TO MY FAITHFUL FRIEND OF TWENTY YEARS Joljit (Srafjam Brooks PREFACE. In a time of social unrest and uncertainty like the present, when the wisest are often per¬ plexed, it may not be amiss to go back to first principles. Instead of asking why government should or should not do this or that particular thing, that some one may be urging it to do or denying that it has any business to do, we may ask why it should do anything at all ? — may endeavor to get down to the principles of its action. If we can succeed in this, we may gain no little help in meeting some of the problems that now confront and embarrass us. If we find the logical justification for what political society already does, we shall at least know what may be attempted consistently therewith, and shall be spared those embarrassments that only arise because we have not taken this justification into V VI PREFACE. account. The conviction has come home to the author in the course of the studies the results of which are here given to the public, that political advances are frequently opposed on grounds which, if acted on and carried to their appropriate conclusion, would result in undoing government altogether — save for pur¬ poses of defence in time of war. The main positions of the book were stated in lectures at the School of Applied Ethics in Plymouth, 1894, and were afterwards more fully developed in a course of lectures before the Society for Ethical Culture of Philadelphia. I am indebted to Professor Henry Carter Adams and to Mr. A. L. Hodder for helpful suggestions while revising the proof-sheets — the more helpful, I may say, as they have not at all times shared my point of view. W. M. S. Philadelphia, Pa. CONTENTS. CHAPTER I. PAGE The Idea of Anarchy and the Idea of Government 3 CHAPTER II. The Possibility of Anarchy . . . . .11 CHAPTER III. The Problem of Government stated . . . .29 CHAPTER IV. Anarchy or Government in Defensive War CHAPTER V. 37 Vlll CONTENTS. CHAPTER VII. PAGE Anarchy or Government in the Industrial Realm . 93 CHAPTER VIII. An Illustration : the Pullman-Chicago Strike of 1894 * * * * * • * • . 129 APPENDIX. Note i. — On the different relation which quasi-public cor¬ porations and their employees respectively sustain to the public, and on the consequent unequal bearing of arbitration upon them . . . . . . .165 Note II. •—On varying Judicial opinion as to the rights of employees of quasi-public corporations . . . 171 Index of Authors quoted • 175 THE IDEA OF ANARCHY AND THE IDEA OF GOVERNMENT. ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. CHAPTER I. THE IDEA OF ANARCHY AND THE IDEA OF GOVERNMENT. Anarchy is a word that has a bad sound in our ears, but I do not now use it in a bad sense. If it necessarily meant disorder, riot, and crime, there would be little room for argument about it. I use it, however, in its simple literal sense, as a name for a state of society without govern¬ ment . 1 It is always convenient in considering a thing to have a term for its opposite, — it saves circumlocutions and waste of breath, — and I know of no word which is thus antitheti- 1 The Greek word, avapxLa, is made up of av priv. and apxla or apx'f}-, meaning a beginning or making a beginning, that is, taking the lead, guiding, commanding, governing; an¬ archy is accordingly simply no-governing or no-government. 3 4 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. cal to government save anarchy. The opposite of despotic government may be constitutional government, the opposite of monarchy or aris¬ tocracy may be democracy, but the opposite of government itself, of any kind of “archy,” is only an-archy. Further, “government” may itself be used in more than one sense. Originally to govern meant to take the rudder, to pilot, or to steer 1 — and hence, in general, to direct or control. When people in any enterprise choose a di¬ rector or leader (or a body of such persons), they in one sense set up a government. We speak colloquially of the government of a uni¬ versity, of a church, of a trade association, meaning the directors, managers, or trustees of it. But government, as we ordinarily use the word, is something more than this. The root idea is the same, but the form it has assumed is peculiar. Government in this sense is not merely direction or rule, but direction or rule enforcing itself. It is rule, not only for those who voluntarily submit themselves to it, but for 1 Latin, gubernare. Greek KvfHepvav, to steer or pilot. THE IDEA OF ANARCHY. 5 all the members of a community or society. Government might indeed be called the organ¬ ized force of a society, or (when it is not demo¬ cratic in form) organized force imposing itself on a society. Those subject to it are not free to obey it or not, as they like; they are bound to obey it — if not actively, then passively by submitting to physical penalties (for disobedi¬ ence). If, for example, we do not pay the taxes assessed upon us by the government under which we live, our property may to a corre¬ sponding extent be taken away from us. No association of the kind I at first alluded to could do the like, in case we failed to pay our dues or pledges to it; though it is of course possible that government might step in, and, viewing our dues and pledges as contracts, undertake to hold us bound by them. The most the association itself could do would be to exclude us from membership. 1 1 Cf. Professor Henry Sidgwick: “ The obvious differences [from the power of a leading critic of literature, when he directs people to read certain books, or of a physician, when he orders vaccination] is that the legislature’s orders might be enforced by physical violence; if it commanded vaccination 6 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. So with laws. Any association may have its rules or requirements, binding on its members, and they may be called its laws. But in such associations as I first mentioned they are only morally, not literally, binding, and are in this way very different from the laws of the State or Government. It is not left to the option of citizens whether they obey the laws of the State or not, it is not simply a matter of honor; but they may be physically obliged to obey — that is, if they fail, they may be fined, imprisoned, or even put to death. I am not arguing the right or wrong of this now, but simply stating the fact. There are these two types of association under penalties, the requisite physical force would be exercised by certain members of the community for the enforcement of the penalties, and this exercise of force would not be resisted by the will of the rest of the community.” {Elements of Politics , p. 598.) Again, “The general distinction between the * quasi¬ government ’ (if I may so call it) of such associations [indus¬ trial, literary, etc.] when neither aided nor represented by the state, and the government with which we are concerned as students of politics, is, that the former, in an orderly com¬ munity, can inflict no penalty worse than exclusion from the benefits of the association, and perhaps from voluntary relations with its members.” {Ibid. p. 547.) So Hobbes, “ Law in gen¬ eral is not counsel, but command.” {Leviathan, chap, xxvi.) THE IDEA OF ANARCHY. 7 in human society, one working with the volun¬ tary consent of all concerned, the other using more or less force (or, if not actually using force, supposed to have the right to use it when necessary) ; and it is the latter type that is the State and furnishes us with the phenomena of Government proper. But if this is so, the an¬ tithesis of government is not necessarily a com¬ pany of dissociated, not to say disorderly, individuals. Anarchy is not inconsistent with association, but only with enforced association. It means simply a state of society in which no one is bound or obliged to do anything (whether to associate with others or anything else); it is not opposed to order, but only to enforced order; not to rule, but only to obligatory rule. In other words, it is synonymous with liberty. Under such a system, individuals would simply be left free to do as they chose; compulsion would disappear; the only bonds in society would be moral bonds. I think no violence is done to language in using “anarchy” and “government” in these senses (certainly not in so using “ govern- 8 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. ment”); and in any case, inasmuch as in talk¬ ing of a thing we must have a distinct idea of what we are talking about, this, I allow myself to say, is what I have in mind in now treating of anarchy and government. It is not the words I wish to discuss nor the views which others may connect with the words, but the possible states of society which I have just described,— the further and more explicit meaning of which I shall elaborate as I go along. Understanding the terms, then, in this way, my inquiry is, Which is better, Anarchy or Government ? In other words, What is the justification of Government (if there be any), and why should we not be contented with a system of Liberty or Anarchy ? THE POSSIBILITY OF ANARCHY. CHAPTER II. THE POSSIBILITY OF ANARCHY. That liberty, or complete absence of govern¬ ment, would mark an ideal state of society, seems hardly to admit of doubt. “ In heaven,” says Channing, “ nothing like what we call government on earth can exist. . . . The voice of command is never heard among the spirits of the just.” 1 Compulsion, in itself con¬ sidered, is always an evil. 2 The evil may be counterbalanced by the good resulting from the compulsion, but of itself it is none the less an evil. If we suppose a case in which, if anywhere in the world, forcible restraint is justified, — namely, to prevent a man from committing robbery or murder, — must we not still admit that it would be better if 1 Collected Works (A. U. A. Ed., Boston, 1875), P* 361- 2 So John Stuart Mill, “ All restraint, qua restraint, is an evil.” — On Liberty , chap. v. 11 12 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. the man could be led to restrain himself ? If he could be persuaded to desist from such designs, would it not be better than to force him ? Is not substituting our will for his will so far taking away his dignity as a responsi¬ ble and moral being—and, in just this aspect of the matter, an injury, though from every other point of view, a good ? If this is so, compulsion, interference with liberty of any kind, is always, however necessary or legiti¬ mate, the mark of an imperfect state of society. In an ideal state, whether here or elsewhere, it would cease — the occasion and the justifi¬ cation for it would be gone. Men would do what was right, moved by love of the right alone. Professor Huxley after defining anarchy (as a term of political philosophy) to mean “a state of society in which the rule of each individual by himself is the only government the legiti¬ macy of which is recognized,” says, “ In this sense, strict anarchy may be the highest con¬ ceivable grade of perfection of social exist¬ ence; for, if all men spontaneously did justice THE POSSIBILITY OF ANARCHY. 13 and loved mercy, it is plain that all swords might advantageously be turned into plough¬ shares, and that the occupation of judges and police would be gone.” 1 So Hobbes, who de¬ fended what might almost be called political absolutism, admitted that “ if men could rule themselves, every man by his own command, that is to say, could they live according to the laws of nature, there would be no need at all of a city, nor of a common coercive power.” 2 Even taking men as they are, government can only be defended on the ground of its necessity, not because it is intrinsically desir- 1 Collected Essays, Vol. I. p. 391. Alfred Russell Wallace describes the ideally perfect social state as follows: “ Our best thinkers maintain that it is a state of individual freedom and self-government, rendered possible by the equal develop¬ ment and the just balance of the intellectual, moral, and physical parts of our nature — a state in which we shall each be so perfectly fitted for a social existence, by knowing what is right, and at the same time feeling an irresistible impulse to do what we know to be right, that all laws and all punishments shall be unnecessary.” (The Malay Archipelago , chap, xl.) 2 Philosophical Elements, chap. vi. 13, note. Hobbes uses “ city ” as the equivalent of the Latin civitas. So the Greeks designated city and state by the same word, toXls. Cf. Bluntschli, Allgemeine Staatslehre, S. 24, Anm. 14 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. able. No one can question that when a man can say with an old Greek writer, “ I have gained this by philosophy — that I do, without being commanded, what others do from fear of the laws,” he is on a higher level than those who have to be commanded, nor can one deny that to the extent such philosophy is really operative in the world, “ laws ” be¬ come a superfluity. In a similar spirit the late Bishop of Massachusetts said: “He is the benefactor of his race who makes it possible to have one law less. He is the enemy of his kind who would lay upon the shoulders of arbitrary government one burden which might be carried by the educated conscience and character of the community.” 1 There is hardly a thing which government does, of which we cannot say that it would be better if it could be done without government. As Emerson 1 Sermon before The Ancient and Honorable Artillery Company of Boston, reported in Boston Transcript , 4 June, 1888. Bishop Brooks states what may be held to be the com¬ plementary truth in the same discourse: “Every just war hastens the day when war shall be no longer. Every righteous law makes man more fit to live with less constraint.” THE POSSIBILITY OF ANARCHY. 15 tersely puts it, “The more reason the less government ”; 1 or, to turn it round, to what¬ ever extent government is necessary, it is because more or less of unreason exists. Indeed, men have lived with very little gov¬ ernment. An eminent Frenchman visited America in the last century and afterwards wrote: “ Can a people without government be happy? Yes, if you can suppose a whole people with good morals; and this is not a chimera. Will you see an example ? Observe the Quakers of America. Though numerous, though dispersed over the surface of Pennsyl¬ vania, they have passed more than a century without municipal government, without police, without coercive measures, to administer the state or to govern the hospitals.” 2 The pict- 1 “ Character ” in Lectures and Biographical Sketches (Works, Vol. X. p. 120). He continues, “ In a sensible family, nobody ever hears the words ‘ shall ’ and ‘ sha’n’t ’; nobody commands, and nobody obeys, but all conspire and joyfully co-operate. Take off the roofs of hundreds of happy houses, and you shall see this order without ruler, and the like in every intelligent and moral society.” 2 Brissot de Warville in Preface to his New Travels in the United States, London, 1794 (2d ed. p. 16). He became l 6 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. ure may be exaggerated and more or less inaccurate; yet it is none the less interesting and suggestive. And communities without the high standards of morality characteristic of the Quakers have yet somehow got along without much in the way of what we should call gov¬ ernment. They might have done better with government, but they did not perish for lack of it. We think government indispensable for the protection of life and property. But people may protect themselves, and those who cannot may contract with those stronger than they, to protect them. In early times when violence was rife, the custom was, says M. one of the Girondists in the French Revolution, and lost his head in its later scenes. Emerson’s picture of life in New England in the early part of the century is interesting from this point of view. He wrote from Boston in 1822 to Mr. John E. Hill of Baltimore : “ I hold that government never existed in such perfection as here. Except in the newspapers and titles of office, no being could be more remote, no sound more strange. Indeed, the only time when government can be said to make itself seen and felt is our festivals [he writes on the eve of the 4th of July], when it bears the form of a kind of general committee for popular amusements.” (Cabot’s Memoir , Vol. I. p. 91.) THE POSSIBILITY OF ANARCHY. 1 7 Leroy-Beaulieu, to place one’s self under the protection of “ some brigand rather more honest than the rest,” and make a bargain with him. The great men of Greek antiquity, and of almost every other antiquity, were, he adds, “professed brigands punctual in their per¬ formance and faithful to their word.” So, as is well known, in the middle ages, when gov¬ ernment was weak or non-existent, small pro¬ prietors of freeholds placed themselves under the patronage of powerful lords and became by choice their vassals, or even their serfs . 1 A more primitive arrangement still seems to have been for a man’s family to protect him. In ancient Scandinavia, Mr. Spencer tells us, a man’s relations and friends avenged his death, and if they did not, they instantly lost the reputation that constituted their own principal security . 2 So among the old German tribes the protection of rights and of liberty rested upon the family . 3 Sometimes, in still less developed 1 Leroy-Beaulieu, The Modern State , p. 71. 2 Sociology , Vol. II. § 533. 3 Cf. Dr. Lujo Brentano on the place of the family among the ancient German tribes, in The Relation of Labor to the Law of C i8 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. communities, a man was thrown back sternly on his individual self. Sir John Lubbock tells us of tribes among whom the public does not con¬ cern itself at all in the punishment of criminals, and if any one among them suffers an injury or affront without endeavoring to revenge himself, he is slighted by all the rest, and accounted a coward, a person of no esteem . 1 It is evident that while such an arrangement would work hardship among the weaker members of the tribe, it would tend to the survival of the strong, To-day, pp. 22, 23. A survival of the old idea of family obliga¬ tion is found in Morocco, where the state does not undertake to nourish criminals when in prison, but leaves this to their families. (Leroy-Beaulieu, The Modern State, p. 173.) Ven¬ dettas are, of course, remnants of the primitive order of things. It is said that among our North American Indians, in case of murder, only the family of the deceased “have the right of taking satisfaction; they collect, consult, and agree. The rules of a town or of the nation have nothing to do or say in the business.” (Trans. American Antiq. Soc. Vol. I. p. 281.) In ancient Greece, though the state punished, it did not prose¬ cute or try criminals in the first place ; this was left to the family of the sufferer, nor was the accused person placed under arrest until he was found guilty. (Lubbock, Origin of Civiliza¬ tion, chap, x.) 1 Origin of Civilization, chap. x. (quoting Du Tertre on the Caribbians and Tapinambous). THE POSSIBILITY OF ANARCHY. 19 the manly, the capable. Indeed, during a great part of human history it has been accounted a mark of honor to avenge one’s own wrongs ; it is said that down to the thirteenth century, Italian nobles “regarded it as disgraceful to submit to laws rather than to do themselves justice by force of arms .” 1 All this seems to show that the State or Gov¬ ernment is not an absolute necessity of human society, that anarchy, or leaving men to them¬ selves, is a more or less practicable arrange- 1 Spencer, Sociology , Vol. II. § 522. With these nobles may be compared the ranchmen of Wyoming, U. S. A., whose motto might be said to be, “ The state be blowed ”; no one being respected among them who has any use for the constable or the sheriff. (Philadelphia Evening Telegraph on “ Western Lawlessness,” 16 April, 1892.) Even in settled communities, a man’s taking justice into his own hands is sometimes regarded leniently. Not long ago General von Kirchoff of the Prussian army shot the editor of a Berlin paper for publishing a para¬ graph to the effect that the General’s daughter had eloped with a manservant. “ What man of honor,” asked the German War Minister, von Schellendorf, “would not act as General von Kirchoff when the law would not help him avenge the slanders on his daughter’s reputation?” Von Kirchoff was, indeed, found guilty and sentenced to imprisonment, but was soon pardoned by the Emperor and gazetted for the order of the Red Eagle. (.Public Ledger , 5 March, 1894.) 20 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. ment . 1 In our own country there have been times and places in which law was either weak or non-existent, and yet society did not go to pieces. The early settlers in Illinois, who came from Virginia, cared nothing, it is said, for the protection or company which villages afforded; each one depended upon himself and his trusty rifle for protection. They did indeed form squads to pursue Indian marauders, and they had their regulating soci¬ eties for punishing law-breakers, but generally 1 Aristotle’s statement, “ man is, by nature, a political animal ” ( Pol. i. 2), would seem to require qualification. That man is, by nature, a social animal may, however, be safely affirmed. A state or government is an expedient rather than an organic necessity — something that society may conceivably outgrow, the ends of which may possibly be attained by purely moral means. A state is only necessary now because moral forces are inadequate to the attainment of the ends of society and need the supplementing of physical force. Thomas Aqui¬ nas modified the Aristotelian dictum by saying, “ homo est animal sociale el politician ” (Zte Regimine Principurn). It is sometimes claimed that Hegel was the first to formulate the antithesis of State and Society. (So J. S. Mann, in Pro¬ ceedings of the Aristotelian Society. Vol. I. No. 3, pp. 92-98.) See Professor Ritchie’s instructive discussion of “The Distinction between Society and the State,” in the Appendix to his Prin¬ ciples of State Interference. THE POSSIBILITY OF ANARCHY. 21 they lived in solitude (aside from the compan¬ ionship of their families); and, says their his¬ torian, “ they possessed greater individuality than any people on earth .” 1 A gentleman, whose courtly figure and imposing presence I myself remember as a boy, once testified in Congress as to the manner in which the pio¬ neers of the West shifted for themselves in the absence of the government. “I have lived many years of my life,” he declared, “without the jurisdiction of magistrates or law of any kind. Yet . . . even under these circumstances we administered justice and respected the laws of God. Debts were collected as readily as they are now and law by the common consent of the people was virtually enforced. . . . Although officers and a penal code were want¬ ing, when a murder or other felony was com¬ mitted, a jury was empanelled, and if the accused was found guilty by his peers, a gallows was erected and he was hanged.” 2 ♦ 1 J. Gillespie in Rufus Blanchard’s History of Illinois, p. 114. 2 Speech by the Hon. Augustus C. Dodge in the House of Representatives, February 7, 1846. See Memoirs by the Rev. William Salter, Iowa Historical Record, January, 1887. 22 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. According to Mr. Bryce, there are parts of our country even now—he speaks of a district in Western New York and Ohio — where the people have deliberately concluded that it is cheaper and simpler to take the law into their own hands on those rare occasions when a police is needed, than to be at the trouble of organizing and paying a force for which there is usually no employment. Their method is a volunteer jury, and, in a clear case, a simple seizure and execution of the criminal . 1 Yes, sometimes spontaneous justice actually competes with organized justice and proves itself the better. A few years ago there died in a little town in Iowa a remarkable man named Thomas Chilson. He was a blacksmith, but was crippled by an accident, and in time such qualities were discovered in him that his fellow-townsmen and the farmers around used to come to him to have him settle their dis¬ putes. For years previous to his death it was not uncommon to see in front of his modest dwelling the motley collection of vehicles which 1 The American Commonwealth , Part V. chap. 94. THE POSSIBILITY OF ANARCHY. 23 is a familiar spectacle in the vicinity of a rural court house. Inside, gathered about the cripple’s chair, were the litigants, their respec¬ tive witnesses, and as many curious spectators as were able to get within hearing distance. His judgments, it is said, were almost invari¬ ably respected. The people in the neighbor¬ hood became thus accustomed, instead of “going to law,” to “going to Chilson,” the process being a great deal cheaper, costing nothing in fact, and the results being much more satisfactory . 1 Such an instance raises the query whether it would not be well to have it always possible for private enterprise to compete with government ? The idea may be impracticable (Chilson, I be¬ lieve, dealt only with civil cases), and yet it has something to recommend it. If it were feasi¬ ble, then though government existed, individ¬ uals would not be subject to it, if they did not choose to be . 2 A distinguished French •t 1 Boston Post , August 7, 1889. 2 It may seem as if an instance of this were furnished in the public schools of America, for we may send our children 24 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. economist has been daring enough to suggest competition between governments like that which already exists between individuals or between private associations. He asks why should not political monopolies disappear as industrial and commercial monopolies are (ac¬ cording to him) now doing ? 1 It might be thought an ideal arrangement if in the same territory 2 we could have a choice of governments just as we now have a choice of colleges to to private schools if we like. But the illustration is not per¬ fect, for we are all obliged to pay for the support of the public schools. 1 M. de Molinari, quoted in Leroy-Beaulieu’s The Modern State , pp. 123, 124. 2 M. de Molinari speaks of the rights of secession , and so it would seem as if he must have the same territory in mind. The right' of emigration, of withdrawing from a country, is surely no longer in question. Among primitive tribes, leaving one chief and going to another is more or less frequent; it may only mean going from one village to another (cf. Spencer’s Sociology , Vol. II. §§ 452 and 485). So in the feudal age, “the freeman might choose his lord” {Ibid. § 459). But liberty of government (with the right of secession) in a great modern territorial state can only be possible if there are differ¬ ent governments in the same territory. Whether this is a consistent or whether it is a self-contradictory conception, I leave for the present undetermined. THE POSSIBILITY OF ANARCHY. 25 which to send our boys, or of shops in which to do our trading. If there were several govern¬ ments, and we were bound to none of them, government in the sense in which it is opposed to anarchy, or complete individual liberty, would really cease to be. Mr. Spencer has told us that among the Kaffirs the king governs only so long as they choose to obey — they leave him, if he governs ill . 1 If, without leaving our abode, we might refuse to obey a government we did not like, no one could have much objection to govern¬ ment. Emerson seems to imagine something of this sort, when he says (though with a touch of the humor that gave a saving grace to so much that he wrote), “ It would be but an easy extension of our commercial system to pay a private emperor a fee for services, as we pay an architect, an engineer, or a lawyer. If any man has a talent for righting wrong, for administering difficult affairs, for counselling poor farmers how to turn their estates to good husbandry, 1 Sociology , Vol. II. § 466. 26 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. for combining a hundred private enterprises to general benefit, let him in country-town, or in Court street, put up his sign-board, Mr. Smith, Governor, Mr. Johnson, Working-King.” 1 The idea may be fanciful, voluntary govern¬ ment may be even a contradiction in terms, yet in what I might call the intention of the idea, I do not see how one can fail to find something attractive. 1 “The Young American,” in Nature, Addresses and Lec¬ tures (Works, Vol. I. p. 364). THE PROBLEM OF GOVERN¬ MENT STATED. CHAPTER III. THE PROBLEM OF GOVERNMENT STATED. In the light, then, of what has gone before, we may say that the abstract presumption is against government. If restraint is an evil, however necessary, and government involves more or less restraint, then government is to this extent an evil, however necessary and beneficial it may be from some other point of view. If every¬ thing could be done in society without violating any one’s freedom, it would be vastly better. However government may accord with the free¬ dom of many or of most in a society, it always involves force (or the right to use it) against some. I see no way of blinking this fact. “The one thing that characterizes the State,” says M. Leroy-Beaulieu, “ is coercive power; but what characterizes spontaneous associations is merely the force of persuasion .” 1 1 The Modern State, p. 56. Cf. Sir James Fitzjames Stephen, “ Force is an absolutely essential element of all law 2 9 30 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. Who does not see the difference at the present moment, for example, between any amount of agitation and appeal to conscience in behalf of the arbitration of labor differences, and a law obliging arbitration ? The one rests on freedom, the other might be enforced by the whatever. Indeed, law is nothing but regulated force subjected to particular conditions and directed toward particular objects.” (. Liberty , Equality , Fraternity , p. 239.) Again, “The differ¬ ences between a rough and a civilized society is n-ot that force is used in the one case and persuasion in the other, but that force is (or ought to be) guided with greater care in the second case than in the first” (Ibid. p. 32). So John Stuart Mill, “ Penal sanction is the essence of law ” ( Utilitarianism, chap, v.); Lord Pembroke, “ Law is nothing but public opinion organized and equipped with force ” ( Liberty and Socialism , quoted in D. G. Ritchie’s Principles of State Interference , p. 56); Shadworth IT. Hodgson, “ Looking back to the history of law, it is found to arise from the combination of the sense of justice with a de facto power enforcing it” ( Theory of Practice, Vol. II. p. 171); John Grote, “Law is the public reason of a society, participated in more or less by the mass of individuals, enforceable upon all who will not participate in it ” (Examina¬ tion of the Utilitarian Philosophy, p. 155); Goldwin Smith, “ Let the edifice of law be as moral and effectual as you will, its foundation is the force of the community ” (Essays on Ques¬ tions of the Day , p. 203, 2 ed.). A distinction is sometimes made between power and force (potentia and vis , Macht and Gezvalt — see Bluntschli, Allgemeine Siaatslehre, SS. 334, 340); it is not, however, a distinction between force and persuasion, THE PROBLEM OF GOVERNMENT. 31 courts. In the latter case, whether the parties wished to arbitrate or no would make no dif¬ ference—they would be obliged to; just as it makes no difference now whether people with some private grievance against one another wish to fight it out on the streets or no ; they are sim¬ ply not allowed to — their freedom is restrained. but between legitimate and illegitimate, or lawful and unlawful, force. Force used on the side of right and law is as truly force {i.e. an interference with freedom) as when used in behalf of wrong and lawlessness. Law itself, it may be added, is as much law when it does not accord with abstract right and justice, as when it does so accord. The so-called Fugitive Slave Law in the United States before the late Civil War is an instance. Any rule {i.e. established method of procedure) that is enforced by a community, or is enforced on a community, is a law. It may not be law as we should like to have it, or, as we may say, it ought to be, but it is law all the same. The nature of the State as an organization of force or power comes to clear manifestation in the revolutions that sometimes take place in a state; these generally mean the rising of some new class to a share in political power. This was the essential significance of the English revolution in 1832, and of the French revolution of 1789. Actual violence is often used; and when concessions are made, it is often in fear of violence. Violence or the right to use it is the basis of every state in existence, whether constitutional or other. Political alternatives lie simply in deciding who shall use the force (or control its use), whether an individual, or a class, or a majority of the people. 32 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. From this point of view the essential problem of government might be stated as follows : Flow far may a community or society use force in attaining its objects ? Or, to put it differently, how far may the community itself act, and how far may it trust to the private initiative and action of individuals P 1 For wherever the com¬ munity itself acts, — acts as a body,—it may always happen that single persons will not agree with it and hence will only co-operate or submit as they are forced to. If a community acted and put no obligation on individual mem¬ bers, it would not be really the community act¬ ing, but simply the majority (or whatever might be the number of those deciding on the action). Hence community — or social — action and the use of force (or at least the right to use it) are inseparable, so long as the action is not unani¬ mous. Indeed, if the action were unanimous and yet no arrangement were made to enforce the 1 Professor Huxley states the problem of government as follows : “ What ought to be done and what to be left undone by society as a whole, in order to bring about as much welfare of its members as is compatible with the natural order of things.” {CollectedEssays , Vol. I. p. 427.) THE PROBLEM OF GOVERNMENT. 33 conclusion reached against any individual in the future who should change his mind and rebel, there would be no government in the proper sense of the term ; just as in case different nations now agreed henceforth to arbitrate their differences, instead of going to war about them, and yet should make no arrangement for re¬ straining a nation that took it into its head to go to war, no government would really be set up by the antecedent agreement, however unani¬ mous that agreement might be. Government means power to enforce a decis¬ ion— this is its essential nature . 1 In a wholly ideal order of things, social action would be possible without government; in the present order of things social action and government are practically interconvertible terms. 1 Cf. Professor J. W. Burgess, “ An organization may be conceived which would include every member of a given popu¬ lation, or every inhabitant of a given territory, and which might continue with great permanence, and yet it would not be the state. If, however, it possesses the sovereignty over the popu¬ lation, then it is the state.’’ (Political Science and Constitu¬ tional Law , Vol. I. p. 52.) Again, “The state must have the power to compel the subject against his will; otherwise it is no state, it is only an anarchic society.” {Ibid. p. 55.) D ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT IN DEFENSIVE WAR. CHAPTER IV. ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT IN DEFENSIVE WAR. I have said that the presumption is always against government, since interference with freedom is, in itself, an evil. But this is far from disposing of the matter. In a similar way it might be said that inasmuch as pain is an evil (in itself considered), the pre¬ sumption is always against anything that brings pain. So it is, and yet we justify many things that bring pain (whether to our¬ selves or to others), because we think that in the long run they result in a counter¬ balancing good. The question is whether government may not be justified in a similar way. The illus¬ trations I have given show that government is not always a necessity, and suggest that in an ideal order of things there will be no occasion for it; but where there is occasion, when it would be an advantage, not to say a necessity, 37 38 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. is there any reason why a society should not use it ? Is restraint or compulsion not only an evil, is it a wrong? Let us take an instance. Let us suppose that a tribe or community is threatened with invasion, that without having done any wrong itself, it is confronted with another tribe that wishes to dispossess it of its lands and possessions, and, if need be, to wipe it out. May it resist ? Few would question this right. There may be those who would teach an undiluted doctrine of non-resistance, but I cannot stop to enter into the ethics of this view now, save to say that if it had been consistently acted upon by living beings in general in the past, man would probably never have developed himself on this planet at all. I must take for granted that a tribe in the situation I have described has a right to resist. The practical question is, How ? Shall all the able-bodied men fight (or help support, by their labor at home, those who do) and, if any are reluctant and unwilling, may they be rightfully obliged to do their DEFENSIVE WAR. 39 »part ? or, must we say, on the contrary, that every individual’s freedom is so sacred that it is wrong to do violence to it, and that non¬ interference must be practised, even if it leads to the ruin of the tribe ? I think every one would feel that a claim in behalf of freedom like the one just mentioned is strained and exaggerated, and that an individual could not really ask to be left free to do as he liked, save as he was ready to act in a way not inconsistent with the interests of his tribe. Probably conscience itself, in one who was thus cowardly and unwilling, would be on the side of those who forced him into the ranks (or to labor, at home); at least it would not be strongly against them. But if this is so, mere respect for men’s freedom is not a principle of morality. All depends on how they use this freedom, as to whether others are absolutely bound not to interfere with it. If they use it in such a way as to endanger the existence of the society of which they are members, they have no valid title to it. And this is 40 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. quite consistent with saying that interference with freedom is, in itself considered, an evil (for it is always better that people should do right of their own accord than that they should be forced to); it is simply saying that under certain circumstances it is not a wrong — and that the evil involved in it may be counterbalanced by a larger good. Moreover, suppose that the tribe in the case under consideration, instead of being defeated, succeeds in its resistance, despite the cowardice and lack of patriotism of a few. Does it seem right, in such circum¬ stances, that persons should share in the bless¬ ings of continued security, who had done nothing to bring them about (though they might have helped to this end) ? If men are to have blessings, may they not, in the name of right itself, be expected to bear their share of the social burden in securing them? I sus¬ pect it is in accordance with a deep instinct of even primitive man when Homer says of certain of his heroes that “ not without good right do they eat the fat and drink the sweet, for DEFENSIVE WAR. 41 they fight ever in the front .” 1 It is im¬ possible to get up much sympathy in behalf of the rights of those who leave it to others to defend their tribe or country in time of danger, unless of course, as in the case of Quakers, they have conscientious scruples against war. If, then, I am correct in my reasoning, there is a right of government (i.e. of using force) in a society, under such circumstances as I have imagined. Compulsion thus far would appear to be justified, whether it be to force men into the field, or to oblige them to labor at home. The right to personal freedom and the right of property in what one produces, give way under the pressure of public needs — they are not absolute rights. At the same time, it should be added, this is not saying that men should , in fact , be forced (under the supposed circumstances), but only that they may be'if there is occasion to do so — may be, that is, without violation of right or justice. Doubtless it would be better if all could be 1 Iliad , XII. 31S-320. 42 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. induced to do their duty of their own accord; - for then public needs would be met without any corresponding admixture of evil. If all people could be induced to act in the right way, gov¬ ernment might never have arisen among men. In other words, it is only the right of govern¬ ment (for defensive war) that we have estab¬ lished ; but whether in a given crisis, force should actually be used, or, on the other hand, it would be better to leave individuals to their own impulses, is a question for practical judg¬ ment at the time. A call for volunteers or for voluntary contributions might have better effect than any possible conscription or measure of taxation could have. In dealing with alterna¬ tives like these, we are in the field of political expediency, not of political principle. Principle simply says that we should take whatever course seems most likely to be both immediately and permanently productive of good results. But can government be justified for any end beyond this of which I have spoken ? Of course one who was writing a history of government would have to admit that many governments DEFENSIVE WAR. 43 have owed their origin to the necessities of aggressive war; and such governments I do not undertake to defend . 1 But I am simply now asking, What justifies government at all? It may well be that some types of government can not be justified. If a society has a right to exist at all, it has a right to defend itself against attack — defend itself, as a society, I mean, and act as a body. Government, so far, is for a thoroughly public purpose. But why should government go any further ? Why should gov¬ ernment interfere in private quarrels and under¬ take to protect the life and the property of individuals ? Why should it not restrict itself to the public concern ? This has been the rule sometimes. “Among the lower races,” says Sir John Lubbock, “ the chiefs scarcely take any cog¬ nizance of offences, unless they relate to such things as directly concern, or are supposed to concern, the interests of the community gen- 1 About the year 200 b . c . a large force of Japanese made a plundering expedition into Corea. It is amusing to hear this gravely spoken of as one of the strongest historical supports of Japanese rights in the Corean peninsula. 44 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. erally. As regards private injuries, every one must protect or avenge himself /’ 1 In Mediaeval Europe, too, individuals were often left to protect themselves or to find such protection as they were able to get by a species of contract. Yes, Mr. Spencer, in his Sociology , gives us instances of governments that hardly last longer than during periods of public danger, coming into being with the emergencies of war and practically passing away when war is over . 2 What real justification is there for government (; i.e . any kind of social coercion) save in the time of war? Why should the community mix itself up in men’s private affairs, and make pri¬ vate quarrels and injuries matters of public con¬ cern ? Modern communities do so interfere. Our policemen, our courts, our laws, have for a large part of their purpose the remedying of private wrongs and the settling of differences between individuals. Why should they ? It is astonishing to find how little thorough¬ going political philosophy there is on this point. 1 Origin of Civilization , chap. x. 2 Sociology, Vol. II. §§ 451, 473, 478. DEFENSIVE WAR. 45 Most writers seem to take it for granted that government should protect life and property; it is a kind of first principle with them; they have no reasoning to offer. Mr. Herbert Spencer hardly differs from the rest; radical political thinker that he is, he seems almost as implicitly as any school-boy to take for granted that gov¬ ernment should protect life and property. And yet if we ask, Why? — if we press for reasons, — we are brought, I think, into a circle of con¬ ceptions of far-reaching importance, conceptions that throw light on the problem of government in all its phases, conceptions that tend to under¬ mine those narrow mechanical notions of the province of government, with which the name of Mr. Spencer, among others, is associated. What I have in mind, I shall endeavor to make clear in the next chapter. ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT IN PROTECTING LIFE AND PROPERTY. CHAPTER V. ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT IN PROTECTING LIFE AND PROPERTY. We have seen that government — social action, along with its incidents of compulsion on unwilling members — is justified in defend¬ ing a society against the unjust attack of an enemy. But when the society is no longer in danger, why should it not leave individuals entirely to themselves ? Why should it inter¬ fere in their private quarrels ? Why should it make a private injury a public wrong? If, indeed, quarrels become so widespread as to threaten the life of society, it might act to prevent or settle them for the same reason that it acts as a body against an external foe . 1 1 An ordinance was issued in France in 1296 prohibiting “ private wars and judicial duels so long as the king is engaged in war ” — implying, then, that at other times they were not for¬ bidden. The question is why should they be, when they do not endanger the life of the community? E 49 50 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. But when the situation is not so grave and is nowise different from what we ordinarily meet with in human societies, — where there are simply occasional thefts, assaults, robberies, murders, and the like,—why should the society interfere ? Primitive societies often do not, conceiving that each individual should be his own protector or that his blood relatives should come to his aid. Why should modern societies ? Why should they not restrict them¬ selves absolutely to matters of public concern — and, if the society is not threatened from without, allow government to fall into disuse, leaving all private wrongs to be dealt with by individuals themselves ? The question turns at bottom on what we mean by society or, more accurately speaking, a society. A society, if we stop to think of it, is a peculiar phenomenon. It is made up of individuals, and yet any number of individ¬ uals do not of themselves make a society. It is not one individual and another and another and so on — but these conceived of as some¬ how fitting together, making a unity, a body, PROTECTING LIFE AND PROPERTY. 51 an organism . 1 In any physical body there are the same chemical elements as might exist separately, detached, or, as we say, in a free state, outside — but the body is not simply the sum of these elements, any more than a house is simply the sum of its bricks. A body is a peculiar combination of its elements; and it is bricks going together in such a way as to make one object that constitutes the house. So with a society. It is not simply a lot of individuals, but these individuals conceived as making up a whole, with ties to one another and more or less conscious of them, feeling that in some sense they belong to one another, that they are not mere units , but members together of a some¬ what beyond their individual selves. Such is the characteristic mark of a society. What the circumstances and forces are that lead to formation of societies is another ques¬ tion . 2 It is enough for our present purpose 1 For extended analysis and criticism of the idea of organ¬ ism, as applied to a society, see Prof. J. S. Mackenzie’s An Intro¬ duction to Social Philosophy, chap, iii., “The Social Organism.” % This inquiry might be said to belong to the province of the sociologist (cf. such works as Bagehot’s Physics and Politics , Morgan’s Ancient Society , Ward’s Dynamic Sociology , and par- 52 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. that we find them,—groups of people who feel that in some sense they are one, — classes, tribes, races, peoples, nations, and the like. Wherever such units exist, it is not true to fact to say that the members of them are individuals merely; the ties may be weak or they may be strong, the consciousness of be¬ longing to a larger whole may be faint or it may be vivid and clear, but where there are no ties, where there is no social conscious¬ ness, properly so called, there is no society, however many individuals more or less cogni¬ zant of one another there may be. Mr. Spencer tells us of certain Asiatic savages that they are “like tigers—two of them cannot dwell in one den ” ; “ their houses are scattered singly or in groups of two or three .” 1 It is plain that such people are a tribe in only a very limited sense of the word. It is the sense of belonging to one another that makes a tribe. On the other hand, even though the aggre- ticularly, Prof. Franklin H. Giddings’ just published The Prin¬ ciples of Sociology ); but the student of politics may take societies for granted — they are the starting-point of his specific inquiries. 1 The “Abors”; see Sociology , Vol. II. § 449. PROTECTING LIFE AND PROPERTY. 53 gates be very large, there may be more or less of a tribal or social consciousness. Englishmen or Germans, for example, do not feel that they are merely their own private selves; even an American, conglomerate nationality as we are over here, feels more or less dimly that he is a part of a larger whole, and when, whatever our old-world descent, we say to ourselves, “We are all Americans,” we have an indescrib¬ able sense of unity. But if I have correctly stated the meaning of a society, the line between public interests and private interests can hardly be called an absolute one. If in a society the individuals composing it are not mere individuals, but members of the society, then does not only whatever affects the society affect them, but whatever affects them affects the society. If any one of them is injured, the society is injured, on the supposition that it is a real social body. The essential idea is as old as Paul — and older. The Apostle gave utter¬ ance to it in a passage that has become clas¬ sical, having in mind the new Christian society that was forming in his time : 54 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. “ And whether one member suffer, all the members suffer with it .” 1 Plato expressed the thought (with the usual political reference) in the following language: “Is not that the best ordered state . . . which most nearly approaches to the condition of the individual—as in the body, when but a finger is hurt, the whole frame, drawn towards the soul, and forming one realm under the ruling power therein, feels the hurt, and sympathizes all together with the part affected, and we say that the man has a pain in his finger.” 2 In other words, just as the man, though not the finger, feels the pain of the finger, so the state, though not the individual, feels the inju¬ ries or sufferings of the individual. There is no absolute line between them; the one is simply the whole of which the other is the part — and an injury to the part is an injury to the whole, a wrong to the part is a wrong to the whole. In the light of this conception the question of how a private injury becomes a matter- of public concern may be said to answer itself. 1 I Corinthians, xii. 26. 2 Republic, 462. (Jowett’s translation.) PROTECTING LIFE AND PROPERTY. 55 It would hardly be going beyond the bounds to say that a society in which this was not the case would not be a real society. If a wrong to any one individual excites no resent¬ ment in the minds of the rest, there is not properly a society, but simply an aggregate of individuals — the social bond does not exist. The imperfect protection (or absence of protec¬ tion) of individuals in primitive societies sim¬ ply proves that while up to a certain point (e.g. when the life of the society is threat¬ ened) there may have been a consciousness of solidarity, beyond that there was a feeble social consciousness or else none at all. Men felt that they were one in time of danger; but at other times they had a feeble consciousness of unity or none. To whatever extent, then, there is a true social consciousness in a group or society of people, to that extent there must be an interest on the part of the whole society in the good or ill fortunes of any member. It may be difficult to develop such a consciousness, — many causes may stand in the way, the bigness of the territory which a 56 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. society inhabits, the incoming of new elements, the lack of common descent or of a common religion, the variety of manners ; 1 but this is only saying that true social wholes are not made offhand, — and I am only arguing that to whatever extent there is a true social whole, a real society or community, to that extent, inter¬ est, public interest, in individuals, in whatever happens to them, and especially if it be an injury, is natural, legitimate, indeed inevitable. And yet let us not fail to realize all that this means and involves. If a society does make private injuries a matter of concern to itself,-—if it undertakes to protect the lives and property of its members,—it does to a certain extent interfere with that struggle for 1 Herodotus mentions four ties that bound together the Hellenic aggregate: i. Fellowship of blood; 2. Fellowship of language; 3. Fixed domiciles of Gods and sacrifices common to all; 4. Like manners and dispositions. {Hist. viii. 144; cf. Grote’s comments, History of Greece, Part II. chap, ii.) Professor J. W. Burgess defines a nation as “ a population having a common language and literature, a common tradition and history, a common custom, and a common consciousness of rights and wrongs.” ( Political Science and Constitutional Lazo, Vol. I. p. 2.) PROTECTING LIFE AND PROPERTY. 57 existence between individuals which is some¬ times thought to be the method and main¬ spring of progress in the race. If a society supplements with its own strength the strength of its weaker members, it does to that extent help to perpetuate in existence those who otherwise might be crowded out of existence. If the supreme principle is, as is sometimes maintained, a fair field and no favors, each one prospering or failing in life, according to his natural endowments, then is government, so far as it is a means of giving protection to those who might not be able to defend them¬ selves, an interference with this principle, since it puts on an equality, as regards the security of their persons and property, people of unequal natural endowments. The power¬ ful, the capable, can generally defend them¬ selves ; it is the less gifted persons who look to some one else to defend them —as in the Sandwich Islands it is an injured person too weak to retaliate who appeals to the king or principal chief . 1 v 1 Spencer, Sociology , Vol. II. § 522. 58 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. And the logical implication of the views of some thinkers would seem to be that gov¬ ernment, in this aspect of it, is an interfer¬ ence with a kind of natural justice. Mr. Herbert Spencer is one whom I have in mind — not that he would say this, but that he has a general mode of thought from which this would not be an illegitimate inference. He, for example, objects, in common with many others, to taxes that fall in more than due proportion on those whose greater power have brought them greater means, only to give to citizens of smaller powers more benefits than they have earned; he calls this a burdening the better for the benefit of the worse . 1 He would have it, on the contrary, that each one should gain “ neither more nor less of benefit than his activities normally bring.” 2 “The superior,” he says, should “have the good of his superiority; and the evil of his inferiority,” and he would put a “veto on all public action which abstracts from some men 1 Sociology , Vol. II. § 581. 2 Ibid. Vol. II. § 575. PROTECTING LIFE AND PROPERTY. 59 part of the advantages they have earned, and awards to other men advantages they have not earned.” 1 This is indeed his fundamental rule of jus¬ tice and injustice. Mr. Spencer gives particular instances of what he means — he condemns public libraries and public museums and public schools, since these mean the taxation of the more well-to-do for the benefit of the less well- to-do, and every one, he maintains, should have all the benefits of his exertions to himself, and none should have more benefits than his own exertions entitle him to . 2 True, he does not “ condemn aid given to the inferior by the superior” voluntarily , but it is difficult to see why he should not, since this involves an inter¬ ference with the principle of benefit purely in proportion to merit as truly as public aid does. In other words, Mr. Spencer believes that each individual should stand on his own legs and that the fittest should survive — he holds to the 1 Ibid . Vol. II. § 567. 2 “The Sins of Legislators” and the “Great Political Su¬ perstition,” in The Man versus The State. Cf. Sociology , Vol. II. § 569. 6o ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. beneficence of the struggle for existence in the human world as truly as in the animal world, and says that government (or the corporate action of society) should not interfere with the struggle. But the question is, whether government for the protection of life and property is not itself an interference with this principle. Mr. Spen¬ cer does not say so ; he rather recognizes the legitimacy of government for the protection of life and property; but it is difficult to see how he can do so in consistency with the language which I have just quoted. He always guards himself by saying that individuals should not “aggress ” against one another — he would have the struggle for existence go on, but says that it must go on “without violence .” 1 But why without violence ? Suppose the lower orders of creation were interdicted from using violence in their mutual struggles. Suppose ani¬ mals, birds, fishes, were forbidden to “ aggress ” against one another and could heed the command. What would be the consequence ? Is not a part of the very meaning of the struggle in the 1 “ The Sins of Legislators ” in The Man versus The State. PROTECTING LIFE AND PROPERTY. 6 X animal world violence and aggression ? And Spencer tells us the process is beneficent; he recounts how carnivorous animals remove from herbivorous herds individuals past their prime, and weed out the sickly, malformed, and the least fleet and powerful . 1 Why should not the same process go on with equal beneficence among men ? Mr. Spencer indeed once says that “the poverty of the incapable, the distresses that come upon the imprudent, the starvation of the idle, and those shoulderings aside of the weak by the strong, which leave so many in shallows and in miseries, are decrees of a large, far-seeing benevolence.” 2 But what is the line which separates these innocent, justifiable, “shoulderings aside of the weak by the strong” from the aggressions that are objectionable? Why is not outwitting a man in a bargain if we are clever enough, or failing to keep a contract with him if we can brave the consequences, or even taking 1 Ibid. 2 Social Statics , reaffirmed with approval (save as regards its teleological implications), in “The Sins of Legislators,” The Matt versus The State. 62 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. his property or enslaving him, if we are strong enough-—why may not all this be justifiable, since it is only the weaker and the less capable members of the community who will be the sufferers, and the stronger members will only be thereby asserting their power and getting the natural reward of their superior endow¬ ments ? What would be the struggle for exist¬ ence in the animal world in which deceit and the right of might had no part ? Far be it from me to assert or even suggest that Mr. Spencer would sanction deceit and violence in human society. Few men have such an abhorrence of aggression as he. But I am not now discussing his personal feelings, but the logic of his philosophy. My question is simply, whether, accepting the struggle for existence and the survival of the fittest in human society in the way he does, as not only more or less natural and inevitable, but as normal and desirable, he is consistent in favoring government for the protection of life and prop¬ erty, since this is itself an interference with the struggle for existence and tends to promote the PROTECTING LIFE AND PROPERTY. 63 survival of the so-called “ fit ” and “ unfit ” alike. If there were complete anarchy or liberty in a society, the process of natural selection might go on unhindered—there would then be no social check on the strong and they could have the full benefit of their superior abilities, whether they crowded the weak out of exist¬ ence, or — what might be more sensible—made slaves of them, or — what might be cheaper still — left them to be “free laborers,” whom they hired as they had need . 1 But with social action — that is, with a so¬ ciety looking on individuals, not as individuals merely, but as members of itself and hence to be protected, guarded as it would its own life — an end is so far put to the inter-individual strug¬ gle for existence, and the strength of all is, in a sense, given to each one. Plainly this takes us into a different order of conceptions, from one 1 When the shade of Achilles declares that he would rather have the lowest lot on earth than be king of the dead, he takes as the type of the lowest earthly condition, not the slave, but the free laborer. ( Odyssey , xi. 489.) Cf. Mr. Gladstone’s comments on this passage. (-Studies on Homer , Vol. III. p. 74 -) 64 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. in which the “struggle for existence” plays a determining part . 1 In fact, \Ve may safely say that to the extent an unhindered struggle for existence goes on in a society, there is no real society, and just to the extent a society exists, there is co-operation between all for the benefit of all, instead of a competitive struggle, in which each one acts for himseli alone. Personally Mr. Spencer, as we know, favors social protection of life and property; he would even have civil justice, as we already have criminal justice, free of cost to the citizen . 2 But for the life of me I can not see how this would be equit¬ able, if such things as public libraries and public schools are inequitable. For if people should only get what they pay for, if it is wrong that they 1 Professor Huxley says, “ The first men who substituted the state of mutual peace for that of mutual war, whatever the motive which impelled them to take that step, created society. But, in establishing peace, they obviously put a limit upon the struggle for existence” (Collected Essays, Yol. IX. p. 204). Again, he speaks of “ that struggle for existence — the war of each against all — the mitigation or abolition of which was the chief end of social organisation ” {Ibid., p. 206). 2 Sociology , Yol. II. § 580. PROTECTING LIFE AND PROPERTY. 65 should have the chance to “read newspapers and novels for nothing / 1 why is it not equally wrong that they should get justice for nothing? Why should not those pay for the courts who need them ? Why should the community be taxed for the benefit of a few ? I think that I myself, for example, have never been in a court (on business, I mean) in my life; I believe that I have never had occasion to invoke the aid of a policeman in my life. Why then, if I take a notion to stand on my rights, and to say with Mr. Spencer that I ought not to have my individuality trenched upon by having money taken away from me that I might use for my private ends , 1 may I not claim to be freed from the duty of helping to support courts and policemen? What justice is there — i.e., ac¬ cording to this notion of justice — in my being taxed for what I don’t need or use ? 2 1 Sociology , Vol. II. § 569. 2 It may be said that I may need the help of courts and police¬ men in the future and that indeed I might have needed it in the past — and that my tax is a sort of insurance against risk. Granted. But why should I be compelled to pay for this sort of insurance any more than for insurance on my house or on my 66 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. The answer to such questions (if there be an answer) is to be found in another realm of con¬ ceptions than that which Mr. Spencer makes use of . 1 It is not got by asking, What do I receive and therefore what shall I give, but — What does the community need, and am I a member of the community ? If it does need courts and policemen that it may fulfil the func¬ tions of a true community, and if I belong to it, then in the nature of the case I should do my life ? If I may take my risks in the latter case, why not in the former ? But, in any case, it may be urged, am I not enjoying the protection of police and courts by the act of living in a society in which they exist, and may not the fact that I have never had to call on them explicitly be urged as the best possible testimony to the extent and efficiency of that protection ? If indeed my act of residence in a policed society were my own choice, there would perhaps be no way of meeting this argument and I should have to admit that taxing me for the-support of courts and police¬ men would be justified without departing from individualistic premises. But as I am virtually forced to live here (or, if I go elsewhere, in societies that are similarly policed), I can hardly be equitably compelled to support one social arrangement when I might have preferred another — that is, on the individualistic or quid pro quo view of equity. 1 Mr. Spencer makes use of the conception of a society as an organism, but in a very imperfect way. PROTECTING LIFE AND PROPERTY. fiy part towards enabling it to fulfil these functions, whether I get any exact personal return for my contributions or not. To sum up briefly: if we take strictly the vague popular idea that each man should be the architect of his own fortunes, and that success or failure should depend on the intrinsic worth of each individual , 1 we are conducted straight¬ way to anarchy. Government should cease alto¬ gether (save in time of war), and people should be thrown absolutely upon their own resources . to protect themselves against private aggression of any kind. If, however, we take the social standpoint, if there is any meaning in the concept of a society and any sense in looking at things from that point of view, then may a society interfere to protect the lives and property of its members, — may, not because individuals wish it to interfere, not because a majority determine that it shall interfere, not on the basis of any hocus-pocus of elections or of an 1 Cf. James Weir, Jr., M.D., in Century Magazine, October, 1894, p. 953. 68 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. imaginary social compact , 1 but because in the nature of the case it must interfere or have the right to interfere, else it ceases to be a society, a real whole, a true social body. A society that does not repel an injury against one of its mem¬ bers, or see that it is repelled, is as absurd a thing as an individual man who should not guard and preserve against harm any part of his own body. The different parts make up, are , the man on his physical side; the members are the society. Yet it must be admitted that all that has been said goes only to prove what may be called the right of government, in the connection con¬ sidered ; whether, in addition to this^government is expedient and actually advisable, is another question. As, when a society is attacked from without, it has the right to force its unwilling 1 It is interesting to find Mr. Spencer trying to demonstrate the rightfulness of social action for the protection of life and property (and also the wrongfulness of social action for any further purpose), by imagining how, for example, Englishmen would vote if their wishes were taken now. See “The Great Political Superstition ” in The Alan versus The State and Sociology , Vol. II. § 579, PROTECTING LIFE AND PROPERTY. 69 1 members to lend their assistance, and yet may find it practically better to use no force, but let every one respond to the public need according to his own free will, so in the face of wrong and injuries to its individual members it is conceiv¬ able that it should find it better instead of remedying them itself, to leave this to be done by the individuals concerned or their relatives, or by associations that might spontaneously arise and undertake a righting of wrongs as their special function. It is still a common notion that the industry of a country prospers best when government has least to do with it, that it regulates itself better than society could regulate it; and it is a question whether the protection of life and property may not be safely left to private hands, whether spontaneous regulating agencies would not arise that would do better than any which society could contrive. It is evident that the only inherent social demand is that indi¬ vidual life and property shall be protected, not that this shall be done in a particular manner. If a society sees that protection is 70 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. given, it may be as well as if it gave the pro¬ tection itself. We have really then here a question of ways and means, of practical policy, and not a question of ethical principle. If a society had plenty of Thomas Chilsons at its disposal, it could probably get along without courts for the adjudication of disputes about property. In the same way, if individuals of means and of public spirit would give a society policemen and militia-men, and so prevent or punish crimes against the person, the society would be spared the expense of having its own armed force and its own criminal judiciary. A society, a large body, always acts with difficulty, and if individuals would act in its spirit and in X harmony with its needs, such spontaneous action would make a great saving for the society. A system of liberty or anarchy is always prefer¬ able, if it meets social needs. But there are difficulties with private agencies, whether individual or associated. In the first place, they are liable to be partial, to interest themselves in some individuals and not in others, while the society must PROTECTING LIFE AND PROPERTY. y x ask for the equal protection of all its members. Moreover, and for the same reason, these agencies would have to extend over the entire territory of a society, either by each one of them taking a part of the territory or by all uniting to form one agency for the whole territory ; to arrange all this by private agreement might not be easy. Still further, they would have to avoid clashing with one another, and so, while meaning to serve the public, bring fresh trouble to the public; yet private agencies are apt to clash with one another. And, lastly, they would have to proceed and act according to methods and rules which should commend themselves to the ethical sense of the society as a whole ; and yet private agencies are always disposed to wish to form their own rules and regulations. Practically, then, I suspect that leaving the protection of life and property to private agencies would not work well; it might in an approximately- ideal state of society, it might in exceptional circumstances now; but taking men as they ordinarily are, it would 72 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. be apt to result in more or less of that inse¬ curity, confusion, and disorder which we ordinarily associate with “anarchy” and to which it is the idea of government to put an end. Under the rule of private agencies some persons in the society would be likely to be left defenceless ; the different agencies would be warring more or less with one another; and they would be so likely to want to act their own way that society would be obliged to interfere more or less and say what they might and might not do. Yet such regulation would itself evidently be gov¬ ernment (in essence), and the private associ¬ ations would not be unlike our corporations for various public purposes to-day, whose status, duties, functions, and methods have to be more or less prescribed by law, and which so far from taking the place of govern¬ ment, themselves necessitate government. Moreover, it has been taken for granted that voluntary associations for the protection of life and property would be forthcoming; but as matter of fact, when there has been PROTECTING LIFE AND PROPERTY. 73 a state of liberty or anarchy in the past, such associations have not always arisen, or, if they have, they have been very limited in the operation, and many persons have been left without any real security. Sometimes, too, as in the middle ages, individuals could only get security by sacrificing their freedom — and the not unnatural result of anarchy or liberty in large periods of human history has been lords on the one hand and serfs or slaves on the other . 1 1 As to the practical working of liberty apart from state regulation, the following language of Professor Burgess may be quoted: “ Deprive the state, either wholly or in part, of the power to determine the elements and the scope of individual liberty, and the result must be that each individual will make such determination, wholly or in part, for himself; that the determinations of different individuals will come into conflict with each other; and that those individuals only who have power to help themselves will remain free, reducing the rest to personal subjection.” ( Political Science and Constitutional Law , Vol. I. p. 55.) So Sir James Fitzjames' Stephen says: “ If human experience proves anything at all, it proves that, if restraints are minimized, if the largest possible measure of liberty is accorded to all human beings, the result will not be equality, but inequality, reproducing itself in a geometrical ratio.” ( Liberty , Equality , Fraternity, Chap. IV. p. 182, Eng. Ed.) An illustration of this is furnished in what 74 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. By no means would I underestimate what might be done under liberty or anarchy; one may hope for the time, whether on this earth or elsewhere, when all may be left to the voluntary action of individuals and govern¬ ment pass away; but at present and, I suspect, for a long time to come, society itself will have to act if all its members are Lichtenstein tells us of the Bushmen, viz. that the weaker among them, “ if he would preserve his own life, is obliged to resign to the stronger his weapons, his wife, and even his children.” (Quoted in Spencer’s Sociology, Vol. II. § 536.) A very clever writer, whom no student of theoretical politics should overlook, Mr. Wordsworth Donisthorpe, urges that the right of might is still in place. “ Anarchy! [he says] the word has a dreadful ring about it. Why* it is opposed to property; so it is urged. Not at all. The maxim of the anarchist is, ‘ Let him take who hath the power; let him keep who can.’ That is property, is it not? ‘ But what is to pre¬ vent the strong from robbing the weak? Suppose the many, finding themselves poor, take it into their heads to expropriate the few, what then? ’ Why not? If it can be shown that the robbery of the rich can be effected — effected with advan¬ tage to the poor, I cannot see for the life of me why it should not be done. It is contrary to morality? . . . But J deny it. Morality is co-extensive with self-interest.” (Individu¬ alism: A System of Politics , p. 257.) If Anarchy had any necessary connotation of this sort, we should have to reject it on principle. PROTECTING life and property. 7 5 to be properly protected, and progress will only be made by strengthening its arms and leading it to do more perfectly the work it has already undertaken. Private effort may answer for single individuals, but the only instrument that can be reasonably expected (as things are) to serve all — all, no matter who they be or how much they pay into the social fund, all simply by virtue of their mem¬ bership in the society — is that which is the representative of the society, made not by indi¬ viduals, but by the society ; namely, government. A man who pays not a cent of taxes may yet under government, when threatened with robbery or murder, have the whole resources of the commonwealth to defend him against the wrong. It is not a question of how much he pays, but of membership in the society. What voluntary association could be. expected to do the like ? Even the pqrson who has committed a crime can not have private vengeance wreaked on him; the officer of the law steps in and says that the man can be punished only after due ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. trial. The individual who breaks the law has rights protected by law — in modern societies. It is sometimes said that progress is away from status to contract — and there is much truth in the assertion. But it is not after all, owing to any contract that a member of a modern civilized soci¬ ety has the protection of life and property of which I am speaking; he has it simply in virtue of his membership in the society; it is not a contract¬ ual relation at all, but a vital, organic relation. We must, of course, admit that modern socie¬ ties perform this duty of protecting the lives and property of their members very imperfectly; but to say that they ought not to perform it at all, that every one ought to take care of himself or at least provide for himself by contracting with others more powerful than he, since anything else involves an interference with liberty, is to go from the modern world to feudalism, from civilization back to barbarism. Anarchy as an expedient is debatable; it may always be a ques¬ tion how far it is better, wiser, for a society as such to act, and how far it is better to leave things in individual hands. But anarchy as a matter PROTECTING LIFE AND PROPERTY. 77 of right, anarchy based on the notion that a society has no business to act, since this in¬ volves an interference with the freedom of indi¬ viduals,— anarchy founded on the idea that each person is his own master and has an inherent sacred right to do as he pleases uncon¬ strained,—is, from a social point of view, absurd . * 1 There is no individual right to act against the common good ; strictly speaking, it may even be questioned whether we have a right to act against our own good — we may be left free (whether by nature or by society) to do so, but it may well be held that we have a positive right to act only in consistency with our welfare (to the extent we know it). So far as I can make out, there is no such thing under heaven, as the right to do as we please — using the phrase, “as we please,” with scientific strictness . 2 1 If a distinction is made between Government and the State, it may be said that anarchy as against Government is debatable, but as against the State it is absurd — understand¬ ing by the State the power and right of a society to act (sover¬ eignty), and by Government the actual use of that power. 2 On the whole subject of individual rights, compare the searching and exhaustive criticism of Professor D. G. Ritchie, in his Natural Rights (London, 1895). 73 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. The right of government then would seem to be fully made out, so far as the protection of life and property is concerned, as well as for purposes of defensive war. As to the expedi¬ ency of government in this relation, opinions may differ. For this is a question of fact: if government is not necessary, no one would advocate it — no one can believe in restrictions on freedom on their own account; no one could favor government if it did not seem, as con¬ trasted with the method of liberty or anarchy, the better expedient of the two. All that we can say is that the experience of mankind seems to point to government as the better expedient. Yet we should not be too confident, and the libertarian may have a great deal to say, to which we might profitably listen, about the inefficiency of present government and the possibility that private enterprise might do most of the things that government now does, and do them equally well or better. It is a mistake and a great superstition to suppose that government is something that goes right of itself. When government is a failure, it is in- PROTECTING LIFE AND PROPERTY. 79 deed a more colossal failure than any private enterprise could possibly be. By the very greatness of its possible dignity as an agent of society as a whole, is measured the depth of its possible shame, —as an old Latin proverb says that the worst things are the corruption of the best . 1 We expect great things of the united action of an entire society — we look for something commensurate with the sweep and vastness of the energies that are in operation, and we should find it. 1 A discussion of the possibilities — and I might say of the actualities — of wAgovernment would make a book by itself. It must be borne in mind that I am not weighing the arguments pro and con for government, as it usually exists ; I am raising the more fundamental question, why government should exist at all — even supposing it serves its proper ends. , ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT IN PROMOTING THE HIGHER ENDS OF LIFE. CHAPTER VI. ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT IN PROMOTING THE HIGHER ENDS OF LIFE. May the method of government be used for other ends than those I have already men¬ tioned ? May a society, as such, rightfully act to procure other blessings than those of suc¬ cessful defense in war, and of security for the lives and possessions of its members ? I fail to see why not — why not, that is, if it needs to and can do 'so with success. Aristotle remarked that political communities arose “for the sake of life,” but that they continued for “the sake of good life .” 1 It is not enough for a community, or for its members, to exist; they should attain some development and per¬ fection of being . 2 A community may, for aught 1 Politics , i. 2 ; cf. iii. 9. 2 Logically prior to this is the consideration of the problem of providing the means of subsistence, to which I devote a special chapter later on (Chap. VII.). 83 8 4 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. I can see, provide for the education of its members, with the same right with which it acts for their personal security. If it be objected that people ought to provide for their own education, the same thing might be said with reference to public provision for the security of each one’s person and posses- sions. The argument which Mr. Spencer urges against public education conducts straightway to a thoroughly atomistic conception of society, — a conception which, if acted on, would dissolve society. All the same a society might leave education in private hands as a matter of policy. It might be better that it should, if individuals of means and public spirit were forthcoming who would meet the entire public need. The only justification of social action is that individuals are not likely to do so, that some portions of the community may be unprovided for; the positive reason for soci¬ ety’s action is simply that the needs of all (whether as regards themselves or their chil¬ dren) may in some measure be met — just as PROMOTING THE HIGHER ENDS OF LIFE. §5 the reason for social action for the protection of life and property is that this blessing may not depend on an accident or a contract, but may come to each one as an organic right. So with training in the sense of the beauti¬ ful. I see not how a person can be said to have any natural right to put up an ugly build¬ ing in the community. It may be less bother¬ some to let him have his own way; but, on the other hand, if a community, feeling that a certain amount of order and symmetry in the architecture on its streets is desirable for the sake of the training in the appreciation of beautiful things which this would give to the citizens, proceeds to make certain legislative requirements to that effect, I can discover no rightful liberties that are curtailed by so doing. By spectacles also, by celebrations and noble amusements, a community may provide for the aesthetic training of its members, as certain of the Greek cities used to do. All depends, of course, on whether the community needs to act for these ends and can act with advantage; for if individuals of their own motion would 86 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. do all that was required, this would be simpler and better. In a similar way, a society may encourage the sort of family life which experience proves to be the best for the interests of the society, namely, by giving public sanction to that type of marriage and refusing it to any other. So it might even act to encourage the best type of religion, if it could be conceived to know enough to be able to say which is the best type. I do not mean that it should act in this realm ; rather I am certain that under present circumstances and perhaps under any circum¬ stances likely to be actual, it should not. But I can discover no reason for contesting its abstract right to act in this manner, in certain conceivable circumstances. The position of John Stuart Mill seems the reasonable one, who held it inadmissible to say that “the protection of persons and that of property” were “the sole purposes of gov¬ ernment.” “The ends of government,” he said, “are as comprehensive as those of the social union. They consist of all the good, and all PROMOTING THE HIGHER ENDS OF LIFE. gy the immunity from evil, which the existence of government can be made either directly or indirectly to bestow .” 1 In other words, no line of principle can be drawn as to how far a soci¬ ety may go, and where it must stop, in securing social welfare . 2 We can only say that it may go as far as it needs to go and can go. If it does not need to do this or that, since private 1 Principles of Political Economy , Book V. chap. ii. sec. 2. 2 I am aware that as a matter of practical policy Mill urged that “letting alone should be the general practice,” and “that every departure from it, unless required by some great good, is a certain evil.” ( Principles of Political Economy , Book V. chap, xi.) But the fact that he says, “ unless required by some great good,” shows how far removed he was from those who regard laisser faire as an absolute principle. The presump¬ tion might be said to be in the same way against government interference for the protection of life and property; it is only because this is “required by some great good,” that the pre¬ sumption is overridden. This also seems to have been ad¬ mitted by Professor W. S. Jevons (with special reference to industrial problems), who regarded laisser faire as, in gen¬ eral, a sound practical rule, but not as a principle. Cf. the language of the Preface to his The State in Relation to Labor. “The all-important point is to explain if possible why, in general, we uphold the rule of laisser faire , and yet in large classes of cases invoke the interference of local or central authorities.” 88 AiVARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. individuals are able and willing to do the same, surely it should not; or, even if it would be better that it should do a certain thing, it should not attempt the task, if it is not really equal to it. Liberty or anarchy is always sim¬ pler and better if it will meet social require¬ ments. The question then of how far practically a society should go at any given time and in the midst of any given set of circumstances, is not a question that can be determined by abstract considerations. It is a question, not for theorists, but for practical men of affairs, — for those who know the circumstances, and who by their experience and training are fitted to judge about them. Here is the field of statesmanship, and one man, acquainted with history and in touch with the tendencies of his time and the actual stream of events, is worth a dozen closet philosophers. Political philosophy itself can not take the place of political training and the best service such philosophy can render the statesman is to help him get rid of false PROMOTING THE HIGHER ENDS OF LIFE, gg principles and of superstitions , 1 to assist him to an open, plastic mind, and make him free to act in view of the circumstances that confront him. 1 If careful ethical and political thinking tends to dissipate superstitions about government, it equally tends to dissipate superstitions about rights against government. ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT IN THE INDUSTRIAL REALM. 4 f CHAPTER VII. ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT IN THE INDUSTRIAL REALM. I now take up a question of peculiar difficulty. In the realm of industry, which is better — the method of liberty or the method of gov¬ ernment ? All our instinctive feelings and pre¬ possessions are in favor of liberty. This is as it should be, for government always requires special justification. Let us, however, look into the matter. Mr. Spencer says, “The continued existence of a society implies, first, that it shall not be destroyed bodily by foreign foes, and implies, second, that it shall not be destroyed in detail by failure of its members to support and propa¬ gate themselves.” 1 This latter presupposition brings before us what may be broadly called 1 Sociology , Vol. II. § 563. 93 94 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. the industrial problem. How shall a society proceed, to the end that its members may not fail to support and propagate themselves ? — this is the industrial problem from the social point of view. It might be said that a society does best by leaving its members to provide for them¬ selves, — individually or by free association; that a spontaneous organization thereby arises better than any that could be consciously con¬ trived. This is only saying that anarchy is better than government in this relation — save in so far as government keeps the peace and holds men to their contracts with one another. But the question is one of fact and cannot be determined a priori. It surely does not follow of itself, because a society should preserve itself against an enemy and against starvation, that the only way to do the latter is to leave each individual to shift for himself or to get such help as he can by contracting with others. The strong and capable can doubtless meet their needs in this way, and many of the weak might find a place of some sort in an order of THE INDUSTRIAL REALM. 95 things of this description, but there can scarcely be said to be a guarantee that all would — and what would there be to hinder the strong from taking advantage of the weak in the contracts made between them ? It is conceivable, then, that in place of leaving individuals to themselves, a society should somehow attempt to organize the industrial activity of its members, and guar¬ antee subsistence and corresponding work to all,—just as societies now undertake to pro¬ tect all from aggression, irrespective of their ability to protect themselves. Mr. Spencer would indeed object to such a method as involving inequity. For if there were sociab- (i.e. governmental) action for industrial ends, the strong and the capable would be obliged to support a scheme for which they might get no corresponding bene¬ fit, and which would not, indeed, be intended for their special benefit. And, on the other hand, the less capable members of the society might get benefits that their own individual efforts would not enable them to attain. All this would be inequity according to Mr. Spen- 96 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. cer. And plainly, if the rule of equity or justice is as he states it, namely, that “the superior shall have the good of his superiority and the inferior the evil of his inferiority,” or that people shall “take the consequences of their conduct, neither increased or decreased ,” 1 then is social action unjust which puts the inferior anywise on an equality with the supe¬ rior, even if it be only in guaranteeing to them (in exchange for work) the necessaries of life. But we have seen that on similar grounds it might be held wrong to protect the weak from the natural results of their inferiority in the loss of their property or life — and if the social, as opposed to the in¬ dividualistic point of view, is justified in the one connection, it is difficult to see any a priori reason why it may not be justified in the other. The question is, of course, twofold: one of fundamental principle, the other of ways and means or expediency. The former runs back to this: Do we wish all to live? — all, 1 Sociology , Vol. II. § 567. THE INDUSTRIAL REALM. 97 that is, who are willing to work and behave themselves. We may not so wish ; we may follow the suggestions of certain naturalists,- and say that only those should live who can maintain themselves in a competitive struggle for existence — the robust, vigorous, self-rely¬ ing, no matter if in individual cases somewhat unscrupulous, members of the species. We may say that the earth belongs to them, and that we should not by any laws or types of social organization hinder them from win¬ ning the victory. This is the question of principle, of fundamental ethical theory. If we answer it in the way just indicated, we are bound to oppose social interference in the industrial realm, and may, if sternly logical, oppose government for protecting life and property as well. But if we take the ground that all members of a society, unless positively unworthy, somehow have claims on the soci¬ ety, if we have a sense of social unity and solidarity,—then we are in an absolutely dif¬ ferent camp of social theory; there is no pos¬ sible reconciliation that I can see between H gg ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. those who take the individualistic 1 and the social point of view. Yet even if we take the social point of view, it does not of itself follow that we shall favor the social organization of industry. As in deal¬ ing with the protection of life and property, we saw that it was a question of expediency whether a society should itself give this protec¬ tion or should leave it to be provided by indi¬ viduals and voluntary associations, itself simply seeing that this was done, so as regards pro¬ vision for the material wants of its members, it may itself act with this end in view or may leave it to individuals and voluntary associa¬ tions to act, simply seeing that the provision is actually made. In other words, we have here too a question of expediency rather than of ethical principle. If a society sees that none 1 1 am aware that “ individualism ” is used in various senses, and on account of this vagueness I eschew the word altogether in the present discussion. But the sense in which I here use “ individualistic ” has been made plain by the preceding paragraph. A true individualism, however, might be said to be entirely reconcilable with the social point of view; for the good of individuals may be held to be the final end of social action. THE INDUSTRIAL REALM. 99 of its members suffer want (without blame of their own), it is as good as if it provided against that want itself. Social oversight, social right of action, is involved in the very notion of a society ; but whether a society shall act or no, whether it has a duty to act, is in this realm, as in every other, simply a question of practical judgment in view of the facts and circumstances at hand. Viewing the matter in this light then, we have simply to ask, How do things go when individuals are left to themselves ? How does liberty or anarchy work ? And more particu¬ larly : Do individuals succeed when put upon their own resources ? Do all who are willing to work get the chance to work ? Do the stronger respect the weaker and refuse to take advantage of them ? Do all share in some measure in the benefits, conveniences, and comforts that go to make up the material basis of life ? If these questions can be answered in the affirmative, liberty or anarchy in this realm is surely justi¬ fied. Even if social action could accomplish the same result, anarchy would be better, since 100 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. social action (men being what they are) involves the use of more or less constraint or force, and constraint, even the wisest and justest, is, in itself considered, an evil. But if liberty or anarchy does not work in the manner described, if it leaves some members of the society unpro¬ vided for (through no fault of their own), if it allows the weak to be taken advantage of by the strong, if it results not in trifling but in great inequalities of material circumstance, then it is not justified. What are the facts ? We have them in a measure before us to-day; for while anarchy or liberty has passed away as regards the protec¬ tion of life and property, and government is in its place, we live in an order of anarchy or liberty (substantially) as regards the industrial needs of the community. So we can actually observe. What do we see ? A trained sociologist ought to answer this question and what a layman like myself can say may not have much value. But my impression is that in this free industrial order in which we live, a great many have hardly enough to eat, THE INDUSTRIAL REALM. IOI and not because they are unable and unwilling to work ; 1 that a great many more,—a large number, — while they have enough to eat, have little or no share in the comforts and decencies of life; further, that there is a large, growing class of the unemployed, or irregularly em¬ ployed, for whom there is little or no work to do, mechanical inventions tending to make men’s labor more and more unnecessary (as electric wires make horses to draw street cars unnecessary), the human-being having, however, nothing but his labor to live on; still further, that the stronger members of the industrial organism are apt to take advantage of the weaker, to drive hard bargains with them, to get their labor for as little as they can — so that as a result they, the stronger, get more than a fair share of the wealth that is jointly produced, a result attributable not to the fact that they are of superior ability, but to the fact that their ability is rare (and in their rareness their economic strength consists), while the laborers are at a disadvantage not because it is 1 1 do not deny that some are in want through their own fault. 102 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. only labor they have to sell, but because this labor is plentiful (wherein consists their eco¬ nomic weakness) ; and hence the division into classes, the inequalities of condition and advan¬ tage, the misunderstandings, the enmities, and perhaps now and then public disorder and riot. So far as I can judge, then, it would be stretching a point to say unqualifiedly that liberty or anarchy in industrial affairs works well. What we can say is that the world somehow gets along under it, that society does not go to pieces without government in this rela¬ tion any more than it did without government for the protection of life and property; that the weak suffer the natural consequences of their lack of endowments and at the worst starve (though they do not strictly need to, as there are generally workhouses or poorhouses in which they may take refuge); while on the other hand the superior members of the race, as Mr. Spencer would call them, get the re¬ wards of their superiority, and society goes on. Yet I doubt if any one would hold that all this satisfies the social consciousness. Some- THE INDUSTRIAL REALM. 103 how we say instinctively from a social point of view that there ought to be an industrial order in which all the able-bodied members of a society should have a place, in which all should contribute according to their strength and varying gifts, and in which all should in turn receive in not greatly unequal measure from the fund of wealth produced. If it is really true that this does not tend to be ac¬ complished under liberty or anarchy, then there would seem to be no other course than for the society to see what it can do itself. If leaving individuals to themselves results not in satisfying the needs of the social body or the requirements of the social conscious¬ ness, but in excessive wealth on the one hand, and excessive poverty on the other, in social disorder and private war, and even in the loss of opportunity in some cases to get a living by labor at all, then would industrial liberty or anarchy appear to condemn itself. Of course all would be different if individuals were universally moralized ( i.e . socialized in thought and disposition); in that case, free- 104 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. dom might bring all that social action (gov¬ ernment) could bring—and more. But before proceeding further, let us notice a little more closely the peculiar conditions under which the industrial problem presents itself at the present time. They are not con¬ ditions that have always existed. The marked phenomenon of modern industrial society is the extent to which the division of labor is carried. Where men produce directly their own means of subsistence, they of course get what they produce. In primitive agricultural regions this is still sometimes the case. Even when an exchange of products takes place, there is apt to be a substantial equivalence between what is bought and what is sold. But in a complicated state of industrial soci¬ ety such as generally exists in modern com¬ munities, no one literally gets what he pro¬ duces, nor would it always be of use to him if he did. The shoemaker can not live on shoes ; he wants bread. The carpet weaver can not live on carpets; he wants a house and clothes to cover himself with. The railroad president THE INDUSTRIAL REALM. 105 does not make his living, — hardly any of us do,—we make or do something and in ex¬ change for this, get our living. In short, what one produces and what one gets are two distinct things, and there seems to be no necessary connection between them. How is what one gets determined (under the present system) ? Not really by the util¬ ity of what one produces and has to sell, not either by the cost of producing it and bring¬ ing it to market; but rather by the quantity of things of the same sort that happen to be in the market. If there is much of it, buyers can take advantage of the producer, and give little; if there is little, the producer can take advantage of those who wish to buy, and get much. / Such is the working and meaning of the so-called law of supply and demand. And Mr. Spencer seems to regard this as justice. “ In the average of cases,” he says, “a pro¬ portioning of rewards to personal merits naturally takes place under the free play of supply and demand .” 1 He thinks that the 1 “ A Rejoinder to M. de Laveleye,” Contemporary Review , I0 6 anarchy or government. only business of government, in this relation, is to maintain those conditions under which a free play of supply and demand is possible . 1 “ Interferences with the law of supply and demand,” of which there have been so many instances in English legislation, he roundly de¬ nounces as among the “sins of legislators .” 2 Now I confess I can not see that what takes place under the so-called law of supply and demand has anything to do with justice (save by accident). I admit that what men do get ordinarily depends upon this law (and there is no objection to calling it, loosely speaking, a “law”), but that this has anything to do with what they ought to get, I see no reason for holding. It may be more than they ought to April, 1885. Cf. the language of Professor W. G. Sumner: “The distribution which takes place under the free play of sup¬ ply and demand gives us our definition of justice, as applied to the contribution which an individual puts into social effort and the share he gets out of the social product. There is no other definition of justice which can be seriously considered.” (.Princeton Review , November, 1882.) This is sufficiently positive. 1 Sociology, Vol. II. §§ 567, 568. 2 “ The Sins of Legislators ” in The Man versus The State. THE INDUSTRIAL REALM. 107 get, and it may be less — accidentally it may be the same ; but in principle I do not see that the things have anything in common. Let me illustrate. In the little town of Weymouth, Mass., a few summers ago, there was a great scarcity of ice — almost an ice famine. Strange to say, one dealer did not put up his prices. “Why?” he was one day asked. “Why?” he replied, “Why should I? It has n’t cost me any more.” The honest countryman was a very simple individual according to the standards of our cur¬ rent political economy. For, from this stand¬ point, it would be said that the supply of ice not being equal to the demand for it, the price should rise to a point at which only a few could afford to buy it, and so the ratio of supply and demand be equalized again. Probably most of the dealers in the neighborhood acted on this principle. Whether they knew anything of political economy or no, they knew their chance and probably made the most of it. But this one simply reasoned that the ice having cost him no more than usual, he did io8 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. not need to charge more, and could sell as he ordinarily had, to cover the cost and his customary rate of profit. It probably looked to him like taking advantage of people, to put up the price. In other words, it seemed fairer and squarer not to act in accordance with the so-called law of supply and demand than to act in accordance with it—and I suspect that, looking at the matter abstractly, we should all agree with him . 1 1 1 beg that my illustration of the simple-minded country¬ man be taken in the way I use it. If, instead of charging as he did, he had put up the price with the thought of making up for losses he had sustained the previous year or of anticipating losses he feared he should meet with another year, this would have been nowise inconsistent with the standard of fairness he had in his mind; it would simply mean that he estimated cost for a term of years instead of for one year. It would, however, be equally consistent with the so-called law of supply and demand, to put up the price regardless of such considerations — simply on the principle of charging as much as “ the traffic would bear.” I am simply maintaining that “ supply and demand ” furnishes no guarantee of fairness. On the other hand, I do not forget that there may be a certain economic advantage (whatever the seller’s intentions) in a rise of prices in time of scarcity — that is, so far as it tends to make persons (those who buy at all) less wasteful. Further, if the line between those who do and those who do not buy were on a THE INDUSTRIAL REALM. IO9 Fairness, equity, justice then, instead of being what takes place under a free play of the law of supply and demand, may in certain circumstances consist, according to one old- fashioned standard, precisely in disregarding that law. Yet Mr. Spencer would say that to enforce justice of this sort would be wrong (that it might be inadvisable, any one would grant ), 1 that to interfere with free contract basis of needs, if it could be made out that those who need the article in question most would be those who could afford or, at least, would be able (without grossly unequal sacrifice) to get it, the objections on grounds of justice would fall away. If I am asked what practically could take the place of the regulating influence of supply and demand, I can only answer, that the advisability of which in general we are here discuss¬ ing— namely, some kind of social action. If there were a scarcity of some necessary article, the society might give notice accordingly and say that only those who really needed it should have it — that, for example, ice for ice-water and for champagne was not to be had, the supply being only sufficient for cases of sickness. The price, however, would not need to rise beyond some relation to the cost of production. In this way the less well-to-do might still be able to get ice, while under a regime of supply and demand it might be put quite beyond their reach (save at an enormous sacrifice). Indeed the rich might want it for water and champagne more effectively than others for dire need. 1 Though not necessarily, or in all circumstances, inadvisable. 110 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. was vicious in principle, that society had no business to do anything but maintain those conditions under which an ice-dealer could put up his prices to any point at which a customer would (or might, because of dire necessity, be obliged to) buy. It seems to me on the other hand that not only has society no absolute duty to keep up such conditions, not only has so- called freedom of contract no inherent sanctity, but that it is purely a question of expediency whether a society shall in certain circumstances maintain these conditions or shall interfere with them; i.e. whether it shall allow or abridge freedom of contract. In other words, freedom of contract is not, in and of itself, a right, any more than any other kind of freedom, if used against social advantage. In a complex organization of industry like the present one, then, it is a matter of accident whether the free play of supply and demand (free contract) works what most people would call justice or not. If unlimited production of useful things were possible and if all men were equally gifted and were situated in something THE INDUSTRIAL REALM. 111 like similar circumstances, it probably would — not because men meant to do justice, but because they would be virtually compelled to do it. But these are imaginary suppositions. To speak of only one of them, —and the one which goes to the root of all, — men are not made equal. They may have equal rights, but that is another matter. They are not equal in fact. Those capable of organizing and leading industrial enterprise are in a minority, are indeed few; hence they can put a price on their services which would be impossible if they were many. Their services are not worth more on this account, but they can get more for them. Because the community needs their services and cannot perhaps get along with¬ out them, they can, if they like, put “famine prices” on the commodity (organizing and directing talent) which they have to sell; while, on the other hand, those who have only labor or physical skill, though they are just as neces¬ sary, are many, and hence can about as readily be taken advantage of as the others can take advantage. 112 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. These things being so, it seems idle to expect (men being not unwilling to take advantage of one another, as so often happens) that the free play of supply and demand will work substan¬ tial justice; and it may be doubted whether, save in exceptional circumstances, it works justice at all. It is an illusion to imagine, as Mr. Spencer does, that under the free action of supply and demand a person gets what he gives; he gets simply what he can get, which may be more and may be less than he gives. The free exchange of Jacob and Esau is well known. None the less does jus¬ tice absolutely condemn the bargain—as every child who hears the story will bear witness. Indeed, it is a question if this sort of a notion of justice is applicable in a highly complex form of industrial society. It is, of course, where a man works for himself and exchanges finished products with another; but when he works for others and is part of a great industrial machine, what he gives is a more or less minute part of a social prod¬ uct and the value of it may be almost im- THE INDUSTRIAL REALM. 113 possible to tell , 1 and what he gets may be determined without the slightest reference to that, but on an entirely different basis; namely, by how many people there are ready to do the same thing, and what is the lowest any one is willing to do it for. But in a normal type of social organization, an individual gets back more than he gives; he gives what he can or needs to give, and in turn receives of all the benefits of social organization (so far as he needs them); if he needs protection for his life or possessions, he may get a great deal more than he ever paid for, and if he needs education for his children, it is quite as little a question of a quid pro quo. As a member he simply gets whatever the society, of which he is a part, is able to give ; the riches of the whole go to each one, accord¬ ing to his circumstances and needs. Of course, 1 Cf. Schaffle, “ The proportionate share of each in the value created by a joint product can not possibly be determined in associated production of any kind, whether under the capital¬ istic system or in the socialistic plan which excludes private capital.” ( The Impossibility of Social Democracy, p. 75.) ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. 114 this is where one not only gives as a member, but receives as a member. But if one received only what he was able to bargain for, his share in social benefits would be a matter of accident and might be very small. If, for instance, under the present organi¬ zation of society, a man paid taxes according to his ability, but, when it came to protect¬ ing him against robbery or assault, he received only as much protection as he was able to bargain for or buy at the time, he might get little or none, if he was poor. But this, we plainly see, would do violence to our very idea of a political society. For this implies that when one does his duty to the society, one gets from it whatever in the way of pro¬ tection he needs — so that if one pays little, or even nothing, the whole resources of the society none the less come to his assistance in time of need. This is only saying that, so far as the protection of life and property is concerned, the organic idea of society is completely carried out; that a member is a member altogether; that he receives as well THE INDUSTRIAL REALM. 115 as gives an organic part of the whole, and contractual relations no longer exist. In a social organization of the industry of a people the same thing, in essence, would be true. Under such an arrangement one would work, would cast in his contribution to the fund of social wealth, but would not be left to his own devices to get what he could in return. He would work as a duty, and receive as a right, just as he now receives the protection of his person and goods as a right. If a man is left to bargain for police protec¬ tion, we call the society in which this hap¬ pens a corrupt political society. That is, in the one realm as in the other contracting would so far cease to exist, and at least a minimum of the necessaries and comforts of life would be provided for all (save the unworthy). I realize how great a change this would involve in the industrial constitution of soci¬ ety; or rather it is so great a change that it is difficult to bring home to ourselves what it would involve. We could perhaps only find anything that could be compared to it H6 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. if we imagined a state of things now in which every man was his own policeman, in which the weaker were left defenceless or else were driven into bargains with the powerful in which they virtually lost their lib¬ erty, and then that the society in which this was the case awoke to the thought that this insecurity, defencelessness, and enslavement of many of its members were intolerable, and hence that it must somehow try to organize itself as a whole, as one united body, to pro¬ tect the lives, liberties, and possessions of all alike. This too would be a great change, and if we were living in the midst of an order of thorough-going anarchy of the kind de¬ scribed, we might think that the change was impracticable, that for the society to act as a body, — to organize itself throughout its entire domain, — for the ends mentioned, would be too gigantic a task. It is not strange then that we think in a similar manner when we contemplate the idea of society organizing itself as a whole for industrial ends now. However intolerable the THE INDUSTRIAL REALM. II 7 present industrial anarchy, we may ask our¬ selves, Can government successfully take its place? Can such a change as has been sug¬ gested be effected ? It may well be that present societies are not up to the task of organizing industry in the way proposed; that if they essayed it, they would break down, and in sheer incompetence would have to leave individuals to shift for themselves. It may always be that only one way out of a difficulty exists, and yet that we are unable to take the way, — as a man who has fallen into deep water might save himself if he could swim, and yet may not be able to swim. Modern societies do not discharge their present tasks so well that we can have unmixed confidence as to their capacity to do more. And yet some societies do better than others — government is not everywhere conducted in so second-rate a manner as it is here in America — and perhaps all of them might do better than at present. The trouble, it must be remembered, is not in any irreme¬ diable cause, but in the lack of public spirit, ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. Eh in the feebly developed social consciousness, among the members of the societies, — some¬ thing particularly true in the case of a con¬ glomerate society still in the process of making, like our own Moreover, the change might be accom¬ plished gradually. For a society to attempt all at once to regulate the entire industrial life of its members, would be folly. But if it proceeded step by step, making sure of itself as it went along, it might not fare so ill. We must remember that most societies already perform ...certn ur ~ ind nstrial—funotions. They, for example, provide highways for their mem¬ bers to walk or drive on, and bridges over the streams or tunnels under them; they ordinarily transport the letters of the mem¬ bers to their destination. All this might be done by private enterprise, and tolls be charged for passage along the streets and highways, and the charges allowed to go as high as the traffic would bear. But societies generally find it better to render such ser¬ vices themselves, and charge simply for the THE INDUSTRIAL REALM 1 19 cost of them — or, if they allow toll-roads and toll-bridges in certain places, they regu¬ late their charges and so assert control over them. There seems to be no reason in the nature of things why if they go so far, they should not go farther — why, for instance, they should not transmit our telegrams and our express parcels as well as our letters (England, we know, does this), why in these days when rapid movement is such a neces¬ sity they should not construct railways as well as make streets and highways (as Ger¬ many does). And as little does there seem to be any absolute reason why a society should not manage the mining of the coal in its domain, or of the silver or the gold, and the digging of the oil that lies within its territory, and the raising of the harvests and the manufacture of the goods needed by its members. In fact, I see no a priori reason why it should not do anything it can do, if the needs of the community would be thereby better met than they are at present. 120 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. This question is a practical one, not one of abstract theory. What is a society able to do and what does it need to do satisfac¬ torily to meet the industrial wants of its mem¬ bers ?— that is the essence of it. Talk about the abstract rights of individuals to act as they please unrestrained by law and government, has about as much pertinence and value as declamation against government interference to curb the strong and protect the weak in interests of life and property. A society has as much right to act in the one realm as in the other. The only question is, Can it act to advantage ? In a given case — as, for example, in relation to railroad transporta¬ tion— the question is simply, Is there need of government interference or are private agencies doing already well enough, and, secondly, are we sure, even if there is need, that government can help matters ? Just what form social action shall take is a question of detail. Government may either manage itself or may control private manage¬ ment. In either case, it is social action — i.e. THE INDUSTRIAL REALM. 121 government and not liberty or anarchy. If a society says, railways may charge only so and so much a mile, or may not discriminate in their charges between shippers, this is in essence regulation (i.e. refusal to leave things to regu¬ late themselves) as truly as if the society owned the railways. It is at once seen that if gov¬ ernment fixed fares, fixed wages and set a limit beyond which a division of profits should not go, it would be about the same as if government managed the railroads ; under such circum¬ stances they would hardly any longer belong to the category of private business and would become in effect public agencies. Something like this is the case with the companies that have charge of the liquor traffic in Norway and Sweden according to the Gothenburg system ; they are strictly regulated — they can only divide profits up to a certain point, all the sur¬ plus going to public purposes. It may very well be that such an arrangement is better than for the cities in question to attempt to conduct the liquor traffic in propria persona. Taking all things into account, I believe that 122 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. the sound general tendency for modern so¬ cieties is to assert themselves more and more in the industrial realm (whether by one specific method or another). I believe that here as elsewhere anarchy or liberty should more and more give way to government. If men were at heart just, — all men, —there would be no need of this, or, for that matter, of government at all; or if all were equal, even if they were not just, there might be no need of it. But as they are not equal and as many are all too ready to take advantage of the rest, society must act, if it conceives itself as a so¬ ciety at all. It must express its sense of what is reasonable and right, and make all its mem¬ bers bound by it. Laws are always, at least when enacted, ahead of some people (though in a democratic society like ours they express the average sense and conscience of the people); they so far involve constraint. It would, of course, be better if societies could get along without constraint, but thus far in the history of humanity they do not seem to have been able to — and progress for THE INDUSTRIAL REALM. 123 the present is, I believe, in the direction not of less, but of more constraint . 1 No unvary¬ ing rule can be laid down, but this, in general and in the long run, is, I believe, the sound tendency. And in my judgment this tendency will not have worked itself out to its legiti¬ mate result, until the whole industrial life of a people conforms to the requirements of the social conscience, until every able-bodied person has a place in the industrial order, until industrial inventions and improvements become at last public property and accrue to the common benefit — to the end that all the 1 Not of course for all, which would be absurd, but for the few whose instincts and ambitions lead them into antisocial courses of conduct. I have not perhaps sufficiently dwelt upon the fact that law, while it means constraint for some, always means liberty for others and possibly the only kind of liberty they enjoy, and that in a democratic society, law may mean liberty far more than it does constraint — liberty for the mass, and constraint only for those who do not find their interests in harmony with those of the mass. Liberty may in one sense be said to be largely created by government — as Professor Burgess has clearly shown in his distinguished work, Political Science and Constitutional Law. A fresh instance of how law may preserve or even create liberty would be given in case corporations were forbidden to \ 124 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. members of a society alike may reap the advan¬ tages (in increased enjoyment and lessened toil) of advancing civilization . 1 I have said that in the long run social action and regulation represent the sound tendency. And yet I equally make bold to say that in the still longer run, and consider¬ ing not the course, but the issue of things, social action will tend to become unnecessary; that owing to the increasing depth and perva¬ siveness of the social consciousness, the forms of discharge employees for activity in labor organizations. Under readily conceivable (and sometimes actual) circumstances, the employees of a corporation may practically have little or no liberty (in respect to association for the improvement of their economic condition) in the absence of such a law. The Legis¬ lature of Missouri passed an act to this effect in 1893; an d it is interesting, as indicating the confused state of the public mind in reference to the subject, that another organ of the public will of this Commonwealth — the Supreme Court — has declared the act unconstitutional, on the ground of its interference with the right of terminating a contract. Another illustration of abridging freedom to secure more freedom would be to forbid the employment of women and children in factories for more than a certain number of hours a day. Without the aid of such legislation women and children may have no real choice in the matter. But see infra , p. 158 n. 1 This may by some be called Socialism. But “ Socialism ” THE INDUSTRIAL REALM. 125 social regulation will more and more become mere forms,—not that men will ever rebel against them or care to undo them , 1 but that they will spontaneously harmonize with their requirements, just as many do with the laws against robbery and murder and adultery now and would, though the laws were blotted out. I hold in perfect consistency to the two ideals, — government now and an end of gov¬ ernment in time to come. The social con¬ sciousness, in proportion as it is real, demands is an historical word and I have wished simply to develope my own thoughts without going into the question as to how far they agree with the thoughts of others. One may always have a doubt how far he has the right to claim or to disclaim an historical name. I hope my readers will be good enough to let my argu¬ ments stand on their own merits. I must add, too, that Social¬ ism like Individualism is a word that has been used in so many senses that it has to be either very carefully defined or else, in my judgment, avoided altogether in a scientific treatise. Such definitions as Professor Flint’s, “ any theory of social organ¬ ization which sacrifices the legitimate liberties of individuals to the will and interests of the community,” ( Socialism , 1895) ^ eacl nowhere and are simply ludicrous. For my own part I do not see that a true Socialism need be anywise incompatible with a true Individualism. See supra , p. 98 n. 1 By this I do not mean that many laws ought not to be undone, just as no small part of political progress in the past 126 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. government under existing circumstances; but finally the social consciousness may be so per¬ fect that government will be allowed to drop away like an out-grown shell. To work for the enlarging and deepening and spreading of the social consciousness in the minds of our American people, to increase the sense of our belonging to one another, to make us feel more and more that an injury to one is an injury to all, is, in my judgment, one of the great ethical tasks of to-day. has been by abrogating laws that were fitted to special con¬ ditions or were made in the interests of a class. I have in mind now simply the principle of social regulation, when presumably applied to relatively permanent conditions and in furtherance of common interests. AN ILLUSTRATION: THE PULL- MAN-CHICAGO STRIKE OF CHAPTER VIII. AN ILLUSTRATION : THE PULLMAN-CHICAGO STRIKE OF 1894. The Pullman-Chicago strike belongs to the past, but the issues involved in it do not. It is even questionable if the issues are com¬ monly understood. The author wishes to state them, as they appear to him. The underlying issue seems to be the same as has already been stated generally; namely, Should the members of a society be left to themselves in pursuing industrial ends (so they abstain from violence or fraud), or should the society anywise interfere ? Is liberty (anarchy ) 1 better, or is some measure of social action (gov¬ ernment) better, in this realm ? We live in a peculiar situation to-day. Mod¬ ern societies have renounced the method of 1 1 need not say that I use “ anarchy ” here simply in the sense of the absence of government. K 129 130 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. liberty or anarchy in dealing with the problem of protecting life and property, but hold to it and even cherish it in the industrial realm. They no longer leave it to individuals to pro¬ tect their lives and possessions as best they can , 1 but they do leave it to them to get their subsistence as best they can. Societies organize themselves as a whole to protect their members in their personal and property rights, and they are supposed to furnish this protec¬ tion quite irrespective of the ability of indi¬ viduals to protect themselves; they put the weaker and abler members on the same level in this respect. But in dealing with the problem of subsis¬ tence for their members, they are still individ¬ ualistic ; they think their members should help themselves (either by producing their own sub¬ sistence or by contracting for it with others more advantageously situated than they), and that each should fare well or ill according to 1 This may be said roughly to have been the significance of the feudal epoch, when individuals either protected them¬ selves by the force of their own arms or got protection from some one more powerful than they in exchange for services. THE PULLMAN-CHICAGO STRIKE. 13 I his individual merits and capacity: indeed, some persons hold that to put the less capable and the more capable so far on an equality as to assure to both the necessaries and the decencies of life, would be not only a mistake of policy, but wrong in principle, — unjust . 1 From a practical point of view, however, the question of anarchy (liberty) or govern¬ ment in the industrial realm is purely one of expediency. If it would be wrong in principle to put the weak on a level with the strong in the respect just mentioned, it must be equally wrong to put the two on the same level as regards the security of their lives and possessions, — that is, modern societies, even as at present constituted, are based on injustice. But we have already dealt with this phase of the question . 2 We have seen that the very notion of a society involves a 1 So Mr. Herbert Spencer. It is interesting to notice the contrast in the ideas of justice in the two cases. As regards protecting life and property, it would commonly be called unjust not to do as much for the weak as for the strong — not to put them so far on an absolute level of equality. 2 Supra , chap. v. 132 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. departure from the individualistic conception of justice. But even after the social standpoint is taken, it is still an open question as to how social ends may best be actually secured, — whether by the method of government or by the method of liberty or anarchy. The justi¬ fication of government for the protection of life and property is only that on the whole, in average existing circumstances, it meets the ends of social existence better than liberty or anarchy does,—not that under other circum¬ stances anarchy might not do as well or better. And the only real question about anarchy in the industrial realm is, How does it work ? Does it meet the needs of the social organism, does it satisfy the require¬ ments of the social consciousness? If it works well, if men succeed in meeting their needs when left to themselves, if the strong do not take advantage of the weak (whether from motives of conscience, or of interest, or because the weak tjy combination make themselves a match for them), if there is thus maintained THE PULLMAN-CHICAGO STRIKE. 133 a kind of equilibrium in the social body, so that none get too much and none too little,— if, I say, anarchy works well, there can be no objection to it, and there is rather everything in its favor, since society (as such) is thereby so far saved the necessity of exerting itself, and of using the compulsion, that is incident to social action (government) and is always, in itself considered, an evil. But how liberty in industry actually works is another matter. How it sometimes works was shown not long ago in Pullman and Chicago. Far be it from me to say that events of this sort are always the result of a system of liberty. If we go into the country districts of New England, we find government reduced almost to a vanishing point. Beyond the school-house and the roads and once a year the tax-collector, there is scarcely a sign of government; in their whole industrial life the people are left to them¬ selves, and they take care of themselves — the inequalities between them are of slight impor¬ tance. But if we go into our great cities or 134 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. manufacturing towns, what a different sight presents itself! Here the many are not em¬ ploying themselves, but are employed by others. More and more a system of large production is developing itself (made possible by the won¬ derful technical advances of the age, and by a more extensive use of the principle of the division of labor), which means that relatively fewer, as time goes on, continue to be their own employers. Even in agriculture there seems to be a tendency of the same sort in the far West, though whether the tendency is a permanent one remains to be seen . 1 Everywhere (save 1 This is a mooted question. Some of the facts which give rise to the appearance of the development of a large system of agricultural production in the far West are suggested by the figures of the Eleventh Census. See Abstract of the Eleventh Census: iSgo (Washington, 1894), pp. 62-65. The average size of farms has increased in certain states and territories as follows: ( i8 7 ° 184 (acres) Colorado. . .J 1880 259 “ ( 1890 v» ►H 00 ( l8 ?o 30 Utah.... .J 1880 69 “ ( 1890 126 “ THE PULLMAN-CHICAGO STRIKE. 135 possibly in agricultural industry) the old era of many individual producers seems to be pass¬ ing away, and a system of organized, consoli¬ dated production is establishing itself. There is undoubtedly a saving to society, an advantage to the great body of consumers, in such a system, else under free conditions it would hardly arise. But in these altered circumstances the indus¬ trial problem takes on a new form. The New England farmer boy who goes to the city and becomes a great employer is the same human r 1870 Montana. 3 1880 ( 1890 ( 1 87° Wyoming. 3 18S0 ( 1890 ( 1870 Arizona. ■} 1880 ( 1890 r 1870 Nevada.. 1880 ( 1890 In both California and Oregon, however, the average size of farms has diminished, and in the “ West Division” as a whole, there has been a decrease from 336 to 324 acres during the period in question. 164 ( acres) 267 66 351 66 25 66 272 66 586 66 127 66 177 66 910 66 201 66 378 66 1301 66 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. 136 being as before, but he has now chances that he could never have had on his ancestral fields, where if he wanted anybody to work for him he was obliged to pay more than the man could get by working on his own field. He is face to face with people divorced from the land and without, perhaps, any means of sup¬ port, save such as he and others gifted like him may provide. In other words, in an era of great production masses of people become dependent on their employers. They have little or no alternative ; they can not employ them¬ selves,— if they tried to, they could not com¬ pete with those who produce on a large scale, — and they must either be employed or go without the means of subsistence . 1 Hence they must take such terms as their employers are willing to grant. If the latter are just- minded (i.e. if they have something like the 1 1 do not think that I need to discuss whether this would not be changed by a society’s taking the rental value of the land and natural opportunities within its domain into a public fund and using it for public purposes, as Mr. Henry George has suggested. I believe that allowing for time in which to make the change, it would be a just one — and no doubt for a THE PULLMAN-CHICAGO STRIKE. 13 7 same regard for others which they have for themselves), they will of course give as much as they can, considering their own needs, the needs of their business, and the competitive relation to other employers in which they stand. But if they think of their workmen simply as means whereby they may carry on their busi¬ ness and make profit for themselves, they will give as little as they can—and yet have effi¬ cient service. I need not say that the ordinary notion of private (as opposed to what might be called public or properly political) economy — the economy of the private business world, I mean — is that one should pay as little for services as one can get them for, just as one pays as little as possible for raw materials, or for tools or machinery. Here then is the trouble — employers wanting to pay as little as possible, workingmen wanting to get as much while the result would be to ease the hard necessities which some labor under now, since fresh opportunities for employment would be opened. But that the effect would be in any way to alter the system of great production or the essential facts of depend¬ ence, to which I have alluded, I see no reason for believing. 138 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. as possible, and employers in the nature of the case being in the position of advantage, since they are relatively few and the working¬ men many. Hence, in the absence of outside interference, workingmen are likely to be taken advantage of . 1 They may check this tendency somewhat by organizing themselves and com¬ bining with one another, instead of each one standing alone and competing against one an¬ other. The success of such a device depends on the completeness of the organization — since those who do not enter it may always defeat the efforts of those who do — and such com¬ pleteness it is difficult to attain. And even if the organization were complete, it would hardly be possible to hold out in any demands long, unless the resources of the organization were beyond what workingmen are ever likely to be able to make them . 2 1 1 need not say that if those capable of being employers were many, and those who could perform manual labor few, the situation would be reversed, and the workingmen would be those who could take advantage. Sometimes even now conditions may be such that they can — though rarely. 2 As showing what labor organizations can do, or least have THE PULLMAN-CHICAGO STRIKE. 139 In other words, a system of liberty or anar¬ chy, in an era of large production, means large gains for a few (limited only by the extent to which they compete against one another ) 1 and small gains for the many; it means the rise of industrial classes; and whether the inferior class are contented and resigned, or occasionally indulge in resent¬ ment and rebellion, depends altogether on the sort of men and women they happen to be. A partial illustration of the truth of what has been said has been furnished recently in the town of Pullman. Mr. Pullman himself is a man of exceptional talents, ability, and foresight. He organized the production of a commodity which the community wants done in Great Britain, the elaborate historical study, The His¬ tory of Trade Unionism by Sidney and Beatrice Webb (1894), may be consulted. 1 Large producers are beginning to learn that it is often better not to compete, but to combine instead — those who refuse to enter the combination being undersold and driven out of the market. See Dr. Ernst von Halle’s Trusts (1895), and Mr. Henry D. Lloyd’s Wealth against Commonwealth (1894),—the latter being a detailed study of the history and methods of the Standard Oil Trust. 140 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. on a large scale, became a large employer of labor and made correspondingly large profits. A small employer, I may say, can not make a great deal of money — much less a man who works for and by himself. It is as a great German physicist, Professor Ernst Mach, said by way of illustration a few years ago before the Imperial Academy of Sciences in Vienna, “ A single human being, restricted wholly to the profits of his own labor, could never amass a fortune, but on the contrary the accumulation of the labor of many men in the hands of one is the foundation of wealth and power .” 1 1 Address on “ The Economical Character of Physical Research,” translated and printed in The Open Court, October 25, and November i, 1894. The whole passage is as fol¬ lows: “Just as a single human being, restricted wholly to the fruits of his own labor, could never amass a fortune, but on the contrary the accumulation of the labor of many men in the hands of one is the foundation of wealth and power, so, also, no knowledge worthy of the name can be gathered up in a single human mind limited to the span of a human life and gifted only with finite powers, except by the most exquisite economy of thought and by the careful amassment of the economically ordered experience of thousands of co-workers. What strikes us here as the fruits of sorcery are simply the THE PULLMAN-CHICAGO STRIKE . 141 Mr. Pullman’s accumulations have gone into the millions. The surplus earnings of the Company of which he is President, for the year ending July, 1894, — the reduction of wages took place September, 1893, and the strike to recover them, May, 1894, — were $2,320,417 — that is, after paying the usual eight per cent dividends to the stockholders, and, of course, the wages to its employees. The preceding year the surplus had been $4,006,448. Such are the fruits of strong and able business management under a regime of liberty or anarchy; the superior rewards of superior talent, as Mr. Spencer would say. The wages of those employed, up to the time of the reduction, had been as good as the average paid to similar grades of workingmen elsewhere, possibly a little better — many had a few hundred dollars in the savings bank. 1 rewards of excellent housekeeping, as are the like results in civil life. But the business of science has this advantage over every other enterprise, that from its amassment no one suffers the least loss. This, too, is its blessing, its freeing and saving power.” 1 Report on the Chicago Strike of June-July, 1894, by the United States Commission, 1894, p. 28. I am indebted to this report for most of the facts cited in what follows. 142 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. When the pressure of the hard times began to be felt in 1893, wages were reduced. Stock¬ holders were not made to suffer; there is no pretence that Mr. Pullman or any of the officials of the Company was made to suffer 1 — but those who were getting least in return for their labor were made to take lower returns still. There is, of course, nothing to hinder this under a rule of liberty or anarchy; if the employees did not wish to take the lower wages, they were not forced to; they could stop work and go elsewhere. In May, 1894, they asked for the old scale of wages, and not getting them, they did stop work. There is, of course, nothing to prevent this either in a system of liberty where each one may, indi¬ vidually or in concert with others, act as he sees fit. 1 Mr. Pullman stated before the United States Commission, August 27, 1894, that the salaries of himself and of the officers of the Company had not been reduced. The policy of the Lehigh Valley Railroad may be contrasted, the management of which ordered a reduction of ten per cent in all salaries of its officers over $1000 per annum to go into effect Decem¬ ber 1, 1894, but left wages and salaries less than $1000 undis¬ turbed. THE PULLMAN-CHICAGO STRIKE. 143 Later on, an association of public-spirited citizens in Chicago, known as the Civic Fed¬ eration, urged arbitration on the Company as a means of healing the differences that had arisen — did so twice. In each case the Com¬ pany refused the appeal. The Federation asked whether at least the rents which the men had to pay for their houses could not be reduced to correspond with the reduction in wages — for the houses which many lived in belonged to the Company; but the Com¬ pany replied with entire truth that rents and wages were different things—and that the reduction of wages constituted no reason why it should lose the customary returns on its houses. It is a matter of record that some persons had been given little more than enough work to pay their rent, — in single instances twenty cents being left over for food and clothes for the family after the month’s rent was deducted. 1 The Company gave a similar an- 1 Instances to this effect were given before the Grand Jury. See Z. S. Holbrook in Bibliotheca Sacra , January, 1895, P 1 I ^ 3 * 144 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. swer to a similar question on the part of a committee of its employees. It declined to receive any communication whatever on the subject from the American Railway Union, which many of the employees had joined; and it also refused to consider arbitration when solicited to do so by the Common Council of Chicago and the Mayor of the City. The Second Vice-President of the Company said once, in language the distinctness of which leaves nothing to be desired, “ We shall not allow any one to tell us how our business shall be conducted, and we shall not consent to arbitration. Our business is our own private affair, and we want no interference by Federal, or State or any other Government.” 1 It is of course the right of people under a system of industrial liberty or anarchy, to talk in this way; it is the very meaning of such anarchy. Business or industry is conceived of, under this system, as a private matter, with which the public authority has nothing to do. Then came another incident which is entirely 1 Quoted in The Outlook, 14 July, 1894. THE PULLMAN-CHICAGO S TP IKE. 145 permissible according to such a conception of things. The American Railway Union — a body of railroad employees with its main strength in the West — decided that its mem¬ bers should stop handling Pullman cars, until the Company should consent to the proposed arbi¬ tration. This was the Chicago strike (or boy¬ cott) proper. It was a purely sympathetic strike. The railroad men had no grievances; they were simply led to do as they did because they had a fellow feeling for their comrades in Pullman. It is astonishing to hear that men have a right to act as they choose out of regard for their own interests, but not when they are moved by sympathy for others. Such a state¬ ment is sometimes made. One who formerly held high station in the Commonwealth of Illinois has recently urged that while local strikes should be permitted, sympathetic strikes should be forbidden by law, whether violence is committed or no. 1 To desire to promote 1 Ex-Governor G. Koerner, in The Open Court , November 29, 1894. 146 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. another’s interests we ordinarily think is as exemplary a motive as to be solicitous for our own. To incur great risks, to run the chance of losing the very means of life, not for the sake of justice to ourselves but because we wish to win it for others, would commonly be thought to approach the sublime. Surely, if it is permissible to strike at all, there is neither logic nor common sense in denying the right when it happens to be exercised for unselfish ends. The strike of the American Railway Union may have been headlong and foolish (considering that it was so incomplete an organization and so little likely to be able to accomplish the end it had in view), but more than this cannot be said, if we keep to the standpoint of industrial liberty. Have then a body of railroad employees, it may be asked, the right to paralyze the industry or commerce of a country ? It all depends upon what standpoint we take. If we believe that all industrial ends should be secured by voluntary agencies and the free play of individual interests, — that is, if we THE PULLMAN-CHICAGO STRIKE. take the standpoint of industrial liberty or anarchy, — it is difficult to see how we can deny such a right — supposing, of course, that no violence is done or contract broken. Such an extreme result would have to be regarded as simply one of the regrettable incidents of a system of liberty, which was, however, to be preserved, even at this cost. And the standpoint of liberty is that commonly taken by Americans. At least up till now we have commonly believed that the purpose of govern¬ ment was simply to keep the peace and enforce contracts; that to interfere in the industrial world 1 and particularly to put re¬ straints on any one’s freedom to act as he saw fit (so long as he molested no one else) was beyond its sphere. If we adhere then to this standpoint, it is difficult to see how we can question the right of railroad employees to quit the service of their employers for any reason that seems good to them; how we can question the right of 1 Except by protecting manufacturers and others against foreign competition. 148 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. any number of them to do the same; how we can question their right to do anything they choose, just as the Pullman Company claims the right to manage its business in any way it chooses — anything, that is, short of breaking a contract, or of violence, or of incitement thereto. To unite, to combine, to do a thing is no more a sin against liberty than to do the thing individually — rather is it an inter¬ ference with liberty to prevent men from unit¬ ing, or combining. If government is only to keep the peace, it has no business to interfere with combinations — whether of employers or of workingmen — or with anything these combinations may do, short of committing fraud or making breaches of the peace. If, however, we take the ground that such an industrial paralysis as the country had a taste of in 1894 is intolerable,—as we well may, — if we say that workingmen have not the right to inflict such injuries on the social organism, we do in effect and in principle take a totally different standpoint from that of industrial liberty and go over into the camp THE PULLMAN-CHIC AGO STRIKE. 149 of those who hold that industrial welfare is not to be entrusted merely to the free play of individual interests, but that society, as such, may in this realm, as it already does in others, act and regulate. And the simple logic of events is taking many, who are reluc¬ tant to part with individualist principles in themselves considered, in this new direction. But, to return. Later on, violence in con¬ nection with the strike did come. To many the strike and the violence in and about Chicago are synonymous. If this were so, there would be nothing to discuss about the strike; for violence is not a subject of dis¬ cussion in civilized communities. It is simply something to be put down. Liberty or anarchy in the industrial realm is matter for discussion, but society has already passed on liberty or anarchy with respect to the rights of person and property and condemned it. All the force used in civilized society (save for momentary self-defence) is used by society itself and its appointed agents. Private war, private re¬ dress of wrongs, is forbidden — society by ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. 150 its police and its courts undertakes to stand guard over personal and property rights: and despite its halting and unsatisfactory perform¬ ance, we think it on the whole better that society should so act than that there should be a regime of liberty or anarchy. To dally with violence or with threats to violence is, in this age of the world, a mistake. The working¬ men, so far as they are inclined this way should be taught by hard experience that it is not the true way in which to proceed. It is salutary in the long run for them, as well as needful for civilization, that plundering property or assaulting persons should at once be put a stop to — at whatever cost to the offender. Yet it is fair to say that the more thought¬ ful among workingmen, and, as a rule, the leaders among them, are opposed to violence — and that whatever violence takes place ordinarily does so in spite of their earnest efforts to prevent it. 1 Mr. Debs said last sum- 1 It is doubtful if the actual strikers took much part in the violence in Chicago. After the force of the strike was broken, the New York Times , a conservative paper, admitted as much. “ Perhaps,” it said, “ the majority of the outrages in Chicago THE PULLMAN-CHIC AGO STRIKE. 15 I mer in the midst of the strike, “I have abso¬ lute confidence that we will win the battle, win it without violence. I understand how serious a disaster to our cause violence or lawlessness would be, and I am commanding upon all my lieutenants regard for the law and respect for property rights.” 1 Shortly before this The Central Labor Union of New York passed a resolution in this lan¬ guage : “ Be it resolved, that while The Cen¬ tral Labor Union denounces the action of the Federal Government and the police, it also places itself on record as' against all incendiarism and anarchy, and it denounces the fire-bugs who have brought disgrace upon a fair fight of organized labor.” 2 and the neighborhood were not the work of strikers in particu¬ lar, but of ‘ lewd fellows of the baser sort ’ in general, taking advantage of the temporary relaxation of law and order.” (14 July, 1894.) President Huntington of the Southern Pacific Railroad Company said, as reported in the same journal (July 9), “Probably a large majority of the surging and lawless masses now destroying property in Chicago and other places are not and never have been railroad employees.” 1 Quoted in The Outlook , July 14, 1894. 2 Quoted in New York Times , July 9, 1894. 152 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. The fact is, as a person of any intelligence must know, that the moment a cause resorts to violence to gain its ends, that moment it alienates public sympathy and the people who might have been for it turn against it, and approve the use of the strong arm of the law to put it down. 1 The graver question and the only real issue connected with the events of last summer is whether there is any remedy for such griev¬ ances as the Pullman Company’s employees had when they quitted work. I confess I do not see how there is any remedy under a system of liberty or anarchy such as we essentially have now—that is, any other remedy than the one that was tried and failed and that, 1 Whether the Chief Executive of the Nation did right (legally and constitutionally) in sending troops to Chicago or not, I will not presume to judge; nor whether the courts exceeded their constitutional powers in issuing the much-discussed injunc¬ tions (for alleged disregarding of which some of the leaders have been imprisoned); but that the reign of violence and terror that more or less existed in Chicago during the early part of July, 1894, had to be put an end to, if not in one way then in another, if not by the local authorities, then by the authority of the nation itself, there can be no manner of doubt. THE PULLMAN-CHICAGO STRIKE. 153 under the then-existing circumstances, was almost bound to fail. If a corporation is not just-minded in the first place, if it will not confer with its men as a body in the second place, and if it will not listen to suggestions of reasons from the outside in the third place, — these are all its rights under liberty or anarchy and I do not believe that in the average of cases its employees can develop a sufficient amount of strength to make them a match for it. They may form their unions, and in some cases help matters a little by means of them ; and others may enter on sympathetic strikes and boycotts to aid them; all this is possible under anarchy and is indeed a necessary right and the only resource under anarchy; and yet so long as workingmen are many, and capable employers few, the former are in a position of natural disadvantage, which all such efforts as I have mentioned can not make up for. Anarchy will work with ideal employers, and it may work with those who employ on a small scale, whatever their character, not to 154 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. say with those who work for themselves; but with great employers, as we sometimes find them — it means the possibility of just such hard, mean, unjust treatment as the Pullman Company dealt out to its employees from September, 1893, to the date of the strike. To my mind, such a possibility is the reductio ad absurdum of anarchy, taken anywise as a principle of social life. For it is the very function of a society to see that its members are not imposed upon, if it can help it. I do not say that it should of necessity itself secure justice, but it should see that justice is some¬ how secured. If this can not be done, or at least is not done, under liberty, then the soci¬ ety should itself interfere. Herein lies the only basis for interference to protect life and property; namely, that private enterprise and individual contracting to this end are not ade¬ quate ; it is as good a basis for any other form of social interference. The justification of government is always, not its abstract desirability, but its practical necessity. I think that the events in Pullman THE PULLMAN-CHICAGO STRIKE. and in Chicago, indeed the trend of affairs in the modern industrial world generally, go to show that our old system of liberty or anarchy is breaking down, just as feudal anarchy broke down at the beginning of the modern epoch in Europe in the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries. There was not sufficient security for life and property then (when individuals were left to get it as they could), and it was in the name of the common people that the great consolidated monarchies arose that mark the beginning of the modern political epoch, undertaking as they did to protect every subject of them alike in certain fundamental rights. 1 There seems to 1 This is possibly too abstract a statement, but its substantial truth will hardly be contested. Professor Burgess says, “The absolute monarchies of the fifteenth, sixteenth, and seventeenth centuries . . . gave liberty to the common man at the same time that they subjected the nobles to the law of the state. In fact they gave liberty to the common man by subjecting the nobles to the law of the state.” (. Political Science and Con¬ stitutional Law , Vol. I. p. 56.) As confirming this interpreta¬ tion of the absolute monarchy, Professor Burgess cites Ranke, Franzosische Geschielite, Bd. I. S. 34; Ranke, Englische Geschichte, Bd. I. S. 97; Von Sybel, Ueber die Entwickelung der absoluten Monarchic in Preussen , S. 24 ff.; Krones, Hand- buch der Geschichte Oesterreichs , Bd. IV. S. 488. Professor ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. 156 be no sufficient guarantee against industrial injustice under a system of free contract now. Somehow then society must begin itself to act — must give its weaker members a strength that they have not in themselves, must support them, when they threaten to be worsted in a contest, with its own strong arm. To leave people to the tender mercies of Pullmans, Carnegies, Havemeyers, and the rest will not do, any more than it did to leave English- Burgess remarks of the absolute monarchy in England, “In . . the absolute monarchy of the Tudors, the people were, in reality, the sovereign, the state; but, apparently, the king was the state. England under the Tudors was a demo¬ cratic political society under monarchic government.” (. Politi¬ cal Science and Constitutional Law , I. 93.) As to France, “ Louis XI. cultivated the democracy with great assiduity and made the crown the bearer of its power against the aristocracy.” {Ibid. I. 127. Cf. Kitchin’s History of France, Vol. II. p. 100.) It is by no means asserted that the monarchs acted unselfishly in this matter. Professor Lindley M. Keasbey probably states the truth when he says, “Within each geographic unity some Teutonic prince, actuated by personal ambition and yet sup - ported for the most part by the entire peasant class, whose aim was to free themselves from the exactions of the petty lords, began step by step to bring under his control all the agricultural fiefs of the land.” {Political Science Quarterly , Vol. VIII. p. 615.) (The italics are mine.) THE PULLMAN-CHICAGO STRIKE . 157 men and Frenchmen to the mercies of lords, barons, and dukes in the olden time. A power stronger than the strong man must arise. No monarch indeed like Henry VII. or Louis XI. will accomplish the change for us; it is the people, the democracy, who must effect it — and prove once more that a nation is mightier than any individual or company of individuals in it. In just what manner the public sense of what is fair and just in industrial relations shall proceed to express itself, is a question of detail. The significant thing is that modern socie¬ ties are already, under one provocation or another, beginning to move in this direction. The rents of the Irish peasants are no longer left entirely to free contract, but sometimes are determined judicially. England’s factory legislation all proceeds on the basis that work¬ ingmen, and particularly working-women, are not to be left to their own resources to bargain with their employers as best as they can for satisfactory sanitary conditions and hours of toil, but that the nation is, on occasion, to say 158 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. what is reasonable and right in these relations, and make it binding on employers. In our own country, legislation is beginning to develop on the English lines. All of it is, of course, a violation of the principles of pri¬ vate liberty and free contract. 1 The Interstate Commerce Commission that has recently been established, is also an interference with freedom of contract and the right of individuals or cor¬ porations to manage their business as they see fit. When discriminations between shippers are forbidden, this is an asserting of social control and an abridging of private rights. Hence the practical question is simply whether modern societies shall go on in the direction they are going. Already many of our commonwealths 1 On this ground, the Supreme Court of Illinois has recently pronounced unconstitutional an. act of the Legislature of the Commonwealth, limiting the laboring day for women in factories to eight hours. See also the reference to the action of the Supreme Court of Missouri, supra p. 124, n. It is quite possible that constitutional changes will have to be made before legis¬ lation of the English type can have free and undisputed course in this country. Constitutions may be temporary barriers to social action, but they can not be permanent barriers among a free people. THE PULLMAN-CHIC AGO STRIKE . 159 have so-called Labor Bureaus; a few years ago a National Labor Bureau was established. But if labor and capital are their own masters and are to adjust all their relations according to their own light and mutual agreement, it is difficult to see the propriety of such Bureaus — even for information’s sake; why should not labor and capital get their own information ? A still further step has been taken. The President of the United States appointed the head of the National Labor Bureau, the Hon. Carroll D. Wright, and two other citizens a commission to investigate the causes of the late Chicago strike, hear the pros and cons that might be urged about it, and make a report with suggestions and recommendations. The investigation was not to be directed par¬ ticularly to the violence accompanying the strike,—that at the time was summarily dealt with at last, — but rather to the controversy or dispute that led to the strike; such was the language of the Chief Executive in appoint¬ ing the Commission. 1 1 The exact language is as follows: “ The said Commission i6o ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. Evidently this proceeds on the supposition that the nation has something to do with such controversies; for if it has nothing to do with them, and if corporations and their employees have a right to act as on together or fail to get on as they see fit, it is an impertinence to appoint a commission to examine into their affairs. 1 I make bold to say that the appointment of “The United is hereby directed to visit the state of Illinois, and the city of Chicago, and such other places in the United States as may appear proper in the judgment of the Commission, to the end that it make a careful inquiry into the causes of any pending dispute or existing controversies and hear all persons inter¬ ested therein, who may come before it.” (The italics are mine.) 1 Cf. The Nation , in discussing the report of the Com¬ mission : “ Labor disputes are generally very simple, and nobody can possibly settle them but the parties to them. . . . The interference of outsiders, unless asked for by both sides, ought to be a gross impertinence.” (22 November, 1894.) The same journal says (December 13, 1894), in commenting on Attorney-General Olney’s report as contrasted with that of the Commission: “ Attorney-General Olney’s report brushes aside the merits of the Pullman strike and takes up simply the duty and activity of the Government in view of the lawlessness that grew out of it. This was all that the authorities at Washington had any occasion to consider carefully at any time , and it is really all they need to consider now.” (The italics are mine.) THE PULLMAN-CHICAGO STRIKE. ifa States Strike Commission ” was one of the greatest advances away from the old ideas of industrial liberty or anarchy to new concep¬ tions of the rights and duties of society as a whole, that this country has ever made or is soon likely to make. And now if the nation goes ahead and does something on the basis of the recommendations which the Commission has made, it will only be taking another step along the same general line. It may establish a system of arbitration for the adjusting of differences between railroad employees and their employers or, for that matter, between any set of employers and employees who do not seem to be able to get along together. 1 1 The most discriminating treatment of the subject of arbitra¬ tion that I remember to have seen is in an article by Mr. Charles Worcester Clark in the Atlantic Monthly , January, 1891. The Arbitration Bill, dealing with “ carriers engaged in interstate commerce and their employees,” which was passed by the House of Representatives (but not acted upon by the Senate) in the spring of 1895, provides only that a controversy “ may be submitted ” to an arbitrating board. Should it become a law, it would remain to be seen whether advantage would actually be taken of its provisions. M 1(32 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. This would not mean, as the matter is sometimes absurdly misconceived, that laborers would be obliged to work and employers to carry on their business according to the decis¬ ions of the arbitrating board, whether they wished to or not, but only that if they wished to continue working or doing business, they would have to do so on the lines laid down. 1 ’T is as with the Irish peasants : they are not obliged to live on the land the rents of which are judicially fixed, but if they wish to live on it, they need not pay more than the rent determined on — and the landowner may not ask for more. If the nation does not in some way come to the assistance of those who are at a dis¬ advantage in the industrial struggle, it is folly to forbid them to strike. If there is no social protection, it follows as a matter of course that people — singly or by combination — must protect themselves. It is as absurd that persons, for whom society does nothing in the way of securing to them what they conceive 1 See Appendix, Note I. THE PULLMAN-CHICAGO STRIKE. ^3 to be their rights, should be enjoined or for¬ bidden to take peaceful means to win these rights, whether it be striking, boycotting, or any other means that stop short of violence or fraud, as it would be to prevent people from using their fists or their guns to defend their lives and property, in case society pro¬ vided no policemen and no courts. If peaceful strikes and boycotts are to be enjoined, it can be only in case the same authority, which does this, says also, We will take care of your rights and make resort to strikes and boycotts unnecessary. We seem to be in this country at a parting of the ways. The public mind itself is per¬ plexed, is not clear; and the judiciary, even the highest judiciary of the land, is more or less at variance with itself. 1 But it is one course or the other. If it is liberty, then there must be liberty all around. To say that railroad or any other employees may not act as they see fit (whether it be by striking, boycotting, or by other procedure that involves neither vio- 1 See Appendix, Note 2. 164 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. lence nor breach of contract) and yet to leave their employers free to fix wages, hours of labor and other conditions of employment as they like, is simply monstrous. Either hands off, — or hands on impartially! And I have confi¬ dence enough in the American people, and in the uprightness of the Judiciary of the land, to believe that in the long run the right thing, the equal thing, will be done. APPENDIX. Note i (see p. 162). On the different relatio7i 'which quasi-public corporations a7id their e77ipioyees respectively sustain to the public , and on the co7iseque7it unequal bearing of arbitratio7i 7ip07i theTn. An exception to the statement on p. 162, relative to the practical meaning of arbitration would, of course, have to be made in the case of railroads and other semi-public corporations, which by their charters virtually contract to render the public a certain service. That such corpo¬ rations have a duty of this sort is sometimes lost sight of, but is clearly stated in a recent decision of Mr. Justice Gaynor of the Supreme Court of New York. (In the matter of the Application of Loader for a writ of manda¬ mus v. the Brooklyn Heights Railroad Company, January 24, 1895.) The decision was on an appeal of Joseph Loader, during the Brooklyn street-car strike, for a writ of mandamus to compel the Brooklyn Heights Railroad Company to run its cars. As the point is of great im¬ portance, not only in itself, but in its bearing on the practical working of arbitration, I will quote Judge Gaynor’s language at length. He says: — “ This railroad corporation is not in the position of a mere private individual or company carrying on business for private 165 1 66 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. gain, which may suspend business temporarily or permanently at pleasure. On the contrary, it has a dual relation: a public relation to the people of the state, and a private one to its stockholders. It must not be forgotten here, though it may seem to be growing dim, if not wholly forgotten elsewhere, that in its chief aspect it is a public corporation, having duties to perform to the public which transcend any obligation which in its private aspect it owes to its stockholders. It has received franchises of great value from the state, and had conferred upon it the state’s transcendent power of eminent domain. In return it took upon itself the performance of public duties and func¬ tions, in the performance of which it is in law and in fact, not an independent individual or entity, but the accountable agent of the state. Though these principles are old, and inherent in the idea of the sovereignty of the people, it would seem that in the recent rapid growth of corporate power, and of the tendency to use public franchises for the aggrandizement of individuals first and for the service and benefit of the public second, they have come to be somewhat overlooked and need to be restated. They have often been declared by the highest court of this state and the Supreme Court of the United States. (Olcott v. The Supervisors, 16 Wall. 687, 694; Bloodgood v. The Mohawk &c. R. Co., 19 Wend. 9; The People v. N. Y. C. & H. R. R. Co., 28 Hun. 543.) The duty of the Company now before the court is to carry passengers through certain streets of Brooklyn, and to furnish, man, and run cars enough to fully accommodate the public. It may not lawfully cease to perform that duty for even one hour. The directors of a private business company may, actuated by private greed, or motives of private gain, stop business and refuse to employ labor at all unless labor comes down to their conditions, however distressing; for such are the existing legal, industrial and social conditions. But APPENDIX . 167 the directors of a railroad corporation may not do the like; they are not merely accountable to stockholders; they are accountable to the public first and their stockholders second. They have duties to the public to perform, and they must perform them. If they can not get labor to perform such duties at what they offer to pay, then they must pay more, and as much as is necessary to get it. Likewise, if the conditions in point of hours or otherwise which they impose, repel labor, they must adopt more lenient or just conditions. They may not stop their cars for one hour, much less one week or one year, to thereby beat or coerce the price or conditions of labor down to the price or conditions they offer.” Judge Gaynor quotes from a case decided upon appeal by the Supreme Court of New York in 1883 , “after mature deliberation.” The case arose out of the failure of the New York Central and Hudson River Railroad Company to receive and forward freight as a common carrier. The language of the court was as follows: “ According to the statements of the case a body of laborers, acting in concert, fixed a price for their labor, and refused to work at a less price. The respondents (the railroad company) fixed a price for the same work, and refused to pay more. In doing this, neither did an act violative of any law, or subjecting either to any pen¬ alty. The respondents had a lawful right to take their ground in respect of the price to be paid, and adhere to it, if they chose; but if the consequence of doing so were an inability to exercise their corporate franchises to the great injury of the public, they (the railroad company) cannot be heard to assert that such consequences must ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. 168 be shouldered and borne by an innocent public, who neither directly nor indirectly participated in their causes.” (The People v. N. Y. C. & H. R. R. Co., 28 Hun. 543.) The court in that case allowed a writ of mandamus to compel the corporation to do its corporate duty. Judge Gaynor further says, “ Besides, the persistence of the company in failing to run its cars except as it may gradu¬ ally get employees to accept its terms , being in itself unlaw¬ ful, as I have shown, must necessarily by its bad example tend to public disquiet, if not to some disorder. In respect of the question of hours and of wages between the company and its employees, its duty was to have gone on, and now is to go on with its full complement of employees, having the right gradually and from day to day to supersede its employees if it can, by new em¬ ployees who will work on its terms, or to supersede them all at once when it has obtained a sufficient number of new employees for that purpose ; but in such a controversy it has not the right to stop its cars while it is thus grad¬ ually getting other men. If the people of the state were running these roads they would not thus incommode and damage themselves ; and it must not be forgotten that this corporation is entrusted with the running of these roads as the servant of the people of the stateT In concluding his opinion, Judge Gaynor quotes the language of Mr. Justice Cullen in a similar case a few days earlier: “ Each party has the right to obtain the best terms it can; and as was said in the freight hand¬ lers’ case [The People v. N. Y. C. & H. R. R. Co., 28 Hun. 543, above cited], if the company cannot get men APPENDIX. 169 at the price that it thinks fair, it is bound to get them at a price it may deem exorbitant, because its duty is to run its roadP (The italics in the above paragraphs are my own.) It is evident that a railroad company, being in this situation in the eyes of the law, can not pursue the course that would be open to a private corporation, of stopping its operations, rather than comply with the decision of a Board of Arbitration, in case such decision was displeasing to it; but it is also evident that the loss of liberty not only inheres in the nature of its express contract with the public, but is in a way compensated for by its extraordinary privileges. In case it did choose to suspend, it would in effect forfeit its charter. On the other hand, the employees of a railroad company are under no contract with the public to render continuous service. They have indeed no contractual relations with the public at all, but only with the company employing them. If they were a part of the company, sharing in its privileges and participating in its profits, they would of course have a duty to the public just as the company has ; but accord¬ ing to their actual status, they are simply hired by the company and have not even the right of continuity of employment at its hands. 1 Hence there is no reason, 1 So the Hon. Carl Schurz in discussing “ Corporations, Em¬ ployes and the Public” (North American Review , February, 1884) : “It will scarcely be denied that, if there is a difference between the two as to the degree in which they owe obligation to the public, it springs from the fact that the corporations are in the enjoyment of valuable public franchises which carry public ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. 170 either in law or morals, why, in case they choose to give up their employment rather than accept the terms of the decision of a Board of Arbitration, they should not do so; though they would have no right to molest others who were ready to take their places on the terms laid down. If this right or liberty to quit work were denied or abridged by the public, this could only happen equita¬ bly in case the public gave them some counterbalancing advantage (in respect to their wages or the tenure of their employment) and they became in effect public servants rather than simply the servants of the company employ¬ ing them. 1 It is true that Judge Ricks of the United States Circuit Court used language at variance with this view on one occasion. (Toledo, Ann Arbor & N. M. Ry. Co. v. Pennsylvania Co. et al ., 34 Fed. Rep. 747.) In address¬ ing an “Admonition to Accused” (locomotive engineers and firemen), he said, “ Your employers owe a high duty duties with them, while their employes are simply wage-workers who, as a class, had been favored by the public or the state not a whit more than other working-people in private employment.” 1 Mr. Schurz remarks as follows in the article just quoted: “ The more intelligent and the more capable of logical reason¬ ing he is, the more strenuously and consistently will he cling to the doctrine that if, as a railroad or a telegraph employe, he is to be debarred from certain means of righting his wrongs, which are open to other working-men, he must be entitled to some kind of protection to compensate him for this; that, if he is bound in duty to the public in the matter of service, he should not be left altogether at the mercy of a private corporation organized for private profit in the matter of pay and treatment.” APPENDIX. 171 to the public, which they are compelled to perform under penalties of the law, and they have in turn a higher claim upon you and your services than that due from the ordi¬ nary employee!" (The italics are mine). But with all respect to the learned Judge, it must be said that such a “ higher claim ” is without logical warrant in the existing state of law on the subject. What I have said as to the different bearings of arbi¬ tration on corporations and on their employees, applies only of course to semi-public corporations. As to all others, there would be equal liberty on the part of the corporation to suspend business and on the part of the employees to stop working, if either chose to do so rather than accept the award of the Arbitrating Board. Note 2 (see p. 163). On varying Judicial opinio 7 i as to the rights of e?nployees of quasi-public corporations. The cases I have in mind are for the most part those dealing with the rights of railroad employees. Sometimes their right to stop work in a body, with or without notice, is strongly asserted, so they break no contract, do no vio¬ lence, and have no malicious intent. (Judge Caldwell, U. S. Circuit Court, District of Nebraska, in case of Oliver Ames, 2d, et al. v. Union Pacific R. Co. et al ., No. 1, see Interstate Commerce Reports, Vol. IV. No. 52, pp. 619-624; also Justice Harlan, U. S. Circuit Court of Appeals, in case of P. M. Arthur et al ., Intervenors, Appts. v. Thomas F. Oakes et al ., see Interstate Commerce Reports , Vol. IV. Nos. 61, 62, pp. 744-764.) 172 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT . Sometimes, on the other hand, this right is questioned. Judge Dundy (U. S. Circuit Court, District of Nebraska), for example, in answer to a petition from the Receivers of the Union Pacific Railway Company, sought on January 27, 1894, to restrain their employees from striking, when reduced wage schedules should go into effect on the 1st day of March, following. (See review of the case by Judge Caldwell, as cited above.) So Judge Jenkins (U. S. Circuit Court, Eastern District of Wisconsin) enjoined on December 19, 1893, the employees of the Receivers of the Northern Pacific Railroad Company, not only from combining to quit the service of the Receivers with the ob¬ ject of crippling the property in their custody, but from so quitting as to cripple the property, when a strike on ac¬ count of reduced wages was imminent. (See Farmers 1 Loan and Trust Co. v. Northern Pacific R. Co. et al ., 60 Fed. Rep. 803; and a review and, in part, reversal, of the order by Justice Harlan, as cited above.) Judge Taft (U. S. Circuit Court, Northern District of Ohio, in case of Toledo, Ann Arbor and N. M. Ry. Co. v. Pennsylvania Co. et al ., 54 Fed. Rep. 730), while admitting the right of railroad employees to strike on their own behalf, denied their right to quit their employment when they chose to do this rather than handle the freight of a connecting road whose employees had struck ; he pronounced such a sympathetic or boycott strike criminal, since its aim would be to lead the road against whom the strike was directed to do a criminal thing, i.e. violate the Interstate Commerce Law by not handling the freight of the second-named road. (It is plain, I may say, that so long as e?nployees remain in APPENDIX. 173 the service of a railroad company , they do a criminal act in refusing to handle freight from connecting roads; but that they may not quit the service rather than handle such freight, without becoming guilty of criminal conduct, is a novel position.) Judge Speer (U. S. Circuit Court, Southern District of Georgia, in case of Waterhouse v. Comer, 55 Fed. Rep. 149, 19 L. R. A. 403) went still further. He asserted that “ vi any conceivable strike upon the transportation lines of the country, whether main lines or branch roads, there will be interference and restraint of Interstate or foreign com¬ merce ” ; also, having in mind the act of July 2,1890, known as the Sherman Anti-Trust Law, and the Interstate Com¬ merce Act (February 4, 1887, 24 St. at Large, p. 379, and amended March 2, 1889, 25 St. at Large, p. 885), coupled with sec. 5440 of Revised Statutes, that it would “ be practically impossible hereafter for a body of men to com¬ bine to hinder and delay the work of the transportation company without becoming amenable to the provisions of these statutes.” An engineer, he held, might as an individual leave the service of the Receiver (the Central Railroad of Georgia, about which the case arose, was in the hands of a Receiver at this time), but even he could “ not do so in such manner as to injure the property or impede its proper management.” The same Judge uses the following remarkable language: “ Organized labor, when injustice has been done or threatened to its mem¬ bership, will find its useful and valuable mission in pre¬ senting to the courts of the country a strong and resolute 1 74 ANARCHY OR GOVERNMENT. protest, and a petition for redress against unlawful trusts and combinations which would do unlawful wrong to it. Its membership need not doubt that their counsel will be heard, nor that speedy and exact justice will be adminis¬ tered wherever the courts have jurisdiction.” This is, of course, equivalent to saying (keeping the use of language familiar to my readers) that liberty and the methods of liberty, such as strikes and boycotts, should give way to government and the methods of government, in disposing of industrial wrongs. And though thus far government restriction on indus¬ trial liberty in this country has been rather in behalf of incorporated capital than of labor, I doubt not that in the long run equal justice will be done. Judge Speer, in the case just mentioned, abridged the liberty of the Receiver, and compelled him to recognize and treat with the em¬ ployees of the road in a manner he had not wished to. Justice Harlan, in the opinion cited above, suggests the true and, as I believe, probable line of future develop¬ ment. While indicating the rights of liberty under pres¬ ent laws (or absence of laws), he declared that the evils resulting from their exercise, arising in many cases, as he said, “from the inconsiderate conduct of employers and employees, both equally indifferent to the general welfare,” were, to be “ met and remedied by legislation restraming alike employees and employers so far as necessary ade¬ quately to guard the rights of the public as involved in the existence, maintenance, and safe management of public highways.” (The italics are mine.) INDEX OF AUTHORS. (QUOTED OR REFERRED TO.) Aquinas, 20 n. Aristotle, 20 n., 83. Bagehot, 51 n. Bluntschli, 13 n., 30 n. Brentano, Dr. Lujo, 17 n. Brooks, Bishop, 14. Bryce, Prof. Jas., 22. Burgess, Prof. J. W., 33 n., 56 n., 73 n., 123 n., 155 n., 156 n. Caldwell, Judge, 171. Channing, 11. Clark, Mr. C. W., 161 n. Cleveland, President, 159 n. Cullen, Judge, 168. Donisthorpe, Mr. W., 74 n. Dundy, Judge, 172. Emerson, 15, 16 n., 25. Flint, Prof. R., 125 n. Gaynor, Judge, 165, 167, 168. George, Mr. Henry, 136 n. Giddings, Prof. F. H., 51 n. Gillespie, J., 21 n. Gladstone, Mr., 63 n. Grote, George, 56 n. Grote, John, 30 n. von Halle, Dr. Ernst, 139 n. Harlan, Justice, 171, 174. Hegel, 20 n. Herodotus, 56 n. Hobbes, 6n., 13. Hodgson, Mr. S. H., 30 n. Homer, 40, 63 n. Huxley, 12, 32 n., 64 n. Jenkins, Judge, 172. Jevons, W. S., 87 n. Keasbey, Prof. L. M., 156 n. Kitchin, 156 n. Koerner, Mr. G., 145. Krones, 155 n. Leroy-Beaulieu, M., 17, 18 n., 29. Lloyd, Mr. H. D., 139 n. Lubbock, Sir John, 18, 43. Mach, Prof. Ernst, 140. Mackenzie, Prof. J. S., 51 n. Mann, Mr. J. S., 20 n. 176 INDEX OF AUTHORS. Mill, J. S., 11 n., 30 n., 86 n., 87 n. de Molinari, M., 2411. Morgan, Mr. L. H., 51 n. The Nation , 160 n. St. Paul, 53. Pembroke, Lord, 30 n. Plato, 54. Ranke, 155 n. Ricks, Judge, 170. Ritchie, Prof. D. G., 20 n., 77 n. Smith, Mr. Goldwin, 30 n. Speer, Judge, 173. Spencer, Mr. Herbert, 17, 19 n., 24n., 25, 44, 45, chaps, v., vi., vii passim, 13 m. Stephen, Sir J. F., 29 n., 73 n. Sumner, Prof. W. G., 106 n. von Sybel, 155 n. Taft, Judge, 172. Tucker, Mr. Benj. R., 26 n. Wallace, Mr. A. R., 1311. Ward, Mr. L. F., 51 n. Salter, Rev. W., 21 n. Schaffle, 113 m Schurz, Mr. Carl, 169 n., 170 n. Sidgwick, Prof. H., 5 n., 6 n. de Warville Brissot, 15. Webb, Mr. and Mrs. Sidney, 139 m Weir, Jr., Dr. Jas., 67 n. Wright, Mr. Carroll D., 159. SI l V' ,r V I V S ( \l VfM-V, jfY? V yr . ^ ' V . v t* v v v.. if MM H * _to..* ' ■ t- .. * ■ 1 "MBS UM u AHH,YHH