt-cured Salumi Sausage Smoked Steak Stewed Tandoor Tartare List articles Beef dishes Chicken dishes Countries by meat consumption Fish dishes Food and drink prohibitions Goat dishes Lamb dishes Meatball dishes Pork dishes Ham dishes Sausage dishes Sausages Seafood dishes Smoked foods Steaks Veal dishes Related subjects Animal rights Bushmeat Butcher Cannibalism Carnism Case-ready meat Christian vegetarianism Cultured meat Entomophagy Ethics of eating meat Factory farming Feed conversion ratio Environmental impact of meat production List of meat dishes Marbled Meat analogue Meat cutter Meat tenderness Pescetarianism Pink slime Plant-based diet Preservation Psychology of eating meat Meat paradox Red meat Semi-vegetarianism Slaughter Slaughterhouse Veganism Vegetarianism White meat  Food portal  Category: Meat v t e Food industry criticism Books The Jungle (1906) Modern Meat (1984) Fast Food Nation (2001) Reefer Madness (2003) Shopped (2004) Chew on This (2006) My Secret Life on the McJob (2006) The Omnivore's Dilemma (2006) Eating Animals (2009) Wheat Belly (2011) Farmageddon: The True Cost of Cheap Meat (2014) Meat Atlas (annual) Films The Jungle (1914) McLibel (1997) The Corporation (2003) Super Size Me (2004) The Future of Food (2004) We Feed the World (2005) Wal-Mart: The High Cost of Low Price (2005) Our Daily Bread (2005) Earthlings (2005) Fast Food Nation (2006) Black Gold (2006) King Corn (2007) Food, Inc. (2008) Million Calorie March: The Movie (2008) The World According to Monsanto (2008) Fresh (2009) Bananas!* (2009) Big Boys Gone Bananas!* (2011) The Dark Side of Chocolate (2010) Forks Over Knives (2011) A Place at the Table (2013) Fed Up (2014) Cowspiracy (2014) Super Size Me 2: Holy Chicken! (2017) Organizations Coca-Cola Cargill Tesco Nestlé boycott McDonald's Concepts Child labour in cocoa production Fair trade coffee Fast food criticism Food safety Genetically modified food (controversies) By country China v t e Animal rights Topics (overviews, concepts, issues, cases) Overviews Animal rights movement Animal rights by country or territory Anarchism and animal rights Animal rights and punk subculture Animal rights and the Holocaust Animal rights in Jainism, Hinduism, and Buddhism Christianity and animal rights Moral status of animals in the ancient world Timeline of animal welfare and rights Universal Declaration on Animal Welfare Concepts Abolitionism Ahimsa Animal cognition Animal consciousness Animal ethics Animal law Animal protectionism Animal welfare Animal-free agriculture Anthrozoology Cambridge Declaration on Consciousness Carnism Equal consideration of interests Ethics of eating meat Ethics of uncertain sentience Ethology Meat paradox Nonviolence Open rescue Opposition to hunting Personism Sentientism Sentiocentrism Speciesism Veganism Vegaphobia Vegetarianism Issues Animal agriculture Animal product Battery cage Bile bear Chick culling Concentrated animal feeding operation Fish farming Fur farming Fur trade Insect farming Intensive animal farming Intensive pig farming Livestock Poultry farming Slaughterhouse Wildlife farming Animal testing Animal testing on non-human primates Animal testing regulations Covance Great ape research ban Green Scare Huntingdon Life Sciences Model organism Nafovanny Operation Backfire Animal welfare Animal euthanasia Cruelty to animals Pain in animals Pain in amphibians Pain in cephalopods Pain in crustaceans Pain in fish Pain in invertebrates Pain and suffering in laboratory animals Welfare of farmed insects Fishing Commercial fishing Fishing bait Recreational fishing Wild animals Culling wildlife Hunting International primate trade Ivory trade Predation problem Wild animal suffering Wildlife management Other Abandoned pets Animal sacrifice Animals in sport Live food Cases Brown Dog affair Cambridge University primates McLibel case Pit of despair Silver Spring monkeys University of California, Riverside 1985 laboratory raid Unnecessary Fuss Advocates (academics, writers, activists) Academics and writers Contemporary Carol J. Adams Kristin Andrews Tom Beauchamp Marc Bekoff Steven Best Paola Cavalieri Stephen R. L. Clark Alasdair Cochrane J. M. Coetzee Alice Crary David DeGrazia Sue Donaldson Josephine Donovan Lawrence Finsen Gary L. Francione Robert Garner Valéry Giroux John Hadley Oscar Horta Melanie Joy Hilda Kean Will Kymlicka Thomas Lepeltier Andrew Linzey Clair Linzey Dan Lyons Martha Nussbaum David Pearce Siobhan O'Sullivan Clare Palmer Bernard Rollin Mark Rowlands Richard D. Ryder Peter Singer Steve F. Sapontzis Jeff Sebo Gary Steiner Cass Sunstein David J. Wolfson Corey Lee Wrenn Historical David Renaud Boullier Peter Buchan Mona Caird Priscilla Cohn Henry Crowe Herman Daggett Richard Dean Wilhelm Dietler William Hamilton Drummond Edward Payson Evans Thomas G. Gentry Arthur Helps John Hildrop John Lawrence Charles R. Magel Mary Midgley J. Howard Moore José Ferrater Mora Edward Nicholson Humphrey Primatt Tom Regan Henry Stephens Salt Arthur Schopenhauer Laurids Smith John Styles Johann Friedrich Ludwig Volckmann Adam Gottlieb Weigen Jon Wynne-Tyson Activists Contemporary James Aspey Greg Avery Matt Ball Martin Balluch Carole Baskin Barbi Twins Brigitte Bardot Brigitte Gothière Bob Barker Gene Baur Yves Bonnardel Rod Coronado Karen Davis Chris DeRose John Feldmann Bruce Friedrich Juliet Gellatley Tal Gilboa Antoine Goetschel Jordan Halliday Ronnie Lee Evanna Lynch Bill Maher Keith Mann Jim Mason Dan Mathews Jo-Anne McArthur Luísa Mell Ingrid Newkirk Heather Nicholson Jack Norris David Olivier Alex Pacheco Craig Rosebraugh Nathan Runkle Jasmin Singer Kim Stallwood Marianne Thieme Darren Thurston Louise Wallis Gary Yourofsky Historical Cleveland Amory Henry B. Amos Ernest Bell Frances Power Cobbe Alice Drakoules Robert Enke Lewis Gompertz James Granger Barry Horne Marie Huot Lizzy Lind af Hageby Jill Phipps Catherine Smithies Henry Spira Andrew Tyler Movement (groups, parties) Groups Contemporary Animal Aid Animal Ethics Animal Justice Project Animal Legal Defense Fund Animal Liberation Front Anonymous for the Voiceless Centre for Animals and Social Justice Chinese Animal Protection Network Cruelty Free International Direct Action Everywhere Equanimal Farm Animal Rights Movement Great Ape Project Hunt Saboteurs Association In Defense of Animals Korea Animal Rights Advocates L214 Last Chance for Animals Mercy for Animals New England Anti-Vivisection Society Oxford Centre for Animal Ethics People for Animals People for the Ethical Treatment of Animals Sentience Politics Society for the Prevention of Cruelty to Animals United Poultry Concerns UPF-Centre for Animal Ethics Historical Bands of Mercy Humanitarian League (1891–1919) Oxford Group Parties Animal Justice Party (Australia) Animal Politics EU (Europe) Animal Protection Party of Canada (Canada) Animal Welfare Party (UK) Animal Justice Party of Finland (Finland) Animalist Party Against Mistreatment of Animals (Spain) DierAnimal (Belgium) Human Environment Animal Protection (Germany) Italian Animalist Party (Italy) Party for Animal Welfare (Ireland) Party for the Animals (Netherlands) People Animals Nature (Portugal) V-Partei³ (Germany) Media (books, films, periodicals, albums) Books Moral Inquiries on the Situation of Man and of Brutes (1824) Animals' Rights (1892) The Universal Kinship (1906) Animals, Men and Morals (1971) Animal Liberation (1975) The Case for Animal Rights (1983) The Lives of Animals (1999) Striking at the Roots (2008) An American Trilogy (2009) An Introduction to Animals and Political Theory (2010) Animal Rights Without Liberation (2012) Political Animals and Animal Politics (2014) Animal (De)liberation (2016) Sentientist Politics (2019) Films The Animals Film (1981) A Cow at My Table (1998) Shores of Silence (2000) The Witness (2000) Meet Your Meat (2002) The Meatrix (2003) Peaceable Kingdom (2004) Earthlings (2005) Behind the Mask (2006) Your Mommy Kills Animals (2007) The Cove (2009) Peaceable Kingdom: The Journey Home (2009) Forks Over Knives (2011) Vegucated (2011) An Apology to Elephants (2013) Speciesism: The Movie (2013) The Ghosts in Our Machine (2013) Unlocking the Cage (2016) Dominion (2018) Periodicals Journals Animal Sentience Between the Species Cahiers antispécistes Journal of Animal Ethics Relations. Beyond Anthropocentrism Magazines Arkangel Bite Back Muutoksen kevät No Compromise Satya Albums Animal Liberation (1987) Tame Yourself (1991) Manifesto (2008) Salvation of Innocents (2014) Onward to Freedom (2014) Category ( 85 ) Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Ethics_of_eating_meat&oldid=998522566" Categories: Animal rights Cruelty to animals Ethical consumerism Issues in ethics Hidden categories: Webarchive template wayback links CS1 maint: archived copy as title CS1 French-language sources (fr) All articles with dead external links Articles with dead external links from July 2016 Articles with permanently dead external links Articles with short description Short description matches Wikidata Use dmy dates from March 2018 All articles with unsourced statements Articles with unsourced statements from June 2017 Articles with unsourced statements from December 2015 Navigation menu Personal tools Not logged in Talk Contributions Create account Log in Namespaces Article Talk Variants Views Read Edit View history More Search Navigation Main page Contents Current events Random article About Wikipedia Contact us Donate Contribute Help Learn to edit Community portal Recent changes Upload file Tools What links here Related changes Upload file Special pages Permanent link Page information Cite this page Wikidata item Print/export Download as PDF Printable version Languages العربية Español हिन्दी ไทย Türkçe Tiếng Việt Edit links This page was last edited on 5 January 2021, at 19:30 (UTC). Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization. Privacy policy About Wikipedia Disclaimers Contact Wikipedia Mobile view Developers Statistics Cookie statement