key: cord-0962143-rb1731d7 authors: Silva, Diego S; Jackson, Carly; Smith, Maxwell J title: Mere rhetoric? Using solidarity as a moral guide for deliberations on border closures, border reopenings and travel restrictions in the age of COVID-19 date: 2021-07-16 journal: BMJ Glob Health DOI: 10.1136/bmjgh-2021-006701 sha: 9cf8892a09343f1faec75c0885b2901408d31d39 doc_id: 962143 cord_uid: rb1731d7 nan Every government is responsible for, and accountable to, its own people. But Member States can only truly keep their own people safe if they are accountable to each other at the global level. -Dr. Tedros Adhanom Ghebreyesus, 74th World Health Assembly, 31 May 2021 1 As we enter the second half of 2021, the global health community continues to be vexed by the following question: what justifies states' continued use of international travel restrictions, including border closures, during the COVID-19 pandemic? The corollary to this question is: with declining case counts in a handful of countries and more than 2.25 billion vaccines administered globally, at what point, and under what conditions, is the reopening of state borders and the reduction of travel restrictions justified? The answers to these two questions are multifaceted and includes being clear on a country or region's epidemiology and the legal obligations of states. However, answering these questions must also balance ethical values that are often implicit and underpin these scientific and legal deliberations. Arguably, the primary ethical challenge in this context is upholding the right of sovereign states to protect their residents and reduce the risk of spreading SARS-CoV-2 while respecting the generally accepted right to the free movement of people 2 and goods across international borders. Politicians across the world have repeatedly argued that 'we're all in this together' (or other such similar remarks), on both domestic and global stages, with regard to reducing the morbidity and mortality associated with COVID-19 and, in turn, returning to a 'normal', prepandemic life. This appeal to solidarity is laudable but empty unless we understand what we mean when we use the term or invoke its spirit. We argue that a more nuanced understanding of solidarity in global health can provide states and intergovernmental organisations with a useful moral compass to guide deliberations about the continued use, and the future easing, of border closures and other travel restrictions. Moreover, describing what solidarity entails could begin to provide an ethical understanding of well-established calls for collaboration and cooperation that exists in international law-for example, Article 2 of the International Covenant on Economic, Social, and Political Rights 3 -that help shape present-day global health and also shape our thinking about borders in the context of pandemics. We require articulating what solidarity is, why solidarity is morally and instrumentally important, and how solidarity can help guide policy decisions about borders, travel restrictions and freedom. ► Solidarity, and the rhetoric of solidarity, is commonly used by world leaders in the context of global efforts to control COVID-19. ► Solidarity is a relational value that means that persons in positions of power stand with others, usually marginalised persons, for the sake of justice. ► Marginalised persons and communities are best positioned to know what is important to them. As such, solidarity means leading with governments of lowincome and middle-income countries on COVID-19related matters. ► Therefore, solidarity means that decisions regarding the continued use or easing of international and regional travel restrictions must be made together by high-income, middle-income and low-income countries. Solidarity is increasingly invoked by policymakers and politicians in addressing the challenges related to COVID-19, often as it relates to the actions (or inactions) of high-income countries (HICs) toward low-income and-middle-income countries (LMICs 5 The importance of noting the rhetorical use of solidarity is twofold: first, to underscore its centrality in global health politics, and second, to suggest that if politicians and other decision-makers invoke the value of solidarity, they ought to be clear about that to which solidarity commits them. In other words, if solidarity is being invoked to communicate moral commitments that ought to guide action, rather than being invoked as mere platitude (and we will charitably reject such a conclusion), we must be clear about what solidarity requires in this context. In practice, solidarity generally denotes actions and costs that persons in positions of power willingly accept to stand with others, usually marginalised persons or groups, for the sake of justice or fairness. 6 Solidarity is a relational value, which '…holds that individuals and communities are bound together, or mutually interdependent, and thus, that personal and collective well-being are intimately linked'. 7 It has an intuitive appeal during public health emergencies, including pandemics, given the adage that viruses do not respect borders. COVID-19 has demonstrated what global successes are possible when countries and regions choose to act in concert with each other, 8 and what global failures come about when we ignore such an imperative. 9 Critically, solidarity also requires that when persons in positions of power stand with marginalised groups, it is the latter-that is, the marginalised-who lead in whatever activities they have identified as critical for their well-being. This conclusion rests on the notion of epistemic justice, 10 which means (among other things) giving primacy to the experiences and knowledge of marginalised persons in matters in which they are protagonists. Solidarity justifies action in one of two ways, which are not mutually exclusive: first, we should act in solidarity because it is the right thing to do, 11 that is, for the sake of justice or fairness. Second, we can invoke solidarity in an instrumental manner, as a means of achieving some other important goals that cannot be achieved unless we act collectively. 12 In the context of COVID-19, acting in a solidaristic manner means taking actions that reduce risks of transmission for ourselves and others and working to ensure the effects of COVID-19 are not disproportionately located among the least advantaged. The reasons are straightforward: arresting transmission promotes everyone's well-being, and those persons living in HICs will not be truly safe until everyone is safe from COVID-19 (and vice versa). What solidarity does not tell us is how to uphold and promote it as a value. Acting in solidarity with others sometimes requires acting in potentially counterintuitive ways. At first glance, solidarity might suggest to us that borders should not be closed insofar as this appears to be insular, self-interested thinking. On the other hand, one might argue that solidarity requires closing borders to arrest the transmission of SARS-CoV-2 since it is in everyone's interests, so long as some key moral conditions are met (see further). The reopening of borders and travel, and the continued use of intermittent international travel restrictions, requires coordinated efforts regionally and globally. There is a growing chorus of states, intergovernmental organisations 13 (eg, WHO, the World Bank Group, World Trade Organisation, etc) and scholars 14 calling for countries to work together, particularly on the challenge of equitable vaccine distribution and vaccination passports, which taken in concert are seen as central to reopening international travel. Through the Digital Documentation of COVID-19 Certificates specifications, the WHO '… will guide Member States on how to digitally document COVID-19 vaccination status, SARS-CoV-2 test results, and COVID-19 recovery status'. 15 The push for such coordination is not merely from countries and United Nations agencies, but also encompasses industry, too. For example, the International Air Transport Association (IATA), a trade association for airlines globally, makes it clear that international standards in testing and vaccine harmonisation (ie, 'globally standardised approach… with regard to equivalent treatment of different vaccines and mutual recognition of vaccination certificates' between countries) are two necessary conditions for largescale air travel as COVID-19 begins to wane. 16 Critically for IATA, they claim that the aviation industry is ready to collaborate in earnest with national governments, '… BMJ Global Health provided governments set benchmarks against which we can plan for restart'. 15 The instrumental impetus behind efforts to coordinate equitable vaccine distribution and passports for the mass reopening of international travel is intuitively clear, that is, first and foremost, to improve global, regional and local economies. It can also be defended by appealing to the value of solidarity. As noted previously, solidarity acknowledges the relational nature of persons and communities and calls for working together to tackle challenges that cannot be resolved otherwise. Critically, and perhaps overlooked by politicians and others in positions of power who-nonetheless-invoke the rhetoric of solidarity, acting solidaristically commits the economically and politically powerful to support marginalised persons in leading efforts toward their own empowerment while providing the material resources necessary to ensure everyone's well-being is promoted and ensured. In the context of global cooperation in reopening international travel, solidarity means that G7 and G20 nations, as well as intergovernmental organisations, must not make decisions unilaterally without genuine intervention by governments in LMICs and in accordance with their best interests. The colonial history of international health is littered with examples of initiatives being done onto peoples in LMICs. Solidarity is antithetical to such actions. Concretely, representatives from LMICs must have some meaningful decision-making powers when negotiating not just global vaccine distribution (which they do not have, to date) but also on matters of vaccination passports and the movement of persons and goods, more broadly. In short, cooperation between states, as well as between states and the private sector, should not exclude meaningful participation of LMICs. If we take heads of states seriously when they appeal to solidarity in the context of COVID-19, they must accept the obligations entailed by solidarity as persons in positions of power. In the context of opening borders and reducing travel restrictions, this means working together across countries and between regions to ensure actions taken to ease travel restrictions do not disproportionately negatively impact LMICs. However, more importantly, it also means leading with governments from LMICs. Anything less would mean that invocations of solidarity are insincere and hypocritical. Twitter Diego S Silva @DiegoSilvaPhD and Maxwell J Smith @maxwellsmith int/ directorgeneral/ speeches/ detail/ director-general-s-closing-remarks-at-theworld-health-assembly Universal Declaration of Human Rights OHCHR. International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights The International community must guarantee equal global access to a covid-19 vaccine Macron says it is in Europe's interest to provide Africa with COVID-19 vaccines Key ethical concepts and their application to COVID-19 research A failure in solidarity: ethical challenges in the development and implementation of new tuberculosis technologies ACT together 2020-2021 Impact Report int/ director-general/ speeches/ detail/ director-general-s-openingremarks-at-the-media-briefing-on-covid Epistemic justice as a condition of political freedom? Solidarity in the moral imagination of bioethics Solidarity in Biomedicine and Beyond 067D C974 D204 F6ED E679 world bank leaders: why we are calling for a new commitment to vaccine equity and defeating the pandemic. The Washington Post Global coordination on Crossborder travel and trade measures crucial to COVID-19 response Revised scope and direction for the Smart Vaccination Certificate and WHO's role in the Global Health Trust Framework revisedscope-and-direction-for-the-smart-vaccination-certificate-and-whos-role-in-the-global-health-trust-framework Acknowledgements We thank Drs Lisa Forman and Roojin Habibi for several important conversations about the content of this paper and for politely suggesting/ implying we completely rewrite an earlier draft of it (they were totally right). Contributors DS, CJ and MJS all shaped the core ideas of the paper. DS drafted the paper and led the editing of it. CJ and MJS helped draft and edit the paper.Funding This study was funded by WHO (Ethics of Public Health Emergency Preparedness). Patient consent for publication Not required.Provenance and peer review Not commissioned; externally peer reviewed.Data availability statement There are no data in this work.Open access This is an open access article distributed in accordance with the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 Unported (CC BY 4.0) license, which permits others to copy, redistribute, remix, transform and build upon this work for any purpose, provided the original work is properly cited, a link to the licence is given, and indication of whether changes were made. See: https:// creativecommons. org/ licenses/ by/ 4. 0/. Diego S Silva http:// orcid. org/ 0000-0002-8195-6404 Carly Jackson http:// orcid. org/ 0000-0002-7116-9466 Maxwell J Smith http:// orcid. org/ 0000-0001-5230-0548