J-'(,;Aii.^;ii ■.„,'>.ih< i.>.^-rr\ ■■',^ . /J, ,•,„■■; V,. ijj^ 
 
THE 
 
 elemen'ts 
 
 Intelleotcial Philosophy. 
 
 BY 
 
 REV. J. DE CONCILIO, 
 
 Author of ^'■Catholicity and Pantheism," '^'■Knowledge of Mary ^^ etc. 
 
 'How charming is divine philosophy! 
 Not harsh and crabbed, as dull fools suppose; 
 But musical as is Apollo's lute, 
 And a perpetual feast of iiectar'd sweets, 
 Where no crude surfeit reigns." 
 
 • —Milton's Comut, 
 
 New York: 
 
 D. & J. SADLIER & CO., 31 BARCLAY STREET. 
 
 Montreal : 275 Notre Dame Street. 
 
 ' 1878. 
 
Cop)'right, 
 D. & J. SADLIER & CO., 
 
 1878. 
 
 n. J. HKwnr, mhntek, 97 rosE street, new yosk. 
 
CONTENTS. 
 
 ■* 
 
 PAGE 
 
 Introduction to Philosophy 7 
 
 LOGIC. 
 Introduction 21 
 
 Part- First. 
 
 CHAPTER 
 
 I.— Matter of Reasoning, 25 
 
 II. — Cf the Different Objects which a Universnl Idea may 
 Represent, and of the Different Modes of Represent- 
 ing them, 44 
 
 III. — Of the Expression of Ideas or of Terms, ... 54 
 
 IV. — Proximate Matter of Reasoning ; and, first, of the Na- 
 ture of Judgment and Proposition, .... 59 
 
 V. — Different Species and Properties of Propositio iS, . . 65 
 
 VI. — Truth of Judgments and Propositions, .... 74 
 
 Part Second. — Form of Reasoning. 
 
 I. — of the Essential vStructure of Reasoning, ... 78 
 
 II. — Different Species of Reasoning, 95 
 
 III. — Of the Expression of Reasoning, 102 
 
 IV. — Faults of Reasoning, 104 
 
 Part Third. — End of Reasoning. 
 
 I. — Of the Nature and the Necessity of Method, . . . 107 
 
 II. — Elements and Means of Method, 113 
 
 III. — Division of Method — that is, of Method of Invention and 
 
 of Discipline 120 
 
 m 
 
 24535 
 
iv Contents, 
 
 • 
 
 CHAPTER PACE 
 
 IV. — Of Science according to its Strictest Acceptation, inas- 
 much as it is Knowledge, 125 
 
 V. — Of Science in its more Enlarged Signification, inasmuch 
 
 as it is a System of Truths, 131 
 
 ONTOLOGY. 
 
 Introduction— Object of Metaphysics— Definition of 
 Ontology, 141 
 
 I. — Of Being, considered in Itself and in a most General 
 
 Way, 143 
 
 II. — Of the Determinations of Being in General — Essence 
 
 and Existence, 152 
 
 III. — Of the Manner in which Essence and Existence co-ope- 
 rate to form a Real Being, 161 
 
 IV. — Of the Properties of Being, 164 
 
 v.— Of the Causes of Beings, 1S5 
 
 VI. — Division of Being, . . . , ., . . . 206 
 
 VII.— Of the Use of Ontology, 230 
 
 i ' ANTHROPOLOGY. 
 
 Introduction, 241 
 
 I. — On the Nature of Man in General, 242 
 
 II. — On the Principles from which the Nature of Man Re- 
 sults — Soul and Body — and, first, of the Soul, . . 252 
 
 III. — Of the Human Body 274 
 
 IV. — Of the Manner according to which the Soul and the 
 
 Body are united together and conspire to form Man, . 276 
 
 .-..A ' K , , . . , . , •• ' 
 
 
 
■,>v^ ^'V^ 
 
 PREFACE. 
 
 THE author who should attempt to write a book 
 on the elements of intellectual philosophy 
 should in our opinion strictly attend to, and be 
 guided by, the following principles, which have re- 
 ference to the language, to the style, and to the 
 matter of the book. 
 
 I. The book should be written in English. The 
 matter treated of in philosophy is hard enough to 
 understand, even by the brightest intellect which 
 ., just comes from the study of belles-lettres, fascinated 
 by the matchless beauties of the ancients clothed 
 in the finest language, to undertake to master hard, 
 dry things, without flesh and blood, but abstract 
 and immaterial. Now, to present such things in a 
 foreign language is to render the difficulty of appre- 
 hending them unnecessarily greater, and to heighten 
 the aversion which young minds naturally feel for 
 abstract ideas. It is like covering a beautiful paint- 
 ing with a double veil. For language, after all, is a 
 veil which covers the idea. Now, if you clothe an 
 idea in language foreign to the student, no matter 
 how well he may be supposed to know it, you oblige 
 him, in order to look at the idea, first to uncover 
 
j^ Preface, 
 
 the veil of the foreign language to make room for 
 the veil of his own native language, and then to 
 catch the idea. In other words, you oblige the 
 student first to translate into his own language, and 
 then to grasp the matter. In the second place, to 
 write a book on the elements of philosophy in the 
 Latin language is to confine the study of this most 
 necessary science only to those who have gone 
 through a classical course ; whereas we know by sad 
 experience how necessary and how important it is 
 for all our young men to be imbued with proper, 
 true philosophical principles, to the absence of which 
 we may attribute all the errors and evils which afflict 
 society. 
 
 With regard to the style, of course it must be of 
 a didactic nature — that is, brief and concise, but 
 above all perfectly clear. Nor would we be averse 
 now and then, when the occasion presents itself, 
 from changing the nature of the style for one a 
 little more pleasing and attractive, so as to lighten 
 the difficulty and mix the useful with the sweet. 
 
 Finally, with regard to the matter, a book of 
 elementary philosophy should contain nothing but 
 the_doctrijifi.,j;eceiveiLJijr_th^^ and_greatest oJL 
 
 Christian schools, the^ (^iM:t|;ine most receiveTTn the 
 Churcli^Jhat_iipon^ which the^Holy See h^s_always 
 lookedjipon with marked and never-ceasingpartial- 
 ity. 
 
 These are the principles which have guided us in 
 writing these Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 I 
 
Preface, ^ 
 
 As to the language, not only have we written it in 
 English, but we have been most chary and particu- 
 lar in our choice. Whenever we had two words to 
 choose from, we always preferred that which was the 
 easiest of comprehension and of Anglo-Saxon origin. 
 We have thought proper to discard, whenever it was 
 possible, all words which may remind one too much * 
 
 of the schools, always translating into the best 
 English we could muster, anything of such a na- 
 ture ; so that in reading our Elements the young 
 student will meet with no hard word which may 
 require the use of the dictionary, or which may 
 stop him in his endeavor to catch the idea. 
 
 With regard to the style, it has been our constant 
 effort to make it as clear as possible, at the same time 
 that we have tried to be brief. There is hardly a 
 theory laid down which is not illustrated by one or 
 more examples. ArA we venture to assert that owing 
 to this lucidity of style onr Elemcttts could be studied, 
 and in great part understood, without a teacher by 
 any young man of parts. We have also, whenever 
 we possibly could, tried to illustrate our theories by 
 quotations from the poets, to loosen the tension of 
 the mind by something pleasing and interesting. At 
 the end of Ontology we have shown by an abstract of 
 all the natural sciences how they are an application of 
 the principles of Ontology. 
 
 With regard to the matter, we have followed Iff 
 throughout the philosophy of the "Angel of the * • • 
 Schools," in which we were brought up from our youth, 
 
4 Preface, 
 
 and from which we have never swerved in our man- 
 hood, experience and more profound studies having 
 led us to adhere to that philosophy more tenaciously 
 and more ardently. Every one knows that all modern 
 errors have originated in the abandonment of Catholic 
 philosophy as embodied in the Catholic schools, and 
 especially in that of St. Thomas. Consequently the 
 only way to put a barrier to these errors, to refute 
 them, is to turn back to that grand philosophy created 
 by geniuses as great as Plato or Aristotle, and guided 
 by the truth of God, which those heathen geniuses 
 had not. 
 
 Of course, these being only elements, we have used 
 a great moderation in the treating of all the questions 
 connected with this science ; yet it will be found 
 that nQ_ sij igleimportant question has been^mitted 
 of which it is necessary for the student to know 
 something. 
 
 Besides the usual parts, our Elements will close 
 with a book on the external and internal evidences of 
 Christianity as a complement of this science — that is 
 to say, we shall in an elementary way, and without 
 going too deeply into the matter, show the philoso- 
 phical force of the proofs of the divhiity of Chris- 
 tian revelation. 
 
 All this we have attempted to do. Tut have we 
 succeeded ? No effort on our part has been or will 
 be spared to make this book come nearer to these 
 principles we laid down for our guidance. As for 
 the rest, it is not for us to pronounce judgment, 
 
Preface, ft 
 
 but others, and especially for the learned professors of 
 this study scattered throughout the land, from whom 
 we shall thankfully receive any suggestion or correc- 
 tion which they shall see fit to make. 
 
 At present only Logic, Ontology, and the first part 
 of Anthropology are published. Next year, if God 
 gives us strength, we shall publish the rest. 
 
 Jersey City, Feast of SS. Peter and Paul, 
 
 « :■' ■-" ■:■■'- l;:^; \y^K .<1..,CS y-it'^<., ^ 
 
 -^■V:^^:-. ;:-!'.. ..^:X^v^. ..'^it S-t jl5.^A 
 
 ■5i. "A .:i/'y; ■•'i 
 
ELEMENTS OF 
 
 INTELLECTUAL PHILOSOPHY. 
 
 INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY. 
 
 ARTICLE I. 
 
 DEFINITION OF PHILOSOPHY. 
 
 Q. What is the meaning of the word philosophy? 
 
 A. It means love of wisdom, and a philosopher is 
 a lover of wisdom. This word was used for the first 
 t*me by Pythagoras, who, on being asked what art he 
 professed, answered that he was a philosopher. 
 
 Q. What did the ancients mean by the science 
 of philosophy ? 
 
 A. They meant the knowledge of everything. 
 This could well be in olden times, when, sciences 
 being in their infancy, all human knowledge could be 
 collected into one science. la this sense philosophy 
 was defined by Cicero the science of all huinaii and 
 divine things and of their causes. 
 
 Q. Does it embrace the same objects now? 
 
 A. Sciences being so much developed in our times, 
 it would be utterly impossible to comprehend them 
 all in one. Hence they have been divided, a particu- 
 lar object being set apart for each one ; therefore the 
 object of philosophy has been also narrowed down. 
 
 Q. Explain the object of philosophy. 
 
 A. The better to do so we will premise a few 
 remarks. 
 
 7 
 
8. Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 1st. Science consists in understanding the princi- 
 ples from which a thing is derived: Scire res per 
 causas — to know things by their causes. 
 
 2d. There are two kinds of knowledge, common 
 and scientific. The first is satisfied with merely know- 
 ing the existence of a thing ; the second goes beyond 
 that, and is not content with merely apprehending 
 the existence of a thing, but wants to find out why 
 the thing is so and not otherwise, and what is the 
 principle which causes it. 
 
 For instance, who had net seen, from the time of 
 the first man who made a lamp and suspended it to 
 the wall of his cottage or to the roof, that when first 
 hung in its place it oscillated for some time from 
 side to side until at length it came to a perpendicu- 
 lar? Men before Galileo perceived this fact, and 
 passed on without seeing anything more in it. This 
 is common knowledge. One day Galileo, observing 
 this very fact, and noticing by more accurate observa- 
 tions that the oscillations were regular, perceived 
 in this fact the principles of the law of gravitation 
 and motion, and invented the pendulum. This is 
 scientific knowledge. 
 
 3d. We remark that all the sciences, though dis- 
 tinct and different from each other according to their 
 different objects, are yet connected together by the 
 necessary fact of the dependence of one upon the 
 other. For particular sciences depend upon those 
 which are less so, and these in their turn upon those 
 which are more general. Chemistry, for instance, is the 
 science of the elements of bodies and of their proper- 
 ties, but it could not exist without another less par- 
 ticular science which must precede it, called physics. 
 This latter science, which treats of the phenomena of 
 bodies and their causes, could not exist without an- 
 
. Introduction to Philosophy. 9 
 
 other science more general which treats of the nature 
 and properties of bodies and of all the material world, 
 together with their causes, and which is called cos- 
 mology. But the world is a being, an existence, and 
 therefore it could not be properly understood without 
 the science of being in general^ its properties and causes, 
 which is called ontology. We conclude, therefore, 
 that, as every particular science depends upon another 
 science less particular and more general, there must be 
 a science which investigates the most c )mmon princi- 
 ples of being, and which depends on no other, but on 
 which all others depend. This science is philosophy. 
 The objects, therefore, of philosophy are the most 
 common principles of being. 
 
 Q. What do you mean by the most common prin- 
 ciples of being ? 
 
 A. As St. Thomas has remarked, the most common 
 principles of being are the first and supreme principles, 
 beyond which there can be no other. Thus the last 
 end, being common to all beings, is also the first and 
 supreme end ; the most common cause, being that 
 from which all things are originated, is the first cause, 
 upon which every other cause depends; the idea of 
 being, as it is the most common idea and the simplest, 
 is also the first idea, on which all others depend and 
 from which all others originate. Therefore by the 
 most common principles arc meant the first and su- 
 preme principles, from which everything proceeds and 
 draws its existence. And because principles of this 
 kind are not the property of this or that particular 
 being, but of all beings in general, it follows that the 
 objects of philosophy are the supreme principles of 
 everything, and not of this or that particular thing. 
 
 Q. Give the definition of philosophy according to 
 the preceding remarks. 
 
lO Ele^nents of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 A. Philosophy is tJiat' science which ifwestigates the 
 first and supreme principles of being. 
 
 It is called science because it investigates principles 
 and cause, and therefore is a knowledge of an object 
 by its causes. 
 
 0/ the first and supreme principles, because the 
 other sciences investigate this or that principle and 
 cause ; philosophy only investigates the supreme and 
 highest principles. 
 
 Of being, because philosophy does not take as its 
 object any particular thing, but whatever comes 
 under the denomination of being. 
 
 ARTICLE II. 
 
 DIVISION OF PHILOSOPHY. 
 
 Q. How is philosophy divided ? 
 
 A. The objects of philosophy are the supreme prin- 
 ciples of being. Therefore the parts of this science 
 must be as many as there are natural divisions or 
 parts of being. Now, being may be divided into 
 three parts, rational, realy and moral. The rational 
 is that which exists only in the mind as its own 
 work. The real is that which has true existence 
 outside and independent of us. The moral is that 
 which originates in the will of man in its relation with 
 moral law. The rational is called logic, and has for 
 its object the order which our mind puts in its ideas. 
 The moral is the science of ethics, and treats of the 
 free actions of men as directed and guided by moral 
 law. The real is called metaphysics, and is subdi- 
 vided into three parts, because, as St. Thomas ob- 
 serves, real being may be classified under four heads. 
 It may be either material or separated from matter. 
 If separated from matter, this may proceed from 
 
Introduction to Philosophy. ;- la 
 
 two causes. It may be separated from matter, not 
 because it is so in reality, but because our mind, 
 in considering a material object, may choose to leave 
 aside the material part of it, and fix its attention only 
 on the interior nature of the thing, which operation 
 of the mind, as we shall see, is called abstraction, and 
 the thing thus obtained an abstract ; or it may be 
 separated from matter because it is so in reality, as 
 spiritual substances, of which there are two, God and 
 the human soul. The objects of metaphysics are, 
 therefore, the material being, the abstract being, the 
 soul, and God. Hence there are four parts of philo- 
 sophy — cosmology, which treats of the material world ; 
 ontology, which speaks of being in common and in the 
 abstract ; anthropology, which treats of man, and of the 
 human soul especially ; and theology, which treats of 
 God as he can be known from reason. 
 
 . ARTICLE III. 
 
 USE OF PHILOSOPHY ; OR, ITS CONNECTION WITH 
 ALL THE SCIENCES AND ARTS. 
 
 Q. What is the use of philosophy ? 
 
 A. The use of philosophy cannot be fully pointed 
 out in this introduction, but will be seen at the end 
 of the course. Yet, to excite in the student an ardent 
 desire and love for such a study, we shall briefly point 
 out its use and its connection with all the sciences 
 and arts by developing the following argument. All 
 the sciences and arts depend upon philosophy as to 
 their certainty, as to their principles, and as to their 
 method. Therefore all the sciences and arts depend 
 upon philosophy and are impossible without it. And, 
 first, as to their certainty. Philosophy has for itg 
 object the supreme principles of everything. CoQ- 
 
12 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 sequently its objects are also those supreme principles 
 of certainty and evidence, those criteria of truth, 
 supported by which our mind clings to tiuth without 
 hesitation or fear of the contrary, and with perfect 
 assurance and satisfaction. In this sense philosophy 
 has a character of universality which subjects to it all 
 the sciences and arts. For instance, physical sciences 
 have for their object everything which comes within 
 the observation of the senses. But is what falls 
 under the observation of the senses a true and ex- 
 terior reality, or merely a sensation and a modifica- 
 tion of our soul ? If what falls under our senses is 
 not an objective reality, but merely an internal modi- 
 fication ; if our souls perceive no more than the im- 
 age of objects, as some of the ancient philosophers 
 thought ; if odors, colors, figures, and forms are not 
 qualities of real bodies ; if these bodies and these 
 qualities are not the determining causes of taste, of 
 smell, of sight, etc., is it not evident that the base 
 of all physical sciences crumbles down, and that all 
 those sciences play about mere fictions of our mind, 
 sheer and useless idealities ? The natural philosopher 
 studies the body. But what is a body? Is it an 
 illusion, a sheer appearance, as was pretended by the 
 Indian pantheists, and as was held by Berkeley only a 
 century ago ? And is it not clear that upon the solu- 
 tion of all these questions depends the certainty of 
 all physical sciences ? Again, the natural philosophers 
 seek for the causes of all the operations of bodies. 
 For, by examining a sufficient number of operations 
 and constant facts, they endeavor to explain the 
 causes of such operations and assign laws by which 
 the material world is directed. Now, if, as Hume pre- 
 tends, the idea of cause is a chimera, the certainty of all 
 physical sciences is shaken, and we must consider as 
 
Introduction to Philosophy. 13 
 
 dreams and visions all those pretended laws of the 
 universe of which natural sciences endeavor to demon- 
 strate the reality, generality, and permanence. Then 
 all the relations of causality become simple relations 
 of succession and time, all the operations of nature 
 become isolated ; we have no longer any co-ordination 
 or union among beings, and that magnificent and ad- 
 mirable connection which binds the facts of the sensi- 
 ble world to each other and to their universal princi- 
 ple vanishes from our eyes to make room for a com- 
 plete chaos. In the second place, all the sciences and 
 arts depend upon philosophy for their principles, 
 because the objects of philosophy are the supreme 
 principles of everything. Thus physical sciences are 
 founded upon the idea of being, of substance, of 
 matter, of quality ; upon the ideas of cause and effect. 
 Without these ideas they could not proceed one step 
 in these investigations. But what is being ? What is 
 substance ? What is matter, and what distinguishes 
 it from spirit ? All these ideas must be given by 
 philosophy. 
 
 Mathematical sciences depend upon it. Arithmetic 
 is founded upon the idea of number, and consequently 
 upon the ideas of unity and distinction; algebra upon 
 the idea of signs representing known and unknown 
 quantities; geometry upon the ideas of form and 
 size, and consequently upon the idea of extension 
 and space ; mechanics upon the ideas of force, of move- 
 ment, and of weight. Consequently, all mathematical 
 sciences depend upon philosophy for their principles. 
 
 Moral sciences depend upon it, because they depend 
 upon the ideas of the good and the just. Now, to deter- 
 mine what is really good and just depends absolutely 
 upon a true and correct system of philosophy. For 
 if we hold, with the sensists, that man is but an ag- 
 
14 Elements of IntelUobual Philosophy. 
 
 gregate of sensations, we shall have the consequence 
 that that only is good which is agreeable or which is 
 useful, and Jience the moral of pleasure and of in- 
 terest. 
 
 Political sciences, legislation, civil and social right, 
 the right of nations, social and domestic economy, 
 public and private education — in fact, all the sciences 
 which have more or less connection with the govern- 
 ment of nations, of the family, and of the individual, 
 borrow from philosophy their principles and their 
 rules : because none can govern a man, a family, or a 
 nation without having studied the human soul, its 
 laws and its destiny ; without knowing its nature, its 
 faculties, the motives which can influence the human 
 heart and the human will ; without knowing" the 
 objects which one must propose to it for its actions. 
 And are not all these things the essential province of 
 philosophy ? 
 
 Medical sciences are closely allied to psychological 
 and moral sciences. Our soul and body are united 
 with a bond too intimate to permit the physiologist 
 to Ignore the influence of the organism on the soul 
 and of the soul on the organism. The most perfect 
 knowledge of the organs, and of the physical causes 
 which derange them, would be incomplete and almost 
 useless, if he who practises the art of healing, directing 
 his attention exclusively to physical causes, were to 
 disregard moral causes ; if a deep knowledge of the 
 passions, of habits, of their influence, could not enable 
 him to combat the derangement of the organism by 
 re-establishing order and tranquillity in the thoughts 
 and mental functions of the patient ; because man is 
 not merely passive, and none can determine how far 
 the free development of his activity may modify the 
 power which he has of imagining and of feeling, and 
 
Introduction to Philosophy. 15 
 
 in a certain way change all his different modes of 
 existence. 
 
 But does philosophy rule over the aesthet'cal sci- 
 ences, over literature as forms of our thought.-,, over 
 arts? Certainly, because it furnishes the idea of the 
 beautiful, as well as of truth and goodness. All 
 ideas depend on it, and by the very fact that it 
 seeks truth in all things it is its office to determine 
 what is really beautiful. And, first of all, is not truth 
 eminently beautiful? What strikes the intellect more 
 than the splendor of evidence, than the light of com- 
 plete knowledge which illumines objects? What 
 more pleasant and more keenly delightful than that 
 which arises from the contemplation and possession 
 of truth? 
 
 Order also has a secret charm for us which entices 
 us and causes us to reproduce it in all our works. But 
 what is order? Order in th > disposition of objects, 
 order in the distribution of colors, in the reproduction 
 of sounds and forms, is regularity, fitness, and harmo- 
 ny; order in the imagination is the conformity of our 
 fancy images with the realities of nature ; order in our 
 thoughts is their logical concatenation ; order in our 
 actions is the accomplishment of our duty, the con- 
 formity of the same actions with moral law ; order 
 in society is subordination, in the family obedience 
 and love, in the individual is the subjection of his 
 passions to his will, and of the latter to God ; order 
 in the exercise of authority is the general good, in the 
 exercise of the intellect is truth, in the object of our 
 love is perfection. Now, all this is assuredly beautiful 
 and is taught by philosophy ; and this science does 
 not leave it to the individual caprice to determine the 
 notion of the beautiful, but from the constant expe- 
 rience of all that which mankind calls beautiful in 
 
1 6 Elements of Intellectua I Ph ilosophy. 
 
 nature and art, in man and in society, rises to the 
 essential and universal idea of the beautiful and de- 
 termines its laws. If the idea of the beautiful were 
 something changeable, individual, and relative ; if its 
 essence could be modified according to the difference 
 of sensations, of tastes and temperaments, then all 
 arts would be at an end, because there can be no art 
 where science has not discovered fixed principles and 
 laws. All esthetic sciences, therefore, depend upon 
 philosophy. 
 
 All industrial sciences depend upon it for its prin- 
 ciples, because all these sciences have for their object 
 that which is useful, and that which is useful is inse- 
 parable f^om the true, the good, and the beautiful. 
 Run over all the arts which are destined to provide 
 for the wants of men, to increase the sum of their en- 
 joyments, and you will not find one which can be con- 
 sidered truly useful if it is in opposition with the im- 
 mutable ideas of the true, the just, and the beautiful. 
 Let human industry create and multiply wants unna- 
 tural and fictitious, contrary to man's true nature, and 
 it will be highly injurious to man ; let human in- 
 dustry create and multiply wants contrary to his intel- 
 ligence, to his morality, to the physical laws of his 
 body, and their usefulness disappears, and they be- 
 come dangerous, and sap the very foundation of 
 man's happiness. 
 
 History depends upon philosophy ; for devoid of it, 
 it would be a catalogue of facts and events without any 
 connection, without cause, without any warrant of 
 authenticity, if it confined itself to gather up indiffer- 
 ently whatever is transmitted to it by the memory, too 
 frequently fallacious, of men and peoples. But history 
 becomes science when one seeks the laws and the moral 
 causes of events, when a sound criticism discusses 
 
•^ Introduction to Philosophy. 1 7 
 
 with seventy the proofs and motives of credibility — 
 in one word, when one studies to reconcile in all the 
 annals of nations human liberty with the providen- 
 tial action of God, and thus creates a philosophy of 
 history. 
 
 Finally, all the sciences depend upon philosophy 
 for their method. Man, in all his investigations, must 
 use certain rules to discover truth, to prove it when 
 found, to illustrate, to defend it from the attacks of 
 its enemies, to explain it to others. All this is called 
 by the general name of method. And where shall we 
 find the proper rules to discover truth, to prove it, to 
 defend it, and to explain it toothers, if not in philoso- 
 phy — in that part which teaches the laws for directing 
 and guiding human thought in its researches? And, 
 last of all, our faith, without which we cannot attain 
 our eternal destiny, depends in a certain sense upon 
 philosophy, ist. Philosophy must enable us to find 
 out the true Church, by examining the motives of cre- 
 dibility upon which it rests and recommends itself to 
 our minds, and by proving the necessity of an infal- 
 lible guide for the solution of problems which it 
 cannot solve, and which it is absolutely important for 
 it to know. When this infallible guide is found and 
 accepted, it io true that philosophy must bow then 
 in silent submission to the dogmas which the Church 
 proposes as the object of its acceptance as solution 
 of philosophy's own problems, and of others far 
 greater, because the Church teaches the philosophy of 
 God, who, being infinite, has truths to tell far above the 
 ken of human philosophy ; but even after accepting 
 this philosophy of the infinite, this supreme science of 
 man is eminently useful in putting these supernatural 
 and superintelligible truths in scientific order, in illus- 
 trating them by means of created images and simili- 
 tudes which may bear a faint impression of those 
 
1 8 Elements of Intellectual Ph ilosophy. 
 
 truths, and which may serve to recommend their ac- 
 ceptance to man, and in defending them from the at- 
 tacks of their enemies. 
 
 These are in a few words the use of philosophy, so 
 neglected and despised by the ignorant crowd. We 
 will conclude these remarks with the words of the poet : 
 
 "With thee, serene Philosophy, with thee 
 And thy bright garland let me crown my song, 
 Effusive source of evidence and truth ! 
 A lustre shedding ovt-r the ennobled mind. 
 Stronger than summer noon, and pure as that 
 Whose mild vibrations soothe the parted soul 
 New to the dawn of celestial day. 
 
 Hence through her nourished powers, enlarged by thee, 
 She springs aloft with elevated pride 
 Above the tangling mass of low desires 
 That bind the fluttering crowd, and, angel-winged, 
 The height of science and of virtue gains. 
 Without thee what were unenlightened man ? 
 A savage running through the woods and wilds 
 In quest of prey, and with the unfashioned fur 
 Rough clad ; devoid of every finer art 
 And elegance of life. Nor happiness 
 Domestic mixed of tenderness and care, 
 Nor moral excellence, nor social bliss. 
 Nor guardian law were his ; nor various skill 
 To turn the furrow or to guide the tool 
 Mechanic ; nor the heaven-conducted prow 
 Of navigation bold that fearless braves ' , ' 
 
 The burning line or dares the wintery pole, > 
 
 Mother severe of infinite delights ! 
 Nothing save rapine, indolence, and guile, 
 And woes on woes, a still revolving train, 
 Whose horrid circle had made human life - v 
 
 Than non-existence worse ; but, taught by thee. 
 Ours are the plans of policy and peace •, ^ 
 
 To live like brothers, and conjunctive all 
 
 , Embellish life. While thus laborious crowds "^ "*• 
 
 Ply the tough car. Philosophy directs "^'^ 
 
 The ruling helm ; or, like the liberal breath ' 
 
 ^ ' Of potent heaven, invisible, the sail 
 
 ' Swells out and bears th' inferior world along." 
 
 — Thomson, Summef. 
 
LOGIC 
 
 '• He that is of reason's skill bereft, 
 
 And wants the staff of wisdom him to stay, 
 Is like a ship in the midst of temi)est left, 
 Without an helm or pilot her to sway." 
 
 — Spenssr. 
 
 it , ■■. U. 
 
i^: >. 
 
LOGIC. 
 
 JNTROD UCTION, 
 
 Q. Give a general idea of logic. 
 
 A. Logic may be generally understood as meaning 
 the right use of those faculties which are destined to 
 acquire knowledge. 
 
 Q. How many kinds of logic are there? 
 
 A. Two, natural and scientific. The first is that 
 disposition of our mind by which we are enabled to 
 use rightly the faculties destined to acquire know- 
 ledge. Every one knows by experience that men 
 without education acquire ideas of many things, pass 
 their judgment upon them, deduce one idea from 
 others, and this they do more or less happily in pro- 
 portion to the talent which nature has given them. 
 This natural aptitude or facility to use rightly the fac- 
 ulties destined to acquire knowledge is called natural 
 logic. But as natural aptitudes are mostly imperfect, 
 and must go through a certain training and discipline 
 to become perfect, so it is with the natural faculty of 
 reasoning. It must be regulated and trained to dis- 
 charge its office properly and perfectly. And as rea- 
 son, reflecting upon the operations of other faculties, 
 has invented so many arts, so, reflecting upon its own 
 acts, it has given origin to a science which directs and 
 brings to perfection the natural ability for reasoning. 
 This science is called artificial or scientific logic, and 
 in this limited sense may be defined : that science or 
 part of philosophy which treats of reasoning in order 
 to direct the mind in the acquisition of truth. 
 
 Q. Explain the definition. *?jt>' 
 
22 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 A. It is called science because logic is neither art, 
 rfor science and art together, but simply a science, since 
 a science is a knowledge of a thing deduced from its 
 principles. Now, logic treats of reasoning not merely 
 by inventing rules to form it, but by considering it in 
 the principles which originate it. Therefore logic is a 
 science and not an art. 
 
 Q. What is the exact difference between science 
 and art ? 
 
 A. Art is that which gives certain rules hoiv to do a 
 thing. For instance, the art of building is that which 
 gives rules how to build ; grammar is the art which 
 gives rules how to write and speak correctly ; rhetoric 
 the art which gives rules how to convince and to per- 
 suade. Science, on the contrary, is a knowledge of a 
 certain object drawn from the cause anc' principles of 
 the object. From this distinction it is clear that sci- 
 ence also may give rules how to do a thing, but it 
 draws them from the principles constituting the thing, 
 whereas art only gives rules and knows nothing of the 
 principles from which they are derived. A carpenter 
 applying his level carries out a rule of his art to see 
 if a piece of wood is perfectly level, but he knows 
 not from what principles that rule is derived. He 
 has art, but not science ; if he knew the principle 
 of that rule, then he would have science. 
 
 Q. Continue the explanation. 
 
 A. We have said that logic treats of reasoning in 
 order to state its peculiar object. For if logic be a 
 science, it must have an object to treat aboi^t. Now, 
 this object cannot be words, as some of the ancients 
 thought ; nor can it be the acts of the mind, inasmuch 
 as they really exist, because real things are the object 
 of metaphysics ; therefore the object of logic is that 
 order which our reason puts in its conceptions to 
 form reasoning. Finally, we have said ; In order to 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy, 23 
 
 direct the mind in the acquisition of truth, to deter- 
 mine tlie true nature oi logic ; because the true na- 
 ture of logic is not to give directions how to act ex- 
 ternally, as moral sciences, but how to speculate^ how 
 to enquire after truth. 
 
 Q. How is logic divided ? 
 
 A. Philosophers have distinguished three things in 
 reasoning: the materials of reason, called the matter ; 
 the combination and construction of those materials, 
 called \.\\t form ; and the purpose or object for which 
 we reason, called the end. Take, for instance, this 
 rearoning : 
 
 That which is spiritual is immortal. 
 
 But the soul is spiritual. 
 
 Therefore it is immortal. 
 
 In this reasoning the propositions and ideas are what 
 philosophers call the matter; the order and the locat- 
 ing of the propositions is called the form ; the result 
 of the reasoning is called the end. Now, in viev of 
 these three elements, we shall divide logic into three 
 parts. The first will treat of the matter of reasoning ; 
 the second of the form, and the third of the end, oi" 
 reasoning. This division is both clear and accurate, 
 because, to have a scientific knowledge of a thing, one 
 must know its principles and causes. Now, there are 
 four different causes for everything — the material, the 
 formal, the efficient, and the final. Take, for example, 
 a building. What is its material cause ? Bricks, mor- 
 tar, lumber, etc. What is its formal cause ? The de- 
 sign in the mind of the architect, and which, carried 
 out, gives it shape and form. The efficient causes are 
 the architect and all those who construct it. The 
 final cause is the object for which the building is 
 wanted — for instance, to live in it in comfort and 
 elegance. Say the same of reasoning. The efficient 
 
24 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 cause of reasoning is our intellect, of which we shall 
 speak in anthropology, or the science of man and his 
 faculties. The material cause of reasoning are ideas 
 and propositions ; the formal cause is the order and 
 location of the propositions; the final cause is the 
 science which we intend to acquire and which results 
 from our reasoning. 
 
 
PART FIRST. 
 
 CHAPTER I. 
 
 MATTER OF REASONING. 
 
 Q. How many kinds of matter has reasoning? 
 
 A. Two kinds ; one is called remote, the other 
 proximate or near. The remote matter are ideas or 
 terms, the proximate are judgments and propositions; 
 because, strictly speaking, reasoning results from judg- 
 ,ments and propositions, and these, in their turn, from 
 terms and ideas. We shall speak first of ideas, and 
 then of judgments. 
 
 Q. Of what ideas shall we treat in logic ? 
 
 A. It has been remarked by eminent philosophers 
 that in logic we consider ideas, not inasmuch as they 
 are ideas of. this or of that particular object, bi'*^ in- 
 asmuch as they can be the object of all sciences. 
 Now, no other idea can represent the object of all 
 sciences except a universal idea. Therefore, in logic 
 we treat of universal ideas. For instance, if in logic 
 we gave the idea of a body as an extended substance, 
 then this idea of body could not be applied to all the 
 sciences treating of bodies, but only to geometry, 
 which is founded on extension. We must, therefore, 
 in logic treat of ideas in such a way as to render them 
 applicable to all sciences ; and this can be said only 
 of universal ideas. 
 
 We shall divide this chapter into three articles. 
 The first will treat of universal ideas considered in 
 themselves ; the second will treat of that thing which 
 
 as 
 
26 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. : 
 
 universal ideas represent ; the third will treat of the 
 expression of ideas — that is, terms or words. 
 
 ARTICLE FIRST. 
 
 0/ Universal Ideas considered in themselves ; and, first, 
 
 of Idea in general. 
 
 Q. What remarks rnust be made in order to under- 
 stand what an idea /^ in general? 
 
 A. Reflecting upon the fact of our knowledge, we 
 find that we cannot know any object, of whatever 
 nature it may be, unless the object enters in some 
 way or other into our minds, and thus presents itself 
 before it ; because, on the one hand, we know from 
 experience that the operation of knowing takes place 
 within us, and for that reason is called an immanent 
 act, to distinguish it from those acts which are called 
 transient, or passing, because they are accomplished 
 outside of us. On the other hand, we cannot deny 
 that, in order to effect an operation, the subject and 
 the object must come in a certain kind of contact wit! 
 each other. Therefore, if the act of knowing is accom 
 plished within us, and if to do that the intellect mu^ 
 come in contact with the object it wants to know, it \ 
 absolutely necessary that the object should enter ii 
 some manner or other into our minds. But how cai 
 this be done? It is certainly impossible that object 
 could enter as they are in nature into our intellect. 
 for this would be absurd, and we might say with thi! 
 poet: «' , • ^:* ,.;_,- .>,;,. 
 
 " Then what vast body must v/e make the mind, '*< 
 
 ..J Wherein are men, beasts, trees, towns, seas, and lands,, ~ 
 ., And yet each thing a proper place doth find, 
 
 And each thing in the true proportion stands."* 
 
 ■ * Davies' Poems, * ', /' 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 27 
 
 How, then, can the act of knowing be accomplished? 
 Thus : As objects, to be known, cannot enter into our 
 mind as they exist in nature, they must enter therein 
 by means of their image and similitude. This image, 
 as it may be called, or similitude, or impression, of 
 the objects which enter into our minds is called idea.'^ 
 An idea, therefore, taken in this sense, may be defined, 
 the image of the nature of things existing in our intel- 
 lect, by means of which lue apprehend them. 
 
 Q. What consequences can you draw from said 
 definition? 
 
 A. The following: i. An idea is neither exclusively 
 objective — that is, the object itself— nor exclusively 
 subjective, mere work of the mind, but something 
 between the two. It is objective inasmuch as it repre- 
 sents the nature of things ; it is subjective inasmuch 
 as it is an image dwelling in the subject or intellect, 
 and is the principle and cause of its knowledge. 
 
 2. That, though the image o idea represents ob- 
 jects to the intellect, yet it is not the image that the 
 intellect apprehends. The idea is only a means by 
 which objects enter in communication with the intel- 
 lect and present themselves before it to be known. 
 Suppose I want to know my own face, what do I do ? 
 I go before a mirror, and an image of my face is in- 
 stantly reproduced in the glass. But is it an image of 
 my face which I know, or my own face by means of 
 that image ? Surely my own face through that image. 
 Or suppose I want to see an object at a distance from 
 me which my ordinary power of vision cannot reach, 
 what do I do? I use a telescope, which puts me in 
 contact with the object I want to see. But is it the 
 telescope I see, or the object ? The object, certainly ; 
 
 ♦ St. Thomas, P.P. qu. 12, art. 2 ; qu. 79, art. 3. 
 
2 8 Elements of Intellectual Pk ilosophy. 
 
 the telescope is only a means to put me in communi- 
 cation with the object. Likewise, the intellect cannot 
 know any object except it comes in contact with it. 
 But it cannot come in contact with it as it is in nature, 
 substance and modification together. Therefore it 
 comes in contact with it by its similitude.* But, this 
 done, is it the idea I perceive or the object ? Evi- 
 dently the object, as the idea is only a means of con- 
 tact. 
 
 3. The idea, strictly speaking, resides in the intel- 
 lect, and does not represent anything else except the 
 nature of the object, and, in this sense, it differs from 
 the sensible image, which, as we shall see, is also 
 necessary to render sensible knowledge possible ; be- 
 cause a sensible image is also necessary for sensitive 
 knowledge, and is both objective and subjective. 
 When I see a geranium or a rosebush, the image of 
 those objects must enter into my eyes, else I could 
 not see them. When I touch a hard body, such as 
 stone or iron, an impression of those bodies or an 
 image must enter the sense of touch, or I would never 
 feel them. But a sensible image differs from the idea 
 in this ; that the former resides in the senses and re- 
 presents the exterior qualities of bodies, whereas the 
 latter is in the intellect and represents the nature of 
 objects. Hence we have defined it an image of the 
 nature of an object residing in the intellect. ' * r v 
 . 4. Finally, the idea being a means and principle of 
 knowledge, it is followed by an act of the mind called 
 apprehension. This may be defined that operation 
 of the mind by which it knows an object without 
 affirming or denying anything about it. I hear the 
 words *• soul," " body," " world " mentioned ; the act 
 
 * How this similitude is effected will be seen in anthropology. 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 29 
 
 of the mind by which I know these objects is callec' 
 apprehension. We liave added, without affirming or 
 denying anything about it, to distinguish apprehen- 
 sion from judgments, which always affirm or deny a 
 predicate of a subject. 
 
 Q. How many kinds of ideas are there? 
 
 A. Ideas are intellectual images. Now, images can 
 differ from each other for two reasons: either because 
 the objects they represent are different, or because 
 they have a different way of representing them. The 
 picture of a flower-garden and that of a shipwreck are 
 two different images, because each represents a differ- 
 ent object ; as likewise the representation of a storm 
 in verses and another in music are also two different 
 images, because, though they represent the same 
 object, they exhibit it in different ways. The differ- 
 ence of ideas, therefore, may originate from the differ- 
 ence of the objects which they represent, or from the 
 different way of representing objects. 
 
 ARTICLE SECOND. 
 
 Difference of Ideas according to the Difference of Objects, 
 
 Q. How many kinds of ideas are there according to 
 this difference ? 
 
 A. There are, first, concrete and abstract ideas. Be- 
 fore defining them we must remark that whatever 
 exists in nature either exists in itself, not requiring 
 anything to lean upon, to cling to, in order to exist, or 
 it must lean on something to exist. When a thing 
 does not require any other object to lean on in order 
 to exist, but is self-supporting, it is called substance ; 
 when it requires sohiething to hang on in order to ex- 
 ist, it is called accident^ modification^ or quality. The 
 
30 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy, 
 
 tendrils of the vine winding around the oak for sup- 
 port may be an image of the accident, whereas the 
 stronor and robust oak which defies wind and storms 
 may be taken as an image of the substance, but 
 only as an image, because, after all, in nature both 
 the vine and the oak are substances. Here is a better 
 example : a table is a substance because it exists in 
 itself; the roundness or the squareness of the table are 
 an accident, because neither could exist without the 
 table. 
 
 We must remark, in the second place, that all ob- 
 jects in nature are substances accompanied by their 
 accidents or modifications. But it is clear that our 
 mind, which is endowed with the faculty of analysis or of 
 dividing, can separate one from the other and consider 
 them apart. In the example just given the mind may 
 consider the substance of the table independently of 
 its form or shape ; or it may lay aside the substance 
 of the table and fix its attention upon the size and the 
 shape The apprehension by the mind of an object just 
 as it is III nature^ substance and modijication together, is 
 called a concrete idea. The appreheiision by the mind of 
 a substance without its modifications, or of modifications 
 without their substance, is called an abstract idea. 
 
 Again, ideas according to this difference may be sim- 
 ple or composite: they are simple when they repre- 
 sent an object not composed of parts, as God, soul ; 
 they are composite when they represent an object com- 
 posed of parts, as the idea of a building, a steam- 
 engine. Absolute and relative : they are absolute when 
 the object represented by the idea does not involve 
 any relation with any other, as exist e7ice ; they are 
 relative when it does involve it, 2js> father, son, effect. 
 Positive diad negative : the first is such when the idea 
 represents the reality of a thing, as fruitful, perfect ; 
 
Elements of Intellccttial Philosophy. 31 
 
 the second is such when it represents that which a 
 being is wanting in, as barren, imperfect. 
 
 Finally, it may be collective, singular, particular, and 
 universal. An idea is called collective when it repre- 
 sents the union of various individuals, as an army, a 
 congregation, a people. It is singular when it repre- 
 sents an individual, such as Napoleon, Washington, 
 Irving. It is called particular when it represents an 
 object less extensive in relation to another, as the idea 
 of man is a particular idea in relation to thot of ani- 
 mal. We shall speak of universal ideas in the next 
 article. 
 
 Q. How many kinds of ideas are there in respect to 
 the manner in which they represent objects? 
 
 A. It is an ordinary fact that sometimes our mind 
 perceives objects in such a way that it can easily dis- 
 tinguish them from all others ; and oftentimes it per- 
 ceives them in such a way that it cannot distinguish 
 them from others. For instance, if I should see the 
 hemlock, the pine, the oak-tree, I could easily distin- 
 guish them from all other trees, my acquaintance with 
 those trees being very accurate. But if an exotic plant 
 were put before me I could not distinguish it from 
 others. When we perceive an object in such a way as 
 to be able to distinguish it from all others, then our 
 idea of the object is called clear ; otherwise, obscure. 
 But if we have such an idea of the object as to be able 
 not only to distinguish it from others but to distin- 
 guish its particular properties from the particular pro- 
 perties of other objects, then our idea of the object 
 is called distinct; otherwise, indistinct. But if we 
 should have such an idea of the object as to be able 
 not only to distinguish it from others in itself and in 
 its properties, but could tell the peculiar nature and 
 characteristics of the properties of that object from 
 
3 2 Elements of Intellectual Ph ilosophy. 
 
 the peculiar nature and characteristics of tiie proper- 
 ties of other objects, then our idea of it is called ade- 
 quate^ and its opposite inadequate. To give an in- 
 stance of both distinct and adequate ideas, we will 
 take a plant with which we are so well acquainted 
 that we can tell the particular size, shape, and color of 
 its trunk, its bark, its foliage, its flowers, and its fruits. 
 This certainly would be having a distinct idea of that 
 plant. But a botanist could go further, and be able 
 to tell not only the particular nature and properties of 
 that plant, but the particular nature and properties of 
 each part of the plant. He would have an adequate 
 idea of the plant. 
 
 ARTICLE SECOND. 
 On Universal Ideas. 
 
 Q. What is the meaning of a universal idea ? 
 
 A. If an i'^ea be an image, a universal idea must 
 mean nvc .al image. The word universal is derived 
 fror tne L" .n Avords unuin versus a/ia, and signifies a 
 thing .. ^iicli refers to many ; so that, in order to call a 
 thing universal, t'lese two elements are required, o?te 
 and many. Hence a universal image means an image 
 representing a thing common to many. Now, the ques- 
 tion arises — Is it possible that an idea can represent 
 something common to many? This question, upon 
 which all philosophy rests, has been discussed at 
 all times, and more especially from the eleventh cen- 
 tury to the fourteenth, and has been answered dif- 
 ferently, but the principal opinions may be reduced to 
 four. 
 
 Q. State distinctly the state of the question and 
 give the opinions of the various systems. 
 
 A. As an idea is an image, we repeat, a universal idea 
 

 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 33 
 
 must be a universal image. Now, an image represents 
 a reality, as it must be the image of something. There- 
 tote a universal image must represent a universal reality, 
 or some real thing common to many. This is agreed 
 upon by all philosophers. But the question comes 
 up. Is there in nature such a thing as a universal object 
 which a universal idea may represent ? According to 
 the different answers which philosophers have given 
 to this question have arisen different opinions with re- 
 gard to the nature of universal ideas. The first opin- 
 ion, held by philosophers called Nominalists, holds that 
 in 'lature there is no such thing as a universal object 
 common to many, and that consequently what we call 
 universal ideas are mere words or names, or at most 
 certain conceptions of our mind representing a number 
 of individual things. In the first sense this opinion 
 was held by the Epicureans, and in the eleventh cen- 
 tury probably by Roscellinus. In the second sense it 
 was taught by Occam in the middle ages, and was held 
 in modern times by Hobbes, Robinet, Condillac, and 
 other sensists. 
 
 The second is the opinion of the Conceptualists. 
 They maintain that a universal nature or object cannot 
 possibly exist either actually or potentially — that is to 
 say, that it neither exists nor is there any cause which 
 could ever make it exist ; but they contend that the 
 mind can conceive such a thing as a universal nature 
 merclyasitsown offspring, not as representing anything 
 really existing or possible to exist, and consequently 
 universal ideas are nothing more than mere concep- 
 tions of our mind, representing nothing real. This 
 opinion was held by the Stoics of old and by Abelardus 
 in the middle ages, and is maintained by all the 
 idealists of our time. 
 
 The third is the opinion of the Realists. They 
 
34 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 teach that universal natures do really exist, and that 
 therefore they can be represented by a universal image. 
 This opinion was held by the Platonists, and is held by 
 the Pantheists of our days, with this difference : that 
 Platonists taught that these universal natures existed 
 in themselves and were the types of individual things, 
 whereas Pantheists contend that they exist in indi- 
 vidual natures but with a distinct existence. 
 
 The fourth is the opinion of St. Thomas, and lies 
 between the opinion of the Realists and that of the 
 Conceptualists. He teaches that natures represented by 
 universal ideas are not mere intellectual offspring and 
 forms with no foundation in nature, as is held by the 
 Idealists, nor that such universal natures exist in fact, 
 but that such ideas are formed by our mind not arbitrar- 
 ily, but with a foundation in reality. Hence St. Thomas 
 holds that universal Jitures exist formally in their 
 universal form in the mind, but fundamentally in re- 
 ality ; and consequently a universal idea is formally so 
 in the mind, but receives its foundation from reality. 
 To give the four opinions in a few words, we say a 
 universal idea is like a universal portrait. Now, a por- 
 trait must have an original. Is there a universal 
 origin'al in nature from which to draw this portrait ? 
 Some answer no, and say that this universal por- 
 trait is a mere word having no meaning whatever. 
 Others answer : There is not, nor can there be, a univer- 
 sal original, but the mind may invent one as its own 
 fancy work. Others say: To be sure there is such a 
 universal original, and the portrait may represent it 
 exactly. Finally, St. Thomas comes in and says: Let 
 us distinguish ; in nature there is no such thing as a 
 universal original from which to draw a universal por- 
 trait, and yet this universal portrait, which we call uni- 
 versal idea, is not altogether a fancy work of our mind, 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 35 
 
 because the mind has a reason and a foundation for 
 this work, as it makes the universal portrait from find- 
 ing in reality one nature common to many individuals. 
 Hence this universal portrait as such is a work of the 
 mind, but the original is supplied by that one nature 
 found in real things to be common to many indi- 
 viduals. I see, for instance, Peter, John, James, etc., 
 all with their peculiar and individual differences. But 
 amid all these differences I perceive two elements 
 common to them all, rationality and animality. I 
 form of these two elements an idea which is com- 
 mon to all three ; I compare this notion with all the 
 men I can see, and find in them the same common 
 elements. I have therefore good reason to form the 
 universal idea of the species man, consisting of the 
 elements of animality and rationality. But every one 
 can perceive at a glance that that universal idea, as 
 such, does not exist in nature, for in nature I find 
 those two elements determined and contracted by in- 
 dividual conditions in each man, and therefore form- 
 ally the universal idea exists only in the mind. But 
 can any one say that I have no foundation in reality 
 for such an idea, since I have drawn it from the obser- 
 vation of many individuals of the species in which it 
 is found contracted, and I have formed it by elimi- 
 nating from those two elements all individual con- 
 ditions, and then by comparing the notion of those 
 two elements with as many individuals of the species 
 as I can observe, and by finding it always as agreeable 
 to them ? 
 
 ARTICLE THIRD. 
 
 True Opinion about the Nature of Universal Ideas. 
 
 Q. What do you think of the opinion of the Nomi- 
 nals? 
 
/ ,»,- ,• '> '.■■ > ■ 
 
 o 
 
 6 Elements of hitellectual Philosophy, 
 
 A. They say that universal ideas are mere sounds 
 or conceptions of a number of individuals. Now, 
 such opinion is false. i. Universal ideas cannot 
 be mere words, for words, as every one knows, are 
 signs of ideas. Now, a sign cannot exist without a 
 thing signified by the sign ; therefore all these words 
 which the Nominals call universal must always sup- 
 pose a universal conception of the mind. 
 
 2. It will not do to say that the best part of the 
 Nominals admit that a certain conception of the mind 
 corresponds to these words, because this conception is 
 not a universal idea, but a conception of a plurality 
 and number. For how could such a conception re- 
 present a plurality of individuals? Only in two 
 ways — either they represent this number of indi- 
 viduals distinctly and severally, or they represent it 
 in common and confusedly in consequence of a cer- 
 tain similitude among them. The first supposition 
 is impossible, because individuals are surrounded by 
 so many qualities and accidents that each one of 
 them has an existence all its own and distinct from 
 that of others. Therefore each one of them implies 
 an idea and a conception all its own, and consequently 
 it is impossible that one idea could represent distinctly 
 and severally a number of individuals as individuals. 
 How could I, for instance, express distinctly and seve- 
 rally by one idea Washington, Shakspere, Homer, 
 Michael Angelo, Titus Oates, Arnold, Robespierre, 
 and Joan d'Arc ? If it is said that one conception re- 
 presents a number of individuals in consequence of a 
 certain similitude among them, then we say that, by 
 the admission of the Nominals themselves, that which 
 is represented by universal ideas are not individual 
 things as such, but that in which they resemble each 
 other. Therefore a universal idea must be something 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 3 7 
 
 common to many. 3. Besides this, we always attribute 
 to individuals that which is signified by the universal 
 idea, or words, as the Nominals call them. For in- 
 stance, we say Peter is a man, the horse is an animal. 
 Now, in the opinion which we are refuting such expres- 
 sions would be absurd, because they would mean no- 
 thing, as they would amount to this : Peter is a mere 
 name, the horse is a mere sound. We conclude with 
 the remark of Leibnitz, that if the opinion of the 
 Nominals were true, all the sciences which rest on 
 universal ideas would be a mere empty sound and 
 sceptics would win the day. 
 
 Q. What is to be said of the second opinion ? 
 
 A. That it is also false. i. Because it is a fact 
 that we divide all real existences and individuals ac- 
 cording to the various universal ideas of genus, spe- 
 cies, and the like ; for instance, we refer Peter and 
 Socrates to the genus animal and to the species mariy 
 and the horse and the lion to the species brute. Now, 
 if nothing real and objective in nature corresponded 
 with these universal ideas, by what right could we 
 refer the horse and the lion to the species brute and 
 man to the species man? We could only say that 
 Peter corresponds with a certain fancy work of our 
 brain called man. 
 
 2. In the second place, if the opinion of the Concep- 
 tualists were admitted, all the sciences would be at 
 an end, because all the sciences cannot be possible 
 without universal propositions and ideas. If, there- 
 fore, universal ideas represented nothing real and ob- 
 jective, the sciences founded upon them would be 
 mere fictions of our mind and not sciences of real 
 things. 
 
 Q. Examine the third opinion. 
 
 A. I. Universal natures cannot exist in reality. 
 
38 Eiemenls of Intellectual P/tiiosophy. 
 
 This will be demonstrated when w speak of the 
 essences of things. We conclude, therefore, that the 
 third opinion must be false. Besides, ideas must re- 
 present that to which they are applied. If universal 
 ideas, therefore, represented universal natures, we 
 could not apply them except to universal natures. 
 But all mankind applies them to individual things or 
 persons ; we say, for instance, Walter is a man, my 
 horse is an animal. Therefore universal ideas do 
 not represent universal natures. 
 
 Q. Prove the fourth opinion. 
 
 A. According to the doctrine of St. Thomas, uni- 
 versal ideas, as such, exist formally in our mind, 
 but fundamentally in individual things. Now, that 
 natures represented by universal ideas exist funda- 
 mentally in individual things is proved from this: 
 the nature which the intellect perceives in the uni- 
 versal ideas is the same which, restricted and contracted 
 by individual conditions, is found in individual things. 
 This is so true that we predicate it of each individual, 
 and say Peter is a man, the horse is an animal. 
 Therefore it is clear that natures represented by uni- 
 versal ideas are the same as those of individual objects. 
 But they exist formally, as universal, only in the intel- 
 lect, and are its own work. In fact, the natures of 
 things may be supposed to be universal in a threefold 
 sense : i. In themselves, considered in the elements 
 which make them such natures; 2. Inasmuch as 
 they exist in individuals; 3. Inasmuch as they exist 
 in the intellect. But we cannot admit the two first 
 suppositions, because the natures of things cannot, in 
 the first place, be supposed to be universal in them- 
 selves, for the reason that all that which belongs to 
 the nature of an object, considered in itself, must 
 belong to every individual possessing that nature ; for 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 39 
 
 instance, all the elements composing human nature 
 must belong to every man. If, therefore, universality 
 belonged to human nature in itself, every man would 
 be a universal, which is absurd. We cannot admit 
 the second supposition, that a nature possesses uni- 
 versality as it exists in individuals, because everything 
 which is found in an individual is contracted and 
 determined by its individual conditions. Therefore 
 universality must be attributed to the ^natures of 
 things, inasmuch as they are found in the intellect 
 — that is to say, the nature of things, being found in 
 the same things contracted by individual qualities, is 
 lendered universal by the consideration of the intel- 
 lect, which deprives it of its individual qualities and 
 considers it as common to all. 
 
 Q. Define, then, a universal idea. 
 
 A. It is an idea representing a common nature y found 
 out by the intellect in a number of individuals of that 
 nature, 
 
 ARTICLE FOURTH. 
 
 Observations respecting the Nature, Elements , and Pro- 
 perties of Universal Ideas. 
 
 Q. What remarks should we make in order to illus- 
 trate the definition just given ? 
 
 A. 1. We must observe in what manner an idea 
 is rendered universal. The natures of things, as we 
 have said, are singular. In what manner, then, can 
 our intellect render them universal? We answer, by 
 way of abstraction and reflection. Our intellect is en- 
 dowed with a certain faculty of separating, in a given 
 object, one thing from another, and of fixing its atten- 
 tion and consideration upon one, laying aside all others ; 
 as, for instance, having before it the object man, it 
 
40 Elemenis of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 can separate it in all its elements and take the element 
 animality for its present consideration, laying aside 
 reason ; or it may put on one side animality and take 
 reason for its consideration. Our intellect exercises 
 this faculty especially about individual things ; be- 
 cause, seeing that its proper object is not the indi- 
 vidual and the singular, but the nature of things, and 
 on the other hand finding all the objects of nature 
 clothed with individual qualities by the faculty of sepa- 
 ration, it takes off from those individual objects quality 
 after quality until the bare nature is left. The nature 
 of things thus deprived of and purified from its indi- 
 vidual qualities is called universal inetaphysic, and the 
 operation by which the intellect has reduced it to that 
 state is called abstraction. The nature thus deprived of 
 its individual conditions is neither universal nor singu- 
 lar. It is not singular, because it has been stripped of 
 all those individual qualities which made it so. It is 
 not universal, because it only exhibits the essential 
 elements of a nature which, in themselves, are not uni- 
 versal ; else all individuals containing those elements 
 would be universal. Hence, for an idea to be truly 
 universal, it is not sufficient that the essence repre- 
 sented by it be only abstracted from its individual 
 qualities, but something else is necessary. It is abso- 
 lutely necessary that the intellect, liaving abstracted 
 the essence from individual things, should consider it 
 fit to be found in all individuals which lie under it. 
 Then only can we say with propriety that the idea is 
 universal, because then only we find in it unity and 
 plurality — uttity the abstract nature, plurality the 
 individuals possessing it. 'Such an idea is called uni- 
 versal logic, or, strictly speaking, universal, and the 
 second operation of the intellect, seeking for the same 
 nature in \x\dW\d\x2iXs, comparison or reflection. By two 
 
. Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 41 
 
 ways, then, an idea is rendered universal — by abstrac- 
 tion and reflection. 
 
 " Doubtless this could not be but that she* turns 
 
 Bodies to p )irits by sublimation strange ; 
 As fire converts to fire the things it burns, 
 
 As we our meats into our nature change, 
 From their gross matter she abstracts the forms, 
 
 And draws a kind of quintessence from things, 
 Which to her proper nature she transforms, 
 
 To bear them light on her celestial wings 
 This doth she when from things particular 
 
 She doth abstract the universal kinds, § 
 
 Which bodiless and immaterial are, 
 
 And can be only lodg'd within our minds." f 
 
 Q. How is a universal idea distinguished from all 
 other ideas ? 
 
 A. It is easy to distinguish it from singular and 
 particular ideas. The only idea with which it might 
 possibly be confounded is the collective. But it is 
 easy to distinguish one from the other if we attend to 
 these two observations: i. The universal idea can be 
 predicated of all individuals comprised within a spe- 
 cies or a genus, whereas the collective idea can only 
 be predicated of many, but not of all, which are com- 
 prised in a species. . For instance, take the species 
 man; that idea, man, applies to all the individuals of 
 the species, but the idea army cannot apply to all in- 
 dividuals of the species man, but only to a number of 
 them. 2. The universal idea can be predicated of 
 every individual of the species separately, whereas the 
 collective idea cannot be predicated except of all indi- 
 viduals taken together. For instance, we apply the 
 specific idea man to every individual man taken 
 separately, but we could not predicate the collective 
 
 * The soul, t Davies' Poems, 
 
42 Elements of Iitie Hectical Philosophy. • . 
 
 idea people of every separate individual forming a 
 people. 
 
 Q. What are the elements of a universal idea? 
 
 A. Two : conipreJiensioti and extension. To have a 
 universal idea it is necessary that the nature repre- 
 sented by it be abstracted from its individual condi- 
 tions, and also that it be thought as applicable to 
 many individuals. Tfie essential constituents of the 
 abstract nature are called the comprehension of an 
 idea. Its capacity of being applied to many is called 
 the extension of an idea. 
 
 These two elements are governed by the following 
 law : They are always contrary to each other. In pro- 
 portion as the comprehension or the contents of an 
 idea increases, its extension or applicability to many 
 diminishes ; and, on the contrary, in proportion as 
 its extension increases its comprehension diminishes. 
 This law is expressed by the following formula : The 
 comprehension of an idea is in the inverse ratio of its 
 extension. For instance, if to the idea animal you 
 add the element of reason, you increase its compre- 
 hension or contents, but you belittle its extension ; as 
 in the former state it could be applied not only to the 
 human species but also to the brute species, whereas 
 by addir ^ that element you can only apply it to the 
 human species. 
 
 Q. What are the properties of universal ideas? 
 
 A. A universal idea represents a nature capable of 
 being attributed to many individuals or species. This 
 capacity of being attributed to many individuals or 
 species is called Predicability of an idea. 
 
 Again, this nature included in the universal idea is 
 abstracted from all its individual conditions which make 
 it belong to this particular individual place or time. 
 Now, by the abstraction these particular conditions 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy, 43 
 
 are thrown aside, and, therefore, in this state the 
 nature belongs to all time and place. This property 
 is called Perpetuity of an idea. This must not be 
 understood in the sense that it does positively exist at 
 all time and is eternal; because the actual and real 
 existence of the universal idea is in our mind and 
 follows the conditions of our mind. Our mind not 
 being eternal, neither is the universal idea eternal. 
 The universal idea, therefore, is perpetual in a nega- 
 tive sense — that is to say, inasmuch as it bears no par- 
 ticular traits of this or that time, place, and indi- 
 vidual. 
 
CHAPTER II. 
 
 OF THE DIFFEREXT OBJECTS WHICH A UNIVERSAL IDEA 
 MAY REPRESENT, AND OF THE DIFFERENT MODES OF 
 REPRESENTING THEM. 
 
 Q. What necessity is there for studying the differ- 
 ent objects of a universal idea and the different modes 
 Df representing them? 
 
 A. One cannot have a correct notion of an image if 
 he does not know the objects it represents and the 
 different ways of representing them. Having, there- 
 fore, said that a universal idea is an image formed in 
 the intellect, to understand it well we must study the 
 objects it may represent and the different ways it has 
 of representing them. In other words, a universal 
 idea represents something common to many. We must, 
 therefore, study what is this something common^ and in 
 how many ways it may be attributed to many. We 
 shall begin from the ways or modes in which a uni- 
 versal idea represents objects — ways or modes which 
 have been called by philosophers categorema, or, sim- 
 ply, universals. 
 
 Q. How many universals are there ? 
 
 A. The idea is called universal inasmuch as it 
 represents an object as attributable to many. There- 
 fore the modes or ways of representing an object 
 universally must be as many as there are ways of 
 attributing a thing to many. Now, a thing may be 
 attributed to many in the following ways : It may be 
 attributed to them as representing an element of 
 their ess' nee; or as representing that particular ele- 
 
Elements of Intellectua I Ph ilosophy. 4 5 
 
 ment which distinguishes them from all others and in 
 which none other can share ; or as representing the 
 full and complete essence ; or as something not form- 
 ing an element of the essence, but a necessary conse- 
 quence of it; or, finally, as something not at all 
 necessary to the essence, but accidental to it. For 
 instance, take the idea animal in respect to man ; 
 what does this idea- represent with respect to man ? 
 An element of his essence, because animality enters 
 as an element in man's essence. Take the idc ' rea- 
 sonable ; what does it represent with regard to man ? 
 That peculiar element of his essence which distin- 
 guishes man from all other beings inferior to himself. 
 Take the idea reasonable animal ; what does it repre- 
 sent in respect to man? His complete essence. 
 Take the idea capable of learning ; what does it 
 represent with regard to man ? Something which 
 necessarily follows from his essence. Take the idea 
 white ; what does it represent ? Something not at 
 all necessary but quite accidental to the essence of 
 man. 
 
 There are, therefore, five modes of representing 
 something as common to many: as a part of their 
 essence ; as their complete essence ; as that peculiar 
 element which distinguishes them from all others ; as 
 something necessarily following from, or something 
 quite accidental to, the essence. There are no other 
 possible ways of representing something as common 
 to many. The first — that is, that common thing 
 which forms an element of the essence of many — is 
 called genus. The second — that is, that common 
 thing which represents the complete essence of many 
 —•is called species. The third is that peculiar ele- 
 ment which distinguishes the essence from that of 
 others, and is called differejice. The fourth is that 
 
46 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 which necessarily derives from the essence, and is 
 called property. The fifth is called accident. 
 
 Q. Speak of the first universal, genus, and point 
 out its offices. 
 
 A. Genus is defined : A tiniversal nature, zvhieh may 
 be attributed to several species as an element of their re- 
 spective essences. Before explaining this definition we 
 must remark that we are obliged necessarily to ex- 
 plain the gemis by means of the species, and vice versd, 
 as they are relative terms. That they are naturally re- 
 lated is clear from the fact that two things are neces- 
 sary to form the nature of genus — first, it must be 
 found in several species, and not in several indi- 
 viduals, as some have said, because genus is attribut- 
 able only to that which is immediately under it. But 
 directly under the genus is the species, not the indi- 
 vidual. Therefore genus must be attributable to 
 several species. The second is, that genus is at- 
 tributed to species as an element of its essence, 
 which it has in common with other species. Thus 
 animal, which is genus respecting man and the brutes, 
 contains only an element of their essence. 
 
 Q. What is species ? 
 
 A. A universal notio7i which can be attributed to many 
 individuals as their complete essetice. To have the 
 nature of species, therefore, two things are required : 
 I. It must be applicable to many individuals, be- 
 cause it is a universal notion, just because it is attri- 
 butable to many individuals. 2. It must be attribut- 
 A ed to many individuals as their complete essence. 
 Thus, man is attributable to Peter, John, Walter, and 
 all individuals of the human species, as representing 
 their com ple te essence. 
 
 Q. What is difference ? 
 
 A. A universal idea which can be attributed to many 
 
 \ 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. /^*j 
 
 individuals^ as that clement ivhich distinguishes their 
 essence from all other essences. Reasonableness in man 
 is just the difference wliicli distinguislics liis essence 
 from all others. And it is to be remarked that differ- 
 ence is a universal idea, inasmuch as it is predicated 
 of many individuals as the distinj^uishing element of 
 their essence, and not in any other sense. We con- 
 clude, therefore : Genus is a universal idea which repre- 
 sents a common element of the essence of a number 
 of species. Difference represents that element which 
 distinguishes the species from each other, species the 
 complete essence of many individuals. 
 
 Q. What are the degrees of universals? 
 
 A. Three : supreme, middle, and loivcst. Genus is 
 called supreme when it has no other above it, as sub- 
 stance. It is called middle when it has other genuses 
 above and under it, as body, which has the genus sub- 
 stance above it and two before \t, living bodies and 
 inorganic bodies. It is called lowest when it has no 
 genus under it but species, as the genus animal, which 
 has two species under it, reasonable and unreasonable 
 animals. Likewise species and difference are called 
 supreme if they have no species or difference placed 
 above them ; middle if they have them above and 
 below them ; lowest when they have none but indi- 
 viduals below them. 
 
 ARTICLE SECOND. 
 On Property and Accident. 
 
 Q. Define the universal called property. 
 
 A. It is rt universal idea representing something coin- 
 mon to many individuals, as necessarily emanating from 
 their essence. Freedom in man, for instance, is a pro- 
 perty, because, though it is a quality which does not 
 
I 
 
 48 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 enter in the definition of his essence, is yet neces- 
 sarily flowing from it. And if so "owing, it is 
 clear that it must have the same qualifications as 
 the essence. Now, the essence has three qualifications : 
 I. It is applicable only to the species, because by 
 means of the essence individuals are classified in their 
 own species. 2. It must be applicable to all the indi- 
 v'iduals of the species. 3. And that for ever, because 
 neither the species nor the individual can ever exist 
 without their nature. Property, therefore, must be 
 applicable to one species, to all the individuals of the 
 species, and for ever. These three qualities distin- 
 guish property from all accidents ; from those acci- 
 dents which are applicable to the species, but not 
 to all individuals. We can say, for instance, that 
 every man is free, but we cannot say that every man 
 is a poet, the latter being an accident which be- 
 comes some of the species, but not all ; from those 
 which belong to all the individuals of the species, but 
 not exclusively to that species. I can predicate free- 
 dom of man alone, but to have two feet or to possess 
 teeth 1 can say of man and many of the species brute. 
 ' Q. Define accident. 
 
 A. It is quite the contrary of property, and may be 
 defined : That universal notion wJiich may be fomid 
 or not in a number of individuals tvithout at all inter- 
 fering with their nature. Hence, in order to have the 
 idea of accident it is not necessary that it should be 
 separable from an individual ; it is enough that we 
 may conceive the individual as without that accident, 
 leaving at the same time his nature unchanged. To 
 be black is inseparable from the raven, yet that quality 
 is an accident in the raven, as we can easily think its 
 essence without that quality. 
 
 Q. How can universals be predicated of a thing? 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 49 
 
 A. Before answering the question we must make 
 two remarks: i. That universals may not only be 
 predicated of real objects, but may be predicated of 
 each other ; as, for instance, accident may have its 
 genus, species, difference, property, and accident. 
 Thus the accident red is a species under the genus 
 color, the difference of which might be determined by 
 a given shade of red, etc. 
 
 Second remark. Universals may be predicated in 
 the abstract form or in the concrete, as we may say 
 animality and animal, reasonable and reasonableness, 
 free and freedom, learned and doctrine. 
 
 Having premised these two remarks, we give the 
 rules how universals may be predicated of things : 
 
 1st rule. Difference^ property^ and accident arc never 
 predicated of a subject in the abstract form,. but always 
 in the concrete. Because these universals represent a 
 quality, and therefore must be applied as adjectives 
 which qualify a thing. Now, adjectives are concrete 
 and not abstract; hence we must say man is reason- 
 able and free, and not man is reasonableness and free- 
 dom ; Peter is learned, and not Peter is doctrine. 
 
 2d rule. Genus and species are predicated in the con- 
 crete form when it is question of substances. Ilcncc it 
 is right to say Peter is a man, but wrong to say Peter 
 is humanity. The reason is that substances are attri- 
 buted in their true and complete sense, and therefore 
 in concrete. 
 
 3d rule. Genus and species^ when it is question of 
 accidental things, are predicated in the abstract. I can 
 say, for instance, whiteness is a color, but not that 
 which is white is colored, because when the accident 
 is expressed in a concrete form, as when we say 
 colored instead of color, the principal idea which is 
 meant is no longer the accident but the substance 
 
50 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 which upholds it, and therefore there would be no 
 more question of accidents but of substances. 
 
 4th rule. Universals are predicated in alt their com- 
 pre/iensioUy but not in alt their extension. Because, in 
 order to attribute a universal idea to a thing, it is 
 necessary that I shouW find all the elements compos- 
 ing that universal idea in the thing to which I wish to 
 attribute it ; but it is by no means necessary that that 
 thing should be the only one to which the universal 
 may be applied, otherwise it would no longer be uni- 
 versal. 
 
 ARTICLE SECOND. 
 
 Of the Objects of Universal Ideas, or of Being and its 
 
 Categories. 
 
 Q- What is the object of universal ideas? 
 
 A. It is being, or one of its determinations. Because 
 the idea, inasmuch as it is an image which represents 
 things to be known, is a means of knowledge; there- 
 fore all that which can be an object of our knowledge 
 can be the object of our ideas. But the object of our 
 knowledge can only be being or one of its determina- 
 tions, as a thing can be known inasmuch as it is. These, 
 therefore, are the objects of universal idea. 
 
 Now, that being can stand for the object of uni- 
 versal idea is beyond doubt, as we daily say being is, 
 being is not. Nothing can be and not be at tu. same 
 time. But we must remark that when the idea has 
 being for its object it does not represent it, in any of 
 the five modes above spoken of — that is, as genus, 
 species, difference, property, or accident — because, as we 
 shall see in Ontology, being in general cannot be any 
 of these things. 
 
 Q. How many are the determinations of being? 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 5 1 
 
 They are innumerable, as every being is a determi- 
 nation of being. But here we intend to speak only of 
 those supreme divisions and classifications of being in 
 which all other beings are included, because the object 
 of logic is not this or that particular being, but the 
 order of the conceptions of our mind. It is necessary, 
 therefore, to explain those common divisions and uni- 
 versal conceptions which put in order and distribute 
 all beings into so many classes and categories. 
 
 Q. How many categories are there ? 
 
 Ten ; because being, universally considered, can be 
 divided into substance and accident, meaning here by 
 accident everything which is not a substance. Sub- 
 stance, being the base of all the variety of accidents, 
 and hence fixed and determinate in its idea, is taken 
 always in the same for all substances, and therefore is 
 not divided into other genuses. Accident, being more 
 vague and confused and various, in order to determine 
 and to fitly classify it, is divided into nine classes. 
 Because accident is added to substance and deter- 
 mines it. Now, substance maybe determined by nine 
 things — by quantity, relation, quality, action, passion^ 
 time, place, site, and habit. Hence accident is divided 
 into all these classes. Being in general, therefore, is 
 divided into ten grand orders, which are called cate- 
 gories — that is, supreme genuses of things — and which 
 are substance, quantity, relation, quality, action, passion, 
 time, space, site, habit. This is the celebrated division 
 of being accepted and illustrated by the greatest 
 thinkers of antiquity. We shall give here the defini- 
 tion of substance, accident, relation, and quality, as 
 they occur so frequently in logic, and shall speak of 
 the rest in Ontology. • ' 
 
 Substance is that which exists in itself, and not in 
 another^ as Peter, tree, stone. By this substance is 
 
52 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy, ^ 
 
 easily distinguished from accident, Avhich is that 
 which must lean on another in order to exist, as 
 white, square, round, etc, — things which cannot exist 
 without leaning on another. 
 
 It is to be carefully remarked that the essence of 
 the substance is to be in itself and not by itself. The 
 first means that the substance requires no other being 
 to lean on in order to exist, which is true ; the second 
 would mean that substance does not require a cause 
 to create it, which is false of finite substances. 
 
 Relation can be defined that order luhich an object 
 has with regard to another ; how an object lies to an- 
 other. For instance, paternity is a relation which im- 
 plies the order in which a father stands to his son. 
 
 This category may be real or logical : it is real when 
 it exists actually in nature, as the relation of pater- 
 nity ; it is logical when it is placed by our mind. 
 
 Quality. This accident may be defined tJiat ivhich 
 of itself gives a special manner of being to the sub- 
 stance. 
 
 It is called an accident to distinguish it from the 
 specific difference, which is also a quality, but consti- 
 tutes tlie essence. The other words distinguish it 
 from other accidents because other accidents modify 
 the substance more or less, but this they do not by 
 themselves, but in consequence of something else ; as, 
 for instance, quantity qualifies the substance, not 
 by itself, but by the extension of parts which it pro- 
 duces in it. But when I say Peter is good, this 
 quality gives of itself a new mode of existence to 
 Peter. 
 
 Q. Recapitulate all we have said in this chapter. 
 
 A. From what we have said in this chapter it is 
 evident how many and what are the different species 
 of universal ideas. A universal idea is an intellectual 
 
Eleinenls of Intellectual Philosophy, 53 
 
 representation. Now, these representations or forms 
 are as different as are the objects they represent 
 and the modes of representing them ; and, as there 
 are five modes of representing an object in a universal 
 way—genus, species, difference, property, and acci- 
 dent— so, under this respect, there aie five universal 
 ideas— those of genus, species, difference, property, 
 and accident. With regard to the object, as there are • 
 ten most universal objects, so there are ten universal 
 ideas— substance accident, and this subdivided into 
 relation, quantity, quality, action, passion, time, place, 
 and habit, 
 

 • 
 
 CHAPTER III. 
 
 OF THE EXPRESSION OF IDEAS OR OF TERMS. 
 
 ARTICLE FIRST. 
 
 Definition and Division of Terms. 
 
 Q. What are terms ? 
 
 A. Among the many means we have of manifesting 
 our ideas, words claim the first place. 
 
 " The words . . . the speaking picture of thn mind, 
 The extract of the soul, that labor'd how 
 To leave the image of herself behind." 
 
 — Daniels* Poems. 
 
 Words, inasmuch as they form a part of a proposi- 
 tion or reasoning, are called terms, because they are 
 the very thing to which a proposition or reasoning may 
 be finally reduced ; though the idea itself which forms 
 part of the judgment or proposition is oftentimes called 
 term. A term, therefore, strictly speaking, may be 
 defined that into which a simple proposition may be 
 resolved. For instance, God is holy; this proposition 
 mav be resolved into God and holy ; these, therefore, 
 are e terms of the proposition. 
 
 Q. How are terms divided inasmuch as they are 
 signs of ideas? 
 
 I. A term may be of as many kinds as there are ideas, 
 because they are destined exactly to express ideas, 
 and everything which has relation with another object 
 may easily be called after it, as we say generally 
 wholesome food, drink, and so forth, not because such 
 
 54 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 55 
 
 things are subject to health, but because they have 
 relation with it, inasmuch as they are either its 
 cause or its sign. Likewise, terms having relation to 
 ideas may reasonably be called after them. Hence, as 
 there are abstract, concrete, collective, particular, 
 universal, and individual ideas, and so forth, so there 
 are also abstract, concrete, collective, particular, 
 universal, and individual terms. But besides, terms 
 as signs may be divided into three great classes. 
 Some signify a thing by themselves, such as the term 
 man ; others cannot express anything by themselves, 
 but must be joined to others, as some^ every^ which 
 uttered by themselves mean nothing, but have a mean- 
 ing when united to those of the former class, as some 
 mcn^ every tree; others, finally, may or may not 
 signify something by themselves. The first are called 
 by modern philosophers terms significative by them- 
 selves ; the second, significative by means of others ; 
 the third are called mixed terms. The first, however, 
 strictly deserve the name of terms. 
 
 Q. How are terms significative by themselves sub- 
 divided ? 
 
 A. I. Into positive and negative. The first signify 
 something, as wrt'w / the second express the absence 
 of something, as impotent — that is, the absence of 
 power. About the latter we must remark that some 
 of them are negative as to the word, but positive as 
 to the meaning, as innocence, immortality, infinity^ 
 which imply a positive perfection ; others are positive 
 as to the word and negative as to the sense, as jnortal, 
 corruptible, blind. 
 
 2. Into complex and incomplex, the first are those 
 which are formed of more than one significative word, 
 as Washington Irving ; the second of one, as tree^ 
 spiritual. 
 
56 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 3. Into nnivocal, equivocal, analogical. The first are 
 those which are applied to several objects under the 
 same signification, as animal, which is applied to man 
 and to beasts. 
 
 The second are those which are applied to several 
 things in a different meaning, as scorpion, which means 
 the animal of such name, and is also given to one of 
 the signs of the Zodiac. 
 
 The third are those which lie between the two for- 
 mer ones, and which are not applied to more than one 
 thing in the same meaning, nor in a meaning alto- 
 gether different, but are applied to something in con- 
 sequence of a certain similarity with other things ; as 
 when we say the air is very healthy, the term heal- 
 thy is analogical, because, although the term can be 
 strictly applied only to the human body, it is yet by 
 analogy or resemblance applied to air, to food, to 
 color, etc. 
 
 ARTICLE SECOND. 
 
 Properties of Terms. 
 
 Q. How many are the properties of terms? 
 
 A. Five : supposition, alienation, amplification, re- 
 striction, and appellation ; because every term may be 
 applied either in its proper meaning, and then we 
 have supposition ; or in a meaning not its own, and 
 then wc have alienation ; or in a wider meaning, and 
 then we have amplification ; or in more restricted 
 sense, and we have restriction ; or it may be added to 
 illustrate another term, and then we have appellation. 
 
 The supposition of a term is, therefore, nothing 
 more than the use of the word in its proper sense. 
 The appellation may be twofold. It is material when 
 the term is used not for its object but for itself, as in 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 57 
 
 that sophism mentioned and refuted by Clement of 
 Alexandria : ** What thou utterest passeth through 
 thy mouth. But thou utterest house ; therefore 
 house passeth through thy mouth." The supposition 
 of the term here is material ; it means the word house, 
 but not the object signified by the work. On this also 
 is founded that beautiful impersonification of the five 
 vowels : 
 
 "We are little airy creatures, 
 All of different voice and features ; 
 One of us in glass is set, 
 One of us you'll find \njet. 
 T'other you may see in tin, 
 , And the fourth a box within ; 
 If the fifth you should pursue, 
 It can never fly from you" 
 
 — Swift. 
 
 When the term is used to mean the object, then the 
 supposition is formal, as a house must have walls and 
 roof. 
 
 Q. How is formal supposition subdivided ? 
 
 A.. I. Into logical and real. It is logical when the 
 term expresses that which exists only logically, as 
 animal is a pred?cable called genus. It is real when 
 the term is used to express that which really agrees 
 with the object, as the animal is sensitive. 
 
 2. Into collective and distributive. It is collective 
 when we use a common word for all the objects signi- 
 fied and taken together, as the apostles were twelve. 
 It is distributive when the term can be used not only 
 for all but for each one, as man is rational. But with 
 regard to this distributive supposition we must remark 
 that the individual objects may be either each indi- 
 vidual, or not each individual but each species, as all 
 animals were in Noe's ark. The sense here is that 
 
5 8 Elements of Intellectual Ph ilosophy. 
 
 not each individual animal was there, but each indi- 
 vidual species. 
 
 Q. What is appellation, and how is it subdivided ? 
 
 A. It is the application of one term to another, and 
 it is formal and material — formal when it naturally 
 agrees with the other, as the physician cures ; material 
 when it is merely accidental, as the physician sings or 
 dances. 
 
 Q. What is alienation ? 
 
 A. The use of a term not in its own proper mean- 
 ing, but in another, as the Lion of jfuda, the Sun of 
 Jiisiice. 
 
 Q. What is amplification ? 
 
 A. It is the extension of a term from a less compre- 
 hensive sense to a greater, as great men will always be 
 honored — meaning not only great men of the present 
 time, but of all time and place ; and that playful 
 amplification of Pitt : 
 
 " From the small acorn see the oak arise, 
 Supremely tall and towering in the skies ! 
 Queen of the groves ! her stately head she rears, 
 Her bulk increasing with increasing years ; 
 Now moves in pomp majestic o'er tlie deep, 
 While in her womb ten thousand thunders sleep — 
 Hence Britain boasts her far-extended reign, 
 And by the expanded acorn rules the main." 
 
 - Q. What is restriction ? 
 
 A. The use of a term which has a broader significa- 
 tion in a more narrow one, as Eve was the mother of 
 all living. Living, in this phrase, is taken in a more 
 restricted sense than it has, naturally meaning every- 
 thing which has life, from the plant to God, whereas 
 in the phrase it is merely to express men. 
 
 >■« 
 
CHAPTER IV. 
 
 PROXIMATE MATTER OF REASONING ; AND, FIRST, OF THE 
 NATURE OF JUDGMENT AND PROPOSITION. 
 
 ARTICLE FIRST. 
 
 Nature and Definition of Jndgment. 
 
 Q. What is judgment ? 
 
 A. We have said that our mind acquires universal 
 ideas when it considers a quality as applicable to a 
 number of subjects. If, then, the mind applies a 
 quality to one or more subjects, or removes it from 
 them, we have another act of the mind called judg- 
 ment. For instance, our mind may reflect on the 
 quality rational^ as applicable to Peter, John, Walter, 
 Andrew, and to all men, but it may do more : from 
 the possibility it may pass to the fact and actually 
 apply that quality to them, and say Peter is rational, 
 John is rational, all men are rational ; or it may 
 deny a quality of a subject, as man is not bird. In the 
 first instance we have a universal idea ; in the second, 
 a judgment. 
 
 Q. In what exactly lies the nature of judgment? 
 
 A. To be able to affirm or to deny a quality of a 
 subject it is necessary that the mind should, in the 
 first place, compare the idea of the subject with the 
 idea of the quality ; and, next, that it should perceive 
 the agreement or the disagreement which may exist be- 
 tween the two, otherwise it could not affirm or deny 
 one or the other. Now, though the comparing of 
 
 89 
 
6o Elements of hitellectual Philosophy. 
 
 the quality with the subject be necessary to render a 
 judgment possible, yet the true nature of judgment 
 lies exactly in the agreement or disagreement of the 
 quality with the subject, and in the affirming or de- 
 nying on or the other. Because to form a judgment, 
 as we have said, the actual application to, or the re- 
 moving of a quality from, a subject is necessary. But 
 in the mere comparison of the two terms that appli- 
 cation is wanting. When I raise, for instance, a ques- 
 tion in my mind. Is Peter honest ? and begin to com- 
 pare the two terms, I have not pronounced a judgment 
 as yet, because I have made no application. When I 
 say Peter is honest, then I have formed a judgment. 
 The essence, therefore, of the judgment lies not in 
 the comparison of the two terms but in the discovery 
 of the agreement or disagreement of the two ideas, 
 subject and quality, and in the affirmation or denial of 
 the same. And as definition must express the nature 
 of a thing, so we may rightly define judgment the per- 
 ception of the agreement of a quality with a subject, 
 or the disagreement of a quality from a subject ; or, 
 with St. Tliomas, that act of the mind by which it unites 
 or divides by affirming or denying. The thing which 
 is affirmed or denied is caXX^d predicate ; that of which 
 something is affirmed or denied is called subject ; and 
 the judgment, if it affirm something of the subject, is 
 called affirmative ; if it deny, is called negative. 
 
 Q. What conclusions do you draw from the nature 
 of judgment? • 
 
 A. I. That judgment is a more perfect knowledge 
 relatively to ideas, because by means of the idea no- 
 thing is affirmed or denied of a subject, and hence 
 its knowledge is not complete ; whereas the nature of 
 judgment consists exactly in that affirmation or nega- 
 tion. Therefore judgment is a more perfect know- 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 6i 
 
 Icdcje than simple apprehension, and is therefore a 
 proximate matter of reasoning, as being a more per- 
 fect knowledge of a thing. '' 1 '..,.'1 
 
 2. In judgment there is always found a universal 
 percepL'on ; because, the essence of judgment consist- 
 ing iii affirming or denying a predicate of a subject, or, 
 in other words, in saying that one of the terms is the 
 other, as man is rational, there lurks in that affirma- 
 tion the perception of the unity of being between the 
 subject and the predicate, man and rational. But to see 
 unity common to a plurality is a universal perception ; 
 therefore in every judgment there is always a univer- 
 sal perception. This is also the case when the judg- 
 ment is negative, as when wp say Peter is not a phi- 
 losopher, because I discover that not to be a philoso- 
 pher is common also to Peter, from which it is evident 
 how important to reasoning and logic are universal per- 
 ceptions. 
 
 ARTICLE SECOND. . , . 
 
 Nature of Propositions. 
 
 \ 
 
 Q. Give the definition and elements of a proposition. 
 
 A. Judgment is so called when confined within the 
 mind ; when it comes out of the mind clothed in words 
 it is called proposition. Man is a reasonable being is 
 a judgment expressed in words, and therefore a pro- 
 position. And because judgment affirms or denies 
 something of a subject, according to this a proposition 
 may be defined a discourse, by which we affirm or 
 deny a quality of a subject. Hence three elements 
 enter into a proposition — the thing of which something 
 is affirmed or denied, and which is called subject ; the 
 quality which is affirmed or denied, and which is called 
 predicate ; and, finally, the verb is or is net, which, 
 
62 Elements of IntellecHial Philosophy. 
 
 strictly speaking, expresses the essence of judgment — 
 that is, the act of the mind forming tlie agreement 
 or disagreement. Tiie first two are called the terms 
 of a proposition. The verb is, because uniting them 
 together, is called copula. 
 
 Q. What remarks ought to be made as to the 
 copula in a proposition.^ 
 
 A. I. The copula is always necessary in a proposi- 
 tion, and no proposition can be formed without the 
 verb to be. Because to establish a proposition it is 
 not sufficient to express the subject and the predicate, 
 but it is also necessary to express the agreement or dis- 
 agreement which one has with the other. Now, this 
 agreement or disagreement cannot be expressed by 
 means of the predicate only, because the predicate 
 without the copula would imply no relation to the 
 subject. Therefore the copula is necessary in every 
 proposition. 
 
 2. Having established the necessity of the copula, 
 and having said that it is a verb, we must pay atten- 
 tion to its signification, to its mood, its tense, and to 
 the special manner of using it. As to its significa- 
 tion, we must remark that to be, in the proposition, 
 docs not mean to exist, because the copula docs not 
 express the real existence of the terms ; as, for instance, 
 when I say Shakspere is the greatest English poet, 
 I do not mean to say that Shakspere does actually 
 exist now, I mean merely to unite that predicate to 
 Shakspere. Therefore the copula in propositions 
 merely expresses the agreement of the predicate with 
 the subject, or the act of the intellect applying the 
 predicate to the subject. Whether the objects signi- 
 fied by the terms exist or not it is no business of the 
 copula to express. It is by a different act of the mind 
 and by investigating the nature of the terms that it 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 6 
 
 ■> 
 
 can be found out whether they be r:al or logical. Nor 
 is it contrary to this theory to say that there are some 
 propositions in which the copula expresses the real 
 existence, as Socrates is ; because that proposition 
 amounts to this: Socrates is existing; in which case 
 also the copula expresses the union of the two terms. 
 
 Q. Of what mood and tense must the copula be? 
 
 A. As to the mood, it must be the indicative mood, 
 because the copula in a proposition is used to affirm 
 and declare a predicate of a subject or to deny it of 
 the subject. But of all the moods of a verb only the 
 indicative has the office to afifirm, to declare, to deny. 
 Therefore the copula in a proposition must be in the 
 indicative mood. 
 
 As to the tense, it must be the present tense, be- 
 cause the copula, as we have said, does not express 
 the real existence of the terms, but the act by which 
 the mi'^J unites the predicate with the subject or 
 separates one from- the other. But this act is done 
 when the mind judges — that is, in the present time. 
 Tlicrcfore the copula must be in the present tense. 
 If there be any propositions having the copula in the 
 past or future tense, the time past or future must be 
 applied to the tenses, and not to the copula. The pro- 
 position, for instance, The Messias was the Redeemer 
 of Israel, must be understood to mean the Messias is 
 he who was the Redeemer of Israel, the predicate 
 being zvho was the Redeemer of Israel. 
 
 I'inally, we must remark that the copula in a pro- 
 l)osition may be incorporated in the predicate, as, 
 for instance, in the proposition John is sleeping, the 
 predicate sleeping may be incorporated in the copula, 
 and we can say John sleeps. From this originate 
 those verbs which grammarians call adjective — that is, 
 tliose which contain the verb to be as an attribute to 
 
64 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy, 
 
 distinguish them from the verb to be as substantive. 
 In conclusion one must pay close attention to the 
 nature of the copula, because from it all these things 
 proceed. The copula is nothing else but the act of 
 the mind uniting or separating the predicate from the 
 subject, in which the essence of judgment consists. It 
 follows from this, ist, that the copula is as necessary 
 to the proposition as that act is essential to judgment ; 
 2d, that the copula does not express the real exis- 
 tence of the subject or predicate, but merely the act 
 of the mind uniting or separating them ; 3d, that that 
 act being nothing else but an affirmatJon or negation, 
 the office of the indicative mood, the copula expressing 
 it must be also in the indicative mood ; 4th, that, the 
 act being performed in the present time, the copula 
 must be in the present tense ; 5th, that in that act 
 the predicate being considered as applicable to the 
 subject, it may easily be incorporated in the copula, 
 the office of which is just to refer the predicate to the 
 subject. 
 
 • . »'> .'ill •, jt ' ■ • ■ ■ 1 ': . _ ,^ ' : 
 
 / •' ; '■ '■!(' li. :'■•'■''''. ^ "''■■ . ■ . • ' ' ' ■ : 
 
 t 
 
 . I I - , J < ' .« . ' . I " i • '■'•.' 
 
 .■l(Vf ■ I •{ . I ,.■"•'•' ,•''■'" 
 
 ,1 (i ; • ''.i • ' 1 . >! ( ' • , , ' . ' , ■ ■• "■ 
 
 
 
' • (■ > 
 
 CHAPTER V. 
 
 DIFFERENT SPECIES AND PROPERTIES OF PROPO- 
 SITIONS. 
 
 ARTICLE FIRST. 
 
 Difference of Proposition considered as to the Copula. 
 
 Q. What causes the difference of propositions? 
 
 A. From the nature of a being immediately arise 
 its difteren^ species and properties, because the spe- 
 cies of a thing is nothing more than the nature of the 
 thing itself differently modified, and its properties are 
 an immediate consequence of that nature. Having, 
 therefore, determined the nature of judgment and pro- 
 position, it will be easy to deduce from it their divi- 
 sion and properties. The nature of judgment or 
 proposition lies in applying or not a predicate to a 
 subject ; therefore propositions must be different, ac- 
 cording to the difference of such application. This 
 application may vary from two causes, from itself 
 and from the way it is made, or from the terms 
 which are applied — that is, either from the copula or 
 the terms. 
 
 Q. How many different propositions are there, con- 
 sidered as to the copula? 
 
 A. In propositions the predicate may either be ap- 
 plied to the subject or denied of the subject ; or it 
 may be denied of the subject, but at the same time 
 insinuating that another may be agreeable to it. 
 When the predicate is applied to the subject, then the 
 proposition is affirmative, such as God is infinite, the 
 
 H 
 
66 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 Church is imperishable ; when the predicate is denied 
 of the subject then t^e proposition is negative- — man is 
 not a pure spirit, beauty is not imperishable ; when it 
 is denied of the subject, insinuating that some other 
 predicate may be agreeable to it, then the proposition 
 is called indefinite ; as, The brute is not man, in which 
 proposition, if we remove the predicate man from 
 brute, we insinuate that some other attribute may 
 apply to it. Hence, an indefinite proposition is nei- 
 ther affirmative nor negative, but partakes of both. 
 These propositions, liowever, are not so common or 
 important ; more common and important are the 
 affirmative and the negative. 
 
 Q. To what law are affirmative and negative propo- 
 sitions subject? 
 
 A. To the following : In affirma<^ive propositions 
 the predicate is applied in all its comprehension or in 
 the totality of the elements of which it is composed, 
 but not in all its extension — that is, not in its full capa- 
 city of being applied. Homer is an epic poet ; Bacon 
 is a naturalist ; the predicate epic poet in the first 
 proposition is applied to Homer in the totality of 
 elements composing that idea — that is, every quality 
 forming an epic poet agrees with Homer — but not in its 
 full capacity of being applied, as that predicate may 
 be applied, to others, as to Dante, Milton. Virgil, etc. 
 In the second proposition the predicate naturalist 
 agrees with Bacon in the same sense — that is, in the 
 totality of elements forming that idea — but may be ap« 
 plied to others, such as Locke, Hobbes, Condillac, 
 etc. The reason of this law is drawn from the very 
 nature of affirmative propositions, because when we 
 affirm a predicate of subject in a proposition we say 
 that one thing is the other. Now, we could not say 
 that unless all the elements of the predicate agreed 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 67 
 
 with the subject ; therefore, in these propositions, the 
 predicate must be taken in its comprehension, but 
 not in all its extension, because when we affirm a pre- 
 dicate of a subject we want to express the quality 
 with which the subject is endowed, and not the num- 
 ber of individuals which may have it. 
 
 In negative propositions the predicate is not denied 
 in all its comprehension but in all its extension, be- 
 cause, in order to say that a thing is not another, it is 
 sufficient that a single element of the one is not found 
 in the other; but it is denied in all its extension, be- 
 cause if that which is signified by the predicate could 
 agree with any part of the subject, we could not sim- 
 ply remove the predicate from the subject. For 
 instance, when we say The circle is not square we 
 mean to say that no possible circle can ever be square, 
 otherwise we could not say, absolutely speaking, the 
 circle is not square. 
 
 Q. In how many ways can we affirm or deny a pre- 
 dicate of a subject ? 
 
 A. In two ways : by simply affirming or denying the 
 predicate of a subject, or by expressing the manner or 
 mode in which a predicate may be applicable to a sub- 
 ject. In the first case we have simple propositions, in 
 the second w^^/rt-/ propositions. Thus, when I say The 
 rose is fragrant, I utter a simple proposition ; when I 
 say ^lan is necessarily reasonable, I pronounce a modal 
 proposition, because I express the manner in which 
 the predicate agrees with the subject. 
 
 Q. How many ways or modes are there by which a 
 predicate may agree or disagree with a subject ? 
 
 A. Four; and hence there can be four species of 
 modal propositions. The predicate may agree or dis- 
 agree with a ^v\i]Qzt possibly ox impossibly ^ necessarily or 
 accidentally ; and, therefore, propositions may express 
 
68 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy 
 
 the possibility or impossibility of a predicate agreeing 
 with a subject, the necessity or contingency of its agree- 
 ing or not with it. If they express the possibility they 
 are called possible, as Man can be a philosopher ; they 
 are called impossible if they express the impossibility 
 of the predicate agreeing with the subject — as, Man can- 
 not be infinite ; necessary if they express the necessity 
 — as. The soul is necessarily immortal ; contingent if 
 they e?;press the contingency — as, The Ethiopian is 
 black by accident. 
 
 Q. What other modes of affirming or denying, and, 
 consequently, how many kinds of propositions, are 
 there ? 
 
 A. Two, absolute and hypothetical. We can apply 
 or not the predicate to the subject absolutely, without 
 expressing the case when it may or may not agree 
 with the subject, or we may express the case when 
 it may or may not apply to the subject. In the first 
 case we have absolute propositions — as, Man is a rea- 
 sonable animal ; in the second we have hypotheti- 
 cal or conditional propositions — as. Where there is 
 smoke there must be fire. These latter propositions 
 are threefold, connex, conjunctive, and disjunctive. 
 The first is that in which the condition is expressed 
 by the word if; as, If there are footprints some one 
 must have walked. This proposition is formed of 
 two, one which expresses the condition, and is called 
 antecedent — as. If there are footprints; the other 
 affirms or denies the predicate, and is called conse- 
 quent, because depending on the first — as, some one 
 must have walked. The truth of these propositions 
 does not lie in the truth of the antecedent or conse- 
 quent, but in the connection ; if the connection is 
 true the proposition is true; if false, false — as, If 
 donkeys had wings they would fly. This proposition 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 69 
 
 is true, though it is not true that donkeys can have 
 win^Ts because the connection is true. On the con- 
 trary, if I said, If America exists Rome exists, both 
 antecedent and consequent are true, but the proposi- 
 tion is false, because there is no connection between 
 the two. 
 
 The conjunctive proposition is that in which the 
 propositions are united by the words and, not ; as, for 
 instance, He is not both dead and alive. Conjunctive 
 proposition, then, is that in which is expressed the 
 impossibility of two things being together, and in 
 order to be true it is necessary that there should be a 
 repugnance between the two. Hence the following 
 proposition is not true : Peter cannot both sleep and 
 breathe, be -use those two things can go together. 
 
 A disjunctive proposition is that in which proposi- 
 tions are united together by the words either, or; as, 
 for instance, It is either night or day. This propo- 
 sition, to be true, two conditions are necessary: i. 
 That there be a true opposition between the proposi- 
 tions of which it is composed. 2. That the enume- 
 ration of parts be complete, otherwise the adversary 
 may catch at that which is omitted. 
 
 ARTICLE SECOND. 
 Difference of Propositions^ Considered as to their Terms. 
 
 Q. How are propositions divided under this respect ? 
 
 A. The other cause of difference in propositions, as 
 we have said, is the difference of terms. Terms may 
 be different either on account of their extension or 
 of their number. Hence we have difference of pro- 
 positions from the difference of terms as to their 
 extension and as to their number. 
 
 As extension renders terms singular, particular, and 
 
5 o Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 universal, so propositions under this respect may be 
 singular, particular, and universal. They are called 
 singular if their subjects be singular — as, Peter is a 
 philosopher ; particular if the subjects be particular — 
 as, Some men are good writers ; and, finally, universal 
 if the subjects be universal — as, All men are rational 
 animals. Let it be carefully remarked that the ex-' 
 tension of propositions is taken from the subjects, and 
 not from the predicate. Because the predicate is at- 
 tributed in the proposition only to the subject men-r 
 tioned, therefore the subject must determine the ex- 
 tension of the proposition ; as when I say Peter is a 
 philosopher, Longfellow is a poet, the predicate philo- 
 sopher in the example is applied only to Peter, there- 
 fore Peter must determine the extent of the proposi- 
 tion. 
 
 Q. How are propositions divided as to the number 
 of the terms? 
 
 • A. Into single and multiple. Are called single 
 when they are formed of one subject and one predi- 
 cate — as, Blessed are the meek. Are multiple when 
 they are composed of more than one subject or more 
 than one predicate ; as, Franklin was a mechanic, a 
 philosopher, and a statesman. This proposition is 
 equivalent to these three : Franklin was a mechanic, 
 Franklin was a philosopher, Franklin Avas a statesman. 
 
 There are different kinds of single and multiple pro- 
 positions. As to the single proposition, it may be so 
 by itself or by reduction. The example. The nieek are 
 blessed, shows a proposition single in itself. They arc 
 called single by reduction when, though we may affix 
 to the subject or to predicate various terms and other 
 propositions, yet they can all be reduced to one idea. 
 For instance, He who betrayed the cause of American 
 independence was Arnold, called emphatically the 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 7 1 
 
 Traitor. All this can be reduced to one idea — Arnold 
 betrayed the cause of American independence. 
 
 Multiple propositions are divided into explicit or im- 
 plicit. They are called explicit when openly they 
 have more than one term or proposition ; implicit 
 when apparently they seem to be one, but ♦^heir mean- 
 ing is equivalent to more than one, proposition — as, 
 Among animals man only is reasonable ; the word 
 only turns that proposition into two : all animals do 
 not reason, man reasons. 
 
 ARTICLE THIRD, i. 
 Properties of Propositions. 
 
 Q. What and how many are the properties of pro- 
 positions ? 
 
 A. Property is called that which follows necessarily 
 from the nature of a thing, which always accompanies 
 it and is never separated from it. Now, admitting 
 the nature of proposition, three things follow from it 
 — opposition^ conversion^ and equivalence. These are 
 consequent upon every species of proposition ; every 
 species of proposition being able to have its opposite, 
 its converse, and its equivalent. Therefore there are 
 three properties of propositions, opposition, conver- 
 sion, and equivalence. 
 
 Q. What is opposition? . 
 
 It is the affirming and denying in two propositions 
 the same predicate of the same subject, at the same 
 time and under the same respect. This opposition may 
 be threefold, contradictory, contrary, and subcontrary, 
 and hence there may be contradictory, contrary, and 
 subcontrary propositions. Propositions are called con- 
 tradictory when of the two propositions onq is uni- 
 versal, the other is particular — as. All men are just, some 
 
72 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 man is not just. They are called contrary when both 
 are universal — as, All men are just ^ all men arc not just ; 
 subcontrary when both propositions are particular — 
 some men are just ^ some men are not just. Of these last 
 St. Thomas observes that, properly speaking, they can- 
 not be called opposite, because, in order to have oppo- 
 sition, it is necessary that the subject be the same in 
 both propositions. Now, in subcontrary propositions, 
 the subject, being taken in particular, is not the same 
 in both. 
 
 Q. What have you to observe with regard to the 
 truth of such propositions? 
 
 A. I. Contradictories cannot be both true or false, 
 but one must be true and the other false. Because 
 otherwise the same thing would and would not be at 
 the same time. As in the example, All men are just, 
 some men are not just, it is evident that one of them 
 must be false, otherwi - one thing would and would 
 not be at the same time, since one proposition is in- 
 cluded in the other. 
 
 Contraries cannot be both true, because if the 
 affirmative is true the negative must be false, since 
 the predicate is affirmed and denied of the same sub- 
 ject in an universal sense. They can be either one true 
 and the other false when the predicate necessarily 
 agrees with the subject — as, All men are reasonable, all 
 men are not reasonable ; or may be both false when 
 the predicate only accidentally agrees with the sub- 
 ject — as. All men are philosophers, no man is a 
 philosopher. 
 
 Subcontraries cannot be both false, but must be 
 either both true if the predicate agrees with the sub- 
 ject only accidentally — as, Some men are rich, some 
 men are not rich; or one false and the other true 
 when the predicate agrees necessarily with the sub- 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 'j'}, 
 
 ject — as, Some men have a soul, some men have not 
 a soiil. 
 
 Q. What is the meaning of equivalence of propo- 
 sitions? • • V . 
 
 A. When we please we can reduce opposite propo- 
 sitions to the same signification, and when this is done 
 we have the equivalence of propositions. This is ac- 
 complished by means of the particle not, thus : Con- 
 tradictory propositions are rendered equivalent by 
 placing the particle not before the subject of either 
 proposition. For instance, the contradictories, All 
 men are rich, some men are not rich, I can make 
 equivalent by saying not all men are rich, and I re- 
 duce to the same sense as some men are rich. Con- 
 traries are made equivalent by placing the particle 
 not after the subject of the affirmative ; as, for in- 
 stance, All men are just, all men are not just. I can 
 put not after men in the first proposition, and reduce 
 the sense to no man is just. 
 
 Q. What is conversion? 
 
 A. The changing of the place of the predicate into 
 that of the subject, and vice versd, keeping safe the 
 truth of the proposition — as. Every man is a reason- 
 able animal ; I could say every reasonable animal is a 
 man. 
 
 Q. What is the use of equivalence and conversion? 
 
 A. They are of very great use in discovering soph- 
 isms of adversaries, in understanding obscure and 
 difficult propositions by reducing them to a clearer 
 form. 
 
 
 r 
 
 J -1 . 
 
 
CHAPTER VI. 
 
 TRUTH OF JUDGMENTS AND PROPOSITIONS. 
 
 ARTICLE FIRST. 
 
 What is Logical Truth f 
 
 Q. Give an idea of truth in general. 
 
 A. To answer this question, we must remark that 
 whatever exists may have a twofold relation with the 
 intellect. Things may be related to the intellect 
 inasmuch as they draw their existence from it, or in- 
 asmuch as they are known by it. Thus, a house is 
 referred to the intellect of the architect in a different 
 way from that in which it is referred to the intellect 
 of the beholders. To the intellect of the architect it is 
 related inasmuch as it originates from it ; to that of 
 the beholders inasmuch as it is known by it. Now, it 
 is evident that things could not exist except they were 
 conceived by the intellect, which is their cause, in 
 which case the relation they have with such intellect 
 is an essential relation ; but things could exist very 
 well without any other intellect knowing them, conse- 
 quently the relation they have with the intellect 
 which merely knows them is an accidental relation. 
 The house spoken of in the example is related essen- 
 tially to the intellect of the architect ; whereas it is 
 related only accidentally to the beholders' mind. We 
 must remark, in the second place, that between the 
 object and the conception of the intellect either pro- 
 ducing it or merely knowing it there may pass a re- 
 lation of agreement and conformity, or disagreement, 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 75 
 
 because oftentimes the object does not correspond 
 with the intellect of the artist, and frequently the in- 
 tellect does not apprehend a thing just as it is. The 
 (V^rconcnt of the thing with the intellect from ivhich tt is 
 p'odiiccd is called metaphysical truth. The agreement 
 of an object ivith the intellect knozuing it is called logical 
 truth. On the contrary, the discrepancy of the thing 
 ivith the intellect which originates it is called metaphysi- 
 cal falsehood ; and the discrepancy of the object zvith Uic 
 intellect knowing it is called logical falsehood. Both 
 kinds of truths are defined by St. Thomas the equation 
 of the object with the intellect. We shall speak in this 
 article only of logical truth, which we have defined 
 the agreement of the object with the intellect which 
 knows it. 
 
 Q. How many kinds of logical truths are there? 
 
 A. Logical truth may be different, according as we 
 coi\sider the things which are known and the manner 
 of knowing them. Considering the manner of know- 
 ing things, logical truth may be mediate or immediate. 
 It is called immediate when the intellect discovers the 
 truth of a judgment the moment it is presented to it, 
 — as, The whole is greater than any of its parts ; of this 
 judgment the intellect perceives the truth the moment 
 it perceives the terms. On the contrary, when the 
 intellect, in order to know the truth of a judgment, 
 must make use of other truths better known to it, 
 that truth is called mediate ; as, when hearing that the 
 human soul is immortal, in order to perceive the truth 
 of that proposition I must have recourse to other 
 propositions better known to me. As to the terms, 
 logical truth may be of fact and of reason. It is truth 
 of fact when the objects are subject to experience ; it 
 is of reason when the terms ar : concerned about ab- 
 stract principles. 
 
76 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 ARTICLE SECOND. 
 
 Is Truth found in the Act of Apprehension or in that 
 
 of Judgment ? 
 
 Q. In what act is truth found ? 
 
 A. The acts of our mind are three — apprehension, 
 judgment, and reasoning. Reasoning is nothing else 
 but a series of judgments and ideas formed by the 
 mind. Hence, truly, the acts of knowing are ideas 
 and judgments. Besides, strictly speaking, reasoning 
 is nothing more than a third judgment deduced from 
 two others, and is true or not according to the truth 
 and order of the two first. Hence truth can only be 
 sought in ideas and judgments. It is found perfectly 
 in judgments. Locke, Rosmini, Galuppi, and others 
 contend that it can be i'ound in ideas. We follow the 
 opinion of St. Thomas, whose doctrine on this point 
 seems to us more simple, natural, and true. It is as 
 follows : 
 
 1. Truth, really and perfectly, is only in judg- 
 ments. We prove it as follows : Truth consists in the 
 agreement between the object and the intellect, and 
 hence to know the truth is to know just this conform- 
 ity. But to know that the apprehension of the intel- 
 lect is conformable with the object is the work of 
 judgment. Therefore truth perfectly can be found 
 in judgment, because then only the intellect possesses 
 truth perfectly when it not only has it, but when it 
 knows that it has it. 
 
 Truth is that thing after which the tendency of the 
 intellect is drawn, and is, therefore, the perfection of 
 the intellect. Therefore, truly and perfecMy, it is 
 found only in that act of the mind which is a com- 
 plete and true knowledge, such as judgment. 
 
 2. Truth is found imperfectly in apprehension, 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy, 'jy 
 
 inasmuch as by means of the simple apprehension 
 the intellect apprehends something as true, but does 
 not know it to be such. In fact, simple apprehen- 
 sions of the intellect represent the essence of things, 
 as we shall see; and therefore they must be comform- 
 able to the things apprehended. Now, in this con- 
 formity between apprehension and the object appre- 
 hended lies truth. Therefore, even in aoprehension 
 we can find logical truth. But logical tru.a is said to 
 be imperfectly in apprehension and in an incipient 
 state, because the intellect, by means of the simple 
 apprehension, does not know this conformity, as this 
 belongs to judgment. 
 
 ♦ . • . • • • 
 
 . ...^ 
 
!;^v\^'Vo^A■•>■^;.'■.^•:v'..^^'■ vi"' V' '.-.^o^V'. 
 
 PART SECOND. 
 
 FORM OF REASONING. 
 
 Having treated of the matter of reasoning, which 
 are terms and propositions, we must now speak of 
 the form — that is, we must see how those terms and 
 propositions must be placed together in order to form 
 reasoning. All that can be said, however, with 
 regard to the form of reasoning may be brought 
 under four heads — first, the essential structure and 
 order of reasoning; second, its different species; 
 third, its external expression ; fourth, its defects. 
 
 CHAPTER I. 
 
 OP THE ESSENTIAL STRUCTURE OP REASONING, 
 
 ARTICLE FIRST. 
 
 Of the Structure of Reasoning in General, 
 
 Q. What is reasoning? 
 
 A. Propositions which may appear before the mind 
 are of two kinds. Some are so evident that the mo- 
 ment they "are presented before the mind their truth 
 can be at once perceived ; as, The whole is greater than 
 
 one of its parts; ,a thing cannot be and ffot be at the 
 
 78 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 79 
 
 same time. These are called truths evident of them- 
 selves, or first truths. Others, and they the greatest 
 number, are such as cannot be at once perceived by 
 the mind. For instance. The soul is immortal ; a spiri- 
 tual being cannot occupy space ; time is the measure of 
 movement, and so forth. Now, in order to know these 
 truths our mind must employ others better known to 
 it, and which have some connection and relation with 
 those it wants to know, and by placing and comparing 
 them together comes to the knowledge of those it did 
 not know. This operation is called reasoning or dis- 
 course, and may be defined tliat act of the mind by which 
 from two judgments a third is deduced, or that act which 
 deduces the unknown from the known. For instance, 
 the miiid cannot see the connection between the sub- 
 ject soul and the predicate immortal. What does it 
 do? It compares both with a third idea, to see 
 whether they agree or disagree with that third idea, 
 and if it discover that they do agree it draws the con- 
 clusion that they must agree together. This third idea 
 may be spiritual, and the reasoning may be constructed 
 as follows : 
 
 That which is spiritual is immortal. 
 
 But the soul is spiritual. 
 
 Therefore it is immortal. 
 
 Q. What is the order of reasoning ? 
 
 A. It consists exactly in this: The mind wishes to 
 know if a proposition be true or false ; in other words, 
 if a predicate agrees with a subject. In order to find 
 this out, the mind does nothing more nor less than 
 what men do when they wish to find out if the length 
 of two bodies is tne same or not: they take a tiiird 
 one as a rule, and try it first with the one and then 
 with the other ; and thus they can tell if their length 
 agrees together or not. The mind does the same 
 
8o Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 when it wants to know if a predicate agrees with a 
 subject. It takes a third idea, and makes it, as it 
 were, the rule or measure, and compares it first with 
 the subject and then with the predicate. Now, natu- 
 rally three suppositions can result from this compari- 
 son : I. That third idea may be found to agree both 
 with the predicate and the subject. 2. It may be 
 found to agree with the one and not with the other. 
 3. It may be found to agree with neither. In the 
 first case, when the third idea is found to agree both 
 with the subject and the predicate, then the mind 
 knows and concludes that the predicate and subject 
 agree together, founded on that principle that two things 
 which agree zvith a third agree together. For instance, 
 the mind does not know if the soul is simple. It takes 
 for a third idea that which has no parts, and compares 
 subject and predicate with that third idea, thus: That 
 which is simple has no parts. But the soul has no 
 parts ; therefore it is simple. These reasonings are 
 called affirmative. In the second case, when the 
 third idea is seen to agree with the one and not with 
 the other, the mind concludes that they do not agree 
 together, on the principle that i7vo things^ one of which 
 agrees zvith a third and the other 7iot, do not agree to- 
 gether. For instance, the mind knows the disagree- 
 ment between these two ideas, a material substance 
 and the human soul, by means of the third idea, a 
 thinking substance, and reasons thus : A thinking 
 substance is not material. But the soul is a thinking 
 substance; therefore it is not material. Here the 
 third idea, a thinking substance, agrees with the sub- 
 ject soul, but not with the predicate material. In the 
 third supposition nothing can be concluded, as, the 
 third idea not agreeing with any of the terms, no con- 
 nection whatever is established between them. 
 
Elements of Intellectual Ph ilosophy. 8 1 
 
 Q. What are, then, the elements and fundamental 
 principles of reasonini^? 
 
 A. It must result from three propositions, and 
 these ordained in such a way that the mind may see 
 the last proposition as included in the two first. 
 
 It must be formed of three terms : the subject, the 
 predicate, and the third idea. 
 
 We have said three propositions ; because in every 
 reasoning three comparisons are made, one of the 
 predicate with the third idea ; the other of the third 
 idea with the subject ; the third of the subject with 
 the predicate. And from each of these comparisons 
 arise a judgment and a proposition. They must be 
 arranged in such a way that the last be contained in 
 the two first ; otherwise there would be no reasoning, 
 but three unconnected propositions. The three terms 
 are called as follows : The predicate the major term, 
 because ordinarily speaking it is more extensive ; the 
 subject the minor term, because generally more re- 
 stricted ; the third idea the middle tQrrc\y from the office 
 which it exercises. Likewise also the propositions : 
 that in which the third idea is compared with the 
 predicate is called the major proposition ; that in which 
 the third id^a is compared with the subject is called 
 the minor ; that in which the subject and the predicate 
 are compared is called consequent or consequence. 
 And because ordinarily in the first proposition the 
 predicate is compared with the third idea, and in the 
 second the subject is compared with the third idea, 
 the first is always called the major, the .second the 
 minor, and both together, in regard to the conse- 
 quence, are caW^d premises. 
 
 All reasonings are either affirmative or negative. 
 The foundation of the affirm:*tive is that principle 
 that tivo things which agree with a third agree together* 
 
82 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 .' 
 Of the negative the principle is tivo things of which 
 one agrees with a thirds ami the other does not, cannot 
 agree together. 
 
 Now, gathering together all wc have said, it is 
 evident that in order to have reasoning the following 
 things are necessary : ist. That the mind be respect- 
 ing the truth of a proposition in the state of doubt, 
 desirous to rem v^e it ; this is the end of reasoning. 
 2d. It must have a third idea, which is the means 
 whereby it reasons. 3d. It must compare this third 
 idea with the terms of the proposition it wants to 
 know, which constitutes the nse of that third idea. 
 4th. It must deduce from that comparison the truth 
 it wants to find out, which is the effect of reasoning. 
 We shall speak of each of these separately. 
 
 ARTICLE SECOND. 
 Of the End which causes the Mind to Reason. 
 
 Q. What are the difierent states the mind may find 
 itself in with regard to truth ? 
 
 A. The end which incites the mind to reason is 
 that it may remove that state of doubt in which it 
 finds itself with regard, to a certain truth, and take up 
 another state. To explain this properly we must 
 give an idea of the different states in which the mind 
 may find itself with regard to truth. Our mind, 
 when a truth is presented before it, may be affected 
 if. three different ways. It may adhere to it without 
 any hesitation or fear of its contrary ; it may adhere 
 to it with a certain hesitation and fear of its con- 
 trary ; or it may not adhere to it at all and remain in a 
 state of suspense, hanging, as it were, between yes and 
 no. Each of these things constitutes a state of the 
 mind with regard to truth : the first is called certainty ; 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 83 
 
 the second is called probability or opinion ; the thir<l 
 is called doubt. 
 
 Q. What is certainty ? 
 
 A. That state of the mind by which it firmly adheres to 
 a known truth ivithoiit fear of the opposite. It may be 
 metaphysical, physical, and moral. It is called metaphy- 
 sical certainty when it is founded on the very essence 
 of things ; for instance, it is metaphysically certain 
 that a square has four sides. .It is called physical 
 when it is founded on the constancy of natural and 
 physical laws, as it is physically certain that a body 
 gravitates towards its centre. It is called moral when 
 it is founded on the testimony of men and the laws 
 governing human acts ; as, for instance, it is morally 
 certain that Washington was the first President of 
 the United States. Hence, ?is it is evident, meta- 
 physical certainty is absolute, as founded on the 
 essences of things which are immutable. Physical 
 and moral certainties are hypothetical, as they 
 are founded on the supposition of the constancy 
 of the laws which govern the physical and the 
 moral world. This last observation gives rise to an- 
 other distinction of certainty, intritisic and extrinsic. 
 It is intrinsic when it arises from the knowledge of the 
 thing itself. It is extrinsic when it is founded on the 
 testimony of others. 
 
 O. How many degrees of certainty are there? 
 
 A. Certainty is made up of two elements the cling- 
 ing of the mind to the truth ; and the exclusion of 
 any tendency to the opposite. Now, as regards the 
 second element, certainty has no degrees, because this 
 excluding all fear of the opposite is incapable either 
 of increase or diminution. As regards the first ele- 
 ment, the clinging of the mind, .this may admit of 
 degrees, as the mind may cling to a truth with more 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy, 
 
 or less tenacity ; for instance, in metaphysical cer- 
 tainty the clinging of the nnind is stronger and more 
 tenacious than in the other two. 
 
 Q. What is probability ? 
 
 A. That state of the mind in ivJiich it adheres to a 
 truth luith a kind of fear of the opposite. It may be 
 also intrinsic and extrinsic. It is intrinsic when 
 founded on the essence of the thing itself, extrinsic 
 when it is founded pn arguments outside the thing 
 itself. M , 
 
 It may have different degrees, according to the va- 
 lue and number of arguments and motives which sup- 
 port it. Because an opinion in respect to another 
 opinion may be equally probable, more probable, 
 most probable in proportion as the arguments sup- 
 porting it grow in weight and number. But it must 
 be remarked that all these degrees of probability can 
 never, no matter what their weight or number may 
 be, reach to certainty, because if they remain probable 
 they must always imply some fear of the opposite, 
 and no being by mere union with another of the 
 same kind can change its nature, hence, even united 
 together, all these degrees of probability must imply 
 some fear of the opposite. But certainty essentially 
 excludes all fear. Therefore a number of degrees of 
 probability can never give certainty. 
 
 Q. What is doubt? 
 
 A. That state of the mind in which it does not 
 adhere either to one side or the other of an object 
 proposed, but haags in suspense. It has been beauti- 
 fully personified by Spenser in his " Faerie Queene " : 
 
 '* His name was Doubt, that had a double face ; 
 Th* one forward looking, th' other backward bent." 
 
 J , - ■ 
 
 As it is clear, doubt differs from certainty and pro- 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 85 
 
 bability.. because both imply adliesion ; doubt implies 
 suspension. 
 
 It may be positive or negative, because the mind 
 may withdraw its adhesion either because it sees no 
 reason in the one or other of the two things, or be- 
 cause it perceives equal reasons on both sides. From 
 which it appears that a negative doubt cannot have 
 any degrees, whereas the positive can, in proportion as 
 the reasons pro and con diminish or increase ; in the 
 latter case the doubt approaches nearer to probability. 
 
 Q. Wiiat is ignorance \ 
 
 A. The absence of knowledge. \Vc have not 
 enumerated it among the states of* the mind because 
 it is rather the absence of a state. 
 
 Q. In what state is the mind before reasoning? 
 
 A. In the state of doubt. It could not be in igno- 
 rance, because he who is ignorant about something 
 cannot wish for nor seek it. Now, to reason is to 
 seek for something. Therefore, when the mind pro- 
 ceeds to reason it cannot be in ignorance. It' cannot 
 be in a state of adhesion or certainty* because if it 
 knew a truth it would not seek for it. Therefore, in 
 order to reason the mind must neither be in itjnorance 
 nor in the state of adhesion, but must be wavering 
 between the two ; neither be ignorant altogether nor 
 certain, but in the state of doubt. Doubt, therefore, 
 must always go before reasoning and demonstration. 
 Hence the truth which the mind wants to find out by 
 reasoning before the demonstration is called the qtics- 
 tion ; after, it is called thesis. This do '.bt is called 
 methodical doubt. And it is distinguished from that 
 of the sceptics and from that of Descartes. Sceptics 
 doubted of everything, and wished to remain in doubt ; 
 whereas the doubt called methodical is invented just 
 to bring one out of doubt, and it is called methodical 
 
86 Elements of Intellectual Pkilosophy. 
 
 because it is taken and supposed by necessity of 
 metliod, whereas the doubt of the sceptics is called 
 systematic because assumed on system. It is dis- 
 tinguished from that of Descartes, who held that 
 science must proceed from doubt; but his doubt was 
 universal, extending to all first and self-evident truths, 
 whereas oui' doubt is particular, extending only to 
 those truths of mediate evidence which need to be 
 demonstrated. 
 
 Q. What does the mind aim at in reasoning ? 
 
 A. It seeks to remove the state of doubt and to as- 
 sume another state. But doubt excluded, there are no 
 other states but that of probability and certainty. 
 Therefore the mind in reasoning aims at probability and 
 certainty. From this arises the division of reasoning 
 \vito probable and apodictic^ though strictly speaking the 
 mind in reasoning properly aims at certainty, and at 
 probability only indirectly and incidentally. The rea- 
 son is this : In probability, as we have said, two ele- 
 ments are found, the adhesion of the mind to the object 
 and the fear of the contrary. Now, the mind when it 
 aims at probability in reasoning is not led to do so from 
 the fear oTthe opposite, for in this respect probability 
 is akin to doubt, and the mind would shrink from it as 
 it does from doubt. Therefore it aims at probability, 
 to adhere to the truth and to avoid the fear of the 
 opposite. Hence it strictly aims at certainty, which 
 excludes fear and implies firmness of adhesion. When 
 it cannot possibly attain certainty, then it aims at 
 probability; but only indirectly and accidentally. We 
 may, therefore, draw as a general conclusion of the 
 whole article that the mind in reasoning aims at cer- 
 tainty as the proper end of that operation. 
 
. Elements of Intellectual Philosophy, 87 
 
 ARTICLE THIRD. 
 
 Of the Means which the Mind uses in Reasoning, or 
 of the Middle Term, 
 
 Q. What is meant by middle term ? 
 
 A. It is that third idea with which the mind com- 
 pares the predicate and the subject. It finds it out as 
 follows : When the mind doubts about a proposition 
 it shows that it does not know its truth or its false- 
 ilood. Now, to know the truth or falsehood of a pro- 
 position does not mean anything else but to know the 
 unity or non-unity of being between the predicate and 
 the subject ; or, in other words, to know if the predi- 
 cate be or not the same as the subject ; since the 
 whole form of a proposition consists in telling if the 
 subject be the predicate or not. To reason, there- 
 fore, is to endeavor to know the unity or non-unity of 
 being between the subject and the predicate. Hence 
 to find the middle term is nothing else than to find the 
 similitude or agreement between the predicate and the 
 subject. Now, when we want to find out a similitude 
 between two things which is not yet apparent, the 
 way we follow is this : to consider both things from 
 every side, to see if we can find out some com "^n, 
 point of resemblance. In the same manner the m: * 
 acts when it proceeds to reason ; it considers from 
 every point of view the subject and the predicate, to 
 see if it can find some point wliich may present a 
 similitude with or difference from the other. This 
 point of similitude which it finds first in the one and 
 then in the other, or of difference which it finds in. one 
 and not in the other, it assumes as the middle term. 
 Hence to find the middle term we must consider both 
 subject and predicate from every possible side. 
 
 Q. What and how many are these sides according 
 
88 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 to which we may consider the terms of a proposition, 
 and from them draw the middle term ? - ; » 
 
 A, They are ten ; and from the office they fulfil 
 are called common points, or topics, of argumentation, 
 because the predicate and the subject cannot be con- 
 sidered except from these points of cause, effect, subject, 
 adjuncts, contraries, similes, name, dejinition, division, 
 and authority. From all these we can take ,the mid- 
 dle term. -^ ^ •= . .i • 
 
 Q. Give an example from each. >f •: ." o^^ ";-fi; 
 
 A. We take the middle term from cause when we 
 show the effects from these causes ; as, for instance, 
 showing from its material cause that the human body 
 is corruptible ; thus, that which is made of matter is 
 corruptible. But the human body is made of matter, 
 therefore it is corruptible. 
 
 From the effects we take the middle term, showing 
 the cause from its effects. The most wonderful dra- 
 matic productions argue a most powerful imagina- 
 tion. But Shakspere has produced the most won- 
 derful plays, therefore he must have had the most 
 powerful imagination. *' f'i^'' '/**'• ■■ " >.'*''. : 
 
 We take the middle term from the subject when we 
 show of the accident something deduced from its sub- 
 ject ; for instance, that quality which leans on a more, 
 noble subject is in itself more noble. But the quali- 
 ties of the soul lean on a subject more noble than the 
 •body, therefore they are more noble than those ot- 
 the body. -nur, •!»> njrA-^ 
 
 'j^-From the adjuncts or circumstances when we show 
 something from all that surrounds the subject, such 
 as t.'me, place, persons, means, and the like. 
 
 Fiom contraries, making one contrary exclude an- 
 other ; as, for instance, T'^uth is a good of the intel- 
 lect, therefore falsehood is its evil 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy, 89 
 
 From similes, showing one to be like to the other ; as, 
 Americans gained their independence by those virtues 
 which make up pure patriotism, therefore they will 
 continue to preserve it by the same virtues. v?;** 
 
 We take the middle term from the name in two 
 ways: i. From its signification; as, Angel mean? a 
 messenger, therefore angels are messengers between 
 God and men. From its etymology philosophy means 
 love of wisdom, therefore philosophers love wisdom. 
 
 From the definition is drawn the middle term when 
 we argue from those elements which compose it ; 
 as, science is to know a thing from the principles 
 which constitute it. But I know the principles of a 
 certain subject, therefore I have the science of that 
 subject. 
 
 From division we take the middle term when we 
 argue from the parts to the whole, and from the whole 
 to the parts. As, for instance, the head, the arms, the 
 hands, the fingers, and all the other parts of the 
 human body are animated, therefore the whole body 
 is animated. <.. , ... ' ,> .. .. . ..'\^:uu 
 
 Finally from authority, when we take the middle 
 term from the authority of others. 
 
 Q. What criterion must guide us in assuming the 
 middle term? .,, , ,. , ,(;.,i,..| ,..;> •; ■ . 
 
 A. In assuming the middle term we must pay atten- 
 tion to two rules : ist, In affirmative propositions the 
 middle term must never be more extensive or ample 
 than the predicate. For instance, to show that man 
 is an animal I could not take the middle term, sub- 
 stance, and say. Man is substance; but the substance 
 is animal, therefore man is an animal. This reason- 
 ing proves nothing, because the middle term, sub- 
 stance, is much more extensive than animal. Again, 
 the following reasoning would be vain : Peter is a man; 
 
go Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 but John is a man, therefore John is Peter. Here the 
 middle term, man, is more ample than Peter. 
 I 2d. On the contrary, in negative propositions the 
 middle term must not be more restricted than the 
 predicate. The following reasoning would, therefore, 
 be bad : The finite is material ; but the soul is not 
 material, therefore it is not finite. The reasoning is 
 false because the middle term, material, is taken in a 
 more restricted sense than the predicate, finite. The 
 reason of both rules is found in what we have already 
 said. The middle term is that side of similitude or 
 difference by means of which the predicate agrees with 
 the subject in force or not. But in affirmative propo- 
 sitions the predicate must agree with the subject in all 
 its comprehension ; therefore the middle term, which 
 must represent that comprehension, must not be more 
 extensive than the predicate, otherwise it would have 
 less comprehension. On the contrary, in negative 
 propositions the predicate must be denied of the sub- 
 ject in all its extension. Therefore the mrddle term, 
 which must represent that extension, must not be less 
 extensive than the predicate. , .. .; , , , ,,,.; j 
 
 ■ri.,,. ;, . ARTICLE FOURTH. ., ..: . \ .U 
 
 Of the Use of the Middle Tcriiiy or of Figures and 
 
 Modes. 
 
 , Q. How is the middle term to be used ? 
 i A. The use of an instrument or means consists in 
 making it available for the end for which it has been 
 invented. Now, the middle term is intended for the 
 object of comparing it with the two terms of the pro- 
 position by means of the artificial structure of the 
 premises ; therefore the proper use of the middle term 
 consists in this comparison and in the artificial struc- 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy, 91 
 
 ture of the premises. This comparison may be made 
 in different ways. Because the middle term in that 
 comparison may vary in two ways, either because of 
 the place it occupies in the structure of the reasoning, 
 and of the figure it makes in the premises, now ap- 
 pearing as predicate and now as subject, or because 
 of the manner according to which propositions are 
 formed, negative or affirmative, universal or particular, 
 by the help of the same middle term. The diversity 
 which the structure of the reasoning takes from the 
 figure the middle term makes in the premises is called 
 the figure of syllogism ; that which arises from the 
 second — that is, the different manner of propositions — 
 is called the mode of syllogism. Hence, to understand 
 what and how many are the uses of the middle term 
 we must speak of the figures and modes of syllogism. 
 
 Q. What is a figure? 
 
 A. That different disposition which the middle tertn 
 takes in relation to the extreme terms in the premises. 
 
 This disposition or placing may be made in^ three 
 different ways. The first is, when the middle term is 
 subject in the major and predicate in the minor, as in 
 this reasoning : Every animal (middle term subject) 
 has a sensitive appetite ; but man is an animal (middle 
 term predicate), therefore man has a sensitive appetite. 
 
 The second way is, when the middle term acts as 
 predicate in both premises. Every man is endowed 
 with reason ; but no horse is endowed with reason ; 
 therefore no horse is man. • ' ''•"'^ " ^ i ^^ u 
 
 The third is, when the middle term officiates as sub- 
 ject in both premises ; as, for instance, Being is op- 
 posed to nothingness. But being is identical with 
 good ; therefore good is opposed to nothingness. 
 
 There is a fourth figure which can be reduced to the 
 first ; therefore we do not speak of it. 
 
92 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 Q. V^XxdX 2S^ modes ? :;;;!," ... 
 1 A . 7 Z/^y may be defined the disposition or locating of the 
 premises according to their universality or particularity, 
 their affirtnation or negation, , - r. ;; ^ ;•, 
 
 Q. How many modes can a syllogism have? 
 
 A. Sixty-four; because every figure can have six- 
 teen modes, since in every figure the premises may be 
 either both universal or both particular, or the major 
 universal and the minor particular ; and each of these 
 modes has four others under it, according to affirma- 
 tion or negation, because the premises, either univer- 
 sal or particular, may be both affirmative or both 
 negative, or the major negative and the minor affirma- 
 tive, or vice versa. Of all these modes only ten arrive 
 at a conclusion. Each one may amuse himself by 
 enumerating them for exercise. 
 
 '■*■" 
 
 ' ARTICLE FIVE. 
 
 Of the Deduction of the Consequent from the Premises. 
 
 : Q. In what manner is the consequence deduced 
 from the premises known by the intellect? . ,' , 
 f A. We can gather from all we have said that in 
 reasoning the mind in the major compares the middle 
 term with the predicate, and sees that they agree to- 
 gether ; hence, when in the minor it comes to compare 
 the middle term with the subject, it may be really 
 said to be comparing the predicate with the subject, 
 because it knows and has seen in the major that the 
 predicate is the same as the middle term. In a word, 
 in the minor it sees the predicate in the subject by 
 means of the middle term as through a lens. From 
 this we can conclude how the mind comes to the 
 knowledge of the consequence. Because that which 
 it affirms without hesitation in the consequence it has 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 93 
 
 already seen in the minor, and would contradict itself 
 if it affirmed in the consequent something contrary to 
 what it has said in the premises. Hence, it has been 
 rightly said that the premises stand to the knowledge 
 of the consequences as the cause to the effect, because 
 the mind, having known the premises, cannot ignore 
 the consequences, as, having supposed the action of 
 the cause, the effect must follow. 
 
 ARTICLE SIXTH. 
 Rules of Reasoning, 
 
 Q. How many rules of reasoning are there ? 
 
 A. The following: 1st. There cannot be more than 
 three terms in the reaso7iing. The reason of the rule 
 may be gathered from all we have said. But here we 
 must observe that oftentimes a fourth term is hidden, 
 and this happens when a term is used equivocally, now 
 in one sense and then in another — as, for instance, the 
 rat is a syllable; but a syllable cannot eat cheese, 
 therefore the rat cannot eat cheese. 
 
 2d rule. In the conclusion no term must be taken in a 
 more extensive sense than it has in the premises ; be- 
 cause that which is more extensive and universal can- 
 not be found in that which is less so. Hence, if the 
 term in the conclusion is taken in a^ more universal 
 sense, it cannot be found in the premises and could 
 not be deduced from it. Against this rule is that 
 sopl.ism of Cellius: "You are not what I am; but I 
 am a man, therefore you are not a man." 
 
 3d rule. The middle term should not enter into the con- 
 clusion, because its use consists in comparing it with 
 the other two terms, which is only done in the pre- 
 mises — as, for instance. Napoleon was a general ; but 
 Napoleon was poor, therefore Napoleon was a poor 
 
94 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 . , '■ ■ ' 
 
 general. Shakspere was a poet ; but Shakspere was 
 
 poor, therefore he was a poor poet. 
 
 4th rule. The middle tertn must be takett in a uni- 
 versal sense^ at least in one of tJie premises ; because if 
 it was taken in a particular sense in both premises we 
 should have two terms and not one — as, for instance, 
 a certain animal is endowed with reason ; but the 
 nightingale is a certain animal, therefore the nightin- 
 gale is endowed with reason. 
 
 5th rule. No conclusion can be drawn from two nega- 
 tive propositions, because when both are negative it is 
 clear that the middle term agrees neither with the 
 predicate nor with the subject, and therefore nothing 
 can be concluded from them. Hence the following 
 reasoning would be bad : Man is not eternal ; but the 
 animal is not eternal, therefore man is not an animal. 
 
 6th rule. No coficlusion can be drawn from two par- 
 ticular premises^ because in this case the middle term 
 would be taken in particular senses in both premises. 
 
 7th rule. The cojiclusion must share ifi the fortune of 
 the zueaker party ; that is to say, if one of the premises 
 is particular the conclusion must be particular, be- 
 cause otherwise the terms would be more ample in the 
 conclusion than in the premises ; if of the premises 
 one is negative, the other affirmative, the conclusion 
 must be negative, because in this second case the mid- 
 dle term agrees with the one and not with the other, 
 and therefore subject and predicate do not agree 
 together. 
 
 8th rule. We cannot draw a negative conclusicn from 
 two affirmative premises. The reason is clear. 
 
 V ♦ .{- 
 
CHAPTER II. 
 
 DIFFERENT SPECIES OF REASONING. 
 ARTICLE FIRST. 
 
 Of the Variety of Reasonings ; and, first, of the Indue- 
 
 tive Syllogism. 
 
 Q. Whence arises variety of syllogisms? 
 
 A. We must distinguish three things in the mid- 
 dle term : i. What it is in itself. 2. The connec- 
 tion which it has with the extreme terms. 3. The 
 special form by which they are connected. Because, 
 the middle term must be something in itself, and in 
 order to become the middle term must have some con- 
 nection with the extreme terms, and also have such 
 connection under a certain form. Now, since the 
 variety of syllogisms originates in the middle term, it 
 is clear that such a variety arises from the three heads 
 just mentioned — that is, from the intrinsic diversity of 
 the middle term, from the different connection it has 
 with the extremes, and from the difference of form. 
 
 Q. What is the division arising from the first head ? 
 
 A. From the first head arises the division of syllo- 
 gisms into inductive and deductive, or into indtiction 
 and syllogism properly so called. Because the middle 
 term, considered in itself, may represent either a uni- 
 versal idea or particular ideas ; in other words, it may 
 represent a whole from which a part is deduced, or 
 the parts from which the whole arises. In the first 
 case the syllogism is called deductive or syllogism 
 
96 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. , 
 
 simply, in the second it is called inductive or induc- 
 tion simply. 
 
 Q. What is induction ? 
 
 A. That kind of reasoning in which, from the 
 enumeration of the particular parts of a subject, is 
 •gathered the whole and the universal. For instance, 
 the lion, the horse, the ox, the leopard, man, and the 
 like are sensitive. But all these constitute the genus 
 animal ; therefore the genus animal is sensitive. 
 
 Induction may be of two kinds, complete and in- 
 complete, because the enumeration of the particulars 
 may be complete or incomplete, and according as it 
 is the one or the other induction is complete or incom- 
 plete. I 
 
 O. What is to be observed as to the incomplete 
 induction ? 
 
 A. Wc must carefully observe in what sense we 
 can say that the enumeration of its parts is not com- 
 plete. Because if by this it is meant to convey the idea 
 that from an incomplete enumeration of parts we 
 can draw a general consequence without adding to or 
 supposing anything more in that incomplete enu- 
 meration, as some modern logicians have thought, it 
 is false, and would be contrary to that rule of reason- 
 ing which forbids 'the consequence to have a greater 
 extension than the premises. The whole is certainly 
 more ample and universal than some of its parts. 
 But in the incomplete induction, according to these 
 logicians, the consequence contains the whole because 
 universal, and the premises contain only some parts 
 because the induction is incomplete ; therefore the 
 incomplete induction, as it is explained by some 
 modern logicians, is repugnant to the fundamental 
 rules of syllogisms, because in it the consequence is 
 more ample than the premises. Therefore, in order 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy, 97 
 
 to avoid such inconvenient, if the enumeration of 
 parts is not complete it must be made so in some 
 way. This is done by adding after the incomplete 
 enumeration of parts the phrases and so forth, and the 
 like^^s the ancients observed, who held that induction 
 could conclude nothing except to the enumeration of 
 parts one could add and so on of the rest. 
 
 Q. For what reason and upon what foundation 
 could you add and so on of the rest ? 
 
 A. That phrase is added in force of the principles of 
 analogy, that nature is limited to one thing ; that nature ^ 
 ivhen not prevented^ zvorks always in the same manner. 
 Upon this, having observed that a certain property is 
 constantly found in many individuals, we become as- 
 sured that it belongs to their nature ; and because 
 nature works always in the same way in all individu- 
 als, we attribute the same property to the rest of the 
 individuals not mentioned in the enumerations. The 
 true difference, therefore, between complete and in- 
 complete induction is this : that in the first the enu- 
 meration of parts is actually complete ; in the other 
 it is not actually complete, but becomes so by means 
 of the phrases, and so on luith the rest, and the like. 
 
 Q. What is the principle on which both deductions 
 rest? 
 
 A. That which agrees or disagrees ivith all the par- 
 ticidars implied in the idea of the subject agrees or dis- 
 agrees with the subject taken as a whole or universally. 
 
 Q. What has Bacon done with regard to induction? 
 
 A. Modern philosophers sing loudly the praises of 
 Bacon for the services he has rendered to philosophy 
 in teaching the inductive process. But we have to 
 observe that he has done nothing as to the logical 
 form of induction which was not known and tauejht 
 by the ancients. All that Bacon has done is to point 
 
98 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy, 
 
 out the way how to proceed in the observation of par- 
 ticular facts by way of negation and affirmation, so 
 that truly he has treated only of the most common 
 part of induction. 
 
 ARTICLE SECOND. 
 
 Of Deductive Syllogism and its Species. 
 
 Q. What is deductive syllogism ? 
 
 A. If, in reasoning, instead of particulars we take 
 the universal as the middle term, then we have the 
 inductive syllogism, or syllogism properly so called, 
 which may be defined that reasoning in which from 
 the luiiversal is deduced the particular contained in it — 
 for instance, Every animal is sensitive ; but man is an 
 animal, therefore he is sensitive. 
 
 Q. How many kinds of syllogisms are there? 
 
 A. Several, i. The syllogism h priori and ii pos- 
 teriori. The first is that in which the middle term is 
 something which by its nature is understood before 
 that which it is intended to demonstrate, and acts as 
 the cause of that which is demonstrated. Hence it is 
 called also from the cause — for instance, every being 
 endowed with reason has a will ; but man is endowed 
 with reason, therefore he has a will. Here the middle 
 term, reason, is the true cause of the will, as reason io a 
 rational tendency. The second is when we assume as 
 middle term something which is conceived by the 
 mind as posterior to the thing which we want to de- 
 monstrate, as when we prove a thing from its effects 
 or properties. 
 
 2. Syllogisms from the proximate reason and from 
 the remote, reason. The first is that in which the mid- 
 dle term contains the proximate and adequate reason 
 of the thing. The second is that in which the middle 
 term contains only the remote cause of the thing. 
 
Elemenis of Intellectual Philosophy. 99 
 
 3. Direct and indirect syllogisms. The first is that in 
 which the middle term contains a truth which has some 
 connection with the proposition to be demonstrated. 
 It is called indirect when, having supposed, as hypothe- 
 sis, the contrary proposition, we take as middle term 
 an absurdity, and show that the absurdity proceeds 
 from that hypothesis. It is called also demonstration 
 from absurd consequences. For instance, wishing to 
 demonstrate the free will of man, we take as middle 
 term the absurdities which would follow from the de- 
 nial of it — for instance, the destruction of virtue, of 
 reward and penalty, etc. 
 
 4. Syllogisms from statements admitted by adversa- 
 ries, called ex datis, and it is that in which the middle 
 term is something admitted by the adversary. 
 
 ARTICLE THIRD. 
 
 Of Demonstrative or Apodictic, and Probable Syllogisms, 
 
 Q. What is the next thing to be considered in the 
 middle term, and what division of the syllogisms arises 
 therefrom ? 
 
 A. The next thing to be considered in the middle 
 term is the connection it has with the extremes, and 
 from this arises another division of the syllogism — that 
 of demonstrative and probable. This division of the 
 syllogism is made from its efficacy in demonstrating a 
 truth. But the efficacy of reasoning results from the 
 connection which the middle term has with the ex- 
 tremes; therefore this division of the syllogism into de- 
 monstrative and probable depends on the connection 
 which the middle term has with the extremes. Thus, 
 in order to have a demonstrative syllogism, it is neces- 
 sary that the middle term should be so connected with 
 the extremes as to contain tho: proximate, necessary, and 
 
I oo Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 proper cause of a thing. Cause ^?\\\zf^ the syllogism is 
 intended to produce science, that is, knowledge certain, 
 necessary, and evident. But science is knowledge de- 
 duced from its cause ; therefore the middle term of the 
 demonstrative syllogism must contain the cause. This 
 cause must be necessary, because, if it were acciden- 
 tal, the conclusion would not be necessary, and hence 
 unscientific. It must be the proper cause, because a 
 common cause would belong not only to the thing we 
 want to demonstrate, but also to others, and therefore 
 could produce only probable knowledge. It must 
 be tic proximate cause, since the remote cause would 
 give but an inadequate knowledge. 
 
 Q. What is probable syllogism, and by what criterion 
 may we distinguish it from the other? 
 
 A. The syllogism is called probable when its middle 
 term has no necessary connection with the extremes — 
 as, for instance, when the middle term is drawn from 
 etymology, from authority, from a common cause, from 
 effects not necessarily connected with that reason 
 alone and such as can originate in some other cause, 
 etc., or from some accident, etc. By keeping in view 
 all these things one can have a criterion to distinguish 
 the probable from the demonstrative syllogism. 
 
 ARTICLE. FOURTH. 
 Of Categorical and IlypotJictical Syllogisms. 
 
 Q. Define these two kinds of syllogisms. 
 
 A. The connection of the middle term with the ex- 
 tremes must be put in a special form. Now, gene- 
 rally speaking, the middle term may be conwected with 
 the extremes in two forms, either in an absolute way 
 or conditionally; hence the division of syllogisms 
 into categorical and conditional or hypothetical. 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. loi 
 
 The categorical or absolute syllogism is that in 
 which the middle term is connected with the extremes 
 in an absolute way. The conditional is that in which 
 the middle term is connected by way of a conditional 
 proposition in the major. iVIoderns call the first sim- 
 ple and the second composite. 
 
 Q. What are the species of conditional syllogisms? • 
 
 A. A conditional syllogism is that in which the mid- 
 dle term in the major is bound by a certain condition. 
 Therefore this syllogism may be of as many kinds as 
 there are ways in which a term may be bound to an- 
 other by way of condition — that is to say, as there are 
 species of conditional propositions. Now, these pro- 
 positions are of three kinds — connex, conjiuictive, and 
 disjunctive. Therefore there are three kinds of condi- 
 tional syllogism — connex, conjunctive, and disjunctive. . 
 
 The first is that in whir': ihe major is a connex pro- 
 position. For instance, If the soul is a spiritual princi- 
 ple, it is immortal ; but the soul is a spiritual princi- 
 ple, therefore it is immortal. 
 
 The second is that in which the major is a conjunc- 
 tive proposition ; as, One cannot sleep and be awake 
 at the same time ; but John is asleep, therefore he is 
 not awake. 
 
 The third is that in which the major is a disjunctive 
 proposition ; as, Peter is either alive or dead ; but he is 
 alive, therefore he is not dead. 
 
 .-■ V '■■'■■ ■ ' ' ' '■ * I. y ■« ■ . ' s ' . ' . ' 
 
CHAPTER III. 
 
 OF THE EXPRESSION OP REASONING. 
 ARTICLE FIRST. 
 
 Different Ways of Expressing a Reasoning. 
 
 (^. Define the different ways of giving expression 
 to reasoning. 
 
 A. Besides syllogism and induction, of which we 
 have spoken, there are the enthymeme, the epichi- 
 lema, the sorites, the prosyllogism, and the dilemma. 
 
 Oftentimes in reasoning the premises are so easy 
 and clear that we omit one of them — as. Virtue is the 
 greatest good in the world ; therefore it should be 
 practised. Here the major is left out ; that is, that 
 which is the greatest good should be practised. When 
 the reasoning is so expressed it is called enthymeme. 
 On the contrary, we have the epichirema when to 
 one or both premises we add proof — as, Idleness is 
 hurtful because the parent of all vices. But what is 
 hurtful should be avoided, therefore idleness should be 
 avoided. 
 
 The sorites is a reasoning composed of several pro- 
 positions, so arranged that the predicate of the first is 
 the subject of the second, and so on until in the conse- 
 quence the predicate of the first proposition is united 
 with the subject of the last — as. Truth is the object of 
 the intellect. That which is the object of the intel- 
 lect perfects it. That which perfects the intellect is 
 the proper good of man. That which is the proper 
 
 to* 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 103 
 
 good of man is to be followed. Therefore truth is to 
 be followed. 
 
 The prosyllogism is the union of two syllogisms so 
 connected together that the consequence of the first 
 officiates as the major of the second. For instance, 
 Sensible goods do not fully satisfy human aspirations ; 
 but that which does not fully satisfy human aspira- 
 tions is not the true happiness of a man, therefore 
 reasonable goods are the true happiness of man. But 
 that which is not man's true happiness must not be 
 exclusively sought for ; therefore sensible goods must 
 not be exclusively sought for. 
 
 The dilemma is a syllogism which has for its mrjor 
 a disjunctive proposition, and from each of the 
 members of which we endeavor to draw a conclusion 
 against the adversary. For instance : Christianity was 
 either propagated by the force of miracles or without 
 miracles. If it was propagated by miracles, it is 
 divine ; if it was not propagated by miracles, this is 
 the greatest of all miracles, that a religion opposed by 
 the whole world and contradicting all human passions 
 should subdue this world and should be propagated 
 all over by twelve rude and ignorant fishermen. 
 
 All these expressions of reasoning can be reduced to 
 the syllogism, as one can easily see by himself; as, for 
 instance, the dilemma given above may be reduced to 
 the following syllogisms : If the Christian religion was 
 propagated by means of miracles it is divine. But it 
 was propagated by means of miracles, therefore it is 
 divine. The minor is proved by this other syllogism : 
 If we deny that miracles propagated it, we must ac- 
 count for that propagation effected without miracles. 
 But this would be a greater miracle under the circum- 
 stances ; therefore the Christian religion was propa- 
 gated by means of miracles. 
 
CHAPTER IV. 
 
 ;; FAULTS OF REASONING. 
 
 '* ARTICLE FIRST. 
 
 Sophistries of Thought, 
 
 Q. What is a sophism ? 
 
 A. Reasoning is intended to bring us to the know- 
 ledge of the truth ; therefore it is faHacious when 
 under the appearance of truth it insinuates falsehood. 
 This fault is called sophism. This insinuation of 
 falsehood under the appearance of truth may arise 
 from two sources: cither from \.\\q. form when the 
 rules laid down to construct reasoning are not kept, or 
 from the matter when this is in reality false but ap- 
 pears under the garb of truth. We shall say nothing 
 of the fallacies originating from the form, as they can 
 be easily detected by means of the rules laid down. 
 We shall therefore speak of the faults proceeding from 
 the matter. These may be divided into two, fallacies 
 of thought and fallacies of words. 
 
 Q. Speak of each of them. 
 -' A. Among the fallacies of thoughts the first is that 
 called of accident^ which occurs when we attribute to 
 a subject a predicate as substantial and necessary 
 when it only agrees with it accidentally. For in- 
 stance. Reason is oftentimes faulty, therefore it is an 
 evil. 
 
 The next is the fallacy of passing from the absolute 
 to the relative, and vice versd. It is committed when 
 we attribute something to the subject In an absolute and 
 
Elements of Intellectual Ph ilosophy. t o 5 
 
 unconditional manner when It may be attributed to it 
 only under certain respects and conditions; as, Medi- 
 cine gives health to the body, therefore it should al- 
 ways be taken. 
 
 3. The fallacy of false cause. This is perpetrated 
 when we assign as the cause of something that which 
 is not really so ; as. The soul united to the body thinks, 
 therefore the soul separated from the body cannot 
 think. 
 
 4- I^^M^^^^ ^^^^ question or principle. This is com- 
 mitted when we assume as the premises of reasoning 
 that which must be proved, though we use different 
 words — as. The human soul is imperishable, therefore 
 it is immortal. 
 
 5. The ignoraniia elenchi. It is incurred when the 
 adversary tries to evade the question and to find a 
 contradiction against our statement which is really not 
 to be found therein. 
 
 6. Fallacy of mafiy questions. This is committed 
 when the adversary, to the many interrogations which 
 he heaps one upon the other, wants a single answer, 
 either affirmative or negative, whereas, in order to an- 
 swer properly, it would be necessary to distinguish and 
 give an answer to each question in particular. 
 
 ARTICLE SECOND. 
 . Fallacies of Words. 
 
 O. What are the fallacies of words? 
 
 A. I. Figure o{ expression. This proceeds from the 
 fact that an expression may seem like to another 
 when in reality it is not. 
 
 2. Equivocation — when we make use of. an am- 
 biguous term in the same argument, •. • > ' ^r^ . :v 
 
 3. Fallacy of pronunciation, when we use promis- 
 
I o6 Elements of Intellectual Ph ilosophy. 
 
 cuously a word which by a slight variety of pronun- 
 ciation may be made to signify different things. 
 
 4. Amphibology — when, in consequence of the 
 structure and placing of words — there arises an am- 
 biguous sense which may be applied to one or to the 
 contrary part. For instance, that answer given by the 
 oracle of Apollos to Pyrrhus, King of Epirus: Aio te 
 JEacida Rofnanos vincere posse (" Pyrrhus the Romans 
 shall, I say, subdue ") — which closely resembles, as 
 Shakspere remarks, the witch prophecy, "The duke 
 yet lives that Henry shall depose." 
 
 5. Fallacy of composition. This is committed when 
 that which is only true in a divided sense is taken in a 
 composite sense — as, Every man can live and die. 
 
 6. Fallacy of division. This is the contrary of that 
 of composition, and is committed when that which 
 is true in a composite sense is used in a divided sense. 
 
 Q. How are fallacies refuted ? 
 
 A. If the syllogism be false in the matter, then we 
 must deny that proposition which contains falsehood. 
 If it be faulty because the fallacy renders the sense 
 ambiguous, then we must clear up the meaning of that 
 proposition which presents the ambiguity. 
 
PART THIRD. 
 
 END OF REASONING. 
 
 Q. Of what shall we treat in the third part of logic ? 
 
 A. The end of reasoning being certainty or science, 
 since a knowledge which is certain and acquired by 
 reasoning is called science, it follows that we must 
 speak of science in this third part. But in science we 
 must distinguish two things — that which is properly 
 so called and th^ way by which we arrive at it, which 
 is called inethod. Therefore, in treating of science we 
 must speak of science and of method. And because 
 in everything we find first the way to it and then the 
 thing itself, therefore we shall speak of method first 
 and then of science. We shall treat of method in 
 three chapters: i, its nature and necessity; 2, its 
 elements and means ; 3, its divisions. 
 
 CHAPTER I. 
 
 OF THE NATURB AND THE NECESSITY OF METHOD. 
 
 ARTICLE FIRST. 
 
 Definition and Necessity of Method in general. 
 
 Q. Define method and its nature. ' 
 A. If science is to be acquired by means of reason- 
 ing, it is evident that it is Jiidden and fav from us, and 
 
 X07 
 
1 08 Elements of Intellectual Ph ilosophy. 
 
 that we arrive at it by a slow process of the mind. 
 Now, that which is far away and is cicquired slowly by 
 a process of the mind sup^^oses a way which leads to it ; 
 therefore scierce supposes a way which leads to it. 
 This way is called method, which may be defined 
 that way or order which the mind follows in the ac- 
 quis it ion of science. 
 
 From this definition it appears what things are neces- 
 sary to have method, and in what the nature of the lat- 
 ter properly consists. The method is a way or road. 
 Now, we find three things in a road — the starting-point, 
 the term at which we arrive, and the means, which lies 
 between the two. Three things, likewise, are neces- 
 sary in method : the principle, from which it starts, 
 the means, and the end. The principle or principles, 
 which may be different and various, are those truths, 
 of immediate evidence, and indemonstrable, which are 
 always supposed in science, and which are taken as a 
 starting-point, and maybe of fact 3.\\6. of reason : of 
 fact — as, The ivorld exists ; of reason — as, Nothing can 
 be and not be at the same time. The end, or term, is sci- 
 ence, because it is that which method aims at. The 
 means is that order or process of acts which the mind 
 pursues to arrive, from the principles, at science. 
 
 Now, the nature of method does not consist in the 
 principles or the end but in the process, because, as to 
 the principles, they must be already known ; as to the 
 term — that is. Science, or the acquisition of truth — this 
 follows, and is a consequence of, the method. There- 
 fore, strictly speaking, the nature of method lies in 
 the order and process of the mind. 
 • Q. What is the difference between method and 
 reasoning ? .^ii:-<'. h ; ^ 
 
 A. A doubt might arise from what we have said 
 whether method and reasoning be not the same thing ; 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy, 109 
 
 because if method is a process, so is reasoning ; if 
 method arrives at science by that process so does rea- 
 soning; if method starts Irom indemonstrable princi- 
 ples, so does reasoning. In what, then, are they distin- 
 guished from each other ? To answer this question we 
 must distinguish with St. Thomas* two kinds of pro- 
 cesses in human science ; " The first is a process of suc- 
 cession (and time), as when, after having considered one 
 thing, we turn around to consider another, and thus 
 complete our first knowledge. The other process is 
 by way of causality, when from the principles we draw 
 conclusions which naturally originate from them." 
 The first process is that of one who views a variety 
 of objects one after the other ; the second is that 
 of one who considers the light as springing from the 
 sun, the flower as budding from the tr ^, etc. The 
 first process is method ; the second is reasoning. 
 
 Q. Is method necessary? 
 
 A. By the nature of our mind we are so constituted 
 that we cannot understand everything at once and sim- 
 ultaneously, but must understand things successively, 
 and part after part. Now, to do this well we must 
 follow an order of some kind. Therefore it is neces- 
 sary, in order to acquire science, to follow a certain 
 order. But the essence of method lies just in this 
 order ; therefore method is necessary. 
 
 ARTICLE SECOND. 
 Method must be One and Definite — Eclecticism, 
 
 Q. What can you say of the eclecticism of Cousin ? 
 
 A. This philosopher has broached a very strange 
 theory about method. He maintains that pure error 
 is not to be found in the human mind, and that error 
 
 ♦ I p. qu. 14, art. 7. 
 
no Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 is an incomplete truth. From this he concludes that 
 all the erroneous systems of philosophers cannot be 
 called so in the sense that they do not contain any 
 truth at all, but only in the sense that they contain 
 truth in an incomplete manner. This truth, in the 
 long succession of centuries up to our times, has al- 
 ready been exhausted by philosophers, some of them 
 pvesenting one part and some another, but none ex- 
 hibiting the whole truth. Hence we cannot find any 
 new truth ; but our business is to gather the truths 
 scattered here and there. From these statements he 
 concludes that it is not proper to have any determi- 
 nate and definite system in the nineteenth century, 
 but that we should gather all that is good and true 
 here and there in every system, and, rejecting the 
 false, endeavor to reconcile all systems. This sort of 
 method is called eclecticism. 
 
 Now, without entering into the examination of the 
 principles assumed — that pure error is impossible, that 
 error is an incomplete truth; for this shall be done in 
 Metaphysics — we say that this theory is contradictory, 
 because at the same time that it rejects all sorts of 
 method it supposes already a definite method. Be- 
 cause how could the mind gather the truth here and 
 there in this system or in the other, separate it from 
 falsehood, and keep the one and reject the other, with- 
 out a rule to guide it in this selection and discrimina- 
 tion ? Now, this rule guiding the mind in this process 
 implies a method. Therefore eclecticism, which re- 
 jects all method, supposes a method. We conclude, 
 therefore, that a method is necessary to acquire science, 
 and that this must be definite. In fact, a method 
 must start from a definite point. Now, a definite point 
 of starting renders the way also definite. Method, 
 therefore, must be one and definite. 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. iii 
 
 ARTICLE THIRD. 
 
 Q. How can we determine the true method ? 
 
 A. This is a very difficult question, and cannot be 
 answered here in consequence of the many controver- 
 sies which have arisen on the point, and to answer 
 which more knowledge of philosophy is needed than 
 we hitherto acquired. We must, therefore, leave the 
 answer to this question for another part of this work. 
 Here we shall give those essential characteristics 
 which must accompany a true method, whatever it 
 may be. Now, the first essential character of true 
 method is that it must be agreeable to the nature of our 
 intellectual faculties. Because method is that process 
 which our mind follows in the acquisition of truth. 
 But our mind and our intellectual faculties in the 
 acquisition of truth follow always that way which is 
 natural to them ; therefore true method must be 
 agreeable to the nature of our mind. Moreover, 
 method is a guide and a help to lead our faculties to 
 science. But a guide contrary to the nature and 
 faculties of a being would be a hindrance rather than 
 a help ; therefore true method should be agreeable to 
 the nature of our faculties. ;, 
 
 From this it follows that a true method must pro- 
 ceed after these laws : i. In the investigation of truth 
 it must start from that which is better known to come 
 to that which is less known. This law is clear, and 
 we shall only explain what is meant by it. That 
 which is more knowable may be understood in two 
 ways — m itself and according to its nature^ or in rela- 
 tion to our mind. A thing is called better known in 
 ttself and according to its nature when it is naturally 
 first and more perfect than another, as the cause with 
 regard to its effects. Hene God, who is most per- 
 
112 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. v 
 
 feet and necessary, is, according to his nature, the most 
 knowable of all beings. But oftentimes that which is 
 most knowable according lo its nature is less known 
 in regard to us — as, for instance, some cause which, 
 according to its nature, is always more knowable than 
 itt effects, may, with regard to us, be less known than 
 its effects. Now, in the law laid down, when we say 
 that we must proceed from that whicK is better known 
 to that which is less known, we mean with regard to 
 what is better known to our mind, and not with re- 
 gard to that which is better known in itself and by its 
 own nature. The reason is easily understood. In 
 every road the starting-point is that which is nearer 
 to the one who is to go. But the method is the road 
 of our mind ; therefore its starting-point should be 
 that which is nearer to, and better ktioivn with regard 
 to it. 
 
 The second law is that the mind should proceed 
 from the better known to the less known gradually, 
 and not by leaps ; because the last conclusion results 
 from the preceding conclusions, and hence the know- 
 ledge of the last conclusion is the effect of the pre- 
 ceding conclusions. Whenever one of tbem is missing 
 the knowledge of our mind is no longer perfect. 
 
 The third law prescribes that between the various 
 gradations and conclusions there should be a con- 
 nection. , 
 
 7 'r^'^v ■^,-. '• . '«%.'.' .^t'' v:>'»' .1-..' ' 
 
 t" 
 
 
 \. 
 
 
CHAPTER II. 
 
 ELEMENTS AND MEANS OF METHOD. ' 
 
 ARTICLE FIRST. 
 
 Of the Elements of Method ; and, firsts of Analysis and 
 
 Synthesis. 
 
 Q. What are the elements of method ? 
 
 A. The essence of method, as we have seen, consists 
 not in the principles from which Jt starts, nor in the 
 term where it ends, but in that process by which from 
 the principles we arrive at the end. Now, this pro- 
 cess implies an order of operations which must be gone 
 through to obtain an end. The elements of method, 
 therefore, are those operations by which the mind, by 
 means of reasoning, arrives at science. 
 
 Q. How many of these operations are there? 
 
 A. Two, analysis and synthesis. The first is that 
 act of the mind which resolves a certain subject into 
 its elements ; and because we cannot resolve anything 
 except it is composite, therefore analysis is that opera- 
 tion of the mind which travels from the composite to 
 the simple. And, again, because the whole is more 
 complex than its parts, the effect more complex than 
 the cause, the particular more co.nplex than the uni- 
 versal, the example more so thau the rule, and the fact 
 more so than the principle, hence analysis, after all, 
 is that operation which travels from the whole to the 
 parts, from the effects to the cause, from the particular 
 to the universal, from the example to the rule, from 
 
 the facts to the principle. Thus, when the natural 
 
 113 
 
114 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy^ 
 
 philosopher, from the experience of natural pheno- 
 mena, discovers a law, he proceeds by way of analysis ; 
 when an artist, from the various examples, draws a 
 rule, he also makes use of analysis. 
 
 The following lines of Pope are a specimen of the 
 finest analysis. He wants to prove the superiority of 
 reason over the senses, as he states in the first two 
 lines : 
 
 " Far as creation's ample range extends. 
 The scale of sensual, mental powers ascends." 
 
 And he proves it by the following analysis : 
 
 " Mark how it mounts to man's imperial race, 
 From the green myriads in the peopled grass ; 
 What modes of sight betwixt each wide extreme. 
 The mole's dim curtain and the lynx's beam ; 
 Of smell, the headlong lioness between, 
 And hound, sagacious, on the tainted green; 
 Of hearing, from the life that fills the flood, 
 To that which warbles through the vernal wood ; 
 The spider's touch, how exquisitely fine ! 
 Feels at each thread, and lives along the line; 
 In the wise bee what sense so subtly true 
 From poisonous herbs extracts the healing dew! 
 How instinct varies in the grovelling swine, 
 Compared, half-reasoning elephant, with thir .' 1 
 'Twixt that and reason, what nice barrier, 
 For ever separate, yet for ever near I 
 Remembrance and reflection, hvnv allied ; 
 What thin partitions sense from thought divide ! 
 And middle natures, how they long to join, 
 Yet never pass the insuperable line I 
 Without this just gradation could they be 
 Subjected, these to those, or all to thee? 
 The powers of all subdued by thee alone. 
 Is not thy reason all these powers in one ?" - ■■ ' 
 
 "■ -■ — Essay on Man, 
 
 Synthesis is the opposite of analysis. It means 
 composition. But only the simple is put together. 
 Hence synthesis, after all, means that act of the mind 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 1 1 5 
 
 which proceeds from the simple to the composite ; 
 and as the parts are more simple than the whole, the 
 cause more simple than the effect, the universal more 
 so than the particular, the principle more so than the 
 fact, the rule more so than the example, hence we 
 have the operation called synthesis, when from the 
 parts we go to the whole, from the cause to the effect, 
 from the universal to the particular, from the principle 
 to the fact, from the rule to the examples. 
 
 ARTICLE SECOND. 
 
 Use of Analysis and Synthesis. ' 
 
 Q. When and how must these two operations be 
 used? 
 
 A. A great dispute has arisen among philosophers as 
 to when and how to use these two operations; some 
 wanting to use synthesis first, and then analysis, and 
 others wanting to use analysis first, and synthesis after- 
 wards. To resolve this question we must observe, in 
 the first place, that when the mind* sets out to inves- 
 tigate an object, it must know it somewhat, at least 
 confusedly; because if it knew it net it would not set 
 out upon its investigation. 
 
 2. In force of the nature of our intellect, this object 
 to be investigated must be presented before it in a 
 complex state. 
 
 3. The mind truly knows it when it knows all its 
 parts and the manner by which they are knit to- 
 gether. If this last observation needed any proof it 
 might be demonstrated thus : Then only have we a 
 true knowledge when it corresponds to the reality of 
 the object. Now, to get at the reality of an object 
 which is complex two things are required ; the parts 
 and their union, made according to the nature of the 
 
Ii6 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy, 
 
 object. Therefore it is only when we know the parts 
 of a complex object, and the manner after which they 
 are knit together, that we can be said to have true 
 knowledge of it. 
 
 Having premised these things, we come to the solu- 
 tion of the question, Which must we use first in the 
 acquisition of science, synthesis or analysis? We 
 say, in the first place, that it is impossible not to make 
 use of analysis in science ; because, when we come to 
 know and to distinguish the parts of a whole appre- 
 hended in a confused manner at first, the process 
 which we follow is analytic. Again, it is impossible 
 not to use synthesis ; because, to have a perfect 
 knowledge of a whole, it is not sufficient to know its 
 pr.rts, but it is necessary to know how they lie to each 
 other and to the whole. This process, as it is evident, 
 is synthetic ; therefore in science we must use both. 
 
 Besides, we are so made by nature that our know- 
 ledge ordinarily begins from experience and from 
 facts, and from them arises to principles. Now, this 
 is analysis. On the other hand, experience is not suffi- 
 cient to give us science, because it does nothing-more 
 than to affirm a fact ; hence we stand in need of syn- 
 thesis also, which shows the connection of facts with 
 principles; therefore science needs both these opera- 
 tions. The second question is, How are they to be 
 used, supposing that they are both necessary? 
 
 We have said that the first thing we do after that 
 confused knowledge of an object is to separate and 
 distinguish the parts, and then we study the i.ianner 
 in which they are used. Therefore we begin first by 
 analysis and then use synthesis. Again, we have said 
 that our knowledge starts from experience. Now, ex- 
 perience implies analysis^ therefore in science we 
 begin first from analysis. This, of course, '- under- 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 117 
 
 stood in a subjective sense, inasmuch as science is an 
 act of our mind, but not inasmuch as when, after hav- 
 ing acquired science, we wish to impart it to others. 
 In that case we use analysis first and synthesis 
 afterwards, or vica versa, just as we see it more con- 
 ducive to our object of imparting it. 
 
 ARTICLE THIRD. 
 On Definition 
 
 Q. What is definition ? 
 
 A. Whatever may be tne starting-point of our 
 minds, either analysis or synthesis, it must have some 
 fixed limits, in order not to be too much distracted and 
 wandering about. These limits are appointed by defi- 
 nition and division. 
 
 Definition is a short discourse which declares what 
 is that of which we are treating. It may declare a 
 name or a thing, and hence is distinguished into no- 
 minal and real. It is called nominal when it explains 
 the signification of a name ; r^«/ when it manifests the 
 nature of the thing signified by the name. Both may 
 be formed in different ways, and, therefore, are of dif- 
 ferent kinds. The nominal definition may be formed 
 in three different ways: i. From the etymology, as 
 when we say, TJie word philosophy means love of zvisdom. 
 2. From the common use in which a word is taken — 
 as, A wise man is understood by all to mean one who 
 judges from the standpoint of the highest causes. 3. From 
 our special signification — as, / mean by eloquejice the 
 present impassioned state of my soul transfused into 
 words. 
 
 A real definition maybe also formed in three ways: 
 I. By giving the essential constituents of a being; as, 
 Man is a reasonable animal. 2. By explaining the man- 
 
ii8 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy, 
 
 ner in which it has been produced ; as, The circle is a 
 figure described by the extremity of a straight line 
 turning upon the other fixed extremity. This is called 
 genetic definition. 3. By describing the thing by its 
 most important accidents and exterior causes ; as, 
 Man is an animal, provident, sagacious, full of reason 
 and counsel. This is called descriptive and is used in 
 oratory. The nominal definition must always precede 
 the real, it being of the utmost importance in a dis- 
 pute to be agreed upon the signification of the terms 
 used. But to determine the nature of a thing the 
 real definition is the most important and necessary to 
 a methodic process. 
 
 Q. Give the laws of definition. 
 
 A. I . The definition must be clearer than that which 
 is defined^ because the whole object of the definition 
 is just this. 
 
 2. The thing defined must not enter into the definition^ 
 at least under the same respect in which it is defined^ 
 otherwise we should declare the unknown by th^ un- 
 known. 
 
 3. It must be convertible tvith the thing de fitted. 
 
 4. // must be formed from the proximate genus and 
 the specific difference of the thing to be defined, because 
 the definition must fix the proper limits of a being. 
 Now, every being agrees in some things with other 
 beings and disagrees in other things; therefore a defi- 
 nition must express that in which the object defined 
 agrees with others and that in which it differs from 
 them. This is done by using the proximate genus 
 and the specific difference. 
 
 
 '■}■•', \:-,.y^^: i:''. 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy, 119 
 
 ARTICLE FOURTH. 
 
 Of Division. 
 
 Q. What is division, and how many kinds of divisions 
 are there ? 
 
 A. Division is the distribution of a whole into its 
 parts ; it is of as many kinds as we may suppose a whole 
 to be. Now, a whole can be so actually or potentially. 
 It is actually so when it is really composed of parts, 
 which may be physical, as in a house the walls, the 
 roof, etc.; metaphysical, as in man animality and ra- 
 tionality ; accidental, as the modifications of a being ; 
 logical, when they are supposed by the mind. 
 
 It is potentially so when it actually has no parts, 
 but can have them as the universal relatively to the 
 particular ; genus, for instance, respectively to species ; 
 because, though genus actually does not contain the 
 species, yet it maybe divided according to the species, 
 as animals may be divided into reasonable and unrea- 
 sonable. Division, therefore, may distribute the ac- 
 tual and the potential whole. 
 
 Q. What are the laws of division? 
 
 A. The following: i. It must be entire; that is, 
 that no part of the subject must be left out, so that 
 all the parts put together may be equal to the whole. 
 
 2. The parts must be somewhat opposed to each 
 other, so that the one does not contain the other.' 
 
 3. The division should be effected in an orderly 
 way; that is, a subject should be divided first in its 
 more general parts, and these in their turn subdivided, 
 and so on. 
 
 4. It should not be too minute, which would engen- 
 der confusion. 
 
• .^ -* 
 
 ■? ■■ 
 
 CHAPTER III. 
 
 DIVISION OF METHOD— THAT A5, OF METHOD OF INVEN- 
 TION AND OF DISCIPLINE. 
 
 Q. How many kinds of method" are there? 
 
 A. Two, method of invention and method of dis- 
 cipline. We can attain science in two ways : either by 
 discovering it ourselves or by learning it from one who 
 has already found it. The first is called method of 
 invention ; the other, of discipline. 
 
 Q. What are the truths which the intellect may 
 discover ? 
 
 A. Four questions may always be raised upon a 
 subject: i. Whether it exists? 2. What is it? 3. 
 What are its qualities ? 4. What originates its ex- 
 istence, and for what does it exist ? Hence there are 
 four truths which may be discovered in a subject : 
 existence, essence and nature, qualities, and the causes 
 of existence. Of these four truths two properly be- 
 long to science : What is it, and from whence comes 
 it, and why ? That is the essence and the efficient 
 and.final cause of a thing. The others are subject to 
 experience, and are a way to science, but not science 
 itself. 
 
 Q. What are the means to obtain truth ? 
 
 A. They can be of two kinds, direct and indirect, 
 because we can either discover truth by ourselves or 
 learn it from others ; the first is called direct, the 
 other indirect. The direct may belong to sensitive 
 and to intellectual knowledge. Now, using these two 
 means to arrive at science, two things may happen : 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 121 
 
 either we arrive at the. knowledge of the principles and 
 of the nature of a thing or we do not. If the first, then 
 our mind is satisfied and rests ; if the second, the mind, 
 to be satisfied, seeks some other means, and supposes 
 a principle which may explain all the accidents of the 
 subject, and which may fulfil the office of its nature 
 for the time being until it succeeds really to find it 
 out. This supposed principle is called hypothesis. 
 
 Such is the way which the mind follows in the pursuit 
 of truth. Of t.he senses and of the intellect, and of their 
 value as means of truth, and of the indirect means— 
 that is, the testimony of others — we shall speak in 
 another place. Here we shall say a few words with 
 regard to experience and to hypothesis. 
 
 Q. What is experience, and what are its laws ? 
 
 A. Experience has often been confounded with 
 observation. To observe is to look at the facts jii"*- 
 as they happen, and nothing more, whereas experience 
 means always a certain knowledge of some properties 
 revealed by observation. Hence is it that, though 
 observation is satisfied with one fact, experience 
 requires several, and most rarely is satisfied with 
 one, and when this happens the fact must be of 
 the highest importance and equivalent to many facts. 
 This is the reason also why the word experience has 
 been extended not only to mean the gathering of a 
 property of an object from the observation of many 
 facts, but is used to mean the artificial reprbduction 
 of facts to force, as it were, the object more clearly 
 to reveal its properties. Thus chemists, for instance, 
 make experiments by reproducing facts and pheno- 
 mena to force the object to reveal itself. In one 
 word, experience and experiment are ordained to 
 gather from the observation of facts the properties 
 and qualities of beings. 
 
122 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy 
 
 » 
 
 The laws which must guide us in the experience of 
 facts are: i. We must pay attention to the least 
 circumstances of place, of time, of manner, because 
 the least influence of these things causes a variation 
 in the experiment. 2. We must repeat and vary 
 the experiment, try it with other instruments and 
 under different circumstances, oftentimes using a con- 
 trary process, in order that the phenomenon may be 
 known under all its aspects. 3. We must protract 
 the experiment for a certain time, and pay attention 
 to those more constant and stable effects and con- 
 ditions which may accompany the phenomenon. 
 These laws require the utmost diligence in their ob- 
 ^ servation, and the greatest patience in continuing 
 them. 
 
 Q. What is hypothesis, and what are its laws ? 
 
 A. We have said that oftentimes, in spite of all our 
 constancy in experimenting, we cannot find the prin- 
 ciple and reason of a phenomenon. Then we put 
 forth a principle which may better explain it ; this is 
 called hypothesis, which may be defined : A probable 
 opinion put forth to explain the nature and reason of 
 a phenomenony which nature and reason are not known 
 by experience^ nor as yet demonstrated by reason. The 
 laws are: i. We must only take as an hypothesis that 
 principle which may explain most of the circum- 
 stances, and these the most important. 
 
 2. That it contain nothing repugnant to the laws 
 of nature already known. 
 
 3. That, among the hypotheses, should be chosen 
 which proceeds in the most simple way. ■ 
 
 If in the prosecution of the experiments we find out 
 that that hypothesis explains the true nature of the 
 phenomenon, then the probability becomes certainty 
 and the hypothesis becomes thesis. 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 1 23 
 
 ARTICLE SECOND. 
 
 Of the Method of Discipline. 
 
 Q. What is meant by teaching? 
 
 A. When science is found the method employed to 
 communicate it to others is called didactic, or of dis- 
 cipline. In order to understand the nature of this 
 method we must see what it is to teach science. 
 
 To teach is to manifest the science which we know, 
 and to cause others to learn it. But to know, in a 
 scientific way, means to deduce a conclusion from 
 principles certain and evident ; therefore to teach 
 science implies inducing the mind of the pupil to 
 draw consequences from known principles. Hence it 
 appears that the teacher is not the principal cause of 
 the science in the disciple, but a guide who, by means 
 of signs — that is, words — leads the disciple and induces 
 him to draw conclusions from known principles in the 
 same manner as he drew them himself. "Hence the 
 principle or cause of the science in this case is not 
 the teacher but the reason of the disciple. 
 
 From this appears the strangeness of the opinion of 
 those who hold that the analytic method is good to 
 discover science, the synthetic to impart it. We say 
 that in general the best method of teaching science is 
 the same one which discovered it. Because to teach 
 is to incite the mind of the disciple to form those 
 same demonstrations which are in our mind; there- 
 fore the easiest method is the same followed by us in 
 the formation of those demonstrations. 
 
 Besides, between the method of invention and 
 that of discipline exists the same difference which 
 intervenes between nature and art, because the in- 
 ventive method is natural, that of discipline is arti- 
 ficial. But art must imitate nature ; therefore the 
 
124 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy, 
 
 method of discipline must imitate the method of in- 
 vention. 
 
 This, however, must not be understood so strictly 
 as to forbid the use of any other method. The best 
 rule in this matter is, that method is the best which 
 best facilitates the acquisition of science, and there- 
 fore when the analytic answers the purpose let the 
 analytic be followed ; when the synthetic, let the latter 
 be followed, because the easiest and the clearest way 
 is always the most natural. 
 
 , i ;rf , ; 
 
 ■( 
 
 .•>.' 
 
 . ') , 
 
 j^, r* ^ ' - > 
 
 
CHAPTER IV. 
 
 OF SCIENCE, ACCORDING TO ITS STRICTEST ACCEPTATION, 
 INASMUCH AS IT IS KNOWLEDGE. 
 
 ARTICLE FIRST. 
 
 Idea of Science. 
 
 Q. In how many ways can the word science be 
 used ? 
 
 A. In two ways, though both are connected to- 
 gether. In the first place, science implies a particular 
 knowledge of an object. But our mind can have also 
 several distinct ideas of an object, and form several 
 distinct conclusions about it, which it may put to- 
 gether in order and form a whole body of knowledge. 
 Hence, in the second place, science may be used also 
 to express that orderly series of scientific knowledge 
 we form about an object. In this chapter we shall 
 treat of science in the first signification, leaving it to 
 the next to treat of it in its second acceptation. 
 
 Q. Give an idea of science inasmuch as it is a spe- 
 cial knowledge of an object. 
 
 A. It is called a special knowledge of a set purpose, 
 because science does not mean any knowledge what- 
 ever, but only a perfect knowledge. This sense is 
 attached to science even by common sense, because 
 men generally attach a different sense to the word 
 knowledge and to that of science, meaning by the 
 latter a fuller, more evident, and more noble know- 
 ledge. Science, therefore, implies a perfect knowledge. 
 From this idea we can draw the elements necessary 
 and essential to the conception of science, because 
 
126 Elements of Intellectual Philosophyi 
 
 three things are necessary to have a perfect knowledge : 
 
 1. It must be certain, because, besides certainty, there 
 is nothing but doubt and probability, or opinion. But 
 doubt is the want of knowledge, and probability is an 
 imperfect knowledge, always implying a certain fear 
 of the contrary ; therefore we can call perfect only 
 that knowledge which is accompanied by a certainty. 
 
 2. It must be evident, either mediately, or immedi- 
 ately ; because, if knowledge is certain, it is necessary 
 that the mind should have no fear of the contrary. 
 To have no fear of the contrary the mind must feel 
 perfectly secure about it. To feel perfectly secure 
 it is necessary that it should sec clearly into the 
 principles on which it is founded, and discover the 
 connection between those principles and the conclu- 
 sions drawn from them ; therefore science must be 
 evident knowledge. Moreover, if this knowledge were 
 not evident but obscure, it would not be perfect but 
 imperfect. 3. It must be a k*' 'ge deduced from 
 its causes, because otherv. it c ild be neither cer- 
 tain, evident, nor perfec - -^♦^ .ertain, because then 
 only can we be said to have certainty when not only 
 do we know that a thing is but also that it must be so, 
 which absolutely excludes all fear of the opposite. 
 But the necessity that a thing must be so is only 
 known when we discover the cause and the connection 
 which it has with it. Therefore knowledge, to be cer- 
 tain, must be deduced from its causes. It could not 
 be evident, because when the mind can see no connec- 
 tion between a thing and its cause it cannot have true 
 evidence, as it can see a void, and never can rest until 
 it discovers that connection. It could not be perfect, 
 since that knowledge alone is perfect which leaves 
 nothing to discover, and when we know not the cause 
 of a thing we cannot say that there is nothing more 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy, 127 
 
 to discover; therefore science must be a knowledge 
 deduced from its principles. 
 
 Q. Give a full definition of science according to the 
 above principles. 
 
 A. A knowledge, certain and evident, deduced from 
 its principles or causes. Here a difficulty might be 
 raised. We cannot always investigate the cause of an 
 object, and yet we can have a scientific knowledge of 
 it. For instance, God has no cause, and yet we can 
 have the science of Him, which is called Theology. 
 
 In answer to this difficulty we say that when we 
 cannot investigate the cause of an object, in that case 
 the knowledge of its effects performs the office of the 
 cause, as when we say God exists because He has 
 created the world, God is most perfect because He 
 is the cause of all the perfections of creatures ; here 
 the knowlec-^e of the effect performs the office of 
 cause. 
 
 O. How can we make the effect officiate as cause? 
 Is not this contradictory? 
 
 A. When a cause has produced a certain effect, it 
 has imposed the necessity of its own existence for 
 having produced that effect, and of its being such by 
 nature as the effect produced requires ; because as, on 
 one side, the effect must necessarily exist since the 
 cause has acted, and must be such, and not otherwise, 
 as the cause has made it, so likewise, on the other 
 hand, the cause must necessarily exist because its 
 effects exist ; it must necessarily have produced it, 
 because the effect is already produced, and must 
 necessarily be so-and-so, because the effect is so- 
 and-so, and not otherwise. Therefore in this case 
 the effect performs the office of cause in the con- 
 struction of science, since we can argue from a certain 
 effect the existence of the cause, its being produced 
 
128 Elements of Intelleclual Philosophy, 
 
 by the cause, and somewhat the nature of the cause. 
 Hence St. Thomas has observed that when we de- 
 monstrate the cause by its effects, then the effect 
 officiates as the cause, and the definition of the effect 
 is (nven instead of that of the cause. Here we must 
 observe that we do not say that the effect is the cause 
 of the existence of the cause, as Hegel objected 
 with regard to the demonstration of the existence of 
 God from His effects. We only say that the effect 
 merely officiates as the cause in the demonstration, in- 
 asmuch as we have said every effect necessarily sup- 
 poses a cause, and such a cause as befits the effect ; 
 and, therefore, supposing the existence of the effect, 
 the cause also must exist, and be such as the effect 
 requires. Besides, by the same cause we do not 
 merely understand the efficient and the final causes, 
 but also the principles essential to a being, ^ hich form 
 it, which may be reduced to the formal cause. But 
 the essential principles of a being may be easily read 
 and discovered in their effects more or less, according 
 as the effect approaches the cause and equals its 
 power, as we must find the similitude of the cause in 
 its effect. Therefore, even when we demonstrate from 
 effects, science is knowledge from its causes. It may 
 not be quite perfect, but it is science for all that, be- 
 cause containing all the elements of science. 
 
 Q. What must you observe as to the object of 
 science ? 
 
 A. I. Science must have for its object the essence 
 and the immutable relations of the essence of things. 
 It must have for its object the essence, because science 
 is knowledge certain and universal. But such know- 
 ledge must have an Qbject, which cannot be otherwise 
 than immutable; therefore the object of science must 
 be immutable. But only essences are immutable; 
 
Elements of Intellectual Ph ilosophy. 129 
 
 therefore the object of science must be the essences 
 of things. 
 
 Of these essences we must know the elements and 
 their immutable relations, because science lies in the 
 knowledge of the connection and relation between 
 effects and their causes. But we could not know this 
 connection between effects and their causes without 
 knowing the elements and the immutable relations of 
 the essences of things ; therefore, etc. 
 
 The second observation is in relation to what is 
 necessary in the intelligent subject in order to have 
 scientific knowledge. Because it is not necessary, in 
 order to have a scientific knowledge of an object, to 
 have been able to produce it, as was asserted by Vico, 
 who held that the intellect knows only what it docs ; 
 but it is sufficient that there exist a means which may 
 represent to our mind effects and their causes, their 
 relations and essences, in which means the mind may 
 see all those things. This means we have in ideas, 
 and the force of reading them lies in our intellect. 
 The principle of Vico would only render possible one 
 science — that is, mathematics, which is the creation of 
 man ; and upon this principle the German panthe- 
 ists have constructed their system, as we shall see in 
 its proper place. 
 
 ARTICLE SECOND. 
 Of Science in Relation to Opinion and Faith. 
 
 Q. How is science distinguished from opinion and 
 faith? : ,.,-.: ^ , 
 
 A. As to opinion, science Is distinguishable from it 
 in four ways: i. \n knowledge, \^\\\q\\ in science most 
 firmly clings to the object known without the least 
 
1 30 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 fear of the opposite, whereas opinion impHes an adhe- 
 sion of the mind with fear of the opposite. 
 
 2. As to the matter; this in science being always 
 necessary and immutable, whereas in opinion it is 
 oftentimes mutable and contingent. 
 
 3. For the means, which in science is the demon- 
 strative syllogism, deducing certain and evident know- 
 ledge from its causes, whilst in opinion the means 
 is the probable syllogism. 
 
 4. For the manner according to which they are pro- 
 duced, science being produced by one efficacious de- 
 monstration, whilst opinion is engendered by the 
 aid of various syllogisms in consequence of their 
 weakness. 
 
 As to faith, science can be distinguished from it 
 for two reasons: I. The certainty of science consists 
 in two things — in the intrinsic evidence of the object 
 and in the firmness of adhesion of the mind. On the 
 contrary, faith consists only in the firmness of the ad- 
 hesion of the mind, not caused by the internal evi- 
 dence of the object as perceived by the mind, but by 
 the external evidence only if we speak of human 
 faith, and by other causes if we speak of divine faith, 
 the clinging of the mind which the latter implies being 
 caused also by an internal operation of God upon the 
 soul. 
 
 2. In science we adhere to the qqx\z\w^\ox\ forced by 
 the necessity of the principles. In faith we cling to 
 the object prompted by the will, which presents that 
 belief as good. r" . 
 
'^\«\\y^X\^:'S"^ ^ ','>•-•.'-:.. \\':VW\' '-^ ^-t\ 
 
 CHAPTER V. 
 
 OF SCIENCE IN ITS MORE ENLARGED SIGNIFICATION INAS- 
 MUCH AS IT IS A SYSTEM OF TRUTHS, 
 
 ARTICLE FIRST." 
 Idea of Science in this Second Sense. 
 
 Q. What do you mean by science in this second 
 sense ? 
 
 A. Any system of truths belonging to a definite 
 order of things and presented in one body. 
 
 Q. Is not science, understood in this latter sense, 
 confounded with art, in which truths and rules are 
 also presented in one body ? 
 
 A. Art is only an order of rules upon some particu- 
 lar thing, whereas science is always a deduction. In 
 art we do not always find the evidence of principles ; 
 in science always. In art the order of rules which it 
 gives cannot, strictly speaking, be called a system ; in 
 science the body of truths which it exhibits is always 
 called a system. Three things, therefore, are the pro- 
 perty of science in this second sense : principles, de- 
 duction, and system. 
 
 Q. What about principles? 
 
 A. A principle is that from which a thing proceeds ; 
 and because we here speak of knowledge, the principle 
 is that by which a thing is known. But we do not 
 know by means of another principle, except that 
 which cannot be known by itself; therefore we must 
 call principles those propositions known of them- 
 selves, and which are the cause of the knowledge of 
 
 »3I 
 
132 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. , 
 
 many others — for instance, Every effect supposes a 
 cause ; Those things which are equal to a third are 
 equal to one another. NotJmig can be and not be at the 
 same time ; from which it appears that there are three 
 properties of a principle — evidence, necessity, and 
 universality. Evidence is that property by which 
 a thing, in being presented to our mind, makes itself 
 known most clearly. It is of two kinds, mediate 
 and immediate. It is called immediate when the 
 thing can be known by itself without the need of any 
 other, as the principles above mentioned. It is called 
 mediate when the truth cannot be known by itself, 
 but stands in need of other truths to be known. The 
 evidence of principles must be immediate, because it 
 must be the cause of the knowledge of other truths. 
 From this property of evidence flows the other, of ne- 
 cessity. Because if the thing is evident by itself the 
 mind cannot refuse its adhesion to it, but must neces- 
 sarily give it. This is called the necessity of a prin- 
 ciple. Finally, universality, the third property of a 
 principle, is a consequence flowing from the very na- 
 ture of a principle. A principle is that which is the 
 cause of knowledge of many other truths. Now, 
 this must be understood, inasmuch as these truths 
 are contained in that principle. Now, this property 
 of being able to extend to many truths, and in all 
 cases, is called the universality of a principle ; there- 
 fore a principle must be universal. 
 
 Q. Can there be one principle for all sciences? 
 
 A. This is impossible, because, i, the principles of 
 sciences must correspond with the real and objective 
 principles of things. But the species of things which 
 are the object of our knowledge are many and various ; 
 therefore many and various must be the principles 
 of sciences. 2. A principle is a law — that is, ex- 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 133 
 
 presses a certain respect according to which things 
 comprehended in it are regulated. But things are 
 many and various, and various are the respects under 
 which they may be regarded ; therefore various must 
 be .the principles of sciences. It is true that there 
 exists one principle which is the foundation of cer- 
 tainty, the principle of contradiction, but this can 
 never be such as to enable us to derive from its first 
 cause the science of an object. This principle does 
 not regard any matter of science. 
 
 Q. How are principles divided ? 
 
 A. Into proper and common. Common principles 
 V. are those which are used in all sciences ; as, Nothing is 
 done witho7tt a sufficient reason ; It is impossible that a 
 thing be and not be at the same time, of the same kind. 
 Proper and other principles are those which regard 
 the special matter of a particular science ; as, Do as 
 you would be done by, which is a principle of the 
 moral science. 
 
 Into analytic and synthetic. The first are those in 
 which the predicate is found in the idea of the sub- 
 ject ; as. The ivhole is greater than any of its parts. 
 The second are those in which the predicate is not 
 included in that of the subject, but is attached to it in 
 force of our experience ; as. Every body tends towards 
 its centre. In other words, the one originates in the 
 nature of the subject, the other does not. 
 
 The opposite of the analytic principles is absolute, 
 repugnant, and contradictory, and not even God him- 
 self could effect it ; but the opposite of synthetic 
 principles is contradictory only hypothetically, that is, 
 supposing that the laws according to which bodies are 
 governed be maintained constant. For instance, it is 
 an absolute contradiction to say that a thing is and is 
 not at the same time, and God himself could not effect 
 
134 Elements of Intellectual Ph ilosophy. 
 
 such a thing; but it is not contradictory in itself to 
 say that a body, instead of tending towards its centre, 
 should tend upwards, because this may be done by 
 suspending the law of gravitation, which is net essen- 
 tial to the nature of the body. It is only contra- 
 dictory in the hypothesis that the laws now governing 
 bodies be constant ; hence, admitting the law of gravi- 
 tation actually in force in a given body, it is a contra- 
 diction to say that it could tend upwards. 
 
 Q. What is the means of science? 
 
 A. The other thing most necessary to science is 
 reasoning. Some philosophers, as the school of Locke 
 and Condillac, pretend that the only means of science 
 is induction. But such a theory is absurd. Induction, 
 of itself, does nothing more than generalize a fact, but 
 says nothing of the reason why such a fact is so and 
 not otherwise, and why it takes place, nor discovers 
 the connection between cause and effect. Now, all this 
 is necessary to science ; therefore induction alone can- 
 not suffice for science. Therefore we must hold that 
 the primary and essential means of science is the apo- 
 dictic reasoning. And as science, inasmuch as it is a 
 system, cannot prove everything apodictically, so all 
 other kinds of argumentations are most useful, even 
 those which produce nothing more than probable 
 knowledge. 
 
 Q. What is the last thing necessary to science ? 
 
 A. The connection, or order. For science must 
 equal its subject ; and as then only we have truth 
 when the form of the intellect is equal with the 
 thing, so science is true and perfect only when it is a 
 true image of its object. But the object is in itself 
 perfectly well arranged and set in order ; therefore 
 science also must be well arranged in its cognitions. 
 Here we may recall the observation of Vico, that in 
 
Elements of Intellectual Ph ilosophy. 1 3 5 
 
 knowing an object we should divide it in its parts and 
 construct it gradually in our minds, as if we were 
 making it. Nay, this is just what gives to a treatise 
 the character of science — the order and connection of 
 the deductions. ; 
 
 ARTICLE THIRD. 
 
 Distinction and Order of Sciences. 
 
 Q. What is there to be observed about the unity 
 and distinction of sciences? 
 
 A. The true and principal criterion of the unity of 
 sciences is their object. Science, in this second sense, 
 is a system of knowledge belonging to a certain order 
 of things ; therefore, if that order of things be one, 
 the science will be one, and hence the unity of each 
 science depends upon the unity of its object. But we 
 must draw a distinction here. The object of the sci- 
 ence may be considered materially and formally. We 
 consider it materially when we look it everything and 
 every element which constitutes its being ; we consider 
 it formally when we look only at that respect accord- 
 ing to which it is the object of a given science. Now, 
 the unity of a science is constituted by its formal ob- 
 ject, but not by its material ; hence it may happen 
 that many things materially different from each other 
 may form one object of a science, being regarded 
 under one peculiar aspect. For instance, how many 
 are the material objects of physics? Numberless; 
 yet they form one object of that science, inasmuch as 
 they are regarded under the one aspect as phenomena 
 of bodies. On the contrary, it may happen that an 
 object materially one may form the object of many 
 sciences, in each of them being considered under a 
 peculiar aspect. Man, for instance, one material ob- 
 
136 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. - 
 
 ject, may be the object of anatomy, physiology, pa- 
 thology, psychology, and so forth. The formal object, 
 therefore, is that which gives unity to a science. 
 
 As to distinction, we say that unity is the foundation 
 of distinction, because a thing is distinct from others 
 because it is in itself one. But unity is given to science 
 by its formal object ; therefore from the formal object 
 arises the distinction of sciences. Hence a science is 
 different from others, according as its formal object. is 
 more or less different ; as, for instance, theology is dis- 
 tinct from cosmology, because their formal objects are 
 different ; natural theology is distinct from revealed 
 theology, because their formal object is different. 
 
 Omitting all other distinction^ of sciences, we shall 
 say a word of that well-known distinction into specu- 
 lative and practical. A speculative science is that 
 which regards its object only as truth ; practical, that 
 which regards its object as to be acted on ; or, in other 
 words, speculative sciences are those which have for 
 their object the contemplation of truth ; practical, 
 those which have for their end action. 
 
 Q. What is the order and dependence of sciences? 
 
 A. Though sciences be different, yet they must be 
 set in order and be dependent. When many things 
 are destined to one end it is • ecessary that one of 
 them should govern and regulate the others. But all 
 sciences and arts are destined to one end — the perfec- 
 tion of man ; therefore it is necessary that one of them 
 should govern and regulate all others and take the 
 name of wisdom. But one may ask. What is that sci- 
 ence which may rule and govern all others? That 
 which has certainly the aptitude to govern and rule 
 others. But, as Aristotle remarks, among men those 
 are naturally able to govern who have more intellectual 
 power ; and those who are more robust in body but 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 1 3 7' 
 
 wanting in talent are naturally liable to be governed. 
 Hence that science must be the first and govern all 
 others which is most intellectual. But that which is 
 most intellectual is occupied about those objects which 
 are most intelligible. The intelligible is the universal ; 
 therefore that science is first which has a more uni- 
 versal object. But philosophy has an object more 
 universal than other science ; therefore philosophy is 
 that first science on which all depend. And here we 
 conclude this first part of philosophy with that from 
 which we started, after having given a brief idea of 
 the matter, the form, and the end of reasoning. 
 
 M ' '■ . V '- 1 
 
 
ONTOLOGY 
 
 »39 
 
/ '1^;-! . ' ' 
 
 1i;i 
 
 ':■ riK'ji 
 
ONTOLOGY. 
 
 INTRODUCTION— OBJECT OF METAPHYSICS— DEFINI- 
 TION OF ONTOLOGY, 
 
 Q. Give the object of metaphysics. 
 
 A. In Logic we have spoken of being inasmuch as 
 it is the product of the mind, and have explained the 
 nature of reasoning. This was obliged to be done be- 
 fore all things else, not because of the dignity of the 
 object, but by necessity of method, as we have shown 
 in the Introduction to Philosophy. We proceed now 
 to speak of real being, which forms the object of meta- 
 physics. This word, composed of two Greek words, 
 means that which follows physics, and was given by 
 the compilers of Aristotle's works to those thirteen 
 books in which they found the philosopher treated 
 of real being, the name happily chiming with the ob- 
 ject of these books, since metaphysics treats of things 
 separated from matter either by abstraction of the 
 mind, as being in common, or by their nature, as the 
 soul and God, and if it treat at all of material 
 things it does so in a more noble way than physics. 
 
 Q. Give the division of metaphysics. 
 
 A. It has been divided into four parts — Ontology, 
 Anthropology, Cosmology, and Natural Theology. 
 
 Q. What is Ontology, and what are its parts ? 
 
 A. Ontology is that part which treats of real being, 
 
 X4X 
 
142 Introduction. 
 
 considered in common and in a general way. But 
 about real being, considered in a general way, our 
 mind may naturally enquire the following things : 
 I. What is the nature of real being, considered in a 
 general way ? 2. What are its properties ? 3. What 
 are its principles and causes? 4. How is it divided? 
 Therefore, according to this natural order, we shall 
 treat of these four things : of the nature of real being 
 in general, of its properties, of its causes, and of its 
 divisions. Beginning from the first, we shall treat of 
 it in the following chapters: i. Of being considered 
 in itself and in a most general way ; 2. Of the first de- 
 terminations of being — that is, of essence and exis- 
 tence ; and 3. Of the manner in which these two last 
 concur in forming real being. 
 
 
 \ .■:- 
 
 •«:S' «■;* 
 
 ^.».v 
 
 l.„. 
 
CHAPTER I. 
 
 OF BBING^ CONSIDERED IN ITSELF AND IN A MOST 
 GENERAL WAY. 
 
 ARTICLE FIRST. 
 
 Of the Idea of Being in Itself 
 
 Q. Can you give a definition of being? 
 
 A. We cannot, because a definition must be com- 
 posed of the proximate genus and of the specific dif- 
 ference of the thing defined. Now, being can have 
 neither; therefore it is incapable of being defined. 
 The minor is proved thus: Every genus must have 
 specific dift'erences, which are not comprehended in 
 the essence and idea of the genus, but lie outside of 
 it. For instance, the genus animal has two specific 
 differences, reasonable and brute. These are outside 
 the essence and idea of the genus. Now, there can 
 be nothing which is not comprehended in the idea of 
 being; therefore being cannot be defined. It may be 
 declared by saying that being is everything which is 
 in any way whatever, or that which can be positively 
 conceived. 
 
 Q. What consequences do you draw from this doc- 
 trine? 
 
 A. I . That being is the most general and simple idea.. 
 The most general, because nothing can be more inti- 
 mate and essential to all things than that of being 
 something. Now, this is just what is meant by being. 
 Therefore this idea is applicable to all things, and 
 hence most general. Again, being agrees with, and is 
 
144 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 attributed not only to, all things but also to all con- 
 ceptions and ideas ; therefore it is the most general 
 of all ideas. 
 
 It is the most simple — that is, it has a less number 
 of elements and a more restricted comprehension than 
 all other ideas, because, as we have said in Logic, the 
 comprehension of an idea is in the inverse ratio of its 
 extension. Consequently, this idea, being the most 
 general, is the least comprehensive, and hence most 
 simple. 
 
 2. Being is the first idea, both in the chronological a7id 
 logical order. This idea is first in the chronological 
 order, inasmuch as it is acquired by our minds before 
 any other idea. For our mind is so constructed that 
 it must travel in its investigations from that which is 
 less perfect to that which is more so, and hence from 
 that which is more general and confused to that which 
 is less general and more distinct. But no idea is more 
 general than that of being ; therefore it is the first 
 which is acquired by the mind. Hence the first thing 
 we perceive in all things is that they are, that they 
 are something, and, gradually proceeding forward in 
 the knowledge of them, we come to know them more 
 perfectly and more minutely. 
 
 This idea is also first in the logical order, by which 
 we understand that all other ideas are subject, and can 
 be reduced to the idea of being. In fact, everything 
 can be resolved into its primitive and more simple ele- 
 ments. But the idea of being is common to all ideas, 
 and is the most simple of them all ; therefore they all 
 can be reduced to that idea. 
 
 Again, all other ideas are determinations of the idea 
 of being ; therefore they can be reduced to that idea. 
 Take, for instance, the idea of Shakspere. This is 
 an individual idea of the greatest of our English poets, 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 145 
 
 the most individual expression of somebody. But let 
 us resolve that into its more general elements, and 
 ask, What is the greatest of English poets ? A man — 
 something more general yet. But what is a man ? 
 A twofold substance, spiritual and material, united 
 together by one personality — more general still. But 
 what is a substance ? It is a being that stands by it- 
 self. Here we have reduced the idea of Shakspere 
 to the idea of being by stripping it of its determina- 
 tions ; therefore the idea of being is the first in the 
 logical order. 
 
 Being is the best known of all ideas, because we be- 
 come acquainted with things unknown by means of 
 that which we know. But we have the idea of being 
 by itself, and by its means we are introduced to the 
 knowledge of all other things ; therefore being is the 
 best known of all ideas. 
 
 The idea of being, therefore, does not include in 
 itself any determination of substance or accident, of 
 essence or existence, of reality or possibility ; because 
 with none of these conceptions can we reconcile the 
 characters and properties which become the idea of 
 being. 
 
 Q, What is the idea of not being ? 
 
 A. The negation of the idea of being — that is, Jtot/i- 
 ing. But nothing has not an idea of its own, since every- 
 thing is known inasmuch as it is, and nothing is the 
 negatioii of being ; therefore not/iing cannot be known 
 by itself or possess an idea of its own, but must be 
 conceived through the idea of being. 
 
 
I 
 
 46 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy, 
 
 ARTICLE SECOND. 
 
 Of the Univocal Attributio7i of Being and of the Principle 
 
 of Contradiction. 
 
 Q. In how many ways can a nature or property be 
 predicated of various subjects? 
 
 A. In two ways, univocally and equivocally. The 
 first is when that nature or property is attributed to, 
 and found in, the subject in the same degree and un- 
 der the same signification. The second is when that 
 nature or property is attributed to many, not because 
 found in them in the same degree, but in consequence 
 of a certain resemblance and proportion between the 
 subjects. For instance, we attribute the nature of 
 reasonable to all the subjects called men, in the same 
 degree and under the same signification ; therefore we 
 attribute it univocally. But we attribute the quality of 
 healthy to the animal body, to food, to air, to place, 
 not in the same sense and degree, but on account of 
 the resemblance between the objects called healthy ; 
 we attribute it, therefore, equivocally. 
 
 Q. To what can the idea of being be attributed 
 univocally? 
 
 A, Only to itself, as when we say. Being is ; then 
 being is attributed to itself in the same identical signifi- 
 cation. From this manner of attribution proceed va- 
 rious analytical judgments, as that which we call oiidcn- 
 iity, and which is expressed thus : That ivhich is^ is; that 
 which is not, is not. The judgment called of excluded 
 means — as. Something either is or is not ; or as that 
 spoken of — Being is. But on close consideration all 
 these judgments may be reduced to one, which is the 
 foundation of all judgments, and which is called the 
 principle of contradiction, which is expressed thus : 
 A thing cannot be and not be at the same time. 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 147 
 
 Q. Is this principle important in science ? 
 
 A. It is most important, as that which comprehends 
 all the judgments which arise from the univocal attri- 
 bution of being. 
 
 Q. What are its properties? 
 
 A. \. It is knoivn by itself. 
 
 Principles called self-evident, or known by them- 
 selves, are those in which the predicate is contained in 
 the idea of the subject ; so much so that the moment 
 we know the terms, that very mome.it we perceive the 
 truth of the judgment. Take the principle, for in- 
 stance, The whole is greater than any of its parts. 
 All we have to do to perceive the truth of this judg- 
 ment is to understand the terms, in which we find 
 that any part of a whole is contained in it as one of 
 its elements, and that, therefore, the whole is greater 
 than any of its parts, as a total is greater than the 
 units composing it. Now, in no other principle is this 
 quality of self-evidence found better than in that of 
 contradiction, because in it the predicate enters as 
 identical with the subject, since the terms of such 
 principle are, Being is being, not being is not being; 
 therefore the principle of contradiction is self-evident. 
 
 2. It is the most universal judgment and principle. 
 The narrowing of a judgment arises from two causes: 
 from the subjects to which they extend, and from the 
 matter of which they treat. For instance, the fol- 
 lowing judgment, Man is a reasonable animal^ is nar- 
 rowed down by the subject, because it extends to man 
 only, and even as to him it applies neither to his will, 
 his liberty, his body, his soul in general, but only to 
 his specific difference of being reasonable. And be- 
 cause the matter of which a judgment treats is repre- 
 sented by the predicate, as may be seen in the above 
 judgment, and in any other like it, we may say that a 
 
148 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 judgment is restricted and determined by .the predi- 
 cate and the subject. Hence the greater or lesser 
 universality of a judgment depends exclusively on the 
 terms composing it. Now, among all judgments, 
 there is none which has such universal terms as the 
 principle of contradiction, because its terms are being 
 and not being. Therefore it is the most universal prin- 
 ciple, and there can be no judgment not contained 
 therein. 
 
 3. It is the first and supreme principle. 
 
 A principle, to be such, must have two qualities : 
 I. It must be self-evident. 2. To it we must be able 
 to reduce all other principles. But we have shown 
 that the principle of contradiction is self-evident. We 
 can show also that we can reduce all other principles 
 to it, because principles and judgment are reducible 
 to another when they can be resolved into another, 
 more general, in which they are contained. For in- 
 stance, the principle, TJie head is smaller than the body, 
 is true, because it can be reduced to that other more 
 general principle, The part is siuallcr than the whole. 
 But the principle of contradiction is the most common 
 and universal principle; therefore to it can be reduced 
 all other principles ; therefore it holds the primacy 
 over all other principles. This is so true that no other 
 principle can be produced which may claim the prece- 
 dence over the principle ^f contradiction. Attempts 
 have been made by sevei. philosophers to bring for- 
 ward a principle which could pretend to this prece- 
 dence, but they have all failed. Des Cartes produced his 
 pet theory: I think, therefore I am ; but this principle 
 is true, because founded on that of contradiction. A 
 thing cannot be and not be at the same time, because 
 if the latter were not true how could one say, I think, 
 therefore I am ? since in that case it would not be con- 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 149 
 
 tradictory that one should think and not exist at the 
 same time. Leibnitz proclaimed his principle of suffi- 
 ciont reason, Nothing can exist without a sufficient 
 reason^ and pretended partial primacy for it ; but all 
 in vain, since, if the principle of contradiction were 
 not true, it would be possible for a thing to exist and 
 have no sufficient reason to account for it. Conse- 
 quently, Leibnitz was wrong in saying that the princi- 
 ple of cu itradiction was first among necessary truths, 
 and the principle of sufficient reason was first among 
 contingent truths, since all truths depend upon the 
 principle of contradiction, and it holds precedence of 
 them all. 
 
 ARTICLE THIRD. 
 Of the Analogical Attribution of Being. 
 
 Q. Of what is being predicated analogically ? 
 
 A. We have said that being is predicated univocally 
 only of itself; therefore it is attributed analogically to 
 all other subjects. These may be God and the crea- 
 ture, and the latter may be a substance or an accident ; 
 therefore being is predicated analogically of God, of 
 creatures, of substances, and of accidents. This may 
 be briefly demonstrated as follows : 
 
 I. We can attribute something univocally to a 
 number of subjects when they agree in the same spe- 
 cies, or at least in the same genus. When they do not 
 agree even as to genus, then we attribute the same 
 thing to them only in consequence of a certain com- 
 mon aspect or relation. Now, being cannot be genus, 
 as we have shown in the first article ; therefore we 
 cannot predicate being of God and creatures, of sub- 
 stances and accidents, univocally, but equivocally in 
 force of a certain common aspect we discover between 
 
150 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 them. Therefore God and the creature agree in the 
 common attribution, being, but only by a certain ana- 
 logy between them, and not because they belong to 
 the same species or genus or have tlie same being. 
 
 2. Univocals have this special property of their 
 own : that they are found, according to their common 
 aspect, in the same manner in all those subjects to 
 which they are attributed, as man, which is predicated 
 of many individuals, and is found in all of them in the 
 same manner. On the contrary, in analogous things 
 the common feature is found in a different way in the 
 subjects, as the attribute sound, which may be predi- 
 cated of food, of the animal body, of the mind, etc., 
 and which is not found in the same manner in these 
 several subjects. But being is not found in the same 
 manner in God and in the creature, in the substance 
 and in the accident ; therefore it can only be attri- 
 buted to them analogically. 
 
 3. Univocals are restricted by the difference which 
 lies outside the common nature, whereas analogicals 
 are determined always by the different manner in which 
 they enjoy that common aspect which makes them ana- 
 logicals. For instance, mtimal is not determined and 
 narrowed down by the different manner in which it is 
 found in man and in the brute, because it is the same 
 in both ; but by the difference of reasonable or un- 
 reasonable, which lies outside the essence of the ani- 
 mal. Now, being cannot be narrowed down by any 
 difference lying outside the nature of being — because 
 what is there which is not being ? — but it is narrowed 
 down by the different manner of being. Therefore 
 being is predicated analogically of those different sub- 
 jects. That being is found differently in God and in 
 the creature, in the substance and the accident, as 
 we have supposed in the minor of all the preceding 
 
Elements of Intellectual Ph ilosophy, 1 5 1 
 
 arguments, is evident ; because God is the essential, 
 most pure, infinite, independent being, the fulness of 
 all perfections of being ; whereas creatures are not 
 essential or necessary beings, nor have they the ful- 
 ness of being, but have a borrowed, finite, dependent 
 
 being. ■ v. , . . 
 
 Substances are independent of accidents as to their 
 existence ; accidents cannot exist without the sub- 
 stance. The latter possesses being directly and in 
 itself; the accident only indirectly and by means of 
 the substance. The being of the substance is strictly 
 such, but the accident is only an adjunct, an appendage 
 to the being of the substance. Therefore it is evi- 
 dent that being is found in a different manner in God 
 and in the creature, in the substance and the accident, 
 and that, therefore, we can predicate being of all these 
 subjects only analogically. 
 
 
 
^. ^v '■> - ■ ■ --v ♦' ! ■ , ,0 :;-,'^^ 
 
 CHAPTER II. 
 
 OF THE DETERMINATIONS OF BEING IN GENERAL,— 
 ESSENCE AND EXISTENCE. 
 
 ARTICLE FIRST. 
 
 How are Determinations of Being to be Understood ? 
 
 Q. How is the idea of being determined and nar- 
 rowed down ? 
 
 A. Being, as we have described it in the first chap- 
 ter, indeterminate and common, does not exist in 
 nature. To represent, therefore, a real being, that 
 idea, in force of its vagueness and indetermination, is 
 not sufficient, but must be made more definite and 
 contracted. But how is this to be done ? How can 
 being be made definite? AH other ideas can be 
 made more definite by adding something distinct 
 and different from them ; as, for instance, the idea 
 of animal is made more definite by adding to it 
 the element of reasonable. But this cannot be done 
 with the idea of being, because what can we add to it 
 which is not being? To limit, therefore, the idea of 
 being must be done by the same idea of being a little 
 more explicit ; because ideas must correspond to ob- 
 jects, but objects are so many special beings ; there- 
 fore their ideas can be nothing more than so many ex- 
 plicit conceptions of being. 
 
 Q. What are the first limitations of being ? 
 
 A. Two : essence and existence. But to under- 
 stand these two limitations it is necessary to speak 
 first o{ possibility. The idea of possibility has been 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 153 
 
 variously misrepresented by philosophers. A possible 
 is that which is capable of being. This aptitude may 
 be of two kinds: intrinsic and extrinsic. A being is 
 called intrinsically possible when the elements which 
 must constitute it do not clash with each other; be- 
 cause possibility has relation to being, hence all that 
 which may be is possible. But to prevent a thing from 
 being can be effected only by the principle of contra- 
 diction ; therefore all that which does not involve 
 an interior repugnance is possible. Now, the mere 
 intrinsic possibility or agreement of the elements 
 which have to constitute the being would not of 
 itself be sufficient for a being really to exist. An- 
 other condition is required, because everything which 
 may be cannot come from the mere possibility to the 
 actual act of being, except by means of a being 
 already in act which may carry that aptitude into 
 reality. To be able to exist by means of this exter- 
 nal agent carrying that internal aptitude into the ac- 
 tual fact of being is called extrinsic possibility. And 
 because these extrinsic agents or causes may be either 
 God or creatures, extrinsic possibility is divided, ac- 
 cording to St. Thomas, into possibility according to 
 the supreme cause — God — and into possibility accord- 
 ing to the proximate causes, meaning creatures. 
 
 Everything which is contrary to possibility is called 
 impossible, which may also be of two, kinds, intrinsic 
 and extrinsic impossibility. The first occurs when the 
 terms or elements of a thing are contradictory, as a 
 square circle, a four-angle triangle, a material spirit. 
 The second is found wjien there is no external cause to 
 carry the intrinsically possible into reality. From 
 these definitions we may gather that all that which is 
 intrinsically impossible is also externally so, and can 
 never be effected, even by God himself. 
 
154 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 Q. Give the different misrepresentations of this 
 idea by philosophers. 
 
 A. Hobbes, Spinoza, Robinet, doing away with all 
 idea of the possible, have said that thing only is pos- 
 sible which really exists. This is absurd. Possible is 
 that which may be. Now, if we look at the idea of 
 being in itself, we find tha^ it can extend not only to 
 things really existing, but also to many more. On 
 the other hand, if we regard the causes which may 
 reduce possibilities to act, we find that they could ef- 
 fect a great deal more than they actually do. We 
 know by the testimony of internal consciousness that 
 we could do a great many more things than we do. 
 God could certainly create many more things than he 
 has created, else his power were limited ; therefore the 
 idea of such philosophers is false. 
 
 Others have said that the omnipotence of God is 
 the index and the test of the intrinsic possible, that 
 alone being possible which can be effected by that 
 perfection. Now, in the first place, these philosophers 
 turn around in a circle, for if we ask them what is that 
 which God's omnipotence can do, they will answer. 
 That which is intrinsically possible ; and if we beg of 
 them to tell us what is intrinsically possible, they will 
 subjoin, That which God's power can do. 
 
 Finally, others, like Descartes, have said that the 
 intrinsic possibility of things depends upon the will 
 of God. If God wills a thing, well and good ; it is in- 
 trinsically possible. If he do not will it, it is impos- 
 sible. Now, according to this opinion, it would follow 
 that if God pleased to make the circle square he could 
 do so, or that a triangle should have four angles, which 
 is absurd, because that which involves a contradiction 
 is nonentity, a mere nothing. Consequently, in the 
 supposition of God's effecting that which is intrinsically 
 
Elements of Intellectual Ph ilosophy. 155 
 
 impossible, we would have the infinite power of God 
 exercising itself about, and resulting in, a nullity worse 
 than Parturient monies^ nascctur ridiculus mus, 
 
 ARTICLE SECOND. 
 Definition of Essence, 
 
 Q. What is essence ? 
 
 A. The idea of essence, in consequence of its sim- 
 plicity, is developed in various ways, and, according to 
 these different ways, it takes different names. Gather- 
 ing these different ways under certain heads, we may 
 say that essence may be considered under a threefold 
 aspect: i, in itself; 2, relatively to itsefifects; 3, re- 
 spectively to its conception in our minds. Considered 
 in itself, it may be defined : That ivhick causes a thing" 
 to be what it is and distinguishes it from all others. 
 Under this aspect it is strictly and properly called 
 essence. 
 
 Considered in its effects, it is defined : That first 
 radical and intimate principle of all actions; and proper- 
 ties zvhich may belong to a being. In this regard it is 
 called nature. 
 
 Finally, considering it relatively to our way of ap- 
 prehending it, it may be defined : That which is first 
 conceived as the first thing in a beings or that which is 
 expressed by the definition. Under this relation it is 
 called conception^ or reason. 
 
 From these definitions we draw the following corol- 
 laries : 
 
 I. Essence in the first sense— that is, in itself— 
 can only be attributed to substances, because the es- 
 sence is that which causes a being to be what it is 
 ind to be distinguished from all others ; therefore 
 it can be attributed to that only which strictly and 
 
156 Elements of Intellectual Ph ilosopky. 
 
 perfectly exists. But this can be said only of sub- 
 stances, because accidents are imperfect beings or 
 the mere complement of a being. Therefore essences, 
 strictly and properly speaking, can be attributed only 
 to substances. We say this not as meaning that acci- 
 dents have no essence, but as implying that it can be 
 attributed to accidents only imperfectly in the same 
 sense as being is predicated of them. 
 
 2. Essences dwell intimately in things, because 
 they are the principle and origin of the properties and 
 actions of things. Hence Plato was wrong in admit- 
 ting essences separated from things and existing in 
 themselves, and which were the cause of the being and 
 knowledge of things, because things are what they are 
 in force of their essence, and become known by means 
 of the essence. Therefore, if essences were separated 
 from objects, they would no longer be what they are, 
 and would not become known. 
 
 3. It follows that the essence is that by means of 
 which things are truly and properly known, and the first 
 thing we conceive about an object when wc come to 
 think about it. Hence the opinion of Locke and Gio- 
 bertl Is false which asserts that the essences of thincfs 
 are unknowable, and that our mind knows only certain 
 essences which it forms itself. Such an opinion is ab- 
 surd, first, because our knowledge can only be called 
 true knowledge when it corresponds to the reality of 
 things. But that by which things are what they are 
 is the essence ; therefore we have a knowledge of 
 things only when we know their essences. Conse- 
 quently, if essence were unknowable, we could never 
 have a true knowledge of things, and would fall into 
 scepticism. 
 
 2. Sciences would become impossible, inasmuch as 
 they are founded upon the essence of things. 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy, 157 
 
 3. It is a fact that we know the real essences of 
 many things, inasmuch as we perceive in them certain 
 differences which cause them to be what they are and 
 enable us to distinguish them from others, and which 
 differences we perceive as the source of all the pro- 
 perties of such things. For instance, we can distin- 
 guish plants from brutes, brutes from men, men from 
 pure spirits ; and we see something in all these as the 
 principle and source of their properties. Now, if 
 this is not knowing the real essence of these things, 
 what is? 
 
 4. Finally, we cannot see why the essences of 
 things should be unknowable and unthinkable. Every- 
 thing is knowable inasmuch as it is and in the way it 
 is. But the essence is that by which a thing is what 
 it is ; therefore everything is knowable by its essence, 
 and it cannot be impossible that essences should be 
 known and be the object of our thought. 
 
 Q. How are essences distinguished ? 
 
 A. Essences cause beings to be what they are; 
 therefore they must be different, according to the dif- 
 ference of beings. Now, beings are first classified 
 as substances and accidents ; therefore there must be 
 essences of substances and essences of accidents. The 
 first are found perfectly in the beings of which they 
 are the essence ; the second only imperfectly. The 
 essences of substances, then, are divided into essences 
 of material substances and essences of simple and im- 
 material substances. The first are composed of matter 
 and form, and cannot be without matter. The others 
 are forms only, without matter, and consequently are 
 more perfect than the first.* 
 
 r. * St Thomas, Z7« £»/a // £'«Mii//a. „ . i . >.* ' 
 
 f • » " ' ■ ^ . 
 
1 5 8 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy, 
 
 • '•'■■. .- ' ' ARTICLE THIRD. " * ' 
 
 , Remarks on Essences. 
 
 Q. What rema'rks have you to make on essences ? 
 
 A. The first is about the indivisibility of essences. 
 From our having distinguished essences of simple sub- 
 stances, one must not infer that such essences are simple, 
 having one single property ; nor from our having dis- 
 tinguished essences of compound substances has any 
 one a right to conclude that such essences may be di- 
 vided into parts like their substances. With the exclu- 
 sion of the divine essence, all other essences are formed 
 of more than one property, but they are all indivisi- 
 ble in spite of that. Essences locate objects in their 
 proper species and genus, cause them to be what they 
 are and to be distinguished from all others. Hence 
 it happens that definitions which express essences 
 must be composed of the proximate genus and the 
 specific difference, because the essences of creatures 
 must have something which agrees with other crea- 
 tures, and something which may distinguish them 
 from others. Consequently, they must have at least a 
 twofold property, that of the proximate genus and that 
 of the specific difference. But, nevertheless, they are 
 indivisible, as Aristotle says, like the species of num- 
 bers, to which if we add or subtract a unit their spe- 
 cies is changed. Likewise with essences: if we add 
 to them one property or take away one property, they 
 are no longer the same essences. For instance, if we add 
 to the genus animal the species reasonable we have 
 man ; or if we take reasonable we have the brute. 
 Essences, therefore, are composed of more than one 
 property, but are indivisible in the sense that we can 
 neither add to nor subtract from them any property 
 necessary to make such essences. 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy, 159 
 
 The second remark is that to all essences may be 
 attributed the three following qualities : immutability, 
 necessity^ and eternity. But as this may be misunder- 
 stood, it is necessary to explain in what sense an es- 
 sence is immutable, necessary, and eternal. Essences 
 cannot be said to be immutable, necessary, and eternal 
 in the sense that they have a position and actual exist- 
 ence in themselves. Before they actually existed in 
 themselves they did not exist at all ; they were created 
 in time, and might, absolutely speaking, be destroyed. 
 Hence in this sense they are mutable, contingent, 
 and temporary. But they are said to be immutable, 
 necessary, and eternal in two ways: i. As to the 
 elements of which they are composed. These, as 
 we have said, are indivisible, inasmuch as we can 
 neither add to nor subtract from them, otherwise they 
 would not form the same essence. In this sense they 
 cannot change. Now, what is unchangeable is neces- 
 sary and eternal ; therefore essences, with regard to 
 the elements of which they are composed, are im- 
 mutable, necessary, and eternal. For instance, a tri- 
 angle is composed of three angles and three sides ; 
 ' and hence at no time will it ever be possible that it 
 could have four angles and four sides and remain a 
 triangle. 
 
 2. Essences are immutable, necessary, eternal in- 
 asmuch as they are found positively in God's essence 
 and intellect, because wc know that in God are to be 
 found the archetypes of all things. Essences, there- 
 fore, inasmuch as they exist in the divine intellect, in 
 which are the archetypes of all things, are immutable, 
 necessary, and eternal. ,"• 
 
 But from the fact that essences, as to the elements 
 from which they result, and inasmuch as they are seen 
 by the divine intellect in God's essence, are immu- 
 table, necessary, and eternal, wc cannot infer that they 
 
1 60 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 do or must actually exist in themselves outside the 
 essence of God. But the only inference we can draw 
 is that if they ever exist in themselves— :i thing de- 
 pending on the free-will of God — they must necessarily 
 be composed of such elements. 
 
 The last remark regards essences in relation to 
 their properties and action. 
 
 And, first, as to properties. These being so bound 
 up with the essence, it follows that by adding or sub- 
 tracting one of them the essence vanishes ; and, vice 
 versdy excluding the essence, the properties also van- 
 ish. This, of course, must be understood 0^ essential 
 properties. 
 
 With regard to the action, we remark that, the es- 
 sence being the most intimate and first principle of 
 action in a thing, these actions must be agreeable in 
 nature to the essence, because every being acts as it is. 
 If it were otherwise, the being would and would not 
 be such a being, which is a contradiction. 
 
 ARTICLE FOURTH. 
 Oti Existence. 
 
 Q. What is existence ? 
 
 A. The idea of existence is so simple that it can 
 hardly be defined. We shall treat of it as follows : We 
 have said that in God exist the archetypes of all es» 
 sences — that is to say, the idea of the elements of 
 which the essences of things must be composed ; and 
 we have remarked also that as snch they have no real 
 existence in themselves. But suppose God determines 
 to realize those ideas, and does so in fact ; in that case 
 the essences are actualized. This gives the idea of 
 existence, which may be defined that by which an 
 essence is brought out of nothing, or the realization 
 or actuality of an essence in itself. 
 
CHAPTER III. 
 
 OF THE MANNER IN WHICH ESSENCE AND EXISTENCE 
 CO-OPERATE TO FORM A REAL BEING. 
 
 Q. How do essence and existence co-operate to 
 form a real being? 
 
 A. To have real being essence and existence are 
 necessary. This is proved as follows: First the es- 
 sence is necessary. The essence is that by which a 
 thing is what it is and is distinguished from all others ; 
 the radical, internal principle of all the properties and 
 actions of the thing — that which is manifested by the 
 idea of the thing. But all real being is something 
 in itself, by which something it is distinct from all 
 others ; it has properties and actions, and, conse- 
 quently, an internal principle from which its actions 
 proceed, and is necessarily possessed of a conception 
 peculiar to itself. Therefore in all real being the es- 
 sence is necessary. 
 
 Existence is also necessary. Existence is the act 
 of the essence, or that by which the essence is put 
 beyond the sphere of' possibility by having undergone 
 the action of the cause. But all essences of real being 
 must be actual and not potential ; they must have 
 passed from under the action of the cause, because 
 when a thing is under the action of the cause it is on 
 the way to existence, but does not as yet exist, and, 
 when it is in nothingness, is not real. Therefore 
 existence is necessary to real being. 
 
 We must remark here that essence and existence are 
 distinct in created beings, but not so in God. In fact, if 
 
 iSi 
 
1 62 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 in creatures essence were the same thing as existence, 
 creatures would always exist by the necessity of their 
 nature. Because that is indispensable to them which 
 is required by their essence ; if, therefore, in the sup- 
 position their essence were the same as existence, 
 the latter would be indispensable to them, and hence 
 their existence would be necessary by the necessity 
 of their nature. But such a thing cannot be said of 
 creatures, which do not exist by the necessity of their 
 nature ; therefore in creatures essence is distinct from 
 existence. 
 
 2. If there were a creature in which essence were 
 not distinct from existence, to it we should naturally 
 attribute all that which belongs to being, as such. But 
 it does not become being, as such, to be an effect, be- 
 cause in that case every being would be an effect, and 
 God also. Therefore, if in creatures existence were 
 not distinct from essence, their being would not be 
 an effect ; in other words, they would no longer be 
 creatures. 
 
 But if essence and existence were distinct in all 
 beings, all beings would have an existence by acci- 
 dent ; all would be potential beings first before being 
 actual ; all beings would be produced without our 
 ever being able to find a necessary cause always in 
 act. But this would be a contradiction ; therefore we 
 must, on the other hand, admit the necessity of a 
 being in which essence and existence are not distinct, 
 and which may be the cause of all the others. This 
 is the uncreated Being. This will be better explained 
 in Theology. 
 
 Q. How are essence and existence distinguished ? 
 
 A. They cannot be distinguished as true parts of 
 a whole, because a part is not the whole. But the es- 
 sence is not a part of the substance but of the whole — 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 1 63 
 
 that is, of the whole substance. Therefore essence and 
 existence cannot be distinct from each as true integral 
 parts, nor concur to form the real being as parts form 
 the whole. Again, the part does not exhibit the idea 
 of the whole. But the essence exhibits the idea of 
 the whole being ; therefore essence cannot consti- 
 tute the real being as an integral part constitutes the 
 whole. They concur, therefore, as act and potenti-. 
 ality, because the act of the essence is existence. We 
 might also say that they concur as two acts, because 
 the essence is the act of being, inasmuch as it makes 
 it be such and no other ; existence is the act of being, 
 inasmuch as it draws it out of nothing and determines 
 it to the act.* 
 
 * St. Thomas. C0K/r , lib. ii. ch. 34. 
 
 
 
 
itv.:-/ ■■■ ■.. . .. :, . .. . ,■,.. ; ., .. . ... . ■ . ■ . " 
 
 .k 
 
 CHAPTER IV. 
 
 • ., . . OJf THE PROPERTIES OF BEING. 
 
 ARTICLE FIRST. 
 
 • ■• V . Qn Unity. 
 
 Q. How can being have properties, and what can 
 they be ? 
 
 A. In the first place, the properties of being cannot 
 be something merely ideal or purely negative. Not 
 ideal, because that which is fashioned by the intellect 
 and has only a logical existence cannot be the property 
 of being. Not purely negative, because the idea of pro- 
 perty implies always something positive and real. On 
 the other hand, the idea of being is the most common 
 and universal, and comprehends everything in itself. 
 What, consequently, is there positive and real in 
 beings distinct from itself, which may answer as its 
 properties? 
 
 Nothing. Therefore if a property must be some- 
 thing positive, and if there can be nothing positive 
 which is not included in being, we must conclude that 
 the properties of being cannot be anything else than 
 being itself, inasmuch as it is affected either by some 
 negation or some other extrinsic relation which may 
 really be attributed to it. As to negation, this can- 
 not affect being, except in the sense that we deny of it 
 its being divided, because being, taken universally, does 
 not present this or that distinction ; hence we cannot 
 
 deny of it this or that particular thing, but only that 
 
 164 
 
Elements of Intellectual Ph ilosophy. 1 6 5 
 
 which is opposed to being, which is next to absolute 
 negation — that is, division, as we shall see. 
 
 Division alone, therefore, can be denied of being ; 
 and this negation of division constitutes the first 
 property of being, which is unity. 
 
 With regard to extrinsic relations, there cannot be 
 any others than those referring to the intellect and 
 to the will, because only the relation to the intellect 
 and to the will is common to all beings. But the 
 relation of being to the intellect is called truth, and 
 the relation of being to the will goodness ; therefore 
 the properties of being are no more than three — 
 unity, truth, and goodness. And they arise from being 
 in this order : first unity, next truth, and, finally, 
 goodness.* 
 
 Q. Explain the idea of metaphysical unity. 
 
 A. The first property of being, then, is unity. This 
 may be defined : TJiat property of being by which it is un- 
 divided in itself and divided from others. 
 
 This is called metaphysical unity, but to under- 
 stand it well it is necessary to carefully determine 
 it. First, it must not be confounded with numeri- 
 cal unity — to wit, that unity which is the measure 
 and principle of number. From this arise two, 
 three, four — that is, number ; but from metaphysical 
 unity no number can arise, at least directly, but only 
 being. Neither must we confound the property of 
 unity with that quality which makes a thing unique, 
 because the latter property implies that a thing is 
 sole, or that which excludes the existence of an equal 
 thing, whereas the former excludes a division of it- 
 
 * This natural m>stery of three distinct things in being, and which, though dis» 
 tinct from each other, cannot be anything else than one being, can only beexplained by 
 a higher and more sublime mystery, the principal dogma of our faith — the Trinity. 
 We shall develop this view in the internal evidences of Christianity in the second 
 volume of this work. 
 
1 66 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 self. In a word, metaphysical unity adds nothing to 
 being, except the negation of its being divided. But 
 from this, however, we cannot deduce that the idea 
 of unity is a negative one. Also iinmefise, immortal, 
 immutable seem to express a negative, yet their idea 
 is positive ; likewise unity, which, after all, does not 
 imply anything else, except the same entity * of being, 
 inasmuch as it is not divided. We have added to the 
 definition that which divides it from others, so that 
 this unity implies two elements, that of being undi- 
 vided in itself and divided from others. The first is 
 necessary and essential to metaphysical unity ; the 
 second is a consequence of the first, because a being 
 is distinct from others, for the very reason that it is 
 in itself undivided. 
 
 Q. Prove that every being is one. 
 
 A. Everything is and is called being inasmuch as 
 it has an entity of its own. But that which has an en- 
 tity of its own does not contain more t' .n one being, 
 and is, therefore, in itself undivided ; and that which 
 has an entity of its own does not share it with others, 
 and is, therefore, distinct and divided from others, all 
 of which things are necessary conditions to establish 
 metaphysical unity ; therefore every being is one. 2. 
 Every being has an essence, by which it is restricted 
 to be this and not another. Now, to be restricted to a 
 particular existence means, first, to be confined and 
 restricted under special form, and not to be divided 
 into several entities ; besides, if it is restricted to a 
 special existence it is necessarily distinct and divided 
 from all others ; therefore every being is one. 
 
 3. Finally, a being is either simple or composite — 
 that is, either immaterial or material. If it be simple, 
 
 .* ' *'-'/! !• V • Word uied by Boitley. * ,' 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 1 6 7 
 
 it is undivided in itself, both actually and potentially, 
 and not only undivided but indivisible, and this by 
 necessity of nature. If it be composite, then it may 
 be divisible potentially ; but actually it is always un- 
 divided, because it does not possess its entity when its 
 parts are divided, but only when they are united; 
 therefore every being is itself undivided. Every being, 
 therefore, is one, and unity is convertible with being. 
 
 Q. What remarks must be made on the nature of 
 unity ? 
 
 A. We have said that the idea of metaphysical 
 unity implies two elements, indivision in itself and di- 
 vision from other beings — the first necessary and essen- 
 tial, the second a consequence of the first. Now, we 
 must make some remarks on both. As to the first, it 
 is clearly seen that unity, or indivision in itself, is a 
 perfection of being, and that a being is perfect in pro- 
 portion to its indivision, and for that reason we say 
 that the idea of unity is positive. 
 
 We have said, moreover, that unity is convertible 
 with being ; therefore it is different in proportion to 
 the difference of being. Now, beings may be simple 
 or composite ; therefore unity may be twofold : the 
 unity of simplicity^ which consists in a thing not only 
 being undivided actually, but in being altogether 
 indivisible ; the unity of composition, which agrees 
 with composite beings, and which implies actual 
 indivision and potential division — that is, though 
 actually undivided it may be divided. Again, this 
 composition may be essential or accidental — as, for 
 instance, the union of the body and soul is essential, 
 the union of many soldiers to form an army is acci- 
 dental ; hence two kinds of unity of composition, 
 natural and accidental. 
 
 This indivision, whether it belongs to composite or 
 
1 68 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy, 
 
 simple beings, whether it agrees with them naturally 
 or accidentally, inasmuch as it is considered as really 
 corresponding to itself, is called identity. Wherefore 
 identity is, strictly speaking, the absolute conformity 
 of a being with itself; and only in a loose sense can 
 we call identity the conformity of one being with 
 another. 
 
 As to the other element of unity — that is, distinction 
 from other beings — this may be of different kinds and 
 has several degrees. 
 
 Distinction, like indivision, follows the condition of 
 being. Now, one being may be divided from another 
 either really or logically ; therefore the distinction of 
 one being from another may be of two kinds, logical 
 and real. It is logical when things are not really dis- 
 tinct from each other, but are so conceived and dis- 
 tinguished by the intellect ; for instance, in God his 
 essence and his attributes are not leally distinct, but 
 our intellect, the better to know them, considers them 
 separately by a logical distinction. Real is when a 
 thing is not really another; as, between cause and 
 effect there passes a real distinction. Both are of dif- 
 ferent kinds: the real is subdivided into substantial, 
 accidental, and modal ; the substantial is that which 
 exists between separate substances — for instance, be- 
 tween man and the brute, or between the principles 
 really distinct of a composite substance, as between 
 the soul and bod} , which are the principles forming 
 man. 
 
 Accidental and modal distinction is that which 
 exists between the substance and its modifications, or 
 between one accident and another and its modes. 
 
 Logical distinction is subdivided, in a twofold man- 
 ner, into purely mental or logical and into virtually 
 logical. The former occurs when the mind makes the 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 1 69 
 
 distinction without having any foundation in reality, 
 as if one were to distinguish man from reasonable 
 animal. The second is when it is made with some 
 foundation in reality, as when we distinguish in the 
 human soul the rational, the sensitive, and the vege- 
 tative principle, because, though the soul is but one 
 principle, it has yet these three faculties and affords 
 some foundation for that distinction. 
 
 Distinction may have different degrees, because 
 that which is different from another may be so more 
 or less, according as it is more or less conformable 
 with the other. Now, the limits of conformity or 
 non-conformity determine the degrees of distinction. 
 This gives rise to various notions, i. Things may be 
 distinct from each other as to the essence, inasmuch 
 as the essence of one is not the essence of the other, 
 and in this case they are called diverse^ and the dis- 
 tinction diversity. 2. Things may agree in the es- 
 sence or some other common feature, but vary as to 
 the manner in which the essence or the feature common 
 to both is found in each; and in this case those things 
 are called different, and the distinction difference. 3. 
 Or they may agree in the essence and in the determi- 
 nations of the essence, but vary as to their qualities; 
 and in this case they are called dissimilar, and the 
 distinction dissimilarity ; and if they agree, similar ^ 
 and the agreement similarity. 4. If things agree in 
 essence, determination of the essence, and qualities, 
 but vary in quantity, they are called unequal^ and the 
 distinction inequality ; and if they are even in this, 
 equal, and the agreement equality. 5. Finally, if 
 things are considered as divided only in respect to 
 number, they are called distinct, and the division dis- 
 tinction, ., . , .... .. 
 
1 70 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy, 
 
 ARTICLE SECOND. 
 
 On the Truth of Being. 
 
 Q. Give the idea of metaphysical truth. 
 
 A. In Logic we defined truth to be the conformity 
 or the agreement of things with the intellect. Now, 
 things may Lc regarded as related to the intellect in 
 two ways : either because they are produced by it, or 
 because they are merely the object of its apprehen- 
 sion. For instance, all natural things can be referred 
 to the divine intellect in the first manner, not only 
 inasmuch as they are known by it but also inasmuch 
 as they are created by it. They can be referred to the 
 human intellect only in the second manner, inasmuch 
 as they are known by it. From this arises the distinc- 
 tion of truth into metaphysical and logi«.d. Meta- 
 physical truth consists in the agreement of all natural 
 things with the divine intellect, on which they depend 
 for their existence. Logical truth consists in the 
 agreement of the conceptions of our intellect with the 
 things which those conceptions represent. Here we 
 treat merely of metaphysical truth, to establish which 
 two things are required : the entity of the thing which 
 is the foundation of truth, and its agreement with the 
 type existing in the divine intellect. 
 
 Q. What errors were maintained by Wolfius and 
 Locke with regard to the essence of metaphysical 
 truth? 
 
 A. Wolfius and his followers held that the formal 
 reason or essence of truth consists only in the entity 
 of a thing. Locke maintained that it lies in the 
 agreement of the real existence of things with the 
 ideas of our intellect. Both these opinions are false. 
 The first is false because, if the entity of a thing alone 
 
Elements of Intellectual Ph ilosophy. 171 
 
 established \\s truth, truth would not imply any rela- 
 tion, but would be altogether the same thing with 
 being, and hence entity and truth would be only two 
 words meaning the identical thing. But this conse- 
 quence is false by the admission of the Wolfians them- 
 selves, who teach that truth is not the thing itself, 
 but a transcendental property of being. Therefore 
 the essence of truth cannot consist in the entity of a 
 thing. 
 
 The second opinion is false. The essence of truth 
 cannot be placed in the agreement of things with an 
 intellect to which they are related only accidentally, 
 but witli an intellect to which they are necessarily and 
 essentially related. Now, things are related neces- 
 sarily and essentially only to the divine intellect, and 
 only accidentally to our intellect ; therefore the truth 
 of things must be found in their conformity with the 
 divine intellect. 
 
 Q. Prove that every being is true. 
 
 A. I. Every being is just what i is. But every 
 being is just what it is because God has thought to 
 make it so ; therefore every being is what God has 
 thought it to be, and, therefore, conformable with 
 the divine type. 
 
 2. If things did not correspond with the divine 
 archetypes after which God made them, we should 
 conclude that either he knew not or could not create 
 them just as he thought them out. But the first sup- 
 position is repugnant to infinite Wisdom ; the second, 
 to divine Omnipotence. Therefore all beings must be 
 conformable with the divine archetypes. Hence wich 
 reason was it said by the schoolmen that being and 
 truth are convertible terms — that is, that every truth is 
 being because the truth of things is founded upon 
 the entity of a thing, and every being is true be- 
 
172 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 cause every being necessarily implies a relation with 
 the divine intellect. 
 
 Q. What remarks must be made on the nature of 
 truth? :■;. - •■ ,. ;., 
 
 A. From what we have said it is clear that the 
 nature of metaphysical truth is such that it absolutely 
 excludes the contrary ; hence it would be abstird to 
 say thi there can be metaphysical falsehood, and if 
 we call anything false we do so only in a logical sense 
 — that is, it is true in itself, but we may misapprehend 
 it. 
 
 It is clear, in the second place, that truth is neces- 
 sary and universal, because all beings must necessa- 
 rily be related to their types which are in the divine 
 intellect; whereas logical truth is accidental, because 
 things are not necessarily and by their nature related 
 to our intellect, but, on the contrary, the latter is re- 
 lated to them. Finally, it is clear also that in meta- 
 physical truth the intellect is the measure of things, 
 because things have in themselves just what the intel- 
 lect has idealized and proposed to create ; on the con- 
 trary, in logical truth things are the measure of the 
 intellect, because the latter can know just what things 
 represent. Hence in metaphysical truth first comes 
 the operation of the intellect and next the thing ; in 
 logical truth first the thing and then the operation of 
 the intellect. , - . r • 
 
 Q. Is truth one or manifold ? 
 
 A. We must answer by making a distinction. If we 
 speak of logical truth, then it is not one but many ; 
 because logical truth is the agreementof the conception 
 of the intellect with the things which those concep- 
 tions represent ; therefore there can be as many logical 
 truths as there are things of which faithful conceptions 
 may be formed by the intellect. , 
 
Elements of Intellectual 'Philosophy, 173 
 
 If we speak of metaphysical truth, then we must dis- 
 tinguish again. If we look at truth in its formal rea- 
 son or essence, that which really makes it truth, then 
 it is only one ; because that which makes all being-: 
 true is their conformity with the divine intellect. Now, 
 this relation with the divine intellect is only one and 
 the same in all things ; therefore in this sense meta- 
 physical truth is one. If we look at truth in its 
 fundamental aspect — that is, at the entity of things 
 — as there are various entities, so we may say that 
 there are various truths. But it must be under- 
 stood that truth in the latter sense is only taken 
 improperly and analogically, and not in its true and 
 proper sense. 
 
 Q. Is truth necessary, immutable, and eternal ? 
 
 A. W^ must again distinguish. If we speak of 
 metaphysical truth, it is so, because this truth is, pro- 
 perly speaking, in the divine intellect. But everything 
 which is found in the divine intellect is necessary, im- 
 mutable, and eternal; therefore truth is necessary, 
 immutable, and eternal. But if we speak of logical 
 truth, then we must again distinguish. If it is ques- 
 tion of the truth of first principles and their most 
 immediate consequences, this is certainly necessary, 
 immutable, and eternal, because no one can be de- 
 ceived or change his opinion about them. But their 
 necessity, immutability, and eternity is like that of es- 
 sences, of which we have spoken. If we speak of those 
 truths which are discovered by reasoning, and are 
 deduced immediately from first principles, then the 
 conformity of our intellect with them may change, not 
 because what has been once conformable with things 
 may change in itself but because our intellect may dis- 
 miss it and turn to error. Hence in the sense ex- 
 plained we may say w'*^h Shakspere : 
 
J 74 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 "s ) .. " Truth is truth to the end of reckoning";* t> '.V i f 
 or with Bryant : 
 
 " Truth crushed to earth shall rise again: If,,-, •, ; ■ 
 The eternal years of God are hers." f 
 
 ,/•(•,. . .1. .;?,t^i'n',"U» '>v.; ;.i.;.;:jf •(.iiUiiiiU'!;:.. •; i)..j ^r;, , 
 
 '• • ' ' ARTICLE THIRD. ^' - ■'' it . j:*. ■ ; ' J/i . 
 
 Of the Goodness of Being. 
 
 .1 i,\ • 
 
 Q. Give an idea of the goodness of being. 
 
 A. Some have said that, formally speakir ^, good- 
 ness is the same as being. But if such were the case, 
 goodness would add nothing to being, and the idea of 
 both would be the same. Now,, this is false, because 
 either in speaking or thinking we distinguish these 
 two ideas from each other. Others have held that 
 the formal conception of goodness is the same as that 
 of perfection. This is also false, because we think a 
 being perfect by considering it alone by itself, and in- 
 asmuch as it does no't fail to have all those things 
 requisite for its essence, virtue, and operation, the 
 very things in which perfection consists. On the con- 
 trary, goodness always implies a relation to a ten- 
 dency of which it forms the proper object, because 
 that which a tendency yearns after is goodness. We 
 are obliged, therefore, to conclude that goodnesr, for- 
 mally and essentially considered, lies in its being 
 sought after by a tendency or appetitive faculty, and 
 it may therefore be defined: That property for which a 
 thing is sought after. •'' " '' -'^ ' <* - -. » 
 
 Q. How many kinds of goodness are there ? 
 
 A. Three kinds, metaphysical, physical, and moral. 
 The first consists in this, that a being is sought as 
 being in general ; the second, inasmuch as it is such a 
 
 V 'V.i * **■ »*. 
 
 • " Measure for Measure." ''i'iW^i^r- lUiVK V,li:i f Bryant's poems. 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 171 
 
 being in particular ; the third, inasmuch as it is agree- 
 able with moral laws. We shall speak here only of 
 metaphysical goodness. • ; • 
 
 Q. Prove that every being is good. . . . 
 
 A. That this metaphysical goodness is the common 
 and necessary property of every being is proved thus : 
 The formal reason of the goodness of a being lies in 
 the fact that it may be sought after by an appetitive 
 tendency. But every being may be sought after by an 
 appetitive tendency ; therefore every being is good. 
 The major is apparent from the definition of goodness 
 we have already given. The minor is proved as follows : 
 A thing is appetible inasmuch as it is perfect, because 
 every being seeks and desires only its own perfection. 
 But every being, as being, is perfect, because every 
 being, as such, is in act, and a thing is called perfect 
 inasmuch as it is in act. Therefore every being is 
 appetible. 
 
 O. What remarks have you to make on the nature 
 of goodness? 
 
 A. I. It is clear from the reason just given that, 
 
 though goodness in its formal idea is distinct from 
 
 perfection and entity, it has yet a strict alliance 
 
 with both ; because every being is good inasmuch as 
 
 it is perfect, and is perfect inasmuch as it is being, so 
 
 that being is the foundation of the perfect, and the 
 
 perfect the ground-work of the good ; hence in order 
 
 being comes first, next the perfect, and last the good. 
 
 For this reason it is said that goodness is convertible 
 
 with being. ,,.:,. _..yT...M\, ■..:-■• v;;,'.V 
 
 ■ ,. "t . -■ ■ <■ • . . ■ 
 
 ■ > II Q^Q truth is clear : whatever is, is right." 
 
 . «,' ' ; • — roPE. 
 
 2. As being may be either essential or accidental, 
 so metaphysical goodness may be either essential or 
 
176 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 accidental. Essential goodness is that which is be- 
 coming to essences ; and as essences are incapable of 
 "rowth or decrease, so neither is essential goodness 
 capable of such change. Accidental goodness is capa- 
 ble of 'Tfovvth or decrease, because accident does not 
 constitute the essence, but is added to the essence 
 already constituted, as to be learned is accidental to 
 goodness, and therefore may be pable of increase 
 or diminution. 3. From this theory of the goodness 
 of being other most important corollaries follow in 
 relation to evil. 
 
 Evil is the opposite of good, and is defined : The 
 absence of a perfection required vt a being. For in- 
 stance, sight is required in man's body, and hence its 
 absence is a real evil. But if a perfection is not re- 
 quired by the nature of a being, its absence cannot be 
 called evil ; hence if a stone is not endowed with a 
 rational principle, this can nev6r be called an evil. 
 
 In this sense Pope has said : 
 
 " Then say not man's imperfect, Heaven in fault ; 
 Say rather man's as perfect as he ought : 
 His knowledge measured to his state and place, 
 His time a moment, and a point his space." 
 
 —Essay on Man. 
 
 From this it follows : i. That evil is not in itself an 
 entity. Every entity is good, because, as we have 
 said, good is convertible v/ith being. Now, evil is the 
 opposite of good ; therefore evil is the opposite of 
 entity, or the privation of being. 2. Evil is founded 
 and exists in good. If evil has no entity of its own, it 
 follows that it cannot exist in itself; therefore it 
 must exist in some being. But every being is good ; 
 therefore evil must exist in good. 3. Einl supposes a 
 cause^ and this cannot be hit a good. Evil is the pri- 
 vation and the absence of a certain perfection which 
 
Elemenis of Intellectual Ph ilosophy. 1 7 7 
 
 the nature of being requires and must have. But that 
 a certain being should be deprived of its natural per- 
 fection, this must originate in a cause which may draw 
 that being outside its disposition and order ; there- 
 fore evil supposes a cause. This cause must be good. 
 Because a nonentity cannot be cause, as it cannot act ; 
 if evil, therefore, must have cause, this must be an 
 entity. But good and entity are convertible ; there- 
 fore good is the cause of evil. 4. Good is the cause of 
 evil only accidentally. Every effect must have a pro- 
 portion and likeness with its cause ; therefore the 
 proper effect of good cannot be but good. If, there- 
 fore, sometimes it produces evil, this cannot be but by 
 accident. 5. Metaphysical evil, propounded by Leibnitz^ 
 is an absurdity. Metaphysical evil, according to 
 Leibnitz, consists in the limitation of the creature, in- 
 asmuch as it cannot have other perfections than those 
 required by its essence and nature. Now, this is not 
 evil, because evil is the absence of a perfection re- 
 quired by the nature of a being. But perfections 
 which are not required by the nature of a being 
 are not due to it ; therefore their absence cannot be 
 an evil. Hence metaphysical evil, invented by Leib- 
 nitz and his followers, does not exist. 
 
 Q. What is the order of the transcendental proper- 
 ties of being? 
 
 A. They proceed from being in this manner: first is 
 unity, next truth, and, last, goodness. That unity 
 is the first transcendental property of being is evident 
 because it is absolute, ancf becomes being by itself 
 and not by any denomination to any exterior thing, as 
 truth, which implies a relation to an intellect ; and 
 goodness, which implies a relation to an appetitive 
 faculty. Now, the absolute is before the relative ; 
 therefore unity is before truth and goodness. Next 
 
1 78 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy, 
 
 comes truth, because, i. Truth implies a relation to 
 an intellect, goodness to an appetitive faculty or a 
 will. But the intellect precedes the will; therefore 
 truth is before goodness. 2. Because goodness is, in 
 a certain manner, founded on truth; health, for in- 
 stance, to be good, must be real, true health, because 
 if it were false it could not be good health. Now, the 
 foundation of a thing precedes the thing itself; there- 
 fore truth is before goodness. From this, of course, 
 we must not conclude that the aforesaid properties are 
 really distinguishable from being; their distinction 
 from it being only logical, without a foundation in re- 
 ality. ,.•..- 
 
 ' ' ' . . . . • • ' * 
 
 ■ ' '• • ARTICLE FOURTH. ,7 
 
 The Beautiful. 
 
 Q. Why do you speak here of the beautiful, and 
 what is its definition ? 
 
 We speak here of the beautiful because it has such 
 close connection with unity, truth, and goodness. 
 Nov/, before giving the definition of the beautiful we 
 must distinguish three things about it : the formal 
 essence of the beautiful, its foundation, and its effect. 
 
 And, first, as to its foundation. The beautiful is 
 founded on goodness, because our soul cannot take 
 pleasure in anything except what it desires and craves 
 for. But our soul cannot crave except what it appre- 
 hends as good ; therefore our soul cannot take plea- 
 sure except in what it appllehends as good. Now, our 
 soul does take pleasure in the beautiful ; therefore it 
 must apprehend something good in the beautiful as its 
 foundation. '^^r. f>^M'<J"r^.: ;>>:>: ,,7,,:' li/v^iI^/ -.? ..ifs.,,., 
 '• As to its effect, it is admitted by all philosophers, 
 and confirmed by the common sense of mankind, that 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 179 
 
 the effect of the beautiial consists in giving pleasure. 
 The simplest child, for instance, in looking at the sky 
 in its most magnificent apparel, in looking at a land- 
 scape, cries out, with pleasure beaming from its eyes, 
 Oh ! how beautiful, how charming. And what the 
 child does, so do the most consummate artists, as was 
 the case with Michael Angelo in the presence of the 
 Apollo of Belvedere, when he stood, day after day, 
 rapt in pleasure, contemplating that wonderful repre- 
 sentation of the human form divine, chiselled with 
 such admirable art and truth, which has not as yet 
 been surpassed ; the effect of the beautiful, therefore, 
 is to give pleasure. 
 
 As to its essence, the beautiful consists in variety 
 reduced to unity by order and proportion of the parts 
 with each other and with the whole. 
 
 Q. Explain the definition. 
 
 A. The beautiful consists, i, in variety y because if 
 we were to contemplate unity bare and naked, and no- 
 thing but unity, we should soon get tired and wearied 
 and turn a\vay from it in disgust. 
 
 2. In unity ; because if we saw a number of objects 
 without any connection or relation with each other, 
 the same effect would result : we should take no plea- 
 sure '\i\ contemplating them. 
 
 3. Order is required, because a number of objects 
 put together without any idea or principle regulating 
 their arrangement would present nothing but con- 
 fusion, and be not only unable to cause pleasure but 
 render impossible the unity required for the beautiful. 
 
 4. Proportion is required between the parts and the 
 whole. This proportion means that there should be 
 a kind of softening in the variety of each part, so as to 
 gently make way for the unity of the whole ; because 
 if the parts were kept in their decided, crude variety 
 
, 1 80 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 unity could never be effected. But if, in the extremes 
 of each part, a softening of their variety is produced, 
 so that one part may, by its extreme being softened 
 down, ahiiost touch the extreme of the other part, also 
 softened down, the unity is gently procured without 
 disturbing the variety of the parts. If the extremes 
 of these parts could not be softened down, their 
 nature not permitting it, then between one part and 
 another a third must be placed, of such nature as to 
 answer for the keeping of the proportions required to 
 result in unity. To illustrate this theory about pro- 
 portion we may make use of the parts of creation, the 
 best representation of the beautiful. God has created 
 spiritual beings and sensitive beings, living and inani- 
 mate beings. Had he kept the variety of each of 
 these species in their crude state, so to speak, thfe har- 
 mony and the beauty of creation would have been 
 marred in consequence of the too great contrast be- 
 tween them. But God put an intermediate species 
 between each to soften down the contrast and make 
 way for the unity of the whole. Hence between the 
 purely spiritual species and the sensitive God has 
 placed man, partaking of the spiritual and the sensible 
 softened down in him ; between the sensitive beings, 
 such as animals, and the living beings, such as plants, 
 God has placed a kind of animal endowed with one 
 sense, and that very dull, so as to approach the two 
 species together, such as the polypus and all corallines ; 
 between the living beings or plants and the inanimate 
 God has placed something which seems to be border- 
 ing between the plant and the animal, such as the fungi, 
 under which name botanists comprehend also a large 
 number of microscopic plants forming the appearances 
 called mouldiness, mildew, smut, rust, brand, etc. 
 Q. How is the beautiful divided? ^" " t-f '^f 
 
Elements of Intellectual Ph ilosophy. 1 8 1 
 
 A. The beautiful is divided into natural, artificial, 
 and moral ; and the natural is subdivided into spiritual 
 and corporal. 
 
 The beautiful natural is that which is found in every 
 being and in the whole assemblage of created beings 
 forming the universe. That in every being we find a 
 variety reduced to unity by order and proportion is 
 evident ; because, first, every nature is composed of 
 different principles, which are so connected together 
 by order and proportion as to make a beautiful whole. 
 Take, for instance, man. He is composed of body 
 and soul : the body consists of motive, vegetative, sen- 
 sitive faculties; the soul of intellectual and volitive 
 faculties. The motive faculties are subject to the 
 vegetative, then to the sensitive. The variety of the 
 senses is brought into unity by what is called a com- 
 mon sensorium. These are brought into communica- 
 tion with the intellectual faculties by means of the 
 imagination, which is, as it were, a faculty akin to the 
 senses and to the intellect. The will governs all these 
 faculties. 
 
 "The elements 
 So mixed in hitn that Nature mijjht stand up j 
 
 And say to all the world, • 7'his is a man.'' " 
 
 — Shakspere, 
 
 That the same variety reduced to unity by order 
 and proportion is admired in the universe is too evi- 
 dent to need any demonstration ; therefore we may 
 conclude that every being is beautiful. 
 
 The spiritual beautiful is that which is admired in 
 spiritual beings ; the corporal that which is admired in 
 corporal beings. • „ ... ^x v,.. t^ .:.■,. -..- . •.^,' v-> N-wimrf- 
 
 The artificial beautiful is that which is produced by 
 human genius and art, and must consist of the same 
 
1 8 2 Elements of Intellectual Ph ilosophy. 
 
 elements — that' is, variety reduced to unity by order 
 and proportion. 
 
 The moral beautiful consists in the conformity of 
 the human actions with the eternal principle of right. 
 
 We must remark in general, in support of the theory 
 of the beautiful given above, that in works, either of 
 nature or art, where the variety is made of objects 
 forming each one a whole by itself, and, as it were, 
 independent, the unity cannot be found as actually 
 existing in them in a material sense, but results from 
 the order and proportions of the parts, which all are 
 made to conspire in l-epresenting and expressing an 
 idea intended by the artist. Thus in the universe we 
 cannot find a material unity, as it is made up of a 
 numberless variety of objects, each forming an indi- 
 viduality by itself. But all conspire", by their order 
 and proportion in being and in action, to show forth 
 the grandeur and the infinite excellence of the Creator, 
 the idea which God intended to express. 
 
 The same must be said of artificial beauty. When in 
 the productions of art the variety is made up of indi- 
 vidual objects, each forming a whole by itself, the 
 unity which must be sought in such productions can 
 only be ideal ; that is, the artist must so choose its 
 objects, and arrange and dispose them in such a man- 
 ner, and put such proportion between them that they 
 naturally suggest the idea he wanted to incorporate. 
 Take, /or instance, the " Last Judgment" of Michael 
 Angelo in the Sistine Chapel. The great artist could 
 not put in such a picture a material unity, as it is formed 
 of a great number of objects having an individuality of 
 their own. But he so chose and arranged each ob- 
 ject that they all conspire in representing the dread- 
 ful horror of that day — the idea which he wanted to 
 express. This he has attained by representing the 
 
Elcfnents of Intellectual Philosophy. 183 
 
 Judge with such dread majesty on his countenance, 
 by surrounding that majesty with such an array of 
 angels and saints, themselves in awe and almost 
 trembling, and by a multitude of horror-stricken 
 wretches awaiting that judgment, that tlie beholder is 
 at once impressed with the idea of the artist and 
 almost feels the horror of that day subduing his soul. 
 
 The second remark is that, as we have sho\Vn every 
 being, as such, to be beautiful, it follows that being 
 is convertible with the beautiful, and that an object is 
 beautiful in the same proportion as it is a being, and 
 that consequently the Supreme Being is the supreme 
 beauty, which beauty in him consists in the infinite 
 variety of his attributes, reduced to infinite simplicity 
 of his essence, or rather, as the Christian revelation 
 teaches us, in the mystery of the Trinity, which is vari- 
 ety of persons and unity of essence, the supreme type 
 of all beauty. But enough of the beautiful. 
 
 Q. Say a word on the sublime. 
 
 A. Being may oftentimes by its fulness seem to 
 transcend our capacity of apprehension and the 
 ordinary limits of other beings. Then we are accus- 
 tomed to call it sublime. Hence the true foundation 
 of the sublime is the infinite, which alone has natu- 
 rally no limit ; and in proportion as beings approach 
 more or less the infinite they assume more or less the 
 /:haracters of the sublime. Hence it follows that in 
 the works of art the sublime is obtained by the ideal 
 and the indeterminate, which, by leaving the object 
 expressed not deprived of its entity, but in a kind of 
 ideal and indeterminate condition, enhance its grandeur 
 before our imagination. 
 
 Such is the definition which God gave of himself to 
 Moses, " I am who am," which has been called sublime 
 by all the geniuses of mankind. Such is the descrip- 
 
1 84 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 tion of Satan by Milton, etc. The sublime is of 
 three kinds, because being may transcend the limits 
 of our capacity of apprehension by its entity, by its 
 force, by its extension as to duration and grace. If 
 the being transcend the limits by its nature, then it is 
 called the sublime ontological ; if by its force, the sub- 
 lime dynamic ; if by its duration or space, the mathe- 
 matical sublime. 
 
 1 I.' 
 
CHAPTER V. 
 
 ON THE CAUSES OF BEINGS. 
 ARTICLE FIRST. 
 
 On the Nature and Idea of Cause. 
 
 Q. Why do we treat of the cauiies of being, and 
 what order shall we follow in speaking of them ? 
 
 A. The idea of cause has such connection with that 
 of being that the mind, in reasoning upon one, cannot 
 pass over the other ; because every being is either 
 cause or caused^ hence the idea of cause always follows 
 being. Hence, having spoken of the properties of 
 being, we must now speak of its causes. And to give 
 an orderly and adequate idea of them we shall first 
 give an idea of cause and of its nature ; 2, of its diffe- 
 rent species; 3, of the relations they have with their 
 effects and with themselves. 
 
 Cause is understood to be the principle of a thing ; 
 hence it takes ordinarily the name of principle. But, 
 strictly speaking, the idea of cause is different from 
 that of principle. Principle, in its strictest accepta- 
 tion, means merely something from which another 
 thing proceeds in any manner whatever. Cause means 
 something upon which another thing depends as to its 
 being. Hence the idea of cause implies a certain de- 
 pendence and inferiority of being in the thing which 
 is caused, whereas the idea of principle does not imply 
 a dependence or inferiority of being as regards the 
 thing proceeding from it.* 
 
 ♦ Hence the Church calls the Father in God the principle of His Son, but not the 
 rnnse, because the Son is perfectly equal to the Father in nature and attributes, and 
 in no way inferior to Him. 
 
 185 
 
1 8 6 Elements of Intellectual Ph ilosophy. 
 
 Hence it is apparent that the idea of cause, i, is 
 narrower than that of principle, because every cause 
 is principle, but not every principle is cause. 2. Cause 
 implies always a real and positive influx upon the 
 being which depends upon it, and which is called 
 effect. 3. Cause, at least in nature if not in time, is 
 conceived always before the effect. After all these 
 remarks we may define cause to be that ivhich posi- 
 tively concurs in tJie being of a thing. Hence the idea 
 of cause is always relative, implying a necessary rela- 
 tion to that thing to the being of which the cause has 
 concurred. 
 
 The term of this relation, as we have said, is called 
 effect. From this relation arise those principles of 
 immediate evidence ; Every effect supposes a cause ; 
 No being can be the cause of itself; All that ivhich 
 is contained in the effect must be found in the causey 
 etc. 
 
 Q. What was Hume's error as to the idea of cause? 
 
 A. Hume asserted that the idea of cause has no 
 objective value ; that is to say, that it does not repre- 
 sent a real thing. He proved his assertion thus : Ob- 
 servation is the only source of our knowledge ; but 
 observation cannot give us the idea of cause ; there- 
 fore the idea of cause is not objective. He proved 
 his minor thus : Cause implies a connection with the 
 effect; now, observatioi merely manifests a succes- 
 sion of facts in nature, but not their connection; 
 therefore observation cannot give the idea of cause. 
 He concludes from this that the principle of causality 
 — that is, that every effect must have a cause — is a 
 prejudice of our mind. 
 
 Now, how absurd this opinion is every one can see 
 by himself, and we could easily pass it unnoticed, as 
 it is founded on that principle that all our knowledge 
 
Elements of Intellectual Ph ilosophy, 187 
 
 is derived from observation, which principle we shall 
 prove to be utterly false. Yet we shall make a few 
 remarks upon it the better to illustrate the idea of 
 cause. We say, in the first place, that the idea of 
 cause is objective. Hume admits that the idea of 
 cause would be objective if observation not only mani- 
 fested to us a succession but also a connection in 
 natural facts. Now, such is the case ; therefore the 
 idea of cause is objective. The minor is proven by 
 the following reasons : Succession implies the idea of 
 one thing following another, connection the idea of one 
 thing springing or proceeding from another. Such is 
 the difference between succession and connection. 
 Now, observation, manifests not only many things 
 following one another, but also many things springing 
 and proceeding from othtrs. In fact, we have our 
 senses, sight, hearing, taste, and we know that they 
 were given us for an object — the sight to see, the ears 
 to hear, and the palate to taste — and we use them 
 whenever we wish to feel their action or effect. 
 Again, everybody feels that when he wants to talk 
 he talks, and when he wants to move he moves, and if 
 he wants to be at rest he can do so at once. We feel, 
 therefore, that these facts are not only things which 
 follow one after the other, but which spring and ori- 
 ginate one from the other. 
 
 Besides, to feel that a certain thing is wholesome 
 and another hurtful does not exceed the power of ob- 
 servation, as it Is manifest to all mankind. But this 
 implies that we can feel that one thing proceeds 
 from another; therefore observation manifests to us 
 not only the succession but the connection of facts. 
 When we eat, for instance, something unwholesome, 
 and we feel a certain effect from it injurious to our 
 health, we certainly observe the connection between 
 
1 8 8 Elements of Intellectual Ph ilosophy. 
 
 the eating of that thing and the injurious effect result- 
 ing thereby, and not merely the succession of one 
 thing after the other, because we feel that that injuri- 
 ous effect only follows the eating of that particular 
 thing; hence we feel their connection. 
 
 Now, nothing more, even according to Hume, is nec- 
 essary to render the idea of cause objective ; therefore 
 that idea is objective. This we have said, confining 
 ourselves within the limits of observation, and we add 
 that our mind, by observing from all these facts and 
 depriving them of their particular circumstances, forms 
 the general idea of cause and of effect. 
 
 If, then, the idea of cause is objective, it is evident 
 that what Hume asserts about the principle of causali- 
 ty — that it is a prejudice of our mind — is false ; because 
 if a certain reality correspc^ds to the idea of cause — 
 that is, a thing which really concurs to the existence 
 of another — it is clear that we can argue rightly from 
 the existence of the effect to the existence of the 
 cause. 
 
 ARTICLE SECOND. 
 
 Of the va'/ious Causes; and, first, of Material and 
 ' Formal Causes. 
 
 Q. How many kinds of causes are there ? 
 
 A. We have defined cause to be that which concurs 
 positively to the existence of a thing. Now, four are 
 the principles which can concur in the existence of 
 anything; therefore there are four kinds of causes. 
 Of these four principles two are intrinsic and two ex- 
 trinsic. The two intrinsic principles, speaking of ma- 
 terial things, are the matter and the form, both of 
 which are necessary to constitute composite beings. 
 
Elemen is of Intellectua I Ph ilosophy, 1 8 9 
 
 But matter could not have its form if this were not 
 given to it by an exterior agent, and this exterior agent 
 would not act except prompted by an end in view. 
 Therefore, besides the matter and the form, two exte- 
 rior agents concur in the existence of a thing, the ex- 
 terior agent and the end which moves it. These, 
 then, are the four causes: the material (matter), the 
 formal (form), the efficient cause (the agent), and the 
 final cause (the end). And as in any given effect of 
 the kind we are speaking of we first observe the 
 material cause, then the formal, and afterwards the 
 agent and the end, so we shall speak first of the 
 material and formal causes, and then of the other 
 two. 
 
 Q. What is the causality of matter and form ? 
 
 A. Matter, or the material cause, is nothing but that 
 thing out of which something is shaped ; for instance, 
 the log or block out of which a sculptor makes a 
 statue is called the material cause. The figure or 
 shape which the sculptor gives it is called the for- 
 mal cause. But it is to be remarked that the cau- 
 sality of matter and form does not consist in any action 
 which they may perform, because whosoever performs 
 an action is called agent ; hence action cannot be predi- 
 cated of the material or formal cause, but of the effi- 
 cient cause. The causality, therefore, of matter and 
 form cannot consist in an action. If it does not con- 
 sist in an action, then their causality lies in their entity, 
 being used by the agent to form composite beings. To 
 this causality corresponds a double effect depending 
 one upon another. The first is proper to each, and it 
 is for matter to hold the form and for the form to ter- 
 minate and shape the matter. The second is common 
 to both, and is the whole composite resulting from the 
 union of both. 
 
190 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 Q. What is meant by intrinsic and extrinsic form ? 
 
 The form, before it is appHedto matter, has another 
 mode of existence in the efficient cause, and this other 
 mode is so ncxessary to the form, and has such strict 
 connection with it, that it could never be applied to 
 matter if it did not previously exist in the agent. For 
 it is the agent that must produce such a form on the 
 matter. But the agent could never intend to intro- 
 duce such form in the matter if the similitude of that 
 form were not already existing in him, because none 
 can give what he has not; therefore there must be 
 the similitude of the form in the agent. This, inas- 
 much as it is considered as having to be introduced in 
 matter, is called extrinsic form to distinguish it from 
 that which is really introduced in matter, and which is 
 called intrinsic. 
 
 This extrinsic form may be of two kinds, because it 
 is of such a nature as are the agents in which it is 
 found. Now, agents may be of two kinds, because they 
 are distinguished by the manner of their acting, which 
 may be either byway of nature or by way of intellect. 
 Hence natural agents and intellectual agents. Like- 
 wise the extrinsic form is distinguished in two ways 
 according to agents, by nature, or by intellect ; in those 
 agents which act by nature the form is found accord- 
 ing to natural being, as in man when he generates man, 
 in fire which engenders fire ; in those agents that act 
 by intellect it is found according to the intelligible 
 being, as the similitude of a building is in the mind of 
 the architect. But as agents by nature do not of 
 themselves intend to introduce the form, but are led 
 and guided by those who act by intellect, as the arrcw 
 reaches the mark because it is thrown by the archer, 
 so agents by nature may be considered rather as in- 
 struments of the agents by intellect ; hence the name 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 1 9 1 
 
 of extrinsic form has been applied more properly to 
 the form of the effect which exists in the intellect 
 of the agent. Taken in this sense, it has been defined 
 thdit form by looking at which the artist zvorks. This 
 has received the name of exemplary cause, because, as 
 it is apparent, it concurs in the production of the effect, 
 serving as model and example. It was also called 
 idea, and received for the first time that name by 
 Plato, and from it the name of idea was applied to 
 that which serves as means of knowledge. 
 
 But one must carefully remark the difference which 
 exists between them. Both agree in this : that they 
 are a similitude of something existing in the intellect, 
 but are distinguished by these several heads: I. The 
 idea which makes us understand objects is not the 
 object of our knowledge, but a means by which 
 the intellect perceives things. On the contrary, the 
 exemplary cause is not the means but the object at 
 which the mind of the agent looks. 2. The first does 
 not always belong to the practical intellect, whereas the 
 second always does, being intended to be outwardly 
 expressed. 3. The first has no connection either with 
 the efficient or the final cause; but the exemplary 
 cause has, because it has connection with the efficient 
 cause, inasmuch as it determines and euides the acrent 
 in its operation. It has connection with the final 
 cause, in the sense that the end of the agrent is nothing 
 more than the reproduction of that form. 
 
 ARTICLE THIRD. 
 
 On Efficient Cause. 
 
 Q. Define an efficient cause. 
 
 A. The form, as we have said, would not be given 
 to matter but for the action of the efficient cause. 
 
192 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 This may be defined : That extrinsical principle from 
 which primarily and properly the movement of the ac- 
 tion begins. It is called extrinsical principle to distin- 
 guish the efficient cause from the material and formal 
 causes, which are intrinsic principles. We have added 
 frojH zuhich the movement of the action primarily begins^ 
 to distinguish the efficient from the final cause ; be- 
 cause, though we may say in a certain sense that from 
 the end everything that regards the causing of some- 
 thing takes its rise, yet, strictly speaking, the move- 
 ment of the action begins primarily in the agent, and 
 the end does nothing more than to excite the agent 
 to begin the movement. Finally, we have added /r^ 
 perly to distinguish the efficient cause from the sim- 
 ple occasional cause, from which oftentimes the action 
 begins, but does not properly proceed from it. 
 
 Q. What subjects can be really efficient causes? 
 
 A. Malebranche, and many Cartesians with him, are 
 of opinion that to be really efficient cause can be said 
 of God only, who alone can really act. Creatures, on 
 their part, do nothing more than present to God the 
 occasion for acting, but in themselves are really devoid 
 of activity. This opinion was called occasionalism, be- 
 cause it denies to the creature all real activity, and 
 makes them exhibit only the occasion for God to act 
 in them. 
 
 3. Now, this opinion is false and contains several ab- 
 surd things. In fact, that it is not impossible that the 
 creature should have the power of acting can be demon- 
 strated as follows : If such a thing involved any repug- 
 nance, it ought to involve it ' .her on the part of God 
 or on that of the creature, liut it does not involve 
 repugnance on the part of either; therefore it is not 
 impossible that creatures should really act. 
 
 To act follows to_ be, and is proportionate to the 
 
Elements of Intellectual Ph ilosophy. 1 93 
 
 amount of being. This can be seen in God Himself, to 
 whom occasionalists allow the oower of acting, because 
 God acts as He is, and the power of acting is in pro- 
 portion to His being, and that kind oi poivcr becomes 
 Him because that (^^/«^ becomes Him. Hence to act 
 becomes Him, because to be becomes Him. But crea- 
 tures have a being ; therefore it is not repugnant on 
 their part that they should have the power of acting. 
 It is not repugnant on the part of God, because if 
 God could communicate to creatures their being, why 
 could not He also communicate them the power of 
 acting? 
 
 2. The principal reasons which occasionalists al- 
 lege to show that impossibility are derived from two 
 heads: i. God being a most perfect cause, it in- 
 volves a contradiction that there should be other 
 efficient causes besides Him; 2, because God can by 
 Himself produce all the effects which take place in the 
 world. If acts, therefore, all other causes are useless. 
 
 As to the first reason, if that principle were true we 
 might conclude from it that not only is it impossible 
 that any creature should act but that any creature should 
 exist. God is a most perfect being ; therefore it is 
 impossible that there should be other true beings be- 
 sides Him. But as it is not impossible that besides the 
 most perfect infinite being there should be other true 
 finite beings created bv the former, likewise it is not 
 impossible that besides that first and most perfect 
 Cause there should be other causes created by the 
 former. On the contrary, the opposite opinion would 
 involve a contradiction ; because as God's perfection 
 would not be infinite if He could not give existence to 
 other things outside Himself, so His action would not 
 be infinite if He could not communicate it to others. 
 And this, far from implying necessity or insufficiency on 
 
194 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 His part, would be a sign and an effect of His immense 
 perfection and goodness, by which He can communi- 
 cate His similitude not only as to being but also as to 
 action. 
 
 With regard to the second reason, if this were of any 
 value we could turn it againsi the occasionalists, be- 
 cause God is fully sufficient, to act all alone by Himself, 
 and, in that case, not only the action of creatures would 
 become usehss, but also the occasions, since He could 
 produce all sorts of effects without waiting for us to 
 present Him with occasions. Why should God wait, 
 for instance, that I should put water in my m.outh, in 
 order to take occasion to quench, by His own ac- 
 tion alone, my thirst? Could he not do that Himself 
 without waiting for that occasion? Besides, even 
 granting that God could do all by Himself, ye<- for ' 
 all that secondary causes would not be useles;-; ; be- 
 cause, as St. Thomas teaches, it is against the idea of 
 wisdom that there should be anything useless in the 
 works of the wise. Now, if created things did not 
 act in the production of effects, but all was done by 
 God Himself, he would employ other things to pro- 
 duce effects uselessly and without reason. By admit- 
 ting secondary causes, of course, we do not mean to 
 attribute to them an infinite virtue ; nor is this nec- 
 essary to the idea of cause, as Malebranche contends. 
 We say that everything has the power of acting pro- 
 portionate to its being. But to the creature we 
 attribute a being, therefore a power acting propor- 
 tionate to that being. 
 
 3. Finally, if the opinion of the occasionalists were 
 true, God would be the real uithor of all the crimes 
 which are committed in the worlc, as He would be the 
 only real agent, which is absurd. 
 
 Gathering all we have said together, we say that 
 
Elements of Intellectual Ph ilosophy. 1 9 5 
 
 the nature of cause can be attributed to all those 
 things which liave being, and can be attributed to 
 them in the S3me degree and proportion as being; 
 and because being properly becomes the substance, of 
 substance alone, therefore, may we predicate the name 
 of cause. Hence the truth of that saying of St. 
 Thomas, that every substance has the power of acting. 
 
 Q. How niany species of efficient causes are there? 
 
 A. The nature of cause lies in, this: that it is a prin- 
 ciple from which the movement of the action proceeds ; 
 therefore there are different causes in consequence of the 
 difference of the movement and the action. But every 
 movement may be different from two heads, either 
 from its nature or from its term ; consequently, 
 causes may differ either in consequence of the nature 
 of their action, or in consequence of the effect or term 
 which they produce. As to the manner of acting, the 
 cause may he: principal or instrumental. The principal 
 cause is that which acts by itself — not moved by an- 
 other nor used as a means by another cause ; as, The 
 artist is the principal cause of his work. Instrumental 
 cause is that which is used as a means by the principal ; 
 as, The brush and the colors in the hand of the 
 painter, which do something, and hence they are called 
 cause ; but as they cannot do that something without 
 being handled by the painter, they are, therefore, called 
 instrumental causes. 
 
 2. Free and necessary cause. A free cause is 
 that which acts with deliberation and choice, as mas- 
 ter of its action, as the will of man in respect to par- 
 ticular goods. A necessary cause is that which is im- 
 pelled to act by the force of its nature, and which does 
 not regulate its act by deliberation, as all the action 
 of natural agents inferior to man. 
 
 3. First and secondary cause. The first is that 
 
1 9 6 Elements of Intellectual Ph ilosophy. 
 
 which admits of no other cause preceding it, such as 
 God in respect to all created causes. Secondary is 
 that which is moved by the primary cause, such as all 
 creatures relatively to God. 
 
 4. Cause by itself and by accidctit. The cause by 
 itself is that which does that to which it is destined 
 by its own nature, as for fire to burn, for man to rea- 
 son. Cause by accident is when to the natural effect 
 of a cause another effect is added accidentally con- 
 nected with it ; afj, for instance, a man digging the 
 foundation of a house finds a treasure. The actual 
 effect of the man's action is the digging, but accident- 
 ally the other effect is connected with it. 
 
 On the part of the effect, efficient causes may be 
 univocal, equivocal^ aftalogous. The cause is called 
 univocal when it produces an effect like to itself in 
 species, as in the case of the generation of animals 
 which engender an animal of the same species as them- 
 selves. It is called equivocal when it produces an ef- 
 fect similar to the cause as to genus, as the sun in re- 
 spect to its effects. It is called analogous when the 
 cause does not agree with the effect either as to spe- 
 cies or genus, but yet has a certain likeness with it, as 
 God in respect to His creatures. 
 
 Proximate and remote. Proximate is that which 
 produces the effect immediately, remote when it pro- 
 duces it by means of other causes. 
 
 ARTICLE FOURTH. 
 On Final Cause. 
 
 Q. What is the nature and definition of final cause ? 
 
 A. The efficient cause would not be moved to act 
 but for the final cause. The end can be defined : That 
 for the sake of which something is done, or that at 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 1 9 7 
 
 which one aims in acting. This shows the difference 
 of the final from all other causes. The mu.ter is that 
 out of which something is made, the form is that 
 which gives it figure and shape, the agent is that 
 which makes it, and the end is that for which it is 
 made, and is called the end because, having obtained 
 it, the action terminates and the agent rests. 
 
 That the end is a true cause is clear from consider- 
 ing that it concurs positively in the production of 
 something by determining the agent and moving it to 
 act. 
 
 . The nature of its causality, besides, consists in 
 moving the tendency of the agent and in arousing the 
 wish of the agent to attain it, because, as the influx 
 of the efficient cause consists in acting, that of the 
 final cause is in being wished for. 
 
 The way by which the final cause acts is by exhi- 
 biting its goodness, true or seeming. This is ex- 
 pressed by Pope so elegantly : 
 
 " Modes of self-love the passions wc may call : 
 'Tis real good, or siemingy jiioi'cs them all." 
 
 — Essay on Man, 
 
 Because every being wishes its own perfection. But 
 the perfection of a being is its good ; therefore the 
 end, in order to excite a desire for itself, must show 
 itself as the good and the perfection of the agent. 
 
 Q. On what being can the end exercise its influ- 
 ence, and for what being is it becoming to have an 
 end? 
 
 A. To act for an end becomes all beings, of what- 
 ever nature they may be ; be they endowed with 
 knowledge or not, be they spiritual or material, all 
 beings must aim at an end. 
 
 Q. Prove this. 
 
198 Eleme7tts of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 A. First proof : From what we have said of causes 
 we see that by necessity of nature they are subject to 
 this order : the matter does not receive its form ex- 
 cept it is given it by the agent, and the agent is not 
 moved to give that form except when determined 
 hy an end, because if it were not determined by an 
 end to a certain special effect, there would be no 
 reason why it should produce one effect in preference 
 to another ; therefore once we take away the end, 
 neither efficient cause aor formalTs possible, and con- 
 sequently no effect can be obtained. 
 
 2. Agents are either free or necessary causes ; but 
 it is clear that free agents are induced to act by an 
 end, because, being free, they are indifferent to act or 
 not to act, to act in this or in another way, to act this 
 or the contrary way, and the end alone can determine 
 them to a choice. Necessary agents arc called so be- 
 cause they are by nature determined and necessitated 
 to act. Now, this determination comes to them from 
 the end ; therefore every agent aims at an end. 
 
 But it is to be observed that not all agents aim at 
 an end in the same manner. This depends upon their 
 nature. Every being acts according to its nature. 
 But agents are different by nature ; therefore they 
 aim at an end in a different manner. In fact, all the 
 agents in nature may be divided into three classes. 
 Some are gifted with reason and intellect, by which 
 they cannot only apprehend the end but also see how 
 it befits their nature, and can discover the aptitude of 
 the means which exist in order to obtain it. Others 
 are without intellect, but are endowed with senses, by 
 which they may apprehend the end at which they may 
 aim, but cannot see the relation which exists between 
 it and their nature, nor the aptitude of the means to 
 obtain it. Finally, others have neither intellect nor sense, 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 199 
 
 and cannot apprehend the end at all, as the arrow 
 which goes to the mark. The first have a perfect 
 knowledge of the end, and can reason upon the means 
 to be chosen, and heive no need that any one should 
 direct them to it, but being, in force of their reason 
 and will, masters of their acts, go to their end by them- 
 selves ; and of such, strictly speaking, it is said that they 
 aim at an end. The second, knowing by the way of 
 the senses the end, and apprehending it somewhat, 
 aim at it in a certain way, but according to the man- 
 ner of their knowledge, that is, instinctively, urged by 
 nature, and not perfectly by themselves, as they have 
 not the mastery of their acts. Finally, those that 
 have neither sense nor intellect are not moved by 
 themselves to seek the end by an intellect external 
 to them. 
 
 Q. How many different ends may there be ? 
 
 A. The nature of the end lies in this : that it must be 
 intended by the agent as the term of its tendency and 
 operation. Therefore it may be different, according 
 to the different way of intending it as a term. Hence 
 it may be proximate, intermediate, and ultimate : 
 proximate if it is the first and immediate term of 
 the tendency : ultimate if it is the very thing which 
 the agent intends to cease operation and rest after ; 
 intermediate if it is a term of the tendency, but 
 neither proximate nor last. 
 
 2. Principal and accessory. The first is that which 
 is principally aimed at by the agent, and hence this 
 is the principal term of the tendency. The second is 
 that which is sought by the agent along with the 
 principal, but not so that, if it could not be attained, 
 the agent would cease to seek the principal. 
 
 End of the action and end of the agent. The 
 first is the natural term of the action, as the end of 
 
200 Elements of hitellcctual Philosophy. 
 
 the act of singing is to sing. The second is that 
 which the agent proposes to himself, as a singer might 
 propose to himself riches or delight. 
 
 Objective and subjective. Objective is the ob- 
 ject which is sought for. Subjective is the use to 
 which the agent intends to put the object. 
 
 ARTICLE FIFTH. 
 
 Of the Relation of Cause:: ivith their Effects and among 
 
 Themselves. 
 
 Q. How many are the relations which causes may 
 have ? 
 
 A. Relation arises from the respect which one thing 
 has to another. Now, a cause may be considered in 
 respect to its own effects or to another cause with 
 which it is connected. Therefore causes may have 
 relations cither with their own effects or with other 
 causes ; and we must speak first of the one and then 
 of the other. 
 
 Q. What are the relations which a cause may have 
 with its own effects? 
 
 A. That a cause has relation with its own effects is 
 clear from all we have said with regard to the idea of 
 cause and effect ; for we have seen that between cause 
 and effect there is not merely succession but a neces- 
 sary connection, and that the effect cannot possibly 
 exist without receiving its being from the cause. A 
 necessary consequence flows from this, namely, that 
 between the effect and its cause there is a necessary 
 and true relation, which consists in the effect depending 
 as to its being upon its cause. Also from this neces- 
 sary dependence of the effect upon its cause three 
 other relations arise which will better illustrate its 
 idea. Wherever several beings are connected to- 
 
Elements of Intellectual Ph ilosophy. 2 o i 
 
 gether it is necessary that we should find these three 
 other things r a relatioit of order, htcdiXxsQ conniction 
 implies order, a certain location of the parts cc inect- 
 ed in view of an end ; a relation of naturf, because 
 things, in order to be connected, should have a certain 
 natural affinity ; a relation of dignity, because where 
 there is dependence and connection among a number 
 of beings it is necessary that one should be more 
 noble than the other. The relation, therefore, of de- 
 pendence of the effect upon its cause gives rise to 
 three other relations, that of order, of nature, and of 
 dignity. We shall speak of each separately. 
 
 With regard to the relation of order, this must con- 
 sist in the priority of the cause with regard to its 
 effect; because if the effect depends as to its being 
 upon the cause, a relation of order in this case can- 
 not consist in anything else except that the cause 
 must be before the effect. But it must be remarked 
 that this priority may be of two kinds, priority of 
 time and priority of nature. The first consists in the 
 one being temporarily before the other ; the second 
 consists in this: that though cause and effect may be 
 supposed to exist simultaneously, yet the cause must 
 be conceived always first, inasmuch as the effect could 
 not exist without it. With regard to the priority of 
 nature, there is no doubt that the cause is always be- 
 fore the effect. But with regard to priority of time 
 we must remark that we may consider the cause only 
 as a certain being in itself, irrespectively of any rela- 
 tion to any effect, or we may consider it as merely a 
 cause. If we consider it in the first sense, it is clear 
 that it can exist before the effect ; and this is not 
 impossible, especially in what are called successive 
 causes, in which case it is necessary that the cause 
 which produces by way of movement and possession 
 
202 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 should exist previously to the effect. In the second 
 case the cause cannot exist before the effect ; because a 
 thing is called a cause inasmuch as it produces an effect ; 
 therefore it cannot possibly be called a cause before 
 actually producing the effect. 
 
 With regard to the relation of affinity or proportion, 
 this consists in a certain similitude which the effect 
 must have with its cause ; because the effect, so to 
 speak, is an emanation of the cause — something 
 drawn, as it were, from the cause, since no being 
 gives what it has not. Now, all this necessarily im- 
 plies "a similitude between the effect and its cause ; 
 therefore there must be a similitude between the ef- 
 fect and the cause. This similitude, however, varies 
 in proportion as the effect is more or less adequate 
 to the activity of the cause. From this arises the 
 distinction of effects into univocal, equivocal, and 
 analogous, which we have already defined above. 
 
 With regard to the relation of dignity, we must 
 observe that it is different in proportion to the manner 
 according to which the cause concurs in the effect. 
 Now, to determine this the following remarks are to be 
 kept in view: If the question is about material and 
 intrinsic formal causes, they are less noble than their 
 effect, because the part is less noble than the whole ; 
 but material and formal causes act as the part towards 
 the formation of the whole, therefore they are less 
 noble than their effect. We have said the intrinsic 
 formal causes, because the extrinsic formal cause — 
 that is to say, the exemplar and -type which is in the 
 mind of the artist — may be more noble than the ef- 
 fect, as are all the types of things existing in the di- 
 vine mind. If it is a question of the principal final 
 cause in agents who act according to order, it is al- 
 ways more noble than the effect, because no man who 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 203 
 
 acts according to order will spend more in order to 
 get what is less, nor employ what is more noble to 
 attain what is less so. Now, the effect with regard to 
 the end is like a means to an end ; therefore in one 
 who acts according to order the end is always nobler 
 than the effect. If it is a question of the efficient 
 cause, it is either more noble than the effect or equal 
 to it, because the cause is either univocal or equivocal. 
 If it is univocal, it is equally as noble as the effect, 
 which belongs to the same species ; if it is equivocal, 
 it is nobler than the effect, because the effect in this 
 case belongs to a species inferior to the cause. 
 
 Q. What is the relation of causes among them- 
 selves ? 
 
 A. A relation always means connection ; therefore 
 we can have relation between causes only when we 
 can find 1 hem connected together to obtain an effect. 
 Beside^, a connection between two things may be 
 either proper or accidental. We intend to speak here 
 of the proper connection. This relation between 
 causes may be of order, of nature, and of dignity, 
 as we have said of the relations of causes with their 
 effects. 
 
 Of the relation of nature among causes we think 
 we have said enough already when we spoke of the 
 proportion which the nature of the final cause must 
 have with the efficient cause, and the proportion 
 which the agent must have with the formal cause, and 
 this with the material. We shall speak of the relation 
 of order and dignity. 
 
 As to the relation of order, we may distinguish be- 
 tween causes of the same nature from those of a dif- 
 ferent nature. The first are those which belong to the 
 same kind, but are all ordained and bound together to 
 produce the same effect ; for instance, a number of 
 
204 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy . 
 
 efficient causes bound together so that one depends 
 upon the other, and all produce something. The 
 second are those belonging to difTcront kinds, as the 
 final, the efficient, the formal; etc., which are different, 
 but still one depending upon the other. 
 
 Now, if the causes be of the same nature, and are, in 
 themselves, in proper order, whatever other accidental 
 order may be found among them, it is always neces- 
 sary that there should be a first and a last one in that 
 order, and that we should not have a progression ad 
 infinitum; because, in such a case, in order to obtain 
 the effect it is necessary that the action of one cause 
 should pass to another, and from this to a third, and 
 so on, till we have the effect. Hence if the series of 
 such causes were infinite, the action and the move- 
 ment should have to go through an infinite series to 
 reach the effect. But the infinite, as such, cannot be 
 outstepped ; therefore we cannot admit an infinite 
 series of causes. 
 
 Besides, in a series of causes naturally in order the 
 first is the cause of the second, this of the third, and so 
 on. Take away, therefore, the first cause and you take 
 away also the last, for the same reason. But in an 
 infinite series we cannot find a first cause, because 
 otherwise it would be finite ; and, on the other hand, 
 without the first there would be no middle, and con- 
 sequently no last, cause, therefore no effect at all. 
 Hence, in causes of themselves well arranged there 
 cannot be an infinite series, but there must be a first 
 and a last. Therefore in this series of efficient causes 
 there must be always a first from which all others de- 
 pend, and in the series of final causes there must be a 
 primary end to which all other ends are directed. 
 With regard to different causes, besides the theory 
 that in them we cannot have an infinite progression, 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 205 
 
 for the same reason we may determine also which of 
 them must be first and which last. In causing, the 
 first is the end, bee jse it moves the agent ; next 
 comes the agent, who must act ; and finally comes the 
 form which the agent intends to give to the matter. 
 
 As to the relation of dignity between causes, it is 
 clear that the formal cause is more noble than the 
 material, because the form gives being to matter. 
 Now, that which gives is more noble than that which 
 receives; therefore the form is more noble than the 
 matter. Next, the efficient cause is more noble than 
 the form, because the form is given by it and is its 
 own likeness. Finally, the final cause is the noblest 
 of them all, because all causes act in order to obtain 
 the end. But the end is sought as good and perfec- 
 tion ; therefore all other causes stand in relation to 
 the final cause as the imperfect to the perfect. 
 
CHAPTER VI. 
 
 DIVISION OF BEING, 
 ARTICLE FIRST. 
 
 Of Substance mid Accident. 
 
 Q. What is the subject of this chapter ? 
 
 A. Being, as we have said in Logic, is divided into 
 ten categories, or supreme genera, because it is first 
 divided into substance and accident, and this latter 
 is divided into nine other genera. We shall speak, 
 then, of these ten categories, and first of substance 
 and accident. 
 
 Substance is defined that which exists in itself 
 and not in another on which it may lean as subject. 
 We must pay attention to several remarks in order to 
 understand this definition. What is meant by those 
 words: that thing which exists in itself? i. They ex- 
 clude all inherence of the thing called substance in any 
 other being in order to exist, and cause it to be distin- 
 guished from the accident, the essence of Avhich is to 
 lean on, or inhere in, another thing as subject. 2. 
 Those words, which exists in itself, must not be taken in 
 such a sense as to exclude from the idea of substance the 
 idea of an efficient cause, because these words merely 
 point out to an existence in one's self and not in 
 another, but may or may not admit of an efficient 
 cause. If that which exists in itself is infinite, then 
 the substance does not require a cause in order to ex- 
 
 ao6 
 
Elements of Intellectual Ph ilosophy. 2 07 
 
 ist, but exists of its own nature. If the substance is 
 finite, then, though existing in itself, it requires a 
 cause to make it so. In other words, to exist in 
 itself does not mean to exist by itself. The first 
 means that a thing does not require to lean on any 
 subject in order to exist ; the second means that the 
 thing does not require any cause to give it existence, 
 but enjoys existence in force of its own essence. 
 
 2. That which exists in itself and not in another 
 is called substance, principally from its being the 
 subject of the accident. For the word substance is 
 derived from those two Latin words, sub^ under, an'^. 
 stare, to be placed or located. Now, that the substance 
 is tile subject of accidents is demonstrated as follows: 
 If the subject of accidents were not the substance, it 
 should be another accident. But the accident cannot 
 exist in itself, but must lean on another in order to ex- 
 ist ; therefore this same accident, supporting otner acci- 
 dents, must either lean on a substance or on another 
 accident, and this on another, and so on ad infinitum. 
 But a progress ad infinitum cannot be admitted ; there- 
 fore the substance must be the subject of accidents. 
 
 But wc must remark here again that it is not neces- 
 sary for the essence of a substance to be the subject of 
 accidents. The essence of a substance is to be in itself. 
 Besides this, it may or may not be subject of accidents. 
 Finite substances which are perfectible are all subject 
 to modifications or accident. The infinite substance, 
 which is God, being absolutely perfect, is not subject 
 to modifications. 
 
 Q. What are the errors of philosophers as to the 
 idea of s'^bstance ? 
 
 A. First, Locke contended that substance is a number 
 or an accumulation of accidents, which we perceive by 
 means of the senses, gathered and co-existing together 
 
2o8 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 in a wp.y unknown to us. We say, in the first place, 
 that such an idea of substance is false, even accord- 
 ing to experience, both of the senses and of conscious- 
 ness ; of the senses, because through them we perceive 
 bodies under every variety and succession of modifica- 
 tions, and yet in perceiving them we perceive that 
 we experience something standing permanent un- 
 der a variety and succession of modifications, and 
 even under the conflict of contrary modifications; of 
 internal consciousness, for we are conscious that our 
 soul is subject to great variety of thoughts, of desires, 
 of volitions succeeding each other, and oftentimes 
 clashing with each other, and yet we perceive at the 
 same time something standing permanent and the 
 same under all that variety and conflict of modifica- 
 tions. In the second place, the opinion of Locke 
 refutes itself. Because, we may ask, those qualities or 
 accidents which form the accumulation are either able 
 to exist in themselves or they are not. If they are, 
 then they are so many substances; if they are not, 
 then they must lean on something existing in itself in 
 order to exist. It will not do to say that those modi- 
 fications can acquire the force of existing in them- 
 selves by aggregation or accumulation, because if 
 the qualities have not singly of their nature the force 
 of existing in themselves, but demand a subject to 
 lean on, this want of leaning on a subject must be felt 
 with stronger reason by the whole assemblage, for the 
 mere gathering cannot change its nature ; therefore the 
 opinion of Locke is false. , Spinoza also held an er- 
 roneous opinion as to substance. He defined a sub- 
 stance to be that which exists in itself, and can be con- 
 ceived by itself — that is, that the idea of which does 
 not require the idea of another in order to be con- 
 ceived. 
 
Elements of Intellectual Ph ilosophy, 209 
 
 This definition of substance can apply only to God, 
 for a thing which exists in itself, and which can be 
 conceived by itself, is that only which does not re- 
 quire a cause in order to exist, because if it required a 
 cause to exist we could not conceive it by itself, but 
 would be obliged to have the idea of the cause in order 
 to conceive it. God alone, therefore, exists in Him- 
 self in such a way that he does not require any cause 
 or principle in order to exist or be known. The de- 
 finition of Spinoza, therefore, would render impossible 
 all created substances. 
 
 ARTICLE SECOND. 
 Principle of Individuali::ation. 
 
 Q. What can be called true substance ? 
 
 A. Substance may be divided into first and second, 
 or into real and logical. The substance first and real 
 is the individual. The substance second and logical 
 are the species and genera, because these have not an 
 existence in themselves, except inasmuch as they are 
 confined to the individual. The real and proper sub- 
 stance, therefore, is the individual. This is defined by 
 St. Thomas, " that which is in itself undivided and dis- 
 tinguishable from others." The words "that which is 
 in itself undivided " mean that it cannot be divided and 
 be applicable to many things, in contradistinction of 
 the universal, which means something which is com- 
 mon to many; the words "and distinguishable from 
 others " mean that it is such a thing, and not this or 
 that. 
 
 Q. What is meant by the principle of individuali- 
 zation ? 
 
2 1 o Elemeti is of In te lleciual Pli ilosopJiy. 
 
 A. We shall answer by an example. Let us take, 
 for instance, the human species. Thi*,consists of the 
 elements animality and reason. All the individuals 
 belonging to this species have these elements, ani- 
 mality and reason, for every man is a reasonable 
 animal. Now, we may ask, so long as every indi- 
 vidual of the human species has all the elements of the 
 species, animality and reason, what is that thing which 
 contracts, as it were, the speciesand constitutes the indi- 
 viduals in each species ; or, in other words, what is that 
 which makes the number of individuals in each spe- 
 cies, and makes them undivided in themselves and dis- 
 tinguishable from others? Now, to answer this ques- 
 tion accurately we must distinguish between beings. 
 In material beings the principle of individualization is 
 matter, because the principle of individualization must 
 be intrinsic and substantial to the being. But in 
 material beings there are two things which are intrin- 
 sic and substantial — matter and form. Form cannot 
 discharge this office of individualizing, because the 
 form of its own nature is common to many, and 
 therefore- cannot be the principle of excluslveness and 
 incommunicability. This office, therefore, must be 
 fulfilled bv matter. But it must be remarked that 
 matter may be considered in two ways — as abstracted 
 from quantity and extension and common to all the 
 beings comprised within a species, or as it is found in 
 the real world marked by quantity. It is in the latter 
 sense that matter is the principle of individualization. 
 
 As to immaterial substances, if these have their ex- 
 istence in matter as its form, as in the case of the 
 human soul, their individualization arises from the re- 
 lation and order which they have to their bodies, 
 because the same reason given above applies to them 
 also. 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 211 
 
 " 'Tis true that the souls 
 Of all men are alike ; of tlie same substance, 
 By the same Maker into all infus'd ; 
 But yet the several matters which they work on, 
 How different they are I need not tell you." 
 
 — RuTTER, Shepherd's Jlolyday. 
 
 But if they be purely spiritual, as we know by 
 revelation angels to be, they are individualized by 
 their own reality. God is individualized by His very 
 nature and absolute simplicity. 
 
 Q. How many kinds of substances are there? 
 
 A. Various kinds ; Complete and incomplete. 
 Complete substances are those which are not destined 
 to exist united with another substance, so as to form 
 together a perfect whole, as man, a tree. Incomplete 
 are those which are destined to be united, such as the 
 human soul. 
 
 A complete substance may be endowed with intelli- 
 gence, as man ; or not have inteMigence, as plant. If 
 it is endowed with intelligence, it is called person ; if 
 it is not endowed with intelligence, it is called an 
 individual or siippositwn. Hence the sitppositum may 
 be defined : An individual and complete substance in- 
 comnmnicably existing. A person may said to be an 
 individual and complete substance of the rational nature. 
 
 Q. What do you call that act by which the sub- 
 stance really exists and acts ? 
 
 A subsistence, which may be defined : That actuality 
 by which a complete substance exists and acts without 
 communicating with another substance. Here two 
 questions arise of the greatest importance. The first is : 
 Can a complete substance really exist and act without 
 a subsistence of any kind ? In answer to this first 
 question we say no substance can really exist and act 
 without a subsistence, because, although we can con- 
 ceive the essence and nature of a thing as possible 
 
212 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 without a subsistence, yet we cannot conceive the 
 nature as actually existing and acting without it, be- 
 cause it is just that act or last complement of being 
 which makes it really actual ; hence the saying of 
 schoolmen, that actiones stmt suppositoriim — actions 
 belong to the suppositum — meaning that actions im- 
 ply a subsistence in order to be possible. 
 
 The second question is this : Admitting that no 
 complete substance can really exist and act without a 
 subsistence, it is asked : Is it necessary that this com- 
 plete substance should have its own subsistence, or 
 can it have the subsistence of another and made ac- 
 tually to exist and to act by the subsistence of another 
 nature ; or, in other words, does each nature absolutely 
 require its own subsistence in order to exist and act ; 
 or is it possible and sufficient for it to subsist by the 
 actuality of another nature ? 
 
 This question must be answered in the affirmative, 
 because we can conceive that although a complete 
 substance cannot exist or act without a subsistence, 
 yet it is not necessary that this subsistence should be 
 its own, because this complete substance might be 
 united in a most intimate manner with a higher sub- 
 sistence, in which case the subsistence of the inferior na- 
 ture should give way to the superior. This is the case 
 of our body. It would have a subsistence of its own 
 were it not united to the soul, and that in such a way 
 as to form one individuality. But because of this union 
 its own subsistence must give way before that of 
 the soul, a much superior substance. When separated 
 from the soul our body resumes its own subsistence. 
 Therefore in created substances nature and subsistence 
 are distinct and may be separated.* 
 
 * Upon this theory and truth is founded the fundamental mystery of Chris- 
 tianity—that mystery which has ransomed and deified the world— the Incarnation. 
 Of it more in the internal evidences of Christianity. 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy, 2 1 3 
 
 Q. What about the action of substances? 
 
 A. With regard to action there is this difference be- 
 tween complete and incomplete substance : that the 
 former bears exclusively the attribution of every ac- 
 tion it performs, whereas, in the case of the latter, 
 every action it may do is not attributed to it, but to the 
 suppositum or complete substance resulting from the 
 union. For instance, man is a complete substance, 
 and therefore he bears the responsibility of every one 
 of his actions ; but his soul and body are each an in- 
 complete substance, and, therefore, whatever action 
 may be performed by either is attributed not to it 
 but to the complete substance — that is, man. The 
 reason of this is because the operation must be of a 
 piece with being. 
 
 **The "work the touchstone of nature is. 
 And by their cperations things are known."* 
 
 But the being of an incomplete substance, though 
 existing in itself, yet does nc exist for itself, but for 
 the whole ; therefore it does not act for itself, but for 
 the whole. On the contrary, a complete substance 
 exists in itself and for itself; therefore it acts also for 
 itself and must be responsible for its action. 
 
 There is also this difference between substances as 
 to their actions: that rational substances, or persons, 
 have a perfect mastery over their own actions, direct 
 themselves to apprehend the end, and endeavor to 
 discover the agreement or disagreement between their 
 actions and the end which they propose to themselves. 
 Unintelligent substances must be directed to their end 
 by others. 
 
 " What things soever are to an end referr'd. 
 And in their motion still that end regard, 
 
 ♦ Davies' Poems. 
 
214 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 Always the fitness of the means respect, 
 Those as conducive choose, and those reject, 
 Must by a judgment foreign and urtknowh ' 
 
 Be guided to their end, or by their own ; 
 For to design an end, and to pursue 
 That end by means, and have it still in view, 
 . Demands a conscious, wise, reflecting cause, 
 Which freely moves, and acts by reason's laws ; 
 That can deliberate, means elect, and find 
 Their due connection with the end designed." 
 
 — Blackmore, The Creation, 
 
 1 
 
 ARTICLE THIRD. 
 
 Q. What is an accident ? 
 
 A. Tlie accident is opposed to substance, and 
 therefore is that thing which does not exist in itself^ 
 but is obliged to lean on the substance in order to exist. 
 
 There are two kinds of accidents — absolute and 
 modal. The first are those which lean on the sub- 
 stance, such as movement, heat, cold. The modal acci- 
 dents are called the different modes, or manners, ac- 
 cording to which accidents lean on the substance — for 
 instance, velocity or tardiness in movement, more or 
 less intensity of heat, cold, and so forth. 
 
 Q. What questions can be raised with regard to ac- 
 cidents ? 
 
 A. Two questions. The first is : Is the being of 
 the accident different from, or identical with, the being 
 of the sijbstance? We answer that accidents are 
 added to a\ubstance — they come, they go. Now, if 
 the being oi\the accident were identical with that of 
 the substance, it would follow that the same thing 
 would be added>to itself, that it would come upon it- 
 self and go from itself, which is absurd. Therefore 
 the being of the accident is different from that of the 
 substance. ' ""' ' 
 
 The second question is as follows ; Can accidents 
 
'• r 
 
 Elemenis of Intellectual Philosophy, 2 1 5 
 
 ever exist without their own substance ? with regard to 
 which question we answer that it is not necessary that 
 an accident should lean on its own natural substance, 
 so to speak, but it may be upheld by a foreign force 
 or substance. For instance, extension, color, taste, 
 etc., are all accidents of bodies, and, therefore, bodies 
 may be called the natural and native substance of 
 such accidents. But it is not absolutely necessary 
 that these accidents should be upheld by the sub- 
 stance of bodies. They may be supported by a for- 
 eign force — a spiritual substance, for example ; be- 
 cause it is intrinsically necessary for the nature of 
 the accident to be supported, but it is quite indifferent 
 to the same nature zuhat it is supported by — Its own 
 native substance, or any other force sufficient to up- 
 hold it. God, therefore, could, by His infinite power, 
 effect that accidents should exist without the sub- 
 stance. In "ib case they would not exist in them- 
 selves, but be supported by Omnipotence.* 
 
 ARTICLE FOURTH. 
 
 Of Quantity, Relation, and Quality. 
 
 Q. How many accidents are there ? 
 
 A. Nine — quantity, relation, quality, action, pas- 
 sion, time, site, habit. In this article we shall speak 
 of the first three. 
 
 Q. What kind of substance does quantity belong to, 
 and what is its definition ? 
 
 A. Quantity is a proper accident of corporal sub- 
 stances, because these alone can have it. But, in order 
 to give an adequate definition of it it, is necessary to 
 
 * This occurs in the mystery of the Eucharist, where the accidents of bread and 
 wine— that is, the color, the taste, the smell, etc. — are upheld, not by the substances 
 of bread and wine, because those two substances have been changed into the sub- 
 stance of the flesh and blood of our Lord, but are supported by Omnipotence. 
 
2i6 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 determine in what its essence consists. Now, in conse- 
 quence of this accident quantity, corporal substances 
 are endowed with the following qualities: i. ex- 
 tension — that is, the possession of distinct parts, one 
 of which is not the other ; 2, occupation of a certain 
 locality ; 3, impenetrability — that is, that all these 
 distinct parts cannot be in each other's places at 
 the same time ; 4, capacity of being divided, or di- 
 visibility ; 5, capacity of being measured, or ;«^«^«- 
 rability. That these qualities belong to corporal sub- 
 stances in force of their quantity is beyond doubt. 
 We ask, therefore, in which of these qualities are we 
 to place the essence of quantity ? Some have placed 
 it in one, some in another. We hold as follows : The 
 proper office of the essence is to be that first internal 
 and radical principle in a being which gives rise to all 
 its properties. Hence that must be called the essence 
 of quantity which is the root and principle of all its 
 properties. Now, among the five properties of quan- 
 tity just mentioned, that which is the first internal 
 and radical principle of all others seems to be exten- 
 sion. In this, therefore, must we place the essence of 
 quantity. This we prove as follows : It cannot be oc- 
 cupation of space, because this property belongs to 
 the corporal substance, inasmuch as it is made up of 
 parts, and we must conceive the body first as having 
 parts and then as occupying space. It cannot be im- 
 penetrability, which also supposes the body first hav- 
 ing parts and extension, and afterwards the quality 
 of one part not being able to occupy the space of 
 another at the same time, both being obliged to hold 
 their respective places. Neither can it be divisibility 
 or measurability, for the same reason. Therefore the 
 essence of quantity lies in extension ; and, as each 
 thing is to be defined by its specific difference, we 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 2 1 7 
 
 may define quantity that accident by zvhich corporrA 
 substances have extension. 
 
 Quantity may be of two kinds — continual and sepa- 
 rate. The first is that the parts of which exist to- 
 gether, but united so as to form one mass or a whole, 
 as a line. The separate is that the parts of which are 
 disjointed and divided, as number. The continual 
 quantity has three dimensions — length, breadth, and 
 depth. If a continual quantity is considered only in 
 regard to its length, it is called line; if it is looked at 
 in reference to its breadth and depth, it is called sur- 
 face ; if it is regarded as having all these qualities, it 
 is called body. 
 
 Finally, quantity may be fiyiite and infinite. The 
 first is that which has limits; the second is that which 
 is conceived as having no limits. 
 
 Q. Can there be a quantity really infinite ? 
 
 A. We answer negatively as to both quantities, 
 continual and separate. The first cannot be really in- 
 finite, because a continual quantity may be either a 
 body, a surface, or a line ; but none of these can be really 
 infinite. Therefore continual quantity cannot be infi- 
 nite. The minor is proved as follows : 
 
 1. All bodies have a surface; but, surface is the 
 limit of a body, therefore all bodies are limited, and 
 cannot be actually infinite. 
 
 2. The surface is terminated by the line ; therefore 
 all surface is limited. 
 
 3. All lines are terminated by points ; therefore all 
 lines are limited, and consequently all continual quan- 
 tity is limited. 
 
 Separate quantity cannot be infinite, because all 
 that which can become greater or less cannot be infi- 
 nite. But, supposing a given number, you can always 
 add to or subtract from it a unity, and thus make it 
 
2i8 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 greater or less. Therefore no separate quantity can 
 be infinite. 
 
 Q. Can any quantity be potentially infinite? 
 
 A. If we speak of separate quantity we must 
 answer, Yes ; because to every number we may 
 always add other units. But if we talk of continual 
 quantity, we must make a distinction. When that 
 continual quantity is abstracted from every sensible 
 form that is a mathematical quantity, it may be po- 
 tentially infinite, because it is not impossible to 
 think of an abstract quantity to which we are con- 
 tinually adding. But if by continua.1 quantity we mean 
 that which actually belongs to bodies in nature, then 
 it is impossible that it should be infinite, because what- 
 ever exists in nature has definite, determinate being, 
 and hence the quantity which accompanies it has a de- 
 finite form also. Therefore in this sense there cannot 
 be a continual quantity even potentially infinite. 
 
 Q. Give the definition and elements of relation ? 
 
 A. Relation is defined: the order which a thing has 
 witJi another ; or, the Jiow tzvq things lie to each other. 
 From this definition it is clear that to obtain relation 
 three things are required: i, the subject, or that 
 which is related ; 2, the term, or that to which the 
 subject is related ; 3, the principle, or reason why 
 the subject is related to the term. Thus in the rela- 
 tion of paternity the father, who generates, is the sub- 
 ject ; the son, who is generated, is the term; the 
 foundation or reason for the relation is generation. 
 
 The subject and the term, because the relation runs 
 between them, are called the extremes, and oftentimes 
 the terms, of the relation. Now, extremes in every 
 relation must have this proper qualification: that, 
 considered as such — that is, as relatives — they must 
 exist together, both as to their being and as to their 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 2 1 9 
 
 being known ; as to their being, because the father 
 could not exist without the son, and vice vcrsd ; as 
 to their being known — that is to say, that the know- 
 ledge of the one must necessarily carry along with it 
 the knowledge of the other — because, when we consider 
 relative terms as such, the knowledge of one must 
 necessarily imply the knowledge of the other. 
 
 Q. Speak of the distinction of relation. 
 
 A. In logic we divided relation into real and logic. 
 Here we must add that real relation may be mutual 
 and not mutual. It is called mutual, or strictly real, 
 when the relation is real in both extremes, as in the 
 example above given of paternity and sonship. It is 
 called not mutual when the foundation of the relation 
 is real in one extreme and not in the other, but placed 
 there by our mind. Such is the relation of creation. 
 On the creature's side it is real, because it has placed 
 in it something real ; on God's side it is logical, be- 
 cause His creating the universe effected nothing new 
 in His nature. 
 
 Q. Do real relations truly exist? 
 
 A. Certainly, i. Because none can doubt that a 
 father is a true father of his son, and vice vcrsd ; that 
 two plus two are equal to four; that two red roses are 
 similar in color. But paternity and sonship, equality 
 and similarity are mere relations ; therefore there 
 exist true relations. 
 
 2. It is certain that there exists in the universe an 
 admirable order of different beinni. and none could 
 assert that it is merely a fiction of our fancy, or a 
 pure extrinsic denomination, because in that order 
 and harmony lies the whole good of the universe. 
 But such order is nothing more than a real chain of 
 relations; therefore there exist true relations. 
 ' ■ 3. We judge of the rights and duties in civil society 
 
220 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 by merely considering the relations among indivi- 
 duals ; but if the relations between individuals were 
 not real, the rights and duties emanating from them 
 would not be real. Therefore we must admit real 
 relations. 
 
 Q. Under how many heads may we bring all these 
 relations? 
 
 A. Under three heads. Relation is the order which 
 a thing has with another; therefore there are as many 
 relations as there are ways by which a thing may have 
 order with another. Now, a thing may have order 
 with another (i) inasmuch as it forms one of its essen- 
 tial elements, and both together constitute a genus 
 or a species, as the relation which exists between the 
 human soul and the body. 2. A thing may have 
 order with. another as the cause to the effect — as the 
 relation of a father to his child, of an architect to the 
 building, etc. 3. A thing may have order with an- 
 other in consequence of the agreement or disagree- 
 ment of both in some accidental quality — as two 
 red roses, two white lilies, etc. 
 
 Q. Give the essence and definition of quality. 
 
 A. Quality is a name which is given to different 
 things, and also to all the categories of accidents ; 
 but, taken as a special category, it is defined : that 
 accident which modifies and affects the substance in 
 itself. Upon which definition we observe that it is 
 called accident to distinguish it from the specific 
 difference which also qualifies the substance ; but 
 spirituality, for instance, qualifies the substance of 
 the soul, yet it belongs to its essence, and is not 
 an accident. We have added which modifies and 
 affects the substance, to distinguish it from other acci- 
 dents. Because, though all accidents are affections 
 of the substance, and are added to it to supply some 
 
Elements of Intellectual Ph ilosopky. 2 2 1 
 
 defect or imperfection, yet the quality properly and 
 intrinsically is that which modifies the substance. 
 Quantity, for instance, is given to the substance to 
 give it extension and impenetrability of parts ; re- 
 lations are effects, as it were, of substances. Other 
 accidents might more properly be called adjacent, 
 rather than intrinsic, perfections of the substance ; 
 but quality alone is intrinsic to it, as healthy food, 
 fresh air, strong man, charming sky — all qualities 
 inherent to these various substances. 
 
 Q. How many kinds of qualities are there? 
 
 A. Four: those which modify the substance in it- 
 self — as to be well, to be healthy ; those which affect 
 it in its operation by adding or diminishing efficacy — 
 as the power of vision in a young person, the weak- 
 ness of the same in an aged man ; those which affect 
 it according to physical movement, inducing some 
 sensible transformation — as hot air, cold air, moist 
 air, etc. ; those which affect the form or figure of the 
 substance — as a square table, an oval face, a hooked 
 nose. The first qualities arc called disposition or 
 habits; the second, power or impotence ; the third, 
 alterations ; the fourth, /(?r;« and^^//r^. 
 
 The following lines may be taken as an example of 
 the different kinds of qualities: 
 
 ** Queen of fragrance* lovely \ Rose, 
 The beauties of thy leaves disclose ! 
 The winter 's past, the tempests fly, 
 SoftX gales breathe gently through the sky ; 
 The lark, sweet warbling on the wing, 
 Salutes the gay return of spring ; 
 ^ The silver dews, the vernal showers, 
 
 Call forth a bloomy waste of flowers ; 
 1\i^joyotis fields, the shady woods, 
 Are clothed with green or swell with buds ; 
 
 * Quality of power. t Of disposition. :( Of power, etc. 
 
2 2 2 Elements of Intellectual Ph ilosophy. 
 
 Then haste thy beauties to disclose, 
 Queen of fragrance, lovely Rose ! " 
 
 — Broome, The Rosebud. 
 
 ARTICLE THIRD. 
 
 Action mid Passion. 
 
 Q. What is action, and how many kinds of action 
 
 are there ? 
 
 A. In another chapter we have spoken of causes, and 
 
 especially of the efficient cause, or of the agent, and of 
 the effects which emanate from it. This emanation 
 from the cause producing the effect is called action. 
 From this we can understand how, in order to have 
 action, three things are required : i, a principle which 
 acts — that is, the substance ; 2, a principle accord- 
 ing to which the action is performed to determine its 
 kind — that is, the essence, which is the interior prin- 
 ciple of every action ; 3, a principle through which 
 the substances may act — that is, the faculties, which, 
 as we shall show, in creatures are the proximate 
 principle of operations distinct from the essence. 
 Action is of two kinds — immanent and transient. The 
 first is that which terminates in the subject, acting 
 in such a manner that it is itself both the principle 
 and the term of the action. The second is that which 
 terminates outside the subject — that is, the action 
 begins in the subject and terminates outside of it. 
 
 Q. What are the opinions of philosophers as to both 
 kinds of action ? 
 
 A. As to immanent actions, some have said that 
 they are not true actions, inasmuch as they have no 
 real term. Against transjent actions, Leibnitz has 
 said that they are impossible, on the plea that in order 
 to have a transient action something must pass from 
 
Elements of Intellectual Ph ilosophy. 223 
 
 the agent to the subject acted upon, but this is im- 
 possible ; therefore, etc. Now, both these opinions 
 are false. i. As to immanent actions. When I 
 study, for instance, I perform an immanent action, 
 because the term of the action remains in me. But is 
 the result of mv action less real because it takes place 
 in myself? Certainly not, since the perfection of 
 my intellect, the consequence of my study, is surely 
 something real — as real as the distinction which exists 
 between a learned and an ignorant man, between a 
 cultivated man and a boor. 
 
 " Base-minded they that want intelligence ; 
 For God himself for wisdom most is praised, 
 And men to God thereby are nighest raised." 
 
 —Spenser, 
 
 With regard to the possibility of transient actions, 
 we deny that it is necessary that an accident should 
 travel from the agent to the subject acted upon to 
 render possible such actions ; because all that is ne- 
 cessary in this case is that the agent should apply its 
 efficacy and force upon the subject to produce in it a 
 new state. Secondly, if this possibility were denied, 
 many absurd consequences Vv'ould follow ; for if all 
 those actions which do not terminate in the agent did 
 not exist, man would no longer be responsible for all 
 those actions which pass from him, such as theft, 
 murder, etc. ; he would no longer be liable either to 
 reward or punishment ; all the order and harmony of 
 the universe, which is kept by one series of beings 
 acting upon another, would be a mere optical delu- 
 sion. 
 
 Q. What is the term of both actions? 
 
 A. The direct term must always be something posi- 
 tive, but as to the indirect term it may be negative. 
 In fact, every agent acts always for an end; but the 
 
224 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 end is equivalent to good ; therefore every agent in 
 acting intends some good. But good is convertible 
 with being, and being is something positive ; there- 
 fore every agent in acting intends something positive. 
 But that which the agent intends is the term of his 
 action ; therefore the direct term of every action is 
 something positive. The negative, therefore, can 
 only be an indirect term, since to destroy can never 
 be meant by any agent positively acting, but only 
 indirectly. 
 
 Q. What is passion? 
 
 A. To receive in one's self the term of the action of 
 the agent is called passion^ and the subject patient. 
 Now, though action and passion agree in one act and 
 one movement, the principle of which is the action, 
 the term the passio'i, yet they are distinguished from 
 each other; betnuse, certainly, it is not the same 
 thing to give and to receive, to do and to suffer, to 
 perfect and to be perfected, to be principle and end. 
 But action implies to give, to do, to perfect, to be 
 principle; passion means to receive, to suffer, to be 
 perfected, to be the term ; therefore action and passion 
 are not the same thing. This truth is more evident 
 in transient actions. In them the action is in the 
 agent, the passion in the subject outside the agent. 
 But the same universal accident cannot be in two 
 subjects at the same time ; therefore action and pas- 
 sion are in reality distinct from each other — two acci- 
 dents really and specifically distinct, hence two cate- 
 
 gories. 
 
Elements of Intellectual Ph ilosophy. 225 
 
 ARTICLE FOURTH. 
 
 Of the Categories Where, When, Site, and Habit. 
 
 Q. Give the definition of the category Where. 
 
 A. Bodies are circumscribed by place. Now, this 
 circumscription of tlie body proceeding from the de- 
 termination of place constitutes the category ivJiere, 
 to understand which we must first speak of place. 
 This is defined by Aristotle the surface of body 
 which first and immovably surrounds and circum- 
 scribes another body. We say which first surrounds 
 and circumscribes, because place is that surface which 
 immediately surrounds and touches the body. For 
 instance, suppose I lay a book on a table, the table 
 is the place with regard to the book ; but the table 
 serves as a place to the book, not as a whole, but in 
 part ; that is, that part of its surface which imme- 
 diately touches the book. We say immovably be- 
 cause, though that surface could be moved and 
 changed, yet it could not have the name of place if 
 it is not considered as immovable in respect to the 
 body which it circumscribes and contains. 
 
 This circumscription coming to a body from its be- 
 ing in a place constitutes the category where. But 
 here we must make a most important observation. The 
 determination proceeding from place is twofold. The 
 determination or boundary which a body receives 
 from a place is called being circumscribed by a place. 
 But, besides the body, a spirit may be in a certain 
 place, and the spirit may not be infinite or immense 
 like God, who is everywhere, but limited and finite. 
 Now, when a spirit is present in a certain place it can- 
 not be said to occupy that place or to be bounded by 
 such a place, because this would require juxtaposition 
 of parts, and the spirit has none; it can only be said 
 
226 Elements of Intellectual Ph ilosophy. 
 
 to be destined to, ( to bo designated by, that place. 
 Now, this determination which a created spirit re- 
 ceives from place is called to be in a definitive place ^ 
 because place merely defines or designates where the 
 spirit is, but neither contains nor surrounds it.* 
 
 Q. What is space ? 
 
 A. It is very difficult to define space, and philoso- 
 phers have broached all sorts of opinions about it. 
 On the one hand, space cannot be what our fancy 
 imagines — something really existing as containing 
 an immense number of bodies — because extension can- 
 not exist as something separate from bodies. What 
 could it be but a body? And where could the body 
 be contained? In another? And where would this 
 third one be ? In a fourth, and so on ad infinitmn ? 
 
 On the other hand, it seems contradictory to sup- 
 pose that that which contains all bodies is the same 
 thing with that which it contains. If, therefore, space 
 must not be something separate, and at the same time 
 it must be something distinct, from bodies, what else 
 can it be to satisfy both requirements except what 
 St. Thomas defines it to be, tJic extension of bodies, in- 
 asimicJi OS it is considered to contain either the same 
 body to which it belongs or other bodies ? 
 
 Having thus explained the idea of space, it is hardly 
 necessary to prove it, because if the capacity to con- 
 tain must be found in a body, what else can it be but 
 its extension and dimension? Therefore it is clear that 
 the nature of space lies in extension. Hence it is that 
 whenever we want to measure space we only measure 
 extension. From this it appears that that space which 
 we imagine to exist outside the limits of the universe, 
 
 *' The, schoolmen called the manner in which a material object is in a place esse 
 in loco circumscriptive. The manner in which a spirit is in a place esse in loco de/I- 
 nitivt. We have rendered in the text the idea of the schoolmen as accurately as we 
 could. 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 227 
 
 and in which we fancy the world to have been created, 
 is not a reahty but a fiction, which St. Augustine jest- 
 ingly calls spacious nothing. 
 
 But it may be asked : Where is the world ? What 
 vast body contains it? The world is nowhere but in 
 itself. It is not contained in any other space or 
 body, but God's infinite power upholds it. 
 
 Q. Give the idea of the category When. 
 
 A. Things may be bounded not only by place, 
 but also by time. Now, as the boundary of bodies 
 proceeding from place gives the category where, so 
 also the determination of things arising from time 
 gives the category when. 
 
 To understand this we must give the idea of time. 
 Time is a kind of duration by which we mean, the 
 permanence of a thing in its existence. Hence dura- 
 tion may be of as many kinds as there are modes of 
 existence. The first is that of the Being absolutely 
 immutable, which is God. The second is that of 
 beings immutable as to their being, but chJingeable as 
 to their operations. The last is that of being change- 
 able as to both being and operations. According to 
 these three modes of being we may distinguish three 
 kinds of duration. The first is called eternity, the 
 perfect possession of interminable life all in one — that 
 is, having neither beginning nor end nor succession. 
 The second is called csvnni, which is an interminable 
 life of a being created but naturally imperishabl'\ and 
 belongs to immortal spirits. The third is that of 
 beings mutable as to being and operations. Time, 
 therefore, is nothing more than the duration of beings 
 mutable as to being and operations. And because by 
 time we measure the changes and movements of 
 such mutable beings, determining the beginning and 
 the end of such movements, Aristotle has defined 
 
228 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 time to be the measure of movement by marking its 
 before and its after. 
 
 " Time past and time to come are not, 
 Time present is our only lot." 
 
 — Montgomery. 
 
 O. What is the idea of site ? 
 
 A. The disposition or location of the parts of a 
 body with regard to a place is called site. From 
 this it might appear that the category site is con- 
 founded with that of where ; but if we consider both 
 accurately we shall find a great difference between 
 them ; because where implies merely that a body is 
 found in such a place, whereas site implies the manner 
 and the how it is found — perpendicularly, horizontally, 
 leaning, or lying, etc. Site, therefore, is the how a body 
 is found in a place. Here we may remark that we are 
 accustomed to apply the idea of site to spiritual 
 things ; but this we do metaphorically. Hence God, 
 says St. Tht)mas, is said to be sitting in consequence 
 of His immutability, to be standing in cortsequence 
 of His power to repel His enemies. 
 
 Q. What is habit ? 
 
 A. That determination or distinctiot. which ac- 
 crues to bodies from that which clothes them. From 
 this definition we can see that, in order to have this 
 category, two or more substances are required — one 
 which is clothed, the other which clothes ; that this 
 accident consists in neither of these two substances, 
 but in the contact of both or in the clothing. 
 
 Q. Give a r6sum6 of the whole of ontology. 
 
 A. We can see now as in a picture the whole series 
 of truths explained in ontology, and how they descend 
 one from another in beautiful order from the idea of 
 being. Setting out from the idea of being, we have 
 
Elements of Intellectual Ph ilosophy, 229 
 
 investigated its nature universally considered, then wc 
 have studied its elements and Jioiv they constitute 
 being, then we have studied its properties of unity, 
 truth, goodness, and beauty. We have enquired after- 
 wards into the causes of being, and have acquired a clear 
 and distinct conception of them. Finally, we have 
 proceeded to study the divisions of being, and have 
 seen that it is divided into ten classes — first, substance 
 in its complete and incomplete state, and then the 
 accidents of quantity, quality, relation, action, passion, 
 space, time, site, and habit, and thus we acquired the 
 most general idea applicable to all things. We con- 
 clude with the words of the poet, which recapitulate 
 the whole ontology, and especially the two supreme 
 categories — substance and accident. 
 
 The poet introduces a sibyl foretelling the fate of 
 the eldest son of Being, which is Substance: 
 
 " Your son, said she, nor can you prevent it, 
 Shall subject be to many an accident. 
 O'er all his brethren he shall reign as king, 
 Yet every one shall make him underling ; 
 And those that cannot live from him asunder 
 Ungratefully shall strive to keep him under. 
 In worth and excellence he shall outgo them ; 
 Yet, being above them, he shall be below them. 
 From others he shall stand in need of nothing, 
 Yet on his brothers shall depend for clothing. 
 To find a foe it shall not be his hap, 
 And Peace shall lull him in her flowery lap ; 
 Yet shall he live in strife, and at his door 
 De. ouripj? War shall nev3r cease to roar ; 
 Yet it shall be his natural property 
 To harbor those that are at enmity. 
 What power, what force, what mighty spell, if not 
 Your learned hands, can loose this Gordian knot ? " 
 
 —Milton. 
 
■v''- ■ 
 
 CHAPTER VII. 
 
 OF' THE USE OF ONTOLOGY. 
 
 Q. What do young people think of ontology? 
 
 A. That it is a hard, dry study, of no practical use 
 whatever. 
 
 Q. Is that so? 
 
 A. It is certainly a little dry and hard to under- 
 stand ; but as to its use, it is of the greatest importance 
 to understand anything scientifically, and every science 
 and art is founded upon ontology. 
 
 Q. Can you give any example in art and science 
 showing how they are founded on ontology ? 
 
 A. In art we will take as an example grammar, 
 which is the art of speaking and writing correctly. 
 In the first place, the foundation of the whole gram- 
 mar is the substantive verb to be, which implies real 
 existence. Without it language would not express a 
 reality, but would be merely a construction and ar- 
 rangement of words having no real meaning what- 
 ever. The substantive verb to be, therefore, makes 
 our grammar and our speech real and objective. But 
 this substantive verb corresponds to the universal 
 idea of being as described in ontology. 
 
 Next come the nouns, which are divided into sub- 
 stantive and adjective. These correspond to the 
 great division of being into substance and accident. 
 The pronouns, personal or indicative, are founded upon 
 the idea of the person or the individual ; / express- 
 ing always a personality, this or that expressing an 
 
 individuality. 
 
 330 
 
Elements of hitellectual Ph ilosophy. 2 3 t 
 
 Next follow the numbers, which are singular, plural — 
 collective and universal. These are founded upon 
 the property of being nnity^ which gives rise to dis- 
 tinction and plurality. 
 
 As to the verbs, they are active, passive, and neuter. 
 The active verb, which means to do or to act, is 
 founded upon the idea of cause and action. When 
 the verb expresses an immanent action it is called 
 active intransitive, as I sleep, I think ; when it ex- 
 presses a transient action it is called active transitive, 
 as I strike ; the two grand divisions of action. 
 
 The passive verb, which means to be acted upon, to 
 suffer, is founded on the idea of passion, the neuter 
 on both. 
 
 As to the moods of verbs, they are the infinitive, 
 the indicative, the subjunctive, the potential, and the 
 imperative. For this division there is no real ground, 
 at least so far as the potential and subjunctive are 
 concerned. The subjunctiv^e is merely an elliptical 
 mode of expression, and the potential is made up of 
 two or more verbs, and therefore it canno:, with any 
 propriety, be called an inflection of any of them. 
 This leaves us the indicative, by which simple assertions 
 are made ; the imperative, by which commands are 
 given; and the infinitive, which expresses the meaning 
 of the verb in the abstract, as to love, to do, to think. 
 The indicative is founded on the idea of being as as- 
 serting something, the imperative on the idea of 
 cause, the infinitive on the idea of action or passion. 
 The tenses, present, past, and future, are founded upon 
 the idea of time. 
 
 The adverb is a qualification added to a verb, such 
 as to do well, to do quickly ; and is founded on the 
 ideas of quality — as to do ill, justly, wisely ; on the 
 idea of quantity — as v;o work so much, considerably ; 
 
232 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 of time — as to do it now, then, soon, when ; of place 
 — as to write here, hence, there, where. 
 
 The preposition is a word connecting two words 
 together so as to indicate the relation which the things 
 or ideas signified by them bear to each other, and, as 
 it is evident, is founded on the idea of relation — as the 
 heavens above us, the enemies of our salvation about 
 us, the regret after sin, friendships among equals, 
 love between brothers, etc. 
 
 F'inally, the conjunction, which joins words together, 
 is founded also on the idea of relation. 
 
 The syntax, which is that part of grammar which 
 teaches how words are to be arranged and connected 
 together, is also founded pre-eminently on ontology, 
 because its fundamental rule is to arrange and con- 
 nect words in such a manner as to maintain the proper 
 relations of being. For instance, if I should in speak- 
 ing break that first rule of syntax that a verb agrees 
 with its nominative in number and person, and 'w\- 
 stGa.d o( ssiylng, *' I read, PeUr /cams," I should say, 
 ** I reads, Peter learn,'' I would break the proper rela- 
 tions of being; for if it is I who read I cannot 
 express that relation of being in the nominative and 
 then deny it in the verb ; if it is Peter who learns, one 
 person, I cannot contradict that and express in the 
 verb that they are many who learn. , 
 
 Grammar, therefore, which takes its objective reality 
 from the idea of real being ; which finds its ideas of the 
 substantive and adjective nouns in the conception of 
 substance and accidents ; which forms its verbs, active, 
 passive, and neuter, on the ideas of cause, action, and 
 passion ; its tenses from the idea of time ; which 
 takes its ideas of adverbs, prepositions, and conjunc- 
 tions from the various kinds of accident ; which give§ 
 rules of syntax from the natural and essential relations 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy, 233 
 
 of being — is altogether founded on ontology, and can- 
 not be known scientifically without it. 
 
 Q. Show by the example of the natural sciences 
 how they are founded on the ideas we acquire in on- 
 tology. 
 
 A. The first natural science is physics, the object 
 of which is to study the causes of the phenomena 
 which h.ini»eii in matter and which do not cause any 
 change in the composition of bodies. A physical 
 phenomenon is any fact which is accomplished or 
 takes place in matter \ ithout altering its composition. 
 A body which falls, a sound which is produced, a cer- 
 tain quantity of water which is frozen, are so many 
 phenomena. Now, to enquire into such facts which 
 do not alter the composition of bodies is the object 
 of physics. We say of phenomena which do not alter 
 ths composition of bodies, because to enquire into 
 those facts which modify more or less the nature of 
 bodies is the object of chemistry. 
 
 it is evident that physics is an application of on- 
 tology to a particular object, for the first question 
 which this science puts is. What is matter, or a body? 
 — that is, it studies the nature of the object it works 
 upon, and finds out that any limited quantity of mat- 
 ter is a body ; that a body is not formed by a con- 
 tinual quantity of matter, but of elements infinitely 
 small, which cannot be physically divided, and are" 
 placed in juxtaposition with each other without 
 touching each other, being designedly maintained at 
 a distance by mutual attraction and repulsion, which 
 elements are called atoms, and a group of them mole- 
 cules. It finds out also that a body may be in dif- 
 ferent states: the solid state, as stone, metal; the 
 liquid state, as water, oil; the gaseous state, as 
 steam ; that the difference of these three states con- 
 
234 Elements of httelLctual Philosophy. 
 
 sists in the cohesion of the parts or molecules; in 
 solids the cohesion being so strong as to require a 
 great effort to separate them; in liquids much less 
 effort, as the cohesion is weaker ; in gases much less, 
 as the cohesion is the weakest. 
 
 Having enquired into the essence and nature of 
 bodies, it passes on to investigate their properties, 
 some of which, because found constantly in all bodies, 
 it calls essential, such as extension, divisibility, im- 
 penetrability, elasticity, mobility, inertia; others it 
 finds only in some bodies, and it concludes to be acci- 
 dental to bodies, such as solidity, fluidity, ductility, 
 porosity, compressibility. 
 
 Physics proceeds next to enquire into the causes of 
 t\vQSQ phenoituna, in order to understand them scientifi- 
 cally. We say phenomena and not bodies, because to 
 enquire into the cause of bodies belongs to cosmology. 
 It discovers that the followincr are the causes for the 
 phenomena of bodies: attraction, heat, light, mag- 
 netism, and electricity. These are called physical agents 
 or forces. After studying these causes the natural 
 philosopher, by observing the constant relations be- 
 tween the phenomenon of a body and its cause, dis- 
 covers and assigns what are called physical laws, and 
 attains the object and use of this science. For in- 
 stance, after studying attraction and finding it to be a 
 force inherent in matter by which particles and masses 
 of matter are drawn towards each' other, and carefully 
 observing that this force increases in proportion to the 
 quantity of matter which the attracting body contains 
 and in proportion to the diminishing of the distance be- 
 tween the bodies, it establishes the law that the force of 
 attraction in bodies is in proportion to the mass and to 
 the greater or less distance, the attraction increasing 
 as the mass increases and as the distance diminishes. 
 
Elanetits of Intellectual Ph ilosophy. 235 
 
 The student will here carefully remark how ontology, or 
 the general science of being, has guided' the natural 
 philosopher to his science ; for as ontology enquires 
 into the nature and essence of beings so the natural 
 philosopher enquires into the essence and nature 
 of bodies ; as the first enquires into the proper- 
 ties of being, so does the second enquire into the 
 properties of bodies ; as the first enquires into the 
 causes of being, so does the latter seek into the 
 causes of the phenomena of bodies; as the first 
 investigates the most general division of being, so 
 does the second enquire into the most general di- 
 vision of bodies, which division gives rise to all 
 natural sciences. 
 
 Q. Give a brief idea of the different natural sci- 
 ences. 
 
 A. The body may be inorganic, living, and animal. 
 This supreme division of general physics gives rise 
 to a host of natural sciences. When natural science 
 analyzes the inorganic body into its elements and its 
 constituent principles it is called chemistry,, which is 
 the science of whatever has relation to the simple or 
 elementary — that is, bodies which invariably present 
 the same characteristics however they may be divided. 
 On the contrary, those bodies which are composite 
 are aggregations of several elements combined in 
 a different way and united by their natural affinities. 
 Now, these bodies present themselves to our observa- 
 tion in different states — the gaseous, the liquid, and 
 the solid. The science which investigates the nature, 
 properties, causes, and action of gases, together with 
 the laws which govern them, is called gasology. 
 That which studies liquids is called hydrology. The 
 science which studies the nature, properties, causes, 
 action, laws of the solids is called mineralogy. With 
 
 •J 
 
236 Elements 0/ Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 regard to organic bodies, the science which studies the 
 first organic bodies— that is, the plant — is botany. 
 That which studies the organic life of animal bodies is 
 called zoology, which is divided into two sciences — 
 anatomy and physiology; the first is the study of the 
 nature, properties, causes, functions, and use of the 
 elementary parts of the animal body or of the skele- 
 ton ; the second is the science of the nature, proper- 
 ties, causes, functions, and uses of th.e organs of the 
 animal body. Medicine, with all its subordinate sci- 
 ences, is the science of the causes of the alterations 
 produced in the animal organism and of the means of 
 repairing them. 
 
 The next grand division of bodies is that which 
 separates them into celestial and terrestrial. The 
 celestial bodies are the object of a particular science 
 called astronomy^ the object of which is to ex- 
 plain the phenomena and to account for the move- 
 ments of those huge bodies which gravitate in Bpace. 
 To this another science is allied, called cosmo- 
 graphy, which teaches the structure, the form, the 
 location, and the relations of the parts which com- 
 pose the universe. 
 
 The terrestrial body is the object of two other 
 sciences, geography and geology. The first gives the 
 description of the earth, its exterior figure, its division, 
 and all those particulars presented by its surface. The 
 second penetrates into the very bowels of the earth, 
 aNd seeks to know its interior structure, the different 
 materials of which it is composed, their formation, 
 their relative location, and the different revolutions to 
 which it has been subject. 
 
 These divisions arise from considering bodies in their 
 concreteness, but there is another branch of physical 
 science which di cs not consider them in themselves 
 
Elements of Intellectual Ph ilosophy, 237 
 
 and in their elements, but in tlic abstract as to their 
 quantity, number, or extension. 
 
 Arithmetic -d^wd ali^cbra consider quantity in itshit^h- 
 est abstraction, and treat of the combinations of 
 quantities which can be expressed by simple relations 
 of number. ]hit every specified quantity may be re- 
 garded from a twofold relation — that of time and of 
 space, because time and space are the necessary con- 
 ditions of all reality which is capable of measure. The 
 relation of a particular quantity to space exi)ressed by 
 a figure is the object oi geometry — a Science which has 
 received such a name from the use to which it was 
 formerly destined, that of measuring the earth, and 
 which has retained its primitive name, though it has 
 made such immense progress. 
 
 The relation which a dcfmitc quantity bears to time 
 is exjiressed by movement, because we may say that 
 it is through movement that time is rendered visible 
 in space. Now, movement cannot be conceived ex- 
 cept as the product of a force. The science of the 
 forces which cause movement is called mechanics. 
 These forces may l)c considered under two aspects, in- 
 asmuch as they neutralize each ether, and under this 
 aspect they are the object o( staties ; inasmuch as they 
 produce the movement, and then they are the object 
 of dyiuimics. Of co-irse the science of mechanics is 
 subdivided into several branches, according to the na- 
 ture of the bodies to which the moving forces arc 
 applied, such as hydraulics, which considers the move- 
 ment of fluids; hydrometry, which h, s for its object 
 the weight, the force, the intensity of fluids, etc. 
 
 The student will sec by this brief sketch of natural 
 sciences how they are nothing else than an application 
 of ontology; how each studies first the nature of its 
 object, its properties, its causes, and its laws. Onto- 
 
238 Elements of Ijitelkctual Philosophy, 
 
 logy, therefore, which teaches the native properties, 
 causes, divisions, laws of being, is of the utmost im-. 
 portance to all sciences which treat of a particular 
 being. 
 
ANTHROPOLOGY 
 
 •• Know then thyself; .... 
 The proper study of mankind is man." — Pope. 
 839 
 
ANTHROPOLOGY. 
 
 INTRODUCTION. 
 
 Q. What is anthropology ? 
 
 A. The science which has for its object man. The 
 science which treats of the human soul is called psy- 
 chology ; but as in philosophy we cannot speak of the 
 human soul without mentioning its union with the 
 body, so we must treat of the whole man, and there- 
 fore study anthropology, which means the science of 
 man ; yet we shall principally occupy ourselves about 
 the soul. 
 
 Q. What method shall we follow in speaking of 
 man, and principally of his soul? 
 
 A. We shall follow the method of St. Thomas, who 
 
 says: "In every spiritual substance three things are 
 
 to be remarked — the essence, the faculties, and the 
 
 operations." Hence he concludes, with regard to the 
 
 soul, that three things are to be remarked in it — its 
 
 essence, its faculties, and its operations. W^e shall 
 
 follow this method, and shall enquire into these three 
 
 things: What is the nature of the human soul? what 
 
 are its faculties ? and what are its operations ? This 
 
 method and order will render the things to be treated 
 
 clearer and more easy of comprehension. 
 
 941 
 
CHAPTER I. 
 
 ON THE NATURE OF MAN IN GENERAL. 
 ARTICLE FIRhl', 
 
 That Man is not Body alojie, but is made up of ancthc? 
 Principle called the Soul. 
 
 O. What is the definition of man ? 
 
 A. Man is defined to be a reasonable animal^ be- 
 cause lie not only lives and feels but reasons. In call- 
 ing him an animal vio. determine his proximate genus, 
 in which he agrees with all those beings which have 
 souls. In calling him reasonable we define the specific 
 difference of man which distinguishes him from all 
 other animals. Hence man must result from two 
 elements — a body and a reasonable soul — both of 
 which make one substantial whole. 
 
 Q. Is this admitted by all ? 
 
 A. No. In Germany, in England, France, and our 
 own country some would-be philosophers have held 
 that man is nothing more than a well-organized body. 
 But, because there are certain operations in man 
 which seem to suppose another principle in him be- 
 sides the body, these philosophors, in order to ac- 
 count for such operations, and unwilling to admit a 
 reasonable soul in man, have been forced to invent 
 different systems. Some have said that these opera- 
 tions — such as the act of judgment, of reasoning, and 
 so forth — can be easily accounted for by means of 
 chemical forces and laws. .Others, following the prin- 
 ciple of Descartes, that whatever happens in the body 
 
 242 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 243 
 
 is the result of mechanical laws, have held that all 
 the operations of man can be easily explained by 
 means of the laws of movement. Others, finally, see- 
 ing that these operations of man cannot be accounted 
 for by means either of chemical or mechanical laws, 
 have invented certain forces which they call vital^ 
 different from physical properties, but, like these, in- 
 herent in the very matter of the organs. To these 
 vital forces they attribute all the distinctive opera- 
 tions of man. The first system has been called cJienii- 
 calisin, the other mechanicism, and the last organicism. 
 
 We shall prove first in general that in man, besides 
 the body, there is another principle distinct from the 
 body; that the simplest operations of the mind can^ 
 not be explained without this principle. Next we 
 shall say a word on each system in particular. 
 
 Proof I. The human body holds the first and mosf. 
 perfect rank among living bodies. But such a body 
 cannot exist by itself alone, but must have another 
 principle ; therefore there must be another principle 
 in man besides his body. The minor is proved : if a 
 body is living, there must necessarily be some princi- 
 ple which gives it life. Now, this principle must be 
 either the body itself or something distinct from the 
 body. But it cannot be the body itself, because, as 
 St. Thomas remarks, it is evident that to be the 
 principle of life does not become the body as body, 
 otherwise all bodies would be living, which is contrary 
 to experience ; therefore in living bodies life must 
 arise from a principle other than the body. 
 
 2. It is evident that we have ideas or forms of many 
 things in our mind. We have the forms or ideas of 
 the firmament, of the sun, the stars, the sky, the 
 forms of mountains, of the boundless ocean, and so 
 forth. But this would be utterly impossible if in man 
 
2 44 Elements of Inieliectual Ph ilosopJiy. 
 
 there were nothing more than the body ; therefore, 
 etc. 
 
 The minor is proved from the principle and the ex- 
 perience that it is impossible for a body to have more 
 tiian one form at a time. No mechanical or chemical 
 process can make a body take two different forms at the 
 same time. A sculptor, for instance, cannot by any 
 mechanical skill make a block of wood take the form of 
 a man and a serpent at the same time ; a chemist by 
 no chemical skill can make a body take the solid, the 
 liquid, and gaseous forms at the same time. Conse- 
 quently, if man were nothing more than a body, he 
 could only have the form of one thing at a time ; but 
 man has the ideas or forms of different things at the 
 same time ; therefore there must be in him another 
 principle besides the body. 
 
 " No body can at once two forms admit 
 Except the one the other do deface ; 
 But in the soul ten thousand forms do sit, 
 
 And none intrudes into her neighbor's place."* 
 
 3. It is a principle of reason as well as experience 
 that a thing which is received into another must take 
 the shape and the form of the recipient. This princi- 
 ple was expressed by the schoolmen as follows : 
 Omne quod rccipitur ad inoduvi rccipientis rccipitiir ; 
 and by the poet : 
 
 " All things received do such proportions take 
 As those things wherein they are received ; 
 So little glasses little faces make, 
 And narrow webs on narrow frames are weaved." f 
 
 Now, in consequence of this principle, if man were 
 only a body the forms of things which he apprehends 
 
 * Davies's Poems. t Ibid. 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 245 
 
 should take the form, shape, and size of the body. 
 But this is contrary to experience, because we have 
 ideas of all things conformable to their actual reality; 
 for we are those 
 
 " Wherein are men, beasts, trees, seas, and lands, 
 And yet oach thing a proper place doth find, 
 And each thing in the due proportion stands."* 
 
 Q. Say something of each system in particular. 
 
 A. Having proved that man could not perform the 
 simplest operation of the mind, which is apprehension, 
 if he were only a body, we proceed to make some re- 
 marks on each system, and first against those who ex- 
 plain the operations of man by means of chemical forces 
 and the laws of movement, i. We know by experience 
 that oftentimes we are undecided which operation to 
 choose ; we discuss the question with ourselves to see 
 which we should choose ; and finally, we know that we 
 choose that which seems to us best, or, in fact, which 
 we wish to choose. 
 
 But the freedom of doubting, consulting, and choos- 
 ing cannot possibly belong to chemical forces, or be 
 done by mechanical laws, for all these acts are done 
 necessarily ; therefore all these operations of man can- 
 not be explained by those forces. 
 
 2. We know also by experience that after having 
 commenced a certain action we can upon the instant 
 stop it and begin another, and drop it again to under- 
 take a new one. But this would be impossible under 
 the laws of movement and mechanical forces. How 
 often, for instance, would the engineer wish to possess 
 this power of instantly stopping the engine he is guid- 
 ing, and cannot under the laws of movement, but 
 must let it go on to carry death and desolation to 
 hundreds ! 
 
 * Davies. 
 
246 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 Finally, we remark against the third system that 
 to have recourse to vital properties to explain the 
 operations of man is only confoundirig the question 
 more and more, because a property is not a principle, 
 but the consequence of some vital principle ; therefore 
 that from which property originates, and not property 
 itself, must be th'^^'principle of life. But these philoso- 
 phers contend that these properties are properties of 
 organic bodies ; they come to admit, then, that, after 
 all, the body is the principle of life. But we have 
 shown, with the clearest evidence, that a body cannot 
 be the principle of life; tbTefore we must admit an- 
 other principle in man besides the body. This is 
 called the soul, which, as far as we have described it, 
 may be defined as the first principle of life in things to 
 which we attribute life. 
 
 ARTICLE SECOND. 
 
 This Principle called the Soul is One, but does not Form 
 
 the Whole Man. 
 
 Q. Is the soul a single principle or multiple ? 
 
 A. Some philosophers, having admitted in man, 
 besides the body, another principle which causes 
 him to move and to act, and having examined these 
 operations and found them different in nature, have 
 come to the conclusion that the principle which 
 causes man to perform all these operations must 
 be more than one. Some have admitted a dou- 
 ble principle — one which performs intellectual ope- 
 rations, another which feels and vegetates. Others 
 have admitted three — one the principle of intel- 
 lectual operations, another the principle of sensa- 
 tion, the last the principle of vegetation. But these 
 opinions are false, and we must admit only one 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy, 247 
 
 principle of all these operations and prove it as fol- 
 lows : 
 
 I. Because we know by experience that an opera- 
 tion of the soul, when it is too intensely attended to, 
 hinders other operations. For instance, when a man 
 is absorbed in an intense intellectual work the opera- 
 tions of the sensitive and vegetative life are either 
 suspended or imperfectly carried on ; and, contrariwise, 
 when a man is plunged into some sensible operation 
 he is unfit for intellectual work. This principle ex- 
 plains all those anecdotes of absent-minded persons, 
 of which we have so many examples.* Now, this 
 would be impossible if the principles of action in man 
 were multiple, because in that case each one would 
 attend to its own department without any trouble or 
 hindrance — one could attend to thought, another to 
 sensation, and another to vegetation and locomotion ; 
 therefore there must be one principle in man. 
 
 The common sense of mankind rejects such an 
 opinion of more than one principle, because all men in 
 sp'iaking not only say, I understand, but also, I feel, I 
 live, I move, I grow, and such like expressions, attri- 
 buting all these different operations to one subject, the 
 me. Now, this they could not do if they were not con- 
 scious that the principle of all these operations is the 
 same and identical ; therefore we must admit one prin- 
 ciple in man. 
 
 " And these three powers f three sorts of men do make ; 
 For some, like plants, their veins do only fill : 
 And some, like beasts, their senses' pleasure takj ; 
 And some, like angels, do contemplate still. 
 
 * That, for instance, of the man who, passing by a toll-gate, cried out to the 
 keeper, " What's to pay?" The man at the gate replied, " Kor what ?" "' How for 
 what ?" replied the traveller ; " for my horse." " What horse ?" rejoined the keeper. 
 Whereupon the traveller, looking at his legp, exclaimed : " Excuse me, I thought I 
 was on horseback." 
 
 t Intellectual, sensitive, and vegetative. 
 
248 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 Tlicrcfurc the fables turned some men to flowers, 
 
 And others did with brutish forms invest, 
 And did ot others make celestial powers, 
 
 Like angels, which still travel, yet still rest. 
 Yet these three powers are not three souls but one. 
 
 As one and two are both contained in three, 
 Three being one number by itself alone 
 
 A shadow of the blessed Trinity." 
 
 — Davies. 
 
 But as some of the operations which man performs 
 cannot be accounted for by tlie soul alone, but require 
 the body also, such as sensation, so we must admit 
 that man consists of a body and a soul united to- 
 gether. 
 
 ARTICLE THIRD. 
 
 Man results from the Substantial Union of Body and 
 
 Soul. 
 
 Q. Is this union between the body and soul of man 
 accidental or substantial ? 
 
 A. Plato, who held that the soul is the whole man, 
 and who could not deny that there is a certain union 
 between the soul and the body, contended that this 
 union was merely accidental and exterior — the same 
 union, for instance, which exists between our bodies 
 and the clothes we put on, between the engineer and 
 the locomotive which he runs, or between the pilot 
 and his ship. 
 
 The true opinion is that the union between the soul 
 and the body is intrinsic and substantial. 
 
 Q, What do you mean by substantial union ? 
 
 A. To explain this we *^nust recall some points of 
 ontology. I. Subsistence is that last complement 
 of a substance by which it obtains the mastery over 
 itself and its own acts, becomes responsible for its 
 
Elements of hiiellectual Philosophy, 249 
 
 actions, and is incommunicable to all others. This is 
 called a complete substance or suppositum. 
 
 2. Every substance existing in nature is a supposi- 
 tum. 
 
 3. The subsistence of a created substance is neces- 
 sary only in thi.j sense : that no substance can possibly 
 exist without a subsistence. But it is not necessary 
 in the sense that every substance should have a sub- 
 sistence of its own nature and species, because it may 
 happen to subsist of the subsistence of another. 
 
 4. This happens when a substance is intended to 
 form such an intimate union with another substance 
 of a superior nature as both to form a complete subject 
 and individual. Because in this case, as nature in- 
 tends to form of two substances one complete indi- 
 vidual, it is evident that both substances cannot be 
 each one an entity perfectly complete, havinj^ the 
 mastery and attribution of its own acts, and exclusive 
 and incommunicable ; because in that case there would 
 be two perfect individuals, which is a^c^ainst the sup- 
 position, as we are speaking of a case where nature 
 intends to form one individual of two substances. 
 
 5. We understand also in this case which of the two 
 substances would have to yield, its own subsistence. 
 It must be the substance of the auporier nature — that 
 is, the inferior nature must have no last complement 
 of its own, but must be completed by the last comple- 
 ment of the superior nature ; so that the superior na- 
 ture's subsistence is that which completes both and 
 forms the individual. This is called substantial union, 
 which may be defined : the union of two substances 
 both made to subsist by a single subsistence, that of 
 one of the substances united. 
 
 The substantial union of the body and the soul in 
 man means that, so long as the body is actually united 
 
250 ElemetUs of Intellectual Philosophy 
 
 to the soul, it has no subsistence of its own, but sub- 
 sists on the substance of the soul ; that the soul gives 
 its own coinplcment to the body, and has the owner- 
 ship of both, and of the acts of both, is responsible for 
 them, and is exclusive and incommunicable to all 
 others. 
 
 The proof of this truth lies in the fact that man is 
 considered by all as one individual. We do not say 
 the hand of Raphael painted that Madonna, the hand 
 of Apelles made that statue, the hand of Homer 
 wrote the Iliad and the hand of Pope translated it, 
 but Raphael made that Madonna, Apelles made that 
 statue. Homer wrote the Iliad and Pope translated 
 it ; because, although these actions were done im- 
 mediately by their hands, guided by their mind, which 
 conceived their masterpieces, yet the actions of either 
 are and must be attributed to one individuality, be- 
 cause both the body and the soul of those geniuf s 
 subsisted in one subsistence, that of the highest prin- 
 ciple in them — the soul. 
 
 We conclude, therefore, with the poet : 
 
 "Then dwelleth she not therein as in a tent, 
 Nor as a pilot in his ship doth sit, 
 Nor as the spider in his web is pent. 
 Nor as the wax retains the print in it," 
 
 but is substantially united to the body, inasmuch as 
 it causes it to subsist of its own subsistence, so that 
 both form one individuality and one person. 
 
 ARTICLE FOURTH. 
 
 Of MatCs Essence, 
 
 Q. What is man's essence ? 
 
 A. The essence of man consists in those elements 
 which are absolutely necessary actually to constitute 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 251 
 
 man. Ikit for this three things are necessary : an in- 
 telhgent soul, a body, and a substantial union between 
 them in the sense just explained. By these three 
 constituents of his essence is man distinguished from 
 all other animals, to which he seems to bear a certain 
 likeness. Inasmuch as he has a body he is like to 
 animals, but is distinguished from them inasmuch as 
 he is endowed with a rational soul. Again, inasmuch 
 as he is a rational substance he agrees with all intelli- 
 gent substances, and differs from them in consequence 
 of his possessing a body ; hence by his essence man is 
 placed as a link between the pure, intelligent sub- 
 stances and the sensitive substances, thus binding to- 
 gether the chain of beings which the Creator has 
 mode. 
 
 *' How poor, how rich, how abject, how august. 
 
 Mow complicate, how wonderful is man ! 
 
 How passint>; wonder He who made him such ! 
 
 Who centred in our make such strin\^c extremes^ 
 
 From dilFcrent natures niaivellously mixt, 
 
 Conne tion exquisite of distant worlds ! 
 
 Distinguished link in being's endless chain 1 
 
 Midvsay from nothing to the Deity ! 
 
 A beam ethereal, sully 'd, and absorpt f 
 
 '1 ho' sullj-'d and dishonored, still divine! 
 
 Dim miniature of greatness absolute ! 
 
 An heir of gl jry ! a frail cliild of dust ! 
 
 lleli)lcss immortal ! insect infinite! 
 
 A worm ! a god ! " 
 
 — Young. 
 
 It is clear from all we have said that the genetic 
 definition of man may be the following: An indi- 
 viduality rr'^ulting from tivo substances, a body and a 
 rational soul. 
 
 We say genetic, because this definition gives the 
 genesis ..rcording to which man is formed, yet we 
 shall retain the more conmion definition, that of 
 rational animal. 
 
CHAPTER II. 
 
 ON Tim PRINCIPLES FROM WHICH THE NATURE OF MAN 
 RESULTS—SOUL AND BODY— AND, FIRST, OF THE SOUL. 
 
 ARTICLE FIRST. 
 
 The Sold is not a Material but a Simple Being, 
 
 Q. How shall vvc proceed in the knowledge of the 
 soul? 
 
 A. Havinij seen that there are two principles which 
 form man, and beginning to treat of the soul as the 
 principal part of man, we must remark that we are so 
 made by nature that, when we cannot perceive things 
 directly in themselves, we endeavor to become ac- 
 quainted with them by removing things from them 
 and by comparing them with other objects — that is to 
 say, by investigating which things agree with thosj 
 we want to know and which things do not. Now; it 
 is certain that the soul is in the body, and that it is 
 distinct from it, and yet we cannot perceive it directly 
 in itself and know that it is there, in consequence of 
 observing certain operations which the body could 
 not perform ; therefore the most natural method of 
 coming to the knowledge of the soul, as we cannot 
 perceive it in itself, is to remove from it certain things 
 which cannot possibly agree with its operations. 
 
 The first of these things which cannot agree with 
 the operations of the soul is mnleriality; hence we 
 must say that it is simple. 
 
 Q. What do you mean by material, simple, and 
 spiritual? 
 
 A. Material is that which is composed of parts 
 
 3sa 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 253 
 
 which are divisible, as bodies. Simple is that which 
 has no parts, and which is incapable of separation, 
 division, increase, or diminution. If a being not only 
 does not result from pc.rts, but is independent of the 
 body for its specific and distinctive operations, then 
 it is called spiritual. 
 
 Before proving that the soul is not material, we 
 must remark that although we have proved it to be 
 distinct from the body, yet this question must not be 
 confounded with the present, which enquires whether 
 this principle is of the same nature as the body, 
 since some philosophers have admitted that the soul, 
 though a distinct principle from the body, is yet 
 of the same nature as the body. Democritus and 
 Leucippus contended that it is a little globe of fire. 
 The Pythagoreans held that it is formed from atoms 
 floating in the air, and which, differently united, take 
 different shapes. The materialists are those who 
 maintain that the soul is composed of parts. 
 
 Q. Show the simplicity of the soul. 
 
 A. The soul perceives, judges, reasons, and has the 
 consciousness of itself and of its acts. But these 
 operations would be impossible if the soul were ma- 
 terial. 
 
 Therefore the soul is not material but simple. The 
 major is admitted by al! ; the minor must be proved. 
 And, first, the soul could not perceive if it were ma- 
 terial. Because all things which may be perceived 
 are either corporal or simple substances. But if the 
 soul were material it could perceive neither; tliere- 
 fore if the soul were material it could not perceive at 
 all. It could not perceive material substances ; be- 
 cause if it could perceive them, being itself material, 
 two suppositions could be made, either that each part 
 of the soul perceives each part of the object appre- 
 
254 Elements of In tellectua I Ph ilosophy. 
 
 hended, or that each part of the soul perceives it whole 
 and entire. If the first supposition is admitted we 
 could never have an entire perception of the object. 
 But we do have entire perceptions of objects ; there- 
 fore the first supposition is inadmissible. The second 
 supposition cannot be made, because in that case we 
 would have as many entire perceptions of the object 
 as there would be parts of the soul, the same as a 
 glass broken in a hundred fragments ; each fragment 
 represents the same object whole and entire. But 
 this is contrary to experience, as we are conscious 
 that we have only one entire perception of each object 
 we apprehend. Therefore, if the soul were material, 
 it could not perceive material substances. 
 
 It could not perceive simple substances, because a 
 material thing, being composed of parts, could not per- 
 ceive that which is indivisible, except the latter could 
 be cut up into parts. But this is impossible, as that 
 which is naturally indivisible cannot be divided with- 
 out changing its nature ; therefore, if the soul were 
 material, it could not apprehend simple substances. 
 
 2. If the soul were material it could not form judg- 
 ments. I. Because judgment is made up of percep- 
 tions and ideas. But we have shown that if the soul 
 were material it could not perceive at all ; therefore 
 it could not form judgments. 
 
 2. Judgment requires that two ideas, that of the 
 subject and the predicate, should be compared to- 
 gether, put face to face, to discover whether they 
 agree or disagree. 
 
 But this comparison would be impossible if the soul 
 were material. 
 
 Therefore, if the soul were material, it could not 
 judge. 
 
 The minor is proved from the principle that a com- 
 
Elements of Intellectual Ph ilosopliy. 255 
 
 parisoti between two thin^js cannot be made unless 
 both tilings exist simultaneously in the same subject, 
 else how could the subject compare the two together, 
 put them face to face, if both did not exist in it at the 
 same time ? But if the substance forming the subject 
 were material and composed of parts, the idea of the 
 subject and the predicate could not be found in the 
 same subject, but one part would perceive one term, 
 the other the second term. Therefore, if the soul 
 were material, it could not judge, 
 
 3. It could not reason, because in reasoning it is 
 necessary that the same subject which perceives the 
 premises should draw the conclusion. But the same 
 subject could not be had in a material substance, as 
 we have proved ; therefore, if the soul were material, it 
 could not reason. 
 
 4. It could not have consciousness of itself and its 
 acts, because consciousness is a reflex operation and 
 takes place when the soul turns in upon itself to in- 
 vestigate its own actions. But matter, which has one 
 part outside the other, could not return upon itself; 
 therefore, if the soul were material, it could not have 
 the consciousness of itself and its actions. 
 
 Second Dcuionstration. 
 
 If the soul were corporal, all its operations would 
 be so many movements, because all the operations of 
 bodies can be reduced to movement. But the ope- 
 rations of the soul cannot be explained by means of 
 movement ; therefore the soul is not material. 
 
 That the operations of the soul cannot be explained 
 by means of movement is clear: i. Because no body 
 by means of motion moves itself, but must be moved 
 by another ; but the soul moves and determines itself, 
 as we know by experience. 2. Because the acts of 
 
256 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy 
 
 thinking and of knowing arc immanent and terminate 
 in tile soul, whereas movement is a transient act, pass- 
 ing from one body into another ; therefore the act of 
 knowing is not movement. 
 
 3. The power of movement in material substances 
 becomes by use weaker and weaker until it ceases al- 
 together ; whereas the intellective faculties are per- 
 fected more and more by exercise. 
 
 " If rJie the body's nature did partake, 
 
 Her strength would with tlie body's strength decay; 
 But when the body's strong sinews shxke 
 The soul is most active, quick, and gay." 
 
 — Davies. 
 
 4. The soul can perceive contrary things at the same 
 time, so much so that by means of the knowledge of 
 one it comes to know the other. For instance, we ac- 
 quire the idea of eternity by the ideas of time and of 
 succession, the idea of the most perfect by that which 
 is imperfect, the idea of the absolute by the idea of 
 the contingent, etc. 
 
 Kut the same parts of the body cannot receive con- 
 trary movements ; therefore the operations of the soul 
 cannot be explained by movement. 
 
 Q. What answer would you give to a materialist 
 who should object to this doctrine thus : The soul is 
 in the body, but there can be nothing in the body ex- 
 cept a material thing ; therefore the soul is material ? 
 
 A. The soul is in the body as a body, each part of 
 which touches the corresponding parts of the body, 
 just as putting one hand against the other, or as fill- 
 ing a pitcher with water, we deny ; because if the 
 soul were in the body in this manner it would be ma* 
 teriafl. The soul is in the body inasmuch as it acts in 
 and upon it, we grant ; and this is the manner accord- 
 
Elements of Intellectual Ph ilosophy. 257 
 
 ing to which immaterial things are in space and 
 matter. 
 
 Second Objection. 
 
 The soul is subject to the same vicissitudes as the 
 body, and the faculty of intelligence is developed in 
 man according to the age, sex, temperament, and dis- 
 position of the individual; therefore it is clear that 
 the soul must be of the same nature as tlie body. 
 
 A. As we shall see by and by, in consequence of 
 the union between the body and the soul the hitter 
 must depend upon the body as the instrument which 
 furnishes the materials for its operations. Therefore. 
 it the body is tiny and weak, old and '"lulty, the 
 instrument also which furnishes the materials for the 
 soul's operation is tiny, weak, old, and faulty; and 
 hence the operations of tlie soul cannot be performed 
 at all, or performed imperfectly, not because the 
 soul is the same as the body or of the same nature, 
 but because the body in those conditions cannot fur- 
 nish the proi)er materials to the soul. Deprive 
 Raphael, for instance, of canvas and pencil and col- 
 ors, or give him the worst canvas and pencil and 
 colors you could find, and, no matter how granci 
 his conceptions might be in his mind, he cotdd 
 not carry them out or express them. Likewise, 
 great as the native power of intelligence may be, yet, 
 if to come from the power to the act, it needs ma- 
 terials administered to it by the body ; if the body is 
 in such a state as to be unable to furnish tiiose ma- 
 terials, the power will remain power and never come 
 to the act, not for want of native force (jr because it is 
 of a material nature, but because the material is want- 
 ing in conse([uence of the want in the instrument. 
 
258 Elcme7its of hitcllechial Philosophy. 
 
 "Tlicsc imperfections, then, we must impute 
 
 Not to the ajjent but to the instrument ; 
 Wc must not blame Apollo, but his lute, 
 
 If false accords Irom false strings be sent. 
 The soul in all hath one intelligence, 
 
 Though too much moisture in an infant's brain, 
 And too much dryness in an old man's sense, 
 
 Cannot the prints of outward thiii,ns retain. 
 Then doth the soul want work and idle sit : 
 
 And this wc childness and dotage call , 
 Yet hath she then a quiet and active wit, 
 
 If she had stulFand tools to work withal." 
 
 — Davies. 
 
 ARTICLE THIRD. 
 On the Spirituality of the Soul. 
 
 Q. If the soul is not material, can you say, r.t least, 
 that it depends on the body for its being and ts spe- 
 cific operations ? 
 
 A. No ; but we must hold that the human soul has 
 a subsistence of its own independent of the body, 
 and, therefore, is spiritual. Proof: 
 
 I. That which acts by itself subsists by itself. But 
 the soul has operations which it performs independent- 
 ly of the body — the operation of intelligence ; there- 
 fore the soul subsists by itself.. The minor is proven, 
 because, from the objects perceived, it is certain that 
 the soul can understand the nature of all bodies. But 
 if the soul were a body, and used bodily orphans, it 
 could not perform such operations ; therefore in 
 these operations the soul does not depend upon the 
 body. In fact, as St. Thomas remarks, that subject 
 which can know something must not contain in its 
 nature any element of those things it wants to know, 
 otherwise that element which would naturally be 
 found in it would hinder the knowledge of other 
 
 V 1 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 259 
 
 things, as we see in the tongues of sick people, covered 
 witli bitter coating: they cannot taste anything 
 sweet, but everything tastes bitter. If, therefore, the 
 intellectual principle had the nature of a body it could 
 not know the nature of all bodies. 
 
 Again, how can she several bodies know 
 
 If in herself a body's form she bear? 
 How can a mirror sundry faces show, 
 
 If from all shapes and forms it be not clear? 
 Nor could wc by our eyes all colors learn, 
 
 Except our eyes were of all colors void ; 
 Nor sundry tastes can any tongue discern 
 
 Which is with gross and bitter humors cloy'd." 
 
 — Davies. 
 
 2. If our souls were not independent of the body in 
 their operations tlicy could not have universal per- 
 ceptions. But they do have universal perceptions ; 
 therefore they do not depend upon the body for 
 their operations. The major is proven : That which 
 is received into any recipient must take the form of 
 the recipient. But matter is contracted and particu- 
 lar; therefore whatever is receivxid in it must take a 
 contracted and particular form. If, therefore, the 
 soul depended upon matter for its operation, all the 
 forms it could take would be contracted and particular. 
 
 3. The will has a tendency after intellectual and in- 
 corporeal good, and is not confined to this or that par- 
 ticular good, but is drawn towards good in general or 
 to whatever object in which it can see an element or 
 feature of goodness. But if the soul depended upon 
 the organs of the body for its operations, this would be 
 impossible, because bodily organs always tend toward 
 some individual object, and never toward general and 
 abstract objects ; therefore the soul is independent of 
 the bodily organs in its operations. 
 
26o Ele7iients of Intellectual Philosophy, 
 
 4. Wc oftentimes are conscious of a hard struggle 
 going on between the body i?.nd the soul, and observe 
 thdt when it wishes the soul can repress, and does in 
 fact repress, tlie movements of the body. Now, this 
 is a clear sign that the soul can act independently of 
 the body; therefore the soul is spiritual. 
 
 Q. What remarks are to be made upon what has 
 been said ? 
 
 A. I. That opinion of Locke, Hume, Condillac, 
 which holdj that a soul is not a substance by itself, 
 but an aggregate of modifications, is false ; because 
 we have proved that the soul is a substance, as it has a 
 subsistence of its own independent of the body. 
 
 2. That the opinion of Locke, who doubted whether 
 it would not be possible for matter to think, is absurd, 
 because to know and to understand is the act of an. 
 immaterial subject exclusively ; consequently, not even 
 God Almighty, as Locke thought, can cause matter to 
 think, because God cannot effect a contradiction. 
 
 3. The human soul has an existence independent 
 of the body; but it has also sensitive faculties. Now, 
 as these stand in nedd of the body to perform their 
 functions, it follows that the soul in man, inasmuch as 
 it is sensitive, is dependent upon the body in the 
 sense that it must be united to corporal organs and 
 stands in"need of them to experience sensibility. 
 
 "Mysterious thought, swift angel of the mind ! 
 By space unbounded, though to space coniin'd, 
 I low dost thou glow with just disdain, how scora • 
 That thought could ever think thee earthly born I 
 Thou who canst distance motion in thy flight, 
 Wing with aspiring plume the wondrous height, 
 Swifter than light outspeed the flame of day, 
 Pierce tlirough dark profound and shame the darting ray , 
 Throughout the universal systems range, 
 New form old systems, and new systems change ; 
 
Elements of Intellechial Pli ilosophy, 2 6 1 
 
 Through nature traffic on, from pole to pole, 
 And stamj) new worlds on thy dilated soul ; 
 (By time unlimited, unbounded by space,) 
 Sure demonstration of thy heavenly lacc ; 
 periv'd from that which is derived from none. 
 Which ever is but of Himself alone." 
 
 — Brooke, Universal Beatity, 
 
 ARTICLE TIIIKI). 
 
 Hoiv the Human Soul Originates. 
 
 Q. How docs man's soul originate ? 
 
 A. The soul being a spiritual substance, entirely 
 different from the body, we may ask, How does it ori- 
 ginate? Is it produced in the same manner as the 
 body, and by the same principles? 
 
 There have been several answers to this question. 
 Omitting that of the Emanatists, who held that the 
 soul emanated from the divine substance, as we shall 
 refute this opinion when speaking against pantheism, 
 we mention the opinion of the Traducians and that of 
 some Catholic philosophers. The Traducians main- 
 tained that the soul of a chihl is transmitted to him 
 from the body of the parents; and others, from the 
 soul. Rosmini holds that the soul of a child, inasmuch 
 as it is a sensitive substance, is transmitted by genera- 
 tion, and that it becomes afterward rational and intel- 
 lective by the apparition of the idea of being which 
 God exhibits before it. Now, all these opinions are 
 false. 
 
 The first is false because bodies cannot give that 
 which they have not — a thing transcending their na- 
 ture. But such would be the case if souls were trans- 
 mitted from the parents* bodies, because souls are 
 spiritual, the body is material. The body, therefore, 
 would give that which it has not — that which trans- 
 cends its own nature and power. It would produce 
 
262 Elements of Intellectual P/i ilosophy, 
 
 an c fleet mk- ' r i iM * to its cause ; therefore it is absurd to 
 hold that souls could be transmitted from the body. 
 
 The second opinion, which holds that souls are 
 transmitted from the parents' soul, is also false. 
 I. Because the parents' souls are spiritual ; but a i.pir- 
 itual substance cannot generate — that is, be divided 
 and corru[)ted — as it has no parts; therefore, etc. 
 
 2. If we do not admit that they are generated from 
 the parents' souls as parts detached from them, we 
 can make two suppositions: They must either be cre- 
 ated from nothing by the parents' soul (an opinion 
 which has been recently broached by Dr. Frohscam- 
 mer), or we must say that the soul of the parent must 
 draw them out from some existing matter. Hut nei- 
 ther supposition is possible. Not the first, because 
 creation from nothing belongs to God alone: 
 
 " For all (liiiifjcs made are cither made of naught 
 Or nade of stiifTthat ready-inaJc doth stand ; 
 Of i.;ui.;;ht nn crcr.furo ever forme 1 ai;;;ht, 
 For th.it is ijropcr to ihc Almighty hand." 
 
 The second suppc sition cannot be admitted, because 
 forms drawn out from matter are always depending 
 upon it and accidental, not self-subsisting, as the srul. 
 The opinion of Rosmini is also false, because, I. It 
 is impossible that the sensitive soul should be derived 
 from the parents' by way of generation. The nature 
 of the human soul is one intcHcctual, sensitive, and 
 vegetative. But it is proper to every being to be pro- 
 duced in the same manner as its being becomes it ; 
 therefore for one being it is becoming to be produced 
 by one agent, especially when this one being is simple 
 and cannot be divided into parts nor produced suc- 
 cessively — that is, first one part and then another; 
 therefore the same principle which produces the intel- 
 ligent must produce the sensitive and vegetative soul. 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy, 263 
 
 2. Eitlicr the sensitive soul, which becomes rational 
 by tlie apparition of bein^, is destroyed when it be- 
 comes rational or it is not destroyed. If it is de- 
 stroyed, then God creates a new soul ; if it is not 
 destroyed, then we may encpiire Mow is it that it be- 
 comes, alonjj with the rational soul, one simple and 
 spiritual being? Doer it change its essence? In 
 fact, it changes and it does not change its essence. It 
 changes, inasmuch as the sensitive soul in the suppo- 
 sition would have another essence and would belong 
 to another species ; it does not change it, inasmuch 
 as the sensitive soul would not be destroyed. In that 
 case it would and would not be. But this is a con- 
 tradiction ; therefore the opinion of Rosmini is false. 
 
 Having excluded all possible suppositions which 
 might be supposed to account for the origin of the 
 soul, we must conclude that it is created by God. 
 
 " Tlicn if her heavenly form do not agree 
 
 With ;iny matter which the world contains, 
 Then she of nothin^tj must created be ; 
 And 10 create to God alone pertains." 
 
 — Da.'IES. 
 
 Objection : If the parent were not the originator of 
 both body and soul, he could not be said to be the 
 father of the child, but only the father of the body of 
 the child. 
 
 In answering wc distinguish: If the soul wore not 
 united to the body at the moment of generation — a 
 union which causes the action of the father to ter- 
 minate in a human person — it is granted ; otherwise it 
 is denied. If the father generated the body of the 
 chilli first, and this existed by itself as a distinct indi- 
 viduality for some time, then the objection would 
 stand ; but the case is otherwise. At the same mo- 
 ment that the father generates, at that very same in- 
 
2 64 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy, 
 
 stant what is being generated is united substantially 
 to a si)iritual soul created by God, so that what the 
 father generates is not an individuality apart from 
 the soul, but is an individuality, because the soul 
 makes it subsist of its own subsistence. Therefore 
 Wvi objection does not stand, because the father's ac- 
 tion terminates in one individuality and personality 
 by the union with the soul, and therefore must he be 
 called the father of the child and not of his body. 
 
 ARTICLE FOURTH. 
 When docs the Soul Begin to be ? 
 
 Q. What arc the opinions of philosophers as to the 
 time when the soul takes its origin ? 
 
 A. Pythagoras and i^lato maintained that Immaa 
 souls, before they were united to a body, lived a bet- 
 ter life in the stars, and that they would be there still 
 were it not that some of them became guilty of a 
 grave crime, and were in consequence cast away from 
 heaven and condemned to be enclosed in the body as 
 in a dark dungeon, with the additional penalty of 
 losing all remembrance of their former state. 
 
 Leibnitz held that all the souls of men who were to 
 be born were created by God since the beginning of the 
 world and were ci. closed in so many tiny bodies, which 
 were the germs of their own bodies contained in 
 Adam, which germs, evolving in the course of time 
 and actpilring the proper size, constitute men's bodies. 
 
 Q. What are we to think of these opinions? 
 
 A. That both are false. As to the fust, it is evi- 
 dent that according to this opinion the union of the 
 soul and body would be against nature. Now, this 
 is false, because the union of the soul and body is 
 intended by nature as the object of generation. But 
 
Elements of Intcllcciiial Ph ilosophy. 265 
 
 what is intcncled as the object of a natural action can- 
 not be unnatural; therefore the union of the soul and 
 bodv nuist be natural. 
 
 2. It follows from this opinion that the union of 
 the soul and body is accidental ; but we have shown 
 that it is a substantial union. 
 
 3. As there are no proofs allejjed in confirmation of 
 this opinion as to the pre-existencc of soul, since, 
 according to these philosophers, Ave have lost all 
 memory of such a state, we have reason to reject it 
 as a fiction or dream. 
 
 Against the second opinion we observe : 
 
 1. The animal is said to be engendered when the 
 soul is united to the body, but, according to the 
 opinion of Leibnitz, this could not be in the case of 
 man, because the animal in his case would already 
 exist ; therefore in this case we cannot say that the 
 animal is generated. 
 
 2. The principle of sufTicient reason has a great 
 weight with Leibnitz, but no sufficient reason can be 
 produced why the soul of men should be created be- 
 fore man's generation — there is no sufficient reason 
 why the soul should exist without action for so long a 
 time; therefore the opinion of Leibnitz is false. 
 
 3. We observe also that it is a mere hypothesis, 
 without any foundation in reality. 
 
 Q. What is the true opinion? 
 
 A. That the soul is created by God at the moment 
 when the matter which is to form the body is fit to 
 receive it. IJut there are two opinions about this pre- 
 cise moment. Some, like the ancients, liave said that 
 that moment means when the body is fully organized, 
 which they suppose to be forty days after the concep- 
 tion for males and eighty days for females. 
 
 Others — and this opinion is held by all modern phy- 
 
266 Elements of Inkllectnal Philosophy, 
 
 sioloj^ists and metaphysicians — say that that moment 
 is when tlic germ administered by the female is fecun- 
 dated by the male. 
 
 The reasons for this opinion arc most convincing: 
 I. It is impossible that the matter administered by 
 the female and fecundated by the male could begin to 
 be organized without an interior living principle. 
 •* Opera enim vitai non possuntesse a principio extrin- 
 sic© sicut sentiri, nutriri et augeri " (St. Thomas, qu. 
 cxviii. art. 2). The acts of life, such as to feel, to be 
 nourished, and to grow, cannot originate in an extrinsic 
 principle. Therefore, in order to obtain the process 
 of organization, we may admit a twofold hypothesis, 
 either that the soul is there at the moment of the 
 conception to begin as the interior principle the pro- 
 cess of organization, or that another internal principle 
 effects this process and makes way for the soul when 
 the organization is completed. But the second hypo- 
 thesis is absurd ; therefore the soul is there at the 
 moment of the conception. 2. If the soul were united 
 to the body at any other moment than that of the fecun- 
 dation, then the parents could not be called the gene- 
 rators of a human person, but only of a body destined 
 to be united to a soul and to form a person after the 
 union, because it is evident that the generative action 
 of the parents would not terminate in a human person 
 so long as the soul is not there contemporaneously with 
 the action. Ikit this is against the common sense of 
 mankind, who feel and hold firmly that the parents of 
 a man are the parents of his personality and not of his 
 body only ; therefore, etc. 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 267 
 
 ARTICLE FIFTH. 
 On the Immortality of the Soul. 
 
 Q. What remarks ought to be made before proving 
 the immortality of the soul? 
 
 A. The following: i. That a living being which 
 has no end to its duration is called immortal^ and this 
 property immortality. 
 
 2. ImnMjrtality may become a living being either 
 essentially or naturally or by grace. It becomes es- 
 sentially only that being who exists by necessity of 
 his nature, and whose existence is identical with his 
 essence, so that his non-existence would be a contra- 
 diction. This being is God. It becomes naturally 
 that being which, though not existing by necessity 
 of nature, is yet so constituted that it cannot cease to 
 be except by annihilation effected by almighty power. 
 It becomes by grace that being which God by His 
 own grace maintains in existence, though naturally 
 prone to dissolution. 
 
 The second manner of immortality becomes the 
 soul. To demonstrate, therefore, the immortality of 
 the soul we have to show three things: i, that it is 
 naturally indestructible ; 2, that it continues to act 
 even after its separation from the body; 3, that it 
 cannot be annihilated by any external cause. 
 
 As to the first, a thing may be intrinsically de- 
 stroyed for two reasons — either because it is composed 
 of parts distinct from each other, which, once discon- 
 nected and separated, the thing perishes; or because, 
 though not composed of parts, it may depend like the 
 accident on something else, which being destroyed, 
 it is itsflf destroyed. 
 
 But the human r.oul is neither of these things* 
 therefore it is intrinsically indestructible. 
 
268 Elements of Intellectual 1 'hilosophy. 
 
 The minor has to prove that the human soul is not 
 composed of parts and'-that it is not an accident. 
 
 1. Tiuit which is simple is not composed of parts ; 
 but the soul is simple, therefore it is not composed of 
 parts. 
 
 2. That which subsists of itself is not an accident 
 dependent upon any other object in order to exist. 
 lUit the soul subsists in itself. 
 
 The jfore it is not an accident dependent upon the 
 body in order to exist. 
 
 As' to the second, that the soul separated from the 
 body continues to act : 
 
 Operation is the action of a substance. 
 
 But the soul is a substance, and continues to exist 
 after the body has been destroyed. 
 
 Therefore the soul, after the dissolution of the 
 body, continues to act. 
 
 But action follows the nature of a being.* 
 
 Therefore the soul continues the actions, after the 
 dissolution of the body, agreeably to its nature as a 
 rational substance, which are acts of intelligence and 
 will. 
 
 " But (as the body h'ving) wit and will 
 
 Can judge and choose without the body's aid, 
 
 Though on sucli objects they are working still 
 As through tlie body's organs are convey 'd, 
 
 So wlicn the body serves her turn no more. 
 And all her senses are extinct and gone, 
 
 She can discourse of what she learned before, 
 
 In heavenly contemplation all alone." 
 
 —Davif.s. 
 
 Thirdly, we have to prove that the soul is extrin- 
 sically immortal — that there is no exterior cause which 
 may destroy it. 
 
 • Oferaiio stquiiur «tse. 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy, 269 
 
 The extrinsical cause which might annihilate the 
 soul may be either a creature or God. 
 
 But the creature cannot, and God will not, annihi- 
 late the soul. 
 
 Therefore no exterior cause can destroy the soul. 
 
 The first part of the minor is clear. 
 . The destructive force of a creature is of a piece with 
 its productive force. 
 
 But the creature cannot produce anything out of 
 nothing; therefore it cannot reduce anything to no- 
 thing. 
 
 That God will not annihilate the soul is also evi- 
 dent ; for if we regard the power of God in itself, 
 without reference to His other attributes, God could 
 annihilate souls as well as other creatures, because a 
 finite being is in itself indifferent to be and not to be, 
 and that which fixes it in being is the creative act of 
 God, and it continues to exist as long as the creative 
 act continues to determine it to existence. If that 
 act were withdrawn the creature would immediately 
 cease to exist. 
 
 ]Jut looking at the power of God in relation to His 
 other attributes, we deny that He could annihilate the 
 soul. 
 
 Proof: To annihilate the soul would be contrary to 
 His providence, wisdom, goodness, and justice ; but 
 God cannot do anything contrary to these attributes, 
 therefore God cannot annihilate the soul. 
 
 Proofs of the major : i. It is contrary to providence 
 and wisdom. It behooves the providence and wisdom 
 of God not to destroy those natural qualities which He 
 Himself has given to beings, nor deprive essences of 
 those properties which become them. But immortal- 
 ity becomes the soul and all other spiritual substances ; 
 
2 yo Elements of Intellectual Ph ilosophy, 
 
 therefore to annihilate the soul would be against the 
 wisdom and providence of God. 
 
 It would be contrary to His goodness. 
 
 We have an imperative, ardent, continual desire 
 after happiness — a desire which cannot be said to be 
 found only in this or that man, at this or that time, 
 in this or that place, but is found in all men, at 
 all times, and in all places. This desire, therefore, 
 being so universal in time and space, must be said to 
 have been implanted in man's nature by the Creator's 
 hand, because whatever is universal in all times and 
 places is natural and must come from nature's Author. 
 
 But this craving after happiness could not be satis- 
 fied without the soul's immortality ; it behooves, 
 therefore, God's goodness to keep the soul immortal. 
 
 That the craving after happiness could not be satis- 
 fied without immortality is proved from two reasons : 
 I. Because happiness is the perfect fulness of inter- 
 minable life, and if one could entertain the thought 
 for a moment that this .ulncss of life could after cer- 
 tain time cease even for a day, the joy resulting from 
 that exuberant overflow and fulness of life would be 
 marred and be overcome by the unutterable pain of 
 having to lose it, and thus it would cease to be hap- 
 piness. 
 
 2. We have an imperative, insatiable craving after 
 truth and perfection. 
 
 " Dive into the l)ottom of the soul, the base 
 
 Sustaining all ; what find wc ? Knowledge and love. 
 
 As light and heat essential to the sun, 
 
 These to the soul ; and why, if souls expire ? " 
 
 —Young. 
 
 But if the soul is not immortal this craving could 
 not be satisfied, as nothing in this world can appease 
 
Ele7Hen(s of hitellcctual Ph ilosophy. 271 
 
 it. One thing can fill up that void, and one thing 
 only: it is the contemplation of infinite truth, of im- 
 mense beauty, and the possession of infinite and most 
 enticing loveliness — that is, the vision and the posses- 
 sion of God. 
 
 " How littio lovely here ! IIow little known ! 
 JSinall knowledge we tlig up with endless toil, 
 And love unfeigned may purchase perieci hate ; 
 Why starved on eariii our angel appetites 
 While brutal are indulged their fulsome fill ? 
 Were their capacities divine conferred, 
 As mock diadem in savage sport? 
 Rank insult of our pompous /^^rr;//, 
 Which reaps but pain fioin set ming claims so fair? 
 In future ages lies no redress ? And shuts 
 Eternity tiie door on our complaint ? 
 This cannot be. To love and kno-u> in man 
 Is boundless appetite and boundless power, 
 And these demonsiiate boundless powers, too. 
 Objects, power, appetites— Heaven suits all." 
 
 — Young. 
 
 It is contrary to justice. 
 
 It IS an established fact that on earth there are 
 good and wicked men ; it is also certain that Divine 
 justice must give a fitting reward to virtue and due 
 punishment to vice. But we do not observe this just 
 and equitable distribution of rewards and punish- 
 me:its, because too often we see the wicked prosper and 
 enjoy the fruits of their iniquities, whilst frequently 
 we see the just oppressed and down-trodden by the 
 wicked. There must be, therefore, another life after 
 the body is dissolved, where the accounts will be 
 balanced, where the rewards and punishments will be 
 distributed equitably according to the good and t*vil 
 which men have done. But if the sotd were not im- 
 mortal this future life would be impossible; there- 
 fore it behooves tlie justice of God to keep the soul 
 immortal. 
 
272 Elements of Intellectual Ph ilosophy. 
 
 It will not do to say that a fitting reward of the just 
 is the peace and tranquillity of conscience and the 
 satisfaction and pleasure which accompany the doing 
 of good, and, on the contniry, that the fitting punish- 
 ment of vice is the remruse of conscience wliich follows 
 crime; because this reward and punishment would be 
 reduced to very small proportions. IJesidcs, we know 
 by cxpcrienro that the more the wicked man plunges 
 into vice the less lie feels the pangs of conscience, and 
 we know also that it is not always true that the just 
 feels peace and tranquillity; he is too often agitated 
 by doubts, perplexities, and scruples suggested to his 
 n^ind by his over-delicate conscience, and is tossed to 
 and fro by a variety of conflicting emotions, so as to 
 feel very little peace. In this case Avhere would his 
 reward be? And when the just has to suffer death 
 for the sake of his principles, what would then be his 
 reward ? It is clear, therefore, that the pleasure of 
 doing good is not a fitting reward of virtue, nor the 
 remorse of conscience a proportionate doom for vice. 
 
 " The soul, of origin divine, 
 
 God's glorious image freed from clay, 
 In heaven's eternal sphere shall shine, 
 A star of day. 
 
 " The sun is but a spark of fire, 
 A transient meteor in the sky ; 
 The soul, immortal as its sire, 
 Shall never die." 
 
 — MoNTnOMRRY. 
 
 Q. Give the definition of the soul. 
 
 A. We may define the soul in general to be that first 
 principle of life in those things which by experience we 
 know to be living. To illustrate this definition we must 
 remark first that of bodies some are living and some 
 are not living. Those are called living which move 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 273 
 
 themselves in force of an interior princii)lc ; not living 
 are those whicii are moved by an exterior principle. 
 Now, this principle of life interior to livin,c; bod'cs is 
 calleil by a general name, soul. Jiut not every princi- 
 ple of life may b< called soul, because, thou<jh some 
 other part of tlie body may be a [jrinciple of life, such 
 as the heart in nvm, yet that part would not be called 
 soul. The soul must be the first i)rinciple of life. We 
 have said, finally, in those tliiiii^s lohicli we know by ex- 
 perience to live^ because (lod also lives ; spiritual sub- 
 stances entirely separated from matter live, yet they 
 arc not called souls, because we do not know them 
 by experience. From the definition of soul in 
 general we may frame the definition of the human 
 soul. If the soul be the first principle of life, it is 
 clear that this life is different in different animals in 
 proportion as life is manifested in them. IJut in 
 man all kinds of life arc manifested, vegetative, sen- 
 sitive, and intellectual ; therefore the human soul 
 must be the principle of these three kinds of life, and 
 may be defined that first principle by ivhieJi man vege- 
 tates, feels, and reasons. Or it maybe defined in the 
 words of St. Augustine, which amount to the same: 
 " A certain substance endowed with reason and fit to 
 govern a body." * It is called substance to show that 
 it is not an aggregate of qualities or modifications; 
 endowed with reason, by whicli it is to he understood 
 that it is simple, spiritual, ingenerable, incorruptible, 
 and immortal ; fit to govern a body, because the 
 human soul is destined to form a whole with the body 
 which it animates. 
 
 * " Sulmtantia quxdnm ratinnif particeps rcgcndo corpori accommoda.a." — Dt 
 Quantilalt Animct, q\\, iii, n. 22. 
 
CHAPTER III. 
 
 OF I IJI-: HUMAN noDY. 
 
 Q. How must \vc> treat of the body in i)hiIosopliy? 
 
 A. Various sciences treat of tlje liunian botly, sucli 
 as analouiy, pliysioioi^y, etc. ; but in philosoijliy \vc 
 must treat of the human body in rehition to that 
 wiiich is first and sujireme in it, because philosophy 
 treats of things accordin;^ to their supreme causes. 
 Now, tiiat which is sui)reme in tiie body is its relation 
 to the soul witii whicli it is united and which it serves; 
 lience wc shall say a few tlun^^s respcctinij this rela- 
 tion and aptitude. i. I'lic liuinan body is the most per- 
 fect of all liviiii^ bodies in couseqiience of tins relation to 
 the soul. \\\ the univi-rse there is a woiuhrrful con- 
 nection nmotif^ bei»v.js. We find always that that whicli 
 is the least and most inferior element of a supreme 
 j^enus touches the boundaries of that whicli is the su- 
 preme part of an inferior '^<rnus. This is clearly seen in 
 the ^^cnus animal. The least of this f^enus, likcr the 
 moUusks, which liave barely the sense of touch and are 
 affixed to the earth like plants, touch the cf)nfines of 
 the supreme one of the inferior ^enus, livinij^ or plant, 
 such as the polypsjs and the corals. Accordiii'^ to this 
 theory, therefore, we must admit, in the pjenus of cor- 
 poral thin<4s, bodies snp(;rior to all others and more 
 noble, such as touch on the boundaries of the least 
 amonjf spiritual things, and that is the human body; 
 therefore the human body is the most perfect and 
 noble of all living bodies. 
 
 '74 
 
Elements of Intellectual Pk ilosophy. 275 
 
 •' Look nature tliroii;(h ; 'lis neat gradation all. 
 Hy wliat iiiinuti; d(Krci;s her scale ascends! 
 Kacli middle naiure joined at each exirouie, 
 'i'u that alcove joined, to tliat beneath : 
 Parts into parts reciprcically siiot 
 Abhor divorce ; wiiat love of union rcijjns I 
 Here dormant matter waits u call to life ; 
 Half life, half death, joined there. I!er«: life and sense ; 
 'Iherc sense frum reason steals a giitnmerinK rn) • 
 Reason shines in man." 
 
 — YouNd. 
 
 Q. In wliat (Iocs this perfection consist ? 
 
 A. In the j^reatest possible variety of or^^ans. Be- 
 cause the body is made for the soul. Now, the soul 
 stands in need of the body for this reason, tlfat, not 
 possessinp^ truth in itself, it must acquire it from sensi- 
 ble objects; hence the necessity of the senses and of 
 the faculty of feeling. But the operation of fcelinj^ 
 cannot be performed without corporal organs; hence 
 the need of corporal organs ; and as the faculty of 
 feelinj^ is manifold, various, therefore must be the 
 orfjans (jf feeling. Hut all these or^^-lns nmst be sub- 
 ject to ii j,'eneral organ mf)st excpn'sitely made, in 
 order that it: may feel • ""erent and contrary sensa- 
 tions and brine; them to .nity. This common and 
 general sense is the touch. Of these senses, and espe- 
 cially of the touch, we shall speak in the second part of 
 Anthropology. Wc conclude for the present that the 
 human body is sitperior to all living bodies, because 
 no other can feel so exquisitely and so delicately as 
 the human body, and because of the variety of its 
 organs, superior in their nature, structure, uses, and 
 functions to those of all other living bodies. 
 
• -:.)'- CHAPTER IV. .^' 
 
 OF r/r^ MANNER ACCORDING TO WHICH THE SOUL AND 
 THE BODY ARE UNITED TOGETHER AND CONSPIRE TO 
 FORM MAN. ,,,.... 
 
 ARTICLE FIRST. 
 
 Ufiion of the Body and Soul as to Being — Seat of the 
 
 Soul. . , ■ 
 
 Q. Under how many aspects may we consider the 
 union of the soul and the body? ' '■■■' ""': 
 
 A. Under two aspects: the soul is united to the 
 body as to being and as to action. As to being, we 
 have seen that both soul and body form one complete 
 substance, that both substances, the body and the 
 soul, meet together in one single subsistence — that 
 of the soul — so that the soul causes the body to have 
 actual reality and existence. Hence the soul has 
 been called the living and substantial form, or the 
 actuality of the body. Of this we have spoken before, 
 but closely connected with the present topic is the 
 question of the seat of the soul. Since the soul is the 
 living form of the body, it must be somewhere in the 
 body. But where? Philosophers have answered this 
 question in different ways. Descartes held that the 
 seat of the soul was in the pineal gland, whence, as 
 upon a throne, it gives direction and movement to the 
 whole machine. A poet has wittily expressed this 
 opinion as follows : 
 
 ** Alma, they strenuously maintain, 
 
 Sits cock-horse on her throne, the brain, 
 376 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 277 
 
 (T 
 
 And from that seat of thought dispenses ''; ' 
 
 Her sovereign pleasure to the senses. 
 
 Two optic nerves they say she ties 
 
 Like spectacles across the eyes, 
 
 By which the spirits bring her word 
 
 Whene'er the balls are fixed or stirred. . . 
 
 Wise nature likewise, they suppose, 
 
 Has drawn two conduits down our nose ; 
 
 Could Alma else with judgment tell 
 
 When cabbage stinks or roses smell? 
 
 By nerves about our palate placed 
 
 She likewise judges of the taste ; 
 
 Else (dismal thought !) our warlike men 
 
 Might drink thick port for fine champagne. 
 
 Hence, too, that she might better hear, 
 
 She sets a drum at either ear, 
 
 And loud or gentle, harsh or sweet, 
 
 Are but th' a/a;-?/;;/j which they beat. ' 
 
 Last, to enjoy her sense of feeling 
 
 (A thing she most delights to deal in), 
 
 A thousand little nerves she sends 
 
 Quite to our toes and fingers' ends ; 
 
 And these in gratitude again 
 
 Return their spirits to the brain, 
 
 In which their figure being printed 
 
 (As just before I think I hinted). 
 
 Alma informed can try the case, ' 
 
 As she had been upon the place." 
 
 — Prior, Alma, 
 
 Others maintain that the soul is in tlie heart, and 
 others in some other part of the body. 
 
 Now, all these opinions which locate the soul in a 
 particular part of the body are necessarily false, be- 
 cause you can locate, enclose, surround, circumscribe, 
 bound off only that which is extended, as that which 
 is extended, having parts, can be surrounded by cor- 
 responding parts of another body. That which is , 
 simple cannot be surrounded, not having parts which 
 can be circumscribed by parts of a body. Hence 
 those who locate the soul in a particular part of the 
 
278 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy, 
 
 body and enclose it therein have been rightly accused 
 of making the soul material. ^ ■■, ■-:'.■'■■'■ :, , 
 
 The true opinion is that the soul is whole and en- 
 tire in the whole body, and whole and entire in each 
 part of the body. This doctrine of the Christian 
 schools of the Middle Ages has been cried down by 
 modern wiseacres ; but reason is on the side of the 
 Christian schools. In order to illustrate and prove 
 the scholastic doctrine we must recall a few princi- 
 ples: 
 
 1. That the soul is simple and cannot be divided 
 into parts. 
 
 2. That simple things abide in a place not by con- 
 tact of extension but contact of action.* We say 
 that a thing is in space by contact of extension when 
 the parts of this thing are located in, and put in jux- 
 taposition with, the corresponding part of space. If I 
 lay a book on the table, the different parts forming 
 the extension of the book touch the corresponding 
 parts of the table. The book, therefore, is on the 
 table by contact of extension. Now, when a thing 
 is simple and has no parts, it is evident that it can- 
 not be in a place by contact of extension, when this 
 very extension is wanting to it ; it can only be in a 
 place by acting upon or in it. Having recalled these 
 principles, it is easy to demonstrate our thesis. 
 
 1. Incorporal things are said to be in space not by 
 contact of extension but by contact of action. But 
 the soul acts in the whole body ; therefore the soul is 
 in the whole body. v' , .^ . 
 
 2. The soul is the substantial form of the body, in- 
 asmuch as it makes it real and living ; therefore the 
 soul is in the whole body. 
 
 'I' " Incorporalia non sunt in loco per contactum quantitatis, sed per contactum vir^ 
 tutis."— St. Thomas. 
 
Elements of Intellectual Phibsophy. 2 79 
 
 3. Demonstration that the soul is whole and entire 
 in each part of the body. 
 
 The soul acts not only in the whole body but also 
 in each part of the body. Now, if it were not whole 
 and entire in each part of the body, it would have to 
 divide itself and be part in one part of the body and 
 part in another. But this is impossible, because the 
 soul is simple ; therefore the soul is whole and entire 
 in each part of the body. ' ■ '" 
 
 Q. Please to illustrate this point by analogy. 
 
 A. Great opposition has been raised against this 
 doctrine because persons want to see this truth by 
 imagination ; by figuring to themselves how can it be 
 that a being is whole and entire in the whole and in 
 each part of the body, forgetting that we cannot form 
 any sensible image of a spiritual fact. Yet, to en- 
 able the student to perceive this truth, we shall make 
 use of some comparisons. Take, for instance, light. 
 Light, apparently, is in the air in the same manner 
 as the soul is in the body. First, it penetrites the 
 whole air through and impregnates it with its beams; 
 secondly, it seems to be whole and entire in each par- 
 ticle of air. This is gathered from two facts : first, 
 when air is divided light remains whole and entire, aS 
 in each particle of air the same amount of light is 
 seen ; secondly, when air becomes foul and corrupted 
 light continues always pure. 
 
 " But as the fair and cheerful morning light 
 
 Doth here and there her silver beams impart, 
 And in an instant doth herself unite f ?>;;,- t 
 
 To the transparent air in all and every part — 
 Still resting whole when blows the air divide, 
 
 Abiding pure when th' air is most corrupted ; 
 Throughout the air her beams dispersing wide, 
 
 And when the air is tossed not interrupted — 
 
 .-(■.. 
 
2 8o Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 > So doth the piercing soul the body fill, 
 
 Being all in all, and all in part diifus'd ; 
 Indivisible, incorruptible still, 
 Nor forc'd, encounter'd, troubled, or confused." 
 
 — Davies. 
 
 Take another instance. An orator is speaking be- 
 fore a large audience ; he develops his subject with 
 the greatest force and earnestness, and his audience 
 are enlightened and carried away with enthusiasm. His 
 voice, which is but a sound, is divided, each one of the 
 audience receiving more or less ; those who are nearest 
 to the orator receiving a stronger sound, those furi:hest 
 from him the least sound — each, in one word, receiving 
 a varied quantity of sound. But thought is indivisible, 
 and each one of the hearers receives it whole and 
 entire, all equally, those who sit near as well as those 
 who are afar. Because thought — that is, that which is 
 spiritual — is indivisible ; wherever it penetrates it must 
 penetrate whole and entire ; wherever a spirit exists it 
 must exist whole and entire. It is the same of the soul, 
 which is a spirit. It communicates itself to all the 
 parts of the. body, it lives in each of them, and 
 wherever it is it must be whole and entire. .; o,i 
 
 Take another example. My mind develops a 
 thought, and after this one another thought, and then 
 another, and so on, a great number of thoughts follow- 
 ing one another, agreeing with one another or clashing 
 with one another. In each of these thoughts, in each 
 of these intellecLual acts, my rr'iid is whole and 
 entire; and yet it differs in each one of them, being 
 sometimes right, sometimes wrong, sometimes false, 
 other times true; in other words, my intelligence 
 manifests itself in different ways, though it is whole 
 and entire in each. Now, the same must be said of the 
 soul. It acts in one way in one organ, and in another 
 
Elements of Intellectual Pk ilosophy. 2 8 1 
 
 organ in another way, but in every act and in every 
 mode of acting it is itself which acts, and itself whole 
 and entire ; it is its activity which appears in all these 
 
 different modes. 
 
 ■ '.'.■•'..' 
 
 >. -.' ' ' ARTICLE SECOND. . , , , 
 
 Of the Union of the Soul and Body as to Action. 
 
 Q. Is there a union of the body and soul as to 
 action ? .... ,^ ., ., ; , 
 
 A. That there should be a union and a mutual cor- 
 respondence of action between two beings, one of 
 which subsists on the subsistence of the other, is evi- 
 dent from reason and is confirmed by experience. 
 For we know by experience that, given certain 
 thoughts and feelings of the soul, certain correspond- 
 ing movements result in the body; and, vice versdy 
 given a certain state of the body, a corresponding state 
 manifests itself in the soul. This mutual correspon- 
 dence between the soul and the body as to their 
 action has been called communication or commercium. 
 
 Q. How *j this communication between the soul 
 and the body explained? 
 
 A. Various systems have been invented to explain 
 this mutual influence of the soul over the body, and 
 vice versd, but they may be reduced to five : occa- 
 sionalism^ pre-established harmony, plastic mediator ship, 
 physical influx, and substantial union. '■■' -i ::-. 
 
 Q. Explain and give your opinion of the first system. 
 
 A. It was taught by Malebranche, who started from 
 a principle of his own, that in the universe there are 
 no efficient causes and that God alone does every- 
 thing. From this principle he concluded that neither 
 the soul can really act upon the body nor the latter 
 on the soul, as neither of them can be real agents. 
 
282 Elements of Intellectual Ph ilosophy. 
 
 Against this doctrine the opponents of Malebranche 
 said : If what you say is true, if God alone acts in 
 every being, and consequently neither the soul can 
 act upon the body nor the body upon the soul, how 
 do you explain that harmony and correspondence 
 which exists between the soul and the body ? — for when 
 certain thoughts and feelings arise in the soul, a cor- 
 responding movement succeeds in the body, and vice 
 versd. Suppose a man has received an insult, which 
 just at this moment has come to his knowledge, and 
 which has put his soul in a fierce rage ; do we not see 
 corresponding movements in the body, the eye shoot- 
 ing fire, the face becoming first blanched and then 
 crimson, the lips compressed, the. hand clenched, and 
 the utterance interrupted? How do you explain this? 
 How do I explain it ? says our philosopher. Nothing 
 easier. I have said that God is the sole agent, and I 
 cling to that, and explain that correspondence of 
 thoughts and movements by saying that God takes 
 occasion from that modification of the soul to ex- 
 cite a corresponding movement in the body. Hence 
 the thoughts and feelings of the soul are mere occa- 
 sions which God takes to act upon the body, and vice 
 versd. This system is therefore called occasionalism^ 
 or the system of occasional causes. : ?.,, 
 
 Now, we may remark upon this system : i. That it 
 is founded on the assumption that there can be no real 
 efficient causes in the universe besides God, from 
 which principle Malebranche deduces that whatever 
 happens either in the soul or in the body must be 
 effected by God. But we have shown in Ontology 
 that this principle is false. Therefore the system 
 raised upon it is false. 
 
 2. This system destroys the substantial union be- 
 tween the soul and the body. Because what kind of 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 283 
 
 union can there exist between two machines, if the en- 
 gineer alone is the agent who produces similar move- 
 ments in both independently of either, and without 
 the least communication between them ? 
 
 Q. Explain the second system. 
 
 A. Leibnitz admitted that finite beings can be real 
 agents, but denied that the action can pass from one to 
 another, and therefore arrived by another road at the 
 same conclusion as Malebranche. The latter denied 
 that the soul and the body could act upon each other, 
 on the principle that they are not real agents. Leib- 
 nitz denied that they can act upon each other, be- 
 cause the action of one cannot pass over to the other. 
 Hence the same objection was made against Leibnitz: 
 How do you account for the harmony between the 
 actions of the soul and the movements of the body, 
 and vice versd ? How do I account for it ? Thus : 
 All you have to do is to suppose that each being of 
 the universe is a simple substance called a ino?iad, and 
 that each of these monads is a representative force and 
 can represent all that which happens in the universe; 
 that God has established among all these monads a 
 parallelism of perceptions, of wishes, of actions, and 
 motions in such a manner that without communicating 
 anything to each other they all move in a most per- 
 fect harmony, each one representing what the other 
 does and suffers. So that in our case, the soul being a 
 representative force, and the body being also a repre- 
 sentative force, God has established such a parallel- 
 ism between them that in proportion as perceptions, 
 wishes, and actions are developed in the soul they 
 are immediately represented by corresponding move- 
 ments in the body, and vice versu. This system is 
 called pre-established harmony. #*;n^t^r .e/jn / -^ 
 
 Now, we observe that this system, though eminently 
 
284 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 ingenious, is false for the following reasons: i. Be- 
 cause it is founded on the principle that transient 
 actions are impossible. For this is the fundamental 
 principle of the whole system of Leibnitz : as the 
 action of one agent cannot be communicated to an- 
 other, it follows that the interchange of modifications 
 between the body and the soul are effected by a pre- 
 established harmony of affections and movements. 
 Now, we have shown this principle to be false ; false, 
 therefore, is the system which rests upon it. 
 
 2. This system destroys altogether the substantial 
 union which we have proved to exist between the 
 body and the soul. But this substantial union is ad- 
 mitted even by Leibnitz ; therefore his system is false. 
 That Leibnitz admits a substantial union between the 
 body and the soul is evident from these words of his 
 Theodicea : "There exists between the soul and the 
 body a true union, from which results the suppositum." 
 On the other hand, there can be no doubt that the 
 system of Leibnitz destroys the substantial union be- 
 tween the body and the soul. Because whence would 
 this union result, if the soul cannot act upon the body, 
 nor the body upon the soul ? Nay, instead of finding 
 any substantial union between the soul and the body 
 in the system we are refuting, we could not even dis- 
 cover between these two terms a collective union 
 such as would exist between the different parts of 
 a machine. The system of Leibnitz, therefore, is 
 false. 
 
 Finally, in this system and in the other God would 
 be the author of all the errors, crimes, and disorders 
 which occur and are perpetrated among men. 
 
 Q. What is the third system ? 
 
 A. To obviate the difficulties which are brought 
 forward against occasionalism and pre-established bar- 
 
Elemejtts of Intelledua I Ph ilosophy. 285 
 
 mony, John Clerc hit upon a new expedient : You 
 say the body cannot act upon the soul ; I grant that. 
 You insist that the soul cannot have any influence 
 upon the body; I admit that also. Therefore to 
 render possible this apparent mutual communication 
 and interchange of actions between the soul and the 
 body, all you have to do is to suppose a third sub- 
 stance intermediate between the soul and the body. 
 The soul gives its commands to this intermediate 
 substance, and this transmits them to the body ; the 
 body communicates its sensations to this medium, and 
 it humbly transfers them to the soul. This interme- 
 diate substance between the soul and the body was 
 called the plastic mediator, 
 
 Q. What do you think of this system ? 
 
 A. That it is even more absurd than the two former 
 ones. I. What is this third substance ? Is it a spirit 
 or a body? If it be said that it is neither the one nor 
 the other, but something partaking of both natures — 
 something between the spiritual and the corporal — we 
 say that such a thing is a contradiction. 
 
 2, This system destroys also the substantial union 
 between the body and the soul ; for in what does this 
 union consist ? It does not consist in two things 
 being brought together by means of a third, but its 
 nature lies exactly in the fact that two substances 
 meet together directly, touching each other, so to 
 speak, by means of the subsistence of one of those 
 substances. Now, if we explained the communication 
 of the body and the soul by means of a third sub- 
 stance, partaking of the nature of both, we should 
 have to suppose that the body and soul do not meet 
 directly together, that the two substances do not 
 touch each other; therefore, by admitting a plastic 
 mediator to explain the communication between the 
 
286 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 soul and the body, we would destroy their substantial 
 union. 
 
 Q. What is the next system ? 
 
 A. Physical influx, invented by Eulerus and held 
 by all the followers of Locke. This system explains 
 the union between the soul and the body by means of 
 the mutual action of one upon the other. The body 
 incites and induces the soul to choose those percep- 
 tions and those acts which correspond to its organic 
 movements, and on the other hand the soul moves and 
 induces the body to make such movements as are 
 agreeable and befitting to the soul's perceptions and 
 acts. In this real and mutual influence of the soul 
 upon the body, and of the body upon the soul, lie 
 the union and communication between the two; hence 
 the system is called //y/j/c^/ iVi/?^^. 
 
 Q. What do you think of such a system ? 
 
 A. Though this system avoids the error of Male- 
 branche that there are no efficient causes besides God, 
 and that of Leibnitz that an action cannot pass from 
 an agent to an object acted upon, and though it rejects 
 the plastic mediator, yet we cannot admit it for the 
 following reasons : 
 
 I. Because it destroys the substantial union be- 
 tween the soul and the body. For, according to this 
 system, the union between the soul and the body is 
 explained as follows : the body acts upon the soul and 
 incites it to have perceptions and to elicit acts, and 
 the soul, in its turn, incites the body to movement ; 
 therefore in this system the body and the soul are 
 two separate beings, and do not form one complete 
 substance, but are two complete substances accident- 
 ally united in order that one may act upon the other. 
 But this implies that there is no substantial union be- 
 tween the soul and the body ; therefore this system 
 
Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 287 
 
 destroys the substantial union between the soul and 
 the body. 
 
 2. In this system it is said that the body acts upon 
 the soul. Then it acts without the soul ; because how 
 could it otherwise be said that it acts upon the soul? 
 But if it acts without the soul, then what gives it 
 movement, since no body can produce movement ex- 
 cept it be moved by some other agent ? Therefore 
 this system leads to absurdities. 
 
 In one word, in the examination of all these sys- 
 tems we ought to keep carefully in view the theories 
 already established. Man's nature results from the 
 substantial union between the body and the soul. If 
 we deny this union, or do not carefully describe its 
 exact nature, we destroy man's nature and necessarily 
 fall into absurdities. Now, in all the aforesaid systems 
 we fail to observe that this substantial union between 
 the soul and the body is maintained. Therefore they 
 destroy man's nature and lead to many errors. 
 
 Q. What is the true system about the union be- 
 tween the soul and the body? 
 
 A. The system of the schoolmen, which may be 
 formulated in a few words, as follows: If the soul be 
 the subsisting principle of the body, as we have de- 
 monstrated, or, in other words, if the soul be the 
 living, substantial form of the body, it follows that 
 the soul must necessarily act upon the body, and that 
 the movements of the body should be felt in the 
 soul. 
 
 We prove this system as follows : 
 
 The operation of anything emanates from its sub- 
 sistence. But the body receives its subsistence from 
 the soul ; therefore it must receive from the soul the 
 power of acting. Now, if the soul be the principle 
 from which the body derives the power of acting, it 
 
288 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy. 
 
 is necessary also that the soul, along with the body, 
 should be the subject of those powers by means of 
 which the body acts. And if not the body alone, but 
 the whole composite — that is, the body and the soul — 
 is the subject of all the bodily powers, it follows 
 necessarily that not only the soul should be able to 
 incite the members of the body to operation, but also 
 that the operations of the body should be felt in the 
 soul. 
 
 For the sake of clearness we shall put the same 
 argument in another form. We have proved that the 
 body subsists on the subsistence of the soul. Now, 
 what does this imply ? Does it imply that the body 
 has no radical power to act without the soul ? Cer- 
 tainly not ; the body is a substance, and, as such, has 
 a natural radical power of acting. But, admitting this 
 radical natural power of acting, does it follow that 
 the body can actually and really act without the soul? 
 Certainly not ; because actiones sunt siippositorwn. 
 Action implies subsistence, which is that last comple- 
 ment of a being which causes it to be distinct from 
 others, independent of and incommunicable to others. 
 Without that a substance is an abstract thing and 
 not a reality — a potentiality, but not an actual exist- 
 ence. Now, the body has no subsistence of its own, 
 but subsists on the subsistence of the soul ; therefore 
 it really receives the power of acting from the soul. 
 The soul, then, is the principle from which the body 
 derives the power to act. Now, the consequence which 
 results from this truth is that the soul, along with the 
 body, must be the subject of those powers by means 
 of which the body acts, because originally the power 
 emanates from the soul ; those powers, therefore, by 
 which the body acts must be in both. But if the 
 whole composite — that is, the body and the soul — is 
 
EUments of Intellectual Philosophy. 289 
 
 the subject of those powers by which the body acts, 
 who can fail to see the consequence that not only the 
 soul must be able to move the body to act, but that 
 the movements of the body should be felt in the soul ? 
 In one word, the body subsists on the subsistence of 
 the soul ; therefore it receives the power to act from 
 the soul. If this power of the body is received from 
 the soul, it follows that it must be found in both con- 
 jointly, and that, consequently, not only the soul 
 must be able to move the body, but it must feel 
 somewhat the movements of the body. 
 
 Q. Give a resume of all we have said in this first 
 part of Anthropology. 
 
 A. We have treated of man's nature, and to treat 
 of it accurately we have considered it first in general, 
 and then we have distinguished those elements from 
 which it results — soul and body ; then we have con- 
 sidered each element in particular ; and, finally, we 
 have investigated the manner in which these elements 
 are united together. In other words : Two things are 
 necessary to constitute man — i, body and soul; 2, a 
 substantial union between the two; therefore, to 
 speak of man properly, it was necessary to consider 
 two things— his body and soul, and the substantial 
 union of both. This we have done in two ways, first 
 in general, and then in particular. And with this we 
 end the first part of Anthropology. 
 
 " O ignorant man ! what dost thou bear 
 
 Lock'd up within the casket of thy breast? 
 What jewels and what riches hast thou there, 
 
 What heavenly treasures in so weak a chest? 
 Look in thy soul, and thou shalt benuties find 
 
 Like those which drown'd Narcissus in the flood : 
 Honor and pleasure both are in the mind, 
 
 And all that in the world i? counted good. 
 
290 Elements of Intellectual Philosophy, 
 
 Think of her worth, and think that God did mean 
 
 This worthy mind should worthy things embrace. 
 Blot not her beauties with thy thoughts unclean, 
 
 Nor her dishonor with thy passions base. 
 And when thou thinkest of her eternity, 
 
 Think not that death against her nature is, 
 Think it a birth ; and, when thou go'st to die. 
 
 Sing like a man as if thou went'st to bliss." 
 
 —Davies., 
 
Jt