X .tk% FR 1C ■ri''~v, Z. "‘"'J.QP DISSERTATION FIRST EXHIBITING A GENERAL VIEW OF THE PROGRESS OF METAPHYSICAL AND ETHICAL PHILOSOPHY SINCE THE REVIVAL OF LETTERS IN EUROPE. By DUGALD STEWART, Esq. F.R.SS. Lond. and Edin., LATE PROFESSOR OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY IN THE UNIVERSITY OF EDINBURGH. ■ . PREFACE, CONTAINING SOME CRITICAL REMARKS ON THE DISCOURSE PREFIXED TO THE FRENCH ENCYCLOPEDIA WHEN I ventured to undertake the task of contributing a Preliminary Dissertation to the Encyclopedia Britannica, my original in¬ tention was, after the example of D’Alembert, to have begun with a general survey of the va¬ rious departments of human knowledge. The outline of such a survey, sketched by the com¬ prehensive genius of Bacon, together with the corrections and improvements suggested by his illustrious disciple, would, I thought, have ren¬ dered it comparatively easy to adapt their intel¬ lectual map to the present advanced state of the sciences; while the unrivalled authority which their united work has long maintained in the republic of letters, would, I flattered myself, have softened those criticisms which might be expected to he incurred by any similar attempt of a more modern hand. On a closer examina¬ tion, however, of their labours, I found myself under the necessity of abandoning this design. Doubts immediately occurred to me with respect to the justness of their logical views, and soon terminated in a conviction that these views are radically and essentially erroneous. Instead, therefore, of endeavouring to give additional currency to speculations which I conceived to he fundamentally unsound, I resolved to avail myself of the present opportunity to point out their most important defects;—defects which, I am nevertheless very ready to acknowledge, it is much more easy to remark than to supply. The critical strictures which, in the course of this discussion, I shall have occasion to offer on my predecessors, will, at the same time, account for my forbearing to substitute a new map of my own, instead of that to which the names of Bacon and D’Alembert have lent so great and so well-merited a celebrity; and may perhaps suggest a doubt, whether the period be yet ar¬ rived for hazarding again, with any reasonable prospect of success, a repetition of their bold experiment. For the length to which these strictures are likely to extend, the only apology I have to offer is the peculiar importance of the questions to which they relate, and the high au¬ thority of the writers whose opinions I presume to controvert. Before entering on his main subject, D’Alem¬ bert is at pains to explain a distinction—which he represents as of considerable importance—^be¬ tween the Genealogy of the sciences, and the Encyclopedical arrangement of the objects of human knowledge.1 “ In examining the for¬ mer,” he observes, “ our aim is, by remounting 1 “ 11 ne faut pas confondre I’ordre Encyclopedlque des connoissances humaines avee la Gdneaiogie des Scieneeo.” Avertissement, p. 7- DISS. I. PART I. A 2 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. to the origin and genesis of our ideas, to trace the causes to which the sciences owe their birth; and to mark the characteristics hy which they are distinguished from each other. In order to ascertain the latter, it is necessary to compre¬ hend, in one general scheme, all the various de¬ partments of study; to arrange them into pro¬ per classes; and to point out their mutual rela¬ tions and dependencies.” Such a scheme is some¬ times likened hy D’Alembert to a map or chart of the intellectual world; sometimes to a Ge¬ nealogical1 or Encyclopedical Tree, indicating the manifold and complicated affinities of those studies, which, however apparently remote and unconnected, are all the common offspring of the human understanding. For executing suc¬ cessfully this chart or tree, a philosophical deli¬ neation of the natural progress of the mind may (according to him) furnish very useful lights; although he acknowledges that the results of the two undertakings cannot fail to differ widely in many instances,—the laws which regulate the generation of our ideas often interfering with that systematical order in the relative arrange¬ ment of scientific pursuits, which it is the pur¬ pose of the Encyclopedical Tree to exhibit.2 In treating of the first of these subjects, it can¬ not he denied that D’Alembert has displayed much ingenuity and invention; hut the depth and solidity of his general train of thought may he questioned. On various occasions, he has evidently suffered himself to he misled hy a spi¬ rit of false refinement; and on others, where probably he was fully aware of his inability to render the theoretical chain complete, he seems to have aimed at concealing from his readers the faulty links, hy availing himself of those epi¬ grammatic points, and other artifices of style, with which the genius of the French language enables a skilful writer to smooth and varnish over his most illogical transitions. The most essential imperfections, however, of this historical sketch, may he fairly ascribed to a certain vagueness and indecision in the au¬ thor’s idea, with regard to the scope of his in¬ quiries. What he has in general pointed at is to trace, from the theory of the Mind, and from the order followed by nature in the develope- ment of its powers, the successive steps hy which the curiosity may he conceived to have been gradually conducted from one intellectual pur¬ suit to another; hut, in the execution of this design (which in itself is highly philosophical and interesting), he does not appear to have paid due attention to the essential difference between the history of the human species, and that of the civilised and inquisitive individual. The former was undoubtedly that which prin¬ cipally figured in his conceptions, and to which, I apprehend, he ought to have confined himself exclusively; whereas, in fact, he has so com¬ pletely blended the two subjects together, that it is often impossible to say which of them was uppermost in his thoughts. The consequence is, that, instead of throwing upon either those strong and steady lights, which might have been expected from his powers, he has involved both in additional obscurity. This indistinctness is more peculiarly remarkable in the beginning of his Discourse, where he represents men in the earliest infancy of science, before they had time to take any precautions for securing the means of their subsistence, or of their safety,—as phi¬ losophising on their sensations, on the exist¬ ence of their own bodies, and on that of the material world. His Discourse, accordingly, sets out with a series of Meditations, precisely analogous to those which form the introduction 1 It is to be regretted, that the epithet Genealogical should have been employed on this occasion, where the author s wish was to contradistinguish the idea denoted by it, from that historical view of the sciences to which the word Genealogy had been previously applied. . . 2 The true reason of this might perhaps have been assigned in simpler terms by remarking^ that the order of invention is, in most cases, the reverse of that fitted for didactic communication. This observation applies not only to the analytical and synthetical processes of the individual, but to the progressive improvements of the species, when compared with the arrangements prescribed by logical method, for conveying a knowledge of them to students. In an enlightened age, the sciences are justly considered as the basis of the arts ; and, in a course of liberal education, the former are always taught prior to the latter. But, in the order of invention and discovery, the arts preceded the sciences. Men measured land before they studied speculative geometry ; and governments were established before politics were studied^ as. a science. A remark somewhat similar is made by Celsus, concerning the history of medicine : “ Non medicinam ration! esse posterio- rem, sed post medicinam inventam, rationem esse qusesitam.” PREFACE TO THE FIRST DISSERTATION. 3 to the philosophy of Descartes; meditations which, in the order of time, have been uniform¬ ly posterior to the study of external nature; and which, even in such an age as the present, are confined to a comparatively small number of recluse metaphysicians. Of this sort of conjectural or theoretical his¬ tory, the most unexceptionable specimens which have yet appeared, are indisputably the frag¬ ments in Mr Smith’s posthumous work on the History of Astronomy, and on that of the An¬ cient Systems of Physics and Metaphysics. That, in the latter of these, he may have occa¬ sionally accommodated his details to his own peculiar opinions concerning the object of Phi¬ losophy, may perhaps, with some truth, be al¬ leged ; but he must at least be allowed the me¬ rit of completely avoiding the error by which D’Alembert was misled; and, even in those in¬ stances where he himself seems to wander a little from the right path, of furnishing his suc¬ cessors with a thread, leading by easy and al¬ most insensible steps, from the first gross per¬ ceptions of sense, to the most abstract refine¬ ments of the Grecian schools. Nor is this the only praise to which these fragments are en¬ titled. By seizing on the different points of view from which the same object was contem¬ plated by different sects, they often bestow a certain degree of unity and of interest on what before seemed calculated merely to bewilder and to confound; and render the apparent aber¬ rations and caprices of the understanding, sub¬ servient to the study of its operations and laws. To the foregoing strictures on D’Alembert’s view of the origin of the sciences, it may be added, that this introductory part of his Dis¬ course does not seem to have any immediate connection with the sequel. We are led, in¬ deed, to expect, that it is to prepare the way for the study of the Encyclopedical Tree after¬ wards to be exhibited; but in this expectation we are completely disappointed,—no reference to it whatever being made by the author in the farther prosecution of his subject. It forms, accordingly, a portion of his Discourse altoge¬ ther foreign to the general design; while, from the metaphysical obscurity which pervades it, the generality of readers are likely to receive an impression, either unfavourable to the perspi¬ cuity of the writer, or to their own powers of comprehension and of reasoning. It were to be wished, therefore, that, instead of occupying the first pages of the Encyclopedic, it had been re¬ served for a separate article in the body of that work. There it might have been read by the logical student, with no small interest and ad¬ vantage ; for, with all its imperfections, it bears numerous and precious marks of its author’s hand. In delineating his Encyclopedical Tree, D’A¬ lembert has, in my opinion, been still more un¬ successful than in the speculations which have been hitherto under our review. His venera¬ tion for Bacon seems, on this occasion, to have prevented him from giving due scope to his own powerful and fertile genius, and has engaged him in the fruitless task of attempting, by means of arbitrary definitions, to draw a veil over in¬ curable defects and blemishes. In this part of Bacon’s logic, it must, at the same time, be owned, that there is something peculiarly capti¬ vating to the fancy; and, accordingly, it has united in its favour the suffrages of almost all the succeeding authors who have treated of the same subject. It will be necessary for me, therefore, to explain fully the grounds of that censure, which, in opposition to so many illus¬ trious names, I have presumed to bestow on it. Of the leading ideas to which I more particu¬ larly object, the following statement is given by D’Alembert. I quote it in preference to the corresponding passage in Bacon, as it contains various explanatory clauses and glosses, for which we are indebted to the ingenuity of the commentator. “ The objects about which our minds are oc¬ cupied, are either spiritual or material, and the media employed for this purpose are our ideas, either directly received, or derived from reflec¬ tion. The system of our direct knowledge con¬ sists entirely in the passive and mechanical ac¬ cumulation of the particulars it comprehends; an accumulation which belongs exclusively to the province of Memory. Reflection is of two kinds, according as it is employed in reasoning on the objects of our direct ideas, or in study¬ ing them as models for imitation. 4 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. “ Thus, Memory, Reason, strictly so called, of its successive operations on the subjects of and Imagination, are the three modes in which thought, hy creating abstract and general ideas, the mind operates on the subjects of its thoughts, remote from the perceptions of sense, leads to By Imagination, however, is here to he under- the exercise of Imagination as the last step of stood, not the faculty of conceiving or repre- the process. Thus metaphysics and geometry senting to ourselves what we have formerly per- are, of all the sciences belonging to Reason, ceived a faculty which differs in nothing from those in which Imagination has the greatest the memory of these perceptions, and which, if it share. I ask pardon for this observation from were not relieved hy the invention of signs, those men of taste, who, little aware of the near would he in a state of continual exercise. The affinity of geometry to their own pursuits, and power which we denote hy this name has a still less suspecting that the only intermediate nobler province allotted to it, that of render- step between them is formed by metaphysics, ine imitation subservient to the creations of are disposed to employ their wit in depreciating genius its value. The truth is, that, to the geometer “ These three faculties suggest a correspond- who invents, Imagination is not less essential ing division of human knowledge into three than to the poet who creates. They operate, branches, 1. History, which derives its materials indeed, differently on their object, the former from Memory; 2. Philosophy, which is the pro- abstracting and analyzing, where the latter corn- duct of Reason; and 3. Poetry (comprehending bines and adornstwo processes of the mind, under this title all the Fine Arts), which is the it must at the same time he confessed, which offspring of Imagination.1 If we place Reason seem from experience to he so little congenial, before Imagination, it is because this order ap- that it may he doubted if the talents of a great pears to us conformable to the natural progress geometer and of a great poet will ever he united of our intellectual operations.2 The Imagina- in the same person. But whether these talents tion is a creative faculty; and the mind, before he or he not mutually exclusive, certain it is, it attempts to create, begins by reasoning upon that they who possess the one, have no right to what it sees and knows. Nor is this all. In despise those who cultivate the other. Of all the faculty of Imagination, both Reason and the great men of antiquity, Archimedes is per- Memory are, to a certain extent, combined,— haps he who is the best entitled to he placed hy the mind never imagining or creating objects the side of Homei. hut such as are analogous to those whereof it D’Alembert afterwards proceeds to observe, has had previous experience. Where this ana- that of these three geneial blanches of the En logy is wanting, the combinations are extrava- cyclopedical Tree, a natural and convenient suh- gant and displeasing; and consequently, in that division is afforded by the metaphysical distri- agreeahle imitation of nature, at which the fine bution of things into Material and Spiritual, arts aim in common, invention is necessarily “ With these two classes of existences, he ob- suhjected to the control of rules which it is the serves farther, “ history and philosophy aie business of the philosopher to investigate. equally conversant; hut as for Imagination, i( In farther justification of this arrangement, her imitations are entirely confined to the mate- it may he remarked, that reason, in the course rial world ;—a circumstance, he adds, “ which 1 The latitude given by D’Alembert to the meaning of the word Poetry is a real and very important improvement on Bacon, who restricts it to Fictitious History or Fables. {De Aug- Scient. Lib. ii. cap. i.) D’Alembert, on the other nan , employs it in its natural signification, as synonymous with invention or creation. “ La Pemture, la Sculpture, 1 A.rc i ec- ture, la Poesie, la Musique, et leurs differentes divisions, composent la troisieme distribution generate qui nait de I Imagi¬ nation, et dont les parties sont comprises sous le nom de Beaux-Arts. On peut les rapporter tons a la 1 oesie, en prenant ce mot dans sa signification naturelle, qui n’est autre chose qu’invention ou creation.” , 2 In placing Ileason before Imagination, D’Alembert departs from the order in which these faculties^ are arranged by Bacon. “ Si nous n’avons pas placd, comme lui, la Raison apres ITmagination, c’est que nous avons suivi dans le systeme Encyclopedique, 1’ordre metaphysique des operations de 1’esprit, plutot que Pordre historique de ses progres depms la re¬ naissance des lettres (Disc. Prelim.) How far the motive here assigned for the change is valid, the reader will be enabled to judge from the sequel of the above quotation. PREFACE TO THE FIRST DISSERTATION. 5 conspires with the other arguments above stated, in justifying Bacon for assigning to her the last place in his enumeration of our intellectual fa¬ culties.” 1 Upon this subdivision he enlarges at some length, and with considerable ingenuity; but on the present occasion it would be quite superfluous to follow him any farther, as more than enough has been already quoted to enable my readers to judge, whether the objections which I am now to state to the foregoing ex¬ tracts he as sound and decisive as I apprehend them to he. Of these objections a very obvious one is sug¬ gested by a consideration, of which D’Alembert himself has taken notice,—that the three facul¬ ties to which he refers the whole operations of the understanding are perpetually blended to¬ gether in their actual exercise, insomuch that there is scarcely a branch of human knowledge which does not, in a greater or less degree, furnish employment to them all. It may be said, indeed, that some pursuits exercise and in¬ vigorate particular faculties more than others; that the study of History, for example, al¬ though it may occasionally require the aid both of Reason and of Imagination, yet chiefly fur¬ nishes occupation to the Memory; and that this is sufficient to justify the logical division of our mental powers as the ground-work of a corre¬ sponding Encyclopedical classification.2 This, however, will be found more specious than solid. In what respects is the faculty of Memory more essentially necessary to the student of history than to the philosopher or to the poet; and, on the other hand, of what value, in the circle of the sciences, would be a collection of historical de¬ tails, accumulated without discrimination, with¬ out a scrupulous examination of evidence, or without any attempt to compare and to genera¬ lize ? For the cultivation of that species of his¬ tory, in particular, which alone deserves a place in the Encyclopedical Tree, it may be justly af¬ firmed, that the rarest and most comprehensive combination of all our mental gifts is indispen¬ sably requisite. Another, and a still more formidable objec¬ tion to Bacon’s classification, may be derived from the very imperfect and partial analysis of the mind which it assumes as its basis. Why were the powers of Abstraction and Generaliza¬ tion passed over in silence ?—powers which, ac¬ cording as they ara cultivated or neglected, con¬ stitute the most e»seTitia/ of all distinctions be¬ tween the intellectual cnaracters of individuals. A corresponding distinction, too, not less im¬ portant, may be remarked among the objects of human study, according as our aim is to treasure up particular facts, or to establish general con¬ clusions. Does not this distinction mark out, with greater precision, the limits which separate philosophy from mere historical narrative, than that which turns upon the different provinces of Reason and of Memory ? I shall only add one other criticism on this celebrated enumeration, and that is, its want of distinctness, in confounding together the Sciences and the Arts under the same general titles. Hence a variety of those capricious arrange¬ ments, which must immediately strike every reader who follows Bacon through his details;— the reference, for instance, of the mechanical arts to the department of History; and conse¬ quently, according to his own analysis of the Mind, the ultimate reference of these arts to the faculty of Memory ; while at the same time, in his tripartite division of the whole field of hu- 1 In this exclusive limitation of the province of Imagination to things Material and Sensible, D’Alembert has followed the definition given by Descartes in his second Meditation : “ Imaginary nihil aliud est quam rei corporeaz fignram sen imagr- nem contemplari a power of the mind, which (as I have elsewhere observed) appears to me to be most precisely ex¬ pressed in our language by the word Conception. The province assigned to Imagination by D’Alembert is more extensive than this, for he ascribes to her also a creative and combining power ; but still his definition agrees with that of Descartes, inasmuch as it excludes entirely from her dominion both the intellectual and the moral worlds. 2 I allude here to the following apology for Bacon, suggested by a very learned and judicious writer:—“ On a tail cependant a Bacon quelques reproches assez fonde's. On a observe que sa classification des sciences repose sur une distinction qui n’est pas rigoureuse, puisque la memoire, la raison, et 1’imagination concourent necessairement dans chaque art, comme dans chaque science. Mais on pent rdpondre, que 1’un ou 1’autre de ces trois facultes, quoique secondee par les deux autres, peut cependant jouer le role principal. En prenant la distinction de Bacon dans ce sens, sa classifica¬ tion reste exacte, et devient tres utile.”—(Degeraxdo, Hist. Comp. Tome I. p. 298.) 6 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. man knowledge, the art of Poetry has one en¬ tire province allotted to itself. These objections apply in common to Bacon and to D’Alembert. That which follows has a particular reference to a passage already cited from the latter, where, by some false refinements concerning the nature and functions of Imagina¬ tion, he has rendered the classification of his pre¬ decessor incomparably more indistinct and illo¬ gical than it seemed to he before. That all the creations or new combinations of Imagination, imply the previous process of de¬ composition or analysis, is abundantly manifest; and, therefore, without departing from the com¬ mon and popular use of language, it may un¬ doubtedly be said, that the faculty of abstraction is not less essential to the Poet, than to the Geo¬ meter and the Metaphysician.1 But this is not the doctrine of D’Alembert. On the contrary, he affirms, that Metaphysics and Geometry are, of all the sciences connected with reason, those in which Imagination has the greatest share ;— an assertion which, it will not be disputed, has at first sight somewhat of the air of a paradox ; and which, on closer examination, will, I apprehend, be found altogether inconsistent with fact. If indeed D’Alembert had, in this instance, used, as some writers have done, the word Imagina¬ tion as synonymous with Invention, I should not have thought it worth while (at least so far as the geometer is concerned) to dispute his proposi¬ tion. But that this was not the meaning annex¬ ed to it by the author, appears from a subsequent clause, where he tells us, that the most refined operations of reason, consisting in the creation of generals which do not fall under the cogniz¬ ance of our senses, naturally led to the exercise of Imagination. His doctrine, therefore, goes to the identification of Imagination with Abstraction ; two faculties so very different in the direction which they give to our thoughts, that, according to his own acknowledgment, the man who is habitually occupied in exerting the one, seldom fails to impair both his capacity and his relish for the exercise of the other. This identification of two faculties, so strong¬ ly contrasted in their characteristical features, was least of all to he expected from a logician, who had previously limited the province of Ima¬ gination to the imitation of material objects; a limitation, it may be remarked in passing, which is neither sanctioned by common use, nor by just views of the philosophy of the mind. Upon what ground can it be alleged, that Milton’s portrait of Satan’s intellectual and moral cha¬ racter was not the offspring of the same creative faculty which gave birth to his Garden of Eden ? After such a definition, however, it is difficult to conceive, how so very acute a writer should have referred to Imagination the abstractions of the geometer and of the metaphysician; and still more, that he should have attempted to justify this reference, by observing, that these abstractions do not fall under the cognisance of the senses. My own opinion is, that, in the composition of the whole passage, he had a view to the unexpected parallel between Homer and Archimedes, with which he meant, at the close, to surprise his readers. If the foregoing strictures be well-founded, it seems to follow, not only that the attempt of Bacon and of D’Alembert to classify the sciences and arts according to a logical division of our faculties, is altogether unsatisfactory; but that every future attempt of the same kind may be expected to be liable to similar objections. In studying, indeed, the Theory of the Mind, it is necessary to push our analysis as far as the nature of the subject admits of; and, wherever the thing is possible, to examine its constituent principles separately and apart from each other: but this consideration itself, when combined with what was before stated on the endless variety of forms in which they may be blended 1 This assertion must, however, be understood with some qualifications ; for, although the Poet, as well as the Geometer and the Metaphysician, be perpetually called upon to decompose, by means of abstraction, the complicated objects of per¬ ception, it must not be concluded that the abstractions of all the three are exactly of the same kind. Those of the Poet amount to nothing more than to a separation into parts of the realities presented to his senses ; which separation is only a preliminary step to a subsequent recomposition into new and ideal forms of the things abstracted ; whereas the abstractions of the Metaphysician and of the Geometer form the very objects of their respective sciences. PREFACE TO THE FIRST DISSERTATION. 7 together in our various intellectual pursuits, is sufficient to show how ill adapted such an ana¬ lysis must for ever remain to serve as the basis of an Encyclopedical distribution.1 The circumstance to which this part of Ba¬ con’s philosophy is chiefly indebted for its po¬ pularity, is the specious simplicity and compre¬ hensiveness of the distribution itself;—not the soundness of the logical views by which it was suggested. That all our intellectual pursuits may be referred to one or other of these three heads, History, Philosophy, and Poetry, may undoubtedly be said with considerable plausi¬ bility ;—the word History being understood to comprehend all our knowledge of particular facts and particular events; the word Philoso¬ phy, all the general conclusions or laws inferred from these particulars by induction; and the word Poetry, all the arts addressed to the ima¬ gination. Not that the enumeration, even with the help of this comment, can be considered as complete; for, to pass over entirely the other objections already stated, under which of these three heads shall we arrange the various branches of pure mathematics ? Are we therefore to conclude, that the magni¬ ficent design, conceived by Bacon, of enumerat¬ ing, defining, and classifying the multifarious objects of human knowledge;—a design, on the successful accomplishment of which he himself believed that the advancement of the sciences essentially depended;—Are we to conclude, that this design was nothing more than the abortive offspring of a warm imagination, un¬ susceptible of any useful application to enlight¬ en the mind, or to accelerate its progress ? My own idea is widely different. The design was, in every respect, worthy of the sublime genius by which it was formed. Nor does it follow, because the execution was imperfect? that the attempt has been attended with no ad¬ vantage. At the period when Bacon wrote, it was of much more consequence to exhibit to the learned a comprehensive sketch, than an ac¬ curate survey of the intellectual world;—such a sketch as, by pointing out to those whose views had been hitherto confined within the limits of particular regions, the relative positions and bearings of their respective districts as parts of one great whole, might invite them all, for the common benefit, to a reciprocal exchange of their local riches. The societies or acade¬ mies which, soon after, sprung up in different countries of Europe, for the avowed purpose of contributing to the general mass of information, by the collection of insulated facts, conjectures, and queries, afford sufficient proof, that the anti¬ cipations of Bacon were not, in this instance, altogether chimerical. In examining the details of Bacon’s survey, it is impossible not to be struck (more especially when we reflect on the state of learning two hundred years ago) with the minuteness of his information, as well as with the extent of his views; or to forbear admiring his sagacity in pointing out, to future adventurers, the unknown tracks still left to be explored by human cu¬ riosity If his classifications be sometimes arti¬ ficial and arbitrary, they have at least the merit of including, under one head or another, every particular of importance; and of exhibiting these particulars with a degree of method and of ap¬ parent connection, which, if it does not always satisfy the judgment, never fails to interest the fancy, and to lay hold of the memory. Nor must it be forgotten, to the glory of his genius, that what he failed to accomplish remains to this day a desideratum in science ;—that the in¬ tellectual chart delineated by him is, Avith all its imperfections, the only one of which modern philosophy has yet to boast;—and that the united talents of D’Alembert and of Diderot, 1 In justice to the authors of the Encyclopedical Tree prefixed to the French Dictionary, it ought to be observed, that it is spoken of by D’Alembert, in his Preliminary Discourse, with the utmost modesty and diffidence ; and that he has ex- pressed, not only his own conviction, but that of his colleague, of the impossibility of executing such a task in a manner likely to satisfy the public. “ Nous sommes trop convaincus de I’arbitraire qui regnera toujours dans une pareille division, pour croire que notre systeme soit 1’unique ou le meilleur ; il nous suffira que notre travail ne soit pas entierement desap- prouve par les bons esprits.” And, some pages afterwards, “ Si le public eclaire donne son approbation a ces changemens, elle sera la recompense de notre docilite ; et s’il ne les approuve pas, nous n’en serons que plus convaincus de 1’impossi- bilitd de former un Arbre Encyclopedique qui soit au gre de tout le monde.” 8 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. aided by all the lights of the eighteenth century, have been able to add but little to what Bacon performed. After the foregoing observations, it will not he expected that an attempt is to he made, in the following Essay, to solve a problem which has so recently baffled the powers of these eminent writers, and which will probably long continue to exercise the ingenuity of our suc¬ cessors. How much remains to he previously done for the improvement of that part of Logic, whose province it is to fix the limits by which contiguous departments of study are defined and separated! And how many unsuspected affinities may he reasonably presumed to exist among sciences, which, to our circumscribed views, appear at present the most alien from each other ! The abstract geometry of Apol¬ lonius and Archimedes was found, after an in¬ terval of two thousand years, to furnish a torch to the physical inquiries of Newton; while, in the further progress of knowledge, the Etymo¬ logy of Languages has been happily employed to fill up the chasms of Ancient History; and the conclusions of Comparative Anatomy, to il¬ lustrate the Theory of the Earth. For my own part, even if the task were executed with the most complete success, I should be strongly in¬ clined to think, that its appropriate place in an Encyclopaedia would be as a branch of the article on Logic;—certainly not as an exordium to the Preliminary Discourse; the enlarged and re¬ fined views which it necessarily presupposes be¬ ing peculiarly unsuitable to that part of the work which may be expected, in the first instance, to attract the curiosity of every reader. Before concluding this preface, I shall sub¬ join a few slight strictures on a very concise and comprehensive division of the objects of Human Knowledge, proposed by Mr Locke, as the ba¬ sis of a new classification of the sciences. Al¬ though I do not know that any attempt has ever been made to follow out in detail the general idea, yet the repeated approbation which has been lately bestowed on a division essentially the same, by several writers of the highest rank, renders it in some measure necessary, on the present occasion, to consider how far it is found¬ ed on just principles; more especially as it is completely at variance not only with the lan¬ guage and arrangement adopted in these preli¬ minary essays, but with the whole of that plan on which the original projectors, as well as the con- tinuators, of the Encyclopcedia Britannica, ap¬ pear to have proceeded. These strictures will, at the same time, afford an additional proof of the difficulty, or rather of the impossibility, in the actual state of logical science, of solving this great problem, in a manner calculated to unite the general suffrages of philosophers. “ All that can fall,” says Mr Locke, tou [iiov oraga'didovrii aXXoi; aXXaiv.—(Plato, Leg. lib. vi.) Et quasi cursores vital lampada tradunt.—Lucret. 14 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. CHAPTER I. FROM THE REVIVAL OF LETTERS TO THE PUBLICATION OF BACON’S PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS. The long interval, commonly known by the name of the middle ages, which immediately pre¬ ceded the revival of letters in the western part of Europe, forms the most melancholy blank which occurs, from the first dawn of recorded civilisation, in the intellectual and moral his¬ tory of the human race. In one point of view alone, the recollection of it is not altogether un¬ pleasing, inasmuch as, by the proof it exhibits of the inseparable connection between ignorance and prejudice on the one hand, and vice, mi¬ sery, and slavery on the other, it affords, in conjunction with other causes, which will after¬ wards fall under our review, some security against any future recurrence of a similar cala¬ mity. It would furnish a very interesting and in¬ structive subject of speculation, to record and to illustrate (with the spirit, however, rather of a philosopher than of an antiquary), the various abortive efforts, which, during this protracted and seemingly hopeless period of a thousand years, were made by enlightened individuals, to impart to their contemporaries the fruits of their own acquirements. For in no one age from its commencement to its close, does the continuity of knowledge (if I may borrow an expression of Mr Harris), seem to have been entirely interrupted: “ There was always a faint twilight, like that auspicious gleam which, in a summer’s night, fills up the interval between the setting and the rising sun.”1 On the present occasion, I shall content myself with remarking the important effects produced by the numerous monastic esta¬ blishments all over the Christian world, in pre¬ serving, amidst the general wreck, the inesti¬ mable remains of Greek and Roman refinement, and in keeping alive, during so many centuries, those scattered sparks of truth and of science, which were afterwards to kindle into so bright a flame. I mention this particularly, because, in our zeal against the vices and corruptions of the Romish church, we are too apt to forget, how deeply wre are indebted to its superstitious and apparently useless foundations, for the most pre¬ cious advantages that we now enjoy. The study of the Roman Law, which, from a variety of causes, natural as well as accidental, became, in the course of the twelfth century, an object of general pursuit, shot a strong and aus¬ picious ray of intellectual light across the sur¬ rounding darkness. No study could then have been presented to the curiosity of men, more happily adapted to improve their taste, to enlarge their views, or to invigorate their reasoning powers; and although, in the first instance, prosecuted merely as the object of a weak and undistinguishing idolatry, it nevertheless con¬ ducted the student to the very confines of ethical as well as of political speculation ; and served, in the meantime, as a substitute of no inconsider¬ able value for both these sciences. According¬ ly we find that, while in its immediate effects it powerfully contributed, wherever it struck its roots, by ameliorating and systematizing the ad¬ ministration of justice, to accelerate the progress of order and of civilization, it afterwards furnish¬ ed, in the further career of human advancement, the parent stock on which were grafted the first rudiments of pure ethics and of liberal politics taught in modern times. I need scarcely add, that I allude to the systems of natural jurispru- Philological Inquiries, Part HI. chap. i. i DISSERTATION FIRST. 15 dence compiled by Grotius and bis successors;— systems which, for a hundred and fifty years, engrossed all the learned industry of the most enlightened part of Europe; and which, how¬ ever unpromising in their first aspect, were des¬ tined, in the last result, to prepare the way for that never to he forgotten change in the literary taste of the eighteenth century, c< which has everywhere turned the spirit of philosophical inquiry from frivolous or abstruse speculations, to the business and affairs of men.”1 The revival of letters may he considered as coeval with the fall of the Eastern empire, to¬ wards the close of the fifteenth century. In con¬ sequence of this event, a number of learned Greeks took refuge in Italy, where the taste for literature already introduced by Dante, Petrarch, and Boccacio, together with the liberal patro¬ nage of the illustrious House of Medicis, secu¬ red them a welcome reception. A knowledge of the Greek tongue soon became fashionable; and the learned, encouraged by the rapid diffusion which the art of printing now gave to their labours, vied with each other in rendering the Greek authors accessible, by means of Latin translations, to a still wider circle of readers. For a long time, indeed, after the era just mentioned, the progress of useful knowledge was extremely slow. The passion for logical disputation was succeeded by an unbounded ad¬ miration for the wisdom of antiquity; and in proportion as the pedantry of the schools disap¬ peared in the universities, that of erudition and philology occupied its place. Meanwhile, an important advantage was gain¬ ed in the immense stock of materials which the ancient authors supplied to the reflections of speculative men; and which, although frequent¬ ly accumulated with little discrimination or pro¬ fit, were much more favourable to the develope- ment of taste and of genius than the unsubstan¬ tial subtleties of ontology or of dialectics. By such studies were formed Erasmus,2 Ludovicus Vives,3 Sir Thomas More,4 and many other ac¬ complished scholars of a similar character, who, if they do not rank in the same line with the daring reformers by whom the errors of the Catholic church were openly assailed, certainly exhibit a very striking contrast to the barbarous and unenlightened writers of the preceding age. The Protestant Reformation, which followed immediately after, was itself one of the natural consequences of the revival of letters, and of the invention of printing. But although, in one 1 Dr Robertson, from whom I quote these words, has mentioned this change as the glory of the present age, meaning, I presume, the period which has elapsed since the time of Montesquieu. By what steps the philosophy to which he alludes took its rise from the systems of jurisprudence previously in fashion, will appear in the sequel of this Discourse. 2 The writings of Erasmus probably contributed still more than those of Luther himself to the progress of the Reforma¬ tion among men of education and taste; but, without the co-operation of bolder and more decided characters than his, little would to this day have been effected in Europe among the lower orders. “ Erasmus imagined,” as is observed by his bio¬ grapher, “ that at length, by training up youth in learning and useful knowledge, those religious improvements would gradually be brought about, which the Princes, the Prelates, and the Divines of his days could not be persuaded to admit or to tolerate.” (Jortin, p. 279.) In yielding, however, to this pleasing expectation, Erasmus must have flattered himself with the hope, not only of a perfect freedom of literary discussion, but of such reforms in the prevailing modes of instruc¬ tion, as would give complete scope to the energies of the human mind ;—for, where books and teachers are subjected to the censorship of those who are hostile to the dissemination of truth, they become the most powerful of all auxiliaries to the authority of established errors. It was long a proverbial saying among the ecclesiastics of the Romish church, that “ Erasmus laid the egg, and Luther hatched itand there is more truth in the remark, than in most of their sarcasms on the same subject. 3 Ludovicus Vives was a learned Spaniard, intimately connected both with Erasmus and More ; with the former of whom he lived for some time at Louvain, “ where they both promoted literature as much as they could, though not with¬ out great opposition from some of the divines.”—Jortin, p. 255. “ He was invited into England by Wolsey, in 1523; and coming to Oxford, he read the Cardinal’s lecture of Humanity, and also lectures of Civil Law, which Henry VIII. and his Queen, Catherine, did him the honour of attending—(Ibid. p. 207.) He died at Bruges in 1554. In point of good sense and acuteness, wherever he treats of philosophical questions, he yields to none of his contempo¬ raries ; and in some of his anticipations of the future progress of science, he discovers a mind more comprehensive and sagacious than any of them. Erasmus appears, from a letter of his to Budseus, dated in 1521, to have foreseen the bn - liant career which Vives, then a very young man, was about to run. “ Vives in stadio literario, non minus feliciter quam gnaviter decertat, et si satis ingenium hominis novi, non conquiescet, donee omnes a tergo reliquerit.”—I or this letter ( le whole of which is peculiarly interesting, as it contains a character of Sir Thomas More, and an account of the extraordinary accomplishments of his daughters), See Jortin’s Life of Erasmus, Vol. II. p. 366. et seq. 4 See Note A. 16 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. point of view, only an effect, it is not, on the present occasion, less entitled to notice than the causes by which, it was produced. The renunciation, in a great part of Europe, of theological opinions so long consecrated by time, and the adoption of a creed more pure in its principles and more liberal in its spirit, could not fail to encourage, on all other subjects, a congenial freedom of inquiry. These circum¬ stances operated still more directly and power¬ fully, by their influence, in undermining the au¬ thority of Aristotle;—an authority which foi many years was scarcely inferior in the schools to that of the Scriptures; and which, in some Universities, was supported by statutes, requir¬ ing the teachers to promise upon oath, that in their public lectures, they would follow no other guide. Luther,1 who was perfectly aware of the cor¬ ruptions which the Romish church had contriv¬ ed to connect with their veneration for the Sta- girite,2 not only threw off the yoke himself, but, in various parts of his writings, speaks of Aris¬ totle with the most unbecoming asperity and contempt.3 In one very remarkable passage, he asserts, that the study of Aristotle was wholly useless, not only in Theology, but in Natural Philosophy. “ What does it contribute,” he asks, “ to the knowledge of things, to trifle and cavil in language conceived and prescribed by Aristotle, concerning matter, form, motion, and time?”4 The same freedom of thought on to¬ pics not strictly theological, formed a prominent feature in the character of Calvin. A curious instance of it occurs in one of his letters, where he discusses an ethical question of no small mo¬ ment in the science of political economy;— “ How far it is consistent with morality to ac¬ cept of interest for a pecuniary loan ?” On this question, which, even in Protestant countries, continued, till a very recent period, to divide the opinions both of divines and lawyers, Calvin treats the authority of Aristotle and that of the church with equal disregard. To the former he opposes a close and logical argument, not un¬ worthy of Mr Bentham. To the latter he replies, by showing, that the Mosaic law on this point was not a moral but a municipal prohibition; a prohibition not to be judged of from any par¬ ticular text of Scripture, but upon the principles of natural equity.5 The example of these two Fathers of the Reformation would probably have been followed by consequences still greater and more immediate, if Melanchthon had not unfor¬ tunately given the sanction of his name to the doctrines of the Peripatetic school:6 but still, among the Reformers in general, the credit of these doctrines gradually declined, and a spirit of research and of improvement prevailed. The invention of printing, which took place 1 Born 1483, died 1546. . . . 2 In one of his letters he writes thus : “ Ego simpliciter credo, quod impossihue sit ecclesiain reiormari, nisi tunnitus canones, decretales, scholastica theologia, philosophia, logica, ut nunc habentur, eradicentur, etalia instituantur.”—Bruck- Eri Hitt Crit. Phil. Tom. IV. p. 95. 3 For a specimen of Luther’s scurrilitj against Aristotle, see Bayle, Art. Luther, Note HH. In Luther’s Colloquia Mensalia we are told, that “ he abhorred the Schoolmen, and called them sophistical locusts, cater¬ pillars, frogs, and lice.” From the same work we learn, that “ he hated Aristotle, but highly esteemed Cicero, as a wise and a good man.”—See Jortin’s £,i/e of EmswMs, p. 121. _ ... 4 u Nihil adjumenti ex ipso haberi posse non solum ad theologiam seu sacras literas, verum etiam ad ipsam naturalem philosophiam. Quid enim juvet ad rerum cognitionem, si de materia, forma, motu, tempore, nugari et cavillari queas ver¬ bis ab Aristotele conceptis et prsescriptis ?”—Bruck. Hist. Phil. Tom. IV. p. 101. The following passage to the same purpose is quoted by Bayle: “ Non mihi persuadebitis, philosophiam esse garruhta- tem illam de materia, motu, infinite, loco, vacuo, tempore, quae fere in Aristotele sola discimus, talia quae nec intellectum, nec affectum, nec communes hominum mores quidquam juvent; tantum contentionibus serendis, seminandisque idonea.”—. Bayle, Art. Luther, Note HH. I borrow from Bayle another short extract from Luther: “ Nihil ita ardet animus, quam histrionem ilium (Aristotelem), qui tarn vere Grseca larva ecclesiam lusit, multis revelare, ignominiamque ejus cunctis ostendere, si otium esset. Habeo in manus commentariolos in 1. Physicorum, quibus fabulam Aristsei denuo agere statui in meum istum Protea (Aristotelem). Pars crucis meae vel maxima est, quod videre cogor fratrum optima ingenia, bonis studiis nata, in istis coems vitam agere, et operam perdere.”—Ibid. That Luther was deeply skilled in the scholastic philosophy we learn from very high authority, that of Melanchthon; who tells us farther, that he was a strenuous partizan of the sect of Nominalists, or, as they were then generally called, Terminists Bruck. Tom. IV. pp. 93, 94, et seq. * See Note B. ..... 6 “ Et Melanchthoni quidem prsecipue debetur conservatio philosophise Aristotelicae in academiis protestantium. Scripsit is compendia plerarumque disciplinarum philosophise Aristotelicse, quse in Academiis diu regnarunt.”—Heineccxi, Elem. Hist. Phil. § ciii. See also Bayle’s Dictionary, Art. Melanchthon. DISSERTATION FIRST. 17 very nearly at the same time with the fall of the Eastern Empire, besides adding greatly to the efficacy of the causes above-mentioned, must have been attended with very important effects of its own, on the progress of the human mind. For us who have been accustomed, from our in¬ fancy, to the use of hooks, it is not easy to form an adequate idea of the disadvantages which those laboured under, who had to acquire the whole of their knowledge through the medium of universities and schools;—blindly devoted as the generality of students must then have been to the peculiar opinions of the teacher who first unfolded to their curiosity the treasures of lite¬ rature and the wonders of science. Thus error was perpetuated; and, instead of yielding to time, acquired additional influence in each suc¬ cessive generation.* In modern times, this in¬ fluence of names is, comparatively speaking, at an end. The object of a public teacher is no longer to inculcate a particular system of dog¬ mas, but to prepare his pupils for exercising their own judgments; to exhibit to them an outline of the different sciences, and to suggest subjects for their future examination. The few attempts to establish schools and to found sects, have all, after perhaps a temporary success, proved abortive. Their effect, too, during their short continuance, has been perfectly the reverse of that of the schools of antiquity; for where¬ as these were instrumental, on many occasions, in establishing and diffusing error in the world, the founders of our modern sects, by mixing up important truths with their own peculiar tenets, and by disguising them under the garb of a tech¬ nical phraseology, have fostered such prejudices against themselves, as have blinded the public mind to all the lights they were able to commu¬ nicate. Of this remark a melancholy illustra¬ tion occurs, as M. Turgot long ago predicted, in the case of the French Economists; and many examples of a similar import might be pro¬ duced from the history of science in our coun¬ try; more particularly from the history of the va¬ rious medical and metaphysical schools which successively rose and fell during the last century. With the circumstances already suggested, as conspiring to accelerate the progress of know¬ ledge, another has co-operated very extensively and powerfully; the rise of the lower orders in the different countries of Europe,—in conse¬ quence partly of the enlargement of commerce, and partly of the efforts of the Sovereigns to re¬ duce the overgrown power of the feudal aristo¬ cracy. Without this emancipation of the lower or¬ ders, and the gradual diffusion of wealth by which it was accompanied, the advantages de¬ rived from the invention of printing would have been extremely limited. A certain degree of ease and independence is essentially requisite to inspire men with the desire of knowledge, and to afford the leisure necessary for acquiring it; and it is only by the encouragement which such a state of society presents to industry and ambi¬ tion, that the selfish passions of the multitude can be interested in the intellectual improve¬ ment of their children. It is only, too, in such a state of society, that education and books are likely to increase the sum of human happiness; for while these advantages are confined to one privileged description of individuals, they but furnish them with an additional engine for de¬ basing and misleading the minds of their infe¬ riors. To all which it may be added, that it is chiefly by the shock and collision of different and opposite prejudices, that truths are gradually cleared from that admixture of error which they have so strong a tendency to acquire, wherever the course of public opinion is forcibly con- 1 It was in consequence of this mode of conducting education by means of oral instruction alone, that the different sects of philosophy arose in ancient Greece; and it seems to have been with a view of counteracting the obvious inconveniences resulting from them, that Socrates introduced his peculiar method of questioning, with an air of sceptical diffidence, those whom he was anxious to instruct; so as to allow them, in forming their conclusions, the complete and unbiassed exercise of their own reason. Such, at least, is the apology offered for the apparent indecision of the Academic school, by one of its wisest as well as most eloquent adherents. “ As for other sects,” says Cicero, “ who are bound in fetters, before they are able to form any judgment of what is right or true, and who have been led to yield themselves up, in their tender years, to the guidance of some friend, or to the captivating eloquence of the teacher whom they have first heard, they as¬ sume to themselves the right of pronouncing upon questions of which they are completely ignorant; adhering to whatever creed the wind of doctrine may have driven them, as if it were the only rock on which their safety depended.”—Cic. Lucullus, 3. DISS. I. PART I. C 18 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. strained and guided within certain artificial channels, marked out hy the narrow views of human policy. The diffusion of knowledge, therefore, occasioned hy the rise of the lower orders, would necessarily contribute to the im¬ provement of useful science, not merely in pro¬ portion to the arithmetical number of cultivated minds now combined in the pursuit of truth, but in a proportion tending to accelerate that important effect with a far greater rapidity. Nor ought we here to overlook the influence of the foregoing causes, in encouraging among authors the practice of addressing the multitude in their own vernacular tongues. The zeal of the Reformers first gave birth to this invaluable innovation, and imposed on their adversaries the necessity of employing, in their own de¬ fence, the same weapons.1 2 From that moment the prejudice began to vanish which had so long confounded knowledge with erudition; and a revolution commenced in the republic of let¬ ters, analogous to what the invention of gun¬ powder produced in the art of war. “ All the splendid distinctions of mankind,” as the Cham¬ pion and Flower of Chivalry indignantly ex¬ claimed, <{ were thereby thrown down; and the naked shepherd levelled with the knight clad in steel.” To all these considerations may he added the gradual effects of time and experience in cor¬ recting the errors and prejudices which had misled philosophers during so long a succession of ages. To this cause, chiefly, must he ascrib¬ ed the ardour with which we find various inge¬ nious men, soon after the period in question, employed in prosecuting experimental inquiries ; a species of study to which nothing analogous occurs in the history of ancient science.3 * The boldest and most successful of this new school was the celebrated Paracelsus, born in 1493, and consequently only ten years younger than Luther. “ It is impossible to doubt,” says Le Clerc, in his History of Physic, “ that he pos¬ sessed an extensive knowledge of what is called the Materia Medica, and that he had employed much time in working on the animal, the vege¬ table, and the mineral substances of which it is composed. He seems, besides, to have tried an immense number of experiments in chemistry; hut he has this great defect, that he studiously conceals or disguises the results of his long ex¬ perience.” The same author quotes from Pa¬ racelsus a remarkable expression, in which he calls the philosophy of Aristotle a wooden foun¬ dation. “ He ought to have attempted,” con¬ tinues Le Clerc, “ to have laid a better ; hut if he has not done it, he has at least, hy discover¬ ing its weakness, invited his successors to look out for a firmer basis.”5 Lord Bacon himself, while he censures the moral frailties of Paracelsus, and the blind em¬ piricism of his followers, indirectly acknowledges the extent of his experimental information: “ The ancient sophists may he said to have hid, hut Paracelsus extinguished the light of nature. The sophists were only deserters of experience, hut Paracelsus has betrayed it. At the same time, he is so far from understanding the right method of conducting experiments, or of record¬ ing their results, that he has added to the trouble and tediousness of experimenting. By wander¬ ing through the wilds of experience, his disciples sometimes stumble upon useful discoveries, not hy reason, but by accident;—whence rashly proceeding to form theories, they carry the smoke and tarnish of their art along with them; and, like childish operators at the furnace, at¬ tempt to raise a structure of philosophy with a few experiments of distillation.” Two other circumstances, of a nature widely different from those hitherto enumerated, al¬ though, probably, in no small degree to be ac¬ counted for on the same principles, seconded, with an incalculable accession of power, the sud- 1 “ The sacred books were, in almost all the kingdoms and states of Europe, translated into the language of each respec¬ tive people, particularly in Germany, Italy, France, and Britain.”—(Mosheim’s Eccles. IJist. Voh III. p. 205.) The effect of this single circumstance in multiplying the number of readers and of thinkers, and in giving a certain stability to the mutable forms of oral speech, may be easily imagined. The common translation of the Bible into English is pronounced by Dr Lowth to be still the best standard of our language. . „ 2 “ Hmc nostra (ut ssepe diximus) felicitatis cujusdam sunt potius quam facultatis, et potius temporis partus qua?n ingenn. — Nov. Org. Lib. i. c. xxiii. * Histoire de la Medecine (a la Haye, 1729), p. 819. DISSERTATION FIRST. 19 den impulse which the human mind had just re¬ ceived. The same century which the invention of printing and the revival of letters have made for ever memorable, was also illustrated by the dis¬ covery of the New World, and of the passage to India by the Cape of Good Hope;—events which may be justly regarded as fixing a new era in the political and moral history of mankind, and which still continue to exert a growing influence over the general condition of our species. “ It is an era,” as Raynal observes, “ which gave rise to a revolution, not only in the commerce of nations, but in the manners, industry, and government of the world. At this period new connections were formed by the inhabitants of the most distant regions, for the supply of wants which they had never before experienced. The productions of climates situated under the equa¬ tor, were consumed in countries bordering on the pole; the industry of the north was trans¬ planted to the south; and the inhabitants of the west were clothed with the manufactures of the east; a general intercourse of opinions, laws and customs, diseases and remedies, virtues and vices, was established among men.” <£ Every thing,” continues the same writer, “ has changed, and must yet change more. But it is a question, whether the revolutions that are past, or those which must hereafter take place, have been, or can he, of any utility to the hu¬ man race. Will they add to the tranquillity, to the enjoyments, and to the happiness of man¬ kind ? Can they improve our present state, or do they only change it ?” I have introduced this quotation, not with the design of attempting at present any reply to the very interesting question with which it con¬ cludes, hut merely to convey some slight notion of the political and moral importance of the events in question. I cannot, however, forbear to remark, in addition to Raynal’s eloquent and impressive summary, the inestimable treasure of new facts which these events have furnished for illustrating the versatile nature of man, and the history of civil society. In this respect (as Ba¬ con has well observed) they have fully verified the Scripture prophecy, multi pertransibunt et au- gebitur scientia ; or, in the still more emphatical words of our English version, “ Many shall go to and fro, and knowledge shall be increased.”1 The same prediction may be applied to the gra¬ dual renewal, (in proportion as modern govern¬ ments became effectual in securing order and tranquillity) of that intercourse between the dif¬ ferent states of Europe, which had, in a great measure, ceased during the anarchy and turbu¬ lence of the middle ages. In consequence of these combined causes, aid¬ ed by some others of secondary importance,2 the Genius of the human race seems, all at once, to have awakened with renovated and giant strength, from his long sleep. In less than a 1 “ Neque omittenda est pi'ophetia Danielis de ultimis mundi temporibus; multi pertraruilnint et augebitur scientia: Ma- nifeste innuens et significans, esse in fatis, id est, in providentia, ut pertransitus mundi (qui per tot longinquas navigationes impletur plane, aut jam in opere esse videtur) et augmenta scientiarum in eandem setatem incidant.”—Nov. Org. Lib. xciii. 2 Such as the accidental inventions of the telescope and of the microscope. The powerful influence of these inventions may be easily conceived, not only in advancing the sciences of Astronomy and of Natural History, but in banishing many of the scholastic prejudices then universally prevalent. The effects of the telescope, in this respect, have been often re¬ marked ; but less attention has been given to those of the microscope, which, however, it is probable, contributed not a little to prepare the way for the modem revival of the Atomic or Corpuscular Philosophy, by Bacon, Gassendi, and New¬ ton. That, on the mind of Bacon, the wonders disclosed by the microscope produced a strong impression in favour of the Epicurean physics, may be inferred from his own words. “ Perspicillum (microscopicum) si vidisset Democritus, exsilu- isset forte; et modum videndi Atomum, quem ille invisibilem omnino affirmavit, inventum fuisse putasset.”—Nov. Org. Lib. ii. § 39. We are told in the life of Galileo, that when the telescope was invented, some individuals carried to so great a length their devotion to Aristotle, that they positively refused to look through that instrument: so averse were they to open their eyes to any truths inconsistent with their favourite creed—{Vita di Galileo, Yenezia, 1744). It is amusing to find some other followers of the Stagirite, a very few years afterwards, when they found it impossible any longer to call in question the evidence of sense, asserting that it was from a passage in Aristotle, where he attempts to explain why stars become visible in the day-time when viewed from the bottom of a deep well, that the invention of the telescope was bor¬ rowed. The two facts, when combined, exhibit a truly characteristical portrait of one of the most fatal weaknesses incident to humanity; and form a moral apologue, daily exemplified on subjects of still nearer and higher interest than the phenomena of the heavens. In ascribing to accident the inventions of the telescope and of the microscope, I have expressed myself in conformity to common language; but it ought not to be overlooked, that an invention may be accidental with respect to the particular author, and yet may be the natural result of the circumstances of society at the period when it took place. As to the in¬ struments in question, the combination of lenses employed in their structure is so simple, that it could scarcely escape the notice of all the experimenters and mechanicians of that busy and inquisitive age. A similar remark has been made by 20 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. century from the invention of printing, and the fall of the Eastern empire, Copernicus discovered the true theory of the planetary motions, and a very few years afterwards, was succeeded by the three great precursors of Newton,—Tycho Brahe, Kepler, and Galileo. The step made by Copernicus may he justly regarded as one of the proudest triumphs of hu¬ man reason;—whether we consider the sagacity which enabled the author to obviate, to his own satisfaction, the many plausible objections which must have presented themselves against his con¬ clusions, at a period when the theory of motion was so imperfectly understood; or the hold spi¬ rit of inquiry which encouraged him to exercise his private judgment, in opposition to the autho¬ rity of Aristotle,—to the decrees of the church of Rome,—and to the universal belief of the learned, during a long succession of ages. He appears, indeed, to have well merited the enco¬ mium bestowed on him by Kepler, who calls him “ a man of vast genius, and, what is of still greater moment in these researches, a man of a free mind.” The establishment of the Copernican system, beside the new field of study which it opened to Astronomers, must have had great effects on philosophy in all its branches, by inspiring those sanguine prospects of future improvement, which stimulate curiosity, and invigorate the inventive powers. It afforded to the common sense, even of the illiterate, a palpable and incontrovertible proof, that the ancients had not exhausted the stock of possible discoveries; and that, in mat¬ ters of science, the creed of the Romish church was not infallible. In the conclusion of one of Kepler’s works, we perceive the influence of these prospects on his mind. “ Haec et cetera hujusmodi latent in pandectis sevi sequentis, non antea discenda, quam librum hunc Deus arbiter saeculorum recluserit mortalihus.”1 I have hitherto taken no notice of the effects of the revival of letters on Metaphysical, Moral, or Political science. The truth is, that little de¬ serving of our attention occurs in any of these departments prior to the seventeenth century; and nothing which hears the most remote ana¬ logy to the rapid strides made, during the six¬ teenth, in mathematics, astronomy, and physics. The influence, indeed, of the Reformation on the practical doctrines of ethics appears to have been great and immediate. We may judge of this from a passage in Melanchthon, where he combats the pernicious and impious tenets of those theologians who maintained, that moral distinctions are created entirely by the arbitrary and revealed will of God. In opposition to this heresy, he expresses himself in these memorable words :—“ Wherefore our decision is this; that those precepts which learned men have commit¬ ted to writing, transcribing them from the com¬ mon reason and common feelings of human na¬ ture, are to be accounted as not less divine, than those contained in the tables given to Moses; and that it could not be the intention of our Maker to supersede, by a law graven upon stone, that which is written with his own finger on the table of the heart.”2—This language was, un¬ doubtedly, a most important step towards a just system of Moral Philosophy; hut still, like the other steps of the Reformers, it was only a return to common sense, and to the genuine spirit of Christianity, from the dogmas imposed on the credulity of mankind by an ambitious priest¬ hood.5 Many years were yet to elapse, before Condorcet concerning the invention of printing. “ L’invention de 1’Imprimerie a sans doute avance le progres de 1 espece humaine ; mais cette invention dtoit elle-meme une suite de I’usagede la lecture repandu dans un grand nombre <*e pays. Vie de Turgot. 1 Epit. Astron. Copernic. < . . , . , 2 Proinde sic statuimus, nihilo minus divina praecepta esse ea, quae a sensu communi et naturae judicio mutuati docti ho¬ mines gentiles literis mandarunt, quam quae extant in ipsis saxeis Mosis tabulis. Neque ille ipse caelestis 1 ater pluns a nobis fieri eas leges voluit, quas in saxo scripsit, quam quas in ipsos animorum nostrorum sensus impresserat. Not having it in my power at present to consult Melanchthon’s works, I have transcribed the foregoing paragraph on the authority of a learned German Professor, Christ. Meiners—See his Historia Doctrine de Ven Deo. . Lemgoviae, GoO, p. 12. 3 It is observed by Dr Cudworth, that the doctrine which refers the origin of moral distinctions to the arbitrary ap¬ pointment of the Deity, was strongly reprobated by the ancient fathers of the Christian church, and that “ it crept up afterward in the scholastic ages; Occam being among the first that maintained that there is no act evil, hut as it is prohi¬ bited by God, and which cannot he made good, if it be commanded by him. In this doctrine he was quickly followed by Petrus Alliacus, Andreas de Novo Castro, and others.”—See Treatise of Immutable Morality. It is pleasing to remark, how very generally the heresy here ascribed to Occam is now reprobated by good men of ail DISSERTATION FIRST. 21 any attempts were to be made to trace, with analytical accuracy, the moral phenomena of human life to their first principles in the consti¬ tution and condition of man, or even to disen¬ tangle the plain and practical lessons of ethics from the speculative and controverted articles of theological systems.1 A similar observation may be applied to the powerful appeals, in the early Protestant wri¬ ters, to the moral judgment and moral feelings of the human race, from those casuistical subtle¬ ties, with which the schoolmen and monks of the middle ages had studied to obscure the light of nature, and to stifle the voice of conscience. These subtleties were precisely analogous in their spirit to the pia et religiosa caUiditas, after¬ wards adopted in the casuistry of the Jesuits, and so inimitably exposed by Pascal in the Pro¬ vincial Letters. The arguments against them employed by the Reformers, cannot, in strict pro¬ priety, be considered as positive accession to the stock of human knowledge; but what scientific discoveries can be compared to them in value !8 From this period may be dated the decline5 of that worst of all heresies of the Romish church, which, by opposing Revelation to Rea¬ son, endeavoured to extinguish the light of both ; and the absurdity, so happily described by Locke, became every day more manifest, of at¬ tempting “ to persuade men to put out their eyes, that they might the better receive the re¬ mote light of an invisible star by a telescope.” persuasions. The Catholics have even begun to recriminate on the Reformers as the first broachers of it; and it is to be regretted, that in some of the writings of the latter, too near approaches to it are to be found. The truth is, as Burnet long ago observed, that the effects of the Reformation have not been confined to the reformed churches;—to which it may be added, that both Catholics and Protestants have, since that era, profited very largely by the general progress of the sciences and of human reason. I quote the following sentence from a highly respectable Catholic writer on the law of nature and nations:—“ Q,ui ra- tionem exsulare jubent a moralibus praeceptis quae in sacris literis traduntur, et in absurdam enormemque Luthe-ri sen- tentiam imprudentes incidunt (quam egregie et elegantissime refutavit Melchior Canus Loc. Theolog. Lib. ix; et x.), et ea docent, quae si sectatores inveniant moralia omnia susque deque miscere, ac revelationem ipsam inutilem omnino et ineffi- cacem redderepossent.”—(Lampredi Feorentini Juris Natures et Gentium Thcoremata, Tom. II. p. 195. Pisis, 1782). For the continuation of the passage, which would do credit to the most liberal Protestant, I must refer to the original work. The. zeal of Luther for the doctrine of the Nominalists had probably prepossessed him, in his early years, in favour of some of the theological tenets of Occam, and afterwards prevented him from testifying his disapprobation of them so explicitly and decidedly as Melanchthon and other reformers have done. 1 “ The theological system (says the learned and judicious Mosheim) that now prevails in the Lutheran academies, is not of the same tenor or spirit with that which was adopted in the infancy of the Reformation. The glorious defenders of re¬ ligious liberty, to whom we owe the various blessings of the Reformation, could not, at once, behold the truth in all its lustre, and in all its extent; but, as usually happens to persons that have been long accustomed to the darkness of igno¬ rance, their approaches towards knowledge were but slow, and their views of things but imperfect.”—(Maclaine’s Transl. of Mosheim. London, 2d ed. Yol. IV. p. 19-) He afterwards mentions one of Luther’s early disciples (Amsdorff) “ who was so far transported and infatuated by his excessive zeal for the supposed doctrine of his master, as to maintain, that good works are an impediment to salvation”—Ibid. p. 39. Mosheim, after remarking that “ there are more excellent rules of conduct in the few practical productions of Luther and Melanchthon, than are to be found in the innumerable volumes of all the ancient casuists and moralisers,” candidly ac¬ knowledges, “ that the notions of these great men concerning the important science of morality were far from being suffi¬ ciently accurate or extensive. Melanchthon himself, whose exquisite judgment rendered him peculiarly capable of re¬ ducing into a compendious system the elements of every science, never seems to have thought of treating morals in this manner ; but has inserted, on the contrary, all his practical rules and instructions, under the theological articles that relate to the law, sin, free-will, faith, hope, and charity.”—Mosheim’s Eccles. Hist. Vol. IV. pp. 23. 24. The same author elsewhere observes, that “ the progress of morality among the reformed was obstructed by the very same means that retarded its improvement among the Lutherans ; and that it was left in a rude and imperfect state by Calvin and his associates. It was neglected amidst the tumult of controversy ; and, while every pen was drawn to main¬ tain certain systems of doctrine, few were employed in cultivating that master-science which has virtue, life, and manners, for its objects.”—Ibid. pp. 120. 121. _ _ . 2 “ Et tamen hi doctores angelici, cherubici, seraphici, non modo universam philosophiam ac theologian! erronbus quam- plurimis inquinarunt: verum etiam in philosophiam moralem invexere sacerrima ista principia probabilismi, methodi dirigendi intentionem, reservationis mentalis,peccati philosophici, quibus Jesuitse etiamnum mirifice delectantur.”—Heinecc. Elem. Histor. Phil. § ci. See also the references. With respect to the ethics of the Jesuits, which exhibit a very fair picture of the general state of that science, prior to the Reformation, See the Provhicial Letters ; Mosheim’s Ecclesiastical History, Vol. IV. p. 354; Dornford’s Translation of Putter's Historical Developcment of the present Political Constitution of the Germanic Empire, Vol. II. p. 6.; and the Appendix to Penrose’s Hampton Lectures. 3 I have said, the decline of this heresy; for it was by no means immediately extirpated even in the reformed churches. “ As late as the year 1598, Daniel Hofman, Professor of Divinity in the University of Helmstadt, laying hold of some particular opinions of Luther, extravagantly maintained, that philosophy was the mortal enemy of religion ; that tiuth was divisible into two branches, the one philosophical and the other theological; and that what was true in philosophy was fa.se in theology.”—Mosheim, Vol. IV. p. 18. 22 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. In the meantime, a powerful obstacle to the progress of practical morality and of sound policy, was superadded to those previously existing in Catholic countries, by the rapid growth and ex¬ tensive influence of the Machiavelian school. The founder of this new sect, or, to speak more correctly, the systematizer and apostle of its doctrines, was born as early as 1469, that is, about ten years before Luther; and, like that reformer, acquired, by the commanding superio¬ rity of his genius, an astonishing ascendant, though of a very different nature, over the minds of his followers. No writer, certainly, either in ancient or in modern times, has ever united, in a more remarkable degree, a greater variety of the most dissimilar and seemingly the most discordant gifts and attainments;—a profound acquaintance with all those arts of dis¬ simulation and intrigue, which in the petty cabinets of Italy, were then universally con¬ founded with political wisdom; an imagination familiarized to the cool contemplation of what¬ ever is perfidious or atrocious in the history of conspirators and of tyrants; combined with a graphical skill in holding up to laughter the comparatively harmless follies of ordinary life. His dramatic humour has been often compared to that of Moliere; but it resembles it rather in comic force, than in benevolent gaiety or in chastened morality. Such as it is, however, it forms an extraordinary contrast to that strength of intellectual character, which, in one page, reminds us of the deep sense of Tacitus, and in the next, of the dark and infernal policy of Caesar Borgia. To all this must be supperadded a purity of taste, which has enabled him, as an historian, to rival the severe simplicity of the Grecian masters; and a sagacity in combining historical facts, which was afterwards to afford lights to the school of Montesquieu. Eminent, however, as the talents of Ma- chiavel unquestionably were, he cannot be num¬ bered among the benefactors of mankind. In none of his writings does he exhibit any marks of that lively sympathy with the fortunes of the human race, or of that warm zeal for the inte¬ rests of truth and justice, without the guidance of which, the highest mental endowments, when applied to moral or to political researches, are in perpetual danger of mistaking their way. What is still more remarkable, he seems to have been altogether blind to the mighty changes in human affairs, which, in consequence of the re¬ cent invention of printing, were about to result from the progress of Reason and the diffusion of Knowledge. Through the whole of his Prmce (the most noted as well as one of the latest of his publications) he proceeds on the supposition, that the sovereign has no other object in go¬ verning, but his own advantage; the very cir¬ cumstance which, in the judgment of Aristotle, constitutes the essence of the worst species of tyranny.1 He assumes also the possibility of retaining mankind in perpetual bondage by the old policy of the double doctrine; or, in other words, by enlightening the few, and hoodwink¬ ing the many;—a policy less or more practised by statesmen in all ages and countries; but which, wherever the freedom of the press is re¬ spected, cannot fail, by the insult it offers to the discernment of the multitude, to increase the insecurity of those who have the weakness to employ it. It has been contended, indeed, by some of Machiavel’s apologists, that his real object in unfolding and systematising the mys¬ teries of King-Craft, was to point out indirectly to the governed the means by which the en¬ croachments of their rulers might be most ef¬ fectually resisted; and, at the same time, to satirize, under the ironical mask of loyal and courtly admonition, the characteristical vices of princes.2 But, although this hypothesis has been sanctioned by several distinguished names, and derives some verisimilitude from various in¬ cidents in the author’s life, it will be found, on examination, quite untenable; and accordingly it is now, I believe, very generally rejected. One thing is certain, that if such were actually 1 “ There is a third kind of tyranny, which most properly deserves that odious name, and which stands in direct opposi¬ tion to royalty; it takes place when one man, the worst perhaps and basest in the country, governs a kingdom with no other view than the advantage of himself and his family.”—Atustotle’s Politics, Book vi. chap. x. See Dr Gillies’# Translation. * See Note C. DISSERTATION FIRST. 23 MacliiavePs views, they were much too refined for the capacity of his royal pupils. By many of these his hook has been adopted as a manual for daily use; hut I have never heard of a single instance, in which it has been regarded by this class of students as a disguised panegyric upon liberty and virtue. The question concerning the motives of the author is surely of little moment, when experience has enabled us to pronounce so decidedly on the practical effects of his precepts. “ About the period of the Reformation,” says Condorcet, “ the principles of religious Machia- velism had become the only creed of princes, of ministers, and of pontiffs ; and the same opinions had contributed to corrupt philosophy. What code, indeed, of morals,” he adds, “ was to he expected from a system, of which one of the principles is,—that it is necessary to support the morality of the people by false pretences, and that men of enlightened minds have a right to retain others in the chains from which they have themselves contrived to escape !” The fact is perhaps stated in terms somewhat too unquali¬ fied ; but there are the best reasons for believing that the exceptions were few, when compared with the general proposition. The consequences of the prevalence of such a creed among the rulers of mankind were such as might he expected. “ Infamous crimes, as¬ sassinations, and poisonings (says a French his¬ torian), prevailed more than ever. They were thought to he the growth of Italy, where the rage and weakness of the opposite factions con¬ spired to multiply them. Morality gradually disappeared, and with it all security in the inter¬ course of life. The first principles of duty were obliterated by the joint influence of atheism and of superstition.”1 And here, may I he permitted to caution my readers against the common error of confound¬ ing the double doctrine of Machiavelian politi¬ cians, with the benevolent reverence for establish¬ ed opinions, manifested in the noted maxim of Fontenelle,—“ that a wise man, even when his hand was full of truths, would often content himself with opening his little finger.” Of the advocates for the former, it may he justly said, that “ they love darkness rather than light, because their deeds are evil;” well knowing, if I may borrow the words of Bacon, “ that the open day-light doth not show the masks and mummeries, and triumphs of the world, half so stately as candle-light.” The philosopher, on the other hand, who is duly impressed with the latter, may be compared to the oculist, who, after removing the cataract of his patient, pre¬ pares the still irritable eye, by the glimmering dawn of a darkened apartment, for enjoying in safety the light of day.® Machiavel is well known to have been, at bottom, no friend to the priesthood; and his character has been stigmatized by many of the order with the most opprobrious epithets. It is nevertheless certain, that to his maxims the royal defenders of the Catholic faith have been indebted for the spirit of that policy which they have uniformly opposed to the innovations of the Reformers. The Prince was a favourite book of the Emperor Charles V.; and was called the Bible of Catharine of Medicis. At the court of the latter, while Regent of France, those who approached her are said to have professed open- 1 Millot. 1 How strange is the following misrepresentation of Fontenelle’s fine and deep saying, by the comparatively coarse hand of the Baron de Grimm ! “ II disoit, que s’il eut tenu la verite dans ses mains comme un oiseau, il 1’auroit etouffee, tant il regardoit le plus beau present du ciel inutile et dangereux pour le genre humain.”—(Memoires Historiqnes, &c. par le Baron de Grimm. Londres, 1814. Tome I. p. 340.) Of the complete inconsistency of this statement, not only with the testimony of his most authentic biographers, hut with the general tenor both of his life and writings, a judgment may be formed from an expression of B’Alembert, in his very ingenious and philosophical parallel between Fontenelle and La Motte. “ Tous deux ont porte trop loin leur revolte ddcidee, quoique douce en apparence, contre les dieux et les lois du Pamasse ; mais la libertd des opinions de la Motte semble tenir plus intimement a 1’interet personnel qu’il avoit de les soutenir; et la liberte des opinions de Fontenelle a V inter et general, peut-ltre quelquefois mal entendu, qu'il prenoit au progres de la raison dans tous les genres. What follows may be regarded in the light of a comment on the maxim above quoted : “ La finesse de la Motte est plus developpee, celle de Fontenelle laisse plus a deviner a son lecteur. La Motte, sans jamais en trop dire, n’oublie de ce que son sujet lui presente, met habilement tout en oeuvre, et semble craindre perdre par des reticences trop subtiles quelqu’un de ses avantages ; Fontenelle, sans jamais etre obscur, excepte pour ceux qui ne meritent pas meme qu’on soit clair, se manage a la fois et le plaisir de sous-entendre, et celui d’esperer qu’il sera pleine- ment entendu par ceux qui en sont dignes.”—Eloge de la Motte. 24 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. ly its most atrocious maxims ; particularly that which recommends to sovereigns not to commit crimes by halves. The Italian cardinals, who are supposed to have been the secret instigators of the massacre of St Bartholomew, were bred in the same school.1 It is observed by Mr Hume, that <£ there is scarcely any maxim in the Prince, which subse¬ quent experience has not entirely refuted.” “ Machiavel,” says the same writer, 44 was cer¬ tainly a great genius ; but having confined his study to the furious and tyrannical governments of ancient times, or to the little disorderly prin¬ cipalities of Italy, his reasonings, especially upon monarchical governments, have been found ex¬ tremely defective. The errors of this politician proceeded, in a great measure, from his having lived in too early an age of the world, to be a good judge of political truth.”4 To these very judicious remarks, it may he added, that the bent of Machiavel’s mind seems to have disposed him much more strongly to combine and to generalize his historical reading, than to remount to the first principles of politi¬ cal science, in the constitution of human nature, and in the immutable truths of morality. His conclusions, accordingly, ingenious and refined as they commonly are, amount to little more (with a few very splendid exceptions) than em¬ pirical results from the events of past ages. To the student of ancient history they may he often both interesting and instructive; but, to the modern politician, the most important lesson they afford is, the danger, in the present circum¬ stances of the world, of trusting to such re¬ sults, as maxims of universal application, or of permanent utility. The progress of political philosophy, and along with it of morality and good order, in every part of Europe, since the period of which I am now speaking, forms so pleasing a comment on the profligate and short-sighted policy of Ma¬ chiavel, that I cannot help pausing for a mo¬ ment to remark the fact. In stating it, I shall avail myself of the words of the same profound writer, whose strictures on Machiavel’s Prince I had already occasion to quote. 44 Though ad kinds of government,” says Mr Hume, 44 he im¬ proved in modern times, yet monarchical govern¬ ment seems to have made the greatest advances towards perfection. It may now he affirmed of civilized monarchies, what was formerly said of republics alone, that they are a government of laws, not of men. They are found susceptible of order, method, and constancy, to a surprising degree. Property is there secure, industry en¬ couraged, the arts flourish, and the prince lives secure among his subjects, like a father among his children. There are, perhaps, and have been for two centuries, near two hundred absolute princes, great and small, in Europe; and allow¬ ing twenty years to each reign, we may suppose that there have been in the whole two thousand monarchs, or tyrants, as the Greeks would have called them. Yet of these there has not been one, not even Philip II. of Spain, so had as Tiberius, Caligula, Nero, or Domitian, who were four in twelve among the Roman Emperors.”5 For this very remarkable fact, it seems diffi¬ cult to assign any cause equal to the effect, but the increased diffusion of knowledge (imperfect, alas ! as this diffusion still is) by means of the Press; which, while it has raised, in free states, a growing bulwark against the oppression of rulers, in the light and spirit of the people, has, even under the most absolute governments, had a powerful influence—by teaching princes to re¬ gard the wealth and prosperity and instruction of their subjects as the firmest basis of their gran¬ deur—in directing their attention to objects of national and permanent utility. How encoura¬ ging the prospect thus opened of the future his¬ tory of the world ! And what a motive to ani¬ mate the ambition of those, who, in the solitude of the closet, aspire to bequeath their contribu¬ tions, how slender soever, to the progressive mass of human improvement and happiness ! In the bright constellation of scholars, histo¬ rians, artists, and wits, who shed so strong a lustre on Italy during that splendid period of its history which commences with the revival of 1 Voltaire, Essay on Universal History. 2 Essay on Civil Liberty. 2 Ibid. DISSERTATION FIRST. 25 letters, it is surprising how few names occur, which it is possible to connect, by any palpable link, with the philosophical or political specula¬ tions of the present times. As an original and profound thinker, the genius of Machiavel com¬ pletely eclipses that of all his contemporaries. Not that Italy was then destitute of writers who pretended to the character of philosophers; hut as their attempts were, in general, limited to the exclusive illustration and defence of some one or other of the ancient systems for which they had conceived a predilection, they added but little of their own to the stock of useful know¬ ledge, and are now remembered chiefly from the occasional recurrence of their names in the catalogues of the curious, or in the works of philological erudition. The zeal of Cardinal Bessarion, and of Marsilius Ficinus, for the re¬ vival of the Platonic philosophy, was more pe¬ culiarly remarkable, and, at one time, produced so general an impression, as to alarm the follow¬ ers of Aristotle for the tottering authority of their master. If we may credit Launoius, this great revolution was on the point of being ac¬ tually accomplished, when Cardinal Bellarmine warned Pope Clement VIII. of the peculiar dan¬ ger of showing any favour to a philosopher whose opinions approached so nearly as those of Plato to the truths revealed in the Gospel. In what manner Bellarmine connected his con¬ clusions with his premises, we are not informed. To those who are uninitiated in the mysteries of the conclave, his inference would certainly ap¬ pear much less logical than that of the old Ro¬ man Pagans, who petitioned the Senate to con¬ demn the works of Cicero to the flames, as they predisposed the minds of those who read them for embracing the Christian faith. By a small band of bolder innovators belong¬ ing to this golden age of Italian literature, the Aristotelian doctrines were more directly and powerfully assailed. Laurentius Valla, Marius Nizolius, and Franciscus Patricius,1 2 have all of them transmitted their names to posterity as philosophical reformers, and, in particular, as revolters against the authority of the Stagirite. Of the individuals just mentioned, Nizolius is the only one who seems entitled to maintain a per¬ manent place in the annals of modern science. His principal work, entitled Antibarbarus^ is not only a bold invective against the prevailing ignorance and barbarism of the schools, but con¬ tains so able an argument against the then fashion¬ able doctrine of the Realists concerning general ideas, that Leibnitz thought it worth while, a centu¬ ry afterwards, to republish it, with the addition of a long and valuable preface written by himself. At the same period with Franciscus Patricius, flourished another learned Italian, Albericus Gentilis, whose writings seem to have attracted more notice in England and Germany than in his own country. His attachment to the reform¬ ed faith having driven him from Italy, he sought an asylum at Oxford, where, in 1587, he was ap¬ pointed professor of the Civil Law, an office which he held till the period of his death in 1611.3 He was the author of a treatise De Jure Belli, in three books, which appeared successively in 1588 and 1589, and were first published to¬ gether at Hanau in 1598. His name, however, has already sunk into almost total oblivion; and I should certainly not have mentioned it on the present occasion? were it not for his indisputable merits as the precursor of Grotius, in a depart¬ ment of study which, forty years afterwards, the celebrated treatise De Jure Belli et Pads was 1 His Discussion.es Peripateticoe were printed at Venice in 1571. Another work, entitled Novade Universis Philosophia, also printed at Venice, appeared in 1593. I have never happened to meet with either; but from the account given of the au- thor by Thuanus, he does not seem to have attracted that notice from his contemporaries, to which his learning and talents entitled him (Thuan. Hist. Lib. cxix. xvii.). His Discussiones Peripateticce are mentioned by Brucker in the following terms: “ Opus egregium, doctum, varium, luculentum, sed invidia odioque iti Aristotelem plenum satis superquc."—(Hist. Phil. Tom. IV. p. 425). The same very laborious and candid writer acknowledges the assistance he had derived from Pa- tricius in his account of the Peripatetic philosophy—“ In qua tractatione fatemur egregiam enitere Patricii dpctrinam, m- genii elegantiam prorsus admirabilem, et quod primo loco ponendum est, insolitam veteris philosophise cognitionem, cujus ope nos Peripatetics; discipline historie multoties lucem attulisse, grati suis locis professi sumus.”—Ibid. p. 426.^ 2 Antibarbarus, sive de Verts Principiis et Vera Ratione Philosophandi contra Pseudo-philosophos. Parmae, 1553. “ Les taux philosophes,” dit Fontenelle, “ dtoient tous les scholastiques passes et pre'sens; et Nizolius s’eleve avec la derniere hardi- esse contre leurs ide'es monstrueuses et leur langage barbare. La longue et constante admiration qu’on avoit eu pour Ans- tote, ne prouvoit, disoit-il, que la multitude des sots et la duree de la sottise.” The merits of this writer are much too lightly estimated by Brucker—See Hist. Phil. Tom. IV. Pars I. pp. 91. 92. 3 Wood’s Athence Oxonienses, Vol. II. col. 90. Dr Bliss’s edition. DISS. I. PART I. D 26 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. to raise to so conspicuous a rank among the branches of academical education. The avowed aim of this new science, when combined with the anxiety of Gentilis to counteract the effect of Machiavel’s Prince, by representing it as a warning to subjects rather than as a manual of instruction for their rulers, may he regarded as satisfactory evidence of the growing influence, even at that era, of better ethical principles than those commonly imputed to the Florentine Secre¬ tary. 1 The only other Italian of whom I shall take notice at present, is Campanella;2 * a philoso¬ pher now remembered chiefly in consequence of his eccentric character and eventful life, but of whom Leibnitz has spoken in terms of such high admiration, as to place him in the same line with Bacon. After looking into several of his works with some attention, I must confess I am at a loss to conceive upon what grounds the eulogy of Leibnitz proceeds; but as it is difficult to suppose, that the praise of this great man was, in any instance, the result of mere caprice, I shall put it in the power of my read¬ ers to judge for themselves, by subjoining a faithful translation of his words. I do this the more willingly, as the passage itself (whatever may be thought of the critical judgments pro¬ nounced in it), contains some general remarks on intellectual character, which are in every re¬ spect worthy of the author. “ Some men, in conducting operations where an attention to minutiae is requisite, discover a mind vigorous, subtile, and versatile, and seem to be equal to any undertaking, how arduous soever. But when they are called upon to act on a greater scale, they hesitate and are lost in their own meditations ; distrustful of their judg¬ ment, and conscious of their incompetency to the scene in which they are placed: men, in a word, possessed of a genius rather acute than comprehensive. A similar difference may be traced among authors. What can be more acute than Descartes in Physics, or than Hohhes in Morals ! And yet, if the one be compa¬ red with Bacon, and the other with Campa¬ nella, the former writers seem to grovel upon the earth,—the latter to soar to the Heavens, by the vastness of their conceptions, their plans, and their enterprises, and to aim at objects be¬ yond the reach of the human powers. The former, accordingly, are best fitted for deliver¬ ing the first elements of knowledge, the latter for establishing conclusions of important and general application.”5 The annals of France, during this period, present very scanty materials for the History of Philosophy. The name of the Chancellor de 1’Hopital, however, must not be passed over in silence. As an author, he does not rank high; nor does he seem to have at all valued himself on the careless effusions of his literary hours; but, as an upright and virtuous magis¬ trate, he has left behind him a reputation un¬ rivalled to this day.4 His wise and indulgent principles on the subject of religious liberty, and the steadiness with which he adhered to them, under circumstances of extraordinary dif¬ ficulty and danger, exhibit a splendid contrast to the cruel intolerance, which, a few years be- 1 The claims of Albericus Gentilis to be regarded as the father of Natural Jurisprudence, are strongly asserted by his countryman Lampredi, in his very judicious and elegant work, entitled, Juris Publici Theoremata, published at Pisa in 1782. “ Hie primus jus'aliquod Belli et esse et tradi posse excogitavit, et Belli et Pads regulas explanavit primus, et fortasse in causa fuit cur Grotius opus suum conscribere aggrederetur: dignus sane qui prae ceteris memoretur, Italiae enim, in qua ortus erat, et unde Juris Romani disciplinam hauserat, gloriam auxit, effecitque ut quae fuerat bonarum arti- um omnium restitutrix et altrix, eadem esset et prima Jurisprudentiae Naturalis magistra.” 2 Born 1568, died 1639. s Leibnit. Opera, Yol. VI. p. 303, ed. Dutens—It is probable that, in the above passage, Leibnitz alluded more to the elevated tone of Campanella’s reasoning on moral and political subjects, when contrasted with that of Hobbes, than to the intellectual superiority of the former writer above the latter. No philosopher, certainly, has spoken with more reverence than Campanella has done, on various occasions, of the dignity of human nature. A remarkable instance of this occurs in his eloquent comparison of the human hand with the organs of touch in other animals. (Vide Campan. Physiohg. cap. xx. Art. 2.) Of his Political Aphorisms, which form the third part of his treatise on Morals, a sufficient idea for our purpose is conveyed by the concluding corollary, “ Probitas custodit regem populosque; non autem indocta Machiavellistarum astu- tia.” On the other hand, Campanella’s works abound with immoralities and extravagancies far exceeding those of Hobbes. In his idea of a pei'fect commonwealth (to which he gives the name of Civitas Solis), the impurity of his imagi¬ nation, and the unsoundness of his judgment, are equally conspicuous. He recommends, under certain regulations, a com¬ munity of women ; and, in every thing connected with procreation, lays great stress on the opinions of astrologers. 4 Magistral au-dessus de tout eloge; et d’apres lequel on a jugd tous ceux qui ont ose s’asseoir sur ce meme tribunal sans avoir son courage ni ses lumieres.”—Henault, Abrege, Chronologique. DISSERTATION FIRST. 27 fore, had disgraced the character of an illustri¬ ous Chancellor of England. The same philo¬ sophical and truly catholic spirit distinguished his friend, the President de Thou,1 2 and gives the principal charm to the justly admired pre¬ face prefixed to his history. In tracing the pro¬ gress of the human mind during the sixteenth century, such insulated and anomalous examples of the triumph of reason over superstition and bigotry, deserve attention, not less than what is due, in a history of the experimental arts, to Friar Bacon’s early anticipation of gunpowder, and of the telescope. Contemporary with these great men was Bo- din (or Bodinus),8 an eminent French lawyer, who appears to have been one of the first that united a philosophical turn of thinking with an extensive knowledge of jurisprudence and of history. His learning is often ill digested, and his conclusions still oftener rash and unsound; yet it is hut justice to him to acknowledge, that, in his views of the philosophy of law, he has approached very nearly to some leading ideas of Lord Bacon;3 while, in his refined combina¬ tions of historical facts, he has more than once struck into a train of speculation, hearing a strong resemblance to that afterwards pursued by Montesquieu.4 Of this resemblance, so re¬ markable an instance occurs in his chapter on the moral effects of Climate, and on the atten¬ tion due to this circumstance by the legislator, that it has repeatedly subjected the author of The Spirit of Laws (but in my opinion without any good reason) to the imputation of plagia¬ rism.5 A resemblance to Montesquieu, still more honourable to Bodinus, may be traced in their common attachment to religious as well as to civil liberty. To have caught, in the six¬ teenth century, somewhat of the philosophical spirit of the eighteenth, reflects less credit on the force of his mind, than to have imbibed, in the midst of the theological controversies of his age, those lessons of mutual forbearance and charity, which a long and sad experience of the fatal effects of persecution has to this day so im¬ perfectly taught to the most enlightened nations of Europe. As a specimen of the liberal and moderate views of this philosophical politician, I shall quote two short passages from his Treatise De la Republique, which seem to me objects of con¬ siderable curiosity, when contrasted with the general spirit of the age in which they were written. The first relates to liberty of con¬ science, for which he was a strenuous and in¬ trepid advocate, not only in his publications, but as a member of the Etals Generaux, assembled at Blois in 1576. <£ The mightier that a man is (says Bodin), the more justly and temperate¬ ly he ought to behave himself towards all men, but especially towards his subjects. Wherefore the senate and people of Basil did wisely, who, having renounced the Bishop of Rome’s religion, would not, upon the sudden, thrust the monks and nuns, with the other religious persons, out of their abbeys and monasteries, but only took order, that, as they died they should die both for themselves and their successors, expressly for¬ bidding any new to be chosen in their places, so that, by that means, their colleges might, by 1 “ One cannot help admiring,” says Dr Jortin, “ the decent manner in which the illustrious Thuanus hath spoken ot Calvin “ Acri vir ac vehementi ingenio, et admirabili facundia prseditus; turn inter protestantes magni nominis theolo- gus.”—(Life of Erasmus, p. 555.) The same writer has remarked the great decency and moderation with which Thuanus speaks of Luther—lUd. p. 113. 2 Born 1530, died 1596. 3 See, in particular, the preface to his book, entitled Methodus adfacilem Historiarum cognitionem. * See the work De la Reyublique, passim. In this treatise there are two chapters singularly curious, considering the time when they were written ; the second and third chapters of the sixth book. The first is entitled, Des Finances ; the second, Le Moyen d'emptchcr que les Monnoyes soyent altere.es de Prix ou falsifies. The reasonings of the Author on various points there treated of, will be apt to excite a smile among those w'ho have studied the Inquiry into the Wealth of Nations ; but it reflects no small credit on a lawyer of the sixteenth century to have subjected such questions to philosophical examination, and to have formed so just a conception as Bodin appears evidently to have done, not only of the object, but of the im¬ portance of the modern science of political economy. Thuanus speaks highly of Bodin’s dissertations ~De Re Monetaria, which I have never seen. The same historian thus ex¬ presses himself with respect to the work De Republica: “ Opus in quo ut omni scientiarum genere non tincti sed imbuti in¬ genii fidem fecit, sic nonnullis, qui recte judicant, non omnino ab ostentationis innato genii vitio vacuum se probavit.—Hist. Lib. cxvii. ix. 5 See Note D. 28 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. little and little, by tbe death of the fellows, he extinguished. Whereby it came to pass, that all the rest of the Carthusians, of their own accord, forsaking their cloisters, yet one of them all alone for a long time remained therein, quietly and without any disturbance, holding the right of his convent, being never enforced to change either his place, or habit, or old ceremonies, or religion before by him received. The like older was taken at Coire in the diet of the Giisons; wherein it was decreed, that the ministers of the reformed religion should he maintained of the profits and revenues of the church, the reli¬ gious men nevertheless still remaining in their cloisters and convents, to he by their death sup¬ pressed, they being now prohibited to choose any new instead of them which died. By which means, they which professed the new religion, and they who professed the old, were both pro¬ vided for.”1 2 * * The aim of the chapter from which I have extracted the foregoing passage, is to show, that “ it is a most dangerous thing, at one and the same time, to change the form, laws, and cus¬ toms of a commonwealth.” The scope of the author’s reasonings may be judged of from the concluding paragraph. “ We ought then in the government of a well-ordered state and commonwealth, to imitate and follow the great God of Nature, who in all things proceedeth easily, and by little and little; who of a little seed causeth to grow a tree for height and greatness, right admirable, and yet for all that insensibly; and still by means con¬ joining the extremities of nature, as by putting the spring between winter and summer, and autumn betwixt summer and winter, mode¬ rating the extremities of the terms and seasons, with the self-same wisdom which it useth in all other things also, and that in such sort, as that no violent force or course therein appeareth. 8 Notwithstanding these wise and enlightened maxims, it must be owned, on the other hand, that Bodin has indulged himself in various spe¬ culations, which would expose a writer of the present times to the imputation of insanity. One of the most extraordinary of these, is his elaborate argument to prove, that, in a w^ell con¬ stituted state, the father should possess the right of life and death over his children ;—a paradox which forms an unaccountable contrast to the general tone of humanity which characterizes his opinions. Of the extent of his credulity on the subject of witchcraft, and of the deep horror with which he regarded those who affected to be sceptical about the reality of that crime, he has left a lasting memorial in a learned and curious volume entitled Demonomanie;5 * * while the ec- 1 Book iv. chap, iii The book from which this quotation is taken was published only twenty-three years after the mur¬ der of Servetus at Geneva ; an event which leaves so deep a stain on the memory not only of Calvin, but on that ot the milder and more charitable Melanchthon. The epistle of the latter to Bullinger, where he applauds the conduct ot the iudges who condemned to the flames this incorrigible heretic, affords the most decisive of all proofs, how remote the senti¬ ments of the most enlightened Fathers of the Reformation were from those Christian and philosophical principles ot tole- ration, to which their noble exertions have gradually, and now almost universally, led the way. , . 2 IMd The substance of the above reflection has been compressed by Bacon into the following well-known aphorisms. “ Time is the greatest innovator ; shall we then not imitate time ? “ What innovator imitates time, which innovates so silently as to mock the sense ?” The resemblance between the two passages is still more striking in the Latin versions of their respective authors. _ Deum igitur prsepotentem naturae parentem imitemur, qui omnia paulatim : namque semina perquam exigua m ar- bores excelsas excrescere jubet, idque tarn occulte ut nemo sentiat.”—Bodinus. “ Novator maximus tempus ; quidni igitur tempus imitemur ?” “ Q,uis novator tempus imitatur, quod novationes ita insinuat, ut sensus fallant ?”—Bacon. _ . . , The Treatise of Bodin De la Republique (by far the most important of his works) was first printed at 1 aris in 7 , am was reprinted seven times in the space of three years. It was translated into Latin by the author himsel ? '¥1 a view chiefly (as is said) to the accommodation of the scholars of England, among whom it was so highly esteemed, t la ec uivs upon it were given in the University of Cambridge, as early as 1580. In 1579, Bodin visited London in the sm e o le Due d’Alencon ; a circumstance which probably contributed not a little to recommend his writings, so very £°on a er eir publication,’to the attention of our countrymen. In 1606, the treatise of The Republic was done inlo English by Kichard Knolles, who appears to have collated the French and Latin copies so carefully and judiciously, that his version is, in some respects, superior to either of the originals. It is from this version, accordingly, that I have transenbed the passages above quoted ; trusting, that it will not be unacceptable to my readers, while looking back to the intellectual attainments o our forefathers, to have an opportunity, at the same time, of marking the progress which had been made in England, moie t tan two centuries ago, in the arts of writing and of translation. _ _ „ at io'i For Dr Johnson’s opinion of Knolles’s merits as an historian, and as an English writer, see the Rambler, ^o. i&s. * De la Demonomanie des Sorciers. Par J. Bodin Angevin, a Paris, 1580. This book, which exhibits so melancholy DISSERTATION FIRST. 20 cen tricity of his religious tenets was such, as to incline the candid mind of Grotius to suspect him of a secret leaning to the Jewish faith.1 In contemplating the characters of the eminent persons who appeared about this era, nothing is more interesting and instructive, than to remark the astonishing combination, in the same minds, of the highest intellectual endowments, with the most deplorable aberrations of the understand¬ ing ; and even, in numberless instances, with the most childish superstitions of the multitude. Of this apparent inconsistency, Bodinus dues not furnish a solitary example. The same re¬ mark may be extended, in a greater or less de¬ gree, to most of the other celebrated names hitherto mentioned. Melanchthon, as appears from his letters, was an interpreter of dreams, and a caster of nativities; * and Luther not only sanctioned, by his authority, the popular fables about the sexual and prolific intercourse of Satan with the human race, but seems to have serious¬ ly believed that he had himself frequently seen the arch enemy face to face, and held arguments with him on points of theology.5 Nor was the study of the severer sciences, on all occasions, an effectual remedy against such illusions of the imagination. The sagacious Kepler was an as¬ trologer and a visionary ; and his friend Tycho Brahe, the Prince of Astronomers, kept an idiot in his service, to whose prophecies he listened as revelations from above.4 During the long night of Gothic barbarism, the intellectual world had again become, like the primitive earth, “ with¬ out form and voidthe light had already ap¬ peared ; ii and God had seen the light that it was goodbut the time was not yet come to “ di¬ vide it from the darkness.”5 In the midst of the disorders, both political and moral, of that unfortunate age, it is pleasing to observe the anticipations of brighter pro¬ spects, in the speculations of a few individuals. Bodinus himself is one of the number;6 and to his name may be added that of his countryman and predecessor Budseus.7 But, of all the writers of the sixteenth century, Ludovicus Vives seems to have had the liveliest and the a contrast to the mental powers displayed in the treatise De la Repullique, was dedicated by the author to his friend, the President de Thou; and it is somewhat amusing to find, that it exposed Bodin himself to the imputation of being a nia- o-ician. For this we have the testimony of the illustrious historian just mentioned—(Thuavus, Lib. cxvii- ix.)—Nor did it recommend the author to the good opinion of the Catholic church, having been formally condemned and prohibited by the Roman Inquisition. The Reflection of the Jesuit Martin del Rio on this occasion is worth transcribing. “ Adeo lubricum et periculosum de his disserere, nisi Deum semper, et catholicam Jidem, ecclesiceqne Romance censuram tanquam cynosuram sequaris."— Disquisitionum Magicarum, Libri Sex. Auctore Martino del Rio, Societatis Jesu Presbytero. Yenit. 1640, p. 8. 1 Epist. ad Cordesium (quoted by Bayle.) 2 Jortin’s Life of Erasmus, p. 156. 3 See Note E. * See the Life of Tycho Brahe, by Gassendi. _ _ 5 I have allotted to Bodin a larger space than may seem due to his literary importance; but the truth is, I know of no political writer, of the same date, whose extensive and various and discriminating reading appears to me to have contri¬ buted more to facilitate and to guide the researches of his successors, or whose references to ancient learning have been more frequently transcribed without acknowledgment. Of late his works have fallen into very general^ neglect; otherwise it is impossible that so many gross mistakes should be current about the scope and spirit of his principles. By many he has been mentioned as a zealot for republican forms of government, probably for no better reason than that he chose to call his book a Treatise De Republica; whereas, in point of fact, he is uniformly a warm and able advocate for monarchy ; and, although no friend to tyranny, has, on more than one occasion, carried his monarchical principles to a very blameable ex¬ cess JSee, in particular, chapters fourth and fifth of the Sixth Book.) On the other hand, Grouvelle, a writer of some note, has classed Bodin with Aristotle, as an advocate for domestic slavery. “ The reasonings of both,” he says, “ are re¬ futed by Montesquieu.” (De VAutorite, de Montesquieu dans la Revolution presente. Paris, 1789.) _ Whoever has the curiosity to compare Bodin and Montesquieu together, will be satisfied, that, on this point, their sentiments were exactly the same; and that, so far from refuting Bodin, Montesquieu has borrowed from him more than one argument in support of his general conclusion. ,. The merits of Bodin have been, on the whole, very fairly estimated by Bayle, who pronounces lam one of the ablest men-that appeared in France during the sixteenth century.” “ Si nous voulons disputer h Jean Bodin la qualitd d’ecnvain exact et iudicieux, laissons lui sans controverse, un grand genie, un vaste savoir, une me'moire et une lecture prodigieuses. * See, in particular, his Method of Studying History, chap. vii. entitled Confutatio eorum qui quatuor Monarchies Aureaquc Scecula statuerunt. In this chapter, after enumerating some of the most important discoveries and inventions of the moderns, he concludes with mentioning the art of printing, of the value of which he seems to have formed a very just estimate. “ Una Typographia cum omnibus veterum inventis certare facile potest. Itaque non minus peccant, qui a vetenbus aiunt omnia comprehensa, quam qui illos de veten multarum artium possessione deturbant. Habet Natura scientiarum thesauros innumerabiles, qui nullis aetatibus exhauriri possunt.” In the same chapter Bodinus expresses himseil tnus : “ Alt as ilia quam auream vocant, si ad nostram conferatur,/ermi videri possit.” _ . , . i The works of Budseus were printed at Basle, in four volumes folio, 1557. My acquaintance^ with them is muen too slight to enable me to speak of them from my own judgment. No scholar certainly stood higher in the estimation oi n s age. “ Quo viro,” says Ludovicus Yives, “ Gallia acutiore ingenio, acriroe judicio, exaction? dihgentia, majore eruui- tione nullum unquam produxit; hac vero setate nec Italia quidem.” The praise bestowed on him by o er con e p 3 writers of the highest eminence is equally lavish. 30 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. most assured foresight of the new career on which the human mind was about to enter. The following passage from one of his works would have done no discredit to the Novum Or¬ ganon :—“ The similitude which many have fancied between the superiority of the moderns to the ancients, and the elevation of a dwarf on the back of a giant, is altogether false and puerile. Neither were they giants, nor are we dwarfs, hut all of us men of the same standard,—and we the taller of the two, by adding their height to our own : Provided always that we do not yield to them in study, attention, vigilance, and love of truth ; for, if these qualities he wanting, so far from mounting on the giant’s shoulders, we throw away the advantages of our own just stature, by remaining prostrate on the ground.”1 2 I pass over, without any particular notice, the names of some French logicians who flourished about this period, because, however celebrated among their contemporaries, they do not seem to form essential links in the History of Science. The hold and persevering spirit with which Ra¬ mus disputed, in the University of Paris, the authority of Aristotle, and the persecutions he incurred by this philosophical heresy, entitle him to an honourable distinction from the rest of his brethren. He was certainly a man of un¬ common acuteness as well as eloquence, and placed in a very strong light some of the most vulnerable parts of the Aristotelian logic; with¬ out, however, exhibiting any marks of that deep sagacity which afterwards enabled Bacon, Des¬ cartes, and Locke, to strike at the very roots of the system. His copious and not inelegant style as a writer, recommended his innovations to those who were disgusted with the barbarism of the schools;8 while his avowed partiality for the reformed faith (to which he fell a martyr in the massacre of Paris), procured many prose¬ lytes to his opinions in all the Protestant coun¬ tries of Europe. In England his logic had the honour, in an age of comparative light and re¬ finement, to find an expounder and methodiser in the author of Paradise Lost; and in some of our northern universities, where it was very early introduced, it maintained its ground till it was supplanted by the logic of Locke. It has been justly said of Ramus, that, “ al¬ though he had genius sufficient to shake the Aristotelian fabric, he was unable to substitute any thing more solid in its placehut it ought not to he forgotten, that even this praise, scanty as it may now appear, involves a large tribute to his merits as a philosophical reformer. Be¬ fore human reason was able to advance, it was necessary that it should first he released from the weight of its fetters.3 * * * * 1 Vives de Cans. Corrupt. Artium, Lib. i. Similar ideas occur in the works of Roger Bacon : “ Quanto juniores tanto perspicaciores, quia juniores posteriores successione temporum ingrediuntur labores priorum.”—(Opus Majus, edit. Jebb. p. 9.) Nor were they altogether overlooked by ancient waiters. “ Yeniet tempus, quo ista quae latent nunc in lucem dies extrahet, et longioris aevi diligentia. Yeniet tempus, quo poster! nostri tam aperta nos ignorasse mirabuntur.” (Seneca, Qucest. Nat. Lib. vii. c. 25.) This language coincides exactly with that of the Chancellor Bacon ; but it was re¬ served for the latter to illustrate the connection between the progress of human knowledge, and of human happiness ; or (to borrow his own phraseology) the connection between the progress of knowledge, and the enlargement of man’s power over the destiny of his own species. Among other passages to this purpose, See Nov. Org. Lib. i. cxxix. 2 To the accomplishments of Ramus as a writer, a very flattering testimony is given by an eminent English scholar, by no means disposed to overrate his merits as a logician. “ Pulsa tandem barbarie, Petrus Ramus politioris literaturae vir, ausus est Aristotelem acrius ubique et liberius incessere, universamque Peripateticam philosophiam exagitare. Ejus Dialetica exiguo tempore fuit apud plurimos summo in pretio, maxime eloquentiae studiosos, idque idio scholasticorum, quorum dictio et stylus ingrata fuerant auribus Ciceronianis.”—Logicce Artis Compendium, Auctore R. Sanderson, Episc. Lincoln, pp. 250. 251. Edit. Decima. Oxon. The first edition was printed in 1618. 3 Dr Barrow, in one of his mathematical lectures, speaks of Ramus in terms far too contemptuous. “ Homo, ne quid gravius dicam, argutulus et dicacnlus."—“ Sane vix indignationi meae tempero, quin ilium accipiam pro suo merito, regeram- que validius in ejus caput, quae contra veteres jactat convicia.” Had Barrow confined this censure to the weak and arro¬ gant attacks made by Ramus upon Euclid (particularly upon Euclid’s definition of Proportion), it would not have been more than Ramus deserved ; but it is evident he meant to extend it also to the more powerful attacks of the same reformer upon the logic of Aristotle. Of these there are many which may be read with profit even in the present times. I select one passage as a specimen, recommending it strongly to the consideration of those logicians who have lately stood forward as advocates for Aristotle’s abecedarian demonstrations of the syllogistic rules. “ In Aristotelis arte, unius pnecepti uni- cum exemplum est, ac ssepissime nullum : sed unico et singular! exemplo non potest artifex effici; pluribus opus est et dissimilibus. Et quidem, ut Aristotelis exempla tantummodo non falsa sint, qualia tamen sunt ? Omne 6 est a : omne c est b : ergo omne c est a. Exemplum Aristotelis est puero a grammaticis et oratoribus venienti, et istam mutorum Mathema- ticorum linguam ignoranti, novum et durum: et in totis Analyticis ista non Attica, non lonica, non Dorica, non vEolica, non communi, sed geometrica lingua usus est Aristoteles, odiosa pueris, ignota populo, a communi sensu remota, a rhetoricse usu et ab humanitatis usu alienissima.”—(P. Rami pro Philosophica Parisiensis Academia; Disciplina Oratio, 1550). If these strictures should be thought too loose and declamatory, the reader may consult the fourth chapter (De Conversionibus) of the seventh Look of Ramus’s Dialectics, where the same charge is urged, in my opinion, with irresistible force of argument. DISSERTATION FIRST. 31 It is observed with great truth, hy Condorcet, that, in the times of which we are now speak- ing, £< the science of political economy did not exist. Princes estimated not the number of men, hut of soldiers in the state;—finance was merely the art of plundering the people, with¬ out driving them to the desperation that might end in revolt;—and governments paid no other attention to commerce hut that of loading it with taxes, of restricting it hy privileges, or of disputing for its monopoly.” The internal disorders then agitating the whole of Christendom, were still less favourable to the growth of this science, considered as a branch of speculative study. Religious con¬ troversies everywhere divided the opinions of the multitude;—involving those collateral dis¬ cussions concerning the liberty of conscience, and the relative claims of sovereigns and sub¬ jects, which, by threatening to resolve society into its first elements, present to restless and aspiring spirits the most inviting of all fields for enterprise and ambition. Amidst the shock of such discussions, the calm inquiries which medi¬ tate in silence the slow and gradual amelioration of the social order, were not likely to possess strong attractions, even to men of the most sanguine benevolence; and, accordingly, the po¬ litical speculations of this period turn almost en¬ tirely on the comparative advantages and disad¬ vantages of different forms of government, or on the still more alarming questions concerning the limits of allegiance and the right of resist¬ ance. The dialogue of our illustrious countryman Buchanan, De Jure Regni apud Scotos, though occasionally disfigured by the keen and indig¬ nant temper of the writer, and by a predilection (pardonable in a scholar warm from the schools of ancient Greece and Rome) for forms of policy unsuitable to the circumstances of modern Europe, bears, nevertheless, in its general spirit, a closer resemblance to the political philosophy of the eighteenth century, than any composition which had previously appeared. The ethical paradoxes afterwards inculcated by Hobbes as the ground-work of his slavish theory of govern¬ ment, are anticipated and refuted, and a power¬ ful argument is urged against that doctrine of Utility which has attracted so much notice in our times. The political reflections, too, inci¬ dentally introduced by the same author in his History of Scotland, bear marks of a mind worthy of a better age than fell to his lot. Of this kind are the remarks with which he closes his narrative of the wanton cruelties exercised in punishing the murderers of James the First. In reading them, one would almost imagine, that one is listening to the voice of Beccaria or of Montesquieu. {£ After this manner,” says the historian, u was the cruel death of James still more cruelly avenged. For punishments so far exceeding the measure of humanity, have less effect in deterring the multitude from crimes, than in rousing them to greater efforts, both as actors and as sufferers. Nor do they tend so much to intimidate by their severity, as by their frequency to diminish the terrors of the specta¬ tors. The evil is more peculiarly great, when the mind of the criminal is hardened against the sense of pain; for in the judgment of the un¬ thinking vulgar, a stubborn confidence generally obtains the praise of heroic constancy.” After the publication of this great work, the name of Scotland, so early distinguished over Europe by the learning and by the fervid genius1 of her sons, disappears for more than a century and a half from the History of Letters. But from this subject, so pregnant with melancholy and humiliating recollections, our attention is forcibly drawn to a mighty and auspicious light which, in a more fortunate part of the island, was already beginning to rise on the philosophi¬ cal world.2 1 Praefervidum Scotorum ingenium. . that, at the end of the sixteenth century, the Scottish nation were advancing not less rapidly than their neighbours, in every species of mental cultivation, is sufficiently attested by their literary remains, both in the Latin language and in then- own vernacular tongue. A remarkable testimony to the same purpose occurs in the dialogue above quoted, the author of which had spent the best years of his life in the most polished society of the Continent. “ As often,” says Buchanan, as I turn my eyes to the niceness and elegance of our own times, the ancient manners of our forefathers appear sober and venerable, but withal rough and horrid.”—“ Quoties oculosad nostri temporis munditiaset elegantiam refero, antiquitas ilia sancta et sobiia, sed horrida tamen, et nondum satis expolita fuisse videtur.”—(De Jure Regni apud Scotos.') One would think, that he conceived the taste of his countrymen to have then arrived at the ne plus ultra of national refinement, Aurea nunc, olim sylvestribus horrida dumis. 32 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. CHAPTER II. FROM THE PUBLICATION OF BACON’S PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS, TILL THAT OF THE ESSAY ON HUMAN UNDERSTANDING- SECTION I. Progress of Philosophy in England during this period. BACON.1 The state of science towards the close of the sixteenth century, presented a field of observa¬ tion singularly calculated to attract the curio¬ sity, and to awaken the genius of Bacon; nor was it the least of his personal advantages, that, as the son of one of Queen Elizabeth’s ministers, he had a ready access, wherever he went, to the most enlightened society in Europe. While yet only in the seventeenth year of his age, he was removed by his father from Cambridge to Paris, where it is not to be doubted, that the novelty of the literary scene must have largely contri¬ buted to cherish the natural liberality and inde¬ pendence of his mind. Sir Joshua Reynolds has remarked, in one of his academical Dis¬ courses, that “ every seminary of learning is surrounded with an atmosphere of floating knowledge, where every mind may imbibe some¬ what congenial to its own original concep¬ tions.” * He might have added, with still great¬ er truth, that it is an atmosphere, of which it is more peculiarly salutary for those who have been elsewhere reared to breathe the air. The remark is applicable to higher pursuits than were in the contemplation of this philosophical artist; and it suggests a hint of no inconsider¬ able value for the education of youth. The merits of Bacon, as the father of Experi¬ mental Philosophy, are so universally acknow¬ ledged, that it would be superfluous to touch upon them here. The lights which he has struck out m various branches of the Philosophy of Mind, have been much less attended to; al¬ though the whole scope and tenor of his specu¬ lations show, that to this study his genius was far more strongly and happily turned, than to that of the Material World. It was not, as some seem to have imagined, by sagacious anticipa¬ tions of particular discoveries afterwards to be made in physics, that his writings have had so powerful an influence in accelerating the ad¬ vancement of that science. In the extent and accuracy of his physical knowledge, he was far inferior to many of his predecessors; but he surpassed them all in his knowledge of the laws, the resources, and the limits of the human un¬ derstanding. The sanguine expectations with which he looked forwards to the future, were founded solely on his confidence in the untried capacities of the mind, and on a conviction of the possibility of invigorating and guiding, by means of logical rules, those faculties which, in all our researches after truth, are the organs or instruments to be employed. “ Such rules,” as he himself has observed, ,g 'prans- conceive on what grounds Burnet proceeded, in hazarding so extraordinary an opinion—See p It is still more difficult, on the other hand, to account for the following very bold decision of Mr Hume.^1 it from an essay first published in 1742 ; but the same passage is to be found in the last edit Locke and bv himself. “ The first polite prose we iiave, was writ by a man (Dr Swift) who is still aliv . -r JL.i ’ Harrington even Temple, they knew too little of the rules of art to be esteemed elegant writers. The prose , g ’ and Milton, is altogether stiff and pedantic, though their sense be excellent.” tnpvhmistible How insignificant are the petty grammatical improvements proposed by Swift, whe11 ^ aUh the hi her qua_ riches imparted to the English tongue by the writers of the seventeenth century; and how inter , Addison ' lities and graces of style, are his prose compositions, to those of his immediate predecessors, Dryden, p , 2 Born 1588, died 1679. 3 Divine Legation, Pref. to Vol. II. p. 9. 4 See Note G. DISSERTATION FIRST. 41 decidedly hostile to all the forms of popular go¬ vernment ; and it is said to have been with the design of impressing his countrymen with a just sense of the disorders incident to democratical establishments, that he published, in 1618, an English translation of Thucydides. In these opinions he was more and more confirmed by the events he afterwards witnessed in England; the fatal consequences of which he early foresaw with so much alarm, that, in 1640, he withdrew from the approaching storm, to enjoy the so¬ ciety of his philosophical friends at Paris. It was there he wrote his book De Give, a few copies of which were printed, and privately circulated in 1642. The same work was after¬ wards given to the public, with material cor¬ rections and improvements, in 1647, when the author’s attachment to the royal cause being strengthened by his personal connection with the exiled king, he thought it incumbent on him to stand forth avowedly as an advocate for those principles which he had long professed. The great object of this performance was to strength¬ en the hands of sovereigns against the rising spirit of democracy, by arming them with the weapons of a new philosophy. The fundamental doctrines inculcated in the political works of Hobbes are contained in the following propositions. I recapitulate them here, not on their own account, but to prepare the way for some remarks which I mean after¬ wards to offer on the coincidence between the principles of Hobbes and those of Locke. In their practical conclusions, indeed, with re¬ spect to the rights and duties of citizens, the two writers differ widely; but it is curious to observe how very nearly they set out from the same hypothetical assumptions. All men are by nature equal; and, prior to government, they had all an equal right to en¬ joy the good things of this world. Man, too, is (according to Hobbes) by nature a solitary and purely selfish animal; the social union being en¬ tirely an interested league, suggested by pruden¬ tial views of personal advantage. The necessary consequence is, that a state of nature must be a state of perpetual warfare, in which no indivi¬ dual has any other means of safety than his own strength or ingenuity ; and in which there is no room for regular industry, because no secure en¬ joyment of its fruits. In confirmation of this view of the origin of society, Hobbes appeals to facts falling daily within the circle of our own experience. “ Does not a man (he asks), when taking a journey, arm himself, and seek to go well accompanied ? When going to sleep, does he not lock his doors ? Nay, even in his own house, does he not lock his chests ? Does he not there as much accuse mankind by his actions, as I do by my words ?”1 An additional argu¬ ment to the same purpose may, according to some later Hobhists, be derived from the in¬ stinctive aversion of infants for strangers; and from the apprehension which, it is alleged, every person feels, when he hears the tread of an unknown foot in the dark. For the sake of peace and security, it is ne¬ cessary that each individual should surrender a part of his natural right, and be contented with such a share of liberty as he is willing to allow to others; or, to use Hobbes’s own language, “ every man must divest himself of the right he has to all things by nature ; the right of all men to all things being in effect no better than if no man had a right to any thing.”2 In conse¬ quence of this transference of natural rights to an individual, or to a body of individuals, the multitude become one person, under the name of a State or Republic, by which person the common will and power are exercised for the common defence. The ruling power cannot be withdrawn from those to whom it has been com¬ mitted ; nor can they be punished for misgovern- ment. The interpretation of the laws is to be sought, not from the comments of philosophers, hut from the authority of the ruler ; otherwise society would eA^ery moment be in danger of re¬ solving itself into the discordant elements of which it was at first composed. The will of the magistrate, therefore, is to be regarded as theulti- 1 Of Man, Part I. chap. xiii. 2 De Corpore Politico, Part I chap. i. § 10. DISS. 1. PART I. 42 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. mate standard of right and wrong, and his voice to be listened to by every citizen as the voice of conscience. Not many years afterwards,1 Hobbes pushed the argument for the absolute power of princes still farther, in a work to which he gave the name of Leviathan. Under this appellation he means the body politic ; insinuating that man is an untameable beast of prey, and that govern¬ ment is the strong chain by which he is kept from mischief. The fundamental principles here maintained are the same as in the hook De Give; but as it inveighs more particularly against ec¬ clesiastical tyranny, with the view of subjecting die consciences of men to the civil authority, it lost the author the favour of some powerful pro¬ tectors he had hitherto enjoyed among the Eng¬ lish divines who attended Charles II. in France ; and he even found it convenient to quit that kingdom, and to return to England, where Crom¬ well (to whose government his political tenets were now as favourable as they were meant to be to the royal claims) suffered him to remain un¬ molested. The same circumstances operated to his disadvantage after the Restoration, and obliged the King, who always retained for him a very strong attachment, to confer his marks of favour on him with the utmost reserve and circumspection.2 The details which I have entered into, with respect to the history of Hobbes’s political writ¬ ings, will be found, by those who may peruse them, to throw much light on the author’s reason¬ ings. Indeed, it is only by thus considering them in their connection with the circumstances of the times, and the fortunes of the writer, that a just notion can be formed of their spirit and tendency. The ethical principles of Hobbes are so com¬ pletely interwoven with his political system, that all which has been said of the one may be applied to the other. It is very remarkable, that Descartes should have thought so highly of the former, as to pronounce Hobbes to be “ a much greater master of morality than of metaphysics;” a judgment which is of itself sufficient to mark the very low state of ethical science in France about the middle of the seven¬ teenth century. Mr Addison, on the other hand, gives a decided preference (among all the books written by Hobbes) to his Treatise on Hu¬ man Nature ; and to his opinion on this point I most implicitly subscribe ; including, however, in the same commendation, some of his other philosophical essays on similiar topics. They are the only part of his works which it is pos¬ sible now to read with any interest; and they everywhere evince in their author, even when he thinks most unsoundly himself, that power of setting his reader a-thinking, which is one of the most unequivocal marks of original genius. They have plainly been studied with the utmost care both by Locke and Hume. To the former they have suggested some of his most important observations on the Association of Ideas, as well as much of the sophistry displayed in the first book of his Essay, on the Origin of our Know¬ ledge, and on the factitious nature of our moral principles; to the latter (among a variety of hints of less consequence), his theory concern¬ ing the nature of those established connections among physical events, which it is the business of the natural philosopher to ascertain,3 and the substance of his argument against the scho¬ lastic doctrine of general conceptions. It is from the works of Hobbes, too, that our later Neces¬ sitarians have borrowed the most formidable of those weapons with which they have combated the doctrine of moral liberty; and from the same source has been derived the leading idea 1 In 1651. 2 See Note H. 3 The same doctrine, concerning the proper object of natural philosophy (commonly ascribed to Mr Hume, both by his followers and by his opponents), is to be found in various writers contemporary with Hobbes. It is stated, with uncom¬ mon precision and clearness, in a book entitled Scepsis Scientifica, or Confessed Ignorance the way to Science, by Joseph Glanvill, (printed in 1665). The whole work is strongly marked with the features of an acute, an original, and, in matters of science, a somewhat sceptical genius; and, when compared with the treatise on witchcraft, by the same author, adds another proof to those already mentioned, of the possible union of the highest intellectual gifts with the most degrading intellectual weaknesses. With respect to the Scepsis Scientifica, it deserves to be noticed, that the doctrine maintained in it concerning physical causes and effects does not occur in the form of a detached observation, of the value of which the author might not have been fully aware, but is the very basis of the general argument running through all his discussions. DISSERTATION FIRST. 43 which runs through the philological materialism of Mr Horne Tooke. It is probable, indeed, that this last author borrowed it, at second¬ hand, from a hint in Locke’s Essay; but it is repeatedly stated by Hobbes, in the most ex¬ plicit and confident terms. Of this idea (than which, in point of fact, nothing can be imagin¬ ed more puerile and unsound), Mr Tooke’s etymologies, when he applies them to the solu¬ tion of metaphysical questions, are little more than an ingenious expansion, adapted and level¬ led to the comprehension of the multitude. The speculations of Hobbes, however, con¬ cerning the theory of the understanding, do not seem to have been nearly so much attended to during his own life, as some of his other doc¬ trines, which, having a more immediate refer¬ ence to human affairs, were better adapted to the unsettled and revolutionary spirit of the times. It is by these doctrines, chiefly, that his name has since become so memorable in the an¬ nals of modern literature; and although they now derive their whole interest from the extra¬ ordinary combination they exhibit of acuteness and subtlety with a dead-palsy in the powers of taste and of moral sensibility, yet they will be found, on an attentive examination, to have had a far more extensive influence on the subsequent history, both of political and of ethical science, than any other publication of the same period. ANTAGONISTS OF HOBBES. Cudworth1 was one of the first who success¬ fully combated this new philosophy. As Hobbes, in the frenzy of his political zeal, had been led to sacrifice wantonly all the principles of re¬ ligion and morality to the establishment of his conclusions, his works not only gaATe offence to the friends of liberty, but excited a general alarm among all sound moralists. His doctrine, in particular, that there is no natural distinction between Right and Wrong, and that these are dependent on the arbitrary will of the civil ma¬ gistrate, was so obviously subversive of all the commonly received ideas concerning the moral constitution of human nature, that it became in¬ dispensably necessary, either to expose the so¬ phistry of the attempt, or to admit, with Hobbes, that man is a beast of prey, incapable of being governed by any motives but fear, and the de¬ sire of self-preservation. Between some of these tenets of the courtly Hohbists, and those inculcated by the Cromwel¬ lian Antinomians, there was a very extraor¬ dinary and unfortunate coincidence; the latter insisting, that, in expectation of Christ’s second coming, “ the obligations of morality and natural law were suspended; and that the elect, guided by an internal principle, more perfect and divine, were superior to the beggarly elements of justice and humanity.”3 It was the object of Cudworth to vindicate, against the assaults of both parties, the immutability of moral distinctions. In the prosecution of his very able argument on this subject, Cudworth displays a rich store of enlightened and choice erudition, penetrated throughout with a peculiar vein of sobered and subdued Platonism, from whence some German systems, which have attracted no small notice in our own times, will be found, when stripped of their deep neological disguise, to have bor¬ rowed their most valuable materials.3 ' Born 1617, died 1668. 5 Hume—For a more particular account of the English Antinomians, See Mosheim, Vol. IY. p. 534, et seq. 3 The mind, according to Cudworth, perceives, by occasion of outward objects, as much more than is represented to it by sense, as a learned man does in the best written book, than an illiterate person or brute. “ To the eyes of both, the same characters will appear; but the learned man, in those characters, will see heaven, earth, sun, and stars ; read pro¬ found theorems of philosophy or geometry; learn a great deal of new knowledge from them, and admire the wisdom of the composer; while, to the other, nothing appears but black strokes drawn on white paper. The reason of which is, that the mind of the one is furnished with certain previous inward anticipations, ideas, and instruction, that the other wants.”—“ In the room of this book of human composition, let us now substitute the book of Nature, written all over with the characters and impressions of divine wisdom and goodness, but legible only to an intellectual eye. To the sense both of man and brute, there appears nothing else in it, but, as in the other, so many inky scrawls ; that is, nothing but figures and colours. But the mind, which hath a participation of the divine wisdom that made it, upon occasion of those sensible delineations, exerting its own inward activity, will have not only a wonderful scene, and large prospects of 44 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. Another coincidence between the Hohbists and the Antinomians, may he remarked in their common zeal for the scheme of necessity ; which both of them stated in such a way as to he equally inconsistent with the moral agency of man, and with the moral attributes of God.1 The strongest of all presumptions against this scheme is afforded by the other tenets with which it is almost universally combined; and ac¬ cordingly, it was very shrewdly observed by Cudworth, that the licentious system which flou¬ rished in his time (under which title, I pre¬ sume, he comprehended the immoral tenets of the fanatics as well as of the Hobbists), “ grew up from the doctrine of the fatal necessity of all actions and events, as from its proper root.” The unsettled, and, at the same time, disputa¬ tious period during which Cudworth lived, af¬ forded him peculiarly favourable opportunities of judging from experience, of the practical ten¬ dency of this metaphysical dogma; and the re¬ sult of his observations deserves the serious at¬ tention of those who may be disposed to regard it in the light of a fair and harmless theme for the display of controversial subtility. To argue, in this manner, against a speculative principle from its palpable effects, is not always so illogi¬ cal as some authors have supposed. “ You re¬ peat to me incessantly,” says Rousseau to one of his correspondents, 4 4 that truth can never be injurious to the world. I myself believe so as firmly as you do; and it is for this very reason I am satisfied that your proposition is false.”2 But the principal importance of Cudworth, as an ethical writer, arises from the influence of his argument concerning the immutability of right and wrong on the various theories of mo¬ rals which appeared in the course of the eigh¬ teenth century. To this argument may, more particularly, he traced the origin of the cele¬ brated question, Whether the principle of moral approbation is to be ultimately resolved into Reason, or into Sentiment ?—a question which has furnished the chief ground of difference be¬ tween the Systems of Cudworth and of Clarke, on the one hand; and those of Shaftesbury, Hutcheson, Hume, and Smith, on the other. The remarks which I have to offer on this con¬ troversy must evidently be delayed, till the writ¬ ings of these more modern authors shall fall un¬ der review. The Intellectual System of Cudworth embraces a field much wider than his treatise of Immu¬ table Morality. The latter is particularly direct¬ ed against the ethical doctrines of Hobbes, and of the Antinomians; but the former aspires to tear up by the roots all the principles, both phy¬ sical and metaphysical, of the Epicurean philo¬ sophy. It is a work, certainly, which reflects much honour on the talents of the author, and still more on the boundless extent of his learn¬ ing ; but it is so ill suited to the taste of the present age, that, since the time of Mr Harris and Dr Price, I scarcely recollect the slightest reference to it in the writings of our British me¬ taphysicians. Of its faults (beside the general disposition of the author to discuss questions placed altogether beyond the reach of our facul¬ ties), the most prominent is the wild hypothesis of a plastic nature ; or, in other words, 44 of a vital and spiritual, but unintelligent and neces¬ sary agent, created by the Deity for the execu- other thoughts laid open before it, and variety of knowledge, logical, mathematical, and moral, displayed ; but also clearly read the divine wisdom and goodness in every page of this great volume, as it were written in large and legible characters.” I do not pretend to be an adept in the philosophy of Kant; but I certainly think I pay it a very high compliment, when I suppose, that, in the Critic of Pure Reason, the leading idea is somewhat analogous to what is so much better expressed in the foregoing passage. To Kant it was probably suggested by the following very acute and decisive remark of Leibnitz on Locke’s Essay : “ Nempe, nihil est in intellectu, quod non fuerit in sensu, nisi ipse intellectus.” In justice to Aristotle, it may be here observed, that, although the general strain of his language is strictly conformable to the scholastic maxim just quoted, he does not seem to have altogether overlooked the important exception to it pointed out by Leibnitz. Indeed, this exception or limitation is very nearly a translation of Aristotle’s words. Ka) uLrog Ss Co vs) vatiTOi Itrnv, wrong ra vonra' Ivri fiv yag rwv clviu ro abro hrn voovv, ku) to imoufiivtiv. “ And the mind itself is an object of knowledge, as well as other things which are intelligible. For, in immaterial beings, that which understands is the same with that which is understood.”—(De A?iima, Lib. iii. cap. iv.) I quote this very curious, and, I suspect, very little known sentence, in order to vindicate Aristotle against the misrepresentations of some of his present idolaters, who, in their anxiety to secure to him all the credit of Locke’s doctrine concerning the origin of our ideas, have overlooked the occasional traces which occur in his works, of that higher and sounder philosophy in which he had been educated. 1 “ The doctrines of fate or destiny were deemed by the Independents essential to all religion. In these rigid opinions, the whole sectaries, amidst all their other differences, unanimously concurred.”—Hume’s History, chap. Ivii. 2 “ Vous repdtez sans cesse que la verite ne peut jamais faire de mal aux hommes; je le crois, et e’est pour moi la preuve que ce que vous dites n’est pas la vdritd.” DISSERTATION FIRST. 45 tion of his purposes.” Notwithstanding, how¬ ever, these, and many other abatements of its merits, the Intellectual System will for ever re¬ main a precious mine of information to those whose curiosity may lead them to study the spi¬ rit of the ancient theories; and to it we may justly apply what Leibnitz has somewhere said, with far less reason, of the works of the school¬ men, “ Scholasticos agnosco abundare ineptiis; sed aurum est in illo cano.”1 Before dismissing the doctrines of Hobbes, it may be worth while to remark, that all his lead¬ ing principles are traced by Cudworth to the re¬ mains of the ancient sceptics, by some of whom, as well as by Hobbes, they seem to have been adopted from a wish to flatter the uncontrolled passions of sovereigns. Not that I am disposed to call in question the originality o! Hobbes; for it appears, from the testimony of all his friends, that he had much less pleasure in read¬ ing than in thinking. “ If I had read,” he was accustomed to say, “ as much as some others, I should have been as ignorant as they are.” But similar political circumstances invariably repro¬ duce similar philosophical theories; and it is one of the numerous disadvantages attending an inventive mind, not properly furnished with ac¬ quired information, to be continually liable to a waste of its powers on subjects previously ex¬ hausted. The sudden tide of licentiousness, both in principles and in practice, which burst into this island at the moment of the Restoration, con¬ spired with the paradoxes of Hobbes, and with the no less dangerous errors recently propagated among the people by their religious instructors, to turn the thoughts of sober and speculative men towards ethical disquisitions. The esta¬ blished clergy assumed a higher tone than be¬ fore in their sermons; sometimes employing them in combating that Epicurean and Machia- velian philosophy which was then fashionable at court, and which may be always suspected to form the secret creed of the enemies of civil and religious liberty;—on other occasions, to over¬ whelm, with the united force of argument and learning, the extravagances by which the igno¬ rant enthusiasts of the preceding period had ex¬ posed Christianity itself to the scoffs of their li¬ bertine opponents. Among the divines who ap¬ peared at this era, it is impossible to pass over in silence the name of Barrow, whose theological works (adorned throughout by classical erudition, and by a vigorous, though unpolished eloquence), exhibit, in every page, marks of the same inven¬ tive genius which, in mathematics, has secured to him a rank second alone to that of Newton. As a writer, he is equally distinguished by the re¬ dundancy of his matter, and by the pregnant brevity of his expression; but what more pecu¬ liarly characterises his manner, is a certain air of powerful and of conscious facility in the exe¬ cution of whatever he undertakes. Whether the subject be mathematical, metaphysical, or theological, he seems always to bring to it a mind which feels itself superior to the occasion ; and which, in contending with the greatest dif¬ ficulties, “ puts forth but half its strength.” He has somewhere spoken of his Lectiones Ma~ thematicce (which it may, in passing, be remarked, display metaphysical talents of the highest order), as extemporaneous effusions of his pen; and I have no doubt that the same epithet is still more literally applicable to his pulpit discourses. It is, indeed, only thus we can account for the va¬ riety and extent of his voluminous remains, when we recollect that the author died at the age of forty-six.2 To the extreme rapidity with which Barrow committed his thoughts to writing, I am inclined to ascribe the hasty and not altogether consist- 1 The Intellectual System was published in 1678. The Treatise concerning Eternal and Immutable Morality did not appear till a considerable number of years after the author’s death. _ * In a note annexed to an English translation of the Cardinal Maury’s Principles of Eloquence, it is stated, upon the au¬ thority of a manuscript of Dr Doddridge, that most of Barrow’s sermons were transcribed three times, and some muc i oftener. They seem to me to contain verv strong intrinsic evidence of the incorrectness of this anecdote. Mr ja am Hill, in his Account of the Life of Barrow, addressed to Dr Tillotson, contents himself with saying,_ that “ Some ot his ser¬ mons were written four or five times over;”—mentioning, at the same time, a circumstance which may accoun or is fact, in perfect consistency with what I have stated above,—that Barrow was very ready to lend his sermons as o en desired.” 46 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. ent opinions which he has hazarded on some im¬ portant topics. I shall confine myself to a single example, which I select in preference to others, as it hears directly on the most interesting of all questions connected with the theory of morals. “ If we scan,” says he, “ the particular nature, and search into the original causes of the seve¬ ral kinds of naughty dispositions in our souls, and of miscarriages in our lives, we shall find inordinate self-love to be a main ingredient, and a common source of them all; so that a divine of great name had some reason to affirm,—that original sin (or that innate distemper from which men generally become so very prone to evil, and averse to good), doth consist in self-love, dispo¬ sing us to all kinds of irregularity and excess.” In another passage, the same author expresses himself thus:—“ Reason dictateth and pre- scribeth to us, that we should have a sober re¬ gard to our true good and welfare ; to our best interests and solid content; to that which (all things being rightly stated, considered, and com¬ puted) will, in the final event, prove most bene¬ ficial and satisfactory to us: a self-love working in prosecution of such things, common sense cannot hut allow and approve.” Of these two opposite and irreconcileable opi¬ nions, the latter is incomparably the least wide of the truth; and accordingly Mr Locke, and his innumerable followers, both in England and on the Continent, have maintained, that virtue and an enlightened self-love are one and the same. I shall afterwards find a more conve¬ nient opportunity for stating some objections to the latter doctrine, as well as to the former. I have quoted the two passages here, merely to show the very little attention that had been paid, at the era in question, to ethical science, by one of the most learned and profound divines of his age. This is the more remarkable, as his works everywhere inculcate the purest lessons of practical morality, and evince a singular acuteness and justness of eye in the observation of human character. Whoever compares the views of Barrow, when he touches on the theory of morals, with those opened about fifty years afterwards by Dr Butler, in his Discourses on Human Nature, will be abundantly satisfied, that, in this science, as well as in others, the progress of the philosophical spirit during the intervening period was not inconsiderable. The name of Wilkins (although he too wrote with some reputation against the Epicureans of his day), is now remembered chiefly in conse¬ quence of his treatises concerning a universal lan¬ guage and a real character. Of these treatises, I shall hereafter have occasion to take some notice, under a different article. With all the ingenuity displayed in them, they cannot be considered as accessions of much value to science; and the long period since elapsed, during which no at¬ tempt has been made to turn them to any prac¬ tical use, affords of itself no slight presumption against the solidity of the project. A few years before the death of Hobbes, Dr Cumberland (afterwards Bishop of Peterbo¬ rough) published a book, entitled, De Legibus Natures, Disquisitio Philosophical the principal aim of which was to confirm and illustrate, in opposition to Hobbes, the conclusions of Grotius, concerning Natural Law. The work is executed with ability, and discovers juster views of the object of moral science, than any modern sys¬ tem that had yet appeared; the author resting the strength of his argument, not, as Grotius had done, on an accumulation of authorities, but on the principles of the human frame, and the mutual relations of the human race. The cir¬ cumstance, however, which chiefly entitles this publication to our notice, is, that it seems to have been the earliest on the subject which at¬ tracted, in any considerable degree, the attention of English scholars. From this time, the writings of Grotius and of Puffendorff began to be gene¬ rally studied, and soon after made their way into the Universities. In Scotland, the im¬ pression produced by them was more peculiarly remarkable. They were everywhere adopted as the best manuals of ethical and of political in¬ struction that could be put into the hands of students, and gradually contributed to form that memorable school, from whence so many philo¬ sophers and philosophical historians were after¬ wards to proceed. From the writings of Hobbes to those of Locke, the transition is easy and obvious; but before prosecuting farther the history of philo¬ sophy in England, it will be proper to turn our DISSERTATION FIRST. 47 attention to its progress abroad, since the period at which this section commences.1 2 In the first place, however, I shall add a few miscellaneous remarks on some important events which oc¬ curred in this country during the lifetime of Hobbes, and of which his extraordinary longe¬ vity prevented me sooner from taking notice. Among these events, that which is most im¬ mediately connected with our present subject, is the establishment of the Royal Society of London in 1662, which was followed a few years afterwards by that of the Royal Academy of Sciences at Paris. The professed object of both institutions was the improvement of Experi¬ mental Knowledge, and of the auxiliary science of Mathematics; but their influence on the general progress of human reason has been far greater than could possibly have been foreseen at the moment of their foundation. On the happy effects resulting from them in this re¬ spect, La Place has introduced some just reflec¬ tions in his System of the World, which, as they discover more originality of thought than he com¬ monly displays, when he ventures to step beyond the circumference of his own magic circle, I shall quote, in a literal translation of his words. “ The chief advantage of learned societies, is the philosophical spirit to which they may be ex¬ pected to give birth, and which they cannot fail to diffuse over all the various pursuits of the nations among whom they are established. The insulated scholar may without dread abandon himself to the spirit of system; he hears the voice of contradiction only from afar. But in a learned society, the collision of systematic opinions soon terminates in their common de¬ struction ; while the desire of mutual conviction creates among the members a tacit compact, to admit nothing but the results of observation, or the conclusions of mathematical reasoning. Ac¬ cordingly, experience has shown, how much these establishments have contributed, since their origin, to the spread of true philosophy. By setting the example of submitting every thing to the examination of a severe logic, they have dissipated the prejudices which had too long reigned in the sciences, and which the strongest minds of the preceding centuries had not been able to resist. They have constantly opposed to empiricism a mass of knowledge, against which the errors adopted by the vulgar, with an enthusiasm which, in former times, would have perpetuated their empire, have spent their force in vain. In a word, it has been in their bosoms that those grand theories have been conceived, which, although far exalted by their generality above the reach of the multitude, are for this very reason entitled to special encourage¬ ment, from their innumerable applications to the phenonema of nature, and to the practice of the arts.”® In confirmation of these judicious remarks, it 1 Throughout the whole of this Discourse, I have avoided touching on the discussions which, on various occasions, have arisen with regard to the theory of government, and the comparative advantages or disadvantages of different political forms. Of the scope and spirit of these discussions it would be seldom possible to convey a just idea, without entering into details of a local or temporary nature, inconsistent with my general design. In the present circumstances of the world, besides, the theory of government (although, in one point of view, the most important of all studies) seems to possess a very subordinate interest to inquiries connected with political economy, and with the fundamental principles of legisla¬ tion. What is it, indeed, that renders one form of government more favourable than another to human happiness, but the superior security it provides for the enactment of wise laws, and for their impartial and vigorous execution ? These considerations will sufficiently account for my passing over in silence, not only the names of Needham, of Sidney, and of Milton, but that of Harrington, whose Oceana is justly regarded as one of the boasts of English literature, and is pronounced by Hume to be “ the only valuable model of a commonwealth that has yet been offered to the public.”—Essays and Trea¬ tises, Yol. I. Essay xvi. A remark which Hume has elsewhere made on the Oceana, appears to me so striking and so instructive, that I shall give it a place in this note. “ Harrington,” he observes, “ thought himself so sure of his general principle, that the balance of power depends on that of property, that he ventured to pronounce it impossible ever to re-establish monarchy in England : But his book was scarcely published when the King was restored ; and we see that monarchy has ever since subsisted on the same footing as before. So dangerous is it for a politician to venture to foretell the situation of public affairs a few years hence.”—Ibid. Essay vii. How much nearer the truth, even in the science of politics, is Bacon’s cardinal principle, that knowledge is power !—a principle, which applies to Man not less in his corporate than in his individual capacity ; and which may be safely trusted to as the most solid of all foundations for our reasonings concerning the future history of the world. 2 The Royal Society of London, though not incorporated by charter till 1662, may be considered as virtually existing, at least as far back as 1638, when some of the most eminent of the original members began first to hold regular meetings at Gresham College, for the purpose of philosophical discussion. Even these meetings were but a continuation of those previously held by the same individuals, at the apartments of Dr Wilkins in Oxford.—See Sprat’s History of the Royal Society. 48 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. may be farther observed, that nothing could have been more happily imagined than the esta¬ blishment of learned corporations for correcting those prejudices which (under the significant title of Idola Specus), Bacon has described as in¬ cident to the retired student. While these idols of the den maintain their authority, the cultiva¬ tion of the philosophical spirit is impossible; or rather, it is in a renunciation of this idolatry that the philosophical spirit essentially consists. It was accordingly in this great school of the learned world, that the characters of Bacon, Descartes, Leibnitz, and Locke were formed ; the four individuals who have contributed the most to diffuse the philosophical spirit over Europe. The remark applies more peculiarly to Bacon, who first pointed out the inconveni¬ ences to be apprehended from a minute and mechanical subdivision of literary labour ; and anticipated the advantages to be expected from the institution of learned academies, in enlar¬ ging the field of scientific curiosity, and the cor¬ respondent grasp of the emancipated mind. For accomplishing this object, what means so effec¬ tual as habits of daily intercourse with men whose pursuits are different from our own; and that expanded knowledge, both of man and of nature, of which such an intercourse must ne¬ cessarily be productive ! Another event which operated still more for¬ cibly and universally on the intellectual cha¬ racter of our countrymen, was the civil war which began in 1640, and which ultimately terminated in the usurpation of Cromwell. It is observed by Mr Hume, that “ the prevalence of democratical principles, under the Common¬ wealth, engaged the country gentlemen to bind their sons apprentices to merchants; and that commerce has ever since been more honourable in England, than in any other European king¬ dom.”1 “ The higher and the lower ranks (as a later winter has remarked) were thus brought closer together, and all of them inspired with an activity and vigour that, in former ages, had no example.”2 To this combination of the pursuits of trade, with the advantages of a liberal education, may be ascribed the great multitude of ingenious and enlightened speculations on commerce, and on the other branches of national industry, which issued from the press, in the short interval be¬ tween the Restoration and the Revolution ; an interval during which the sudden and immense extension of the trade of England, and the cor¬ responding rise of the commercial interest, must have presented a spectacle peculiarly calculated to awaken the curiosity of inquisitive observers. It is a very remarkable circumstance with re¬ spect to these economical researches, which now engage so much of the attention both of states¬ men and of philosophers, that they are altogether of modern origin. “ There is scarcely,” says Mr Hume, 11 any ancient writer on politics who has made mention of trade; nor was it ever con¬ sidered as an affair of state till the seventeenth century.”3—The work of the celebrated John de Witt, entitled, “ The true interest and political maxims of the republic of Holland and W est Fries¬ land,” is the earliest publication of any note, in which commerce is treated of as an object of na¬ tional and politicalconcern,in opposition to the par¬ tial interests of corporations and of monopolists. Of the English publications to which I have just alluded, the greater part consists of anony¬ mous pamphlets, now only to be met with in the collections of the curious. A few bear the names of eminent English merchants. I shall have occasion to refer to them more particularly afterwards, when I come to speak of the writings of Smith, Quesnay, and Turgot. At present, I shall only observe, that, in these fugitive and now neglected tracts, are to be found the first rudiments of that science of Political Economy, which is justly considered as the boast of the present age; and which, although the aid of learning and philosophy was necessary to rear it to maturity, may he justly said to have had its cradle in the Royal Exchange of London. Mr Locke was one of the first retired theorists (and this singular feature in his history has not 1 History of England, chap. Ixii. 2 Chalmehs’s Political Estimate, &c. (London, 1804) p. 44. a Essay of Civil Liberty. DISSERTATION FIRST. 49 been sufficiently attended toby his biographers), who condescended to treat of trade as an object of liberal study. Notwithstanding the manifold errors into which he fell in the course of his reasonings concerning it, it may be fairly ques¬ tioned, if he has anywhere else given greater proofs, either of the vigour or of the originality of his genius. But the name of Locke reminds me, that it is now time to interrupt these nation¬ al details, and to turn our attention to the pro¬ gress of science on the Continent, since the times of Bodinus and of Campanella. SECTION II. Progress of Philosophy in Prance during the Seventeenth Century. MONTAIGNE—CHARRON—LA ROCHEFOUCAULD. At the head of the French writers who con¬ tributed, in the beginning of the seventeenth century, to turn the thoughts of their country¬ men to subjects connected with the Philosophy of Mind, Montaigne may, I apprehend, be justly placed. Properly speaking, he belongs to a period somewhat earlier; but his tone of think¬ ing and of writing classes him much more natu¬ rally with his successors, than with any French author who had appeared before him.1 In assigning to Montaigne so distinguished a rank in the history of modern philosophy, I need scarcely say, that I leave entirely out of the ac¬ count what constitutes (and justly constitutes) to the generality of readers the principal charm of his Essays; the good nature, humanity, and unaffected sensibility, which so irresistibly attach us to his character,—lending, it must be owned, but too often a fascination to his talk, when he cannot be recommended as the safest of com¬ panions. Nor do I lay much stress on the in¬ viting frankness and vivacity with which he un¬ bosoms himself about all his domestic habits and concerns^ and which render his book so ex¬ pressive a portrait, not only of the author, but of the Gascon country gentleman, two hundred years ago. I have in view chiefly the minute¬ ness and good faith of his details concerning his own personal qualities, both intellectual and mo¬ ral. The only study which seems ever to have engaged his attention was that of man ; and for this he was singularly fitted, by a rare com¬ bination of that talent for observation which be¬ longs to men of the world, with those habits of abstracted reflection, which men of the world have commonly so little disposition to cultivate. “ I study myself,” says he, “ more than any other subject. This is my metaphysic; this my natural philosophy.” 2 He has accordingly pro¬ duced a work, unique in its kind; valuable, in an eminent degree, as an authentic record of many interesting facts relative to human nature; but more valuable by far, as holding up a mirror in which every individual, if he does not see his own image, will at least occasionally perceive so many traits of resemblance to it, as can scarce¬ ly fail to invite his curiosity to a more careful review of himself. In this respect, Montaigne’s writings may be regarded in the light of what painters call studies; in other words, of those slight sketches which were originally designed for the improvement or amusement of the artist, but which, on that account, are the more likely to be useful in developing the germs of similar endowments in others. Withouta union of these two powers (reflection ' Montaigne was born in 1533, and died in 1592. DISS. I. PART I. 2 Essays, Book iii. chap. xiii. Cr 50 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. and observation), the study of Man can never be successfully prosecuted. It is only by re¬ tiring within ourselves that we can obtain a key to the characters of others; and it is only by observing and comparing the characters of others that we can thoroughly understand and appre¬ ciate our own. After all, however, it maybe fairly questioned, notwithstanding the scrupulous fidelity with which Montaigne has endeavoured to delineate his own portrait, if he has been always sufficient¬ ly aware of the secret folds and reduplications of the human heart. That he was by no means exempted from the common delusions of self-love and self-deceit, has been fully evinced in a very acute, though somewhat uncharitable, section of the Port-Royal logic; but this consideration, so far from diminishing the value of his Essays, is one of the most instructive lessons they afford to those who, after the example of the author, may undertake the salutary but humiliating task of self-examination. As Montaigne’s scientific knowledge was, ac¬ cording to his own account, <£ very vague and imperfect,”1 and his book-learning rather sen¬ tentious and gossiping, than comprehensive and systematical, it would be unreasonable to expect, in his philosophical arguments, much either of depth or of solidity.2 The sentiments he hazards are to be regarded but as the impressions of the moment; consisting chiefly of the more obvious doubts and difficulties which, on all metaphysical and moral questions, are apt to present them¬ selves to a speculative mind, when it first at¬ tempts to dig below the surface of common opinions. In reading Montaigne, accordingly, what chiefly strikes us, is not the novelty or the refinement of his ideas, but the liveliness and felicity with which we see embodied in words the previous wanderings of our own imaginations. It is probably owing to this circumstance, rather than to any direct plagiarism, that his Essays appear to contain the germs of so many of the paradoxical theories which, in later times, Hel- vetius and others have laboured to systematise and to support with the parade of metaphysical discussion. In the mind of Montaigne, the same paradoxes may be easily traced to those deceitful appearances which, in order to stimulate our faculties to their best exertions, nature seems purposely to have thrown in our way, as stum¬ bling-blocks in the pursuit of truth; and it is only to be regretted on such occasions, for the sake of his own happiness, that his genius and temper qualified and disposed him more to start the problem than to investigate the solution. When Montaigne touches on religion, he is, in general, less pleasing than on other subjects. His constitutional temper, it is probable, pre¬ disposed him to scepticism; but this original bias could not fail to be mightily strengthened by the disputes, both religious and political, which, during his lifetime, convulsed Europe, and more particularly his own country. On a mind like his it may be safely presumed, that the writings of the Reformers, and the instruc¬ tions of Buchanan, were not altogether without effect; and hence, in all probability, the per¬ petual struggle, which he is at no pains to con¬ ceal, between the creed of his infancy, and the lights of his mature understanding. He speaks, indeed, of ££ reposing tranquilly on the pillow of doubtbut this language is neither reconcileable with the general complexion of his works, nor with the most authentic accounts we have re¬ ceived of his dying moments. It is a maxim of his own, that, ££ in forming a judgment of a man’s life, particular regard should be paid to his behaviour at the end of itto which he pathetically adds, ££ that the chief study of his own life was, that his latter end might be de¬ cent, calm, and silent.” The fact is (if we may credit the testimony of his biographers), that, in his declining years, he exchanged his boast¬ ed pillow of doubt for the more powerful opiates prescribed by the infallible church; and that he 1 Book i. chap. xxv. 2 Montaigne s education, however, had not been neglected by his father. On the contrary, he tells us himself, that George Buchanan, the great poet of Scotland, and Marcus Antonius Muretus, the best orator of his time, were among the number of his domestic preceptors.”—“ Buchanan,” he adds, “ when I saw him afterwards in the retinue of the late Mareschal de Brissac, told me, that he was about to write a treatise on the education of children, and that he would take the model of it from mine.”—Book i. chap. xxv. DISSERTATION FIRST. 51 expired in performing what his old preceptor Buchanan would not have scrupled to describe as an act of idolatry.1 2 The scepticism of Montaigne seems to have been of a very peculiar cast, and to have had little in common with that either of Bayle or of Hume. The great aim of the two latter writers evidently was, by exposing the uncertainty of our reasonings whenever we pass the limit of sensible objects, to inspire their readers with a complete distrust of the human faculties on all moral and metaphysical topics. Montaigne, on the other hand, never thinks of forming a sect; hut, yielding passively to the current of his re¬ flections and feelings, argues, at different times, according to the varying state of his impressions and temper, on opposite sides of the same ques¬ tion. On all occasions, he preserves an air of the most perfect sincerity; and it was to this, I presume, much more than to the superiority of his reasoning powers, that Montesquieu al¬ luded, when he said, “ In the greater part of authors I see the writer; in Montaigne I see nothing hut the thinker.” The radical fault of his understanding consisted in an incapacity of forming, on disputable points, those decided and fixed opinions which can alone impart either force or consistency to intellectual character. For remedying this weakness, the religious con¬ troversies, and the civil wars recently engender¬ ed by the Reformation, were but ill calculated. The minds of the most serious men, all over Christendom, must have been then unsettled in an extraordinary degree; and where any pre¬ disposition to scepticism existed, every external circumstance must have conspired to cherish and confirm it. Of the extent to which it was car¬ ried, about the same period, in England, some judgment may be formed from the following de¬ scription of a Sceptic by a winter not many years posterior to Montaigne. “ A sceptic in religion is one that hangs in the balance with all sorts of opinions; whereof not one but stirs him, and none sways him. A man guiltier of credulity than he is taken to be; for it is out of his belief of every thing that he believes nothing. Each religion scares him from its contrary, none persuades him to itself. He would be wholly a Christian, but that he is something of an Atheist; and wholly an Atheist, but that he is partly a Christian; and a perfect Heretic, but that there are so many to distract him. He finds reason in all opinions, truth in none; indeed, the least reason perplexes him, and the best will not satisfy him. He finds doubts and scruples better than resolves them, and is ahvays too hard for himself”2 If this portrait had been presented to Montaigne, I have little doubt that he would have had the candour to acknowledge, that he recognised in it some of the most prominent and characteristical fea¬ tures of his own mind.3 The most elaborate, and seemingly the most serious, of all Montaigne’s essays, is his long and somewhat tedious Apology for Haimond de Sebonde, contained in the twelfth chapter of his second book. This author appears, from Mon¬ taigne’s account, to have been a Spaniard, who professed physic at Thoulouse, towards the end of the fourteentli century; and who published a treatise, entitled, Theologia Naturalis, which was put into the hands of Montaigne’s father by a friend, as a useful antidote against the inno¬ vations with which Luther was then beginning to disturb the ancient faith. That, in this parti¬ cular instance, the book answered the intended purpose, may be presumed from the request of old Montaigne to his son, a few days before his 1 “ Sentant sa fin approcher, il fit dire la messe dans sa chambre. A 1’eldvation de I’hostie, il se leva sur son lit pour I’adorer; mais une foiblesse 1’enleva dans ce moment meme, le 15 Septembre 1592, a GO ans.”—Nouveau Diet. Histor. a. Lyon, 1804, Art. Montaigne. 2 Micro-cosmography, or a Piece of the World Discovered, in Essays and Characters. For a short notice of the author of this very curious book (Bishop Earle), See the edition published at London in 1811. The chapter containing the above passage is entitled, A Sceptic in Religion ; and it has plainly suggested to Lord Clarendon some of the ideas, and even expressions, which occur in his account of Chillingworth. 3 “ The writings of the best authors among the ancients,” Montaigne tells us on one occasion, “ being full and solid, tempt and carry me which way almost they will. He that I am reading seems always to have the most force; and I find that every one in turn has reason, though they contradict one another.”—Book ii. chap. xii. 52 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. death, to translate it into French from the Spa¬ nish original. His request was accordingly- complied with; and the translation is referred to hy Montaigne in the first edition of his Essays, printed at Bourdeaux in 1580; hut the execu¬ tion of this filial duty seems to have produced on Montaigne’s own mind very different effects from what his father had anticipated.1 The principal aim of Sehonde’s hook, accord¬ ing to Montaigne, is to show that “ Christians are in the wrong to make human reasoning the basis of their belief, since the object of it is only conceived hy faith, and by a special inspiration of the divine grace.” To this doctrine Mon¬ taigne professes to yield an implicit assent; and, under the shelter of it, contrives to give free vent to all the extravagances of scepticism. The essential distinction between the reason of man, and the instincts of the lower animals, is at great length, and with no inconsiderable inge¬ nuity, disputed; the powers of the human un¬ derstanding, in all inquiries, whether physical or moral, are held up to ridicule; an universal Pyrrhonism is recommended; and we are again and again reminded, that “ the senses are the be¬ ginning and the end of all our knowledge” Who¬ ever has the patience to peruse this chapter with attention, will be surprised to find in it the ru¬ diments of a great part of the licentious philo¬ sophy of the eighteenth century; nor can he fail to remark the address with which the author avails himself of the language afterwards adopt¬ ed by Bayle, Helvetius, and Hume :—“ That, to be a philosophical sceptic, is the first step to¬ wards becoming a sound believing Christian.”3 It is a melancholy fact in ecclesiastical history, that this insidious maxim should have been sanctioned, in our times, hy some theologians of no common pretensions to orthodoxy; who, in direct contradiction to the words of Scripture, have ventured to assert, that “ he who comes to God must first believe that he is not.” Is it necessary to remind these grave retailers of Bayle’s sly and ironical sophistry, that every argument for Christianity, drawn from its in¬ ternal evidence, tacitly recognises the authority of human reason; and assumes, as the ultimate criteria of truth and of falsehood, of right and of wrong, certain fundamental articles of belief, discoverable hy the light of Nature ?5 Charron is well known as the chosen friend of Montaigne’s latter years, and as the confi¬ dential depositary of his philosophical senti¬ ments. Endowed with talents far inferior in force and originality to those of his master, he possessed, nevertheless, a much sounder and more regulated judgment; and as his reputation, notwithstanding the liberality of some of his peculiar tenets, was high among the most re¬ spectable and conscientious divines of his own church, it is far from improbable, that Mon¬ taigne committed to him the guardianship of his posthumous fame, from motives similar to those which influenced Pope, in selecting Warburton as his literary executor. The discharge of this trust, however, seems to have done less good to Montaigne than harm to Charron; for while the unlimited scepticism, and the indecent levities The very few particulars known with respect to Sebonde have been collected by Bayle.—See his Dictionary, Art. Sebonde. * This expression is Mr Hume’s ; but the same proposition, in substance, is frequently repeated by the two other writers, and is very fully enlarged upon by Bayle in the Illustration upon the Sceptics, annexed to his Dictionary. * “ I once asked Adrian Turnelus," says Montaigne, “ what he thought of Sebonde’s treatise. The answer he made to me was, That he believed it to be some extract from Thomas Aquinas, for that none but a genius like his was capable of such ideas.” I must not, however, omit to mention, that a very learned Protestant, Hugo Grotius, has expressed himself to his friend Bignon not unfavourably of Sebonde’s intentions, although the terms in which he speaks of him are somewhat equivocal, and imply but little satisfaction with the execution of his design. “ Non ignoras quantum excoluerint istam materiam (argumentum soil, pro Religione Christiana) philosophica sultilitate Raimundus Sebundus, dialogorum varietate Ludovicus Vives, maxima autem turn eruditione turn facundia vestras Philippus Mornaeus.” The authors of the Nouveau Dictionnaire Historique (Lyons, 1804) have entered much more completely into the spirit and drift of Sebonde’s reasoning, when they observe, “ Ce livre offre des singularites hardies, qui plurent dans le temps aux philosophes de ce siecle, et qui ne deplairoicnt pas a ceux du noire." It is proper to add, that I am acquainted with Sebonde only through the medium of Montaigne’s version, which does not lay claim to the merit of strict fidelity; the translator himself having acknowledged, that he had given to the Spanish phi¬ losopher tk un accoutrement k la Franchise, et qu’il 1’a devetu de son port farouche et maintien barbaresque, de maniere qu’il a mes-hui assez de facjon pour se presenter en toute bonne compagnie.” DISSERTATION FIRST. 53 of the former, were viewed by the zealots of those days with a smile of tenderness and indul¬ gence, the slighter heresies of the latter were marked with a severity the more rigorous and unrelenting, that, in points of essential import¬ ance, they deviated so very little from the stand¬ ard of the Catholic faith. It is not easy to guess the motives of this inconsistency; but such we find from the fact to have been the temper of religious bigotry, or, to speak more correctly, of political religionism in all ages of the world.1 As an example of Charron’s solicitude to pro¬ vide an antidote against the more pernicious er¬ rors of his friend, I shall only mention his inge¬ nious and philosophical attempt to reconcile, with the moral constitution of human nature, the apparent discordancy in the judgments of different nations concerning right and wrong. His argument on this point is in substance the very same with that so well urged by Beattie, in opposition to Locke’s reasonings against the existence of innate practical principles. It is difficult to say, whether, in this instance, the coincidence between Montaigne and Locke, or that between Charron and Beattie, be the more remarkable.2 3 Although Charron has affected to give to his work a systematical form, by dividing and sub¬ dividing it into books and chapters, it is in re¬ ality little more than an unconnected series of essays on various topics, more or less distantly related to the science of Ethics. On the powers of the understanding he has touched but slight¬ ly ; nor has he imitated Montaigne, in anato¬ mizing, for the edification of the world, the pe¬ culiarities of his own moral character. It has probably been owing to the desultory and po¬ pular style of composition common to both, that so little attention has been paid to either by those who have treated of the history of French philosophy. To Montaigne’s merits, indeed, as a lively and amusing essayist, ample justice has been done; but his influence on the subsequent habits of thinking among his countrymen re¬ mains still to be illustrated. He has done more, perhaps, than any other author (I am inclined to think with the most honest intentions), to in¬ troduce into men's houses (if I may borrow an expression of Cicero) what is now called the new philosophy,—a philosophy certainly very different from that of Socrates. In the fashion¬ able world, he has, for more than two centuries, maintained his place as the first of moralists; a circumstance easily accounted for, when we at¬ tend to the singular combination, exhibited in his writings, of a semblance of erudition, with what Malebranche happily calls his air du monde, and air cavalier.'5 As for the graver and less attractive Charron, his name would pro¬ bably before now have sunk into oblivion, had it not been so closely associated, by the acci¬ dental events of his life, with the more cele¬ brated name of Montaigne.4 1 Montaigne, cet auteur charmant, Tour-a-tour profond et frivole, Dans son chateau paisiblement, Loin de tout frondeur malevole, Doutoit de tout impunement, Et se moquoit tres librement Des bavards fourrds de 1’e'cole. Mais quand son eleve Charron, Plus retenu, plus mdthodique, De sagesse donna le^on, II fut pres de perir, dit-on, Par la haine theologique. Voltaire, Epitre au President Hinault. . * See Beattie’s Essay on Fable and Romance ; and Charron de la Sagesse, Liv. ii. c. 8. It may amuse the curious reader also to compare the theoretical reasonings of Charron with a memoir in'the Phil. Trans, for 1773, by Sir Roger Curtis, containing some particulars with respect to the country of Labrador. 3 “ Ah I’aimable homme, qu'il est de bonne compagnie ! C’est mon ancien ami; mais, h force d’etre ancien, il m’est nou¬ veau.”—Madame de SEVI&^^E,. * Montaigne himself seems, from the general strain of his writings, to have had but little expectation of the posthumous fame which he has so long continued to enjoy. One of his reflections on this head is so characteristical of the author as a man, and, at the same time, affords so fine a specimen of the graphical powers of his now antiquated style, that I am tempted to transcribe it in his own words : “ J’ecris mon livre k peu d’hommes et a peu d’anne'es ; s’il q’eut ete une matiere de duree, il 1’eut fallu commettre k un langage plus ferme. Selon la variation continuelle qui a suivi le notre jusqu’k cette 54 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. The preceding remarks lead me, by a natural connection of ideas (to which I am here much more inclined to attend than to the order of dates), to another writer of the seventeenth cen¬ tury, whose influence over the literary and phi¬ losophical taste of France has been far greater than seems to be commonly imagined. I allude to the Duke of La Rochefoucauld, author of the Maxims and Moral Reflections. Voltaire was, I believe, the first who ventur¬ ed to assign to La Rochefoucauld the pre-emi¬ nent rank which belongs to him among the French classics. u One of the works,” says he, “ which contributed most to form the taste of the nation to a justness and precision of thought and ex¬ pression, was the small collection of maxims by Francis Duke of La Rochefoucauld. Although there he little more than one idea in the hook, that self-love is the spring of all our actions, yet this idea is presented in so great a variety of forms, as to he always amusing. When it first appeared, it was read with avidity; and it con¬ tributed, more than any other performance, since the revival of letters, to improve the vivacity, correctness, and delicacy of French composition.” Another very eminent judge of literary merit (the late Dr Johnson) was accustomed to say of La Rochefoucauld’s Maxims, that it was al¬ most the only hook written by a man of fashion, of which professed authors had reason to he jea¬ lous. Nor is this wonderful, when we consider the unwearied industry of the very accomplish¬ ed writer, in giving to every part of it the high¬ est and most finished polish which his exquisite taste could bestow. When he had committed a maxim to paper, he was in use to circulate it among his friends, that he might avail himself of their critical animadversions; and, if we may credit Segrais, altered some of them no less than thirty times, before venturing to submit them to the public eye. That the tendency of these maxims is, upon the whole, unfavourable to morality, and that they always leave a disagreeable impression on the mind, must, I think, he granted. At the same time, it may he fairly questioned, if the motives of the author have in general been well understood, either by his admirers or his oppo¬ nents. In affirming that self-love is the spring of all our actions, there is no good reason for supposing that he meant to deny the reality of moral distinctions as a philosophical truth;—a supposition quite inconsistent with his own fine and deep remark, that hypocrisy is itself an ho¬ mage which vice renders to virtue. He states it merely as a position which, in the course of his experience as a man of the world, he had found very generally verified in the higher classes of society, and which he was induced to announce without any qualification or restriction, in order to give more force and poignancy to his satire In adopting this mode of writing, he has un¬ consciously conformed himself, like many other French authors, who have since followed his example, to a suggestion which Aristotle has stated with admirable depth and acuteness in his Rhetoric. “ Sentences or apophthegms lend much aid to eloquence. One reason of this is, that they flatter the pride of the hearers, who are delighted when the speaker, making use of general language, touches upon opinions which they had before known to be true in part. Thus, a person who had the misfortune to live in a bad neighbourhood, or to have worthless children, would easily assent to the speaker who should affirm, that nothing is more vexatious than to have any neighbours; nothing more irrational than to bring children into the world.”1 This observation of Aristotle, while it goes far to ac¬ count for the imposing and dazzling effect of these rhetorical exaggerations, ought to guard us against the common and popular error of mis- heure, qux peut esperer que sa forme presente soit en usage d’ici a cinquante ans ? il ecoule tous les jours de nos mains, et depuis que je vis s est altere de moitie. Nous disons qu’il est a cette heure parfait: Autant en dit du sien chaque siecle. C est anx oons et utiles ecrits de le clouer a eux, et ira sa fortune selon le credit de notre etat." How completely have both the predictions in the last sentence been verified by the subsequent history of the French language! , h (’yvupiai) ray; Xayay; fiorjuav fttya.Xnr, ftixy fuy om r»jv Qo^nKornra, rus ux^ouruv' %ulgt>vffi yaj, lav r/; Jta.Ho'kov Xiyuv, Tf“ txetni Ttctra, tfcoviri. H fitv yap yvcofAV, llgnrui, xudoXov hrn' pstii^ovtri at xctHoXou Xtyofiivov, a satr* ^a; ^ayaraXa^aavavrs; rvy^ovre cloh u r,s yi/rar; ry^fi aas^Wva; »j rl*va/; (puvXon, urohfar a* rev uVavra;, aySiv yurcyia, ■^uXitan^o))' ?), on ovoiv wXitJiangov riuvovoiu;.—Arist. Rhet. Lib. il. c. xxi. The whole chapter is interesting and instructive, and shows how profoundly Aristotle had meditated the principles of the rhetorical art. 1 1 DISSERTATION FIRST. 55 taking them for the serious and profound genera¬ lisations of science. As for La Rochefoucauld, we know, from the best authorities, that, in pri¬ vate life, he was a conspicuous example of all those moral qualities of which he seemed to deny the existence; and that he exhibited, in this respect, a striking contrast to the Cardinal de Retz, who has presumed to censure him for his want of faith in the reality of virtue. In reading La Rochefoucauld, it should ne¬ ver be forgotten, that it was within the vortex of a court he enjoyed his chief opportunities of studying the world; and that the narrow and exclusive circle in which he moved was not likely to afford him the most favourable speci¬ mens of human nature in general. Of the Court of Lewis XIV. in particular, we are told by a very nice and reflecting observer (Madame de la Fayette), that C£ ambition and gallantry were the soul, actuating alike both men and wo¬ men. So many contending interests, so many different cabals were constantly at work, and in all of these, women bore so important a part, that love was always mingled with business, and business with love. Nobody was tranquil or in¬ different. Every one studied to advance him¬ self by pleasing, serving, or ruining others. Idle¬ ness and languor were unknown, and nothing was thought of but intrigues or pleasures.” In the passage already quoted from Voltaire, he takes notice of the effect of La Rochefou¬ cauld’s Maxims, in improving the style of French composition. We may add to this remark, that their effect has not been less sensible in vitiating the tone and character of French philosophy, by bringing into vogue those false and degrading representations of human nature and of human life, which have prevailed in that country, more or less, for a century past. Mr Addison, in one of the papers of the Taller, expresses his in¬ dignation at this general bias among the French writers of his age. “ It is impossible,” he ob¬ serves, “ to read a passage in Plato or Tully, and a thousand other ancient moralists, without being a greater and better man for it. On the contrary, I could never read any of our modish French authors, or those of our own country, who are the imitators and admirers of that nation, without being, for some time, out of humour with myself, and at everything about me. Their business is to depreciate human nature, and to consider it under the worst appearances; they give mean interpretations and base motives to the worthiest actions. In short, they endeavour to make no distinction between man and man, or between the species of man and that of the brutes.”1 It is very remarkable, that the censure here bestowed by Addison on the fashionable French wits of his time should be so strictly applicable to Helvetius, and to many others of the most admired authors whom France has produced in our own day. It is still more remarkable to find the same depressing spirit shedding its malig¬ nant influence on French literature, as early as the time of La Rochefoucauld, and even of Mon¬ taigne ; and to observe how very little has been done by the successors of these old writers, but to expand into grave philosophical systems their loose and lively paradoxes; disguising and for¬ tifying them by the aid of those logical princi¬ ples, to which the name and authority of Locke have given so wide a circulation in Europe. In tracing the origin of that false philosophy on which the excesses of the French revolu¬ tionists have entailed such merited disgrace, it is usual to remount no higher than to the profli¬ gate period of the Regency; but the seeds of its most exceptionable doctrines had been sown in that country at an earlier era, and were indebt¬ ed for the luxuriancy of their harvest, much more to the political and religious soil where they struck their roots, than to the skill or fore¬ sight of the individuals by whose hands they were scattered. I have united the names of Montaigne and of La Rochefoucauld, because I consider their writings as rather addressed to the world at large, than to the small and select class of spe¬ culative students. Neither of them can be said to have enriched the stock of human knowledge by the addition of any one important general 1 Tatler, No. 103. The last paper of the Tatler was published in 1711 ; and, consequently, the above passage must be understood as referring to the modish tone of French philosophy prior to the death of Louis XIV. 56 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. conclusion; but the maxims of both have oper rated very extensively and powerfully on the taste and principles of the higher orders all over Europe, and predisposed them to give a welcome reception to the same ideas, when afterwards reproduced with the imposing appendage of lo¬ gical method, and of a technical phraseology. The foregoing reflections, therefore, are not so foreign as might at first be apprehended, to the subsequent history of ethical and of metaphysi¬ cal speculation. It is time, however, now to turn our attention to a subject far more inti¬ mately connected with the general progress of human reason,—the philosophy of Descartes, DESCARTES—GASSENDI—MALEBRANGHE. According to a late writer,1 whose literary decisions (excepting where he touches on reli¬ gion or politics) are justly entitled to the high¬ est deference, Descartes has a better claim than any other individual, to be regarded as the fa¬ ther of that spirit of free inquiry, which in mo¬ dern Europe has so remarkably displayed itself in all the various departments of knowledge. Of Bacon, he observes, “ that though he pos¬ sessed, in a most eminent degree, the genius of philosophy, he did not unite with it the genius of the sciences; and that the methods proposed by him for the investigation of truth, consisting entirely of precepts which he was unable to ex¬ emplify, had little or no effect in accelerating the rate of discovery.” As for Galileo, he re¬ marks, on the other hand, ii that his exclu¬ sive taste for mathematical and physical re¬ searches, disqualified him for communicating to the general mind that impulse of which it stood in need.” “ This honour,” he adds, “ was reserved for Descartes, who combined in himself the cha- racteristical endowments of both his predecessors. If, in the physical sciences, his march be less sure than that of Galileo—if his logic be less cautious than that of Bacon—yet the very te¬ merity of his errors was instrumental to the progress of the human race. He gave activity to minds which the circumspection of his rivals could not awake from their lethargy. He call¬ ed upon men to throw off the yoke of authority, acknowledging no influence but what reason should avow: And his call was obeyed by a multitude of followers, encouraged by the bold¬ ness, and fascinated by the enthusiasm of their leader.” In these observations, the ingenious author has rashly generalised a conclusion deduced from the literary history of his own country. That the works of Bacon were but little read there till after the publication of D’Alembert’s Preliminary Discourse, is, I believe, an unquestionable fact;8 not that it necessarily follows from this, that, even in France, no previous effect had been produced by the labours of Boyle, of Newton, and of the other English experimentalists, trained in Bacon’s school. With respect to England, it is a fact not less certain, that at no period did the philosophy of Descartes produce such an impression on public opinion, either in Physics or in Ethics, as to give the slightest colour to the supposition, that it contributed, in the most distant degree, to the subsequent advances made by our countrymen in these sciences. In Logic and Metaphysics, indeed, the case was different. Here the writings of Descartes did much; and if they had been studied with proper attention, they might have done much more. But of this part of their me¬ rits, Condorcet seems to have had no idea. His eulogy, therefore, is rather misplaced than ex¬ cessive. He has extolled Descartes as the father of Experimental Physics: He would have been nearer the truth, if he had pointed him out as the father of the Experimental Philosophy of the Human Mind. In bestowing this title on Descartes, I am far from being inclined to compare him, in the nura- 4 ^onaorceu ^ f i 2 One reason for this is well pointed out by D’Alembert. 44II n’y a que les chefs de secte en tout genre, dont e?s ouvrages puissent avoir un certain eclat; Bacon n’a pas dte du nombre, et la forme de sa philosophie s’y opposoit: el e dtoit trop sage pour e'tonner personne.”—Disc- Prd. DISSERTATION FIRST. 57 ber or importance of the facts which he has re¬ marked concerning our intellectual powers, to various other writers of an earlier date. I al¬ lude merely to his clear and precise conception of that operation of the understanding (distin¬ guished afterwards in Locke’s Essay by the name of Reflection), through the medium of which all our knowledge of Mind is exclusively to be ob¬ tained. Of the essential subserviency of this power to every satisfactory conclusion that can be formed with respect to the mental phenome¬ na, and of the futility of every theory which would attempt to explain them by metaphors borrowed from the material world, no other phi¬ losopher prior to Locke seems to have been ful¬ ly aware ; and from the moment that these truths were recognised as logical principles in the study of mind, a new era commences in the history of that branch of science. It will be necessary, therefore, to allot to the illustration of this part of the Cartesian philosophy a larger space than the limits of my undertaking will permit me to afford to the researches of some succeeding inquirers, who may, at first sight, appear more worthy of attention in the present times. It has been repeatedly asserted by the Ma¬ terialists of the last ^entury, that Descartes was the first Metaphysician by whom the pure im¬ materiality of the human soul was taught; and that the ancient philosophers, as well as the schoolmen, went no farther than to consider mind as the result of a material organisation, in which the constituent elements approached to evanescence in point of subtlety. Both of these propositions I conceive to be totally un¬ founded. That many of the schoolmen, and that the wisest of the ancient philosophers, when they described the mind as a spirit, or as a spark of celestial fire, employed these expressions, not with any intention to materialise its essence, but merely from want of more unexceptionable lan¬ guage, might be shown with demonstrative evi¬ dence, if this were the proper place for entering into the discussion. But what is of more im¬ portance to be attended to, on the present oc¬ casion, is the effect of Descartes’ writings in dis¬ entangling the logical principle above mentioned, from the scholastic question about the nature of mind, as contradistinguished from matter. It were indeed to be wished, that he had perceiv¬ ed still more clearly and steadily the essential importance of keeping this distinction constant¬ ly in view ; but he had at least the merit of il¬ lustrating, by his own example, in a far greater degree than any of his predecessors, the possi¬ bility of studying the mental phenomena, with¬ out reference to any facts but those Avhich rest on the evidence of consciousness. The meta¬ physical question about the nature of mind he seems to have considered as a problem, the so¬ lution of which was an easy corollary from these facts, if distinctly apprehended; but still as a problem, whereof it was possible that different views might be taken by those who agreed in opinion, as far as facts alone were concerned. Of this a very remarkable example has since oc¬ curred in the case of Mr Locke, who, although he has been at great pains to show, that the power of refection bears the same relation to the study of the mental phenomena, which the power of observation bears to the study of the material world, appears, nevertheless, to have been far less decided than Descartes with respect to the essential distinction between Mind and Matter ; and has even gone so far as to hazard the un¬ guarded proposition, that there is no absurdity in supposing the Deity to have superadded to the other qualities of matter the power of thinking. His scepticism, however, on this point, did not prevent his good sense from perceiving, with the most complete conviction, the indispensable ne¬ cessity of abstracting from the analogy of mat¬ ter, in studying the laws of our intellectual frame. The question about the nature or essence of the soul, has been, in all ages, a favourite sub¬ ject of discussion among Metaphysicians, from its supposed connection with the argument in proof of its immortality. In this light it has plainly been considered by both parties in the dispute; the one conceiving, that if Mind could be shown to have no quality in common with Matter, its dissolution was physically impossible; the other, that if this assumption could be dis¬ proved, it would necessarily follow, that the whole man must perish at death. For the last of these opinions Dr Priestley and many other specula¬ tive theologians have of late very zealously con¬ tended ; flattering themselves, no doubt, with H DISS. I. PART i. 58 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. the idea, that they were thus preparing a triumph for their own peculiar schemes of Christianity. Neglecting, accordingly, all the presumptions for a future state, afforded by a comparison of the course of human affairs with the moral judg¬ ments and moral feelings of the human heart; and overlooking, with the same disdain, the presumptions arising from the narrow sphere of human knowledge, when compared with the in¬ definite improvement of which our intellectual powers seem to be susceptible, this acute but superficial writer attached himself exclusively to the old and hackneyed pneumatological argu¬ ment ; tacitly assuming as a principle, that the future prospects of man depend entirely on the determination of a physical problem, analogous to that which was then dividing chemists about the existence or non-existence of Phlogiston. In the actual state of science, these speculations might well have been spared. Where is the sober metaphysician to be found, who now speaks of the immortality of the soul as a logi¬ cal consequence of its immateriality; instead of considering it as depending on the will of that Being by whom it was at first called into exist¬ ence ? And, on the other hand, is it not uni¬ versally admitted by the best philosophers, that whatever hopes the light of nature encourages beyond the present scene, rest solely (like all our other anticipations of future events) on the general tenor and analogy of the laws by which we perceive the universe to he governed ? The proper use of the argument concerning the im¬ materiality of mind, is not to establish any posi¬ tive conclusion as to its destiny hereafter ; hut to repel the reasonings alleged by materialists, as proofs that its annihilation must he the ob¬ vious and necessary effect of the dissolution of the body.1 I thought it proper to state this consideration pretty fully, lest it should be supposed that the logical method recommended by Descartes for studying the phenomena of mind, has any ne¬ cessary dependence on his metaphysical opinion concerning its being and properties, as a separate substance.2 3 Between these two parts of his system, however, there is, if not a demonstrative connection, at least a natural and manifest af¬ finity ; inasmuch as a steady adherence to his logical method (or, in other words, the habitual exercise of patient refection), by accustoming us to break asunder the obstinate associations to which materialism is indebted for the early hold it is apt to take of the fancy, gradually and insensibly predisposes us in favour of his me¬ taphysical conclusion. It is to be regretted, that, in stating this conclusion, his commentators should so frequently make use of the word spiri¬ tuality ; for which I do not recollect that his own works afford any authority. The proper expression is immateriality, conveying merely a negative idea; and, of consequence, implying nothing more than a rejection of that hypothesis concerning the nature of M(pd, which the scheme of materialism so gratuitously, yet so dogmati¬ cally assumes.5 The power of Reflection, it is well known, is the last of our intellectual faculties that unfolds itself; and, in by far the greater number of in¬ dividuals, it never unfolds itself in any consider¬ able degree. It is a fact equally certain, that, long before the period of life when this power begins to exercise its appropriate functions, the understanding is already preoccupied with a 1 “ We shall here be content,” says the learned John Smith of Cambridge, “with that sober thesis of Plato, in his Timasus, who attributes the perpetuation of all substances to the benignity and liberality of the Creator; whom he there¬ fore brings in thus speaking, vpik; ix. a6a.va.roi ovSi uXuroi, x. r. X. You are not of yourselves immortal nor indissoluble, but would relapse and slide back from that being which I have given you, should I withdraw the influence of my own power from you ; but yet you shall hold your immortality by a patent from myself." (Select Discourses, Cambridge, 1660.) I quote this pas¬ sage from one of the oldest partisans of Descartes among the English philosophers. Descartes himself is said to have been of a different opinion. " “ On a e'te etonne,” says Thomas, “ que dans ses Medi¬ tations Metaphysiques, Descartes n’ait point parle de 1’immortalite de fame. Mais il nous apprend lui-memepar une de ses lettres, qu’ayant e'tabli clairement, dans cet ouvrage, la distinction de fame et de la matiere, il suivoit ne'cessairement de cette distinction, que fame par sa nature ne pouvoit perir avec le corps.”—Eloge de Descartes. Note 21. 2 I employ the scholastic word substance, in conformity to the phraseology of Descartes; but I am fully aware of the strong objections to which it is liable, not only as a wide deviation from popular use, which has appropriated it to things material and tangible, but as implying a greater degree of positive knowledge concerning the nature of mind, than our fa¬ culties are fitted to attain—For some further remarks on this point, See Note I. 3 See Note K. DISSERTATION FIRST. 59 chaos of opinions, notions, impressions, and as¬ sociations, bearing on the most important ob¬ jects of human inquiry; not to mention the in¬ numerable sources of illusion and error con¬ nected with the use of a vernacular language, learned in infancy by rote, and identified with the first processes of thought and perception. The consequence is, that when man begins to reflect, he finds himself (if I may borrow an allusion of M. Turgot’s) lost in a labyrinth, in¬ to which he had been led blindfold.1 2 3 To the same purpose, it was long ago complained of by Bacon, <{ that no one has yet been found of so constant and severe a mind, as to have de¬ termined and tasked himself utterly to abolish theories and common notions, and to apply his intellect, altogether smooth and even, to par¬ ticulars anew. Accordingly, that human reason which we have, is a kind of medley and unsorted collection, from much trust and much accident, and the childish notions which we first drank in. Whereas, if one of ripe age and sound senses, and a mind thoroughly cleared, should apply himself freshly to experiment and par¬ ticulars, of him were better things to he hoped.” What Bacon has here recommended, Des¬ cartes attempted to execute; and so exact is the coincidence of his views on this fundamental point with those of his predecessor, that it is with difficulty I can persuade myself that he had never read Bacon’s works. * In the prosecution of this undertaking, the first steps of Descartes are peculiarly interesting and instructive; and it is these alone which merit our attention at present. As for the details of his system, they are now curious only as exhibiting an amusing contrast to the extreme rigour of the principle from which the author sets out; a contrast so very striking, as fully to justify the epigram¬ matic saying of D’Alembert, that “ Descartes began with doubting of every thing, and ended in believing that he had left nothing unexplained.” Among the various articles of common belief which Descartes proposed t#subject to a severe scrutiny, he enumerates particularly, the con¬ clusiveness of mathematical demonstration; the existence of God; the existence of the material world; and even the existence of his own body. The only thing that appeared to him certain and incontrovertible, was his own existence; by which he repeatedly reminds us, we are to un¬ derstand merely the existence of his mind, ab¬ stracted from all consideration of the material organs connected with it. About every other proposition, he conceived, that doubts might reasonably be entertained; but to suppose the non-existence of that which thinks, at the very moment it is conscious of thinking, appeared to him a contradiction in terms. From this single postulatum, accordingly, he took his departure ; resolved to admit nothing as a philosophical truth, which could not be deduced from it by a chain of logical reasoning.5 Having first satisfied himself of his own ex¬ istence, his next step was to inquire, how far his perceptive and intellectual faculties were en¬ titled to credit. For this purpose, he begins with offering a proof of the existence and at¬ tributes of God;—truths which he conceived to be necessarily involved in the idea he was able to form of a perfect, self-existent, and eternal being. His reasonings on this point it would be useless to state. It is sufficient to observe, that they led him to conclude, that God cannot possibly be supposed to deceive his creatures ; and therefore, that the intimations of our senses, and the decisions of our reason, are to be trusted to with entire confidence, wherever they afford us clear and distinct ideas of their respective ob¬ jects.4 1 “ Quand rhomme a voulu se replier sur lui-meme, il s’est trouve dans un labyrinthe, oii il dtoit entrd les yeux bandds.”—CEuvres ds Turgot, Tom. II. p. 261. 2 See Note L. 3 “ Sic autem rejicientes ilia omnia, de quibus aliquo modo possumus dubitare, ac etiam falsa esse fingentes, facile quidem supponimus nullum esse Deum, nullum ccelum, nulla corpora; nosque etiam ipsos, non habere manus, nec pedes, nec denique ullum corpus : non autem ideo nos qui talia cogitamus nihil esse: repugnat enim, ut putemus id quod cogitat, eo ipso tempore quo cogitat, non existere. Ac proinde baec cognitio, ego cogito, ergo sum, est omnium prima et certissima, qute cuilibet ordine philosophanti occurrat.”—Princip. Philos. Pars I. § 7- * The substance of Descartes’ argument on these fundamental points, is thus briefly recapitulated by himself in the conclusion of his third Meditation:—“ Dum in meipsum mentis aciem converto, non modo intelligo me esse rem in- completam, et ab alio dependentem, remque ad majora et meliora indefinite aspirantem, sed simul etiam intelligo ilium, a 60 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. As Descartes conceived the existence of God (next to the existence of his own mind) to he the most indisputable of all truths, and rested his confidence in the conclusions of human rea¬ son entirely on his faith in the divine veracity, it is not surprising that he should have rejected the argument from final causes, as superfluous and unsatisfactory. To have availed himself of its assistance would not only have betrayed a want of confidence in what he professed to re¬ gard as much more certain than any mathema¬ tical theorem; hut would obviously have ex¬ posed him to the charge of first appealing to the divine attributes in proof of the authority of his faculties; and afterwards, of appealing to these faculties, in proof of the existence of God. It is wonderful that it should have escaped the penetration of this most acute thinker, that a vicious circle of the same description is involved in every appeal to the intellectual powers, in proof of their own credibility ; and that unless this credibility he assumed as unquestionable, the farther exercise of human reason is altogether nugatory. The evidence for the existence of God seems to have appeared to Descartes too irresistible and overwhelming, to be subjected to those logical canons which apply to all the other conclusions of the understanding.1 Extravagant and hopeless as these prelimi¬ nary steps must now appear, they had never¬ theless an obvious tendency to direct the atten¬ tion of the author, in a singular degree, to the phenomena of thought; and to train him to those habits of abstraction from external objects, which, to the hulk of mankind, are next to im¬ possible. In this way he was led to perceive, with the evidence of consciousness, that the at¬ tributes of Mind were still more clearly and distinctly knowahle than those of Matter; and that, in studying the former, so far from at¬ tempting to explain them by analogies borrowed from the latter, our chief aim ought to he, to banish as much as possible from the fancy every analogy, and even every analogical expression, which, by inviting the attention abroad, might divert it from its proper business at home. In one word, that the only right method of philo¬ sophising on this subject was comprised in the old stoical precept (understood in a sense some¬ what different from that originally annexed to it) nec te qucesiveris extra. A just conception of this rule, and a steady adherence to its spirit, constitutes the ground-work of what is properly called the Experimental Philosophy of the Hu¬ man Mind. It is thus that all our facts relating to Mind must he ascertained; and it is only upon facts thus attested by our own conscious¬ ness, that any just theory of Mind can he • reared. Agreeably to these views, Descartes was, I think, the first who clearly saw that our idea of Mind is not direct, hut relative;—relative to the various operations of which we are conscious. What am I ? he asks, in his second Meditation : A thinking being,—that is, a being doubting, quo pendeo, majora ista omnia non indefinite et potentia tantum, sed reipsa infinite in se habere, atque ita Deum esse; totaque vis argumenti in eo est, quod agnoscam fieri non posse ut existam talis naturae qualis sum, nempe ideam Dei in me habens, nisi revera Deus etiam existeret, Deus, inquam, file idem cujus idea in me est, hoc est, habens omnes illas perfectiones quas ego non comprehendere, sed quocunque modo attingere cogitatione possum, et nullis plane defectibus obnoxius. Ex his satis patet, ilium fallacem esse non posse : omnem enim fraudem et deceptionem a defectu aliquo pen- dere lumine natural! manifestum est.” The above argument for the existence of God (very improperly called by some foreigners an argument a priori), was long considered by the most eminent men m Europe as quite demonstrative. For my own part, although I do not think that it is by any means so level to the apprehension of common inquirers, as the argument from the marks of design every¬ where manifested in the universe, I am still less inclined to reject it as altogether unworthy of attention. It is far from being so metaphysically abstruse as the reasonings of Newton and Clarke, founded on our conceptions of space and of time; nor would it appear, perhaps, less logical and conclusive than that celebrated demonstration, if it were properly unfolded, and stated in more simple and popular terms. The two arguments, however, are in no respect exclusive of each other; and I have always thought, that, by combining them together, a proof of the point in question might be formed, more im¬ pressive and luminous than is to be obtained from either, when stated apart. 1 How painful is it to recollect, that the philosopher who had represented his faith in the veracity of God, as the sole foundation of his confidence in the demonstrations of mathematics, was accused and persecuted by his contemporaries as an atheist; and that, too, in the same country (Holland), where, for more than half a century after his death, his doctrines were to be taught in all the universities with a blind idolatry ! A zeal without knowledge, and the influence of those earth¬ ly passions, from which even Protestant divines are not always exempted, may, it is to be hoped, go far to account for this inconsistency and injustice, without adopting the uncharitable insinuation of D’Alembert: “ Malgre toute la sagacite qu’il avoit employee pour nrouver 1’existence de Dieu, il fut accuse de la nier par des mimstres, qui peut-ctre ne la croyoient pas." DISSERTATION FIRST. 61 knowing, affirming, denying, consenting, refu¬ sing, susceptible of pleasure and of pain.1 Of all these things I might have had complete ex¬ perience, without any previous acquaintance with the qualities and laws of matter; and therefore it is impossible that the study of mat¬ ter can avail me aught in the study of my¬ self. This, accordingly, Descartes laid down as a first principle, that nothing comprehensible by the imagination can be at all subservient to the knowledge of Mind ; and that the sensible images involved in all our common forms of speaking concerning its operations, are to he guarded against with the most anxious care, as tending to confound, in our apprehensions, two classes of phenomena, which it is of the last importance to distinguish accurately from each other.2 To those who are familiarly acquainted with the writings of Locke, and of the very few among his successors who have thoroughly en¬ tered into the spirit of his philosophy, the fore¬ going observations may not appear to possess much either of originality or of importance; hut when first given to the world, they formed the greatest step ever made in the science of Mind, by a single individual. What a contrast do they ex¬ hibit, not only to the discussions of the school¬ men, but to the analogical theories of Hobbes at the very same periotf! and how often have they been since lost sight of, notwithstanding the clearest speculative conviction of their truth and importance, by Locke himself, and by the greatest part of his professed followers ! Had they been duly studied and understood by Mr Horne Tooke, they would have furnished him with a key for solving those etymological riddles, which, although mistaken by many of his con¬ temporaries for profound philosophical discove¬ ries, derive, in fact, the whole of their mystery, from the strong bias of shallow reasoners to re¬ lapse into the same scholastic errors, from which Descartes, Locke, Berkeley, Hume, and Reid, have so successfully laboured to emancipate the mind. If any thing can add to our admiration of a train of thought manifesting in its author so un¬ exampled a triumph over the strongest prejudices of sense, it is the extraordinary circumstance of its having first occurred to a young man, who had spent the years commonly devoted to aca¬ demical study, amid the dissipation and tumult of camps.3 Nothing could make this conceiv¬ able, but the very liberal education which he had previously received under the Jesuits, at the college of La I'leche f where, we are told, that while yet a hoy, he was so distinguished by .U j^°n sum comPages membrorum, quae corpus humanum appellatur; non sum etiam tenuis aliquis aer istis mem- bns inrusus ; non ventus, non ignis, non vapor, non halitus Quid igitur sum ? res cogitans ; quid est hoc ? nempe du- bitans, intelligens, affirmans, negans, volens, nolens,” &c Med. Sec. “ Itaque cognosco, nihil eorum quae possum Imaginatione comprehendere, ad hanc quam de me habeo notitiam perti- nere ; mentemque ab illis diligentissime esse avocandam, ut suam ipsa naturam quam distinctissime percipiat.—Ibid. A tew sentences before, Descartes explains with precision in what sense Imagination is here to be understood. “ Nihil aliud est imaginari quam rei corporeae figuram seu imaginem contemplari.” following extracts from a book published at Cambridge in 1660 (precisely ten years after the death of Descartes), while they furnish a useful comment on some of the above remarks, may serve to show, how completely the spirit of the Cartesian philosophy of Mind had been seized even then, by some of the members of that university. 1 he souls of men exercising themselves first of all xivtnru Tgefianxip, as the Greek philosopher expresseth himself, merely by a progressive kind of motion, spending themselves about bodily and material acts, and conversing only with sensible things; they are apt to acquire such deep stamps of material phantasms to themselves, that they cannot imagine their own Being to be any other than material and divisible, though of a fine ethereal nature. It is not possible for us well to know what our souls are, but only by their xlvwru; xvxXixat, their circular or reflex motions, and converse with themselves, which can only steal from them their own secrets.”—Smith's Select Discourses, p. 65, 66. If we reflect but upon our own souls, how manifestly do the notions of reason, freedom, perception, and the like, offer themselves to us, whereby we may know a thousand times more distinctly what our souls are than what our bodies are. For the former, we know by an immediate converse with ourselves, and a distinct sense of their operations ; whereas all our knowledge of the body is little better than merely historical, which we gather up by scraps and piecemeal, from more doubtful and uncertain experiments which we make of them ; but the notions which we have of a mind, i. e. something within us that thinks, apprehends, reasons, and discourses, are so clear and distinct from all those notions which we can fasten upon a body, that we can easily conceive that if all body-being in the world were destroyed, yet we might then as well subsist as now we do.”—Ibid. p. 98. 3 « Descartes porta les armes, d’abord en Hollande, sous le celebre Maurice de Nassau ; de-la en Allemagne, sous Maxi- milien de Baviere, au commencement de la guerre de trente ans. II passa ensuite au service de I’Empereur Ferdinand II. pour voir de plus pres les troubles de la Hongrie. On croit aussi, qu’au siege de la Rochelle, il combattit, comme volon- taire, dans une bataille centre la flotte Angloise.”—Thomas, Eloge de Descartes, Note 8. When Descartes quitted the profession of arms, he had arrived at the age of twenty-five. 4 It is a curious coincidence, that it was in the same village of La Fleche that Mr Hume fixed his residence, while com- 62 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. habits of deep meditation, that he went among his companions by the name ot the Philosopher. Indeed, it is only at that early age, that such habits are to be cultivated with complete suc¬ cess. The glory, however, of having pointed out to his successors the true method of studying the theory of Mind, is almost all that can he claimed by Descartes in logical and metaphysical science. Many important hints, indeed, may be gleaned from his works ; but, on the whole, he has added very little to our knowledge of human nature. Nor will this appear surprising, when it is re¬ collected, that he aspired to accomplish a simi¬ lar revolution in all the various departments of physical knowledge;—not to mention the time and thought he must have employed in those mathematical researches, which, however lightly esteemed by himself, have been long regarded as the most solid basis of his fame.1 Among the principal articles of the Cartesian philosophy, which are now incorporated with our prevailing and most accredited doctrines, the following seem to me to he chiefly entitled to notice : 1. His luminous exposition of the common logical error of attempting to define words which express notions too simple to admit of analysis. Mr Locke claims this improvement as entirely his own; hut the merit of it un¬ questionably belongs to Descartes, although it must he owned that he has not always sufficient¬ ly attended to it in his own researches.2 2. His observations on the different classes of our prejudices—particularly on the errors to which we are liable in consequence of a careless use of language as the instrument of thought. The greater part of these observations, if not the whole, had been previously hinted at by Bacon ; but they are expressed by Descartes with greater precision and simplicity, and in a style better adapted to the taste of the present age. 3. The paramount and indisputable authority which, in all our reasonings concerning the hu¬ man mind, he ascribes to the evidence of con¬ sciousness. Of this logical principle he has availed himself, with irresistible force, in refu¬ ting the scholastic sophisms against the liberty of human actions, drawn from the prescience of the Deity, and other considerations of a theolo¬ gical nature. 4. The most important, however, of all his improvements in metaphysics, is the distinction which he has so clearly and so strongly drawn between the primary and the secondary qualities of matter. This distinction was not unknown to some of the ancient schools of philosophy in Greece ; but it was afterwards rejected by Aris¬ totle, and by the schoolmen; and it was reserv¬ ed for Descartes to place it in such a light, as (with the exception of a very few sceptical or rather paradoxical theorists) to unite the opi¬ nions of all succeeding inquirers. For this step, so apparently easy, but so momentous in its con¬ sequences, Descartes was not indebted to any long or difficult processes of reasoning; but to those habits of accurate and patient attention to the operations of his own mind, which, from his early years, it was the great business of his life to cultivate. It may be proper to add, that the epithets primary and secondary, now universally employed to mark the distinction in question, were first introduced by Locke ; a circumstance posing his Treatise of Human Nature. Is it not probable, that be was partly attracted to it, by associations similar to those which presented themselves to the fancy of Cicero, when he visited the walks of the Academy ? In the beginning of Descartes’ dissertation upon Method, he has given a very interesting account of the pursuits which occupied his youth, and of the considerations which suggested to him the bold undertaking of reforming philosophy. 1 Such too is the judgment pronounced by D’Alembert. “ Les Mathematiques, dont Descartes semble avoir fait assez peu de cas, font neanmoins aujourd’hui la partie la plus solide et la moins conteste'e de sa gloire.” To this he adds a very in¬ genious reflection on the comparative merits of Descartes, considered as a geometer and as a philosopher. “ Comme philo- sophe, il a peut-etre dte aussi grand, mais il n’a pas dte si heureux. La Geometrie, qui par la nature de son objet doit toujours gagner sans perdre, ne pouvoit manquer, etant manide par un aussi grand genie de faire des progres tres-sensibles et apparens pour tout le monde. La Philosophie se trouvoit dans un etat bien different, tout y etoit a commencer; et que ne content point les premiers pas en tout genre ! le m'erite de les faire dispense de cclui d'en faire de grands."—Disc. Prelim. 2 “ The names of simple ideas are not capable of any definitions; the names of all complex ideas are. It has not, that I know, been yet observed by any body, what words are, and what are not capable of being defined.”—(Locke’s Essay, Book iii. chap. iv. § iv.)—Compare this with the Principia of Descartes, 1.10.; and with Lord Stair’s Philologia Nova Expe~ rimentalis, pp. 9 and 79, printed at Leyden in 1686. DISSERTATION FIRST. 63 which may have contributed to throw into the shade the merits of those inquirers who had pre¬ viously struck into the same path. As this last article of the Cartesian system has a close connection with several of the most refined conclusions yet formed concerning the intellectual phenomena, I feel it due to the me¬ mory of the author, to pause for a few moments, in order to vindicate his claim to some leading ideas, commonly supposed hy the present race of metaphysicians to be of much later origin. In doing so, I shall have an opportunity, at the same time, of introducing one or two remarks, which, I trust, will he useful in clearing up the obscurity, which is allowed by some of the ablest followers of Descartes and Locke, still to hang over this curious discussion. I have elsewhere observed, that Descartes has been very generally charged by the writers of the last century, with a sophistical play upon words in his doctrine concerning the non-exist¬ ence of secondary qualities; while, in fact, he was the first person by whom the fallacy of this scholastic paralogism was exposed to the world.1 In proof of this, it might be sufficient to refer to his own statement, in the first part of the Prin- cipia ;2 hut, for a reason which will immediate¬ ly appear, I think it more advisable, on this occa¬ sion, to borrow the words of one of his earliest and ablest commentators. <{ It is only (says Father Malehranche) since the time of Descartes, that to those confused and indeterminate questions, whether fire is hot, grass green, and sugar sweet, philosophers are in use to reply, hy distinguish¬ ing the equivocal meaning of the words express¬ ing sensible qualities. If hy heat, cold, and savour, you understand such and such a dispo¬ sition of parts, or some unknown motion of sensible qualities, then fire is hot, grass green, and sugar sweet. But if by heat and other qualities you understand what I feel hy fire, what I see in grass, &c. fire is not hot, nor grass green ; for the heat I feel, and the colours I see, are only in the soul.”5 It is surprising how this, and other passages to the same purpose in Male¬ hranche, should have escaped the notice of Dr Reid; for nothing more precise on the ambigui¬ ty in the names of secondary qualities is to be found in his own works. It is still more sur¬ prising that Buffier, who might have been ex¬ pected to have studied with care the speculations of his illustrious countryman, should have di¬ rectly charged, not only Descartes, but Male¬ hranche, with maintaining a paradox, whicx they were at so much pains to banish from the schools of philosophy.4 The important observations of Descartes upon this subject, made their way into England very soon after his death. They are illustrated at considerable length, and with great ingenuity, hy Glanville, in his Scepsis Scientifica, published “Descartes, Malebranche, and Locke, revived the distinction between primary and secondary qualities. But thev made the secondary qualities mere sensations, and the primary ones resemblances of our sensations. They maintained that colour, sound, and heat, are not any thing in bodies, but sensations of the mind. The paradoxes of these philo¬ sophers were only an abuse of words. For when they maintain, as an important modern discovery, that there is no heat in the fire, they mean no more than that the fire does not feel heat, which every one knew before.”—Reid’s Inquiry, chan, v. sect. viii. 2 See sections Ixix. Ixx. Ixxi. The whole of these three paragraphs is highly interesting; but I shall only quote two sentences, which are fully sufficient to show, that, in the above observations, I have done Descartes no more than strict justice. “ Patet itaque in re idem esse, cum dicimus nos percipere colores in objectis, ac si diceremus nos percipere aliquid in objectis, quod quidem quid sit ignoramus, sed a quo efficitur in nobis ipsis sensus quidam valde manifestus et perspicuus, qui vocatur sensus cobrum. Cum vero putamus nos percipere colores in objectis, etsi revera nesciamus quidnam sit quod tunc nomine colons appellamus, nec ullam similitudinem intelligere possimus, inter colorem quem supponimus esse in objectis, et ilium quem experimur esse in sensu, quia tamen hoc ipsum non advertimus, et multa alia sunt, ut mag¬ nitude, figura, numerus, &c. quae clare percipimus not aliter a nobis sentiri vel intelligi, quam ut sunt, aut saltern esse possunt in objectis, facile, m eum errorem delabimur, ut judicemus id, quod in objectis vocamus colorem, esse quid omnino simile colon quem sentimus, atque ita ut id quod nullo modo percipimus, a nobis clare percipi arbitraremur.” 3 Recherche de la Verite, Livre vi. chap. ii. J ai admire souvent que d’aussi grands hommes que Descartes et Malebranche, avec leurs sectateurs, fissent valoir, comme une rare decouverte de leur philosophie, que la chaleur etoit dans nous-mtmes et nullement dans le feu ; au lieu que le commun des hommes trouvoient que la chaleur etoit dans le feu aussi lien que dans nous Mais en ce fameux debat, de quoi s’agit-il ? Uniquement de 1’imperfection du langage, qui causoit une idee confuse par le mot de chaleur, ce mot expri- mant egalement deux choses, qui a la verite ont quelque rapport ou analogie, et pourtant qui sont tres diff'erentes; savoir, 1. le sentiment de chaleur qui nous eprouvons en nous ; 2. la disposition qui est dans le feu a produire en nous ce senti¬ ment de chaleur.”—Cours de Sciences, par le Pere Buffier, p. 819. A Paris, 1732. 64 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. about thirteen years before Malebranche’s Search after Truth. So slow, however, is the progiess of good sense, when it has to struggle against the prejudices of the learned, that, as lately as 1713, the paradox so clearly explained and re¬ futed by Descartes, appears to have kept some footing in the English universities. In a papei of the Guardian, giving an account of a visit paid by Jack Lizard to his mother and sisters, after a year and half s residence at Oxford, the following precis is given of his logical attain¬ ments. “ For the first week (it is said) Jack dealt wholly in paradoxes. It was a common jest with him to pinch one of his sister s lap dogs, and afterwards prove he could not feel it. When the girls were sorting a set of knots, he would demonstrate to them that all the ribbons were of the same colour ; or rather, says Jack, of no colour at all. My Lady Lizard herself, though she was not a little pleased with her son’s improvements, was one day almost angry with him ; for having accidentally burnt her fingers as she was lighting the lamp for her tea-pot, in the midst of her anguish, Jack laid hold of the opportunity to instruct her, that there was no such thing as heat in the fire.” This miserable quibble about the non-exist¬ ence of secondary qualities, never could have attracted the notice of so many profound think¬ ers, had it not been for a peculiar difficulty con¬ nected with our notions of colour, of which I do not know anyone English philosopher who seems to have been sufficiently aware. That this qua¬ lity belongs to the same class with sounds, smells, tastes, heat and cold, is equally admitted by the partisans of Descartes and of Locke ; and must, indeed, appear an indisputable fact to all who are capable of reflecting accurately on the sub¬ ject. But still, between colour and the other qualities now mentioned, a very important dis¬ tinction must be allowed to exist. In the case of smells, tastes, sounds, heat and cold, every person must immediately perceive, that his senses give him only a relative idea of the external quality; in other words, that they only convey to him the knowledge of the existence of cer¬ tain properties or powers in external objects, which fit them to produce certain sensations in his mind; and, accordingly, nobody ever hesitat¬ ed a moment about the truth of this part of the Cartesian philosophy, in so far as these qualities alone are concerned. But, in the application of the same doctrine to colour, I have conversed with many, with whom I found it quite in vain to argue; and this, not from any defect in their reasoning powers, but from their incapacity to reflect steadily on the subjects of their conscious¬ ness ; or rather, perhaps, from their incapacity to separate, as objects of the understanding, two things indissolubly combined by early and con¬ stant habit, as objects of the imagination. The silence of modern metaphysicians on this head is the more surprising, as D’Alembert long ago invited their attention to it as one of the most wonderful phenomena in the history of the hu¬ man mind. “ The bias we acquire,” I quote his own words, c< in consequence of habits con¬ tracted in infancy, to refer to a substance ma¬ terial and divisible, what really belongs to a sub¬ stance spiritual and simple, is a thing well worthy of the attention of metaphysicians. No¬ thing,” he adds, “ is perhaps more extraordi¬ nary, in the operations of the mind, than to see it transport its sensations out of itself, and to spread them, as it were, over a substance to which they cannot possibly belong.”—It would be difficult to state the fact in question in terms more brief, precise, and perspicuous. That the illusion, so well described in the above quotation, was not overlooked by Des¬ cartes and Malebranche, appears unquestionable, from their extreme solicitude to reconcile it with that implicit faith, which, from religious con¬ siderations, they conceived to be due to the testi¬ mony of those faculties with which our Maker has endowed us. Malebranche, in particular, is at pains to distinguish between the sensation, and the judgment combined with it. “ The sensa¬ tion never deceives us; it differs in no respect from what we conceive it to be. The judgment, too, is natural, or rather (says Malebranche), it is only a sort of compound sensation ;x but this 1 He would have expressed himself more accurately, if he had said, that the judgment is indissolubly combined with the sensation ; but his meaning is sufficiently obvious. DISSERTATION FIRST. 65 judgment leads us into no error with respect to philosophical truth. The moment we exercise our reason, we see the fact in its true light, and can account completely for that illusive appear¬ ance which it presents to the imagination.” Not satisfied, however, with this solution of the difficulty, or rather perhaps apprehensive that it might not appear quite satisfactory to some others, he has called in to his assistance the doctrine of original sin; asserting, that all the mistaken judgments which our constitution leads us to form concerning external objects^and their qualities, are the consequences of the fall of our first parents ; since which adventure (as it is somewhat irreverently called by Dr Beattie), it requires the constant vigilance of reason to guard against the numberless tricks and im¬ postures practised upon us by our external senses.1 In another passage, Malebranche ob¬ serves very beautifully (though not very con¬ sistently with his theological argument on the same point), that our senses being given us for the preservation of our bodies, it was requisite for our well-being, that we should judge as we do of sensible qualities. “ In the case of the sensations of pain and of heat, it was much more advantageous that we should seem to feel them in those parts of the body which are im¬ mediately affected by them, than that we should associate them with the external objects by which they are occasioned; because pain and heat, having the power to injure our members, it was necessary that we should be warned in what place to apply the remedy; whereas colours not being likely, in ordinary cases, to hurt the eye, it would have been superfluous for us to know that they are painted on the retina. On the contrary, as they are only useful to us, from the information they convey with respect to things external, it was essential that we should be so formed as to attach them to the corresponding objects on which they depend.”2 The two following remarks, which I shall state with all possible brevity, appear to me to go far towards a solution of the problem proposed by D’Alembert. 1. According to the new theory of vision com¬ monly (but, as I shall afterwards show, not alto¬ gether9% ) ascribed to Dr Berkeley, lineal dis¬ tance from the eye is not an original perception of sight. In the meantime, from the first moment that the eye opens, the most intimate connection must necessarily be established between the notion of colour and those of visible extension and figure. At first, it is not improbable that all of them may be conceived to be merely modifications of the mind; but, however this may be, the mani¬ fest consequence is, that when a comparison between the senses of Sight and of Touch has taught us to refer to a distance the objects of the one, the indissolubly associated sensations of the other must of course accompany them, how far soever that distance may extend.3 2. It is well known to be a general law of our constitution, when one thing is destined, either by nature or by convention, to be the sign of another, that the mind has a disposition to pass on, as rapidly as possible, to the thing signified, without dwelling on the sign as an object worthy of its attention. The most remarkable of all ex- 1 “ We are informed by Father Malebranche, that the senses were at first as honest faculties as one could desire to be endued with, till after they were debauched by original sin ; an adventure from which they contracted such an invincible propensity to cheating, that they are now continually lying in wait to deceive us.”—Essay on Truth, p. 241, second edition. 2 Recherche de la Verite, Liv. i. chap. xiii. § 5. In Dr Iteid’s strictures on Descartes and Locke there are two remarks which I am at a loss how to reconcile. “ Colour,” says he, “ differs from other secondary qualities in this, that whereas the name of the quality is sometimes given to the sensation which indicates it, and is occasioned by it, we never, as far as I can judge, give the name of colour to the sensation, but to the quality only.” A few sentences before, lie had observed, “ That when we think or speak of any particular colour, however simple the notion may seem to be which is presented to the imagination, it is really in some sort compounded. It involves an unknown cause, and a known effect. The name of colour belongs indeed to the cause only, and not to the effect. But as the cause is unknown, we can form no distinct con¬ ception of it, but by its relation to the known effect. And, therefore, both go together in the imagination, and are so close¬ ly united, that they are mistaken for one simple object of thought.”—Inquiry, chap. vi. sect. 4. These two passages seem quite inconsistent with each other. If in the perception of colour, the sensation and the qua¬ lity “ be so closely united as to be mistaken for one single object of thought,” does it not obviously follow, that it is to this compounded notion the name of colour must, in general, be given ? On the other hand, when it is said that the name of colour is never given to the sensation, hut to the quality only, does not this imply, that every time the word is pronounced, the quality is separated from the sensation, even in the imaginations of the vulgar,? 3 See Note M. DISS. I. PATIT I. I 66 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. amples of this occurs in the acquired perceptions of sight, where our estimates of distance are frequently the result of an intellectual process, comparing a variety of different signs together, without a possibility on our part, the moment afterwards, of recalling one single step of the process to our recollection. Our inattention to the sensations of colour, consiclered as affections of the Mind, or as modifications of our own being, appears to me to he a fact of precisely the same description; for all these sensations were plainly intended by nature to perform the office of signs, indicating to us the figures and distances of things external. Of their essential importance in this point of view, an idea may be formed, by supposing for a moment the whole face of nature to exhibit only one uniform colour, without the slightest variety even of light and shade. Is it not self-evident that, on this sup¬ position, the organ of sight would be entirely useless, inasmuch as it is by the varieties of colour alone that the outlines or visible figures of bodies are so defined, as to be distinguishable one from another ? Nor could the eye, in this case, give us any information concerning diver¬ sities of distance ; for all the various signs of it, enumerated by optical writers, pre-suppose the antecedent recognition of the bodies around us, as separate objects of perception. It is not there¬ fore surprising, that signs so indispensably sub¬ servient to the exercise of our noblest sense, should cease, in early infancy, to attract notice as the subjects of our consciousness; and that afterwards they should present themselves to the imagination rather as qualities of Matter, than as attributes of Mind.1 To this reference of the sensation of colour to the external object, I can think of nothing so analogous as the feelings we experience in sur¬ veying a library of books. We speak of the volumes piled up on its shelves, as treasures or magazines of the knowledge of past ages; and contemplate them with gratitude and reverence, as inexhaustible sources of instruction and delight to the mind. Even in looking at a page of print or of manuscript, we are apt to say, that the ideas we acquire are received by the sense of sight; and we are scarcely conscious of a metaphor, when we employ this language. On such oc¬ casions we seldom recollect, that nothing is per¬ ceived by the eye but a multitude of black strokes drawn upon white paper, and that it is our own acquired habits which communicate to these strokes the whole of that significancy whereby they are distinguished from the unmeaning scrawling of an infant or a changeling. The knowledge which we conceive to be preserved in books, like the fragrance of a rose, or the gild¬ ing of the clouds, depends, for its existence, on the relation between the object and the percipient mind; and the only difference between the two cases is, that in the one, this relation is the local and temporary effect of conventional habits; in the other, it is the universal and the unchange¬ able work of nature. The art of printing, it is to be hoped, will in future render the former relation, as well as the latter, coeval with our species; but, in the past history of mankind, it is impossible to say how often it may have been dissolved. What vestiges can now be traced of those scientific attainments which, in early times, drew to Egypt, from every part of the civilised world, all those who were anxious to be initia¬ ted in the mysteries of philosophy ? The sym¬ bols which still remain in that celebrated coun¬ try, inscribed on eternal monuments, have long lost the correspondent which reflected upon them their own intellectual attributes. To us ' In Dr Iteid’s Inquiry, he has introduced a discussion concerning the perception of visible figure, which has puzzled me since the first time (more than forty years ago) that I read his work. The discussion relates to this question, “ Whether there be any sensation proper to visible figure, by which it is suggested in vision ?” The result of the argument is, that “ our eye might have been so framed as to suggest the figure of the object, without suggesting colour, or any other quality ; and, of consequence, there seems to be no sensation appropriated to visible figure; this quality being suggested immediately by the material impression upon the organ, of which impression we are not conscious.”—Inquiry, chap. vi. sect. 8. To my apprehension, nothing can appear more manifest than this, that, if there had been no variety in our sensations of colour, and still more, if we had had no sensation of colour whatsoever, the organ of sight could have given us no information, either with respect to figures or to distances ; and, of consequence, would have been as useless to us, as if we had been af¬ flicted, from the moment of our birth, with a gutta serena. DISSERTATION FIRST. 67 they are useless and silent, and serve only to at¬ test the existence of arts, of which it is impos¬ sible to unriddle the nature and the objects. Variis nunc sculpta figuris Marmora, trunca tamen visuntur mutaque nobis; Signa repertorum tuimur, cecidere reperta. What has now been remarked with respect to written characters, may be extended very nearly to oral language. WTien we listen to the dis¬ course of a public speaker, eloquence and per¬ suasion seem to issue from his lips; and we are little aware, that we ourselves infuse the soul into every word that he utters. The case is exactly the same when we enjoy the conversa¬ tion of a friend. We ascribe the charm entirely to his voice and accents; but without our co¬ operation, its potency would vanish. How very small the comparative proportion is, which, in such cases, the words spoken contribute to the intellectual and moral effect, I have elsewhere endeavoured to show. I have enlarged on this part of the Cartesian system, not certainly on account of its intrinsic value, as connected with the theory of our ex¬ ternal perceptions (although even in this respect of the deepest interest to every philosophical in¬ quirer), but because it affords the most palpable and striking example I know of, to illustrate the indissoluble associations established during the period of infancy between the intellectual and the material worlds. It was plainly the inten¬ tion of nature, that our thoughts should be ha¬ bitually directed to things external; and accord¬ ingly the bulk of mankind are not only indis- posed to study the intellectual phenomena, but are incapable of that degree of reflection which is necessary for their examination. Hence it is, that when we begin to analyse our own internal constitution, we find the facts it presents to us so very intimately combined in our conceptions with the qualities of matter, that it is impossible for us to draw distinctly and steadily the line between them ; and that, when Mind and Mat¬ ter are concerned in the same result, the former is either entirely overlooked, or is regarded only as an accessary principle, dependent for its ex¬ istence on the latter. To the same cause it is owing, that we find it so difficult (if it be at all practicable) to form an idea of any of our intel¬ lectual operations, abstracted from the images suggested by their metaphorical names. It was objected to Descartes by some of his contempo¬ raries, that the impossibility of accomplishing the abstractions which he recommended, fur¬ nished of itself a strong argument against the soundness of his doctrines.1 The proper an¬ swer to this objection does not seem to have oc¬ curred to him, nor, so far as I know, to any of his successors;—that the abstractions of the understanding are totally different from the ab¬ stractions of the imagination i and that we may reason with most logical correctness about things considered apart, which it is impossible, even in thought, to conceive as separated from each other. His own speculations concerning the indissolubility of the union established in the mind between the sensations of colour and the primary qualities of extension and figure, might have furnished him, on this occasion, with a tri¬ umphant reply to his adversaries; not to men¬ tion that the variety of metaphors, equally fitted to denote the same intellectual powers and ope¬ rations, might have been urged as a demonstra¬ tive proof, that none of these metaphors have any connection with the general laws to which it is the business of the philosopher to trace the mental phenomena. When Descartes established it as a general principle, that nothing conceivable by the power of imagination could throw any light on the operations of thought (a principle which I consider as ex¬ clusively his own), he laid the foundation-stone of the Experimental Philosophy of the Human Mind. That the same truth had been previous¬ ly perceived, more or less distinctly, by Bacon and others, appears probable from the general complexion of their speculations; but which of them has expressed it with equal precision, or laid it down as a fundamental maxim in their logic ? It is for this reason, that I am disposed to date the origin of the true Philosophy of Mind from the Principia of Descartes rather 1 See, in particular, Gassendi Opera, Tom. III. pp. 300, 301 Lugduni, 1058. 68 preliminary dissertations. than from the Organon of Bacon, or the Essay of Locke ; without, however, meaning to com¬ pare the French author with our two countiy- men, either as a contributor to our stock of facts relating to the intellectual phenomena, or as the author of any important conclusion concerning the general laws to which they may he referred. It is mortifying to reflect on the inconceivably small number of subsequent inquirers by whom the spirit of this cardinal maxim has been fully seized; and that, even in our own times, the old and inveterate prejudice to which it is op¬ posed, should not only have been revived with success, but should have been very generally re¬ garded as an original and profound discovery in metaphysical science. These circumstances must plead my apology for the space I have as¬ signed to the Cartesian Metaphysics in the crowded historical picture which I am at present attempting to sketch. The fulness of illustra¬ tion which I have bestowed on the works of the master, Avill enable me to pass over those of his disciples, and even of his antagonists, with a correspondent brevity.1 After having said so much of the singular merits of Descartes as the father of genuine me¬ taphysics, it is incumbent on me to add, that his errors in this science were on a scale ol propor¬ tionate magnitude. Of these the most promi¬ nent (for I must content myself with barely mentioning a few of essential importance) were his obstinate rejection of all speculations about final causes;2 his hypothesis concerning the lower animals, which he considered as mere ma¬ chines;3 4 his doctrine of innate ideas, as under¬ stood and expounded by himself;* his noted para¬ dox of placing the essence of mind in thinking, and of matter in extension ;5 and his new modi¬ fication of the ideal theory of perception, adopt¬ ed afterwards, with some very slight changes, by Malebranche, Locke, Berkeley, and Hume.0 To some of these errors I shall have occasion to refer in the sequel of this Discourse. The fore¬ going slight enumeration is sufficient for my present purpose. In what I have hitherto said of Descartes, I have taken no notice of his metaphysico-physio- logical theories relative to the connection be¬ tween soul and body. Of these theories, how¬ ever, groundless and puerile as they are, it is necessary for me, before I proceed farther, to say a few words, on account of their extensive and lasting influence on the subsequent history of the science of Mind, not only upon the Con¬ tinent, but in our own island. The hypothesis of Descartes, which assigns to the soul for its principal seat the pineal gland or conarion, is known to every one who has perused 1 The Cartesian doctrine concerning the secondary qualities of matter, is susceptible of various other important applica¬ tions. Might it not be employed, at least as an argumcnlum ad homincm against Mr Hume and others, who, admitting this part of the Cartesian system, seem nevertheless to have a secret leaning to the scheme of materialism ? Mr Hume has somewhere spoken of that little agitation of the brain xve call thought. If it be unphilosophical to confound our sensations of co- lour, of heat, and of cold, with such qualities as extension, figure, and solidity, is it not, if possible, still moie so, to con¬ found with these qualities the phenomena of thought, of volition, and of moral emotion ? , 2 It is not unworthy of notice, that, in spite of his own logical rules, Descartes sometimes seems insensibly to adopt, on this subject, the common ideas and feelings of mankind. Several instances ot this occur in his treatise on the Passions, where he offers various conjectures concerning the uses to which they are subservient. Ihe following sentence is more peculiarly remarkable : “ Mihi persuadere nequeo, naturam indedisse hominibus ullum affectum qui semper vitiosuo sit, nullumque usum bonuni et laudabilem habeat.”—Art. clxxv. , 3 This hypothesis never gained much ground in England ; and yet a late writer of distinguished eminence m some branches of science, has plainly intimated that, in his opinion, the balance of probabilities inclined in its favour. ‘ I omit mentioning other animals here,” says Mr Kirwan in his Metaphysical Essays, “ as it is at least doubtful whether they are not mere automatons."—-Met. Essays, p. 41. Eond. 1809. _ _ 4 I have added the clause in Italics, because, in Descartes’ reasonings on this question, there is no inconsiderable portion of most important truth, debased by a large and manifest alloy of error. _ 5 To this paradox may be traced many of the conclusions of the author, both on physical and on metaphysical subjects. One of the most characteristical features, indeed, of his genius, is the mathematical concatenation of his opinions, even on questions which, at first sight, seem the most remote from each other; a circumstance which, when combined with the ex¬ traordinary perspicuity of Ins style, completely accounts for the strong hold his philosophy took of every mind, thoroughly initiated, at an early period of life, in its principles and doctrines. In consequence of conceiving the essence ot matter to consist in extension, he was necessarily obliged to maintain the doctrine of a universal plenum; upon which doctrine the theory of the Vortices came to be grafted by a very short and easy process. The same idea forced him, at the very outset of his Metaphysical Meditations, to assert, much more dogmatically than his premises seem to warrant, the non-extension of Mind; and led him on many occasions to blend, very illogically, this comparatively disputable dogma, with the facts he has to state concerning the mental phenomena. 4 See Note N. DISSERTATION FIRST. f,9 the Alma of Prior. It is not, perhaps, equally known, that the circumstance which determined him to fix on this particular spot, was the very plausible consideration, that, among the different parts of the brain, this was the only one he could find, which, being single and central, was fitted for the habitation of a being, of which he conceived unity and indivisibility to be essen¬ tial and obvious attributes.1 In what manner the animal spirits, by their motions forwards and backwards in the nervous tubes, keep up the communication between this gland and the dif¬ ferent parts of the body, so as to produce the phenomena of perception, memory, imagination, and muscular motion, he has attempted parti¬ cularly to explain; describing the processes by which these various effects are accomplished, with as decisive a tone of authority, as if he had been demonstrating experimentally the circula¬ tion of the blood. How curious to meet with such speculations in the works of the same phi¬ losopher, who had so clearly perceived the ne¬ cessity, in studying the laws of Mind, of ab¬ stracting entirely from the analogies of Matter; and who, at the outset of his inquiries, had car¬ ried his scepticism so far, as to require a proof even of the existence of his own body ! To those, however, who reflect with attention on the method adopted by Descartes, this inconsist¬ ency will not appear so inexplicable as at first sight may be imagined; inasmuch as the same scepticism which led him to suspend his faith in his intellectual faculties till he had once proved to his satisfaction, from the necessary veracity of God, that these faculties were to be regarded as divine oracles, prepared him, in all the sub¬ sequent steps of his progress, to listen to the suggestions of his own fallible judgment, with more than common credulity and confidence. The ideas of Descartes, respecting the com¬ munication between soul and body, are now so universally rejected, that I should not have al¬ luded to them here, had it not been for their manifest influence in producing, at the distance of a century, the rival hypothesis of Dr Hartley. The first traces of this hypothesis occur in some queries of Sir Isaac Newton, which he was pro¬ bably induced to propose, less from the convic¬ tion of his own mind, than from a wish to turn the attention of philosophers to an examination of the correspondent part of the Cartesian sys¬ tem. Not that I would be understood to deny that this great man seems, on more than one oc¬ casion, to have been so far misled by the ex¬ ample of his predecessor, as to indulge himself in speculating on questions altogether unsuscep¬ tible of solution. In the present instance, how¬ ever, there cannot, I apprehend, be a doubt, that it was the application made by Descartes of the old theory of animal spirits, to explain the mental phenomena, which led Newton into that train of thinking which served as the ground¬ work of Hartley’s Theory of Vibrations.2 It would be useless to dwell longer on the re- 1 See in particular, the treatise De Passionibus, Art. 31. 32. See also Note O. 2 The physiological theory of Descartes, concerning the connection between soul and body, was adopted, together with some of his sounder opinions, by a contemporary English philosopher, Mr Smith of Cambridge, whom I had occasion to mention in a former note ; and that, for some time after the beginning of the eighteenth century, it continued to afford one of the chief subjects of controvers}r between the two English universities, the Alma of Prior affords incontestable evi¬ dence. From the same poem it appears, how much the reveries of Descartes about the seat of the soul, contributed to wean the wits of Cambridge from their former attachment to the still more incomprehensible pneumatology of the schoolmen. Here Matthew said, Alma in verse, in prose the mmd By Aristotle’s pen defin’d, Throughout the body squat or tall, Is, bona fide, all in all, And yet, slap-dash, is all again In every sinew, nerve, and vein ; Buns here and there like Hamlet’s Ghost, While everywhere she rules the roast. This system, Bichard, we are told, The men of Oxford firmly hold ; The Cambridge wits, you know, deny With ipse dixit to comply. They say, (for in good truth they speak With small respect of that old Greek) That putting all his words together, * ’Tis three blue beans in one blue bladder. 70 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. veries of a philosopher, much better known to the learned of the present age by the boldness of his exploded errors, than by the profound and important truths contained in his works. At the period when he appeared, it may perhaps be questioned, whether the truths which he taught, or the errors into which he fell, were most in¬ structive to the world. The controversies pro¬ voked by the latter had certainly a more imme¬ diate and palpable effect in awakening a general spirit of free inquiry. To this consideration may be added an ingenious and not altogether unsound remark of D’Alembert, that “ when absurd opinions are become inveterate, it is sometimes necessary to replace them by other errors, if nothing better can be done. Such (he continues) are the uncertainty and the vanity of the human mind, that it has always need of an opinion on which it may lean; it is a child to whom a play-thing must occasionally be present¬ ed, in order to get out of its hands a mischie¬ vous weapon; the play-thing will soon be aban¬ doned, when the light of reason begins to dawn.1 Among the opponents of Descartes, Gassendi was one of the earliest, and by far the most for¬ midable. No two philosophers were ever more strongly contrasted, both in point of talents and of temper; the former as far superior to the latter in originality of genius—in powers of con¬ centrated attention to the phenomena of the in¬ ternal world—in classical taste—in moral sensi¬ bility, and in all the rarer gifts of the mind, as he fell short of him in erudition—in industry as a book-maker—in the justness of his logical views, so far as the phenomena of the material universe are concerned—and, in general, in those literary qualities and attainments, of which the bulk of mankind either are, or think them¬ selves best qualified to form an estimate. The reputation of Gassendi, accordingly, seems to have been at its height in his own lifetime ; that of Descartes made but little progress, till a con¬ siderable time after his death. The comparative justness of Gassendi’s views in natural philosophy may be partly, perhaps chiefly, ascribed to his diligent study of Bacon’s works ; which Descartes (if he ever read them), has nowhere alluded to in his writings. This extraordinary circumstance in the character of Descartes is the more unaccountable, that not only Gassendi, but some of his other corre¬ spondents, repeatedly speak of Bacon in terms which one should think could scarcely have fail¬ ed to induce him to satisfy his own mind whe¬ ther their encomiums were well or ill founded. One of these, while he contents himself, from very obvious feelings of delicacy, with mention¬ ing the Chancellor of England as the person who, before the time of Descartes, had entertained the justest notions about the method of prose¬ cuting physical inquiries, takes occasion, in the same letter, to present him, in the form of a friendly admonition from himself, with the fol¬ lowing admirable summary of the instauratio magna. If the fundamental doubt of Descartes be admit- 5 The limited numhpr nf /hf1 ° f P ll osoPhers (who were distinguished by the name of Egoists), is unavoidable. face of the s-lohe imVlu np if eSi of hunlorous tales, mid even of jests, which, it should seem, are in circulation over the race or the globe, might perhaps be alleged as an additional confirmation of this idea. 80 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. and only o/ice, the pleasure of a short interview. “ The conversation,” we are told, “ turned on the non-existence of matter. Malebianche, who had an inflammation in his lungs, and whom Berkeley found preparing a medicine in his cell, and cooking it in a small pipkin, exerted his voice so violently in the heat of their dispute, that he increased his disorder, which carried him off a few days after.”1 It is impossible not to regret, that of this interview there is no other recordor rather, that Berkeley had not made it the groundwork of one of his own dialogues. Fine as his imagination was, it could scarcely have added to the picturesque effect of the real scene.2 Anthony Arnauld, whom I have already men¬ tioned as one of the theological antagonists of Malehranche, is also entitled to a distinguished rank among the French philosophers of this period. In his book on true and false ideas, writ¬ ten in opposition to Malebranche’s scheme of our seeing all things in God, he is acknowledg¬ ed by Dr Reid to have struck the first mortal blow at the ideal theory ; and to have appioxi- mated very nearly to his own refutation of this ancient and inveterate prejudice.3 A step so important would, of itself, be sufficient to esta¬ blish his claim to a place in literary history ; but what chiefly induces me again to bring forward his name, is the reputation he has so justly ac¬ quired by his treatise, entitled, The Art of Thinking ;4 a treatise written by Arnauld, in conjunction with his friend Nicole, and of which (considering the time when it appeared) it is hardly possible to estimate the merits too highly. No publication, certainly, prior to Locke’s Essay, can be named, containing so much good sense, and so little nonsense on the science of Logic ; and very few have since appeared on the same subject, which can be justly preferred to it, in point of practical utility. If the author had lived in the present age, or had been less fetter¬ ed by a prudent regard to existing prejudices, the technical part would probably have been re¬ duced within a still narrower compass ; but even there, he has contrived to substitute for the puerile and contemptible examples of common logicians, several interesting illustrations from the physical discoveries of his immediate pre- ^ Thfs interview happenedin 1715, when Berkeley was in the thirty-first, and Malebranche in the seventy-seventh year of his age. What a change in the state of the philosophical world (whether for the better or worse is a difteren Question') has taken place in the course of the intervening century ! •*. r* 4.r.* i • .£» q Dr Warburton, who, even when he thinks the most unsoundly, always possesses the rare merit of thinking for himself, is one of the ver^ few English authors who have spoken of Malebranche with the respect due to his extraordinary talents “ AlWousayof Malebranche,” he observes in a letter to Dr Hurd, “ is strictly true ; he is an admirable writer. There is somethin/very different in the fortune of Malebranche and Locke. When Malebranche first appeared, it was with a general apnLse and admiration ; when Locke first published his Essay, he had hardly a single^ approver. Now Locke fsSersTrd Malebranche silnk into obscurity. All this maybe easily accounted for. The intrinsic merit of either was out of the question. But Malebranche supported his first appearance on a philosophy in the highest vogue , that phi- losophy has been^verturned by the Newtonian, and Malebranche has fallen with his master. It was to no purpose to tell the world, that Malebranche could stand without him. The public never examines so narrowly. Not but that there was another cause sufficient to do the business ; and that is, his debasing Ins noble work with his ^stein °^seei^^ things in God. When this happens to a great author, one half of his readers out of folly, the other out of malice, d veil only on the unsound part, and forget the other, or use all their arts to have it forgotten. , , ri-0v,riTlfllir n^mself bv “But the sage Locke supported himself by no system on the one hand; nor, on the other, did he dishonour himself by any whimsies. The consequence of which was, that, neither following the fashion, nor str^mg the imagination, he, at first, had neither followers nor admirers; but being everywhere clear, and everywhere solid, he at length worked his way and afterwards was subject to no reverses. He was not affected by the new fashions in philosophy, who leaned upon none of the old ; nor did he afford ground for the after-attacks of envy and folly by any fanciful hypotheses, which, when grown stale, are the most nauseous of all things.” , The foregoing reflections on the opposite fates of these two philosophers, do honour on the who « tration ; but the unqualified panegyric on Locke will be now very generally allowed to furnish an additional example of “ that national spirit? which,” according to Hume, “ forms the great happiness of the English, and pleads them to bestow on all their eminent writers such praises and acclamations, as may often appear partial and exceasive. u 3 The following very concise and accurate summary of Arnauld’s doctrine concerning ideas, is given by rue -er. tonius Arnaldus, ut argumenta Malebranchii eo fortius everteret, peculiarem sententiam detendit, asseruitque, ideas earum- nue nerceptiones esse unum idemque, et non nisi relationibus differre. Ideam scilicet esse, quatenus ad objectum refertur quod mens considerat; perceptionem vero, quatenus ad ipsam mentem quae percipit; dupheem tamen illam relatione unam pertinere mentis modificationem.”-^. Phil, de Jdeis, pp. 247. 248. Anthony Arnauld farther held that “ Mate¬ rial things are perceived immediately by the mind, without the intervention of ideas. —{Hist, de Ideis, p. 26.) In Hus e. spect his°doctrine coincided exactly with that of Reid. -1 More commonly known by the name of the Port-Royal Logic. * DISSERTATION FIRST. 81 dceessors: and has indulged himself in some short excursions, which excite a lively regret that he had not, more frequently and freely, given scope to his original reflections. Among these excursions, the most valuable, in my opi¬ nion, is the twentieth chapter of the third part, which deserves the attention of every logical student, as an important and instructive supple¬ ment to the enumeration of sophisms given by Aristotle.1 2 The soundness of judgment, so eminently displayed in the Art of Thinking, forms a curi¬ ous contrast to that passion for theological con¬ troversy, and that zeal for what he conceived to be the purity of the Faith, which seems to have been the ruling passions of the author’s mind. He lived to the age of eighty-three, con¬ tinuing to write against Malebranche’s opinions concerning Nature and Grace, to his last hour. “ He died,” says his biographer, <{ in an obscure retreat at Brussels, in 1692, without fortune, and even without the comfort of a servant.; he, whose nephew had been a Minister of State, and who might himself have been a Cardinal. The pleasure of being able to publish his senti¬ ments, was to him a sufficient recompense.” Nicole, his friend and companion in arms, worn out at length with these incessant disputes, ex¬ pressed a wish to retire from the field, and to enjoy repose. {£ Repose /” replied Arnauld; “ won’t you have the whole of eternity to re¬ pose in ?” An anecdote which is told of his infancy, when considered in connection with his subse¬ quent life, affords a good illustration of the force of impressions received in the first dawn of reason. He was amusing himself one day with some childish sport, in the library of the Cardi¬ nal du Perron, when he requested of the Cardi¬ nal to give him a pen :—C{ And for what pur¬ pose ?” said the Cardinal.— ritory wanted in point of scenery and of climate. In this respect, the coincidence between the taste of Locke and that of Descartes throws a pleasing light on the characters of both. The plan of the Essay on Human Understanding is said to have been formed as early as 1670; bat the various employments and avocations of the Author prevented him from finishing it till 1687, when he fortunately availed himself of the leisure which his exile in Holland afforded him, to complete his long meditated design. He re¬ turned to England soon after the Revolution, and published the first edition of his work in 1690; the busy and diversified scenes through which he had passed during its progress, having probably contributed, not less than the acade¬ mical retirement in which he had spent his youth, to enhance its peculiar and characte- ristical merits. Of the circumstances which gave occasion to this great and memorable undertaking, the fol¬ lowing interesting account is given in the Pre¬ fatory Epistle to the Reader. “ Five or six friends, meeting at my chamber, and discoursing on a subject very remote from this, found them¬ selves quickly at a stand, by the difficulties that rose on every side. After we had a while puzzled ourselves, without coming any nearer a resolution of those doubts which perplexed us, it came into my thoughts that we took a wrong course, and that, before we set ourselves upon inquiries of that nature, it was necessary to ex¬ amine our own abilities, and see what objects our understandings were, or were not, fitted to deal with. This I proposed to the company, who all readily assented, and thereupon it was agreed, that this should be our first inquiry. Some hasty and undigested thoughts on a sub¬ ject I had never before considered, which I set down against our next meeting, gave the first entrance into this discourse, which having been thus begun by chance, was continued by en¬ treaty; written by incoherent parcels, and, after long intervals of neglect, resumed again as my humour or occasions permitted; and at last in retirement, where an attendance on my health gave me leisure, it was brought into that order thou now seest it.” Mr Locke afterwards informs us, that “ when he first put pen to paper, he thought all he should have to say on this matter would have been contained in one sheet, but that the far¬ ther he went the larger prospect he had ;—new discoveries still leading him on, till his book grew insensibly to the bulk it now appears in.” On comparing the Essay on Human Under¬ standing with the foregoing account of its origin and progress, it is curious to observe, that it is the fourth and last book alone which bears di¬ rectly on the author’s principal object. In this book, it is further remarkable, that there are few, if any references to the preceding parts of the Essay; insomuch that it might have been published separately, without being less intel¬ ligible than it is. Hence, it seems not unreason¬ able to conjecture, that it was the first part of the work in the order of composition, and that it contains those leading and fundamental thoughts which offered themselves to the au¬ thor’s mind, when he first began to reflect on the friendly conversation which gave rise to his philosophical researches. The inquiries in the first and second books, which are of a much more abstract, as well as scholastic nature, than the sequel of the work, probably opened gradu¬ ally on the author’s mind in proportion as he studied his subject with a closer and more con¬ tinued attention. They relate chiefly to the origin and to the technical classification of our ideas, frequently branching out into collateral, and sometimes into digressive discussions, with¬ out much regard to method or connection. The third book (by far the most important of the whole), where the nature, the use, and the abuse of language are so clearly and happily illustrated, seems, from Locke’s own account, to have been a sort of after-thought; and the two excellent chapters on the Association of Ideas and on En¬ thusiasm (the former of which has contributed, as much as any thing else in Locke’s writings, to the subsequent progress of Metaphysical Phi¬ losophy, were printed, for the first time, in the fourth edition of the Essay. I would not be understood, by these remarks, to undervalue the two first books. All that I have said amounts to this, that the subjects which they treat of are seldom susceptible of any prac- DISSERTATION FIRST. 103 tical application to the conduct of the under¬ standing ; and that the author has adopted a new phraseology of his own, where, in some in¬ stances, he might have much more clearly con¬ veyed his meaning without any departure from the ordinary forms of speech. But although these considerations render the two first hooks inferior in point of general utility to the two last, they do not materially detract from their merit, as a precious accession to the theory of the Human Mind. On the contrary, 1 do not hesitate to consider them as the richest con¬ tribution of well-observed and well-described facts, which was ever bequeathed to this branch of science by a single individual, and as the indisputable, though not always acknowledged, source of some of the most refined conclusions, with respect to the intellectual phenomena, which have been since brought to light by succeeding inquirers. After the details given by Locke himself, of the circumstances in which his Essay was be¬ gun and completed; more especially, after what he has stated of the cc discontinued way of writ¬ ing,” imposed on him by the avocations of a busy and unsettled life, it cannot be thought surprising, that so very little of method should appear in the disposition of his materials; or that the opinions which, on different occasions, he has pronounced on the same subject, should not always seem perfectly steady and consistent. In these last cases, however, I am inclined to think that the inconsistencies, if duly reflected on, would be found rather apparent than real. It is but seldom that a writer possessed of the powerful and upright mind of Locke, can rea¬ sonably be suspected of stating propositions in direct contradiction to each other. The pre¬ sumption is, that, in each of these propositions, there is a mixture of truth, and that the error lies chiefly in the unqualified manner in which the truth is stated; proper allowances not being made, during the fervour of composition, for the partial survey taken of the objects from a particular point of view. Perhaps it would not be going too far to assert, that most of the seem¬ ing contradictions which occur in authors ani¬ mated with a sincere love of truth, might be fairly accounted for by the different aspects Avhich the same object presented to them upon different occasions. In reading such authors, accordingly, when we meet with discordant ex¬ pressions, instead of indulging ourselves in the captiousness of verbal criticism, it w ould better become us carefully and candidly to collate the questionable passages; and to study so to re¬ concile them by judicious modifications and cor¬ rections, as to render the oversights and mis¬ takes of our illustrious guides subservient to the precision and soundness of our own conclusions. In the case of Locke, it must be owned, that this is not always an easy task, as the limitations of some of his most exceptionable propositions are to be collected, not from the context, but from different and widely separated parts of his Essay.1 2 In a work thus composed by snatches (to bor¬ row a phrase of the author’s), it was not to be expected, that he should be able accurately to draw the line between his own ideas, and the hints for which he was indebted to others. To those who are well acquainted with his specula¬ tions, it must appear evident, that he had studied diligently the metaphysical writings both of Hobbes and of Gassendi; and that he was no stranger to the Essays of Montaigne, to the phi¬ losophical works of Bacon, or to Malebranche’s Inquiry after Truth.9, That he was familiarly conversant with the Cartesian system may be presumed from what we are told by his bio- 1 That Locke himself was sensible that some of his expressions required explanation, and was anxious that his opi¬ nions should be judged of rather from the general tone and spirit of his work, than from detached and isolated proposi¬ tions, may be inferred from a passage in one of his notes, where he replies to the animadversions of one of his antagonists (the Reverend Mr Lowde), who had accused him of calling in question the immutability of moral distinctions. “ But (says Locke) the good man does well, and as becomes his calling, to be watchful in such points, and to take the alarm, even at expressions which, standing alone by themselves, might sound ill, and be suspected.”—(Locke’s Works, Vol. II. p. 93. Note.) . . 2 Mr Addison has remarked, that Malebranche had the start of Locke, by several years, in his notions on the subject of Duration (Spectator, No. 94.) Some other coincidences, not less remarkable, might be easily pointed out in the opinions of the English and of the French philosopher. 104 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. graplier, that it was this which first inspired him with a disgust at the jargon of the schools, and led him into that train of thinking which he after¬ wards prosecuted so successfully. I do not, however, recollect that he has anywhere in his Essay mentioned the name of any one of these authors.1 It is probable, that, when he sat down to write, he found the result of his youth¬ ful reading so completely identified with the fruits of his subsequent reflections, that it was impossible for him to attempt a separation of the one from the other ; and that he was thus occasionally led to mistake the treasures of me¬ mory for those of invention. That this was really the case, may be farther presumed from the peculiar and original cast of his phraseo- logy, which, though in general careless and un¬ polished, has always the merit of that charac- teristical unity and raciness of style, which de¬ monstrate, that, while he was writing, he con¬ ceived himself to be drawing only from his own resources. With respect to his style, it may be further ob¬ served, that it resembles that of a well educated and well informed man of the world, rather than of a recluse student who had made an object of the art of composition. It everywhere abounds with colloquial expressions, which he had pro¬ bably caught by the ear from those whom he considered as models of good conversation; and hence, though it now seems somewhat antiqua¬ ted, and not altogether suited to the dignity of the subject, it may be presumed to have contri¬ buted its share towards his great object of turn¬ ing the thoughts of his contemporaries to logi¬ cal and metaphysical inquiries. The author of the Characteristics, who will not be accused of an undue partiality for Locke, acknowledges, in strong terms, the favourable reception which his book had met with among the higher classes. “ I am not sorry, however,” says Shaftesbury, to one of his correspondents, “ that I lent you Locke’s Essay, a book that may as well qualify men for business and the world, as for the sciences and a university. No one has done more to¬ wards the recalling of philosophy from barbarity, into use and practice of the world, and into the company of the better and politer sort, who might well be ashamed of it in its other dress. No one has opened a better and clearer way to reasoning.”2 In a passage of one of Warburton’s letters to Hurd, which I had occasion to quote in the first part of this Dissertation, it is stated as a fact, that, £C when Locke first published his Essay, he had neither followers nor admirers, and hardly a single approver.” I cannot help suspecting very strongly the correctness of this assertion, not only from the flattering terms in which the Essay is mentioned by Shaftesbury in the foregoing quotation, and from the frequent allusions to its doctrines by Addison and other popular writers of the same period, but from the unexampled sale of the book, during the fourteen years which elapsed between its publication and Locke’s death. Four editions were printed in the space of ten years, and three others must have ap¬ peared in the space of the next four; a refer¬ ence being made to the sixth edition by the au¬ thor himself, in the epistle to the reader, prefix¬ ed to all the subsequent impressions. A copy of the thirteenth edition, printed as early as 1748, is now lying before me. So rapid and so extensive a circulation of a work, on a subject so little within the reach of common readers, is the best proof of the established popularity of the author’s name, and of the respect generally entertained for his talents and his opinions. That the Essay on Human Understanding should have excited some alarm in the University of Oxford, was no more than the author had rea¬ son to expect from his boldness as a philosophi¬ cal reformer; from his avowed zeal in the cause of liberty, both civil and religious; from the suspected orthodoxy of his Theological Creed; and (it is but candid to add) from the apparent 1 The name of Hobbes occurs in Mr Locke’s Reply to the Bishop of Worcester. See the Notes on his Essay, B. iv. c. 3. It is curious that he classes Hobbes and Spinoza together, as writers of the same stamp ; and that he disclaims any intimate acquaintance with the works of'bither. “ I am not so well read in Hobbes and Spinoza as to be able to say what were their opinions in this matter, but possibly there be those who will think your Lordship’s authority of more use than those just¬ ly decried names,” &c. &c. ’ See Shaftesbury’s First Letter to a Student at the University. DISSERTATION FIRST. 105 coincidence of his ethical doctrines with those of Hobbes.1 It is more difficult to account for the long continuance, in that illustrious seat of learn¬ ing, of the prejudice against the logic of Locke (by far the most valuable part of his work), and of that partiality for the logic of Aristotle, of which Locke has so fully exposed the futility. In the University of Cambridge, on the other hand, the Essay on Human Understanding was, for many years, regarded with a reverence ap¬ proaching to idolatry; and to the authority of some distinguished persons connected with that learned body may be traced (as will afterwards appear) the origin of the greater part of the ex¬ travagancies which, towards the close of the last century, were grafted on Locke’s errors, by the disciples of Hartley, of Law, of Priestley, of Tooke, and of Darwin.2 To a person who now reads with attention and candour the work in question, it is much more easy to enter into the prejudices which at first opposed themselves to its complete success, than to conceive how it should so soon have acquired its just celebrity. Something, I suspect, must be ascribed to the political importance which Mr Locke had previously acquired as the champion of religious toleration; as the great apostle of the Revolution ; and as the intrepid opposer of a tyranny which had been recently overthrown. In Scotland, where the liberal constitution of the universities has been always peculiarly fa¬ vourable to the diffusion of a free and eclectic spirit of inquiry, the philosophy of Locke seems very early to have struck its roots, deeply and permanently, into a kindly and congenial soil. Nor were the errors of this great man implicit¬ ly adopted from a blind reverence for his name. The works of Descartes still continued to be studied and admired; and the combined systems of the English and the French metaphysicians served, in many respects, to correct what was faulty, and to supply what was deficient, in each. As to the ethical principles of Locke, where they appear to lean towards Hobbism, a powerful antidote against them was already prepared in the Treatise De Jure Belli et Pads, which was then universally and deservedly re¬ garded in this country as the best introduction that had yet appeared to the study of moral science. If Scotland, at this period, produced no eminent authors in these branches of learn¬ ing, it was not from want of erudition or of ta¬ lents ; nor yet from the narrowness of mind in¬ cident to the inhabitants of remote and insula¬ ted regions; but from the almost insuperable difficulty of writing in a dialect, which imposed upon an author the double task of at once ac¬ quiring a new language, and of unlearning his own.3 4 The success of Locke’s Essay, in some parts of the Continent, was equally remarkable; owing, no doubt, in the first instance, to the very accurate translation of it into the French language by Coste, and to the eagerness with which every thing proceeding from the author of the Letters m Toleration^ may be presumed to 1 “ It was proposed at a meeting of the heads of houses of the University of Oxford, to censure and discourage the reading of Locke’s Essay; and, after various debates among themselves, it was concluded, that each head of a house should endeavour to prevent its being read in his college, without coming to any public censure.”—(See Des Maizeaux’s note on a letter from Locke to Collins—Locke’s Works, Vol. X. p. 284. * I have taken notice, with due praise, in the former part of this discourse, of the metaphysical speculations of John Smith, Henry More, and Ralph Cudworth ; all of them members and ornaments of the University of Cambridge about the middle of the seventeeth century. They were deeply conversant in the Platonic Philosophy, and applied it with great success in combating the Materialists and Necessitarians of their times. They carried, indeed, some of their Platonic no¬ tions to an excess bordering on mysticism, and may, perhaps, have contributed to give a bias to some of their academical successors towards the opposite extreme. A very pleasing and interesting account of the characters of these amiable and ingenious men, and of the spirit of their philosophy, is given by Burnet in the History of his Own Times. To the credit of Smith and of More it may be added, that they were among the first in England to perceive and to acknowledge the merits of the Cartesian Metaphysics. 3 Note S. 4 The principle of religious toleration was at that time very imperfectly admitted, even by those philosophers who were the most zealously attached to the cause of civil liberty. The great Scottish lawyer and statesman, Lord Stair, himself no mean philosopher, and, like Locke, a warm partizan of the Revolution, seems evidently to have regretted the impunity which Spinoza had experienced in Holland, and Hobbes in England. “ Execrabilis ille Atheus Spinosa adeo impudens est, ut affirmet omnia esse absolute necessaria, et nihil quod est, fuit, aut erit, aliter fieri potuisse, in quo omnes superiores Atheos excessit, aperte negans omnem Deitatem, nihilque pneter potentias natune agnoscens. “ Vaninus Deitatem non aperte negavit, sed causam illius prodidit, in tractatu quem edidit, argumenta pro Dei existen- tia tanquam futilia et vana rejiciens, adferendo contrarias omnes rationes per modum objectionum, easque prosequendo ut DISS. I. PART II. O 106 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. have been read by the multitude of learned and enlightened refugees, whom the revocation of the edict of Nantz forced to seek an asylum in Protestant countries. In Holland, where Locke was personally known to the most distinguish¬ ed characters, both literary and political, his work was read and praised by a discerning few, with all the partiality of friendship;1 but it does not seem to have made its way into the schools till a period considerably later. The doctrines of Descartes, at first so vehemently opposed in that country, were now so completely triumph¬ ant, both among philosophers and divines,2 that it was difficult for a new reformer to obtain a hearing. The case was very nearly similar in Germany, where Leibnitz (who always speaks coldly of Locke’s Essay)5 was then looked up to as the great oracle in every branch of learn¬ ing and of science. If I am not mistaken, it was in Switzerland, where (as Gibbon observes) “ the intermixture of sects had rendered the clergy acute and learned on controversial topics,” that Locke’s real merits were first appreciated on the Continent with a discriminating impartia¬ lity. In Crousaz’s Treatise of Logic (a book which, if not distinguished by originality of ge¬ nius, is at least strongly marked with the sound and unprejudiced judgment of the author), we everywhere trace the influence of Locke’s doc¬ trines ; and, at the same time, the effects of the Cartesian Metaphysics, in limiting those hasty expressions of Locke, which have been so often misinterpreted by his followers.4 Nor do Crou¬ saz’s academical labours appear to have been less indissolubiles videantur; postea tamen larvam exult, et atheismum clare professus est, et justissime in inclyta urbe ThOEOSA DAMNATUS E8T ET CREMATES. “ Horrendus Hobbesius tertius erat atheismi promotor, qui omnia principia moralia et politica subvertit, eorumque ioco naturaiem vim et humana pacta, ut prima principia moralitatis, societatis, et politic! regiminis substituit: nec ta¬ mer Spirosa aut Hobbies, cieamvis ir regioribes reeormatis vixerirt et mortei sirt, redem exempla FACTI SERT IR ATHEOREM TERROREM, ET RE VEL EEEAM P-®RAM SERSERIRT.” (Physiol. Nova ExperimentallS. Lugd. Batav. 16G6, pp. 16, 17-) 1 Among those whose society Locke chiefly cultivated while in Holland, was the celebrated Le Clerc, the author of the BiUiotheque Universelle, and the BiUiutheque Choisie, besides many other learned and ingenious publications. He appears to have been warmly attached to Locke, and embraced the fundamental doctrines of his Essay without any slavish deference for his authority. Though he fixed his residence at Amsterdam, where he taught Philosophy and the Belles Lettres, he was a native of Geneva, where he also received his academical education. He is, therefore, to be numbered with Locke’s Swiss disciples. I shall have occasion to speak of him more at length afterwards, when I come to mention his controversy with Bayle. At present, I shall only observe, that his Eloge on Locke was published in the Biblioth&que Choisie (Anne'e 1705,) Tom. VI.; and that some important remarks on the Essay on Human Understanding, particularly on the chapter on Power, are to be found in the 12th Vol. of the same work (Anne'e 1707-) 2 Quamvis huic sec tie (Cartesiame) initio acriter se opponerent Theologi et Philosophi Belgse, in Academiis tamen eorum hodie (1727,) vix alia, quam Cartesiana principia inculcantur—(Heireccii Elem. Hist. Philosoph.) In Gravesande’s Introductio ad Philosophiam. published in 1736, the name of Locke is not once mentioned. It is probable that this last au¬ thor was partly influenced by his admiration for Leibnitz, whom he servilely followed even in his physical errors. s In Lockio sunt qusedam particularia non male exposita, sed in summa longe aberravit a janua, nec naturam mentis veritatisque intellexit—(Leibritz. Op. Tom. V. p. 355. ed. Dutens.) M. Locke avoit de la subtilite et de Paddresse, et quelque espece de metaphysique superficielle qu’il savoit relever— {Hid. pp. 11, 12.) Heineccius, a native of Saxony, in a Sketch of the History of Philosophy, printed in 1728, omits altogether the name of Locke in his enumeration of the logical and metaphysical writers of modern Europe. In a passage of his logic, where the same author treats of clear and obscure, adequate and inadequate ideas (a subject on which little or nothing of any value had been advanced before Locke), he observes, in a note, “ Debemus hanc Doctrinam Leibnitio, eamque deinde sequutus est illust. Wolfius.” 4 Of the Essay on Human Understanding Crousaz speaks m the following terms : “ Clarissimi, et merito celebratissimi Lockii de Intellectu Humano eximium opus, et auctore suo dignissimum, logicis utilissimis semper annumerabitur.”— {Prcefat.) If Pope had ever looked into this Treatise, he could not have committed so gross a mistake, as to introduce the author into the Dunciad, among Locke’s Aristotelian opponents; a distinction for which Crousaz was probably indebted to his acute strictures on those passages in the Essay on Man, which seem favourable to fatalism. Prompt at the call, around the goddess roll Broad hats, and hoods, and caps, a sable shoal; Thick and more thick the black blockade extends, A hundred head of Aristotle’s friends. Nor wert thou, Isis ! wanting to the day (Though Christ-church long kept prudishly away). Each staunch Polemic, stubborn as a rock, Each fierce Logician, still expelling Locke, Came whip and spur, and dash’d through thm and thick On German Crousaz, and Dutch Burgersdyck. Warburton, with his usual scurrility towards all Pope’s adversaries as well as his own, has called Crousaz a blundering Swiss ; but a very different estimate of his merits has been formed by Gibbon, who seems to have studied his works much more carefully than the Right Reverend Commentator on the Dunciad. “ M. de Crousaz, the adversary of Bayle and Pope, is not distinguished by lively fancy or profound reflection ; and DISSERTATION FIRST. 107 useful than his writings; if a judgment on this point may be formed from the sound philosophi¬ cal principles which he diffused among a nume¬ rous race of pupils. One of these (M. Alla- mand), the friend and correspondent of Gibbon, deserves particularly to be noticed here, on ac¬ count of two letters published in the posthumous works of that historian, containing a criticism on Locke’s argument against innate ideas, so very able and judicious, that it may still be read with advantage by many logicians of no small note in the learned world. Had these letters hap¬ pened to have sooner attracted my attention, I should not have delayed so long to do this tardy j ustice to their merits.1 I am not able to speak with confidence of the period at which Locke’s Essay began to attract public notice in France. Voltaire, in a letter to Horace Walpole, asserts, that he was the first person who made the name of Locke known to his countrymen ;2 but I suspect that this asser¬ tion must be received with considerable quali¬ fications. The striking coincidence between some of Locke’s most celebrated doctrines and those of Gassendi, can scarcely be supposed to have been altogether overlooked by the followers and admirers of the latter ; considering the im¬ mediate and very general circulation given on the Continent to the Essay on Human Understanding, by Coste’s French version. The Gassendists, too, it must be remembered, formed, even before the death of their master, a party formidable in talents as well as in numbers; including, among other distinguished names, those of Moliere,5 even in his own country, at the end of a few years, his name and writings are almost obliterated. But his Philosophy had been formed in the school of Locke, his Divinity in that of Limborch and Le Clerc; in a long and laborious life, several generations of pupils were taught to think, and even to write ; his lessons rescued the Academy of Lausanne from Cal- vinistic prejudices ; and he had the rare merit of diffusing a more liberal spirit among the people of the Pays de Vaud."— (Gibbon’s Memoirs^) In a subsequent passage Gibbon says, “ the logic of Crousaz had prepared me to engage with his master Locke, and his antagonist Bayle ; of whom the former may be used as a bridle, and the latter applied as a spur to the curiosity of a young philosopher.”—(IUd.) The following details, independently of their reference to Crousaz, are so interesting in themselves, and afford so strong a testimony to the utility of logical studies, when rationally conducted, that I am tempted to transcribe them. “ December 1755. In finishing this year, I must remark how favourable it was to my studies. In the space of eight months, I learned the principles of drawing; made myself completely master of the French and Latin languages, with which I was very superficially acquainted before, and wrote and translated a great deal in both ; read Cicero’s Epistles ad Familiares, his Brutus, all his Orations, his Dialogues de Amicitia et de Senectute; Terence twice, and Pliny’s Epistles. In French, Giannoni’s History of Naples, 1’Abbe Barrier’s Mythology, and M. Iloehat’s Memoires sur la Suisse, and wrote a very ample relation of my tour. I likewise began to study Greek, and went through the grammar. I began to make very large collections of what I read. But what I esteem most of all,—from the perusal and meditation of De Crousaz’s logic, I not only understood the principles of that science, but formed my mind to a habit of thinking and reasoning, I had no idea of before.” After all, I very readily grant, that Crousaz’s logic is chiefly to be regarded as the work of a sagacious and enlightened compiler; but even this (due allowance being made for the state of philosophy when it appeared) is no mean praise. “ Good sense (as Gibbon has very truly observed) is a quality of mind hardly less rare than genius.” 1 For some remarks of M. Allamand, which approach very near to Reid’s Objections to the Ideal Theory, See Note T. Of this extraordinary man Gibbon gives the following account in his Journal; “ C’est un ministre dans le Pays de Vaud, et un des plus beaux genies que je connoisse. II a voulu embrasser tous les genres ; mais c’est la. Philosophic qu’il a le plus approfondi. Sur toutes les questions il s’est fait des systemes, ou du moins des argumens toujours originaux et tou- jours ingenieux. Ses idees sont fines et lumineuses, son expression heureuse et facile. On lui reproche avec raison trop de rafinement et de subtilitd dans 1’esprit; trop de fierte, trop d’ambition, et trop de violence dans le caractere. Cet homme, qui auroit pu eclairer ou troubler une nation, vit et mourra dans 1’obscurite'.” It is of the same person that Gibbon sneeringly says, in the words of Vossius, “ Est sacrificulus in pago, et rusticos decipit.” 2 “ Je peux vous assurer qu’avant moi personne en France ne connoissoit la poesie Angloise; h peine avoit on entendu parler de Locke. J’ai e'te' persecute' pendant trente ans par une nude de fanatiques pour avoir dit que Locke est 1’Her- cule de la Metaphysique, qui a pose les bornes de I’Esprit Humain.”—(Ferney, 1768.) In the following passage of the Age of Louis XIV. the same celebrated writer is so lavish and undistinguishing in his praise of Locke, as almost to justify a doubt whether he had ever read the book which he extols so highly. “ Locke seul a developpd Ventendement humain, dans un livre oil il n’y a que des veritds; et ce qui rend 1’ouvrage parfait, toutes ces verites sont claires.” 3 Moliere was in his youth so strongly attached to the Epicurean theories, that he had projected a translation of Lu¬ cretius into French. He is even said to have made some progress in executing his design, when a trifling accident de¬ termined him, in a moment of ill humour, to throw his manuscript into the fire. The plan on which he was to proceed in this bold undertaking does honour to his good sense and good taste, and seems to me the only one on.which a successful version of Lucretius can ever be executed. The didactic passages of the poem were to be translated into prose, and. the descriptive passages into verse. Both paxts would have gained greatly by this compromise; for, where Lucretius wishes to unfold the philosophy of his master, he is not less admirable for the perspicuity and precision of his expressions, than he is on other occasions, where his object is to detain and delight the imaginations of his readers, for the charms of his figurative diction, and for the bold relief of his images. In instances of the former kind, no modern language can give 108 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. Chapelle,1 and Bernier;* all of them eminent¬ ly calculated to give the tone, on disputed ques¬ tions of Metaphysics, to that numerous class of Parisians of both sexes, with whom the practical lessons, vulgarly imputed to Epicurus, were not likely to operate to the prejudice of his specu¬ lative principles. Of the three persons just men¬ tioned, the two last died only a few years before Locke’s Essay was published; and may be pre¬ sumed to have left behind them many younger pupils of the same school. One thing is certain, that, long before the middle of the last century, the Essay on Human Understanding was not only read by the learned, but had made its way into the circles of fashion at Paris.3 In what man¬ ner this is to be accounted for, it is not easy to say; but the fact will not be disputed by those who are at all acquainted with the his¬ tory of French literature. In consequence of this rapid and extensive circulation of the work in question, and the strong impression that it everywhere produced, by the new and striking contrast which it ex¬ hibited to the doctrines of the schools, a very re¬ markable change soon manifested itself in the prevailing habits of thinking on philosophical subjects. Not that it is to be supposed that the opinions of men, on particular articles of their former creed, underwent a sudden alteration. I speak only of the general effect of Locke’s dis¬ cussions, in preparing the thinking part of his readers, to a degree till then unknown, for the unshackled use of their own reason. This has always appeared to me the most characteristical feature of Locke’s Essay; and that to which it is chiefly indebted for its immense influence on the philosophy of the eighteenth century. Few books can be named, from which it is possible to ex¬ tract more exceptionable passages; but, such is the liberal tone of the author; such the man¬ liness with which he constantly appeals to reason, as the paramount authority which, even in re¬ ligious controversy, every candid disputant is bound to acknowledge; and such the sincerity and simplicity with which, on all occasions, he appears to inquire after truth, that the general effect of the whole work may be regarded as the best of all antidotes against the errors involved in some of its particular conclusions.4 To attempt any general review of the doctrines even the semblance of poetry to the theories of Epicurus ; while, at the same time, in the vain attempt to conquer this dif¬ ficulty, the rigorous precision and simplicity of the original are inevitably lost. The influence of Gassendi’s instructions may be traced in several of Moliere’s comedies; particularly in the Femmes Savantes, and in a little piece Le Mariage Force, where an Aristotelian and a Cartesian doctor are both held up to the same sort of ridicule, which, in some other of his performances, he has so lavishly bestowed on the medical professors of his time. 1 The joint author, with Bachaumont, of the Voyage en Provence, which is still regarded as the most perfect model of that light, easy, and graceful badinage which seems to belong exclusively to French poetry. Gassendi, who was an in¬ timate friend of his father, was so charmed with his vivacity while a boy, that he condescended to be his instructor in phi¬ losophy; admitting, at the same time, to his lessons, two other illustrious pupils, Moliere and Bernier. I he life of Cha¬ pelle, according to all his biographers, exhibited a complete contrast to the simple and ascetic manners of his master; but, if the following account is to be credited, he missed no opportunity of propagating, as widely as he could, the speculative principles in which he had been educated. “ II dtoit fort eloquent dans 1’ivresse. II restoit ordinairement le dernier a table, et se mettoit a expliquer aux valets la philosophie d’Epicure.”—(Biographic Universelle, article Chapelle, Paris, 1813.) He died in 1686. 2 The well known author of one of our most interesting and instructive books of travels. After his return from the East, where he resided twelve years at the court of the Great Mogul, he published at Lyons, an excellent Abridgment of the Philosophy of Gassendi, in 8 vols. 12mo; a second edition of which, corrected by himself, afterwards appeared, in seven volumes. To this second edition (which I have never met with) is annexed a Supplement, entitled Doutes de M. Bernier sur quelques uns des principaux Chapitres de son Abrege de la Philosophie de Gassendi. It is to this work, I presume, that Leibnitz alludes in the following passage of a letter to John Bernouilli; and, from the manner in which he speaks of its contents, it would seem to be an object of some curiosity. “ Frustra qusesivi apud typographos librum cui titulus ; Doutes de M. Bernier sur la Philosophie, in Gallia ante annos aliquot editum et mihi visum, sed nunc non repertum. Vel- lem autem ideo iterupi legere, quia ille Gassendistorum fuit Princeps; sed paullo ante mortem, libello hoc edito ingenue professus est, in quibus necGassendus nee Cartesius satisfaciant.”—(Leibnitii et Jo. Bernouilli Commerc. Epist. 2 voL 4to. Laussanse et Genevas, 1745.) Bernier died in 1688. 3 A decisive proof of this is afforded by the allusions to Locke’s doctrines in the dramatic pieces then in possession of the French stage. See Note U. 4 The maxim which he constantly inculcates is, that “ Reason must be our last judge and guide in every thing.”— (Locke’s Works, Vol. III. p. 145.) To the same purpose, he eisew'here observes, that “ he who makes use of the light and faculties God has given him, and seeks sincerely to discover truth by those helps and abilities he has, may have this satisfaction in doing his duty as a rational creature; that, though he should miss truth, he will not miss the reward of it- For he governs his assent right, and places it as he should, wrho in any case or matter whatsoever, believes or disbelieves, according as reason directs him. He that does otherwise, transgresses against his own light, and misuses those faculties which were given him to no other end, but to search and follow the clearer evidence and greater probability.”—-(Ibid. p. 125.) DISSERTATION FIRST. 109 sanctioned, or supposed to be sanctioned, by the name of Locke, would be obviously incompatible with the design of this Discourse; but, among these doctrines, there are two, of fundamental importance, which have misled so many of his successors, that a few remarks on each form a necessary preparation for some historical details which will afterwards occur. The first of these doctrines relates to the origin of our ideas; the second to the power of moral perception, AND THE IMMUTABILITY OF MORAL DISTINC¬ TIONS. On both questions, the real opinion of Locke has, if I am not widely mistaken, been very grossly misapprehended or misrepresented, by a large portion of his professed followers, as well as of his avowed antagonists. 1. The objections to which Locke’s doctrine concerning the origin of our ideas, or, in other words, concerning the sources of our knowledge, are, in my judgment, liable, I have stated so fully in a former work,1 that I shall not touch on them here. It is quite sufficient, on the pre¬ sent occasion, to remark, how very unjustly this doctrine (imperfect, on the most favourable con¬ struction, as it undoubtedly is) has been con¬ founded with those of Gassendi, of Condillac, of Diderot, and of Horne Tooke. The substance of all that is common in the conclusions of these last writers, cannot be better expressed than in the words of their Master, Gassendi. “ All our knowledge (he observes in a letter to Descartes) appears plainly to derive its origin from the senses; and although you deny the maxim, 6 Quicquid est in intellectu praeesse debere in sensu,’ yet this maxim appears, nevertheless, to be true; since our knowledge is all ultimately obtained by an influx or incursion from things external; which knowledge afterwards under¬ goes various modifications by means of analogy, composition, division, amplification, extenuation, and other similar processes, which it is un¬ necessary to enumerate.”* This doctrine of Gassendi’s coincides exactly with that ascribed to Locke by Diderot and by Horne Tooke; and it differs only verbally from the more concise statement of Condillac, that “ our ideas are nothing more than transformed sensations.” “ Every idea,” says the first of these writers, “ must necessarily, when brought to its state of ultimate decomposition, resolve it¬ self into a sensible representation or picture; and since every thing in our understanding has been introduced there by the channel of sensation, whatever proceeds out of the understanding is either chimerical, or must be able, in returning by the same road, to re-attach itself to its sensible archetype. Hence an important rule in phi¬ losophy,—that every expression which cannot find an external and a sensible object, to which 1 Philosophical Essays. 2 “ Deinde oinnis nostra notitia videtur plane ducere originem asensibus ; et quamvis tu neges quicquid est in intellectu praeesse debere in sensu, videtur id esse nihilominus vermn, cum nisi sola incursione vigiTTramv, ut loquuntur, fiat; per- ficiatur tamen analogia, compositione, divisione, ampliatione, extenuatione, aliisque similibus modis, quos commemorare nihil est necesse.”—( Objectiones in Meditationem Sccundam.) This doctrine of Gassendi’s is thus very clearly stated and illustrated, by the judicious authors of the Port Royal Logic: “ Un philosophe qui est estime dans le monde commence sa logique par cette proposition : Omnis idea orsum ducit a sensibus. Toute idee tire son origine des sens. II avoue neanmoins que toutes nos iddes n’ont pas e'te dans nos sens telles qu’elles sont dans notre esprit: mais il pretend qu’elles ont au moins etd formdes de celles qui ont passe par nos sens, ou par composition, comme lorsque des images separees de 1’or et d’une montagne, on s’en fait une montagne d’or; ou par ampliation et diminu¬ tion, comme lorsque de i’image d’un homme d’une grandeur ordinaire on s’en forme un geant ou un pigmde; ou par ac¬ commodation et proportion, comme lorsque de Tidee d’une maison qu’on a vue, on s’en forme I’image d’une maison qu’on n’a pas vue. Et ainsi, dit il, nous concevons Dieu aui ne peut tomber sous i.es sens, sous l’xmage d’un vene¬ rable vieillard.” “ Selon cette pensee, quoique toutes nos idees ne fussent semblables a quelque corps particulier que nous ayons vu, ou qui ait frappe nos sens, elles seroient neanmoins toutes corporelles, et ne vous representeroient rien qui ne fut entre dans nos sens, au moins par parties. Et ainsi nous ne concevons rien que par des images, semblables a celles qui se forment dans les cerveau quand nous voyons, ou nous nous imaginons des corps.”—{L'Art de Penser, 1 Partie. c. 1.) The reference made, in the foregoing quotation, to Gassendi’s illustration drawn from the idea of God, affords me an opportunity, of which I gladly avail myself, to contrast it with Locke’s opinion on the same subject. “ How many amongst us will be found, upon inquiry, to fancy God, in the shape of a man, sitting in heaven, and to have many other absurd and unfit conceptions of him ? Christians, as well as Turks, have had whole sects owning, or contending earnestly for it, that the Deity was corporeal and of human shape : And although we find few amongst us, who profess themselves Anthropomor- phites (though some I have met with that own it), yet, I believe, he that will make it his business, may find amongst the ignorant and uninstructed Christians, many of that opinion.” ^—(Vol. I. p. 67.) * In the judgment of a very learned and pious divine, the bias towards Anthropomorphism, which Mr Locke has here so severely reprehended, is not confined to “ ignorant and uninstructed Christians.” “ If Anthropomorphism (says Dr Maclaine) was banished from theology, orthodoxy would be deprived of some of its most precious phrases, and our confessions of faith 110 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. it can thus establish its affinity, is destitute of signification.”—{Oeuvres de Diderot, Tom. VI.) Such is the exposition given by Diderot, of what is regarded in France as Locke’s great and capital discovery ; and precisely to the same purpose we are told by Condorcet, that “ Locke was the first who proved that ad our ideas are compounded of sensations.,,—{Esquisse Historique, &c.) If this were to be admitted as a fair account of Locke’s opinion, it would follow, that he has not advanced a single step beyond Gassendi and Hobbes; both of whom have repeatedly expressed themselves in nearly the same words with Di¬ derot and Condorcet. But although it must be granted, in favour of their interpretation of his language, that various detached passages may be quoted from his work, which seem, on a superficial view, to justify their comments, yet of what weight, it may be asked, are these pas¬ sages, when compared with the stress laid by the author on Reflection, as an original source of our ideas, altogether different from Sensation ? “ The other fountain,” says Locke, “ from which experience furnisheth the understanding with ideas, is the perception of the operations of our own minds within us, as it is employed about the ideas it has got; which operations, when the soul comes to reflect on and consider, do furnish the understanding with another set of ideas, which could not be had from things without; and such are Perception, Thinking, Doubting, Be- “ Let the ideas of being and matter be strongly joined either by education or much thought, whilst these are still com¬ bined in the mind, what notions, what reasonings will there be about separate spirits ? Let custom, from the very childhood, have joined figure and shape to the idea of God, and what absurdities will that mind be liable to about the Deity ?”—(Yol. II. p. 144.) The authors of the Port Royal Logic have expressed themselves on this point to the very same purpose with Locke; and have enlarged upon it still more fully and forcibly. (See the sequel of the passage above quoted.) Some of their remarks on the subject, which are more particularly directed against Gassendi, have led Brucker to rank them among the advocates for innate ideas (Brucker, Historia de I dels, p. 271), although these remarks coincide exactly in substance with the foregoing quo¬ tation from Locke. Like many other modern metaphysicians, this learned and laborious, but not very acute historian, could imagine no intermediate opinion between the theory of innate ideas, as taught by the Cartesians, and the Epicurean account of our knowledge, as revived by Gassendi and Hobbes ; and accordingly thought himself entitled to conclude, that whoever rejected the one must necessarily have adopted the other. The doctrines of Locke and of his predecessor Arnauld will be found, on examination, essentially different from both. Persons little acquainted with the metaphysical speculations of the two last centuries are apt to imagine, that when “ all knowledge is said to have its origin in the senses,” nothing more is to be understood than this, that it is by the impressions of external objects on our organs of perception, that the dormant powers of the understanding are at first awakened. The foregoing quotation from Gassendi, together with those which I am about to produce from Diderot and Condorcet, may, I trust, be useful in correcting this very common mistake; allot* these quotations explicitly asserting, that the external senses furnish not only the occasions by which our intellectual powers are excited and developed, but all the materials dbout which our thoughts are conversant; or, in other words, that it is impossible for us to think of anything, which is not either a sensible image, or the result of sensible images combined together, and transmuted into new forms by a sort of logical che¬ mistry. That the powers of the understanding would for ever continue dormant, were it not for the action of things ex¬ ternal on the bodily frame, is a proposition now universally admitted by philosophers. Even Mr Harris and Lord Mon- boddo, the two most zealous, as well as most learned of Mr Locke’s adversaries in England, have, in the most explicit man¬ ner, expressed their assent to the common doctrine. “ The first class of ideas (says Monboddo) is produced from ideas fur¬ nished by the senses ; the second arises from the operations of the mind upon these materials: for I do not deny, that in this our present state of existence, all our ideas, and all our knowledge, are ultimately to be derived from sense and matter.” (Vol. I. p. 44. 2d Ed.) Mr Harris, while he holds the same language, points out, with greater precision, the essential dif¬ ference between his philosophy and that of the Hobbists. “ Though sensible objects may be the destined medium to awa¬ ken the dormant energies of man’s understanding, yet are those energies themselves no more contained in sense, than the explosion of a cannon in the spark which gave it fire.”—(Hermes.) On this subject see Elements of the Philosophy of the Human Mind, Vol. I. chap. i. sect. 4. To this doctrine I have little doubt that Descartes himself would have assented, although the contrary opinion has been generally supposed by his adversaries to be virtually involved in his Theory of Innate Ideas. My reasons for thinking so, the reader will find stated in Note X. and systems of doctrine would be reduced within much narrower bounds.”—(Note on Mosheim’s Church History, Vol. IV. p. 550.) On this point I do not presume to offer any opinion ; but one thing I consider as indisputable, that it is by means of Anthropomorphism, and other idolatrous pictures of the invisible world, that superstition lays hold of the infant mind. Such pictures operate not upon Reason, but upon the Imagination; producing that temporary belief with which I conceive all the illusions of imagination to be accompanied. In point of fact, the bias of which Locke speaks extends in a greater or less degree to all men of strong imaginations, whose education has not been very carefully superintended in early infancy. I have applied to Anthropomorphism the epithet idolatrous, as it seems to be essentially the same thing to bow down and worship a graven image of the Supreme Being, and to worship a supposed h’keness of Him conceived by the Imagination. In Bernier’s Abridgment of Gassendi's Philosophy (Tom. III. p. 13 el seq.) an attempt is made to reconcile with the Epi¬ curean account of the origin of our knowledge, that more pure and exalted idea of God to which the mind is gradually led by the exercise of its reasoning powers : But I am very doubtful, if Gassendi would have subscribed, in this instance, to the comments of his ingenious disciple. DISSERTATION FIRST. Ill lleving, Reasoning, Knowing, Willing, and all the different actings of our own minds, which, we being conscious of, and observing in ourselves, do from these receive into our understandings ideas as distinct as we do from bodies affecting our senses. This source of ideas every man has wholly in himself: And though it be not sense, as having nothing to do with external objects, yet it is very like it, and might properly enough be called internal sense. But as I call the other Sensation, so I call this Reflection ; the ideas it affords being such only as the mind gets by rejlecting on its own operations within itself.”1 2 —(Locke’s Works, Vol. I. p. 78.) “ The understanding seems to me not to have the least glimmering of any ideas which it doth not receive from one of these two. External objects furnish the mind with the ideas of sensible qualities ; and the mind furnishes the understand¬ ing with ideas of its own operations.,,—(Ibid. p. 79.) In another part of the same chapter, Locke expresses himself thus : “ Men come to he fur¬ nished with fewer or more simple ideas from without, according as the objects they converse with afford greater or less variety; and from the operations of their minds within, according as they more or less reflect on them. For, though he that contemplates the operations of his mind, cannot but have plain and clear ideas of them; yet, unless he turn his thoughts that way, and consider them attentively, he will no more have clear and distinct ideas of all the ope¬ rations of his mind, and all that may be ob¬ served therein, than he will have all the parti¬ cular ideas of any landscape, or of the parts and motions of a clock, who will not turn his eyes to it, and with attention heed all the parts of it. The picture, or clock, may be so placed, that they may come in his way every day; hut yet he will have but a confused idea of all the parts they are made up of, till he applies himself with attention to consider them in each particular. “ And hence we see the reason why it is pretty late before most children get ideas of the operations of their own minds; and some have not any very clear or perfect ideas of the great¬ est part of them all their lives Children, when they first come into it, are surrounded with a world of new things, which, by a con¬ stant solicitation of their senses, draw the mind constantly to them,—forward to take notice of new, and apt to he delighted with the variety of changing objects. Thus, the first years are usually employed and directed in looking abroad. Men’s business in them is to acquaint themselves with what is to he found without; and so grow¬ ing up in a constant attention to outward sensa¬ tions, seldom make any considerable reflection on what passes within them, till they come to be of riper years; and some scarce ever at all.”— (Ibid. pp. 80. 81.) I beg leave to request more particularly the attention of my readers to the following pa¬ ragraphs : I answered, ’twere better if you were dead. I desire you to forgive me this uncharitableness.” The letter is subscribed, your most humble and most unfortunate servant. Is. Newton.* The rough draft of Mr Locke’s reply to these afflicting acknowledgments was kindly communicated to me by a friend some years ago. It is written with the magnanimity of a philosopher, and with the good-humoured forbearance of a man of the world; and it breathes throughout so tender and so unaffected a veneration for the good as well as great qualities of the excellent person to whom it is addressed, as demonstrates at once the conscious integrity of the writer, and the supe¬ riority of his mind to the irritation of little passions. I know of nothing from Locke’s pen which does more honour to his * It is dated at the Bull in Shoreditch, London, September 1093 ; and is addressed, For John Locke, Esq. at Sir Fra. Masham't, Bart, at Oates, in Essex. DISSERTATION FIRST. 119 ing. These tracts are entirely of a practical nature, and were plainly intended for a wider circle of readers than his Essay ; hut they every¬ where bear the strongest marks of the same zeal for extending the empire of Truth and of Reason, and may he justly regarded as parts of the same great design.1 It has been often remarked, that they display less originality than might have been expected from so bold and powerful a think¬ er; and, accordingly, both of them have long fallen into very general neglect. It ought, how¬ ever, to be remembered, that, on the most im¬ portant points discussed in them, new suggestions are not now to be looked for; and that the great object of the reader should be, not to learn some¬ thing which he never heard of before, but to learn, among the multiplicity of discordant pre¬ cepts current in the world, which of them were sanctioned, and which reprobatedby the judgment of Locke. The candid and unreserved thoughts of such a writer upon such subjects as Education, and the culture of the intellectual powers, possess an intrinsic value, which is not diminished by the consideration of their triteness. They not only serve to illustrate the peculiarities of the author’s own character and views, but, con¬ sidered in a practical light, come recommended to us by all the additional weight of his dis¬ criminating experience. In this point of view, the two tracts in question, but more especially that on the Conduct of the Understanding, will always continue to be interesting manuals to such as are qualified to appreciate the mind from which they proceeded.* It must not, however, be concluded from the apparent triteness of some of Locke’s remarks, to the present generation of readers, that they were viewed in the same light by his own contempo- temper and character; and I introduce it with peculiar satisfaction, in connection with those strictures which truth has ex¬ torted from me on that part of his system which to the moralist stands most in need of explanation and apology. MR LOCKE TO MR NEWTON. “ Sir, Oates, 5th October 93. “ I have been ever since I first knew you so kindly and sincerely your friend, and thought you so much mine, that I could not have believed what you tell me of yourself, had I had it from any body else. And though I cannot but be mightily troubled that you should have had so many wrong and unjust thoughts of me, yet, next to the return of good offices, such as from a sincere good will I have ever done you, I receive your acknowledgment of the contrary as the kindest thing you could have done me, since it gives me hopes I have not lost a friend I so much valued. After what your letter expresses, I shall not need to say anything to justify myself to you : I shall always think your own reflection on my carriage both to you and all mankind will sufficiently do that. Instead of that, give me leave to assure you, that I am more ready to forgive you than you can be to desire it; and I do it so freely and fully that I wish for nothing more than the op¬ portunity to convince you that I truly love and esteem you; and that I have still the same good will for you as if nothing of this had happened. To confirm this to you more fully, I should be glad to meet you anywhere, and the rather, because the conclusion of your letter makes me apprehend it would not be wholly useless to you. I shall always be ready to serve you to my utmost, in any way you shall like, and shall only need your commands or permission to do it. “ My book is going to press for a second edition; and, though I can answer for the design with which I writ it, yet, since you have so opportunely given me notice of what you have said of it, I should take it as a favour if you would point out to me ttye places that gave occasion to that censure, that, by explaining myself better, I may avoid being mistaken by others, or unwillingly doing the least prejudice to truth or virtue. I am sure you are so much a friend to both, that, were you none to me, I could expect this from you. But I cannot doubt but you would do a great deal more than this for my sake, who, after all, have all the concern of a friend for you, wish you extremely well, and am, without compliment,” &c. &c. (For the preservation of this precious memorial of Mr Locke, the public is indebted to the descendants of his friend and relation the Lord Chancellor King, to whom his papers and library were bequeathed. The original is still in the posses¬ sion of the present representative of that noble family ; for whose flattering permission to enrich my Dissertation with the above extracts, I feel the more grateful, as I have not the honour of being personally known to his Lordship.) 1 Mr Locke, it would appear, had once intended to publish his thoughts on the Conduct of the Understanding, as an ad¬ ditional chapter to his Essay. “ I have lately,” says he, in a Letter to Mr Molyneux, “ got a little leisure to think of some additions to my book against the next edition, and within these few days have fallen upon a subject that I know not how far it will lead me. I have written several pages on it, but the matter, the farther I go, opens the more upon me, and I cannot get sight of any end of it. The title of the chapter will be, Of the Conduct of the Understanding, which, if I shall pursue as far as I imagine it will reach, and as it deserves, will, 1 conclude, make the largest chapter of my Essay.” (Locke’s JFbrfo, Yol. IX. p. 407.) 2 A similar remark may be extended to a letter from Locke to his friend Mr Samuel Bold, who had complained to him of the disadvantages he laboured under from a weakness of memory. It contains nothing but what might have come from the pen of one of Newberry’s authors ; but with what additional interest do we read it, when considered as a comment by Locke on a suggestion of Bacon’s !—(Locke’s Works, Yol. X. p. 317-) It is a judicious reflection of Shenstone’s, that “ every single observation published by a man of genius, be it ever so tri¬ vial, should be esteemed of importance, because he speaks from his own impressions ; whereas common men publish common things, which they have perhaps gleaned from frivolous writers. I know of few authors to whom this observation applies more forcibly and happily than to Locke, when he touches on the culture of the intellectual powers. His precepts, indeed, are not all equally sound ; but they, in general, contain a large proportion of truth, and may always furnish to a specula¬ tive mind matter of useful meditation. 120 preliminary dissertations. raries. On the contrary, Leibnitz speaks of the Treatise on Education as a work of still greater merit than the Essay on Human Understanding.1 2 * Nor will this judgment be wondered at by those who, abstracting from the habits of thinking in which they have been reared, transport them¬ selves in imagination to the state of Europe a hundred years ago. How flat and nugatory seem now the cautions to parents about watching over those associations on which the dread of spirits in the dark is founded ! But how different was the case (even in Protestant countiies) till a very recent period of the last century ! I have, on a former occasion, taken notice of the slow hut (since the invention of printing) cer¬ tain steps by which Truth makes its way in the world; “ the discoveries, which, in one age, are confined to the studious and enlightened few, be¬ coming, in the next, the established, creed of the learned; and, in the third, forming part of the elementary principles of education.” The har¬ mony, in the meantime, which exists among truths of all descriptions, tends perpetually, by blending them into one common mass, to increase the joint influence of the whole; the contributions of individuals to this mass (to borrow the fine allusion of Middleton) 44 resembling the drops of rain, which, falling separately into the water, mingle at once with the stream, and strengthen the general current.” Hence the ambition, so natural to weak minds, to distinguish themselves by paradoxical and extravagant opinions; for these, having no chance to incorporate themselves with the progressive reason of the species, are the more likely to immortalise the eccentricity of their authors, and to furnish subjects of won¬ der to the common compilers of literary history. This ambition is the more general, as so little expence of genius is necessary for its gratification. *4 Truth (as Mr Hume has well observed) is owe thing, but errors are numberless;” and hence (he might have added) the difficulty of seizing the former, and the facility of swelling the num¬ ber of the latter.® Having said so much in illustration of Locke s philosophical merits, and in reply to the common charge against his metaphysical and ethical prin¬ ciples, it now only remains for me to take notice of one or two defects in his intellectual character, which exhibit a strong contrast to the general vigour of his mental powers. Among these defects, the most prominent is, the facility with which he listens to historical evidence, when it happens to favour his own con¬ clusions. Many remarkable instances of this occur in his long and rambling argument (some¬ what in the style of Montaigne) against the ex¬ istence of innate practical principles; to which may be added, the degree of credit he appears to have given to the popular tales about mer¬ maids, and to Sir William Temple’s idle story of Prince Maurice’s 44 rational and intelligent parrot.” Strange ! that the same person who, in matters of reasoning, had divested himself, almost to a fault, of all reverence for the opinions of others, should have failed to perceive, that, of all the various sources of error, one of the most copious and fatal is an unreflecting faith in hu¬ man testimony ! The disrespect of Locke for the wisdom of antiquity, is another prejudice which has fre¬ quently given a wrong bias to Ids judgment. The idolatry in which the Greek and Roman writers were held by his immediate predecessors, although it may help to account for this weak¬ ness, cannot altogether excuse it in a man of so strong and enlarged an understanding. Locke (as we are told by Dr Warton) 44 affected to de¬ preciate the ancients; which circumstance (he adds), as I am informed from undoubted autho¬ rity, was the source of perpetual discontent and dispute betwixt him and his pupil, Lord Shaftes- 1 Leib. Op. Tom. VI. p. 226. , , .. , 2 Descartes has struck into nearly the same train of thinking with the above, but his remarks apply much be ter o writings of Locke than to his own. * a-(P' i a l “ L’experience m’apprit, que quoique mes opinions surprennent d’abord, parce qu’elles sont tort uitlerentesyies \u - eaires, cependant, apres qu’on les a comprises on les trouve si simples et si conformes au sens cornmun, qu on cesse entierement de les admirer, et par la meme d’en faire cas: parceque tel est le naturel des. hommes qu ns n estimen que les choses qui leur laissent d’admiration et qu’ils ne possedent pas tout-a-fait. C’est ainsi que quoique la sante sou le plus grand de tous les biens qui concernent le corps, c’est pourtant celui auquel nous faisons le moms de reflexion, et que nous goutons le moins. Or, la connoissance de la verite est comme la sante de Tame; lorsque on la possede on u‘y pense plus.”—Lettres, Tome I. Lettre xliii.) DISSERTATION FIRST. 121 bury ; who, in many parts of the Characteristics, has suggested some of the maxims in his Tract has ridiculed Locke’s philosophy, and endea- on Education.3 He had been treated, himself, voured to represent him as a disciple of Hobbes.” it would appear, with very little indulgence by To those who are aware of the direct opposition his parents; and probably was led by that filial between the principles of Hobbes, of Montaigne, veneration which he always expressed for their of Gassendi, and of the other minute philosophers memory, to ascribe to the early habits of self- with whom Locke sometimes seems unconsci- denial imposed on him by their ascetic system ously to unite his strength,—and the principles of ethics, the existence of those moral qualities of Socrates, of Plato, of Cicero, and of all the which he owed to the regulating influence of his soundest moralists, both of ancient and of mo- own reason in fostering his natural dispositions; dern times, the foregoing anecdote will serve at and which, under a gentler and more skilful cul- once to explain and to palliate the acrimony of ture, might have assumed a still more engaging some of Shaftesbury’s strictures on Locke’s and amiable form. His father, who had served Ethical paradoxes.1 in the Parliament’s army, seems to have retain- With this disposition of Locke to depreciate ed through life that austerity of manners which the ancients, was intimately connected that con- characterised his puritanical associates; and, tempt which he everywhere expresses for the notwithstanding the comparative enlargement study of Eloquence, and that perversion of taste and cultivation of Mr Locke’s mind, something which led him to consider Blackmore as one of of this hereditary leaven, if I am not mistaken, the first of our English poets.2 That his own continued to operate upon many of his opinions imagination was neither sterile nor torpid, ap- and habits of thinking. If, in the Conduct of pears sufficiently from the agreeable colouring the Understanding, he trusted (as many have and animation which it has not unfrequently thought) too much to nature, and laid too little imparted to his style : but this power of the mind stress on logical rules, he certainly fell into the he seems to have regarded with a peculiarly jea- opposite extreme in everything connected with lous and unfriendly eye ; confining his view ex- the culture of the heart; distrusting nature al- clusively to its occasional effects in misleading together, and placing his sole confidence in the the judgment, and overlooking altogether the effects of a systematical and vigilant discipline, important purposes to which it is subservient, That the great object of education is not to both in our intellectual and moral frame. Hence, thwart and disturb, but to study the aim, and to in all his writings, an inattention to those more facilitate the accomplishment of her beneficial attractive aspects of the mind, the study of which arrangements, is a maxim, one should think, (as Burke has well observed) ’ les Auciianoes’ les Serafhins, les Chehtjb!ns, les Tuones, les Verttjs, les Brincipautes, les Dominations, les Puissances. “Au centre de ces Augustes Spheres, delate le Soleie de Justice, l’Orient d’Enhaut, dont tous les Astres empruntent leur lumiere et leur splendeur.” “ La Theodicte de Leibnitz,” the same author tells us m another passage, “ est un de mes livres de devotion : J’ai intitule mon Exemplaire, Manuel de Philosophic Chretienne." muuuc gr.oss appetHe of Love (says Gibbon) becomes most dangerous when it is elevated, or rather disguised, by sen¬ timental passion. The remark is strikingly applicable to some of the most popular novels and dramas of Germany; and something very similar to it will be found to hold with respect to those speculative extravagancies which, in the German systems ot philosophy, are elevated or disguised by the imposing cant of moral enthusiasm. , .on0 ot Leibnitz’s controversial discussions with Dr Clarke, there is a passage which throws some light on his taste, not only m matters of science, but in judging of works of imagination. “ Du temps de M. Boyle, et d’autres excellens homines qui lleurissoient en Angleterre sous Charles II. on n’auroit pas ose nous debiter des notions si crenses. (The notions here al¬ luded to are those of Newton concerning the law of gravitation.) J’espcre que le beautemps reviendra sous un aussi bon enu- vernement que celui d a present. Le capital de M. Boyle etoit d’inculquer que tout se faisoit mechaniquement dans la phy¬ sique. Mais c est un malheur des hommes, de se degouter enfin de la raison meme, et de s’ennuyer de la lumiere. Les clnmeres commencent a revenir, et plaisent parce' qu’elles ont quelque chose de merveilleux. II arrive dans le pays philo- sophique ce qui est arrive dans le pays poetique. On s’est lasse' des romans raisonnables, tel que la Clelie Francoise ou l Aramene Allemande; et on est revenu depuis quelque temps aux Contes des Fles."—(Cinquieme Ecrit de M. Leibnitz p. 260.) b rom this passage it would seem, that Leibnitz looked forward to the period, when the dreams of the Newtonian philo¬ sophy would give way to some of the exploded mechanical theories of the universe ; and when the Fairy-tales then in fa¬ shion (among which number must have been included those of Count Anthony Hamilton) would be supplanted by the re¬ vival ot such reasonable Romancesfs the Grand Clelia. In neither of these instances does there seem to be much probability, at present, that his prediction will be ever verified. 1 i lbej<^.ri?a? wl'!ter‘Vvho, of late years> have made the greatest noise among the sciolists of this country, will be found m ^‘Zni l0r 1 ,r. fai”e t0 the new which they have struck out, than to the unexpected and grotesque forms in Hinch they have combined together the materials supplied by the invention of former ages, and of other nations. It is this '° ^ru ,an(^ error their philosophical systems, and of right and wrong in their works of fiction, which has enabled them to perplex the understandings, and to unsettle the principles of so many, both in Metaphysics and Ethics, n pom o proiound and extensive erudition, the scholars of Germany still continue to maintain their long established su¬ periority over the rest of Europe. s A very inteiesting account is given by Leibnitz, of the circumstances which gave occasion to his Theodiccea. in a letter DISS. I. PART II. I: 130 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. progress of reason and good sense among the Metaphysicians of this country since the time of Leibnitz, that the two theories of which I have been speaking, and which, not more than a century ago, were honoured by the opposition of such an antagonist as Clarke, are now re¬ membered only as subjects of literary history. In the arguments, however, alleged in support of these theories, there are some logical principles involved, which still continue to have an ex¬ tensive influence over the reasonings of the learned, on questions seemingly the most remote from all metaphysical conclusions. The two most prominent of these are, the principle of the Sufficient Reason, and the Law of Continuity ; both of them so intimately connected with some of the most celebrated disputes of the last cen¬ tury, as to require a more particular notice than may, at first sight, seem due to their importance. I. Of the principle of the Sufficient Reason, the following succinct account is given by Leib¬ nitz himself, in his controversial correspondence with Dr Clarke: “ The great foundation of Mathematics is the principle of contradiction or identity; that is, that a proposition cannot be true and false at the same time. But, in order to proceed from Mathematics to Natural Philo¬ sophy, another principle is requisite (as I have observed in my Theodiccea); I mean, the prin¬ ciple of the Sufficient Reason ; or, in other words, that nothing happens without a reason why it should be so, rather than otherwise : And, ac¬ cordingly, Archimedes was obliged, in his book De JEquilibrio, to take for granted, that if there be a balance, in which every thing is alike on both sides, and if equal weights are hung on the two ends of that balance, the whole will be at rest. It is because no reason can be given why one side should weigh down rather than the other. Now, by this single principle of the Sufficient Reason, may be demonstrated the being of a God, and all the other parts of Metaphysics or Natural Theology; and even, in some measure, those physical truths that are independent of Mathematics, such as the Dynamical Principles, or the Principles of Forces.” to a Scotch gentleman, Mr Burnet of Kemney ; to whom he seems to have unbosomed himself on all subjects without any reserve: “ Mon livre intitule' Essais de Theodicee, sur la bonte de Dieu, la liberte de I’homme, et 1’origine de mal, sera bientot acheve. La plus grande partie de cet ouvrage avoit ete' faite par lambeaux, quand je me trouvois chez la feue Heine de Prusse, oil ces matieres dtoient souvent agite'es a 1’occasion du Dictionnaire et des autres ouvrages de M. Bayle, qu’on y lisoit beaucoup. Apres la mort de cette grande Princesse, j’ai rassemble' et augments ces pie'ces sur Pexhortation des amis qui en e'toient informes, et j’en ai fait Pouvrage dont je viens de parler. Comme j’ai medite' sur cette matiere depuis ma jeunesse, je pretends de Pavoir discutee a fond.”—(Leibnitz, Opera, Tom. VI. p. 284.) In another letter to the same correspondent, he expresses himself thus: / “ La plupart de mes sentimens ont e'te' enfin arrete's apres une deliberation de 20 ans: car j’ai commence bien jeune a mediter, et je n’avois pas encore 15 ans, nuand je me promenois des journees entieres dans un bois, pour prendre parti entre Aristote et Lemocrite. Cependant j’ai change et rechange sur des nouvelles lumieres, et ce n’est que depuis environ 12 ans que je me trouve satisfait, et que je suis arrive a des demonstrations sur ces matieres qui n en paroissent point capables : Cependant de la maniere que je m’y prends, ces demonstrations peuvent etre sensibles comme cedes des nombres, quoique le sujet passe 1’imagination.”—(Ibid. p. 253.) The letter from which this last paragraph is taken is dated in the year 1697> My chief reason for introducing these extracts, was to do away an absurd suspicion, which has been countenanced by some respectable writers (among others bv Le Clerc), that the opinions maintained in the Theodicee of Leibnitz were not his real sentiments, and that his own creed, on the most important questions there discussed, was not very different from that of Bayle. Gibbon has even gone so far as to say, that “ in his defence of the attributes and providence of the Deity, he was suspected of a secret correspondence with his adversary.”—(Antiquities of the House of Brunswick.) In support of this very improbable charge, I do not know that any evidence has ever been produced, except the following passage, in a letter of his, addressed to a Professor of Theology in the University of Tubingen (Pfaffius):—“ Ita prorsus est, vir summe re- verende, uti scribis, de Theodicaea mea. Item acu tetigisti; et miror, neminem hactenus fuisse, qui sensum hunc meum senserit. Neque enim Philosophorum est rem serio semper agere ; qui in fingendis hypothesibus, uti bene mones, ingenii sui vires experiuntur. Tu, qui Theologus, in refutandis erroribus Theologum agis.” In reply to this it is observed, by the learned editor of Leibnitz’s works, that it is much more probable that Leibnitz should have expressed himself on this particular occasion in jocular and ironical terms, than that he should have wasted so much ingenuity and learning in sup¬ port of an hypothesis to which he attached no faith whatever; an hypothesis, he might have added, with which the whole principles of his philosophy are systematically, and, as he conceived, mathematically connected. It is difficult to believe, that among the innumerable correspondents of Leibnitz, he should have selected a Professor of Theology at Tubingen, as the sole depository of a secret which he was anxious to conceal from all the rest of the world. Surely a solitary document such as this weighs less than nothing, when opposed to the details quoted in the beginning of this note; not to mention its complete inconsistency with the character of Leibnitz, and with the whole tenor of his writings. For my own part, I cannot help thinking, that the passage in question has far more the air of persiflage provoked by the vanity of Pfaffius, than of a serious compliment to his sagacity and penetration. No injunction to secrecy, it is to be observed, is here given by Leibnitz to his correspondent. DISSERTATION FIRST. 131 ¥ \ Some of the inferences deduced by Leibnitz from this almost gratuitous assumption are so paradoxical, that one cannot help wondering he was not a little staggered about its certainty. Not only was he led to conclude, that the mind is necessarily determined in all its elections by the influence of motives, insomuch that it would be impossible for it to make a choice between two things perfectly alike; but he had the boldness to extend this conclusion to the Deity, and to assert, that two things perfectly alike could not have been produced even by Divine Power. It was upon this ground that he rejected a vacuum^ because all the parts of it would be perfectly like to each other; and that he also rejected the supposition of atoms, or similar particles of mat¬ ter, and ascribed to each particle a monad, or active principle, by which it is discriminated from every other particle.1 The application of his principle, however, on which he evidently valued himself the most, was that to which I have already alluded; the demonstrative evidence with which he conceived it to establish the impossibility of free-agency, not only in man, but in any other intelligent being :8 a conclusion which, under whatever form of words it may he disguised, is liable to every objection which can be urged against the system of Spinoza. With respect to the principle from which these important consequences were deduced, it is ob¬ servable, that it is stated by Leibnitz in terms so general and vague, as to extend to all the different departments of our knowledge; for he tells us, that there must be a sufficient reason for every existence, for every event, and for every truth. This use of the word reason is so extreme¬ ly equivocal, that it is quite impossible to annex any precise idea to the proposition. Of this it is unnecessary to produce any other proof than the application which is here made of it to things so very different as existences, events, and truths; in all of which cases, it must of necessity have different meanings. It would be a vain attempt, therefore, to combat the maxim in the form in which it is commonly appealed to: Nor, indeed, can we either adopt or reject it, without con¬ sidering particularly how far it holds in the va¬ rious instances to which it may be applied. The multifarious discussions, however, of a phy¬ sical, a metaphysical, and a theological nature,3 necessarily involved in so detailed an examina¬ tion, would, in the present times (even if this were a proper place for introducing them), be equally useless and uninteresting; the peculiar opinions of Leibnitz on most questions connect¬ ed with these sciences having already fallen into complete neglect. But as the maxim still con¬ tinues to be quoted by the latest advocates for the scheme of necessity, it may not be altogether superfluous to observe, that, when understood to refer to the changes that take place in the material universe, it coincides entirely with the common maxim, that “ every change implies the operation of a cause and that it is in con¬ sequence of its intuitive evidence in this particu¬ lar case, that so many have been led to acquiesce in it, in the unlimited terms in which Leibnitz has announced it. One thing will be readily • See Note CC. 2 The following comment on this part of the Leibnitzian system is from the pen of one of his greatest admirers, Charles Bonnet: “ Cette Metaphysique transcendante deviendra un peu plus intelligible, si Ton fait attention, qu’en vertu du principe de la raison suffisante, tout est necessairement lid dans I’univers. Toutes les Actions des Etres Simples sont har- moniques, ou subordonnees les unes aux autres. L’exercice actuel de 1’activite d’une monade donnee, est determine par 1’exercice actuel de 1’activite des monades auxquelles elle correspond immediatement. Cette correspondance continue d’un point quelconque de Punivers jusqu’a ses extremitds. Representez-vouz les ordres circulaires et concentriques qu’une pierre excite dans une eau dormante : Elies vont toujours en s’dlargissant et en s’affoiblissant. “ Mais, Petat actuel d’une monade est necessairement determine par son dtat antecedent: Celui-ci par un etat qui a precedd, et ainsi en remontant jusqu’a Pinstant de la creation. ****** “ Ainsi le passe, le prdsent, et le futur ne forment dans la meme monade qu’une seul chaine. Notre philosophe disoit ingdnieusement, que le present est toujours gros de Vavenir. “ II disoit encore que PEternel Gedmetre resolvoit sans cesse ce Probleme; Pdtat d’une monade dtant donnd, en ddter- miner Pdtat passd, prdsent, et futur de tout Punivers.”—Bonnet, Tom. VIII. p. 303, 304, 305.) 3 Since the time of Leibnitz, the principle of the sufficient reason has been adopted by some mathematicians as a legiti¬ mate mode of reasoning in plane geometry ; in which case, the application made of it has been in general just and logical, notwithstanding the vague and loose manner in which it is expressed. In this science, however, the use of it can never be attended with much advantage; except perhaps in demonstrating a few elementary truths (such as the 5th and 6th propo¬ sitions of Euclid’s first book), which are commonly established by a more circuitous process : and, even in these instances, the spirit of the reasoning might easily be preserved under a different form, much less exceptionable in point of phraseology. 132 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. granted, that the maxim, when applied to the determinations of intelligent and moral agents^ is not quite so obvious and indisputable, as when applied to the changes that take place in things altogether inanimate and passive. What then, it may he asked, induced Leibnitz, in the enunciation of his maxim, to depart from the form in which it has generally been stated, and to substitute, instead of the word cause, the word reason, which is certainly not only the more unusual, but the more ambiguous expression of the two ? Was it not evidently a perception of the impropriety of calling the motives from which we act the causes of our actions; or, at least of the inconsistency of this language with the common ideas and feelings oi mankind ? The word reason is here much less suspicious, and much more likely to pass current without examination. It was therefore with no small dexterity, that Leibnitz contrived to express his general principle in such a manner, that the impropriety of his language should he most ap¬ parent in that case in which the proposition is instantaneously admitted by every reader as self- evident ; and to adapt it, in its most precise and definite shape, to the case in which it was in the greatest danger of undergoing a severe scrutiny. In this respect, he has managed his argument with more address than Collins, or Edwards, or Hume, all of whom have applied the maxim to mind, in the very same words in which it is usually applied to inanimate matter. But on this article of Leibnitz’s philosophy, which gave occasion to his celebrated controversy with Clarke, I shall have a more convenient op¬ portunity to offer some strictures, when I come to take notice of another antagonist, more formi¬ dable still, whom Clarke had soon after to contend with on the same ground. The person I allude to is Anthony Collins, a writer certainly not once to be compared with Leibnitz, in the grasp of his intellectual powers ; but who seems to have studied this particular question with greater at¬ tention and accuracy, and who is universally al¬ lowed to have defended his opinions concerning it in a manner far more likely to mislead the opi¬ nions of the multitude. II. The same remark which has been already made on the principle of the Sufficient Reason may he extended to that of the Law of Continui¬ ty. In both instances the phraseology is so in¬ determinate, that it may he interpreted in vari¬ ous senses essentially different from each other ; and, accordingly, it would he idle to argue against either principle as a general theorem, without attending separately to the specialties of the manifold cases which it may he understood to comprehend. Where such a latitude is taken in the enunciation of a proposition, which, so far as it is true, must have been inferred from an induction of particulars, it is at least possible that, while it holds in some of its applications, it may yet he far from possessing any claim to that universality which seems necessarily to belong to it, when considered in the light of a metaphy¬ sical axiom, resting on its own intrinsic evi¬ dence. Whether this vagueness of language was the effect of artifice, or of a real vagueness in the author’s notions, may perhaps he doubted; but that it has contributed greatly to extend his re¬ putation among a very numerous class of readers, may be confidently asserted. The possession of a general maxim, sanctioned by the authori¬ ty of an illustrious name, and in which, as in those of the schoolmen, more seems to he meant than meets the ear, affords of itself no slight gratification to the vanity of many; nor is it inconvenient for a disputant, that the maxims to which he is to appeal should he stated in so du¬ bious a shape, as to enable him, when pressed in an argument, to shift his ground at pleasure, from one interpretation to another. The extra¬ ordinary popularity which, in our own times, the philosophy of Kant enjoyed, for a few years, among the countrymen of Leibnitz, may, in like manner, be in a great degree ascribed to the imposing aspect of his enigmatical oracles, and to the consequent facility of arguing without end, in defence of a system so transmutable and so elusive in its forms. The extension, however, given to the Law of Continuity, in the later publications of Leibnitz, and still more by some of his successors, has been far greater than there is any reason to think was originally in the author’s contempla¬ tion. It first occurred to him in the course of one of his physical controversies, and was probably DISSERTATION FIRST. 133 suggested by the beautiful exemplifications of it which occur in pure geometry. At that time it does not appear that he had the slightest idea of its being susceptible of any application to the ob¬ jects of natural history; far less to the succes¬ sion of events in the intellectual and moral worlds. The supposition of bodies perfectly hard, having been shown to be inconsistent with two of his leading doctrines, that of the constant maintenance of the same quantity of force in the Universe, and that of the proportionality of forces to the squares of the velocities,—he found himself reduced to the necessity of asserting, that all changes are produced by insensible gra¬ dations, so as to render it impossible for a body to have its state changed from motion to rest, or from rest to motion, without passing through all the intermediate states of velocity. From this assumption he argued, with much ingenuity, that the existence of atoms, or of perfectly hard bodies, is impossible; because, if two of them should meet with equal and opposite motions, they would necessarily stop at once, in violation of the law of continuity. It would, perhaps, have been still more logical, had he argued against the universality of a law so gratuitously assumed, from its incompatibility with an hypo¬ thesis, which, whether true or false, certainly involves nothing either contradictory or impro¬ bable : but as this inversion of the argument would have undermined some of the fundamental principles of his physical system, he chose ra¬ ther to adopt the other alternative, and to an¬ nounce the law of continuity as a metaphysical truth, which admitted of no exception whatever. The facility with which this law has been adopt¬ ed by subsequent philosophers is not easily ex¬ plicable ; more especially, as it has been main¬ tained by many who reject those physical errors, in defence of which Leibnitz was first led to advance it. One of the earliest, and certainly the most illustrious, of all the partizans and defenders of this principle, was John Bernouilli, whose dis¬ course on motion first appeared at Paris in 1727, having been previously communicated to the Royal Academy of Sciences, in 1724 and 1726.1 It was from this period it began to attract the general attention of the learned; although many years were yet to elapse, before it was to ac¬ quire that authority which it now possesses among our most eminent mathematicians. Mr Maclaurin, whose Memoir on the Percus¬ sion of Bodies gained the prize from the Royal Academy of Sciences, in 1724, continued from that time, till his death, the steady opposer of this new lawt. In his Treatise of Fluxions, pub¬ lished in 1742, he observes, that “ the existence of hard bodies void of elasticity has been reject¬ ed for the sake of what is called the Law of Continuity ; a law which has been supposed to be general, without sufficient ground.” 2 And still more explicitly, in his Posthumous Account of Newton's Philosophical Discoveries, he complains of those who “ have rejected hard bodies as im¬ possible, from far-fetched and metaphysical con¬ siderationsproposing to his adversaries this unanswerable question, “ Upon what grounds is the law of continuity assumed as an universal law of nature ?”s 1 “ En effet (says Bernouilli), un pareil principe de duretd (the supposition to wit of bodies perfectly hard) ne scauroit exister ; c’est une chimere qui repugne a cette loi generale que la nature observe constarament dans toutes ses operations ; je parle de cet ordre immuable et perpe'tuel etabli depuis la creation de Punivers, qu'on pent appeller nor de continuite, en vertu de laquelle tout ce qui s’execute, s’execute par des degres infiniment petits. II semble que le bon sens dicte, qu’aucun changement ne peut se faire par saut; natura non opcratur per saltum; rien ne peut passer d’une extremite a Pautre, sans passer par tous les degres du milieu,” &c. The continuation of this passage (which I have not room to quote) is curious, as it suggests an argument, in proof of the law of continuity, from the principle of the sufficient reason. It may be worth while to observe here, that though, in the above quotation, Bemouilli speaks of the law of continuity as an arbitrary arrangement of the Creator, he represents, in the preceding paragraph, the idea of perfectly hard bodies, as in¬ volving a manifest contradiction. 2 Maclaurin’s Fluxions, Vol. II. p. 438. s Nearly to the same purpose Mr llobms, a mathematician and philosopher of the highest eminence, expresses himself thus : “ M. Bernouilli (in his Discours sur les Lois de la Communication du Mouvement), in order to prove that there are no bodies perfectly hard and inflexible, lays it down as an immutable law of nature, that no body can pass from motion to rest instantaneously, or without having its velocity gradually diminished. That this is a law of nature, M. Bernouilli thinks is evident from that principle, Natura non operatur per saltum, and from good sense. But how good sense can, of itself, WITHOUT EXPERIMENT, DETERMINE ANY OF THE LAWS OF NATURE, IS TO ME VERY ASTONISHING. Indeed, from any thing M. Bernouilli has said, it would have been altogether as conclusive to have begun at the other end, and have disput. 134 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. In the speculations hitherto mentioned, the law of continuity is applied merely to such suc¬ cessive events in the material world as are con¬ nected together hy the relation of cause and effect; and, indeed, chiefly to the changes which take place in the state of bodies with respect to motion and rest. But in the philosophy of Leihnitz, we find the same law appealed to as an indisputable principle in all his various re¬ searches, physical, metaphysical, and theologi¬ cal. He extends it with the same confidence to mind as to matter, urging it as a demonstrative proof, in opposition to Locke, that the soul never ceases to think even in sleep or in deliquium ;1 nay, inferring from it the impossibility that, in the case of any animated being, there should he such a thing as death, in the literal sense of that word.2 It is hy no means probable that the author was at all aware, when he first intro¬ duced this principle into the theory of motion, how far it was to lead him in his researches con¬ cerning other questions of greater moment; nor does it appear that it attracted much notice from the learned, but as a new mechanical axiom, till a considerable time after his death. Charles Bonnet of Geneva, a man of unques¬ tionable talents and of most exemplary worth, was, as far as I know, the first who entered fully into the views of Leihnitz on this point; perceiving how inseparably the law of con¬ tinuity (as well as the principle of the suffi¬ cient reason) was interwoven with his scheme of universal concatenation and mechanism; and inferring from thence not only all the paradoxi¬ cal corollaries deduced from it hy its author, hut some equally hold conclusions of his own, which Leihnitz either did not foresee in their full extent, or to which the course of his inquiries did not particularly attract his attention. The most remarkable of these conclusions was, that all the various beings which compose the uni¬ verse, form a scale descending downwards with¬ out any chasm or saltus, from the Deity to the simplest forms of unorganised matter;3 a pro¬ position not altogether new in the history of philosophy, hut which I do not know that any writer before Bonnet had ventured to assert as a metaphysical and necessary truth. With what important limitations and exceptions it must he received, even when confined to the compa- ed, that no body can pass instantaneously from motion to rest; because it is an immutable law of nature that all bodies shall be flexible.”—(Robins, Vol. II. p. 174. 175-) In quoting these passages, I would not wish to be understood as calling in question the universality of the Law of Con¬ tinuity in the phenomena of moving bodies; a point on which I am not led by the subject of this discourse to offer any opinion; but on which I intend to hazard some remarks in a Note at the end of it—See Note LD. All that I would here assert is, that it is a law, the truth of which can be inferred only by an induction from the phenomena; and to which, ac¬ cordingly, we are not entitled to say that there cannot possibly exist any exceptions. 1 “ Je tiens que 1’ame, et mcme le corps, n’est jamais sans action, et que Fame n’est jamais sans quelque perception ; meme en dormant on a quelque sentiment confus et sombre du lieu oil Ton est, et d’autres choses. Mais quand l'experience ne le confirmeroit pas, je crois qu'il y en a demonstration. C’est a peu pres comme on ne scauroit prouver absolument par les experiences, s’il n’y a point de vuide dans I’espace, et s’il n’y a point de repos dans la matiere. Et cependant ces questions me paroissent decidees demonstrativement, aussi bien qu’k M. Locke.”—(Leib. Op. Tome II. p. 220.) 2 See Note EE. 3 “ Leibnitz admettoit comme un principe fondamental de sa sublime philosophie, qu’il n’y a jamais de sauts dans la nature, et que tout est continu ou nuancd dans le physique et dans le moral. C’etoit sa fameuse Loi de Continuity, qu’il croyoit retrouver encore dans les mathematiques, et q’avoit ete cette loi qui lui avoit inspird la singuliere pre¬ diction dont je parlois.”* “ Tous les etres, disoit il, ne forment qu’une seule chaine, dans laquelle les differentes classes, comme autant d’anneaux, tiennent si dtroitement les unes aux autres, qu’il est impossible aux sens et a rimagination de fixer preaisdment le point oil quelqu’un commence ou finit: toutes les especes qui bordent ou qui occupent, pour ainsi dire, les regions d’inflection, et de rebroussement, devoit etre Equivoques et doudes de caracteres qui peuvent se rapporter aux especes voisins dgalement. Ainsi, 1’existence des zoophytes ou Plant-Animaux n’a rien de monstrueux ; mais il est meme convenable a 1’ordre de la nature qu’il y en ait. Et telle est la force du principe de continuitd chez moi, que non seulement je ne serois point dtonnd d’apprendre, qu’on eut trouvd des etres, qui par rapport a plusieurs propridtds, par exemple, celle de se nourrir ou de se multiplier, puissent passer pour des vegdtaux a aussi bon droit que pour des animaux, . . . J’en serois si peu dtonnd, dis-je, que meme je suis convaincu qu’il doit y en avoir de tels, que 1’Histoire Naturelle parviendra peut-efre a connoitre un jour,” &c. &c (Contemplation de la Nature, pp. 341. 342.) Bonnet, in the sequel of this passage, speaks of the words of Leibnitz, as a prediction of the discovery of the Polypus, deduced from the Metaphysical principle of the Law of Continuity. But would it not be more philosophical to regard it as a query founded on the analogy of nature, as made known to us by experience and observation ?j- * I,a prediction de la ddcouverte des Polypes. + Ad eum modum summus opifex rerum seriem concatenavit a planta ad hominem, ut quasi sine ullo cohoereant intervallo ; sic ZuoQvra cum plantis bruta conjungunt; sic cum homine simia quadrupedes. Itaque in hominis quaque specie invenimus divinos, humanos, feros—Scaliger, (prefixed as a motto to Mr White’s Essay on the regular gradation in Man- London, 1799-) DISSERTATION FIRST. 135 rative anatomy of animals, has been fully de¬ monstrated by Cuvier;1 and it is of material consequence to remark, that these exceptions, how few soever, to a metaphysical principle, are not less fatal to its truth than if they exceeded in number the instances which are quoted in sup¬ port of the general rule.* At a period somewhat later, an attempt has been made to connect the same law of continuity with the history of human improvement, and more particularly with the progress of invention in the sciences and arts. Helvetius is the most noted writer in whom I have observed this last extension of the Leibnitzian principle; and I have little doubt, from his known opinions, that, when it occurred to him, he conceived it to af¬ ford a new illustration of the scheme of necessi¬ ty, and of the mechanical concatenation of all the phenomena of human life. Arguing in sup¬ port of his favourite paradox concerning the ori¬ ginal equality of all men in point of mental capa¬ city, he represents the successive advances made by different individuals in the career of discovery, as so many imperceptible or infinitesimal steps, each individual surpassing his predecessor by a trifle, till at length nothing is wanting but an additional mind, not superior to the others in natural powers, to combine together, and to turn to its own account, their accumulated la¬ bours. 2 To this criticism, the only reply made by Eontenelle was a single sentence, which he addressed to a Journalist who had urged him to take up arms in his own defence. “ Je laisserai mon censeur jouir en paix de son triomphe; je consens que le diable ait dtd prophete, puisque le Jesuite le veut, et qu’il croit cela plus orthodoxe.”—(D’A i. e m n e ux, Eloge tle^ la Matte. J We are told by D’Alembert, that the silence of Fontenelle, on this occasion, was owing to the advice ot Da 158 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. opinions which took place during Fontenelle’s life, that a book which, in his youth, was cen¬ sured for its impiety, was regarded before his death as a proof of his respect for religion. The most solid basis of Fontenelle’s fame is his History of the Academy of Sciences, and his Eloges of the Academicians. Both of these works, but more especially the latter, possess, in an eminent degree, all the charms of his former publications, and are written in a much simpler and better taste than any of the others. The materials, besides, are of inestimable value, as succinct and authentic records of one of the most memorable periods in the history of the human mind; and are distinguished by a rare imparti¬ ality towards the illustrious dead, of all coun¬ tries, and of all persuasions. The philosophi¬ cal reflections, too, which the author has most skilfully interwoven with his literary details, discover a depth and justness of understanding far beyond the promise of his juvenile Essays; and afford many proofs of the soundness of his logical views,1 as well as of his acute and fine discrimination of the varieties and shades of character, both intellectual and moral. The chief and distinguishing merit of Fonte- nelle, as the historian of the Academy, is the happy facility with which he adapts the most abstruse and refined speculations to the compre¬ hension of ordinary readers. Nor is this excel¬ lence purchased by any sacrifice of scientific precision. What he aims at is nothing more than an outline; but this outline is always exe¬ cuted with the firm and exact hand of a master. “ When employed in composition (he has some¬ where said) my first concern is to be certain that I myself understand what I am about to writeand on the utility of this practice every page of his Historical Memoirs may serve as a comment.2 As a writer of Eloges, he has not been equal¬ led (if I may be allowed to hazard my own opi¬ nion) by any of his countrymen. Some of those, indeed, by D’Alembert and by Condorcet, ma¬ nifest powers of a far higher order than belonged to Fontenelle; but neither of these writers pos¬ sessed Fontenelle’s incommunicable art of in¬ teresting the curiosity and the feelings of his readers in the fortunes of every individual whom he honoured by his notice. In this art it is not improbable that they might have succeeded bet¬ ter had they imitated Fontenelle’s self-denial in sacrificing the fleeting praise of brilliant colour¬ ing, to the fidelity and lasting effect of their portraits; a self-denial which in him was the more meritorious, as his great ambition plainly was to unite the reputation of a hel-esprit with that of a philosopher. A justly celebrated aca¬ demician of the present times (M. Cuvier), who has evidently adopted Fontenelle as his model, has accordingly given an interest and truth to his Eloges, which the public had long ceased to expect in that species of composition.3 But the principal charm of Fontenelle’s Eloges Motte. “ Fontenelle bien tente de terrasser son adversaire par la facilite qu’il y trouvoit, fut retenu par les avis prudens de La Motte; cet ami lui fit craindre de s’alie'ner par sa reponse une societe qui s’appeloit Legion, quand on avoit affaire au dernier de ses membres.” The advice merits the attention of philosophers in all countries, for the spirit of Jesuitism is not confined to the Church of Home. 1 An instance of this which happens at present to recur to my memory, may serve to illustrate and to confirm the above remark. It is unnecessar}' to point out its coincidence with the views which gave birth to the new nomenclature in chemistry. “ If languages had been the work of philosophers, they might certainly be more easily learned. Philosophers would have established everywhere a systematical uniformity, which would have proved a safe and infallible guide ; and the man- ner of forming a derivative word, would, as a necessary consequence, have suggested its signification. The uncivilised nations, who are the first authors of languages, fell naturally into that notion with respect to certain terminaiions, all of which have some common property or virtue; but that advantage, unknown to those who had it in their hands, was not carried to a sufficient extent.” * From this praise, however, must be excepted, the mysterious jargon in which (after the example of some of his con¬ temporaries) he has indulged himself in speaking of the geometry and calculus of infinites. “ Nous le disons avec peine (says D’Alembert), et sans vouloir outrager les manes d’un homme cdlebre qui n’est plus, il n’y a peut-etre point d’ouvrage oil Ton trouye des preuves plus frdquentes de Tabus de la metaphysique, que dans Touvrage tres connu de M. Fontenelle, qui a pour litre Elemens de la Geometric de Vlnfini ; ouvrage dont la lecture est d’autant plus dangereuse aux jeunes geo¬ metres que Tauteur y prdsente les sophismes avec une sorte d’dlegance et de grace, dont le sujet ne paroissoit pas suscep¬ tible.”—{Melanges, &c. Tom. Y. p. 264.) a D’Alembert, in his ingenious parallel of Fontenelle and La Motte, has made a remark on Fontenelle’s style when he aims at simplicity, of the justness of which French critics alone are competent judges. “ L’un et Tautre ont dcrit en prose avec beaucoup de clarte, d’dlegance, de simplicitd meme ; mais La Motte avec une simplicite plus naturelle, et Fontenelle DISSERTATION FIRST. 159 aiises rrom the pleasing pictures which they everywhere present of genius and learning in the scenes of domestic life. In this respect, it has been justly said of them by M. Suard,1 that “ they form the noblest monument ever raised to the glory of the sciences and of letters.” Fon- tenelle himself, in his Eloge of Vorignon, after remarking, that in him the simplicity of his cha¬ racter was only equalled by the superiority of his talents, finely adds, “ I have already be¬ stowed so often the same praise on other mem¬ bers of this academy, that it may be doubted whether it is not less due to the indi viduals, than to the sciences which they cultivated in com¬ mon.” What a proud reply does this reflection afford to the Machiavellian calumniators of phi¬ losophy ! ** The influence of these twm works of Fon- tenelle on the studies of the rising generation all over Europe, can be conceived by those alone who have compared them with similar produc¬ tions of an earlier date. Sciences which had long been immured in colleges and cloisters, began at length to breathe the ventilated and wholesome air of social life. The union of phi¬ losophy and the fine arts, so much boasted of in the schools of ancient Greece, seemed to promise a speedy and invigorated revival. Geometry, Mechanics, Physics, Metaphysics, and Morals, became objects of pursuit in courts and in camps ; the accomplishments of a scholar grew more and more into repute among the other characteristics of a gentleman : and (what was of still greater importance to the world) the learned discovered the secret of cultivating the graces of writing, as a necessary passport to truth, in a refined but dissipated age. Nor was this change of manners confined to one of the sexes. The other sex, to whom na¬ ture has entrusted the first development of our intellectual and moral powers, and who may, therefore, be regarded as the chief medium through which the progress of the mind is con¬ tinued from generation to generation, shared also largely in the general improvement. Fontenelle aspired above all things to be the philosopher of the Parisian circles; and certainly contributed not a little to diffuse a taste for useful know¬ ledge among women of all conditions in France, by bringing it into vogue among the higher classes. A reformation so great and so sudden could not possibly take place, without giving birth to much affectation, extravagance, and folly; but the whole analogy of human affairs encourages us to hope, that the inconveniencies and evils connected with it will be partial and temporary, and its beneficial results permanent and progressive.2 Among the various moral defects imputed to Fontenelle, that of a complete apathy and in- avec une simplicity plus ytudi^e: car la simplicity peut Petre, et des lors elle devient maniere, et cesse d’etre modele.” An idea very similar to this is happily expressed by Congreve, in his portrait of Amoret: Coquet and Coy at once her air, Both studied, though both seem neglected: Careless she is with artful care. Affecting to seem unaffected. 1 Notice sur la Vie et les Ecrits du Docteur Robertson. (Paris, lb 17-) ! Among the various other respects in which Fontenelle contributed to the intellectual improvement of his countrymen, it ought to be mentioned, that he was one of the first writers in France who diverted the at tention of metaphysicians from the old topics of scholastic discussion, to a philosophical investigation of the principles of the fine arts. Various original hints upon these subjects are scattered over his works: but the most favourable specimens of his talents for this very delicate species of analysis are to be found in his Dissertation on Pastorals, and in his Theory concerning the Delight we derive from Tragedy.* His speculations, indeed, are not always just and satisfactory; but they are seldom deficient in novelty or re¬ finement. Their principal fault, perhaps, arises from the author’s disposition to carry his refinements too far; in con¬ sequence of which, his theories become chargeable with that sort of sublimated ingenuity which the French epithet Alambique expresses more precisely and forcibly than any word in our language. Something of the same philosophical spirit may be traced in Fenelon’s Dialogues on Eloquence, and in his Letter on Rhetoric and Poetry. The former of these treatises, besides its merits as a speculative discussion, contains various prac¬ tical hints, well entitled to the attention of those who aspire to eminence as public speakers; and of which the most apparently trifling claim some regard, as the results of the author’s reflections upon an art which few ever practised with greater success. Let me add, that both of these eminent men (who may be regarded as the fathers of philosophical criticism in France) were zealous partizans and admirers of the Cartesian metaphysics. It is this critical branch of metaphysical science which, * In the judgment of Mr Hume, “ there is not a finer piece of criticism than Fontenelle’s Dissertation on Pastorals; in which, by a number of reflections and philosophical reasonings, he endeavours to fix the just medium between simplicity and refinement, which is suitable to that species of poetry.” 160 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. sensibility to all concerns but his own is by far the most prominent. A letter of the Baron de Grimm, written immediately after Fontenelle s death, but not published till lately, has given a new circulation in this country to some anec¬ dotes injurious to bis memory, which had long ago fallen into oblivion or contempt in France. The authority, however, of this adventurer, who earned his subsistence by collecting and retail¬ ing, for the amusement of a German Prince, the literary scandal of Paris, is not much to be relied on in estimating a character with which he does not appear to have had any opportunity of becoming personally acquainted; more especially as, during Fontenelle’s long decline, the great majority of men of letters in France were dis¬ posed to throw his merits into the shade, as an acceptable homage to the rising and more dazzling glories of Voltaire.1 It is in the Aca¬ demical Memoirs of D’Alembert and Condorcet (neither of whom can be suspected of any un¬ just prejudice against Voltaire, but who were both too candid to sacrifice truth to party feel¬ ings) that we ought to search for Fontenelle’s real portrait:8 Or rather (if it be true, as Dr Hutcheson has somewhere remarked, that “ men have commonly the good or bad quali¬ ties which they ascribe to mankind”) the most faithful Eloge on Fontenelle himself is to be found in those which he has pronounced upon others. That the character of Fontenellc would have been more amiable and interesting, had his vir¬ tues been less the result of cold and prudent calculation, it is impossible to dispute. But his conduct through life was pure and blameless; and the happy serenity of his temper, which prolonged his life till he had almost completed his hundredth year, served as the best comment on the spirit of that mild and benevolent philo¬ sophy, of which he had laboured so long to ex¬ tend the empire. It is a circumstance almost singular in his history, that since the period of Ijlis death, his reputation, both as a man and as an author, has been gradually rising. The fact has been as remarkably the reverse with most of those who have calumniated his memory. While the circle of mental cultivation was thus rapidly widening in France, a similar pro¬ gress was taking place! upon a larger scale, and under still more favourable circumstances, in England. To this progress nothing contributed in my opinion, has been most successfully cultivated by French writers; although too many of them have been infected (after the example of Fontenelle) with the disease of sickly and of hyper-metaphysical subtlety. From this censure, however, must be excepted the Abbe Dubos, whose Critical Reflections on Poetry and Painting is one of the most agreeable and instructive works that can b@ put into the hands of youth. Few books are better calculated for leading their minds gradually from literature to philosophy. The author’s theories, if not alway s profound or just, are in general marked with good sense as well as with ingenuity; and the subjects to which they relate are so peculiarly^ attrac¬ tive, as to fix the attention even of those readers who have but little relish for speculative discussions. “ Ce qui fait la bontdde cet ouvrage (says Voltaire) c’est qu’il n’y a que pen d’erreurs, et beaucoup de re'flexions vraies, nouvelles, et pro- fondes. 11 manque cependant d’ordre et sur-tout de pre'cision ; il auroit pu etre e'crit avec plus de feu, de grace, et d’el£- gance ; mats Vecrivain pense et fait penser."—(Siecle de Louis XIV.) 1 As to Voltaire himself, it must be mentioned, to his honour, that though there seems never to have been much cordia¬ lity between him and Fontenelle, he had yet the magnanimity to give a place to this Nestor of French literature in his catalogue of the eminent persons who adorned the reign of Louis XIV.: a tribute of respect the more flattering, as it is the single instance in which he has departed from his general rule of excluding from his list the names of all his living con¬ temporaries. Even Fontenelle’s most devoted admirers ought to be satisfied with the liberality of Voltaire’s eulogy, in which, after pronouncing Fontenelle “ the most universal genius which the age of Louis XIV. had produced,” he thus sums up his merits as an author. “ Enfin on 1’a regarde; comme le premier des hommes dans 1’art nouveau de repandre de la lumiere et des graces sur les sciences abstraites, et il a eu du merite dans tous les autres genres qu’il a traites. 'iantde talens ont ete soutenus par la connoissance des langues et de 1’histoire, et il a tie sans contredit au-dessus de tous les sgavans qui n'ont pas eu le don de Vinvention." * Condorcet has said expressly, that his apathy was confined entirely to what regarded himself; and that he was always an active, though frequently a concealed friend, where his good offices could be useful to those who deserved them. “ On a cru Fontenelle insensible, parce que sachant miiitriser les mouvemens de son ame il se conduisoit d’apres son esprit, toujours juste et toujours sage. D’ailleurs, il avoit consenti sans peine a conserver cette reputation d’insensibilite; il avoit souffert les plaisanteries de ses societe's sur sa froideur, sans chercher a les de'tromper, parce que, bien sur que les vraies amis n’en seroit pas la dupe, il voyoit dans cette reputation un moyen commode de se delivrer des indifferens sans blesser leur amour- propre.” (Eloge de Fontenelle, par Condorcet.) Many of Fontenelle’s sayings, the import of which must have depended entirely on circumstances of time and place un¬ known to us, have been absurdly quoted to his disadvantage, in their literal and most obvious acceptation. “ I hate war (said he), for it spoils conversation.” Can any just inference be drawn from the levity of this convivial sally, against the humanity of the person who uttered it? Or rather, when connected with the characteristical finesse of Fontenelle’s wit, does it not lead to a conclusion precisely opposite ? DISSERTATION FIRST. 161 more powerfully than the periodical papers pub¬ lished under various titles by Addison1 and his associates. The effect of these in reclaiming the public taste from the licentiousness and grossness introduced into England at the period of the Restoration ; in recommending the most serious and important truths by the united at¬ tractions of wit, humour, imagination, and elo¬ quence ; and, above all, in counteracting those superstitious terrors which the weak and igno¬ rant are so apt to mistake for religious and moral impressions—has been remarked by numberless critics, and is acknowledged even by those who felt no undue partiality in favour of the authors.8 Some of the papers of Addison, however, are of an order still higher, and bear marks of a mind which, if early and steadily turned to philoso¬ phical pursuits, might have accomplished much more than it ventured to undertake. His fre¬ quent references to the Essay on Human Under¬ standing, and the high encomiums with which they are always accompanied, show how suc¬ cessfully he had entered into the spirit of that work, and how completely he was aware of the importance of its object. The popular nature of his publications, indeed, which rendered it necessary for him to avoid everything that might savour of scholastic or of metaphysical discussion, has left us no means of estimating his philosophical depth, but what are afforded by the results of his thoughts on the particular topics which he has occasion to allude to, and by some of his incidental comments on the scientific merits of preceding authors. But these means are sufficiently ample to justify a very high opinion of his sound and unprejudiced judgment, as well as of the extent and correct¬ ness of his literary information. Of his powers as a logical reasoner he has not enabled us to form an estimate; but none of his contempo¬ raries seem to have been more completely tinc¬ tured with all that is most valuable in the me¬ taphysical and ethical systems of his time.3 But what chiefly entitles the name of Addi¬ son to a place in this Discourse, is his Essays on the Pleasures of Imagination ; the first attempt in England to investigate the principles of the fine arts ; and an attempt which, notwithstand¬ ing many defects in the execution, is entitled to the praise of having struck out a new avenue to the study of the human mind, more alluring than any which had been opened before. In this respect, it forms a most important supple¬ ment to Locke's Survey of the Intellectual Powers ; and it has, accordingly, served as a text, on which the greater part of Locke’s disciples have been eager to offer their comments and their corrections. The progress made by some of these in exploring this interesting region has been great; but let not Addison be defrauded of his claims as a discoverer. Similar remarks may be extended to the hints suggested by Addison on Wit, on Humour, and on the causes of Laughter. It cannot, indeed, be said of him, that he exhausted any one of these subjects; but he had at least the merit of starting them as problems for the consideration of philosophers ; nor would it be easy to name among his successors, a single writer who has made so important a step towards their solution, as the original proposer. The philosophy of the papers to which the fore¬ going observations refer, has been pronounced to be slight and superficial, by a crowd of modern metaphysicians, who were but ill entitled to erect themselves into judges on such a question.4 The singular simplicity and perspicuity of Addison’s style have contributed much to the prevalence 1 Born in 1672, died in 1719- _ , „ c „ 2 See Pope’s Imitations of Horace, Book II. Epistle I. “ Unhappy Dryden, &c. &c. f f . 3 I quote the following passage from Addison, not as a specimen of his metaphysical acumen, hut as a proof of his good sense in divining and obviating a difficulty which I believe most persons will acknowledge occurred to themselves when they first entered on metaphysical studies:— ... . , ;+ ;s “ Although we divide the soul into several powers and faculties, there is no such division in the soul^; sincedf “ the whole soul that remembers, understands, wills, or imagines. Our manner of considering the ^Xt^rdsubiects of will, imagination, and the like faculties, is for the better enabling us to express ourselves in^ch f st^2on obJirves; speculation, not that there is any such division in the soul itself. In another part of the same p p , herself.”— that “ what we call the faculties of the soul are only the different ways or modes in which the soul can exert ^ "For some important remarks on the words Powers and Faculties, as applied to the Mind, see Locke, B. II. Ch. xxi. § 20. * See Note R It. x DISS. I. PART II. 162 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. of this prejudice. Eager for the instruction, and unambitious of the admiration of the multi¬ tude, he everywhere studies to bring himself down to their level; and even when he thinks with the greatest originality, and writes with the most inimitable felicity, so easily do we en¬ ter into the train of his ideas, that we can hard¬ ly persuade ourselves that we could not have thought and written in the same manner. He has somewhere said of “ fine writing,” that it “ consists of sentiments which are natural, with¬ out being obvious and his definition has been applauded by Hume, as at once concise and just. Of the thing defined, his own periodical essays exhibit the most perfect examples. To this simplicity and perspicuity, the wide circulation which his works have so long main¬ tained among all classes of readers, is in a great measure to he ascribed. His periods are not constructed, like those of Johnson, to cc elevate and surprise,” by filling the ear and dazzling the fancy; but we close his volumes with greater reluctance, and return to the perusal of them with far greater alacrity. Franklin, whose fugitive publications on political topics have had so extra¬ ordinary an influence on public opinion, both in the Old and New Worlds, tells us that his style in writing was formed upon the model of Addison: Nor do I know anything in the history of his life which does more honour to his shrewdness and sagacity. The copyist, indeed, did not pos¬ sess the gifted hand of his master,—Museo con- tingens cuncta lepore ; hut such is the effect of his plain and seemingly artless manner, that the most profound conclusions of political economy assume, in his hands, the appearance of indis¬ putable truths; and some of them, which had been formerly confined to the speculative few, are already current in every country of Europe, as proverbial maxims.1 To touch, however slightly, on Addison’s other merits, as a critic, as a wit, as a specula¬ tive politician, and, above all, as a moralist, would lead me completely astray from my pre¬ sent object. It will not he equally foreign to it to quote the two following short passages, which, though not strictly metaphysical, are, both of them, the result of metaphysical habits of thinking, and hear a stronger resemblance than anything I recollect among the wits of Queen Anne’s reign, to the best philosophy of the pre¬ sent age. They approach, indeed, very nearly to the philosophy of Turgot and of Smith. “ Among other excellent arguments for the immortality of the soul, there is one drawn from the perpetual progress of the soul to its perfec¬ tion, without a possibility of ever arriving at it; which is a hint that I do not remember to have seen opened and improved by others who have written on this subject, though it seems to me to carry a great weight with it. A brute arrives at a point of perfection that he can never pass. In a few years he has all the endowments he is capable of; and were he to live ten thousand more, would he the same thing he is at present. Were a human soul thus at a stand in her ac¬ complishments, were her faculties to be full¬ blown, and incapable of further enlargement, I would imagine it might fall away insensibly, and drop at once into a state of annihilation. But can we believe a thinking being, that is in a perpetual progress of improvement, and tra¬ velling on from perfection to perfection, after having just looked abroad into the works of its Creator, and made a few discoveries of his in¬ finite goodness, wisdom, and power, must perish at her first setting out, and in the very begin¬ ning of her inquiries ?”2 The philosophy of the other passage is not unworthy of the author of the Wealth of Nations. The thought may he traced to earlier writers, hut certainly it was never before presented with the same fulness and liveliness of illustration; nor do I know, in all Addison’s works, a finer in¬ stance of his solicitude for the improvement of his fair readers, than the address with which he 1 The expressions “ Laisscz^ nous fair e'' and pas trap gouvernerf which comprise, in a few words, two of the most im¬ portant lessons of Political Wisdom, are indebted chiefly for their extensive circulation to the short and luminous comments of Franklin—(See his Political Fragments, § 4.) 2 This argument has been prosecuted with great ingenuity and force of reasoning (blended, however, with some of the peculiarities of his Berkeleian metaphysics) by the late Dr James Hutton (See his Investigation of the Principles of Know. ledge, Yol. III. p. 195, et seq. Edin. 1794.) DISSERTATION FIRST. 163 nere insinuates one of the sublimest moral les¬ sons, while apparently aiming only to amuse them with the geographical history of the muff and the tippet. “ Nature seems to have taken a particular care to disseminate her blessings among the dif¬ ferent regions of the world, with an eye to the mutual intercourse and traffic among mankind; that the natives of the several parts of the globe might have a kind of dependance upon one another, and he united together by their com¬ mon interest. Almost every degree produces something peculiar to it. The food often grows in one country, and the sauce in another. The fruits of Portugal are corrected by the products of Barhadoes; the infusion of a China plant, sweetened with the pith of an Indian cane. The Philippine Islands give a flavour to our Euro¬ pean bowls. The single dress of a woman of quality is often the product of a hundred cli¬ mates. The muff and the fan come together from the opposite ends of the earth. The scarf is sent from the torrid zone, and the tippet from beneath the pole. The brocade petticoat rises out of the mines of Peru, and the diamond neck¬ lace out of the bowels of Indostan.” But I must not dwell longer on the fascinat¬ ing pages of Addison. Allow me only, before I close them, to contrast the last extract with a remark of Voltaire, which, shallow and con¬ temptible as it is, occurs more than once, both in verse and in prose, in his voluminous writings. II muril, k Moka, dans le sable Arabique, Ce Caffe' ne'cessaire aux pays des frimats ; II met la Fievre en nos climats, Et le remede en Amerique. (Epitre au Hoi du Prusse, 1750.) And yet Voltaire is admired as a philosopher by many who will smile to hear this title bestow¬ ed upon Addison ! It is observed by Akenside, in one of the notes to the Pleasures of Imagination, that c< Philoso¬ phy and the Fine Arts can hardly be conceiv¬ ed at a greater distance from each other than at the Revolution, when Locke stood at the head of one party, and Dryden of the other.” He observes, also, that “ a very great progress to¬ wards their re-union had been made within these few years.” To this progress the chief impxdse was undoubtedly given by Addison and Shaftesbury. Notwithstanding, however, my strong parti¬ ality for the former of these writers, I should be truly sorry to think, with Mr Hume, that {C Addison will be read with pleasure when Locke shall be entirely forgotten.”—(Essay on the Differ'ent Species of Philosophy.) A few years before the commencement of these periodical works, a memorable accession was made to metaphysical science, by the pub¬ lication of Berkeley’s New Theory of Vision, and of his Principles of Human Knowledge. Possess¬ ed of a mind which, however inferior to that of Locke in depth of reflection and in soundness of judgment, was fully its equal in logical acute¬ ness and invention, and in learning, fancy, and taste, far its superior,—Berkeley was singularly fitted to promote that re-union of Philosophy and of the Fine Arts which is so essential to the prosperity of both. Locke, we are told, despis¬ ed poetry; and we know from one of his own letters, that, among our English poets, his fa¬ vourite author was Sir Richard Blackmore. Berkeley, on the other hand, courted the society of all, from whose conversation and manners he could hope to add to the embellishments of his genius; and although himself a decided and High Church Tory,1 lived in habits of friend¬ ship with Steele and Addison, as well as with Pope and Swift. Pope’s admiration of him seems to have risen to a sort of enthusiasm. He yielded to Berkeley’s decision on a very delicate question relating to the exordium of the Essay on Man; and on his moral qualities he has be¬ stowed the highest and most unqualified eulogy to be found in his writings. , 1 See a volume of Sermons, preached in the chapel of Trinity College, Dublin. See also a Discourse addressed to Ma¬ gistrates, &c. printed in 1736. In both of these publications, the author carries his Tory principles so far, as to represent the doctrine of passive obedience and non-resistance as an essential article of the Christian faith. “ The Christian religion makes every legal constitution sacred, by commanding our submission thereto. Let every soul be subject to the higher powers, saith St Paul, for the powers that be are ordained of God." 164 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. “ Even in a Bishop I can spy desert; Seeker is decent; Bundle has a heart; Manners with candour are to Benson given; To Berkeley every virtue under Heaven.” With these intellectual and moral endow¬ ments, admired and blazoned as they were by the most distinguished wits of his age, it is not surprising that Berkeley should have given a popularity and fashion to metaphysical pursuits, which they had never before acquired in Eng¬ land. Nor was this popularity diminished by the boldness of some of his paradoxes : on the contrary, it was in no small degree the effect of them; the great bulk of mankind being always prone to mistake a singularity or eccentricity of thinking, for the originality of a creative genius. The solid additions, however, made by Berke¬ ley to the stock of human knowledge were im¬ portant and brilliant. Among these, the first place is unquestionably due to his New Theory of Vision ; a work abounding with ideas so dif¬ ferent from those commonly received, and, at the same time, so profound and refined, that it was regarded by all hut a few accustomed to deep metaphysical reflection, rather in the light of a philosophical romance, than of a sober inquiry after truth. Such, however, has been since the progress and diffusion of this sort of knowledge, that the leading and most abstracted doctrines contained in it, form now an essential part of every elementary treatise of optics, and are adopted by the most superficial smatterers in science as fundamental articles of their faith. Of a theory, the outlines of which cannot fail to be familiar to a great majority of my readers, it would he wholly superfluous to attempt any explanation here, even if it were consistent with the limits within which I am circumscribed. Suffice it to observe, that its chief aim is to dis¬ tinguish the immediate and natural objects of sight from the seemingly instantaneous conclu¬ sions which experience and habit teach us to draw from them in our earliest infancy; or, in the more concise metaphysical language of a later period, to draw the line between the ori¬ ginal and the acquired perceptions of the eye. They who wish to study it in detail, will find ample satisfaction, and, if they have any relish for such studies, an inexhaustible fund of enter¬ tainment, in Berkeley’s own short hut masterly exposition of his principles, and in the excellent comments upon it by Smith of Cambridge; by Porterfield; by Beid; and, still more lately, by the author of the Wealth of Nations.1 That this doctrine, with respect to the acquir¬ ed perceptions of sight, was quite unknown to the best metaphysicians of antiquity, we have direct evidence in a passage of Aristotle’s Nico- machian Ethics, where he states the distinction between those endowments which are the imme¬ diate gift of nature, and those which are the fruit of custom and habit. In the former class, he ranks the perceptions of sense, mentioning particularly the senses of seeing and of hearing. The passage (which I have transcribed in a Note) is curious, and seems to me decisive on the subject.2 The misapprehensions of the ancients on this very obscure question will not appear surprising, when it is considered, that forty years after the publication of Berkeley’s Theory of Vision, and sixty years after the date of Locke’s Essay, the subject was so imperfectly understood in France, that Condillac (who is, to this day, very gene¬ rally regarded by his countrymen as the father of genuine logic and metaphysics) combated at great length the conclusions of the English phi¬ losophers concerning the acquired perceptions of sight; affirming that “ the eye judges naturally of figures, of magnitudes, of situations, and of 1 By this excellent judge, Berkeley’s New Theory of Vision is pronounced to be “ one of the finest examples of Philoso¬ phical Analysis that is to be found in our own, or any other language.”—(Essays on Philosophical Subjects. Lond. 1795, p. 215.) 2 Ob ya.Q \k rS •ttoXXockis r troXkdzis dasvirai ra; aurO'/urei; iXalioy.it, aXX’ ataTtaXit, i%ovris a %gn/raf/,itoi i%optv. (Ethic. Nicomach. Lib. ii. cap. 1.) “ For it is not from seeing often, or from hearing often, that we get these senses; but, on the contrary, instead of get¬ ting them by using them, we use them because we have got them.” Had Aristotle been at all aware of the distinction so finely illustrated by Berkeley, instead of appealing to the percep¬ tions of these two senses, as instances of endowments coeval with our birth, he would have quoted them as the most striking of all examples of the effects of custom in apparently identifying our acquired powers with our original faculties. DISSERTATION FIRST. 165 distances.” His argument in support of this opinion is to be found in the sixth section of his Essay on the Origin of Human Knowledge. It is difficult to suppose, that a person of mature years, who had read and studied Locke and Berkeley with as much care and attention as Condillac appears to have bestowed on them, should have reverted to this ancient and vulgar prejudice; without suspecting that his metaphy¬ sical depth has been somewhat overrated by the world.1 It is but justice, however, to Condillac to add, that, in a subsequent work, he had the candour to acknowledge and to retract his er¬ ror ;—a rare example of that disinterested love of truth, which is so becoming in a philosopher. I quote the passage (in a literal, though some¬ what abridged version), not only to show, that, in the above statement, I have not misrepre¬ sented his opinion, hut because I consider this remarkable circumstance in his literary history as a peculiarly amiable and honourable trait in his character. “ We cannot recall to our memory the igno¬ rance in which we were born : It is a state which leaves no trace behind it. We only re¬ collect our ignorance of those things, the know¬ ledge of which we recollect to have acquired; and to remark what we acquire, some previous knowledge is necessary. That memory which now renders us so sensible of the step from one acquisition to another, cannot remount to the first steps of the progress; on the contrary, it supposes them already made; and hence the origin of our disposition to believe them‘connate with ourselves. To say that we have learnt to see, to hear, to taste, to smell, to touch, appears a most extraordinary paradox. It seems to us that nature gave us the complete use of our senses the moment she formed them, and that we have always made use of them without study, because we are no longer obliged to study in order to use them. I retained these prejudices at the time I published my Essay on the Origin of Human Knowledge ; the reasonings of Locke on a man horn blind, to whom the sense of sight was afterwards given, did not undeceive me : and I maintained against this philosopher that the eye judges naturally of figures, of sizes, of situa¬ tions, and of distances^—Nothing short of his own explicit avowal could have convinced me, that a writer of so high pretensions and of such unquestionable ingenuity as Condillac, had real¬ ly commenced his metaphysical career under so gross and unaccountable a delusion. In bestowing the praise of originality on Berkeley’s Theory of Vision, I do not mean to say, that the whole merit of this Theory is ex¬ clusively his own. In this, as in most other cases, it may be presumed, that the progress of the human mind has been gradual : And, in point of fact, it will, on examination, be found, that Berkeley only took up the inquiry where Locke dropped it; following out his principles to their remoter consequences, and placing them in so great a variety of strong and happy lights, as to bring a doctrine till then understood but by a few, within the reach of every intelligent and attentive reader. For my own part, on com¬ paring these two philosophers together, I am at a loss whether most to admire the powerful and penetrating sagacity of the one, or the fertility of invention displayed in the illustrations of the other. What can be more clear and forcible than the statement of Locke quoted in the Note below; and what an idea does it convey of his superiority to Condillac, when it is considered, that he anticipated d priori the same doctrine which was afterwards confirmed by the fine analysis of Berkeley, and demonstrated by the judicious experiments of Cheselden; while the 1 Voltaire, at an earlier period, had seized completely the scope of Berkeley’s theory ; and had explained it with equal brevity and precision, in the following passage of his Elements of the Newtonian Philosophy:— “ II faut absolument conclure, que les distances, les grandeurs, les situations ne sont pas, a proprement parler, des choses visibles, c’est a dire, ne sont pas les objets propres et immediats de la vue. L’objet propre et immediat de la vue n’esi autre chose que la lumiere coloree: tout le reste, nous ne le sentons qu’a la longue et par experience. Nous apprenons a voir, precisement comme nous apprenons h parler et a lire. La difference est, que 1’art de voir est plus facile, et que la nature est egalement h tous notre maitre. “ Les jugemens soudains, presque uniformes, que toutes nos ames a un certain age portent des distances, des grandeurs, des situations, nous font penser, qu’il n’y a qu’h. ouvrir les yeux pour voir la maniere dont nous voyons. On se trompe, il y faut le secours des autres sens. Si les hommes n’avoient que le sens de la vue, ils n’auroient aucun moyen pour con- noitre 1’etendue en longeur, largeur et profondeur, et un pur esprit ne la connoitroit peut-etre, a moins que Dieu ne la lui rdve'lat.”—Phys. Newton, Chap. 7. 166 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. French metaphysician, with all this accumula¬ tion of evidence before him, relapsed into a pre¬ judice transmitted to modern times, from the very infancy of optical science !1 I believe it would he difficult to produce from any writer prior to Locke, an equal number of im¬ portant facts relating to the intellectual phenome¬ na, as well observed, and as unexceptionahly de¬ scribed, as those which I have here brought under my reader’s eye. It must appear evident, besides, to all who have studied the subject, that Locke has, in this passage, enunciated, in terms the most precise and decided, the same general con¬ clusion concerning the effect of constant and early habits, which it was the great object of Berkeley’s Theory of Vision to establish, and which, indeed, gives to that work its chief value, when considered in connection with the Philo¬ sophy of the Human Mind. Berkeley himself, it is to he observed, by no means lays claim to that complete novelty in his Theory of Vision, which has been ascribed to it by many who, in all probability, derived their whole information concerning it from the traditional and inexact transcripts of book-mak¬ ing historians. In the introductory sentences of his Essay, he states very clearly and candid¬ ly the conclusions of his immediate predecessors on this class of our perceptions; and explains, with the greatest precision, in what particulars his own opinion differs from theirs. “ It is, I think, agreed by all, that distance, of itself, can¬ not be seen. For distance being a line directed end-wise to the eye, it projects only one point in the fund of the eye, which point remains in¬ variably the same, whether the distance be longer or shorter “ I find it also acknowledged, that the esti¬ mate we make of the distance of objects consi¬ derably remote, is rather an act of judgment grounded on experience, than of sense. For ex¬ ample, when I perceive a great number of inter¬ mediate objects, sucli as houses, fields, rivers, and the like, which I have experienced to take i “ We are farther to consider,” says Locke, “ concerning perception, that the ideas we receive by sensation are often in grown people altered by the judgment, without our taking notice of it. When we set before our eyes a round globe, of any uniform colour, v. g. gold, alabaster, or jet, it is certain that the idea thereby imprinted in our mind is of a flat circle, va¬ riously shadowed, with several degrees of light and brightness coming to our eyes. But we having by use been accustomed to perceive what kind of appearance convex bodies are wont to make in us, what alterations are made in the reflections of light by the difference of the sensible figure of bodies; the judgment presently, by an habitual custom, alters the appear¬ ances into their causes, so that, from what truly is variety of shadow or colour, collecting the figure it makes it pass for a mark of figure, and frames to itself the perception of a convex figure, and an uniform colour ; when the idea we receive from thence is only a plane variously coloured, as is evident in painting. * * * * “ But this is not, I think, usual in any of our ideas, but those received by sight ;* because sight, the most comprehensive of all our senses, conveying to our minds the ideas of lights and colours, which are peculiar only to that sense ; and also the far different ideas of space, figure, or motion, the several varieties whereof change the appearances of its proper objects, viz. light and colours, we bring ourselves by use to judge of the one by the other. This, in many cases, by a settled habit in things whereof we have frequent experience, is performed so constantly and so quick, that we take that for the perception of our sensation, which is an idea formed by our judgment; so that one, viz. that of sensation, serves only to excite the other, and is scarce taken notice of itself: as a man who reads or hears with attention or understanding, takes little notice of the characters or sounds, but of the ideas that are excited in him by them. “Nor need we wonder that it is done with so little notice, if we consider how very quick the actions of the mind are pei- formed; for as itself is thought to take up no space, to have no extension, so its actions seem to require no time, but many of them seem to be crowded into an instant. I speak this in comparison to the actions of the body. Any one may easily observe this in his own thoughts, who will take the pains to reflect on them. How, as it were in an instant, do our minds with one glance see all the parts of a demonstration, which may very well be called a long one, if we consider the time it will require to put it into words, and step by step show it to another ? Secondly, we shall not be so much surprised that this is done in us with so little notice, if we consider how the facility which we get of doing things by a custom of doing makes them often pass in us without our notice. Habits, especially such as are begun very early, come at last to produce actions in us, which often escape our observations. How frequently do we in a day cover our eyes with our eye-lids, with out perceiving that we are at all in the dark ? Men that have by custom got the use of a bye-word, do almost in every sentence pronounce sounds, which, though taken notice of by others, they themselves neither hear nor observe; and, then? fore, it is not so strange, that our mind should often change the idea of its sensation into that of its judgment, and make one serve only to excite the other, without our taking notice of it.”—(Locke’s Works, Yol. I. p. 123, et seq.) * Mr Locke might, however, have remarked something very similar to it in the perceptions of the ear; a very large pro¬ portion of its appropriate objects being rather judged of than actually perceived. In the rapidity (for example) of common conversation, how many syllables, and even words, escape the notice of the most attentive hearer; which syllables and words are so quickly supplied from the relation which they bear to the rest of the sentence, that it is quite impossible to dis¬ tinguish between the audible and the inaudible sounds ! A very palpable instance of this occurs in the difficulty expe¬ rienced by the most acute ear in catching proper names or arithmetical sums, or words borrowed from unknown tongues, the first time they are pronounced. DISSERTATION FIRST. 167 up a considerable space; I thence form a judg¬ ment or conclusion, that the object I see beyond them is at a great distance. Again, when an object appears faint and small, which, at a near distance, I have experienced to make a vigorous and large appearance, I instantly conclude it to be far off. And this, ’tis evident, is the result of experience, without which, from the faintness and littleness, I should not have inferred any¬ thing concerning the distance of objects. “ But when an object is placed at so near a distance, as that the interval between the eyes bears any sensible proportion to it, it is the re¬ ceived opinion that the two optic axes, concur¬ ring at the object, do there make an angle, by means of which, according as it is greater or less, the object is perceived to be nearer or far¬ ther off. “ There is another way mentioned by the optic writers, whereby they will have us judge of those distances, in respect of which the breadth of the pupil hath any sensible bigness; and that is, the greater or less divergency of the rays, which, issuing from the visible point, do fall on the pupil; that point being judged nearest, which is seen by most diverging rays, and that remoter, which is seen by less diver¬ ging rays.” These (according to Berkeley) are the “ com¬ mon and current accounts” given by mathema¬ ticians of our perceiving near distances by sight. He then proceeds to show, that they are unsa¬ tisfactory ; and that it is necessary, for the so¬ lution of this problem, to avail ourselves of prin¬ ciples borrowed from a higher philosophy : Af¬ ter which, he explains, in detail, his own theory concerning the ideas (sensations) which, by ex¬ perience, become signs of distance;1 2 * or (to use his own phraseology) “ by which distance is suggested* to the mind.” The result of the whole is, that, “ a man boi-n blind, being made to see, would not at first have any idea of dis¬ tance by sight. The sun and stars, the remotest objects as well as the nearest, would all seem to be in his Eye, or rather in his Mind.”* From this quotation it appears, that, before Berkeley’s time, philosophers had advanced greatly beyond the point at which Aristotle stopped, and towards which Condillac, in his first publication, made a retrograde movement. Of this progress some of the chief steps may be traced as early as the twelfth century in the Optics of Alhazen ;4 and they may be perceived still more clearly and distinctly in various op¬ tical writers since the revival of letters; parti¬ cularly in the Optica Promota of James Gre¬ gory. 5 Father Malebranche went still farther, and even anticipated some of the metaphysical i \ Tn°r assi?ting persons unaccustomed to metaphysical studies to enter into the spirit and scope of Berkeley’s Theory, the best illustration I know of is furnished by the phenomena of the Phantasmagoria. It is sufficient to hint at this application ot these phenomena, to those who know anything of the subject. r 2 The word suggest is much used by Berkeley, in this appropriate and technical sense, not only in his Theory of Visioti, but m his Principles of Human Knowledge, and in his Minute Philosopher. It expresses, indeed, the cardinal principle on which his Theory o/1 Vision hinges; and is now so incorporated with some of our best metaphysical speculations, that one cannot easily conceive how the use of it was so long dispensed with. Locke (in the passage quoted in the Note, p. 107.) uses the word excite for the same purpose; but it seems to imply an hypothesis concerning the mechanism of the mind, and by no means expresses the fact in question with the same force and precision. It is remarkable, that Dr lleid should have thought it incumbent on him to apologise for introducing into philosophy a word so familiar to every person conversant with Berkeley’s works. “ I beg leave to make use of the word suggestion be¬ cause I know not one more proper to express a power of the mind, which seems entirely to have escaped the notice of'phi¬ losophers, and to which we owe many of our simple notions which are neither impressions nor ideas, as well as many origi¬ nal principles of belief. I shall endeavour to explain, by an example, what I understand by this word. We all know that a certain kind of sound suggests immediately to the mind a coach passing in the street; and not only produces the imagina¬ tion, but the belief, that a coach is passing. Yet there is no comparing of ideas, no perception of agreements or disagree¬ ments to produce this belief; nor is there the least similitude between the sound we hear, and the coach we imagine and believe to be passing.” 8 So far Dr Reid’s use of the word coincides exactly with that of Berkeley ; but the former will be found to annex to it a meaning more extensive than the latter, by employing it to comprehend not only those intimations which are the result of experience and habit; but another class of intimations (quite overlooked by Berkeley), those which result from the original trame or the human mind.—(See Reid’s Inquiry, chap. ii. sect. 7*) I request the attention of my readers to this last sentence, as I have little doubt that the fact here stated gave rise to tne theory which Berkeley afterwards adopted, concerning the non-existence of the material world. It is not, indeed, sur¬ prising that a conclusion, so very curious with respect to the objects of sight, should have been, in the first ardour of dis¬ covery, too hastily extended to those qualities also which are the appropriate obiects of touch. 4 Alhazen, Lib. ii. N N. 10. 12. 39. 4 See the end of Prop. 28. 168 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. reasonings of Berkeley concerning tlie means by which experience enables us to judge of the dis¬ tances of near objects. In proof of this, it is sufficient to mention the explanation he gives of the manner in which a comparison ot the percep¬ tions of sight and of touch teaches us giadually to estimate by the eye the distances of all those objects which are within reach of our hands, or of which we are accustomed to measure the dis¬ tance, by walking over the intermediate ground. In rendering this justice to earlier writers, I have no wish to detract from the originality of Berkeley. With the single exception, indeed, of the passage in Malehranche which I have just referred to, and which it is more than pro¬ bable was unknown to Berkeley when his theory first occurred to him,1 I have ascribed to his predecessors nothing more than what he has himself explicitly acknowledged to belong to them. All that I wished to do was, to supply some links in the historical chain, which he has omitted. The influence which this justly celebrated work has had, not only in perfecting the theory of optics, but in illustrating the astonishing ef¬ fects of early habit on the mental phenomena in general, will sufficiently account to my intelli¬ gent readers for the length to which the fore¬ going observations upon it have extended. Next in point of importance to Berkeley’s New Theory of Vision, which I regard as by far the most solid basis of his philosophical fame, may be ranked his speculations concerning the Objects of General Terms, and his celebrated argument against the existence of the Material World. On both of these questions I have elsewhere ex¬ plained my own ideas so fully, that it would be quite superfluous for me to resume the consi¬ deration of them here.2 3 In neither instance are his reasonings so entirely original as has been commonly supposed. In the former, they co¬ incide in substance, although with immense im¬ provements in the form, with those of the scho¬ lastic nominalists, as revived and modified by Hobbes and Leibnitz. In the latter instance, they amount to little more than an ingenious and elegant development of some principles of Malebranche, pushed to certain paradoxical but obvious consequences, of which Malebranche, though unwilling to avow them, appears to have been fully aware. These consequences, too, had been previously pointed out by Mr Norris, a very learned divine of the church of England, whose name has unaccountably failed in obtain¬ ing that distinction to which his acuteness as a logician, and his boldness as a theorist, justly entitled him!5 The great object of Berkeley, in maintaining his system of idealism, it may be proper to re¬ mark in passing, was to cut up by the roots the scheme of materialism. “ Matter (he tells us himself) being once expelled out qf nature, drags with it so many sceptical and impious notions. * * * * Without it your Epicureans, Hobbists, and the like, have not even the shadow of a pretence, but become the most cheap and easy triumph in the world.” Not satisfied with addressing these abstract speculations to the learned, Berkeley conceived them to be of such moment to human happiness, that he resolved to bring them, if possible, with¬ in the reach of a wider circle of readers, by throwing them into the more popular and amu¬ sing form of dialogues.4 The skill with which 1 Berkeley’s Theory was published when he was only twenty-five ; an age when it can scarcely be supposed that his me¬ taphysical reading had been very extensive. 2 See Philosophical Essays. „ „ . . 3 Another very acute metaphysician of the same church (Arthur Collier, author of a Demonstration of t ic Non-cxis ence and Impossibility of an External World) has met with still greater injustice. His name is not to be found in any ot our Bio¬ graphical Dictionaries. In point of date, his publication is some years posterior to that of A orris, and there oie i oes no possess the same claims to originality ; but it is far superior to it in logical closeness and precision, and is not obscured o the same degree with the mystical theology which Norris (after the example ol Malebranche) connected wit le sc erne of Idealism. Indeed, when compared with the writings of Berkeley himself, it yields to them less m force o argumen , than in composition and variety of illustration. The title of Collier’s book is “ Clavis Universalis, or a New Inquiry a er Truth, being a Demonstration, &c. &c. By Arthur Collier, Hector of Langford Magna, near Sarum. (Lond. printed or Robert Gosling, at the Mitre and Crown, against St Dunstan’s Church, Fleet Street, 1713.)” The motto prefixed by Co - lier to his work is from Malebranche, and is strongly characteristical both of the English and l rench Inquirer afier Tru i. “ Vulgi assensus et approbatio circa materiam difficilem est certum argumentum falsitatis istius opmionis cui assenti ur. —(Maleb. De Inquir. Verit. Lib. iii. p. 194.) See Note S S. rT i a 4 I allude here chiefly to Alciphron, or the Minute Philosopher; for as to the dialogues between Hylas and Philonous, t aspire to no higher merit than that of the common dialogues between A and B ; being merely a compendious way ot s a - ing and of obviating the principal objections which the author anticipated to his opinions. DISSERTATION FIRST. 169 he has executed this very difficult and unpro¬ mising task cannot be too much admired. The characters of his speakers are strongly marked and happily contrasted; the illustrations exhibit a singular combination of logical subtlety and of poetical invention; and the style, while it every¬ where abounds with the rich, yet sober colour¬ ings of the author’s fancy, is perhaps superior, in point of purity and of grammatical correct¬ ness, to any English composition of an earlier date.1 The impression produced in England by Berkeley’s Idealism was not so great as might have been expected; but the novelty of his pa¬ radoxes attracted very powerfully the attention of a set of young men who were then prose¬ cuting their studies at Edinburgh, and who formed themselves into a society for the express purpose of soliciting from the author an expla¬ nation of some parts of his theory which seemed to them obscurely or equivocally expressed. To this correspondence the amiable and excellent prelate appears to have given every encourage¬ ment ; and I have been told by the best autho¬ rity, that he was accustomed to say, that his reasonings had been nowhere better understood than by this club of young Scotsmen.2 The in¬ genious Dr Wallace, author of the Discourse on the Numbers of Mankind, was one of the leading members; and with him were associated several other individuals whose names are now well known and honourably distinguished in the learned world. Mr Hume’s Treatise of Human Nature, which was published in 1739, affords sufficient evidence of the deep impression which Berkeley’s writings had left upon his mind; and to this juvenile essay of Mr Hume’s may be traced the origin of the most important meta¬ physical works which Scotland has since pro¬ duced. It is not, however, my intention to prosecute farther, at present, the history of Scottish phi¬ losophy. The subject may be more convenient¬ ly, and I hope advantageously resumed, after a slight review of the speculations of some Eng¬ lish and French writers, who, while they pro¬ fessed a general acquiescence in the doctrines of Locke, have attempted to modify his funda¬ mental principles in a manner totally incon¬ sistent with the views of their master. The re¬ marks which I mean to offer on the modern French school will afford me, at the same time, a convenient opportunity of introducing some strictures on the metaphysical systems which have of late prevailed in other parts of the Con¬ tinent. SECTION V. Hartleian School. The English writers to whom I have alluded in the last paragraph, I shall distinguish by the title of Dr Hartley’s School; for although I by no means consider this person as the first author of any of the theories commonly ascribed to him (the seeds of all of them having been previously sown in the university where he was educated), it was nevertheless reserved for him to combine them together, and to exhibit them to the world in the imposing form of a system. Among the immediate predecessors of Hart¬ ley, Dr Law, afterwards Bishop of Carlisle, 1 Dr Warton, after bestowing high praise on the Minute Philosopher, excepts from his encomium “ those passages in the iourth dialogue, where the author has introduced his fanciful and whimsical opinions about vision.” (Essay on the Writings and Genius of Pope, Vol. II. p. 264.)—If I were called on to point out the most ingenious and original part of the whole work, it would be the argument contained in the passages here so contemptuously alluded to by this learned and (on all questions of taste) most respectable critic. 2 The authority I here allude to is that of my old friend and preceptor, Dr John Stevenson, who was himself a member of the Rankenian Club, and who was accustomed for many years to mention this fact in his Academical Prelections. DISS. I. PART II. * \ 170 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. seems to have been chiefly instrumental in pre¬ paring the way for a schism among Locke s dis¬ ciples. The name of Law was first known to the public by an excellent translation, accom¬ panied by many learned, and some very judi¬ cious notes, of Archbishop King s work on the Origin of Evil", a work of which the great ob¬ ject was to combat the Optimism of Leibnitz, and the Manicheism imputed to Bayle. In making this work more generally known, the translator certainly rendered a most acceptable and important service to the world, and, indeed, it is upon this ground that his best claim to li¬ terary distinction is still founded.1 In his own original speculations, he is weak, paradoxical, and oracular;2 affecting, on all occasions, the most profound veneration for the opinions of Locke, but much more apt to attach himself to the errors and oversights of that great man, than to enter into the general spirit of his meta¬ physical philosophy. To this translation, Dr Law prefixed a Dis¬ sertation concerning the Fundamental Principle of Virtue, by the Reverend Mr Gay: a per¬ formance of considerable ingenuity, but which would now be entitled to little notice, were it not for the influence it appears to have had in suggesting to Dr Hartley the possibility of ac¬ counting for all our intellectual pleasures and pains, by the single principle of the Association of Ideas. We are informed by Dr Hartley himself, that it was in consequence of hearing some account of the contents of this dissertation, be was first led to engage in those inquiries which produced his celebrated Theory of Human Nature. The other principle on which this theory pro¬ ceeds (that of the vibrations and vibratiuncles in the medullary substance of the brain) is also of Cambridge origin. It occurs in the form of a query in Sir Isaac Newton’s Optics; and a distinct allusion to it, as a principle likely to throw new light on the phenomena of mind, is to be found in the concluding sentence of Smith’s Harmonies. Very nearly about the time when Hartley’s Theory appeared, Charles Bonnet of Geneva published some speculations of his own, pro¬ ceeding almost exactly on the same assumptions. Both writers speak of vibrations (ebranlemens) in the nerves; and both of them have recourse to a subtle and elastic ether, co-operating with the nerves in carrying on the communication between soul and body.3 This fluid Bonnet conceived to be contained in the nerves, in a manner analogous to that in which the electric fluid is contained in the solid bodies which con¬ duct it; differing in this respect from the Car¬ tesians as well as from the ancient physiologists, who considered the nerves as hollow tubes or pipes, within which the animal spirits were in¬ cluded. It is to this elastic ether that Bonnet ascribes the vibrations of which he supposes the nerves to be susceptible; for the nerves them¬ selves (he justly observes) have no resemblance to the stretched cords of a musical instrument.4 * * * 8 1 King’s argument in proof of the prevalence in this world, both of Natural and Moral Good, over the corresponding Evils, has been much and deservedly admired ; nor are Law’s Notes upon this head entitled to less praise. Indeed, it is in this part of the work that both the author and his commentator appear, in my opinion, to the greatest advantage. 2 As instances of this I need only refer to the first and third, of his Notes on King; the former of which relates to the word substance; and the latter to the dispute between Clarke and Leibnitz concerning space. His reasonings on both sub¬ jects are obscured by an affected use of hard and unmeaning words, ill becoming so devoted an admirer of Locke. The same remark may be extended to an Inquiry into the Ideas of Space and Time, published by Dr Law in 1734. The result of Law’s speculations on Space and Time is thus stated by himself: “ That our ideas of them do not imply any external ideatum or objective reality; that these ideas (as well as those of infinity and number) are universal or abstract ideas, existing under that formality no where but in the mind ; nor affording a proof of any thing, but of the power which the mind has to form them.”—(Law’s Trans, of King, p. 7- 4th edit.) This language, as we shall afterwards see, approaches very nearly to that lately introduced by Kant. Dr Law’s favourite author might have cautioned him against such jargon. (See Essay on the Human Understanding, Book II. Chap, xiii- § 17, 18.) The absurd application of the schoiastie word substance to empty space; an absurdity in which the powerful mind of Gravesande acquiesced many years after the publication of the Essay on Human Understanding, has probably contributed not a little to force some authors into the opposite extreme of maintaining, with Leibnitz and Dr Law, that, our idea of space does not imply any external ideatum or objective reality. Gravesande’s words are these : “ Substantiae, sunt aut cogitantes, aut non cogitantes; cogitantes duas novimus, Deum et Mentem nostram : praeter has et alias dari in dubium non revocamus. Duae etiam substantiae, quae non cogitant, nobis notae sunt Spatium et Corpus.”—Gravesande, Introd. ad Philosophiam, § 19. 8 Essai Andlytique de I'Ame, Chap. v. See also the additional notes on the first chapter of the seventh part of the Con. temptation de la Nature. _ • • •, j * Mais les nerfs sont mous, ils ne sont point tendus comme les cordes d’un instrument; les objets y exciteroient-ils done DISSERTATION FIRST. 171 Hartley’s Theory differs in one respect from this, as he speaks of vibrations and vibratiuncles in the medullary substance of the brain and nerves. He agrees, however, with Bonnet, in thinking, that to these vibrations in the nerves the co-operation of the ether is essentially ne¬ cessary; and, therefore, at bottom the two hy¬ potheses may be regarded as in substance the same. As to the trifling shade of difference be¬ tween them, the advantage seems to me to be in favour of Bonnet. Nor was it only in their Physiological Theo¬ ries concerning the nature of the union between soul and body, that these two philosophers agreed. On all the great articles of metaphy¬ sical theology, the coincidence between their conclusions is truly astonishing. Both held the doctrine of Necessity in its fullest extent; and both combined with it a vein of mystical devo¬ tion, setting at defiance the creeds of all esta¬ blished churches. The intentions of both are allowed, by those who best knew them, to have been eminently pure and worthy; but it cannot be said of either, that his metaphysical writings have contributed much to the instruction or to the improvement of the public. On the con¬ trary, they have been instrumental in spreading a set of speculative tenets very nearly allied to that sentimental and fanatical modification of Spinozism, which, for many years past, has pre¬ vailed so much, and produced such mischievous effects in some parts of Germany.1 But it is chiefly by his application of the asso¬ ciating principle to account for all the mental phenomena, that Hartley is known to the world; and upon this I have nothing to add to what I have already stated in another work.—(Phil. Essays, Essay IV.)—His Theory seems to be al¬ ready fast passing into oblivion; the temporary popularity which it enjoyed in this country having, in a great measure, ceased with the life of its zealous and indefatigable apostle Hr Priestley. * It would be unfair, however, to the translator of Archbishop King, to identify his opinions with those of Hartley and Priestley. The zeal with which he contends for man’s free agency is sufficient, of itself, to draw a strong line of distinction between his Ethical System and theirs.—(See his Notes on King, passim.)—But I must be allowed to say of him, that the gene¬ ral scope of his writings tends, in common with that of the two other metaphysicians, to depre¬ ciate the evidences of Natural Religion, and more especially to depreciate the evidences which the light of nature affords of a life to come ;— les vibrations analogues a celle d’une corde pincee ? Ces vibrations se communiqueroient-elles a Tinstant au siege de Tame ? La chose paroit difficile k conqevoir. Mais si Ton admet dans les nerfs un fluide dont la subtilitd et 1’dlasticite approche de celle de la lumiere ou de Tether, on expliquera facilement par le secours de ce fluide, et lacdleritd avec laquelle les impres¬ sions se communiquent a Tame, et celle avec laquelle Tame Execute tant d’operations differentes.”—(Essai Anal. Chap, v.) “ Au reste, les physiologistes qui avoient cru que les filets nerveux etoient solides, avoient cede a des apparences trom- peuses. Ils vouloient d’ailleurs faire osciller les nerfs pour rendre raison des sensations, et les nerfs ne peuvent osciller. Ils sont mous, et nullement dlastiques. Un nerf coupe ne se retire point. C’est le fluide invisible que les nerfs renfer- ment, qui est doud de cette dlasticite qu’on leur attribuoit, et d’une plus grande elasticitdencore.”—( Contcmp. de la Nature. VII. Partie, Chap. i. Note at the end of the chapter.) M. Quesnai, the celebrated author of the Economical System, has expressed himselt to the same purpose concerning the supposed vibrations of the nerves: “ Plusieurs physiciens ont pense que le seul ebranlement des nerfs, causd par les objets qui touchent les organes des corps, suffit pour occasioner le mouvement et le sentiment dans les parties oh les nerfs sont dbranles. Ils se representent les nerfs comme des cordes fort tendus, qu’un leger contact met en vibration dans toute leur dtendue. Des philosophes, peu instruits en anatomie, ont pu se former un telle idee ...... Mais cette tension qu on sup¬ pose dans les nerfs, et qui les rend si susceptibles d’dbranlement et de vibration, est si grossierement imaginee qu il seroit ridicule de s’occuper serieusement a la refuter.” (Econ. Animate, sect. 3. c. 13.) _ _ _ ..... As this passage from Quesnai is quoted by Condillac, and sanctioned by his authority (Traite des Animaux, Chap, m.), it would appear that the hypothesis which supposes the nerves to perform their functions by means of vibrations was going fast into discredit, both among the metaphysicians and the physiologists of F ranee, at the very time when it was beginning to attract notice in England, in consequence of the visionary speculations of Hartley. 1 In a letter which I received from Dr Parr, he mentions a treatise of Dr Hartley’s which appeared about a year before the publication of his great work ; to which it was meant by the author to serve as a precursor. Of this rare treatise I liad never before heard. “You will be astonished to hear,” says Dr Parr, “that in this book,, instead of the doctrine of ne¬ cessity, Hartley openly declares for the indifference of the will, as maintained by Archbishop King. ’ We are told by Hartley himself that his notions upon necessity grew upon him while he was writing his observations upon man; but it is curious (as Dr Parr remarks), that in the course of a year, his opinions on so very essential a point should have undei- gone a complete change. ' a Dr Priestley’s opinion of the merits of Hartley’s work is thus stated by himselfSomething was done in this held ot knowledge by Descartes, very much by Mr Locke, but most of all by Dr Hartley, who has thrown more useiuJ ig i upon the theory of the mind, than Newton did upon the theorv of the natural world.”—(Remarks on Reid, Beattie, and Uswa , p. 2. London, 1774.) 172 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. “ a doctrine equally necessary to comfort the weakness, and to support our lofty ideas of the grandeur of human nature;”1 and of which it seems hard to confine exclusively the knowledge to that portion of mankind who have been fa¬ voured with the light of Revelation. The in¬ fluence of the same fundamental error, arising, too, from the same mistaken idea, of thus strengthening the cause of Christianity, may be traced in various passages of the posthumous work of the late Bishop of LlandafF. It is won¬ derful that the reasonings of Clarke and of But¬ ler did not teach these eminent men a sounder and more consistent logic; or, at least, open their eyes to the inevitable consequences of the rash concessions which they made to their ad¬ versaries. * Among the disciples of Law, one illustrious exception to these remarks occurs in Dr Paley, whose treatise on Natural Theology is unques¬ tionably the most instructive as well as inte¬ resting publication on that subject which has appeared in our times. As the hook was in¬ tended for popular use, the author has wisely avoided, as much as possible, all metaphysical discussions; hut I do not know that there exists any other work where the argument from final causes is placed in so great a variety of pleasing and striking points of view. SECTION YI. Condillac, and other French Metaphysicians of a later date. While Hartley and Bonnet were indulging their imagination in theorising concerning the nature of the union between soul and body, Condillac was attempting to draw the attention of his countrymen to the method of studying the phenomena of Mind recommended and ex¬ emplified by Locke.3 Of the vanity of expect¬ ing to illustrate, by physiological conjectures. J Smith’s Theory of Moral Sentiments, 6th ed. Yol. I. pp. 325, 326. Dr Law’s doctrine of the sleep of the soul, to which his high station in the church could not fail to add much weight in the judgment of many, is, I believe, now universally adopted by the followers of Hartley and Priestley ; the theory of vi¬ brations being evidently inconsistent with the supposition of the soul’s being able to exercise her powers in a separate state from the body. 2 Without entering at all into the argument with Dr Law or his followers, it is sufficient here to mention, as an histori¬ cal fact, their wide departure from the older lights of the English church, from Hooker downwards. “ All religion,” says Archbishop Tillotson, whom I select as an unexceptionable organ of their common sentiments, “ is founded on right no¬ tions of God and his perfections, insomuch that Divine Revelation itself does suppose these for its foundations; and can signify nothing to us unless they be first known and believed; so that the principles of natural religion are the foundation of that which is revealed.”—(Sermon 41.) “ There is an intrinsical good and evil in things, and the reasons and respects of moral good and evil are fixed and immutable, eternal and indispensable. Nor do they speak safely who make the Divine will the rule of moral good and evil, as if there were nothing good or evil in its own nature antecedently to the will of God; but, that all things are therefore good and evil because God wills them to be so.”—(Sermon 88.) “Natural religion is obe¬ dience to the natural law, and the performance of such duties as natural light, without any express and supernatural reve¬ lation, doth dictate to men. These lie at the bottom of all religion, and are the great fundamental duties which God re¬ quires of all mankind. These are the surest and most sacred of all other laws ; those which God hath rivetted in our souls and written upon our hearts ; and these are what we call moral duties, and most valued by God, which are of eternal and perpetual obligation, because they do naturally oblige, without any particular and express revelation from God ; and these are the foundation of revealed and instituted religion; and all revealed religion does suppose them and build upon them.”— Sermons 48. 49. 3 It may appear to some unaccountable, that no notice should have been taken, in this Dissertation, of any French me¬ taphysician during the long interval between Malebranche and Condillac. As an apology for this apparent omission, I beg leave to quote the words of an author intimately acquainted with the history of French literature and philosophy, and emi¬ nently qualified to appreciate the merits of those who have contributed to their progress. “ If we except,” says Mr Adam Smith, in a Memoir published in 1755, “the Meditations of Descartes, I know of nothing in the works of French writers which aspires at originality in morals or metaphysics; for the philosophy of Regius and that of Malebranche are nothing more than the meditations of Descartes unfolded with more art and refinement. But Hobbes, Locke, Dr Mandeville, Lord Shaftesbury, Dr Butler, Dr Clarke, and Mr Hutcheson, each in his own system, all different and all incompatible, have tried to be original, at least in some points. They have attempted to add something to the fund of observations cel. DISSERTATION FIRST. 173 the manner in which the intercourse between the thinking principle and the external world is carried on, no philosopher seems ever to have been more completely aware; and, accordingly, he confines himself strictly, in all his researches concerning this intercourse, to an examination of the general laws by which it is regulated. There is, at the same time, a remarkable coin¬ cidence between some of his views and those of the other two writers. All of the three, while they profess the highest veneration for Locke, have abandoned his account of the origin of our ideas for that of Gassendi; and, by doing so, have, with the best intentions, furnished arms against those principles which it was their com¬ mon aim to establish in the world.1 It is much to he regretted, that by far the greater part of those French writers who have since speculated about the human mind, have acquired the whole of their knowledge of Locke’s philosophy through this mistaken comment upon its fundamental principle. On this subject I have already ex¬ hausted all that I have to offer on the effect of Condillac’s writings; and I flatter myself have sufficiently shown how widely his commentary differs from the text of his author. It is this commentary, however, which is now almost universally received on the Continent as the doctrine of Locke, and which may justly he re¬ garded as the sheet-anchor of those systems which are commonly stigmatised in England with the appellation of French philosophy. Had Condillac been sufficiently aware of the conse¬ quences which have been deduced (and I must add logically deduced) from his account of the origin of our knowledge, I am persuaded, from his known candour and love of truth, that he would have been eager to acknowledge and to retract his error. In this apparent simplification and generali¬ sation of Locke’s doctrine, there is, it must he acknowledged, something, at first sight, ex¬ tremely seducing. It relieves the mind from the painful exercise of abstracted reflection, and amuses it with analogy and metaphor when it looked only for the severity of logical discus¬ sion. The clearness and simplicity of Condil¬ lac’s style add to the force of this illusion, and flatter the reader with an agreeable idea of the powers of his own understanding, when he finds himself so easily conducted through the darkest labyrinths of metaphysical science. It is to this cause I would chiefly ascribe the great popula¬ rity of his works. They may he read with as little exertion of thought as a history or a novel; and it is only when we shut the hook, and at¬ tempt to express in our own words the sub¬ stance of what we have gained, that we have the mortification to see our supposed acquisitions vanish into air. The philosophy of Condillac was, in a more peculiar manner, suited to the taste of his own country, where (according to Mad. de Stael) “ few read a hook but with a view to talk of it.” s Among such a people, speculations which are addressed to the power of reflection can never expect to acquire the same popularity with theories expressed in a metaphorical lan- lected by their predecessors, and already the common property of mankind. This branch of science, which the English themselves neglect at present, appears to have been recently transported into France. I discover some traces of it not only in the Encycloptdic, but in the Theory of Agreeable Sensations, by M. de Pouilly; and much more in the late discourse of M. Rousseau, On the Origin and Foundation of the Inequality of Ranks among Men." Although I perfectly agree with Mr Smith in his general remark on the sterility of invention among the French meta¬ physicians posterior to Descartes, when compared to those of England, I cannot pass over the foregoing quotation with¬ out expressing my surprise, lif, To find the name of Malebranche (one of the highest in modern philosophy) degraded to a level with that of Regius; and, 2dly, To observe Mr Smith’s silence with respect to Buffier and Condillac, while he men¬ tions the author of the Theory of Agreeable Sensations as a metaphysician of original genius. Of the merits of Condillac, whose most important works were published several years before this paper of Mr Smith’s, I am about to speak in the text; and those of Buffier I shall have occasion to mention in a subsequent part of this discourse. In the mean time, I shall only say of him, that I regard him as one of the most original as well as sound philosophers of whom the eighteenth century has to boast. 1 Condillac’s earliest work appeared three years before the publication of Hartley’s Theory. It is entitled, “ Essai sur l Origine des Connoissances Humaines. Ouvrage ou Von reduit a un seul principe tout ce qui concerne Ventendement humain." This seul principe is the association of ideas. The account which both authors give of the transformation of sensations into ideas is substantially the same. * “ En France, on ne lit guere un ouvrage que pour en parler.”—(Allcmagne, Tom. I. p. 292.) The same remark, I am much afraid, is becoming daily more and more applicable to our own island. 174 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. guage, and constantly recalling to the fancy the impressions of the external senses. The state of society in France, accordingly, is singularly unfavourable to the inductive philosophy of the human mind; and of this truth no proof more decisive can he produced, than the admiration with which the metaphysical writings of Con¬ dillac have been so long regarded. On the other hand, it cannot be denied that Condillac has, in many instances, been eminent¬ ly successful, both in observing and describing the mental phenomena; but, in such cases, he commonly follows Locke as his guide; and, wherever he trusts to his own judgment, he seldom fails to wander from his way. The best part of his works relates to the action and re¬ action of thought and language on each other, a subject which had been previously very pro¬ foundly treated by Locke, but which Condillac has had the merit of placing in many new and happy points of view. In various cases, his conclusions are pushed too far, and in others are expressed without due precision; but, on the whole, they form a most valuable accession to this important branch of logic; and (what not a little enhances their value) they have been instrumental in recommending the subject to the attention of other inquirers, still better qua¬ lified than their author to do it justice. In the speculation, too, concerning the origin and the theoretical history of language, Condil¬ lac was one of the first who made any consider¬ able advances; nor does it reflect any discredit on his ingenuity, that he has left some of the principal difficulties connected with the inquiry very imperfectly explained. The same subject was soon after taken up by Mr Smith, who, I think, it must be owned, has rather slurred over these difficulties, than attempted to remove them; an omission on his part the more re¬ markable, as a very specious and puzzling ob¬ jection had been recently stated by Rousseau, not only to the theory of Condillac, but to all speculations which have for their object the so¬ lution of the same problem. “ If language” (says Rousseau) “ be the result of human con¬ vention, and if words be essential to the exer¬ cise of thought, language would appear to be necessary for the invention of language.”1 — “ But” (continues the same author) “ when, by means which I cannot conceive, our new gram¬ marians began to extend their ideas, and to generalise their words, their ignorance must have confined them within very narrow bounds. How, for example, could they ima¬ gine or comprehend such words as matter, mind, substance, mode, figure, motion, since our phi¬ losophers, who have so long made use of them, scarcely understand them, and since the ideas attached to them, being purely metaphysical, can have no model in nature ?” “ I stop at these first steps” (continues Rous¬ seau), “ and intreat my judges to pause, and consider the distance between the easiest part of language, the invention of physical substantives, and the power of expressing all the thoughts of man, so as to speak in public, and influence so¬ ciety. I entreat them to reflect upon the time and knowledge it must have required to dis¬ cover numbers, abstract words, aorists, and all the tenses of verbs, particles, syntax, the art of connecting propositions and arguments, and how to form the whole logic of discourse. As for myself, alarmed at these multiplying diffi¬ culties, and convinced of the almost demon¬ strable impossibility of language having been formed and established by means merely human, I leave to others the discussion of the problem, i Whether a society already formed was more necessary for the institution of language, or a language already invented for the establishment of society ?’ ”* Of the various difficulties here enumerated, that mentioned by Rousseau, in the last sentence, was plainly considered by him as the greatest of all; or rather as comprehending under it all 1 That men never could have invented an artificial language, if they had not possessed a natural language, is an observa¬ tion of Dr Iteid’s; and it is this indisputable and self-evident truth which gives to Rousseau’s remark that imposing plau¬ sibility, which, at first sight, dazzles and perplexes the judgment. I by no means say, that the former proposition affords a key to all the difficulties suggested by the latter ; but it advances us at least one important step towards their solution. * Discours sur VOrigine et les Fondemens de I'Inegalite parmi les Hommes DISSERTATION FIRST. 175 the rest. But this difficulty arises merely from his own peculiar and paradoxical theory about the artificial origin of society; a theory which needs no refutation, but the short and luminous aphorism of Montesquieu, that “ man is born in society, and there he remains.” The other dif¬ ficulties touched upon by Rousseau, in the for¬ mer part of this quotation, are much more se¬ rious, and have never yet been removed in a manner completely satisfactory: And hence some very ingenious writers have been led to conclude, that language could not possibly have been the work of human invention. This ar¬ gument has been lately urged with much acute¬ ness and plausibility by Dr Magee of Dublin, and by M. de Bonald of Paris.1 It may, how¬ ever, be reasonably questioned, if these philoso¬ phers would not have reasoned more logically, had they contented themselves with merely af¬ firming, that the problem has not yet been solv¬ ed, without going so far as to pronounce it to n be absolutely insolvable. For my own part, when I consider its extreme difficulty, and the short space of time during which it has engaged the attention of the learned, I am more dispos¬ ed to wonder at the steps which have been al¬ ready gained in the research, than at the num¬ ber of desiderata which remain to employ the ingenuity of our successors. It is justly re¬ marked by Dr Ferguson, that, “ when language has attained to that perfection to which it ar¬ rives in the progress of society, the speculative mind, in comparing the first and the last stages of the progress, feels the same sort of amaze¬ ment with a traveller, who, after rising insen¬ sibly on the slope of a hill, comes to look down from a precipice, to the summit of which he scarcely believes he could have ascended with¬ out supernatural aid.”2 With respect to some of the difficulties point¬ ed out by Rousseau and his commentators, it may be here remarked in passing (and the ob¬ servation is equally applicable to various pas¬ sages in Mr Smith’s dissertation on the same subject), that the difficulty of explaining the theory of any of our intellectual operations af¬ fords no proof of any difficulty in applying that operation to its proper practical purpose; nor is the difficulty of explaining the metaphysical nature of any part of speech a proof, that, in its first origin, it implied any extraordinary effort of intellectual capacity. How many metaphy¬ sical difficulties might be raised about the ma¬ thematical notion of a line ? And yet this notion is perfectly comprehended by every peasant, when he speaks of the distance between two places; or of the length, breadth, or height of his cottage. In like manner, although it may be difficult to give a satisfactory account of the origin and import of such words as of or by, we ought not to conclude, that the invention of them implied any metaphysical knowledge in 1 The same theory has been extended to the art of writing; but if this art was first taught to man by an express reve¬ lation from Heaven, what account can be given of its present state in the great empire of China ? Is the mode of writing practised there of divine or of human origin ? s Principles of Moral and Political Science, Vol- I. p. 43. Edin. 1792. To this observation may be added, by way of com¬ ment, the following reflections of one of the most learned prelates of the English church :—“ Man, we are told, had a lan¬ guage from the beginning; for he conversed with God, and gave to every animal its particular name. But how came man by language ? He must either have had it from inspiration, ready formed from his Creator, or have derived it by the exer¬ tion of those faculties of the mind, which were implanted in him as a rational creature, from natural and external objects with which he was surrounded. Scripture is silent on the means by which it was acquired. We are not, therefore, war¬ ranted to affirm, that it was received by inspiration, and there is no internal evidence in language to lead us to such a sup¬ position. On this side, then, of the question, we have nothing but uncertainty; but on a subject, the causes of which are so remote, nothing is more convenient than to refer them to inspiration, and to recur to that easy and comprehensive argu¬ ment, Ails irsXusro (houXn' that is, man enjoyed the great privilege of speech, which distinguished him at first, and still continues to distinguish him as a rational creature, so eminently from the brute creation, without exerting those reasoning faculties, by which he was in other respects enabled to raise himself so much above their level. Inspiration, then, seems to have been an argument adopted and made necessary by the difficulty of accounting for it otherwise; and the name of inspiration carries with it an awfulness, which forbids the unhallowed approach of inquisitive discussion.”—(Essay on the Study of Antiquities, by Dr Bur¬ gess, 2d edit. Oxford, 1732. Pp. 85, 86.) It is farther remarked very sagaciously, and I think very decisively, by the same author, that “ the supposition of man having received a language ready formed from his Creator, is actually inconsistent with the evidence of the origin of our ideas, which exists in language For, as the origin of our ideas is to be traced in the words through which the ideas are conveyed, so the origin oflanguage is referable to the source from whence our (first) ideas are derived, namely, nature1 and external objects.”—(Ibid. pp. 83, 84.) 176 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. the individual who first employed them.1 Their import, we see, is fully understood by children of three or four years of age. In this view of the History of Language I have been anticipated by Dr Ferguson. “ Parts of speech” (says this profound and original writer), which, in speculation, cost the gram¬ marian so much study, are, in practice, familiar to the vulgar. The rudest tribes, even the idiot and the insane, are possessed of them. They are soonest learned in childhood, insomuch that we must suppose human nature, in its lowest state, competent to the use of them; and, with¬ out the intervention of uncommon genius, man¬ kind, in a succession of ages, qualified to ac¬ complish in detail this amazing fabric of lan¬ guage, which, when raised to its height, appears so much above what could be ascribed to any simultaneous effort of the most sublime and comprehensive abilities.”2 It is, however, less in tracing the first rudi¬ ments of speech, than in some collateral inqui¬ ries concerning the genius of different languages, that Condillac’s ingenuity appears to advantage. Some of his observations, in particular, on the connection of natural signs with the growth of a systematical prosody, and on the imitative arts of the Greeks and Romans, as distinguished from those of the moderns, are new and cu¬ rious ; and are enlivened with a mixture of his¬ torical illustration, and of critical discussion, seldom to he met with among metaphysical writers. But through all his researches, the radical error may, more or less, be traced, which lies at the bottom of his system ;3 and hence it is, 1 In this remark I had an eye to the following passage in Mr Smith’s dissertation“ It is worth while to observe, that those prepositions, which, in modern languages, hold the place of the ancient cases, are, of all others, the most general, and abstract, and metaphysical; and, of consequence, would prolably be the last invented. Ask any man of common acuteness, what relation is expressed by the preposition above? He will readily answer, that of superiority. 15y the preposition below ? He * will as quickly reply, that of inferiority. But ask him what relation is expressed by the preposition off and, if he has not beforehand employed his thoughts a good deal upon these subjects, you may safely allow him a week to consider of his answ'er.” 5 The following judicious reflections, with which M Baynouard concludes the introduction to his Elemens de la Langur. Romane, may serve to illustrate some of the above observations. The modification of an existing language is, I acknow¬ ledge, a thing much less wonderful than the formation of a language entirely new ; but the processes of thought, it is rea¬ sonable to think, are, in both cases, of the same kind; and the consideration of the one is at least a step gained towards the elucidation of the other. “ La langue Ilomane est peut-etre la seule a la formation de laquelle il soit permis de remonter ainsi, pour dexouvrir et expliquer le secret de son industrieux mecanisme. . . . J’ose dire que 1’esprit philosophique, consult^ sur le choix des moyens qui devraient dpargner a 1’ignorance beaucoup d’dtudes penibles et fastidieux, n’eut pas dtd aussi heureux quel’ig- norance elle-meme ; il est vrai qu’elle avoit deux grands maitres ; la Necessite et le Tems. “ En considerant a quelle epoque d’ignorance et de barbarie s’est forme et perfectionne ce nouvel idiome, d’apres des principes indiquds seulement par 1’analogie et 1’euphonie, on se dira peut-etre comme je me le suis dit; 1’homme porte en soi-meme les principes d’une logique naturelle, d’un instinct regulateur, que nous admirons quelquefois dans les enfans. Oui, la Providence nous a dote' de la faculte indestructible et des moyens ingenieux d’exprimer, de communiquer, d’dterni- ser par la parole, et par les signes permanens ou elle se reproduit, cette pensee qui est Pun de nos plus beaux attributs, et qui nous distingue si eminemment et si avantageusement dans Pordre de la creation.”—(Elemens de la Grammaire de la Langue Romane avant VAn. 1000. Pp. 104, 105. A Paris, 1810.) In the theoretical history of language, it is more than probable, that some steps will remain to exercise the ingenuity of our latest posterity. Nor will this appear surprising, when we consider how impossible it is for us to judge, from our own experience, of the intellectual processes which pass in the minds of savages. Some instincts, we know, possessed both by them and by infants (that ot imitation, for example, and the use of natural signs), disappear in by far the greater number of in¬ dividuals, almost entirely in the maturity of their reason. It does not seem at all improbable, that other instincts connect¬ ed with the invention ot speech, may be confined to that state of the intellectual powers which requires their guidance: nor is it quite impossible, that some latent capacities of the understanding may be evolved by the pressure of necessity. The facility with which infants surmount so many grammatical and metaphysical difficulties, seems to me to add much weight to these conjectures. In tracing the first steps of the invention of language, it ought never to be forgotten, that ive undertake a task more si¬ milar than might at first be supposed, to that of tracing the first operations of the infant mind. In both cases, we are apt to attempt an explanation from reason alone, of what requires the co-operation of very different principles. To trace the theoretical history of geometry, in which we know for certain, that all the transitions have depended on reasoning alone, is a problem which has not yet been completely solved. Nor has even any satisfactory account been hitherto given of the experimental steps by which men were gradually led to the use of iron. And yet how simple are these problems, when compared with that relating to the origin and progress of language! 3 A remarkable instance of this occurs in that part of Condillac’s Cours d'Etude, where he treats of the art of writing : “ Vous savez, Monseigneur, comment les memes noms ont etd transporte's des objets qui tombent sous ks sens a ceux qui fes echappent. Vous avez remarque, qu’il y en a qui sont encore en usage dans 1’un et 1’autre acceptation, et qu’il y en a qui sont devenus les noms propres des choses, dont ils avoient d’abord dtd les signes figures. “ Les premiers, tel que le mouvement de 1’ame, son penchant, sa reflexion, donnent un corps a des choses qui n’en ont pas. Les seconds, tels que la pensee, la volonte, le desir, ne peignent plus rien, et laissent aux idees abstraites cette spiritualite qui les de'robe aux sens. Mais si le langage doit etre I’image de nos pensees, on a perdu beaucoup, lorsqu’ oubliant la pre- DISSERTATION FIRST. 177 that, with all his skill as a writer, he never ele¬ vates the imagination, or touches the heart. That he wrote with the best intentions, we have satisfactory evidence; and yet hardly a philo¬ sopher can be named, whose theories have had more influence in misleading the opinions of his contemporaries.1 In France, he very early attained to a rank and authority not inferior to those which have been so long and so deserved¬ ly assigned to Locke in England; and even in this country, his works have been more gene¬ rally read and admired, than those of any fo¬ reign metaphysician of an equally recent date. The very general sketches to which I am here obliged to confine myself, do not allow me to take notice of various contributions to metaphy¬ sical science, which are to he collected from writers professedly intent upon other subjects. I must not, however, pass over in silence the name of Buflbn, who, in the midst of those magnificent views of external nature, which the peculiar character of his eloquence fitted him so admirably to delineate, has frequently indulged himself in ingenious discussions con¬ cerning the faculties both of men and of brutes. His subject, indeed, led his attention chiefly to man, considered as an animal; hut the pecu¬ liarities which the human race exhibit in their physical condition, and the manifest reference which these bear to their superior rank in the creation, unavoidably engaged him in specula¬ tions of a higher aim, and of a deeper interest. In prosecuting these, he has been accused (and perhaps with some justice) of ascribing too much to the effects of bodily organisation on the intellectual powers; hut he leads his reader in so pleasing a manner from matter to mind, that I have no doubt he has attracted the curio¬ sity of many to metaphysical inquiries, who would never otherwise have thought of them. In his theories concerning the nature of the brutes, he has been commonly considered as leaning to the opinion of Descartes; but I can¬ not help thinking, without any good reason. Some of his ideas on the complicated operations of insects appear to me just and satisfactory; and while they account for the phenomena, without ascribing to the animal any deep or comprehensive knowledge, are far from de¬ grading him to an insentient and unconscious machine. In his account of the process by which the use of our external senses (particularly that of sight) is acquired, Buffon has in general foliow- iniere signification des mots, on a dff'ace jusqu’au traits qu’ils donnoient aux idees. Toutes les langues sont en cela plusou moins defectueuses, toutes aussi ont des tableaux plus ou moins conserves.”—(Cours d'Etude, Tome II. p. 212. a Parme, 1775.) ... . , . Condillac enlarges on this point at considerable length ; endeavouring to show, that whenever we lose sight of the ana¬ logical origin of a figurative word, we become insensible to one of the chief beauties of language. “ In the word examen, for example, a Frenchman perceives only the proper name of one of our mental operations. A Roman attached to it the same idea, and received over and above the image of weighing and balancing. The case is the same with the words awe and anima ; pensee and cogitatio. In this view of the subject, Condillac plainly proceeded on his favourite principle, that all our notions of our mental ope. rations are compounded of sensible images. Whereas the fact is, that the only just notions we can form of the powers of the mind are obtained by abstracting from the qualities and laws of the material world. In proportion, therefore, as the analogical origin of a figurative word disappears, it becomes a fitter instrument of metaphysical thought and reasoning— (See Philosophical Essays, Part I. Essay V. Chap, iii.) 1 A late writer (M. de Bonald), whose philosophical opinions, in general, agree nearly with those of La Harpe, has, how¬ ever, appreciated very differently, and, in my judgment, much more sagaciously, the merits, of Condillac : “ Condillac a eu sur I’esprit philosophique du dernier siecle, Pinfluence que Voltaire a prise sur 1’esprit religieux, et J. J. Rousseau sur les opinions politiques. Condillac a mis de la sdcheresse et de la minutie dans les esprits; Voltaire du penchant it la raillerie et k la frivolite ; Rousseau les a rendus chagrins et mecontens Condillac a encore plus fausse I’esprit de la nation, parce que sa doctrine etoit enseignee dans les premieres etudes a des jeunes gens qui n’avoient encore lu ni Rous¬ seau ni Voltaire, et que la maniere de raisonner et la direction philosophique de I’esprit s’etdndent a tout.”—(Recherchcs Phil. Tome I. pp. 187, 188.) The following criticism on the supposed perspicuity of Condillac’s style is so just and philosophical, that I cannot refrain from giving it a place here : Condillac est, ou paroit etre, clair et methodique ; mais il faut prendre garde, que la clarte des pensdes, comme la transparence des objets physiques, peut tenir d’un de'faut de profondeur, et que la methode dans les dcrits, qui suppose la patience de I’esprit, n’en prouve pas toujours la justesse ; et moins encore la fecondite. II y a aussi une clarte de style en quelque sorte toute materielle, qui n’est pas incompatible avec 1’obscuritd dans les idees. Rien de plus facile a entendre que les mots de sensations transformies dont Condillac s’est servi, parce que ces mots ne parlent qu a 1’imagination, qui se figure a volontd des transformations et des changemens. Mais cette transformation, appliquee aux operations de I’esprit, n’est qu’un mot vide de sens; et Condillac lui-meme auroit ete bien embarrasse d’en dormer une explication satisfaisante. Ce philosophe me paroit plus heureux dans ses apper^us que dans ses demonstrations: La route de la verite semble quelquefois s’ouvrir devant lui, mais retenu par la circonspection naturelle a un esprit sans chaleur, et intimidd par la faiblesse de son propre systeme, il n’ose s’v engager.”—(Ibid. Tome I. pp. 33. 34.) DISS. I. PART II. Z 178 preliminary dissertations. ed the principles of Berkeley; and, notwith¬ standing some important mistakes which have escaped him in his applications of these prin¬ ciples, I do not know that there is anywhere to be found so pleasing or so popular an exposition of the theory of vision. Nothing certainly was ever more finely imagined, than the recital which he puts into the mouth of our first pa¬ rent, of the gradual steps by which he learned the use of his perceptive organs ; and although there are various parts of it which will not hear the test of a rigorous examination, it is impos¬ sible to read it without sharing in that admira¬ tion, with which we are told the author himself always regarded this favourite effusion of his eloquence. Nor are these the only instances in which Buffon has discovered the powers of a metaphy¬ sician. His thoughts on probabilities (a sub¬ ject widely removed from his favourite studies) afford a proof how strongly some metaphysical questions had laid hold of his curiosity, and what new lights he was qualified to throw on them, if he had allowed them to occupy more of his attention.1 * 3 * In his observations, too, on the peculiar nature of mathematical evidence, he has struck into a train of the soundest think¬ ing, in which he has been very generally fol¬ lowed by our later logicians.9 Some particular expressions in the passage I refer to are excep¬ tionable; but his remarks on what he calls Verites de Definition are just and important; nor do I remember any modern writer, of an earlier date, who has touched on the same argu¬ ment. Plato, indeed, and after him Proclus, had called the definitions of geometry Hypothe¬ ses ; an expression which may be considered as involving the doctrine which Buffon and his successors have more fully unfolded. What the opinions of Buffon were on those essential questions, which were then in dispute among the French philosophers, his writings do not furnish the means of judging with certainty. In his theory of Organic Molecules, and of In¬ ternal Moulds, he has been accused of entertain¬ ing views not very different from those of the ancient atomists; nor would it perhaps be easy to repel the charge, if we were not able to op¬ pose to this wild and unintelligible hypothesis the noble and elevating strain, which in general so peculiarly characterises his descriptions of natqre. The eloquence of some of the finest passages in his works has manifestly been in¬ spired by the same sentiment which dictated to one of his favourite authors the following just and pathetic reflection:—“ Le spectacle de la nature, si vivant, si anime pour ceux qui recon- noissent un Dieu, est mort aux yeux de Tath^e, et dans cette grande harmonic des etres ou tout parle de Dieu d’une voix si douce, il n’aper^oit qu’un silence eternel.”5 * * * I have already mentioned the strong bias to¬ wards materialism which the authors of the En¬ cyclopedic derived from Condillac’s comments upon Locke. These comments they seem to have received entirely upon credit, without ever being at pains to compare them with the origi¬ nal. Had D’Alembert exercised freely his own judgment, no person was more likely to have perceived their complete futility; and, in fact, he has thrown out various observations which strike at their very root. Notwithstanding, however, these occasional glimpses of light, he invariably reverts to the same error, and has once and again repeated it in terms as strong as Condillac or Gassendi. The author who pushed this account of the origin of our knowledge to the most extraordi¬ nary and offensive consequences, was Helvetius. His book, De VEsprit, is said to have been com- 1 See his Essai cT Arithmctlque Morale. 3 See the First Discourse prefixed to his Natural History, towards the end. 3 Rousseau—In a work by Hdrault de Sechelles (entitled Voyages a Montbar, contemnt des details trh interessans sur le caractere, la persunne, et les ecrits de Buffon, Paris, 1801), a very different idea of his religious creed is given from that which I have ascribed to him ; but, in direct opposition to this statement, we have a letter, dictated by Buffon, on his death-bed, to Madame Necker, in return for a present of her husband’s book, On the Importance of Religious Opinions. The letter (we are told) is in the hand-writing of Buffon’s son, who describes his father as then too weak to hold the pen.—(Melanges ex¬ traits des Manuscrits de Madame Necker. 3 Vols. Paris, 1788.) The sublime address to the Supreme Being, with which Buffon closes his reflections on the calamities of war, seems to breathe the very soul of Fenelon. “ Grand Dieu ! dont la seule presence soutient la nature et maintient 1’harmonie des loix de I’univers,” &c. &c. &,c DISSERTATION FIRST. 179 posed of materials collected from the conversa¬ tions of the society in which he habitually lived; and it has accordingly heen quoted as an au¬ thentic record of the ideas then in fashion among the wits of Paris. The unconnected and desul¬ tory composition of the work certainly furnishes some intrinsic evidence of the truth of this anecdote. According to Helvetius, as all our ideas are derived from the external senses,1 the causes of the inferiority of the souls of brutes to those of men, are to he sought for in the difference be¬ tween them with respect to bodily organisation. In illustration of this remark he reasons as fol¬ lows :— “1. The feet of all quadrupeds terminate ei¬ ther in horn, as those of the ox and the deer; or in nails, as those of the dog and the wolf; or in claws, as those of the lion and the cat. This peculiar organisation of the feet of these animals deprives them not only of the sense of touch, considered as a channel of information with re¬ spect to external objects, hut also of the dexte¬ rity requisite for the practice of the mechanical arts. “ 2. The life of animals, in general, being of a shorter duration than that of man, does not permit them to make so many observations, or to acquire so many ideas. “ 3. Animals being better armed and better clothed by nature than the human species, have fewer wants, and consequently fewer motives to stimulate or to exercise their invention. If the voracious animals are more cunning than others, it is because hunger, ever inventive, inspires them with the art of stratagems to surprise their prey. “ 4). The lower animals compose a society that flies from man, who, by the assistance of weapons made by himself, is become formidable to the strongest amongst them. “ 5. Man is the most prolific and versatile animal upon earth. He is horn and lives in every climate; while many of the other animals, as the lion, the elephant, and the rhinoceros, are found only in a certain latitude. And the more any species of animals capable of making obser¬ vations is multiplied, the more ideas and the greater ingenuity is it likely to possess. “ But some may ask (continues Helvetius), why monkeys, whose paws are nearly as dexte¬ rous as our hands, do not make a progress equal to that of man ? A variety of causes (he ob¬ serves) conspire to fix them in that state of in¬ feriority in which we find them:—1. Men are more multiplied upon the earth. 2. Among the different species of monkeys, there are few whose strength can be compared with that of man; and, accordingly, they form only a fugi¬ tive society before the human race. 3. Monkeys being frugiverous, have fewer wants, and, there¬ fore, less invention than man. 4. Their life is shorter. And, finally, the organical structure of their bodies keeping them, like children, in perpetual motion, even after their desires are sa¬ tisfied, they are not susceptible of lassitude {ennuiJ, which ought to be considered (as I shall prove afterwards) as one of the principles 1 In combating the philosophy of Helvetius, La Harpe (whose philosophical opinions seem, on many occasions, to have been not a little influenced by his private partialities and dislikes) exclaims loudly against the same principles to which he had tacitly given his unqualified approbation in speaking of Condillac. On this occasion he is at pains to distinguish between the doctrines of the two writers; asserting that Condillac considered our senses as only the occasional causes of our ideas, while Helvetius represented the former as the productive causes of the latter—f Cours de Litterat. Tome XV. pp. 348, 349.) But that this is by no means reconcileable with the general spirit of Condillac’s works (although perhaps some detached expres¬ sions may be selected from them admitting of such an interpretation), appears sufficiently from the passages formerly quot¬ ed. In addition to these, I beg leave to transcribe the following : “ Dans le systeme que toutes nos connoisances viennent des sens, rien n’est plus aise que de se faire une notion exacte des iddes. Car elles ne sont que des sensations ou des por¬ tions extraites de quelque sensation pour etre considerees a part; ce qui produit deux sortes d’idees, les sensible^ et les abstraites.”—(Traitc des Systemes, Chap, vi.) “ Puisque nous avons vu que le souvenir n’est qu’une maniere de sentir, c’est une consequence, que les idees intellectuelles ne different pas essentiellement des sensations memes.”—(Traite des Sensa¬ tions, Chap. viii. § 33.) Is not this precisely the doctrine and even the language of Helvetius ? In the same passage of the Lycie, from which the above quotation is taken from La Harpe, there is a sweeping judgment pronounced on the merits of Locke, which may serve as a specimen of the author’s competency to decide on metaphysical questions : “ Locke a prouvd autant qu’il est possible a 1’homme, que I’ame est une substance simple et indivisible, et par consequent immaterielle. Cependant, il ajoute, qu’il n’oseroit affirmer que Dieu ne puisse douer la matiere de pensee. Condillac est de son avis sur le premier article, et le combat sur le second. Je suis entierement de 1’avis de Condillac, et tons les bons mttaphysiciens conviennent que c'est la seule inexactitude qu'on puisse relever dans I'ouvrage de Locke."—(Cours de LitteraU Tome XV. p. 149.) 180 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. to which the human mind owes its improve¬ ment. “ By combining (he adds) all these differences between the nature of man and of beast, we may understand why sensibility and memory, though faculties common to man and to the lower ani¬ mals, are in the latter only sterile qualities.”1 The foregoing passage is translated literally from a note on one of the first paragraphs of the book De VEsprit; and in the sentence of the text to which the note refers, the author trium¬ phantly asks, £C Who can doubt, that if the wrist of a man had been terminated by the hoof of a horse, the species would still have been wander¬ ing in the forest ?” Without attempting any examination of this shallow and miserable theory, I shall content myself with observing, that it is not peculiar to the philosophers of modern France. From the Memorabilia of Xenophon it appears, that it was current among the sophists of Greece; and the answer given it by Socrates is as philosophical and satisfactory as any thing that could possibly be advanced in the present state of the sciences. “ And canst thou doubt, Aristodemus, if the gods take care of man ? Hath not the privilege of an erect form been bestowed on him alone ? Other animals they have provided with feet, by which they may he removed from one place to another; hut to man they have also given the use of the hand. A tongue hath been bestowed on every other animal; but what animal, except man, hath the power of making his thoughts in¬ telligible to others ? “ Nor is it with respect to the body alone that the gods have shown themselves bountiful to man. WTio seeth not that he is as it were a god in the midst of this visible creation ? So far doth he surpass all animals whatever in the endowments of his body and his mind. For if the body of the ox had been joined to the mind of man, the invention of the latter would have been of little avail, while unable to execute his purposes with facility. Nor would the human form have been of more use to the brute, so long as he remained destitute of understanding. But in thee, Aristodemus, hath been joined to a wonderful soul, a body no less wonderful; and sayst thou, after this, the gods take no care of me ? What wouldst thou then more to con¬ vince thee of their care ?” 2 A very remarkable passage to the same pur¬ pose occurs in Galen’s treatise, De Usu Partium. “But as of all animals man is the wisest, so hands are well fitted for the purposes of a wise animal. For it is not because he had hands that he is therefore wiser than the rest, as An¬ axagoras alleged; hut because he was wiser than the rest that he had therefore hands, as Aris¬ totle has most wisely judged. Neither was it his hands, hut his reason, which instructed man in the arts. The hands are only the organs by which the arts are practised.” 3 The contrast, in point of elevation, between the tone of French philosophy, and that of the best heathen moralists, was long ago remarked by Addison; and of this contrast it would be difficult to find a better illustration than the passages which have just been quoted. The disposition of ingenious men to pass sud¬ denly from one extreme to another in matters of controversy, has, in no instance, been more strikingly exemplified than in the opposite theo¬ ries concerning the nature of the brutes, which successively became fashionable in France du¬ ring the last century. While the prevailing creed of French materialists leads to the rejec¬ tion of every theory which professes to discri¬ minate the rational mind from the animal prin¬ ciple of action, it is well known that, hut a few years before, the disciples of Descartes allowed no one faculty to belong to man and brutes in common; and even went so far as to consider the latter in the light of mere machines. To this paradox the author was probably led, partly by his anxiety to elude the objection which the 1 It is not a little surprising that, in the above enumeration, Helvetius takes no notice of the want of language in the lower animals ; a faculty without which, the multiplication of individuals could contribute nothing to the improvement of the species. Nor is this want of language in the brutes owing to any defect in the organs of speech ; as sufficiently appears from those tribes which are possessed of the power of articulation in no inconsiderable degree. It plainly indicates, there¬ fore, some defect in those higher principles which are connected with the use of artificial signs- a Mrs Sarah Fielding’s Translation. * Galen, De Us. Part. 1. 1. e. 3. DISSERTATION FIRST. 181 faculties of the lower animals have been sup¬ posed to present to the doctrine of the immorta¬ lity of the soul, and partly by the difficulty of reconciling their sufferings with the Divine Goodness. Absurd as this idea may now appear, none of the tenets of Descartes were once adopted with more implicit faith by some of the profoundest thinkers in Europe. The great Pascal admired it as the finest and most valuable article of the Cartesian system ; and of the deep impression it made on the mind of Malebranche, a most de¬ cisive proof was exhibited by himself in the pre¬ sence of Fontenelle. “ M. de Fontenelle con- toit,” says one of his intimate friends,1 “ qu’un jour etant alle voir Malehranche aux PP. de TOratoire de la Rue St Honore, une grosse chienne de la maison, et qui etoit pleine, entra dans la salle ou ils se promenoient, vint caresser le P. Malebranche, et se rouler a ses pieds. Apres quelques mouvemens inutiles pour la chasser, le philosophe lui donna un grand coup de pied, qui fit jetter a la chienne un cri de dou- leur, et a M. de Fontehelle un cri de compas¬ sion. Eh quoi (lui dit froidement le P. Male¬ branche) ne s^avez vous pas bien que cela ne se sent point ?” On this point Fontenelle, though a zealous Cartesian, had the good sense to dissent openly from his master, and eA en to express his appro¬ bation of the sarcastic remark of La Motte, que cette opinion sur lesanimaux etoit une debauche de raisonnement. Is not the same expression equally applicable to the opposite theory quoted from Helvetius ? 2 From those representations of human nature which tend to assimilate to each other the facul¬ ties of man and of the brutes, the transition to atheism is not very wide. In the present in¬ stance, both conclusions seem to be the neces¬ sary corollaries of the same fundamental maxim. For if all the sources of our knowledge are to he found in the external senses, how is it possible for the human mind to rise to a conception of the Supreme Being, or to that of any other truth either of natural or of revealed religion ? To this question Gassendi and Condillac, it cannot be doubted, were both able to return an answer, which seemed to themselves abundantly satisfactory. But how few of the multitude are competent to enter into these refined explana¬ tions ? And how much is it to be dreaded, that the majority will embrace, with the general prin¬ ciple, all the more obvious consequences which to their own gross conceptions it seems neces¬ sarily to involve ? Something of the same sort may be remarked in the controversy about the freedom of the human will. Among the multi¬ tudes whom Leibnitz and Edwards have made converts to the scheme of necessity, how com¬ paratively inconsiderable is the number who have acquiesced in their subtle and ingenious attempts to reconcile this scheme with man’s ac¬ countableness and moral agency ? Of the prevalence of atheism at Paris, among the higher classes, at the period of which we are now speaking, the Memoires and Correspondance of the Baron de Grimm afford the most unques¬ tionable proofs.3 His friend Diderot seems to have been one of its most zealous abettors; who, 1 The Abb^ Trublet in the Mercure de Juillet, 1757 (See CEuvres de Fontenelle, Tome II. p. 137. Amsterdam, 17b‘4.) 2 In La Fontaine’s Discours d Madame de la Sabliere (Liv. X. Fable I.), the good sense with which he points out the ex¬ travagance of both these extremes is truly admirable. His argument (in spite of the fetters of rhyme) is stated, not only with his usual grace, but with singular clearness and precision ; and considering the period when he wrote, reflects much honour on his philosophical sagacity. 8 The Systeme de la Nature (the boldest, if not the ablest, publication of the Parisian atheists) appeared in 1770. It bore on the title-page the name of Mirabaud, a respectable but not very eminent writer, who, after long filling the office of per¬ petual secretary to the French Academy, died at a very advanced age in 1760. (He was chiefly known as the author of very indifferent translations of Tasso and Ariosto.) It is now, however, universally admitted that Mirabaud had no share whatever in the composition of the Systeme de la Nature. It has been ascribed to various authors; nor am I quite certain, that, among those who are most competent to form a judgment upon this point, there is yet a perfect unanimity. In one of the latest works which has reached this country from France (the Correspondance inidite de Galiani, 1818), it seems to be assumed by the editors, as an acknowledged fact, that it proceeded from the pen of the Baron d’Holbach. The Abbe Galiani having remarked, in one of his letters to Madame Epinay, that it appeared to him to come from the same hand with the Christianisme Devoile and the Militaire Philosophe, the editors remark in a note, “ On peut rendre homage a la sagacitd de I’Abbe Galiani. Le Christianisme Devoile est en effet le premier ouvrage philosophique du Baron d’Holbach. C’est en vain que la Biographic Universelle nous assure, d’apres le temoignage de Voltaire, que cet ouvrage est de Damilaville.” Having mentioned the name of Damilaville, I am tempted to add, that the article relating to him in the Biographic Uni- verselle, notwithstanding the incorrectness with which it is charged in the foregoing passage, is not unworthy of the reader’s 182 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. it appears from various accounts, contributed to render it fashionable, still more by the extraor¬ dinary powers of his conversation, than by the odd combination of eloquence and of obscurity displayed in all bis metaphysical productions.1 In order, however, to prevent misapprehen¬ sion of my meaning, it is proper for me to cau¬ tion my readers against supposing that all the eminent French philosophers of this period were of the same school with Grimm and Diderot. On this subject many of our English writers have been misled by taking for granted that to speak lightly of final causes is, of itself, sufficient proof of atheism. That this is a very rash as well as uncharitable conclusion, no other proof is necessary than the manner in which final causes are spoken of by Descartes himself, the great object of whose metaphysical writings plainly was, to establish by demonstration the existence of God. The following vindication of this part of the Cartesian philosophy has been lately offered by a French divine, and it may be extended with equal justice to Buffon and many others of Descartes’s successors : “ Quelques au¬ teurs, et particulierement Leibnitz, ont critique cette partie de la doctrine de Descartes; mais nous la croyons irreprochable, si on veut bien 1’entendre, et remarquer que Descartes ne parle que des Fins totales de Dieu. Sans doute, le soleil par exemple, et les etoiles, ont ete faits pour 1’homme, dans ce sens, que Dieu, en les creant, a eu en vue Futilite de I’homme ; et cette utility a ete sa fin. Mais cette utilite a-t-elle ete 1’unique fin de Dieu ? Croit-on qu’en lui attribuant d’autres fins, on affoibliroit la re- connoissance de I’homme, et 1’obligation ou il est de louer et de benir Dieu dans toutes ses oeuvres ? Les auteurs de la vie spirituelle, les plus mystiques meme, et les plus accr^dites, ne 1’ont pas cru.”—(M. 1’Abbe Emery, Editor of the Thoughts of Descartes upon Religion and Mo¬ rals, Paris, 1811, p. TO.) As to the unqualified charge of atheism, which has been brought by some French ecclesiastics against all of their countrymen that have pre¬ sumed to differ from the tenets of the Catholic church, it will be admitted, with large allow¬ ances, by every candid Presbyterian, when it is recollected that something of the same illiberali- ty formerly existed under the comparatively enlightened establishment of England. In the present times, the following anecdote would ap¬ pear incredible, if it did not rest on the unques¬ tionable testimony of Dr Jortin: “ I heard Dr B. say in a sermon, if any one denies the unin¬ terrupted succession of bishops, I shall not scruple to call him a downright atheist. This, when I was young (Jortin adds), was sound, orthodox, and fashionable doctrine.”—(Tracts, Yol. I. p. 486.)2 How far the effects of that false philosophy of which Grimm’s correspondence exhibits so dark and so authentic a picture, were connected with the awful revolution which soon after followed, it is not easy to say. That they contributed greatly to blacken its atrocities, as well as to re¬ volt against it the feelings of the whole Chris¬ tian world, cannot be disputed. The experi¬ ment was indeed tremendous, to set loose the passions of all classes of men from the restraints attention, as it contains some very remarkable marginal notes on the Christianisme Devoile, copied from Voltaire’s own handwriting. Since writing the above note, I have seen the Memoirs of M. Suard, by M. Garat (Paris, 1820), in which the biographer, whose authority on this point is perfectly decisive, ascribes with confidence to Baron d’Holbach the Systeme de la Nature, and also a work entitled La Morale et La Legislation Universelle (Yol. I. pp. 210, 211.) According to the same author, the Baron d’Holbach was one of Diderot’s proselytes—(LUd. p. 208.) His former creed, it would appear, had been very different. 1 And yet Diderot, in some of his lucid intervals, seems to have thought and felt very differently. See Note TT. 2 See Note U U. Of the levity and extravagance with which such charges have sometimes been brought forward, we have a remarkable instance in a tract entitled Athei Detecti, by a very learned Jesuit Father Hardouin ; (see his Opera Varia Posthuma, Amsterdam, 1733, in fob) where, among a number of other names, are to be found those of Jansenius, Descartes, Malebranche, Arnauld, Nicole, and Pascal. Large additions on grounds equally frivolous, have been made in later times, to this list, by authors, who having themselves made profession of Atheism, were anxious, out of vanity, to swell the number of their sect. Of this kind was a book published at Paris, under some of the revolutionary governments, by Pierre Sylvain Marechal, en¬ titled Dictionnaire des Athecs. Here we meet with the names of St Chrysostom, St Augustin, Pascal, Bossuet, Fenelon, Bellarmin, Labruyere, Leibnitz, and many others not less unexpected. This book he is said to have published at the suggestion of the celebrated astronomer Lalande, who afterwards published a supplement to the Dictionary, supplying the omissions of the author. See the Biographic Universelle, articles Marechal, Lalande. DISSERTATION FIRST. 183 imposed by religious principles; and the result exceeded, if possible, what could have been an¬ ticipated in theory. The lesson it has afforded has been dearly purchased; hut let us indulge the hope that it will not he thrown away on the generations which are to come. A prediction, which Bishop Butler hazarded many years before, does honour to his political sagacity, as well as to his knowledge of human nature; that the spirit of irreligion would pro¬ duce, some time or other, political disorders, si¬ milar to those which arose from religious fana¬ ticism in the seventeenth century.1 * * Nearly about the time that the Encyclopedie was undertaken, another set of philosophers, since known by the name of Economists, formed themselves into an association for the purpose of enlightening the public on questions of political economy. The object of their studies seemed widely removed from all abstract discussion; but they had, nevertheless, a metaphysical sys¬ tem of their own, which, if it had been brought forward with less enthusiasm and exaggeration, might have been useful in counteracting the gloomy ideas then so generally prevalent about the order of the universe. The whole of their theory proceeds on the supposition that the ar¬ rangements of nature are wise and benevolent, and that it is the business of the legislator to study and co-operate with her plans in all his own regulations. With this principle, another was combined, that of the indefinite improve¬ ment of which the human mind and character are susceptible; an improvement which was re¬ presented as a natural and necessary consequence of wise laws, and which was pointed out to le¬ gislators as the most important advantage to he gained from their institutions. These speculations, whatever opinion may he formed of their solidity, are certainly as remote as possible from any tendency to atheism, and still less do they partake of the spirit of that philosophy which would level man with the brute creation. With their practical tendency in a political view we are not at present concern¬ ed; hut it would he an unpardonable omission, after what has been just said of the metaphysi¬ cal theories of the same period, not to mention the abstract principles involved in the Economi¬ cal System, as a remarkable exception to the ge¬ neral observation. It may he questioned, too, if the authors of this system, by incorporating their ethical views with their political disquisi¬ tions, did not take a more effectual step towards discountenancing the opinions to which they were opposed, than if they had attacked them in the way of direct argument.8 On the metaphysical theories which issued from the French press during the latter half of the last century, I do not think it necessary for me to enlarge, after what I have so fully stated in some of my former publications. To enter into details with respect to particular works would be superfluous, as the remarks made upon any one of them are nearly applicable to them all. The excellent writings of M. Prevost, and of M. Begerando, will, it is to he hoped, gradually introduce into France a sounder taste in this branch of philosophy.5 At present, so far as I am acquainted with the state of what is called ! “ Is there no danger that all this may raise somewhat like that levelling spirit, upon atheistical principles, which in the last age, prevailed upon enthusiastic ones ? Not to speak of the possibility, that different sorts of people may unite in it upon these contrary principles.”—(Sermon preached before the House of Lords, January 30, 1741.) As the fatal effects of both these extremes have, in the course of the two last centuries, been exemplified on so gigantic a scale in the two most civilised countries of Europe, it is to be hoped that mankind may in future derive some salutary admonitions from the experience of their predecessors. In the meantime, from that disposition common both to the higher and lower orders to pass suddenly from one extreme to another, it is at least possible that the strong re-action produced by the spirit of impiety during the French He volution may, in the first instance, impel the multitude to something approach¬ ing to the puritanical fanaticism and frenzy of the Cromwellian Commonwealth. 2 For some other observations on the Ethical principles assumed in the Economical System, see Elements of the Philosophy of the Human Mind, Vol. II. Chap. iv. Sect. 6. § 1. towards the end. 3 Some symptoms of such a reformation are admitted already to exist, by an author decidedly hostile to all philosophical systems. “ Bacon, Locke, Condillac, cherchoient dans nos sens I’origine de nos ide'es ; Helvetius y a trouve nos idees elles- rnemes. Juger, selon ce philosophe, n'est autre chose que sentir.* Aujourd’hui les bons esprits, eclaire's par les e've'nemens I was somewhat surprised, in looking over very lately the Principia of Descartes, to find (what had formerly escaped me), that the mode of speaking objected to in the above paragraph may plead in its favour the authority of that philosopher: “ Cogitationis nomine, intelligo ilia omnia, quae nobis consciis in nobis fiunt, quatenus eorum in nobis conscientia est: Atque 184 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. Ideologic in that country, it does not appear to me to furnish much matter either for the in¬ struction or amusement of my readers. The works of Rousseau have, in general, too slight a connection with metaphysical science, to come under review in this part of my discourse. But to his Emile, which has been regarded as a supplement to Locke’s Tveotise on Education, some attention is justly due, on account of vari¬ ous original and sound suggestions on the ma¬ nagement of the infant mind* which, among many extravagancies, savouring strongly both of intellectual and moral insanity, may he gathered by a sober and discriminating inquirer. The estimate of the merits of this work, formed by Mr Gray, appears to me so just and impar¬ tial, that I shall adopt it here without a com¬ ment. “ I doubt” (says he, in a letter to a friend) “ you have not yet read Rousseau’s Emile. Every body that has children should read it more than once; for though it abounds with his usual glorious absurdity, though his general scheme of education he an impracticable chimera, yet there are a thousand lights struck out, a thousand important truths better expressed than ever they were before, that may be of service to the wisest men. Particularly, I think he has observed children with more attention, knows their mean¬ ing, and the working of their little passions, better than any other writer. As to his religi¬ ous discussions, which have alarmed the world, and engaged their thoughts more than any other parts of his book, I set them all at nought, and wish they had been omitted.”—(Gray’s Works by Mason, Letter 49.) The most valuable additions made by French writers to the Philosophy of the Human Mind are to be found, not in their systematical trea¬ tises on metaphysics, but in those more popu¬ lar compositions, which, professing to paint the prevailing manners of the times, touch occasionally on the varieties of intellectual character. In this most interesting and im¬ portant study, which has been hitherto almost entirely neglected in Great Britain,1 France must be allowed not only to have led the way, but to remain still unrivalled. It would be endless to enumerate names; hut I must not pass over those of Vauvenargues2 and Du- sur la secrete tendance de toutes ces opinions, lea ont soumises a un examen plus severe. La transformation des sensations en idees ne paroit plus qu’un mot vide de sens. On trouve que Vhomme statue ressemble un peu trop a Vhomme machine, et Condillac est modifie' ou meme combattu sur quelques points, par tous ceux qui s’en servent encore dans 1’enseignement phiiosophique.”'—(Recherches Philosophiques, &[C. par M. de Bonald, Tome I. pp. 34. 3o.) 1 Manv precious hints connected with it may, however, be collected from the writings of Lord Bacon, and a few from those of Mr Locke. It does not seem to have engaged the curiosity of Mr Hume in so great a degree as might have been expected from his habits of observation and extensive intercourse with the world. The objects of Dr Reid’s inquiries led him into a totallv different track. . , . . „ . , Among German writers, Leibnitz has occasionally glanced with a penetrating eye at the varieties of genius; and it were to be wished that he had done so more frequently. How far his example has been followed by his countrymen in later times, I am unable to judge, from my ignorance of their language. ^ t _ u A work expressly on this subject was published by a Spanish physician (Huarte) in the seventeenth century. A T rench translation of it, printed at Amsterdam in 1672, is now lying before me. It is entitled, Rramen des Esprits pour les Sciences. Oil se montrent les differences des Esprits, qui se trouvent parmi les hommes, et d quel genre de Science chacun est propre en par- ticulier. The execution of this work certainly falls far short of the expectations raised by the title; but, allowances being made for the period when it was written, it is by no means destitute of merit, nor unworthy of the attention of those who may speculate on the subject of Education. For some particulars about its contents, and also about the author, see Bayle s Dictionary, Art. Hudrte; and The Spectator, No. 30. n . 2 The Marquis de Yauvenargues, author of a small volume, entitled Introduction d la Connoissance de l Esprit Humain. He entered into the army at the age of eighteen, and continued to serve for nine years ; when, having lost his health irre¬ coverably, inconsequence of the fatigues he underwent in the memorable retreat from Prague, in December 1742, he re¬ solved to quit his profession, in the hope of obtaining some diplomatic employment better suited to his broken constitution. Soon after, he was attacked by the small-pox, which unfortunately turned out of so malignant a kind, as to disfigure his countenance, and deprive him almost totally of sight. He died in 1747, at the age of thirty-two. T he small volume above mentioned was published the year before his death. It bears everywhere the marks of a powerful, original, and elevated mind; and the imperfect education which the author appears to have received gives it an additional charm, as the genuine result of his own unsophisticated reflections. Marmontel has given a most interesting picture of his social character : “ En le lisant, je crois encore 1’entendre, et je ne ita non modo intelligere, velle, imaginari, sed etiam sentire, idem est hie quod cogitare.”—(Princ. Phil. p. 2.) Dr Reid, too, has said that “ the sensation of colour is a sort of thought” (Inquiry, Chap. vi. § 4.); but no names, how great soever, can sanction so gross an abuse of language. After all, there is some difference between saying, that sensation is a sort of thought, and that thought is a sort of sen¬ sation. DISSERTATION FIRST. 185 clos.1 Nor can I forbear to remark, in justice to an author whom I have already very freely censured, that a variety of acute and refined observations on the different modifi¬ cations of genius may be collected from the writings of Helvetius. The soundness of some of his distinctions may perhaps be question¬ ed ; but even his attempts at classification may serve as useful guides to future observers, and may supply them with a convenient nomencla¬ ture, to which it is not always easy to find cor¬ responding terms in other languages. As ex¬ amples of this, it is sufficient to mention the fol¬ lowing phrases: Esprit juste, Esprit borne, Es¬ prit etendu, Esprit fin, Esprit delie, Esprit de lumiere. The peculiar richness of the French tongue in such appropriate expressions (a cir¬ cumstance, by the way, which not unfrequently leads foreigners to overrate the depth of a talka¬ tive Frenchman) is itself a proof of the degree of attention which the ideas they are meant to convey have attracted in that country among the higher and more cultivated classes. The influence, however, of the philosophical spirit on the general habits of thinking among men of letters in France, was in no instance dis¬ played to greater advantage, than in the nume¬ rous examples of theoretical or conjectural history, which appeared about the middle of last century. I have already mentioned the attempts of Con¬ dillac and others, to trace upon this plan the first steps of the human mind in the invention of language. The same sort of speculation has been applied with greater success to the mecha¬ nical and other necessary arts of civilised life ;8 and still more ingeniously and happily to the different branches of pure and mixed mathema¬ tics. To a philosophical mind, no study certain¬ ly can be more delightful than this species of history; but as an organ of instruction, I am not disposed to estimate its practical utility so highly as D’Alembert. It does not seem to me at all adapted to interest the curiosity of novices: nor is it so well calculated to engage the atten¬ tion of those who wish to enlarge their scientific knowledge, as of persons accustomed to reflect on the phenomena and laws of the intellectual world. Of the application of theoretical history, to account for the diversities of laws and modes of government among men, I shall have occasion afterwards to speak. At present I shall only remark the common relation in which all such researches stand to the Philosophy of the Hu¬ man Mind, and their common tendency to ex¬ pand and to liberalise the views of those who are occupied in the more confined pursuits of the subordinate sciences. After what has been already said of tbe general tone of French philosophy, it will not appear surprising, that a system so mystical and spiritual as that of Leibnitz never struck its roots deeply in that country. A masterly out¬ line of its principles was published by Madame du Chatelet, at a period of her life when she was an enthusiastic admirer of the author; and a work on such a subject, composed by a lady of her rank and genius, could not fail to pro¬ duce at first a very strong sensation at Paris; but not long after, she herself abandoned the sais si sa conversation n’avait pas meme quelque chose de plus animd, de plus delicat que ses divins ecrits.” And, on a different occasion, he speaks of him thus: “ Doux, sensible, compatissant, il tenait nos ames dans ses mains. Une serdnite inalterable derobait ses douleurs aux yeux de I’amitid. Pour soutenir I’adversite, on n’avoit besoin que de son exemple ; et temoin de Pegalite de son ame, on n’osait etre malheureux avec lui.” See also an eloquent and pathetic tribute to the genius and worth of Vauvenargues, in Voltaire’s Eloge Funtbre de$ Officiers qui sont marts dans la Guerre de 1741. If the space allotted to him in this note should be thought to exceed what is due to his literary eminence, the singular circumstances of his short and unfortunate life, and the deep impression which his virtues, as well as his talents, appear to have left on the minds of all who knew him, will, I trust, be a sufficient apology for my wish to add something to the cele¬ brity of a name, hitherto, I believe, very little known in this country. 1 The work of Duclos, here referred to, has for its title, Considerations sur les Mceurs de ce Siecle. Gibbon’s opinion of this book is, I think, not beyond its merits : “ L’ouvrage en general est bon. Queiques chapitres (le rapport de I’esprit et du caractere) me paroissent excellens.”—f Extrait du Journal.) 1 have said nothing of La Rochefoucauld and La Bruyere, as their attention was chiefly confined to manners, and to mo¬ ral qualities. Yet many of their remarks show, that they had not wholly overlooked the diversities among men in point of intellect. An observer of sagacity equal to their’s might, I should think, find a rich field of study in this part of human nature, as well as in the other. 2 Particularly by the President de Goguet, in his learned work, entitled, “ De I'Origine des Lois, des Arts, et des Sciences, et de lews Progres chez les Anciens Peuplcs." Paris, ITHli. DISS. I. PART II. 2 A 186 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. German philosophy, and became a zealous partizan of the Newtonian school. She even translated into French, and enriched with a commentary, the Principia of Newton ; and by thus renouncing her first faith, contributed more to discredit it, than she had previously done to bring it into fashion. Since that time, Leibnitz has had few, if any, disciples in France, al¬ though some of his peculiar tenets have oc¬ casionally found advocates there, among those who have rejected the great and leading doc¬ trines, by which his system is more peculiarly characterised. His opinions and reasonings in particular, on the necessary concatenation of all events, both physical and moral (which accord¬ ed hut too well with the philosophy professed by Grimm and Diderot), have been long incor¬ porated with the doctrines of the French ma¬ terialists, and they have been lately adopted and sanctioned, in all their extent, by an au¬ thor, the unrivalled splendour of whose ma¬ thematical genius may be justly suspected, in the case of some of his admirers, to throw a false lustre on the dark shades of his philosophi¬ cal creed.1 Notwithstanding, however, this important and unfortunate coincidence, no two systems can well be imagined more strongly contrasted on the whole, than the lofty metaphysics of Leibnitz, and that degrading theory concerning the origin of our ideas, which has been fashion¬ able in France since the time of Condillac. In proof of this, I have only to refer to the account of both, which has been already given. The same contrast, it would appear, still con¬ tinues to exist between the favourite doctrines of the German and of the French schools. “ In the French empiricism (says a most impartial, as well as competent judge, M. Ancillon), the faculty of feeling, and the faculty of knowing, 1 “ Les £;venemens actuels ont avec les precedens une liaison fondee sur le principe Evident, qu’une chose ne peat pas commence!' d’etre, sans une cause qui la produise. Cet axiome, connu sous le nom de principe de la raison snffisante, s etend aux actions meme que Ton juge indifFe'rentes. La volonte la plus libre ne peut, sans un motif determinant, leur donner naissance; car si, toutes les circonstances de deux positions etant exactement semblables, elle agissoit dans Pune ey s’ab- stenoit d’agir dans Pautre, son choix seroit un effet sans cause ;* elle seroit alors, dit Leibnitz, le hazard aveugle des Lpicu- riens. L’opinion contraire est une illusion de Pesprit qui perdant de vue les raisons fugitives du choix de la volonte dans les choses indifferentes, se persuade qu’elle s’est determine'e d’elle meme et sans motifs. “ Nous devons done envisager Petat pre'sent de Punivers comme Peffet de son etat anterieure, et comme la cause de celui qui va suivre. Une intelligence qui pour un instant donne connoitroit toutes les forces dont la nature est^ animee, et la situation respective des etres qui la composent, si d’ailleurs elle etoit assez vaste pour soumettre ces donnees a 1 analyse, embrasseroit dans la meme formule, les mouveinens des plus grands corps de Punivers et ceux de plus leger atome. ne seroit incertain pour elle, et Pavenir comme le passe, seroit present a ses yeux.”—(Essai Philosophique sur les Probabilites, par Laplace.) _ . . Is not this the very spirit of the Theodiccea of Leibnitz, and, when combined with the other reasonings in the Essay on Probabilities, the very essence of Spinozism? _ _ . This, indeed, is studiously kept by the author out of the reader’s view ; and hence the facility with which some of his propositions have been admitted by many of his mathematical disciples, who, it is highly probable, were not aware of the consequences which they necessarily involve. _ _ , I cannot conclude this note without recurring to an observation ascribed in the above quotation from Laplace to Leib¬ nitz, “ that the blind chance of the Epicureans involves the supposition of an effect taking place without a cause. Phis, I apprehend, is a very incorrect statement of the philosophy taught by Lucretius, which nowhere gives the slightest coun¬ tenance to such a supposition. The distinguishing tenet of this sect was, that the order of the universe does not imply the existence of intelligent causes, but may be accounted for by the active powers belonging to the atoms of matter; which ac¬ tive powers, being exerted through an indefinitely long period of time, might produce, nay, must have, produced, exactly such a combination of things, as that with which we are surrounded. This, it is evident, does not call in question the ne¬ cessity of a cause to produce every effect, but, on the contrary, virtually assumes the truth of that axiom. It only excludes from these causes the attribute of intelligence. It is in the same way when I apply the words blind chance (hazard aveugle) to the throw of a die, I do not mean to deny that I am ultimately the cause of the particular event that is to take place; but only to intimate that I do not here act as a designing cause, in consequence of my ignorance of the various accidents to which the die is subjected, while shaken in the box. If I am not mistaken, this Epicurean Theory approaches very nearly to the scheme, which it is the main object of the Essay on Probabilities to inculcate; and, therefore,, it was not quite fair .in Laplace to object to the supposition of man’s free agency, as favouring those principles which he himself was labouring in¬ directly to insinuate. From a passage in Plato’s Sophist, it is very justly inferred by Mr Gray, that, according to the common opinion then en¬ tertained, “ the creation of things was the work of blind unintelligent matter ; whereas the contrary was the result of phi¬ losophical reflection and disquisition believed by a few people only.”—(Gray's Works by Matthias, Yol. II. p. 414.) On the same subject, see Smith’s Posthumous Essays, p. 106. * The impropriety of this language was long ago pointed out by Mr Hume. “ They are still more frivolous who say, that every effect must have a cause, because it is implied in the very idea of effect. Every effect necessarily presupposes a cause; effect being a relative term, of which cause is the co-relative. The true state of the question is, whether every object, which begins to exist, must owe its existence to a cause?”—( Treatise of Human Nature, Vol. I. p. 1 47-) DISSERTATION FIRST. 187 are one and the same. In the new philosophy of Germany, there is no faculty of knowing, but reason. In the former, taking our departure from individuals, we rise by degrees to ideas, to general notions, to principles. In the latter, beginning with what is most general, or rather with what is universal, we descend to individu¬ al existences, and to particular cases. In the one, what we see, what we touch, what we feel, are the only realities. In the other, nothing is real but what is invisible and purely intellectual.” “ Both these systems (continues M. Ancillon) result from the exaggeration of a sound prin¬ ciple. They are both true and both false in part; true in what they admit, false in what they reject. All our knowledge begins, or ap¬ pears to begin, in sensation; but it does not fol¬ low from this that it is all derived from sensa¬ tion, or that sensation constitutes its whole amount. The proper and innate activity of the mind has a large share in the origin of our re¬ presentations, our sentiments, our ideas. Reason involves principles which she does not borrow from without, which she owes only to herself, which the impressions of the senses call forth from their obscurity, but which, far from owing their origin to sensations, serve to appreciate them, to judge of them, to employ them as instru¬ ments. It would be rash, however, to conclude from hence, that there is no certainty but in reason, that reason alone can seize the mystery of exist¬ ences, and the intimate nat ure of beings, and that experience is nothing but a vain appearance, destitute of every species of reality.”1 With this short and comprehensive estimate of the new German philosophy, pronounced by one of the most distinguished members of the Berlin Academy, I might perhaps be pardoned for dismissing a subject, with which I have, in some of my former publications, acknowledged myself (from my total ignorance of the German language) to be very imperfectly acquainted; but the impression which it produced for a few years in England (more particularly while our intercourse with the Continent was interrupted), makes it proper for me to bestow on it a little more notice in this Dissertation, than I should otherwise have judged necessary or useful. SECTION VII. Kant and other Metaphysicians of the New German School.2 The long reign of the Leibnitzian Philosophy degree, to the zeal and ability with which it was in Germany was owing, in no inconsiderable taught in that part of Europe, for nearly half a 1 Melanges de Litterature et de Philosophic, par F. Ancillon, Preface, (k Paris, 1809.) The intimacy of M. Ancillon’s literary connections both with France and with Germany entitle his opinions on the respective merits of their philosophi¬ cal systems to peculiar weight. If he anywhere discovers a partiality for either, the modest account which he gives of himself would lead us to expect his leaning to be in favour of his countrymen. “ Placd entre la France et PAllemagne, appartenant a la premiere par la langue dans laquelle je hasarde d’dcrire, a la seconde par ma naissance, mes etudes, mes principes, mes affections, et j’ose le dire, par la couleur de ma pensde, je desirerois pouvoir servir de mediateur litte'raire, ou d’interprete philosophique entre les deux nations.” In translating from M. Ancillon the passage quoted in the text, I have adhered as closely as possible to the words of the original; although I cannot help imagining that I could have rendered it still more intelligible to the English reader by laying aside some of the peculiarities of his German phraseology. My chief reason for retaining these, ivas to add weight to the strictures which a critic, so deeply tinctured with the German habits of thinking and of writing, has offered, on the most prominent faults of the systems in which he had been educated. * My ignorance of German would have prevented me from saying anything of the philosophy of Kant, if the extraor¬ dinary pretensions with which it was at first brought forward in this island, contrasted with the total oblivion into which it soon after very suddenly fell, had not seemed to demand some attention to so wonderful a phenomenon in the literary history of the eighteenth century. My readers will perceive that I have taken some pains to atone for my inability to read Kant’s works in the original, not only by availing myself of the Latin version of Born, but by consulting various com¬ ments on them which have appeared in the English, French, and Latin languages. As commentators, however, and even translators, are not always to be trusted to as unexceptionable interpreters of their authors’ opinions, my chief reliance has been placed on one of Kant’s own compositions in Latin ; his Dissertation De Mundi Sensibilis atque Intelligibilis Forma et Prineipiis, which he printed as the subject of a public disputation, when he was candidate for a Professorship in the Uni- 188 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. century, by his disciple Wolfius,1 a man of little genius, originality, or taste, but whose exten¬ sive and various learning, seconded by a metho¬ dical head,* and by an incredible industry and perseverance, seems to have heen peculiarly fitted to command the admiration of his country¬ men. Wolfius, indeed, did not profess to follow implicitly the opinions of his master, and, on some points, laid claim to peculiar ideas of his own; but the spirit of his philosophy is essen¬ tially the same with that of Leibnitz,5 and the particulars in which he dissented from him are too trifling to deserve any notice in the history of literature.4 The high reputation so long maintained by Wolfius in Germany suggested, at different times, to the book-makers at Paris, the idea of intro¬ ducing into France the philosophy which he taught. Hence a number of French abridg¬ ments of his logical and metaphysical writings. But an attempt, which had failed in the hands of Madame de Chatelet, was not likely to suc¬ ceed with the admirers and ahridgers of Wol¬ fius.5 versity of Koenigsberg. It is far from being improbable, after all, that I may, in some instances, have misapprehended his meaning, but I hope I shall not be accused of wilfully misrepresenting it. Where my remarks are borrowed from other writers,”l have been careful in referring to my authorities, that my reader may judge for himself of the fidelity of my statements. If no other purpose, therefore, should be answered by this part of my work, it may at least be of use by call¬ ing forth some person properly qualified to correct any mistakes into which I may involuntarily have fallen ; and, in the meantime, may serve to direct those who are strangers to German literature, to some of the comments on this philosophy which have appeared in languages more generally understood in this country. 1 Born 1679. Died 1?54. 2 The display of method, however, so conspicuous in all the works of Wolfius, will often be found to amount to little more than an aukward affectation of the phraseology and forms of mathematics, in sciences where they contribute nothing to the clearness of our ideas, or the correctness of our reasonings. This affectation, which seems to have been well adapted to the taste of Germany at the time when he wrote, is now one of the chief causes of the neglect into which his writings have fallen. Some of them may still be usefully consulted as dictionaries, but to read them is impossible. They amount to about forty quarto volumes, twenty-three of which are in Latin, the rest in German. In his own country the reputation of Wolfius is not yet at an end. In the preface to Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason, he is called “ Summus omnium dogmaticorum Philosophus.”—(Kantii Opera ad Philosophiarn Criticam, Yol. I. Praef. Auctoris Posterior, p. xxxvi. Latine Yertit. I'red. Born. Lipsiae, 1796.) And by one of Kant’s best commentators his name is advantageously contrasted with that of David Hume: “ Est autem scientifica methodus aut dogmatica, aut sceptica. Primi generis autorem celeberrimum Wolfium, alterius Davidem Humium nominasse sat est.” (Expositio Philos. Criticoe. Autore Conrado Friderico a Schmidt-Phiseldek. Hafniae, 1796.) To the other merits of Wolfius it may be added, that he was one of the first who contributed to diffuse among his coun¬ trymen a taste for philosophical inquiries, by writing on scientific subjects in the German language. “ Were all Baron Wolf’s other merits disputed, there is one (says Michaelis), which must incontestably be allowed him, his having added a new degree of perfection to the German Tongue, by applying it to philosophy.”—(Dissertation on the Influence of Opinions on Language, &c. English Translation, p. 27-) 3 On the great question of Free Will, Wolfius adopted implicitly the principles of the Theodicaea ; considering man merely in the light of a machine; but (with the author of that work) dignifying this machine by the epithet spiritual. This language, which is still very prevalent among German philosophers, may be regarded as a relic of the doctrines of Leibnitz and of Wolfius ; and affords an additional proof of the difficulty of eradicating errors sanctioned by illustrious and popular names. When the system of Pre-established Harmony was first introduced by Wolfius into the University of Halle, it excited an alarm which had very nearly been attended with fatal consequences to the professor. The following anecdote on the subject is told by Euler: “ Lorsque du temps du feu Hoi de Prusse, M. Wolf enseignoit a Halle le systeme de 1’Har- monie Pre-etablie, le Boi s’informa de cette doctrine, qui faisoit grand bruit alors ; et un courtisan repondit a sa Majeste, que tous les soldats, selon cette doctrine, n’etoient que des machines; que quand il en desertoit, c’etoit une suite ndcessaire de leur structure, et qu’on avoit tort par consequent de les punir, comme on 1’auroit si on punissoit une machine pour avoir produit tel ou tel mouvement. Le Hoi se facha si fort sur ce rapport, qu’il donna ordre de chasser M. Wolf de Halle, sous peine d’etre pendu s’il s’y trouvoit au bout de 24 heurs. Le philosophe se refugia alors a Marbourg, oil je lui ai parle peu de temps apres (Lettres a une Princesse d'Allemagne, Lettre 84me.) We are informed by Condorcet, that some reparation was afterwards made for this injustice by Frederic the Great—“ Le lloi de Prusse, qui necroit pas pourtant a 1’Harmonie Pre-etablie, s’est empresse de rendre justice a Wolf des le premier jour de son regne.” 4 Among other novelties affected by Wolfius, was a new modification of the Theory of the Monads. A slight outline of it, but quite sufficient, I should suppose, to gratify the curiosity of most readers, may be found in Euler’s Letters to a German Princess. 5 To what was before remarked, of the opposition in matters of philosophy between the taste of the French and that of the Germans, I shall here add a short passage from an author intimately acquainted with the literature of both nations. “ L’ecole Allemande reconnoit Leibnitz pour chef. Son fameux disciple Wolf regna dans les universites pendant pres d'un demi siecle avec une autorite non contestee. On connoit en France cette philosophic par un grand nombre d’abreges dont quelque-uns sont faits par des auteurs qui seuls auroient suffi pour lui donner de la celebrite. “ Malgre 1’appui de tous ces noms, jamais en France cette philosophic ne s'est soutenue mtme quelques instans. La profondeur apparente des idees, Pair d’ensemble et de systeme, n’ont jamais pu y suppleer a ce qui a paru lui manquer pour en faire une doctrine solide et digne d’etre accueillie. Outre quelque defaut de clarte, qui probablement en a ecarte des esprits pour qui cette qualite de style et de la pensee est devenue un heureux besoin, la forme sous laquelle elle se presente a rebute bien des lecteurs. Quoi qu’aient pu faire les interpretes, il a toujours perce quelque chose de 1’appareil incommode qui Pentoure a son origine. Condillac tourne plus d’une fois en ridicule ces formes et ce jargon scientifique, et il s’applique a DISSERTATION FIRST. 189 From the time of Wolfius till the philosophy of Kant began to attract general notice, I know of no German metaphysician whose speculations seem to have acquired much celebrity in the learned world.1 Lambert® is perhaps the most illustrious name which occurs during this inter¬ val. As a mathematician and natural philoso¬ pher, his great merits are universally known and acknowledged, but the language in which his metaphysical and logical works were written, has confined their reputation within a compa¬ ratively narrow circle. I am sorry that I can¬ not speak of these from my own knowledge; but I have heard them mentioned in terms of the highest praise, by some very competent judges, to whose testimony I am disposed to give the greater credit, from the singular vein of originality which runs through all his mathe¬ matical and physical publications.3 The Critique of Pure Reason (the most cele¬ brated of Kant’s metaphysical works) appeared in 1781.4 The idea annexed to the title by the author, is thus explained by himself: “ Criti- cam rationis purse non dico censuram librorum et Systematum, sed facultatis rationalis in uni- versum, respectu cognitionum omnium, ad quas, ab omni experientia libera, possit anniti, proinde dijudicationem possibilitatis aut impossibilitatis metaphysices in genere, constitutionemque turn fontium, turn ambitus atque compagis, turn vero terminorum illius, sed cuncta haec ex princi- piis.” ( Kantii, Opera ad Pkilosophiam Criticam., Vol. I. Prsefatio Auctoris Prior, pp. 11, 12.) To render this somewhat more intelligible, I shall subjoin the comment of one of his intimate friends,5 whose work, we are informed by Dr Willich, had received the sanction of Kant him¬ self. “ The aim of Kant’s Critique is no less than to lead Reason to the true knowledge of it¬ self ; to examine the titles upon which it founds the supposed possession of its metaphysical knowledge ; and by means of this examination, to mark the true limits, beyond which it cannot venture to speculate, without wandering into the empty region of pure fancy.” The same author adds, “ The whole Critique of Pure Reason is es¬ tablished upon this principle, that there is a free reason, independent of all experience and sensation.” montrer qu’ils ne sont pas plus propres a satisfaire la raison que le gout. Ilest au moins certain, que le lecteur Frangais let re¬ pousse par instinct, et qu'il y trouve un obstacle tree difficile d surmonter."—(Reflexions sur les (Euvres Posthumes d'Ailani Smith, par M. Prevost de Geneve, a Paris, 1794.) 1 Madame de Stael mentions Lessing, Hemsterhuis, and Jacobi, as precursors of Kant in his philosophical career. She adds, however, that they had no school, since none of them attempted to found any system; but they began the war against the doctrines of the Materialists—(Allemagne, Tome III. p. 98.) I am not acquainted with the metaphysical works of any of the three. Those of Hemsterhuis, who wrote wholly in French, were, I understand, first published in a collected form at Paris, in 1792. He was son of the celebrated Greek scholar and critic, Tiberius Hemsterhusius, Profes¬ sor of Latin Literature at Leyden. 2 Born at Mulhausen in Alsace in 1728. Hied at Berlin in 1777* 3 The following particulars, with respect to Lambert’s literary history, are extracted from a Memoir annexed by M. Prevost to his translation of Mr Smith’s Posthumous Works:—“ Get ingenieux et puissant Lambert, dont les mathema- tiques, qui lui doivent beaucoup, ne purent epuiser les forces, et qui ne toucha aucun sujet de physique ou de philosophic rationelle, sans le couvrir de lumiere. Ses lettres cosmologiques, qu’il ecrivit par forme de delassement, sont pleines d’idees sublimes, entees sur la philosophie la plus saine et la plus savante tout-a-la-fois. II avoit aussi dresse sous le titre d'Archi- tectonique un tableau des principes sur lesquels se fondent les connoissances humaines. Get ouvrage au jugement des hommes les plus verses dans 1’etude de leur langue, n’est pas exempt d’obscurite. File peut tenir en partie a la nature du sujet. 11 est a regretter que sa logique, intitule Organon, ne soil traduite ni en Latin, ni en Francais, ni je pense en aucune langue. Un extrait bien fait de cet ouvrage, duquel on e'carteroit ce qui repugne au gout national, exciteroit 1’attention des philosophes, et la porteroit sur une multitude d’obje'ts qu’ils se sont accoutumes a regardgr avec indifference.”—(Pre¬ vost, Tome II. pp. 267, 268.) In the article Lambert, inserted in the twenty-third volume of the Biographic Universelle (Paris 1819), the following ac¬ count is given of Lambert’s logic :—“ Wolf, d’apres quelques indications de Leibnitz, avoit retire de 1’oubli la syllogistique d’Aristote, science que les scholastiques avoient tellement avilie que ni Bacon ni Locke n’avoient ose lui accorder un regard d’inte'ret. II e'toit reserve d Lambert de la montrer sous le plus beau jour et dans la plus riche parure. C’est ce qu’il a fait dans son Novum Organon, ouvrage qui est un des principaux titres de gloire de son auteur.” From the writer of this article (M. Servois) we farther learn, that the Novum Organon of Lambert was translated into Latin from the German ori¬ ginal by a person of the name of Pfleiderer, and that this translation was in the hands of an English nobleman (the late Earl of Stanhope) as lately as 1782. I quote the words of M. Servois, in the hope that they may attract some attention to the manuscript, if it be still in existence. The publication of it would certainly be a most acceptable present to the learned world. “ D’apres le conseil de Le Sage de Geneve, 1’ouvrage fut traduit en Latin par Pfleiderer, aux frais d’un savant Italien; cette traduction passa, on ne sait comment, entre les mains de Milord Mahon, qui la possedoit encore en 1782; on ignore quel est son sort ulterieur.” 4 Kant was born at Koenigsberg, in Prussia, in 1724. Pie died in 1804. h Mr John Schulze, an eminent divine at Koenigsberg, author of the Synopsis of the Critical Philosophy, translated by Dr Willich, and inserted in his Elementary View of Kant's Works—(See pp. 42, 48.) 190 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. When the Critique of Pure Reason first came out, it docs not seem to have attracted much notice,1 hut sucli has been its subsequent suc¬ cess, that it may be regarded, according to Madame de Stael,8 “ as having given the impulse to all that has been since done in Germany, both in literature and in philosophy.”—(AUe- magne, Vol. III. pp. 68, 69.) “ At the epoch when this work was publish¬ ed (continues the same writer), there existed among thinking men only two systems concern¬ ing the human understanding: The one, that of Locke, ascribed all our ideas to our sensations;5 the other, that of Descartes and of Leibnitz, had for its chief objects to demonstrate the spiritua¬ lity and activity of the soul, the freedom of the will,4 and, in short, the whole doctrines of the idealists Between these extremes rea- 1 II se passa quelque terns apres la premiere publication de la Critique dc la Pure Raisoji, sans qu’on fitbeaucoup d’attention a ce livre, et sans que la plupart de philosophes, passione's pour 1’eclectisme, soupc;onassent seulement la grande revolution que cet ouvrage et les productions suivantes de son auteur devoient operer dans la science.”—(Buhle, Hist, de la Phil. Mod. Tom. VI. p. 573. Paris, 181G.) As early, however, as the year 1783, the Philosophy of Kant appears to have been adopted in sowe of the German schools. The ingenious M. Trembley, in a memoir then read before the Academy of Berlin, thus speaks of it:—“ La philosophic de Kant, qui, a la honte de Vesprit humain, paroit avoir acquis tant de faveur dans certaines ecoles.”—(Essai sur les Prtjugls. Reprinted at Neufchatel in 1790.) We are farther told by Buhle, that the attention of the public to Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason was first attracted by an excellent analysis of the work, which appeared in the General Gazette of Literature, and by the Letters on Kant's Philosophy, which Reinhold inserted in the German Mercury.—(Buhi.e, Tom. VI. p. 573.) Of this last philosopher, who appears, in the first instance, to have entered with enthusiasm into Kant’s views, and who afterwards contributed much to open the eyes of his countrymen to the radical defects of his system, I shall have occasion to speak hereafter. Degerando, as well as Buhle, bestows high praise not only on his clearness, but on his eloquence, as a writer in his own language. “ II a tra- duit les oracles Kantiens dans une langue elegante, harmonieuse, et pure * * * II a su exprimer avec un langage eloquent, des hides jusqu’alors inintelligibles,” &c—(Histoire Comparte, &c. Tom. II. p. 271.) That this praise is not undeserved I am very ready to believe, having lately had an opportunity (through the kindness of my learned and revered friend Dr Parr) of reading, in the Latin version of Fredericus Gottolb Born, lleinhold’s principal work, entitled Periculum Novoc Theoriae Facultatis Reprocsentativae Humana;. In point of perspicuity, he appears to me to be greatly superior to Kant; and of this I conceive myself to be not altogether incompetent to judge, as the Latin versions of both authors are by the same hand. 2 The following quotation, from the advertisement prefixed to Madame de Stael’s posthumous work (Considerations sur la Revolution Fraiifaise), will at once account to my readers for the confidence with which I appeal to her historical state¬ ments on the subject of Germany philosophy. Her own knowledge of the language was probably not so critically exact, as to enable her to enter into the more refined details of the different systems which she has described ; but her extraordinary penetration, joined to the opportunities she enjoyed of conversing with all that was then most illustrious in Germany, qua¬ lified her in an eminent degree to seize and to delineate their great outlines. And if, in executing this task, any consider¬ able mistakes could have been supposed to escape her, we may be fully assured, that the very accomplished person, to whose revision we learn that her literary labours at this period of her life were submitted, would prevent them from ever meeting the public eye. I except, of course, those mistakes into which she was betrayed by her admiration of the German school. Of some of the most important of these, I shall take notice as I proceed; a task which I feel incumbent on me, as it is through the medium of her book that the great majority of Fmglish readers have acquired all their knowledge of the new German philosophy, and as her name and talents have given it a temporary consequence in this country which it could not otherwise have acquired. “ Le travail des e'diteurs s’est borne uniquement a la re'vision des e'preuves, et a la correction de ces legeres inexactitudes de style, qui echappent a la vue dans le manuscrit le plus soigne. Ce travail e’est fait sous les yeux de M. A. W. de Schle- gel, dont la rare superiorite d'esprit et de savoir justifie la confance avec laquelle Madame de Stacl le consultoit dans tons ses travaux litteraires, autant que son honorable caractere merite I’estime et 1’amitie qu’elle n’a pas cesse d’avoir pour lui pendant une liaison dc treize annecs." If any further apology be necessary for quoting a French lady as an authority on German metaphysics, an obvious one is suggested by the extraordinary and well merited popularity of her Allemagne in this country. I do not know, if, in any part of her works, her matchless powers have been displayed to greater advantage. Of this no stronger proof can be given than the lively interest she inspires, even when discussing such systems as those of Kant and of Fichte. 3 That this is a very incorrect account of Locke’s philosophy, has been already shown at great length; but in this mistake Madame de Stael has only followed Leibnitz, and a very large proportion of the German philosophers of the present day. “ The philosophy of sensation,” says Frederick Schlegel, “ which was unconsciously bequeathed to the world by Bacon, and reduced to a methodical shape by Locke, first displayed in France the true immorality and destructiveness of which it is the parent, and assumed the appearance of a perfect system of Atheism.”—(Lectures on the History of Literature, from the German ot Fred. Schlegel. F.din. 1818, Vol. II. p. 22.) It is evident, that the system of Locke is here confounded with that ot Condillac. May not the former be called the philosophy of rejlection, with as great propriety as the philosophy of sensation ? 4 In considering Leibnitz as a partizan of the freedom of the will, Madame de Stael has also followed the views of many German writers, who make no distinction between Materialists and Necessitarians, imagining, that to assert the spiritua¬ lity of the soul, is to assert its free agency- On the inaccuracy of these conceptions it would be superfluous to enlarge, after what was formerly said in treating of the metaphysical opinions of Leibnitz. In consequence ol this misapprehension, Madame de Stael, and many other late writers on the Continent, have been led to employ, with a very exceptionable latitude, the word Idealist, to comprehend not only the advocates for the immateriality of the mind, but those also who maintain the Freedom of the Human Will. Between these two opinions, there is certainly DISSERTATION FIRST. 191 sou continued to wander, till Kant undertook to trace the limits of the two empires; of the senses and of the soul; of the external and of the internal worlds. The force of meditation and of sagacity, with which he marked these limits, had not perhaps any example among his predecessors.”—(Allemagne, Yol. III. pp. 70, 72.) The praise bestowed on this part of Kant’s philosophy, by one of his own pupils, is not less warm than that of Madame de Stael. I quote the passage, as it enters into some historical de¬ tails which she has omitted, and describes more explicitly than she has done one of the most im¬ portant steps, which Kant is supposed by his disciples to have made beyond his predecessors. In reading it, some allowances must be made for the peculiar phraseology of the German school. £t Kant discovered that the intuitive faculty of man is a compound of very dissimilar ingre¬ dients ; or, in other words, that it consists of parts very different in their nature, each of which performs functions peculiar to itself; namely, the sensitive faculty, and the understanding Leibnitz, indeed, had likewise remarked the distinction subsisting between the sensitive facul¬ ty and the understanding; but he entirely over¬ looked the essential difference between their functions, and was of opinion that the faculties differed from one another only in degree In the works of the English and French philo¬ sophers, we find this essential distinction be¬ tween the sensitive and the intellectual facul¬ ties, and their combination towards producing one synthetical intuition, scarcely mentioned. Locke only alludes to the accidental limitations of both faculties; but to inquire into the essen¬ tial difference between them does not at all oc¬ cur to him This distinction, then, be¬ tween the sensitive and the intellectual facul¬ ties, forms an essential feature in the philosophy of Kant, and is, indeed, the basis upon which most of his subsequent inquiries are establish¬ ed.”—(Elements of the Crit. Phil, by A. F. M. Willich, M. D. pp. 68, 69, 70.) It is a circumstance not easily explicable, that, in the foregoing historical sketch, no mention is made of the name of Cudworth, author of the treatise on Eternal and Immutable Morality ; a book which could scarcely fail to be known, be¬ fore the period in question, to every German scholar, by the admirable Latin version of it published by Dr Mosheim.1 In this treatise, no necessary connection; Leibnitz, and many other German metaphysicians, denying the latter with no less confidence than that with which they assert the former. In England, the word Idealist is most commonly restricted to such as (with Berkeley) reject the existence of a material world. Of late, its meaning has been sometimes extended (particularly since the publications of lleid) to all those who i-e- tain the theory of Descartes and Locke, concerning the immediate objects of our perceptions and thoughts, whether they admit or reject the consequences deduced from this theory by the Berkeleians. In the present state of the science, it would contribute much to the distinctness of our reasonings were it to be used in this last sense exclusively. There is another word to which Madame de Stael and other writers on the German philosophy annex an idea peculiar to themselves ; I mean the word experimental or empirical. This epithet is often used by them to distinguish what thev call the philosophy of Sensations, from that of Plato and of Leibnitz. It is accordingly generally, if not always, employed by them in an unfavourable sense. In this country, on the contrary, the experimental or inductive philosophy of the hu¬ man mind denotes those speculations concerning mind, which, rejecting all hypothetical theories, rest solely on phenomena for which we have the evidence of consciousness. It is applied to the philosophy of Reid, and to all that is truly valuable in the metaphysical works of Descartes, Locke, Berkeley, and Hume. Nor are the words, experimental and empirical, by any means synonymous in our language. The latter word is now al¬ most exclusively appropriated to the practice of Medicine ; and when so understood always implies a rash and unphiloso- phical use of Experience. “ The appellation Empiric,” says the late Dr John Gregory, “is generally applied to one who, from observing the effects of a remedy in one case of a disease, applies it to all the various cases of that distemper.” The same remark may be extended to the word Empirique in the French language, which is very nearly synonymous with Charlatan. In consequence of this abuse of terms, the epithet experimental, as well as empirical, is seldom applied by foreign writers to the philosophy of Locke, without being intended to convey a censure. 1 The first edition of this translation was printed as early as 1732. From Buhle’s History of Modern Philosophy (a work which did not fall into my hands till long after this section was written), I find that Cudworth’s Treatise of Immutable Mo¬ rality is now not only well known to the scholars of Germany, but that some of them have remarked the identity of the doctrines contained in it with those of Kant. “ Meiners, dans son histoire generale de PEthique, nie que le systeme morale de Cudworth soit identique avec celui de Platon, et pretend au contraire, ‘ que les principes considerds comme ap- partenans de la mani'ere la plus speciale a la morale de Kant, etaient enseignes il y a deja plusieurs generations par I’ecole du philosophe Anglais.”—{Hist, de la Phil. Moderne, Tom. III. p. 577-) In opposition to this, Buhle states his own decid¬ ed conviction, “ qu’ aucune des idees de Cudworth ne se rapproche de celles de Kant.”—{Ibid.) How far this conviction is well founded, the passage from Cudworth, quoted in the text, will enable my readers to judge for themselves. That Cudworth has blended with his principles a vein of Platonic mysticism, which is not to be found in Kant, is un¬ deniable ; but it does not follow from this, that none of Kant’s leading ideas are borrowed from the writings of Cudworth. The assertion of Buhle, just mentioned, is the more surprising, as he himself acknowledges that “ la philosophic 192 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. Cudworth is at much pains to illustrate the Pla¬ tonic doctrine concerning the difference between sensation and intellection ; asserting that 44 some ideas of the mind proceed not from outward sensible objects, but arise from the inward ac¬ tivity of the mind itselfthat 44 even simple corporeal things, passively perceived by sense, are known and understood only by the active power of the mind and that, besides A/cr^^ara and lavras [Mara, there must he Novara or intel¬ ligible ideas, the source of which can be traced to the understanding alone.1 In the course of his speculations on these sub¬ jects, Cudworth has blended, with some very deep and valuable discussions, several opinions to which I cannot assent, and not a few propo¬ sitions which I am unable to comprehend; hut he seems to have advanced at least as far as Kant, in drawing the line between the provin¬ ces of the senses and of the understanding; and although not one of the most luminous of our English writers, he must he allowed to he far superior to the German metaphysician, both in point of perspicuity and of precision. A later writer, too, of our own country (Dr Price), a zealous follower both of Plato and of Cudworth, afterwards resumed the same argument, in a work which appeared long before the Critique of Pure Reason;2 and urged it with much force against those modern metaphysicians, who con¬ sider the senses as the sources of all our know¬ ledge. At a period somewhat earlier, many very interesting quotations of a similar import had been produced by the learned Mr Harris, from the later commentators of the Alexandrian school on the philosophy of Aristotle; and had been advantageously contrasted by him with the account given of the origin of our ideas, not only by Hobbes and Gassendi, hut by many of the professed followers of Locke. If this part of the Kantian system, therefore, was new in Germany, it certainly could have no claim to the praise of originality, in the estimation of those at all acquainted with English literature.3 In order, however, to strike at the root of what the Germans call the philosophy of sensa- morale de Price pre'sente en effet une analogic frappante avec ceile de Kantand in another part of his work, he expresses himself thus on the same subject: “ Le plus remarquable de tous les moralistes modernes de PAngleterre est, sans con- tredit, Richard Price On remarque 1’analogie la plus frappante entre ses idees sur les bases de lamoralite, et celles que la philosophie critique a fait naitre en Allemagne, quoique il ne soit cependant pas possible d’elever le plus petit doute sur I’entiere originalite de ces dernieres.”—(Tom. V. p. 303.) Is there any thing of importance in the system of Price, which is not borrowed from the Treatise of Immutable Morality ?■ The distinguishing merit of this learned and most respectable writer is the good sense with which he has applied the doctrines of Cudworth to the sceptical theories of his own times. In the sequel of Ruble’s reflections on Cudworth’s philosophy, we are told, that, according to him, “the will of God is only a simple blind power, acting mechanically or accidentally.” (“ Chez Cudworth la volonte meme en Dieu, n’est qu’un simple pouvoir aveugle, agissant me'chaniquement ou accidentellement.”) If this were true, Cudworth ought to be ranked among the disciples, not of Plato, but of Spinoza. 1 In this instance, a striking resemblance is observable between the language of Cudworth and that of Kant; both of them having followed the distinctions of the Socratic school, as explained in the Thecetetus of Plato. They who are at all acquainted with Kant’s Critique, will immediately recognise his phraseology in the passage quoted above. 2 See a review of the Prmcipal Questions and Difficulties relating to Morals, by Richard Price, I). D. London, 1758. 3 I have mentioned here only those works of a modern date, which may be reasonably presumed to be still in general circulation among the learned. But many very valuable illustrations of the Platonic distinction between the senses and the understanding may be collected from the English writers of the seventeenth century. Among these it is sufficient to men¬ tion at present the names of John Smith and Henry More of Cambridge, and of Joseph Glanvile, the author of Scepsis Scientifica. Cudworth’s Treatise of Eternal and Immutable Morality, although it appears, from intrinsic evidence, to have been com¬ posed during the lifetime of Hobbes, was not published till 1731, when the author’s manuscript came into the hands of his grandson, Francis Cudworth Masham, one of the Masters in Chancery. This work, therefore, could not have been known to Leibnitz, who died seventeen years before ; a circumstance which may help to account for its having attracted so much less attention in Germany than his Intellectual System, which is repeatedly mentioned by Leibnitz in terms of the highest praise. From an article in the Edinburgh Review (Vol. XXVII. p. 191), we learn, that large unpublished manuscripts of Dr Cudworth are deposited in the British Museum. It is much to be regretted (as the author of the article observes), that they should have been so long withheld from the public. “ The press of the two Universities (he adds) would be properly employed in works, which a commercial publisher could not prudently undertake.” May we not indulge a hope, that this suggestion will, sooner or later, have its due effect ? in the preface of Mosheim to his Latin version of the Intellectual System, there is a catalogue of Cudworth’s unpublished remains, communicated to Mosheim by Dr Chandler, then Bishop of Durham. Among these are two distinct works on the Controversy concerning Liberty and Necessity, of each of which works Mosheim has given us the general contents. One of the chapters is entitled, “ Answer to the Objection against Liberty, [x'/'b'o avuinov." It is not probable that it con¬ tains any thing very new or important; but it would certainly be worth while to know the reply made by Cudworth to an objection which both Leibnitz and La Place have fixed upon as decisive of the point in dispute. DISSERTATION FIRST. 193 lion, it was necessary to trace, with some degree of systematica] detail, the origin of our most important simple notions ; and for this purpose it seemed reasonable to begin with an analytical view of those faculties and powers, to the exer¬ cise of which the development of these notions is necessarily subsequent. It is thus that the simple notions of time and motion presuppose the exercise of the faculty of memory; and that the simple notions of truth, of belief, of doiibt, and many others of the same kind, necessarily presuppose the exercise of the power of reason¬ ing. I do not know, that, in this anatomy of the mind, much progress has hitherto been made by the German metaphysicians. A great deal certainly has been accomplished by the late Dr Reid; and something, perhaps, has been added to his labours by those of his successors. According to Kant himself, his metaphysical doctrines first occurred to him while employed in the examination of Mr Hume’s Theory of Causation. The train of thought by which he was led to them will he best stated in his own words ; for it is in this way alone that I can hope to escape the charge of misrepresentation from his followers. Some of his details would perhaps have been more intelligible to my read¬ ers, had my plan allowed me to prefix to them a slight outline of Hume’s philosophy. But this the general arrangement of my discourse ren¬ dered impossible; nor can any material incon¬ venience result, in this instance, from the order which I have adopted, inasmuch as Hume’s Theory of Causation, how new soever it may have appeared to Kant, is fundamentally the same with that of Malebranche, and of a variety of other old writers, both French and English. 1 “ Since the Essays (says Kant) of Locke and of Leibnitz, or rather since the origin of metaphysics, as far as their history extends, no circumstance has occurred, which might have been more decisive of the fate of this science than the attack made upon it by David Hume.1 2 3 He proceeded upon a single but important idea in metaphysics, the connection of cause and effect, and the concomitant notions of power and action. He challenged reason to answer him what title she had to imagine, that any thing may be so constituted as that, if it be given, something else is also thereby inferred; for the idea of cause denotes this. He proved beyond contradiction, that it is impossible for reason to think of such a connection a priori, for it con¬ tains necessity ; but it is not possible to perceive how, because something is, something else must necessarily be; nor how the idea of such a con¬ nection can be introduced a priori. “ Hence, he concluded, that reason entirely deceives herself with this idea, and that she er¬ roneously considers it as her own child, when it is only the spurious offspring of imagination, impregnated by experience; a subjective neces¬ sity, arising from habit and the association of ideas, being thus substituted for an objective one derived from perception....However hasty and unwarrantable Hume’s conclusion might appear, yet it was founded upon investigation; and this investigation well deserved, that some of the philosophers of his time should have united to solve, more happily if possible, the problem in the sense in which he delivered it: A complete reform of the science might have resulted from this solution. But it is a mortifying reflection, that his opponents, Reid, Beattie, Oswald, and, lastly, Priestley himself, totally misunderstood the tendency of his problem.3 The question was not, whether the idea of cause be in itself proper and indispensable to the illustration of all natu- 1 See the Preface of Kant to one of his Treatises, entitled Prolegomena ad Metaphysicam quamque futuram quce qua Scientia poterit prodire. I have availed myself in the text of the English version of Dr Willich, from the German original, which I have carefully compared with the Latin version of Born. A few sentences, omitted by Willich, I have thought it worth while to quote, at the foot of the page, from the Latin translation—(Elem. of Critical Philosophy, by A. F. M. Wiljlich, M. D. p. 10. et seq. London, 1798.) 2 “ Humius—Qui quidem nullam huic cognitionis parti lucem adfudit, sed tamen excitavit scintillam, de qua sane lumen potuisset accendi, si ea incidisset in fomitem, facile accipientem, cujusque scintillatio diligenter alta fuerit et aucta.” s “ Non potest sine certo qwodam molestiae sensu percipi, quantopere ejus adversarii, Reidius, Oswaldus, Bcattius, et tan¬ dem Priestleius, a scopo qusestionis aberrarent, et propterea quod ea semper acciperent pro concessis, quae ipse in dubium yocaret, contra vero cum vehementia, et maximam partem cum ingenti immodestia ea probare gestirent, quae illi nunquam in mentem venisset dubitare, nutum ejus ad emendationem ita negligerent, ut omnia in statu pristine maneret, quasi nihil quidquam factum videretur.” DISS. I. PART II. 2 B 194 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. ral knowledge, for this Hume had never doubt¬ ed ; but whether this idea be an object of thought through reasoning a priori; and whether, in this manner, it possesses internal evidence, in¬ dependently of all experience; consequently, whether its utility be not limited to objects of sense alone. It was upon this point that Hume expected an explanation.1 “ I freely own it was these suggestions of Hume’s which first, many years ago, roused me from my dogmatical slumber, and gave to my inquiries quite a different direction in the field of speculative philosophy. I was far from being carried away by his conclusions, the fallacy of which chiefly arose from his not forming to him¬ self an idea of the whole of his problem, but mere¬ ly investigating a part of it, the solution of which was impossible without a comprehensive view of the whole. When we proceed on a well founded, though not thoroughly digested thought, we may expect, by patient and continued re¬ flection, to prosecute it farther than the acute genius had done to whom we are indebted for the first spark of this light. I first inquired, therefore, whether Hume’s objection might not be a general one, and soon found, that the idea of cause and effect is far from being the only one by which the understanding a priori thinks of the connection of things; but rather that the science of metaphysics is altogether founded upon these connections. I endeavoured to as¬ certain their number; and, having succeeded in this attempt, I proceeded to the examination of those general ideas, which, I was now convin¬ ced, are not, as Hume apprehended, derived from experience, but arise out of the pure under¬ standing. This deduction, which seemed im¬ possible to my acute predecessor, and which nobody besides him had ever conceived, al¬ though every one makes use of these ideas, without asking himself upon what their objec¬ tive validity is founded; this deduction, I say, was the most difficult which could have been undertaken for the behoof of metaphysics ; and what was still more embarrassing, metaphysics could not here offer me the smallest assistance, because that deduction ought first to establish the possibility of a system of metaphysics. As I had now succeeded in the explanation of Hume’s problem, not merely in a particular in¬ stance, but with a view of the whole power of pure reason, I could advance with sure though tedious steps, to determine completely, and upon general principles, the compass of Pure Reason, both what is the sphere of its exertion, and what are its limits ; which was all that was required for erecting a system of metaphysics upon a proper and solid foundation.” It is difficult to discover any thing in the fore¬ going passage on which Kant could found a claim to the slightest originality. A variety of English writers had, long before this work ap¬ peared, replied to Mr Hume, by observing that the understanding is itself a source of new ideas, and that it is from this source that our notions of cause and effect are derived. “ Our cer¬ tainty (says Dr Price) that every new event re¬ quires some cause, depends no more on experi¬ ence than our certainty of any other the most obvious subject of intuition. In the idea of every change, is included that of its being an effect.”* In the works of Dr Reid, many remarks of the same nature are to be found; but, instead of quoting any of these, I shall produce a passage from a much older author, whose mode of think¬ ing and writing may perhaps be more agreeble to the taste of Kant’s countrymen than the sim¬ plicity and precision aimed at by the disciples of Locke. “ That there are some ideas of the mind (says Dr Cudworth), which were not stamped or im¬ printed upon it from the sensible objects with¬ out, and therefore must needs arise from the in¬ nate vigour and activity of the mind itself, is evident, in that there are, First, Ideas of such things as are neither affections of bodies, nor could be imprinted or conveyed by any local motions, nor can be pictured at all by the fancy ! Although nothing can be more unjust than these remarks, in the unqualified form in which they are stated by Kant, it, must, I think, be acknowledged, that some grounds for them have been furnished by occasional passages which dropped from the pens of most of Mr Hume’s Scottish opponents. 2 Review of the Principal Questions and Difficulties in Morals, Chap. i. sect. 2. The first edition of this book was printed in 1758. DISSERTATION FIRST. 195 in any sensible colours; such as are the ideas of wisdom, folly, prudence, imprudence, know¬ ledge, ignorance, verity, falsity, virtue, vice, honesty, dishonesty, justice, injustice, volition, cogitation, nay of sense itself, which is a species of cogitation, and which is not perceptible by any sense ; and many other such like notions as include something of cogitation in them, or refer to cogitative beings only ; which ideas must needs spring from the active power and innate fecundity of the mind itself,1 2 3 because the cor¬ poreal objects of sense can imprint no such things upon it. Secondly, In that there are many relative notions and ideas, attributed as well to corporeal as incorporeal things, that pro¬ ceed wholly from the activity of the mind com¬ paring one thing with another. Such as are Cause, Effect, means, end, order, proportion, similitude, dissimilitude, equality, inequality, aptitude, inaptitude, symmetry, asymmetry, whole and part, genus and species, and the like.” Immutable Morality, pp. 148, 149. It is not my business at present to inquire into the solidity of the doctrine here maintained. I would only wish to be informed what additions have been made by Kant to the reply given to Mr Hume by our English philosophers, and to direct the attention of my readers to the close resemblance between this part of Kant’s system, and the argument which Cud worth opposed to Hobbes and Gassendi considerably more than a century ago.* The following passage, from the writer last quoted, approaches so nearly to what Kant and other Germans have so often repeated of the dis¬ tinction between subjective and objective truth, that I am tempted to connect it with the fore¬ going extract, as an additional proof that there are, at least, some metaphysical points, on which we need not search for instruction beyond our own island. “ If there were no other perceptive power, or faculty, distinct from external sense, all our perceptions would be merely relative, seeming, and fantastical, and not reach to the absolute and certain truth of any thing; and every one would but, as Protagoras expounds, ‘ think his own private and relative thoughts truths,’ and all our cogitations being nothing but appearan¬ ces, would be indifferently alike true phantasms, and one as another. “ But we have since also demonstrated, that there is another perceptive power in the soul superior to outward sense, and of a distinct na¬ ture from it, which is the power of knowing or understanding, that is, an active exertion from the mind itself. And, therefore, has this grand eminence above sense, that it is no idiopathy, not a mere private, relative, seeming, and fantasti¬ cal thing, but the comprehension of that which absolutely is and is not.”5 After enlarging on the distinction between the sensitive faculty and the understanding, Kant proceeds to investigate certain essential conditions, without which neither the sensitive faculty nor its objects are conceivable. These conditiens are time and space, which, in the lan¬ guage of Kant, are the forms of all phenomena. What his peculiar ideas are concerning their nature and attributes, my readers will find stat¬ ed in his own words at the end of this Discourse, in an extract from one of his Latin publica¬ tions.4 From that extract, I cannot promise them much instruction; but it will at least en¬ able them to judge for themselves of the pecu¬ liar character of Kant’s metaphysical phraseo¬ logy. In the mean time, it will be sufficient to mention here, for the sake of connection, that he denies the objective reality both of time and of space. The former he considers merely as a subjective condition, inseparably connected with the frame of the human mind, in consequence of which, it arranges sensible phenomena ac¬ cording to a certain law, in the order of succes¬ sion. As to the latter, he asserts, that it is nothing objective or real, inasmuch as it is neither 1 This is precisely the language of the German school: “ Les veritds necessaires, “ says Leibnitz, “ sont le produit im- mediat de Tactivite interieure.”—(Tome I. p. 686. Tome II. pp. 42, 325. See Degerando, Hist. Comp. Tome II. p. 96.) 2 In the attempt, indeed, which Kant has made to enumerate all the general ideas which are not derived from expe¬ rience, but arise out of the pure understanding, he may well lay claim to the praise of originality. On this object I shall only refer my readers to Note X X at the end of this Dissertation. 3 Immutable Morality, p. 264, et seq. 4 See Note Y Y. 196 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. a substance, nor an accident, nor a relation; that its existence, therefore, is only subjective and ideal, depending on a fixed law, inseparable from the frame of the human mind. In conse¬ quence of this law, we are led to conceive all external things as placed in space; or, as Kant expresses it, we are led to consider space as the fundamental form of every external sensation. In selecting Kant’s speculations concerning time and space, as a specimen of his mode of writing, I was partly influenced by the consi¬ deration, that it furnishes, at the same time, a remarkable example of the concatenation which exists between the most remote and seemingly the most unconnected parts of his system. Who could suppose that his opinions on these sub¬ jects, the most abstract and the most contro¬ verted of any in the whole compass of metaphy¬ sics, bore on the great practical question of the freedom of the Human Will ? The combina¬ tion appears, at first sight, so very extraordi¬ nary, that I have no doubt I shall gratify the curiosity of some of my readers by mentioning a few of the intermediate steps which, in this argu¬ ment, lead from the premises to the conclusion. That Kant conceived the free agency of man to he necessarily implied in his moral nature (or, at least, that he was anxious to offer no violence to the common language of the world on this point), appears from his own explicit de¬ clarations in various parts of his works. “ Vo¬ luntas libera (says he in one instance) eadem est cum voluntate legibus moralibus obnoxia.”1 In all the accounts of Kant’s philosophy, which have yet appeared from the pens of his admirers in this country, particular stress is laid on the ingenuity with which he has unloos¬ ed this knot, which had baffled the wisdom of all his predecessors. The following are the words of one of his own pupils, to whom we are indebted for the first, and, I think, not the least intelligible, view of his principles, which has been published in our language.2 3 “ Professor Kant is decidedly of opinion, that although many strong and ingenious arguments have been brought forward in favour of the freedom of the will, they are yet very far from being decisive. Nor have they refuted the ar¬ guments urged by the Necessitarians, hut by an appeal to mere feeling, which, on such a ques¬ tion, is of no avail. For this purpose, it is in¬ dispensably necessary to call to our assistance the principles of Kant.” “ In treating this subject (continues the same author), Kant begins with showing that the notion of a Free Will is not contradictory. In proof of this he observes, that, although every human action, as an event in time, must have a cause, and so on ad infinitum; yet it is certain, that the laws of cause and effect can have a place there only where time is, for the effect must he consequent on the cause. But neither time nor space are properties of things; they are only the general forms under which man is allowed to view himself and the world. It fol¬ lows, therefore, that man is not in time nor in space, although the forms of his intuitive ideas are time and space. But if man exist not in time and space, he is not influenced by the laws of time and space, among which those of cause and effect hold a distinguished rank ; it is, there¬ fore, no contradiction to conceive, that, in such an order of things, man may he free.”5 In this manner Kant establishes the possibili¬ ty of man’s freedom ; and, farther than this, he does not conceive himself warranted to proceed on the principles of the critical philosophy. The first impression, certainly, which his argument 1 See Born’s Latin Translation of Kant’s Works, relating to the Critical Philosophy, Vol. II. p. 325, et seq. See also the Preface to Vol. III. 2 A General and Introductory View of Professor Kant's Principles concerning Man, the World, and the Deity, submitted to the consideration of the Learned, by F. A. Nitsch, late Lecturer on the Latin Language and Mathematics in the Royal Frederi- cianum College at Kdnigsberg, and pupil of Professor Kant. London, 1796. Pp. 172, 173. This small performance is spoken of in terms highly favourable, by the other writers who have attempted to introduce Kant’s philosophy into England. It is called by Dr Willich an excellent publication (Elements of the Critical Philosophy, p. 62.); and is pronounced by the author of the elaborate articles on that subject in the Encyclopaedia Londonemis to be a ster¬ ling work. “ Though at present very little known, I may venture,” says this writer, “ to predict, that, as time rolls on, and prejudices moulder away, this work, like the Elements of Euclid, will stand forth as a lasting monument of pure truth.” —See Note Z Z. 3 Nitsch, &c. pp. 17b 1/5- DISSERTATION FIRST. 197 produces on the mind is, that his own opinion was favourable to the scheme of necessity. For if the reasonings of the Necessitarians he ad¬ mitted to he satisfactory, and if nothing can he opposed to them hut the incomprehensible pro¬ position, that man neither exists in space nor in time, the natural inference is, that this propo¬ sition was brought forward rather to save ap¬ pearances, than as a serious objection to the uni¬ versality of the conclusion. Here, however, Kant calls to his aid the prin¬ ciples of what he calls 'practical reason. Deeply impressed with a conviction that morality is the chief concern of man, and that morality and the freedom of the human will must stand or fall to¬ gether, he exerts his ingenuity to show, that the metaphysical proof already brought of the pos¬ sibility of free agency, joined to our own con¬ sciousness of a liberty of choice, affords evidence of the fact fully sufficient for the practical regu¬ lation of our conduct, although not amounting to what is represented as demonstration in the Critique of Pure Reason.1 It is impossible to combine together these two parts of the Kantian system, without being struck with the resemblance they hear to the deceitful sense of liberty to which Lord Kames had recourse (in the first edition of his Essays on Morality and Natural Religion), in order to reconcile our consciousness of free agency with the conclusions of the Necessitarians. In both cases, the reader is left in a state of most un¬ comfortable scepticism, not confined to this par¬ ticular question, but extending to every other subject which can give employment to the hu¬ man faculties.2 In some respects, the functions ascribed by Kant to his practical reason are analogous to those ascribed to common sense in the writings of Beattie and Oswald. But his view of the subject is, on the whole, infinitely more excep¬ tionable than theirs, inasmuch as it sanctions the supposition, that the conclusions of pure reason are, in certain instances, at variance with that modification of reason which was meant by our Maker to be our guide in life ; whereas the constant language of the other writers is, that all the different parts of our intellectual frame are in the most perfect harmony with each other. The motto which Beattie has prefixed to his book, “ Nunquam aliud natura, aliud sapientia dicit,’ expresses, in a few significant words, the whole substance of his philosophy. 1 The account of this part of Kant’s doctrine given by M. Buhle agrees in substance with that of Mr Nitsch : “ Toute moralite des actions repose uniquement sur la disposition practique, en tant qu’elle est determinee par la loi morale seule. Si 1’on considere cette disposition comme phenomena dans la conscience; e’est un evenement naturel, elle obeit a la loi de la causalite', elle repose sur ce que I’homme a eprouve auparavant dans le terns, et elle fait partie du caractere empirique de I’homme. Mais on peut aussi la considerer comme un acte de la liberte raisonnable: Alors elle n’est plus soumise a la loi de la causalite ; elle est inde'pendante de la condition du temps, elle se rapporte a une cause intelligible, la liberte', et elle fait partie du caractere intelligible de I’homme. On ne peut, a la verite, point acquerir la moindre connoissance des objets intelligibles; mais la liberte n’est pas moins un fait de la conscience. Done les actions exterieures sont indifferentes pour la moralite de I’homme. La bonte morale de I’liomme consiste uniquement dans sa volonte moralement bonne, et celle-ci consiste en ce que la volonte soit determine'e par la loi morale seule.”—(Hist, de la Philosophic Moderne, par J. G. Buble, Tom. YI. pp. 504, 505.) Very nearly to the same purpose is the following statement by the ingenious author of the article Leibnitz in the Bio- graphic Universelle:—“ Comment accorder le fatum et la liberte, I’imputation morale et la dependence des etres finies Kant croit echapper a cet e'cueil en ne soumettant a la loi de causalite (au determinisme de Leibnitz) que le monde pheno- menique, et en affranchissant de ce princijfe 1’ame comme noumcne ou chose en soi, envisageant ainsi chaqiie action comme appartenant a un double serie a la fois; a 1’ordre physique ou elle est enchainde a ce qui precede et a ce qui suit par les liens communs de la nature, et d Pordre morale, ou une determination produit un effet, sans que pour expliquer cette voli¬ tion et son resultat, on soit renvoye a un dtat antecedent.” The author of the above passage is M. Staffer, to whom we are indebted for the article Kant in the same work. For Kant’s own view of the subject consult his Critique of Pure Reason, passim, particularly p. 99. et seq. of Born’s Translation, Vol. III. 2 The idea of Kant (according to his own explicit avowal) was, that every being, which conceives itself to be free, whe¬ ther it be in reality so or not, is rendered by its own belief a moral and accountable agent. “ Jam equidem dico: quteque natura, quae non potest nisi sub idea libertatis agere, propter id ipsum, respectu practice, reipsa libera est; hoc est, ad earn valent cunctae leges, cum libertate arctissime conjunctae perinde, ac voluntas ejus etiam per se ipsam, et in philosophia theoretica probata, libera declaretur—(Kantii Opera, Vol. II. p. 926.) This is also the creed professed by the Abbe Galiani, a much more dangerous moralist than Kant, because he is aivyays intelligible, and often extremely lively and amusing. “ L’homme est done libre, puisqu’il est intimement persuade de 1’etre, et que cela vaut tout autant que la liberte. Voila done le mechanisme de Vunivers explique clair comme de Veau de roche." The same author farther remarks, “ La persuasion de la liberte constitue 1’essence de I’homme. On pourroit meme dtTi- nir I’homme un animal qui se croit libre, et ce seroit une definition complete.”—f Corrcspondance de VAbbe. Galiani, Tome l. pp. 339, 340. A Paris, 1818.) 198 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. It is to tlie same practical modification of reason that Kant appeals in favour of the ex¬ istence of the Deity, and of a future state of re¬ tribution, both of which articles of belief he thinks derive the whole of their evidence from the moral nature of man. His system, there¬ fore, as far as I am able to comprehend it, tends rather to represent these as useful credenda, than as certain or even as probable truths. Indeed, the whole of his moral superstructure will he found to rest ultimately on no better basis than the metaphysical conundrum^ that the human mind (considered as a noumenon and not as a phenomenon) neither exists in space nor in time. That it was Kant’s original aim to establish a system of scepticism, I am far from being dis¬ posed to think.1 The probability is, that be began with a serious wish to refute the doctrines of Hume; and that, in the progress of his in¬ quiries, he met with obstacles of which he was not aware. It was to remove these obstacles that he had recourse to practical reason ; an idea which has every appearance of being an after¬ thought, very remote from his views when he first undertook his work. This, too, would seem, from the following passage (which I trans¬ late from Degerando), to have been the opinion of one of Kant’s ablest German commentators, M. Reinhold: “ Practical Reason (as Reinhold ingeniously observes) is a wing which Kant has prudently added to his edifice, from a sense of the inadequacy of the original design to answer the intended purpose. It bears a manifest re¬ semblance to what some philosophers call an ap¬ peal to sentiment, founding belief on the neces¬ sity of acting. Whatever contempt Kant may affect for popular systems of philosophy, this manner of considering the subject is not unlike the disposition of those who, feeling their inabi¬ lity to obtain, by the exercise of their reason, a direct conviction of their religious creed, cling to it nevertheless with a blind eagerness, as a support essential to their morals and their hap¬ piness.” [Hist. Comparee, Vol. II. pp. 243, 244.) The extraordinary impression produced for a considerable time in Germany, by the Critique of Pure Reason, is very shrewdly, and I suspect justly, accounted for by the writer last quoted: “ The system of Kant was well adapted to flat¬ ter the weaknesses of the human mind. Curio¬ sity was excited, by seeing paths opened which had never been trodden before. The love of mystery found a secret charm in the obscui’ity which enveloped the doctrine. The long and troublesome period of initiation was calculated to rouse the ambition of bold and adventurous spirits. Their love of singularity was gratified by the new nomenclature; while their vanity exulted in the idea of being admitted into a privi¬ leged sect, exercising, and entitled to exercise, the supreme censorship in philosophy. Even men of the most ordinary parts, on finding themselves called to so high functions, lost sight of their real mediocrity, and conceived them¬ selves transformed into geniuses destined to form a new era in the history of reason. by an historian of high reputation, as the reformer of Italian philosophy. If the execution of cannot fail at all to thf enlightened views with which the design seems to nave been conceived, it , , much practical utility. “ Ma chi pub veramente dirsi il riformatore dell’ Italiana filosofia, chi la fece tosto conoscere, e respettare da’ pui dotti filosofi delle altre nazioni, chi seppe arricchire di nuovi pregi la logica, la Gen°VeSi- , T«ttoche molti fossero stati i fihSofi die cercarono con "sottili riflfsSn" g H, pye?ettl d ajutare la mente a pensare ed a ragionare con esattezza e verita, e Bacone, Malebranche, Loke, Wolfio, e molt alto sembrassero avere esaunto quanto v’era da scrivere su tale arte, seppe nondimeno il Genovesi trovare nuove Sofir^eneralminWd^n-11^ dH-Prep0ri-« 6 ^ Una lo?ica Piu Piena e comPil>ta, e piu utile non solo alio studio della losofia, e generalmente ad ogm studio scientifico, ma eziandfo alia condotta morale, edalla civile societa Oriyine, de Proyressi, e dello Stato attuale d Ogm Lctteratura dell’ Abate D. Giovanni Andres. Tomo XV. pp. 260. 261. Ve- neziu, loUU*) DISSERTATION FIRST. 203 part of Europe where mathematicians and me¬ taphysicians of the highest rank have produced such poetry as has proceeded from the pens of Boscovich and Stay. It is in this rare balance of imagination, and of the reasoning powers, that the perfection of the human intellect will be allowed to consist; and of this balance a far greater number of instances may be quoted from Italy (reckoning from Galileo1 downwards), than in any other corner of the learned world. The sciences of ethics, and of political eco¬ nomy, seem to be more suited to the taste of the modern Italians, than logic or metaphysics, pro¬ perly so called. And in the two former bran¬ ches of knowledge, they have certainly con¬ tributed much to the instruction and improve¬ ment of the eighteenth century. But on these subjects we are not yet prepared to enter. In the New World, the state of society and of manners has not hitherto been so favourable to abstract science as to pursuits which come home directly to the business of human life. There is, however, one metaphysician of whom Ame¬ rica has to boast, who, in logical acuteness and subtility, does not yield to any disputant bred in the universities of Europe. I need not say, that I allude to Jonathan Edwards. But, at the time when he wrote, the state of America was more favourable than it now is, or can for a long period be expected to be, to such inquiries as those which engaged his attention; inquiries, by the way, to which his thoughts were evi¬ dently turned, less by the impulse of speculative curiosity, than by his anxiety to defend the theo¬ logical system in which he had been educated, and to which he was most conscientiously and zealously attached. The effect of this anxiety in sharpening his faculties, and in keeping his pole* mical vigilance constantly on the alert, may be traced in every step of his argument.2 In the mean time, a new and unexpected mine of intellectual wealth has been opened to the learned of Europe, in those regions of the East, which, although in all probability the cradle of civilisation and science, were, till very lately, better known in the annals of commerce than of philosophy. The metaphysical and ethical remains of the Indian sages are, in a pe¬ culiar degree, interesting and instructive; inas¬ much as they seem to have furnished the germs of the chief systems taught in the Grecian schools. The favourite theories, however, of the Hindoos will, all of them, be found, more or less, tinc¬ tured with those ascetic habits of abstract and mystical meditation which seem to have been, in all ages, congenial to their constitutional tem¬ perament. Of such habits, an Idealism, ap¬ proaching to that of Berkeley and Malebranche, is as natural an offspring, as Materialism is of the gay and dissipated manners, which, in great and luxurious capitals, are constantly inviting the thoughts abroad. To these remains of ancient science in the 1 See a most interesting account of Galileo’s taste for poetry and polite literature in Ginguend, Histoire Litter air e d'ltalie. Tome V. pp. 331, et seq. a Paris, 1812. 2 While this Dissertation was in the press, I received anew American publication, entitled, “ Transactions of the Histori¬ cal and Literary Committee of the American Philosophical Society, held at Philadelphia, for Promoting Useful Knowledge," Vol. [. Philadelphia, 1819. From an advertisement prefixed to this volume, it appears that, at a meeting of this learned body in 1815, it was resolved, “ That a new committee be added to those already established, to be denominated the Committee of History, Moral Science, and General Literature.” It was with great pleasure I observed, that one of the first objects to which the committee has directed its attention is to investigate and ascertain, as much as possible, the structure and grammatical forms of the languages of the aboriginal nations of America. The Report of the corresponding secretary (M. Duponceau), dated January 1819, with respect to the progress then made in this investigation, is highly curious and inte¬ resting, and displays not only enlarged and philosophical views, but an intimate acquaintance with the philological re¬ searches of Adelung, Vater, Humboldt, and other German scholars. All this evinces an enlightened curiosity, and an ex¬ tent of literary information, which could scarcely have been expected in these rising states for many years to come. The rapid progress which the Americans have lately made in the art of writing has been remarked by various critics, and it is certainly a very important fact in the history of their literature. Their state papers were, indeed, always distin¬ guished by a strain of animated and vigorous eloquence; but as most of them were composed on the spur of the occasion, their authors had little time to bestow on the niceties, or even upon the purity of diction. An attention to these is the slow offspring of learned leisure, and of the diligent study of the best models. This I presume was Gray’s meaning, when he said, that “good writing not only required great parts, but the very best of those parts —a maxim which, if true, would point out the state of the public taste with respect to style, as the surest test among any people of the general improve¬ ment which their intellectual powers have received ; and which, when applied to our Trans-atlantic brethren, would justify sanguine expectations of the attainments of the rising generation. * Note of Mason on a Letter of Gray’s to Dr Wharton, on the death of Dr Middleton. 204 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. East, the attention of Europe was first called by Bernier, a most intelligent and authentic tra¬ veller, of whom I formerly took notice as a fa¬ vourite pupil of Gassendi. But it is chiefly hy our own countrymen that the field which he opened has been subsequently explored; and of their meritorious labours in the prosecution of this task, during the reign of our late Sovereign, it is scarcely possible to form too high an estimate. Much more, however, may he yet expected, if such a prodigy as Sir William Jones should again appear, uniting, in as miraculous a degree, the gift of tongues with the spirit of philosophy. The structure of the Sanscrit, in itself, indepen¬ dently of the treasures locked up in it, affords one of the most puzzling subjects of inquiry that was ever presented to human ingenuity. The affinities and filiations of different tongues, as evinced in their corresponding roots and other coincidences, are abundantly curious, hut incomparably more easy in the explanation, than the systematical analogy which is said to exist between the Sanscrit and the Greek (and also between the Sanscrit and the Latin, which is considered as the most ancient dialect of the Greek), in the conjugations and flexions of their verbs, and in many other particulars of their mechanism ; an analogy which is represented as so complete, that, in the versions which have been made from the one language into the other, “ Sanscrit,” we are told, “ answers to Greek, as face to face in a glass.”1 That the Sanscrit did not grow up to the perfection which it now exhibits, from popular and casual modes of speech, the unexampled regularity of its forms seems almost to demonstrate; and yet, should tliis supposition he rejected, to what other hypo¬ thesis shall we have recourse, which does not involve equal, if not greater improbabilities ? The problem is well worthy of the attention of philosophical grammarians; and the solution of it, whatever it may be, can scarcely fail to throw some new lights on the history of the human race, as well as on that of the human mind. SECTION VIII. Metaphysical Philosophy of Scotland. It now only remains for me to take a slight survey of the rise and progress of the Meta¬ physical Philosophy of Scotland; and if, in treating of this, I should be somewhat more minute than in the former parts of this Histo¬ rical Sketch, I flatter myself that allowances will be made for my anxiety to supply some chasms in the literary history of my country, which could not he so easily, nor perhaps so authenti¬ cally, filled up by a younger hand. The Metaphysical Philosophy of Scotland, and, indeed, the literary taste in general, which so remarkably distinguished this country during the last century, may he dated from the lectures of Dr Francis Hutcheson, in the University of Glasgow. Strong indications of the same spe¬ culative spirit may be traced in earlier writers;2 hut it was from this period that Scotland, after a long slumber, began again to attract general notice in the republic of letters.3 The writings of Dr Hutcheson, however, are more closely connected with the history of Ethical than of Metaphysical Science; and I 1 Letter from the Reverend David Brown, Provost of the College of Fort William, about the Smscrit Edition of the Gospels (dated Calcutta, September 1806, and published in some of the Literary Journals of the day.) 4 See Note B B B. 3 An Italian writer of some note, in a work published in 1763, assigns the same date to the revival of letters in Scotland. ‘ Fra i tanti, e si chiari Scrittori che fiorirono nella Gran Bretagna a’ tempi della Regina Anna, noh se ne conta pur uno, DISSERTATION FIRST. 205 shall, accordingly, delay any remarks which I have to offer upon them till I enter upon that part of my subject. There are, indeed, some very original and important metaphysical hints scattered over his works; but it is chiefly as an ethical writer that he is known to the world, and that he is entitled to a place among the philosophers of the eighteenth century.1 Among the contemporaries of Dr Hutcheson, there was one Scottish metaphysician (Andrew Baxter, author of the Inquiry into the Nature of the Human SoulJ, whose name it would be im¬ proper to pass over without some notice, after the splendid eulogy bestowed on his work by Warburton. “ He who would see the justest and precisest notions of God and the soul may read this book, one of the most finished of the kind, in my humble opinion, that the present times, greatly advanced in true philosophy, have produced”2 To this unqualified praise, I must confess, I do not think Baxter’s Inquiry altogether entitled, although I readily acknowledge that it displays considerable ingenuity, as well as learning. Some of the remarks on Berkeley’s argument against the existence of matter are acute and just, and, at the time when they were published, had the merit of novelty. One of his distinguishing doctrines is, that the Deity is the immediate agent in producing the phenomena of the Material World ; but that, in the Moral World, the case is different,—a doctrine which, whatever may be thought of it in other respects, is undoubtedly a great im¬ provement on that of Malebranche, which, by representing God as the only agent in the uni¬ verse, was not less inconsistent than the scheme of Spinoza with the moral nature of Man. “ The Deity (says Baxter) is not only at the bead of Nature, but in every part of it. A chain of material causes betwixt the Deity and the effect produced, and much more a series of them, is such a supposition as would conceal the Deity from the knowledge of mortals for ever. We might search for matter above matter, till we were lost in a labyrinth out of which no phi¬ losopher ever yet found his way.—This way of bringing in second causes is borrowed from the government of the moral world, where free agents act a part; but it is very improperly ap- che sia uscito di Scozia Francesco Hutcheson venuto in Iscozia, a professarvi la Filosofia, e gli studii di umanith, nella Universita di Glasgow, v’insinuo per tutto il paese colie istruzione a viva voce, e con egregie opere date alle stampe, un vivo genio per gli studii filosofici, e literarii, e sparse qui fecondissimi semi, d’onde vediamo nascere si felice frutti, e si copiose.”—(Discorso sopra le Vicende della Litteratura, del Sig. Carlo Denina, p. 224, Glasgow edit. 1763.) I was somewhat surprised to meet with the foregoing observations in the work of a foreigner ; but, wherever he acquired his information, it evinces, in those from whom it was derived, a more intimate acquaintance with the traditionary history of letters in this country than has fallen to the share of most of our own authors who have treated of that subject. I have heard it conjectured, that the materials of his section on Scottish literature had been communicated to him by Mr Hume. Another foreign writer, much better qualified than Denina to appreciate the merits of Hutcheson, has expressed him¬ self upon this subject with his usual precision. “ L’ecole Ecossaise a en quelque sorte pour fondateur Hutcheson, mailre et predecesseur de Smith. C’est ce philosophe qui lui a imprimb son caractere, et qui a commence a lui donner de Teclat.” In a note upon this passage, the author observes,—“ C’est en ce seal sens qu’on peut donner un chef a une bcole de philosophic qui, comme on le verra, professe d’ailleurs la plus parfaite inddpendance de I’autoritb—(See the excellent reflections upon the posthumous works of Adam Smith, annexed by M. Prevost to his translation of that work.) Dr Hutcheson’s first course of lectures at Glasgow was given in 1730. He was a native of Ireland, and is accord¬ ingly called by Denina “ un dotto Irlandesebut he was of Scotch extraction (his father or grandfather having been a younger son of a respectable family in Ayrshire), and he was sent over when very young to receive his education in Scotland. 1 One of the chief objects of Hutcheson’s writings was to oppose the licentious system of Mandeville; a system which was the natural offspring of some of Locke’s reasonings against the existence of innate practical principles. As a moralist, Hutcheson was a warm admirer of the ancients, and seems to have been particularly smitten with that favourite doctrine of the Socratic school which identifies the good with the beautiful. Hence he was led to follow much too closely the example of Shaftesbury, in considering moral distinctions as founded more on sentiment than on reason, and to speak vaguely of virtue as a sort of noble enthusiasm; but he was led, at the same time, to connect with his ethical speculations some collateral inquiries concerning Beauty and Harmony, in which he pursued, with con¬ siderable success, the path recently struck out by Addison in his Essays on the Pleasures of the Imagination. These in¬ quiries of Hutcheson, together with his Thoughts on Laughter, although they may not be very highly prized for their depth, bear everywhere the marks of an enlarged and cultivated mind, and, whatever may have been their effects else¬ where, certainly contributed powerfully, in our Northern seats of learning, to introduce a taste for more liberal and elegant pursuits than could have been expected so soon to succeed to the intolerance, bigotry, and barbarism of the preceding century. 1 See Warburton’s Divine Legation of Moses demonstrated, p. 395 of the first edition. 206 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. plied to the material universe, where matter and motion only (or mechanism, as it is called) comes in competition with the Deity.”1 2 3 * * * * Notwithstanding, however, these and other merits, Baxter has contributed so little to the advancement of that philosophy which has since been cultivated in Scotland, that I am afraid the very slight notice I have now taken of him may be considered as an unseasonable digression. The great object of his studies plainly was, to strengthen the old argument for the soul’s im¬ materiality, by the new lights furnished by New¬ ton’s discoveries. To the intellectual and moral phenomena of Man, and to the laws by which they are regulated, he seems to have paid hut little attention.® While Dr Hutcheson’s reputation as an au¬ thor, and still more as an eloquent teacher, was at its zenith in Scotland, Mr Hume began his literary career, by the publication of his Treatise of Human Nature. It appeared in 1739, but seems at that time to have attracted little or no attention from the public. According to the author himself, “ never literary attempt was more unfortunate. It fell dead-born from the press, without reaching such distinction as even to excite a murmur among the zealots.” It forms, however, a very important link in this Historical Sketch, as it has contributed, either directly or indirectly, more than any other single work, to the subsequent progress of the Philo¬ sophy of the Human Mind. In order to adapt his principles better to the public taste, the author afterwards threw them into the more popular form of Essays; but it is in the original work that philosophical readers will always study his system, and it is there alone that the relations and bearings of its different parts, as well as its connection with the speculations of his imme¬ diate predecessors, can be distinctly traced. It is there, too, that his metaphysical talents ap¬ pear, in my opinion, to the greatest advantage; nor am I certain that he has anywhere else dis¬ played more skill or a sounder taste in point of composition.8 The great objects of Mr Hume’s Treatise of 1 Appendix to the first part of the Inquiry into the Nature of the Human Soul, pp. 109, 110. 2 Baxter was born at Old Aberdeen, in 1686 or 1687, and died at Whittingham, in East Lothian, in 1750. I have not been able to discover the date of the first edition of his Inquiry into the Nature of the Human Soul, but the second edition ap¬ peared in 1737, two years before the publication of Mr Hume’s Treatise of Human Nature. 3 A gentleman, who lived in habits of great intimacy with Dr Held towards the close of his life, and on whose accuracy I can fully depend, remembers to have heard him say repeatedly, that “ Mr Hume, in his Essays, appeared to hwe forgot¬ ten his Metaphysics.” Nor will this supposition be thought improbable, if, in addition to the subtle and fugitive nature of the subjects canvassed in the Treatise of Human Nature, it be considered that long before the publication of his Essays, Mr Hume had abandoned all his metaphysical researches. In proof of this, I shall quote a passage from a letter of his to Sir Gilbert Elliot, which, though without a date, seems from its contents to have been written about 1750 or 1751. The pas¬ sage is interesting on another account, as it serves to show how much Mr Hume undervalued the utility of mathematical learning, and consequently how little he was aware of its importance, as an organ of physical discovery, and as the founda¬ tion of some of the most necessary arts of civilised life. “ I am sorry that our correspondence should lead us into these ab¬ stract speculations. I have thought, and read, and composed very little on such questions of late. Morals, politics, and literature, have employed all my time ; but still the other topics I must think more curious, important, entertaining, and useful, than any geometry that is deeper than Euclid.” I have said that it is in Mr Hume’s earliest work that his metaphysical talents appear, in my opinion, to the greatest advantage. From the following advertisement, however, prefixed, in the latest editions of his works, to the second volume of his Essays and Treatises, Mr Hume himself would appear to have thought differently. “Most of the principles and rea¬ sonings contained in this volume were published in a work in three volumes, called A Treatise of Human Nature ; a work which the author had projected before he left College, and which he wrote and published not long after. But not finding it successful, he was sensible of his error in going to the press too early, and he cast the whole anew in the following pieces, where some negligencies in his former reasoning, and some in the expression, are, he hopes, corrected. Yet several wri¬ ters, who have honoured the author’s philosophy with answers, have taken care to direct all their batteries against that ju¬ venile work, which the author never acknowledged, and have affected to triumph in any advantage which they imagined they had obtained over it; a practice very contrary to all rules of candour and fair dealing, and a strong instance of those polemical artifices which a bigoted zeal thinks itself authorised to employ. Henceforth, the author desires, that the follow¬ ing pieces may alone be regarded as containing his philosophical sentiments and principles.” After this declaration, it certainly would be highly uncandid to impute to Mr Hume any philosophical sentiments or principles not to be found in his Philosophical Essays, as well as in his Treatise. But where is the unfairness of replying to any plausible arguments in the latter work, even although Mr Hume may have omitted them in his subsequent publications ; more especially where these arguments supply any useful lights for illustrating his more popular compositions ? The Treatise of Human Nature will certainly be remembered as long as any of Mr Hume’s philosophical writings ; nor is any person qualified either to approve or to reject his doctrines, who has not studied them in the systematical form in which they were originally cast. That Mr Hume’s remonstrance may be just with respect to some of his adversaries, I believe to be true ; but it is surely expressed in a tone more querulous and peevish than is justified by the occasion. I shall take this opportunity of preserving another judgment of Mr Hume’s (still more fully stated) on the merits of this DISSERTATION FIRST. 207 Human Nature will be best explained in his own words. “ ’Tis evident that all the sciences have a re¬ lation, greater or less, to human nature, and that, however wide any of them may seem to run from it, they still return back by one pas¬ sage or another. Even Mathematics, Natural Philosophy, and Natural Religion, are in some measure dependent on the science of Man, since they lie under the cognisance of men, and are judged of by their powers and faculties If, therefore, the sciences of Mathematics, Na¬ tural Philosophy, and Natural Religion, have such a dependence on the knowledge of man, what may be expected in the other sciences, whose connection with human nature is more close and intimate ? The sole end of logic is to explain the principles and operations of our rea¬ soning faculty, and the nature of our ideas: Morals and criticism regard our tastes and sen¬ timents, and politics consider men as united in society, and dependent on each other Here, then, is the only expedient from which we can hope for success in our philosophical re¬ searches, to leave the tedious lingering method which we have hitherto followed, and, instead of taking now and then a castle or village on the frontier, to march up directly to the capital or centre of these sciences, to human nature it¬ self; which, being once masters of, we may everywhere else hope for an easy victory. From this station we may extend our conquests over all those sciences which more intimately concern human life, and may afterwards proceed at lei¬ sure to discover more fully those which are the objects of pure curiosity. There is no question of importance whose decision is not comprised in the Science of Man, and there is none which can be decided with any certainty before we be¬ come acquainted with that science. In pre¬ tending, therefore, to explain the principles of Human Nature, we, in effect, propose a com¬ plete system of the sciences, built on a foun¬ dation almost entirely new, and the only one upon which they can stand with any security. “ And, as the science of man is the only solid foundation for the other sciences, so the only solid foundation we can give to this science it¬ self must be laid on experience and observa¬ tion. ’Tis no astonishing reflection to consider, that the application of experimental philosophy to moral subjects should come after that to na¬ tural, at the distance of above a whole century; since we find, in fact, that there was about the same interval betwixt the origin of these sci¬ ences ; and that, reckoning from Thales to So¬ crates, the space of time is nearly equal to that hetwixt my Lord Bacon and some late philoso¬ phers in England,1 who have begun to put the science of man on a new footing, and have en¬ gaged the attention, and excited the curiosity of the public.” I am far from thinking, that the execution of Mr Hume’s work corresponded with the mag¬ nificent design sketched out in these observa¬ tions ; nor does it appear to me that he had form¬ ed to himself a very correct idea of the manner in which the experimental mode of reasoning ought to be applied to moral subjects. He had, however, very great merit in separating entire¬ ly his speculations concerning the philosophy of the mind from all physiological hypotheses about the nature of the union between soul and body; and although, from some of his casual expres¬ sions, it may be suspected that he conceived our intellectual operations to result from bodily or¬ ganisation, 2 he had yet much too large a share of good sense and sagacity to suppose, that, by study- juvenile work. I copy it from a private letter written by himself to Sir Gilbert Elliot, soon after the publication of his Philosophical Essays. 1 “ I believe the Philosophical Essays contain every thing of consequence relating to the Understanding, which you would meet with in the Treatise ; and I give you my advice against reading the latter. By shortening and simplifying the ques¬ tions, I really render them more complete. Addo dum minuo. The philosophical principles are the same in both; but I was carried away by the heat of youth and invention to publish too precipitately. So vast an undertaking, planned before I was one and twenty, and composed before twenty-five, must necessarily be very defective. I have repented my haste a hun¬ dred and a hundred times.” " v j 1 “Mr Locke, Lord Shaftesbury, Dr Mandeville, Mr Hutcheson, Dr Butler,” &c. I he only expression in his works I can recollect at present, that can give any reasonable countenance to such a suspi¬ cion, occuis in his Posthumous Dialogues^ where he speaks of 44 that little agitation of the brain which we call thought” (2d Edition, pp. G9, 61.) But no fair inference can be drawn from this, as the expression is put into the mouth of Philo the Sceptic ; whereas the author intimates that Cleanthes speaks his own sentiments. 208 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. ing the latter, it is possible for human ingenuity to throw any light upon the former. His woiks, accordingly, are perfectly free from those gia- tuitous and wild conjectures, which a few years afterwards were given to the world with so much confidence by Hartley and Bonnet. And in this respect his example has been of infinite use to his successors in this northern part of the island. Many absurd theories have, indeed, at different times been produced by our countrymen 5 but I know of no part of Europe where such systems as those of Hartley and Bonnet have been so uniformly treated with the contempt they de¬ serve as in Scotland.1 Nor was it in this respect alone, that Mr Hume’s juvenile speculations contributed to for¬ ward the progress of our national literature. Among the many very exceptionable doctrines involved in them, there are various discussions, equally refined and solid, in which he has hap¬ pily exemplified the application of metaphysical analysis to questions connected with taste, with the philosophy of jurisprudence, and with the theory of government. Of these discussions some afterwards appeared in a more popular form in his philosophical and literary Essays, and still retain a place in the latest editions of his works; but others, not less curious, have been suppressed by the author, probably from an idea, that they were too abstruse to interest the curiosity of ordinary readers. In some of these practical applications of metaphysical principles, we may perceive the germs of several inquiries which have since been successfully prosecuted by Mr Hume’s countrymen; and, among others, of those which gave birth to Lord Karnes’s Historical Law Tracts, and to his Ele¬ ments of Criticism. The publication of Mr Hume’s Treatise was attended with another important effect in Scot¬ land. He had cultivated the art of writing with much greater success than any of his predeces¬ sors, and had formed his taste on the best models of English composition. The influence of his example appears to have been great and gene¬ ral ; and was in no instance more remarkable than in the style of his principal antagonists, all of whom, in studying his system, have caught, in no inconsiderable degree,- the purity, polish, and precision of his diction. Nobody, I believe, will deny, that Locke himself, considered as an English writer, is far surpassed, not only by Hume, but by Reid, Campbell, Gerard, and Beattie; and of this fact it will not be easy to find a more satisfactory explanation, than in the critical eye with which they were led to canvass a work, equally distinguished by the depth of its reasonings, and by the attractive form in which they are exhibited. The fundamental principles from which Mr Hume sets out, differ more in words than in substance from those of his immediate prede¬ cessors. According to him, all the objects of our knowledge are divided into two classes, im¬ pressions and ideas : the former, comprehending our sensations, properly so called, and also our perceptions of sensible qualities (two things be¬ twixt which Mr Hume’s system does not lead him to make any distinction); the latter, the objects of our thoughts when we remember or imagine, or in general exercise any of our intel¬ lectual powers on things which are past, ab¬ sent, or future. These ideas he considers as copies of ouf impressions, and the words which denote them as the only signs entitled to the at¬ tention of a philosopher ; every word professing to denote an idea, of which the corresponding impressions cannot be pointed out, being ipso facto unmeaning and illusory. The obvious re¬ sult of these principles is, that what Mr Hume calls impressions, furnish, either immediately or mediately, the whole materials about which our thoughts can be employed; a conclusion coin¬ ciding exactly with the account of the origin of our ideas borrowed by Gassendi from the an¬ cient Epicureans. With this fundamental principle of the Gas- sendists, Mr Hume combined the logical method recommended by their great antagonists the Cartesians, and (what seemed still more remote from his Epicurean starting ground) a strong leaning to the idealism of Malebranche and of 1 In no part of Mr Hume’s metaphysical writings is there the slightest reference to either of these systems, although he survived the date of their publication little less than thirty years. DISSERTATION FIRST. 209 Berkeley. Like Descartes, he began with doubt¬ ing of every thing, but he was too quick-sighted to be satisfied, like Descartes, with the solutions given by that philosopher of his doubts. On the contrary, he exposes the futility not only of the solutions proposed by Descartes himself, but of those suggested by Locke and others among his successors ; ending at last where Descartes beg^n, in considering no one proposition as more certain, or even as more probable than another. That the proofs alleged by Descartes of the ex¬ istence of the material world are quite incon¬ clusive, had been already remarked by many. Nay, it had been shown by Berkeley and others, that if the principles be admitted on which Des¬ cartes, in common with all philosophers, from Aristotle downwards, proceeded, the existence of the material world is impossible. A few bold thinkers, distinguished by the name of Egoists, had gone still farther than this, and had pushed their scepticism to such a length, as to doubt of everything but their own existence. Accord¬ ing to these) the proposition, eogito, ergo sum, is the only truth which can be regarded as abso¬ lutely certain. It was reserved for Mr Hume to call in question even this proposition, and to admit only the existence of impressions and ideas. To dispute against the existence of these he conceived to be impossible, inasmuch as they are the immediate subjects of consciousness. But to admit the existence of the thinking and percipient I, was to admit the existence of that imaginary substance called Mind, which (ac¬ cording to him) is no more an object of human knowledge, than the imaginary and exploded substance called Matter. From what has been already said, it may be seen, that we are not to look in Mr Hume’s Treatise for any regular or connected system. It is neither a scheme of Materialism, nor a scheme of Spiritualism; for his reasonings strike equally at the root of both these theories. His aim is to establish a universal scepticism, and to produce in the reader a complete distrust in his own faculties. For this purpose he avails himself of the data assumed by the most op¬ posite sects, shifting his ground skilfully from one position to another, as best suits the scope of his present argument. With the single ex¬ ception of Bayle, he has carried this sceptical mode of reasoning farther than any other mo¬ dern philosopher. Cicero, who himself belong¬ ed nominally to the same school, seems to have thought, that the controversial habits imposed on the Academical sect by their profession of universal doubt, required a greater versatility of talent and fertility of invention, than were ne¬ cessary for defending any particular system of tenets;1 and it is not improbable, that Mr Hume, in the pride of youthful genius, was misled by this specious but very fallacious idea. On the other hand, Bayle has the candour to acknow¬ ledge, that nothing is so easy as to dispute after the manner of the sceptics;2 3 * and to this propo¬ sition every man of reflection will find himself more and more disposed to assent, as he ad¬ vances in life. It is experience alone that can convince us, how much more difficult it is to make any real progress in the search after truth, than to acquire a talent for plausible dis¬ putation.5 That this spirit of sceptical argument has been 1 “ Nam si singulas disciplinas percipere magnum est, quanto majus omnes ? quod facere iis necesse est, quibus proposi- tum est, veri reperiendi causa, et contra omnes philosophos et pro omnibus dicere—Cujus rei tantse tamque dimcilis xacul- tatem consecutum esse me non profiteer: Secutum esse prae me fero.”—(Cicero Be Nat. Dear. 1. i. v.) 2 See the passage quoted from Bayle, in page 86 of this Dissertation. _ 3 In the very interesting account, given by Dr Holland, of Velara, a modern Greek physician, whom he met with at-La- rissa in Thessaly, a few slight particulars are mentioned, which let us completely into the character of that ingenious per¬ son. “ It appeared,” says Dr Holland, “ that Velara had thought much on the various topics of Metaphysics and Morals, and his conversation on these topics bore the same tone of satirical scepticism which was apparent as the general feature o his opinions. We spoke of the questions of Materialism and Necessity, on both of which he declared an affirmative opi¬ nion.”—(Holland’s Travels in the Ionian Isles, See. p. 275.) “ I passed this evening with Velara at his own house, and sat with him till a late hour. During part of the time our conversation turned upon metaphysical topics, and chiefly on the old Pyrrhonic doctrine of the non-existence of Matter. Velara, as usual, took the sceptical side of the argument, in w ^ic he showed much ingenuity and great knowledge of the more eminent controversialists on this and other collateral subjec s. - CIbid. p. 370.) We see here a lively picture of a character daily to be met with in more polished and learned societies, dis¬ puting not for truth but for victory; in the first conversation professing himself a Materialist; and in the secon enyin0 the existence of Matter ; on both occasions, taking up that ground where he was most likely to provoke opposi ion. inference is to be drawn from the conversation of such an individual, with respect to his real creed, it is m avour o ose DISS. I. PART II. ^ U 210 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. carried to a most pernicious excess in modern Europe, as well as among the ancient Academics, will, I presume, be now very generally allowed; but in the form in which it appears in Mr Hume’s Treatise.) its mischievous tendency has been more than compensated by the importance of those re¬ sults for which it has prepared the way. The principles which he assumes were sanctioned in common by Gassendi, by Descartes, and by Locke; and from these, in most instances, he reasons with great logical accuracy and force. The conclusions to which he is thus led are often so extravagant and dangerous, that he ought to have regarded them as a proof of the unsoundness of his data; hut if he had not the merit of draw¬ ing this inference himself, he at least forced it so irresistibly on the observation of his successors, as to he entitled to share with them in the ho¬ nour of their discoveries. Perhaps, indeed, it may he questioned if the errors which he adopted from his predecessors would not have kept their ground till this day, had not his sagacity display¬ ed so clearly the consequences which they ne¬ cessarily involve. It is in this sense that we must understand a compliment paid to him by the ablest of his adversaries, when he says, that “ Mr Hume’s premises often do more than atone for his conclusions.”1 The bias of Mr Hume’s mind to scepticism seems to have been much encouraged, and the success of his sceptical theories in the same pro¬ portion promoted, by the recent attempts of Descartes and his followers to demonstrate Self- evident Truths;—attempts which Mr Hume clearly perceived to involve, in every instance, that sort of paralogism which logicians call rea¬ soning in a circle. The weakness of these pre¬ tended demonstrations is triumphantly exposed in the Treatise of Human Nature ; and it is not very wonderful that the author, in the first en¬ thusiasm of his victory over his immediate pre-. decessors, should have fancied that the incon¬ clusiveness of the proofs argued some unsound¬ ness in the propositions which they were em¬ ployed to support. It would, indeed, have done still greater honour to his sagacity if he had as¬ cribed this to its true cause—the impossibility of confirming, by a process of reasoning, the fundamental laws of human belief; hut (as Bacon remarks) it does not often happen to those who labour in the field of science, that the same per¬ son who sows the seed should reap the harvest. From that strong sceptical bias which led this most acute reasoner, on many important ques¬ tions, to shift his controversial ground according to the humour of the moment, one favourable consequence has resulted—that we are indebted to him for the most powerful antidotes we pos¬ sess against some of the most poisonous errors of modern philosophy. I have already made a similar remark in speaking of the elaborate re¬ futation of Spinozism by Bayle; but the argu¬ ment stated by Hume, in his Essay on the Idea of Necessary Connection (though brought forward by the author with a very different view), forms a still more valuable accession to metaphysical science, as it lays the axe to the very root from which Spinozism springs. The cardinal prin¬ ciple on which the whole of that system turns is, that all events, physical and moral, are ne¬ cessarily linked together as causes and effects; from which principle all the most alarming con¬ clusions adopted by Spinoza follow as unavoid¬ able and manifest corollaries. But, if it be true, as Mr Hume contends, and as most philosophers now admit, that physical causes and effects are known to us merely as antecedents and conse¬ quents ; still more, if it be true that the word ne¬ cessity, as employed in this discussion, is alto¬ gether unmeaning and insignificant, the whole system of Spinoza is nothing better than a rope of sand, and the very proposition which it pro¬ opinions which he controverts. These opinions, at least, we may confidently conclude to he agreeable to the general belief of the country where he lives. ^ ^ ^ & & 1 Mr Hume himself (to whom Dr Reid’s Inquiry was communicated previous to its publication, by their common friend Dr Blair) seems not to have been dissatisfied with this apology for some of his speculations. u I shall only say (he ob- serves in a letter addressed to the author), that if you have been able to clear up these abstruse and important subjects, instead of being mortified, I shall be so vain as to pretend to a share of the praise, and shall think that my errors, by hav¬ ing at least some coherence, had led you to make a more strict review of my principles, which were the common ones, and to perceive their futility. —(For the whole of Mr Hume’s letter, see Biographical Memoirs of Smith, Robertson, and Reid, by the author of this Dissertation, p. 417-) DISSERTATION FIRST. 211 fesses to demonstrate is incomprehensible by our faculties. Mr Hume’s doctrine, in the unquali¬ fied form in which he states it, may lead to other consequences not less dangerous : but, if he had not the good fortune to conduct metaphysicians to the truth, he may at least be allowed the merit of haying shut up for ever one of the most fre¬ quented and fatal paths which led them astray. In what I have now said, I have supposed my readers to possess that general acquaintance with Mr Hume’s Theory of Causation which all well- educated persons may he presumed to have ac¬ quired. But the close connection of this part of his work with some of the historical details which are immediately to follow, makes it necessary for me, before I proceed farther, to recapitulate a little more particularly some of his most im¬ portant conclusions. It was, as far as I know, first shown in a sa¬ tisfactory manner by Mr Hume, that “ every de¬ monstration which has been produced for the ne¬ cessity of a cause to every new existence, is fal¬ lacious and sophistical.”1 In illustration of this assertion, he examines three different arguments which have been alleged as proofs of the propo¬ sition in question; the first by Mr Hobbes; the second by Dr Clarke; and the third by Mr Locke. And I think it will now be readily ac¬ knowledged by every competent judge, that his objections to all these pretended demonstrations are conclusive and unanswerable. When Mr Hume, however, attempts to show that the proposition in question is not intuitively certain, his argument appears to me to amount to nothing more than a logical quibble. Of this one would almost imagine that he was not in¬ sensible himself, from the short and slight man¬ ner in which he hurries over the discussion. ££ All certainty (he observes) arises from the comparison of ideas, and from the discovery of such relations as are unalterable, so long as the ideas continue the same. These relations are resemblance, proportions in quantity and number, degrees of any quality, and contrariety ; none of which are implied in this proposition, whatever has a beginning has also a cause of existence. That proposition, therefore, is not intuitively certain. At least, any one who would assert it to be in¬ tuitively certain, must deny these to be the only infallible relations, and must find some other relation of that kind to be implied in it, which it will be then time enough to examine.” Upon this passage, it is sufficient for me to observe, that the whole force of the reasoning hinges on two assumptions, which are not only gratuitous, but false. 1st, That all certainty arises from the comparison of ideas. 2dly, That all the unalterable relations among our ideas are comprehended in his own arbitrary enumeration; Resemblance, proportions in quantity and number, degrees of any quality, and contrariety. When the correctness of these two premises shall be fully established, it will be time enough (to bor¬ row Mr Hume’s own words) to examine the just¬ ness of his conclusion. From this last reasoning, however, of Mr Hume, it may be suspected, that he was aware of the vulnerable point against which his adver¬ saries were most likely to direct their attacks. From the weakness, too, of the entrenchments which he has here thrown up for his own secu¬ rity, he seems to have been sensible, that it was not capable of a long or vigorous resistance. In the mean time, he betrays no want of confidence in his original position; but repeating his as¬ sertion, that “ we derive the opinion of the ne¬ cessity of a cause to every new production, neither from demonstration nor from intuition,” he boldly concludes, that “ this opinion must necessarily arise from observation and experi¬ ence.”—(Vol. I. p. 147.) Or, as he elsewhere expresses himself, “ All our reasonings concern¬ ing causes and effects are derived from nothing but custom; and, consequently, belief is more Treatise of Human Nature, Vol. I. p. 144—Although Mr Hume, however, succeeded better than any of his predeces- sors, m calling the attention of philosophers to this discussion, his opinion on the subject does not possess the merit, in point of originality, which was supposed to belong to it either by himself or by his antagonists. See the passages which I lave quoted in proof of this, in the first volume of the Philosophy of the Human Mind, p. 542. et seq. fourth edit, and also in the second volume of the same work, p. 556. et seq. second edit. Among these, I request the attention of my readers more particularly to a passage from a book entitled, The Procedure, Extent, and Limits of the Human Understanding, published two years before the Treatise of Human Nature, and commonly ascribed to Dr Browne, Bishop of Cork. The coincidence is ruly wonderful, as it can scarcely, by any possibility, be supposed that this book was ever heard of by Mr Hume. 212 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. properly an act of the sensitive than of the cogi¬ tative part of our natures.”—[Ibid. p. 321.) The distinction here alluded to between the sensitive and the cogitative parts of our nature (it may be proper to remind my readers) makes a great figure in the works of Cudworth and of Kant. By the former it was avowedly borrowed from the philosophy of Plato. To the latter, it is not improbable, that it may have been sug¬ gested by this passage in Hume. Without dis¬ puting its justness or its importance, I may be permitted to express my doubts of the propriety of stating, so strongly as has frequently been done, the one of these parts of our nature in contrast with the other. Would it not be more philosophical, as well as more pleasing, to con¬ template the beautiful harmony between them, and the gradual steps by which the mind is train¬ ed by the intimations of the former, for the de¬ liberate conclusions of the latter? If, for example, our conviction of the permanence of the laws of nature be not founded on any process of reasoning (a proposition which Mr Hume seems to have established with demonstrative evidence), but be either the result of an instinctive principle of belief, or of the association of ideas, opera¬ ting at a period when the light of reason has not yet dawned, what can be more delightful than to find this suggestion of our sensitive frame.)1 verified by every step which our reason afterwards makes in the study of physical science ; and con¬ firmed with mathematical accuracy by the never- failing accordance of the phenomena of the heavens with the previous calculations of astro¬ nomers ! Does not this afford a satisfaction to the mind, similar to what it experiences, when we consider the adaptation of the instinct of suc¬ tion, and of the organs of respiration, to the physical properties of the atmosphere ? So far from encouraging scepticism, such a view of hu¬ man nature seems peculiarly calculated to silence every doubt about the veracity of our faculties.2 It is not my business at present to inquire into the soundness of Mr Hume’s doctrines on this subject. The rashness of some of them has, in my opinion, been sufficiently shown by more than one of his antagonists. I wish only to re¬ mark the important step which he made, in ex¬ posing the futility of the reasonings by which Hobbes, Clarke, and Locke, had attempted to demonstrate the metaphysical axiom, that “every thing which begins to exist must have a cause;” and the essential service which he rendered to true philosophy, by thus pointing out indirectly 1 Upon either of these suppositions, Mr Hume would, with equal propriety, have referred our anticipation of the future event to the sensitive part of our nature; and, in point of fact, the one supposition would have answered his purpose as well as the other. 2 It is but justice to Mr Hume to remark, that, in his later publications, he has himself suggested this very idea as the best solution he could give of his own doubts. The following passage, which appears to me to be eminently philosophical and beautiful, I beg leave to recommend to the particular attention of Kant’s disciples :— “ Here, then, is a kind of pre-established harmony between the course of nature and the succession of our ideas ; and though the powers and forces by which the former is governed be wholly unknown to us, yet our thoughts and conceptions have still, we find, gone on in the same train with the other works of nature. Custom is that principle by which this cor¬ respondence has been effected ; so necessary to the subsistence of our species, and the regulation of our conduct in every circumstance and occurrence of human life. Had not the presence of an object instantly excited the idea of those objects commonly conjoined with it, all our knowledge must have been limited to the narrow sphere of our memory and senses; and we should never have been able to adjust means to ends, or employ our natural powers, either to the producing of good, or avoiding of evil. Those who delight in the discovery and contemplation of final causes have here ample subject to employ their wonder and admiration. “ I shall add, for a further confirmation of the foregoing theory, that, as this operation of the mind, by which we infer like effects from like causes, and vice versa, is so essential to the subsistence of all human creatures, it is not probable that it could be trusted to the fallacious deductions of our reason, which is slow in its operations, appears not in any degree during the first years of infancy, and at best is, in every age and period of human life, extremely liable to error and mis¬ take. It is more conformable to the ordinary wisdom of nature to secure so necessary an act of the mind by some in¬ stinct or mechanical tendency which may be infallible in its operations, may discover itself at the first appearance of life and thought, and may be independent of all the laboured deductions of the understanding. As nature has taught us the use of our limbs, without giving us the knowledge of the muscles and nerves by which they are actuated, so has she im¬ planted in us an instinct which carries forward the thoughts in a correspondent course to that which she has established among external objects; though we are ignorant of those powers and forces on which this regular course and succession of objects totally depends.”—(See, in the last editions of Mr Hume’s Philosophical Essays, published during his own lifetime, the two sections entitled Sceptical Doubts concerning the Operations of the Understanding ; and Sceptical Solution of these Doubts. The title of the latter ot these sections has, not altogether without reason, incurred the ridicule of Dr Beattie, who translates it, Doubtful Solution of Doubtful Doubts. But the essay contains much sound and important matter, and throws a strong light on some of the chief difficulties which Mr Hume himself had started. Sufficient justice has not been done to it by his antagonists.) DISSERTATION FIRST. 213 to his successors the only solid ground on which that principle is to be defended. It is to this argument of Hume’s, according to Kant’s own acknowledgment, that we owe the Critique of Pure Reason; and to this we are also indebted for the far more luminous refutations of scep¬ ticism by Mr Hume’s own countrymen. In the course of Mr Hume’s very refined dis¬ cussions on this subject, he is led to apply them to one of the most important principles of the mind,—-our belief of the continuance of the laws of nature; ur, in other words, our belief that the future course of nature will resemble the past. And here, too (as I already hinted), it is very generally admitted, that he has succeeded completely in overturning all the theories which profess to account for this belief, by resolving it into a process of reasoning.1 The only differ¬ ence which seems to remain among philosophers is, whether it can be explained, as Mr Hume imagined, by means of the association of ideas; or, whether it must be considered as an original and fundamental law of the human understand¬ ing ;—a question, undoubtedly abundantly curi¬ ous, as a problem connected with the Theory of the Mind ; hut to which more practical importance has sometimes been attached than I conceive to be necessary.2 That Mr Hume himself conceived his refuta¬ tion of the theories which profess to assign a reason for our faith in the permanence of the laws of nature, to he closely connected with his scep¬ tical conclusions concerning causation, is quite evident from the general strain of his argument; and it is, therefore, not surprising that this re¬ futation should have been looked on with a sus¬ picious eye by his antagonists. Dr Reid was, I believe, the first of these who had the sagacity to perceive, not only that it is strictly and in- controvertibly logical, but that it may he safely admitted, without any injury to the doctrines which it was brought forward to subvert. Another of Mr Hume’s attacks on these doc¬ trines was still bolder and more direct. In con¬ ducting it he took his vantage ground from his own account of the origin of our ideas. In this way he was led to expunge from his Philosophi¬ cal Vocabulary every word of which the mean¬ ing cannot he explained by a reference to the impression from which the corresponding idea was originally copied. Nor was he startled in the application of this rule, by the consideration, that it would force him to condemn, as insigni¬ ficant, many words which are to he found in all languages, and some of which express what are commonly regarded as the most important ob¬ jects of human knowledge. Of this number are the words cause and effect; at least, in the sense in which they are commonly understood both by the vulgar and by philosophers. “ One 1 The incidental reference made, by way of illustration, in the following passage, to our instinctive conviction of the per¬ manency of the laws of Nature, encourages me to hope, that, among candid and intelligent inquirers, it is now received as an acknowledged fact in the Theory of the Human Mind. “ The anxiety men have in all ages shown to obtain a fixed standard of value, and that remarkable agreement of nations, dissimilar in all other customs, in the use of one medium, on account of its superior fitness for that purpose, is itself a con¬ vincing proof how essential it is to our social interests. The notion of its permanency, although it be conventional and ar¬ bitrary, and liable, in reality, to many causes of variation, yet had gained so firm a hold on the minds of men, as to re¬ semble, in its effects on their conduct, that instinctive conviction of the permanency of the laws of nature which is the foimdation of all our reasoning."—(A Letter to the Right Hon. R. Peel, M. P. for the University of Oxford, by one of his Constituents. Second edition, p. 23.) 2 The difference between the two opinions amounts to nothing more than this, whether our expectation of the conti¬ nuance of the laws of nature results from a principle coeval with the first exercise of the senses; or whether it arises gra¬ dually from the accommodation of the order of our thoughts to the established order of physical events. “ Nature (as Mr Hume himself observes) may certainly produce whatever can arise from habit; nay, habit is nothing but one of the prin¬ ciples of nature, and derives all its force from that origin.—(Treatise of Human Nature, Vol. I. p. 313.) Whatever ideas, therefore, and whatever principles we are unavoidably led to acquire by the circumstances in which we are placed, and by the exercise of those faculties which are essential to our preservation, are to be considered as parts of human nature, no less than those which are implanted in the mind at its first formation. Are not the acquired perceptions of sight and of hear¬ ing as much parts of human nature as the original perceptions of external objects which we obtain by the use of the hand ? The passage quoted from Mr Hume, in Note 2. p. 212, if attentively considered, will be found, when combined with these remarks, to throw a strong and pleasing light on his latest views with respect to this part of his philosophy. In denying that our expectation of the continuance of the laws of nature is founded on reasoning, as y^ll as in asserting our ignorance of any necessary connections among physical events, Mr Hume had been completely anticipated by some of his predecessors (See the references mentioned in the Note, p. 211.) I do not, however, think that, before his time, phi¬ losophers were at all aware of the alarming consequences which, on a superficial view, seem to follow from this part of his system. Indeed, these consequences would never have been apprehended, had it not been supposed to form an essential link in his argument against the commonly received notion of Causation. PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. ^14 event (says he) follows another; but we never observe any tie between them. They seem con¬ joined, hut never connected. And as we can have no idea of any thing which never appeared to our outward sense or inward sentiment, the ne¬ cessary conclusion seems to be, that we have no idea of connection or power at all; and that these words are absolutely without any meaning, when employed either in philosophical reasonings or common life.”—(Hume’s Essays, Yol. II. p. 79. Ed. of Lond. 1784.) When this doctrine was first proposed by Mr Hume, he appears to have been very strongly impressed with its repugnance to the common apprehensions of mankind. c< I am sensible (he observes) that of all the paradoxes which I have had, or shall hereafter have occasion to advance in the course of this treatise, the present one is the most violent.”—(Treatise of Human Nature, Vol. I. p. 291.) It was probably owing to this impression that he did not fully unfold in that work all the consequences which, in his subse¬ quent publications, he deduced from the same paradox; nor did he even apply it to invalidate the argument which infers the existence of an intelligent cause from the order of the universe. There cannot, however, be a doubt that he was aware, at this period of his life, of the conclu¬ sions to which it unavoidably leads, and which are indeed too obvious to escape the notice of a far less acute inquirer. In a private letter of Mr Hume’s, to one of his most intimate friends,1 some light is thrown on the circumstances which first led his mind into this train of sceptical speculation. As his narrative has every appearance of the most per¬ fect truth and candour, and contains several passages which I doubt not will be very gene¬ rally interesting to my readers, I shall give it a place, together with some extracts from the cor¬ respondence to which it gave rise, in the Notes at the end of this Dissertation. Every thing connected with the origin and composition of a work which has had so powerful an influence on the direction which metaphysical pursuits have since taken, both in Scotland2 and in Germany, will be allowed to form an important article of philosophical history; and this history I need not offer any apology for choosing to communi¬ cate to the public rather in Mr Hume’s words than in my own.5 From the reply to this letter by Mr Hume’s very ingenious and accomplished correspondent, we learn that he had drawn from Mr Hume’s metaphysical discussions the only sound and philosophical inference : that the lameness of the proofs offered by Descartes and his succes¬ sors, of some fundamental truths universally 1 Sir Gilbert Elliot, Bart, grandfather of the present Earl of Minto. The originals of the letters to which I refer are in Lord Minto’s possession. 2 A foreign writer, of great name (M. Frederick Schlegel), seems to think that the influence of Mr Hume’s Treatise of Human Nature on the Philosophy of England has been still more extensive than I had conceived it to be. His opinion on this point I transcribe as a sort of literary curiosity : “ Since the time of Hume, nothing more has been attempted in England, than to erect all sorts of bulwarks against the practical influence of his destructive scepticism; and to maintain, by various substitutes and aids, the pile of moral prin¬ ciple uncorrupted and entire. Not only with Adam Smith, but with all their late philosophers, national welfare is the ruling and central principle of thought;—a principle excellent and praiseworthy in its due situation, but quite unfitted for being the centre and orach of all knowledge and science." From the connection in which this last sentence stands with the context, would not one imagine that the writer conceived the Wealth of Nations to be a new moral or metaphysical system, devised by Mr Smith, for the purpose of counteracting Mr Hume’s scepticism ? I have read this translation of Mr Schlegel’s lectures with much curiosity and interest, and flatter myself that we shall soon have English versions of the works of Kant, and of other German authors, from the pens of their English disciples. Little more, I am fully persuaded, is necessary, in this country, to bring down the philosophy of Germany to its proper In treating of literary and historical subjects, Mr Schlegel seems to be more in his element, than when he ventures to pronounce on philosophical questions. But even in cases of the former description, some of his dashing judgments on Eng¬ lish writers can be accounted for only by haste, caprice, or prejudice. “ The English themselves (we are told) are now pretty well convinced, that Robertson is a careless, superficial, and blundering historian: although they study his works, and are right in doing so, as models of pure composition, extremely deserving of attention during the present declining state of English style •••••• • • With all the abundance of his Italian elegance, what is the overloaded and affected Roscoe when compared with Gibbon . Coxe, although master of a good and classical style, resembles Robertson in no respect so much as in the superncialness of his researches; and the statesman Fox has nothing in common with Hume but the bigotry of his party zeal.” Such criticisms may perhaps be applauded by a German auditory, but in this country they can injure the reputation of none but their author. J J • See Note CCC. DISSERTATION FIRST. 215 acknowledged by mankind, proceeded, not from any defect in the evidence of these truths, but, on the contrary, from their being self-evident, and consequently unsusceptible of demonstra¬ tion. We learn, farther, that the same conclu¬ sion had been adopted, at this early period, by another of Mr Hume’s friends, Mr Henry Home, who, under the name of Lord Karnes, was afterwards so well known in the learned world. Those who are acquainted with the subsequent publications of this distinguished and most respectable author, will immediately recognise, in the account here given of the im¬ pression left on his mind by Mr Hume’s scepti¬ cism, the rudiments of a peculiar logic, which runs more or less through all his later works ; and which, it must be acknowledged, he has, in various instances, carried to an unphilosophical extreme.1 2 The light in which Mr Hume’s scepticism appears from these extracts to have struck his friends, Sir Gilbert Elliot and Lord Karnes, was very nearly the same with that in which it was afterwards viewed by Reid, Oswald, and Beat- tie, all of whom have manifestly aimed, with greater or less precision, at the same logical doctrine which I have just alluded to. This, too, was the very ground on which Father Buf- fier had (even before the publication of the Treatise of Human Nature) made his 4 stand against similar theories, built by his predeces¬ sors on the Cartesian principles. The coinci¬ dence between his train of thinking, and that into which our Scottish metaphysicians soon after fell, is so very remarkable, that it has been considered by many as amounting to a proof that the plan of their works was, in some mea¬ sure, suggested by his; but it is infinitely more probable, that the argument which runs, in common, through the speculations of all of them, was the natural result of the state of metaphy¬ sical science when they engaged in their philo¬ sophical inquiries.8 The answer which Mr Hume made to this argument, when it was first proposed to him in the easy intercourse of private correspondence, seems to me an object of so much curiosity, as to justify me for bringing it under the eye of my readers in immediate connection with the foregoing details. Opinions thus communicat¬ ed in the confidence of friendly discussion, pos¬ sess a value which seldom belongs to proposi¬ tions hazarded in those public controversies where the love of victory is apt to mingle, more or less, in the most candid minds, with the love of truth. “ Your notion of correcting subtlety by sen¬ timent is certainly very just with regard to mo¬ rals, which depend upon sentiment: And in politics and natural philosophy, whatever con¬ clusion is contrary to certain matters of fact, must certainly be wrong, and there must some error lie somewhere in the argument, whether we be able to show it or not. But, in metaphy¬ sics or theology, I cannot see how either of these plain and obvious standards of truth can have place. Nothing there can correct bad reason¬ ing but good reasoning; and sophistry must be opposed by syllogism.3 About seventy or eighty years ago,4 * * I observe a principle like that which you advance prevailed very much in France, amongst some philosophers and beaux esprits. 1 I allude particularly to the unnecessary multiplication, in his philosophical arguments, of internal senses and of in¬ stinctive principles. 2 Voltaire, in his catalogue of the illustrious writers who adorned the reign of Louis XIV. is one of the very few French authors who have spoken of Buffier with due respect: “ II y a dans ses traite's de mdtaphysique des morceaux que Locke n’aurait pas desavoues, et c’est le seul jesuite qui ait mis une philosophie raisonnahle dans ses ouvrages.” Another French philosopher, too, of a very different school, and certainly not disposed to overrate the talents of Buffier, has, in a work published as lately as 1805, candidly acknowledged the lights which he might have derived from the labours of his prede¬ cessor, if he had been acquainted with them at an earlier period of his studies. Condillac, he also observes, might have profited greatly by the same lights, if he had availed himself of their guidance, in his inquiries concerning the human un¬ derstanding. “ Du moins est il certain que pour ma part, je suis fort fachd de ne connoitre que depuis tres peu de temps ces opinions du Pere Buffier; si je les avais vues plutot enoncees quelque part, elles m’auraient dpargne beaucoup de peines et d’hdsitations.”—“ Je regrette beaucoup que Condillac, dans ses profondes et sagaces meditations sur I’intelligence hu- maine, n’ait pas fait plus d’attention aux idees du Pere Buffier,” &c. &c—Eltmens d'Ideologic, par M. Destutt-Tracy, Tom. III. pp. 136, 137. (See Elements of the Philosophy of the Human Mind, Vol. II. pp. 88, 89, 2d edit.) 3 May not sophistry be also opposed, by appealing to the fundamental laws of human belief; and, in some cases, by appeal- mg to facts for which we have the evidence of our own consciousness ? The word sentiment does not express, with sufficient precision, the test which Mr Hume’s correspondent had manifestly in view. * This letter is dated 1751. 216 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. The occasion of it was this : The famous M. Nicole of the Port Royal, in his Perpetuite de la Foi, pushed the Protestants very hard upon the impossibility of the people’s reaching a con¬ viction of their religion by the way of private judgment, which required so many disquisi¬ tions, reasonings, researches, erudition, impar¬ tiality, and penetration, as not one of a hundred, even among men of education, is capable of. M. Claude and the Protestants answered him, not by solving his difficulties (which seems impos¬ sible), but by retorting them (which is very easy.) They showed, that to reach the way of authority which the Catholics insist on, as long a train of acute reasoning, and as great erudi¬ tion was requisite, as would be sufficient for a Protestant. We must first piwe all the truths of natural religion, the foundation of morals, the divine authority of the Scripture, the de¬ ference which it commands to the church, the tradition of the church, &c. &c. The compari¬ son of these controversial writings begat an idea in some, that it was neither by reasoning nor authority we learn our religion, but by senti¬ ment ; and this was certainly a vei*y convenient way, and what a philosopher would be very well pleased to comply with, if he could dis¬ tinguish sentiment from education. But, to all appearance, the sentiment of Stockholm, Geneva, Rome, ancient and modern Athens, and Memphis, have not the same characters; and no thinking man can implicitly assent to any of them, but from the general principle, that, as the truth on these subjects is beyond human capacity, and that, as for one’s own ease, he must adopt some tenets, there is more satisfac¬ tion and com enience in holding to the cate¬ chism we have been first taught. Now, this I have nothing to say against. I would only observe, that such a conduct is founded on the most universal and determined scepticism. For more curiosity and research give a direct oppo¬ site turn from the same principles.” On this careless effusion of Mr Hume’s pen, it would be unpardonable to offer any critical strictures. It cannot, however, be considered as improper to hint, that there is a wide and essential difference between those articles of faith which formed the subjects of dispute be¬ tween Nicole and Claude, and those laws of be- lief, of which it is the great object of the Trea¬ tise of Human Nature to undermine the autho¬ rity. The reply of Mr Hume, therefore, is evasive, and although strongly marked with the writer’s ingenuity, does not bear upon the point in question. As to the distinction alleged by Mr Hume between the criteria of truth in natural philo¬ sophy and in metaphysics, I trust it will now be pretty generally granted, that however well founded it may be when confined to the meta¬ physics of the schoolmen, it will by no means hold when extended to the inductive philosophy of the human mind. In this last science, no less than in natural philosophy, Mr Hume’s logical maxim may be laid down as a funda¬ mental principle, that “ whatever conclusion is contrary to toiatter of fact must be wrong, and there must some error lie somewhere in the ar¬ gument, whether we be able to show it or not.” It is a remarkable circumstance in the history of Mr Hume’s literary life, and a proof of the sincerity with which he was then engaged in the search of truth, that, previous to the publication of his Treatise of Human Nature, he discovered a stroiag anxiety to submit it to the examination of the celebrated Hr Butler, author of the Ana- logy of Religion, Natural and Revealed, to the Constitution and Course of Nature. For this pur¬ pose he applied to Mr Henry Home, between whom and Hr Butler some friendly letters ap¬ pear to have passed before this period. “ Your thoughts and mine (says Mr Hume to his cor¬ respondent) agree with respect to Hr Butler, and I would be glad to be introduced to him. I am at present castrating my work, that is, cut¬ ting off its nobler parts; that is, endeavouring it shall give as little offence as possible, before which I could not pretend to put it into the doc¬ tor’s hands.”1 In another letter, he acknow¬ ledges Mr Home’s kindness in recommending him to Hr Butler’s notice. “ I shall not trouble 1 For the rest of the letter, see Memoirs of the Life and Writings of Lord Karnes, by Lord Woodhouselee, Vol. 1. p. 84, et seq. DISSERTATION FIRST. 217 you with any formal compliments or thanks, which would be but an ill return for the kind¬ ness you have done me in writing in my behalf, to one you are so little acquainted with as Dr Butler; and, I am afraid, stretching the truth in favour of a friend. I have called on the doc¬ tor, with a design of delivering your letter, but find he is at present in the country. I am a little anxious to have the doctor’s opinion. My own I dare not trust to; both because it concerns myself, and because it is so variable, that I know not how to fix it. Sometimes it elevates me above the clouds ; at other times it depresses me with doubts and fears; so that, whatever be my success, I cannot be entirely disappointed.” Whether Mr Hume ever enjoyed the satisfac¬ tion of a personal interview with Dr Butler, I have not heard. From a letter of his to Mr Home, dated London, 1739, we learn that if any intercourse took place between them, it must have been after the publication of the Treatise of Human Nature. “ I have sent the Bishop of Bristol a copy; but could not wait upon him with your letter after he had arrived at that dignity. At least, I thought it would be to no purpose after I began the printing.”1 In a subsequent letter to the same correspondent, written in 1742, he expresses his satisfaction at the favourable opinion which he understood Dr Butler had formed of his volume of Essays, then recently published, and augurs well from this circumstance of the success of his book. “ I am told that Dr Butler has everywhere recommend¬ ed them, so that I hope they will have some success.”2 3 * These particulars, trifling as they may ap¬ pear to some, seemed to me, for more reasons than one, not unworthy of notice in this sketch. Independently of the pleasing record they afford of the mutual respect entertained by the eminent men to whom they relate, for each other’s philo¬ sophical talents, they have a closer connection with the history of metaphysical and moral in¬ quiry in this island, than might be suspected by those who have not a very intimate acquaintance with the writings of both. Dr Butler was, I think, the first of Mr Locke’s successors who clearly perceived the dangerous consequences likely to be deduced from his account of the ori¬ gin of our ideas literally interpreted; and al¬ though he has touched on this subject but once, and that with his usual brevity, he has yet said enough to show, that his opinion with respect to it was the same with that formerly contended for by Cudworth, in opposition to Gassendi and Hobbes, and which has since been revived in different forms by the ablest of Mr Hume’s an¬ tagonists.5 With these views, it may be rea¬ sonably supposed, that he was not displeased to see the consequences of Locke’s doctrine so very logically and forcibly pushed to their utmost limits, as the most effectual means of rousing the attention of the learned to a re-examination of this fundamental principle. That he was perfectly aware, before the publication of Mr Hume’s work, of the encouragement given to scepticism by the logical maxims then in vogue, is evident from the concluding paragraph of his short Essay on Personal Identity. Had it been published a few years later, nobody would have doubted, that it had been directly pointed at the general strain and spirit of Mr Hume’s philo¬ sophy. “ But though we are thus certain, that we are the same agents or living beings now, which we were as far back as our remembrance reaches: yet it is asked, Whether we may not possibly be deceived in it ? And this question may be ask¬ ed at the end of any demonstration whatever, because it is a question concerning the truth of perception by memory. And he who can doubt, whether perception by memory can in this case be depended on, may doubt also whether per¬ ception by deduction and reasoning, which also includes memory, or indeed whether intuitive perception can. Here then we can go no far- 1 Memoirs of the Li fe and Writings o f Lord Kames, "Vol. I. p. 92. 2 Ibid. p. 404. The Essays here referred to were the first part of the Essays Moral, Political, and Literary, published in 1742. The elegant author of these Memoirs has inadvertently confounded this volume with the second part of that work, containing the Political Discourses (properly so called), which did not appear till ten years afterwards. 3 See the short Essay on Personal Identity, at the end of Butler’s Analogy ; and compare the second paragraph with the remarks on this part of Locke’s Essay by Dr Price. (Review of the Principal Questions and Difficulties relating to Morals, pp. 49, 50. 3d ed. Lond. 1787-) D1SS. T. PART II. 2 E 218 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. ther. For it is ridiculous to attempt to prove the truth of those perceptions whose truth we can no otherwise prove than by other percep¬ tions of exactly the same kind with them, and which there is just the same ground to suspect; or to attempt to prove the truth of our facul¬ ties, which can no otherwise be proved, than by the use or means of those very suspected facul¬ ties themselves.”1 It is, however, less as a speculative meta¬ physician, than as a philosophical inquirer into the principles of morals, that I have been in¬ duced to associate the name of Butler with that of Hume. And, on this account, it may be thought that it would have been better to delay what I have now said of him till I come to trace the progress of Ethical Science during the eigh¬ teenth century. To myself it seemed more na¬ tural and interesting to connect this historical or rather biographical digression, with the ear¬ liest notice I was to take of Mr Hume as an author. The numerous and important hints on metaphysical questions which are scattered over Butler’s works, are sufficient of themselves to account for the space I have allotted to him among Locke’s successors; if, indeed, any apo¬ logy for this be necessary, after what I have al¬ ready mentioned, of Mr Hume’s ambition to submit to his judgment the first fruits of his metaphysical studies. The remarks hitherto made on the Treatise of Human Nature are confined entirely to the first volume. The speculations contained in the two others, on Morals, on the Nature and Founda¬ tions of Government, and on some other topics connected with political philosophy, will fall under our review afterwards. Dr Reid’s Inquiry into the Human Mind (pub¬ lished in 1764) was the first direct attack which appeared in Scotland upon the sceptical conclu¬ sions of Mr Hume’s philosophy. For my own opinion of this work I must refer to one of my former publications.2 It is enough to remark here, that its great object is to refute the Ideal Theory which was then in complete possession of the schools, and upon which Dr Reid con¬ ceived that the whole of Mr Hume’s philosophy, as well as the whole of Berkeley’s reasonings against the existence of matter, was founded. According to this theory we are taught, that “ nothing is perceived but what is in the mind which perceives it; that we do not really per¬ ceive things that are external, but only cer¬ tain images and pictures of them imprinted upon the mind, which are called impressions and ideas.”—cc This doctrine (says Dr Reid on ano¬ ther occasion) I once believed so firmly, as to embrace the whole of Berkeley’s system along with it; till finding other consequences to fol¬ low from it, which gave me more uneasiness than the want of a material world, it came into my mind, more than forty years ago, to put the question, What evidence have I for this doc¬ trine, that all the objects of my knowledge are ideas in my own mind ? From that time to the present, I have been candidly and impartial¬ ly, as I think, seeking for the evidence of this principle; but can find none, excepting the authority of philosophers.” On the refutation of the ideal theory, con¬ tained in this and his other works, Dr Reid himself was disposed to rest his chief merit as an author. “ The merit (says he in a letter to Dr James Gregory) of what you are pleased to call my Philosophy, lies, I think, chiefly in having called in question the common theory of ideas or images of things in the mind being the only objects of thought; a theory founded on natural prejudices, and so universally received as to be interwoven with the structure of lan¬ guage. Yet were I to give you a detail of what led me to call in question this theory, after I had long held it as self-evident and unquestion¬ able, you would think, as I do, that there was much of chance in the matter. The discovery was the birth of time, not of genius; and Berke- 1 I must not, however, be understood as giving unqualified praise to this Essay. It is by no means free from the old scholastic jargon, and contains some reasoning which, I may confidently assert, the author would not have employed, had it been written fifty years later. Whoever takes the trouble to read the paragraph beginning with these words, “ Thirdly, Every person is conscious,” &c. will immediately perceive the truth of this remark. I mention it as a proof of the change to the better, which has taken place since Butler’s time, in the mode of thinking and writing on Metaphysical questions. * See Biographical Memoirs, Edin. 1811. DISSERTATION FIRST. 219 ley and Hume did more to bring it to light than the man that hit upon it. I think there is hard¬ ly any thing that can be called mine in the phi¬ losophy of the mind, which does not follow with ease from the detection of this prejudice. “ I must, therefore, beg of you, most earnest¬ ly, to make no contrast in my favour to the dis¬ paragement of my predecessors in the same pur¬ suits. I can truly say of them, and shall al¬ ways avow, what you are pleased to say of me, that, hut for the assistance I have received from their writings, I never could have wrote or thought what I have done.”1 2 When I reflect on the stress thus laid by Hr Reid on this part of his writings, and his fre¬ quent recurrence to the same argument when¬ ever his subject affords him an opportunity of forcing it upon the attention of his readers, I cannot help expressing my wonder, that Kant and other German philosophers, who appear to have so carefully studied those passages in Reid, which relate to Hume’s Theory of Causation, should have overlooked entirely what he him¬ self considered as the most original and im¬ portant of all his discussions; more especially as the conclusion to which it leads has been long admitted, by the best judges in this island, as one of the few propositions in metaphysical science completely established beyond the reach of controversy. Even those who affect to speak the most lightly of Hr Reid’s contributions to the philosophy of the human mind, have found nothing to object to his reasonings against the ideal theory, but that the absurdities involved in it are too glaring to require a serious ex¬ amination.® Had these reasonings been consi¬ dered in the same light in Germany, it is quite impossible that the analogical language of Leib¬ nitz, in which he speaks of the soul as a living mirror of the universe^ could have been again re¬ vived ; a mode of speaking liable to every ob¬ jection which Reid has urged against the ideal theory. Such, however, it would appear, is the fact. The word Representation (VorstellungJ is 1 An ingenious and profound writer, who, though intimately connected with Mr Hume in habits of friendship, was not blind to the vulnerable parts of his Metaphysical System, has bestowed, in the latest of his publications, the following en¬ comium on Dr Reid’s Philosophical Works. “ The author of an Inquiry into the Mind, and of subsequent Essays on the Intellectual and Active Powers of Man, has great merit in the effect to which he has pursued this history. But, considering the point at which the science stood when he began his inquiries, he has, perhaps, no less merit in having removed the mist of hypothesis and metaphor, with which the subject was enveloped; and, in having taught us to state the facts of which we are conscious, not in figurative language, but in the terms which are proper to the subject. In this it will be our advantage to follow him ; the more that, in former theories, so much attention had been paid to the introduction of ideas or images as the elements of knowledge, that the be¬ lief of any external existence or prototype has been left to be inferred from the mere idea or image; and this inference, indeed, is so little founded, that many who have come to examine its evidence have thought themselves warranted to deny it altogether. And hence the scepticism of ingenious men, who, not seeing a proper access to knowledge through the me¬ dium of ideas, without considering whether the road they had been directed to take was the true or a false one, denied the possibility of arriving at the end.”—(Principles of Moral and Political Science, by Dr Adam Ferguson, Vol. I. pp. 7b, 76.) The work from which this passage is taken contains various important observations connected with the Philosophy of the Human Mind; but as the taste of the author led him much more strongly to moral and political speculations, than to re¬ searches concerning the intellectual powers of man, I have thought it right to reserve any remarks which I have to offer on his philosophical merits for the last part of this Discourse. 2 I allude here more particularly to Dr Priestley, who, in a work published in 177b alleged, that when philosophers called ideas the images of external things, they are only to be understood as speaking figuratively; and that Dr Reid has gravely argued against this metaphorical language, as if it were meant to convey a theory of perception. The same remark has been repeated over and over since Priestley’s time, by various writers. I have nothing to add in reply to it to what I long ago stated in my Philosophical Essays (see Note H. at the end of that work), but the following short quotation from Mr Hume:— “ It seems evident, that, when men follow this blind and powerful instinct of nature, they always suppose the very images, presented by the senses, to be the external objects, and never entertain any suspicion, that the one are nothing but representations of the other. * * * * But this universal and primary opinion of all men is soon destroyed by the slightest phi¬ losophy, which teaches us, that nothing can ever be present to the mind but an image or perception, and that the senses are only the inlets through which these images are conveyed, without being able to produce any immediate intercourse between the mind and the object. The table which we see seems to diminish as we remove farther from it; but the real table, which exists independent of us, suffers no alteration. It was, therefore, nothing but its image which was present to the mind. These are the obvious dictates of reason.”—(Essay on the Academical Philosophy.) Is not this analogical theory of perception the principle on which the whole of Berkeley’s reasonings against the existence of the material world, and of Hume’s scepticism on the same subject, are founded ? The same analogy still continues to be sanctioned by some English philosophers of no small note. Long after the publi¬ cation of Dr Reid’s Inquiry, Mr Horne Tooke quoted with approbation the following words of J. C. Scaliger : “ Sicut in speculo ea quse videntur non sunt, sed eorum species ; ita quae intelligimus, ea sunt re ipsa extra nos, eorumque species in nobis. Est enim quasi rerum speculum intellectus noster; cui, nisi per sensum represententur res, nihil scit ipse.”—(J. C. Scaliqer, de Causis, L. I., cap. Ixvi.) Dfrmwnw of Parley, Vol. I. p. 35, 2d. Edition. 220 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS, now the German substitute for Idea ; nay, one of the most able works which Germany has pro¬ duced since the commencement of its new phi¬ losophical era, is entitled Nova Theoria Facul- tatis Representativce Humana;. In the same work, the author has prefixed, as a motto to the second book, in which he treats of buantur; ne forte judicio depravati et corrupti, in earn opinionem veniant, non esse rerum dif- 1 See in particular Rousseau Du Contrat Social, Liv. iii. c. vi. 2 Many traces of this misanthropic disposition occur in the historical and even in the dramatic works of Machiavel. It is very justly observed by M. de Sismondi, that “ the pleasantry of his comedies is almost always mingled with gall. His laughter at the human race is but the laughter of contempt.” DISSERTATION FIRST. 235 Notes ferentias morales veras et solidas, sed omnia ex Illustrations, utilitate.-—Sic enim Machiavellio dicere placet, Quod si contigisset Ccesarem hello super alum fuisse, Catilina ipso fuisset odiosior,” &c. &c. After these explicit and repeated declarations of his sentiments on this point, it is hard that Bacon should have been numbered among the apolo¬ gists of Machiavel, by such high authorities as Bayle, and the excellent biographer of Lorenzo de Medicis. It has been objected to me, that in the fore¬ going observations on the design of the Prince, I have taken no notice of the author’s vindication of himself and his writings, in his letter to Zenobius Buondelmontius, annexed to the old English translation of Machiavel, printed at London in 1675 and 1680. In the preface to this translation, we are told, that the letter in question “ had never before been published in any language, but lurked for above eighty years in the private cabinets of his own kindred, or the descendants of his admirers in Florence, till, in the Pontificate of Urban VIII., it was procured by the Jesuits and other busy bodies, and brought to Rome with an intention to divert that wise Pope from his design of making one of Nicholas Machiavel’s name and family cardinal, as (not¬ withstanding all their opposition) he did, not long after. When it was gotten into that city, it wanted not those who had the judgment and curiosity to copy it, and so at length came to en¬ joy that privilege which all rare pieces (even the sharpest libels and pasquins) challenge at that court, which is to be sold to strangers, one of which, being a gentleman of this country, brought it over with him at his return from thence in 1645, and having translated it into English, did communicate it to divers of his friends; and by means of some of them, it hath been my good fortune to be capable of making thee a present of it; and let it serve as an apology for our author and his writings, if thou th'nkest he need any.” As the translation of Machiavel, from which Notes this advertisement is copied, is still in the hands uiu *"adi(r.s of many readers in this country, it may not be improper to mention here, that the letter in question is altogether of English fabrication; and (as far as I can learn) is quite unknown on the Continent. It is reprinted at the end of the second volume of Farneworth’s Translation of Machiavel’s works, 1762, with the following statement prefixed to it.1 “ The following letter having been printed in all the editions of the old translation, it is here given to the reader, though it certainly was not written by Machiavel. It bears date in 1537, and his death is placed by all the best historians in 1530. There are, besides, in it many internal marks, which to the judicious will clearly prove it to be the work of some other writer, vainly endeavouring at the style and manner of our excellent author. The letter is indeed a spirited and judicious defence of Machiavel and his writings; but it is written in a style too inflated, and is utterly void of that elegance and precision which so much distinguish the works of the Florentine secretary.” To the author of this last translation we are farther indebted for a very curious letter of Dr Warburton’s, which renders it probable that the forgery was contrived and carried into execution by the Marquis of Wharton. I shall transcribe the letter in Warburton’s words. “ There is at the end of the English transla¬ tion of Machiavel’s works, printed in folio, 1680, a translation of a pretended letter of Machiavel to Zenobius Buondelmontius, in vindication of himself and his writings. I believe it has been generally understood to be a feigned thing, and has by some been given to Nevil, he who wrote, if I do not mistake, the Plato lledivims. But many years ago, a number of the famous Marquis of Wharton’s papers (the father of the Duke) were put into my hands. Amongst these was the press copy (as appearedby the printer’s marks, where any page of the printed letter began and ended) of this remarkable letter in the Marquis’s hand-writing, as I took it to be, compared with 1 In a book published 1816, this letter is referred to without any expression of doubt as to its authenticity. See Milleb’s Lectures on the Philosophy of Modern History, Dublin, 1816, p. 17- 236 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. Notes other papers of his. The person who intrusted Illustrations me these papers, and who I understood had given them to me, called them back out of my hands. This anecdote I communicated to the late Speaker; and, at his desire, wrote down the substance of what I have told you, in his book of the above edition.—W. Gloucester.”1 From a memoir read before the French Insti¬ tute in July 1814, by M. Daunou,2 it appears that some new light has been lately thrown on the writings and life of Machiavel by the dis¬ covery of some of his unpublished papers. The following particulars cannot fail to be gratifying to many of my readers. « M. Ginguene continue son Histoire de la Lit- terature Italienne. et vient de communiquer a la classe Tun des articles qui vont composer le septieme tome de cette histoire. C’est un tableau de la vie et des ecrits de Nicolas Machiavel. La vie de cet ecrivain celebre est le veritable com- mentaire de ses livres ; et jusqu’ici ce commen- taire etoit reste fort incomplet. Par exemple, on se bornait k dire, que la republique de Florence, dontil etoit le secretaire, Favoit charge de diverses missions politiques a la cour de France, a la cour de Rome, aupres du Due de Valentinois, aupres de FEmpereur, au camp de Pise, &c. &c. M. Ginguene le suit annee par annee dans toutes ses legations, il en fait connditre Fobjet et les principales circonstances. Cette vie de vient ainsi une partie essentielle de Fhistoire de Florence, et tient meme a celle des puissances qui etoient alors en relation avec cette republique. On lit peu dans la collection des CEuvres de Machiavel, ses correspondances politiques, qui neanmoins offrent tous ces details et jettent un grand jour sur son caractere et sur ses intentions. Malheu- reusement, ce jour lui est peu favorable, et ne nous eclaire que trop sur le veritable sens dans lequel doit etre pris son Traite du Prince si diversement juge. L’une des pieces les plus curieuses et les plus decisives est une lettre qu’il ecrivit de la campagne ou il s’etoit retir^ Notes apres la rentree des Medicis a Florence II inustratjons> venoit d’etre destitue de ses emplois; implique dans une conspiration contre ces princes, il avoit ete incarcere, mis a la torture, et juge innocent, soit qu’il le fut en effet, soit que les tourmens n’eussent pu lui arracher Faveu de sa faute. Il trace dans ce lettre le tableau de ses occupations et de ses projets, des travaux et des distractions qui remplissent ses journees. Pour sortir d’une position voisine de la misere, il sent la necessite de rentrer en grace avec les Medicis, et n’en troupe pas de meilleur moyen que de dedier le Traite du Prince qu’il vient d’achever a Julien le Jeune, frere du Leon X., et a qui ce Pape avoit confie le gouvernement de Flo¬ rence. Machiavel croit que son Traite ne peut manquer d’etre agreable et utile a un prince, et surtout a un nouveau prince. Quelque terns apres, il fit en effet homage de ce livre, non a Julien, mais a Laurent II. Cette lettre, qui n’est connue en Italic, que depuis peu d’annees, etoit encore ignoree en France. M. Ginguent Fa traduite: il pense qu’elle ne laisse aucune incertitude sur le but et les intentions de Fau- teur du Traite du Prince.”—Some farther de¬ tails on this subject are to be found in a subse¬ quent memoir by the same author, read before the French Institute in July 1815. Soon after reading the above passage in M. Daunou’s Report, I received nearly the same in¬ formation from the north of Italy. It cannot be so well expressed as in the words of the writer :— “ Pray tell Mr Stewart that there is a very remarkable letter of Machiavel’s lately publish¬ ed, written to a private friend at the very time he was engaged in the composition of the Prince, and not only fixing the date of that work, but explaining in a manner disgraceful to the author, the use he made of it, in putting it into the hands of the Medicis family. The letter is besides full of character, and describes, 1 In a letter from Warburton to the Reverend Mr Birch, there is the following passage :—“ I told you, I think, I had several of old Lord Wharton’s papers. Amongst the rest is a manuscript in his own handwriting, a pretended translation of a manuscript apologetical epistle of Machiavel’s, to his friend Zenobio. It is a wonderful fine thing. There are the nrinter’s marks on the manuscript, which makes me think it is printed. There is a postscript of Lord Wharton’s to it, by which it appears this pretended translation was designed to prefix to an English edition of his works. As I know nothing of the English edition of Machiavel, I wish you would make this out, and let me know.”—(Illustrations of the Literary History of the 18f/i century, intended as a sequel to the Literary Anecdotes by John Nichols. Vol. II. p. 88.) 2 Rapport sur les Travaux de la Classe d'Histoire, &c. 1 Juillet, 1814. DISSERTATION FIRST. 237 N«tes in a very lively manner, the life he was leading illustrations. w^en driven away from Florence. This parti- cular letter may be read at the end of the last volume of Pignotti’s Storia della Toscana; a book published here, but which was in all the London shops before I came away. It is to be found also with several others, which are entertaining and curious, in a new collection published at Florence in 1814, of Machiavel’s public dispatches and familiar letters. By the way, I must likewise tell Mr Stewart that my late reading has suggested a slight criticism upon one expression of his with regard to Ma¬ chiavel’s Prince^ where he calls it one of the “ latest of his publications.” The fact is, that the three great works were none of them pub¬ lished in his lifetime, nor for four years after his death. They appear to have been all writ¬ ten at the same period of his life, during the eight or ten years of leisure that were forced upon him; and I believe it may he made out from the works themselves, that the Prince was composed and finished first of the three, then the Discourses, and last of all the History. This and the first having been written for the Medicis family, the MSS. were in their hands, and they published them; the Discourses were printed by the care of some of his personal friends. If Mr Stewart wishes to have the proof of all this in detail, I can draw it out without any trouble.” The foregoing passage will he read by many with no common interest, when it is known that it formed part of a letter from the late Francis Horner, written a very few weeks be¬ fore his death. Independently of the satisfac¬ tion I feel in preserving a memorial of his kind attention to his friends, at a period when he was himself an object of such anxious solicitude to his country, I was eager to record the opi¬ nion of so perfect and accomplished a judge on a question which, for more than two centuries, has divided the learned world; and which, his profound admiration of Machiavel’s genius, com¬ bined with the most unqualified detestation of Machiavel’s principles, had led him to study with peculiar care. The letter is dated Pisa, December 17. 1816. - The united tribute of respect already paid by Mr Horner’s political friends and his political opponents, to his short but brilliant and spotless Notes career in public life, renders all additional eulo- T„ and . , . . Illustrations, gies on his merits as a statesman, equally feeble and superfluous. Of the extent and variety of his learning, the depth and accuracy of his scientific attainments, the classical (perhaps somewhat severe) purity of his taste, and the truly philosophical cast of his whole mind, none had better opportunities than myself to form a judgment, in the course of a friendship which commenced before he left the University, and which grew till the moment of his death. But on these rare endowments of his understanding, or the still rarer combination of virtues which shed over all his mental gifts a characteristi- cal grace and a moral harmony, this is not the proper place to enlarge. Never certainly was more completely realized the ideal portrait so nobly imagined by the Roman poet: “ A calm devotion to reason and justice, the sanctuary of the heart undefiled, and a breast glowing with inborn honour.” Compositum jus fasque animo, sanctosque recessus Mentis, et incoctum generoso pectus honesto. Note D, p. 27. The charge of plagiarism from Bodin has been urged somewhat indelicately against Montes¬ quieu, by a very respectable writer, the Cheva¬ lier de Filangieri. “ On a cru, et 1’on croit peut-etre encore, que Montesquieu a parle le premier de I’influence du climat. Cette opinion est une erreur. Avant lui, le delicat et inge- nieux Fontenelle s’etoit exerce sur cet objet. Machiavel, en plusieurs endroits de ses ouvrages, parle aussi de cette influence du climat sur le physique et sur le moral des peuples. Chardin, un de ces voyageurs qui savent observer, a fai* beaucoup de reflexions sur I’influence physique et moral des climats. L’Abbe Dubos a soutenu et developpe les pensees de Chardin ; et Bodin, qui peut-etre avoit lu dans Polybe que In climat determine les formes, la couleur, et les moeurs des peuples, en avoit deja fait, cent cinquante ans auparavant, la base de son systeme, dans son livre de la Republique, et dans sa Methode de 1’Histoire. Avant tous ces ecrivains, I’im- mortel Hippocrate avoit traite fort au long cette 238 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. Notes matiere dans son fameux ouvrage de Vair, des ®nd+. mux, et des lieux. L’auteur de 1’Esprit des Lois, sans citer un seul de ces philosopnes, etablit a son tour un systeme; mais il ne fit qu’alterer les principes d’Hippocrate, et donner une plus grande extension aux idees de Dubos, de Chardin, et de Bodin. II voulut faire croire au public qu’il avoit eu le premier quelques idees sur ce sujet; et le public 1’en crut sur sa parole.”—La Science de la Legislation, ouvrage traduit de Vita- lien. Paris, 1786. Tom. I. pp. 225, 226. The enumeration here given of writers whose works are in every body’s hands, might have satisfied Filangieri, that, in giving his sanction to this old theory, Montesquieu had no wish to claim to himself the praise of originality. It is surprising, that, in the foregoing list, the name of Plato should have been omitted, who concludes his fifth book, De Legibus, with remarking, that “ all countries are not equally susceptible of the same sort of discipline; and that a wise legisla¬ tor will pay a due regard to the diversity of na¬ tional character, arising from the influence of climate and of soil.” It is not less surprising, that the name of Charron should have been over¬ looked, whose observations on the moral influ¬ ence of physical causes discover as much ori¬ ginality of thought as those of any of his succes¬ sors.—See De la Sagesse, Livre i. chap, xxxvii. / Note E, p. 29. Innumerable instances of Luther’s credulity and superstition are to be found in a book en¬ titled Martini Lutheri Colloquia Mensalia, fyc. first published, according to Bayle, in 1571. The only copy of it which I have seen, is a trans¬ lation from the German into the English tongue by Captain Henrie Bell. (London 1652.) This work, in which are <£ gathered up the fragments of the divine discourses which Luther held at his table with Philip Melanchthon, and divers other learned men,” bears to have been origi¬ nally collected “ out of his holy mouth” by Dr Anthony Lauterbach, and to have been after¬ wards c< digested into common-places” by Dr Aurifaber. Although not sanctioned with Lu¬ ther’s name, I do not know that the slightest doubts of its details have been suggested, even by such of his followers as have regretted the Notes indiscreet communication to the public, of his illusions unreserved table-talk with his confidential com- panions. The very accurate SeckendorfF has not called in question its authenticity; but on the contrary, gives it his indirect sanction, by remarking, that it was collected with little pru¬ dence, and not less imprudently printed : “ Libro Colloquiorum Mensalium minus quidem caute composite et vulgato.” (Bayle, article Luther, Note L.) It is very often quoted as an autho¬ rity by the candid and judicious Dr Jortin. In confirmation of what I have said of Luther’s credulity, I shall transcribe, in the words of the English translator, the substance of one of Luther’s Divine Discourses, “ concerning the devil and his works.” “ The devil (said Lu¬ ther) can transform himself into the shape of a man or a woman, and so deceiveth people; in¬ somuch that one thinketh he lieth by a right woman, and yet is no such matter; for, as St Paul saith, the devil is strong by the child of unbelief. But inasmuch as children or devils are conceived in such sort, the same are very horrible and fearful examples. Like unto this it is also with what they call the Nix in the wa¬ ter, who draweth people unto him as maids and virgins, of whom he begetteth devils’ children. The devil can also steal children away; as sometimes children within the space of six weeks after their birth are lost, and other children, called supposititii, or changelings, laid in their places. Of the Saxons they were called Kill- crops. “ Eight years since,” said Luther, {C at Des¬ sau, I did see and touch such a changed child, which was twelve years of age; he had his eyes, and all members, like another child; he did no¬ thing but feed, and would eat as much as two clowns were able to eat. I told the Prince of Anhalt, if I were prince of that country, I would venture homicidium thereon, and would throw it into the river Moldaw. I admonished the people dwelling in that place devoutly to pray to God to take away the devil. The same was done ac¬ cordingly, and the second year after the change ¬ ling died. “ In Saxony, near unto Halberstad, was a man that also had a killcrop, who sucked the DISSERTATION FIRST. 239 Notes mother and five other women dry, and besides illustrations, devoured very much. This man was advised that he should, in his pilgrimage at Halberstad, make a promise of the killcrop to the Virgin Marie, and should cause him there to be rocked. This advice the man followed, and carried the changeling thither in a basket. But going over a river, being upon the bridge, another devil that was below in the river, called and said, Killcrop ! killcrop ! Then the child in the bas¬ ket (which never before spoke one word), an¬ swered, Ho, ho. The devil in the water asked further, Whither art thou going ? The child in the basket said, I am going towards Hocklestad to our loving mother, to he rocked. The man being much affrighted thereat, threw the child, with the basket, over the bridge into the water. Whereupon the two devils flew away together, and cried Ho, ho, ha, tumbling themselves over one another, and so vanished.”—(pp. 386, 387.) With respect to Luther’s Theological Disputes with the Devil, see the passages quoted by Bayle, Art. Luther, Note U. Facts of this sort, so recent in their date, and connected with the history of so great a charac¬ ter, are consolatory to those who, amid the fol¬ lies and extravagancies of their contemporaries, are sometimes tempted to despair of the cause of truth, and of the gradual progress of human reason. Note F, p. 38. Ben Jonson is one of the few contemporary writers by whom the transcendant genius of Ba¬ con appears to have been justly appreciated; and the only one I know of, who has transmit¬ ted any idea of his forensic eloquence; a subject on which, from his own professional pursuits, combined with the reflecting and philosophical cast of his mind, Jonson was peculiarly qualified to form a competent judgment. cc There hap¬ pened,” says he, “ in my time, one noble speak¬ er, who was full of gravity in his speaking. No man ever spoke more neatly, more pressly, more Notes weightily, or suffered less emptiness, lest idle- *nd ness in what he uttered. No member of his speech hut consisted of its own graces. His hearers could not cough, or look aside from him, without loss. He commanded where he spoke, and had his judges angry and pleased at his de¬ votion. The fear of every man that heard him was, that he should make an end.” No finer description of the perfection of this art is to be found in any author, ancient or modern. The admiration of Jonson for Bacon (whom he appears to have known intimately1) seems almost to have blinded him to those indelible shades in his fame, to which, even at this dis¬ tance of time, it is impossible to turn the eye without feelings of sorrow and humiliation. Yet it is but candid to conclude, from the post¬ humous praise lavished on him by Jonson and by Sir Kenelm Digby,2 3 that the servility of the courtier, and the laxity of the judge, were, in the relations of private life, redeemed by many estimable and amiable qualities. That man must surely have been marked by some rare fea¬ tures of moral as well as of intellectual great¬ ness, of whom, long after his death, Jonson could write in the following words : “ My conceit of his person was never increas¬ ed toward him by his place or honours; hut I have and do reverence him, for the greatness that was only proper to himself, in that he seemed to me ever, by his works, one of the greatest men, and most worthy of admiration, that had been in many ages. In his adversity, I ever prayed that God would give him strength, for greatness he could not want. Neither could I condole in a word or syllable for him, as know¬ ing no accident could do harm to virtue, but rather help to make it manifest.” In Aubrey’s anecdotes of Bacon,9 there are several particulars not unworthy of the atten¬ tion of his future biographers. One expression of this writer is more peculiarly striking: “ In short, all that were great and good loved and 1 Jonson is said to have translated into Latin great part of the books De Augmentis Scientiarum. Dr Warton states this (I do not know on what authority) as an undoubted fact. Essay on the Genius and Writings of Pope. 8 See his letters to M. de Fermat, printed at the end of Fermat’s Opera Mathematical Tolosae, 1679. 3 Lately published in the extracts from the Bodleian library. 240 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. Notes honoured him.” When it is considered, that Illustrations Aubrey’s knowledge of Bacon was derived chief- ly through the medium of Hobbes, who had lived in habits of the most intimate friendship with both, and whose writings shew that he was far from being an idolatrous admirer of Bacon’s philosophy, it seems impossible for a candid mind, after reading the foregoing short but com- prehensive eulogy, not to feel a strong inclina¬ tion to dwell rather on the fair than on the dark side of the Chancellor’s character, and, before pronouncing an unqualified condemnation, care¬ fully to separate the faults of the age from those of the individual. An affecting allusion of his own, in one of his greatest works, to the errors and misfortunes of his public life, if it does not atone for his faults, may, at least, have some effect in softening the asperity of our censures. It was probably owing in part to his court- disgrace, that so little notice was taken of Ba- Notes con, for some time after his death, by those Eng- iiius^ad.ioni lish writers who availed themselves, without any scruple, of the lights struck out in his works. A very remarkable example of this oc¬ curs in a curious, though now almost forgotten hook (published in 1627), entitled, An Apology or Declaration of the Power and Providence of God in the Government of the World, by George Hakewill, D. D. Archdeacon of Surrey. It is plainly the production of an uncommonly liberal and enlightened mind; well stored with various and choice learning, collected both from ancient and modern authors. Its general aim may he guessed at from the text of Scripture prefixed to it as a motto, “ Say not thou, what is the cause that the former days are better than these, for thou dost not inquire wisely concerning this and from the words of Ovid, so happily applied by Hakewill to the “ common error touching the golden age,” Prisca juvent alios, ego me nunc denique natum Gratulor. That the general design of the hook, as well as many incidental observations contained in it, was borrowed from Bacon, there cannot, I ap¬ prehend, be a doubt; and yet I do not recollect more than one or two references (and these very slight ones) to his writings, through the whole volume. One would naturally have expected, that, in the following passage of the epistle de¬ dicatory, the name of the late unfortunate Chan¬ cellor of England, who had died in the course of the preceding year, might have found a place along with the other great clerks there enume¬ rated : <£ I do not believe that all regions of the world, or all ages in the same region, afford wits always alike; but this I think (neither is it my opinion alone, but of Scaliger, Yives, Bu- dseus, Bodin, and other great clerks), that the wits of these latter ages, being manured by in¬ dustry, directed by precepts, and regulated by method, may be as capable of deep speculations, and produce as masculine and lasting births, as any of the ancienter times have done. But if we conceive them to be giants, and ourselves dwarfs; if we imagine all sciences already to have received their utmost perfection, so as we need not but translate and comment on what DISSERTATION FIRST. 241 Notes they have done, surely there is little hope that Illustrations.we should ever come near them, much less match them. The first step to enable a man to the achieving of great designs, is to be persuad¬ ed that he is able to achieve them ; the next not to be persuaded, that whatsoever hath not yet been done, cannot therefore be done. Not any one man, or nation, or age, but rather mankind is it, which, in latitude of capacity, answers to the universality of things to be known.” In another passage, Hakewill ob¬ serves, that, “ if we will speak properly and punctually, antiquity rather consists in old age, than in the infancy or youth of the world.” I need scarcely add, that some of the foregoing sentences are almost literal transcripts of Bacon’s words. The philosophical fame of Bacon in his own country may be dated from the establishment of the Royal Society of London; by the founders of which, as appears from their colleague, Dr Sprat, he was held in so high estimation, that it was once proposed to prefix to the history of their labours some of Bacon’s writings, as the best comment on the views with which they were undertaken. Sprat himself, and his illus¬ trious friend Cowley, were among the number of Bacon’s earliest eulogists; the latter in an Ode to the Royal Society, too well known to require any notice here; the former in a very splendid passage of his History, from which I shall borrow a few sentences, as a conclusion and ornament to this note. “ For, is it not wonderful, that he who had run through all the degrees of that profession, which usually takes up men’s whole time; who had studied, and practised, and governed the common law; who had always lived in the crowd, and borne the greatest burden of civil business; should yet find leisure enough for these retired studies, to excel all those men, who separate themselves for this very purpose? He was a man of strong, clear, and powerful imaginations; his genius was searching and in¬ imitable ; and of this I need give no other proof than his style itself; which as, for the most part, it describes men’s minds, as well as pic- Notes tures do their bodies, so it did his above all T„ and i„ . Illustrations, men living. 1 he course of it vigorous and ma- jestical; the wit bold and familiar ; the compa¬ risons fetched out of the way, and yet the more easy:1 In all expressing a soul equally skilled in men and nature.” Note G, p. 40. The paradoxical bias of Hobbes’s understand¬ ing is never so conspicuous as when he engages in physical or in mathematical discussions. On such occasions, he expresses himself with even more than his usual confidence and arrogance. Of the Royal Society f the Virtuosi, as he calls them, that meet at Gresham College) he writes thus: “ Conveniant, studia conferant, experi- menta faciant quantum volunt, nisi et principiis utantur meis, nihil proficient.” And elsewhere: “ Ad causas autem propter quas proficere ne paullum quidem potuistis nec poteritis, acce- dunt etiam alia, ut odium Hobbii, quia nimium libere scripserat de academiis veritatem : Nam ex eo tempore irati physici et mathematici veri¬ tatem ab eo venientem non recepturos se palam professi sunt.” In bis English publications, he indulges in a vein of coarse scurrility, of which his own words alone can convey any idea. “ So go your ways,” says he, addressing him¬ self to Dr Wallis and Dr Seth Ward, two of the most eminent mathematicians then in Eng¬ land, “ you uncivil ecclesiastics, inhuman di¬ vines, de-doctors of morality, unasinous col¬ leagues, egregious pair of Issachars, most wretched indices and vindices academiarum; and remember Vespasian’s law, that it is unlawful to give ill language first, but civil and lawful to re¬ turn it.” Note H. p. 42. With respect to the Leviathan, a very curious anecdote is mentioned by Lord Clarendon. “ When I returned,” says he, C{ from Spain by Paris, Mr Hobbes frequently came to me, and the word easy, I presume Sprat here means the native and spontaneous growth of Bacon’s own fancy, in opposi¬ tion to the traditionary similes borrowed by common-place writers from their predecessors. DISS. I. PART II. 2 H 242 preliminary dissertations. Notes told me that liis book, which he would call Le- viathan, was then printing in England, and that he received every week a sheet to correct; ana thought it would he finished within a little more than a month. He added, that he knew when I read the hook I would not like it; and theie- upon mentioned some conclusions; upon which I asked him why he would publish such doctiines; to which, after a discourse between jest and ear¬ nest, he said, ‘ The truth is, I have a mind to go home.'’ ” In another passage, the same writer ex¬ presses himself thus:—“ The review and con¬ clusion of the Leviathan is, in truth, a sly ad¬ dress to Cromwell, that, being out of the king¬ dom, and so being neither conquered nor his subject, he might, by his return, submit to his government, and he bound to obey it. This re- , view and conclusion he made short enough to hope that Cromwell might read it; where he should not only receive the pawn of his new subject’s allegiance, by declaring his own obli¬ gations and obedience; but by publishing such doctrines as, being diligently infused by such a master in the art of government, might secure the people of the kingdom (over whom he had no right to command) to acquiesce and submit to his brutal power.” That there is no exaggeration or misrepresen¬ tation of facts in these passages, with the view of injuring the character of Hobbes, may be confidently presumed from the very honourable testimony which Clarendon bears, in another part of the same work, to his moral as well as intellectual merits. “ Mr Hobbes,” he observes, “ is a man of excellent parts; of great wit; of some reading; and of somewhat more thinking; one who has spent many years in foreign parts and observations; understands the learned as well as modern languages; hath long had the reputation of a great philosopher and mathema¬ tician; and in his age hath had conversation with many worthy and extraordinary men. In a word, he is one of the most ancient acquain¬ tance I have in the world, and of whom I have Notes always had a great esteem, as a man, who, be- i]i„strations< sides his eminent learning and knowledge, hath been always looked upon as a man of probity, and of a life free from scandal.” Note I, p. 58. It is not easy to conceive how Descartes re¬ conciled, to his own satisfaction, his frequent use of the word substance, as applied to the mind, with his favourite doctrine, that the essence of the mind consists in thought. Nothing can he well imagined more unphilosophical than this last doctrine, in whatever terms it is expressed; but to designate by the name of substance, what is also called thought, in the course of the same argument, renders the absurdity still more gla¬ ring than it would otherwise have been. I have alluded, in the text, to the difference between the popular and the scholastic notion of substance. According to the latter, the word substance corresponds to the Greek word ouova, as employed by Aristotle to denote the first of the predicaments; in which technical sense it is said, in the language of the schools, to signify that which supports attributes, or which is sub¬ ject to accidents. At a period when every person liberally educated was accustomed to this bar¬ barous jargon, it might not appear altogether absurd to apply the term substance to the human soul, or even to the Deity. But, in the present times, a writer who so employs it may be as¬ sured, that, to a great majority of his readers, it will be no less puzzling than it was to Crambe, in Martinus Scriblerus, when he first heard it thus defined by his master Cornelius.1 How extraordinary does the following sentence now sound even to a philosophical ear ? and yet it is copied from a work published little more than seventy years ago, by the learned and judicious Gravesande: Substantiae sunt aut cogitantes, aut non cogitantes; cogitantes duas novimus, 1 “ When he was told, a substance was that which was subject to accidents, then soldiers, quoth Cramhe, are the most sub¬ stantial people in the world.” Let me add, that, in the list of philosophical reformers, the authors of Martinus Scriblerus ought not to be overlooked. Their happy ridicule of the scholastic Logic and Metaphysics is universally known ; but few are aware of the acuteness and sagacity displayed in their allusions to some of the most vulnerable passages in Locke’s Essav. In this part of the work it is commonly understood that Arbuthnot had the principal share. DISSERTATION FIRST. 243 Notes Deum et mentem nostram. Duae etiam sub- niustradons. stantise’ (lUOe 11011 cogitant> nobis notSB Slintj spatium et corpus.”—Introd. ad Phil. § 19 The Greek word dxua (derived from the parti¬ ciple of e//w) is not liable to these objections. It obtrudes no sensible image on the fancy; and, in this respect, has a great advantage over the Latin word substantia. The former, in its logical acceptation, is an extension to Matter, of an idea originally derived from Mind. The latter is an extension to Mind of an idea originally derived from Matter. Instead of defining mind to he a thinking sub- stance, it seems much more logically correct to define it a thinking being. Perhaps it would he better still, to avoid, by the use of the pronoun that, any substantive whatever, Ci Mind is that which thinks, wills,” &c. The foregoing remarks afford me an opportu¬ nity of exemplifying what I have elsewhere observed concerning the effects which the scho¬ lastic philosophy has left on the present habits of thinking, even of those who never cultivated that branch of learning. In consequence of the stress laid on the predicaments, men became accustom¬ ed in their youth to imagine, that in order to know the nature of any thing, it was sufficient to know under what predicament or category it ought to be arranged; and that, till this was done, it remained to our faculties a subject mere¬ ly of ignorant wonder. Hence the impotent attempt to comprehend under some common name (such as that of substance) the heterogene¬ ous existences of matter, of mind, and even of empty space ; and hence the endless disputes to which the last of these words has given rise in the Schools. In our own times, Kant and his followers seem to have thought, that they had thrown a new and strong light on the nature of space and also of time, when they introduced the word form (forms of the intellect) as a common term applicable to both. Is not this to revert to the scholastic folly of verbal generalization ? And is it not evident, that of things which are unique (such as matter, mind, space, time) no classifica¬ tion is practicable ? Indeed to speak of classi¬ fying what has nothing in common with any thing else, is a contradiction in terms. It was Notes thus that St Augustine felt, when he said, “ Quid uiu^rnal|ions sit tempus, si nemo quaerat a me, scio; si quis interroget, nescio.” His idea evidently was, that, although he annexed as clear and precise a notion to the word time, as he could do to any ob¬ ject of human thought, he was unable to find any term more general, under which it could be comprehended; and, consequently, unable to give any definition, by which it might be ex¬ plained. Note K, p. 58. “ Les Meditations de Descartes parurent en 1641. C’etoit, de tous ses ouvrages, celui qu’il estimoit le plus. Ce qui characterise sur tout cet ouvrage, c’est qu’il contient sa fameuse de¬ monstration de Dieu par 1’idee, demonstration si repetee depuis, adoptee par les unes, et rejettee par les autres; et qu’il est le premier ou la distinc¬ tion de Vesprit et de la matiere soil parfaitement dheloppee, car avant Descartes on n’avoit encore bien approfondi les preuves philosopbiques de la spiritualite de Tame.”—Eloge de Descartes, par M. Thomas. Note 20. If the remarks in the text be correct, the cha- racteristical merits of Descartes’ Meditations do not consist in the novelty of the proofs contained in them of the spirituality of the soul (on which point Descartes has added little or nothing to what had been advanced by his predecessors), but in the clear and decisive arguments by which they expose the absurdity of attempting to ex¬ plain the mental phenomena, by analogies bor¬ rowed from those of matter. Of this distinction, neither Thomas, nor Turgot, nor D’Alembert, nor Condorcet, seem to have been at all aware. I quote from the last of these writers an ad¬ ditional proof of the confusion of ideas upon this point, still prevalent among the most acute lo¬ gicians. “ Ainsi la spiritualite de Vdme, n’est pas une opinion qui ait besoin de preuves, mais le resultat simple et naturel d’un analyse exacte de nos idees, et de nos facultes.”—(Vie de M. Turgot.) Substitute for spirituality the word immateriality, and the observation becomes equal¬ ly just and important. 244 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. Notes and Illustrations. Note L, p. 59. The following extract from Descartes might be easily mistaken for a passage in the Novum Organon. ce Quoniam infantes nati sumus, et varia de rebus sensibilihus judicia prius tulimus, quam integrum nostrse ratioms usum hahexemusj mul- tis prsejudiciis a veri cognitione avertimur, qui- bus non aliter videmur posse liberari, quam si semel in vita, de iis omnibus studeamus dubitare, in quibus vel minimamincertitudinis suspicionem reperiemus. “ Quin et ilia etiam, de quibus dubitabimus, utile erit habere pro falsis, ut tanto clarius, quid- nam certissimum et cognitu facillimum sit, in- veniamus. “ Itaque ad serio philosophandum, veritatem- que omnium rerum cognoscibilium indagandam, primo omnia prsejudicia sunt deponenda; sive accurate est cavendum, ne ullis ex opinionibus olim a nobis receptis fidem habeamus, nisi prius, iis ad novum examen revocatis, veras esse com- pcriamus.”—Princ. Phil Pars Prima, §§ lii. Ixxv. Notwithstanding these and various other si¬ milar coincidences, it has been asserted with some confidence, that Descartes had never read the works of Bacon. “ Quelques auteurs as- surent que Descartes n’avoit point lu les ouvrages de Bacon ; et il nous dit lui-meme dans une de ses letters, qu’il ne lut que fort tard les prin- cipaux ouvrages de Galilee.”—[Ploge de Des¬ cartes, par Thomas.) Of the veracity of Des¬ cartes I have not the slightest doubt; and there¬ fore I consider this last fact (however extraor¬ dinary) as completely established by his own testimony. But it would require more evidence than the assertions of those nameless writers al- 1 uded to by Thomas, to convince me that he had never looked into an author, so highly extolled as Bacon is, in the letters addressed to himself by his illustrious antagonist, Gassendi. At any rate, if this was actually the case, I cannot sub¬ scribe to the reflection subjoined to the fore¬ going quotation by his eloquent eulogist: “Si cela est, il faut convenir, que la gloire de Des¬ cartes en est bien plus grande.” Note M, p. 65. ^otes r and Illustrations. From the indissoluble union between the no- tions of colour and extension, Dr Berkeley has drawn a curious, and, in my opinion, most il¬ logical argument in favour of his scheme of ideal¬ ism ;—which, as it may throw some additional light on the phenomena in question, I shan trans¬ cribe in his own words. “ Perhaps, upon a strict inquiry, we shall not find, that even those who, from their birth, have grown up in a continued habit of seeing, are still irrevocably prejudiced on the other side, to wit, in thinking what they see to be at a dis¬ tance from them. For, at this time, it seems agreed on all hands, that colours, which are the proper and immediate objects of sight, are not without the mind. But then, it will be said, by sight we have also the ideas of extension, and figure, and motion; all which may well be thought without, and at some distance from the mind, though colour should not. In answer to this, I appeal to any man’s experience, whether the visible extension of any object doth not ap¬ pear as near to him as the colour of that object; nay, whether they do not both seem to be in the same place. Is not the extension we see co¬ loured ; and is it possible for us, so much as in thought, to separate and abstract colour from extension ? Now, where the extension is, there surely is the figure, and there the motion too. I speak of those which are perceived by sight.”1 Among the multitude of arguments advanced by Berkeley, in support of his favourite theory, I do not recollect any that strikes me more with the appearance of a wilful sophism than the foregoing. It is difficult to conceive how so very acute a reasoner should not have perceived that his premises, in this instance, lead to a con¬ clusion directly opposite to what he has drawn from them. Supposing all mankind to have an irresistible conviction of the outness and distance of extension and figure, it is very easy to explain, from the association of ideas, and from our early habits of inattention to the phenomena of con¬ sciousness, how the sensations of colour should appear to the imagination to be transported 1 Essay toward a New Theory of Vision, p. 255. DISSERTATION FIRST. 245 Notes out of the mind. But if, according to Berkeley’s Illustrations, doctrines, the constitution of human nature —leads men to believe that extension and figure, and every other quality of the material universe, exists only within themselves, whence the ideas of external and of internal; of remote or of near ? When Berkeley says, “ I appeal to any man’s experience, whether the visible extension of any object doth not appear as near to him as the colour of that objecthow much more reason¬ able would it have been to have stated the in¬ disputable fact, that the colour of the object ap¬ pears as remote as its extension and figure ? No¬ thing, in my opinion, can afford a more conclu¬ sive proof, that the natural judgment of the mind is against the inference just quoted from Berkeley, than the problem of D’Alembert, which has given occasion to this discussion. Note N, p. 68. It is observed by Dr Reid, that “ the system which is now generally*received with regard to the mind and its operations, derives not only its spirit from Descartes, but its fundamental prin¬ ciples; and that, after all the improvements made by Malebranche, Locke, Berkeley, and Hume, it may still be called the Cartesian sys¬ tem.”—Conclusion of the Inquiry into the Human Mind. The part of the Cartesian system here alluded to is the hypothesis, that the communication be¬ tween the mind and external objeets is carried on by means of ideas or images;—not, indeed, transmitted from without (as the Aristotelians supposed) through the channel of the senses, but nevertheless bearing a relation to the quali¬ ties perceived, analogous to that of an impres¬ sion on wax to the seal by which it was stamp¬ ed. In this last assumption, Aristotle and Des¬ cartes agreed perfectly; and the chief differ¬ ence between them was, that Descartes palliat¬ ed, or rather kept out of view, the more obvious absurdities of the old theory, by rejecting the unintelligible supposition of intentional species, and by substituting, instead of the word image, the more indefinite and ambiguous word idea. But there was another and very important step made by Descartes, in restricting the ideal Theory to the primary qualities of matter; its Notes secondary qualities (of colour, sound, smell, lllu^atinls. taste, heat, and cold) having, according to him, no more resemblance to the sensations by means of which they are perceived, than arbitrary sounds have to the things they denote, or the edge of a sword to the pain it may occasion. (Princ. Pars iv. §§ 197, 198.) To this doc¬ trine he frequently recurs in other parts of his works. In these modifications of the Aristotelian Theory of Perception, Locke acquiesced entire¬ ly ; explicitly asserting, that “ the ideas of pri¬ mary qualities are resemblances of them, but that the ideas of secondary qualities have no re¬ semblance to them at all.” —Essay, B. ii. c. viii. § 15. When pressed by Gassendi to explain how images of extension and figure can exist in an unextended mind, Descartes expresses himself thus: 11 Quseris quomodo existimem in me sub- jecto inextenso recipi posse speciem ideamve corporis quod extensum est. Respondeo nullum speciem corpoream in mente recipi, sed puram intellectionem tarn rei corporeae quam incorpo- rese fieri absque ulla specie corporese; ad ima- ginationem vero, quae non nisi de rebus corpo- reis esse potest, opus quidem esse specie quae sit verum corpus, et ad quam mens se applied sed non quae in mente recipiatur.” Besponsio de Us quee in sextam Meditationem objecta sunh § 4. In this reply it is manifestly assumed as an indisputable principle, that the immediate ob¬ jects of our thoughts, when we imagine or con¬ ceive the primary qualities of extension and figure, are ideas or species of these qualities; and, of consequence, are themselves extended and figured. Had it only occurred to him to apply (mutatis mutandis) to the perception of primary qualities, his own account of the per¬ ception of secondary qualities (that it is obtain¬ ed, to wit, by the media of sensations more ana¬ logous to arbitrary signs, than to stamps or pictures), he might have eluded the difficulty started by Gassendi, without being reduced to the disagreeable necessity of supposing his ideas or images to exist in the brain, and not in the mind. The language of Mr Locke, it is oh- 246 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. Notes servable, sometimes implies the one of these illustrations, hypotheses, and sometimes the other. It was plainly with the view of escaping from the dilemma proposed by Gassendi to Descartes, that Newton and Clarke were led to adopt a mode of speaking concerning perception, ap¬ proaching very nearly to the language of Des¬ cartes. “ Is not,” says Newton, “ the senso- rium of animals the place where the sentient substance is present; and to which the sensible species of things are brought, through the nerves and brain, that there they may be perceived by the mind present in that place ?” And still more confidently Dr Clarke: “ Without being pre¬ sent to the images of the things perceived, the soul could not possibly perceive them. A liv¬ ing substance can only there perceive where it is present. Nothing can any more act or be acted upon where it is not present, than it can when it is not.” The distinction between pri¬ mary and secondary qualities was afterwards re¬ jected by Berkeley, in the course of his argu¬ ment against the existence of matter; but he continued to retain the language of Descartes concerning ideas, and to consider them as the immediate, or rather as the only objects of our thoughts, wherever the external senses are con¬ cerned. Mr Hume’s notions and expressions on the subject are very nearly the same. I thought it necessary to enter into these details, in order to show with what limitations the remark quoted from Dr Reid in the be¬ ginning of this note ought to be received. It is certainly true, that the Cartesian system may be said to form the groundwork of Locke’s Theory of Perception, as well as of the scepti¬ cal conclusions deduced from it by Berkeley and Hume; but it is not the less true, that it forms also the groundwork of all that has since been done towards the substitution, in place of his scepticism, of a more solid fabric of meta¬ physical science. Note O, p. 69. After the pains taken by Descartes to ascer¬ tain the seat of the soul, it is surprising to find one of the most learned English divines of the seventeenth century (Dr Henry More) accusing him as an abettor of the dangerous heresy of nullibism. Of this heresy Dr More represents Descartes as the chief author; and, at the same time, speaks of it as so completely extravagant, that he is at a loss whether to treat it as the se¬ rious opinion of the philosopher, or as the jest of a buffoon. “ The chief author and leader of the Nullibists,” he tells us, “ seems to have been that pleasant wit, Renatus Descartes, who, by his jocular metaphysical meditations, has luxated and distorted the rational faculties of some otherwise sober and quick-witted persons/’ To those who are at all acquainted with the phi¬ losophy of Descartes, it is unnecessary to ob¬ serve, that, so far from being a Nullibist, he valued himself not a little on having fixed the precise uhi of the soul, with a degree of accu¬ racy unthought of by any of his predecessors. As he held, however, that the soul was unextend¬ ed, and as More happened to conceive that no¬ thing which was unextended could have any re¬ ference to place, he seems to have thought him¬ self entitled to impute to Descartes, in direct opposition to his own words, the latter of these opinions as well as the former. “ The true no¬ tion of a spirit,” according to More, “ is that of an extended penetrable substance, logically and intellectually divisible, but not physically discernible into parts.” Whoever has the curiosity to look into the works of this once admired, and, in truth, very able logician, will easily discover that his alarm at the philosophy of Descartes was really occa¬ sioned, not by the scheme of nullibism, but by the Cartesian doctrine of the non-extension of mind, which More thought inconsistent with a fundamental article in his own creed—the ex¬ istence of witches and apparitions. To hint at any doubt about either, or even to hold any opinion that seemed to weaken their credibility, appeared to this excellent person quite a suffi¬ cient proof of complete atheism. The observations of More on “ the true no¬ tion of a spirit” (extracted from his Enchiridion Ethicum) were afterwards republished in Glan- ville’s book upon witchcraft;—a work (as I be¬ fore mentioned) proceeding from the same pen Notes and Illustrations. DISSERTATION FIRST. 247 Kotes and Fllustrations. with the Scepsis Scientifica, one of the most acute and original productions of which English philosophy had then to boast. If some of the foregoing particulars should, at first sight, appear unworthy of attention in a historical sketch of the progress of science, I must beg leave to remind my readers, that they belong to a history of still higher importance and dignity—that of the progress of Reason, and of the Human Mind. Note P, p. 70. and fancy, as well as of his classical taste. One Notes of the most remarkable is a letter addressed to nius^lions. Balzac, in which he gives his reasons for prefer- ring Holland to all other countries, not only as a tranquil, but as an agreeable residence for a philosopher; and enters into some very enga¬ ging details concerning his own petty habits. The praise bestowed on this letter by Thomas is by no means extravagant, when he compares it to the best of Balzac’s. “ Je ne s9ais s’il y a rien dans tout Balzac ou il y ait autant d’esprit et d’agrement.” For an interesting sketch of the chief events in the life of Descartes, see the Notes annexed to his Eloge by Thomas; where also is to be found a very pleasing and lively portrait of his moral qualities. As for the distinguishing me¬ rits of the Cartesian philosophy, and more par¬ ticularly of the Cartesian metaphysics, it was a subject peculiarly ill adapted to the pen of this amiable and eloquent, but verbose and decla¬ matory academician. I am doubtful, too, if Thomas has not gone too far, in the following passage, on a subject of which he was much more competent to judge than of some others which he has ventured to discuss. When thirsty, to a stream she did repair, And saw herself transform’d, she wist not how : At first she startles, then she stands amaz’d ; At last with terror she from hence doth fly, And loathes the wat’ry glass wherein she gaz’d, And shuns it still, although for thirst she die. I’or even at first reflection she espies Such strange chimeras, and such monsters there; Such toys, such antics, and such vanities, As she retires and shrinks for shame and fear. I have quoted these verses, chiefly because I think it not improbable that they may have suggested to Gray the following very happy allusion in his fine Fragment De Principiis Co- gitandi: Qualis Hamadryadum quondam si forte sororum Una, novos peregrans saltus, et devia rura (Atque illam in viridi suadet procumbere ripa Fontis pura quies, et opaci frigoris umbra) ; Dum prona in latices speculi de margine pendet, Mirata est subitam venienti occurrere Nympham Mox eosdem, quos ipsa, artus, eadem ora gerentem Una inferre gradus, una succedere sylvie Aspicit alludens; seseque agnoscit in undis : Sic sensu interno rerum simulacra suarum Mens ciet, et proprios observat conscia vultus. Note Z, p. 122. The chief attacks made in England on Locke’s Essay, during his own lifetime, were by Edward Stillingfleet, Bishop of Worcester; John Nor¬ ris, 1 Rector of Bemerton; Henry Lee, B. D. ; Of this person, who was a most ingenious and original thinker. I shall have occasion afterwards to speak. PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. Notes and the Reverend Mr Lowde (author of a JDis- Illustrations.course Gonceming the Nature of Man). Of these four writers, the first is the only one whose ob¬ jections to Locke are now at all remembered in the learned world; and for this distinction, Stil- lingfleet is solely indebted (I speak of him here merely as a metaphysician, for in some other departments of study, his merits are universally admitted) to the particular notice which Locke has condescended to take of him, in the Notes incorporated with the later editions of his Essay. The only circumstance which renders these Notes worthy of preservation, is the record they furnish of Locke’s forbearance and courtesy, in managing a controversy carried on, upon the other side, with so much captiousness and aspe¬ rity. An Irish bishop, in a letter on this sub¬ ject to Mr Molyneux, writes thus: “ I read Mr Locke’s letter to the Bishop of Worcester with great satisfaction, and am wholly of your opi¬ nion, that he has fairly laid the great bishop on his back, but it is with so much gentleness, as if he were afraid not only of hurting him, hut even of spoiling or tumbling his clothes.” The work of Lee is entitled “ Anti-scepticism, or Notes upon each chapter of Mr Locke’s Es¬ say concerning Human Understanding, with an explanation of all the particulars of which he treats, and in the same order. By Henry Lee, B. D. formerly Fellow of Emanuel College in Cambridge, now Rector of Tichmarsh in North¬ amptonshire.”—London, 1702, in folio. The strictures of this author, which are often acute and sometimes just, are marked through¬ out with a fairness and candour rarely to be met with in controversial writers. It will appear remarkable to modern critics that he lays parti¬ cular stress upon the charms of Locke’s style, among the other excellencies which had conspir¬ ed to recommend his work to public favour. es The celebrated author of the Essay on Hu¬ man Understanding has all the advantages desir¬ able to recommend it to the inquisitive genius of this age ; an avowed pretence to new methods of discovering truth and improving learning; an unusual coherence in the several parts of his scheme; a singular clearness in his reasonings , Notes and above all, a natural elegancy of style; an jiiusat"^tions unaffected beauty in his expressions; a j ust pro- portion and tuneable cadence in all his periods.” —(See the Epistle Dedicatory.) Note A A, p. 125. For the information of some of my readers, it may be proper to observe, that the word influx came to be employed to denote the action of body and soul on each other, in consequence of a pre¬ vailing theory which supposed that this action was carried on by something intermediate (whe¬ ther material or immaterial was not positively decided) flowing from the one substance to the other. It is in this sense that the word is un¬ derstood by Leibnitz, when he states as an in¬ surmountable objection to the theory of influx, that “ it is impossible to conceive either mate¬ rial particles or immaterial qualities to pass from body to mind, or from mind to body.” Instead of the term influx, that of influence came gradually to be substituted by our English writers; but the two words were originally synonymous, and were used indiscriminately as late as the time of Sir Matthew Hale.—(See his Primitive Origination of Mankind.) In Johnson’s Dictionary, the primitive and radical meaning assigned to the word influence (which he considers as of French extraction) is “ the power of the celestial aspects operating upon terrestrial bodies and affairsand in the Encyclopaedia of Chambers, it is defined to be “ a quality supposed to flow from the bodies of the stars, either with their heat or light, to which astrologers vainly attribute all the events which happen on the earth.” To this astrolo¬ gical use of the word Milton had plainly a re¬ ference in that fine expression of his L’ Allegro, “ Store of ladies whose bright eyes “ Rain influence.1"1 It is a circumstance worthy of notice, that a word thus originating in the dreams of astro- r The explanation of the word influence, given in the Dictionary of the French Academy, accords perfectly with the tenor of the above remarks. “ Yertu qui, suivant les Astrologues, decoule des Astres sur les corps sublunaires.” DISSERTATION FIRST. 255 Notes logers and schoolmen, should now, in our lan- iins^adti0tls. guage, be appropriated almost exclusively to politics. “ Thus,” says Blackstone, <£ are the electors of one branch of the legislature secured from any undue influence from either of the other two, and from all external violence and com¬ pulsion ; but the greatest danger is that in which themselves co-operate by the infamous practice of bribery and corruption.” And again, <£ The crown has gradually and imperceptibly gained almost as much in influence as it has lost in pre¬ rogative.” In all these cases, there will be found at bot¬ tom one common idea, the existence of some se¬ cret and mysterious connection between two things, of which connection it is conceived to be impossible or unwise to trace what Bacon calls the latens processus. Note BB, p. 126. After these quotations from Locke, added to those which I have already produced from the same work, the reader may judge of the injustice done to him by Leibnitz, in the first sentence of his correspondence with Clarke. ££ II semble que la religion naturelle meme s’affoiblit extremement. Plusieurs font les ames corporelles; d’autres font Dieu lui-meme cor- porel. ££ M. Locke et ses sectateurs, doutent au moins, si les ames ne sont materielles, et naturellement perissables.” Dr Clarke, in his reply to this charge, admits that ££ some parts of Locke’s writings may justly be suspected as intimating his doubts whether the soul be immaterial or no; but herein (he adds) he has been followed only by some Materialists, enemies to the mathematical principles of philo¬ sophy, and Who approve little or nothing in Mr Locke’s writings, but his errors.” To those who have studied with care the whole writings of Locke, the errors here alluded to will appear in a very venial light when compared with the general spirit of his philosophy. Nor can I forbear to remark farther on this occasion, that supposing Locke’s doubts concerning the immateriality of the soul to have been as real as Clarke seems to have suspected, this very cir¬ cumstance would only reflect the greater lustre Notes on the soundness of his logical views concerning' and n ® Illustrations the proper method ot studying the mind;—in the prosecution of which study, he has adhered much more systematically than either Descartes or Leibnitz to the exercise of reflection, as the sole medium for ascertaining the internal phe¬ nomena; describing, at the same time, these phenomena in the simplest and most rigorous terms which our language affords, and avoiding, in a far greater degree than any of his prede¬ cessors, any attempt to explain them by analogies borrowed from the perceptions of the external senses. I before observed, that Leibnitz greatly under¬ rated Locke as a metaphysician. It is with re¬ gret I have now to mention, that Locke has by no means done justice to the splendid talents and matchless erudition of Leibnitz. In a letter to his friend Mr Molyneux, dated in 1697, he expresses himself thus : ££ I see you and I agree pretty well concerning Mr Leibnitz; and this sort of fiddling makes me hardly avoid thinking that he is not that very great man as has been talked of him.” And in another letter, written in the same year to the same correspondent, after referring to one of Leibnitz’s Memoirs in the Acta Eruditorum (De Primae Philosophise Emen- datione), he adds, ££ From whence I only draw this inference, that even great parts will not master any subject without great thinking, and that even the largest minds have but narrow swallows.” Let me add, that in my quotations from Eng¬ lish writers, I adhere scrupulously to their own phraseology, in order to bring under the eye of my readers, specimens of English composition at different periods of our history. I must re¬ quest their attention to this circumstance, as some expressions in the former part of this Dis¬ sertation, which have been censured as Scot¬ ticisms, occur in extracts from authors who, in all probability, never visited this side of the Tweed. Note CC, p. 131. After studying, with all possible diligence, what Leibnitz has said of his monads in different parts of his works, I find myself quite incom- 256 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. Notes petent to annex any precise idea to the word as an<1. he has employed it. I shall, therefore, aim at nothing more in this note, but to collect, into as small a compass as I can, some of his most intelligible attempts to explain its meaning. ££ A substance is a thing capable of action. It is simple or compounded. A simple substance is that which has no parts. A compound sub¬ stance is an aggregate of simple substances or of monads. ££ Compounded substances, or bodies, are mul¬ titudes. Simple substances, lives, souls, spirits, are units.1 Such simple substances must exist everywhere; for without simple substances there could he no compounded ones. All nature therefore is full of life.”—(Tom. II. p. 32.) ££ Monads, having no parts, are neither ex¬ tended, figured, nor divisible. They are the real atoms of nature, or, in other words, the elements of things.”—(Tom. II. p. 20.) (It must not, however, he imagined, that the monads of Leibnitz have any resemblance to what are commonly called atoms by philoso¬ phers. On the contrary, he says expressly, that ££ monads are not atoms of matter, but atoms of substances ;—real units, which are the first principles in the composition of things, and the last elements in the analysis of substances;—of which principles or elements, what we call bo¬ dies are only the phenomena.',,)—(Tom. II. pp. 53. 325.) In another passage we are told, that ££ a mo¬ nad is not a material but & formal atom, it being impossible for a thing to he at once material, and possessed of a real unity and indivisibility. It is necessary, therefore,” says Leibnitz, ££ to revive the obsolete doctrines of substantial forms (the essence of which consists in force), separat¬ ing it, however, from the various abuses to which it is liable.”—{Ibid. p. 50.) ££ Every monad is a living mirror, represent¬ ing the universe, according to its particular point of view, and subject to as regular laws as the universe itself.” £‘ Every monad, with a particular body, makes a living substance.” ££ The knowledge of every soul (dme) extends Notes to infinity, and to all things; but this know- iiiustrna^ons ledge is confused. As a person walking on the margin of the sea, and listening to its roar, hears the noise of each individual wave of which the whole noise is made up, but without being able to distinguish one sound from ano¬ ther, in like manner, our confused perceptions are the result of the impressions made upon us by the whole universe. The case (he adds) is the same with each monad.,, ££ As for the reasonable soul or mind {Vesprit), there is something in it more than in the monads, or even than in those souls which are simple. It is not only a mirror of the universe of created things, but an image of the Deity. Such minds are capable of reflected acts, and of conceiving what is meant by the words I, substance, monad, soul, mind; in a word, of conceiving things and truths unconnected with matter; and it is this which renders us capable of science and of de¬ monstrative reasoning. ££ What becomes of these souls, or forms, on the death of the animal ? There is no alterna¬ tive (replies Leibnitz) hut to conclude, that not only the soul is preserved, but that the animal also with its organical machine continues to exist, although the destruction of its grosser parts has reduced it to a smallness as invisible to our eyes as it was before the moment of conception. Thus neither animals nor souls perish at death; nor is there such a thing as death* if that word he understood with rigorous and metaphysical accuracy. The soul never quits completely the body with which it is united, nor does it pass from one body into another with which it had no connection before; a metamorphosis takes place, but there is no metempsychosis.—(Tom. II. pp. 51, 52.) On this part of the Leibnitzian system, D’Alembert remarks, that it proves nothing more than that the author had perceived better than any of his predecessors, the impossibility of forming a distinct idea of the nature of matter ; a subject, however (D’Alembert adds), on which the theory of the monads does not seem calcu- 1 “ Les substances simples, les vies, les ames, les esprits, sent des unitds.' DISSERTATION FIRST. 257 Notes lated to throw much light. I would rather say Illustrations, (without altogether denying the justness of D’Alembert’s criticism), that this theory took its rise from the author’s vain desire to explain the nature of forces; in consequence of which he suffers himself perpetually to be led astray from those sensible effects which are exclusively the proper objects of physics, into conjectures con¬ cerning their efficient causes, which are altoge¬ ther placed beyond tbe reach of our research. Note D D, p. 134. The metaphysical argument advanced by the Leibnitzians in proof of tbe law of continuity has never appeared to me to be satisfactory. “ If a body at rest (it has been said) begins, per saltum, to move with any finite velocity, then this body must be at the same indivisible instant in two different states, that of rest and of motion, which is impossible.” 1 As this reasoning, though it relates to a phy¬ sical fact, is itself wholly of a metaphysical na¬ ture ; and as the inference deduced from it has been generalised into a law, supposed to extend to all the various branches of human knowledge, it is not altogether foreign to our present sub¬ ject briefly to consider how far it is demonstra¬ tively conclusive, in this simplest of all its pos¬ sible applications. On the above argument, then, I would re¬ mark, 1. That the ideas both of rest and of mo¬ tion, as well as the more general idea conveyed by the word state, all of them necessarily involve the idea of time or duration ; and, consequently, a body cannot be said to be in a state either of rest or of motion, at an indivisible instant. Whe¬ ther the body be supposed (as in the case of mo¬ tion) to change its place from one instant to an¬ other ; or to continue (as in that of rest) for an instant in the same place, the idea of some finite Notes portion of time will, on the slightest reflection, i]iustrations. be found to enter as an essential element into our conception of the physical fact. 2. Although it certainly would imply a con¬ tradiction to suppose a body to be in two differ¬ ent states at the same instant, there does not appear to be any inconsistency in asserting that an indivisible instant may form the limit between a state of rest and a state of motion. Suppose one half of this page to be painted white, and the other black, it might, I apprehend, be said with the most rigorous propriety? that the transition from the one colour to the other was made per saltum ; nor do I think it would be regarded as a valid objection to this phraseology, to repre¬ sent it as one of its implied consequences, that the mathematical line which forms their common limit, must at once be both black and white. It seems to me quite impossible to elude the force of this reasoning, without having recourse to the existence of something intermediate be¬ tween rest and motion, which does not partake of the nature of either. Is it conceivable that a body can exist in any state which does not fall under one or other of the two predicaments, rest or motion ? If this question should be answered in the negative, will it not follow that the transition from one of these states to the other must, of necessity, be made per saltum, and must consequently vio¬ late the supposed law of continuity ? Indeed, if such a law existed, how could a body at rest begin to move, or a body in motion come to a state of rest ? But farther, when it is said that “ it is im¬ possible for a body to have its state changed from motion to rest, or from rest to motion, without passing through all the intermediate de¬ grees of velocity,” what are we to understand by 1 “ Si toto tempore,” says Father Boscovich, speaking of the Law of Continuity in the Collision of Bodies, “ ante con- tactum subsequentis corporis superficies antecedens habuit 12 gradus velocitatis, et sequenti 9, saltu facto momentaneo ipso initio contactus; in ipso momento ea tempora dirimente debuissent habere et 12 et 9 simul, quod est absurdum. Duas enim velocitates simul habere corpus non potest.”—Theoria Phil. Nat. &c. Boscovich, however, it is to be observed, admits the existence of the Law of Continuity in the phenomena of Motion alone (§ 143), and rejects it altogether in things co-existent with each other (§ 142). In other cases, he says, Nature does not observe the Law of Continuity with mathematical accuracy, but only affects it; by which expression he seems to mean, that, where she is guilty of a saltus, she aims at making it as moderate as possible. The expression is certainly deficient in metaphysical precision; but it is not unworthy of attention, inasmuch as it affords a proof, that Boscovich did not (with the Leibnitzians) conceive Nature, or the Author of Nature, as obeying an irresistihle necessity in observing or not observing the Law of Continuity. D1SS. I. PART II. 2 K. 258 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. Notes the intermediate degrees of velocity between rest and and. motion ? Is not every velocity, how small soever, a finite velocity; and does it not diner as essen¬ tially trom a state of rest, as the velocity of light ? It is observed by Mr Playfair (Dissertation on the Progress of Mathematical and Physical Science, Part I. Sect, iii.), that Galileo was the first who maintained the existence of the law of continuity, and who made use of it as a principle in his reasonings on the phenomena of motion. Mr Playfair, however, with his usual discrimi¬ nation and correctness, ranks this among the mechanical discoveries of Galileo. Indeed, it does not appear that it was at all regarded by Galileo (as it avowedly was by Leibnitz) in the light of a metaphysical and necessary law, which could not by any possibility be violated in any of the phenomena of motion. It was probably first suggested to him by the diagram which he employed to demonstrate, or rather to illustrate, the uniformly accelerated motion of falling bo¬ dies ;1 and the numberless and beautiful exem¬ plifications of the same law which occur in pure geometry, sufficiently account for the disposition which so many Mathematicians have shown to extend it to all those branches of physics which admit of a mathematical consideration. My late illustrious friend, who, to his many other great and amiable qualities, added the most perfect fairness and candour in his inquiries after truth, has (in the Second Part of his Disserta¬ tion) expressed himself with considerably great¬ er scepticism concerning the law of continuity, than in his Outlines of Natural Philosophy. In that work he pronounced the metaphysical ar¬ gument, employed by Leibnitz to prove its ne¬ cessity, “ to be conclusive.” (Sect. VI. § 99, b.) In the Second Part of his Dissertation (Sect, ii.), he writes thus on the same subject: “ Leibnitz considered this principle as known a priori, because, if any saltus were to take place, that is, if any change were to happen without Note? the intervention of time, the thing changed must iiiu^rationg be in two different conditions at the same indi- vidual instant, which is obviously impossible. Whether this reasoning be quite satisfactory or no, the conformity of the law to the facts gene¬ rally observed cannot but entitle it to great au¬ thority in judging of the explanations and theo¬ ries of natural phenomena.” The phrase, Law of Continuity, occurs repeat¬ edly in the course of the correspondence be¬ tween Leibnitz and John Bernouilli, and ap¬ pears to have been first used by Leibnitz him¬ self. The following passage contains some in¬ teresting particulars concerning the history of this law : “ Lex Continuitatis, cum usque adeo sit rationi et naturae consentanea, et usum ha- beat tarn late patentem, mirum tamen est earn a nemine (quantum recorder) antea adhibitam fuisse. Mentionem ejus aliquam feceram olim in Novellis Reipublicse Literarise (Juillet, 1687, p. 744), occasione collatiunculse cum Malebranchio, qui ideo meis considerationibus persuasus, suam de legibus motus in Inquisitione Veritatis exposi- tam doctrinam postea mutavit; quod brevi li- bello edito testatus est, in quo ingenue occa- sionem mutationis exponit. Sed tamen paullo pr emptier, quam par erat, fuit in no vis legibus constituendis in eodem libello, antequam mecum communicasset; nec tantum in veritatem, sed etiam in illam ipsam Legem Continuitatis, etsi minus aperte, denuo tamen impegit; quod nolui viro optimo objicere, ne viderer ejus existima- tioni detrahere velle.”—Epist. Leibnit. ad Jo^ Bernouilli, 1697. From one of John Bernouilli’s letters to Leib nitz, it would appear that he had himself a con¬ viction of the truth of this law, before he had any communication with Leibnitz upon the subject. “ Placet tuum criterium pro examinandis re- 1 Descartes seems, from his correspondence with Mersenne, to have been much puzzled with Galileo’s reasonings con¬ cerning the descent of falling bodies ; and in alluding to it, has, on different occasions, expressed himself with an indecision and inconsistency of which few instances occur in his works. (Vide Cartesii Epist. Pars II. Epist. xxxiv. xxxv. xxxvii. xci.) His doubts on this point will appear less surprising, if compared with a passage in the article Mtchanique in D’Alembert s El'tmens de Philosophie. “ Tous les philosophes paroissent convenir, que la vitesse avec laquelle les corps qui tombent com- mencent a se mouvoirest absolument nulle,” &c. &c—(See his Melanges, Tom. IV. p. 219, 2.20.) DISSERTATION FIRST. 259 Notes and Illustrations. gulis motuum, quod legem continuitatis vocas; est enim per se evidens, et velut a natura nobis inditum, quod evanescente insequalitate hypo- thesium, evanescere quoque debeant insequali- tates eventuum. Hinc multoties non satis mi- rari potui, qui fieri potuerit, ut tam incongruas, tam absonas, et tam raanifeste inter se pug- nantes regulas, excepta sola prima, potuerit con- dere Cartesius, vir alias summi ingenii. Mihi videtur vel ab infante falsitatem illarum palpari posse, eo quod ubique saltus ille, naturae adeo inimicus, manifesto nimis elucet.”—Epist. Ber- nouilli ad Leib. 1696. Vide Leibnitzii et Jo. Bernouilli Comm. Epist. 2 vols. 4to. Lausannse et Genevae, 1745.) Note E E, p. 134. Mais il restoit encore la plus grande question, de ce que ces ames ou ces formes deviennent par la mort de Panimal, ou par la destruction de I’mdividu de la substance organise. Et c’est ce qui embarrasse le plus; d’autant qu’il paroit peu raisonnable que les ames restent inutilement dans un chaos de matiere confuse. Cela m’a fait juger enfin qu’il n’y avoit qu’un seul parti raisonnable a prendre; et c’est celui de la conservation non seulement de 1’ame, mais encore de 1’animal meme, et de la ma¬ chine organique; quoique la destruction des parties grossieres 1’ait reduit a une petitesse qui n’echappe pas moins a nos sens que celle ou il etoit avant que de naitre.—(Leib. Op. Tom. II. p. 51.) .... Des personnes fort exactes aux experi¬ ences se sont deja aper^ues de notre terns,1 qu’on peut douter, si jamais un animal tout a fait nouveau est produit, et si les animaux tout en vie ne sont deja en petit avant la conception dans les semences aussi bien que les plantes. Cette doctrine etant posee, il sera raisonnable de juger, que ce qui ne commence pas de vivre ne cesse pas de vivre non plus; et que la mort, comme la generation, n’est que la transforma¬ tion du meme animal qui est tantot augment6, et tantot diminue.—(Ibid. pp. 42, 43.) . . . . Et puisqu’ ainsi il n’y a point de pre- Notes miere naissance ni de generation entierement jii^adon' nouvelle de 1’animal, il s’ensuit qu’il n’y en aura point d’extinction finale, ni de mort entiere prise a la rigueur metaphysique; et que, par conse¬ quent, au lieu de la transmigration des ames, il n’y a qu’une transformation d’un meme animal, selon que les organes sont plies differement, et plus ou moins developpes.—(Ibid. p. 52.) Quant a la Metempsycose, je crois que 1’ordre ne I’admet point; il veut que tout soit expli¬ cable distinctement, et que rien ne se fasse par saut. Mais le passage de Tame d’un corps dans 1’autre seroit un saut etrange et inexplicable. Il se fait toujours dans 1’animal ce qui se fait pre- sentement: C’est que le corps est dans un changement continuel, comme un fleuve, et ce que nous appellons generation ou mort, n’est qu’un changement plus grand et plus prompt qu’a 1’ordinaire, tel que seroit le saut ou la ca- taracte d’line riviere. Mais ces sauts ne sont pas absolus et tels que je desaprouve; comme seroit celui d’un corps qui iroit d’un lieu a un autre sans passer par le milieu. Et de tels sauts ne sont pas seulement defendus dans les mouvemens, mais encore dans tout ordre des choses ou des veri- tes.—The sentences which follow afford a proof of what I have elsewhere remarked, how much the mind of Leibnitz was misled, in the whole of this metaphysical theory, by habits of think¬ ing formed in early life, amidst the hypothetical abstractions of pure geometry; a prejudice (or idol of the mathematical den) to which the most important errors of his philosophy might, with¬ out much difficulty, be traced.—Or comme dans une ligne de geometric il y a certains points distingues, qu’on appelle sommets, points d’in- flexion, points de rebroussement, ou autrement; et comme il y en a des lignes qui en ont une infinite, c’est ainsi qu’il faut concevoir dans la vie d’un animal ou d’une personne les terns d’un changement extraordinaire, qui ne laissent pas d’etre dans la regie generale; de meme que les points distingues dans la courbe se peuvent determiner par sa nature generale ou son equa¬ tion. On peut toujours dire d’un animal c’est 1 The experiments here referred to are the observations of Swammerdam, Malpighi, and Lewenhoeck. 260 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. Notes and Illustrations. tout comme ici, la difference n’est que ou moms.”—(Tom. Y. p. IS.) du plus Note FF, p. 136. The praise which I have bestowed on this Memoir renders it necessary for me to take some notice of a very exceptionable proposition which is laid down in the first paragraph, as a fundamental maxim,—that “ all proper names were at first appellativesa proposition so completely at variance with the commonly re¬ ceived opinions among later philosophers, that it seems an object of some curiosity to inquire, how far it is entitled to plead in its favour the authority of Leibnitz. Since the writings of Condillac and of Smith, it has, so far as I know, been universally acknowledged, that, if there be any one truth in the Theoretical History of Lan¬ guage, which we are entitled to assume as an incontrovertible fact, it is the direct contrary of the above proposition. Indeed, to assert that all proper names were at first appellatives, would appear to be nearly an absurdity of the same kind as to maintain, that classes of objects existed before individual objects had been brought into being. When Leibnitz, however, comes to explain his idea more fully, we find it to be something very different from what his words literally im¬ ply ; and to amount only to the trite and indis¬ putable observation, that, in simple and primi¬ tive languages, all proper names (such as the names of persons, mountains, places of resi¬ dence, &c.) are descriptive or significant of cer¬ tain prominent and characteristical features, distinguishing them from other objects of the same class;—a fact, of which a large proportion of the surnames still in use, all over Europe, as well as the names of mountains, villages, and rivers, when traced to their primitive roots, afford numerous and well known exemplifica¬ tions. Not that the proposition, even when thus ex¬ plained, can be assumed as a general maxim. It holds, indeed, in many cases, as the Celtic and the Saxon languages abundantly testify in our own island; but it is true only under cer¬ tain limitations, and it is perfectly consistent with the doctrine delivered on this subject by No“* the greater part of philologers for the last fifty illustrations, years. In the history of language, nothing is more remarkable, than the aversion of men to coin words out of unmeaning and arbitrary sounds; and their eagerness to avail themselves of the stores already in their possession, in order to give utterance to their thoughts on the new topics which the gradual extension of their ex¬ perience is continually bringing within the circle of their knowledge. Hence metaphors, and other figures of speech; and hence the various changes which words undergo, in the way of amplification, diminution, composition, and the other transformations of elementary terms which fall under the notice of the etymologist. Were it not, indeed, for this strong and universal bias of our nature, the vocabulary of every language would, in process of time, become so extensive and unwieldy, as to render the acquisition of one’s mother tongue a task of immense diffi¬ culty, and the acquisition of a dead or foreign tongue next to impossible. It is needless to observe, how immensely these tasks are facili¬ tated by that etymological system which runs, more or less, through every language; and which everywhere proceeds on certain analogi¬ cal principles, which it is the business of the practical grammarian to reduce to general rules, for the sake of those who wish to speak or to write it with correctness. In attempting thus to trace backwards the steps of the mind towards the commencement of its progress, it is evident, that we must at last arrive at a set of elementary and primitive roots, of which no account can be given, but the arbitrary choice of those who first hap¬ pened to employ them. It is to this first stage in the infancy of language that Mr Smith’s re¬ marks obviously relate; whereas the proposi¬ tion of Leibnitz, which gave occasion to this note, as obviously relates to its subsequent stages, when the language is beginning to as¬ sume somewhat of a regular form, by composi¬ tions and other modifications of the materials previously collected. From these slight hints it may be inferred, l$f, That the proposition of Leibnitz, although DISSERTATION FIRST. 201 Notes it may seem, from the very inaccurate and atld. eauivocal terms in which it is expressed, to Illustrations. U . . 1 . stand in direct opposition to the doctrine or Smith, was really meant by the author to state a fact totally unconnected with the question under Smith’s consideration. 2dly, That even in the sense in which it was understood by the author, it fails entirely, when extended to that first stage in the infancy of language, to which the introductory paragraphs in Mr Smith’s dis¬ course are exclusively confined. Note GG, p. 138. “ Je viens de recevoir une lettre d’un Prince Regnant de I’Empire, ou S. A. me marque avoir vu deux fois ce printems a la derniere foire de Leipsig, et examine avec soin un chien qui parle. Ce chien a prononce distinctement plus de trente mots, repondant meme assez a propos a son maitre : il a aussi prononce tout 1’alpha- bet excepte les lettres m, n, x.”—(Leib. Opera, Tom. V. p. 72.) Thus far tire fact rests upon the authority of the German prince alone. But from a passage in the History of the Academy of Sciences, for the year 1706, it appears that Leibnitz had himself seen and heard the dog. What follows is trans¬ cribed from a report of the Academy upon a letter from Leibnitz to the Abbe de St Pierre, giving the details of this extraordinary occur¬ rence. and is considered hy Cuvier as the ground-work of Buffon’s own system on the same subject. In the connection which I have now pointed out between the Historical, the Philological, and the Geological speculations of Leibnitz, Helvetius might have fancied that he saw a new exemplification of the law of continuity ; but the true light in which it ought to be viewed, is as a faithful picture of a philosophical mind eman¬ cipating itself from the trammels of local and conventional details, and gradually rising from subject to subject, till it embraces in its survey those nobler inquiries which, sooner or later, will be equally interesting to every portion of the human race.1 Note K K, p. 143. Of Locke’s affectionate regard for Collins notwithstanding the contrariety of their opinions on some questions of the highest moment, there exist many proofs in his letters, published by M Des Maizeaux. In one of these, the following passage is remarkable. It is dated from Oates in Essex, 1703, about a year before Locke’s death. “ You complain of a great many defects; and that very complaint is the highest recommenda¬ tion I could desire to make me love and esteem you, and desire your friendship. And if I were now setting out in the world, I should think it my great happiness to have such a companion as you, who had a true relish for truth ; would in earnest seek it with me ; from whom I might receive it undisguised; and to whom I might communicate what I thought true freely. Be¬ lieve it, my good friend, to love truth for truth’s sake, is the principal part of human perfection 1 In the above note, I have said nothing of Leibnitz’s project of a philosophical language, founded on an alphabet of Human Thoughts, as he has nowhere given us any hint of the principles on which he intended to proceed in its formation, although he has frequently alluded to "the practicability of such an invention in terms of extraordinary confidence. (For some remarks on these passages in his works, see Philosophy of the Hitman Mind., Yol. II. pp. 143, ei seq.) In some of Leibnitz’s expressions on this subject, there is a striking resemblance to those of Descartes in one of his letters.—(See the preliminary discourse prefixed to the Abbe Emery’s Pensees de Descartes, p. xiv. et seq.) In the ingenious essay of Michaelis On the Influence of Opinions on Language, and of Language on Opinions (which obtained the prize from the Royal Society of Berlin in 1759, there are some very acute and judicious reflections on the impossibili¬ ty of carrying into effect, with any advantage, such a project as these philosophers had in view. The author’s argument on this point seems to me decisive, in the present state of human knowledge; but who can pretend to fix a limit to the possible attainments of our posterity ! 264 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. Notes in this world, and the seed-plot of all other vir- Illimrations ^ues ’ an^:’ ^ mistake not, you have as much of it as ever I met with in any body. What, then, is there wanting to make you equal to the best; a friend for any one to be proud of ? ’ The whole of Locke’s letters to Col¬ lins are highly interesting and curious; more particularly that which he desired to be deliver¬ ed to him after his own death. From the ge¬ neral tenor of these letters, it may be inferred, that Collins had never let Locke fully into the secret of those pernicious opinions which he was afterwards at so much pains to disseminate. Note L L, p. 144. In addition to the account of Spinoza given in Bayle, some interesting particulars of his his¬ tory may be learnt from a small volume, en¬ titled, La Vie de B. de Spinoza, tiree des ecrits de ce Fameux Philosophe, et du temoignage de plu- sieurs personnes dignes de foi, qui Vont connu par- ticulierement: par Jean Colerus, Ministre de VEglise Lutherienne de la Haye. 1706.1 The book is evidently written by a man altogether unfit to appi’eciate the merits or demerits of Spinoza as an author; but it is not without some value to those who delight in the study of human character, as it supplies some chasms in the narrative of Bayle, and has every appear¬ ance of the most perfect impartiality and can¬ dour. According to this account, Spinoza was a per¬ son of the most quiet and inoffensive manners; of singular temperance and moderation in his pas¬ sions; contented and happy with an income which barely supplied him with the necessaries of life; and of too independent a spirit to accept of any addition to it, either from the favour of princes, or the liberality of his friends. In con¬ formity to the law, and to the customs of his ancestors (which he adhered to, when he thought them not unreasonable, even when under the sentence of excommunication), he resolved to learn some mechanical trade; and fortunately selected that of grinding optical glasses, in which he acquired so much dexterity, that it furnished Notes him with what he conceived to be a sufficient xiiustrat;on8 maintenance. He acquired also enough of the art of designing, to produce good portraits in chalk and china-ink, of some distinguished persons. For the last five years of his life he lodged in the house of a respectable and religious family, who were tenderly attached to him, and from whom his biographer collected various interest¬ ing anecdotes. All of them are very credit¬ able to his private character, and more particu¬ larly show how courteous and amiable he must have been in his intercourse with his inferiors. In a bill presented for payment after his death, he is styled by Abraham Keveling, his barber- surgeon, Benedict Spinoza, of blessed memory; and the same compliment is paid to him by the tradesman who furnished gloves to the mourners at his funeral. These particulars are the more deserving of notice, as they rest on the authority of a very zealous member of the Lutheran communion, and coincide exactly with the account given of Spinoza by the learned and candid Mosheim. “ This man (says he) observed, in his conduct, the rules of wisdom and probity much better than many who profess themselves Christians; nor did he ever endeavour to pervert the senti¬ ments or to corrupt the morals of those with whom he lived; or to inspire, in his discourse, a contempt of religion or virtue.” [Eccles. History, translated by Dr Maclaine, Vol. IV. p. 252.) Among the various circumstances connected with Spinoza’s domestic habits, Colerus men¬ tions one very trifling singularity, which ap¬ pears to me to throw a strong light on his ge¬ neral character, and to furnish some apology for his eccentricities as an author. The ex¬ treme feebleness of his constitution (for he was consumptive from the age of 20) having unfitted him for the enjoyment of convivial pleasures, he spent the greater part of the day in his chamber alone; but when fatigued'with study, he would sometimes join the family party below, 1 The Life of Spinoza by Colerus, with some other curious pieces on the same subject, is reprinted in the complete edi¬ tion of Spinoza’s Works, published at Jena, in 1802. DISSERTATION FIRST. 265 Notes and take a part in their conversation, however . and. insignificant its suhiect might he. One of the Illustrations. » ° amusements with which he was accustomed to unbend his mind, was that of entangling flies in a spider’s web, or of setting spiders a-fight- ing with each other; on which occasions (it is added) he would observe their combats with so much interest, that it was not unusual for him to he seized with immoderate fits of laughter. Does not this slight trait indicate very decidedly a tendency to insanity; a supposition by no means incompatible (as will he readily admitted by all who have paid any attention to the phe¬ nomena of madness) with that logical acumen which is so conspicuous in some of his writ¬ ings ? His irreligious principles he is supposed to have adopted, in the first instance, from his Latin preceptor Vander Ende, a physician and classical scholar of some eminence; hut it is much more probable, that his chief school of atheism was the synagogue of Amsterdam; where, without any breach of charity, a large proportion of the more opulent class of the as¬ sembly may he reasonably presumed to belong to the ancient sect of Sadducees. (This is, I presume, the idea of Heineccius in the followr- ing passage: “ Quamvis Spinoza Cartesii prin- cipia methodo mathematica demon strata dede- rit; Pantheismum tamen ille non ex Cartesio didicit, sed domi habuit, quos sequeretur” In proof of this, he refers to a book entitled Spi- nozismus in Judaismo, by Waechterus.) The blasphemous curses pronounced upon him in the sentence of excommunication were not well calculated to recal him to the faith of his ances¬ tors; and when combined with his early and hereditary prejudices against Christianity, may go far to account for the indiscriminate war which he afterwards waged against priests of all denominations. The ruling passion of Spinoza seems to have been the love of fame. “It is owned (says Bayle) that he had an extreme desire to immor¬ talise his name, and would have sacrificed his life to that glory, though he should have been Notes torn to pieces by the mob.”—(Art. Spinoza.) iiius^jons Note MM, p. 148. In proof of the impossibility of Liberty, Col¬ lins argues thus: “ A second reason to prove man a necessary agent is, because all his actions have a begin¬ ning. For whatever has a beginning must have a cause; and every cause is a necessary cause. “ If anything can have a beginning, which has no cause, then nothing can produce some¬ thing. And if nothing can produce something, then the world might have had a beginning without a cause; which is an absurdity not only charged on atheists, but is a real absurdity in itself.* * * * *Liberty, therefore, or a power to act or not to act, to do this or another thing under the same causes, is an impossibility and atheistical.1 “ And as Liberty stands, and can only be grounded on the absurd principles of Epicurean atheism; so the Epicurean atheists, who were the most popular and most numerous sect of the atheists of antiquity, were the great assertors of liberty; as, on the other side, the Stoics, who were the most popular and numerous sect among the religionaries of antiquity, were the great assertors of fate and necessity.”—(Col¬ lins, p. 54.) As to the above reasoning of Collins, it can¬ not he expected that I should, in the compass of a Note, “ hoult this matter to the bran.” It is sufficient here to remark, that it derives all its plausibility from the unqualified terms in which the maxim (/A^ev uminov) has frequently been stated. “ In the idea of every change (says Dr Price, a zealous advocate for the freedom of the will) is included that of its being an effect.” (Review, fyc. p. 30, 3d edition.) If this maxim he literally admitted without any explanation or restriction, it seems difficult to resist the con¬ clusions of the Necessitarians. The proper statement of Price’s maxim evidently is, that 1 To the same purpose Edwards attempts to show, that “ the scheme of free-will (by affording an exception to that dic¬ tate of common sense which refers every event to a cause) would destroy the proof a posteriori for the being of God.” DISS. I. PART II. 2 L 266 preliminary dissertations. Notes “ in every change we perceive in inanimate mat- ... and. ter, the idea of its being an effect is necessarily involvedand that he himself understood it under this limitation appears clearly from the application he makes of it to the point in dis¬ pute. As to intelligent and active beings, to affirm that they possess the power of self-deter¬ mination, seems to me to he little more than an identical proposition. Upon an accurate analysis of the meaning of words, it will he found that the idea of an efficient cause implies the idea of Mind; and, consequently, that it is absurd to ascribe the volitions of mind to the efficiency of causes foreign to itself. To do so must un¬ avoidably involve us in the inconsistencies of Spinozism; by forcing us to conclude that everything is passive, and nothing active in the universe; and, consequently, that the idea of a First Cause involves an impossibility.—But upon these hints I must not enlarge at present; and shall, therefore, confine myself to what falls more immediately within the scope of this Dis¬ course, Collins’s Historical Statement with re¬ spect to the tenets of the Epicureans and the Stoics. In confirmation of his assertion concerning the former, he refers to the following well known lines of Lucretius: Denique si semper motus connectitur omnis, &c. &c. (Lucret. Lib. 2. v. 251.; On the obscurity of this passage, and the in¬ consistencies involved in it, much might be said; but it is of more importance, on the pre¬ sent occasion, to remark its complete repug¬ nance to the whole strain and spirit of the Epi¬ curean Philosophy. This repugnance did not escape the notice of Cicero, who justly consi¬ ders Epicurus as having contributed more to establish, by this puerile subterfuge, the autho¬ rity of Fatalism, than if he had left the argu¬ ment altogether untouched. “ Nec vero quis- qnam magis con firm are mild videtur non modo fatum, verum etiam necessitatem et vim om¬ nium rerum, sustulisseque motus animi volun¬ taries, quam hie qui aliter obsistere fato fatetur se non potuisse nisi ad has commenticias decli- nationes confugisset.”—(Liber de Fato, cap. 20.) On the noted expression of Lucretius (fatis Notes avolsa voluntas) some acute remarks are made Illus^ldions in a note on the French translation by M. de la Grange. They are not improbably from the pen of the Baron d’Holbach, who is said to have contributed many notes to this translation. Whoever the author was, he was evidently strongly struck with the inconsistency of this particular tenet with the general principles of the Epicurean system. “ On est surpris qu’ Epicure fonde la liberte humaine sur la declinaison des atomes. On de- mande si cette d6clinaison est necessaire, ou si elle est simplement accidentelle. Necessaire, comment la liberte peut elle en etre le resultat ? Accidentelle, par quoi est elle determinee ? Mais on devrait bien plutot etre surpris, qu’il lui soit venu en idee de rendre 1’homme fibre dans un systeme qui suppose un enchainement necessaire de causes et d’effets. C’etoit une recherche curieuse, que la raison qui a pu faire d’Epicure 1’Apdtre de la Liberte.” For the theory which follows on this point, I must refer to the work in question.—(See Traduction Nou- velle de Lucrece, avec des Notes, par M. de la Grange, Vol. I. pp. 218, 219, 220, a Paris, 1768.) But whatever may have been the doctrines of some of the ancient Atheists about man’s free- agency, it will not be denied, that in the History of Modern Philosophy, the schemes of Atheism and of Necessity have been hitherto always con¬ nected together. Not that I would by any means be understood to say, that every Neces¬ sitarian must ipso facto he an Atheist, or even that any presumption is afforded by a man’s at¬ tachment to the former sect, of his having the slightest bias in favour of the latter; hut only that every modern Atheist I have heard of has been a Necessitarian. I cannot help adding, that the most consistent Necessitarians who have yet appeared, have been those who follow¬ ed out their principles till they ended in Spino¬ zism, a doctrine which differs from atheism more in words than in reality. In what Collins says of the Stoics in the above quotation, he plainly proceeds on the supposi¬ tion that all Fatalists are of course Necessita- DISSERTATION FIRST. 267 Notes rians;1 2 and I agree with him in thinking, that Illustrations t^s wou^ ^,e case» ^ they reasoned logically. It is certain, however, that a great proportion of those who have belonged to the first sect have disclaimed all connection with the second. The Stoics themselves furnish one very remarkable instance. I do not know any author by whom the liberty of the will is stated in stronger and more explicit terms, than it is by Epictetus in the very first sentence of the Enchiridion. In¬ deed the Stoics seem, with their usual passion for exaggeration, to have carried their ideas about the freedom of the will to an unphiloso- phical extreme. If the belief of man’s free-agency has thus maintained its ground among professed Fatalists, it need not appear surprising, that it should have withstood the strong arguments against it, which the doctrine of the eternal decrees of God, and even that of the Divine prescience, appear at first sight to furnish. A remarkable instance of this occurs in St Augustine (distinguished in ec¬ clesiastical history by the title of the Doctor of Gracej, who has asserted the liberty of the will in terms as explicit as those in which he has an¬ nounced the theological dogmas with which it is most difficult to reconcile it. Nay, he has gone so far as to acknowledge the essential import¬ ance of this belief, as a motive to virtuous con¬ duct. u Quocirca nullo modo cogimur, aut re- tenta praescientia Dei, tollere voluntatis arbi- trium, aut retento voluntatis arbitrio, Deum, quod nefas est, negare praescium futurorum, sed utrumque amplectimur, utrumque fideliter et veraciter confitemur : illud, ut bene credamus ; hoc ut bene vivamus.,, Descartes has expressed himself on this point nearly to the same purpose with St Augustine. In one passage he asserts, in the most unquali¬ fied terms, that God is the cause of all the ac¬ tions which depend on the Free-will of Man ; and yet, that the Will is really free, he consi- Notes ders as a fact perfectly established by the evi-Illus^ati0ns dence of consciousness. {t Sed quemadmodum existentiae divinae cognitio non debet liberi nos- tri arbitrii certitudinem tollere, quia illud in no- bismet ipsis experimur et sentimus; ita neque liberi nostri arbitrii cognitio existentiam Dei apud nos dubiam facere debeb In depen den tia enim ilia quam experimur, atque in nobis per- sentiscimus, et quae actionibus nostris laude vel vituperio dignis efficiendis sufficit, non pugnat cum dependentia alterius generis, secundum quam omnia Deo subjiciuntur.”—(Cartesii Epistoloe, Epist. VIII. IX. Pars i.) These let¬ ters form part of his correspondence with the Princess Elizabeth, daughter of Frederick, King of Bohemia, and Elector Palatine. We are told by Dr Priestley, in the very in¬ teresting Memoirs of his own Life, that he was educated in the strict principles of Calvinism; and yet it would appear, that while he remained a Calvinist, he entertained no doubt of his being a free-agent. “ The doctrine of Necessity,” he also tells us, “ he first learned from Collins ; * and was established in the belief of it by Hart¬ ley’s Observations on Man.”—(Ibid. p. 19.) He farther mentions in another work, that 44 he was not a ready convert to the doctrine of Necessity, and that, like Dr Hartley himself, he gave up his liberty with great reluctance.”—{Preface to the Doctrine of Philosophical Necessity Illustrated, 2d edit. Birmingham, 1782, p. xxvii.) These instances afford a proof, I do not say of the compatibility of man’s free-agency with those schemes with which it seems most at variance, but of this compatibility in the opinion of some of the profoundest thinkers who have turned their attention to the argument. No conclusion, therefore, can be drawn against a man’s belief in his own free-agency, from his embracing other metaphysical or theological tenets, with which 1 Collins states this more strongly in what he says of the Pharisees. “ The Pharisees, who were a religious sect, as¬ cribed all things to fate or to God’s appointment, and it was the first article of their creed, that Fate and God do all, and, consequently, they could not assert a true liberty when they asserted a liberty together with this fatality and necessity of all things.”—(Collins, p. 54.) 2 We are elsewhere informed by Priestley, that “it was in consequence of reading and studying the Inquiry of Collins, he was first convinced of the truth of the doctrine of Necessity, and was enabled to see the fallacy of most of the arguments m favour of Philosophical Liberty: though (he adds) I was much more confirmed in this principle by my acquaintance with Hartley’s Theory of the Human Mind: a work to which I owe much more than I am able to express.”—(Preface, &c. &c. p. xxvii.) 268 preliminary dissertations. Notes it may appear to ourselves impossible to recon- and •! Illustrations. C1^e 1 ' power of the mind to obey without constraint Note* the impulse of the motives which act upon it*”mustrati0ns. This definition, which is obviously the same in substance with that of Hobbes, is thus very just- As for the notion of liberty, for which Collins ly, as well as acutely, animadverted on by Cuvier, professes himself an advocate, it is precisely that “ N’admettant aucune action sans motif, comme of his predecessor Hobbes, who defines a free- dit-il, il n’y a aucun effet sans cause, Bonnet ao-ent to be, “ he that can do if he will, and for- definit la liberte imrale le pouvoir de Tame de bear if he will.”—(Hobbes’s Works, p. 484, fob suivre sans contrainte les motifs dont elleeprouve ed.) The same definition has been adopted by I’impulsion; et resout ainsi les objections que Leibnitz, by Gravesande, by Edwards, by Bon- Ton tire de la provision de Dieu; mais peut- net, and by all our later necessitarians. It can- etre aussi detournent-t-il 1’idee qu’on se fait not" be better expressed than in the words of d’ordinaire de la liberte. Malgre ces opinions Gravesande : “ JFacultas faciendi quod libuerit, que touch ent au Materialisme et au Fatalisme, qucecunque fuerit voluntatis determination—(In- Bonnet fut tres religieux.” (Biographic Uni- trod. ad Philosoph. § 115.) verselle, a Paris, 1812. Art. Bonnet) Dr Priestley ascribes this peculiar notion of From this passage it appears, that the very free-will to Hobbes as its author;1 but it is, in ingenious writer was as completely aware as fact, of much older date even among modern Clarke or Reid, of the unsoundness of the defi- metaphysicians ; coinciding exactly with the nition of nwral liberty given by Hobbes and his doctrine of those scholastic divines who contend- followers; and that the ultimate tendency of the ed for the Liberty of Spontaneity, in opposition doctrine which limits the free-agency of man to to the Liberty of Indifference. It is, however, to (what has been called) the liberty of spontaneity, Hobbes that the partizans of this opinion are in- was the same, though in a more disguised form, debted for the happiest and most popular illus- with that of fatalism. tration of it that has yet been given. “ I con- For a complete exposure of the futility of this ceive,” says he, “ liberty to be rightly defined, definition of liberty, as the word is employed in The absence of all the impediments to action that the controversy about man’s free-agency, I have are not contained in the nature and intrinsical only to refer to Clarke’s remarks on Collins, and quality of the agent. As, for example, the wa- to Dr Reid’s Essays on the Active Powers of Man. ter is said to descend freely, or to have liberty In this last work, the various meanings of this to descend by the channel of the river, because very ambiguous word are explained with great there is no impediment that way: but not across, accuracy and clearness. because the banks are impediments. And, The only two opinions which, in the actual though water cannot ascend, yet men never say, state of metaphysical science, ought to be stated it wants the liberty to ascend, but the faculty or in contrast, are that of Liberty (or free-will) on power, because the impediment is in the nature the one side, and that of Necessity on the other, of the water, and intrinsical. So also we say, As to the Liberty of Spontaneity (which expresses he that is tied wants the liberty to go, because a fact altogether foreign to the point in question), the impediment is not in him, but in his hands; I can conceive no motive for inventing such a whereas we say not so of him who is sick or phrase, but a desire in some writers to veil the lame, because the impediment is in himself.”— scheme of necessity from their readers, undei a (Treatise of Liberty and Necessity.) language less revolting to the sentiments ot According to Bonnet, “ moral liberty is the mankind ; and, in others, an anxiety to banish DISSERTATION FIRST. 269 Notes it as far as possible from their own thoughts, and. bv substituting: instead of the terms in which Illustrations. J ° . . . it is commonly expressed, a circumlocution which seems, on a superficial view, to concede something to the advocates for liberty. If this phrase (the Liberty of Spontaneity) should fall into disuse, the other phrase (the Liberty of Indifference),1 which is commonly stated in opposition to it, would become com¬ pletely useless; nor would there be occasion for qualifying with any epithet, the older, simpler, and much more intelligible word, Free-will. The distinction between physical and moral necessity I conceive to be not less frivolous than those to which the foregoing animadversions relate. Or this point I agree with Diderot, that the word necessity (as it ought to be under¬ stood in this dispute) admits but of one interpre¬ tation. Note N N, p. 148. To the arguments of Collins, against man’s free-agency, some of his successors have added, the inconsistency of this doctrine with the known effects of education (under which phrase they com¬ prehend the moral effects of all the external cir¬ cumstances in which men are involuntarily placed) in forming the characters of individuals. The plausibility of this argument (on which much stress has been laid by Priestley and others) arises entirely from the mixture of truth which it involves; or, to express myself more correctly, from the evidence and importance of ihefact on which it proceeds, when that fact is stated with due limitations. That the influence of education, in this com¬ prehensive sense of the word, was greatly under¬ rated by our ancestors, is now universally ac¬ knowledged ; and it is to Locke’s writings, more than to any other single cause, that the change in public opinion on this head is to be ascribed. On various occasions, he has ex¬ pressed himself very strongly with respect to the extent of this influence ; and has more than once intimated his belief, that the great majori¬ ty of men continue through life what early edu- Notes cation had made them. In making use, how- Illusat"atic ever, of this strong language, his object (as is evident from the opinions which he has avowed in other parts of his works) was only to arrest the attention of his readers to the practical lessons he was anxious to inculcate; and not to state a metaphysical fact which was to be literally and rigorously interpreted in the controversy about liberty and necessity. The only sound and useful moral to be drawn from the spirit of his observations, is the duty of gratitude to Heaven for all the blessings, in respect of education and of external situation, which have fallen to ou< own lot; the impossibility of ascertaining the involuntary misfortunes by which the seeming demerits of others may have been in part occa¬ sioned, and in the same proportion diminished; and the consequent obligation upon ourselves, to think as charitably as possible of their con¬ duct, under the most unfavourable appearances. The truth of all this I conceive to be implied in these words of Scripture, “ To whom much is given, of him much will be required;” and, if possible, still more explicitly and impressively, in the parable of the Talents. Is not the use which has been made by Ne¬ cessitarians of Locke’s Treatise on Education, and other books of a similar tendency, only one instance more of that disposition, so common among metaphysical Sciolists, to appropriate to themselves the conclusions of their wiser and more sober predecessors, under the startling and imposing disguise of universal maxims, ad¬ mitting neither of exception nor restriction ? It is thus that Locke’s judicious and refined re¬ marks on the Association of Ideas have been ex¬ aggerated to such an extreme in the coarse cari¬ catures of Hartley and of Priestley, as to bring, among cautious inquirers, some degree of dis¬ credit on one of the most important doctrines of modern philosophy. Or, to take another case still more in point; it is thus that Locke’s reflections on the effects of education in modify¬ ing the intellectual faculties, and (where skil¬ fully conducted) in supplying their original 1 Both phrases are favourite expressions with Lord Karnes in his discussions on this subject. See in particular the Ap. pendix to his Essay on Liberty and Necessity, in the last edition of his Essays on Morality and Natural Religion. 270 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. Notes defects, have beeti distorted into the puerile Illustrations. Para^ox of Helvetius, that the mental capacities of the whole human race are the same at the moment of hirth. It is sufficient for me here to throw out these hints, which will he found to apply equally to a large proportion of other theories started hy modern metaphysicians. Before I finish this note, I cannot refrain from remarking, with respect to the argument for Necessity drawn from the Divine prescience, that, if it he conclusive, it only affords an addi¬ tional confirmation of what Clarke has said concerning the identity of the creed of the Ne¬ cessitarians with that of the Spinozists. For, if God certainly foresees all the future volitions of his creatures, he must, for the same reason, foresee all his own future volitions; and if this knowledge infers a necessity of volition in the one case, how is it possible to avoid the same inference in the other ? Note OO, p. 149. A similar application of St Paul’s comparison of the potter is to be found both in Hobbes and in Collins. Also, in a note annexed hy Cowley to his ode entitled Destiny; an ode written (as we are informed hy the author) “ upon an ex¬ travagant supposition of two angels playing a game at chess; which, if they did, the specta¬ tors would have reason as much to believe that the pieces moved thpmselves, as we have for thinking the same of mankind, when we see them exercise so many and so different actions. It was of old said by Plautus, Dii nos quasi pilas homines habent, “ We are hut tennis-balls for the gods to play withal,” which they strike away at last, and still call for new ones; and St Paul says, “ We are but the clay in the hand of the potter” For the comparison of the potter, alluded to by these different writers, see the epistle to the Romans, chap. ix. verses 18, 19, 20, 21. Upon these verses the only comment which I have to offer is a remark of the apostle Peter* that “ In the epistles of our beloved brother Paul are some things hard to he understood, which they that are unlearned and unstable wrest unto their own destruction.” The same similitude of the potter makes a con- Notes spicuous figure in the writings of Hobbes, who iiiust"adtiong has availed himself of this, as of many other in- sulated passages of Holy Writ, in support of principles which are now universally allowed to strike at the very root of religion and mora¬ lity. The veneration of Cowley for Hobbes is well known, and is recorded hy himself in the ode which immediately precedes that on Des¬ tiny. It cannot, however, he candidly supposed, that Cowley understood the whole drift of Hobbes’ doctrines. The contrary, indeed, in the present instance, is obvious from the ode before us; for while Cowley supposed the angels to move, like chess-men, the inhabitants of this globe, Hobbes (along with Spinoza) plainly conceived that the angels themselves, and even that Being to which he impiously gave the name of God, were all of them moved, like knights and pawns, by the invisible hand of fate or ne¬ cessity. Were it not for the serious and pensive cast of Cowley’s mind, and his solemn appeal to the authority of the apostle, in support of the doc¬ trine of destiny, one would be tempted to con¬ sider the first stanzas of this ode in the light of a jeu d’esprit, introductory to the very charac- teristical and interesting picture of himself, with which the poem concludes. Note PP, p. 150. “ Tout ce qui est doit etre, par cela meme que cela est. Voila la seule bonne philosophic. Aussi longtemps que nous ne connaitrons pas cet univers, comme on dit dans 1’ecole, a priori, tout est necessite. La liberte est un mot vide de sens, comme vous allez voir dans la lettre de M. Diderot.”—{Lettre de Grimm au Due de Saxe-Gotha.) warbling of birds and the purling of streams; but, upon the finishing of some secret spell, the fantastic scene breaks up, and the disconsolate knight finds himself on a barren heath, or in a solitary desert.” In this passage one is at a loss whether most to admire the author’s depth and refinement of thought, or the singular felicity of fancy dis¬ played in its illustration. The image of the enchanted hero is so unexpected, and, at the same time, so exquisitely appropriate, that it seems itself to have been conj ured up by an enchanter’s wand. Though introduced with the unpretend¬ ing simplicity of a poetical simile, it has the effect of shedding the light of day on one of the darkest corners of metaphysics. Nor is the language in which it is conveyed unworthy of the attention of the critic; abounding through¬ out with those natural and happy graces, which appear artless and easy to all but to those who have attempted to copy them. The praise which I have bestowed on Addison as a commentator on this part of Locke’s Essay will not appear extravagant to those who may take the trouble to compare the conciseness and elegance of the foregoing extracts with the pro¬ lixity and homeliness of the author’s text. (See Locke’s Essay, Book II. chap. viii. §§ 17, 18.) It is sufficient to mention here, that his chief illustration is taken from “ the effects of manna on the stomach and guts.” Note S S, p. 168. For the following note I am indebted to my 1 Another passage, afterwards quoted by Dr Blair, might have satisfied him of the clearness and accuracy of Addison’s ideas on the subject. “ I have here supposed that my reader is acquainted with that great modern discovery, which is, at present, universally acknowledged by all the inquirers into Natural Philosophy; namely, that light and colours, as apprehended by the imagination. are only ideas in the mind, and not qualities that have any existence in matter. As this is a truth which has been proved incontestibly by many modern philosophers, if the English reader would see the notion explained at large, he may find it in the eighth book of Mr Locke’s Essay on Human Understanding." I have already taken notice (Elements of the Philosophy of the Human Mind. Vol. I. Note P.) of the extraordinary precision of the above statement, arising from the clause printed in Italics. By a strange slip of memory I ascribed the merit of this very judicious qualification, not to Addison, but to Dr Akenside, who transcribed it from the Spectator. The last quotation affords me also an opportunity of remarking the correctness of Addison’s information about the his¬ tory of this doctrine, which most English writers have conceived to be an original speculation of Locke?s. From some of Addison’s expressions, it is more than probable, that he had derived his first knowledge of it from Malebranche. * On the supposition made in this sentence, the face of Nature, instead of presenting a “ rough unsightly sketch,” would, it is. evident, become wholly invisible. But I need scarcely say, this does not render Mr Addison’s allusion less pertinent. DISS. I. PART II. 2 M 274 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. Notes learned friend Sir William Hamilton, Professor Illustrations. Universal History in the University of Edin- burgh. « The Clavis Universalis of Arthur Collier, though little known in England, has been trans¬ lated into German. It is published in a work entitled “ Samlung” &c. &c. literally, “ A Col¬ lection of the most distinguished Authors who deny the existence of their own bodies, and of the whole material world,—containing the dialogues of Berkeley, between Hylas and Phi- lonous, and Collier’s Universal Key translated, with Illustrative Observations, and an Appendix, wherein the existence of Body is demonstrated, by John Christopher Eschenhach, Professor of Philosophy in Rostock.” (Rostock, 1756, 8vo.) The remarks are numerous, and show much reading. The Appendix contains, 1. An ex¬ position of the opinion of the Idealists, with its grounds and arguments 2. A proof of the external existence of body. The argument on which he chiefly dwells to show the existence of matter is the same with that of Hr Reid, in so far as he says, “ a direct proof must not here he expected; in regard to the fundamental prin ciples of human nature, this is seldom possible, or rather is absolutely impossible.” He argues at length, that the Idealist has no better proof of the existence of his soul than of the existence of his body; “ when an Idealist says, lama thinking being; of this I am certain from internal conviction ;—I would ask from whence he derives this certainty, and why he excludes from this conviction the possi¬ bility of deception ? He has no other answer than this, I feel it. It is impossible that I can have any representation of self without the consciousness of being a thinking being. In the same manner, Eschenhach argues that the feeling applies to the existence of body, and that the ground of belief is equally strong and conclusive, in respect to the reality of the objective^ as of the subjective, in perception.” Note TT, p. 182. “And yet Diderot, in some of his lucid intervals, seems to have thought and felt very differently.” The following passage (extracted from his Pensees Philosophiques) is pronounced by La Harpe to he not only one of the most eloquent Notes which Diderot has written, but to be one of the illustrations, best comments which is any where to be found on the Cartesian argument for the existence of God. It has certainly great merit in point of reasoning; but I cannot see with what propriety it can be considered as a comment upon the ar¬ gument of Descartes; nor am I sure if, in point of eloquence, it be as well suited to the English as to the French taste. “ Convenez qu’il y auroit de la folie a refuser a vos semblables la faculte de penser. Sans doute, mais que s’ensuit-il de la? 11 s’ensuit, que si 1’univers, que dis-je 1’univers, si I’aile d’un papillon m’offre des traces mille fois plus distinctes d’une intelligence que vous n’avez d’indices que votre semblable a la faculte de penser, il est mille fois plus fou de nier qu’il existe un Dieu, que de nier que votre semblable pense. Or, que cela soit ainsi, c’est a vos lu- mieres, c’est a votre conscience que j’en appelle. Avez-vous jamais remarque dans les raisonne- mens, les actions, et la conduite de quel que homme que ce soit, plus d’intelligence, d’ordre, de sagacite, de consequence, que dans le meca- nisme d’un insecte ? La divinite n’est elle pas aussi clairement empreinte dans I’ceil d’un ciron, que la faculte de penser dans les Merits du grand Newton ? Quoi ! le monde forme prouverait moins d’intelligence, que le monde explique? Quelle assertion! I’intelligence d’un premier etre ne m’est pas mieux demontree par ses ou- vrages, que la faculte de penser dans un philo- sophe par ses ecrits? Songez done que je ne vous objecte que I’aile d’un papillon, quand je pourrais vous ecraser du poids de 1’univers.” This, however, was certainly not the creed which Diderot professed in his more advanced years. The article, on the contrary, which im¬ mediately follows the foregoing quotation, there is every reason to think, expresses his real sen¬ timents on the subject. I transcribe it at length, as it states clearly and explicitly the same argu¬ ment which is indirectly hinted at in a late pub¬ lication by a far more illustrious author. “ J’ouvre les cahiers d’un philosophe eelebre, et je lis : 4 Athees, je vous accorde que le mouve- ment est essentiel a la matiere ; qu’en concluez- vous ? que le monde resulte du jet fortuit d’a- DISSERTATION FIRST. 275 Notes tomes ? J’aimerois autant que vous me dissiez and oue 1’Iliade d’Homere ou la Henriade de Vol- Illustrations. taire est un resultat de jets lortmts de carac- teres ?’ Je me garderai bien de faire ce raisonne- ment a un athee. Cette comparaison lui don- neroit beau jeu. Selon les lois de I’analyse des sorts, me diroit-il, je ne doit etre surpris qu’une chose arrive, lorsqu’elle est possible, et que la difficulte de revenement est compensee par la quantite des jets. II y a tels nombre de coups dans lesquels je gagerois avec avantage d’amener cent mille six a la fois avec cent mille des. Quelle que fut la somme finie de caracteres avec laquelle on me proposeroit d’engendrer fortuitement 1’Iliade, il y a telle somme finie de jets qui me rendroit la proposition avanta- geuse; mon avantage seroit meme infini, si la quantite de jets accordee etoit infinie,” &c. &c. —(Pensees Philosophiques, par Diderot, XXL) My chief reason for considering this as the genuine exposition of Diderot’s own creed is, that he omits no opportunity of suggesting the same train of thinking in his other works. It may be distinctly traced in the following pas¬ sage of his Traite du Beau, the substance of which he has also introduced in the article Beau of the Encyclopedie. “ Le beau n’est pas toujours 1’ouvrage d’une cause intelligente; le mouvement etablit souvent, soit dans un etre considere solitairement, soit entre plusieurs etres compares entr’eux, une multitude prodigieuse de rapports surprenans. Les cabinets d’histoire naturelle en offrent un grand nombre d’exemples. Les rapports sont alors des resultats de combinaisons fortuites, du moins par rapport a nous. La nature imite en se jouant, dans cent occasions, les productions Notes d’art; et Ton pourroit demander, je ne dis pasIlluSjrnadioi|S si ce philosophe qui fut jete par une tempete sur les bords d’une He inconnue, avoit raison de se crier, a la vue de quelque figures de geo¬ metric ; e Courage, mes amis, void des pas d’hommes ;’ mais combien il faudroit remarquer de rapports dans un etre, pour avoir une certi¬ tude complete qu’il est 1’ouvrage d’un artiste1 2 (en quelle occasion, un seul defaut de symme¬ tric prouveroit plus que toute somme donnee de rapports); comment sont entr’eux le temps de faction de la cause fortuite, et les rapports ob¬ serves dans les effets produits ; et si (a 1’excep- tion des oeuvres du Tout-Puissant)* il y a des cas ou le nombre des rapports ne puisse jamais etre compense par celui des jets.” With respect to the passages here extracted from Diderot, it is worthy of observation, that if the atheistical argument from chances be con¬ clusive in its application to that order of things which we behold, it is not less conclusive when applied to every other possible combination of atoms which imagination can conceive, and affords a mathematical proof, that the fables of Grecian mythology, the tales of the genii, and the dreams of the Rosicrusians, may, or rather must, all of them, be somewhere or other rea¬ lized in the infinite extent of the universe: a proposition which, if true, would destroy every argument for or against any given system of opinions founded on the reasonableness or the unreasonableness of the tenets involved in it; and would, of consequence, lead to the subver¬ sion of the whole frame of the human under¬ standing. 3 1 Is not this precisely the sophistical mode of questioning known among Logicians by the name of Sorites or Acervus ? “ Vitiosum sane,” says Cicero, “ et captiosum genus.”—(Acad. Qucest. Lib. IV. xvi.) 2 To those who enter fully into the spirit of the foregoing reasoning, it is unnecessary to observe, that this parenthetical clause is nothing better than an ironical salvo. If the argument proves any thing, it leads to this general conclusion, that the apparent order of the universe affords no evidence whatever of the existence of a designing cause. * The atheistical argument here quoted from Diderot is, at least, as old as the time of Epicurus. Nam certe neque consilio primordia rerum Ordine se quaeque, atque sagaci mente locarunt Nec quos quaeque darent motus pepigere profecto; Sed quia multimodis, multis, mutata, per omne Ex infinito vexantur percita plagis, Omne genus motus, et coetus experiundo, Tandem deveniunt in taleis disposituras, Qualibus haec rebus consistit summa creata—(Ltjcret. Lib. I. 1. 1020.) And still more explicitly in the following lines : Nam cum respicias immensi temporis omne Praeteritum spatium; turn motus materialis Multimadi quam sint; facile hoc adcredere possis, Semina saepe in eodem, ut nunc sunt, ordine posta.—(Ibid. Lib. III. 1. 867.) 276 preliminary dissertations. Notes Mr Hume, in his Natural History of Religion Illustrations. (Sect. XI.), has drawn an inference from the internal evidence of the Heathen Mythology, in favour of the supposition that it may not be al¬ together so fabulous as is commonly supposed. « The whole mythological system is so natural, that in the vast variety of planets and worlds contained in this universe, it seems more than probable, that somewhere or other it is really carried into execution.” The argument of Di¬ derot goes much farther, and leads to an exten¬ sion of Mr Hume’s conclusion to all conceivable systems, whether natural or not. But further, since the human mind, and all the numberless displays of wisdom and of power which it has exhibited, are ultimately to he re¬ ferred to a fortuitous concourse of atoms, why might not the Supreme Being, such as we are commonly taught to regard him, have been Himself (as well as the Gods of Epicurus)J the result of the continued operation of the same blind causes ? or rather, must not such a Being have necessarily resulted from these causes ope¬ rating from all eternity, through the immensity of space ?—a conclusion, by the way, which, ac¬ cording to Diderot’s own principles, would lead us to refer the era of his origin to a period inde¬ finitely more remote than any given point of time which imagination can assign; or, in other words, to a period to which the epithet eternal may with perfect propriety he applied. The amount, therefore, of the whole matter is this, that the atheistical reasoning, as stated by Di¬ derot, leaves the subject of natural, and, I may add, of revealed religion, precisely on the same footing as before, without invalidating, in the very smallest degree, the evidence for any one of the doctrines connected with either; nay more, superadding to this evidence, a mathema¬ tical demonstration of the possible truth of all those articles of belief which it was the ob¬ ject of Diderot to subvert from their founda¬ tion. It might be easily shown, that these prin¬ ciples, if pushed to their legitimate consequences, instead of establishing the just authority of rea¬ son in our constitution, would lead to the most Notes unlimited credulity on all subjects whatever; illustrations, or (what is only another name for the same thing) to that state of mind, which, in the words of Mr Hume, “ does not consider any one pro¬ position as more certain, or even as more pro¬ bable, than another.” The following curious and (in my opinion) instructive anecdote has a sufficient connection with the subject of this note, to justify me in subjoining it to the foregoing observations. I transcribe it from the Notes annexed to the Abbe de Lille’s poem entitled La Conversation. (A Paris, 1812.) “ Dans la societe du Baron d’Holbach, Dide¬ rot proposa un jour de nommer un avocat de Dieu, et on choisit 1’Abbe Galiani. II s’assit et debuta ainsi: “ Un jour a Naples, un homme de la Basili- cate prit devant nous, six des dans un cornet, et paria d’amener rafle de six. Je dis cette chance etoit possible. II I’amena sur le champ une seconde fois; je dis la meme chose. 11 re¬ mit les des dans le cornet trois, quatre, cinq fois, et toujours rafle de six. Sangue di Bacco, m’ecriai-je, les des sontpipes ; et ils 1’etoient. “ Philosophes, quand je considere Fordre toujours renaissant de la nature, ses lois immu- ables, ses revolutions toujours constantes dans une variete infinie; cette chance unique et con- servatrice d’un univers tel que nous le voyons, qui revient sans cesse, malgre cent autres mil¬ lions de chances de perturbation et de destruc¬ tion possibles, je m’eerie: certes la nature est pipee!” The argument here stated strikes me as irre¬ sistible ; nor ought it at all to weaken its effect, that it was spoken by the mouth of the Abbe Galiani. Whatever his own professed principles may have been, this theory of the loaded die appears evidently, from the repeated allusions to it in his familiar correspondence, to have produced a very deep impression on his mind.—(See Corre- spondance inedite de 1’Abbe Galiani, &c. Vol. I. pp. 18, 42, 141, 142, a Paris, 1818.) 1 Cic. de Nat. Dear. Lib. I. XXIV. DISSERTATION FIRST. As the old argument of the atomical atheists is plainly that on which the school of Diderot are still disposed to rest the strength of their cause, I shall make no apology for the length of this note. The sceptical suggestions on the same subject which occur in Mr Hume’s Essay on the Idea of Necessary Connection, and which have given occasion to so much discussion in this country, do not seem to me to have ever pro¬ duced any considerable impression on the French philosophers. Note U U, p. 182. Among flie contemporaries of Diderot, the author of the Spirit of Laws is entitled to parti¬ cular notice, for the respect with which he al¬ ways speaks of natural religion. A remarkable instance of this occurs in a letter to Dr War- burton, occasioned by the publication of his View of Bolingbrokds Philosophy. The letter, it must be owned, savours somewhat of the politi¬ cal religionist; but how fortunate would it have been for France, if, during its late revolutionary governments, such sentiments as those here ex¬ pressed by Montesquieu had been more gene¬ rally prevalent among his countrymen ! “ Celui qui attaque la religion revelee n’attaque que la re¬ ligion re velee; mais celui qui attaque la religion naturelleattaquetouteslesreligionsdumonde.... II n’est pas impossible d’attaquer une religion revelee, parce qu’elle existe par des faits parti- culiers, et que les faits par leur nature peuvent etre une matiere de dispute; mais il n’en est pas de meme de la religion naturelle; elle est tiree de la nature de I’homme, dont on ne pent pas disputer encore. J’ajoute a ceci, quel peut etre le motif d’attaquer la religion revelee en Angleterre ? On l’y a tellement purge de tout prejuge destructeur qu’elle n’y peut faire de mal et qu’elle y peut faire, au contraire, une infinite de biens. Je sais, qu’un homme en Espagne ou en Portugal que 1’on va bruler, ou qui craint d’etre brule, parce qu’il ne croit point de cer¬ tains articles dependans ou non de la religion revelee, a un juste sujet de 1’attaquer, parce qu’il peut avoir quelque esperance de pourvoir a sa defense naturelle: mais il n’en est pas de meme en Angleterre, ou tout homme qui attaque la religion revel^e 1’attaque sans interet, et ou cet homme, quand il reussiroit, quand meme il auroit raison dans le fond, ne feroit que de- truire une infinite de biens pratiques, pour 6tablir une verite purement speculative.”—(For the whole letter, see the 4to edit, of Montes¬ quieu’s Works. Paris, 1788. Tome V. p. 391. Also Warburton’s Works by Hurd, Vol. VII. p. 553. London, 1758.) In the foregoing passage, Montesquieu hints more explicitly than could well have been ex¬ pected from a French magistrate, at a considera¬ tion which ought always to be taken into the account, in judging of the works of his country¬ men, when they touch on the subject of reli¬ gion ; I mean, the corrupted and intolerant spirit of that system of faith which is imme¬ diately before their eyes. The eulogy bestowed on the church of England is particularly deserv¬ ing of notice, and should serve as a caution to Protestant writers against making common cause with the defenders of the church of Rome. With respect to Voltaire, who, amidst all his extravagancies and impieties, is well known to have declared open war against the principles maintained in the Systeme de la Nature, it is re¬ marked by Madame de Stael, that two different epochs may be distinguished in his literary life ; the one, while his mind was warm from the philosophical lessons he had imbibed in Eng¬ land ; the other, after it became infected with those extravagant principles which, soon after his death, brought a temporary reproach on the name of Philosophy. As the observation is ex¬ tended by the very ingenious writer to the French nation ki general, and draws a line be¬ tween two classes of authors who are frequently confounded together in this country, I shall transcribe it in her own words. “ Il me semble qu’on pourroit marquer dans le dix-huitieme siecle, en France, deux epoques parfaitement distinctes, celle dans laquelle 1’in- fluence de 1’Angleterre s’est fait sentir, et celle ou les esprits se sont precipites dans la destruc¬ tion : Alors les lumieres se sont changees en in- cendie, et la philosophie, magicifinne irritee, a consume le palais ou elle avoit etale ses pro- diges. M En politique, Montesquieu appartient a la 278 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. Notes premiere epoque, Raynal a la seconde ; en reli- and. trion, les ecrits de Voltaire, qui avoit la tolerance pour but, sont inspires par 1 espnt ae la pie miere moitie du siecle, mais sa miserable et vaniteuse ireligion a fl6tri la seconde.”— VAUemagne, Tome III. pp- 37, 38.) Nothing, in truth, can be more striking than the contrast between the spirit of Voltaire’s ear¬ ly and of his later productions. From the for¬ mer may he quoted some of the suhlimest sen¬ timents anywhere to he found, both of religion and of morality. In some of the latter, he appears irrecoverably sunk in the abyss of fatalism. Examples of both are so numerous, that one is at a loss in the selection. In making choice of the following, I am guided chiefly by the com¬ parative shortness of the passages. ‘‘ Consulte Zoroastre et Minos, et Solon, Et le sage Socrate, et le grand Ciceron : Ils ont adore' tons un maitre, un juge, un pere;— Ge systeme sublime a Thomme est ne'cessaire. C’est le sacrd lien de la society, Le premier fondement de la sainte e'quitd ; Le frein du see'ldrat, 1’esperance du juste. Si les cieux, depouillds de leur empreinte auguste, Pouvoient cesser jamais de le manifester. Si Dieu n’existoit pas, il faudroit I’inventer.”1 Nor is it only on this fundamental principle of religion that Voltaire, in his better days, de¬ lighted to enlarge. The existence of a natural law engraved on the human heart, and the li¬ berty of the human will, are subjects which he has repeatedly enforced and adorned with all his philosophical and poetical powers. What can be more explicit, or more forcible, than the following exposition of the inconsistencies of fatalism ? “ Yois de la liberty cet ennemi mutin, Aveugle partisan d’un aveugle destin; Entends comme il consulte, approuve, ou ddlibdre, Entends de quel reproche il couvre un adversaire, Yois comment d’un rival il cherche a se venger, Notes Comme il punit son fils, et le veut corriger. and Il le croyoit done fibre ?_Oui sans doute, et lui-meme ^®*rations. Dement k chaque pas son funeste systeme. Il mentoit a son coeur, en voulant expliquer Ce dogme absurde a croire, absurde a pratiquer. Il reconnoit en lui le sentiment qu’il brave, Il agit comme fibre et parle comme esclave.”2 This very system, however, which Voltaire has here so severely reprobated, he lived to avow as the creed of his more advanced years. The words, indeed, are put into the mouth of a fic¬ titious personage ; hut it is plain, that the writer meant to he understood as speaking his own sentiments. “ Je vois une chaine immense, dont tout est chainon; elle embrasse, elle serre aujourd’hui la nature,” &c. &c. “ Je suis done ramene malgre moi a cette ancienne id6e, que je vois etre la base de tous les systemes, dans laquelle tous les philosophes retomhent apres mille detours, et qui m est de- montre par toutes les actions des hommes, par les miennes, par tous les evenemens que j ai lus, que j’ai vus, et aux-quelles j’ai eu part; c est le Fatalisme, c’est la Necessity dont je vous ai deja parle.”—(Lettres de Memmius d Ciceron. See CEuvres de Voltaire, Melanges, Tome IV. p. 358. 4to. Edit. Geneve, 1771.) “ En effet” (says Voltaire, in another of his pieces), il seroit bien singulier que toute la na¬ ture, tous les astres, oheissent a des lois eter- nelles, et qu’il y eut un petit animal haut de cinq pieds, qui au mepris de ces lois put agir toujours comme il lui plairoit au seul gre de son caprice.” .... .To this passage Voltaire adds the fol¬ lowing acknowledgment:—“ L’ignorant qui pense ainsi n’a pas toujours pense de meme,5 mais il est enfin contraint de se rendre.”—(Le Philosophe Ignorant.) Notwithstanding, however, this change in 1 A thought approaching very nearly to this occurs in one of Tillotson’s Sermons. “ The being of God is so comfortable, so convenient, so necessary to the felicity of mankind, that (as Tully admirably says) Dii immortales ad tisum hommum faln- eati pene videantur If God were not a necessary being of himself, he might almost be saul to be made for the use a benefit of Man.” For some ingenious remarks on this quotation from Cicero, see Jortin s Tracts., Voi. 1. p. .yl. 2 These verses form a part of a Discourse on the Liberty of Man; and the rest of the poem is in the same strain., e s.° very imperfectly did Yoltaire even then understand the metaphysical argument on this subject, that he prefixed to is Discourse the following advertisement. “ On entend par ce mot liberte, le pouvoir de faire ce qu’on veut. Il n y a, et ne neut v avoir d’autre YihcrtL" It appears, therefore, that in maintaining the liberty of spontaneity, Voltaire conceived himselt to be combating the scheme of Necessity; whereas this sort of liberty, no Necessitarian or Fatalist was ever hardy enoug to dispute-Qf of this he refers t0 his Treatise 0f Metaphysics, written forty years before, for the use of Madame du Chatelet, DISSERTATION FIRST. 279 Notes Voltaire’s philosophical opinions, he continued and to the last his zealous opposition to atheism.1 But in what respects it is more pernicious than fatalism, it is not easy to discover. A reflection of La Harpe’s, occasioned by some strictures of Voltaire’s upon Montesquieu, applies with equal force to the numberless in¬ consistencies which occur in his metaphysical speculations: “ Les ohjets de meditation etoient trop etrangers a Texcessive vivacite de son esprit. Saisir fortement par Timagination les ohjets qu’elle ne doit montrer que d’un cote, c’est ce qui est du Poete; les embrasser sous toutes les faces, c’est ce qui est du Philosophe, et Vol¬ taire etoit trop exclusivement Tun pour etre 1’autre.”—(Cours de Litterat. Tome XV. pp. 46, 47.) A late author2 has very justly reprobated that spiritual deification of nature which has been long fashionable among the French, and which, according to his own account, is at present not unfashionable in Germany. It is proper, how¬ ever, to observe, that this mode of speaking has been used by two very ditferent classes of wri¬ ters ; by the one with an intention to keep as much as possible the Deity out of their view, while studying his works; by the other, as a convenient and well understood metaphor, by means of which the frequent and irreverent mention of the name of God is avoided in philo¬ sophical arguments. It was with this last view, undoubtedly, that it was so often employed by Newton, and other English philosophers of the same school. In general, when we find a wri¬ ter speaking of the wise or of the benevolent in¬ tentions of nature, we should be slow in imput¬ ing to him any leaning towards atheism. Many of the finest instances of Final Causes, it is cer¬ tain, which the eighteenth century has brought to light, have been first remarked by inquirers who seem to have been fond of this phraseology; and of these inquirers, it is possible that some would have been less forward in bearing testi¬ mony to the truth, had they been forced to avail themselves of the style of theologians. These speculations, therefore, concerning the intentions Notes or designs of Nature, how reprehensible soever illustrations, and even absurd in point of strict logic the lan- guage may be in which they are expressed, may often be, nay, have often been, a step towards something higher and better ; and, at any rate, are of a character totally different from the blind chance of the Epicureans, or the conflicting principles of the Manicheans Note X X, p. 195. “ In the attempt, indeed, which Kant has made to enumerate the general ideas which are not de¬ rived from experience, but arise out of the pure un¬ derstanding, Kant may well lay claim to the praise of originalityy The object of this problem is thus stated by his friend, Mr Schulze, the au¬ thor of the Synopsis formerly quoted. (The fol¬ lowing translation is by Dr Willich, Elements, &c. p. 45.) “ To investigate the whole store of original notions discoverable in our understanding, and which lie at the foundation of all our knowledge; and at the same time to authenticate their true descent, by showing that they are not derived from experience, but are pure productions of the understanding. “ 1. The perceptions of objects contain, in¬ deed, the matter of knowledge, but are in them¬ selves blind and dead, and not knowledge; and our soul is merely passive in regard to them. « 2. If these perceptions are to furnish know¬ ledge, the understanding must think of them, and this is possible only through notions (con¬ ceptions), which are the peculiar form of our understanding, in the same manner as space and time are the form of our sensitive faculty. “ 3. These notions are active representations of our understanding-faculty; and as they re¬ gard immediately the perceptions of objects, they refer to the objects themselves only mediately. “ 4. They lie in our understanding as pure notions a priori, at the foundation of all our knowledge. They are necessary forms, radical 1 See the Diet. Philosophique, Art. Atheisms. See also the Strictures on the Systems ds la Nature in the Questions sur VEn- cyclopedie; the very work from which the above quotation is taken. 2 Frederick Schlegel. Lectures on the History of Literature. Vol. II. p. 169. Edinburgh, loo. 280 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. Notes and Illustrations. notions, categories (predicaments), of which all our knowledge of them must be compounded: And the table of them follows. “ Quantity ; unity, plurality, totality. “ Quality ; reality, negation, limitation. “ Relation ; substance, cause, reciprocation. “ Modality ; possibility, existence, necessity. “ 5. Now, to think and to judge is the same thing; consequently, every notion contains a particular form of judgment concerning objects. There are four principal genera of judgments : They are derived from the above four possible functions of the understanding, each of which contains under it three species ; namely, with re¬ spect to “ Quantity, they are universal, particular, sin¬ gular judgments. “ Quality, they are affirmative, negative, in¬ finite judgments. i . ™ \ • u ^ 2 Let it not be forgotten, that for this terrible description, Socrates, to whom it is ascribed by Plato (Z)e Rep. ix.) is called “ Prcestantissimus sapiential,” by a writer of the most masculine understanding, the least subject to be transported by en¬ thusiasm. (Tac. Ann. vi. 6.) “ Quae vulnera ! ” says Cicero, in alluding to the same passage. (Z)e Officus, m. 21.) 1 There can hardly be a finer example of Plato’s practical morals than his observations on the treatment of slaves. Genuine humanity and real probity, says he, are brought to the test, by the behaviour of a man to slaves, w om e may wrong with impunity. i part, pn ™ p., r / v • * Eric. Epist. ad Menccc. apud Diog. Laert. lib. x. edit. Meibom. I. 658, 656. DISSERTATION SECOND. 319 less importance as a motive to right conduct than to the completeness of Moral Theory, which, however, it is very far from solely con¬ stituting. With that truth the Epicureans blended another position, which indeed is con¬ tained in the first words of the above statement; namely, that because virtue promotes happi¬ ness, every act of virtue must be done in order to promote the happiness of the agent. They and their modern followers tacitly assume, that the latter position is the consequence of the for¬ mer; as if it were an inference from the necessity of food to life, that the fear of death should he substituted for the appetite of hunger as a mo¬ tive for eating. “ Friendship,” says Epicurus, “ is to be pursued by the wise man only for its usefulness, hut he will begin as he sows the field in order to reap.”1 It is obvious, that if these words he confined to outward benefits, they may be sometimes true, but never can be pertinent; for outward acts sometimes show kindness, but never compose it. If they be ap¬ plied to kind feeling they would indeed be per¬ tinent, but they would be evidently and totally false; for it is most certain that no man ac¬ quires an affection merely from his belief that it would be agreeable or advantageous to feel it. Kindness cannot indeed be pursued on account of the pleasure which belongs to it; for man can no more know the pleasure till he has felt the affection, than he can form an idea of colour without the sense of sight. The moral charac¬ ter of Epicurus was excellent; no man more enjoyed the pleasure or better performed the duties of friendship. The letter of his system was no more indulgent to vice than that of any other moralist.2 Although, therefore, he has the merit of having more strongly inculcated the connection of virtue with happiness, perhaps by the faulty excess of treating it as an exclu¬ sive principle; yet his doctrine was justly charged with indisposing the mind to those exalted and generous sentiments, without which no pure, elevated, bold, generous, or tender virtues can exist.5 As Epicurus represented the tendency of vir¬ tue, which is a most important truth in ethical theory, as the sole inducement to virtuous practice; so Zeno, in his disposition towards the opposite extreme, was inclined to consider the moral sentiments which are the motives of right conduct, as being the sole principles of moral science. The confusion was equally great in a philosophical view; but that of Epi¬ curus was more fatal to interests of higher im¬ portance than those of philosophy. Had the Stoics been content with affirming that virtue is the source of all that part of our happiness which depends on ourselves, they would have taken a position from which it would have been impossible to drive them; they would have laid down a principle of as great comprehension in practice as their wider pretensions; a simple and incontrovertible truth, beyond which every thing is an object of mere curiosity to man. Our information, however, about the opinions of the more celebrated Stoics is very scanty. None of their own writings are preserved. We know little of them but from Cicero, the trans¬ lator of Grecian philosophy, and from the Greek compilers of a later age; authorities which would be imperfect in the history of facts, but which are of far less value in the history of opinions, where a right conception often depends upon the minutest distinctions between words. We know that Zeno was more simple, and that Chrysippus, who was accounted the prop of the Stoic Porch, abounded more in subtile distinc¬ tion and systematic spirit.4 His power was at¬ tested as much by the antagonists whom he call¬ ed forth, as by the scholars whom he formed. “ Had there been no Chrysippus, there would T„v ha ms (Diog. Laert. ibid.) “ Hie est locus,” Gassendi confesses, “ ob quern Epicurus non parum yexatur, quando nemo non reprehendit, parari amicitiam non sui, sed utilitatis gratia.” 2 It is due to him to observe, that he treated humanity towards slaves, as one of the characteristics of a wise man. uts xoXaffuv oiKirx;, iXttieruv fttv >roi, xxi mi’yyviu/xnv rm rm traroubaiwv. (DlOG. LiAERT. ibid. 653.) It is not unworthy of remark, that neither Plato nor Epicurus thought it necessary to abstain from these topics in a city full of slaves, many of whom were men not destitute of knowledge. 3 “ Nil generosum, nil magnificum sapit.” Cicero. . . . Chrysippus, qui fulcire putatur porticum Stoicorum.” Cicero. Elsewhere, “ Acutissimus, sed in scribendo exilis jejunus, senpsit rhetoricam seu potius obmutescendi artem;” nearly as we should speak of a Schoolman. 320 preliminary dissertations. have been no Carneades,” was the saying of the latter philosopher himself; as it might have been said in the eighteenth century, 44 Had there been no Hume, there would have been no Kant and no Reid.” Cleanthes, when one of his followers would pay court to him by laying vices to the charge of his most formidable opponent, Arcesi- laus the academic, answered with a justice and candour unhappily too rare, 44 Silence, do not malign him 5—though he attacks "virtue by his arguments, he confirms its authority by his life. Arcesilaus, whether modestly or churlishly, re¬ plied, I do not choose to be flattered.” Cleanthes, with a superiority of repartee, as well as chari¬ ty, replied, 44 Is it flattery to say that you speak one thing and do another ?” It would be vain to expect that the fragments of the Professors who lectured in the Stoic School for five hundred years, should be capable of being moulded into one consistent system ; and we see that in Epic¬ tetus at least, the exaggeration of the sect was lowered to the level of reason, by confining the sufficiency of virtue to those cases only where happiness is attainable by our voluntary acts. It ought to be added, in extenuation of a noble error, that the power of habit and character to struggle against outward evils has been proved by experience to be in some instances so prodi¬ gious, that no man can presume to fix the ut¬ most limit of its possible increase. The attempt, however, of the Stoics to stretch the bounds of their system beyond the limits of nature, produced the inevitable inconvenience of dooming them to fluctuate between a wild fanaticism on the one hand, and, on the other, concessions which left their differences from other philosophers pure ly verbal. Many of their doctrines appear to be modifications of their original opinions, introduced as opposition be¬ came more formidable. In this manner they were driven to the necessity of admitting that the objects of our desires and appetites are worthy of preference, though they are denied to be constituents of happiness. It was thus that they were obliged to invent a double mo¬ rality; one for mankind at large, from whom was expected no more than the mOrixov,—which seems principally to have denoted acts of duty done from inferior or mixed motives; and the other, which they appear to have hoped from their ideal wise man, is xarogOupa, or perfect observance of rectitude,—which consisted only in moral acts done from mere reverence for morality, unaided by any feelings; all which (without the exception of pity) they classed among the enemies of reason and the disturbers of the human soul. Thus did they shrink from their proudest paradoxes into verbal evasions. It is remarkable that men so acute did not per¬ ceive and acknowledge, that if pain were not an evil, cruelty would not be a vice; and that if patience were of power to render torture in¬ different, virtue must expire in the moment of victory. There can be no more triumph when there is no enemy left to conquer.1 The influence of men’s opinions on the con¬ duct of their lives is checked and modified by so many causes—it so much depends on the strength of conviction, on its habitual combina¬ tion with feelings, on the concurrence or resist¬ ance of interest, passion, example, and sympa¬ thy—that a wise man is not the most forward in attempting to determine the power of its single operation over human actions. In the case of an individual it becomes altogether uncertain. But when the experiment is made on a large scale, when it is long continued and varied in its circumstances, and especially when great bodies of men are for ages the subject of it, we cannot reasonably reject the consideration of the inferences to which it appears to lead. The Roman Patriciate, trained in the conquest and government of the civilized world, in spite of the tyrannical vices which sprung from that training, were raised by the greatness of their objects to an elevation of genius and character unmatched by any other aristocracy; at the mo¬ ment when, after preserving their power by a long course of wise compromise with the people, they were betrayed by the army and the popu¬ lace into the hands of a single tyrant of their own order—the most accomplished of usurpers, 1 “ Patience, sovereign o’er transmuted ill.” But as soon as the ill was really “ transmuted” into good, it is evident that there was no longer any scope left for the exercise of patience. DISSERTATION SECOND. 321 and, if humanity and justice could for a moment be silenced, one of the most illustrious of men. There is no scene in history so memorable as that in which Caesar mastered a nobility of which Lucullus and Hortensius, Sulpicius and Catulus, Pompey and Cicero, Brutus and Cato, were members. This renowned body had from the time of Scipio sought the Greek philosophy as an amusement or an ornament. Some few, j , r See also the Appendix to Ward’s o///ran/.More, 247-271. This account of that ingenious and amiable philoso¬ pher (Bond. 1710) contains an interesting view of his opinions, and many beautiful passages of his writings, but un- rortunately very few particulars of the man. His letters on Disinterested Piety, (see the Appendix to Mr Ward’s work) ms boundless charity, his zeal for the utmost toleration, and his hope of general improvement from “ a pacific and per¬ spicacious posterity,” place him high in the small number of true philosophers who, in their estimate of men, value dis¬ positions more than opinions, and in their search for good, more often look forward than backward. 1 Born in 1651; died in 1715. 2 Born in 1627 ; died in 1704. * Bausset, Histoire de Fenelon, I. 252. 352 preliminary dissertations. persons of her sex and character. In the fer¬ vour of her zeal, she disregarded the usages of the world and the decorums imposed on females. She left her family, took a part in public con¬ ferences, and assumed an independence scarcely reconcilable with the more ordinary and more pleasing virtues of women. Her pious effusions were examined with the rigour which might he exercised on theological propositions. She was falsely charged by Harlay, the dissolute arch¬ bishop of Paris, with personal licentiousness. For these crimes she was dragged from convent to convent, imprisoned for years in the Bastile, and, as an act of mercy, confined during the lat¬ ter years of her life to a provincial town, as a prison at large. A piety thus pure and disin¬ terested could not fail to please Fenelon. He published a work in justification of Madame Guyon’s character, and in explanation of the degree in which he agreed with her. Bossuet, the oracle and champion of the church, took up arms against him. It would he painful to sup¬ pose that a man of so great powers was actuated by mean jealousy, and it is needless. The union of zeal for opinion with the pride of author¬ ity, is apt to give sternness to the administra¬ tion of controversial bishops; to say nothing of the haughty and inflexible character of Bossuet himself. He could not brook the independence of him who was hitherto so docile a scholar and so gentle a friend. He was jealous of novelties, and dreaded a fervour of piety likely to he un¬ governable, and perhaps to excite movements ot which no man could foresee the issue. It must be allowed that he had reason to he displeased with the indiscretion and turbulence of the in¬ novators, and might apprehend that, in preach¬ ing motives to virtue and religion which he thought, unattainable, the coarser hut surer foundations of common morality might be loosened. A controversy ensued, in which he employed the utmost violence of polemical or factious contest. Fenelon replied with brilliant guccess, and submitted his hook to the judg¬ ment of Rome. After a long examination, the commission of ten Cardinals appointed to ex¬ amine it were equally divided, and he seemed in consequence about to he acquitted. But Bossuet had in the mean time easily gained Louis XIV. Madame de Maintenon betrayed Fenelon’s confidential correspondence; and he was banished to his diocese, and deprived of his pensions and official apartments in the palace. Louis XIV. regarded the slightest differences from the authorities of the French church as re¬ bellion against himself. Though endowed with much natural good sense, he was too grossly ignorant to be made to comprehend one of the terms of the question in dispute. He did not, however, scruple to urge the Pope to the con¬ demnation of Fenelon. Innocent XII. (Pigna- telli) an aged and pacific Pontiff, was desirous of avoiding such harsh measures. He said that “ the archbishop of Cambray might have erred from excess in the love of God, but the bishop of Meaux had sinned by a defect of the love of his neighbour.”1 But he was compelled to con¬ demn a series of propositions, of which the first was, “ there is an habitual state of love to God, which is pure from every motive of personal interest, and in which neither the fear of punish¬ ment nor the hope of reward has any part.”2 Fenelon read the bull which condemned him in his own cathedral, and professed as humble a submission as the lowest of his flock. In some of the writings of his advanced years, which have been recently published, we observe with regret that, when wearied out by his exile, ambitious to regain a place at court through the Jesuits, or prejudiced against the Calvinising doctrines of the Jansenists, the strongest anti-papal party among Catholics, or somewhat detached from a cause of which his great antagonist had been the victorious leader, he made concessions to the abso¬ lute monarchy of Rome, which did not become a luminary of the Galilean church.3 Bossuet, in his writings on this occasion, be¬ sides tradition and authorities, relied mainly on the supposed principle of philosophy, that man must desire his own happiness, and cannot de- 1 Bausset, Histoire de Fenelon, II. 220, note. » CEuvres de Bossuet, VIII. 308. Liege, 1767, 8vo. * De Summi Pontificis Auctoritate Dissertatio: (Euvres de Fenelon, tome ii. Versailles, 1820. DISSERTATION SECOND. 353 sire anything else, otherwise than as a means to¬ wards it; which renders the controversy an inci¬ dent in the history of Ethics. It is immediately connected with the preceding part of this Dis¬ sertation, by the almost literal coincidence be¬ tween Bossuet’s foremost objection to the dis¬ interested piety contended for by Fenelon, and the fundamental position of a very ingenious and once noted divine of the English church, in his attack on the disinterested affections, believed by Shaftesbury to be a part of human nature.1 2 LEIBNITZ. There is a singular contrast between the form of Leibnitz’s writings and the character of his mind. The latter was systematical, even to ex¬ cess. It was the vice of his prodigious intellect, on every subject of science where it was not bound by geometrical chains, to confine his view to those most general principles, so well called by Bacon “ merely notionalwhich render it, indeed, easy to build a system, but, only because they may be alike adapted to every state of ap¬ pearances, and become thereby really inappli¬ cable to any. Though his genius was thus naturally turned to system, his writings were, generally, occasional and miscellaneous. The fragments of his doctrines are scattered in Re¬ views ; or over a voluminous Literary Correspond¬ ence; or in the Prefaces and Introductions to those compilations to which this great philoso¬ pher was obliged by his situation to descend. This defective and disorderly mode of publica¬ tion arose partly from the jars between business and study, inevitable in his course of life; but probably yet more from the nature of his system, which, while it widely deviates from the most general principles of former philosophers, is ready to embrace their particular doctrines under its own generalities, and thus to reconcile them to each other, as well as to accommodate itself to popular or established opinions, and compro¬ mise with them, according to his favourite and oft-repeated maxim, “ that most received doc¬ trines are capable of a good sense ;”3 by which last words our philosopher meant a sense reconcil¬ able with his own principles. Partial and oc¬ casional exhibitions of these principles suited better that constant negotiation with opinions, establishments, and prejudices, to which extreme generalities are well adapted, than a full and methodical statement of the whole at once. It is the lot of every philosopher who attempts to make his principles extremely flexible, that they become like those tools which bend so easily as to penetrate nothing. Yet his manner of publi¬ cation perhaps led him to those wide intuitions, as comprehensive as those of Bacon, of which he expressed the result as briefly and pithily as Hobbes. The fragment which contains his ethi¬ cal principles is the Preface to a collection of documents illustrative of international law, pub¬ lished at Hanover in 1693 ;4 to which he often referred as his standard afterwards, especially when he speaks of Lord Shaftesbury, or of the controversy between the two great theologi¬ ans of France. “ Right,” says he, “ is moral power; obligation moral necessity. By moral, I understand what with a good man prevails as much as if it were physical. A good man is he who loves all men as far as reason allows. Justice 1 “ Haec est natura voluntatis humanae, ut et beatitudinem, et ea quorum necessaria connexio cum beatitudine clare intelligitur, necessario appetat Nullus est actus ad quern revera non impellimur motivo beatitudinis, explicite vel implicates" meaning by the latter that it may be concealed from ourselves, as he says, for a short time, by a nearer object. (CEuvres de Bossuet, VIII. 80.) “ The only motive by which individuals can be induced to the practice of virtue, must be the feeling or the prospect of private happiness.” (Brown’s Essays on the Characteristics, p. 159. Lond. 1752.) It must, however, be owned, that the selfishness of the Warburtonian is more rigid; making no provision for the object of one’s own happiness slipping out of view for a moment. It is due to the vejy ingenious author of this forgotten book to add, that it is full of praise of his adversary, which, though just, was in the answerer generous ; and that it contains an assertion of the unbounded right of public discussion, unusual even at the tolerant period of its appearance. 2 Born in 1648 ; died in 1716. * Nouveaux Essais sur VEntendement Humain, liv. i. chap. ii. p. 57- These Essays, which form the greater part of the publication entitled CEuvres Philosophxques, edited by Raspe, Amst. et Leipz. 1765, are not included in Dutens’s edition of Leibnitz’s works. 4 Codex Juris Gentium Diplomaticus. Hanov. 1695. DISS. II. 2 Y 354 preliminary dissertations. is the benevolence of a wise man. To love is to be pleased with the happiness of another ; or, in other words, to convert the happiness of another into a part of one's own. Hence is explained the possibility of a disinterested love. When we are pleased with the happiness of any being, his happiness becomes one of our enjoyments. Wis¬ dom is the science of happiness.’ 1 REMARKS. It is apparent from the above passage, that Leibnitz had touched the truth on the subject of disinterested affection ; and that he was more near clinging to it than any modern philosopher, except Lord Shaftesbury. It is evident, how¬ ever, from the latter part of it, that, like Shaftes¬ bury, he shrunk from his own just conception ; under the influence of that most ancient and far- spread prejudice of the schools, which assumed that such an abstraction as Happiness could be the object of love, and that the desire of so faint, distant, and refined an object, was the first principle of all moral nature, of which every other desire was only a modification or a fruit. Both he and Shaftesbury, however, when they relapsed into the selfish system, embraced it in its most refined form; considering the benevo¬ lent affections as valuable parts of our own hap¬ piness, not in consequence of any of their effects or extrinsic advantages, but of that intrinsic de¬ lightfulness which was inherent in their very essence. But Leibnitz considered this refined pleasure as the object in the view of the bene¬ volent man; an absurdity, or rather a contra¬ diction, which, at least in the Inquiry concerning Virtue, Shaftesbury avoids. It will be seen from Leibnitz’s limitation, taken together with his definition of Wisdom, that he regarded the dis¬ tinction of the moral sentiments from the social affections, and the just subordination of the latter, as entirely founded on the tendency of general happiness to increase that of the agent, not merely as being real, but as being present to the agent’s mind when he acts. In a subse¬ quent passage he lowers his tone not a little. ' As for the sacrifice of life, or the endurance of the greatest pain for others, these things are rather generously enjoined than solidly demon¬ strated by philosophers. For honour, glory, and self-congratulation, to which they appeal under the name of Virtue, are indeed mental plea¬ sures, and of a high degree, but not to all, nor outweighing every bitterness of suffering; since all cannot imagine them with equal vivacity, and that power is little possessed by those whom neither education, nor situation, nor the doc¬ trines of religion or philosophy, have taught to value mental gratifications.” 8 He concludes very truly, that morality is completed by a belief of moral government. But the Inquiry concerning Virtue had reached that conclusion by a better road. It entirely escaped his sagacity, as it has that of nearly all other moralists, that the co¬ incidence of morality with well-understood in¬ terest in our outward actions, is very far from being the most important part of the question; for these actions flow from habitual dispositions, from affections and sensibilities, which deter¬ mine their nature. There may be, and there are many immoral acts, which, in the sense in which words are commonly used, are advan¬ tageous to the actor. But the whole sagacity and ingenuity of the world may be safely chal¬ lenged to point out a case in which virtuous dispositions, habits, and feelings, are not con¬ ducive in the highest degree to the happiness of the individual; or to maintain that he is not the happiest, whose moral sentiments and affections are such as to prevent the possibility of the prospect of advantage through unlawful means from presenting itself to his mind. It would indeed have been impossible to prove to Rega¬ ins that it was his interest to return to a death of torture in Africa. But what if the proof had been easy ? The most thorough conviction on such a point would not have enabled him to set this example, if he had not been supported by his own integrity and generosity, by love of his country, and reverence for his pledged faith. What could the conviction add to that greatness of soul, and to these glorious attributes ? With such virtues he could not act otherwise than he 1 See Notes and Illustrations, note N. * Ibid, note N. DISSERTATION SECOND. 355 did. Would a father affectionately interested in a son’s happiness, of very lukewarm feel¬ ings of morality, but of good sense enough to weigh gratifications and sufferings exactly, he really desirous that his son should have these virtues in a less degree than Regulus, merely because they might expose him to the fate which Regulus chose ? On the coldest calculation he would surely perceive, that the high and glow¬ ing feelings of such a mind during life, altogether throw into shade a few hours of agony in leaving it. And, if he himself were so unfortunate that no more generous sentiment arose in his mind to silence such calculations, would it not be a re¬ proach to his understanding not to discover, that though in one case out of millions such a character might lead a Regulus to torture, yet, in the common course of nature, it is the source not only of happiness in life, hut of quiet and honour in death. A case so extreme as that of Regulus will not perplex, if we hear in mind, that though we cannot prove the act of heroic virtue to be conducive to the interest of the hero, yet we may perceive at once, that nothing is so conducive to his interest as to have a mind so formed that it could not shrink from it, hut must rather embrace it with gladness and tri¬ umph. Men of vigorous health are said some¬ times to suffer most in a pestilence. No man was ever so absurd as for that reason to wisli that he were more infirm. The distemper might return once in a century. If he were then alive, he might escape it; and even if he fell, the balance of advantage would he in most cases greatly on the side of robust health. In esti¬ mating beforehand the value of a strong bodily frame, a man of sense would throw the small chance of a rare and short evil entirely out of the account. So must the coldest and most self¬ ish moral calculator, who, if he he sagacious and exact, must pronounce, that the inconveniences to which a man may he sometimes exposed by a pure and sound mind, are no reasons for regret¬ ting that we do not escape them by possessing minds more enfeebled and distempered. Other occasions will call our attention, in the sequel, to this important part of the subject. But the great name of Leibnitz seemed to require that his de¬ grading statement should not be cited without warning the reader against its egregious fallacy. MALEBRANCHE.1 * * * This ingenious philosopher and beautiful writer is the only celebrated Cartesian who has professedly handled the Theory of Morals.8 His theory has in some points of view a conformity to the doctrine of Clarke; while in others it has given occasion to his English follower Norris5 to say, that if the Quakers understood their own opinion of the illumination of all men, they would explain it on the principles of Malehranche. “ There is,” says he, “ one parent virtue, the universal virtue, the virtue which renders us just and perfect, the virtue which will one day render us happy. It is the only virtue. It is the love of the universal order, as it eternally existed in the Divine reason, where every creat¬ ed reason contemplates it. This order is com¬ posed of practical as well as speculative truth. Reason perceives the moral superiority of one being over another, as immediately as the equal¬ ity of the radii of the same circle. The rela¬ tive perfection of beings is that part of the im¬ movable order to which men must conform their minds and their conduct. The love of order is the whole of virtue, and conformity to order constitutes the morality of actions.” It is not difficult to discover, that in spite of the singular skill employed in weaving this web, it answers no other purpose than that of hiding the whole difficulty. The love of universal or¬ der, says Malehranche, requires that we should value an animal more than a stone, because it is more valuable ; and love God infinitely more than man, because he is infinitely better. But without presupposing the reality of moral dis- 1 Born in 1638 ; died in 1715. * Traite de Morale. Rotterdam, 1684. J Author of the Theory of the Ideal World, who well copied, though he did not equal the clearness and choice of expres¬ sion which belonged to his master. 356 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. tinctions, and the power of moral feelings, the two points to he proved, how can either of these propositions he evident, or even intel¬ ligible? To say that a love of the eternal order will produce the love and practice of every virtue, is an assertion untenable unless we take morality for granted, and useless if we do. In his work on Morals, all the incidental and secondary remarks are equally well consid¬ ered and well expressed. The manner in which he applied his principle to the particulars of human duty, is excellent. He is perhaps the first philosopher who has precisely laid down and rigidly adhered to the great principle, that virtue consists in pure intentions and dispositions of mind, without which, actions, however con- JONATHAN This remarkable man, the metaphysician of America, was formed among the Calvinists of New England, when their stern doctrine retained its rigorous authority.1 2 * 4 His power of subtile ar¬ gument, perhaps unmatched, certainly unsur¬ passed among men, was joined, as in some of the ancient Mystics, with a character which raised his piety to fervour. He embraced their doctrine, probably without knowing it to he theirs. “ True religion,” says he, “ in a great measure consists in holy affections. A love of divine things, for the beauty and sweetness of their moral excellency, is the spring of all holy affections.”3 Had he suffered this noble principle to take the right road to all its fair consequences, he would have entirely concurred with Plato, with Shaftesbury, and Malebranche, in devotion to “ the first good, first perfect, and first fair.” But he thought it necessary after¬ wards to limit his doctrine to his own persua¬ sion, by denying that such moral excellence could he discovered in divine things by those formable to rules, are not truly moral; a truth of the highest importance, which, in the theolo¬ gical form, may he said to have been the main principle of the first Protestant Reformers. The ground of piety, according to him, is the con¬ formity of the attributes of God to those moral qualities which we irresistibly love and revere.1 “ Sovereign princes,” says he, “ have no right to use their authority without reason. Even God has no such miserable right.”8 His dis¬ tinction between a religious society and an established church, and his assertion of the right of the temporal power alone to employ coercion, are worthy of notice, as instances in which a Catholic, at once philosophical and or¬ thodox, could thus speak, not only of the na¬ ture of God, hut of the rights of the church. EDWARDS.* Christians who did not take the same view with him of their religion. All others, and some who hold his doctrines with a more enlarged spirit, may adopt his principle without any limitation. His ethical theory is contained in his Disser¬ tation on the Nature of True Virtue; and in another, On God's Chief End in the Creation, published in London thirty years after his death. True virtue, according to him, consists in be¬ nevolence, or love to being “ in general,” which he afterwards limits to {t intelligent being,” though sentient would have involved a more reasonable limitation. This good-will is felt towards a particular being, first in pro¬ portion to his degree of existence (for, says he, “ that which is great has more existence, and is farther from nothing, than that which is little”); and secondly, in proportion to the degree in which that particular being feels benevolence to others. Thus God, having infinitely more ex¬ istence and benevolence than man, ought to he infinitely more loved; and for the same rea- 1 “ 11 faut aimer 1’Etre infiniment parfait, et non pas un fantome e'pouvantable, un Dieu injuste, absolu, puissant, mais sans bonte et sans sagesse. S’il y avoit un tel Dieu, le vrai Dieu nous defendroit de 1’adorer et de I’aimer. II y a peut-etre plus de danger d’offenser Dieu lorsqu’on lui donne une forme si horrible, que de mepriser ce fantome.” (Traite de Morale, chap, viii.) 2 Ibid. chap. xxii. * Born in 1703, at Windsor in Connecticut; died in 1758, at Princeton in New Jersey. * Notes and Illustrations, note O. * Edwards on Religious Affections, p. 4, 187. Lond. 1796. DISSERTATION SECOND. 357 son, God must love himself infinitely more than he does all other beings.1 2 * He can act only from regard to himself, and his end in creation can only he to manifest his whole nature, which is called acting for his own glory. As far as Edwards confines himself to creat¬ ed beings, and while his theory is perfectly in¬ telligible, it coincides with that of universal benevolence, hereafter to he considered. The term being is a mere encumbrance, which serves indeed to give it a mysterious outside, hut brings with it from the schools nothing ex¬ cept their obscurity. He was betrayed into it by the cloak which it threw over his really un¬ meaning assertion or assumption, that there are degrees of existence ; without which that part of his system which relates to the Deity would have appeared to he as baseless as it really is. When we try such a phrase by applying it to matters within the sphere of our experience, we see that it means nothing hut degrees of certain faculties and powers. But the very application of the term being to all things, shows that the least perfect has as much being as the most perfect; or rather that there can he no difference, so far as that word is concerned, between two things to which it is alike applicable. The justness of the compound proportion on which human vir¬ tue is made to depend, is capable of being tried by an easy test. If we suppose the greatest of evil spirits to have a hundred times the had passions of Marcus Aurelius, and at the same time a hundred times his faculties, or, in Ed¬ wards’s language, a hundred times his quantity of being, it follows from this moral theory, that we ought to esteem and love the devil exactly in the same degree as we esteem and love Mar¬ cus Aurelius. The chief circumstance which justifies so much being said on the last two writers, is their concurrence in a point towards which Ethical Philosophy had been slowly approaching, from the time of the controversies raised up by Hobbes. They both indicate the increase of this tendency, by introducing an element into their theory, for¬ eign from those cold systems of ethical abstrac¬ tion, with which they continued in other respects to have much in common. Malebranche makes virtue consist in the love of order, Edwards in the love of being. In this language we perceive a step beyond the representation of Clarke, which made it a conformity to the relations of things; hut a step which cannot he made without pass¬ ing into a new province;—without confessing, by the use of the word love, that not only per¬ ception and reason, hut emotion and sentiment, are among the fundamental principles of morals. They still, however, were so wedded to scholas¬ tic prejudice, as to choose two of the most aerial abstractions which can he introduced into argu¬ ment,—being and order,—to he the objects of those strong active feelings which were to govern the human mind. BUFFIER.* The same strange disposition to fix on ab¬ stractions as the objects of our primitive feelings, and the end sought by our warmest desires, manifests itself in the ingenious writer with whom this part of the Dissertation closes, under a form of less dignity than that which it assumes in the hands of Malebranche and Clarke. Buf- fier, the only Jesuit whose name has a place in the history of Abstract Philosophy, has no pecu¬ liar opinions which would have required any mention of him as a moralist, were it not for the just reputation of his treatise on First Truths, with which Dr Reid so remarkably, though un¬ aware of its existence, coincides, even in the misapplication of so practical a term as com¬ mon sense to denote the faculty which recog¬ nises the truth of First Principles. His phi¬ losophical writings5 are remarkable for that 1 The coincidence of Malebranche with this part of Edwards, is remarkable. Speaking of the Supreme Being, he says, “ II s'aime invinciblement.” He adds another more startling expression, “ Certainement Dieu ne pent agir que pour lui- meme: il n’a point d’autre motif que son amour propre.” (Traite de Morale, chap, xvii ) 2 Born in 1661; died in 1737- * Cours de Sciences. Paris, 1732, folio. 358 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. perfect clearness of expression, which, since the great examples of Descartes and Pascal, has been so generally diffused as to have become one of the enviable peculiarities of French philo¬ sophical style, and almost of the French lan¬ guage. His ethical doctrine is that most common¬ ly received among philosophers, from Aristotle to Paley and Bentham : “ I desire to be happy; but as I live with other men, I cannot be happy without consulting their happinessa propo¬ sition perfectly true indeed, but far too narrow, as inferring, that in the most benevolent acts a man must pursue only his own interest, from the fact that the practice of benevolence does increase his happiness, and that because a vir¬ tuous mind is likely to be the happiest, our ob¬ servation of that property of virtue is the cause of our love and reverence for it. SECTION VI. Foundations of a more just Theory of Ethics. BUTLER—HUTCHESON—BERKELEY—HUME—SMITH—PRICE—HARTLEY—TUCKER— PALEY—BENTHAM—STEWART—BROWN. From the beginning of ethical controversy to the eighteenth century, it thus appears, that the care of the individual for himself, and his re¬ gard for the things which preserve self, were thought to form the first, and, in the opinion of most, the earliest of all the principles which prompt men and other animals to activity; that nearly all philosophers regarded the appetites and desires, which look only to self-gratification, as modifications of this primary principle of self- love; and that a very numerous body consid¬ ered even the social affections themselves as nothing more than the produce of a more la¬ tent and subtile operation of the desire of in¬ terest, and of the pursuit of pleasure. It is true, they often spoke otherwise; but it was rather from the looseness and fluctuation of their language, than from distrust in their doc¬ trine. It is true, also, that perhaps all repre¬ sented the gratifications of virtue as more un¬ mingled, more secure, more frequent, and more lasting, than other pleasures; without which they could neither have retained a hold on the assent of mankind, nor reconciled the principles of their systems with the testimony of their hearts. We have seen how some began to be roused from a lazy acquiescence in this an¬ cient hypothesis, by the monstrous consequences which Hobbes had legitimately deduced from it. A few, of pure minds and great intellect, laboured to render morality disinterested, by tracing it to reason as its source; without con¬ sidering that reason, elevated indeed far above interest, is also separated by an impassable gulf, from feeling, affection, and passion. At length it was perceived by more th,un one, that through whatever length of reasoning the mind may pass in its advances towards action, there is placed at the end of any avenue through which it can advance, some principle wholly unlike mere reason,—some emotion or sentiment which must be touched, before the springs of will and action can be set in motion. Had Lord Shaftesbury steadily, adhered to his own prin¬ ciples—had Leibnitz not recoiled from his state¬ ment—the truth might have been regarded as promulged, though not unfolded. The writings of both prove, atleast to us, enlightened as we are by what followed, that they were skilful in sound¬ ing, and that their lead had touched the bottom. But it was reserved for another moral philosopher to determine this hitherto unfathomed depth.1 1 The doctrine of the Stoics is thus put by Cicero into the mouth of Cato: “ Placet his, inquit, quorum ratio mihi probatur, simul atque natum sit animal, (hinc enim est ordiendum) ipsum sibi conciliari et commendari ad se conservandum. DISSERTATION SECOND. 359 BUTLER.1 Butler, who was the son of a Presbyterian trader, early gave such promise, as to induce his father to fit him, by a proper education, for being a minister of that persuasion. He was edu¬ cated at one of their seminaries under Mr Jones of Gloucester, where Seeker, afterwards arch¬ bishop of Canterbury, was his fellow-student. Though many of the dissenters had then begun to relinquish Calvinism, the uniform effect of that doctrine, in disposing its adherents to meta¬ physical speculation, long survived the opinions which caused it, and cannot be doubted to have influenced the mind of Butler. When a student at the academy of Gloucester, he wrote private letters to Hr Clarke on his celebrated Demonstra¬ tion, suggesting objections which were really in¬ superable, and which are marked by an acute¬ ness which neither himself nor any other ever surpassed. Clarke, whose heart was as well schooled as his head, published the letters, with his own answers, in the next edition of his work; and, by his good offices with his friend and follower, Sir Joseph Jekyll, obtained for the young philosopher an early opportunity of mak¬ ing his abilities and opinions known, by the ap¬ pointment of preacher at the Chapel of the Master of the Rolls. He was afterwards raised to one of the highest seats on the Episcopal bench, through the philosophical taste of Queen Caroline, and her influence over the mind of her husband, which continued long after her death. “ He was wafted,” says Horace Walpole, “ to the see of Durham, on a cloud of Metaphy¬ sics.”2 Even in the fourteenth year of his widowhood, George II. was desirous of inserting the name of the Queen’s metaphysical favourite in the Regency Bill of seventeen hundred and fifty-one. His great work on the Analogy of Religion to the Course of Nature, though only a commentary on the singularly original and pregnant passage of Origen, which is so honestly prefixed to it as a motto, is, notwithstanding, the most original and profound work extant in any language on the Philosophy of Religion. It is entirely beyond our present scope. His ethical discussions are contained in those deep and sometimes dark Dis¬ sertations which he preached at the Chapel of the Rolls, and afterwards published under the .name of Sermons, while he was yet fresh from the schools, and full of that courage with which youth often delights to exercise its strength in abstract reasoning, and to push its faculties into the recesses of abstruse speculation. But his youth was that of a sober and mature mind, early taught by nature to discern the boundaries of knowledge, and to abstain from fruitless ef¬ forts to reach inaccessible ground. In these sermons,5 he has taught truths more capable of being exactly distinguished from the doctrines of his predecessors, more satisfactorily establish¬ ed by him, more comprehensively applied to par¬ ticulars, more rationally connected with each other, and therefore more worthy of the name of discovery, than any with which we are ac¬ quainted; if we ought not, with some hesita¬ tion, to except the first steps of the Grecian phi¬ losophers towards a Theory of Morals. It is a peculiar hardship, that the extreme ambiguity of language, an obstacle which it is one of the chief merits of an ethical philosopher to vanquish, is one of the circumstances which prevent men et ad suum statum, et ad ea quae conservantia sunt ejus status diligenda; alienari autem ab interitu, iisque rebus quae in- teritum videantur afFerre. Id ita esse sic probant, quod, antequam voluptas aut dolor attigerit, salutaria appetant parvi, aspernenturque contraria. Quod non fieret, nisi statum suum diligerent, interitum timerent. Fieri autem non posset ut ap- peterent aliquid, nisi sensum haberent sui, eoque se et sua diligerent. Ex Quo inteljligi debet, principium ductum esse a se diligendi.” (De Finibus, lib. iii. cap. v.) We are told that diligendo is the reading of an ancient MS. Perhaps the omission of ‘ a’ would be the easiest and most reasonable emendation. The above passage is perhaps the fullest and plainest statement of the doctrines prevalent till the time of Butler. 1 Born in 1692; died in 1752. 2 Walpole’s Memoirs. * See Sermons i. ii. and iii. On Human Nature; v. On Compassion ; viii. On Resentment; ix. On Forgiveness; xi. and xii. On the Love of our Neighbour; and xiii. On the Love of God; together with the excellent Preface. 360 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. from seeing the justice of applying to him so ambitious a term as discovery. Butler owed more to Lord Shaftesbury than to all other wri¬ ters besides. He is just and generous towards that philosopher; yet, whoever carefully com¬ pares their writings, will without difficulty dis ¬ tinguish the two builders, and the larger as well as more regular and laboured part of the edifice, which is due to Butler. Mankind have various principles of action; some leading directly to the private good, some immediately to the good of the community. But the private desires are not self-love, or any form of it; for self-love is the desire of a man’s own happiness, whereas the object of an appe¬ tite or passion is some outward thing. Self-love seeks things as means of happiness; the private appetites seek things, not as means, but as ends. A man eats from hunger, and drinks from thirst; and though he knows that these acts are necessary to life, that knowledge is not the motive of his conduct. No gratification can in¬ deed he imagined without a previous desire. If all the particular desires did not exist inde¬ pendently, self-love would have no object to employ itself about; for there would he no happiness, which, by the very supposition of the opponents, is made up of the gratifications of various desires. No pursuit could be selfish or interested, if there were not satisfactions first gained by appetites which seek their own out¬ ward objects without regard to self; which sa¬ tisfactions compose the mass which is called a man’s interest. In contending, therefore, that the benevolent affections are disinterested, no more is claimed for them than must he granted to mere animal appetites and to malevolent passions. Each of these principles alike seeks its own object, for the sake simply of obtaining it. Pleasure is the result of the attainment, hut no separate part of the aim of the agent. The desire that another person may he gratified, seeks that out¬ ward object alone, according to the general course of human desire. Resentment is as dis¬ interested as gratitude or pity, hut not more so. Hunger or thirst may be, as much as the purest benevolence, at variance with self-love. A re¬ gard to our own general happiness is not a vice, hut in itself an excellent quality. It were well if it prevailed more generally over craving and short-sighted appetites. The weakness of the social affections, and the strength of the private desires, properly constitute selfishness; a vice utterly at variance with the happiness of him who harbours it, and as such, condemned by self-love. There are as few who attain the greatest satisfaction to themselves, as who do the greatest good to others. It is absurd to say with some, that the pleasure of benevolence is selfish because it is felt by self. Understand¬ ing and reasoning are acts of self, for no man can think by proxy; hut no one ever called them selfish. Why? Evidently because they do not regard self. Precisely the same reason applies to benevolence. Such an argument is a gross confusion of self, as it is a subject of feel¬ ing or thought, with self considered as the object of either. It is no more just to refer the private appetites to self-love because they commonly promote happiness, than it would he to refer them to self-hatred in those frequent cases where their gratification obstructs it. But, besides the private or public desires, and besides the calm regard to our own general wel¬ fare, there is a principle in man, in its nature supreme over all others. This natural supre¬ macy belongs to the faculty which surveys, ap¬ proves, or disapproves the several affections of our minds and actions of our lives. As self- love is superior to the private passions, so con¬ science is superior to the whole of man. Pas¬ sion implies nothing hut an inclination to follow it; and in that respect passions differ only in force. But no notion can be formed of the principle of reflection, or conscience, which does not comprehend judgment, direction, superin¬ tendency. Authority over all other principles of action is a constituent part of the idea of con¬ science, and cannot he separated from it. Had it strength as it has right, it would govern the world. The passions would have their power hut according to their nature, which is to he subject to conscience. Hence we may under¬ stand the purpose at which the ancients, perhaps confusedly, aimed, when they laid it down, that virtue consisted in following nature. It is neither easy, nor, for the main object of the DISSERTATION SECOND. 361 moralist, important, to render the doctrines of the ancients by modern language. If Butler re¬ turns to this phrase too often, it was rather from the remains of undistinguishing reverence for antiquity, than because he could deem its em¬ ployment important to his own opinions. The tie which holds together Religion and Morality, is, in the system of Butler, somewhat different from the common representations, but not less close. Conscience, or the faculty of ap¬ proving or disapproving, necessarily constitutes the bond of union. Setting out from the belief of Theism, and combining it, as he had entitled himself to do, with the reality of conscience, he could not avoid discovering, that the being who possessed the highest moral qualities, is the ob¬ ject of the highest moral affections. He con¬ templates the Deity through the moral nature of man. In the case of a being who is to be perfectly loved, “ goodness must be the simple actuating principle within him; this being the moral quality which is the immediate object of love.” “ The highest, the adequate object of this affection, is perfect goodness; which, there¬ fore, we are to love with all our heart, with all our soul, and with all our strength.” “ We should refer ourselves implicitly to him, and cast ourselves entirely upon him. The whole at¬ tention of life should be to obey his commands.”1 Moral distinctions are thus presupposed before a step can be made towards religion: virtue leads to piety; God is to be loved, because good¬ ness is the object of love; and it is only after the mind rises through human morality to di¬ vine perfection, that all the virtues and duties are seen to hang from the throne of God. REMARKS. There do not appear to be any errors in the ethical principles of Butler. The following remarks are intended to point out some defects in his scheme; and even that attempt is made with the unfeigned humility of one who rejoices in an opportunity of doing justice to that part of the writings of a great philosopher which has not been so clearly understood, nor so justly estimated by the generality, as his other works. 1. It is a considerable defect, though perhaps unavoidable in a sermon, that he omits all in¬ quiry into the nature and origin of the private appetites, which first appear in human nature. It is implied, but it is not expressed in his rea¬ sonings, that there is a time before the child can be called selfish, any more than social, when these appetites seem as it were separately to pursue their distinct objects, long antecedent to the state of mind in which all their gratifica¬ tions are regarded as forming the mass called happiness. It is hence that they are likened to instincts, in contradiction to their subsequent distinction, which requires reason and experi¬ ence.2 2. Butler shows admirably well, that unless there were principles of action independent of self, there could be no pleasures and no happi¬ ness for self-love to watch over. A step farther would have led him to perceive, that self-love is altogether a secondary formation; the result of the joint operation of reason and habit upon the primary principles. It could not have existed without presupposing original appetites and or¬ ganic gratifications. Had he considered this part of the subject, he would have strengthened his case by showing that self-love is as truly a derived principle, not only as any of the social affections, but as any of the most confessedly ac¬ quired passions. It would appear clear, that as self-love is not divested of its self-regarding character by considering it as acquired, so the social affections do not lose any part of their dis¬ interested character, if they be considered as formed from simpler elements. Nothing would more tend to root out the old prejudice which treats a regard to self as analogous to a self-evi¬ dent principle, than the proof, that self-love is itself formed from certain original elements, and that a living being long subsists before its ap¬ pearance. 3 1 Sermon xiii. On the Love of God. * The very able work ascribed to Mr Hazlitt, entitled Essay on the Principles of Human Action, Lond. 1805, contains original views on this subject. * Compare this statement with the Stoical doctrine explained by Cicero in the book de Finihus, quoted above, of which it is the direct opposite. DISS. II. 2 z 362 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. 3. It must be owned that those parts of Butler’s themselves the end, or last object in view, of any discour ses which relate to the social affections other desire or aversion. Nothing stands between are more satisfactory than those which handle the moral sentiments and their object. They the question concerning the moral sentiments, are, as it were, in contact with the will. It is It is not that the real existence of the latter is this sort of mental position, if the expression may not as well made out as that of the former. In he pardoned, that explains, or seems to explain both cases he occupies the unassailable ground those characteristic properties which true plnlo- of an appeal to consciousness. All men (even sophers ascribe to them, and which all reflecting the worst) feel that they have a conscience and men feel to belong to them. Being the only de- disinterested affections. But he betrays a sense sires, aversions, sentiments, or emotions, which of the greater vagueness of his notions on this regard dispositions and actions, they neces- suhject. He falters as he approaches it. He sarily extend to the whole character and conduct. makes no attempt to determine in what state of Among motives to action, they alone are just- mind the action of conscience consists. He does ly considered as universal. They may and do not venture steadily to denote it by a name. He stand between any other practical principle fluctuates between different appellations, and and its object; while it is absolutely impos- multiplies the metaphors of authority and com- sible that another shall intercept their con- mand, without a simple exposition of that mental nection with the will. Be it observed, that operation which these metaphors should only though many passions prevail over them, no have illustrated. It commands other principles, other can act beyond its own appointed and li- But the question recurs, why, or how ? mited sphere; and that the prevalence itself, Some of his own hints, and some fainter inti- leaving the natural order undisturbed in any mations of Shaftesbury, might have led him to other part of the mind, is perceived to he a dis- what appears to he the true solution; which, order, when seen in another man, and felt to he perhaps from its extreme simplicity, has escaped so by the mind disordered, when the disorder him and his successors. The truth seems to he, subsides. Conscience may forbid the will to that the moral sentiments in their mature state, contribute to the gratification of a desire. No are a class of feelings which have no other object hut desire ever forbids will to obey conscience. the mental dispositions leading to voluntary action. This result of the peculiar relation of con- and the voluntary actions which flow from these dis- science to the will, justifies those metaphorical positions. We are pleased with some disposi- expressions which ascribe to it authority and the tions and actions, and displeased with others, in right of universal command. It is immutable ; for, ourselves and our fellows. We desire to culti- by the law which regulates all feelings, it must vate the dispositions, and to perform the actions, rest on action, which is its object, and beyond which we contemplate with satisfaction. These which it cannot look; and as it employs no objects, like all those of human appetite or de- means, it never can he transferred to nearer ob- sire, are sought for their own sake. The peculi- jects, in the way in which he who first desires arity of these desires is, that their gratification an object as a means of gratification, may come requires the use of no means. Nothing (unless it to seek it as his end. Another lemarkahle pecu- he a volition) is interposed between the desire liarity is bestowed on the moral feelings by the and the voluntary act. It is impossible, therefore, nature of their object. As the objects of all that these passions should undergo any change other desires are outward, the satisfaction of by transfer from the end to the means, as is the them may he frustrated by outward causes, case with other practical principles. On the other The moral sentiments may always he gratified, hand, as soon as they are fixed on these ends, because voluntary actions and moral dispositions they cannot regard any further object. When spring from within. No external circumstance another passion prevails over them, the end of affects them. Hence their independence. As the moral faculty is converted into a means of the moral sentiment needs no means, and the de¬ gratification. But volitions and actions are not sire is instantaneously followed by the volition, DISSERTATION SECOND. 363 it seems to be either that which first suggests the relation between command and obedience, or at least that which affords the simplest instance of it. It is therefore with the most rigorous precision that authority and universality are ascribed to them. Their only unfortunate pro¬ perty is their too frequent weakness; but it is apparent that it is from that circumstance alone that their failure arises. Thus considered, the language of Butler concerning conscience, that, “ had it strength as it has right it would govern the world,” which may seem to be only an effusion of generous feeling, proves to be a just statement of the nature and action of the highest of human faculties. The union of uni¬ versality, immutability, and independence, with direct action on the will, which distinguishes the moral sense from every other part of our practical nature, renders it scarcely metaphori¬ cal language to ascribe to it unbounded sove¬ reignty and awful authority over the whole of the world within;—shows that attributes, well denoted by terms significant of command and control, are, in fact, inseparable from it, or ra¬ ther constitute its very essence;—justifies those ancient moralists who represent it as alone se¬ curing, if not forming the moral liberty of man ; and finally, when religion rises from its roots in virtuous feeling, it clothes conscience with the sublime character of representing the divine pu¬ rity and majesty in the human soul. Its title is not impaired by any number of defeats; for every defeat necessarily disposes the disinterest¬ ed and dispassionate by-stander to wish that its force were strengthened: and though it may be doubted whether, consistently with the present constitution of human nature, it could he so in¬ vigorated as to be the only motive to action, yet every such by-stander rejoices at all acces¬ sions to its force; and would own, that man be¬ comes happier, more excellent, more estimable, more venerable, in proportion as conscience ac¬ quires a power of banishing malevolent passions, of strongly curbing all the private appetites, of influencing and guiding the benevolent affections themselves. Let it be carefully considered whether the same observations could be made with truth, or with plausibility, on any other part or ele¬ ment of the nature of man. They are entirely independent of the question, whether conscience be an inherent or an acquired principle. If it he inherent, that circumstance is, according to the common modes of thinking, a sufficient proof of its title to veneration. But if pro¬ vision be made in the constitution and circum¬ stances of all men, for uniformly producing it, by processes similar to those which produce other acquired sentiments, may not our rever¬ ence be augmented by admiration of that su¬ preme wisdom which, in such mental contri¬ vances, yet more brightly than in the lower world of matter, accomplishes mighty purposes by instruments so simple ? Should these specu¬ lations be thought to have any solidity by those who are accustomed to such subjects, it would be easy to unfold and apply them so fully, that they may be thoroughly apprehended by every intelligent person. 4. The most palpable defect of Butler’s scheme is, that it affords no answer to the question, “ What is the distinguishing quality common to all right actions ?” If it were answered, “ Their criterion is, that they are approved and com¬ manded by conscience,” the answerer would find that he was involved in a vicious circle; for conscience itself could be no otherwise de¬ fined than as the faculty which approves and commands right actions. There are few circumstances more remarkable than the small number of Butler’s followers in Ethics; and it is perhaps still more observable, that his opinions were not so much rejected as overlooked. It is an instance of the importance of style. No thinker so great was ever so bad a writer. Indeed, the ingenious apologies which have been lately attempted for this defect, amount to no more than that his power of thought was too much for his skill in language. How gene¬ ral must the reception have been of truths so cer¬ tain and momentous as those contained in But¬ ler’s Discourses,—with how much more clear ness must they have appeared to his own great understanding, if he had possessed the strength and distinctness with which Hobbes enforces odious falsehood, or the unspeakable charm of that transparent diction which clothed the un¬ fruitful paradoxes of Berkeley ! 364 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. HUTCHESON.* This ingenious writer began to try bis own strength by private Letters, written in his early youth to Dr Clarke, the metaphysical patriarch of his time; on whom young philosophers seem to have considered themselves as possessing a claim, which he had too much goodness to reject. His correspondence with Hutcheson is lost; but we may judge of its spirit by his answers to Butler, and by one to Mr Henry Home,1 2 * afterwards Lord Kames, then a young adventurer in the prevalent speculations. Nearly at the same period with Butler’s first publication,5 the writ¬ ings of Hutcheson began to show coincidences with him, indicative of the tendency of moral theory to a new form, to which an impulse had been given by Shaftesbury, and which was roused to activity by the adverse system of Clarke. Lord Moles worth, the friend of Shaftesbury, patron¬ ised Hutcheson, and even criticised his manu¬ script. Though a Presbyterian, he was be¬ friended by King, archbishop of Dublin, him¬ self a metaphysician ; and he was aided by Mr Synge, afterwards a bishop, to whom specula¬ tions somewhat similar to his own had occurred. Butler and Hutcheson coincided in the two important positions, that disinterested affections, and a distinct moral faculty, are essential parts of human nature. Hutcheson is a chaste and simple writer, who imbibed the opinions, with¬ out the literary faults of his master, Shaftesbury. He has a clearness of expression, and fulness of illustration, which are wanting in Butler. But he is inferior to both these writers in the appearance at least of originality, and to Butler especially in that philosophical courage which, when it discovers the fountains of truth and falsehood, leaves others to follow the streams. He states as strongly as Butler, that “ the same cause which determines us to pursue happiness for ourselves, determines us both to esteem and benevolence on their proper occasions—even the very frame of our nature.”4 It is vain, as he justly observes, for the patrons of a refined selfishness to pretend that we pursue the happi¬ ness of others for the sake of the pleasure which we derive from it; since it is apparent that there could be no such pleasure if there had been no previous affection. “ Had we no affection dis¬ tinct from self-love, nothing could raise a desire of the happiness of others, but when viewed as a mean of our own.”4 He seems to have been the first who entertained just notions of the formation of the secondary desires, which had been overlooked by Butler. “ There must arise, in consequence of our original desires, secondary desires of every thing useful to gratify the pri¬ mary desire. Thus, as soon as we apprehend the use of wealth or power to gratify our original de¬ sires, we also desire them. From their univer¬ sality as means arises the general prevalence of these desires of wealth and power.”8 Proceed¬ ing farther in his zeal against the selfish system than Lord Shaftesbury, who seems ultimately to rest the reasonableness of benevolence on its subserviency to the happiness of the individual, he represents the moral faculty to be, as well as self-love and benevolence, a calm general im¬ pulse, which may and does impel a good man to sacrifice not only happiness, but even life itself, to virtue. As Mr Locke had spoken of an internal sensation,—Lord Shaftesbury once or twice of a reflex sense, and once of a moral sense,— Hutcheson, who had a steadier, if not a clear¬ er view of the nature of conscience than But¬ ler, calls it a Moral Sense; a name which quickly became popular, and continues to he a part of philosophical language. By sense, he understood a capacity of receiving ideas, to¬ gether with pleasures and pains, from a class of 1 Born in Ireland in 1694; died at Glasgow in 1747- * Woodhouselee’s Life of Lord Karnes, vol. I. Append. No. 3. , * The first edition of Butler’s Sermons was published in 1726, in which year also appeared the second edition or Hutcne- son’s Inquiry into Beauty and Virtue. The Sermons had been preached some years before, though there is no likelihood that the contents could have reached a young teacher at Dublin. The place of Hutcheson’s birth is not mentioned ni any ac¬ count known to me. Ireland may be truly said to be “ incuriosa suornm." 4 Inquiry, p. 152. & Essay on the Passions, p. 17. * Ibid- P- 8. DISSERTATION SECOND. 365 objects. The term moral was used to describe the particular class in question. It implied only that conscience was a separate element in our nature, and that it was not a state or act of the understanding. According to him, it also implied that it was an original and implanted principle; but every other part of his theory might be embraced by those who hold it to be derivative. The object of moral approbation, according to him, is general benevolence ; and he carries this generous error so far as to deny that pru¬ dence, as long as it regards ourselves, can be morally approved;—an assertion contradicted by every man’s feelings, and to which we owe the Dissertation on the Nature of Virtue which But¬ ler annexed to his Analogy. By proving that all virtuous actions produce general good, he fancied that he had proved the necessity of regarding the general good in every act of virtue;—an in¬ stance of that confusion of the theory of moral sentiments with the criterion of moral actions, against which the reader was warned at the open¬ ing of this Dissertation, as fatal to Ethical Philo¬ sophy. He is chargeable, like Butler, with a vicious circle, in describing virtuous acts as those which are approved by the moral sense, while he at the same time describes the moral sense as the faculty which perceives and feels the morality of actions. He was the father of speculative philosophy in Scotland, at least in modern times; for though in the beginning of the sixteenth century the Scotch are said to have been known through¬ out Europe by their unmeasured passion for dialectical subtilties,1 and though this metaphy¬ sical taste was nourished by the controversies which followed the Reformation, yet it languish¬ ed, with every other intellectual taste and talent, from the Restoration, first silenced by civil dis orders, and afterwards repressed by an exem¬ plary but unlettered clergy, till the philosophy of Shaftesbury was brought by Hutcheson from Ireland. We are told by the writer of his Life, (a fine piece of philosophical biography) that “ he had a remarkable degree of rational enthusiasm for learning, liberty, religion, virtue, and human happiness2 that he taught in public with per¬ suasive eloquence; that his instructive conversa¬ tion was at once lively and modest; that he unit¬ ed pure manners with a kind disposition. What wonder that such a man should have spread the love of knowledge and virtue around him, and should have rekindled in his adopted country a relish for the sciences which he cultivated ! To him may also be ascribed that proneness to mul¬ tiply ultimate and original principles in human nature, which characterized the Scottish School till the second extinction of a passion for meta¬ physical speculation in Scotland. A careful perusal of the writings of this now little studied philosopher will satisfy the well-qualified reader, that Dr Adam Smith’s ethical speculations are not so unsuggested as they are beautiful. BERKELEY.* This great metaphysician was so little a mo- as a touchstone of metaphysical sagacity ; show- ralist, that it requires the attraction of his name ing those to be altogether without it, who, like to excuse its introduction here. His Theory of Johnson and Beattie, believed that his specula- Vision contains a great discovery in mental phi- tions were sceptical, that they implied any dis- losophy. His immaterialism is chiefly valuable trust in the senses, or that they had the smallest 1 The character given of the Scotch by the famous and unfortunate Servetus, in his edition of Ptolemy, (1533) is in many respects curious. “ Gallis amicissimi, Anglorumque regi maxime infesti. Subita ingema et in ultionem prona, fero- ciaque. In bello fortes, inedke, vigiliae, algoris patientissimi, decenti forma sed cultu neghgention; invidi natura et caeterorum mortalium contemptores i ostentant plus nimio nobilitatem suam, et in summa etiam egcstate suum genus ad regiam stirpem referunt, nec non dialecticis argutiis sim blandiuntur.”—Subita ingenia is an expression equivalen o le “ Praefervidum Scotorum ingenium” of Buchanan. Churchill almost agrees in words with Seivetus. Whose lineage springs From great and glorious, though forgotten kings. And the strong antipathy of the late King George III. to what he called “ Scotch Metaphysics, proves t ie permanency of the last part of the national character. 2 Life by Dr Leechman, prefixed to Hutcheson’s System of Moral Philosophy, 1755. * Born near Thomastown in Ireland, in 1684 ; died at Oxford in 1753. 366 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. tendency to disturb reasoning or alter conduct. Ancient learning, exact science, polished socie¬ ty, modern literature, and the fine arts, contrib¬ uted to adorn and enrich the mind of this ac¬ complished man. All his contemporaries agreed with the satirist in ascribing I To Berkeley every virtue under heaven. Adverse factions and hostile wits concurred only in loving, admiring, and contributing to advance him. The severe sense of Swift endur¬ ed his visions; the modest Addison endeavour¬ ed to reconcile Clarke to his ambitious specula¬ tions. His character converted the satire of Pope into fervid praise. Even the discerning, fastidious, and turbulent Atterbury said, after an interview with him, “ So much understand¬ ing, so much knowledge, so much innocence, and such humility, I did not think had been the portion of any but angels, till I saw this gentle¬ man.”1 “ Lord Bathurst told me, that the Members of the Scriblerus Club being met at his house at dinner, they agreed to rally Berke¬ ley, who was also his guest, on his scheme at Bermudas. Berkeley, having listened to the many lively things they had to say, begged to be heard in his turn, and displayed his plan with such an astonishing and animating force of eloquence and enthusiasm, that they were struck dumb, and after some pause, rose all up together, with earnestness exclaiming, c Let us set out with him immediately.’”2 It was when thus beloved and celebrated that he conceived, at the age of forty-five, the design of devoting his life to reclaim and convert the natives of North America; and he employed as much influence and solicitation as common men do for their most prized objects, in obtaining leave to resign his dignities arid revenues, to quit his accom¬ plished and affectionate friends, and to bury himself in what must have seemed an intellec¬ tual desert. After four years’ residence at New¬ port in Rhode Island, he was compelled, by the refusal of Government to furnish him with funds for his College, to forego his work of he¬ roic, or rather godlike benevolence; though not without some consoling forethought of the for¬ tune of the country where he had sojourned. Westward the course of empire takes its way. The first four acts already past, A fifth shall close the drama with the day, Time’s noblest offspring is its last. Thus disappointed in his ambition of keeping a School for Savage children, at a salary of a hun¬ dred pounds by the year, he was received, on his return, with open arms by the philosophical queen, at whose metaphysical parties he made one with Sherlock, who, as well as Smalridge, was his supporter, and with Hoadley, who, fol¬ lowing Clarke, was his antagonist. By her in¬ fluence, he was made bishop of Cloyne. It is one of his highest boasts, that though of Eng¬ lish extraction, he was a true Irishman, and the first eminent Protestant, after the unhappy contest at the Revolution, who avowed his love for all his countrymen. He asked, <{ Whether their habitations and furniture were not more sordid than those of the savage Americans?”3 “ Whether a scheme for the welfare of this nation should not take in the whole inhabitants ?” and, “ Whether it was a vain attempt^ to project the flourishing of our Protestant gentry^ exclusive of the bulk of the natives ?”4 He proceeds to pro¬ mote the reformation suggested in this pregnant question by a series of Queries, intimating, with the utmost skill and address, every reason that proves the necessity, and the safety, and the wisest mode of adopting his suggestion. He contributed, by a truly Christian address to the Roman Catholics of his diocese, to their perfect quiet during the rebellion of 1745; and soon after published a letter to the clergy of that per¬ suasion, beseeching them to inculcate indus¬ try among their flocks, for which he received their thanks. He tells them, that it was a say¬ ing among the negro slaves, “ if negro were not negro, Irishman would be negro.” It is difficult to read these proofs of benevolence and fore¬ sight without emotion, at the moment when,5 after a lapse of near a century, his suggestions have been at length, at the close of a struggle of twenty-five years, adopted, by the admis- * See his Querist, 358; published in 1735. 4 Ibid. 255. 4 April 1829. 1 Duncombe’s Letters, 106, 107. * Warton on Pope. DISSERTATION SECOND. 367 si on of the whole Irish nation to the privileges of the British Constitution. The patriotism of Berkeley was not, like that of Swift, tainted by disappointed ambition; nor was it, like Swift’s, confined to a colony of English Pro¬ testants. Perhaps the Querist contains more hints, then original, still unapplied in legislation and political economy, than are to be found in any equal space. From the writings of his advanced years, when he chose a medical Tract1 * 3 to be the vehicle of his philosophical reflections, though it cannot be said that he relinquished his early opinions, it is at least apparent that his mind had received a new bent, and was habitually turned from reasoning towards con¬ templation. His immaterialism indeed modest¬ ly appears, but only to purify and elevate our thoughts, and to fix them on Mind, the para¬ mount and primeval principle of all things. “ Perhaps,” says he, “ the truth about innate ideas may be, that there are properly no ideas or passive objects in the mind but what are de¬ rived from sense, but that there are also, be¬ sides these, her own acts and operations—such are notionsa statement which seems once more to admit general conceptions, and which might have served, as well as the parallel pass¬ age of Leibnitz, as the basis of the modern phi¬ losophy of Germany. From these compositions of his old age, he appears then to have recurred with fondness to Plato and the later Platonists; writers from whose mere reasonings an intellect so acute could hardly hope for an argumentative satisfaction of all its difficulties, and whom he probably rather studied as a means of inuring his mind to objects beyond the visible diurnal sphere, and of attaching it, through frequent meditation, to that perfect and transcendent goodness to which his moral feelings always pointed, and which they incessantly strove to grasp. His mind, enlarging as it rose, at length receives every theist, however imperfect his be¬ lief, to a communion in its philosophic piety. “ Truth,” he beautifully concludes, “ is the cry of all, but the game of a few. Certainly, where it is the chief passion, it does not give way to vulgar cares, nor is it contented with a little ardour in the early time of life ; active perhaps to pursue, but not so fit to weigh and revise. He that would make a real progress in know¬ ledge, must dedicate his age as well as youth, the later growth as well as first fruits, at the altar of Truth.” So did Berkeley, and such were almost his latest words. His general principles of Ethics may be shortly stated in his own words :—“ As God is a being of infinite goodness, his end is the good of his creatures. The general wellbeing of all men of all nations, of all ages of the world, is that which he designs should be procured by the concur¬ ring actions of each individual.” Having stated that this end can be pursued only in one of two ways—either by computing the consequences of each action, or by obeying rules which generally tend to happiness—and having shown the first to be impossible, he rightly infers, “ that the end to which God requires the concurrence of human actions, must be carried on by the ob¬ servation of certain determinate and universal rules or moral precepts, which in their own na¬ ture have a necessary tendency to promote the wellbeing of mankind, taking in all nations and ages, from the beginning to the end of the world.”8 A romance, of which a journey to an Utopia, in the centre of Africa, forms the chief part, called The Adventures of Signor Gau- dentio di Lucca, has been commonly ascribed to him; probably on no other ground than its union of pleasing invention with benevolence and ele¬ gance.5 Of the exquisite grace and beauty of his diction, no man accustomed to English com¬ position can need to be informed. His works are, beyond dispute, the finest models of phi¬ losophical style since Cicero. Perhaps they surpass those of the orator, in the wonderful art by which the fullest light is thrown on the most minute and evanescent parts of the most subtile of human conceptions. Perhaps he also surpassed Cicero in the charm of sim¬ plicity, a quality eminently found in Irish wri¬ ters before the end of the eighteenth century; conspicuous in the masculine severity of Swift, 1 Siris, or Reflections on Tar Water. * Sermon in Trinity College Chapel, on Passive Obedience, 1712. 3 Gentleman's Magazine, January 1777* 368 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. in the Platonic fancy of Berkeley, in the native tenderness and elegance of Goldsmith, and not withholding its attractions from Hutcheson and Leland, writers of classical taste, though of inferior power. The two Irish philosophers of the eighteenth century may be said to have co-operated in calling forth the metaphysical genius of Scotland; for, though Hutcheson spread the taste, and furnished the principles, yet Berkeley undoubtedly produced the scep¬ ticism of Hume, which stimulated the instinc¬ tive school to activity, and was thought incap¬ able of confutation, otherwise than by their doctrines. DAVID HUME.1 The Life of Mr Hume, written by himself, is remarkable above most, if not all writings of that sort, for hitting the degree of interest between coldness and egotism which becomes a modest man in speaking of his private history. Few writers, whose opinions were so obnoxious, have more perfectly escaped every personal imputa¬ tion. Very few men of so calm a character have been so warmly beloved. That he approached to the character of a perfectly good and wise man, is an affectionate exaggeration, for which his friend Dr Smith, in the first moments of his sorrow, may well he excused.2 * But such a praise can never be earned without passing through either of the extremes of fortune; with¬ out standing the test of temptations, dangers, and sacrifices. It may he said with truth, that the private character of Mr Hume exhibited all the virtues which a man of reputable station, under a mild government, in the quiet times of a civilized country, has often the opportunity to practise. He showed no want of the qualities which fit men for more severe trials. Though others had warmer affections, no man was a kinder relation, a more unwearied friend, or more free from meanness and malice. His cha¬ racter was so simple, that he did not even affect modesty; hut neither his friendships nor his de¬ portment were changed by a fame which filled all Europe. His good nature, his plain manners, and his active kindness, procured him at Paris the enviable name of the good David, from a society not so alive to goodness, as without reason to place it at the head of the qualities of a celebrated man.s His whole character is faith¬ fully and touchingly represented in the story of La Roche,4 where Mr Mackenzie, without con¬ cealing Mr HumeV opinions, brings him into contact with scenes of tender piety, and yet pre¬ serves the interest inspired by genuine and un¬ alloyed, though moderated feelings and affec¬ tions. The amiable and venerable patriarch of Scottish Literature was averse from the opinions of the philosopher on whom he has composed this best panegyric. He tells us that he read the manuscript to Dr Smith, “ who declared he did not find a syllable to object to, hut added, with his characteristic absence of mind, that he was surprised he had never heard of the anecdote be¬ fore.”5 So lively was the delineation thus sanc¬ tioned by the most natural of all testimonies. Mr Mackenzie indulges his own religious feel¬ ings by modestly intimating, that Dr Smith’s answer seemed to justify the last words of the tale, “ that there were moments when the phi¬ losopher recalled to his mind the venerable fi¬ gure of the good La Roche, and wished that he had never doubted.” To those who are strangers to the seductions of paradox, to the intoxication of fame, and to the bewitchment of prohibited opinions, it must be unaccountable, that he who revered benevolence should, without apparent regret, cease to see it on the Throne of the Uni¬ verse. It is a matter of wonder that his habitual esteem for every fragment and shadow of moral excellence should not lead him to envy those who contemplated its perfection in that living and paternal character which gives it a power over the human heart. On the other hand, if we had no experience 1 Born at Edinburgh in 1711; died there in 1776- 2 Dr Smith’s Letter to Mr Strahan. annexed to the Life of Hume. * See Notes and Illustrations, note P. 4 Mirror, Nos. 42, 43, 44. 6 Mackenzie’s Life of John Home, p. 21. DISSERTATION SECOND. 369 of the power of. opposite opinions in producing irreconcilable animosities, we might have hoped that those who retained such high privileges would have looked with more compassion than dislike on a virtuous man who had lost them. In such cases it is too little remembered, that repugnance to hypocrisy, and impatience of long concealment, are the qualities of the best formed minds; and that, if the publication of some doctrines proves often painful and mis¬ chievous, the habitual suppression of opinion is injurious to reason, and very dangerous to sin¬ cerity. Practical questions thus arise, so diffi¬ cult and perplexing, that their determination generally depends on the boldness or timidity of the individual,—on his tenderness for the feel¬ ings of the good, or his greater reverence for the free exercise of reason. The time is not yet come when the noble maxim of Plato, “ that every soul is unwillingly deprived of truth,” will be practically and heartily applied by men to the honest opponents who differ from them most widely. In his twenty-seventh year he published at London the Treatise of Human Nature, the first systematic attack on all the principles of know¬ ledge and belief, and the most formidable, if universal scepticism could ever be more than a mere exercise of ingenuity.1 This memorable work was reviewed in a Journal of that time,2 in a criticism not distinguished by ability, which affects to represent the style of a very clear writer as unintelligible—sometimes from a pur¬ pose to insult, but oftener from sheer dulness— which is unaccountably silent respecting the consequences of a sceptical system; and which concludes with a prophecy so much at variance with the general tone of the article, that it would seem to be added by a different hand. “ It bears incontestable marks of a great capa¬ city, of a soaring genius, but young, and Rot yet thoroughly practised. Time and use may ripen these qualities in the author, and we shall probably have reason to consider this, com¬ pared with his later productions, in the same light as we view the juvenile works of Milton, or the first manner of Raphael.” The great speculator did not, in this work, amuse himself, like Bayle, with dialectical ex¬ ercises, which only inspire a disposition towards doubt, by showing in detail the uncertainty of most opinions. He aimed at proving, not that nothing was known, but that nothing could be known;—from the structure of the under¬ standing to demonstrate, that we are doomed for ever to dwell in absolute and universal ig¬ norance. It is true that such a system of uni¬ versal scepticism never can be more than an in¬ tellectual amusement, an exercise of subtilty; of which the only use is to check dogmatism, but which perhaps oftener provokes and pro¬ duces that much more common evil. As those dictates of experience which regulate conduct must be the objects of belief, all objections which attack them in common with the prin¬ ciples of reasoning must be utterly ineffectual. Whatever attacks every principle of belief can destroy none. As long as the foundations of knowledge are allowed to remain on the same level (be it called of certainty or uncertainty) with the maxims of life, the whole system of human conviction must continue undisturbed. When the sceptic boasts of having involved the results of experience and the elements of geometry in the same ruin with the doctrines of religion and the principles of philosophy, he may be answered. That no dogmatist ever claimed more than the same degree of certainty for these various con¬ victions and opinions; and that his scepticism, therefore, leaves them in the relative condition in which it found them. No man knew better, or owned more frankly than Mr Hume, that to 1 Sextus, a physician of the empirical, i. e. anti-theoretical school, who lived at Alexandria in the reign of Antoninus f Pius, has preserved the reasonings of the ancient Sceptics as they were to be found in their most improved state, in the writings of /Enesidemus, a Cretan, who was a Professor in the same city, soon after the reduction of Egypt into a Homan province. The greater part of the grounds of doubt are very shallow and popular. There are, among them, intimations of the argument against a necessary connection of causes with effects, afterwards better presented by Glanville in his Scepsis Sdentifica. See Notes and Illustrations, note Q,. • History of the Works of the Learned, November and December 1739? p. 353—404. This Heview is attributed by some (Chalmers, Biographical Dictionary) to Warburton, but certainly without foundation. DISS. II 3 A 370 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. this answer there is no serious reply. Univer¬ sal scepticism involves a contradiction in terms. It is a belief that there can be no belief. It is an attempt of the mind to act without its structure, and by other laws than those to which its nature has subjected its operations. To reason without assenting to the principles on which reasoning is founded, is not unlike an effort to feel without nerves, or to move without muscles. No man can be allowed to be an opponent in reasoning, who does not set out with admitting all the principles, without the admission of which it is impossible to reason.1 It is indeed a puerile, nay, in the eye of wisdom, a childish play, to attempt either to establish or to confute principles by argument, which every step of that argument must pre¬ suppose. The only difference between the two cases is, that he who tries to prove them can do so only by first taking them for granted; and that he who attempts to impugn them falls at the very first step into a contradiction, from which he never can rise. It must, however, be allowed, that universal scepticism has practical consequences of a very mischievous nature. This is because its univer¬ sality is not steadily kept in view, and con¬ stantly borne in mind. If it were, the above short and plain remark would be an effectual antidote to the poison. But in practice, it is an armoury from which weapons are taken to be employed against some opinions, while it is hidden from notice that the same weapon would equally cut down every other conviction. It is thus that Mr Hume’s theory of causation is used as an answer to arguments for the exist¬ ence of the Deity, without warning the reader that it would equally lead him not to expect that the sun will rise to-morrow. It must also he added, that those who are early accustomed to dispute first principles are never likely to acquire, in a sufficient degree, that earnestness and that sincerity, that strong love of truth, and that conscientious solicitude for the formation of just opinions, which are not the least virtues of men, hut of which the cultivation is the more especial duty of all who call themselves philo¬ sophers. 8 It is not an uninteresting fact, that Mr Hume having been introduced by Lord Kames (then Mr Henry Home) to Dr Butler, sent a copy of his Treatise to that philosopher at the moment of his preferment to the bishopric of Durham; and that the perusal of it did not deter the philosophic prelate from “ everywhere recom¬ mending Mr Hume’s Moral and Political Es¬ says,”1 * 3 published two years afterwards;—Essays which it would indeed have been unworthy of such a man not to have liberally commended, for they, and those which followed them, what¬ ever may he thought of the contents of some of them, must be ever regarded as the best models in any language, of the short hut full, of the clear and agreeable, though deep discussion of difficult questions. Mr Hume considered his Enquiry concerning the Principles of Morals as the best of his wri¬ tings. It is very creditable to his character, that he should have looked hack with most complacency on a Tract the least distinguished by originality, and the least tainted with para¬ dox, among his philosophical works; hut deserv¬ ing of all commendation for the elegant perspi¬ cuity of the style, and the novelty of illustration and inference with which he unfolded to general readers a doctrine too simple, too certain, and too important, to remain till his time undis¬ covered among philosophers. His diction has, indeed, neither the grace of Berkeley nor the strength of Hobbes; hut it is without the verbo¬ sity of the former, or the rugged sternness of the latter. His manner is more lively, more easy, more ingratiating, and, if the word may 1 This maxim, which contains a sufficient answer to all universal scepticism, or, in other words, to all scepticism properly so called, is significantly conveyed in the quaint title of an old and rare book, entitled, Sciti, sivc Sceptices et Scepticorum a Jure Disputationis Exclusio, by Thomas White, the metaphysician of the English Catholics in modern times—“Fortu¬ nately,” says the illustrious sceptic himself, “ since Reason is incapable of dispelling these clouds. Nature herself suffices for that purpose, and cures me of this philosophical delirium" (Treatise of Human Nature, I. 467); almost in the sublime and immor¬ tal words of Pascal: La Raison confond les Dogmatistes, et la Nature les Sceptiques. * It would be an act of injustice to those readers who are not acquainted with that valuable volume entitled, Essays on the Formation of Opinions, not to refer them to it as enforcing that neglected part of morality. To it may be added, a masterly article in the Westminster Review, occasioned by the Essays. * Woodhouselee’s Life of Kames, I. 86, 104. DISSERTATION SECOND. 371 be so applied, more amusing, than that of any other metaphysical writer.1 2 He knew himself too well to be, as Dr Johnson asserted, an imi¬ tator of Voltaire; who, as it were, embodied in his own person all the wit and quickness and versatile ingenuity of a people which surpasses other nations in these brilliant qualities. If he must be supposed to have had an eye on any French writer, it would be a more plausible guess, that he sometimes copied, with a tem¬ perate hand, the unexpected thoughts and famil¬ iar expressions of Fontenelle. Though he care¬ fully weeded his writings in their successive editions, yet they still contain Scotticisms and Gallicisms enough to employ the successors of such critics as those who exulted over the Pata- vinity of the Roman Historian. His own great and modest mind would have been satisfied with the praise which cannot be withheld from him, that there is no writer in our language who, through long works, is more agreeable; and it is no derogation from him, that, as a Scots¬ man, he did not reach those native and secret beauties, characteristical of a language, which are never attained, in elaborate composition, but by a very small number of those who famil¬ iarly converse in it from infancy. The Enquiry affords perhaps the best speci¬ men of his style. In substance, its chief merit is the proof, from an abundant enumeration of particulars, that all the qualities and actions of the mind which are generally approved by man¬ kind agree in the circumstance of being useful to society. In the proof, (scarcely necessary) that benevolent affections and actions have that tendency, he asserts the real existence of these affections with unusual warmth; and he well abridges some of the most forcible arguments of Butler, * whom it is remarkable that he does not mention. To show the importance of his prin¬ ciple, he very unnecessarily distinguishes the comprehensive duty of justice, from other parts of morality, as an artificial virtue, for which our respect is solely derived from notions of utility. If all things were in such plenty that there could never be a want, or if men were so benevolent as to provide for the wants of others as much as for their own, there would, says he, in neither case be any justice, because there would be no need for it. But it is evident that the same reasoning is applicable to every good affection and right action. None of them could exist if there were no scope for their exercise. If there were no suffering, there could be no pity and no relief. If there were no offences, there could be no placability. If there were no crimes, there could be no mercy. Temperance, prudence, pa¬ tience, magnanimity, are qualities of which the value depends on the evils by which they are respectively exercised.3 4 On purity of manners, it must be owned that Mr Hume, though he controverts no rule, yet treats vice with too much indulgence. It was his general disposition to distrust virtues which are liable to exaggeration, and may be easily counterfeited. The ascetic pursuit of purity, and hypocritical pretences to patriotism, had too much withdrawn the respect of his equally calm and sincere nature from these excellent virtues; more especially as severity in both these respects was often at apparent variance with affection, which can neither be long assumed, nor ever overvalued. Yet it was singular that he who, in his Essay on Polygamy and Divorce,* had so 1 These commendations are so far from being at variance with the remarks of the late most ingenious Dr Thomas Brown, on Mr Hume’s “ mode of writing,” (Enquiry into the Relation of Cause and Effect, 3d ed. 327) that they may rather be re¬ garded as descriptive of those excellencies of which the excess produced the faults of Mr Hume as a mere searcher and teacher; justly, though perhaps severely, animadverted on by Dr Brown. 2 Enquiry, sect. ii. part i., especially the concluding paragraphs; those which precede being more his own. 3 “ Si nobis, cum ex hac vita migraverimus, in beatorum insulis, ut fabulae ferunt, immortale sevum degere liceret, quid opus esset eloquentia, cum judicia nulla fierent ? aut ipsis etiam virtutibus ? Nec enim fortitudine indigeremus, nullo pro- posito aut laboreaut periculo; nec justitia, cum esset nihil quod appeteretur alieni; nec temperantia, quae regeret eas quae nullae essent libidines: ne prudentia quidem egeremus, nullo proposito delectu bonorum et malorum. Una igitur essemus beati cogmtioneyerum et scientia.” (Cicero. Fragm. ap. Augustin, de Trinit. iv. 2.) Cicero is more extensive, and therefore more consistent, than Hume ; but his enumeration errs both by excess and defect. He supposes knowledge to render beings happy in this imaginary state, without stooping to inquire how. He omits a virtue which might well exist in it, though we cannot conceive its formation in such a state—the delight in each other’s wellbeing ; and he omits a conceivable though unknown vice, that of unmixed ill-will, which would render such a state a hell to the wretch who harboured the malevolence. 4 Essays and Treatises, vol I. 372 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. well shown the connection of domestic ties with the outward order of society, should not have perceived their deeper and closer relation to all the social feelings of human nature. It cannot he enough regretted, that, in an Enquiry wiit- ten with a very moral purpose, his habit of ma¬ king truth attractive, by throwing over her the dress of paradox, should have given him for a moment the appearance of weighing the mere amusements of society and conversation against domestic fidelity, which is the preserver of do¬ mestic affection, the source of parental fondness and filial regard, and, indirectly, of all the kind¬ ness which exists between human beings. That families are schools where the infant heart learns to love, and that pure manners are the ce¬ ment which alone holds these schools together, are truths so certain, that it is wonderful he should not have betrayed a stronger sense of their importance. No one could so well have proved that all the virtues of that class, in their various orders and degrees, minister to the be¬ nevolent affections; and that every act which separates the senses from the affections tends, in some degree, to deprive kindness of its natural auxiliary, and to lessen its prevalence in the world. It did not require his sagacity to discover that the gentlest and tenderest feelings flourish only under the stern guardianship of these severe virtues. Perhaps his philosophy was loosened, though his life was untainted, by that universal and undistinguishing profligacy which prevailed on the Continent, from the regency of the Duke of Orleans to the French revolution; the most dissolute period of European history, at least since the Roman emperors.1 At Rome, indeed, the connection of licentiousness with cruelty, which, though scarcely traceable in individuals, is generally very observable in large masses, bore a fearful testimony to the value of austere purity. The alliance of these remote vices seemed to be broken in the time of Mr Hume. Pleasure, in a more improved state of society, seemed to return to her more natural union with kindness and tenderness, as well as with refine¬ ment and politeness. Had he lived fourteen years longer, however, he would have seen, that the virtues which guard the natural seminaries of the affections are their only true and lasting friends. The demand of all well-informed men for the improvement of civil institutions—the demand of classes of men growing in intelligence, to be delivered from a degrading inferiority, and admitted to a share of political power propor¬ tioned to their new importance, being feebly yet violently resisted by those ruling Castes who neither knew howto yield nor how to withstand— being also attended by very erroneous principles of legislation, having suddenly broken down the barriers (imperfect as these were) of law and government, led to popular excesses, desolat¬ ing wars, and a military dictatorship, which for a long time threatened to defeat the reforma¬ tion, and to disappoint the hopes of mankind. This tremendous convulsion threw a fearful light on the ferocity which lies hid under the arts and pleasures of corrupted nations; as earthquakes and volcanoes disclose the layers which compose the deeper parts of our planet, beneath a fertile and flowery surface. A part of this dreadful re¬ sult may be ascribed, not improbably, to that relaxation of domestic ties, unhappily natural to the populace of vast capitals, and at that time countenanced and aggravated by the example of their superiors. Another part doubtless arose from the barbarizing power of absolute govern¬ ment, or, in other words, of injustice in high places. A very large portion attests, as strongly as Roman history, though in a somewhat differ¬ ent manner, the humanizing efficacy of the family virtues, by the consequences of the want of them in the higher classes, whose profuse and ostenta¬ tious sensuality inspired the laborious and suffer¬ ing portion of mankind with contempt, disgust, envy, and hatred. The Enquiry is disfigured by another speck of more frivolous paradox. It consists in the at¬ tempt to give the name of virtue to qualities of the understanding; and it would not have de¬ served the single remark about to be made on it, had it been the paradox of an inferior man. He has altogether omitted the circumstance on which depends the difference of our sentiments regarding moral and intellectual qualities. We 1 See Notes and Illustrations, note It. DISSERTATION SECOND. 373 admire intellectual excellence, but we bestow no moral approbation on it. Such approbation has no tendency directly to increase it, because it is not voluntary. We cultivate our natural dis¬ position to esteem and love benevolence and justice, because these moral sentiments, and the expression of them, directly and materially dis¬ pose others, as well as ourselves, to cultivate these two virtues. We cultivate a natural anger against oppression, which guards our¬ selves against the practice of that vice, and be¬ cause the manifestation of it deters others from its exercise. The first rude resentment of a child is against every instrument of hurt. We confine it to intentional hurt, when we are taught by experience that it prevents only that species of hurt; and at last it is still further li¬ mited to wrong done to ourselves or others, and in that case becomes a purely moral sentiment. We morally approve industry, desire of know¬ ledge, love of truth, and all the habits by which the understanding is strengthened and rectified, because their formation is subject to the will.1 But we do not feel a moral anger against folly or ignorance, because they are involuntary. No one but the religious persecutor, a mischievous and overgrown child, wreaks his vengeance on involuntary, inevitable, compulsory acts or states of the understanding, which are no more affected by blame than the stone which the foolish child beats for hurting him. Reasonable men apply to every thing which they wish to move, the agent which is capable of moving it;—force to outward substances, arguments to the under¬ standing, and blame, together with all other motives, whether moral or personal, to the will alone. It is as absurd to entertain an abhor¬ rence of intellectual inferiority or error, however extensive or mischievous, as it would be to cherish a warm indignation against earthquakes or hurricanes. It is singular that a philosopher who needed the most liberal toleration should, by representing states of the understanding as moral or immoral, have offered the most philo¬ sophical apology for persecution. That general utility constitutes a uniform ground of moral distinctions, is a part of Mr Hume’s ethical theory which never can be im¬ pugned, until some example can be produced of a virtue generally pernicious, or of a vice gene¬ rally beneficial. The religious philosopher who, with Butler, holds that benevolence must be the actuating principle of the Divine mind, will, with Berkeley, maintain that pure benevolence can prescribe no rules of human conduct but such as are beneficial to men; thus bestowing on the theory of Moral Distinctions the certainty of demonstration in the eyes of all who believe in God. The other question of moral philosophy which relates to the theory of Moral Approbation, has been by no means so distinctly and satisfactorily handled by Mr Hume. His general doctrine is, that an interest in the wellbeing of others, im¬ planted by nature, which he calls Sympathy in his Treatise of Human Nature, and much less happily Benevolence in his subsequent Enquiry,* prompts us to be pleased with all generally be¬ neficial actions. In this respect his doctrine nearly resembles that of Hutcheson. He does not trace his principle through the variety of forms which our moral sentiments assume. There are very important parts of them, of which it affords no solution. For example, though he truly represents our approbation, in others, of qualities useful to the individual, as a proof of benevolence, he makes no attempt to explain our moral approbation of such virtues as temperance and fortitude in ourselves. He entirely overlooks that consciousness of the rightful supremacy of the moral faculty over every other principle of human action, without an ex¬ planation of which, ethical theory is wanting in one of its vital organs. Notwithstanding these considerable defects, his proof from induction of the beneficial tend¬ ency of virtue, his conclusive arguments for human disinterestedness, and his decisive ob¬ servations on the respective provinces of reason and sentiment in morals, concur in ranking the i “ In liac qusestione primas tenet Voluntas, qua, ut ait Augustinus, peccatur, et recte vivitur." (Hyperaspistes, DiatnU advcrsus Servum Arbitrium Martini Lutheri, per Desiderium Erasmum Itotterdamensem.) '* Essays and Treatises, vol. II. 374 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. Enquiry with the ethical treatises of the highest quiry concerning Virtue, Butler’s Sermons, and merit in our language,—with Shaftesbury’s En- Smith’s Theory of Moral Sentiments. ADAM SMITH.1 The great name of Adam Smith rests upon the Enquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations ; perhaps the only hook which produced an immediate, general, and irrevoc¬ able change in some of the most important parts of the legislation of all civilized states. The works of Grotius, of Locke, and of Montesquieu, which bear a resemblance to it in character, and had no inconsiderable analogy to it in the ex¬ tent of their popular influence, were productive only of a general amendment, not so conspicuous in particular instances, as discoverable, after a time, in the improved condition of human af¬ fairs. 2 3 * The work of Smith, as it touched those matters which may he numbered, and measured, and weighed, bore more visible and palpable fruit. In a few years it began to alter laws and treaties, and has made its way, throughout the convulsions of revolution and conquest, to a due ascendant over the minds of men, with far less than the average obstructions of prejudice and clamour, which choakthe channels through which truth flows into practice. The most eminent of those who have since cultivated and improved the science will be the foremost to address their immortal master, . Tenebris tantis tam clarum extollere lumen Qui primus potuisti, inlustrans commoda vit^e, Te sequor! (Lucret. lib. iii.) In a science more difficult, because both ascend¬ ing to more simple general principles, and run¬ ning down through more minute applications, though the success of Smith has been less com¬ plete, his genius is not less conspicuous. Per¬ haps there is no ethical work since Cicero’s Of¬ fices, of which an abridgement enables the reader so inadequately to estimate the merit, as the Theory of Moral Sentiments. This is not chiefly owing to the beauty of diction, as in the case of Cicero; but to the variety of explanations of life and manners which embellish the book often more than they illuminate the theory. Yet, on the other hand, it must be owned that, for pure¬ ly philosophical purposes, few hooks more need abridgement: for the most careful reader fre¬ quently loses sight of principles buried under illustrations. The naturally copious and flow¬ ing style of the author is generally redundant, and the repetition of certain formularies of the system is, in the later editions, so frequent as to be wearisome, and sometimes ludicrous. Per¬ haps Smith and Hobbes may be considered as forming the two extremes of good style in our philosophy; the first of graceful fulness falling •into flaccidity; while the masterly concision of the second is oftener tainted by dictatorial dry¬ ness. Hume and Berkeley, though they are nearer the extreme of abundance,5 are probably the least distant from perfection. That mankind are so constituted as to sympa¬ thize with each other’s feelings, and to feel pleasure in the accordance of these feelings, are the only facts required by Hr Smith, and they certainly must be granted to him. To adopt the feelings of another, is to approve them. When the sentiments of another are such as would be excited in us by the same objects, we approve them as morally proper. To obtain this accord, it becomes necessary for him who enjoys or suf¬ fers, to lower his expression of feeling to the point to which the by-stander can raise his fel¬ low-feelings ; on which are founded all the higli virtues of self-denial and self-command; and it is equally necessary for the by-stander to raise his sympathy as near as he can to the level of the original feeling. In all unsocial passions, such as anger, we have a divided sympathy be¬ tween him who feels them and those who are the 1 Born in 1723 ; died in 1790. * Notes and Illustrations, note S. 3 This remark is chiefly applicable to Hume’s Essays. His Treatise of Human Nature is more Hobbian in its general tenor, though it has Ciceronian passages. DISSERTATION SECOND. 375 objects of them. Hence the propriety of ex¬ tremely moderating them. Pure malice is al¬ ways to he concealed or disguised, because all sympathy is arrayed against it. In the private passions, where there is only a simple sympathy— that with the original passion—the expression has more liberty. The benevolent affections, where there is a double sympathy—with those who feel them, and those who are their objects—are the most agreeable, and may he indulged with the least apprehension of finding no echo in other breasts. Sympathy with the gratitude of those who are benefited by good actions, prompts us to consider them as deserving of reward, and forms the sense of merit; as fellow-feeling with the resentment of those who are injured by crimes leads us to look on them as worthy of punishment, and constitutes the seme of demerit. These senti¬ ments require not only beneficial actions, hut be¬ nevolent motives for them; being compounded, in the case of merit, of a direct sympathy with the good disposition of the benefactor, and an indirect sympathy with the persons benefited; in the op¬ posite case, with precisely opposite sympathies. He who does an act of wrong to another to gratify his own passions, must not expect that the spec¬ tators, who have none of his undue partiality to his own interest, will enter into his feelings. In such a case, he knows that they will pity the person wronged, and he full of indignation against him. When he is cooled, he adopts the sentiments of others on his own crime, feels shame at the impropriety of his former passion, pity for those who have suffered by him, and a dread of punishment from general and just re¬ sentment. Such are the constituent parts of remorse. Our moral sentiments respecting ourselves arise from those which others feel concerning us. We feel a self-approbation whenever we believe that the general feeling of mankind co¬ incides with that state of mind in which we our¬ selves were at a given time. “ We suppose ourselves the spectators of our own behaviour, and endeavour to imagine what effect it would in this light produce in us.” We must view our own conduct with the eyes of others before we can judge it. The sense of duty arises from putting ourselves in the place of others, and adopting their sentiments respecting our own conduct. In utter solitude there could have been no self-approbation. The rules of morality are a summary of those sentiments; and often beneficially stand in their stead when the self- delusions of passion would otherwise hide from us the non-conformity of our state of mind with that which, in the circumstances, can be entered into and approved by impartial by¬ standers. It is hence that we learn to raise our mind above local or temporary clamour, and to fix our eyes on the surest indications of the ge¬ neral and lasting sentiments of human nature. “ When we approve of any character or action, our sentiments are derived from four sources: first, we sympathize with the motives of the agent; secondly, we enter into the gratitude of those who have been benefited by his actions; thirdly, we observe that his conduct has been agreeable to the general rules by which those two sympathies generally act; and, last of all, when we consider such actions as forming part of a system of behaviour which tends to promote the happiness either of the individual or of so¬ ciety, they appear to derive a beauty from this utility, not unlike that which we ascribe to any well-contrived machine.”1 REMARKS. That Smith is the first who has drawn the at¬ tention of philosophers to one of the most cu¬ rious and important parts of human nature— who has looked closely and steadily into the workings of Sympathy, its sudden action and re¬ action, its instantaneous conflicts and its emo¬ tions, its minute play and varied illusions—is sufficient to place him high among the culti¬ vators of mental philosophy. He is very original in applications and expla¬ nations; though, for his principle, he is some¬ what indebted to Butler, more to Hutcheson, and most of all to Hume. These writers, except Hume in his original work, had derived sym- 1 Theory of Moral Sentiments, II. 304. Edinb. 1801. 376 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. pathy, or great part of it, from benevolence.1 2 Smith, with deeper insight, inverted the order. The great part performed by various sympathies in moral approbation was first unfolded by him; and besides its intrinsic importance, it strength¬ ened the proofs against those theories which ascribe that great function to Reason. Anothei great merit of the theory of sympathy is, that it brings into the strongest light that most import¬ ant characteristic of the moral sentiments which consists in their being the only principles lead¬ ing to action, and dependent on emotion or sen¬ sibility, with respect to the objects of which, it is not only possible but natural for all man¬ kind to agree.3 The main defects of this theory seem to be the following. L Though it is not to be condemned for de¬ clining inquiry into the origin of our fellow- feeling, which, being one of the most certain of all facts, might well be assumed as ultimate in speculations of this nature, it is evident that the circumstances to which some speculators ascribe the formation of sympathy at least contribute to strengthen or impair, to contract or expand it. It will appear, more conveniently, in the next article, that the theory of sympathy has suffered from the omission of these circumstances. For the present, it is enough to observe how much our compassion for various sorts of animals, and our fellow-feeling with various races of men, are proportioned to the resemblance which they bear to ourselves, to the frequency of our intercourse with them, and to other causes which, in the opinion of some, afford evidence that sympathy itself is dependent on a more general law. 2. Had Smith extended his view beyond the mere play of sympathy itself, and taken into ac¬ count all its preliminaries, and accompaniments, and consequences, it seems improbable that he should have fallen into the great error of repre¬ senting the sympathies in their primitive state, without undergoing any transformation, as con¬ tinuing exclusively to constitute the moral sen¬ timents. He is not content with teaching that they are the roots out of which these sentiments grow, the stocks on which they are grafted, the elements of which they are compounded;—doc¬ trines to which nothing could be objected but their unlimited extent. He tacitly assumes, that if a sympathy in the beginning caused or formed a moral approbation, so it must ever continue to do. He proceeds like a geologist who should tell us that the layers of this planet had always been in the same state, shutting his eyes to transition states and secondary forma¬ tions ; or like a chemist who should inform us that no compound substance can possess new qualities entirely different from those which be¬ long to its materials. His acquiescence in this old and still general error is the more remark¬ able, because Mr Hume’s beautiful Dissertation on the Passions3 had just before opened a strik¬ ing view of some of the compositions and de¬ compositions which render the mind of a formed man as different from its original state, as the organization of a complete animal is from the condition of the first dim speck of vitality. It is from this oversight (ill supplied by moral rules, a loose stone in his building) that he has exposed himself to objections founded on expe¬ rience, to which it is impossible to attempt any answer. For it is certain that in many, nay in most cases of moral approbation, the adult man approves the action or disposition merely as right, and with a distinct consciousness that no process of sympathy intervenes between the approval and its object. It is certain that an unbiassed person would call it moral approbation, only as far as it excluded the interposition of any reflection between the conscience and the mental state approved. Upon the supposition of an unchanged state of our active principles, it would follow that sympathy never had any share in the greater part of them. Had he ad¬ mitted the sympathies to be only elements enter¬ ing into the formation of Conscience, their dis¬ appearance, or their appearance only as auxili- 1 There is some confusion regarding this point in Butler’s first sermon on Compassion. ^ 2 The feelings of beauty, grandeur, and whatever else is comprehended under the name of Taste, form no exception, or they do not lead to action, but terminate in delightful contemplation ; which constitutes the essential distinction between them and the moral sentiments, to which, in some points of view, they may doubtless be likened. * Essays and Treatises, vol. II. DISSERTATION SECOND. 377 aries, after the mind is mature, would have been no more an objection to his system, than the conversion of a substance from a transi¬ tional to a permanent state is a perplexity to the geologist. It would perfectly resemble the destruction of qualities, which is the ordinary effect of chemical composition. 3. The same error has involved him in an¬ other difficulty perhaps still more fatal. The sympathies have nothing more of an imperative character than any other emotions. They attract or repel like other feelings, according to their intensity. If, then, the sympathies con¬ tinue in mature minds to constitute the whole of conscience, it becomes utterly impossible to explain the character of command and suprem¬ acy, which is attested by the unanimous voice of mankind to belong to that faculty, and to form its essential distinction. Had he adopted the other representation, it would be possible to conceive, perhaps easy to explain, that con¬ science should possess a quality which belonged to none of its elements. 4. It is to this representation that Smith’s theory owes that unhappy appearance of ren¬ dering the rule of our conduct dependent on the notions and passions of those who surround us, of which the utmost efforts of the most re¬ fined ingenuity have not been able to divest it. This objection or topic is often ignorantly urged; the answers are frequently solid; hut to most men they must always appear to be an ingeni¬ ous and intricate contrivance of cycles and epi¬ cycles, which perplex the mind too much to satisfy it, and seem devised to evade difficulties which cannot be solved. All theories which treat conscience as built up by circumstances inevitably acting on all human minds, are, in¬ deed, liable to somewhat of the same miscon¬ ception ; unless they place in the strongest light (what Smith’s theory excludes) the total de¬ struction of the scaffolding which was neces¬ sary only to the erection of the building, after the mind is adult and mature, and warn the hastiest reader, that it then rests on its own foundation alone. 5. The constant reference of our own dispo¬ sitions and actions to the point of view from which they are estimated by others, seems to he rather an excellent expedient for preserving our impartiality, than a fundamental principle of Ethics. But impartiality, which is no more than a removal of some hinderance to right judg¬ ment, supplies no materials for its exercise, and no ride, or even principle, for its guidance. It nearly coincides with the Christian precept of doing unto others as we would they should do unto us; an admirable practical maxim, but, as Leibnitz has said truly, intended only as a cor¬ rection of self-partiality. 6. Lastly, this ingenious system renders all morality relative,—by referring it to the plea¬ sure of an agreement of our feelings with those of others, by confining itself entirely to the question of moral approbation, and by provid¬ ing no place for the consideration of that quality which distinguishes all good from all bad ac¬ tions ;—a defect which will appear in the sequel to be more immediately fatal to a theorist of the sentimental, than to one of the intellectual school. Smith shrinks from considering utility in that light as soon as it presents itself, or very strange¬ ly ascribes its power over our moral feelings to admiration of the mere adaptation of means to ends,—which might surely be as well felt for the production of wide-spread misery, by a con¬ sistent system of wicked conduct,—instead of ascribing it to benevolence, with Hutcheson and Hume, or to an extension of that very sympathy which is his own first principle. RICHARD PRICE.1 About the same time with the celebrated and eminent non-conformist minister, published work of Smith, but with a popular reception A Beview of the principal Questions in Morals ;a— very different, Dr Richard Price, an excellent an attempt to revive the intellectual theory of 1 Born in 1723; died in 1791. * The third edition was published at London in 1787- O B DiSS. II. 378 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. moral obligation, which seemed to have fallen under the attacks of Butler, Hutcheson, and Hume, even before Smith. It attracted little observation at first; but being afterwards coun¬ tenanced by the Scottish School, may seem to deserve some notice, at a moment when the kindred speculations of the German metaphysi¬ cians have effected an establishment in France, and are no longer unknown in England. The understanding itself is, according to Price, an independent source of simple ideas. “ The various kinds of agreement and disagree¬ ment between our ideas, spoken of by Locke, are so many new simple ideas.” “ This is true of our ideas of proportion, of our ideas of iden¬ tity and diversity, existence, connection, cause and effect, power, possibility, and of our ideas of right and wrong.” “ The first relates to quantity, the last to actions, the rest to all things.” “ Like all other simple ideas, they are undefineable.” It is needless to pursue this theory farther, till an answer shall be given to the observation made before, that as no perception or judgment, or other unmixed act of understanding, merely as such, and without the agency of some inter¬ mediate emotion, can affect the will, the account given by Hr Price of perceptions or judgments respecting moral subjects, does not advance one step towards the explanation of the authority of conscience over the will, which is the matter to be explained. Indeed, this respectable writer felt the difficulty so much as to allow, “ that in contemplating the acts of moral agents, we have both a perception of the understanding and a feeling of the heart.” He even admits, that it would have been highly pernicious to us if our reason had been left without such support. But he has not shown how, on such a supposition, we could have acted on a mere opinion; nor has he given any proof that what he calls sup¬ port is not, in truth, the whole of what directly produces the conformity of voluntary acts to morality.1 * DAVID HARTLEY.* The work of Dr Hartley, entitled Observations on Man,3 is distinguished by an uncommon union of originality with modesty, in unfolding a simple and fruitful principle of human nature. It is disfigured by the absurd affectation of ma¬ thematical forms then prevalent; and it is en¬ cumbered and deformed by a mass of physiolo¬ gical speculations, groundless, or at best uncer¬ tain, wholly foreign from its proper purpose, which repel the inquirer into mental philosophy from its perusal, and lessen the respect of the physiologist for the author’s judgment. It is an unfortunate example of the disposition predomi¬ nant among undistinguishing theorists to class together all the appearances which are observed at the same time, and in the immediate neigh¬ bourhood of each other. At that period, chemi¬ cal phenomena were referred to mechanical prin¬ ciples ; vegetable and animal life were subjected to mechanical or chemical laws; and while some physiologists4 ascribed the vital functions to the understanding, the greater part of metaphysi¬ cians were disposed, with a grosser confusion, to derive the intellectual operations from bodily causes. The error in the latter case, though less immediately perceptible, is deeper and more fundamental than in any other; since it over¬ looks the primordial and perpetual distinction between the being which thinks and the thing which is thought of;—not to be lost sight of, by the mind’s eye, even for a twinkling, without involving all nature in darkness and confusion. 1 The following sentences will illustrate the text, and are in truth applicable to all moral theories on merely intellectual principles :—“ Reason alone, did we possess it in a higher degree, would answer all the ends of the passions. Thus there would he no need of parental affection, were all parents sufficiently acquainted with the reasons for taking upon them the guidance and support of those whom nature has placed under their care, and -were they virtuous enough to be always determined ly those reasons." (Price’s Review, 121.) A very slight consideration will show, that without the last words the preceding part would be utterly false, and with them it is utterly insignificant. * Born in 1705 ; died in 1757- 3 London, 1749. 4 G. E. Stahl, born in 1660; died in 1734; a German physician and chemist of deserved eminence. DISSERTATION SECOND. 379 Hartley and Condillac,1 who, much about the same time, hut seemingly without any know¬ ledge of each other’s speculations,2 * began in a very similar mode to simplify, hut also to muti¬ late the system of Locke, stopped short of what is called Materialism, which consummates the confusion, hut touched its threshold. Thither, it must be owned, their philosophy pointed, and thither their followers proceeded. Hartley and Bonnet,5 still more than Condillac, suffered them¬ selves, like most of their contemporaries, to overlook the important truth, that all the changes in the organs which can he likened to other material phenomena, are nothing more than an¬ tecedents and prerequisites of perception, hearing not the faintest likeness to it; as much outward in relation to the thinking principle, as if they occurred in any other part of matter; and of which the entire comprehension, if it were at¬ tained, would not bring us a step nearer to the nature of thought. They who would have been the first to exclaim against the mistake of a sound for a colour, fell into the more unspeak¬ able error of confounding the perception of ob¬ jects, as outward, with the consciousness of our own mental operations. Locke’s doctrine, that Reflection was a separate source of ideas, left room for this greatest of all distinctions,— though with much unhappiness of expression, and with no little variance from the course of his own speculations. Hartley, Condillac, and Bonnet, in hewing away this seeming deformity from the system of their master, unwittingly struck off the part of the building which, how¬ ever unsightly, gave it the power of yielding some shelter and guard to truths, of which the exclusion rendered it utterly untenable. They became consistent Nominalists; a controversy on which Locke expresses himself with confu¬ sion and contradiction; but on this subject they added nothing to what had been taught by Hobbes and Berkeley. Both Hartley and Con¬ dillac4 have the merit of having been unseduced by the temptations either of scepticism or of useless idealism; which, even if Berkeley and Hume could have been unknown to them, must have been within sight. Both agree in referring all the intellectual operations to the association of ideas, and in representing that association as reducible to the single law, that ideas which en¬ ter the mind at the same time, acquire a ten¬ dency to call up each other, which is in direct proportion to the frequency of their having en¬ tered together. In this important part of their doctrine they seem, whether unconsciously or otherwise, to have only repeated, and very much expanded, the opinion of Hobbes.5 In its sim¬ plicity it is more agreeable than the system of Mr Hume, who admitted five independent laws of association; and it is in comprehension far superior to the views of the same subject by Mr Locke, whose ill-chosen name still retains its place in our nomenclature, but who only appeals to the principle as explaining some fancies and whimsies of the human mind. The capital fault of Hartley is that of a rash generalization, which may prove imperfect, and which is at least pre¬ mature. All attempts to explain instinct by this principle have hitherto been unavailing. Many of the most important processes of reasoning have not hitherto been accounted for by it.6 It would appear by a close examination, that even this theory, simple as it appears, presupposes many facts relating to the mind, of which its authors 1 Born in 1715 ; died in 1780. 2 Trait'z sur VOrigine des Connoissances Humames, 1746 ; Traite des Systemes, 1749 ; Traite des Sensations, 1754. Foreign books were then little and slowly known in England. Hartley’s reading, except on theology, seems confined to the physi¬ cal and mathematical sciences; and his whole manner of thinking and writing is so different from that of Condillac, that there is not the least reason to suppose the work of the one to have been known to the other. The work of Hartley, as we learn from the sketch of his life by his son, prefixed to the edition of 1791, was begun in 1730, and finished in 1746. * Born in 1720; died in 1793. 4 The following note of Condillac will show how much he differed from Hartley in his mode of considering the Newton¬ ian hypothesis of vibrations, and how far he was in that respect superior to him. “ Je suppose ici et ailleurs que les per¬ ceptions de Tame ont pour cause physique I’ebranlement des fibres du cerveau; non que je regarde cette hypothese comme de- montrte, maxs parcequ' elle est la plus commode pour expliquer ma pcnsee.” {CEuvres de Condillac, I. 60. Paris, 1798.) 5 Human Nature, chap. iv. v. vi. For more ancient statements, see Notes and Illustrations, note T. * “ Ce que les logiciens ont dit des raisonnements dans bien des volumes, me paroit entierement superflu, et de nul usage” (Condillac, I. 115); an assertion of which the gross absurdity will be apparent to the readers of Dr Whately’s Treatise on Logic, one of the most important works of the present age. 380 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. do not seem to have suspected the existence. How many ultimate facts of that nature, for ex¬ ample, are contained and involved in Aristotle s celebrated comparison of the mind in its first state to a sheet of unwritten paper!1 The tex¬ ture of the paper, even its colour, the sort of in¬ strument fit to act on it, its capacity to receive and to retain impressions, all its differences, from steel on the one hand to water on the other, certainly presuppose some facts, and may imply many, without a distinct statement of which, the nature of writing could not be ex¬ plained to a person wholly ignorant of it. How many more, as well as greater laws, may he ne¬ cessary to enable mind to perceive outward ob¬ jects ! If the power of perception may be thus dependent, why may not what is called the asso¬ ciation of ideas, the attraction between thoughts, the power of one to suggest another, he affected by mental laws hitherto unexplored, perhaps un¬ observed ? But to return from digression into the intel¬ lectual part of man : It becomes proper to say, that the difference between Hartley and Con¬ dillac, and the immeasurable superiority of the former, are chiefly to be found in the applica¬ tion which Hartley first made of the law of as¬ sociation to that other unnamed portion of our nature with which morality more immediately deals; that which feels pain and pleasure, is influenced by appetites and loathings, by desires and aversions, by affections and repugnances. Condillac’s Treatise an Sensation, published five years after the work of Hartley, reproduces the doctrine of Hobbes with its root, namely, that love and hope are but transformed sensations,2 3 4 by which he means perceptions of the senses; and its wide-spread branches, consisting in de¬ sires and passions, which are only modifications of self-love. 44 The words goodness and beauty,” says he, almost in the very words of Hobbes, 44 express those qualities of things by which they contribute to our pleasures.”5 In the whole of his philosophical works, we find no trace of any desire produced by association, of any disinter¬ ested principle, or indeed of any distinction be¬ tween the percipient and what, perhaps, we may now venture to call the emotive or the pathematic part of human nature, until some more conve¬ nient and agreeable name shall be hit on by some luckier or more skilful adventurer, in such new terms as seem to be absolutely necessary. To the ingenuous, humble, and anxiously con¬ scientious character of Hartley, we owe the know¬ ledge that, about the year 1730, he was inform¬ ed that the Rev. Mr Gay of Sidney College, Cambridge, then living in the west of England, asserted the possibility of deducing all our intel¬ lectual pleasures and pains from association; that this led him (Hartley) to consider the power of association; and that about that time Mr Gay published his sentiments on this matter in a dis¬ sertation prefixed to Bishop Law’s Translation of King’s Origin of Evil.* No writer deserves more the praise of abundant fairness than Hartley in this avowal. The dissertation of which he speaks is mentioned by no philosopher but himself. It suggested nothing apparently to any other read¬ er. The general texture of it is that of home- spun selfishness. The writer had the merit to see and to own that Hutcheson had established as a fact the reality of moral sentiments and dis¬ interested affections. He blames, perhaps just¬ ly, that most ingenious man,5 for assuming that these sentiments and affections are implanted, and partake of the nature of instincts. The ob¬ ject of his dissertation is to reconcile the mental appearances described by Hutcheson with the 1 See Notes and Illustrations, note U. 2 Condillac, III. 21 ; more especially Traitc dcs Sensations, part ii. chap. vi. “ Its love for outward objects is only an effect of love for itself.” 3 Traite des Sensations, part iv. chap. iii. 4 Hartley’s Preface to the Observations on Man. The word intellectual is too narrow. Even mental would be of very doubtful propriety. The theory in its full extent requires a word such as inorganic, (if no better can be discovered) extend¬ ing to all gratification, not distinctly referred to some specific organ, or at least to some assignable part of the bodily frame. 5 It has not been mentioned in its proper place, that Hutcheson appears nowhere to greater advantage than in Letters on the Fable of the Bees, published when he was very young, at Dublin, in a publication called Hibernicus. “ Private vices public benefits,” says he, “ may signify any one of these five distinct propositions : 1. They are in themselves public be¬ nefits ; or, 2. They naturally produce public happiness ; or, 3. They may be made to produce it; or, 4, They may natu¬ rally flow from it; or, 5. At least they may probably flow from it in our infirm nature.” (See a small volume containing Thoughts on Laughter, and Observations on the Fable of the Bees, Glasgow, 1758, in which these letters are republished.) DISSERTATION SECOND. 381 first principle of the selfish system, that “ the true principle of all our actions is our own hap¬ piness.” Moral feelings and social affections are, according to him, “ resolvable into reason, pointing out our private happiness; and when¬ ever this end is not perceived, they are to he ac¬ counted for from the association of ideas.” Even in the single passage in which he shows a glimpse of the truth, he begins with confusion, advances with hesitation, and after holding in his grasp for an instant the principle which sheds so strong a light around it, suddenly drops it from his hand. Instead of receiving the statements of Hutcheson (his silence relating to Butler is unaccountable) as enlargements of the science of man, he deals with them merely as difficulties to be reconciled with the received system of universal selfishness. In the conclusion of his fourth section, he well exemplifies the power of association in forming the love of money, of fame, of power, &c.; hut he still treats these effects of association as aberrations and infirmi¬ ties, the fruits of our forgetfulness and short¬ sightedness, and not at all as the great process employed to sow and rear the most important principles of a social and moral nature. This precious mine may therefore he truly said to have been opened by Hartley; for he who did such superabundant justice to the hints of Gay, would assuredly not have withheld the like tribute from Hutcheson, had he observ¬ ed the happy expression of “ secondary pas¬ sions,” which ought to have led that philoso¬ pher himself farther than he ventured to ad¬ vance. The extraordinary value of this part of Hartley’s system has been hidden by various causes, which have also enabled writers who borrow from it to decry it. The influence of his medical habits renders many of his examples displeasing, and sometimes disgusting. He has none of that knowledge of the world, of that fa¬ miliarity with literature, of that delicate percep¬ tion of the beauties of nature and art, which not only supply the most agreeable illustrations of mental philosophy, but afford the most obvious and striking instances of its happy application to subjects generally interesting. His particular applications of the general law are often mis¬ taken, and seldom more than brief notes and hasty suggestions; the germs of theories which, while some might adopt them without detec¬ tion, others might discover without being aware that they were anticipated. To which it may he added, that in spite of the imposing forms of geometry, the work is not really distinguished by good method, or even uniform adherence to that which had been chosen. His style is en¬ titled to no praise but that of clearness, and a simplicity of diction, through which is visible a singular simplicity of mind. No book perhaps exists which, with so few of the common allure¬ ments, comes at last so much to please by the picture it presents of the writer’s character,—a character which kept him pure from the pursuit, often from the consciousness of novelty, and ren¬ dered him a discoverer in spite of his own modes¬ ty. In those singular passages in which, amidst the profound internal tranquillity of all the Euro¬ pean nations, he foretells approaching convul¬ sions, to he followed by the overthrow of states and churches, his quiet and gentle spirit, else¬ where almost ready to inculcate passive obe¬ dience for the sake of peace, is supported under its awful forebodings by the hope of that general progress in virtue and happiness which he saw through the preparatory confusion. A meek piety, inclining towards mysticism, and sometimes in¬ dulging in visions which borrow a lustre from his fervid benevolence, was beautifully, and perhaps singularly, blended in him with zeal for the most unbounded freedom of inquiry, flowing both from his own conscientious belief and his un¬ mingled love of truth. Whoever can so far subdue his repugnance to petty or secondary faults as to bestow a careful perusal on the work, must be unfortunate if he does not see, feel, and own, that the writer was a great phi¬ losopher and a good man. To those who thus study the work, it will be apparent that Hartley, like other philosophers, either overlooked, or failed explicitly to an¬ nounce, that distinction between perception and emotion, without which no system of mental philosophy is complete. Hence arose the partial and incomplete view of truth conveyed by the use of the phrase “ association of ideas.” If the word association, which rather indicates the connection between separate things, than th.e 382 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. perfect combination and fusion which occur in many operations of the mind, must, notwith¬ standing its inadequacy, still he retained, the phrase ought at least tohe “association of thoughts with emotions, as well as with each other. With that enlargement an objection to the Hart- leian doctrine would have been avoided, and its originality, as well as superiority over that of Condillac, would have appeared indisputable. The examples of avarice and other factitious passions are very well chosen; first, because few will be found to suppose that they are original principles of human nature ;1 secondly, because the process by which they are generated, being subsequent to the age of attention and recollec¬ tion, may be brought home to the understanding of all men ; and, thirdly, because they afford the most striking instance of secondary passions, which not only become independent of the pri¬ mary principles from which they are derived, but hostile to them, and so superior in strength as to be capable of overpowering their parents. As soon as the mind becomes familiar with the frequent case of the man who first pursued money to purchase pleasure, but at last, when he be¬ comes a miser, loves his hoard better than all that it could purchase, and sacrifices all pleasures for its increase, we are prepared to admit that, by a like process, the affections, when they are fixed on the happiness of others as their ultimate object, without any reflection on self, may not only be perfectly detached from self-regard or private desires, but may subdue these, and every other antagonist passion which can stand in their way. As the miser loves money for its own sake, so may the benevolent man delight in the wellbeing of his fellows. His good-will be¬ comes as disinterested as if it had been implant¬ ed and underived. The like process applied to what is called self-love, or the desire of perma¬ nent wellbeing, clearly explains the mode in which that principle is gradually formed from the separate appetites, without whose previous existence no notion of wellbeing could be ob¬ tained. In like manner, sympathy, perhaps it¬ self the result of a transfer of our own personal feelings by association to other sentient beings, and of a subsequent transfer of their feelings to our own minds, engenders the various social af¬ fections, which at last generate in most minds some regard to the wellbeing of our country, of mankind, of all creatures capable of pleasure. Rational self-love controls and guides those far keener self-regarding passions of which it is the child, in the same manner as general benevo¬ lence balances and governs the variety of much warmer social affections from which it springs. It is an ancient and obstinate error of philoso¬ phers to represent these two calm principles as being the source of the impelling passions and affections, instead of being among the last re¬ sults of them. Each of them exercises a sort of authority in its sphere, but the dominion of neither is co-existent with the whole nature of man. Though they have the power to quicken and check, they are both too feeble to impel; and if the primary principles were extinguished, they would both perish from want of nourish¬ ment. If indeed all appetites and desires were destroyed, no subject would exist on which either of these general principles could act. The affections, desires, and emotions, having for their ultimate object the dispositions and actions of voluntary agents, which alone, from the nature of their object, are co-extensive with the whole of our active nature, are, according to the same philosophy, necessarily formed in every human mind by the transfer of feeling which is effected by the principle of association. Gratitude, pity, resentment, and shame, seem to be the simplest, the most active, and the most uniform elements in their composition. It is easy to perceive how the complacency inspired by a benefit may be transferred to a benefactor, thence to all beneficent beings and acts. The well-chosen instance of the nurse familiarly exemplifies the manner in which the child transfers his complacency from the grati¬ fication of his senses to the cause of it, and thus learns an affection for her who is the source of 1 A very ingenious man, Lord Kames, whose works had a great effect in rousing the mind of his contemporaries and countrymen, has indeed fancied that there is “ a hoarding instinct” in man and other animals. But such conclusions are not so much objects of confutation, as ludicrous proofs of the absurdity of the premises which lead to them. DISSERTATION SECOND. 383 his enjoyment. With this simple process con¬ cur, in the case of a tender nurse, and far more of a mother, a thousand acts of relief and en¬ dearment, of which the complacency is fixed on the person from whom they flow, and in some degree extended by association to all who re¬ semble that person. So much of the pleasure of early life depends on others, that the like pro¬ cess is almost constantly repeated. Hence the origin of benevolence may be understood, and the disposition to approve all benevolent, and disapprove all malevolent acts. Hence also the same approbation and disapprobation are ex¬ tended to all acts which we clearly perceive to promote or obstruct the happiness of men. When the complacency is extended to action, benevolence may be said to be transformed into a part of conscience. The rise of sympathy may probably be explained by the process of association, which transfers the feelings of others to ourselves, and ascribes our own feelings to others;—at first, and in some degree, always in proportion as the resemblance of ourselves to others is complete. The likeness in the outward signs of emotion is one of the widest channels in this commerce of hearts. Pity thereby be¬ comes one of the grand sources of benevolence, and perhaps contributes more largely than gra¬ titude. It is indeed one of the first motives to the conferring of those benefits which inspire grateful affection. Sympathy with the sufferer, therefore, is also transformed into a real senti¬ ment, directly approving benevolent actions and dispositions, and more remotely all actions that promote happiness. The anger of the sufferer, first against all causes of pain, afterwards against all intentional agents who produce it, and final¬ ly against all those in whom the infliction of pain proceeds from a mischievous disposition, when it is communicated to others by sympathy, and is so far purified by gradual separation from selfish and individual interest as to be equally felt against all wrong-doers, whether the wrong be done against ourselves, our friends, or our enemies, is the root out of which springs that which is commonly and well called a Sense of Justice—the most indispensable, perhaps, of all the component parts of the moral faculties. It is the main guard against wrong. It relates to that portion of morality where many of the out¬ ward acts are capable of being reduced under certain rules, of which the violations, wherever the rule is sufficiently precise, and the mischief sufficiently great, may be guarded against by the terror of punishment. In the observation of the rules of justice consists duty ; breaches of them we denominate crimes. An abhorrence of crimes, especially of those which indicate the absence of benevolence, as well as of regard to justice, is peculiarly strong; because well-framed penal laws, being the lasting declaration of the moral indignation of many generations of man¬ kind, exceedingly strengthen the same feeling in every individual, as long as they remain in unison with the sentiments of the age and coun¬ try for which they are destined, and, indeed, wherever the laws do not so much deviate from the habitual feelings as to produce a struggle between law and sentiment, in which it is hard to say on which side success is most deplorable. A man who performs his duties may be esteemed, but is not admired; because it requires no more than ordinary virtue to act well where it is shameful and dangerous to do otherwise. The righteousness of those who act solely from such inferior motives, is little better than that “of the Scribes and Pharisees.” Those only are just in the eye of the moralist who act justly from a constant disposition to render to every man his own.1 Acts of kindness, of gene¬ rosity, of pity, of placability, of humanity, when they are long continued, can hardly fail mainly to flow from the pure fountain of an excellent nature. They are not reducible to rules; and the attempt to enforce them by punishment would destroy them. They are virtues of which the essence consists in a good disposition of mind. As we gradually transfer our desire from praise to praiseworthiness, this principle also is adopted into consciousness. On the other hand, 1 “ Justitia est constans et perpetua voluntas suum cuique tribuendi;” an excellent definition in the mouth of the Stoical moralists, from whom it is borrowed, but altogether misplaced by the Roman Jurists in a body of laws which deal only with outward acts in their relation to the order and interest of society. 384 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. when we are led by association to feel a painful contempt for those feelings and actions of our past self which we despise in others, there is developed in our hearts another element of that moral sense. It is a remarkable instance of the power of the law of association, that the con¬ tempt or abhorrence which we feel for the bad actions of others may he transferred by it, in any degree of strength, to our own past actions of the like kind. And as the hatred of had actions is transferred to the agent, the same transfer may occur in our own case in a manner perfectly similar to that of which we are conscious in our feelings towards our fellow-creatures. There are many causes which render it generally feebler; but it is perfectly evident that it requires no more than a sufficient strength of moral feeling to make it equal; and that the most apparently hyperbolical language used by penitents, in de¬ scribing their remorse, may be justified by the principle of association. At this step in our progress, it is proper to ob¬ serve, that a most important consideiation has escaped Hartley, as well as every other philoso¬ pher. 1 The language of all mankind implies that the moral faculty, whatever it may be, and from what origin soever it may spring, is intelligibly and properly spoken of as One. It is as com¬ mon in mind as in matter for a compound to have properties not to be found in any of its con¬ stituent parts. The truth of this proposition is as certain in the human feelings as in any ma¬ terial combination. It is therefore easily under¬ stood, that originally separate feelings may be so perfectly blended by a process performed in every mind, that they can no longer be disjoined from each other, but must always co-operate, and thus reach the only union which we can conceive. The sentiment of Moral Approbation, formed by association out of antecedent affections, may be¬ come so perfectly independent of them, that we are no longer conscious of the means by which it was formed, and never can in practice repeat, though we may in theory perceive, the process by which it was generated. It is in that mature and sound state of our nature that our emotions at the view of Right and Wrong are ascribed to Conscience. But why, it may be asked, do these feelings, rather than others, run into each other, and constitute Conscience ? The answer seems to be what has already been intimated in the ob¬ servations on Butler. The affinity between these feelings consists in this, that while all other feelings relate to outward objects, they alone contemplate exclusively the dispositions and actions of voluntary agents. When they are completely transferred from objects, and even persons, to dispositions and actions, they are fitted, by the perfect coincidence of their aim, for combining to form that one faculty which is di¬ rected only to that aim. The words Duty and Virtue, and the word Ought, which most perfectly denotes Duty, but is also connected with Virtue, in every well-consti¬ tuted mind, in this state become the fit language of the acquired, perhaps, but universally and ne¬ cessarily acquired, faculty of Conscience. Some account of its peculiar nature has been attempted in the remarks on Butler;—for others a fitter oc¬ casion will occur hereafter. Some light may how¬ ever now he thrown on the subject by a short state¬ ment of the hitherto unobserved distinction be¬ tween the moral sentiments and another class of feelings with which they have some qualities in common. The pleasures (so called) of Imagina¬ tion appear, at least in most cases, to originate in association. But it is not till the original cause of the gratification is obliterated from the mind, that they acquire their proper character. Order and proportion may be at first chosen for their con¬ venience : it is not until they are admired for their own sake that they become objects of taste. Though all the proportions for which a horse is valued may be indications of speed, safety, strength, and health, it is not the less true that they only can be said to admire the animal for his beauty, who leave such considerations out of the account while they admire. The pleasure of contemplation in these particulars of nature and art becomes universal and immediate, being entirely detached from all regard to individual beings. It contemplates neither use nor interest. 1 See tujpra, section on Butler. DISSERTATION SECOND. 385 In this important particular the pleasures of imagination agree with the moral sentiments. Hence the application of the same language to both in ancient and modern times. Hence also it arises that they may contemplate the very same qualities and objects. There is certainly much beauty in the softer virtues—much gran¬ deur in the soul of a Hero or a Martyr. But the essential distinction still remains. The purest moral taste contemplates these qualities only with quiescent delight or reverence. It has no further view;—it points towards no action. Conscience, on the contrary, containing in it a pleasure in the prospect of doing right, and an ardent desire to act well, having for its sole object the dispositions and acts of voluntary agents, is not, like moral taste, satisfied with passive contemplation, but constantly tends to act on the will and conduct of the man. Moral taste may aid it, may be absorbed into it, and usually contributes its part to the formation of the moral faculty; but it is distinct from that faculty, and may be disproportioned to it. Con¬ science, being by its nature confined to mental dispositions and voluntary acts, is of necessity excluded from the ordinary consideration of all things antecedent to these dispositions. The circumstances from which such states of mind may arise, are most important objects of con¬ sideration for the understanding; but they are without the sphere of conscience, which never ascends beyond the heart of the man. It is thus that in the eye of conscience man becomes ame¬ nable to its authority for all his inclinations as well as deeds; that some of them are approved, loved, and revered; and that all the outward effects of disesteem, contempt, or moral anger, are felt to be the just lot of others. But, to return to Hartley, from this perhaps intrusive statement of what does not properly belong to him: He represents all the social af¬ fections of gratitude, veneration, and love, in¬ spired by the virtues of our fellow-men, as ca¬ pable of being transferred by association to the transcendent and unmingled goodness of the Ruler of the world, and thus to give rise to piety, to which he gives the name of the theopa- thetic affection. This principle, like all the for¬ mer in the mental series, is gradually detached mss. ii. from the trunk on which it grew: it takes sepa¬ rate root, and may altogether overshadow the parent stock. As such a being cannot be con¬ ceived without the most perfect and constant re¬ ference to his goodness, so piety may not only become a part of conscience, but its governing and animating principle, which, after long lend¬ ing its own energy and authority to every other, is at last described by our philosopher as swal¬ lowing up all of them in order to perform the same functions more infallibly. In every stage of this progress we are taught by Dr Hartley that a new product appears, which becomes perfectly distinct from the ele¬ ments which formed it, which may be utterly dissimilar to them, and may attain any degree of vigour, however superior to theirs. Thus the objects of the private desires disappear when we are employed in the pursuit of our lasting wel¬ fare; that which was first sought only as a means, may come to be pursued as an end, and prefer¬ red to the original end; the good opinion of our fellows becomes more valued than the benefits for which it was at first courted ; a man is ready to sacrifice his life for him who has shown ge¬ nerosity, even to others ; and persons otherwise of common character are capable of cheerfully marching in a forlorn hope, or of almost instinc¬ tively leaping into the sea to save the life of an entire stranger. These last acts, often of almost unconscious virtue, so familiar to the soldier and the sailor, so unaccountable on certain systems of philosophy, often occur without a thought of applause and reward; too quickly for the thought of the latter, too obscurely for the hope of the former; and they are of such a nature that no man could be impelled to them by the mere ex¬ pectation of either. The gratitude, sympathy, resentment, and shame, which are the principal constituent parts of the Moral Sense, thus lose their separate agency, and constitute an entirely new faculty, co-extensive with all the dispositions and actions of voluntary agents; though some of them are more predominant in particular cases of moral sentiment than others, and though the aid of all continues to be necessary in their original cha¬ racter, as subordinate but distinct motives of ac¬ tion. Nothing more evidently points out the 3 0 386 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. distinction of the Hartleian system from all sys¬ tems called selfish, not to say its superiority in respect to disinterestedness over all moral sys¬ tems before Butler and Hutcheson, than that excellent part of it which relates to the Rule of Life. The various principles of human action rise in value according to the order in which they spring up after each other. We can then only be in a state of as much enjoyment as we are evidently capable of attaining, when we prefer interest to the original gratifications— honour to interest—the pleasures of imagination to those of sense—the dictates of conscience to pleasure, interest, and reputation—the well¬ being of fellow-creatures to our own indulgences; in a word, when we pursue moral good and social happiness chiefly and for their own sake. “ With self-interest,” says Hartley, somewhat inaccurately in language, “ man must begin. He may end in self-annihilation. Theopathy, or piety, although the last result of the purified and exalted sentiments, may at length swallow up every other principle, and absorb the whole man.” Even if this last doctrine should he an exaggeration unsuited to our present con¬ dition, it will the more strongly illustrate the compatibility, or rather the necessary connec¬ tion, of this theory with the existence and power of perfectly disinterested principles of human action. It is needless to remark on the secondary and auxiliary causes which contribute to the forma¬ tion of moral sentiment; education, imitation, general opinion, laws and government. They all presuppose the moral faculty: in an improved state of society they contribute powerfully to strengthen it, and on some occasions they en¬ feeble, distort, and maim it; but in all cases they must themselves be tried by the test of an ethical standard. The value of this doctrine will not he essen¬ tially affected by supposing a greater number of original principles than those assumed by Dr Hartley. The principle of association applies as much to a greater as to a smaller number. It is a quality common to it with all theories, that the more simplicity it reaches consistently with truth, the more perfect it becomes. Causes are not to be multiplied without necessity. If by a considerable multiplication of primary desires the law of association were lowered nearly to the level of an auxiliary agent, the philosophy of human nature would still be under indelible obligations to the philosopher who, by his for¬ tunate error, rendered the importance of that great principle obvious and conspicuous. ABRAHAM TUCKER.1 2 * * * * It has been the remarkable fortune of this writer to have been more prized by the culti¬ vators of the same subjects, and more disregard¬ ed by the generality even of those who read books on such matters, than perhaps any other philosopher.8 He had many of the qualities which might he expected in an affluent country gentleman, living in a privacy undisturbed by political zeal, and with a leisure unbroken by the calls of a profession, at a time when Eng¬ land had not entirely renounced her old taste for metaphysical speculation. He was naturally endowed, not indeed with more than ordinary acuteness or sensibility, nor with a high degree of reach and range of mind, hut with a singular capacity for careful observation and original re¬ flection, and with a fancy perhaps unmatched in producing various and happy illustration. The most observable of his moral qualities appear to have been prudence and cheerfulness, good-na¬ ture and easy temper. The influence of his si¬ tuation and character is visible in his writings. Indulging his own tastes and fancies, like most English squires of his time, he became, like 1 Born in 1705; died in 1774. 2 “ I have found in this writer more original thinking and observation upon the several subjects that he has taken in hand than in any other, not to say than in all others put together. His talent also for illustration is unrivalled.” (Paley, Preface to Moral and Political Philosophy.) See the excellent preface to an abridgement, by Mr Hazlitt, of Tucker’s work, published in London in 1807. May I venture to refer also to my own discourse on the Law of Nature and Nations, London, 1799. Mr Stewart treats Tucker and Hartley with unwonted harshness. DISSERTATION SECOND. 387 many of them, a sort of humourist. Hence much of his originality and independence; hence the boldness with which he openly employs il¬ lustrations from homely objects. He wrote to please himself more than the public. He had too little regard for readers, either to sacrifice his sincerity to them, or to curb his own pro¬ lixity, repetition, and egotism, from the fear of fatiguing them. Hence he became as loose, as rambling, and as much an egotist as Montaigne; but not so agreeably so, notwithstanding a con¬ siderable resemblance of genius; because he wrote on subjects where disorder and egotism are unseasonable, and for readers whom they disturb instead of amusing. His prolixity at last increased itself, when his work became so long, that repetition in the latter parts partly arose from forgetfulness of the former; and though his freedom from slavish deference to general opinion is very commendable, it must be owned, that his want of a wholesome fear of the public renders the perusal of a work which is extremely interesting, and even amusing in most of its parts, on the whole a laborious task. He was by early education a believer in Chi’istian- ity, if not by natural character religious. His calm good sense and accommodating temper led him rather to explain established doctrines in a manner agreeable to his philosophy, than to as¬ sail them. Hence he was represented as a time¬ server by free-thinkers, and as a heretic by the orthodox.1 Living in a country where the se¬ cure tranquillity flowing from the Revolution was gradually drawing forth all mental activity towards practical pursuits and outward objects, he hastened from the rudiments of mental and moral philosophy, to those branches of it which touch the business of men.2 Had he recast without changing his thoughts,—had he de¬ tached those ethical observations for which he had so peculiar a vocation, from the disputes of his country and his day,—he might have thrown many of his chapters into their proper form of essays, which might have been compared, though not likened, to those of Hume. But the coun¬ try gentleman, philosophic as he was, had too much fondness for his own humours to engage in a course of drudgery and deference. It may, however, be confidently added, on the authority of all those who have fairly made the experi¬ ment, that whoever, unfettered by a previous system, undertakes the labour necessary to dis¬ cover and relish the high excellencies of this metaphysical Montaigne, will find his toil light¬ ened as he proceeds, by a growing indulgence, if not partiality, for the foibles of the humourist; and at last rewarded, in a greater degree per¬ haps than by any other writer on mixed and applied philosophy, by being led to commanding stations and new points of view, whence the mind of a moralist can hardly fail to catch some fresh prospects of nature and duty. It is in mixed, not in pure philosophy, that his superiority consists. In the part of his work which relates to the intellect, he has adopted much from Hartley, hiding but ag¬ gravating the offence by a change of technical terms; and he was ungrateful enough to coun¬ tenance the vulgar sneer which involves the mental analysis of that philosopher in the ridi¬ cule to which his physiological hypothesis is liable.3 Thus, for the Hartleian term Associa¬ tion he substitutes that of Translation, when he adopts the same theory of the principles which move the mind to action. In the practical and applicable part of that inquiry he indeed far surpasses Hartley; and it is little to add, that he unspeakably exceeds that bare and naked thinker in the useful as well as admirable facul¬ ty of illustration. In the strictly theoretical 1 This disposition to compromise and accommodation, which is discoverable in Paley, was carried to its utmost length by Mr Hey, a man of much acuteness, Professor of Divinity at Cambridge. 2 Perhaps no philosopher ever stated more justly, more naturally, or more modestly than Tucker, the ruling maxim of his life. “ My thoughts,” says he, “ have taken a turn from my earliest youth towards searching into the foundations and measures of right and wrong; my love for retirement has furnished me with continual leisure; and the exercise of my reason has been my daily employment.” 3 Light of Nature, I. c. xviii. of which the conclusion may be pointed out as a specimen of perhaps unmatched fruitfulness, vivacity, and felicity of illustration. The admirable sense of the conclusion of chap. xxv. seems to have suggested Paley s good chapter on Happiness. The alteration of Plato’s comparison of reason to a charioteer, and the passions to the horses, in chap. xxvi. is of characteristic and transcendent excellence. 388 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. part his exposition is considerably fuller; but the defect of his genius becomes conspicuous when he handles a very general principle. The very term Translation ought to have kept up in his mind a steady conviction that the secondary motives to action become as independent, and seek their own objects as exclusively, as the primary principles. His own examples are rich in proofs of this important truth. But there is a slippery descent in the Theory of Human Na¬ ture, by which he, like most of his forerunners, slid unawares into selfishness. He was not pre¬ served from this fall by seeing that all the deli¬ berate principles which have self for their object are themselves of secondary formation; and he was led to the general error by the notion that Pleasure, or, as he calls it, Satisfaction, was the original and sole object of all appetites and de¬ sires ; confounding this with the true but very different proposition, that the attainment of all the objects of appetite and desire is productive of pleasure. He did not see that, without pre¬ supposing Desires, the word Pleasure would have no signification ; and that the representa. tions by which he was seduced would leave only one appetite or desire in human nature. He had no adequate and constant conception, that the translation of Desire from the end to the means occasioned the formation of a new passion, which is perfectly distinct from, and altogether independent of, the original desire. Too fre¬ quently (for he was neither obstinate nor uni¬ form in error) he considered these translations as accidental defects in human nature, not as the appointed means of supplying it with its variety of active principles. He was too apt to speak as if the selfish elements were not de¬ stroyed in the new combination, but remain¬ ed still capable of being recalled, when conve¬ nient, like the links in a chain of reasoning, which we pass over from forgetfulness, or for brevity. Take him all in all, however, the neglect of his writings is the strongest proof of the disinclination of the English nation, for the last half century, to Metaphysical Phi¬ losophy. 1 WILLIAM PALEY.2 This excellent writer, who, after Clarke and Butler, ought to be ranked among the brightest ornaments of the English church in the eigh¬ teenth century, is, in the history of philosophy, naturally placed after Tucker, to whom, with praiseworthy liberality, he owns his extensive obligations. It is a mistake to suppose that he owed his system to Hume, a thinker too refined, and a writer perhaps too elegant, to have natu¬ rally attracted him. A coincidence in the prin¬ ciple of utility, common to both with so many other philosophers, affords no sufficient ground for the supposition. Had he been habitually in¬ fluenced by Mr Hume, who has translated so many of the dark and crabbed passages of But¬ ler into his own transparent as well as beautiful language, it is not possible to suppose that such a mind as that of Paley should have fallen into those principles of gross selfishness of which Mr Hume is a uniform and zealous antagonist. The natural frame of Paley’s understanding fitted it more for business and the world than for philosophy; and he accordingly enjoyed with considerable relish the few opportunities which the latter part of his life afforded of tak¬ ing a part in the affairs of his county as a ma¬ gistrate. Penetration and shrewdness, firm¬ ness and coolness, a vein of pleasantry, fruitful though somewhat unrefined, with an original homeliness and significancy of expression, were 1 Much of Tucker’s chapter on Pleasure, and of Paley’s on Happiness (both of which are invaluable), is contained in the passage of The Traveller, of which the following couplet expresses the main object: “ Unknown to them when sensual pleasures cloy, “ To fill the languid pause with finer joy.” . . „ “ An honest man,” says Mr Hume, “ has the frequent satisfaction of seeing knaves betrayed by their own maxims. (Enquiry into Morals.) , “ I used often to laugh at your honest simple neighbour Flamborough, and one way or another generally cheated him once a year. Yet still the honest man went forward without suspicion, and grew rich, while I still continued tricksy and cun¬ ning, and was poor, without the consolation of being honest.” (Vicar of Wakefield, chap, xxvi.) *”llorn in 1743 ; died in 1805. DISSERTATION SECOND. 389 perhaps more remarkable in his conversation than the restraints of authorship and profession allowed them to be in his writings. Grateful remembrance brings this assemblage of qualities with unfaded colours before the mind at the present moment, after the long interval of twen¬ ty-eight years. His taste for the common busi¬ ness and ordinary amusements of life fortunate¬ ly gave a zest to the company which his neigh¬ bourhood chanced to yield, without rendering him insensible to the pleasures of intercourse with more enlightened society. The practical bent of his nature is visible in the language of his writings, which, on practical matters, is as precise as the nature of the subject requires, but, in his rare and reluctant efforts to rise to first principles, becomes indeterminate and un¬ satisfactory ; though no man’s composition was more free from the impediments which hinder a writer’s meaning from being quickly and clearly seen. He seldom distinguishes more exactly than is required for palpable and direct useful¬ ness. He possessed that chastised acuteness of discrimination, exercised on the affairs of men, and habitually looking to a purpose beyond the mere increase of knowledge, which forms the character of a lawyer’s understanding, and which is apt to render a mere lawyer too subtile for the management of affairs, and yet too gross for the pursuit of general truth. His style is as near perfection in its kind as any in our lan¬ guage. Perhaps no words were ever more ex¬ pressive and illustrative than those in which he represents the art of life to be that of rightly “ setting our habits.” The most original and ingenious of his writ¬ ings is the Horce Paulina. The Evidences of Christianity are formed out of an admirable translation of Butler’s Analogy^ and a most skil¬ ful abridgement of Lardner’s Credibility of the Gospel History. He may be said to have thus given value to two works, of which the first was scarcely intelligible to most of those who were most desirous of profiting by it; and the second soon wearies out the greater part of readers, though the few who are more patient have al¬ most always been gradually won over to feel pleasure in a display of knowledge, probity, charity, and meekness, unmatched by an avow¬ ed advocate in a case deeply interesting his warmest feelings. His Natural Theology is the wonderful work of a man who, after sixty, had studied anatomy in order to write it; and it could only have been surpassed by a man who, to great originality of conception and clearness of exposition, added the advantage of a high place in the first class of physiologists.1 It would be unreasonable here to say much of a work which is in the hands of so many as his Moral and Political Philosophy. A very few re¬ marks on one or two parts of it may be suffi¬ cient to estimate his value as a moralist, and to show his defects as a metaphysician. His ge¬ neral account of virtue may indeed be chosen for both purposes. The manner in which he deduces the necessary tendency of all virtuous actions to the general happiness, from the good¬ ness of the Divine Lawgiver, though the prin¬ ciple be not, as has already more than once ap¬ peared, peculiar to him, but rather common to most religious philosophers, is characterized by a clearness and vigour which have never been surpassed. It is indeed nearly, if not entirely, an identical proposition, that a Being of unmixed benevolence will prescribe those laws only to his creatures which contribute to their wellbeing. When we are convinced that a course of conduct is generally beneficial to all men, we cannot help considering it as acceptable to a benevo¬ lent Deity. The usefulness of actions is the mark set on them by the Supreme Legislator, by which reasonable beings discover it to be His will that such actions should be done. In this apparently unanswerable deduction it is partly admitted, and universally implied, that the prin¬ ciples of right and wrong may be treated apart from the manifestation of them in the Scriptures. If it were otherwise, how could men of perfectly different religions deal or reason with each other on moral subjects? How could they regard rights and duties as subsisting between them ? To what common principles could they appeal 1 See Animal Mechanics, by Mr Charles Bell, published by the Society for Useful Knowledge. 390 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. in their differences ? Even the Polytheists them¬ selves, those worshippers of Gods partial, changeful, passionate, unjust, Whose attributes are rage, revenge, or lust, by a happy inconsistency are compelled, how¬ ever irregularly and imperfectly, to ascribe some general enforcement of the moral code to their divinities. If there were no foundation for morality antecedent to revealed religion, we should want that important test of the conformi¬ ty of a revelation to pure morality, by which its claim to a divine origin is to be tried. The in¬ ternal evidence of religion necessarily presup¬ poses such a standard. The Christian contrasts the precepts of the Koran with the pure and benevolent morality of the Gospel. The Maho¬ metan claims, with justice, a superiority over the Hindoo, inasmuch as the Mussulman reli¬ gion inculcates the moral perfection of one Su¬ preme Ruler of the world. The ceremonial and exclusive character of Judaism has ever been regarded as an indication that it was intend¬ ed to pave the way for a universal religion,—a morality seated in the heart, and a worship of sublime simplicity. These discussions would be impossible, unless morality were previously proved or granted to exist. Though the science of Ethics is thus far independent, it by no means follows that there is any equality, or that there may not be the utmost inequality, in the moral tendency of religious systems. The most ample scope is still left for the zeal and activity of those who seek to spread important truth. But it is absolutely essential to ethical science that it should contain principles, the authority of which must be recognised by men of every conceivable variety of religious opinion. The peculiarities of Paley’s mind are dis¬ coverable in the comparison, or rather contrast, between the practical chapter on Happiness, and the philosophical portion of the chapter on Vir¬ tue. “ Virtue is the doing good to mankind, in obedience to the will of God, and for the sake of everlasting happiness.”1 It is not perhaps very important to observe, that these words, which he offers as “ a definition,” ought in pro¬ priety to have been called a proposition; but it is much more necessary to say that they con¬ tain a false account of virtue. According to this doctrine, every action not done for the sake of the agent’s happiness is vicious. Now, it is plain that an act cannot be said to be done for the sake of any thing which is not present to the mind of the agent at the moment of action. It is a contradiction in terms to affirm that a man acts for the sake of any object, of which, however it may be the necessary consequence of his act, he is not at the time fully aware. The unfelt consequences of his act can no more in¬ fluence his will than its unknown consequences. Nay, further, a man is only with any propriety said to act for the sake of his chief object; nor can he with entire correctness be said to act for the sake of any thing but his sole object. So that it is a necessary consequence of Paley’s proposition, that every act which flows from generosity or benevolence is a vice. So also of every act of obedience to the will of God, if it arises from any motive but a desire of the re¬ ward which he will bestow. Any act of obe¬ dience influenced by gratitude, and affection, and veneration towards supreme benevolence and perfection, is so far imperfect; and if it arises solely from these motives it becomes a vice. It must be owned, that this excellent and most enlightened man has laid the foundations of religion and virtue in a more intense and ex¬ clusive selfishness than was avowed by the Ca¬ tholic enemies of Fenelon, when they persecuted him for his doctrine of a pure and disinterested love of God. In another province, of a very subordinate kind, the disposition of Paley to limit his princi¬ ples to his own time and country, and to look at them merely as far as they are calculated to amend prevalent vices and errors, betrayed him into narrow and false views. His chapter on what he calls the Law of Honour is unjust, even in its own small sphere, because it supposes ho¬ nour to allow what it does not forbid; though the truth be, that the vices enumerated by him are only not forbidden by honour, because they are 1 Paley, book i. chap. vii. DISSERTATION SECOND. 391 not within its jurisdiction. He considers it as “ a system of rules constructed by people of fashion—a confused and transient mode of expression, which may he understood with diffi¬ culty by our posterity, and which cannot now be exactly rendered perhaps in any other language. The subject, however, thus narrowed and low¬ ered, is neither unimportant in practice, nor un¬ worthy of the consideration of the moral philo¬ sopher. Though all mankind honour virtue and despise vice, the degree of respect or contempt is often far from being proportioned to the place which virtues and vices occupy in a just system of Ethics. Wherever higher honour is bestowed on one moral quality than on others of equal or greater moral value, what is called a point of ho¬ nour may he said to exist. It is singular that so shrewd an observer as Paley should not have observed a law of honour far more permanent than that which attracted his notice, in the feel¬ ings of Europe respecting the conduct of men and women. Cowardice is not so immoral as cruelty, nor indeed so detestable, hut it is more despicable and disgraceful. The female point of honour forbids indeed a great vice, but one not so great as many others by which it is not vio¬ lated. It is easy enough to see, that where we are strongly prompted to a virtue by a natural impulse, we love the man who is constantly ac¬ tuated by the amiable sentiment, but we do not consider that which is done without difficulty as requiring or deserving admiration and distinc¬ tion. The kind affections are their own rich re¬ ward, and they are the object of affection to others. To encourage kindness by praise would be to insult it, besides its effect in producing counterfeits. It is for the conquest of fear, it would be still more for the conquest of resent¬ ment, if that were not, wherever it is real, the cessation of a state of mental agony, that the applause of mankind is reserved. Observations of a similar nature will easily occur to every reader respecting the point of honour in the other sex. The conquest of natural frailties, es¬ pecially in a case of far more importance to mankind than is at first sight obvious, is well dis¬ tinguished as an object of honour, and the con¬ trary vice is punished by shame. Honour is not wasted on those who abstain from acts which are punished by the law. These acts may be avoided without a pure motive. Wherever a virtue is easily performed by good men—wherever it is its nature to be attended by delight—wherever its outward observance is so necessary to society as to be enforced by punishment—it is not the proper object of honour. Honour and shame, therefore, may be reasonably dispensed, without being strictly proportioned to the intrinsic mo¬ rality of actions, if the inequality of their distri¬ bution contributes to the general equipoise of the whole moral system. A wide disproportion, however, or indeed any disproportion not justifiable on moral grounds, would be a depravation of the moral principle. Duelling is among us a disputed case, though the improvement of manners has rendered it so much more infrequent, that it is likely in time to lose its support from opinion. Those who excuse individuals for yielding to a false point of honour, as in the suicides of the Greeks and Romans, may consistently blame the faulty prin¬ ciple, and rejoice in its destruction. The shame fixed on a Hindoo widow of rank who volun¬ tarily survives her husband, is regarded by all other nations with horror. There is room for great praise and some blame in other parts of Paley’s works. His political opinions were those generally adopted by mode¬ rate whigs in his own age. His language on the Revolution of 1688 may be very advantageously compared, both in precision and in generous bold¬ ness,1 to that of Blackstone, a great master of classical and harmonious composition, but a fee¬ ble reasoner and a confused thinker, whose writings are not exempt from the taint of sla¬ vishness. It cannot be denied that Paley was sometimes rather a lax moralist, especially on public duties. » “ Government may be too secure. The greatest tyrants have been those whose titles were the most, un P ’ f unbending integrity, and more bv modest independence, by steadiness and sincerity, joined to moderatmn —by the stamp of ^b^d g 7 by the conscientious considerateness which breathed through his well-chosen a g g ’ r of reasoning could'have of thirty-six, to a moral authority which, without these qualities no brilha"f. Lr Hi?s h”lh place was acquired. No eminent speaker in Parliament owed so touchi„| unanimity therefore honourable to his audience and to his country. Regre , . from theatrical display, and whose from every part of a divided assembly, unused to manifatatrons of ^ thosel„ tribute on such an occasion derived its peculiar value e bv whom he w;Lf- praised, wept, and honoured,- whom he was unknown were shed over him; and at the head of r ^ f ATr Tjornpr v,v his discernment and veracity, was one, whose commendation would have been more enhanced in ic e , . , afforded bv the name of Howard. t*lan-Tn ^ siplal Pr C-On*,Ur^^^u^descriotiml wiU^o welftcMveigh'the'wordsof the'mos’ cmn^tent of judges, 2 Those who may doubt the justice of this descnption will cl ^ - certainly verv rare that a piece so deeply philo- who, though candid and even indulgent, was not prodigal of pra _ rpn(ipr Whenever l enter into your ideas, sophical is wrote with so much spirit, and affords so much enter ^nmc-r^ ^ ^ correct and so good English, that I found no man appears to express himself with greater perspicuity. frje^idlv adversaries Dr Campbell and Dr Gerard, and publication) sufficiently shows, that Mr Hume felt no displeasure iq? amiable man an elegant and tender poet, midable antagonists, however he might resent the language o . ’ Truth an unfair appeal to the multitude and a good writer cm miscellaneous literature in prose, but who, in his ^ namnhfeteen on philosophical questions-indulged himself in the personalities and invectives of a popular pamphleteer. 404 PRELIMINARY DISSERTATIONS. sense. Instinct is the habitual power of pro¬ ducing effects like contrivances ot reason, yet so far beyond the intelligence and experience of the agent, as to be utterly inexplicable by refer¬ ence to them. No man, if he had been in search of improper words, could have discovered any more unfit than these two, for denoting that law, or state, or faculty of mind, which compels us to acknowledge certain simple and very ab¬ stract truths, not being identical propositions, to lie at the foundation of all reasoning, and to be the necessary ground of all belief. Long after the death of Dr Reid, his philoso¬ phy was taught at Paris by M. Royer Collard,1 who, on the restoration of free debate, became the most philosophical orator of his nation, and now fills, with impartiality and dignity, the chair of the Chamber of Deputies. His inge¬ nious and eloquent scholar, Professor Cousin, dissatisfied with what he calls