IMAGE EVALUATION 
 TEST TARGET (MT-3) 
 
 t 
 ^ 
 
 / 
 
 
 O 
 
 
 ^/ /A 
 
 
 f/. 
 
 ^<5 
 
 1.0 
 
 I I.I 
 
 11.25 
 
 1:1 liia 
 
 Hf ii£ mil 2.0 
 
 1.8 
 
 1.4 II 1.6 
 
 I 
 
 vw .^ 
 
 <? 
 
 /? 
 
 
 O 
 
 7 
 
 
 / 
 
 > 
 
 Photographic 
 
 Sciences 
 
 Corporation 
 
 23 WEST MAIN STKEBT 
 
 WEBSTtR.N.Y. M580 
 
 (716) 872-4503 
 
V 
 
 1 
 
 CIHM/ICMH 
 
 Microfiche 
 
 Series. 
 
 CIHIVI/ICMH 
 Collection de 
 microfiches. 
 
 Canadian Institute for Historical Microreproouctions / Institut Canadian de microreproductions historlques 
 
Technical and Bibliographic Notes/Notes techniques et bibliographiques 
 
 Th« 
 to 
 
 The Institute has attempted to obtain the best 
 original copy available for fiiming. Features of this 
 copy which may be bibliographicaily unique, 
 which may alter any of the images in the 
 reproduction, or which may significantly change 
 the usual method of filming, are checked below. 
 
 D 
 
 D 
 
 D 
 D 
 
 D 
 
 Coloured covers/ 
 Couverture de couleur 
 
 I I Covers damaged/ 
 
 Couverture endommagde 
 
 Covers restored and/or laminated/ 
 Couverture restaurde et/ou pellicul6e 
 
 I I Cover tit!e missing/ 
 
 Le titre de couverture manque 
 
 Coloured maps/ 
 
 Cartes gdographiques en couleur 
 
 Coloured ink (i.e. other than blue or black)/ 
 Encre de couleur (i.e. autre que bleue ou noire) 
 
 i I Coloured plates and/or illustrations/ 
 
 D 
 
 Planches et/ou illustrations en couleur 
 
 Bound with other material/ 
 Relid avec d'autres documents 
 
 Tight binding may cause shadows or distortion 
 along interior margin/ 
 
 La re liure serr6e peut causer de I'ombre ou de la 
 distortion le long de la marge intSrieure 
 
 Blank leaves added during restoration may 
 appear within the text. Whenever possible, these 
 have been omitted from filming/ 
 II se peut que certaines pages blanches ajout^es 
 lors d'une restauration apparsissont dans le texte, 
 mais, lorsque cela dtait possible, ces pages n'ont 
 pas 6t6 filmdes. 
 
 Additional comments:/ 
 Commentaires suppl^mentaires; 
 
 L'Institut a microfilm^ le meilleur exemplaire 
 qu'il tui a 6t6 possible de se procurer. Les details 
 de cet exemplaire qui sont peut-dtre uniques du 
 point de vue bibliographique, qui peuvent modifier 
 une image reproduite, on qui peuvent exiger une 
 modification dans la mdthode normale de filmage 
 sont indiquds ci-dessous. 
 
 D 
 
 D 
 
 D 
 
 v/ 
 
 n 
 n 
 
 Coloured pages/ 
 Pages de couleur 
 
 Pages damaged/ 
 Pages endommagiies 
 
 Pages restored and/or laminated/ 
 Pages restaurdes et/ou pelliculdes 
 
 Pages discoloured, stained or foxed/ 
 Pages ddcolor^es, tachet^es ou piqu^es 
 
 Pages detached/ 
 Pages ddtachdes 
 
 Showthrough/ 
 Transparence 
 
 Quality of print varies/ 
 Quality in6gale de I'impression 
 
 Includes supplementary material/ 
 Comprend du materiel suppldmentaire 
 
 Only edition available/ 
 Seule Edition disponlble 
 
 Pages wholly or partially obscured by errata 
 slips, tissues, etc., have been refilmed to 
 ensure the best porsible image/ 
 Les pages totalement ou partiellement 
 obscurcies par un feuillet d'errata, une pelure, 
 etc., ont M filmdes d nouveau de faqon d 
 obtenir la meilleure image possible. 
 
 Th( 
 poi 
 of 
 filr 
 
 Ori 
 bei 
 the 
 sio 
 otK 
 firs 
 sio 
 or 
 
 rh( 
 shi 
 
 Tir 
 
 wii 
 
 Ma 
 difi 
 enl 
 be^ 
 
 "9 
 rec 
 me 
 
 This item is filmed at the reduction ratio checked below/ 
 
 Ce document est fWvni au taux de reduction indiqu6 ci-dessous. 
 
 10X ^AX 18X 22X 
 
 26X 
 
 30X 
 
 X 
 
 12X 
 
 16X 
 
 20X 
 
 24X 
 
 28X 
 
 32X 
 
The copy filmed here has been reproduced thanks 
 to the generosity of: 
 
 University of Saskatclwwan 
 Saskatoon 
 
 The images appearing here are the best quality 
 possible considering the condition and legibility 
 of the original copy and in keeping with the 
 filming contract specifications. 
 
 Original copies in printed paper covers are filmed 
 beginning with the front cover and ending on 
 the last page with a printed or illustrated impres- 
 sion, or the back cover when appropriate. All 
 other original copies are filmed beginning on the 
 first page with a printed or illustrated impres- 
 sion, and ending on the last page with a printed 
 or illustrated impression. 
 
 The last recorded frame on each microfiche 
 shall contain the symbol — ► (meaning "CON- 
 TINUED"), or the symbol V (meaning "END"), 
 whichever applies. 
 
 Maps, plates, charts, etc., may be filmed at 
 different reduction ratios. Those too large to be 
 entirely included in one exposure are filmed 
 beginning in the upper left hand corner, left to 
 right and top to bottom, as many frames as 
 required. The following ciagrams illustrate the 
 method: 
 
 L'ttxemplaire film* fut reproduit grfice A la 
 g6n6rosit6 da: 
 
 University of Saskatchewan 
 Saikatoon 
 
 Les images suivantes ont 6x6 reproduites avec le 
 plus grand soin, compte tenu de la condition et 
 de la nettetd de I'exemplaire filmd, et en 
 conformity avec les conditions du contrat de 
 filmage. 
 
 Les exemplaires originaux dont la couverture en 
 papier est imprim6e sont film6s en commen^ant 
 par le premier plat et en terminant soit par la 
 dernidre page qui comporte une empreinte 
 d'impression ou d'illustration, soit par !e second 
 plat, selon le cas. Tous les autres exemplaires 
 originaux sont filmds en co .:men9ant par la 
 premidre page qui comporte une empreinte 
 d'impression ou d'llustration et en terminant par 
 la dernidre page qui comporte una telle 
 empreinte. 
 
 Un des symboles suivants apparaitra sur la 
 dernidre image de cheque microfiche, selon le 
 cas: le symbole ^•- signifie "A SUIVRE", le 
 symbole V signifie "FIN". 
 
 Les cartes, planches, tableaux, etc., peuvent dtre 
 filmds 6 des taux de reduction diff^rents. 
 Lorsque le document est trop grand pour dtre 
 reproduit en un seul clichd, il est film6 6 partir 
 de I'angle supdrieur gauche, de gauche 6 droite, 
 et de haut en bas. en prenant le nombre 
 d'images ndcessaire. Les diagrammes suivants 
 illustrent la mdthode. 
 
 1 
 
 2 
 
 3 
 
 1 
 
 2 
 
 3 
 
 4 
 
 • 
 
 6 
 
Tin- irniK AL system 
 
 OK 
 
 ADAM SMITH. 
 
 
 By KTHBI^ MITIR, M. L. 
 
 Thesis presented to the l"";icult\- of Cornell l-iii\ersity for the 
 degree of Doctor of I'hilosoph)-, M;i)', 1896. 
 
u 
 
 PRKFACK. 
 
 In trcatiii^M)f the ethical system of Adam Smith I have 
 found it necessary to introduce at some length the views 
 of sexeral of his predecessors, in order to show the source 
 and to trace the development of fundamental principles 
 emphasized in the Theory of the Moral Sentitncnts. This 
 reference to previous systems was also necessar>- in order 
 to bring (nit the independent contribution which Smith 
 himself-made to ICnglish ethical thought. 
 
 Though dealing with an ethical subject, this thesis was 
 undertaken primarily as a study in the histor\- of Philoso- 
 phy. I. have tried to acknou ledge m\- indebtedness to the 
 \ arious authors from whom I ha\e receixed help in foot- 
 notes. Mere, however, I wish to acknowledge my obliga- 
 tions for many valuable suggestions to Professor J. \\. 
 Creighton, under whose direction the essay v as written. 
 
 !•:. M. 
 
 Mount Holyokc College, 
 Dee. i8()8. 
 
ERRATA. 
 
 On 1 
 
 age 17 - igtli line Iron, top, for " atlrrts ' read effects. 
 28 — 4th line from top, for " /.<* t/iot " read or tluii. 
 
 .V) ~ 9lh line iVom bottom, for " instrwth-e '• read instinctive. 
 57 — i6th line from top, for ''present " read prevent. 
 61 —20th line from top, for " decote '■ ,cad denote. 
 
•,N' U l^s- '•' 
 
 CONTENTS. 
 
 PART. II. 
 
 PART I. SMITH'S PRHDKCKSSORS. 
 CHAPTKR I. INTRODUCTION 
 
 !:; I. ShAITKSIU'KV. 
 !^ 2. HUTCHKSON. 
 
 ij 3. HuMi:. 
 
 SMITM'S TIll'.OKV OK THK MORAL SENTI- 
 MKN'TS. 
 
 C;HAPTER I. SV.MPATHV. 
 Sympathy thk Soukcf. ok Mouaf. f ri>(;.\ii:Nr. 
 Sympathy thk Soukck or .Mi.rit and Drmkrit. 
 iNi'i.UKNcn: OF Utility, Ci'siom an'D Fasfhon i'pon .Moral 
 Judg.mknt. 
 
 CHAPTER H. -'THE NATURT: OK C'ONSCHCNf'E. 
 § 1. Conscience and Sympathy. 
 5^ 2. Conscience Identified wtth Reason. 
 § 3. Conscience the Sourcic of the .Moral Ideal. 
 
 chap'ter III.- conclusion. 
 
 v^ I. Relation of the Theory of (he Moral Seniiiiietits to other 
 
 ETHrcAL Systems. 
 ^ 2. Function of Reason and of Sense in the Theory of the 
 
 Moral Seii/inieiit<^. 
 
 ^ 2. 
 
,.>^.\V^ '^-^ ■•• 
 
 I'.,. . 
 
 •.. • Kr.^ 
 
 THE ETHICAL SYSTICM OF ADAM SMITH. 
 
 PART i.-SMrni's i'Ri:i)i-:ci':ss()Ks. 
 
 CllAn I'.R I. I\T1<()1)1( TION. 
 
 The \\()i"k of the Mor.il Sense l'hil()S()|)her.s was of the first 
 importance for MnL;iish I'lthics. As a refutation of the extreme 
 e{^(Msin of llobbes, aiu' an exhibilion of the naturahiess of man's 
 social affections, it was most successful. l>ei;innin^L;' with Shaftes- 
 l)ur\', and carried on by ilutcheson and ilume, this line of 
 th(niL,dit is bnJUi^ht to its final c:om])letion in the JV/ron' of the 
 Moral Scutiiitoits of Adam Smith, wIkj was, undoubted!)', cjne 
 (jf the Ljreatesi thinkers Scotland has e\er produced. 
 
 In 1751, Smith, at the ai;!' of twent) -ei^ht, was chosen 
 Professor of Loj^ic in tlis L'l^iversit)' of (ilasj^ow, and in the fol- 
 lowing^ )'ear was elected to the chair of Moral i'hilosoph)' at the 
 same Universitv' : ' a ])osition which had been held shortlx' before 
 this by PVancis Ilutcheson. In the JAvv?/ .S"(7//////(7//.v and the 
 Wealth of Nations we ha\e what has been preser\ed of 
 Smith's lectures at Gias<4'ow, the h'conomic beiiiL;' supplementary 
 to the I'^thical work. - Tlie former is rei^arded by Buckle as the 
 most imi)ortant book that has e\er been written, •' is ranked by 
 Max Miiller as the peer of Kants' Criti(]iic and is, undoubtedly, 
 the work uj^on which the author's fame pre-eminentl\' rests. Hut 
 Smith's ethical \ lews, as ex|)resse(l in the Thco)y are also ex- 
 tremely \aluable, and are worth)' of far more attention than has, 
 as yet, been bestowed ujion them. 
 
 Buckle, certainly, in his History of Civilirjatioii, expresses 
 the most im(]ualified api^roxal and enthusiastic admiration. 
 liut he rej^^ards Smith's wcjrk as so completel)' an P'.thics of .Syin- 
 
 1 Dut^alcl Stewart, Life and Writ incis of Dr. Smith. Introduction. 
 
 2 Ibici, Introduction. Prof. J. VV. Wilson, An Old Master and other Vuliti- 
 cal Essaijx, p. 6. 
 
 3 Buckle, History of Civ ilizutiun in England, \u\. \, \>. 214. 
 
 I 
 
MiiK : 
 
 patli)'. th.il lu' fail-- to riiiphasi/i.' points upon which the author 
 
 was most anxious llialstico> should 
 
 IX- 
 
 aul 
 
 Onckcn, on the 
 
 otlicr hand, in his Die litliik Adiim Smith's iiiiii KdHt's draws so 
 close a parallel between the ethical systems of tiiosc two j^rcat 
 writers, and reL,^-lr(ls Snn'th's \iewof(lut\- as of such paramount 
 ini|)ortanct;, that he practically ignores the ^reat fundamental 
 doctrine of sym|)ath)'. llence, from his treatment, nothin^f l)ut 
 the most erroneous impression as to Smith's re.d position can 
 possibl)' be obtained. ' 
 
 As the 'ilicorv of the Moral Si'iitiiiieiits was written 
 
 rli 
 
 th 
 
 the Wia/th 
 
 i\ (it ions, It is not 
 at all surprisiiiLj that the former should suffer by contrast with 
 the threat l''.conomic work. iUit the Theory is alscj an admir- 
 alile book, showiiiLj a remarkal)le power of (observation and wealth 
 of illustration. Huckle claims so close a connection between the 
 two, that neither can be understood without the other. liut, for 
 the understandiiiLij of the llicory of the Moral Sentiments, a 
 knowledge of the ethical writers who preceeded Smith, is much 
 more imp(;rtant than a kiujwled^^e of his own Wealth of 
 Nations. l*"or, by the former, wi- _L;ain informaticjii as to his 
 statement of the (|uestion, and some idea as tcj how far .Smith 
 is indebted to those earlier thinkers, - nd what he has done in- 
 tiependentl)' for the de\elopement of the ethical problem. With 
 this in \iew we will consider briefly the systems of Shaftesbury, 
 Hutcheson and iiume, before takins; up the special subject of 
 " Adam Smith's Theory (jf the iMoral Sentiments." 
 
 SKCTIoX I. — SilAFTl-.SIJlJRV. 
 
 Shaftesbuf)- is the first of the Moral Sense Phikjsophers. 
 With him, a new phase of ICnglish ICthics begins. Me, in 
 coinmon with all the moralists of his time in hji54land, is an un- 
 com|)romisinL;" opponent of Hobbes. lie, however, differs from 
 the majority in the L;'round of his opposition ; and institutes s 
 new method of attack. - C'udworth and his school had been 
 aroused by Ilcjbbes's insistance that \^oo(\ and evil are deter- 
 mined by the sovereit;n ; and had maintained the essential and 
 eternal distinctions of morality, as independent of any arbitrary 
 will, human or divine. This question possessed no interest for 
 
 SlJ 
 
 titj 
 
 nuj 
 
 anl 
 
 thi 
 
 \\\ 
 
 col 
 
 ini 
 
 w; 
 
 ini 
 
 h. 
 
 cr 
 
 vi 
 
 1'- 
 oi 
 
 ai 
 
 til 
 
 si 
 ir 
 
 1. XoTE. A more satisfactory treatment of Smith's Ethics, recognizing 
 the importance in tlie system of both sympathy and duty, is found in a Ger- 
 man's Dissertation, by J. Schubert, Die Moralphilosophie Adam Smith's, 
 Lei|)zij^, iSyi, which deals particularly with Oncken's views. I shall have 
 occasion to refer to both of those writers later in this work. 
 
 2. Sidgwick History of Ethics. Chap. iv. 
 
llli; l.niKAl, SVMKM Ol' ADAM SMIIII. 
 
 Of 
 
 Sliartcsl)iii'\-. who rct;anlc(l all (lisLUssi(iM>. as to substances, en- 
 tities, and the eti-rnal and inuiuitahle relations <jf thiiij^s a> so 
 much eni|)t\' sound ' It was the e;4oisin of the s\ stem which 
 ani,fered him ; and he set himself to refute so false an account of 
 the nature of man. 
 
 Shafteshur)' aj^rees with Cumberland in insistinL,^ upon the 
 ultimatel)' social character of human nature. Cumberland had 
 compared society to an ori^anism, and had maintained the eciual 
 importance of .s)in|)athy with ii^oism. Ihe [greatest happiness 
 was, for him, the ol)jective end ; and he rei^arded the i^ood of the 
 individual and the L;ood of society as identical - Siiaftesbur)' 
 holds that each individual beini; is a member in a swstem of 
 creatures, wlu'ch a common nature binds toi;ether. The indi- 
 \idual man himself is a svstem, of whicii the \arious appetites, 
 l)assions, and affections, are all united untler the supreme control 
 of reason. Tlie parts of this s\stem are so carefully arranged, 
 and so interdependent, that an)- disarrauLjement or dispropor- 
 ticui, however slight, ma\- mar and (lisfiLiin'e the whole. If a 
 sini^le passicMi is extended loo far, or continued too h^ng, 
 irrecoverable ruin and misei v ma\' result. •' 
 
 Tliis idea of s\stem, or the harmonx' of |)arts, is the leading 
 idea in Shaftesbur)''s ethics. I lis fundamental conce|)t is 
 aesthetic, unity in \ariet)- is the all-per\ adini;' law of tiie world. 
 In e\ery case where parts work toLjether toward a common 
 result, there rules a central principle. The parts <>f thej^j^anism 
 are held toi^ether b\- the soul ; and, in TITcr~lari;er s)stems to 
 which man is eviden'd)' related, individuals are joined with one 
 another into species and i^enera b)' hi,L;her imities. ■* Out of} 
 society, and out of coninumity, man never did nor nexer can 
 e.xist. •'' There is no sense more natural than the sense of fellow- 
 ship ; and this sense, as evinced in lo\(,' of community, is one of 
 the plainest means of self- preservation ; and a most neccs.sary 
 condition of self-enjo)i^ent. '' The mf )ral a nd social system has 
 thus its foundations dee,; in the naUire of man. "^ Just as truly 
 as musical haruKJuy antl proportion are natural, so also is there 
 
 1. Sitlilnqvy. Vt. III. Sec. i. 
 
 2. Da LfijihuH Xaturae. Introduction. 
 
 3. Inqitiri/ conccrnimj Virtue and Mrrit. Bk. 11. I't. 11. Sec. i. 
 
 4. Ibid. The Moralists. I't. 11. Sec. i. Dp. 286. 318. 
 
 5. Ibid. Vol. II. ]). 354. 
 
 Falckenl)er;; Ilistorij of rhiloKi>j)li>j, En.i,'. trans., p. iy6. 
 
 6. Essaij on the fre.edom of Wit and lluiiior. I't. III. Sec. 2. 
 
 7. Adrirjito an Autlior. I't. lii- Sec. 3. 
 The Moralists, [>. 411. 
 
M L' I K 
 
 la harmony and proportion of \irtuc in the character and the 
 affections (jf men. Shaftesbiu)- thus finds a natural basis for 
 
 .iethics, iiulepen(h:nt of self interest or conwnitional fancies. The 
 Vood for him is the beautiful, and the beautiful is the sym- 
 metric;'.! ; hence the essence of \ irtue consists in tlu; balance, the 
 
 u'inony or proportujii, (^1 the aliections and the passujns. 
 
 Shaftesbury is a thoroujjfh-Li'oinc; optimist ; whatever is 
 is rijj^ht. The finalit)- and beauty o( the parts of the world 
 which we can know, ju-^tifies the inference to a like constitution 
 
 o 
 
 fth 
 
 ose w 
 
 hich 
 
 [u-e ima, oroac: 
 
 that the numerous e\ 
 
 I 
 ils, w 
 
 habk 
 
 so 
 
 that 
 
 we may be cerram 
 
 hich we find in the details, work f')r a 
 
 .systein superior to them, and that all apparent imperfections 
 contribute U) the perfection of the whole. ' i-'roni the idea of 
 social and moral harmon\-, Shaftesbur)' infers the existence of a 
 formative pcjwer which works [juri)(jsivel\-, an all rulint^ unity, 
 the soul of the world, the Deity. \\'hat Shaftesbury means by 
 the Deity is however not (|uite clear, lie, at times, uses lan- 
 yua^^e, which, as Leslie Stephen remarks, ^ would fit into an 
 orthodo.x sermon about a personal God ; '* \et his teaching bears 
 much m(jre resemblance to the pantheism of Spinoza. (iizycki 
 concludes that while passaLjes are not wantini;', in which Shaftes- 
 bury rej^ards nature, and the life-L;i\ ini;" power of natiuv, only as 
 the representatives of l'ro\ idence, the Creator endowed with all 
 power, yet his jjroof onl\' leads to a world-.soul, and not to a 
 God. ■* This is the; \iew which is held also by I'owler, ^ who 
 s;))-s : "we ma>' infer that Shaftesbur)" conceived tlie relation of 
 God to the Wcjrld as that of the .Soul to the body. Nature is, 
 as it were, the vesture of God, and (iod the soul of the 
 Universe." As the in(li\idual mind understands, thinks, and 
 plans f(jr tlie indi\ idual self, so the Universal Mind understands 
 and acts for the whole of Nature. " This Universal Mind i:, not 
 only all-powerful and all-wise, but is, also, perfectly ^ood. For 
 a general mind could have no private interests ; but the good of 
 the whole and its own good would, necessarily, be one and the 
 same. " 
 
 Shaftesbury, consistently recognizes no conflict between the 
 
 1. Thp Moralists. Vt. i. Sets. 2, 3. 
 Il)id. .Sec. 4. I't 1 1. 
 
 2. Leslie Su|ilicii, En^/Ush Tliomjht nf llw Nineteenth Century. 
 
 3. The Moralists. I't. 11. Sec. 3. 
 
 4. (}izycki, Die Philosojihie SliKfUshiiry's. \). 62. 
 
 5. T. Fowicr, Shiiflesbtir;/ vnd lltttrhesun. Cluip. iv. p. 106. 
 
 6. The Mordlists.' Pt. ill. Sec. 5. 
 
 •/. Letter concerning Enthusiasm, Sec. 5. 
 
 p. 25. 
 
 I 
 
Tin: KIIIKAI SVSIl.M ()[•■ ADAM SMITH. 
 
 111(1 the 
 fisis for 
 'I'lie 
 syiii- 
 ice, th'j 
 
 111 some cIcl;tvc in 
 
 Uood of the indixidiKil .ind that ofsocictN'. Ihc natural and the 
 self alTections, he ccjininciids as both Liood and both necessar\'. ' 
 15ene\()lence is the principal moral \irtue : but a due re^anl to 
 the interests and the preser\ation (>f tlie indi\ idual is not 1)\' any 
 means U) be neglected. As in particiiiar cases public aliection, 
 on tlie one hand, ma)- be too hiL;!i, so pri\ate affection, on the 
 other hand, ma\' be too weak. These affections toward pri\atc 
 }^ood are necessar}- and ess.'iilial to \irlue. I-"or though no crea- 
 ture can be called \irluoi:s nieitly for possessint;' these affections, 
 yet, since the\' are es^ontia! lo the welbbein;.;' of the system, 
 a creature wantiiiL;" in them is uantin 
 natural rectitude, and is \ icious and defective 
 
 The disinterested impulses, while aimiiiL;' at other's l;i)0(I, 
 lead a man to his own ; while the self-affections, which aim at 
 th<? individual's i,^ood, oiiK' attain their object when kept within 
 strict bounds. In addition to the natural, and tl'.e self affections, 
 Shaftesbury distiiiL^uisl'ies tin; unnatural affections. These are 
 sufficientK' characterised by tlu.ir definition; since the)' arc 
 affections that tend neithei" to public nor to ])ri\ate s^ood. P'rom 
 Shaftesburx's point of \ iew it is not eas)- to understand this 
 classification. I'^or wh\" are the affections, which tend to the 
 ^ood of others, any more natural than the self-affections? The 
 .selfish affections, as he lu'in^elf occasionall)' admits, are just as 
 imijortant for the econonu' of nature. Win-, therefore, ma\- thev 
 not also be classed as natural. And wlu' should those, w hich tend 
 neitlier to public nor to private l;oo(1 be, on that account, termed 
 unnatural? If all e\il works for tlie ^ood of a superior s)stem, 
 and all ap[)arent imperfection contributes to the perfection of the 
 whole, this latter class would appear to be as natural as either of 
 the others. - 
 
 Ujjon the |)n'pcr balance, the harmony of the passions, 
 virtue depends. Tlie \ irtucnis man has at heart the interest of 
 the public. •' \\ hen all the affections and passions tend to the 
 |jublic Li'ood, or the t^ood ol the species, the temper is .said to be 
 entirely [jjood ; and if w j have this universal good aJi our end or 
 aim, we shall never be deceixed by false views of rii,dit and 
 wron<^. "* But Shaflesbur)- alst; defmes \irtue as a lo\e of <(o(xl- 
 nes.s for it;; cjw i, sake, on account of its ou n natural beauty and 
 
 1. fiii/nini,Wi II. I't. I. Sec. 3. 
 
 2. jodl (IcxrhirhU: del' Etiii/i. 
 
 3. Iwinirii, I5k. 1. I'l. iii. Sec. 2 
 
 4. Ibid, lik. 1. I't. II. Sec. i. 
 
10 
 
 MUIK : 
 
 thy or hot. \st, ;iik1 ni;ikc that notice of worth and honesty 
 hject of his affections, lie is not \irtiious. It is this reflectix'e 
 
 worth. ^ Hence to understand his idea of virtue we must 
 include these two elements : a disinterested lo\e of t^oodncss, 
 and that harmony of the passions most conducixe to the [)ublic 
 good. 
 
 This di' interested lo\e of goodness is not natural, and can 
 only be obtained b\' reflection. A j)erson may be generous, 
 kind, coinpassionate , and )et, if he does not reflect U|)on what he 
 himself does, (jr sees others do, so as to take notice of what is 
 wor 
 an o 
 
 notice, which constitutes a truly good character. - Shaftesbury 
 is conscious that just as in art, ignorance and want of taste may 
 rule, so, in the moral sphere, the case may be the same. VV'i; 
 learn by reflection not only to admire, but to have an inclination 
 to admire that which is trul)- admirable. This attainment of a 
 pure moral taste, which correctly distinguishes harmony and 
 discord, is represented b>- Shaftesbury throughout as no easy 
 matter. 
 
 We are led to this redective approxal and disai)proval of 
 the just and natural, or of the unjust and unnatural b>' a first 
 principle in our constitution, by a natural sense of right and 
 wrong.'* 'J'his faculty, which approves of right, and disap- 
 proves of wrong, is wit/. Shaftesbury a sense, and more than 
 once he antici[jates Iluicheson in calling it a moral sense.'* 
 [This doctrine of the Moral Sense is ncjt, however, b)' any me<".ns 
 the central point (jf the system ;•'' the har mony_of the passions 
 and affections isj as we -have seen, the main doctrine. But the 
 Moral Sense is that which exercised the greatest influence upon 
 future writers of the school, especially upon Hutcheson, 
 and is therefore often mistakenl)' considered the fundamental idea 
 of Shaftesbury's ethics. Jlhis Moral Sense is universal, livery 
 human being is endowed with natural inclinations fitted for the 
 percepti(;n of moral harmony. However perverted and corrupt 
 ii heart may be, it yet finds, in all cases, a distinction between 
 two actions or inclinations, from which it approves of the one as 
 suitable, and rejects the other as unsuitable. We have here a 
 
 cl 
 rl 
 
 i 
 
 CI 
 
 1. Ingniry, Bk. n. Pt- i. Sec 3. 
 
 2. Essay on the Freedom of Wit and Humor, p. 121. 
 
 3. Iiit/niry, 15k. i. I't 111. Sec. I 
 
 4. Ibid, Bk I. l*t. 3. Sections i, 2, 3. 
 
 5. Note. For continnatioii of tills view, see Sidgvvick's History of 
 Ethics, Chap. iv. For the opposite opinion, Scliiiljcrt, Die Moral Philos- 
 ophie, Adam iSmilh's. Introductory chapter. 
 
Tin; i/miCAi. snsik.m jv adam smith. 
 
 II 
 
 hint of the "Impartial Spuctator " which afterwards became so 
 im|jortant in Smith's s\stem. 
 
 This moral sense, wliich is Shaftesbury's idea of conscience, 
 has its foundation in nature, and. while in its natural condition, 
 is main!)- emotional ^ As emotional, it d(jes n(jt occupy so 
 commanding" and important a position in man's nature as does 
 reason. Hut it adnn'ts of education and improvement, and this 
 improvement consists in a general i^redominance of the rational 
 element. The office of this educated conscience is the reflective 
 approval of thei^ood, and disapiiroval of the e\il. No rational 
 creature is e\er entirelv de\t)i(l of this moral or leflex sensibility. 
 When, by means of this ri:ilecti\e conscience, the right has been 
 detennined, our <uithor thinks that all that is necessar}- for virtue 
 or goodness has been accomjjlished. Knowledge and virtue are 
 practically one in the sy^^<:m. l*'vil and wickedness, in and for 
 themselves, are nothing. They are merel>- negations of the 
 good, owing to the incompleteness and the limitations of our 
 nature. 
 
 The operation of the Mor.il Sense, when uncorrupt :(1, is 
 always in harmony with rational judgment as to what is or is 
 not conducive to the good of the human species, though it does 
 not neccessarily involve the explicit fcjrmation (jf such a judg- 
 ment. b-\en ;i man who had no moral sense, would alwaj's find 
 it to his interest tf) maintaiti in himself precisely that balance of 
 social and self-regarding affections which is best adapted to 
 .secure the good of societ)', and such a being might be said to 
 have goodness, though not \ irtue. lUit such a man, Shaftesbury 
 holds, is not really to be found. 
 
 The ap[)robati()n or disapprobation of this inoral sense, to- 
 gether with the love and reverence of (iod, form the pro[)cr 
 sanctions of conduct. Neither the fear of future punishment, 
 nor the ho[je of future reuard can possibly be regarded as goixl 
 affections, nor as the source of any truly good acticjn. " No 
 acticjii prompted by these motives can be regarrled as good and 
 virtuou.s. " - Virtue must please by its own worth and beauty, 
 and not because of any external advantage. We are not to 
 corrupt the love of the good f(;r its own sake by mixing with it 
 the hope of future reward. •' We have here a hint of Kant, in 
 
 1. Till' Moralists, Vl ill. Sec. 2. 
 Imiriiry, I't. ill. Sec. 2. 
 
 2. n>id, Rk, II. Pt. II. Sec i. 
 Ihid. Hk. I. I't- I. Srr. 3. 
 
 3. Falckcnbcijr. History oj i'hilosuphij, Enj^. trans., p. 200, 
 
 tmimemm^iimmmmmmmmmmm^a 
 
12 
 
 ML'IU : 
 
 Shaftcsbur)''s view that tlic excellence of the object, and not the 
 reward or punishment shcnild be our ni(jti\e for conchict. 
 
 As to what coiistitutes the end of moral action, Shaftesbury 
 is not very explicit. In tr)ini; to disco\er what he reall)- c(jn- 
 ceives to be the t^ood, there are two |)oints which it is well to 
 keep in mind: — (i.) The j^ood of tlio individual, and the ^^ocjd of 
 society are one and the same. (2.) .Shaftesbur_\' recoi^nizes no 
 possible conflict between \irtue and happiness. Ilence if we can 
 find that which constitutes a person cillicr \irtuous or happ)-, we 
 
 ihall have found the pood. 
 
 th 
 
 der Ih 
 
 lie \anous e.\'])lanations <4'i\ei 
 
 1 of 
 
 ifu 
 
 1 akmi( 
 the t^ood 
 
 IS, however, render ine matter somewnat conuisini;". 
 the more [general defmitions first: — [\.) That alone is 
 in which the nature of man can rest contented and find satisfac- 
 tion. ^ (2.) Life and ha|)piness consist in action and emphjy- 
 nient, and nothing can be called ijood h\\\ what is constant. - 
 (3.) Virtue is the chief of all excellencies and beauties. ^ (4.) 
 It consists in a harmony of the passions and affections, a love of 
 goodness for its (jwn sake, and a lo\e of beautx' and order in 
 societ)'. ■* Tliis arra)' of definitions is not \er)' satisfactorx', and 
 instead of thrcjwing any light up(jn the matter appears rather to 
 'darken counsel with words.' Hut the subject beccjnies clearer 
 when we remember that, to Shaftesbury, the good, the beautiful, 
 and the harmonious are one. This practically reduces (3) and 
 (4) t(J identical propositions ; and we are left w ith the g(KKl, 
 as that in which the nature of man can find satisfaction ; which 
 must, also, be constant and furnish action and emplojinent. 
 Two interpretations of this good have been offered : (1) 
 Hedonistic, the good is pleasure; and ii) it is self-satisfaction. 
 The Hedonistic interpretation is, in this system, indefensible. 
 It fails to fulfil either the reciuirements of constancx', or that 
 of affording satisfaction to the nature (jf man. Morever, 
 Sh.iftesbury states dislinctl}' that the good is not ])leasure, 
 which he sa}'s ma)' be \er}- great, and \-et ver\- contem])tible. ''' 
 This in itself is a sufficient refutation of the aigument for 
 pleasure ; for if pleasure ma)- at the same time be \ er)' great and 
 very contemptible then surel)' it is not the good. The oidy way 
 of escape from this would be to admit c|ualitati\e distinctions in 
 pleasure, and this Shaftesbury denies ; and maintains that the 
 
 1. /»//((/>;/, Vol 1 1., p. 75. 
 
 2. Adcicp to an Antlior, p. 319. 
 
 Tim Moralists p. 223. 
 
 3. Inijuiri/, \'(il 1 1, p. 175. 
 
 4. /hid, Vdl 1 1, p. 75. 
 
 5. The Moralists, p. 229. 
 
Till'. KIHIlAI. >VSIK\I nV A HAM SMllH. 
 
 13 
 
 IKjt the 
 
 so-c.'ilU'd hii;hcr i)lc;isiircs owe their ])n.'eniiiience to tlie .'uhh'tion 
 of new and nobler elements to thi,' pleasure, ratlier than to any 
 change wliicli has takiii place in the character of the pleasure as 
 such. 
 
 Sifii^wick. howe\er, maintains ' that in the ij^reater part of the 
 arL;ument, Shaftes!)ur>' i;"i\es the i^ood of the individual this 
 Hedonistic interpretation,- makini;' it e(|uivalent to pleasure, 
 satistaction, or er;jo\inent ; and (piotes from our author, in con- 
 firmation, that " philosoph)- is niithini; hut the stud)' of happi- 
 ness.'"' 'Ihis passaL;e proves nothini;. It is a mere beL,^i4inL;" of the 
 quc;stio(i. h"or it is just upon the meanini; of " liappiness " in 
 the systeiri that the whole discussion turns. .And whatever else 
 happiness may mean, for .Shafleshur)-, it does not mean pleasure 
 in ail}' ordinarx' acceptation of the term. ' 
 
 The other interpretation of the ^ood, \\hich makes it 
 equivalent to self satisfaction, brings .Sliaftesbury \ery near to 
 Aristotle and the self-realisation moralists ; and this view is 
 certainly more in keepini;' with the whole spirit of the system. 
 If we can discover that which renders one |)leasure valuable and 
 worth}', compared with another which we re;_;ard as indifferent or 
 m(\'Ui, b}' that stamp or character which ( .uises the distinction, 
 Shaftesbur}' sa}'s we ma}' define the L;'ood, '' but not b}' means of 
 the pleasure itself, lie further maintains that it is reason and 
 \irtue, which are thus called upon to ennoble j)leasure. '"' Hence 
 we must conclude that reason and \ irtue, since the}- form the 
 stamp, the reciuinnl characteristic of the so-called hii^her pleas- 
 ures, constitute that for which we are in search —the c;"o(k1. In 
 reason and in \irtue, the nature of man can rest contented and 
 find satisfaction. ihe}' also are constant and furnish per- 
 manent emploxinent and action. The}' thus satisf}' all the tests 
 of the s}'stem, and ma\- therefore be recoL;ni/.ed as the <j[ood for 
 Shaftesbur}-. 
 
 While Shaftesbur}- thus recoi,mi/.t>s reason as an im|)ortant'7 
 factor in the i^ood, in the end or aim of action, he, as we have' 
 seen, almost iijnores its ]),-ut in the formation of moral judg- 
 ments. The <i;reat chani;e, introduced b}- him in the foundation |\oV^ 
 of I''ri_i,^lish ethics, consisterl in basiuL; moral distinctions upon 
 the sentierit nature of man, rather than upon his reas m. IIq 
 
 .V 
 4- 
 
 V 
 
 6. 
 
 Tlip .^fnmh'sis. p. 233. 
 Ilisturij 11} Klliirs, |i. iSi. 
 Till' Mnrnh'sls. I't. ill. .Sic 
 Ailn'ri' to an .{iil/m,, p, 319. 
 7'lir 3/oriilisl, |). 225. 
 /hfif, |i. 229. 
 
 I . 1>S. 
 
»4 
 
 MUIR 
 
 re^ardcfl the affections anrl passions as tlie object of a hit^hcr 
 reflective jiul^ntiLj affection, an innate faculty of moral jucl^ment, 
 
 or sense for rvj 
 
 rht 
 
 and urontr, 
 
 a moral sense. 
 
 W 
 
 e appn^vc 
 
 virtue and condemn \ ice b}- nature, and from this natural feelini^ 
 for ^'ood and e\il, exercise develops a cultivated moral taste, 
 (ioodness recpiires the rellectixe a])i)ro\al and disap[)roval of 
 our own conduct, and that of others. 
 
 Shaftc iburj 's account of the Moral Sense is, ho\ve\er, most 
 unsatisfactory. While, e.\plicitl\', he alinost ii,niores the share of 
 reason in its judgments, and t^reatly e.\ai;jt;erates the share of 
 
 emotion, yet, in wliat he di-scribesas the work of the iiKM-al sense, 
 the constant exercise of reason is imi)lied. l^'or, before we can feel 
 either approbation or disapprobation, we must refer an act tf) a 
 cla.ss, or connect it by association with other acts of a similiar 
 kind. In either case, com|)arison or reflection is involved, and 
 the process is a rational one. The \ery statement, that the 
 approval or disa|)proval must be reflective, implies the influence 
 of reason on the moral judL^ments ; while Shaftesbury's treatment 
 tends to utterl}' obsci'.re the fact of this influence, lie admits 
 that the Moral Sense is capable of cultixation and improve- 
 ment; Init he does not state in what the process of education 
 consists. Me L^enerall)' describes moral decisions as thoUL^h 
 they were immediate, and makes no attempt to analyse the 
 Moral Sense, except b\' the occasional recoL,nu'tion of a rational, 
 as well as an emotional element. As the moral taste becoines 
 better instructed, the rational element becomes more prominent. 
 If, then, we resj^ard Shaftesburx-'s idea of Ljoodncss as tlie 
 reflective approval and disapproval of our r)wn conduct and that 
 of others, we find rea.son necessarii)' implied ; and no less is this 
 the case if we consider his other view of t^oodness, as love to 
 mankind in [general, the study of the um'xersal L;ood, or the 
 promotion of the interest of the whole world in so far as lies within 
 our power. Here ai^ain reason would be indispensable for the 
 consideration of ineans, and the comj)arison of results. Hence, 
 in Shaftesbur)''s s)-stem, it is impossible to reconcile the nature 
 of his criterion of rit^ht action, and the nature of the approving 
 act. The idea of a reflectixe love of goodness, and .i universal 
 bene\()lence, as depenrlent upon sense, appears, however, 
 somewhat more consistent, when we remember that .Shaftesbury 
 regarded human nature as divine. Hence the Moral .Sense is a 
 di\ine though natural instinct. The^^cTthree conceptions — Moral 
 Sense, Henevolence, and tTie great fundamental idea of system 
 or harmony, exercised a great influence upon the succeeding 
 writers of the I'^nulish School. 
 
 tl 
 a I 
 
ajjprovc 
 
 ''•'il taste. 
 I'oval of 
 
 t^r, most 
 share of 
 share of 
 ;il sense, 
 ■ can fee) 
 act to a 
 •siinih'ar 
 wl, and 
 hat the 
 ifluence 
 -atmcnt 
 admits 
 iprove- 
 
 ucation 
 thoiioii 
 
 ■se the 
 itional, 
 --■comes 
 nincMt. 
 IS the 
 id that 
 is this 
 fue to 
 ^r the 
 uithin 
 H- the 
 I once, 
 laturc 
 oving 
 /crsal 
 ever, 
 ^bury 
 ; is a 
 ^oral 
 stem 
 xh'ng 
 
 TIIK KTHICAI SYSTK.M OK ADAM SMUII. 
 
 »5 
 
 
 Si:( TION 11. — lllJTCIII'.SOX. 
 
 Shaftesbiu), as we have seen, difl mnch to refute llobbes. 
 Indixidii.ih'sm was to him an utter impossibih'ty : mail is ever 
 part f)f a s\-stem. Altruism is just as natural as is et^oism, and 
 the bcne\()lent atid the self-re^ardint; affections both necessar\-, 
 and both tjood. Not reason, but sense, which is, however, 
 when uncf)rrupted, never in condict with reason, is man's moral 
 L,aiide. The conduct ap|)ro\ed b\- this moral sense is such as 
 tends to the i/ood of the sNstem as a whole. In this reaction 
 against eL,foism. the cliinax is reached in llutcheson, who not 
 only develops many of Shaftesbur)''s ideas, but, in his '/e;d for 
 benevolence, almost overlooks the claim of the individual as 
 such. Mis elaborate ethical s)'stem ma\-, not unfairl)', be 
 summed up in two terms : the Mor^il Sense, and Benevolence. 
 
 The doctrine of the Mctral Sense was fully de\eloped by 
 Hutcheson. Shaftesbury had sui^^i^^ested the idea, Hutcheson 
 formed the sys/o// of the Moral .Sense. ' By his adoption and 
 (le\elo|)ment of this principK', and b)' thus insistinij upon human 
 nature as the ultimate source of moral distinctions, llutcheson 
 exercised a tremendous influence both upon the philoso|)hy and 
 tht.' theoloj^y of Scotland, - where, perhaps more than in any 
 other countrv, tTre~t^n7n?nc\- had been to retrard revelation as 
 the one source of all l<nowled_i;e of moralit)'. That confidence 
 could be [jlaced in the judL,nnent of tlie human understandini;' in 
 reijjard to conduct, was an entire!}' new idea; but this llutche- 
 son taut^ht ; and insisted that the mind, if free and unfettered, 
 was quite able to deal with ethical problems. lie strenously 
 advocated the ri<^ht of private judi;nii"nt, which had been not 
 onl\' assailed, but almost destroyed b)- the Scotch l^irk, which at 
 that time possessetl unlimited |)ower and influence.'' 
 
 Hutcheson, like Shafteslnuy, rc;^ards the Moral Sense as arr^ 
 oric,M'nal princijile, a natural and immediate determination to , 
 approve certain affections, and acti(Tiis conse(]uent upf)n them. ' 
 It is an instinct, l)ut of so lii<;fli n character, that it is a constant 
 settled determination in the soul itself; as much so as are our 
 powers of jud_L,n'n^ and reasoning; ; and, like other of our |)owers, 
 it may be educated and improved. '"' l^y the |)resentation of 
 lart^er s\-stems, and more extensive affections, it is led to 
 
 1. Fnwlor, Shiif/psliitrii and IfulrlicsnH, p. 237. 
 
 2. Ki<ln)ann, l/fstor;/ <>/ I'liilosopln/, \'ol. n., p. I2|. 
 
 3. I5iicklc, Ilistnrii of Ciisli.-iifio)! \'i)\. iii., \). 293. 
 
 4. Sijsti'm iif Miirnl I'liiloxojilnj, WA. i.. |). ()i. 
 
 5. Ini]uirii, \'()1. II., p. u/). S>/xli hi,, Ch;i\t. w., p. 53. 
 
ifi 
 
 MUIR 
 
 approve (if tin- moix' worth) ()!)jccts, i-\cn whi'ii, by so cloiii;^. it 
 must ()p|)()sc the; effect of narto^ver affections, which, considered 
 in theniseKes, would be (|uile worth)' of approval. ' The exist- 
 ence of this senst; is proved h)- the fact that moral differences of 
 action are admitted !))• all, I'vcn when conscious that they will 
 not themi.elvcs be affecli'd bv' the actions. -' 
 
 Ilutcheson does not distinguish with suffirii-nt clearness 
 between emotions and ideas, j (r confnsi's the ultimate feelint^ 
 of approbatirm or disap|)rol)ation, with the intellectual proces.s, 
 which usuall)- precedes this feelini;'. llis conception of the 
 Moral Sens- is rather that of an emotional, than of a perceptive 
 facult)'. It is more analoij^ous to what lu- describes as the" I'ublic 
 Sense," that is "our determinatioti to In' pleased with the happi- 
 ness of others, and to be uni:as)- at their miser)-," than it is to 
 that of the external senses. ■'• With Shaftesbur)-, the sense of 
 beauty and the Moral Sense were one and the same sense, as 
 applied either to external objects, or to human actions, character, 
 and <Iispositions. Ilutcheson, on the contrar)-, (listinL;uishes be- 
 tween the moral aiTd aesthetic sense. 
 
 The Aloral Sense is from its \ er)- nature, flesijjjned to rej.:;u- 
 late and control all our j)owers ; ;ini| of its diL;nit)', and com- 
 manrlinij nature, we are iminerliatelv- conscious, as we are 
 I conscious of the power itself. 'I'he objects of tl-is sense of moral 
 ^oofi and ev i! are benevol /nee, on the one hanrl, and indifference 
 to the j)ublic i;o()d. on the other. ^ The pursuit of the ij^ood of 
 others is promp'ted b)- an instinct, and approved bv' the Moral 
 Sense. The onlv' actions which this sense determines us to 
 a|)prove as irtuous, are those which proceed, partly at least, 
 from a desire for the happiness of olhi^rs ; '' and the actions 
 which it recommends as the most perfectl)- virtuous, are such as 
 have the most universal unliinited tendenc\- to the L^reatest and 
 most extensive haj)piness of all the rational agents, tf) whom our 
 influence can extend. ''' 
 
 While insisting on the importance and ultimate character of 
 the Moral vSense, Ilutcheson )et acknowledges the necessity and 
 function of reason. Oar power of rellecting and judging, makes 
 us capable of discerning the tendencies of our sen.'.es, a|)petites, 
 and actions, either to our own hajjpiness or to that of otlicrs. 
 
 !. IiKpiirij, \'()1. li., p|). 107, 110, 115. 
 
 2. Ihid, \'(l. r r. Sec. IV., p. .''.03. Siistcm, W 
 
 3. I'liulo'-, Slinftrstini'!/ and liiitlti'Siin, p. 235. 
 
 4. hniiiinj, \'()1. 1 1., |). 172. 
 
 5. Ihid, Vol. II. See. 2. 
 
 6. Ihid, \'o\. II. Sec. 3., p il^i. 
 
 I , 1-. 91. 
 
TIIK KTHICAI, SYSTEM Ol' Ar)AM SMIIM. 
 
 ^> fl'M'll^-. it 
 
 coiisi(|(.rt'(l 
 
 The cxist- 
 
 'erciiccs of 
 
 the)- uill 
 
 clearness 
 itc fed i lit,' 
 a I process, 
 'II (»f the 
 perceptive 
 le" Public 
 he happi- 
 11 it is to 
 ■ sense of 
 sense, as 
 character, 
 lishes be- 
 to yc'^u- 
 ui'l com- 
 
 we are 
 of moral 
 ifference 
 
 i^OOfl of 
 
 le Moral 
 s ns to 
 at least, 
 
 actions 
 
 such as 
 est and 
 loni our 
 
 acter of 
 ity and 
 
 makes 
 petites, 
 
 others. 
 
 it 
 
 This power jud^'es about the means, or the subordinate ends, 
 but about the ultimate ends there is no reasoning. * Reason is 
 ^iven U) man in order that he ma}- jud^f of the tendencies of his 
 actions and not stupidly folloA' the first api)earance of |)ublic 
 <^rood. - Desires, a;T.-:tions, and instincts, mu>t be previous to all 
 exciting reasons, and a moral sense antecedent to all justilyintj 
 reasons.'' It is al\va)'S some i^ood which men |)ursue, and the 
 pursuit of this '^ood is prompted b}- an instinct, and ap])ro\ed 
 b)' the Moral Sense The end is determined by our Moral 
 Sense and affections, but it is reason which finds out the means. 
 The difticult\- noted in .Sh;ifte->bury's system in reL,fard to the 
 relation of rciscjn anrl the ^^oral Sense arises aj^ain here. If 
 moral excisions are entirel\- the result of an innnediate intui- 
 tion of the Moral .Sense, why do tlu-se decisions re(|uire to be 
 corrected or revised. .And if the decisions of this ^Ioral ."^ense 
 are infallible, wh)- should this facultv' be re^^arded asca|)able of 
 education or improvement? .Almost all of the diversitv in 
 nuM'al sentiment arises, llutclieson says, from o|)|)osite conclu- 
 sions of reason about the affects of actions u|)on the public, or 
 about the affections from which thev fl(jvved. Ihe Moral .Sense 
 al\va)-s approves and condemns uniformlv' the same immediate 
 objects, the same affections and dispositions. Hut jjeople reason 
 verv differentl)' in rei;"ard to actions and the notions by which 
 the}- iiave been caused.^ It is in kindlv affection, and desire 
 of the public <^no(\ that true merit is found, and not in reason. 
 The.se .systems, which rcLifard nioralit}' as conformity to reason, 
 realK' presuppose a moral sense. '• 
 
 Uy conscience, Ilutcheson sometimes denotes the moral 
 faculty itself, and sometimes the judi^Uient of the understand- 
 iuLj concerning the springs and effects of actions, upon which 
 the Moral Sense approves or condemns them. W hen we have 
 certain ma.xims and rules concerning the cf)nduct which is v ir- 
 tuous and vicious, and regard them as the laws of ("icxl, or when 
 we are persuaded that other laws are revealed to us in a differ- 
 ent maimer, then conscience ma}- be defined as, " oiu" judgment 
 concerning actions compared with the laws." Other circum- 
 stances being e(]ual, the greater the diligence and caution about 
 
 1. »S'//.'t(fm, Vol. I., p. Q3. 
 
 2. ItKiHiry conccrninii oral (UxhI and Eril, Soc. 4. 
 
 3. lUustratinns on the Moral Some, Sec. i. 
 
 4. System, \'o\. i. pp. 38. 91. 
 
 5. Illustrations on the Moral Schsp. 
 Sec. I., pp. 216. 220, 22y. 
 
 Sec. IV., pj). 80, 81. 
 Sec. v., p. 291. 
 
 .»^;r-ja«<»»???*i«*«|6gS«WS«# 
 
i8 
 
 Ml' Ik 
 
 our fliit)', so much the hotter is tlio character; and the less the 
 (lih^ence and caution, so much the worse is the < haracter.y/ 
 
 llaxiuLj coiisid -red thi- important doctrine ot" the Moral 
 Sense, ue now turn to llutcheson's all-inclusive \irtue, Me- 
 
 ncvolence 
 
 Th 
 
 ere is m 
 
 hii 
 
 man n itui\' a disinteres 
 
 4ed, 
 
 ultimate 
 
 desire for the ha|)|)ines.s <»r others ; and we onl\' approve of those 
 actions as \irtuous, which |)roceed partl\' at least from such a 
 desire. ' The l)est state, and the j^reatest hap|)iness of a human 
 being, consists in uni\er->al, efricacioii^ heneNoU'iue, jind nothin;^' 
 more than this deserves the- name of perfection. The peifeclly 
 virtuous person acts inunediately from the lo\e of others ; while 
 selfish actions are tlie cause of shame and confusion. - It is 
 not any form of selfishness, however, that causes us to des.", ,' 
 till" happiness of others ; we are not prom|)tefl to this by any 
 prospects of personal advantage, .such as wealth, p-ovver, 
 or pleasure. i-Or that which is most noble, [^.-nerous, and 
 virtuous in life, is the sacrifice of all positivf interests, and tne 
 bearin;4" all private evils for the public good ; while submitting 
 also the interests of all smaller systems to the interests of the 
 whole ; without anv other exci^ption or reserve than this, that 
 every man may look upon himself as a part of this system, aiifl, 
 consetiuentl)-, not sacrifice an imi)ortant private interest to a less 
 important interest of other.-. •' While we can.not alwa\-s know 
 the tendencv of our own actions, we m.iv endeavour, to the best 
 of f)ur power, to do that which is most likel)- to tend to the 
 public good ; and vvIhmi we are conscious of a sincere endeavour 
 for this, no evil conseciuences which ma\- result will cause us to 
 t .idemn our conduct. 
 
 This extremely altruistic |K)sition is somewhat modified by 
 Hutches(jn in his later work, ■* where he recognizes three calm, 
 natural, determinations of the will: the calm desire c^f our own 
 happiness, the calm desire of the hap])iness of othirs, and the 
 calm desire of moral perfection ; each of these is alike ultimati;, 
 but when the first comes into conflict with the second or the 
 third, the Moral .Sense never fails to dictate to the agent the 
 voiuntar}' sacrifice of the first to either of the others. Hutche- 
 son never allows much more to the individurd dian the 
 admission that, as a part of the svstein, his rights are to be 
 respected. 
 
 F. Inqninj, \'ol. ii. Sec. 2. 
 
 2. ll'i'l, \'()1. II., pp. 166. 177, 200. 21S. 239, 333. 
 
 3. IIIu.'<tr<(Hoiis npiiii ttir Mornl Si')isf. Scr. vi., p. 319. 
 
 4. Siistem 0/ Moral I'hihisd/ilty, X'ol. i., p. i). 
 
1 
 
 THK KIHICAI, SYSTI'.M Or ADAM SMUH. 
 
 19 
 
 tlir Irss (Ih> 
 
 "k- .M<,ral 
 \irtik-. lic- 
 ''I. iiltiinalc 
 '\t-' of those 
 <>ni such a 
 "' 'i iuiiiiaii 
 ifl luithinj^- 
 ^' P<.'ifcrtl\- 
 ''■'■-^ ; w hifc 
 
 "i- - It is 
 h to (k-s;. . 
 
 i'-' in any 
 h, [;o\vrr, 
 l<-''"iis, and 
 ^. and tne 
 ^iihinitt infe- 
 sts of the 
 this, that 
 tL-ni, and, 
 t to a less 
 ays know 
 " the best 
 'fl lo the 
 iifleavoiir 
 isf lis to 
 
 tlificd b)' 
 ■<^'c cahii, 
 our own 
 and the 
 ultimate, 
 I or the 
 ^vnt the 
 Hutche- 
 lan the 
 <-• to be 
 
 llutchcson is not a I'tih'l.irian, ahhou^h he eonies nuu li 
 nearer to this school tlian Sliaftesbiiiy liad done, and insists 
 repeatedl)' upon the " ^M'eatest happiness ot' thi- ;4reatest 
 number," Ijein^, in \\v:\ th.- tlrst to make u>e of tliis |)hrase. ' 
 That in action, which llutcheson considers of chief importance, 
 is the affection or moti\e. The chftlcuhw ho\\f\iT, arises for 
 him, as it has done, also, for later inora!i-.t>. lliat, in jud^iii}^' 
 actions, we are practicalU- oblisji-d to regard onl\- their effects or 
 consequences Thus, while the motive, the kind affection, is 
 that which constitutes an act reallx' or form.illx' i;oo(l. the 
 Moral Sense points out, as the only ^ood or \irtuous deed, that 
 wiiich is materially y;ood, as tending to the welfare or ha|)|)iness 
 of others. '^ 
 
 Vet llutcheson shows plaiiil}- that neither pK'asure nor use- 
 fulness forms the basis of moral distinction^. The notion unrler 
 which we approve moral conduct is not:(l) that of L;i\ing us 
 pleasure by sympath)-; nor (2; that it is pleasin;^ to our moral 
 sense; nof ''3; that it is useful to the aL;ent himself; nor ('4) 
 that of conformity to the I)i\ine will or laws. We do not 
 approve all conduct, which ;4i\es us pleasure b\- s) inpath\', and 
 sometimes we approve such conduct as does not i4i\e it. W'c 
 are plea.sed in contemplating^ the \irt.ie of another, as an ex- 
 cellence in that other, and not as something;, which brinies 
 pleasure to ourselves. .\or floes our apj)ro\al ()f the conduct of 
 another depend U|)f)n its usefulness; for the approver ne\er 
 expects a reward for the \ irtue of another ; he a|)i)ro\es when 
 he feels no interest of his own promoted; and he would the less 
 ajjprove such actions as are beneficial, the more he considered 
 them as advar.tajjeous to the aL;eiit, and imaj^n'ned him influenced 
 by views of his own adxantat^e. Nor is the notion under which 
 we ap])rovc conformit\- to the l)i\ine will ; for this must mean 
 conformity to his goodness, justice, etc ; so these moral perfec- 
 tions must be {previously known, or else the flefinition by 
 conformity to them is useless. We cannot describe our moral 
 approval, either, as fitness or congrin'tx'. The fitness of means or 
 subordinate ends docs not pro\e them to be good, imless the 
 ultimate end is go(jd ; and the term " fitness " cannot be applied 
 to an end trul\- ultimate. An ultimate end must be settled by 
 an original determination of our nature. Neither cust(jm, 
 association of ideas, nor education can form the original of moral 
 approbation, as these can gi\e us no new senses ; and the 
 
 ^ 
 
 1. Inquiry concerning ^foral Good and Evil, Sec. 3. 
 
 2. Ibid, Vol. II. Sec. iii,p i8} 
 
Ml'IR 
 
 opinion or notion !)>• which uc approve n\u^{ he an ori|^nnaI 
 
 priiui|)k', 
 
 hi 
 
 IS prMici|)lc, as wc lia\e sclmi, 
 
 is the Moral 
 
 Sense by means ot' whieh \vc" identity \ irtue and benevolence; 
 and yet it is the fact that we natural!)' appr(»\e of benevolence, 
 that proves thai we ha\e a Mt)ral Sense. 
 
 While llutchcson admits "the calm desire of moral perfec- 
 tion" as one of tin- ultimates of our nature, and claims that not 
 only universal Ljood-vvill, but also the love of moral excellence, 
 may be ranked as a ri^ht affection, - )et the former, alon^^ with 
 the Moral Sense, so occuj))' his attiMition that the latter is 
 piacticall)' ignored. Had he di-vfloped his sjstem in this direc- 
 
 tion lie would have approached closrly tlie selt-realization 
 moralists. Hut this he has not dtjne, and, as the s) stem stands, 
 we must rej^ard llutcheson as the j^real exptJiient of the Moral 
 Sense and of IkMievolence. 
 
 Shaftesbury had found no conflict, but a complete lianiio)iy> 
 between the t^ood of the individual and that of Society, and ha<^l 
 shown that it is not selt'ishness which makes us desire the j^ood 
 of others. But he h-u! insisted stronj.,dv' upon the |)leasurc 
 which accompam'es the exercise of the benevolent affections, and 
 lest it mii^ht still be thouL,dU that tin- ac(|uisition of this pk-as- 
 ure was the real motive of the benevolent man, liutclieson 
 establi.shed most carefull)- the utterl)- disinterested character 
 of those affections. He also made, as we have seen, Shafles- 
 burj^'s Moral Sense a central doctrine of his svstem, and 
 regarded benevolent actions as the onh* objects of this sense. 
 This brin<rs him somewhat into line with later Utilitarianism, 
 and it was probalilv his distinction here of the formall}' from 
 the materially L^ood that led to Smith's iuLjenious explanati(>n of 
 tlie irret;ularity of our sentiments in regard to motives and to 
 acticjns. 
 
 In considerinj^f the sanctions of conduct, Hiitcheson is atone 
 with Shaftesbiu')-. He art^ues aLjainst those who imagine that 
 an action can onlv be \ irtuous when undertaken with the design 
 of pleasing or obej'ing the Deity. ^ ^'ct the love and veneration 
 of (lod, together with the moral sancti(jn, strictlv' so-called, 
 furnishes the purest of all motives to the exercise of virtue. 
 'I'his love is a|)prf)ved by the moral facultv' as the greatest 
 excellence of mind, and is most useful from ilutcheson's point 
 
 
 t. Inifn'mj. \'u\. i., yy. 1 16, 120, \z\, 128. 
 
 l\)id. i». 2^2. 
 
 3. Illnstrdtionx upon the Mcrol Sfuse. Sec. 6. 
 
THK KIHICAI, SVhll.M OK ADAM SMI 111. 
 
 3t 
 
 '1 orif^M'iial 
 tlic Moral 
 iL'\()Icncc ; 
 'ii'\()lcncc, 
 
 pt-rfcc- 
 >^ thai not 
 xccllciicc, 
 o'lK' with 
 latter is 
 11"^ (hrcc- 
 '-■'hzation 
 11 stands, 
 i<-' A/oral 
 
 'laniioiO'^ 
 I'lfl liad 
 he j^oofl 
 pleasure 
 "lis, and 
 i-s plcas- 
 itchc'son 
 liaractcr 
 Shaftcs- 
 "1, and 
 ^ sense, 
 ■lain'sm, 
 3' n-om 
 ttif^n of 
 and tf) 
 
 at one 
 ic that 
 rlesij^n 
 lation 
 :alled, 
 virtue, 
 catest 
 point 
 
 (.f \ii-'\v ; since the love of moral perfection is a natural ineite- 
 nicnt to all {.food offices, i liutehe.son n ^'ards the Sanctions of 
 luiinan law as sinipl\- pre\enti\e and deterrent. Iluinan punish- 
 ments are onl)- methods of >elf-di reiice, ii) whiih the decrees of 
 ^nill are not the pn)])i'r measure; hut thi> measure is to he found 
 in the neccssit)' of ri'strainin<.,f actions lor the safet)' of the 
 puhlic. -' This theor>- (»f punishment is in harmoii)' with 
 ilutiheson's \ iew of morality, .md forms aiiotlu'r point of 
 a^rei'inent hetweiMi his s) stem ..wA that of later rtilitaiians. 
 
 While the main coiueptioiis of I lutcheson's system are 
 those of the Moral Sense and Hene\ oleiice, ) et his idt'al of 
 moralitv" was, like that of Hutk-r, of a life accordiii;^ to the hiL;hest 
 principl' -s of our nature. ihis \ie\\, as has heeii noted, receives 
 hut litt ,' de\elopinent in the s\stem ; hut that llutcheson 
 re^Mrded it as the ^oal to l)e attained 1)\ the exerci.sc 
 of the Moral .Sense and the practice of uni\ er>al HeiKAolence is 
 shown h\' the follouiiiLr (Uiotalion : "()ur Moral Sense shows 
 this calm extensi\e affection to he the hiL^hest perfection of our 
 nature, what we ma\- see to he the end or desi;^!) of such a 
 structure, anrl, conse(iuentl_\-, what is ie(|uirecl of us hy the 
 author of our nature ; and, therefore, if an\- one like this des- 
 cription hettcr, he ma\' call \iilue- the actini;' accordini; to what 
 we ma)' see from the constitution of our nature we were 
 intended for h\- our Creator." ^ 
 
 Sr.c TION III i It MK. 
 
 In opposition to l^Ljoism as the hasis of conduct, Shaftes 
 ])ur\- had shown the complete harmoiu' hetue en the affecticais 
 (jf s elf lo\e and lo \c for o thers. lie had found also in the 
 natufcTTJT inan a .sense which dislini^niished hetween ri^jht and 
 wronj^, and which led to self-sacrifice for others, if the ^ood of 
 others reciuired that sacrifice. Hut Shatteshurv had emphasized 
 .so stronj.;l)' the pleasure resullinj^' iVom henevolence, and the 
 complete identit}' of \ irtue aiul happiness, that his system was 
 left open to the sus|)icion of still harhourini,'^ a suhtle form of 
 Ilobbes' hated cUjctrine. 
 
 Hutcheson prevents an}' such misapprehension in reL;ard to 
 his views by makinj^ benevolence the (Jtie all-inclusi\e virtue, 
 
 1. T. Fowler, iShnftesltKry niid IfntrlifixiDi, ^), Kjy. 
 
 Sijstrin (ij Miirdl riiilnsniiluj. Hk. i. Clui|). lo. 
 
 2. llluntratiiiHs n)>i>n tin' Moral Srnsi>. Sec. 6. Art 6. 
 
 3. Essay on the Nature and Conduct of the Passions and Affections, Preface, 
 
 p. 16. 
 
ii 
 
 MUIR : 
 
 which cDiistitutos the only object of the Moral Sense. He 
 insists th.'it the |)Icasure resulting', from benevolent actions can 
 on!}- be olitained b\- a disinterested desire for the good of others, 
 and is never to be had b\- merely desirini^ it. Hence the wish to 
 benefit others is (luite distinct from the desire for the pleasure 
 arisinL,^ from benexolence. JUit even here a difficulty arose. 
 The onl\- objects of the moral sense are actions which tend to 
 the general good. Ikit w hat if such an action shall have been 
 performed from an interested moti\e? Hutcheson decided that 
 in such a case the act was materiall\- good, but not formally so ; 
 for to be formal!}- or reall\- good, the motive, al.so, must be 
 ber,e\(jlent. 
 
 Hume entirel)- does away with all such distinctions. His 
 first great problem in the 7";7v;//.sv' is regarding the source of our 
 moral judgments, lie agrees with Shaftesbury and Hutcheson 
 that this is found not in reason, but in sense. J^'or morals have an 
 influence upon the actions and the affections, and .so active a 
 principle as conscience or a sense ol morals could never have as 
 its source an) thing so w holl)' inactixe as reason. ^ Our approv- 
 al or disapproval of an action simpl\- means that from the con- 
 stitution f-jf c)in' nature, we ha\e a feeling or sentiment of prai.se 
 or blame from tlie contemplation of it. Moralit)- is neither a 
 relation of objects, nor a matter of fact, and hence can be, to 
 Hume, no object of the understanding. '^ 
 
 It was difficult to see, e\en in Shaftesbury's .s}stem, any 
 objective \alidit}- for morality, when e\il is regarded as but a 
 negation of the good, and our moral judgments as based on 
 sensations. Hut both Shaftes bury and Hutcheson regarded those 
 judgments as objecti\eI\' called forth, and as not ultimately 
 referable to the person judging. With Hume, however, com- 
 plete ethical sul)jecti\it\- is reached. Vjrtue and „.vice are 
 dislinguished b\- particular i)leasures and pains. We do not 
 ihlerll characTer to be \irtuous merely bixause it i)leases, but in 
 feeling that it pleases after a particular maimer, we, in effect, 
 feel that it is \ irtuous. Hume thus makes virtue and vice .syn- 
 on}'mous with pleasure and j)ain. h'.ach of the passions and 
 operations of the mind has a particular feeling which must be 
 either agreeable or disagreeeable; the first is virtuous, the second 
 vicious. The jjarticular feeling constitutes the very nature of 
 the passion, and, therefore, need not be accounted for. ^ 
 
 ( il 
 tl 
 
 i. 
 
 1. Trentii^e of Ilianaii \<itrn'f, Rk. III. 
 
 2. Ihhl, l!k-. "ill. I't. 111. Sec. 1. 
 
 3. Ihid, 15k. III. Pt. I. Sec. 2. 
 
 Pt. '.' Sec. 3. 
 
■nil-. Ki iiicAi, >^s■l•|:\I .u- .\i>,\m >miiii 
 
 23 
 
 Sense. He 
 t actions can 
 "(1 of others, 
 ' tlie wish to 
 tJie pleasure 
 culty arose, 
 ich tend to 
 have been 
 ccided that 
 ^nnally so ; 
 must be 
 
 tions. fifs 
 ince of our 
 Hutcheson 
 als ha\ e an 
 'O active a 
 er ha\e as 
 Jr approv- 
 1 the con- 
 <^f praise 
 neither a 
 -in be, to 
 
 stem, any 
 as but a 
 based on 
 :lcd those 
 Jtiinately 
 er, com- 
 vice are 
 ' do not 
 s, but in 
 n effect, 
 ice syn- 
 ons and 
 tnust be 
 e second 
 iture of 
 
 ( 
 
 i 
 
 riiis ir.oral pleasure is only excited by tlie character and 
 sentiments of a person, and onl)- 1)\- ihcin when considered with- 
 out any lererence to our particular interest. It is onl}' in means 
 t)f s\ inpath}' that \\e can obtain the pleasure which enal)les us 
 to recognize others as \ u'laous. i lutcheson liad nested as an im- 
 portant determination or sen^e of the soul, the s}-m|jalhetic 
 sense, which he pronounced \cvy (hlTerent iVom any e.\ternal 
 sense. ' H)' its means, whi'U we ,i])prehend the state of others, 
 we natur.ill}' lia\e a fellow -feeliiiLi witli them. In considering^ 
 the pain or distress of another, we feel a strong' sense of pit\- and 
 a _L;re<it inclination to relieve him w ithout .ni\' thouLjht of the ad\ an- 
 tage that we oursehes may obt.iin tliereliy. I'his sNinpathetic' 
 sense, winch takes the 'place of the Moral .Slmisc ot" .Shaftesbury 
 and I lutcheson, becomes a Umdamentai doctrine of Hume's 
 
 system, and is especially important on account of its influencjj 
 upon .Smith's lahics. 
 
 Hume's treatmerit of sympathx' is one of the- most interest- 
 ini;' features of his work. i"or a writer to whom the nnnd is 
 nothini; but a series of sei)ar.ite impressions, and who holds that 
 we can know notlniiL;; but our own feelings, -' to insist upon our 
 knowledj^e of, and entrance into the feelinL;s of others, is most 
 inconsistent. Hut this our author does, and he- maintains that 
 s)'mpath\' is um'versal, and is obserxable through the whole 
 animal creation, but especiall\- in man, who can form no wisli, 
 that has not a reference to societ}'. This sympatliy is the 
 chief source of moral distinctions, and is a more noble source 
 than an\' original instinct of the human nn'nd. ■' 
 
 The origin (jf this principle, ilume explains b\' the con\er- 
 sion of an idea into an impression. The idea or impression of 
 self is alwax's present and lively, antl an\ object related to our- 
 seUes must be conceived with a like \i\acit)'. ( )ther i)eople 
 closel}" resemble ourselxes, and this resemblance makes us 
 easil)- enter into their sentiments. The relations of contiguity 
 and causation assist, and all. together, convey the impression 
 or consciousness of one pi'i'son to the idea of the sentiments or 
 passions of others. Thi.s the idea of another's sentiment or pas^ 
 sion ma\' be so enlivened a-^ to become that vei\' sentiment or 
 passion. In s\ini)athy the mind passes from the idea of self to 
 that of another object, wiiich is contrar\- to the law of transition 
 of ideas. It does so, because the sc//, in<le|)endent of the 
 
 1. ]\utcht'son, Siistprn of MordI I'liildsni, 1,1/^ \'i,\. i. p. ]i). 
 
 2. Tri'iitinr, l',k. I. I't. 4. Sit. 6. 
 
 3. I hid, lik. IV. I't. II. Chap. 6. 
 
 
24 
 
 MUIR : 
 
 •r 
 
 perception of c\cry other object, is in realit}' nothing ; so \vc 
 must turn our view to external objects ; and it is natural for us 
 to consider inf)st attentively such as arc near to us, or resemble 
 us. On account of resemblance, every human being has an 
 achantage o\er e\ery otiier object in operation on the imagina- 
 tion, and by a vivid imaginati(jn we often feel the pains and 
 pleasures of others which are not really in existence. ^ 
 
 In discussing this subject in the 1i)t(]iiiry, Hume gives up 
 his original characteristic position of the Treatise, and s}'m- 
 pathy' becomes practically a fe eling of hu nianit\% In the later 
 work, there is little to differentiate his treatment from that of 
 Ilutcheson. In the T^vvvr/'/.sv', our benevolent or social feeling is 
 regarded as a mere sensitivity to |)leasure and pain, which has 
 become complicated and transformed b)- sj-mpathy. This 
 sympath}- is described b\- Selb\'-Hig"e as a soKent by which 
 1 lunie reduces complex feelings to sim])ler elements. - Hut in 
 ihcjii/qiiiry, s\-mpath}' is just anothcrjianie for benevolence, or 
 iTatural philanthrop)', rather than the name of the process by 
 which the social feeling has been constructed out of non-social 
 or indi\idual feeling. The generosity ascribed to man in the 
 Treatise is e.xceedingl}' limit(;d. In one instance Hume goes so 
 far as to declare that there is no such passion in human minds 
 as the lo\e of mankind, merely as such, independent of personal 
 (jualities or of relation to f)urself, and that it is only by means of 
 s}'mpath\' that we are at all affected by the hai)pincss and the 
 misery of others. JUit in the luicjuiry, where sympathy has 
 been transformed into bene\"olence, Hume, in several instances, 
 expresses an exactl\' opposite opinion. ^ 
 
 Hume speaks, in this later work, of" a thousand instances, 
 which are marks of a general benevolence in human nature, 
 where no real interest binds us to the object,"'* and refers to 
 " the natural i)hilar,thropy of all men."' The controversy be- 
 tween self-lo\e and benexolencc is said to be one which can 
 never be .settled, and our author concludes that the selfish and 
 tlie social sentiments are no more opposed than are the selfish 
 and ambitious, selfish and re\engeful, selfish and \ain. '' There 
 n^ust be an original basis of some kind for seIf-lo\e, and none 
 
 n1 
 
 b 
 
 111 
 
 111 
 
 o| 
 
 el 
 \i 
 
 1. 7'/yv?<('.sr, lik. II. Pt. II. Sec 5. 
 //-/(/, jip. yj, y-o, 339. 340. 
 
 2. EiK/itirii roiicrnu'nii the Human Understanding, hitroduction. 
 
 3. Ihid, Scctiiins i8j, 187, 
 
 4. //-/(/, Sec. 252. 
 
 5. Ibid, Sections 189, 190. 
 
 6. Ibid, Sec. 230. 
 
 a. 
 
iothinj,r; so we 
 ' natural for us 
 ">^, or resemble 
 t»ein<,r has an 
 " the imar^ina- 
 tJie pains and 
 :e. ^ 
 
 lime rr/vcs up 
 
 ^''' -ilLlf' sj'm- 
 ^'1 the later 
 n-om that of 
 cial feelin<»- is 
 '". which has 
 '-'t'ly- This 
 -lit by which 
 Its.-' J JLit in 
 i_evolence, or 
 process by 
 J^ non -social 
 'nan in the 
 ume goes so 
 iman minds 
 "f personal 
 3y means of 
 -ss and the 
 "P'-ithy has 
 1 instances, 
 
 ' instances, 
 an nature, 
 refers to 
 •oversy be- 
 vvhich can 
 'elfish and I 
 
 the selfish 
 •" There 
 and none 
 
 rHI': KIIIK .\1, SVSTF.M OF ADAM SMITU. 25 
 
 more suitable for this can be found than benexoience or 
 humanit)-. The happiness of otluMs in\;u'iabl\- causes us pleas- 
 ure, their miscr\- causes us pain. Hence, Hume concludes, 
 these are ori^^inal principles, which cannot be resohed into 
 otiars whicli are more sinipk'. ' 
 
 As will be seen from this use of sxinpatlu' and an original 
 feelinL,^ of hi'.nianity, 1 1 ume is far removed from the l\t;oism of 
 Ilobbes. Hut equall)- distant, if not still fartlier, is he, in his 
 earlier work, from the extreme bcue\()lent theorx- of Ilutcheson. 
 W'l-ile he holds that the natural selfishness of man lias been 
 ^reatl)' o\ er-estimaterl, and that it is rare to meet with a i)erson, 
 in whom the kind affections do not overbalance the selfish, he )-et 
 admits that each man lo\es himself better than an\' other 
 j)erson, - and upholds a certain amount of selfishness as natural. 
 While, also, the increased beiRwolence of the liiiqiiiry is import- 
 ant, its increased utilitaria!n'sm must be remembered, and, as 
 Selb}- HiL;'!.;c' points out, conseiiuences mis4ht be drawn from this 
 later use of utilit}-, which would completeK' neutralize all the 
 concessions made to benevolence. '■' As the .s\-stem stands, 
 however, Hume is broui^ht much nearer to Ilutcheson in the 
 /w/r/////-)' b\' this treatment of benevolence, which is not only of 
 vastly increased importance on its own account, but has also 
 taken the place of the s}-m|)athy c)f the Tiratisr. 
 
 i'robabl}- Hume's greatest departure from views of the 
 Moral Sense ])hilosophers is to be found in his treatment of nat- 
 ural and artificial \ irtues. Natural virtues are those which have 
 no dependence on the artifice or contrivance of man, ■* while 
 the artificial virtues are inventions, which we rank as moral 
 virtues, simplv because thev tend to the i^^ood of mankind. The 
 i;-ood which results from a natural virtue results from ev erv' single 
 act ; while, from an artificial virtue, a siuLjle act, considered in 
 itself, ma\- often be contrarv' to the public ^^ood, and it is only 
 die concurrence of mankind in a y;eneral scheme or s\-stem of 
 action which is advantai;eous. Now it is onl)- bv' means of sv'in- 
 path) that we are pleased u ith the j^ood of societv', where our 
 own interest is not concerned. Hence sj-mpath)- is the source 
 of the esteem, which v.e pay to all of the artificial virtues and to 
 tho.se of the natural virtues, which tcMid to the ^^ood (jf others. " 
 
 1. KiKiiiinj, Sec. 250. Xiitc. 
 
 2. TrcMti^'r, P.k. 111. I'l. M. p. 1X7. 
 
 3. Kminirij {lSf)4), Introduction. 
 
 4. Tnatisf, p|). 471;, 577, 580. 
 S- I hid, Bk. m. J). 57H. 
 
26 
 
 MUIR : 
 
 Hume insists that justice is not a natural hut an artificial 
 virtue. It arises artificall}-, thou^di necessarily, from education 
 and human invention. ^ It has its origin in the selfishness of 
 mankind, combined w ith the scant)' provision Nature has made 
 for their wants. Hoth man's disposition and his circumstances 
 are thus adverse to societ}'. Hut for this " Nature provides a 
 remedy in the judgment and understanding;, for what is 
 irregular and incommodious in the affections. " - 
 
 The remed)' suL;<;ested is \ery similar to that of Hobbes, 
 but there are here no promises i^i\en. The members of societ)' 
 e.xpress to each other a s^^eneral sense of commtjn interest, and 
 immediately the idea of justice arises, and depenrlent on this 
 idea, such others as those of propert)-, obliL^ation, and r\[.\\\t.. 
 come into existence. This con\ention is not at all one of i^^ood- 
 ness or wickedness, but is entirel)' one of prudence or of folly. 
 Hume's treatment of justice is ver\- much modified in the 
 Enquiry. Its origin he still finds m utilit\', but he no lont^er 
 rej^ards it as an artificial virtue ; for he here pronounces it as 
 natural as sclf-lo\e, benevolence, reason, or forcthoui^ht, and claims 
 that " in so sai^acicus an aiu'mal as man, the necessar)- pnxluct 
 of his reason maj' ji'stly be esteemed natural. " 'I'he keepini^ 
 of promises, and submission to go\ernment, Hume also ranks 
 as artificial virtues. 
 
 We have seen that .Shaftesbur)' rej^arded the judgments 
 of the Moral Sense as al\\a)'s in accord with reason, and that reas- 
 on became in his sj'stem the su[)remc ruler of the moral life. Ilut- 
 
 ♦-cheson departed from Shaftesbury's doctrine on this point and 
 said : "not in reason, but in kind affection, and desire of the 
 public good is virtue found.." .\nd now with Hume, reason, once 
 
 -the supreme governor of the will, has bect^me merel}' the slave 
 of the passions. •' Its functions, along with that of the Moral 
 Sense, have been delegated to sxiripathy. Sxnipath)', or the 
 symimthetic sense, had been mentioned 1))' Jlutcheson as an 
 important inipulse of our nature, which spontaneous!)' assumes 
 any feeling observed in another. ^ This s)'ni|)athy becomes 
 with Hume the basis of our moral judgments, but it is also, by 
 him, curious!)- com|)licated with utilit)-. X'irtue and \ice are 
 .synonymous with pleasure and pain. It is on!)" b)- means of 
 
 itil 
 
 vh| 
 wai 
 obi 
 
 \V 
 
 dol 
 mil 
 th( 
 ini| 
 
 te 
 HI 
 
 oV 
 h:J 
 
 1. TreatwAW^. in. I't. ii. Sec i. 
 
 2. Ihid, Bk. III. |). 487. 
 
 3. Ihid, Bk. II. I't. III. So(-. III. p. 415. 
 FalckenberL,s lUMory of liiilosujilin, p. 233. 
 
 4. Hulchcson, tSystem. Vol, i. p. ly. 
 
THK KIHUAI. SVSTKM OK ADAM SMITH. 
 
 27 
 
 I't 'til artificial 
 
 ''■f"n ^'flucation 
 
 "^' ■'Selfishness of 
 
 i^i"-e has made 
 
 <-i|-cui)istaiiccs 
 
 i"v provides a 
 
 '''^'' what is 
 
 'lat of Hobbcs, 
 ><-''s of societ)' 
 '"^^''■L'.st, and 
 "f't^iit on this 
 ^'1. and rij^ht. 
 ' '"leofn-ood- 
 ^ f>r ,,f folly 
 '''ified in the 
 he no longer 
 '"ounces it as 
 'it. and claims 
 ;^ao- product 
 J he keepino- 
 If also ranks 
 
 - inf'j4'ment.s 
 'If' that reas- 
 ilhfe. Jlut- 
 
 Point and 
 esirc of the 
 ■cason, once 
 '' the slave 
 
 tlie M(„-al 
 '13'. or the 
 eson as an 
 y assumes 
 becomes 
 ■'^ also, by 
 
 vice are 
 
 means of 
 
 Syinpalhv that \vc recot;nizc this moral |>Icasurc and pain ; but 
 it is, nc\ertholess, thcutilit}', the pleasure or pain produced, upon 
 l^'hich f)ur judi^ment of the action depends. As bencxolencc 
 vvas the only object of the Moral Sense, so pleasure is the only 
 object of the s\-in|)athetic sense. ' With all these admissions to 
 the |)leasure-pain theor\- we naturall}' class Hume as a 
 Hedonist. And, indeed, with his ps\ cholo^)-, it is somewhat 
 doubtful how he can ccjiisistentl)- hold any other theor\'. If the 
 mind has, or, rather, is, nothini; but a series of fleeting states, 
 then the onl)' rational procedure would be, to make those fleet- 
 ing states as pleasant as possible. 
 
 Hut Hume is no Utilitarian in an)' recognised sense of the 
 terin. He denies the fundamental principle of the theor)'. 
 He was not led away b}- tin; fallac\- that the desire for an 
 object, e\en an object which, when attained, shall be foimd, or 
 has been found, to gi\e j leasure, is necessarily and always a 
 desire for pleasure. He follows Hutler in holding that self-love 
 is but a secondarv impulse, whose appearance presupposes 
 |)rimar)- im|)ulses. Only after we ha\e experienced the pleasure 
 which comes from the satisfaction of an original impulse, can 
 this become the object of a conscious search after pleasure, or 
 lead to (^goisim. C)n the other hand benexolence, Hume claims, 
 is a primar)' impulse. It is an original affection of the mind, 
 immefli;\tel}- directed toward the happiness of others. After we 
 have experienced the self satisfaction which follows u[K)n its 
 exercise, it is then possible that the exjjectation of their natural 
 consequences may influence us in performing benevolent actions. 
 Hut the original motive is not for pleasure.j 
 
 Hume's treatment of morality is most unsatisfactory. 
 Virtue and vice are synon\'m(^us, as we have seen, with pleasure 
 and jjain, and }-et this pleasure is utterK' disinterested ; it is only 
 when a character is considered in general, without an)' reference 
 to our particular interest tliat this feeling or sentiment of moral 
 good and evil arises. '^ It is from the influence of characters and 
 (jualities, upon those who have intercourse with any person, that 
 ue blame or praise him. ■* Our own interest or pleasure does 
 not at all enter into the case. I'or, in judging of character, men 
 could never agree in their sentiments and judgements, unless 
 they chose some common point of view, from which they might 
 
 1. Martineau. Typpfi of Etinral Thrartj, p. 535. 
 
 2. F;ilckonberi,s lUstorij of I'liilosoii/uf, p. 235. 
 
 3. J''r('nlis(>,Bk. ni. I't. i. |>. 472. 
 
 4. Ibid, Part iii. Sec. i. p. 582. 
 
1 1 'd 
 
 ;■ •'(! 
 
 28 
 
 ML'Ik 
 
 4 
 
 I 
 
 '■", 
 
 survey their object, and which mi^ht cause it to appear the 
 same toall of theni. The only interest or pleasure that appears 
 the same to every spectator, is tliat of the person himself, 
 whose character is examined, is tlh'u of those w ho have some 
 connection with him. These, then, hc'uv^ more constant and 
 universal than our own interest and pleasures, are alf)ne admit- 
 ted in speculation as the standard of \ irtue iiKjrality. They 
 alone produce that [^articular feelinj;- or sentiment, on which 
 moral distinctions dej:)end. ^ Thus, while on the one hand, 
 Hume has made morality entireK' suhjecti\e, dependent on a 
 feeling of j)leasure or pain, which proclaims the presence of 
 virtue and vice, j'et, on the other hand, the feeling of moral 
 approval or disapproval is entirely dependent in its orij^in upon 
 the influence of the character of the jjcrson, who has jjcrformed 
 the i;()od or the evil deed. Hence, lookiuL; at the tjuestion from 
 this point of view, we may say that, with Hume, moral distinc- 
 tions ultimately depend upon, and are called forth by character. 
 When we praise actions, we rei^ard onl)- t he motives that pro- 
 duced them, and consider the ac_ti()ns as si<;hs OT'Tndications of 
 certain p rinciples in the mTn cTor temper. 'rjie^exTernal perform- 
 "aiice has no merit. We must TcxTR \vitTiin to find' tiTe moral 
 qualit}'. We re<;ard tlie actions as sii^ns, and the ultimate 
 object of our praise or blame is the motive that produced them. '^ 
 
 Hume, however, regards actions as infallible sic^iis of 
 character. There is just so much vice or \ irtue in any character 
 as every one places in it, and it is impossible that we can ever 
 be mistaken in regard to this. •' In order that our inference 
 from actions to motives and character should so ine\itably 
 result in a correct judgment, we would natural 1}' conclude that 
 the process was pre-eminentl}' that of reason. Ikit this, as we 
 have seen, is not at all Humes's idea. It is b)- means cjf 
 sj'mpathy that we enter into the pain and pleasure caused by 
 the characters of others, and thus obtain ourselves the sentiment 
 which assures us of the moral quality of the character. Actions 
 can never be finally accounted for by reason, but only by some 
 desire for which no reason can be given. All moraiit)' depends 
 upon our sentiments ; and when any action or qualit)' of the 
 mind is capable of affording a certain kind of pleasure, either to 
 the agent hiinself or to those affected by his character or his 
 acts, we call such an action or (juality virtuous. When the 
 
 ne;/i 
 simi 
 perf 
 can I 
 nii-'i| 
 mail 
 
 VV 
 
 1. Treatise, Pt. 
 
 2. Ibid, Bk. in. 
 
 3. Ibid, Bk. HI. 
 
 III. Sec. I. p. 591. 
 Ft. II. Sec. I. p. 477. 
 I't. II. Sec. VIII. p. 547- 
 
THK RTHICAI. SVSTKM OF ADAM SMITH. 
 
 29 
 
 lf> appear the 
 that appears 
 •erson himself, 
 10 have some 
 ' constant anrl 
 alone adinit- 
 i-ahty. 'I'liey 
 'It, on which 
 li<-^ one hand, 
 -pendent on a 
 presence of 
 '\s of moral 
 ■'^ ori'^in upon 
 as perf(.)i-med 
 luestion from 
 loral distille- 
 ry character, 
 es that pro- 
 id ications of 
 ^al perform - 
 cT th^rrmoral 
 ;lie ultimate 
 need tJiem. 2 
 
 Jc sic^ns of 
 ly character 
 ■c can ever 
 11" inference 
 inevitably 
 "chide that 
 • his, as v\e 
 
 means of 
 caused by 
 
 sentiment 
 Actions 
 ' by .some 
 )' depends 
 it>' of the 
 , either to 
 er or his 
 A'hen the 
 
 nc;j;lect or non-perf(»rmance of an action displea.ses us in a 
 siiin'lar manner, we consider that we arc under an obligation to 
 perform such an act. ^ "The ultimate ends of human action 
 can iievei-. in anv case, be accounted for by rea.son, but recom- 
 niciul thiMusehes entirely to the sentiments and affections of 
 niaukiud, w ithoul aii\' dependence on the intellectual faculties." - 
 
 1 
 
 VARY [[-.SMITH'S '['[[I'.ORV ()[• nil': MORAL Sl'.XTI- 
 
 mi<:n rs. 
 
 ClIAPriCR I.^ SVMPArilY. 
 
 SIX'IION I 
 
 .SVMI'ATIIV TJIi: .SOL'RCK OF OUR MOK.VL 
 JUDCMKNT.S. 
 
 Adam Smith brings to a final comi^letion in his s\-stem 
 the work of the Moral .Sense Philosophers. Hut his importance 
 d(jcs not altogether, or main]}-, consist in the fact that he 
 de\elo[rjd the thought or the work of others ; his Tlicoy is also 
 of great independent \alue. He makes a most ambitious 
 att 'inpt to find in s}'mpath\' a common answer to the two 
 great questions of moralit}* : that of the origin and that of the 
 critcrioti f)f \irtue. .S\nipath)' is the key-note, the central idea 
 of the Theory of the Moral Scntii)tc>its. In our treatment of the 
 work, we shall consider s)inpath\' \\) as the source of our moral 
 distinctions, and (.3) as the source of our judgments of merit and 
 demerit. We shall then treat of the influence of custom, 
 fashion, and utilit}- upon our moral judgments, before taking up 
 in chajjter II. the cjuestion of our Sen.se of Duty. 
 
 The Moral Sense of Shaftesbur)- and Ilutcheson had been 
 discarded by Hume in ffi\(jr of s)-mpath\'. Hut this sj-mpathy 
 is, in the I>ratisi\ nothing more than a means b}' which to 
 resolve our feelings of benexolence into a mere .sensitivity to 
 pain and pleasure. In the llucjuiry on the other hand sjmpathy 
 becomes a feeling of humanit}-, and Hume's system is almost 
 indistinguishable from that of Ilutcheson. Sympathy, also, 
 in both the Treatise and the /inquiry, is so hopelessly mixed 
 
 Trent i 
 
 Bk 
 
 n I. I't. 11. 
 
 Ewiuirij, Ajipcndix i. 
 
 ICC. V. 
 
 p. 517. 
 
i '. 
 
 30 
 
 MUIR : 
 
 with utility, that, as the source of moral distinctions, it was mos- 
 unsatisfactor}-. SiTiith purificfl this principle of the utilitariai 
 colouring it had received with liiune, and made it the main doc 
 trine of his Theorx'. Sj'mpathy primarily implies nothinjj; bul 
 the power of imitating the feelin^^s of others, but Smith finds it 
 an essential element not only in our moral jud<,nnents of others, 
 but also in our judc^nients of our own charactet and conduct, 
 and in our sense of duty, 
 
 Sinith's treatment of sympathy has caused much and 
 serious misunderstanding^ of his work. It has called forth the 
 most widely different interpretations of his views. The relation 
 of reason to .symjiath}- in llie Tlworv is, undoubtedly, the great 
 problem of the work ; but that relation is such, that it is impos- 
 sible to see how one writer can proclaim the sj-stem a purely 
 rational one, and the basis of Kant's Moral Philosophy, ' or how 
 another can regard s)'mpathy as the one great principle, from 
 which Smith reasons, and to w hich all others .ue subservient. - 
 Rea.son and s}mpathy are both important in the Tlico)y and an 
 attempt will be made later to sh.ow what Smith regards as the 
 true relation of those great principles in a system of inorality. 
 We will consider first the treatment of s)'mpathy in the system. 
 
 In distinguishing his princij)le from that of Hume, Snn'th 
 gives an account of the sj-mpathy of !'^e previous sjstein. 
 Hume held that qualities and actions, according to their utility, 
 produce pleasure, and that with the pleasure thus produced we 
 .sympathize. The tendency of qualities to the good of societ}' is 
 the sole cause of approbation, without any sus|jicion of the 
 concurrence of another motive. Virtue is thus placed in utility, 
 and the pleasure, with which we surve)' the utility of any 
 quality, arises on account of our s\-mpathy with the happiness of 
 tho.se who are affected by it. ^ This account of the source of 
 moral a()probation .^eems very objectionable to .Smith, who sa)'s 
 that approbation bestowed for such a cause is just the same as 
 the approval we feel, when we observe a well-contrived machine, 
 a .sympathy with the pleasure of those who are benefitted by it. 
 Such an approbation, Smith does not regard as a moral judgment 
 at all. 
 
 He insists that true sympathy is .something very different 
 from this. According to his principle, we do not sympathize 
 
 1. Oncken, Die, Elhik Smith's und Kant's, p. 100. 
 
 2. Bucklr, Ilistory of Cii'ili.-ation, p. 344. 
 
 3. Theory of th*. Moral Sentiments. Pt. viii. Sec. 1 11. Clia]). 3. 
 Hume, Treatise, Hk. ifi. I't. ill. Sec. I, 
 
 pni 
 i- 
 up* 
 tioi 
 
 <s 
 
 ■il;-!' 
 
IIIK KIIIK Al, >Vr>lKM OK ADAM nMIIM 
 
 ;i 
 
 '^. it was mos- 
 tlic utilitariai 
 tlic main doe- 
 's tiothin^f bui 
 'niitli finds it 
 "ts of others, 
 ■iiifl conduct, 
 
 much and 
 c'd forth the 
 
 11k; relation 
 l\', the <rreat 
 t it is impos- 
 <-'ni a purely 
 ^li>-. ' or Iiow 
 inciple, from 
 subservient. - 
 lico)y and an 
 arris as the 
 
 of mf)rnlity. 
 h the system, 
 fume, Snuth 
 ious s^-stem. 
 their utility, 
 produced we 
 of societ}' is 
 icion of the 
 2d in utility, 
 ility of any 
 happiness of 
 le source of 
 h, who sa)'s 
 he same as 
 cd machine, 
 fitted by it. 
 al judgment 
 
 ry different 
 sympathize 
 
 !>• 3- 
 
 with, or enter into the pleasmr which is received from an>' 
 source, but into the m(jti\es of the a^eiit, and the gratitude (jf 
 the per^^.ons benefited. ' L'tility is neither the first nor the 
 printipal source of our ap|»robation. A sentiment of propriety 
 i-^ in\()l\ed. which is (|uile fli-^tiiict from that of ulilit)'. It is 
 upon this propriety of sef.timeiUs and actions that (iur appn^ba- 
 tion is founded, and not upon utility. - 
 
 Tlv." source of sympath\- .Smith finds in the ima|^nnation. 
 It is onl\- by means of this facult) that we can form an\' con- 
 ce|)t'.)n of the sensations of another. The ima^dnation enables 
 us tfj do so by representing to us what our own sensations would 
 be in a similar case. We |)lace oursehes in the situation of the 
 other persoPi, and enter, as it were, int(j his bod\-, and become, in 
 some measure the ■.ime person \vith him. In jo\-, .sorrtnv, 
 L^ratitude, or in an)- other passion whate\er. we can. b)- imat,M'na- 
 lion, enter into the circumstances, which call forth the passi(jn. 
 and thus create in oursehes emotions similar to those of the 
 |).rson principally affected. •■ 
 
 We are led to imitate the feelini^s (jf another either b\- the 
 perception of its expression and conse(]Uences. or b)' the circum- 
 stances anrl e.Nperiences which occasion it. The latter. .Smith 
 considers a much more powerful inlluence than the former. We 
 are sometimes so influenced by such circumstances atul experi- 
 ences, that we feel for another a jjassion of which he himself is 
 totally incapable. The passion arises in us through iin;ii;ination 
 when we put oursehes in his place, though the circumstances 
 which ha\e thus aroused f)ur imagination, have failed to 
 produce the passion in him. ■* The case of those who have lost 
 their reason furnishes an example of this. The compassion of 
 the spectator cannot be the reflecticm of any sentiment of the 
 sufferer. It must arise altogether from the consideration of 
 what he himself would feel, if he were in the same unhappy 
 situation, and were, at the same time, able to regard it w ith his 
 present reason and judgment. Another example. gi\en by 
 .Smith, of a case in which we feel for others a passion, of which 
 they themsehes are altogether incapable, is f:)ur sympathy with 
 the dead. Our sorrow, here, can be but an illusion of the 
 
 Tlfurih F't. VI 1. Sec. 3. jp. 386. 
 
 Ibid, 
 
 't. IV. 
 
 Cha 
 
 V Ibid, Ft. I. Ser. 1. 
 4. Ibid. Vt. I. Sc<-. 1. p 
 
32 
 
 Milk 
 
 iina^in;iti<J!i. ami no s^inpath)' uilli an\' real sciitiinciil ot 
 another. ' 
 
 Ihe j^rcat object of syiiipath\ is the pro|)riet\ of a 
 sentiment or affection. Where we entirei\- s\ inpathize with the 
 jjassion of another, we appro\e of it as just and proper, and suit- 
 able to its object. - This suitableness, of which we can onl\- 
 jufls^e b)- the concord or dissonance of such affection with our 
 own, Smith calls the " propriet\' " of the passion. •' In judijin^ 
 of an affection or passion as proportionate or disprf)porti()nate to 
 its excitinj^ cause, the onl\' standard b\' which we can jud^e is 
 the corres|)ondent affection in oursebes, We must jud^^e by 
 ourseKes ; we neither ha\e, nor can have, any other method of 
 jud^in^ about them. 
 
 Honar objects, tiiat according to .Smith's principle of moral 
 distinctions, the moral judL;nient passed upon an act would 
 depenrj upon the particular iv^c anrl societ)- to which it 
 belon^efl ■* Hut is this at all peculiar to .Snn'lh's theor\' ? 
 With the e.\cci)tion of a purel\' Intuitif)nist, would not the 
 same ha\e to be said \nv any s)'stem of morality whate\er? We 
 can no more i;et rid of the influence of our a;^e and societ}' than 
 we can of the sell ; and naturall)' so, for the)' are indeed a part 
 of the self. A conception of \irtue, for instance, is final in so far 
 as it defines the ij^oorl as Ljoodness, but as a concrete ideal it is 
 conditioned by the moral proLjress then achie\ed, and is, there- 
 fore, necessarily inadecjuate, and can never, from this point of 
 \iew. be re^^r,u-defl as final. '' 
 
 'I"o return U> the consifleration of s\mpathy. When a 
 pcr.son is in a situation that excites an\' passion, it is agreeable 
 
 1. Theory, Pt. i. Sec i. 
 
 Note. — In givini^ this instance of our sorrow with the dead. Smith 
 mentions as " that which is of real importance in their situation, tliat awful 
 futurity whicii awaits tlieni." This is the first of tiie many references to a 
 future state, which Oncken considers the chief distinction between the ethical 
 system of Smith, and that of any previous English writer. He says : " This 
 belief in a future state is the principal point of distinction between Smith's 
 system and that of earlier writers. It is not found in tiie Moral Piiilosophy 
 of any previous writer in Great Britain, even wliere the concept of God was, 
 though incidently, admitted."" {Die Ethik SiaUh's und Kant's p. go). This 
 is surely a most astonisliing statement. Smith"s belief in a future state in no 
 way differentiates him from previous English writers. The Dissertation of 
 Gay, which appeared in 1731, twenty-eight years before Sinith"s Theory of the 
 Moral Sentiments was published, necessarily implied this belief. And the 
 concept of God was admitted, by no means incidentally, by Cumberland, 
 Cudworth, Clari<e, Butler, More, and jH-obablv all other moral philosophers 
 of Great Britain. 
 
 2. Theory, i't. 1. Sec. 1. Chap. 3. 
 
 3. Ihitl, Pt. VII. Sec. 2. 
 
 4. Bonar, Philosophu and Political Eronomy. 
 
 5. Green, Proler/omina to Ethirs. Chap. 1;. |). 300. 
 
TMK F.IHK Al. SVsn.M dl AI'AM ^MIIII. 
 
 .U 
 
 SL-iitiiiicnt of 
 
 *|>nct>- of a 
 'ii/(^' with the 
 '*^'r, aii'l siiit- 
 \\c can only 
 
 tioii with our 
 In jii(I;,niij; 
 
 ijortioiiate la 
 cm iufl^e is 
 ■^t jii'Ij^v by 
 
 -•r method of 
 
 |>l*-' of nu)r.il 
 
 1 act would 
 
 " which it 
 
 til's theory? 
 
 »uld not the 
 
 ate\er? We 
 
 societ}' than 
 
 bdced a part 
 
 Tiial in so far 
 
 tc ideal it is 
 
 md is, there 
 
 his point of 
 
 When a 
 is agreeable 
 
 • dead, Smith 
 nn, that awful 
 Jfcrcnccs to a 
 ;en the ethical 
 ?.says: "This 
 tvveen Smith's 
 al Piiilosophy 
 
 of God was, 
 I'- 90). This 
 ire state in no 
 'yf-ssertntion of 
 
 Theory of iht 
 'f' And the 
 Cumbedand, 
 
 philosophers 
 
 lo him to know that the spectators of his siiuati< >n enter w itii y 
 him into all its \ari'ius circum-^tanco. and are affi-cted In- them 
 in the same manner as he himself is. ' On the other hand, it 
 is pleasant to tlie s-i ;|,,t;r to observe the correspoiuk-iice of his 
 sentiments with those of another. Hut, though naturally 
 s)'mp<ithetic, we never conci'i\e tor what has befalli-n another, 
 that decree of passion wiiich anim atesthe jjerson |)rin;ipall\' 
 concerned. The i!nai;inar)' chanm- of situation, upon whiih the 
 s\ini)ath)- of the .-spectators is fiuMiished. is but momentary. 
 What the)' fi'cl will a!wa\s be. in ^ome re>pects, different from 
 w hat the person wlio is princi|)ally interested feels. ('ompass- 
 ion can ne\er be (.-Nacth' the -ame as ori_L;inal sorrow. These 
 tuf) sentiments ma)-, however, have such a corri'spondence with 
 one another, as is sulTicient for the harmotu' ofs(jciet}'. In 
 order to attain the pK-asure of nmtual sympath)-, nature teaches 
 the sjjectator to strive, as much as he can, to raise his emotions 
 to a K'\el with that which tlu- object would rt-all}- produce. 
 .And she teaches the person, also, whose |)assion ihi-. object has 
 excited, to brinj^ it dow-n as much as he can to a level with that 
 of the spectator. - 
 
 I'ljon tin: att<-mpt to elev ate, and U])on theattenipt to lower 
 the expression of passion, Smith lounds two different sets of vir- 
 tues. L'i)on the effort of the si)ectat(jr to enter into the situation 
 of the person princii)ally concerned, and to raise his emotions to 
 a level with those of the actor, are foundefj the identic, the 
 amiabk: virtues ; while upon the effort ol the person |)rincipall\' 
 concerned to lower his emotion^ to corre>|)ond with those of the 
 spectator, are foimded what Smith call>, "the j^reat, the awful, 
 the respectable " virtues. •' These are the virtues of self-denial, 
 of self-Ljovernment, of that command of the |)assions, which 
 subjects all the movements of our natvuv, to what our own 
 disunity and lionour. and the proi)riet> of our conduct reciuiro. 
 This latter class is of the utmost imi)ortance. j-'or tiie most 
 perfect knowledj^^e, if not supported bv the most perfect self- 
 command, will not alwav's en;Jile one to do one's dut\-. 4' 
 
 Smith's classification of the passions is, in idea, thous^h not 
 in expression, like that of Shat"tesbur\'. ' I Ic distinguishes the 
 
 Chap. 2. 
 
 1. I'll ear ij, I't. i. Sec. I. 
 
 2. //>/'/, Pt. 1. Chap. 4. 
 
 ^foTK. — In lluH noi'oiiiit of till' niDilf liitiiiii iinil clovatioii of paHninti, until i» pdint i^< reaolifd 
 al whicli th<' purnon interi'ntcil unci till' Hjicctator I'lUi hyiii|ialtii/t' Siirlli Hci^nis to have in mind 
 .Vil.xtotl.-'n wine man, who fei'kHthf mran. t^t'e Aiixlolle'x h't/iiis, lik. ii. Cliap. li. 
 
 3. Thi'iirii, Pt. I. Chap. 5. p. 20. 
 
 4. Ihid, i't. VI. Sec. 3. [). 277. 
 
34 
 
 ML' IK 
 
 i;!' 
 
 (■|| 
 
 ! : 
 
 social, the unsocial, and the selfish passions. ' 'I'he unsocial 
 [)assions are necessai)" parts of the character of human nature. 
 Resentment, when i^uarded and (lualified, is e\fn s.jenerous and 
 noble.- i^ut with all the unsocial passion- , our s)inpathy is 
 divided l)etween the pi-rson who feels llu-in, a..d the person who 
 is the object of them. It is this divirled ssinpath)', which 
 renders the whole set of jjassions, of which resentment is the 
 type, so ungraceful and (lisa^M'eeable. There is another set, the 
 opposite of these, which a redoubled s\inpath\' renders peculiar- 
 ly aj^^recible and becomini^. These are the social passions, such 
 
 as j^enerosity, humam't)', kindness, etc. •' Tlu'se please the in- 
 different spectator upf)n almost e\er\' occasion. liis s\-mpath)- 
 with the person who feels the |)assion, e.\actl\' coincides with his 
 concern for the person who is the object of it. Between these 
 two oppositt^ sets of passions, there is another, which holds a 
 sort of middle place between the social and the unsocial, which is 
 never so aL;ree tble as is the one set. nor so odious as is the 
 other, (irief and jO)- upon account of our own private i^ood or 
 bad fortune constitute this third set of passions. l'",\en when 
 excessive, these arc never so disa_L,neeable as t^.xcessive resent- 
 ment, because no opposite sympath}' can e\er interest us a<^ainst 
 them. Anfl when most suitable to their objects, the)' are ne\er 
 so ajrrecable as impartial humanit}' and just benevf)lence, 
 because no double sympath}- can e\er interest us for them. * 
 
 Smith insists that s)-mpath)' camir)t, in any sense, be re- 
 garded as a selfish principle ; and he considers .sjnipath)- as the 
 real foundation of those .systems which deduce the principle of 
 ap()robation from .self-love. But it is an entirel)' mistaken idea, 
 he says, that .sympathy can ever be selfish. •' When I sx-mpath- 
 ize with the sorrow or the inclij^nation of another, it ma)' be 
 pretended that my emotion is founded in self-lo\e, because it 
 arises from brint^int:^ the case of that other home to myself; from 
 puttinj.^ myself in his situation, and thence conceiving what I 
 shoulcl feel in the liki> circumstances. Hut, thout^h s)'mpathy 
 arises from an imaginary chant^e of situation with the person 
 principally concerned, )et this imai^inar)' chanije is not sujjposed 
 to happen to me in nn- own person and character, but in that of 
 the person with whom I s\inpathi/.e. My grijf is entirely upon 
 
 1. Thconj, Pf. I. Sec. 2. Cliap. 3. 
 
 2. Ihiil, Vt. II. Sec. II. Chaj). 3. 
 Sidj;wick, Historij of Ethics, p. 183. 
 
 3. Thcori/, I't. I Sl'c.ii. Chap. 4." 
 
 4. //*/(/, I't. I. S?r. ii. Chap. S- [>• |2. 
 
 5 Iliid, Vi- vii- Sec. III. Chap. I. p. 373. 
 
 I 
 
 /! I 
 
nil' IIIIUAI. SVSITM OF ADAM SMITir. 
 
 35 
 
 Tlu- unsocial 
 luiinaii nature. 
 II ifc'iicious and 
 ur .s\ inpatli)' i> 
 tlu- person uhc) 
 npatli)-, which 
 ntnicnt is the 
 mother set, the 
 nders peculiar- 
 passions, such 
 please the in- 
 flis sympathy 
 ncifles with his 
 k'tv\een these 
 which holds a 
 -social, which is 
 )us as is the 
 irivate <;ood or 
 I".\en when 
 :essi\e resent- 
 'est us aj^ainst 
 the}' are never 
 bene\fileiice, 
 "or them. ■* 
 
 sense, be re- 
 npathy as the 
 u principle of 
 mistaken idea, 
 II I sympath- 
 her, it ma)- be 
 e, because it 
 ^myself; from 
 ivin<]j what I 
 ^h sjmpathy 
 h the person 
 not supposed 
 but in that of 
 entirely upon 
 
 his account, and not upon my own, and is not, therefore, in the 
 least selfish. That caimot possibly be a selfish passion, which 
 rjoes not arise e\en from the ima;4ination of anything' that has 
 befallen, or that rel I'j "^ to ni\ self 'I'hal |)ity or com|)assion,. 
 which llobbes explained as the consciousness of a |)o-.sible mis-' 
 fortuiK" to oursebt's, similar to that seen to befall another, isi 
 with .Smith, a primary, not a secondar)' emotion ot our nature 1 
 an oriL^in.iI and not a deri\ati\e passion, and one that is purelji 
 (h'sinterestcd in its manifestations, Oncken iiL;htl)- claims thal^ 
 we cannot possibl\- find a more en(.'rL;i'tic o|)ponent of the selfisli 
 view of morality tluui the autlun- of tlu* Abiral .Sentiments. ' 
 
 What .Smith terms "conditional" s\'mpath\- is iinportant. 
 Our a|)probation and disap|)robation of the sentiment of others 
 do not, in e\ery case, depend U|)on their a,L;reement or oisa^rree- 
 iTient with our own. This our author admits, - but adds that 
 e\en in those cases, our approbation is ultimately founded upon 
 .syinpath)'. .\s an illustration, he cites tlie case of a stranger, 
 whom wi' max" observe to be in deep Ljrief on accoimt of the 
 death of liis father. Moth he and his father, probably, are un- 
 known to us, but it is impossible that we should not a|)prove of 
 his ^rief We iiave learned from experience that such a 
 misfortune natural!)' excites such a sorrow ; and we know that 
 if we took time to consider his situation fully, and in all it.s 
 parts, we should, w ithout doubt, most sincerely sympathize with 
 liim. It is upon the consciousness of this conditional sym])athy, 
 that our approbation of his sorrow is founded, e\en in those 
 cases, in which that s)nipath)- does not actuall)' take place ; 
 anrl the general rules derived froiu our preceding experience of 
 what our sentiments would commonl)' correspond with, correct 
 Uf)on this, as upon man)' other occasions, the impropriety of our 
 present emotions. 
 
 Smith treats this "conditional" sxinpathy as an exception 
 to tlie general rule. Hut is it not much rather itself, ordinarily, 
 the rule, and an originall)' excited s)'mpathetic feeling the 
 exception? In our constant contact with others, it is impossible 
 that we sh(Hild react to all of their affections and actions, with 
 an originally e.xcited, .sympathetic feeling. New or unusual 
 events may produce this, l)ut the more frecjuently the case is 
 repeated, so much the more does the emotional character of the 
 judgment disappear. 
 
 Smith differentiates his s)'mpathy, as we have seen, from ^ 
 
 1. Dip Etliik Smiths^ unci Kants, p. 87. 
 
 2. Theory, Part 1. Sec. i. pp. 6, 12. 
 
Ill 
 
 1 
 
 i' I 
 
 3^> 
 
 MUIR 
 
 that of I funic, in that the syin')athy itself, and not utiUt)-, is the 
 
 ' measure of the propriety of affections and actions. Imagination 
 
 lis the source of sx'mpath)', and our \ie\v of the situation which 
 
 .excites the passiiju, rather than our \ie\v of the expression of 
 
 'the passion, is its cause. Sympathy is the onl}' true test of the 
 
 propriety of passions and actions. Vov our entire approbation 
 
 means our complete s\-mpathy, and this inympath)' is our 
 
 standard or measure for judj^MiiJjj others. S)'mpath}- is pleasin;^, 
 
 both to the person principally concerned, and to the 
 
 spectator; and, owint^ to the attempt of the one to lower and of 
 
 the other to elevate his emotions to the point where this mutual- 
 
 ./ly pleasing .sympathy ma}' be enjoj-ed, it becomes the foundation 
 
 ■) of both the "amiable and gentle" and the "awful and respeetal)le " 
 
 virtues. As regards the passions, we mret the social with a 
 
 redouble 1 s)'m|jathy, the unsori.d with a dixided sj nipath)- ; 
 
 while self-regarding passions, such as joj- and grief on our own 
 
 account, occupy a midway position, and receive a moderated 
 
 .sympathy, ncitlier so extreme as that accf)rded to the social, nor 
 
 to the unsocial passions. The real foundation of the selfish 
 
 systems of moralit)', which deduce the principle of approbation 
 
 from self-love, is a misunderstood form of sympathy. Hut 
 
 sympathy can ne\cr, pro[)erl)', be regarded as a selfish |)rinciple. 
 
 SECTION 11. — .SVMi'ATHV TIIK SorRCK OF J 1 ' I KIM KNTS OK 
 
 MKRIT AM) DHMKRIT. 
 
 The sympathy of the spectator is, as we ha\ e .seen, directed 
 to the fitness of the moti\es, or the propriet}' of an action. Hut 
 it is also called forth b}' the utilit}' of the consetjuences, or the 
 merit of an action. An action is proper when the impartial 
 spectator is able to sympathii/.e with the motive f)f the agent. It 
 is meritorious when he can s\'mpathi/,e also '.vith its end or 
 effect. Propriety demands that the feelings shall be suitable to 
 their object ; merit, that the consequences of an act shall be 
 beneficial to others. Propriety and impropriety', then, express 
 the suitableness or unsuitableness of an affection tc/ its exciting 
 cause ; merit and dcincrit refer to the result which the affection 
 tends to produce. ' When the tendenc)' of an affection is 
 beneficial, the agent appears to us a proper (object of reward ; 
 when it is hurtful, lie appears to be the proper object of 
 punishment. - 
 
 Gratitude and resentment are the natural principles, which 
 
 1. Theory yW. ii. Sec. i. Iiitrodurtion. 
 
 2. Tbid, Pt. II. Cliiip. I p. 75. 
 
 
THE ETHICAI, SVSIKM OF AliAM SMITH. 
 
 37 
 
 ')t utilit>-, is the 
 i. Imagination 
 situatif)n which 
 
 expression of 
 true test of the 
 re approbation 
 npathx' is our 
 tli>" is i^Ieasiuf^, 
 , and to the 
 o lower and of 
 ■re this mutual- 
 ' the foundation 
 id respectable " 
 le social with a 
 cd s) mpathy ; 
 f on our o-.\n 
 
 a iTioderated 
 tlie social, nor 
 of the selfish 
 if approbation 
 nipath)'. Jiut 
 ifish |)rinciple. 
 
 ii(;mk\ts of 
 
 seen, directed 
 
 I action, J^it 
 ences, or the 
 the impartial 
 thea^ent. It 
 lith its end or 
 be suitable to 
 
 act shall be 
 
 then, express 
 
 o its exciting 
 
 the affection 
 
 II affection is 
 t of reward ; 
 )er object of 
 
 iciplcs, which 
 
 prompt us to reward and punish. I'ut we do n(jt sympathize 
 with the gratitude of one man, merel)' because aiu^ther has been 
 the cause of his good fortune, unless this other has been tiie 
 cause of it fn.'n moti\es of which we can ap[)ro\e. Our sense, 
 therefore, of the gotjfl desert of an action, is made up of an 
 indirect sympath\- with the pers(jn to whom the action is 
 beneficial, and ot a direct s)mpath\- with the affections and 
 motives of the agent. ^ Hence the onI\- actions which appear 
 to us deser\ing of reward, are actions of a beneficial tendencx', 
 j)roceeding from pn^per motives. The onl}' actions, which seem 
 to demand puiu'shment, are actions of a hurtful tendency pro- 
 ceeding from improjjcr motives. The ff)rmer, alone, seem to 
 require a reward, because the\' alone are the a[;proved objects of 
 gratitude, or excite the s\Tn[)athetic gratitude of the spectator. 
 The latter, alone, deserve punishment because the)' alone are 
 the api)nAed objects of resentment, or excite the s\'mpathetic 
 resentment of the spectator. ''' 
 
 Our s)ini)ath}- w ith unavoidable distress is not more real 
 than is on. fello\\ -feeling with just and natural resentment." 
 .Smith's treatment of resentment is one of the most important 
 parts of his work. lie finds in it a natural means of detence 
 which has been bestowed upon man.'' Ilume had sought in 
 vain for a passion from which our sense of justice might be 
 derived. He concluded that self interest was the original 
 motive U> the establishment of ju.^tice, and s\inpath\- with 
 [)ublic interest the source of the moral approbation which 
 attends that virtue. •' iioth these c\j)lanations are rejected by 
 Smith, wh(j finds in our natural sympatli}' with resentment a 
 sufiicient ground and exjilanation of our sense of justice. Re- 
 
 taliation seems to be the great law, which is dictated to us by 
 natine ; as ever)' man cioeth so shall it be done to him. " 
 Hjneficeiice an 1 gL^njrosity, we think are due to the generous 
 and beneficent. V' The violator of the laws of justice (>ught to be 
 made to feel himself that evil, which he has (U^nc t(j another; 
 and since no rei^ard to the sufferings of others is ca|)able of 
 restraining him, he ought to be overawed by the fear of his 
 own. 'I'he iTian, also, who is bareh' iimocent, who onl)' observe^ 
 the law.s of justice with regard to others ; and merely abstain^^ 
 
 1. Thforn, I't. II, Sec. I. C'lia|). 5. 
 
 2. Ihi(U i't i[. Sec II. Ch;i|). 1. 
 
 3. II>!,1, I'l. 11. See. I. Cliiip. 5. 
 
 4. //'/(/, Ft. II See. Ti. Cl-.ap. i. 
 
 5. Hume, Trcatint', Bk. in p. 500. 
 
 6. Thconj, Vl. 11. Sec. 11. Chap. i. 
 
 82. 
 
 ■mmmmsm^f^. 
 

 I 
 
 '!i! 
 
 ',!) 
 
 J' i 
 
 ' ' , I, 
 
 il 
 
 . .11 
 
 r\ 
 
 38 
 
 iMUik : 
 
 from hurtin^f his neii^hbours, can merit only that his nei<^hbours 
 in their turn, should res|>ect his inncjcence ; and that the same 
 laws should be religiously observed with regard to him. ^ 
 
 In thus insisting upon our sympath)' with resentinent, and 
 finchng in it the source of justice, Smith is e\ idcntl}' influenced 
 by Butler, l^utler claimed that in resentment every man carries 
 about with him that which affords him demonstration that the 
 rules of justice and ecjuity are to be the guide of his actions. 
 For every man naturall)' feels an incHgnation u[K)n seeing 
 instances of cruelty and injustice, and, therefore, cannot commit 
 the same without being self-condemned. Resentment is one of 
 the bonds by which society is held together, a fellow-feeling 
 which each individual has in behalf of the whole species as well 
 as himself This passion in us is plainl)' connected with a sense 
 of virtue and vice, of moral good and evil. It is not called forth 
 either by natural evil or b\' suffering, but its objects are moral 
 evil and injur)'. Cruelt\', injustice, and wrong arouse this 
 indignation, and it is innocently em|jlo)'ed against them. - 
 
 In treating of justice and self-love, .Smith admits that each 
 man is much more d:;( p'\' interested in whatever immediately 
 concerns himself, than in what concerns an}' other man. Yet, 
 when he \iews himself in the light in which he is conscious that 
 others will \iew him, he sees that, to them, he is but one of the 
 multitude, in no respect better than any other in it. Hence he 
 must humble the arrogance of his self-love, and bring it down to 
 something of which others will ap[)rove. He knows that if he 
 violates the rules of justice in his treatment of others, the 
 spectator will natural!}' s}'mpathi/e with the resentment of the 
 injured, anrl that he himself will become the object of hatred 
 and indignation. "' There can be no proper motive for hurting 
 or doing evil "to another, w ith which mankind will sympathize 
 exce[:)t just indignation for evil, which that other has done to us. 
 
 In comparing the virtues rf justice and benefience, Smith 
 finds that the latter is much ic: s c sential to the existence of 
 .society than is the former. ' ; ■ «■ ..ociety ma}' exist from a 
 sense of its utiiit}-, without any n.iiural lo\'e and affection; but it 
 cannot exist <imong those who are at all times read}' to hurt and 
 to injure oi^e another. Beneficence is free and caimot be 
 extf)rted by force, the mere want of it tends to do no real 
 
 1. Thcorij, 15k. ll. Sec. Ii. Cluii). i. 
 
 2. Butler, SeriiKiii mi Jt'csmtiiirnt. 
 
 3. Thrary, I't. 11. Sec. 11. Cha[i 2. 
 4 Ibid, I'l. II. Sec. ii. Chap. 3. 
 
TIIK KTHICAI, SVSTK.M OK AfMM SMITH. 
 
 39 
 
 his iiei<,rhbours 
 that the same 
 :o him. ^ 
 
 scntment, and 
 itly influenced 
 ly man carrie.s 
 ition that the 
 f his actions. 
 
 upon seeinj^ 
 :annot commit 
 nient is one of 
 
 fellou--feeHng 
 ipecies as well 
 fl with a sense 
 lot called forth 
 cts are inoral 
 ^ arou.se this 
 ; them. - 
 
 nits that each 
 immediately 
 man. Vet, 
 conscious that 
 )Ut one of the 
 it. Hence he 
 ■ing- it down to 
 )ws that if he 
 of others, the 
 .Mitment of the 
 ect of hatred 
 i\e for hurting 
 ill sympathize 
 las done to us. 
 
 ;fience, Sir.itli 
 _' existence of 
 exist from a 
 ffection; but it 
 ly to hurt and 
 id cannot be 
 to do no real 
 
 positive e\il. ^ It ina\- disappoint of the {.^ood, which mi<4ht 
 reasonal)l\" ha\ c been e\]jci"tcd, and. upcn that account, it ma)' 
 justl}' excite (ji>]ikc and disappointment, but it cannot provoke 
 an)' resentment ><f which the spectator will approve. 
 
 The ()l)stT\ ance of justice, on the other hand, is not left to 
 the freedom of our own wills. It may be extorted by force, and 
 its \iolati(jn exposes t(j resentment. - The violation of justice is 
 injur)'. It does real and posilixe hurt to sfime particular 
 
 persons, from motives which are naturall)' disappro\ed of It 
 is. theri'lore, the proper object of resentment and of pimishment. 
 In order to enforce the oljser\ance of justice, nature has caused 
 that its \ iolation shall be attended w ith c(Misciousness of ill 
 desert, ami the terrors of merited ])unishment. These form the 
 safe-L,niar(ls of socit-t)'. The)' secure the protection of the weak, 
 and the punishment of tlie i^uilt)'. Smith's \iew of justice is 
 ver)- different from that of Hutcheson, who made it j^racticalh/ 
 iclentical with benexolence ; and from that of Himie, who 
 insisted that it was an artificial \ irtue, or an invention of man 
 for the benefit of societ)'. 
 
 .Smith as^rees with HutliT in holding;' iirml)' to the old 
 retril)Uti\e theor\' of punishment. It is necessar)' for the vvv 
 subsistence of the world that injustice and wrong shall be pun- 
 ished, and as the natural com|>assion of men would render this 
 pum'shment exceeding!)- dil'ticult, indis^nation against \ice and 
 wickedness forms a balance to this weakness of pit)-. The hnv 
 of retaliation is the most important of all natural laws, for upon 
 it justice de|)ends, and U])on justice dei)en(ls the existence of 
 societ)'. ■' Nature, antecedent to all rellections uijon the utility 
 of punishment, has im|)ressed u|)on the human mind in the 
 strongest and most inck'lible characti-rs, an immediate and 
 instructive approbation of the sacred law- of retaliati(.>n. The 
 natural t>-ratification of resentment tends, of its own accord, to 
 produce all the political ends of punishment ; the correction of 
 the crimin.d, and the example to the public. It is even of con- 
 siderable iinp(jrtance, that the e\il which is done without design, 
 should be regarded as a misfortune to the doer as well as to the 
 sufferer. Men are taught, b)- this means, to regard carefully the 
 happiness of others ; and to he cautious, lest b)' an)' carelessness, 
 the)- should arouse the resentment, which the)- feel is ready to 
 
 I. Throrii, Vi. ii. Sec. ii. Chap. i. 
 -J. I''i<l, I't. II. Scr. 2. 
 3. //'/(/, I't. ir. Sec. II. Cliap. 2. 
 Butler, Smitun on litisanliivnt. 
 
 I 
 
 \i ■ i'"n'iiiiii-rr i.-i,m.ivfr.: i'vu.jliis 
 
; I 
 
 40 
 
 MUIR 
 
 ;i'i 
 
 I I 
 
 I,!! 
 
 burst out against thcin, if thc\- sliould, even without design, 
 cause the slightest injur)', unnecessaril)' to another. ' As ,1 
 proof that it is not a regard to the preservation of societj , 
 which (jriginall)' interests us in the punishment of crimes com 
 mitted against indixichials, Smith sa)s : "the concern which we 
 take in the f.rtune and haj)piness of individuals, does not, in 
 common cases, arise from that which we take in the fortune and 
 hapi^iness of society. i\s when a small sum is unjustly taken 
 from us, we do not so much prosecute the injury from a regard 
 to the preservation <jf our whole fortune, as from a regard to 
 that particular sum, which we have lost, so, when a single man 
 is injured or destr())'ed, we demand the punisliment of the 
 wrong that has been done to him, not so much from concern for 
 the genenii intere..*^ of societ)', as from a concern for the very 
 indi\idual who has been injured." - / 
 
 It is interesting to note in this connection that some modern 
 ethical writers have argued for the retributixe theory of punish- 
 ment as forcibly as Smith does here. Professor James Seth 
 claims that it is just this element of retribution that converts 
 calamit)' or misfortun'> into punishinent, and sav's : " the ques- 
 tion is not whether, apart from its effects, there would be any 
 moral propriet)- in the mere infliction of pain for pain's sake. 
 Why separate the act from its effects in this wa\'. In reality 
 they are inseparable. The total conception of punishment may 
 contain various elements indiss( lubly united. The cjuestion is : 
 which is the fundamental ? out of wliich do the others grow? 
 Punishment is an act of justice, and the essence of punishment 
 is retribution. Satisfaction is the primary object of punishment, 
 and th.e other objects include reformation and deterrence. In 
 all punishment, dt>mestic, social, and even civil, justice should 
 be tempered with mere)- and compassion \'et we must re- 
 member that there is a moral order, of which the phj'sical and 
 the civil orders are parts, and that an}' breach of that order 
 must be rectified. Such rectification is punishment." ^ 
 
 Schubjrt points out, as a defect in the Theory^ the fact that 
 Smith nowhere discusses the problem of the Will. In any case 
 where the word Will or Free-Will is mentioned, it b^ars so 
 
 1. Theoriu I't. II. Sec. iii. Cliap. 3. 
 
 2. Ihul, I't. II. Sec. II. Chaj). 3. 
 
 3. Internuliunul Joiirndl of Ethics. Jan. 
 
 1S92. 
 
 )!;! 
 
 NoTK. — For a siinil.ir view, see International Journal of Ethics, July, 
 i8g6, pji. 479, 483. Jlri/i'V.t Thcunj of Punishtnent, l)y J. Ellis MacTaggart, of 
 Trinity Collcj;e, Canibiidj^c. 
 
 sli; 
 ju^ 
 
 IS 
 
IIIK K'lHICAI. SVSIKM Ol ADAM .s.MUH. 
 
 4' 
 
 without design, 
 
 ';<'tlier. ' As ,, 
 'Oil (;f societ\ , 
 crimes con'i 
 iccrii which we 
 '^, (l(K\s not, ill 
 10 fortune and 
 unjustly taken 
 Vom a regard 
 
 m a regard to 
 a single man 
 
 shment of the 
 Hn concern for 
 
 '1 for the very 
 
 t some modern 
 -ory of punish- 
 
 r James Seth 
 
 that converts 
 r>^ : "the ques- 
 
 would be any 
 or pain's sake, 
 ay. In reah"ty 
 mishment may 
 ic (luestion is : 
 
 others grow ? 
 of punishment 
 jf punishment, 
 iterrence. In 
 justice should 
 : ue must re- 
 
 ph>sical and 
 ')f that order 
 nt." ■'' 
 
 , the fact that 
 
 In any case 
 
 1, it b-ars so 
 
 >l" F.tliics, July, 
 Mac I'liggart, of 
 
 slighll}- anfl so accidental!)- upon the problem that we are not 
 juslilied in drawint; an)' conclusion as to Smith's real position 
 on this (|iu slioM. W hile luvsitaling to express a decided judg- 
 nient on the (|Uestion, Schubert is led, for two reasons, to 
 sup|josc that Smith \\(aild natur.dl\- occui))- the stand-point of 
 Determinism. Hi.-, reasons are fl) the spirit of the Tlicoiy 
 is (k't( iim'niNtic ; '2 if .Smith h.id not approved of Ihnme's 
 l)etermiin'stic \ lews, Ik- uouM h,r>c e\i)ressed his disapproval. ' 
 
 ill the s|)irit of the Theorx- I fail to find the Determinism 
 referred to. There would seem to be, on the contrar)-, in Smith's 
 idea of retributiw pum'shment, and of justice, asdei)endent U])r)n 
 resentment, the strongest evidence that our autb.or held the 
 i>pposite view. It would be difficult, otherwise, to gi\'t; an)- 
 UKNUiing to his statement that, "Nature has implanted in the 
 human Ijreast that consciousness of ill desert, and those terrors 
 of merited pum'shment, wh.ich attend up.on the violation of 
 justice." As to the ficl that .Smith makes no mention of 
 Hume's Deterniim"sm, the two writers occuj))- so diametrically 
 opposed s..u)ilpoints in regard to justii:e, that .Snn'th nn'ght, on 
 tliat account, consider it uimecessai-\- t(. draw attention to their 
 equal))' antagonistic jjositions, on a question s(.) intimately 
 related t(j justice and resentment, as is that of b'ree Will and 
 Determinism, if resentment be onci: adnntted as the basis of 
 justice. freedfMU would seem to be at the same time sclmitteii as 
 a necessar)- postulatt.-. 
 
 \\ hile, theoreticall)'. prai-- and 1)1. .ne are due to tlie good 
 and e\il motive alone, )'et, in actual life. Smith finds that the 
 judgment is pronounced on the conseiiuences which folhnv an 
 action. - .Such punishments as are inflicted for breachi's of w hat 
 i;; called civil police or militar)- discipline, are both inflicted and 
 approved of merel)- fi'om a view to the general interest of 
 societ)-, which, we imagine, camiot otherwise be secured. A 
 sentitH'l, lor example, who falls asleep upon his \\ atch, suffers 
 death b)- the laws of war, because such carelessness might 
 endanger the whole ami)'. Although such carelessness appears 
 very blameable, )ct the thought of this crime does lujt naturally 
 e.xcite au) such resentment as would prompt to such dreadful 
 revenge, (ireat firmness and resolution are required before a 
 person can bring himself either to inflict it, or to apprcjve of it 
 when it is inflicted b)' others. " It is plainly, here, not the 
 
 1. Adam Smith';, Mdrn/philoxiiji/iic pp. 55-56. 
 
 2. 'Jlieori/, V{. 11. Sec. 11 1. Chap. 2. 
 
 3. //'/(/, I't. 11. Sec. II. Chap. 3. 
 
.: I 
 
 H 
 
 42 
 
 MUIK 
 
 iij 
 
 ii!'i :;i 
 
 'I'll ri' 
 
 I';' 
 
 motives of the offciulcr, but the coiiscqueiiccs of the action, 
 which call f(jrth such severe punishment^ 
 
 Smith considers that this divcrsit)' of our theory and 
 practice, in regard to praise and blame, is intendefl b)- nature for 
 the hapj)incss and the perfection of the species. ^ If the hurt 
 fulness of the desit^n, and the male\ olence of the affection, wen 
 alone the causes, which excited our resentment, we should feel 
 all the force of that passion ai;ainst an)' person whom w( 
 sus|)ected of such a design, even thou<;h they had not committed 
 any action of which we could disapprove. Tluni^^hts and 
 intentions would become the objects of punishment, and if the 
 indignation of mankind ran as hitj^h against them as against 
 actions, every court of judicature wcnild become a real 
 inquisition. There would be no safety fc^r the most innocent 
 conduct. It is, therefc^re, a necessar}' rule (jf justice in this life, 
 that men are liable to punishment for their actions only, and 
 not for their designs and intentions. Hence this irregularity in 
 human sentiments, concerning merit and demerit, is both 
 .salutary and useful although, at first sight, it appears absurd and 
 unaccountable. 
 
 In examining this irregularit\' of our moral sentiments, 
 Smith is considering a difficult)', which is present in c\'er)' 
 theor)', that has ever been proposed. 1 )ugald Stewart, speaking 
 of this, says : "So far as I know, .Smith is the first philoso- 
 pher, who has been fully aware of the importance of the 
 difficulty. And his remarks on the important [)urposes to 
 which this irregularit)' (jf sentiment is subser\ient, are particular- 
 ly ingenicjus and pleasing. Their object is to show, in 
 opposition to what we should be disposed at first to a[)prehencl. 
 that when Nature miplanted the seeds of this irregularity in the 
 human breast, her leading intention was to prc;mote the happi- 
 ness and the {)erfection of the species." ^ 
 
 Sympathy, then, is not oid)' the source of our judgments of 
 right and wrong, or, as Smith terms it, of propriety and 
 improprict)', but also of our judgments of merit and demerit, or 
 of the qualities of deser\ing" reward and punishment. Where 
 there is no approbation of the conduct (;t the person who con- 
 fers the benefit, there is little sj-mpathy with the gratitude of 
 him who receives it. And where there is no disapprobation of 
 
 1. TfiPorifyVt. II. Sec. in. Cliap. 3. 
 
 2. Life und Writiui/s of Dr. Smith, \>. 40. 
 
 i 
 f 
 
IHK I.IIIKAI, .-V>11.\1 dl' AHAM SMllll. 
 
 43 
 
 }( the action, 
 
 r theory and 
 b)' nature foi 
 If the hurt 
 liffection, wen 
 
 e should feei 
 >u whom \vc 
 lot committed 
 
 hou^dits and 
 lit, and if the 
 Mn as against 
 :ome a real 
 most innocent 
 
 e in this life, 
 ons only, and 
 irrei;ularity in 
 erit, is both 
 irs absurd and 
 
 1 1 sentiments, 
 sent in c\er)- 
 uart, speakini,^ 
 
 first philoso- 
 rtance of the 
 
 I)ur|)oses to 
 are particular- 
 
 to show, in 
 to a|)prehend, 
 ;ularity in the 
 te the happi- 
 
 jud<rments of 
 propriety and 
 d demerit, or 
 lent. Where 
 on who con- 
 gratitude of 
 pprobation of 
 
 the m.. stives of thv person who docs the mischief, there is no 
 
 sort ot sym])ath\^ ui 
 
 ih the rc'scntnient of him who suffers it 
 
 Smith, as we hii\e seen, finds resentment a most important 
 qiialit}'. It forms a natural l)asis for justice, which Ilume, imable 
 to discoxer for it a satisfactor}- foundation in tlie human niii'd, 
 had i)ronounced an arlifuid and not a natural \irtue. lie 
 theri'fore consistenti)' upholds the retributixe theory of pun- 
 ishment, as dcjiending upon a justice based on resentment. The 
 question may occur as to whether the case of militar\' discipline 
 instanced b\' Snn'th as illustratin-; our judgment of actions by 
 their con^e(|uences, rather than b)' their motives is not, more 
 corrcctl\% an instance of a too e\cessi\e resentment, which has 
 retained its original and unusual force through tradition, and in 
 consequence (u its sup|K)Sed necessity. The fact of our judg- 
 ment of actions b\- consec|uences rather than by motives had 
 led llutcheson to distingui-h between the tormall)- and the 
 inateriall) gcjod ; and had led Hume to the doubtful conclusiijn 
 that while tlie moti\e is that which ccjiistitutes an action good, 
 ve can yet infer, from the pleasure (jr displeasure prcxluced, the 
 character of the moti\e. ^ Smith faces the ([uestion honestly, 
 and admits the inc(>nsistenc}- of our theor)- and our practice ; 
 bnt claims that this irregularit\- is a wise pro\ ision of Nature, 
 which leads to th.e increased happiness and the welfare o^ 
 mankind. 
 
 .sK( Tiox III." rut; im i.n.Nc i: oi- t rii.n\-, cisto.m, .and 
 iwsiiiox ii'MX oTR si:niimi;x r.s nv moral 
 
 Al'I'kdllATIOX AXI) l»l,SAri'R()l!.MI()X. \y 
 
 Smith's discussion of the influence of Utilit)' u|)on our 
 moral si'iitiments is mainl)- a criticism of Idume's principle of i 
 .s)'m|jath}-, w hich \\as called forth b)' utilit)'. and a justification ^ 
 of his own |)rinciple of sxmpath)' w ith pro[)riet\-. According 
 to llimie, the utilit}' of all)' object pleases b)' per|)etuall)' suggest- 
 ing the pleasure which it is fitted to |)roniote. luer)- time we look 
 at it, we are put in mind of this pleasure; and the object thus 
 becomes the source of perpetual satisfaction and enjoj-ment. - 
 
 Smith, on the other hand, claims that e\en in regard to a 
 
 1. Hume, Tiratixf, ]\k. ii. I't. ill. Sec, 
 Thcurn, I'.k. III. I't. II. Sec. i. 
 
 2. Tfu'orii, I't. IV. Chap. I. 
 
44 
 
 MUik : 
 
 production of art, it is the fitness, the happ)- coiitri\ance, the 
 propriety, that we \akie ratlier than the end for which the object 
 was intended. I'he .xact adjustment of means for obt, lining 
 any pleasure is often of more imp(jrtance to us than the very 
 pleasure, in the attainment of which the \alue of the means 
 would seem to consist. luen as thus stated, Smith does not 
 seem to ha\c a j^ood arLjument against ilume. Within the 
 moral sphere, where |)rojjriet)', tiie suitabilit)' of a passion to its 
 exciting cause, was itself an end. Smith's principle appcarcfl of 
 much greater \alue than ilume's s)-mpathy with utilitx' ; but the 
 case is \er\' different when we come to appl\' these principles to 
 an object, or to a work of art. We must, sureK', in this case 
 regard the end or aim for which the object was created, as more 
 valuable than the means used to bring about that end. The 
 pcMUt upon which Smith is insisting here, will, howe\er, be better 
 understood if we take some of his own illustrations. 
 
 A i)erson comes into a room, and finds all the chairs stand- 
 ing in the middle of the room. Rather than sec them contimie 
 in that disorder, he takes the trouble to set them all in their 
 places with their backs to the wall. Tlu; whole propriet}- of this 
 new arrangement arises from tliC superior convenience of leaving 
 tlie floor free and disengaged. To attain this convenience, he 
 voluntarily puts himself to more trouble than all he could have 
 suffered from the want of it. l-'or nothing was easier than to 
 have set himself dcjwn upon one of the chairs, which is, probably, 
 what he does when his labour is over. It seems, therefore, what 
 he wanted was not so much the convenience, as that arrange- 
 ment of things which promotes it. \'et it is the convenience, 
 which ultimately recommends that arrangement, and bestowes 
 upon it the whole of its propriety cUid beaut)'. 
 
 This instance, while it shows plainly that the question 
 under discussion is that of the relative importance of means and 
 of ends, does not add anything to Smith's side of the argu- 
 ment. The propriety of arrangement spoken of, is entirely 
 derived from the utility or the convenience which it tends to 
 promote, and must be regarded as subordinate to this utility. 
 This instance is, therefore, in favour of Hume's standard of utility 
 as oj)posed to propriet)'. For even granting that the end in view, 
 the utility, has practically dropped out of sight, v'et it is that end 
 which bestows all that they possess of value upon the 
 means ; and in this, as in anj' other car.e, the end is best .secured, 
 not by being kept c(jnstantl)- before the mind, but by concen- 
 trating tlie attention upon the means best adapted to secure the 
 
THi: ETHICAI. SVSII.M (iK ADAM SMIIH. 
 
 45 
 
 end. With this concentration of the atti-ntion, it would be 
 strange if its immediate objects (lid not sometimes possess for 
 the minfi a si<;nificanc(.; and importfince, sufficient to overbalance 
 for the time, that of the end to which they are subser\ient; but 
 \'et these means rjo not appear of jj^reater \alue than the end to 
 which the\- are the means. 
 
 Smith c|uotes and endors(\s llume's opim'on that "no 
 qualities of the mind are approwd of as \irtuous, but such as 
 are useful and a^ret-'able either to the person himself or to 
 others." ' This, .Snn'lh sa\'s, is a fact, but, ne\ ertheless, it is not 
 the view of this beaut)- or utilit\-, which is either the first or the 
 principal source of our approbation. 'I'hose useful (jualities, and 
 the actions which flow from thinn, meet with ap|>roI)ation, 
 much mo'-e upon account of their threat pro|)riet)-, than ujjon 
 account C)f their utilit\-. I'tilit)' bestows upon them an addi- 
 tional beaut)', and thus recommends them still further to our 
 approbation. Hut this beaut)- is not easil)- percei\efi, and is, 
 certainl)', not the c]ualit)- which first recommends such actions to 
 the majority of men. 
 
 While Smith utterl)' rejects utilit)' as an ethical principle, 
 and e\-en tries to show here that it is not the cause of our 
 approbation of an)' object or work of art, he )'et admits one case 
 in which the principh* of utilit)' is of the first importance. l^\en 
 in this case, hf)W(ner, its importance is not real, but is due to an 
 illusion of the imai^ination. The t^ood which results from this 
 illusion, however, is real, and is of the \er)- first conse(|uence. This 
 important deception, upon which industrial proi^ress mainl)' 
 depends, is the influence that the utilit) of wealth and [greatness 
 has upon the imaj^ination. - .All commercial pros[)erit)', and all 
 progress in the arts and sciences are due to this false view of the 
 utility of wealth. OwinL,^ to this illusion (if the ima^nnation, 
 wealth comes to be reijjarded as one of the threat ends and aims 
 of life, and as worth)' of all the trouble and anxiet)' which its 
 attainment involves. 
 
 In considering^ the importance of this illusion of the 
 imagination in regard to wealth, and the i;reat and momentous 
 interests it subserves. Smith endea\oi.n's to show that the 
 principle best adapted to secure this utilit)', the principle of 
 commercial ambitif)!! or selfishness, brinijs about a ver\' similar 
 state of affairs, to that which would ha\e resulted, had the 
 
 I Theory, Pt iv. Chaj). 3. 
 2. Ifiid, I't. IV. Chaj). i. 
 
46 
 
 MriR 
 
 opposite pn'iici|)k' dI" s\ inpalhy \k\'U (.'inployed. Fhere are 
 in;ui>" ends of life hesidi-s wi-alth, i)Ut, this ;^i\en a-> an end, 
 selfishness, the ^reat ])iin(iple of economics, offers the best 
 ineans of securini^ it. ' I'.acii man is, naturall)', in-tter fitted to 
 take care of himself than of an)' other person, lie is, also, 
 more deeply interested in what concerns himself than in what 
 concerns an>' one else. llis chief business is to i;()\ern the 
 affairs of his own dail\- life, but, in doin^ this, hf)\\e\er. while 
 intendin^f onl)' his own t^ain, he promotes also an end which was 
 no |)art of his intention, the ^oocl of society. And this end he 
 could not so well ha\e promoted, if he had deliberately aimed 
 at the public ^i(()od. 
 
 Sympathy is thus the -^reat ethical principle, and selfishness 
 the great ])rinciple of l'"conomics, and each of these is sui^reme in 
 its own sphere. liut e\en between those distant and clissimilar 
 princijiles there is a connection. h"or selfishness, as we have 
 .seen, proves to be a princi|)le of de\elo[)ment anrl works out the 
 same beneficial results in societ)-, that would ha\e been promot- 
 ed by bene\'olence or s)-m|)ath\'. The wealthy hindowner may 
 have no thought for an\-one but himself, and may most selfishly 
 regard the produce of his fields, but he cannot possibl)- consume 
 the whole harvest. His em|)loyees deri\e from his extravagance 
 a share of the necessaries of life, which the)- ne\'er would have 
 obtained from his humanit)- or his justice. The produce of the 
 soil maintains at all times nearl)- that number of inhabitants it 
 is capable of maintaining. The rich ma\- select that which is 
 most precious, but the)- cannot really consume \er)- much m(M-e 
 than the poor. And, in spite of their selfishness, though they 
 intend only their own comfort, the)' divide with the poor the 
 produce of all their impro\emcnts. - The necessaries of life are 
 distributed in an almost similar nanner, to what the)' would have 
 been if the earth had been dixided into equal i)ortions among all 
 its inhabitants. I'he influence of utility upon the imagination is 
 thus of great l^conomic xalue. While utterly useless as a 
 
 prmci 
 
 pie of 
 
 tnora 
 
 lit^, 
 
 it is, nevertheless, of supreme imp.ortance 
 
 for Economics, and, indirectly, brings about what w c ma)' regard 
 as ethical or moral results. 
 
 The influence of custom is also important both from the 
 aesthetic and from the moral point of \iew. •' Smith ascribes all 
 
 1. Theory, Pt. ii. Sec ii. Chap. 2. 
 
 2. Ihid, Pt. IV. Cha[). i. 
 
 3. Ibid, Pt. I. Chap. 5. 
 
THF, KI'IIK AI. sVM IM (i|' ADAM SMIIH. 
 
 47 
 
 clian'jcs ill architecture and lit.-raturc, as well as those in dress 
 
 and furniture, to this ca 
 
 USl' 
 
 le holds that it is because artistic 
 
 productions are more lastini;, so that a poem or a musical com- 
 position may contimie for a;4i's to remain the same and be in 
 
 much 
 We ima>rine 
 
 voLTUe, that we are unwilling to allow that custom ha- 
 
 influence u[3on our iu(k;nuiU in regard to them. 
 that these arts are founrled upon reason and natiue, not U|)on 
 habit ;md prejudice, 'i'his. ho\\e\er, Smith reL;ards as an error, 
 and claims thai the inlhience of custom and fashion is not 
 more absolute overdress and furniture, than over architecture, 
 poetry, and music. 
 
 The influence of custom and fashion upon moral senti- 
 ments, while not so irrea.t, is similar to what it is evei where 
 
 else. 
 
 Th 
 
 ose w 
 
 ho h 
 
 b 
 
 ia\e heen educateri ainul \ ice Decome so 
 
 accustomed to it that the\ 
 
 lose larsje 
 
 \v th 
 
 I' sense o 
 
 f it^ 
 
 im|)ro- 
 
 priet}', and fail to uiuKrstand or a|)|)reciate the evil or the 
 punishment due tc) it. l-'.ach .i^c and countr\-. also, rei^ards that 
 decree of each (|ualit)', which is commonly to be met with in 
 those who are esteemed amoiiLi tliemsehes, as the golden mean 
 of that particular talent or \irtue. This \aries according as 
 different circumstances render different (lualities more or less 
 habitual to them ; liencc tlicir sentiments concernini,^ the e.xact 
 propriet)- of character and behaviour \ar\- accordinf^ls'. 
 
 Custom and fashion do not exercise so ^n'eat influence in 
 regard to the ^eni-ral st\-le of behaviour and character, as the\- 
 do concerninj^f the pntpriety and impropriet}' (>( particular 
 usages. In matters of threat importance, it is expected that 
 there shall be no \ariation in conduct. Truth and justice, for 
 example, are demanded of all. It is only in matters of small 
 consequence, or with rei^ard to particular usages, that the influ- 
 ence of custom is destructixe of good morals, aiul is capable of 
 establishing as law ful, |)articular usages, which are contrary to 
 the plainest principle of right and wrong. ' 
 
 In this account of the influence and importance of 
 
 ISIOI 
 
 Smith surely gf)cs too far in regartling the great revolutions 
 
 whi 
 
 ich ha\e taken place in art and in literature, as sim 
 
 ply 
 
 change in fashion. The conditions which bring about the form- 
 er, must lie dee|) in the spirit and the needs of the time. If the 
 
 chanue had not been, unc 
 
 on SCI 
 
 ousl\-, first w rouuht in the minds 
 
 of the peo[jle, such a re\'oluti(jn could never have influenced 
 
 Theory, Pt. v. Chap. 2. 
 
48 
 
 Ml'IK 
 
 those who wcvc iinpivpjui'd f<;r it. So also in moral ri'latioiis, 
 tl'ioii<^li custom and fashion arc, muloiihtrdl)-, influential in 
 certain classcvs of soci(.-ty, \'et the dilferent moral perceptions are 
 rooted det'p in tin; conditions ot tlu- people and the aj^e. Hallour 
 considi-rs this (juestion of the inlliience of custom and fasluon 
 from the Naturalistic point of \ie\\. lie a<jfrees with Smith in 
 reijardin<; art and literature as flependeiit in their chan;^t.s n|)on 
 the same |)rinci|)les as the chanties in dress and furm'ture. He 
 sa\ s ; "'The aestiietic likini^s which fashion orit;inates, however 
 tri\ iai, are |)i'rfectl>" ^emn'ne ; and to an ori|^in similar in kind, 
 hov\e\er different in dignity and ])c-rmanence, should l)e traced 
 much of I lie characteristic (|ualil). which seises its special flavour 
 to the hiL;her artistic sentiments of each successive i;eneration.''i 
 'Ihe princi|)le to which Balfour ascribes all such artistic senti- 
 ments and ai'sthetic changes of fashion is a uni\i"rsal "tendenc)' 
 to agreement," which he describes, howe\i:r, as b}- no means a 
 sim|)le, undecomposabie social force, but rather as hii;hl)- com- 
 plex, having as one of its most important I'knients the instinct 
 of uncritical imitation. This instinct he reL;ards as the xcry 
 basis of all effective education and it is this same instinct of im- 
 itation which is the funflainental element in s\-mj)<ith\' upon 
 whicli Smith bases his s\stem. Balfour criticises the statement 
 that " the artist is the creation of his aj^^e," id maintains that 
 while the action of the aL;e is important, it: oortance consists 
 in its destructive rather than in its creative .....icter, since it does 
 not .so much produce as select. While the influence of environ- 
 ment in m(uddin_s4' 'I'l'l develo])in!j[ t^enius is L;reat, yet imiatc 
 and oriLjinal genius is not the creation of aii\' a;^e, l)Ut is a bio- 
 lot^ical accident, the incalculable product of two sets of ancestral 
 tendencies. The a^e floes not create these biological accident;', 
 but chooses from them, cncouraires those which are in harmonv 
 with its spirit, and crushes out and sterilises the rest. Aesthetic 
 likes and ciislikes are not usual!}' connected with the object which 
 happens to exxite them b)' an)' permanent aesthetic bond at all. 
 Their true cause is to be found \v fashion, in that touiciicy to 
 agreement which is so useful, and plays so imiK)rtant a })art in 
 .social ccononi}'. This accordintjj to Balfour, is the only possible 
 view of aesthetics consistent with Naturalism. \'et, he admits 
 that mankind will not easily reconcile themselves to this view. 
 "We must believe that somewhere and for some Bein;^ there 
 shines an unchanging splendour of beauty of which in nature 
 
 I. Balfour, Fotmdations of Belief, W. i. Cliap. 2. 
 
nil. KIIIU \l, SVSTKM ()l AliAM SMIIII. 
 
 49 
 
 and in Art wc sec, cuh of iis tVoin our own standpoint, onlj' 
 passinj,f ^dcanis and >tra)- rcflrctions, whose dilTi-rent aspects uc 
 cannot now co-oidinate, whosi' import wc cannot liill\- compre- 
 hend, but which at least is somelhint,' other than the chance |)Iay' 
 of suhjecti\e siMisii,int\' or the tar-oCf ixdio ofaiucstral hists. No 
 such mystical creed can, ii(<\\e\c'r, be s(|uee/i"fl out of observation 
 and experiment. Scii-nce cannot ,L;i\e it us ; nor can it be forced 
 
 into an\' sort ol con-^istencv with the 
 
 Nat 
 
 ur.ili-.tic 
 
 ri 
 
 ieor\ ot 
 
 th( 
 
 I 
 
 ni\erse 
 
 I" 1 
 
 
 ch.\pti:r II. ^11 II-: N.xirki-: oi' con.sciI'.nci-: 
 
 SIXTION 1. 
 
 (().\S( lI.Mi; .\M) SNMI'AIIIV. 
 
 In treatinij[ of inoralit)', there arc, Smith says, two ([uestion-s 
 to be considered. I irst : wherein does \ irtue consist, or what i.s 
 the tone, temper, nr tenor of conduct, which constitutes the ex- 
 cellent and pr.iiseworthv character, the character which is the 
 natural object of esteem, honour and approbation ? And, 
 sccondl\- ; b\' what power or facult\- in the nn'nd is it, that this 
 character, whate\er it is, is recommended to u> ; (jr, in other 
 words, how, and b\' what means does it come to pass that the 
 mind prefers one tenor of conduct to another, denominates 
 the one right, and the other w roni;", considers one as the object 
 of approbation, honour, and reward, and the other of blame, cen- 
 sure and punishment? - In the preccfliiiL,^ chapters cniraiin was 
 to explain how, accord ini,^ to .Smith, we learn to judi^e of the 
 conduct of our neighbors ; and, as we ha\e seen, he there an- 
 swered his two great (.juestions in regard U) moralit)' b)- fmding 
 that virtue consists '\x\ proprictw or in that degree of sentiment 
 or affection, which is fitting and suitable to its exciting cause : 
 and by finding in s)-mpath\', the s\-mpathetic feelings of the 
 impartial and well-informeel spectator, the power or faculty of 
 the mind which recommends this character to us. 
 
 1. Fi)vii(l(Uions of Iii'lie/,\'l i. Ch:ii). 1 1. p. 66. 
 
 2. Theorij of the. Mural Sentiiii'mts, Vi. \ ii. St.c. i. 
 
so 
 
 Ml'IU 
 
 The chc'ijitcr, with which \\c are nou- to deal, is concerned 
 with a totall)' (Hstinct entjuir)' : Smith's opinions in regard to 
 our judgments concerning our own sentiments and cc)nduct, and 
 particular!}' our sense of dut\-. In reference to our own 
 conduct. Smith answers the two great ([uestions of morality very 
 similarl)' to what he did when c(jnsidering them in their applica- 
 tion to tile conduct of others. \'irtue consists in an exalted 
 propriety, and it is b)- means of the sympath)' of the impartial 
 spectator that this \irtue is reconnnended to us. The work of 
 the impartial s|)ectator is, howe\er, much more difficult when our 
 own conduct forms the object of judgment. P'or it is compara- 
 tivel)- eas)- to judge im|)artiall)' of another, but exceedingl)' dif- 
 ficult to become the impartial spectators of our own conduct. 
 Hence Smith finds it necessary to introduce much more 
 prominently into this part of the discussion, the function and 
 importance of that which is reall)- the great underlying princijjle 
 of his .s)-stem, namely reason. l^\en in judging others, reason was 
 found to be indispensable. l-'or in all cases of conditional sym- 
 pathy, we are depende?i; upon general rules, and genera' rules 
 are formed by reason. Much more are we dependent up( n rea- 
 son when judging of the propriet\- of our own .sentiments and 
 actions. For in order that we ma}' form an}- imjjartial judgment 
 in reference to our own conduct, general rules are necessary, that 
 we ma}' not be imduly influenced by self lo\e and passion, 
 which would tend to bias our judgments, or the judgments of 
 the impartial s|)ectator, in favour of oursebcs. ^ 
 
 The relation o^ this fundamental ]jrinci[)le of reason to 
 .sympathv, the central doctrine of the TJtcory, has been alread} 
 mentioi^ed, and will later be considered more at length. \Vc 
 ha\ e now to see what is implied in Smith's idea of Conscience. 
 
 'I'he principle b}- which we naturally approve or disapprove 
 of our own conduct is \er}' similar to that by which we judge 
 concerning the conduct of others. VVe ;.-ppro\e or disapprove 
 of our own conduct, according as we feel that when we place 
 ourselves in the situation of another man, and \ iew our actions, 
 as it were, with his e}es, and from his station, we either can or 
 cannot entirel}' enter into and s}'mpathize w ith the sentiments 
 and motixes which influenced them. The only wa}' in which 
 we can justly estimate our ow n sentiments and motives is by 
 endeaxoring to \ iew them with the e}es of other people, or as 
 
 1. Tlit'orn, I'L VII. Sec III. Cliap. 
 Ifiitl, I't. 111. Chap. 4. 
 
THi; KTHUAI, SVSl'KM OK ADAM SMIIII. 
 
 51 
 
 c ciulccU (Hir to examine 
 
 other people are likely to \ icw them. \\ 
 
 our own conduct, as we imaL;iiH' an}- fair and impartial spectator 
 
 would examine it. 
 
 If. 
 
 u\nm placm^- oursehes 
 
 iii h 
 
 IS s 
 
 w 
 
 ituation. 
 
 n- 
 
 e thoroughly enter into all the passions and motixes which i 
 fluenced our conduct, we approxe of it h\- s\'mpathy with the 
 approbation of this su|)p()sed e(|uitable judL;"e. If otherwise, we 
 enter into his disap])robation, and condemn it. ' it is, thus, by 
 means of s\'mpath\' alone, that uc can make a just decision in 
 estimatin*;- our own moti\es and conduct. 
 
 Our first moral criticisms are exercised upon the character 
 and conduct of f)ther people, and we observe \er\' (luickl)' how 
 each of these affects us Hut uc soon learn tliat other people arc 
 equally frank with res^arrl to our own conduct. We become 
 anxious to know how far we deserx e theii- censure C)r applause, 
 anrl whether we must necessaril)' appear such as thcx' rejjresent 
 us to be. We be^iii, therefore, to examine our own passions 
 and conduct, and to consider how thi'se must a|)pear to them, 
 by considerini; how the\' would appear to us if in their situation. 
 VVe suppose oursehes the spectators of our fnvn behaviour, and 
 endeavour to ima^n'ne what effect it wiuild, in this h'i;ht, produce 
 upon us. If, in this \iew, it pleases us, we are tolerabl\- well sat- 
 isfied. We can be more indifferent about the actual opinions of 
 others, when we are sure that we are the natural and j^roper ob- 
 jects of ap|)robation. 
 
 VVe here become the im|)artial spectators of our own con- 
 duct, and, in sitting;" thus in judt^inent upon ourselves, the self 
 becomes the hit^iiest court of a|)peal in all cases of morality. 
 From our observations upon the conduct of others, reason has 
 formed rules and measures b\- which to judge, - and these r<"'es, 
 each man, as an impartial spectator, ap|jlies to himself. n 
 endeavoring to exan^.ine and to pass sentence upon m\' own con- 
 duct, I divide m)self, as it were, into two persons. I, the ex- 
 aminer and the judge, represent a different character from the 
 other, I, the person whose conduct is examined into and judged 
 of. The first is the s|)ectator, w hose sentiments with regard to 
 my own conduct, I endeavour to enter into, b}- phicing myself in 
 his situation, and bj- considering how it would appear to me, 
 when seen fiom that jjarticular point of \iew. The second is 
 the agent, the person whom I propcrl}' call m\self, and ofwho.se 
 
 1. Thcori/, Pt. III. ('"nap. i. 
 
 2. IbUl,i'i.vii. Sec. III. Chap 2, 
 
52 
 
 MUIR 
 
 conduct, under tiic character of a spectator, I am endeavoring 
 to form soine o|)inion. Ihe first is the judge, the second the 
 person judged of ' 
 
 SK( TKJN II.— CONSi Il-.Xri-; IDKNTIFIEl) WITH RKASON. 
 
 Conscience is, in tlie I'licory, identified with reason. Speak- 
 ing of IMato's s\-stem. Smith sa\-s : " Tiie judging facult)', I'lato 
 called, as it is \er\- propcrl}' called, reason, and considered it the 
 go'.erning principle of the \\hole. Under this appellation, he 
 comprehended not onl}' that facult\' b}' which we judge of truth 
 and falsehood, but that by which we judge, also, of the propriety 
 or impr(j|)riet}' of desires or affections. -" W'lien considering the 
 motive power to self-sacrifice. Smith plainly identifies reason and 
 conscience. 1 le says : " it (this motive power) is not humanity, 
 it is not benevolence etc. It is a stronger power, a iriore forcible 
 motive, which exerts itself u|)on such occasions. It is reason^ 
 principle, coiisiiriici\ the inhabitant of the breast, the man 
 within, tlie great judge and arbiter of conduct, "" Smith regards 
 the judgment of conscience as ver\ different from an>' individual 
 judgment of man. I le says : " an apjieal lies from the sentence 
 of man, to tnat of a much higlier tribun.d, to the tribunal of con- 
 science, to that of the supposed impartial and well-informed 
 s])ectator. to that of the man within the breast, the great judge 
 and arbiter of conduct. The jurisdiction of the man without is 
 founded in the desire of actual praise, anl in the aversion to ac- 
 tual blame. The jurisdiction of the man withii is founded alto- 
 gether in the desire of praise-worthiness and in the aversion to 
 blame-worthiness." •* The judgments of Conscience are thus very 
 different from those of an\- ituiividiial spectator. 
 
 In estimating our own merit, in judging of our own conduct 
 and character, there are two different standards to which we 
 com|)are them. The one is the idea of e.xact propriet}- and per- 
 fection which conscience sets up for the guidnnce of the life ; the 
 other is that degree of approximation to this idea, which is com- 
 monl}' attained ir. the world, or which is the recognized standard 
 of our own age and country. The wise and virtuous man directs 
 his principal attention to the standard of e.xact propriety and 
 perfection. •' Mis great object is not to act in such a manner as 
 to obtain the actual ap[)robation of those around him, but to act 
 
 1. Thoorij, Ft. Ml. Sec. in. Cluip. i. 
 
 2. Ibid, I't. VII. Sec. II. Chai). i. 
 
 3. IhiO, I't. III. Chap. 3. 
 
 4. Ihid, I't. III. Chap. 2. 
 
 5. Ihid, I't. VII. Sec. 3. 
 
TtlE r.lHIC.M. SYSTEM Ol" ADAM SMITH. 
 
 53 
 
 in such a manner as to rciuicr himself the just and proper object 
 of that approbation. His satisfaction with his own conduct de- 
 pends much m.ore upon this consciousness of deserving ap[)roba- 
 tion, than upon that of really enj(jying it. i 
 
 Smith holds that Conscience is not infallible. The violence 
 and injustice of f)ur selfish passions are son. times so great as 
 utterly to per\ert our judgments concerning our own conduct. 
 The "man within the breast" is induced to make a report \ery 
 different from w hat the real circumstances of the case (lemand. - 
 
 Tht 
 
 ere are two different occasions on w 
 
 hich 
 
 we examme our own 
 
 m- 
 
 conduct, aufl endeavour to \v)w it in the light in which die i 
 partial spectator would \iew it. I'irst, when we are about to act, 
 and, second, when we have acted. In both cases our views, are 
 very apt to be partial. When we are about to act, passion 
 seldoiTi allows us to consider what we are doing with the candour 
 of an indifferent person. W hen the action is over, although we 
 can then enter into the sentiments of the indifferent spectator 
 more C(j()ll\- than before, yet it is so disagreeable to us to think 
 ill of ourselves, that we often purposely turn away our \iew from 
 those circumstances which niight render our judgment unfavour- 
 able. 
 
 '1 he impartial spectator is not onl}- liable to be influenced by 
 our own |)assions, so ;is to give a judgment more favourable to us 
 than the case warrants, but he is als(j liable to err in the other 
 direction. When th.; judgment of others, that of all tlie real 
 spectators, is un mim:)iisl\' and violently against us, the im[)artial 
 spectator seems to give his o|)im'on in our favour with fear and 
 hesitation. On this account, .Smith likens the impartial s|)ecta- 
 tor to the demigods of the poets, who, though parti)' of immor- 
 tal, are yet partly of mortal extraction. When his judgments 
 are directed bv' ihe sense of praise-worthiness and blame-worthi- 
 ness, he seems to act suitably to his divine extraction. When he 
 is astonished and confounded by the judgments of ignorant men, 
 he discovers his connection with mortalitj', and acts suitably 
 rather to the human than to the divine part of his origin. 
 
 In order to guard (nn'selves against the delusions and the 
 self-deceit brought about b\- oin* selfish passions, nature leads us 
 to form insensibh', by observations upon the conduct of others, 
 general rules, concerning what is fit and proper to be done. We 
 observe that some actions shock us, and also shock other people. 
 
 1. Thponj, Pt. III. Chip. 2. 
 
 2. Ihitl, i't. III. Chip. 4. 
 
54 
 
 M V I R 
 
 VVc concluflc that all such actions arc to he cuoidcd, and we fix 
 this j^eiieial rule in our minds, in order to correct the niisrepre- 
 sentati(jns of self-lo\e. ' It is from reason that we derive all 
 those j^eneral niaxiins and ideas, and it is by these that we regu- 
 late the greater part of our moral judgments. - 
 
 A regard for general rules constitutes our sense of duty, a 
 princijile which Smith pronounces of the greatest consecjuence in 
 human life. It is the only principle b\' which the bulk of man- 
 kind are capable of directing their actions. '■'' Our reverence for 
 tliese general rules is (urther enhanced by an opinion, which is 
 first impressed b\' nature, and afterwards confirmed by reason- 
 ing and philosoph}', that these imp(jrtant rules of morality are 
 the commands of the iJeity, who will finalh' reward the obedient 
 and punish the transgressors.'* .Although the sense of duty 
 should be the ruling and the go\erning principle of life, yet 
 Smith maintains, that it should not, b}- any means, be the .sole 
 principle of our conduct. '' It dejiends upon the natural agree- 
 ableness or deformit)- of an affection itself, liow far our actions 
 ought to arise from it, or entirely proceed from a regard to the 
 general rule. The acti(iis to which the bene\olent affections 
 prompt, fHight to proceed as much from the passions as from any 
 regard to general rule.; of conduct. We ought, on the contrary, 
 to resist injuries more from the sense that they deserve and are 
 the proper objects of resentment ; and ought always to punish 
 with reluctance, and more from a sense of dut\-, a sense of the 
 propriet)' of punishing, than from an)' sa\age disposition to re- 
 venge. " Jt depends, also, partly upon the precision and exact- 
 ness, ov the looseness and the inaccuracy of the rules themselves 
 how far our conduct ought to proceed entirely from a regard to 
 them. 
 
 The general rul<^s of almost all of the virtues : of prudence 
 of charity, of generosity, of friendship, are in many respects loose 
 and inaccurate. The}- admit of many exceptions and require so 
 many modifications, that it is scarcely possible to regulate our 
 conduct entirely by a regard to them. The general rules of jus- 
 tice, on the other hand, determine w ith the greatest exactness, 
 every external action w hich it requires. These rules are perfectly 
 clear and most undoubted; they are precise, accurate, and incHs- 
 
 I. 
 
 2. 
 
 3- 
 4- 
 5- 
 6. 
 
 Thfori/, I't, III. Chap. 4. 
 
 Ibid, Pt. VII. 
 Il>i<l I't. III. 
 Ibid. I't. III. 
 /bid, I't. III. 
 Ibid, Pt. VI. 
 
 hoc. III. 
 Chap. 4. 
 Cluip. 5. 
 Cliap. 6. 
 Sec. 3. 
 
 Chap 2. 
 
 bl; 
 
i'MK KTHU'AI. SVS'IKM OK ADAM SMITH. 
 
 55 
 
 pensublc. It may be awkward and pedantic to affect too strict 
 an adherence to the common rules of many of tiie virtues ; but 
 there is no pcdantr\- in stickini; fast b\- the rules of justice. On 
 the contrarx', tlie most sacred ret^ard is due to them, and the 
 actioi>', which this \irtue requires, are never so properly per- 
 formcu, as when the chief motive for performing them is a reve- 
 rential rcL^ard to those general rules, which re(]uire them. ^ 
 Smith's opposition to IIuuk; is no where more clearly shown i 
 than in his treatment of justice. We have already noted, that 
 where Hume i^roiKJunced tiiis \irtue artificial, depending upon i 
 the contri\ance of man, Smith regarded it as the chief of the 
 virtues, and the corner stone of society. He liere again emfjha- 
 sizes its preeminence insisting on the precision, exactness, and 
 supreme importance of the general rules by which the acts re- 
 quired by this virtue are regulated. 
 
 .Sl'XTlUX III. — COXSCIKNCK TIIK SOlRCK OF TllK MORAL IDLAL. 
 
 (Jruided b}- general rules, conscience forms within us an idea 
 of e.xact propriet}- and perfection, -i There exists in the mind of 
 every irian such an idea, graduall\- ff)rmed from his observations 
 upon the character and conduct b(<th of himself, and of other 
 people. It is the slow, gradu.'.I, and progressive work of con- 
 science, the great judge anrl arbitjr of conduct. •* The perfection 
 of this ideal deijends upon the care and attention which each 
 man bestows upon its formation. The wise and \irtuous man 
 forms a much more correct image of it than a man of the opposite 
 character, and endea\'ours more and more to realise it in his 
 life. Hut, in doing so, he is attempting to imitate the work of a 
 divine artist which can never be e(|ualled. 
 
 This perfect virtue, which the sense of dut)' leads us to 
 strive after, is not an\- \\a\' dependent upon the opinion of 
 others. To be amiable and to be meritorious, thai is to deserve 
 love and to deserve reward, are the great characteristics of virtue; 
 and to be odious and punishable of \ice. ■* Man naturally desires 
 not only praise, but praise-worthiness, or to be that thing which, 
 though it should be praised by noborl)-, is howe\er, the natural 
 and proper object of praise. He dreads not onl)- blame, but 
 blame-worthiness, or to be that thing which, though it should be 
 blamed by nobod}', is. however, the natural and proper object 
 
 1. Thcorti, I't 1 1 1. Chap. 6. 
 
 2. tliid, i't. VI. C'linp. 3. 
 3 Il>i(l, ]\k. III. Sec. 3. 
 4. Ihid, Pt. 1 1. Clia|). I. 
 
S^' 
 
 MUiR : 
 
 of blame. Instead of the lo\ e of praise- worthiness being derived 
 from the lo\e of praise, the love of praise is largely derived 
 from that of praise-worthiness. 
 
 Virtue, in every particular instance, necessarily pleases for 
 its own sake. To obtain approbaticjn, even where it is due, may 
 sometimes be of no great importance ; but to deserve approba- 
 tion must alwajs be of the highest. A maa's self-approbation 
 if not the highest, is at least the principal thing about which he 
 can or ought to be an.xious. The lo\e of it is the love of virtue. 
 It is not the thought of being hated and despised that we are 
 afraid of, but that of being hateful and despicable. ^ Moreover 
 it must be noted that \irtue and happiness are united in the 
 Theory. Happiness is said to consist in tranquillity and enjoy- 
 ment. Without tranquillitx' there can be no enjoyment, and 
 where there is traiKiuillit\-, but little else is required I'eace 
 of mind does not, to an\- great e.xtent depend upon outward cir- 
 j:umstances. Virtue is the most desirable thing in life, for it is 
 always accompanied by self satisfaction, and with self-satisfac- 
 tion there never can be misery and wretchedness. - 
 
 The supreme judge of conduct, then, is the self. An appeal 
 lie.s from, the sentence of our fellow men to this higlier tribunal — 
 the tribunal of conscience. That which prompts us to sacrifice 
 our own interests to the interests of others is not reall)' benevo- 
 lence. It is a much stronger power and more forcible motive : 
 the love of what is honourable and noble, a sense of the grand- 
 eur and dignity and superiority of our own character, which is 
 given by reason, or the principle of conscience. Without the 
 approbation of the self, of this highest principle of our natiiie, 
 no action can, properly, be called virtuous. •' The really vir- 
 tuous man governs his whole behaviour and conduct according 
 to the sentiments and emotions which conscience [)rescribes and 
 ap[)ro\es. ■* 
 
 The sentiment or affection of the heart from which any 
 action proceeds is that upon which it.s whole virtue must ulti- 
 mately depend. The grand motive of life must be the desire 
 and atteinpt to realise an ideal which has been divinely implant- 
 ed in man. In order that there may be any progress in the 
 realisation of this ideal, society is necessary. ^ To feel much for 
 
 1. Throrii, Ft. in. Chap. 2. 
 
 2. IMd, l^t. VII, Sec. II. Cliap. i. 
 
 3. /^>('(/, Pt. VII. Sec. III. Chap. 2. 
 IhUl, I't. VI. Chap. I, 
 
 4. 11>id, Ft. III. Clia|)ters 3 and 6. 
 
 5. Ibid, Ft. I. Ctiap. I. Sec 5. 
 
tHt: ETHICAL SVSTK.M OK ADAM SMITH. 
 
 57 
 
 I 
 
 others and little for ourselves, to restrain our selfisli, and strength- 
 en our benevolent affections, constitutes the perfection of human 
 nature, and can alone produce the harmoii}' of sentiments and 
 passions in which their whole grace and |)ropriet>' consists. As, to 
 love our neighbors as we lo\ e oursehes, is the great law of Chris- 
 tianity, so the great precept of nature is to love ourselves only as 
 we love our neighbors, or what comes to the same thing, as our 
 neighbor is capable of loving us. Society is thus necessary for 
 the development of moral character. Hut it is necesar)', also, in 
 a )'et more fundamental wa)' than is here implied. lM)r, as we 
 have alread}' seen, we are not (inl\- dependent upon others as a 
 
 for thi 
 
 rfecti 
 
 )f 
 
 'ter, but, also, for 
 
 first 
 
 means tor tne periection oi moral character, out, also, lorour 
 knowledge of moral distinctions, j-'or these are formed, in the 
 first instance, from our observations u|X)n the conduct of others 
 
 We find, then, that conscience, in the Tlicory is identified 
 with reason ; and in order to present its judgments upcMi our 
 sentiments and conduct from being influenced b\- self-lo\e and 
 passion, reason is said to form, from our obser- ations upon the 
 conduct of others, general rules b\- which its decisions may be 
 guided. We thus Ijecome, b\- means of reason, or conscience, 
 the im|jartial spectatc^rs of our own conduct, and the self is thus 
 constituted the highest cf)urt of appeal in all cases of morality-. 
 Moreover our re\eience for general rules constitutes our sense of 
 dut}' and we come at length, to regard those ules as the laws of 
 God. The sense of dut\' is not here, as it s ii. Kant's s\stem, 
 the sole principal of moralit)', but it is, nexcrtheless the ruling 
 and the governing princijjle, and the only principle b\' which the 
 majority of men are capable of- guiding their conduct. It de- 
 pends upon the natural agreeableness of an affection itself, in 
 how far it, or our sense of dut\-, should have the preeminence in 
 regulating conduct. In acts which should spring from affection 
 or benevolence, the very highest form of conduct must depend 
 upon the affection, and cannot arise solely from our sense of 
 duty. All acts of justice, on the other hand, should proceed 
 entirely from our res|ject for the general rules of this \irtue, as 
 justice is best secured by the most exact compliance with the 
 demands of duty. 
 
 Guided by general rules, conscience forms within us a per- 
 fect ideal of conduct, and our sense of duty leads us constantly 
 to strive to realise this ideal. This perfect \ irtue is not, in any 
 way, dependent upon the opinion of others : it, in every instance 
 necessarily pleases for its own sake. Self-a|)probation is the 
 principal thing about which we can, or ought to be anxious. 
 
58 
 
 MUlR 
 
 Virtue is the most desirable thing in life for it is always accom- 
 panied by self-satisfaction, and self-satisfaction is that which is 
 most essential to happiness. 
 
 CHAPTKR III. CONCLU.SION. 
 
 Sl-XTIOX I. — RKLATION OF TIi:: TIIKORV OF TlIi: MORAL 
 sknti.mf:nts to OTIIFIR KTIIICAL SVSTK.M.S, 
 
 In procecdin<^ now to sum up the results of o''- investij^a- 
 tion, we may first consider the relation of Smith's i ficoiy to the 
 systeins of the precedinj^ writers of the Moral Sense School. 
 The great work of these writers was, as we have seen, their re- 
 cognition of the import.uice of the sentient element in morality, 
 and the proof that man has not onh' instincts and inclinations 
 toward his own gf)od, but that he has eciualh- important natural 
 tendencies which seek to promote the welfare of others. Shaf- 
 tesbury insisted upon the natural harmon\' and just proportions 
 of egoism and altruism, mhintaining that the one is quite as nat- 
 ural and as necessary to man as is the other. Shaftesbury 
 al.so claimed that it was not reason which led men either to be 
 benevolent, or to distinguish right and wrong, but a sense, which 
 he called the Moral Sense. The judgments of this sense, how 
 ever, when uncorruj:)ted, are alwajs in harmony with rea.'-on. 
 Hutcheson, de\eloping Shaftesbury's ideas, found all virtue in 
 benevolence, which he proclaimed the only object of the Moral 
 Sense. The i.)ursuit of the good of others is for him prompt- 
 ed by an instinct and ap|)roved by the Moral Sense. Our moral 
 sense and affections determine the end, but it is reason which 
 finds out the tneans. Virtue is to be found, however, not in rea- 
 son but in kind affections towards the good of others. Hume 
 could .see no necessit)' for the introduction of a new factor, such 
 as the Moral Sense, into human nature when there already ex- 
 isted, in sympathy, that which might, or, as he claimed, did per- 
 form the work allotted to this new sen.sc. More important 
 still, Hume utterly ignores reason, or degrades it to the rank of 
 a passion. He holds, that, by reason, we only mean that pas- 
 sion, which, in the particular instance, has happened to secure 
 
THK KIHKAI. SVSIKM Ol ADAM SMIIH. 
 
 50 
 
 tlie master)'. Moral jiicl^incnts rest oiil)' U|Kjn the f'.'cliii^ of 
 jjlcasure or displeasure w hich an action excites in the spectator. 
 Sympathy thus becomes the source of moral distinctions, but it is 
 entireh' a sympathy with pleasure and pain ; a pleasure and |)ain 
 which, Hume maintained, accompanied all moral actions. Ri^ht 
 and wron<.j thus become s\iim\-mous with pleasure and pain, and 
 with Hume complete ethical subjectivilx' is reached. The trans- 
 ference of moral judgments from the actor to the spectator who 
 pronounces actions ^'ood or bad llnvngli his sympathy ^.nth plea- 
 sure and pain, is the characteristic feature that chstm^aiishes 
 Hume's ethical system from its |)iedecessors. ' / 
 
 To .Adam .Smith this appeared a most objectionable 
 method of settling; moral cjuestioiis. Hence, while he makes 
 .symj>ath\- or fellow feeling the cc-ntral doctrine of his s\-stem, he 
 purifies it from all the utilitarian colouring; it hafl received in 
 Hume's theorv, and makes the s|;ectator sympathise not with 
 pleasure and pain, but w ith the sentiments and motives of the 
 person acting, and tiie gratitude and resentment of the person af- 
 fected by the action. .Smith thus receives and develops the 
 doctrine of the moral sense, which had been transf(jrmed by 
 Hume into a utilitarian s\-mpath\-. J^ut it is alsc; to be noted 
 that he likewise reconsiders the function of rea.son, which Hume 
 had completel} destroyed. Indeed, the most im[}ortant and the 
 most difficult doctrine f)f the Theory is Smith's \iew of the nec- 
 essity of both reason and sjmpath}' for the formation of any 
 moral judgment, and the mutual relation of these great fun- 
 damental principles. 
 
 The problem regarding tlie function of reason and .sympathy 
 in the system, has callecl forth two widel)' differing interpre- 
 tatif)ns of Smith's views. I^\' one class of writers s) mpathy is 
 said to be the one great principle from which Smith reasons, 
 and to which all others are subser\ lent, - "the basis of the 
 whole of moral philosophx." ^ Another writer maintains that 
 .sympathy is no more the fundamental principle in Smith's eth- 
 ics than it is in that of Kant, and contends that they who 
 regard it as such totally misunderstand the .system. * This 
 difference of opinion is not surprising, and ma}' largely be ac- 
 counted for by a fact, which h.is caused a great deal of misun- 
 derstanding and inisrepresentation of Smith's work generally. 
 This fact is Smith's peculiar method of rea.soning. Buckle says 
 
 1. Erdniann, Ili^tarn of I'liiliisopli;/, \'()1. ii. p. 132. 
 
 2. Buckle, Ilistnri/ nf Cirilizdtion, p. 344. 
 
 3. Erdmann, IJistor;/ of Pliilosojiliij, \' A. 11. p. 133. 
 
 4. Oncken, Die Ethik Smith's <ind Kant's p. 100. 
 
6o 
 
 Mil I< 
 
 of this: "in tliat peculiar ff)iiii of declucticjii, which consists in a 
 deliberate suppression of part of the principles, Arlain Smith 
 stands alone." ' It is indeed true that in showin:^ the applica- 
 tions of one principle Smith freciuently loses si^ht of all else. 
 His ethics, for example, knows nothin^^ but altruism, hiseconcjmics 
 nothing but egoism. With both of these principles he is in 
 thorough sj'Tipath)-, but in considering the one totally ignores 
 the other. 
 
 Within his ethical work the same thing is noticeable- 
 Smith is here utter!)' o|)posed to egoism, and regards his view 
 of sympatlu' as the characteristic feature of his work, and as that 
 by means of which he has made an advance on all previous 
 ethical writers, lie therefore makes sympalh}- the central doc- 
 trine of his systein, and emphasizes the fact that it is by means of 
 this principle alone that we are able t(j form our moral judg- 
 ments, h'ollowing his usual method of reasoning, he is almost 
 oblivious to an\' j^hase of the tiuestion except that, which, lur the 
 purpose of his present discu.ssion, ajjpears of paramount import- 
 ance, Hence, while he full\- recognizes, and ultiinatel)' acknoA- 
 ledges, reason as absolutely indispensable to our moral judgments, 
 a large part of his work is necessarily spent upon the explana- 
 tion and vindication of that which he regain, i as his peculiar con- 
 tribution to the development of ethical thought — tlie function of 
 .sympath}'. While thus engaged he makes but little reference to 
 reason, which he, nevertheless, considers the great fundamental 
 principle of morality. For, notwithstanding the promin- 
 ence given to sj-mpathy, .Smith recognizes, as few ethical 
 writers have done, the importance to mondit)- of both reason and 
 sense, and hence deserves to rank far abo\e the philosophers of 
 the Moral Sense school. I^thics, all questions of conduct, ari.se 
 out of the fact of the dualit)- of man's n.iture, and an extreme in- 
 sistance upon either reason or sense, to the exclusion of the other, 
 cannot fail to prc/duce a false \itnv of moralit}'. Reason and 
 sense are equally necessary, for no moral judgment can ever 
 hz formed, which dojs n )t invobe those two elements. That 
 this is the view held by Smith, we hope to make clear. 
 
 SECTION 11. — FUNCTION OK RE.ASON AND OF SKNSK IN THK 
 THKORV OF TIIF MORAL SKNTIMKNTS. 
 
 We shall consider first the opinions of soine writers who h(;ld 
 that reason is utterly ignored in the '/yieory. Sidgwick says : 
 " What we call our conscience is really sympath)' with the feel- 
 
 I. History oj Civilization, p. 344. 
 
\f 
 
 IMK !• IHICAI. SVSIKM OK ADAM SMITH. 
 
 6i 
 
 inj^s of an iiiia;^M'iuir\' iinj)artial spectator, lookinjf at our 
 conduct.''' I laldano sa)s : "Smith makes the nature and 
 vahch'ty of ethical principles depeiid on the state of mind of an 
 indivifkial." -' Schul)ert asks: ' whv. above all thini^s, does Smith 
 acce])t such a principle as the applause of the world for the ex- 
 planation of conscience ?■ •'• We shall endeavor, in answering 
 these objections to Smith's system, to show the (.cpial iiri| ort- 
 ance of reason and s\in|)ath\- in the Tlicory. 
 
 Let us first examine Sid-r 
 
 WW 
 
 statement 
 
 What ue call 
 
 our conscience is reall\- s\inpath\' with the feelin{^^s of an imag- 
 
 inary, impartial spectator, lookinj^f at our conduct. 
 
 Ih 
 
 IS is 
 
 really not what Smith means by conscience. It is, indeed. 
 
 by means of sympatlu- that conscience recognizes 'ight and 
 \vron<^, ' but, as we ha\e seen ui chapter II, conscience itself is 
 not .sympathy or feeliii^r at all, but reason. There would ap- 
 pear to be n(j justification in the 'J'/n'ory for this identification of' 
 
 sym|)atli>' with conscience. A consideration of (jne or two pa.'- 
 .sa^^es will show conclusi\el)' that Smith did not rej.jard the 
 
 ni' 
 
 as one. 
 
 11 
 
 e s; 
 
 I'h 
 
 e word conscience does not necc;ssari 
 
 devote any moral facult)' b)- which we approve or disapprove. 
 
 Out 
 
 ir moral judij^ments would be extremel\- uncertain and pre- 
 carious if the)' depended alto^^ether upon what is liable to so^ 
 many variations as immediate sentiment and feeling'.', 'It is by,' 
 reason that we discover the "general rules of justice, prudence, 
 genenjsit)-, etc., according to which weendeaxour, as well as wcr 
 can, to model the tenor of our conduct.' '^ 'An appeal lies to 
 the tribunal of their own conscience to that of the su|)posed im- 
 l)artial and \\( 11-informed spectatf)!'." Smith here plainly iden- 
 tifies conscience and the impartial spectator, and shows that it is 
 primaril}- upon reason rather than upon sense and feelin^^ that our 
 moral judgments dei)end. When sjjeakinj^r of the motive pcjwer 
 to self-sacrifice, he sa)\s : 'It is reason, princi|)le, conscience, 
 the inhabitant of the breast, the man within, the great judge 
 and arbiter of our conduct.' Conscience and reason are hercj 
 again synonymous terms, but neither here, nor anywhere else inj 
 the Theory, does Smith regard conscience and symjjath)' as one.' 
 
 Ilisturii i)f Elliirs, p. 207. 
 
 R. B. Haklane, 'Life of Adnm SmUh." p. Q3. 
 
 Die MordlithiJoKophip. Addia Sinith's, Pt. lii. 
 
 Theitry, i't. n i. Chap. i. 
 
 IhhK I't. VII. Sec. III. Chap. 2. 
 
 Ibid, Ft. VII. Sec. III. Chap. 3. 
 
62 
 
 MUIR : 
 
 H.'ildaiic inaiiit.'iiiis that "Smith makes the nature aiul 
 vahVlit) of ethical |)riiu;i|>les tlepend upon the state of mind ofan 
 individual." So far is this from beinj^ the case that there are 
 few |)oints which Sniitli has made more clear than this ; that the 
 criterion of moral distinctions is not indix idual. lie sa)s : 
 "Man has been rendered the immediate judj^^e of mankind, but 
 he has been rendered so oid\- in tlie first instance. An appeal 
 hes from his sentence to a much higher tribunal, to tlie tribunal 
 of their own consciences; to that of the supposed impartial and 
 well-informed spectator. The jurisdictions of those two tribu- 
 nals are tountL'd ujjon principles which, thous^h in some respects 
 similar, are in realit)' different and distinct. The jurisdiction of 
 the man u ithout is founded altoiicther in the desire of actual 
 j)rai.se, and in the aversion to actual blame. The jurisdiction f)f 
 the man within is foundi'd alto-^^ether in the desire of praise- 
 worthiness, and in the aversion to blame-worthiness. \, Con- 
 science, the man w ithin, whose jurisdiction is founded altoijether 
 U()on the desire of praise-worthiness is, as weha\e seen, identi- 
 fied by Smith with reason. Ilence reason i^ the supreme ruler 
 in the moral sphere, and the judgments of reason are alwa)'s 
 .universal and can ne\er be re^L,farded as dependin<; upon the 
 , state of mind ofan individual. It is from the tribunal of man 
 that we turn for sentence to this hi<.,dier court of appeal with its 
 standard of exact pro|)riet\- and perfeclion." 'vj 
 
 Schubert holds that, in the Theory, even the general rules 
 are re^^arded as of purel) ein|)irical derivation, '' and asks : " why 
 abo\e all thinj^s does Smith accept such a principle as the 
 applause of the world for the explanation of conscience "? That 
 Smith by no means considered i^i-}icral rules as empirically 
 derived has ;' eady been clearlx shown. The impon:ance of 
 reason in their toriTiatioii receives ^reat cm|)hasis from him. We 
 have had occasion .several times already to note his insistance 
 upon this; but his \iews are clearly expressed in the following: 
 "The <^eneral rules of moralit\- are formed, like all other general 
 mnxims, from experience and induction. We observe in a great 
 variety of particular cases what pleases or displeases our moral 
 faculties, what the.sc approve or disap[)ro\c of, and by induction 
 from this experience, we establish those {general rules. Hut 
 induction is alwaxs rei^arded as one of the operations of rea.5on. 
 I'Vom reason, therefore, we are ver\' i)roperly said to derive all 
 those fi^eneral maxims and ideas. It is b)- these, however, that 
 
 1. 'nit'onj, Pt. m. Chiip. 2. 
 
 2. Jhhl, i't. VI. Sec. 3. 
 
 3. Die Muralphiluxiijiliie Adam Smilh's, Pt. 11 1. 
 
 1) 
 
Nil. I.IIIUAI, SVSIIM ol ADAM SMIIH. 
 
 i 
 
 63 
 
 \vc ro^iiliitc the jj;ri'atcT part of our moral jiKlt,MiKMits, which would 
 
 be 
 
 extremely uiKert.iiii aiul precarious if tliey depended a 
 
 ilto- 
 
 ^'eth'.-r upon what is liable to so many variations as immediate 
 sentiment and feelini;. As our most solid ju(l<^nnents, therefore, 
 with rej^ard to riLjht and w ron<4'. are rej^nilated bj- maxims and 
 ideas deri\ed from an induction of reason, \ irtue may \ery pro- 
 perl)' be said to consist in a conformit\- to reason, and so far this 
 facult)- may be considered as the source and principle of appro- 
 
 Ixit 
 
 ion and disapprobation 
 
 In the face of such a |:assa<j[e as 
 
 ^ 
 
 this it is difficult to see how an}- one could claim that Smith 
 holds that the {general rules of morality are "purel)- empirically 
 deri\ed." And that Smith does not accept the "applause (<f the 
 \\()rld as ;m explanation of conscience" we have alread)' seen. 
 I'"or the judLjments of conscience are not based upon the desire 
 for actual |)raise, but upon the desire for praise-worthiness. 
 Moreover, conscience is reason, and hence does not re(|uire an)' 
 explanation be\-ond itself " Reason is not onl)- the facultv- by 
 which we judge of truth and falsehood, but that also b\ which 
 we jud<.j(j of passions and affection^ 
 
 It is clear, then, that Smith's s)'stem sh(nild not be ranked 
 as a Moral Sense theor\ , or as a mere ethics of s)'inpathy. Can 
 vve, on the other hand, view it. as Oncken does, as a purely 
 rational s) stem ? Oncken finds a close parallel between the 
 ethical theories of Smith and Kant, and consitlers serious])- the 
 question as to how far Kant could either have borrowed from, or 
 been influenced by Smith. He rei^ards the similarit)' between 
 the two systems, which reaches, he claims, to a "coni]jlete iden- 
 tity of words," in the most important part of the work, as one of 
 the most remarkable phenomena in the history of the human 
 mind. ^ This complete similarit)- between the ethical s)stems of • 
 Smith and Kant seems to me purel)- imaginar)-. and it is, more- ,' 
 over, utterl)- impossible that such should exist. The one doc- {, 
 trine which, abo\e all others, Smith feels called upon to empha- 
 size is the place and importance of feeliiii^, of .s)mpath)-, in mor- 
 nlity. That upon which Kant insists, and upon which his system 
 depends, is that in moralit)- feeling has no place, and is of no 
 importance. Just as strongl)' does Smith oppose a purely ra- 
 tional, an ascetic, as a purel)' non-rational s)stem of moralit)-. 
 He insists that our first perceptions of right and wrong are not 
 
 I. '/Vi^'oj'?/, Pt. VII. Sec. III. Chap. 2. 
 2- /liid, I't. VII. Sec. II. Chiip. 2. 
 3. Die Ethik Smith's and Kant's, p. 96. 
 
64 
 
 MUIK : 
 
 the objects of reason, but of immediate sense anri feeling. ^ 
 Sympathy iincloubtedl)- remains the main doctrine of the 77iro>y. 
 
 This, Oncken denies 
 
 md 
 
 mamlams 
 
 that 
 
 s}mpa 
 
 thy 
 
 is o 
 
 f n 
 
 o 
 
 more importance to Smith's sjstem than it is to that of Kant, 
 l^ut so far is this from bein^' the case that, as we ha\e seen. Smith 
 holds that there can be no true moraUty without feeiin^f, while 
 Kant maintains that there can l)e none aith it. .Smith --ajs 
 that it depends npon the character of an affection whether it or 
 a sense of duty should be the source of an action ; and claims 
 that an act which proceeds from a sense of dut)', when the a^ent 
 sliould have been urL(ed to its performance by affection, is not, 
 in the highest sense, t^ood. ^ Kant, on the other haiul, holds 
 that onl)' if an act shall ha\e been |)erformed from a sheer 
 sense of dut\', and in opposition to inclination, is it truly ^ood. 
 Kants' system is thus purely rational, and ascetic, while .Smith 
 regards eciu.dly the rational and the sentient nature of man. 
 Hence, instead of a mar\ellous similarity or idenlit)' between 
 the ethical systems of these authors, there exists an insurmount- 
 able opposition. 
 
 The Tlicon\ then, is neither a purel)- rational, nor )et a 
 purely Moral Sense s)'stiMn of ethics. Both reason and sense are 
 indispensable to the ff)rmation of an\' moral jud|jfment, and each 
 
 of these is sui)reme in its own sphere. 
 
 Th 
 
 e ciuestion mnv arises 
 
 as to the relation of the two i;reat principles, of reason and of 
 sympathv', in the T/ituny. Can the one in any sense be said to 
 be more truly ultimate than the other. .Smith spi;aks of reason 
 as "the ^o\ernin^i,r principle of the whole,""* " I le great judge 
 and arbiter of conduct," '' and as of di\ ine e.xtraction. Sym- 
 pathy is an impulse, a feeling, and the life of impulse and of 
 passion is judgcHi and sentenced at the bar < 'reason. Hence 
 we shall have to conclude that Smith regards reason as supreme, 
 and sympath)' as occufning a subordinate positii^n. Vet it 
 must be noticed that the first perception of right and wrong can 
 never be deri^ ed from reason ; and second!)', that conscience, as 
 rea.son, is dependent upon s\inpath>- for the |)articular instances 
 or cases, out of wliich the general rules arc formed. 
 
 Smith's ethical theory is, as we have seen, only related to 
 
 i 
 
 1, 'J'hinri/, I't. v'li. .Slt. in. Chap. 2: 
 
 2. Dii' hthik StiiHIi's kihI KoiU'sp. I02. 
 2. Then)' J, I't. III. C"h.i|). 6. 
 
 4. /'//'/, I't. VII. ScH\ IP Chap. >. 
 
 5. Ihid, I't. II. Chap. 2. 
 
THi; KTHICAL SYSTKM OF ADAM SMITH. 
 
 6s 
 
 I 
 
 that of Kant by way of opposition. But, in a sense, we may 
 be said to have a hint of Kant's Critique of Pure Reason, in 
 Smith's conception of the relation between sense and reason. 
 Smith finds in the moral sphere that which Kant later discov- 
 ered in regard to the intellect, that while our knowledge is all 
 obtained from experience, it, nevertheless, is not all of exper- 
 ience. To Smith, as to Kant, conception without perception 
 is empty, and perception without conception is blind. Sym- 
 path)-, or the sympathetic sense, is as important and, at the 
 same time, as utterly powerless in itself, as is any bodily sense. / 
 Indispensable to the mind for the attainment of knowledge in 
 the field to which it is adapted, it is, nevertheless, nothing but 
 an instrument or means through which reason can work. The 
 general maxims of morality are formed, like all other general 
 maxims, from experience and induction, and induction i- .il- 
 ways regarded as one o'"the operations of reason. Perceptions 
 are aKva\'s the beginning and constitute the express conditions 
 of thouL^''t. We are not to remain b)' them, nevertheless, as 
 what is .iltimatc. The concrete 'Vorstellungen' are the prelim- 
 inar\- condition, but they must be purified into the abstract He- 
 griff: else we never attain to mastery over ourselves, but float 
 about a helpless prey to our own pictures. ^ As any bodily 
 sense is utterly dependent upon reason, so that it is not the eye 
 which sees, but reason which sees through the eye, as well as 
 reason alone which can make use of the varied perception thus 
 received, so also does reason work through sympathy, in ac- 
 (juiring moral perceptions and in using these so as to form a 
 moral judgment. Hut it is absurd and unintelligible to sup- 
 pose, that the first perception of right and wrong can be de- 
 rived from reason, even in those particular cases, upon the 
 experience, of which the general rules are formed. These 
 first perceptions are not the object of reason but of inmiediate 
 sense and feeling. Just as Kant found that neither reason 
 nor sense is, of itself, competent to form an object, but that 
 the work of both is necessary, so Smith argues that, in the mor- 
 al sphere, it is by s\'mpathy alone that the perceptions can be 
 collected, out of which reason forms the moral object, the moral 
 judgment. Smith thus recognizes the great fact, neglected b)' 
 Kant in his ethics, that man is by no means purely rational. 
 In any syateni of ethics which treats at all adequately the facts 
 
 I. Stcrlin},', Secret oj JIt(jel, Vol. r, [i. 44. 
 
66 
 
 MUIR : 
 
 of the moral life, reason must reign supreme ; and yet, without 
 the aid of sense, ^ reason is powerless. Hence, while Smith 
 makes reason tlie governing principle, he never forgets the im- 
 portance of sense, and maintains the necessity of both for 
 morality, as either without the other would be utterly useless. 
 Smith lias not at all over-emphasized the importance of 
 sympathy. •" The root of morals, the ultimate inducement to 
 moral conduct, is surely to be discovered in those original 
 impulses of our nature which urge us to seek the good of our- 
 selves and of others, and in those reflex feelings wiiich approve 
 or disapprove of actions, according as they are or are not 
 attended by those effects. Our emotions are, as it were, the 
 raw material of morality. At the same time it must, undoubt- 
 edly, be granted that they are often transformed by the action 
 of reason into what almost assumes the character of a new 
 product." ' The root idea of sympathy is the power of imitat- 
 ing the feelings of others, and this instinct of imitation is, as 
 Balfour expresses it, " the very basis of all effective education." 
 It is, indeed, the most important factor in, if not a synonj'm for, 
 that " consciousness of kind " which marks off the animate from 
 the inanimate and ofwhich all association and social organiza- 
 tion are consecjuences I - In endeavouring to find the origin of 
 moral distinctions, Smith, neglecting for the moment man's 
 rational nature, and seeking the fundamental sentient element in 
 moralit>-, rightly finds this in s)'mpathy. " Out of community 
 and out of societ}', man ne\er did nor ever can exist," and it is 
 these inevitable social relations which form the source of 
 morality. As an object would cease to be an object and would 
 become, in realit}', nothing, if removed out of all possible rela- 
 tion to anxthing but itself, so also would morality cease to be 
 if it were not for these indispensable social relations. Hence the 
 precognition of these relations, which is founded alone in sympa- 
 thy or in imitation of the feelings of others, is the fundamental 
 element of moralit)' when viewed from the stand-point of 
 sense or the emotional nature of man. But, while this is true, 
 there is in human nature that which is even more fundamentally 
 important than this s\'mpathy, this instinct of imitation, this 
 consciousness of kind. This deepest and most fundamental 
 principle is not that by which man recognizes, imitates, and 
 
 fl 
 
 
 t. Kiiwler. Sh'i^ftrshur;/ and /fntr.hfKon. \>. 215. 
 2. F. \l. CAdiVmiiii, Priwtplps of Sociologii. 
 
f 
 
 THK KTHICAL SYSTEM OF ADAM SMITH. 
 
 67 
 
 I 
 
 #1 
 
 enters into the feelings and passions of others, but is that which 
 alone differentiates man as man. namely reason. Tlius reason 
 is, as Smith holds, nothing individual, but is universal, and is 
 the supreme moral ruler. Hut reason is dependent upon 
 sympathy, as we have seen.- .for assistance in the formation of 
 its judgments and its rules. Fd:^ without sympathy, man would 
 
 be unable to enter into any 
 possible or where there cott 
 judgments of reason. 
 Morality arises 
 nature, and in so far 
 has endeavoured 
 reason and sense 
 advance upon 
 utilitarian writers 
 rational, and 
 
 where morality would be 
 necessity for the moral 
 
 of human 
 
 alism, and 
 
 ?ion of both 
 
 is system an 
 
 phers or the 
 
 upon the purely