key: cord-017479-s4e47bwx authors: Pulcini, Elena title: Spectators and Victims: Between Denial and Projection date: 2012-03-16 journal: Care of the World DOI: 10.1007/978-94-007-4482-0_6 sha: doc_id: 17479 cord_uid: s4e47bwx This chapter goes into the unproductive metamorphosis of fear, and analyses the defence mechanisms that it generates: namely denial and projection. In the case of global risks, fear provokes self-defensive strategies based on denial (in the face of the nuclear challenge) and self-deception (in the face of global warming); and, in the case of the threat of the other, projective and persecutory strategies based on reactivating the dynamic of the ‘scapegoat’. They are two contrasting but specular responses which, at the emotional level, reflect the divarication between (unlimited) individualism and (endogamous) communitarianism. The first, implosive response converts into an absence of fear, attested to above all by the figure of the global spectator, while the second, explosive response converts into an excess of fear (fear of the other, fear of contamination), fuelled by forms of reinventing community. These responses are defined as irrational since in the first case they inhibit the spectator’s capacity to recognize himself as also a potential victim of the threats, thus preventing his mobilization, and in the second case they give rise to dynamics of demonization-dehumanization of the other, which result in a spiral of violence and impede forms of solidarity. this case a subjective factor comes into play, linked to the capacity and manner of perceiving the threats. It is telling that sociology and psychology converge on the importance of this aspect, underlining the fact that the very characteristics of the risk have a de fi nite in fl uence on the way in which it is perceived. 4 Ulrich Beck had already stressed the fact that the often invisible nature of the global risks, the unforeseeability of their effects and the only potential character of the damage which they provoke mean that they are removed from our perception and require the intervention of a re fl exive attitude interpreting the new scenarios through a knowledge that is equal to the new challenges. But in reality the problem is more complex still, since rather than an absence, we are faced with processes that distort the perception and assessment of the risk, which affect both the emotional and the cognitive spheres, and above all how they interact together. Among the approaches sensitive to this problem, the one which seems to dwell on it most is cognitive psychology. Starting from the classic studies by Chauncey Starr and then Fischoff and Slovic, 5 and on the basis of the so-called psychometric paradigm, cognitive psychology has built complex cognitive maps aimed at providing as exhaustive a list as possible of the variables that in fl uence the subjective perception of risk. The conclusions that have emerged from this interpretative approach show, for example, that concern in the face of threats (whether they derive from particular activities, substances or technologies) grows in correspondence to certain characteristics, amongst which the involuntary nature of the risks, the impossibility of controlling them, their capacity to cause irreversible damage and their originating from an unknown source. But above all, the results stress the fact that individuals are subject to distorted assessments and judgements in relation to the risks they are exposed to. For example, they tend to overestimate threats publicized by the media even if they are infrequent; to consider dangers dealt with voluntarily as more acceptable compared to those to which we are subjected or which are completely unprecedented or not very familiar; to feel fear in the face of very vivid events (11 September 2001), at the same time being quite incapable of a historical memory that links these same events together. While the merit of this approach is that it accepts and recognizes the presence of the subjective aspect and the uncertainty factor in de fi ning the concept of risk, pointing out the presence of non-rational responses, its limits lie, however, in its still strongly assuming the notion of probability. 7 Namely, it ignores what is instead underlined by Mary Douglas, that is, the social and institutional context and the symbolic-cultural factors that in fl uence the perception of the threats, 8 and reproposes the idea of an essentially individualistic and de-contextualized social actor based on an abstract idea of rationality. Finally, what we are most interested in here, in part deriving from the latter aspect, the limit of this approach lies in its failure to account for the why , the deep reasons that pollute a correct perception and assessment of the risks. In this connection, based on the reassessment of the role of emotions that has greatly questioned the hegemonic paradigm of rationality 9 over the last few decades, some authors have underlined that cognitive and emotional factors have to go together in order to recognize the existence of a risk and to weigh up its possible consequences. 10 They have put forward the idea that the information that enters our cognitive system can only have an effective impact on our action if it succeeds in creating images laden with emotion in our psyche. In other words, this means that we can be perfectly aware of particular threats without this involving us emotionally. Put differently, only if this converts into the capacity to 'feel', to react emotionally and imagine its possible effects can our knowledge of the risk be effectively said to be knowledge, and therefore produce apt mobilization. Now, the problem with regard to global risks seems to be prompted, as Günther Anders had already perfectly grasped in his diagnosis of fear in the age of technology, by the very imbalance between knowing and feeling. This imbalance is none other than one of the many variants of the psychic split that characterizes the contemporary subject and that Anders, as has already been hinted, calls the 'Promethean gap'. With this expression, he alludes in general to the detachment between the faculties, fi rst of all between the power to do and the capacity to foresee, which characterizes contemporary homo faber , or rather homo faber who has become homo creator . Paradoxically what corresponds to the immense human power to 115 6.1 Global Risks and Absence of Fear produce and create permitted by developments in technology is man's inability to imagine its consequences: The faculties have got further and further away from each other so now they can no longer see each other; as they cannot see each other, they no longer come into contact, they no longer do each other harm. In short: man as such no longer exists, there only exists he who acts or produces on one hand, and he who feels on the other; man as producer and man as feeling, and only these specialized fragments of men have a reality. 11 No more are our imagination and our emotions equal to our unlimited power; at this point man's soul is irreparably 'outdated' with respect to what he produces and his colossal performances. In short, no more can we keep up-to-date with our Promethean productivity and with the world that we ourselves have built: we are about to build a world that we cannot keep up with, and, in order to "catch" it, demands are made that go way beyond our imagination, our emotions and our responsibility. 12 This 'schizophrenia', 13 which is where the fundamental pathology of our time resides, prompts the paradoxical and ambivalent combination of power and impotence, activity and passivity, knowledge and unawareness that exposes the contemporary Prometheus not only to previously inconceivable risks, but, also and above all, to the impossibility to recognize their destructive potential. This pathological drift appears particularly evident in the risk par excellence of the age of technology, which undermines not only the quality of individuals' lives (like in the case of the possible effects of the biotechnologies), but humankind's very survival on the planet: namely, the risk produced by the creation of the nuclear bomb, which we can recognize as the fi rst effectively global challenge. 14 Before the horror of Hiroshima and the spectre of humankind's self-destruction Anders says: We really have gained the omnipotence that we had been yearning for so long, with Promethean spirit, albeit in a different form to what we hoped for. Given that we possess the strength to prepare each other's end, we are the masters of the Apocalypse. We are in fi nity . 15 But the inability of our imagination to be equal to our unlimited power makes the latter mortally dangerous and transforms us into potential victims of what we ourselves have built: We, the men of today, are the fi rst men to dominate the Apocalypse, hence we are also the fi rst to be endlessly subject to its threat. We are the fi rst Titans, hence we are also the fi rst dwarves or pygmies -or whatever else we care to call ourselves, we beings with our collective deadline -we are no longer mortal as individuals, but as a group; whose existence is exposed to annulment. 16 Suf fi ce it to think that it is impossible to see the bomb simply a means; an impossibility generated by the fact that if someone used the bomb… the means would not be extinguished in the purpose, but, on the contrary, the effect of the presumed "means" would put an end to the purpose. And it would not be one effect, but an unforeseeable chain of effects, in which the end of our life would be but one link among the many. 17 The gap between the power to do and the power to foresee, therefore, gives rise to the paradoxical coexistence of omnipotence and vulnerability, which exposes future humankind and the whole of civilization to the risk of extinction, thereby con fi guring the apocalyptic scenario of a 'world without man'. 18 But the problem does not stop here. Indeed, if men, even when faced with the loss of foresight and projectuality caused by their own action, were capable of recognizing the reality of the danger, a change of direction could be set in motion to restore their control over their future. Or, to put it in terms that allow us to return to our theme, if people felt fear in the face of the spectre of self-destruction and the enormity of the risks ahead, they would probably manage to break that Promethean spiral of unlimitedness and restore sense and purpose to their action. Furthermore, this is the normative premise at the basis of Hans Jonas's whole line of argument in favour of an ethics of responsibility. He starts from a similar diagnosis to that of Anders on the drifts of technological power and the threats, for the whole living world, produced by a ' fi nally unbound Prometheus' to suggest what he de fi nes as a 'heuristics of fear', as the precondition for ethically responsible action. ' […] it is an anticipated distortion of man,' he says, 'that helps us to detect that in the normative conception of man which is to be preserved from that threat […] . We know the thing at stake only when we know that it is at stake .' 19 This means that only the fear of 'losing the world' can push us to responsibly take on the problem of how to preserve it. I shall come back to the nexus between fear and responsibility later on. 20 But the problem, which Anders strongly underlines -showing, unlike Jonas, its complex anthropological and psychic roots -is that today we are in the presence of the unavailability of fear ; in actual fact it is paradoxically absent, due to the additional and deeper manifestation of the Promethean gap which is the imbalance between knowing and feeling . Indeed, there is no one who does not know what the bomb is and who does not know its possible, catastrophic consequences, but, Anders adds, 'most people indeed only "know" it: in the emptiest of manners'. 21 Namely, this 17 22 This asynchrony, Anders points out, is something that pertains to human nature as a matter of fact. In general, in itself this is not bad, since it only shows that feeling is slower to transform. However, so to speak, it degenerates into a pathology when the gap between the faculties becomes too wide, as is happening today. As a consequence, it breaks all bonds and communication between them, 23 and reduces contemporary men to the 'most dissociated, most disproportionate in themselves, most inhuman that have ever existed.' 24 Therefore, it is here, in the inadequacy of our emotional resources with respect to our productive power, that the anthropological root of our 'blindness to the Apocalypse' lies. 25 And this inadequacy, which is true for all the emotions in general, concerns fear fi rst of all. Everyone, in however confused a manner and in spite of the minimization strategies implemented by those who produce it, realize that the bomb is not a pure means whose function ends in the ful fi lment of a purpose, but a monstrous ' unicum ' that, together with our lives and the lives of future generations, can put an end to all purposes tout court . 26 Yet, surprisingly, there is no fear : If today we were to seek out fear ( Angst ),* real fear in Vienna Paris, London, New Yorkwhere the expression ' Age of Anxiety ' is very much in use -, the booty would be extremely modest. Of course, we would fi nd the word 'fear', in swarms even, in whole reams of publications […] . Because today fear has become a commodity; and these days everyone is talking about fear. But those talking out of fear these days are very few. 27 If we are to observe our present-day situation, we could even claim that the more fear becomes the subject of talk in the newspapers and mass media, the more it is withdrawn from emotional perception and is anaesthetized by the reassuring urgency of routine and day-to-day concerns. The anaesthetizing mechanism also works in a directly proportionate manner to the enormity of the risk and the stake at play. While it may be true that at best we 22 Ibid., I, 269. 23 Ibid., I, 267-68. 24 Ibid., I, 271-72. 25 See ibid., Part IV, I, 234ff. Anders underlines its historical roots, such as trust in progress that prevents man from thinking of an 'end', and above all, the con fi guration at the anthropological level of what he de fi nes as the 'medial man', whose passive and conformist action ends up removing his ability to project himself into the future, together with all sense and purpose. See ibid., Part 5, I, 276ff. 26 Ibid., I, 254ff. * Translator's note: Anders only uses one term -Angst -and does not distinguish between anxiety and fear. Since, however, the meaning with which he uses the term Angst coincides more with 'fear' in the acceptation put forward by Elena Pulcini, I have decided to translate it with 'fear' so as to distinguish it from 'anxiety'. 27 Ibid., I, 264. are able to imagine our own death, but not that of tens or thousands of people, and that we may be able to destroy a whole city without batting an eyelid while not managing, however, to imagine the actual, terrible scenario of 'smoke, blood and ruins', it is inevitable that we are totally incapable of perceiving the destruction of all humankind 28 : 'Before the thought of the Apocalypse, the soul remains inert. The thought remains a word.' 29 Even though today the end of humankind has entered the sphere of possibility and even though man himself is responsible for this, the psyche removes the thought of this possibility, thus preventing fear from arising. Hence, we are illiterate in fear -'Analphabeten der Angst' -and 'if one had to seek a motto for our age, the most appropriate thing to call it would be "the era of the inability to feel fear"'. 30 Anders's diagnosis concerning the anaesthetizing of fear and the imbalance between knowing and feeling seems to fi nd a perfect correspondence in that distinctive defence mechanism that Freud de fi ned as 'denial of reality'. 31 More complex and subtle than repression ( Verdrängung ), which indicates the operation with which the subject pushes particular representations linked to an instinct to the unconscious, and which for Freud becomes a sort of prototype of defence mechanisms, denial ( Verleugnung ) causes the Self, despite rationally recognizing a painful and dif fi cult situation, to prevent this reaching the emotional sphere. 32 In other words, while repression is a defence against internal instinctual demands , denial is a defence against the claims of external reality , 33 which is rationally recognized, but not emotionally felt or participated. This converts into that distinctive ambivalence of 'knowing and not-knowing' which, as has recently been 28 Ibid., I, 268-69. 29 Ibid., I, 269. 30 In his recent sociological valuation of the concept of 'denial', Stanley Cohen stresses this ambivalence, pointing this out as the most interesting side of the concept, 36 and above all the most suited to accounting for a series of phenomena that characterize contemporary reality. Explicitly drawing from psychoanalysis, whose worth he acknowledges -if nothing else against the reductive simpli fi cations of cognitive psychology 37 -as more than any other approach having grasped the elusive quality of the concept of denial, Cohen offers a de fi nition that fi rst of all takes into account the meaning that is more general and common to the various forms: […] people, organizations, governments or whole societies are presented with information that is too disturbing, threatening or anomalous to be fully absorbed or openly acknowledged. The information is therefore somehow repressed, disavowed, pushed aside or reinterpreted. Or else the information "registers" well enough, but its implications -cognitive, emotional or moral -are evaded, neutralized or rationalized away.' 38 On the basis of this premise, Cohen analyses the many forms of denial. It can occur in good faith or be deliberate and intentional; it changes in relation to the subjects' different positions, that is, whether they are victims, guilty parties or witnesses; it depends on how the object is evaluated, which can be expressed through a simple refusal to acknowledge the facts, through a different interpretation or through a rationalization that aims to prevent its psychological, political and moral implications. But the most disconcerting and problematic form, since it can affect whole cultures -as is the case today -is what makes the subjects of the denial aware and unaware at the same time, that is, placed on the threshold between consciousness and unconsciousness. Here they do have access to the reality, but in such a way as to ignore it since it is too frightening or painful, or simply too unpleasant to accept. 'We are vaguely aware,' Cohen says, 'of choosing not to look at the facts, but not quite conscious of just what it is we are evading. We know, but at the same time we don't know.' 39 For example, much more than the intentional denial which is often 34 Ibid, 22. 35 Anders, Die Antiquiertheit des Menschen , I, 269-70. 36 Cohen, States of Denial . 37 'The cognitive revolution of the last thirty years has removed all traces of Freudian and other motivational theories. If you distort the external world, this means that your faculties of information processing and rational decision making are faulty.' (Ibid., 42) . 38 Ibid., 1. 39 Ibid., 5. Moreover, this is the core of the Freudian concept, which evidently presupposes the idea of splitting the ego ( Ichspaltung ): 'Freud,' says Cohen, 'was fascinated by the idea that awkward facts of life could be handled by simultaneous acceptance and disavowal. They are too threatening to confront, but impossible to ignore. The compromise solution is to deny and acknowledge them at the same time.' (Ibid., 27) . implemented by political actors and institutional authorities to cover up regrettable facts and unpopular decisions, this is the frame of mind that most interests us and disturbs us because it can explain the widespread and paradoxical indifference with which common people react to situations of suffering, atrocities and violence. 40 Tellingly, the focus of Cohen's whole and documented analysis seems to be the fi gure of the 'passive bystander' who, when faced with other people's suffering (whether this is experienced in a direct manner like a rape or episode of bullying, or is distant like genocide or torture), defensively withdraws from all involvement, pretending not to see and not to know, inhibiting emotional reactions, minimizing the event's capacity or changing channel if the information is transmitted through mass media images. Hence the bystander withdraws from facing up to painful and embarrassing situations and avoids all possible mobilization. Therefore, Cohen seems, quite rightly, to rediscover denial above all as a reaction of defence in the face of other people's suffering where this assumes such proportions as not to be acceptable by the psyche. As a consequence, he fi nds it to be the root of the emotional indifference that today seems to be permeating contemporary societies. Nevertheless, as we have seen, Anders's re fl ection allows us to grasp another aspect of denial that sharpens its paradoxical nature, since it concerns the tendency to ignore, wipe out or minimize something that not only concerns other people's destinies, but that threatens our own lives: like in the exemplary case of denying the global challenge par excellence , the nuclear risk. Consistent with Anders's diagnosis, a few decades ago the psychoanalysis of war had already re fl ected on the radical changes caused by the nuclear threat with respect to the traditional forms of war con fl ict, and hence explained, more or less indirectly, the psychic roots of this speci fi c case of denial. While underlining the abstract or phantasmal nature of the danger at the objective level -due to the invisibility and intangibility of nuclear weapons, the distance of the target, as well as the bureaucratic 'normality' of those who hold the actual decision-making powersome authors have singled out the unprecedented nature of the nuclear con fl ict in its split and autonomization from the individual's instinctual sphere. 41 That is, unlike traditional war, based on mobilizing aggressive instincts, nuclear war (its destructive potential) appears as a mechanical event, or rather, a psychologically unreal event, in which the 'enemy' himself, far from being the object of projective dynamics, becomes an inanimate abstraction with whom all emotional bonds are lost. 42 This sort of 'dehumanization' of war, which affects the relationship with the other and the relationship with oneself to the same extent, thereby producing its 40 'The grey areas between consciousness and unconsciousness are far more signi fi cant in explaining ordinary public responses to knowledge about atrocities and suffering' (ibid., 6). 41 'devitalization', 43 is at the root, together with the enormity of the risk and the impossibility to 'think the unthinkable', 44 of the denial of the danger, which immunizes individuals from emotional involvement, and, therefore, from true awareness. It is telling that, in addition to denial, Martin Wangh spoke of a 'narcissistic withdrawal', 45 as he alluded to the entropic and self-defensive strategy of individuals reduced to passive and indifferent 'spectators' of events. Individuals who, with respect to events, preclude any form of effective reaction and thus inhibit the insurgence of fear at the outset. I will return to the 'spectator phenomenon' shortly. 46 As I have already hinted, this phenomenon is one of the most disturbing pathologies of contemporary individualism. First, however, it is interesting to dwell on one of the -so to speakmore active variants of denial, which consists not only of withdrawal from a reality that is uncomfortable or painful for the psyche, sheltering in a sort of emotional indifference, but of lying to ourselves in order to believe something that does not respond to our rational evaluations, but to our desires. This is self-deception , a defence mechanism that has tellingly been de fi ned as 'the most extreme form of the paradox of irrationality'. 47 Without going into the (at times muddled) analytical controversies relating to a concept that is without doubt slippery and problematic, 48 we can, however, try to sum up the characteristics -shared by many authors -which prove fruitful in further extending the picture relating to the metamorphosis of fear in the global age. Self-deception is what pushes individuals to form a belief that contrasts with the information and proof at their disposal, since their desires end up interfering with their vision of reality and cause them to act in a different way from what their rational judgement would suggest. In other words, it consists of believing something because one desires it to be true, 49 hence it converges, despite some differences, with 43 Martin Wangh speaks of 'dehumanization' and 'devitalization' (meant as the impoverishment of the ability to feel) in 'Narcissism in Our Time: Some Psychoanalytic Re fl ections on Its Genesis," Psychoanalytic Quarterly 52 (1983). 44 The allusion is to the text by Herman Kahn, Thinking About the Unthinkable (New York: Horizon Press, 1962). 45 Martin Wangh, "The Nuclear Threat: Its Impact on Psychoanalytic Conceptualizations," Psychoanalytical Inquiry , no. 6 (1986). 46 The expression ( Zuschauer-Phänomen ) is by Martin Wangh, "Die Herrschaft des Thanatos," in Zur Psychoanalyse der Nuklearen Drohung. Vorträge einer Tagung der Deutchsen Gesellschaft für Psychotherapie, Psychosomatik und Tiefenpsychologie , ed. Carl Nedelmann (Göttingen: Verlag für medizinische Psychologie, 1985). 47 David Pears, "The Goals and Strategies of Self-Deception," in The Multiple Self , ed. Elster, 60; Giovanni Jervis, Fondamenti di psicologia dinamica (Milan: Feltrinelli, 1993) and Massimo Marraffa, "Il problema dell'autoinganno: una guida per il lettore," Sistemi intelligenti , no. 3 (1999): 373-403. 48 '[…] self-deception,' Davidson says, 'is a problem for philosophical psychology. For in thinking about self-deception, as in thinking about other forms of irrationality, we fi nd ourselves tempted by opposing thoughts.' (Donald Davidson, "Deception and Division," in The Multiple Self , ed. Elster, 79). 49 Ibid., 86. the dynamic of wishful thinking. 50 Like denial, meant in its pure form, so to speak, self-deception implies Ichspaltung , no matter what name may be given to what Freud identi fi ed as the splitting of the ego. 51 Finally, like denial, it is an ambivalent phenomenon since it acts in that threshold between consciousness and unconsciousness which, as Cohen stresses in this case too, creates a paradoxical situation of knowing and not-knowing. 52 But while denial appears, as we have seen, effective in explaining the lack of perception and the anaesthetizing of fear in the face of the nuclear threat, selfdeception can prove pertinent in order to understand the complex emotional response that individuals give to the other global risk already brought up above: that is, the twofold environmental risk of global warming and the depletion of the ozone layer, which by no means seems to generate that mobilization of the whole of humankind which it would instead -urgently -require. 53 From this point of view, the recently proposed de fi nition of 'global risks in the making' or 'potentially global' risks, which tends to distinguish them from the global risk par excellence represented by nuclear power, 54 can prove to be extremely useful in explaining the however blurred difference in the subject's reaction and in further enlightening the phenomenology of fear. The inde fi nite nature that without doubt also pertains to the nuclear risk is greatly stressed here, due to the fact that global warming and depletion of the ozone layer have wider margins of uncertainty created by their inertial nature, the impossibility to measure and foresee their future development, and therefore to calculate with certainty, together with their possible effects, the last deadline for possible countermeasures. Their ungraspable and invisible nature, further fuelled by the dif fi culty to point the fi nger of blame mean that, in spite of the alarming international reports on the climate and reliable scienti fi c forecasts on the devastating future damage, moreover given increasing mass media coverage, individuals mostly seem 50 In Paradoxes of Irrationality (in Richard A. Wollheim and James Hopkins, eds., Philosophical Essays on Freud , (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982)), Davidson upholds that in wishful thinking desire produces a belief without providing any proof in its favour, so that in this case the belief is evidently irrational. However, he underlines the differences between self-denial and wishful thinking: unlike the second, the fi rst requires the agent's intervention, that is, the agent has to 'do' something to change his way of seeing things; in the second the belief always takes the direction of positive effect, never of negative, while in the fi rst the thought that it triggers can be painful (see 'Deception and Division', 85ff.). 51 In this connection Pears speaks of 'functional insulation', "Goals and Strategies of Self-Deception", 71; Davidson speaks of 'boundaries': '[…] I postulate such a boundary somewhere between any (obviously) con fl icting beliefs. Such boundaries are not discovered by introspection; they are conceptual aids to the coherent description of genuine irrationalities.' "Deception and Division", 91-92. On self-denial and splitting of the ego, see Herbert Fingarette, Self-Deception (London : Henley-Routledge, 1969) . 52 See Cohen, States of Denial , 37ff. 53 It is important to point out that the second problem (the one relating to the risk of ozone layer depletion) nevertheless found some solutions as of the Montreal Protocol in 1987, made possible due to the fact that they did not require costs or relinquishments in terms of economics or lifestyle. 54 D'Andrea, "Rischi ambientali globali e aporie della modernità". to fail to suitably perceive the phenomenon. Instead, it is often shrugged off with detached irony towards the excessive catastrophism, with resigned declarations of impotence, or the expression of enlightened trust in the capacities of technology to repair the situation. 55 In other words, despite being rationally known and recognized, the risk does not produce such emotional involvement as to give rise to effective answers. At most it produces a widespread and generic feeling of anxiety which ends up imploding, sucked in by the much more real worries of everyday life. The causes of this paradoxical situation can be traced fi rst of all to within the same dynamic of fear of which, as I will recall, Hobbes's diagnosis had grasped an essential aspect. Namely, fear as a necessary and vital passion that allows us to respond to the immediate danger (of death) loses its ef fi cacy when the danger, and the damage it could cause, are shifted to the future, that is, when a time gap inserts itself between the present action (based on destructive passions) and its possible consequences. Thus all certainty and inexorability are taken away from the evil, enabling individuals to imagine it as a remote and avoidable possibility, for which it makes no sense to mobilize themselves immediately. In other words, in this case, fear does not manage to overcome the passions of the present. Hobbes's intuition is all the more valid in the case of global risks, whose possible damage is even more remote and does not concern current individuals, but future generations. That is, fear does not have the strength to change present action (and therefore the underlying desires and passions) when the damage that this action can cause is not an evil for ourselves but for 'others': anonymous, generic and distant in time. In short, by weakening fear, the future nature of the damage makes it easy for essentially selfpreserving and narcissistic individuals to deceive themselves as to the actual entity of the risk and therefore to minimize or deny the possible consequences. In this case, the aim is not so much for individuals to defend themselves emotionally from events that are too painful to bear (like in the case of nuclear con fl ict), but to carry on with a manner of acting that allows them to legitimize and satisfy their current desires, preserve their lifestyles and not lose consolidated privileges. To once again recall the pathologies of the global Self, we could say that the acquisitive voracity of homo creator , orientated towards unlimited growth, combines with the parasitic bent of a consumer individual anchored solely to the present, to prevent access -through the cunning of self-deception -to a correct perception of the catastrophic effects of climate change, global warming, the greenhouse effect and depletion of the ozone layer. This appears all the more paradoxical where these effects start to be dramatically visible: tropicalization of the climate, deserti fi cation, destruction of the ecosystem, lethal viruses and infective diseases are no longer only remote possibilities but the disturbing proof of environmental risks. By now scattered all over the planet, 56 they affect whole geographical areas and populations, damaging the illusion of individuals and states' immunity more and more. Indeed, despite not just abstract information and forecasts, but a more and more invasive state of affairs that is starting to concern them at close quarters, guaranteed and supported by the instrumental interests of local politics and the global economy, individuals prefer to deceive themselves in order not to pay the costs of relinquishing their current desires, assets and pleasures; further eased, in this self-defensive operation, by the morally innocent, innocuous and banally everyday nature of the action that produces the risks. 57 Moreover, the absence of a 'productive' fear, inhibited by denial and self-deception, is not belied by the cyclical outbursts of panic and collective hysteria in the face of the sudden appearance of threats (as has always been the case, from Chernobyl, to SARS and bird fl u). On the contrary, the absence and the excess of fear are nothing but two sides of the same coin, 58 the two extreme and 'unproductive' manifestations of what I de fi ned as global fear . Both denial and self-deception leave individuals in the passive position of spectators of events. Thus they are enclosed in the immunitarian circuit of a self-defensive and self-preserving individualism which anaesthetizes fear and is incapable of converting into effective action, practice or political participation. Alongside the two extroverted pathologies, so to speak, of unlimited individualism, represented by the insatiable voracity of the consumer individual and the omnipotence of homo creator , appears a third, paradoxically introverted con fi guration, namely a passive and impotent individual, who helplessly watches the destructive effects of his own action, over which he seems to have lost all capacity for orientation and control. Against the loss of objective spaces of protection and security, increasingly eroded by the global diffusion of the risks, he seems to seek shelter, as I have already hinted , 59 in a sort of interior immunity , entrenching himself in the emotional indifference that is just one of the many manifestations of narcissism. In addition, the yearning for immunity becomes more tenacious and obstinate the more it is felt to be ineffective and illusory. Thus a new condition is outlined, which to recall the metaphorical fi gures proposed by Hans Blumenberg in his Shipwreck with Spectator , 60 is neither the premodern and 'Lucretian' condition of the spectator watching the shipwreck from a safe place, sheltered from the danger, nor the modern and 'Pascalian' condition of being the actors of our own lives, ' être embarqués ', involved in the things of the world and ready to put ourselves at stake fi rst of all by recognizing the constitutive precariousness of the human condition and accepting the very risk of existence. While modernity had rati fi ed the decline of the spectator fi gure, and enhanced the moments of practice and action, involvement and commitment; and while late modernity had radicalized his condemnation by emphasizing the need to expose oneself to risk and accept the uncertainty and fl uidity of the human condition, 61 the global age seems to be objectively bringing the spectator up-to-date, which nevertheless coincides with a deep and disturbing change with respect to the fi gure of the Lucretian wise man. The erosion of boundaries and disappearance of an 'elsewhere'redrawing global space, cancelling out the distinction between inside and out -is turning into the loss of free areas from where the shipwreck can be observed. At this point, due to the end of every real guarantee of immunity, deprived of the possibility of a safe harbour where he can feel sheltered from the world's dangers, the global Self withdraws into the only space apparently able to protect him from events and threats that he is not able to deal with: namely, the wholly interior space of an emotional indifference, an anaesthetizing of emotions , generated by implementing sophisticated and for the most part unconscious defence mechanisms. In other words, the spectator fi gure is undergoing a process of interiorization , which replaces the spatial distance from the shipwreck and the contemplative safety of the Lucretian subject with the apathetical extraneousness and obstinate blindness of he who refuses to recognize the very risk of the shipwreck, and encloses himself in the entropic space of an inert solitude. Moreover, the spectator phenomenon seems to pervade the whole social structure, due to the spectacularization of reality that, as Jacques Debord had already masterfully diagnosed a few decades ago, deeply upsets the very nature of social relations. 62 By denouncing the erosion of the boundaries between real and virtual and the pervasive power of images (mass media images fi rst of all), and by diagnosing life's 'total colonization' by commodi fi cation processes and the indistinctive overlapping of true and false as the effects of the 'society of the spectacle', Debord had indeed grasped the spectator fi gure as the symptom and symbol of a new form of alienation that invades the individual's whole relationship with the world. Passiveness and submission to the totalitarianism of images, prioritization of appearance, loss of contact with one's desires and genuine needs, atomism and isolation are among the most evident and disturbing characteristics of the spectator-individual, who thus ends up losing all capacity to be involved and to grasp reality. In short, the emotional indifference in which individuals shelter in order to cancel out the awareness of the risks surrounding them, unconsciously implementing powerful defence mechanisms, seems to be a sort of inevitable outcome of a widespread anthropological condition. Or rather, it seems to be the extreme form of a general tendency towards apathy and inertia, produced by a spectacular society that empties reality of its contents and thus deprives individuals of pathos and action. Suf fi ce it to think of the de-realizing effects, with respect to the effective drama of events, produced by mass media images (for example the fi rst Gulf War), 63 or the narcotizing addiction that they cause to dangers and catastrophes of all kinds (from tsunamis to SARS). The images deprive events of the fl esh and blood of the experience and neutralize them in the aseptic and equalizing space of the screen. However, the problem today is no longer the subject's passivization and atomization alone, nor his a-pathetical detachment from reality: aspects which, moreover, sociological re fl ection on narcissism had already underlined some time ago, and to which the most recent and sagacious sociological diagnoses do not fail to draw attention. 64 The problem, as we have seen, regards above all the negation of reality and the possible destructive effects of this denial on the very survival of individuals and the whole of humankind. By withdrawing into the immunitarian space of a selfdefensive apathy, the global spectator performs a dangerously illusory operation which precludes the possibility to perceive and understand what the unprecedented risk of the global age is: namely, that he himself is the potential victim of events from which there is no shelter, or rather, from which there is no other possible shelter than active and universal mobilization. 65 While it may be true that the hallmark of global challenges is that they cross boundaries and no perimeter can be drawn around or circumscribe them, it is also true that everyone, in every corner of the planet, is always potentially exposed to their effects, that everyone is always potentially a victim of a shipwreck which, for the fi rst time, could affect and sweep away humankind and all living beings. By anaesthetizing fear, the denial (and self-deception) strategy paradoxically ends up betraying the very same purpose that it had been implemented for: namely, self-preservation. Or rather, in order to pursue an entropic and defensive selfpreservation that preserves them from all emotional and active involvement, not only are individuals undermining the quality of their lives, but the very preservation of humankind and the world. 63 See Antonio Scurati, Televisioni di guerra. Il con fl itto del Golfo come evento mediatico e il paradosso dello spettatore totale (Verona: Ombre Corte, 2003), who observes how the increase in media exposure of the war phenomenon corresponds to a lesser ability, on the part of the spectator, to grasp its reality. As a result, on the part of the citizen there is less possibility to decide and act. In other words, the 'total visibility' offered by the television medium corresponds, in an only apparent paradox, to the blindness and impotence of the 'total spectator'. 64 This unwillingly nihilistic outcome could perhaps be interpreted as a radical and extreme manifestation of the immunitarian paradigm recognized as the very emblem of modernity, owing to which the preservation of life is paradoxically turned around into its negation. 66 However, what I would like to stress, to go back to Anders's diagnosis, is the fact that -in this case at least -this worrying reversal originates in the pathologies of feeling and the denial of fear, which prevent individuals from recognizing their paradoxical condition of spectators and victims at the same time. Denial, however, is just one of the unproductive metamorphoses of fear in the global age, and only one of the strategies that the global individual uses to contrast the anxious perception of new risks. Denial sums up the individualistic and implosive response to the inde fi nite and unintentional threats produced by techno-economic globalization. In parallel to this there emerges, as I had mentioned, another defence strategy, which responds to what is perceived as the second, fundamental source of danger, essentially generated by economic-cultural globalization: that is, defence against the other . This strategy is specular to the fi rst since it converts more into an excess rather than an absence of fear, and I have suggested de fi ning it as communitarian and explosive . 67 It is based on reducing insecurity and inde fi niteness through the defence mechanism of projection : namely, the fear is displaced onto indirect and specious objects since these appear easier to de fi ne and identify. Many of the ethnoreligious con fl icts that are traversing the planet can at least in part be traced back to this basic defence mechanism which converts inde fi nite anxiety into de fi nite fear. In this case too, we are dealing with a strategy that is anything but new since, as we will see, it results in the classic mechanism of building a 'scapegoat'. However, the novelty lies in the fact that, like in the denial strategy, this strategy seems to be resulting in substantial ineffectiveness . If, as suggested to us by René Girard's enlightening diagnosis, the fundamental goal of creating scapegoats has always been, since the origins of civilization, to keep check on and resolve violence in defence of a given community, today we are instead faced with an escalation in violence which attests to the substantial failure of the scapegoat dynamic. Through a fascinating thesis that I can only brie fl y recall here, 68 Girard claims that in truth this loss of effectiveness has distant roots, since it coincides with the end of the processes which made violence ritual and sacred, and with the revelation of the 66 See Esposito, Immunitas . 67 Here there is a generic allusion to Bauman's 'explosive communities' in Liquid Modernity . 68 Of great use for the issues that follow is the essay by Stefano Tomelleri, "Il capro espiatorio. La rivelazione cristiana e la modernità," Studi perugini , no. 10 (2000): 147-57. victimage mechanism brought on by the advent of Christianity. 69 In other words, while archaic societies had entrusted the rite of sacri fi cing the scapegoat with the function of providing a remedy to internal violence in order to found and preserve social order and peaceful coexistence among men, the revelation of Christ radically damaged this mechanism since, by disclosing the victim's innocence, for the fi rst time it made people aware of the victimizing and persecutory dynamics. By unmasking the nexus between violence and the sacred, the Christian message led to the breakdown of the mythical-ritual universe, and placed people before the unavoidable truth of their violence. Thus it weakened the possibility of resolving the violence through the sacri fi cial mechanism and opened totally new scenarios, affected by a fundamental ambivalence. On one hand, by depriving men of all external justi fi cation for their violence, the Christian revelation of the victim's innocence opened up the possibility of renouncing the scapegoat logic and resolving the problem of the social bond, without any exclusion or sacri fi ce; on the other hand, in the absence of ritual antidotes and their power to create order, it exposed men to the spreading of violence and the persistence -in more ambiguous, disguised and clandestine forms -of the victimage mechanism. That this second scenario is the one which, unfortunately, has ended up prevailing is manifestly undeniable; and, paradoxically, it can be pinpointed as originating above all in modernity. While it may be true that modernity -the time of rights, democracy and equality -seems to offer the possibility of transforming violence into 'soft', peaceful and even emancipatory forms of competition and rivalry, it is also true that, for the same reasons, it can provide a breeding ground which favours the heightening of violence. Indeed modernity produces an ampli fi cation of the mimetic dynamic that Girard recognized as the constitutive source of violent con fl ictuality among men. As has been underlined, the same equality that, à la Tocqueville, can be interpreted as a loss of differences, frees the mimetic desire, which becomes unlimited 70 and inevitably exacerbates rivalry among people. In other words, in a society of equals the desire to be according to the other which pushes the mimetic actor to see the other as model and rival at the same time, triggers a spiral of competitive comparison. Even the smallest difference becomes the opportunity for resentment, envy and hate, and can always provide the opportunity for violent clashes. While on one hand democratic indifferentiation and, we could add, narcissistic and postmodern intolerance towards every difference -which Tocqueville had prophetically diagnosed 71 -provoke the continuance of rivalry and con fl ict, on the other hand the sacri fi cial dynamic, to which premodern societies had entrusted the function of keeping check on violence, seems to have lost its traditional ef fi cacy due to its irreversible disclosure. This means that modern and contemporary societies are exposed to a radical 'crisis of the sacri fi cial system' which, since it is impossible to fi nd a solution in the scapegoat mechanism, can result in a multiplication of violence and its manifestation in increasingly crude and destructive forms. 72 The loss of the victimage mechanism's ef fi cacy, due to the deritualization process, does not equate to its disappearance, however. On the contrary, Girard once again observes that phenomena of 'sacri fi cial substitutions' reappear 'in a shameful, furtive, and clandestine manner' so as to avert moral condemnation (and selfcondemnation). 73 They take on the shape of psychological violence which is easier to conceal, or they re-explode in the exacerbated form of immolating victims to evil ideologies, as was the case of the genocides in the twentieth century. These mechanisms continue in our world usually as only a trace, but occasionally they can also reappear in forms more virulent than ever and on an enormous scale. An example is Hitler's systematic destruction of European Jews, and we see this also in all the other genocides and near genocides that occurred in the twentieth century. 74 Of course the reference to the Nazi genocide is not random, but extremely emblematic of the modern and contemporary reappearance of the victimage mechanism in spite of its disclosure. A fi rst formulation of this can be found in the diagnosis of totalitarianism that Franz Neumann was already suggesting in the 1950s, as he traced its psychic origins back to the transformation of fear into 'persecutory anxiety'. 75 Every time, Neumann says, over the course of history a particular social group (whether it can be de fi ned on the basis of class, religion or race) feels threatened by objective dangers which, together with material survival, compromise its prestige and identity, the deriving anxiety is displaced onto groups and people, who are given the requirements ad hoc , 76 and the guilt made to converge on them. If we are to take up the Freudian distinction between 'realistic anxiety' and 'neurotic anxiety ', 77 Neumann shows how fear and uncertainty are transformed into persecutory anxiety through the projective and hence specious creation of an enemy who becomes the subject of hate and aggression. As a result, the masses threatened with disintegration can rediscover their internal cohesion. In the case of Nazism and the persecution of the Jews, political and ideological manipulation linked up to this social dynamic, took advantage of the mass anxiety and pushed the masses towards 'caesaristic' and regressive identi fi cation 78 with a leader libidinally attributed the task of resolving the anxiety by expelling the evil and its presumed carriers. 79 By recognizing the victimage mechanism as originating in the persecutory transformation of anxiety, Neumann allows us to see its emotional roots, which Girard evidently considers less essential for his so-to-speak ontological diagnosis of violence. However, at the same time, while Neumann particularly stresses the totalitarian outcomes of the scapegoat dynamic, 80 Girard underlines its persistence in 'all the phenomena of nonritualized collective transference that we observe or believe we observe around us.' 81 Although deritualized -and indeed all the more violent for this precise reason -the victimage mechanism continues to act in the same modern democratic societies in all creeping and disguised phenomena of exclusion and discrimination, or in the cyclical explosions of reciprocal aggression and disdain that are fuelled by identity con fl icts: We easily see now that scapegoats multiply wherever human groups seek to lock themselves into a given identity -communal, local, national, ideological, racial, religious, and so on. 82 Evidently, here we are coming back to the topic of identity con fl ict which, as we have seen, is proliferating inside and outside the West, bringing the scapegoat strategy back up-to-date: a strategy which becomes all the more aggressive the more the perception of the threat grows in a global society. By eroding territorial and cultural boundaries, globalization is producing, fi rst of all in Western societies, a disturbing proximity of the other. As a result, the other can increasingly be identi fi ed with the Simmelian fi gure of the 'stranger within', who challenges the order and cohesion of a given community through a swarming and liminal presence that is felt, as suggested 78 Neumann stresses the regressive nature of this identi fi cation mechanism for the very masses who implement it, since it involves alienation and the relinquishment of one's Self: 'Since the identi fi cation of the masses with the leader is an alienation of the individual member, identi fi cation always constitutes a regression'. ( Anxiety and Politics , 277). 79 'Caesaristic identi fi cations may play a role in history when the situation of masses is objectively endangered, when the masses are incapable of understanding the historical process, and when the anxiety activated by the danger becomes neurotic persecutory (aggressive) anxiety through manipulation.' (Ibid . , . 80 It is interesting to see how Neumann indeed also alludes to the unconscious nature of the persecutory dynamic: 'Hatred, resentment, dread, created by great upheavals, are concentrated on certain persons who are denounced as devilish conspirators. Nothing would be more incorrect than to characterize the enemies as scapegoats […] for they appear as genuine enemies whom one must extirpate and not as substitutes whom one only needs to send into the wilderness.' (Ibid., 279) . 81 Girard, I See Satan Fall Like Lightning , 160. 82 Ibid., 160. by Mary Douglas, as potentially contaminating. Coming forth in response to the siege of a hybrid and unstemmable multitude that is penetrating the protected spaces of our identity citadels is the ancestral fear of a 'contamination' endangering the need for 'purity' upon which, Douglas says, every culture and civilization builds its reassuring separations and classi fi cations. 83 The other (the stranger, he who is different, the migrant, the illegal immigrant) becomes the target upon whom to displace our fears, upon whom to project a persecutory anxiety that transforms him into the person responsible for the dangers threatening a society that is increasingly deprived of the traditional control structures. 84 Hence this enables that blaming process which is indispensable for social cohesion and which, however, the anarchic and anonymous logic of globalization seems to be progressively eroding. 85 But since it is no longer possible to rely on ritual expulsion practices or strategies to con fi ne the other to a spatial and territorial elsewhere clearly divided by a de fi nite boundary that traces the separation between an inside and an outside, the exclusion mechanism becomes interiorized and acts at an eminently symbolic level. The exclusion dynamic, as has been underlined, is shifted into the conscience: 'Defence and exclusion, no longer possible towards the outside, will be shifted into the conscience, the imagination, the social mythologies and into the self-evident that these hold up.' 86 Thus immunity is ensured through dehumanization processes that transform the stranger within (the metoikos ) into an 'inside being' in such a way that he remains an 'outside being' all the same. 87 All this can take place in the insidious and hidden forms of psychological violence and everyday discrimination towards those who have crossed the territorial boundaries of a state and broken the taboo of distance and separation, therefore representing a constant challenge to consolidated privileges and to the 'purity' of identity. Or it can occur through cyclical collective mobilization against the weak and marginalized in the attempt to deal with insecurity by displacing the fear onto problems of personal safety, which politics does not then hesitate to exploit, in selflegitimation, in the name of defending public order. 88 But, as we have already seen, it can also convert into a real and proper 'attack on the minorities', in which it is perhaps legitimate to recognize, as suggested by Arjun Appadurai, the distinctive form of violence spreading to the global level. When global insecurity is added to the delirious fantasy of national purity which Appadurai de fi nes as an 'anxiety of incompleteness', the majorities in every single state whose hegemony is threatened tend to transform into 'predatory identities'. Their aim becomes to defend the purity of the ethnos by eliminating the element of disturbance represented by the 'minor differences'. The minorities 'are embarrassments to any state-sponsored image of national purity and state fairness. They are thus scapegoats in the classical sense.' More speci fi cally in the global age they 'are the major site for displacing the anxieties of many states about their own minority or marginality (real or imagined) in a world of a few megastates, of unruly economic fl ows and compromised sovereignties.' 89 From Iraq to ex-Yugoslavia, from Indonesia to Chechnya, from Palestine to Rwanda, to the emblematic case of the clash between Hindus and Muslims within a modern democracy like India, the victimage mechanism seems to reassert itself with a fresh violence that tellingly -testimony to the obsession with purity at its origin -seems to repeat itself in particular towards the body . Indeed, as Appadurai underlines by taking on Douglas's perspective, the body becomes subject to unheardof violations and atrocities (bodies massacred, decapitated, tortured, raped) in view of punishing the minorities for the fact that they 'blur the boundaries between "us" and "them," here and there, in and out, healthy and unhealthy, loyal and disloyal, needed but unwelcome.' 90 Nevertheless, it is precisely this obsessive, punitive and puri fi catory nature that announces the danger that the violence may assume an unstemmable drift. 91 Far from producing a stop to the violence, the scapegoat strategy causes its proliferation, through a sort of perverse up-the-ante that seems to bring the brutality of archaic practices, such as sacri fi ce, and of the starkest materiality back inside the abstract and impersonal space of globalization. 92 But that is not all. Today the spiral of violence is further fuelled by a new factor that upsets the logic -to date essentially one-way -of the persecutors-victims relationship. What happens, unlike for example the emblematic case of Nazism, is that the other tries to overturn his position as victim, and in turn becomes the persecutor, giving rise to a dynamic of hostility and aggression that potentially becomes unlimited owing to its reciprocal and specular nature. Suf fi ce it to think of Islamic terrorism and the projection it puts upon the West as the image of the other and evil, against which, by fuelling passions of resentment , 93 a compact and endogamous Us is condensed together and built. Indeed this proves the fact that the scapegoat, as Girard warns, is not only necessarily embodied in the weak and oppressed but also in the rich and powerful. 94 Hence, in the grip of dehumanization on one hand and demonization on the other, 95 the world becomes a theatre, through the reciprocal invention of an enemy, of an escalation in violence that has much to do with the persecutory metamorphosis of insecurity and anxiety and very little to do with a presumed 'clash of civilizations'. 96 Shifted to the inner Self, the victimage mechanism continues to act, hidden from view. Nonetheless, it ultimately becomes ineffective since it fails in its original purpose to resolve the fear and keep a check on violence. Orphaned of ritualization processes and deprived of an 'elsewhere' that permits the other's spatial and territorial exclusion, the construction of the enemy/victim generates forms of identity cohesion that are as aggressive as they are regressive, fuelled by a reciprocal persecutory projection. Far from restoring cohesion and security to a given community, the scapegoat dynamic gives rise to endogamous and reciprocally exclusive processes of building an Us , whose foremost and manifest effect is to form what I have de fi ned as immunitarian communities : 97 whether they are the 'voluntary ghettoes' and 'communities of fear' that explode cyclically in a West frightened by the siege of the other and anything but free from regressive phenomena, or ethno-religious communities entrenched around the obsession of identity and homogeneity, willing to reactivate atrocious forms of excluding the other, or lastly global communities that come together around the war/terrorism polarization. The metamorphosis of fear in the global age therefore seems to con fi rm, at the emotional level, the pathological split between an unlimited individualism and an endogamous communitarianism , which originates in the implementation of defence mechanisms leading to not only the polarization of an absence and excess of pathos , but also, it needs to be stressed, in their substantial inef fi cacy . On one hand, the denial of fear, we have seen, pushes individuals towards forms of apathy and narcissistic entropy that prevents them from recognizing the new risks produced by global challenges. As a consequence, this produces the individuals' incapacity to perceive their unprecedented condition of spectators and potential victims at the 94 same time, and fuels the illusion of immunity: which means that in the name of entropic self-preservation we end up delivering the whole of humankind to the danger of self-destruction. On the other hand, the persecutory conversion of fear generates perverse and endogamous forms of alliance and solidarity, which thereby result in the reactivation of destructive communities driven by 'primordial loyalties'. This gives rise to the explosive drift of identity con fl icts and to an unlimited escalation of violence at the planetary level. Between Self-obsession and Us-obsession , as the specular polarities of the same immunitarian strategy, we run the risk of not grasping the chance 98 that the global age could actually be capable of offering through the very transformations that it produces and the very challenges that it contains. On one hand, as we will see, the risks that are bearing down on humankind for the fi rst time mean we can think of the latter as a new subject, as a set of individuals linked by their common vulnerability and weakness . Therefore, they are able to take care of the world in the sense of the planet, the 'loss' of which would coincide with the disappearance of the only dwelling of living beings that we know of. On the other hand, the multiplication of differences and the slide of the idea of 'other' towards the notion of 'difference', which can neither be assimilated nor expelled into an elsewhere, for the fi rst time makes it possible to rethink the social bond as the solidaristic coexistence of a plurality of individuals, genders, cultures, races, religions, capable of forming a 'world', à la Arendt, since they are capable of recognizing not only the necessity but also the potential vitality of reciprocal contamination . These real possibilities are, however, only a chance. Insofar as it is a chance, the subjects have the task of knowing how to grasp it. To recall a successful suggestion by André Gorz, we could say that to pro fi t from the chance in the fi rst place means 'to learn to discern the unrealized opportunities which lie dormant in the recesses of the present' 99 ; or, in a word, to lay a wager on the ability to build alternative scenarios and create possibilities that may not yet have been taken up but are still latent. 98 The expression is inspired by Georges Bataille who, as already remembered above, proposes the idea of chance meant as the 'possibility of openness', see On Nietzsche (London: Athlone, 1992), originally published as "Sur Nietzsche," in Oeuvres Complètes, vol. 6 (Paris: Gallimard, 1976). 99 Gorz, Reclaiming Work , 1. Originally published as Des choses cachées depuis la fondation du monde We haven't given up having scapegoats, but our belief in them is 90 percent spoiled. The phenomenon appears so morally base to us, so reprehensible, that when we catch ourselves "letting off steam" against someone innocent, we are ashamed of ourselves Originally published as Je vois Satan tomber comme l'éclaire Democratic and Authoritarian State Neumann says, there must always be a core of truth that makes this choice particularly dangerous: so in the case of the Jews, the core of truth is given by their being 'concrete symbols of a so-called parasitical capitalism, through their position in commerce and fi nance On this see Part II Purity and Danger. An Analysis of Concepts of Pollution and Taboo Mary Douglas underlines that risk itself becomes a resource at the moral and political level and speaks of a 'forensic theory of danger': 'Disasters that befoul the air and soil and poison the water are generally turned to political account: someone already unpopular is going to be blamed for it.' ( Risk and Blame , 5) Risk and Blame Appadurai continues, 'are metaphors and reminders of the betrayal of the classical national project. And it is this betrayal -actually rooted in the failure of the nation-state to preserve its promise to be the guarantor of national sovereignty -that underwrites the worldwide impulse to extrude or to eliminate minorities Originally published as Orrorismo Fear of Small Numbers , chap. 3 again underlines the nexus between the abstract logic of globalization and the brutality of physical violence 519-33; for an interesting treatment of the topic see Stefano Tomelleri