iA ree fore aes ere POLAs fant ae A pO dua Bases SS alt Paras areas SOPOT OES NG Sra, 13 WIG Le (799 CORNELL UNIVERSITY LIBRARY UNDERGRADUATE LIBRARY DATE DUE istory of ancient philosophy, HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY HISTORY ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY BY DR. W. WINDELBAND PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN THE UNIVERSITY OF STRASSBURG Authorisey Cranglation BY HERBERT ERNEST CUSHMAN, Pu.D. INSTRUCTOR IN PHILOSOPHY IN TUFTS COLLEGE Second Bvition FROM THE SECOND GERMAN EDITION NEW YORK CHARLES SCRIBNER’S SONS 1901 Ll atBeirpl a Pw Be LF tye O76 ee (E59 Copyright, 1899, By Cxuaries Scriener’s Sons. All rights reserved. Sin Gok. 3B Aniversity [ress : Joun WILSON AND Son, CAMBRIDGE, U.S.A. TO WILLIAM R. SHIPMAN, LL.D. Professor of English in Cuts College, MY FRIEND AND COUNSELLOR. TRANSLATOR’S PREFACE PROFESSOR WINDELBAND’S Geschichte der Alten Philo- sophie is already well known to German philosophical readers as one of the famous Miller series of hand-books, and yet to that wider circle of English readers it is still a foreign book. In many quarters technical scholars of Greek philosophy have already commended its important innovations, and to these its erudition and scholarship are patent, In its translation, however, under the title of “The History of Ancient Philosophy,” it will reach the general reader and serve as an introduction to the beginner in phi- losophy. I have personally never been able to see why the approaches to the study of philosophy have been made as difficult and uninviting as possible. In other hard sub- jects all sorts of helps and devices are used to allure the beginner within. Into philosophy the beginner has always had to force his way with no indulgent hand to help. In the past the history of thought has too often been entirely separated from the history of affairs, as if the subjec- tive historical processes could have been possible with- out the objective concrete events. Professor Windelhand has gone far to lead the general reader to the history of thought through the history of the affairs of the Greek nation. This is, to my mind, the difficult but absolutely necessary task of the historian of thought, if he wishes to reach any but technical philosophers. This work occu- viii PREFACE pies a unique position in this respect, and may mark the beginning of an epoch in the rewriting of the history of philosophy. I am indebted to many friends for help in my transla- tion of this work. The reader will allow me to mention in particular Professor George H. Palmer, of Harvard, my friend and former teacher, for introducing me to the work ; and my colleagues, Professor Charles St. Clair Wade for much exceedingly valuable assistance, and especially Pro- fessors Charles E. Fay and Leo R. Lewis, whose generous and untiring aid in the discussion of the whole I shall ever remember. Whatever merits the translation may have, are due in no small measure to their help; for whatever defects may appear, I can hold only myself responsible. — So complete are the bibliographies here and elsewhere that I have found it necessary to append only a list of such works as are helpful to the English reader of Ancient Philosophy. HERBERT ERNEST CUSHMAN. Turts CoLLece, June, 1899. PREFACE TO THE SECOND GERMAN EDITION Havine undertaken to prepare a résumé of the history of ancient philosophy for the Handbuch der Klassischen Alter- tumswissenschaft, it seemed expedient to offer to my trained readers, not an extract from the history of the literature of the Greeks and Romans, which can be found elsewhere ; but rather a short and clear presentation, such as would awaken interest and give an insight into the subject matter and the development of ancient philosophy. The necessity of a new edition gives evidence that- this presentation has won itself friends far beyond the circle of those most nearly interested. This, moreover, would not have hap- pened had I not abandoned the idea of presenting a col- lation from the data usually furnished, and had I not given to the subject the form which my long personal experience as an academic teacher had proved to be most available. As a result I found myself in the somewhat painful posi- tion of being compelled to present didactically many very considerable deviations from the previous conception and treatment, without being able in the limitations of this résumé to advance for experts my reasons save in short references. I should have been very glad if I could have found time to justify my innovations by accompanying de- tailed discussions. But, unfortunately, the execution of my whole purpose has been postponed up to this time through more important and imperative tasks. The new x PREFACE edition, therefore, finds me again in the same position of being compelled to trust more in the force of the general relations of the subject matter and in the emphasis briefly laid upon important moments, than in a leisurely extended polemical presentation, which would otherwise have been usual in this particular field. For the chief matters in which I have gone my own ways —the separation of Pythagoras from the Pythagoreans and the discussion of the latter under “ Efforts toward Reconciliation between Heracleitanism and the Theory of Parmenides,” the separation of the two phases of Atomism by the Protagorean Sophistic, the juxtaposition of Democ- ritus and Plato, the conception of the Hellenic-Roman phil- osophy as a progressive application — first ethical and then religious — of science, to which I have also organically con- nected Patristics, —all this the reader finds unchanged in its essentials. My treatment of these questions has found recognition in many quarters, but in many also an expected opposition; and the reader may be assured that I have always been grateful for this latter, and have given it care- ful consideration. This weighing of objections was the more needful since I had occasion in the mean time to deal with the same questions in a larger connection and from a different point of view. The trained eye will not fail to recognize in this second edition the influence of the objec- tions of experts, even where these have not convinced me, in the numerous small changes in the presentation, and in the choice of bibliography and citations. Here, again, the revising hand needed to follow many a kindly suggestion in the discussions of this book, and accept many a gratifying explanation in the works that have appeared during the past. five years. The only change in the external form of the book is in the very desirable addition of an index to the philosophers discussed, PREFACE xi Then may my brief treatise continue to fulfil its task: to solicit friends appreciative of a noble cause, to preserve alive the consciousness of the imperishable worth which the creations of Greek thought possess for all human culture. WILHELM WINDELBAND. StTRAssBuRG, April, 1898. TABLE OF CONTENTS _ PacE TRANSLATOR’S PREFACE . . ... . oe Vil AUTHOR’S PREFACE (TO SECOND GERMAN 2orrrONy eee aE INTRODUCTION 1. Significance of ancient philosophy to European civilization 1 2. Division of ancient philosophy 3 3. Historical methods . .. . 5 5 4-6. Sources and developments of actu pliloasphy. 8 A.— GREEK PHILOSOPHY IntRopucTION: The preliminary conditions of philosophy in the Greek intellectual life of the seventh and sixth cen- turies B.C. . . 2. . - 16-36 7. Geographical survey... . . 16 8. Social and political relations . . - (17 9. The period of ethical reflection: the Saves Wike. Mts - 18 10. Practical and special learning. . . . . - - - - «© 20 11. Religious ideas ew em wm ow ae we, BE 12. The reformation by Byihseonas ,2 fe eS ee eS 2s 13. The first problems of science . . . . » - + - « + 88 1. Tue Mitestan Nature Puttosopay. Pages 36-45. I4.. Whales 2 = «© « a w 20 36 /15. Anaximander . . . 39 43 ‘16. Amaximenes . ... 2.2. + 6+ © «© © xiv 17. 19. 20. 21. 22. 23. 24. * 25. 26. 27. 28. 29. 30. 81. 32. 33. 34. 35. 36. 37. 38. 39. 40. 41. 42, 43. TABLE OF CONTENTS PAGE 2. Tue MetapHysicaL, ConFLict. — HeRACLEITUS AND THE Exxatics. Pages 46-71. ’ Xenophanes . i Heracleitus . 82 Parmenides, . oi Soa cReo ee eter a Saw oe tO! Zeno and Melissus . . . . 2 1. we ee ee ef 665 3. EFFORTS TOWARD ReEcoNcILIATION. Pages 71-100. Himipedocles: 6 6 a ma wow we aoe ee w we AG Anaxagoras . . ce &€ «= & e 80 The beginnings of Aarti Lencippus Bh: ak ae ee, BF _The Pythagoreans . . ow Met we eh ee OS 4. Tue Greek ENLIGHTENMENT. — THE SopuIsts AND Socrates. Pages 100-151. Eclecticism and special research . . . . . . ~~. « 100 ‘ThesSophists! 2 « © & = © % a # % w aoa uw « 708 Socrates . . . oe aoe ee 128 The Megarian and. Bigan: rete ben Setinsil: a we ew oe BS The Cynic School. . . . . . . . .. «. . . 140 The Cyrenaic School. . . . . . . . . . e 145 5. MaTERIALISM AND JpgeALIsM. — DeMocRITUS AND Prato. Pages 151-228. The life and writings of Democritus . . . . . . . 155 The theoretic philosophy of Democritus . . . . . . 159 The practical philosophy of Democritus . . . . . . 170 The life and writings of Plato. . . . . . . . . . «(174 The theory of Ideasof Plato . . . . . . . . «(189 The ethics of Plato . . . ee Oe ee aie ae ee Se 1 04 The nature philosophy of Plato Ce ok ee we o TG 6. ARISTOTLE. Pages 224-292. The Older Academy . . . “Se S @€ ww w Be The life and writings of Aristotle © 8 OR ae ay we at we 80 The logic of Aristotle . . . . . . 2... 1. O47 The metaphysics of Aristotle . . 2. . 1. 2 1. 1. 8576 The physics of Aristotle . . . . . . . . . . . 968 The ethics and poetics of Aristotle . . . « @ » » 989 44. 45. 46. 47. 48. 49. 50. 51. 52. 53. 55. 56. 1. Tue ConTROVERSIES OF THE SCHOOLS. TABLE OF CONTENTS B. — HELLENIC-ROMAN PHILOSOPHY Introduction The Peripatetics The Stoics . The Epicureans 2. SKEPTICISM AND SYNCRETISM. Pages 329-349. The Skeptics Eclecticism . ‘ Mystic Platonism . 3. Patristics. Pages 349-365. The Apologists The Gnostics and their depenentig ee 4 The Alexandrian School of Catechists: Origen . 4. Neo-Pratonism. Pages 365-383. The Alexandrian School: Plotinus . The Syrian School: Jamblichus . The Athenian School: Proclus BIBLIOGRAPHY .... + 2+ + «© © + © «© @ INDEX 2. ss @ 8 Be Ee eee eee we Pages 298-329 xV Pace 293 298 3803 319 329 337 341 352 355 361 366 375 377 385 389 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY INTRODUCTION 1. ScrENTIFIC interest in ancient, especially in Greek, philosophy, is not confined to the value that it possesses as a peculiar subject for historical research and for the study of the growth of civilization. But it is also equally con- cerned in the permanent significance that the content of ancient thought possesses by reason of its place in the development of the intellectual life of Europe. The emphasis falls primarily upon the lifting of mere knowing to the plane of systematic knowledge, or science. Not content with his storing of practical facts, and with his fantastic speculations born of his religious needs, the Greek sought knowledge for its own sake. Knowledge, like art, was developed as an independent function from its involvement in the other activities of civilization. So, first and foremost, the history of ancient philosophy is an insight into the origin of European science in general, It is, however, at the same time the history of the birth of the separate sciences. For the process of differentia- tion, which begins with distinguishing thought from con- duct and mythology, was continued within the domain of science itself. With the accumulation and organic ar- rangement of its facts, the early, simple, and unitary science to which the Greeks gave the name ¢vAogodia, divided into 1 2 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY the special sciences, the single durocopéar, and these then continued to develop on more or less independent lines. Concerning the history and meaning of the name of ‘ phi- losophy,” see especially R. Haym, in Ersch and Gruber’s Ency- klopddie, III. division, vol. 24; Ueberweg, Grundriss, I. § Le Windelband, Praeludien, p. 1ff. The word became a technical term in the Socratic school. It meant there exactly what sci- ence means in German. In later time, after the division into the special sciences, the word philosophy had the sense of ethico-religious practical wisdom. See § 2. The beginnings of scientific life that are thus found in ancient philosophy are most influential upon the entire development that follows. With proportionately few data, Greek philosophy produced, with a kind of grand simplicity, conceptual forms for the intellectual elaboration of its facts, and with a remorseless logic it developed every essential point of view for the study of the universe. Therein con- sists the peculiar character of ancient thought and the high didactic significance of its history. Our present language and our conception of the world are thoroughly permeated by the results of ancient science. The naive ruggedness with which ancient philosophers followed out single motives of reflection to their most one-sided logical conclusions, brings into clearest relief that practical and psychological necessity which governs not only the evolution of the problems of philosophy, but also the repeated historical tendencies toward the solution of these problems. We may likewise ascribe a typical significance to the universal stages of development af ancient philosophy, in view of the fact that philosophy at first turned with undaunted courage to the study of the outer world; thwarted there, it turned back to the inner world, and from this point of view, with renewed strength, it attempted to conceive the World-All. Even the manner in which ancient thought placed its entire apparatus of conceptual knowledge at the service of INTRODUCTION 3 social and religious needs has a peculiar and more than historical value. The real significance of ancient philosophy will be much ex- aggerated if one tries to draw close analogies between the dif- ferent pbases of modern philosophy and its exponents, and those of the ancients. Read K. v. Reichlin-Meldegg, D. Paral- lelismus d. alten u. neuen Philosophie, Leipzig and Heidelberg, 1865. A detailed parallelism is impossible, because all the forms of the modern history of civilization have so much more nearly complete presuppositions, and are more complicated than those of the ancient world. The typical character of the latter is valid in so far as they have ‘‘ writ large” and often nearly grotesquely the simple and elemental forms of mental life, which among moderns are far more complicated in their combinations. 2 The total of that which is usually designated as ancient philosophy falls into two large divisions, which must be distinguished as much in respect to the civilizations that form their background as in respect to the intel- lectual principles that move them. These divisions are, (1) Greek philosophy, and (2) Hellenic-Roman philosophy. We may assume the year of the death of Aristotle, 322 B. c., as the historical line of demarcation between the two. Greek philosophy grew out of an exclusive national culture, and is the legitimate offspring of the Greek spirit. The Hellenic-Roman philosophy came, on the other hand, out of much more manifold and contradictory intellectual movements. After the days of Alexander the Great a culture that was so cosmopolitan that it broke down all national barriers, increased in ever-widening circles among the nations upon the Mediterranean Sca. The fulfilment of these intellectual movements was objectively expressed in the Roman Empire, subjectively in Christianity ; and, be it remarked, the Hellenic-Roman philosophy forms one of the mightiest factors in this very process of amalgamation. Moreover, there is a not less important difference in the scientific interest of the two periods. (Greek philosophy 4 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY began with an independent desire for knowledge.) It was ever concerned in the quest for knowledge that was free ‘from all subordinate purposes. It perfected itself in Aris- totle, partly in his logic, which was a universal theory of knowledge, and partly in the scheme of a developed. system of sciences. The energy of this purely theoretic interest was gradually extinguished in the following time, and was only partly -maintained in, unpretentious work upon the objective special sciences. (The practical question how the Wise Man should live entered into “ philosophy,” however, and knowledge was no longer sought on account of itself but as a means of right living. \ In this way the Hellenic- Roman philosophy fell into dependence upon the general but temporary changes in society,—-a thing that never happened in purely Greek philosophy. Then later its | original ethical tendency changed entirely into the effort to find by means of science a satisfaction for religious aspira- tion. Gn Greece, philosophy, therefore, was science that had ripened into independence; in Hellenism and the Roman Empire, philosophy entered. with a full possession of its consciousness_into the service ofthe. social and religious mission of man. It is obvious, from the elasticity of all historical divisions, that this antithesis is not absolute, but only relative. The post- Aristotelian philosophy is not entirely lacking in endeavors for the essentially theoretical, nor indeed among the purely Greek thinkers are there wanting those who set for philosophy ultimately practical ends, — the Socraties for example. How- ever, comparison of the different definitions which in the course of antiquity have been given for the problem of philosophy, justifies, on the whole, the division we have chosen, which takes the purpose of philosophy in its entirety as the principium divisionis. These divisions approach most nearly among later writers those of Ch. A. Brandis in his shorter work, Gesch. d. Entwick. d. griechischen Phil. u. ihrer Nachwirkungen im romischen Reiche (2 vols., Berlin, 1862 and 1864), although he distin- guishes formally three periods here, as in his larger work. INTRODUCTION 5 These periods are: (1) pre-Socratic philosophy; (2) the devel- opment from Socrates to Aristotle ; (3) post-Aristotelian phi- losophy. Yet he unites the first two divisions as ‘‘ the first half,” and distinctly recognizes their inner relationship in con- trast to the third division, which forms ‘the second half.” Zeller and Schwegler also employ these three periods as the basis of their work upon the Greeks, while Ritter puts the Stoics and Epicureans also in the second period. Hegel, on the other hand, treats the entire Greek philosophy until Aris- totle as the first period, to which he adds the Greco-Roman philosophy as the second and the neo-Platonic philosophy as the third. Ueberweg accepts the divisions of Ritter, with this variation, — he transfers the Sophists from the first period to the second. We purposely desist from dividing here the two chief periods of philosophy into subordinate periods. The demand for com- prehensiveness, which alone would justify further divisions, is satisfied with the simple general divisions, while a comprehen- sive view of the steps in development is provided for in another manner by the treatment of individual doctrines. If a completer subdivision should be insisted upon, the following might be adopted : — (a) Greek philosophy into three periods : — (1) The cosmological, which includes the entire pre-Socratic speculation, and reaches down to about 450 B. c. (§§ 1-8); (2) The anthropological, to which belong the men of the Greek Enlightenment, i. e., the Sophists, Socrates, and the so- called Socratic schools (§ 4) ; (3) The systematic, which by its uniting the two preceding periods is the flowering period of Greek science. (b) Hellenic-Roman philosophy into two sections : — (1) The school-controversies of the post-Aristotelian time, with the accompanying essential ethical tendency, critical skep- ticism, and retrospective erudition (§§ 1 and 2). (2) Eclectic Platonism, with its bifurcation into the rival sys- tems of Christian and neo-Platonic religions (§§ 3 and 4). 3. The scientific treatment of the history of philosophy or of a part of that history, as in this treatise, has a double task. On the one hand it must determine the actual number of those concepts which are claimed to be “philosophic,” and must conceive them in their genesis, particularly in their relation to each other. On the other * 6 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY hand, it must determine the value of each individual philosophic doctrine in the development of the scientific consciousness.. In the first regard the history of philosophy is purely an historical science. As such, it must without any predilec- tion proceed, by a careful examination of the tradition, to establish with philological exactness the content of the philosophic doctrines. It must explain their origin with all the precautionary measures of the historical method. It furthermore must make clear their genetic relations, on the one hand, to the personal life of the philosophers, and, on the other, to civilization as a whole. In this way it will be plain how philosophy has attained to an actual process of development. From this historical point of view, however, there arises for the history of philosophy the critical task of determin- ing-the-restritts which the various systems of philosophy have yielded for the construction of the human concep- tion of the world. The point of view for this critical study need not be the peculiar philosophical attitude of history. Nevertheless it must, on the one hand, be that of inner criticism, which tests the teaching of a philosophical sys- tem by logical compatibility and consistency ; it must, on the other hand, be that of historical generalization, which estimates philosophical teaching according to its intellec- tual fruitfulness and its practical historical efficacy . The history of ancient philosophy as a science has to meet very great and sometimes insuperable difficulties in the fragmentary character of the literary sources. On the other hand, in its critical problem, it is fortunate in being able, after a development of nearly two thousand years, to judge the value of individual teaching with no personal bias. The different points of view taken in investigating the his tory of philosophy are as follows: — INTRODUCTION a (1) The naive point of view of description. According to this the teachings of the different philosophers are supposed to be reported with historical authenticity. So soon, however, as any report is claimed to be of scientific value, the tradition must be criticised; and this, as all other historical criticism, can be accomplished only by investigating the sources. (2) The genetic point of view of explanation, which has three possible forms, — (a) The psychological explanation. This represents the per- sonality and individual relations of the respective philosophers as the actual causes or occasions of their opinions. (b) The pragmatic method. This is an attempt to under- stand the teaching of each philosopher by explaining the contra- dictions and unsolved problems of his immediate predecessors. (c) The kultur-historisch view. This sees in the philosophical systems the progressive consciousness of the entire ideal de- velopment of the human mind. (3) The speculative attitude of criticism. Starting from a systematic conviction, this seeks to characterize the different phases of philosophical development by the contributions thereto which they have severally furnished. (Compare Hegel, in Vor- lesungen iiber d. Gesch. d. Phil., Complete Works, Vol. XIII. 19 ff.; Ueberweg, Grandriss, I. § 3; Windelband, Gesch. d. Phil., Freiburg i. B., 1892, §§ 1 and 2.) Until within the previous century enumeration of the placita philosophorum, with some little application of the pragmatic method, essentially predomi- nated in the history of philosophy. Hegel, with all the exageer- ation of this speculative point of view, was the first to raise philosophy from a mere collection of curiosities to a science. His constructive and fundamental idea — that in the historical order of philosophical theories the categories of true philoso- phy repeat themselves as progressive achievements of human- ity —involved an emphasis upon the kultur-historisch and the pragmatic explanations, and this required only the individual- istic psychological supplementation. On account of Hegel’s speculative conception, on the other hand, historical criticism fell with the disappearance of faith in the absolute philosophy. By this historical criticism the mere establishment of the facts and their genetic explanation are changed into a complete philo- sophical science. Hegel created the science of the history of philosophy according to its ideal purposes, but not until after his day was safe ground presented for achieving such a science by the philological method of getting the data without presupposi- tions. Upon no territory has this method since recorded such far-reaching success as upon the field of ancient philosophy. 8 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY 4. The scientific helps to the study of ancient philos- ophy fall into three classes : — (a) The Original Sources. Only a very few of the writings of ancient philosophers have becn preserved. As to complete single works in the purely Greek philos- ophy, they are to be found only in Plato and Aristotle. The original sources, however, are richer in the Hellenic- Roman period. (The writings of thé ancient Greek think- .ers are preserved in only a fragmentary way through vincidental citations of later literature.) The most comprehensive collection not especially mentioned hereafter, is that of F. W. A. Mullach, Fragmenta philosopho- rum Grecorum (3 vols., Paris, 1860-81). Yet it satisfies to- day neither the demands for completeness nor for accuracy. Nevertheless the works that have come down to us are by no means to be accepted im toto and on trust. Not alone unintentionally, but also from its desire to give to its own teaching, so far as possible, the nimbus of ancient /wisdom, later_antiquity substituted in many instances its own compositions for the writings of the ancients, or in- erpolated their texts. | The sources of Greek philosophy n particular are not only in a very fragmentary but also ‘in a very uncertain state, and we are still limited to a conjecture of a greater or less degree of probability in regard to many very weighty questions. N The philological- historical criticism, which seems indispensable under these circumstances, requires a safe criterion for our guidance, and this criterion we possess in the works of Plato and Aristotle. Opposed to the easy credulity with which in the previous century (according to Buble) tradition was received, Schleier- macher had the especial merit of having begun and incited a fruitful criticism. Brandis, Trendelenburg, Zeller, and Diels were likewise the leaders in this direction. 5. (6) The Corroborative Testimony of Antiquity. Early (according to Xenophon) in ancient literature we find tes- INTRODUCTION ‘ 9 timony on the life and death of notable philosophers. Of importance for us, moreover, are the passages in which Plato and Aristotle —especially in the beginning of his Metaphysics — linked their own teaching to the early phi- losophy. At the time of Aristotle there arose a widely spread, partly historical and partly critical literature, con- cerning what was then ancient philosophy. Unfortunately, ? this has been lost, excepting a few fragments. Especially deplorable is the loss of the writings of this character of Aristotle and his immediate disciples, — Theophrastus in particular. Similar works, likewise no longer extant, issued from the Academy, in which, moreover, commentating also had its beginning at an early time. So, also, the historical | ? and critical work stoi rer. ; This historiography of philosophy, the so-called dox- ography, with its commentating and collating, developed enormously in the Alexandrian literature, and had its three philosophical centres in Pergamus, Rhodes, and Alexandria. These, voluminoys-and—numerous works in their original | 7 form are in the main lost, Yet with all recognition of |! ¢ the erudition that doubtless permeated them, it must still be maintained that they bave exercised a bewildering influence in various ways upon succeeding writers, who took excerpts directly out of them. Besides this almost unavoidable danger of reading later conceptions and theo- ries into the old teaching, there appear three chief sources of error, — (1) In the inclination to fix the succession of ancient philoso- phers after the manner of the later successions of scholarchs. (2) In the fantastic tendency to dignify ancient Greece with { ee the miracuious and the extraordinary. (3) Finally, in the effort that sprang out of an undefined feel- ing of the dependence of Grecian upon Oriental culture. En- couraged by a new acquaintance with the East, some scholars A x have tried to knit every significant fact as closely as possible with Oriental influence. 10 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY Statements at only third or fourth hand are left over to us from the Roman period. The historical notes in the fragments of Varro, in the writings of Cicero (Rud. Hirzel, Untersuch. zu CO. philos. Schriften, 8 parts, Leipzig, 1877- 1883), as well as of Seneca, Lucretius, and Plutarch, are valuable, but must be used with care. The philosophical- historical writings of Plutarch are lost. The .compila- tion preserved under his name, De physicis philosophorum decretts (in Diibner’s edition of the Morais, Paris, 1841), is, according to Diels, an abstract of the Placita of Aétius, dating back to Theophrastus, and was made perhaps in the middle of the second century. The spurious book srepi gtroadpov ioropias, which is falsely ascribed to Galen, is in the main identical with it (published in the nineteenth vol- ume of Kiihn’schen Gesamtausgabe). Many later excerpts of Favorinus are included among the uncritically collected reports; so, also, those of Apuleius and of Gellius (Woctes attice, ed. Hertz, Leipzig, 1884-85; see also Mercklin, Die Zitiermethode u. Quellenbenutzung des A. G., Leipzig, 1860). lLucian’s writings must also be mentioned in this connection. Those numberless historical accounts in the writings of Galen (especially De placitis Hippocratis et Platonis, separately published by Iwan Miller, Leipzig, 1874) and of Sextus Empiricus (Op. ed. Bekker, Berlin, 1842 : ruppaveso. brotuTm@cess and pds waOnuaTcKovs) are philosophically more trustworthy. Out of the same period grew the work of Flavius Philostratus, Vite sophistarum (ed. Westermann, Paris, 1849), and of Atheneus, Deipno- sophiste (ed. Meineke, Leipzig, 1857-69). Finally, there is the book which was regarded for a long time almost as the principal source for a history of ancient philosophy ; viz., that of Diogenes Laertius, wept Blwv, Soyudrav cab aTropbeyudtav tev év Pirocopia eddoxiunadytwv BiBrla déxa (ed. Cobet, Paris, 1850). ‘ Another kind of secondary sources is furnished by the INTRODUCTION 11 writings of the church fathers, who have polemical, apolo- getic, and dogmatic aims in reproducing the Greek phi- losophy. This is especially true of Justin Martyr, Clement of Alexandria, Origen («ara KéAcov), Hippolytus ( Refuta- tioomnium heresium, ed. Duncker, Gitt., 1859, the first book of this being formerly supposed to be a work of Origen under the title dsrocogdotpeva), Eusebius (Prep. evang., ed. Dindorf, Leipzig, 1868), and in certain respects also Tertul- lianand Augustine. The importance of the church fathers as sources for the study of ancient philosophy has attained recently to a completer and more fruitful recognition, especially since the impulse given by Diels to their study. Finally, the activity in commentating and historical re- search was carried on in a lively fashion in the neo- Platonic school. The chief work indeed, that of Porphyry, is not preserved (fiAccodos ictopia). On the other hand, the writings of the neo-Platonists in general offer numerous historical data; and, as already the earlier commentaries of Alexander of Aphrodisias (zu Arist. Met., ed. Hayduck, Berlin, 1891, and zu Arist. Top.,M. Wallies, Berlin, 1891 ; smaller works by Ivo Bruns, Berlin, 1898), — so the com- mentaries of Themistius, and especially Simplicius, contain many carefully and intelligently compiled excerpts from the direct and indirect sources of earlier times. Among - the latest writers of ancient literature the collections of Stobeus and Photius, and those also of Hesychius, appear useful for the history of philosophy. Compare Diels, Doxoqraphi Greci (Berlin, 1879). An ex- cellent and, for a beginning, an extraordinarily instructive collection of the most important passages from the primary and secondary sources is that of Ritter and Preller in their Historia philosophice Greco-romane ex fontium locis conteata (7 ed. is brought out by Schulthess and Wellmann, Gotha, 1888). 6. (ec) The Modern Expositions. Scholarly treatment of ancient philosophy was in modern literature con- 12 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY fined at first to a brief criticism of the latest works of antiquity. Thus, the occasional historical collections con- cerned with ancient philosophy which we find in the Humanistic literature, in the main led back to neo-Platonic sources. The very first work, the History of Philosophy, by Thomas Stanley (London, 1665), scarcely more than reproduced the reports of Diogenes Laertius. Bayle in his Dictionnaire historique et critique (1 ed., Rotterdam, 1697), gaye a. powerful impulse to critical treatment. Later appeared the writings of Brucker, thoroughgoing, industriously compiled, but in point of fact not equal to the task: Kurze Fragen aus der philosophischen Historie (Ulm, 1731 f.), Historia critica philosophie (Leipzig, 1742 f.), Institutiones historia philosophie (Leipzig, 1747; -a compendium for a school manual). With the formation of the great schools of philosophy, particularly in Germany, the history of philosophy began to be treated with reference to its single directions and systems. In the front D. Tiedemann came with his em- pirical-sceptical Geist der Philosophie (Marburg, 1791 ff.). Then followed, from the Kantian point of view, J. G. Buhle with Lehrbuch der Geschichte der Philosophie (Gott., 1796 ff.); Tennemann, Geschichte der Philosophie, 1798 ff.); then the Grundriss der Geschichte der Philosophie (5th ed.), Amada. Wendt, Leipzig, 1829, a much used epitome, commending itself by its careful literary data; and J. F. Fries, Geschichte der Philosophie (1 vol., Halle, 1837). From the Schellingen point of view, there are Fr. Ast’s Grundriss einer Geschichte der Philosophie (Landshut, 1807); E. Reinhold, Geschichte der Philosophie nach den Hauptpunkten ihrer Entwickelung (Jena, 1858). From the point of view of Schleiermacher, are his own notes for his lectures on the history of philosophy in a collection | 1 Upon which a philosophical article of value in part even to- day has been published in German by H. Jacob (1797-98, Halle). INTRODUCTION 13 of three parts, four volumes (Berlin, 1839): H. Ritter, Die Geschichte der Philosophie (Hamburg, 1829 ff.); F. Ch. Potter, Die Geschichte der Philosophie in Umriss (Elberfeld, 1873).1 From the Hegelian point of view, are Hegel’s lectures upon the history of philosophy in his complete works, XIII. ff.; J. E. Erdmann, Grundriss der Geschichte der Philosophie (8 ed., Berlin, 1878). From the Herbartian point of view, is Ch. A. Thilo, Kurze pragmatische Geschichte der Philosophie (Céthen, 2 ed., 1880). With especial reference to the factual development of problems and concepts, ancient philosophy has also been treated by W. Windelband, Geschichte der Philosophie (Freiburg i. Br., 1892). Of the other numerous complete presentations of the history of philosophy, that of J. Berg- mann (Berlin, 1892) may be finally mentioned. Of the presentations in other languages than German which also give valuable contribution to the study of ancient philosophy, may be here mentioned: V. Cousin, Histoire générale de la philosophie (12 ed., Paris, 1884); A. Weber, Histoire de philosophie européenne (Paris, 5 ed., 1892); A. Fouillée, Histoire de la Philosophie (Paris, 3 ed., 1882); R. Blakey, History of the Philosophy of Mind (London, 1848); G. H. Lewes, A Biographical History of Philosophy (London, 4 ed., 1871, German ed., Berlin, 1871). The completest literary data for the historiography of philos- ophy, and particularly ancient philosophy, are found in Ueber- weg, Grundriss d. Philos., a work which presents also in its remarkable continuation by M. Heinze (7 ed., Berlin, 1886) an indispensable completeness in its annotations. The texts fur- nished by Ueberweg himself were at first only superficially systematized by him, and were given an unequal, confused, and, for beginners, untransparent character by his later additions, interpolations, and annotations. 1 An inspiring statement of the development of ancient philosophy is also that of Brandis’s Geschichte der Philos. seit Kant, 1 Part (Breslau, 1842). 14 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY The profounder philological studies at the beginning of the nineteenth century were advantageous to the history of ancient philosophy, since a critical sifting of tradition and a philological and methodical basis for historical- philosophical research was facilitated (compare Zeller, Jahr- biicher der Gegenwart, 1848). The greatest credit for such a stimulus is due to Schleiermacher, whose translation of Plato was a powerful example, and whose special works upon Heracleitus, Diogenes of Apollonia, Anaximander, and others have been placed in Part III. book 2, of his col- lected works. Among the numerous special researches are to be mentioned A. B. Krische’s Forschungen auf dem Gebiete der alten Philosophie (Gitt., 1840) ; also A. Trende- lenburg, Historische Beitrdge zur Philosophie (Berlin, 1846 f.), the author of which deserves credit for his stimula- tion of Aristotelian studies ; H. Siebeck, Untersuchungen zur Philosophie der Griechen (2 ed., Freiburg i. Br., 1888); G. Teichmiiller, Studien zur Geschichte der Begriffe (Berlin, 1874 ff.); O. Apelt, Beitrdge zur Geschichte der griechischen Philosophie (Leipzig, 1891); E. Norden (the same title), Leipzig, 1892, As the first product of these critico-philological studies, « we may consider the praiseworthy work of Ch. A. Brandis, Handbuch der Geschichte der griechisch-rémischen Philoso- phie (Berlin, 1885-60), by the side of which the author placed a shorter and especially finely conceived exposition, Geschichte der Entwickelungen der griechischen Philosophie und ihrer Nachwirkungen im rémischen Reiche (Berlin, 1€62 u. 1864). With less cxhaustiveness, but with a peculiar superiority in the development of the problems, Ludw. Striimpell (2d part, Leipzig, 1854, 1861), K. Prantl (Stuttgart, 2 ed., 1863), and A. Schwegler (3 ed., espe- cially, by Késtlin, Freiburg, 1883) treated the same subject. All these valuable works, and with them the numerous synopses, compendiums, and compilations (see Ueberweg, INTRODUCTION 15 above mentioned, pp. 27-29), are overshadowed beside that masterpiece and, for many reasons, final word upon ancient philosophy: EH. Zeller, Die Philosophie der Griechen (Tii- bingen, 1844 ff.: the first book is published in the fifth edi- tion, the second in the fourth edition, the others in the third edition). Here, upon the broadest philological-histonical foundation and upon original sources, a philosophical, authoritative, and illuminating statement is given of the entire development. Zeller has published a clever sum- mary of the whole in Grundriss d. Gesch. der Alten Philos. (4 ed., Leipzig, 1893). The special sides of ancient philosophy have been presented in the following notable works : — Logic: K. Prantl, Gesch. d. Logik im Abendlande (vols. 1 and 2, Leipzig, 1855 and 1861); P. Natorp, Forschungen z. Gresch. des Erkenntnissproblems im and adds certain more or less happy observations of his own. Among the latter 1 Eus. Prep. ev., 1. 8, 4: evar Aéyer 7d may dei Suocov. Hippolyt. Ref, I. 14: ére &v 1d wav eorw %a peraBodrjjs. He also denied movement to the world-all ; compare Simpl. Phys , 6", 23,6: aici & ev rwttd re uévew kivotpevor ovdey obde perépxerOai pv emumperet GAdobev GAA. 2 This very opposition Aristotle emphasizes in connection with Met., I. 5. 3 Tt is possible, also, that he endeavored to avoid a difficulty here by an indefinite expression, just as Diogenes, IT. 1, reports that Anaximander (no source of authority given) taught: 7a pev pepn peraSdddew. 7d de may dyerdBdnrov elvat. 4 Thus he lets stand the plurality of mythical gods under the meta- physical Godhead. 5 Theophrastus appears to think him the pupil of Anaximander See Zeller, T4. 508, 1. + 50 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY belong the very childish ideas about astronomical objects. For instance, the ‘stars were to him clouds of fire, which were quenched when they set and were enkindled when they rose; he attached great significance to the earth as the fundamental element of the empirical world (with the addition of the water), and he thought it to be endless? in its downward direction. His statement was more happy about the petrifactions he had observed in Sicily, as a proof of the original drying of the earth from its muddy condi- tion Yet Xenophanes apparently held such physical theories concerning the individual and temporary in small esteem compared to his religious metaphysics, which he championed vehemently. To this only can his sceptical remarks in one of his fragments® refer. — The differing statements as to when Xenophanes lived can be reconciled most easily by assuming that the time when he, according to his own statement (Diog. Laert., IX. 19), at twenty- five began his wanderings, coincided with the invasion by the Per- sians under Harpagus (546, in consequence of which so many Jonians left their homes). He himself testifies (loc. cit.) that his wanderings lasted sixty-seven years, at which time he must have attained the age of at least ninety-two. Impoverished during the emigration, if not already poor, which is less prob- able, he supported himself as a rhapsodist by the public render- ing of his own verses. In old age he settled in Elea, the founding of which in 537 by the fugitive Phoenicians he cele- brated in two thousand distichs. According to the preserved fragments, his poetic activity was essentially of the Gnomic order (§ 9). He embodied his teaching in a didactic poem in hexameter, of which only a few fragments remain. These have been collated by Mullach; also by Karsten, Philosophorum Grecorum operum reliquic, I. 1 (Amsterdam, 1835) ; ; Reinhold, De genuina Xenophanis doctrina (Jena, 1847), and in the dif. ferent works about Xenophanes by Franz Kern (Programm, Stob. Ecl., I. 522 (Doz., 348). Achilles Tatius in Jsagoge ad Aratum, 128. Simpl. Phys. 414, 189, 1. Sext. Emp. Adv. math., IX. 361. Hippol. Ref., I. 14 (Dox. 565). Sextus Emp., VIL, 49, 110; VIII. 326. Stob. Eel., I. 224, a a THE METAPHYSICAL CONFLICT 51 Naumburg, 1864; Oldenburg, 1876; Danzig, 1871; Stettin, 1874, 1877) ; Freudenthal, Die Theologie des Xenophanes (Bres- lau, 1886). Compare Arch. f. Gesch. d. Philos., 1. 322 f. The pseudo-Aristotelian treatise De Xenophane, Zenone, Gor- gia (printed in the works of Aristotle, and in Mullach, Fragm. I. 271, also under the title De Aelisso, Xenophune et 'Gorgia), came from the Peripatetic school. According to the investiga- tions of Brandis, Bergk, Ueberweg, Vermehren, and Zeller, we may believe that the last part of this work doubtless treats of Gorgias, and the first part almost as surely of Melissus. ‘The middle portion presupposes an older presentation about Xenoph- anes which was referred wrongly by a later commentator to Zeno, and was supplemented with some statements about Zeno’s views drawn from other sources. This part of the treatise can be used only with the greatest judgment, and then as illustra- tive of what on the one hand the fragments, and on the other the reports, of Aristotle give. ‘ The teaching of Xenophanes, immature as it appears, nevertheless discloses the inadequacy of the- Milesian con- cept of the dpy7. In or behind the change of single things, he said, should be sought a cosmic principle that creates them all, but yet itself always remains unchanged. But if we seriously conceive of. this cosmic principle of Xenophanes as utterly unchangeable, and at the same time regard it as the sole and all-embracing actuality, it is impossible to understand its capacity of being ceaselessly transmuted into individual things. The two ian gata tifs that had been fundamental in the cqncept of the apy now part company, — on the one hand, the reflection upon the fundamental fact of the cosmic process “(Gesehehen), on the other the fundamental-postulate of the permanent, of the unchangeably self- -determined, of Being. ‘The more— difficult their reconciliation appeared, the more conceivable is it that the young science, at whose command there was as yet no wealth of mediating data, and which on the other hand was developed with naive unconcern, should fall upon the expedient of thinking out each motif by itself without regard for the other. From this courageous onesidedness, 52° HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY undaunted as it was at paradoxical consequences, origi- nated the two great metaphysical systems whose opposition determined later thought. These are the theories of Hera- _cleitus and Parmenides. ~~ {8. The doctrine of absolute, ceaseless, and universal mutability already was even in antiquity regarded as the kernel of Heracleitanism. Its watchword is mdvra fet ; and when Plato! gave the phrase a new turn, étc ravta yapel Kat ovdey péver, he gave at the same time the obverse of the proposition, viz., the denial of the permanent. Here in this is Heracleitus, “the Dark,” essentially distinguished from the Milesian philosophers, with whom he, under the name of the “Jonian natural philosophers,” is generally classed (§ 16). MHeracleitus found nothing permanent in the d, and he gave up search for it. In the most varied phrase he presented the fundamental truth of the continuous transmutation of all things into one another. From every realm of life he seized ex- amples, in order to point out the passage of opposites into each other. He described in bold figures the ceaselessness of change, which was to him the essence of the world, and needed no derivation and explanation. There are no truly existing things, but all things only become and pass away again in the play of perpetual world-movement. The apy7 is not so much immutable matter in independent motion, as the Milesians had said, but is the motion itself, from which all forms of matter are later derived as products. This thought is stated by Heracleitus by no means with con- ceptual clearness, but in sensuous pictures. Already the Milesian investigators had noted that all motion and change are connected with temperature changes (§ 16), and so Heracleitus thought that the eternal cosmic motion ex- pressed itself by fire. Fire is the apy, but not as a stuff identical with itself in all its changes, but rather as the 1 Cratyl., 402 a. THE METAPHYSICAL CONFLICT 53 ever-uniform process itself, in which all things rise and pass away. It is the world itself, therefore, in its unorigi- nating and unperishing mutability.1 The exceptional difficulty of this relationship was remarked by the ancients, and from it, especially, the Ephesian got his nickname, oxorewds. Herein appeared the amalgamation of the abstract and the concrete, of the sensuous and the symboli- eal, which, in general, characterized the entire thought and habit of expression of Heracleitus. Neither to oracular pride nor to the assumption of mysteriousness (Zeller, I’. 570 f.) is this deficiency to be attributed in his writing, but to inability to find an adequate form for his aspiring abstract thought. Besides this, a priestly ceremoniousness of tone is unmistak- able. Hence the wrestling with language which appears in nearly all the fragments; hence the rhetorical vehemence of expression and a heaping up of metaphors, in which a power- ful and sometimes grotesque fancy is displayed. Concerning especially his fundamental teaching, his words seem to show in isolated passages that he had only substituted fire for water or air. But more exact search shows that the apy? meant quite a different thing to him. He also identified fire and the world-all and fire and the Godhead ; — nay, hylozoic pantheism finds in the teaching of Heracleitus its own most perfect expression. Yet he meant that this world principle is only the movement represented in the fire. It is the cosmic process itself. Heracleitus proceeded from the point of view that the fire-motion is originally in itself the final ground of things, and accordingly no permanent Being is fundamental in it. He found fire to be the condition of every change, and therefore the object of scientific knowledge. But he did not only mean this in the sense that “ nothing is perma- nent save change,” but also in the higher sense that this eternal movement completes itself in determined and ever- recurrent forms. From this metaphysical thesis he at- tempted to understand the problem of the ever-permanent series of repetitions, the rhythm of movement and the law 1 Fr. 46 (Schust.) xécpor rév abrov dndvray ol're rts Oe@v obte dvOpar ‘ an mov eroingev, GAN fy del kal €oTrw wip deifwov. 54 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY of change. in _o obscure and undeveloped form. originated here the conception: of natural law.) It appeared in the vesture of the mythical Eivapuévn, as an all-determining Fate, or an all-powerful Accn, menacing every deviation with punishment. Since it is to be regarded as the peculiar object of reason, he called it the Adyos, —the reason that rules the world. In the later presentations of this theory, in which its Stoicism appears, it is difficult to get at what is in itself peculiarly Heracleitan (Zeller, 14. 606 f.). But the fundamental thought of a world-order of natural phenomena cannot be denied to Heracleitus. Compare M. Heinze, Die Lehre vom Logos in der griechischen Philosophie (Leipzig, 1872). The most universal form of the cosmic process was, there- fore, for Heracleitus that of opposition and its elimination. From the notion of the “flow of all things,” it followed that every single thing in its continuous change unites in itself perpetually opposing determinations. Everything is only a transition, a point of limit between the vanishing and the about-to-be. The life of nature is a continuous pass- ing into one another of all opposites, and out of their strife come the individual things : 7oAeuos wdvtev yey ratip ort, mavtov b€ Bactrevs.1 But as these antitheses ultimately arise only out of the universal and all-embracing, living, fiery, cosmic force, so they find their adjustment and reconciliation in this same fire. Fire is, in this respect, the “ unseen har- mony.”2 The world-all is consequently the self-divided? and the self-reuniting unity. It is at one and the same + Fr. 75. 2 Compare Fr. 8: dppovin yap dpavis pavepijs kpeirrav. ev Aras Siahopas kal érepornras 6 puyviev Oeds expuipe kal xarédvoev. Comp. Zeller, I‘. 604 f. The dpavjs here obviously characterizes the metaphysical in opposition to the physical. 8 Plato, Symp., 187 a: 16 év diadepdpevov airé aitG. Compare Soph., 242 c; also Fr. 98. a 4 Heracleitus sought to picture this relationship in the obviously unfor THE METAPHYSICAL CONFLICT 55 time strife and peace; or what seems to mean! the same in Heracleitus’ terminology, it is at one and the same time want and fulness.” The physical application of these principles afforded a thoroughgoing theory of the elemental changes in the universe. Action and reaction take place in orderly suc- cession, and indeed in such wise that they are constantly balanced in their results. Thus it happens that single things have the appearance of persisting, when two oppos- ing forces temporarily hold each other in equilibrium, as, for instance, the river appears as a permanent thing because just as much water flows to a point as flows from it. Heracleitus designated this rhythm of change as the two “ Ways” which are identical, the odds catw and the odds dvw.8 By the first Way the original fire changes itself into water and then into earth through condensation ; by the second the earth changes back through liquefac- tion to water and then to fire. This double process is true in one respect for the entire world; for in regularly recurrent periods‘ it develops into individual things from the original fire, and then returns to the initial condition of pure fire. Hence comes the idea of alternating world- formation and world-destruction.5 On the other hand, this tunate figure of the bow and the lyre: wadivrovos [-rpomos] yap déppovin koopov Oxwomep Toéou kal Avpys. As to the meanings, see Zeller, 14. 598 f. 1 Ibid , 641. 2Fr. 67. From these determinations apparently come veixos and prAcrns, the different conditions developed by Empedocles (§ 21). 3 Compare Diog Laert., IX. 8. The designations carw and dvw are to be understood as first of all spatial, but they appear to have acquired a connotation of value. A thing becomes less valuable, the farther it is from the fiery element. 4 He has suggested for these the Great Year (18,000 or 10,800 years ?) ; following perhaps the Chaldeans. 5 The acceptance of successive world-formations and destructions in Heracleitus may be looked upon as assured from the deductions of Zeller, It. 626-640. 56 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY orderly change of matter verifies itself in every single series in nature. How far Heracleitus, however, applied his view to particular physical objects, we do not know. In cosmogony, he appears to have been satisfied with bring- ing the “sea” out of the primitive fire, and then out of the sea the earth on the one hand, and on the other the warm air. The only detail authoritatively attested — one that re- iinds us of XKenophanes — that the sun is a mass of vapor, taking fire in the morning and becoming extinguished in the evening, reconciles us to the loss of other theories of Heracleitus, in case he had any. For Heracleitus was less a physicist than a metaphysician. He thought out a single fundamental principle with profound reflection and vivid imagination. His interest lay in the most general of principles and in anthropological questions. It can scarcely be accidental that in the preserved fragments of Heracleitus there is little peculiarly physical, but much that is metaphysical and anthropological.. If his writing actually had three Adyo. (Diog. Laert., IX. 5), of which one dealt with mept Tov wavros, and both the others were zroAurixds and GeodoyiKde, this is proof that we have to do with a philosopher who did not, as his Milesian predecessors, accord a merely casual consideration to human life, but made it his prime study. The conflict of the pure fire and the lower elements into which everything changes repeats itself in man. The soul as the living principle is fire, and finds itself a captive in a body made out of water and earth, which, on account of its inherent rigidness, is to the soul an abhorrent object. With this theory Heracleitus united ideas of transmigra- tion, of retribution after death, and the like; and he, as Pythagoras, seems to have attached it to certain Mysteries. In general he took a position in religious matters similar to that of Pythagoras. Without breaking entirely with the popular faith, he espoused an interpretation of the myths that inclined toward monotheism and had an ethical import. THE METAPHYSICAL CONFLICT 57 The vitality of the soul, and consequently its perfection in every respect, depends on its deriving its nourishment from the cosmic fire, the universal reason, the Aoyos. The breath is the physical medium of obtaining this nourish- ment, and cessation of the breath stops activity. A further medium of life, however, is sense perception, which is the absorption of the outer through the inner fire; and this accounts for the depression of soul-activity in sleep. The drier and more fiery, the better and wiser is the soul, and the more does it participate in the universal cosmic reason. Since the cosmic reason is cosmic law, the reasonableness of man consists in his conformity to law, and in his con- scious subordination to it. On that account Heracleitus regarded the ethical and political tasks of mankind as expressions of the supremacy of law. His entire aristo- cratic hate against the democracy, that had attained to power, is revealed in diatribes against the anarchy of the multitudes and their caprice. Only in subordination to order and in the last instance to cosmic law, can man win that serenity which constitutes his happiness. In an apprehension of law, however, and in subordination to the universally valid, Heracleitus found the theoretical goal of mankind. Only the reason and not sense perception guarantees the attainment of this goal, and without the reason eyes and ears are bad witnesses. The great mass 1 The well-known Fragment 11 (Sext. Emp. Adv. math., VII. 126), kakul pdptupes avOpdmoiow dpOarpol Kal Gra BapBdpous huxds éyovray, is usually interpreted as a disdain of sense knowledge. Schuster (p. 19 f.) has made an attempt (confuted by Zeller, It. 572 f., 656 f.) to stamp Heracleitus as a sensualist on account of his theory of perception. The correct position liesin the mean between these two authorities. Right knowledge indeed arises in sense when the right soul elaborates it. The criterion to which all things are referred is here again conformity to law, which is universally valid and won only through thought. In sleep and through mere individual perception every one has only his own, and therefore a false, world of ideas. The analogy in practical life is 58 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY of mankind in this respect are badly off. They do not reflect, but live on as the deluded victims of sense, whose greatest deception consists in its simulation of permanent Being amid the transitoriness of all the phenomena of perception. Heracleitus of Ephesus, son of Blyson, belonged to the most eminent family of his native city, which traced its origin to Codrus. In this family the dignity of dpywy Buctre’s was in- herited, and Heracleitus is said to have surrendered it to his brother. The dates of his birth and death are not exactly known. If he survived the banishment of his friend Hermodo- rus (compare E. Zeller, De Herm. Ephesio, Marburg. 1851), who was forced from the city by the democratic ascendency after the throwing off of Persian domination, his death can scarcely have been before 470. About this time he himself went into retirement to devote himself to science. His birth, since he is said to have lived about sixty years, can be placed between 540-530. With these dates, moreover, the statements of Diogenes Laertius agree, for Diogenes places the axuy of Heracleitus .in the sixty-ninth Olympiad. His own writing, in poetically ceremonial prose, supposes that Pythagoras and Xenophanes are already familiar names. It was not probably written until the third decade of the fifth century. His rude partisanship upon the side of the oppressed aristocracy is all that is known of his life, by which is explained his contempt for mankind, his solitariness and bitterness, and his ever emphatic antagonism toward the public and its capricious sentiments. In the collection and attempt at a systematic ordering of the unfortunately meagre fragments of Heracleitus’ book, and in the presentation of his doctrine, the following men have done eminent service: Fr. Schleiermacher (Her. der Dunkle von Ephesus, Ges. Werke III., II. 1-146); Jak. Bernays ( Ges. Abh. herausgez. von Usener, I., 1885, 1-108, and in addition especially the ‘‘ Letters of Heracleitus,” Berlin, 1869); Ferd. Lassalle (Die Philos. Her. des Dunkeln von Ephesus, 2 vols., Berlin, 1858); P. Schuster (Her. v. Ephesus, Leipzig, 1873, in the Acta soc. phil., Lips. ed., Ritschl, III. 1-894); Teich- miller (Neue Studien zu Gesch. der Begriffe, Parts 1 and 2); shown in Fragment 123, fuvev éore mace 16 dpoveiv, Evv vd@ déyovras > Bs a iaxupiferOat xp} TO Evve mdvrwv, Gorep vipw modes kal word iayuporéps * ' ; f Tpepovra yap mdvres of avOpwmuvot vopot bmd Eévds Tod Oeiov. THE METAPHYSICAL CONFLICT 59 J. Bywater (Her. reliquiew, Oxford), 1877, a collection which includes, to be sure, the counterfeited letters, but those, how- ever, that presumably came from ancient sources; Th. Gom- perz (Zu H.’s Lehre und den Ueberresten seines Werke, Vienna, 1887); Edm. Pfleiderer, Die Philos. der Her. v. Eph. im Lichte der Mysterienideen (Berlin, 1886). In the theory of Heracleitus, scientific reflection as the sole true method already so far strengthened itself in the abstract development of his concepts that it set itself over against customary opinion and sense appearance with a rugged self-consciousness. To a still higher degree the same attitude appears in the antagonistic theory of the Eleatic School. 19. The scientific founder of the Hleatic school was Parmenides. What had been set forth by Xenophanes in religious assertions about the unity and singleness of the Godhead and its identity with the world, was developed entirely conceptually by Parmenides as a metaphysical theory. That concept, however, which was placed as central and drew all the others entircly into its circle, was Being. The great Elcatic was led up to his theory through reflec- tions of a purely formal logical nature. In a still obscure and undeveloped form the correlation of consciousness and Being hovered before his mind. All thinking is referred to something thought, and therefore has Being for its con- tent. Thinking that refers to Nothing and is therefore contentless, cannot be. Therefore not-Being cannot be thought, and much the less can it be} It is the greatest of all follies to discuss not-Being at all, for we must speak of it as a thought content, that is, as something being, and must contradict ourselves.? If all thinking refers, however, 1 Verses 35-40 (Mullach) : o@re yap dv yvoins rd ye pt éov* ob yap dvvotdv. ovre Ppdoais, To yap adro voeiv éoriv Te kal eivat. 2 vy. 43-51. Steinhart and Bernays have rightly called attention to the fact that Heracleitus is antagonized here, for he ascribes Being and not-Being alike to the things conceived in the process of Becoming. 60 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY to something being, then is Being everywhere the same. For whatsoever also may be thought as in the particular thing, nevertheless the quality of Being (das Sein) is in all the same. Being is the last product of an abstraction that has compared the particular thought contents. Being alone remains when all difference has been abstracted from the content determinations of actuality. From this fol- lows the fundamental doctrine of the Eleatics, that only the one abstract Being is. The philosophy of Parmenides would be complete in this brief sentence éortw ezvas, if on the one hand there did not follow from this conceptual definition a number of predicates of Being,— predicates primarily negative and susceptible only disjunctively of positive formulation ; and if on the other hand the philosopher did not deviate from the strict logic of his own postulates. In respect to the first, all time and qualitative distinc- tions must be denied to Being. Being is unoriginated and imperishable. It was not and will not be, but only is in timeless eternity.2 For time, wherein perhaps any thing that is, first was and suffered change,? is in no wise different from a thing that is. Being is also unchangeable, entirely homogeneous and unitary in quality. It is also not plural, but is the one unique, indivisible,* absolute cosmic Being. Compare Zeller, I*. 670. The same dialectic in reference to Being and not-Being is repeated in the dialogue, The Sophist (238), in seeking for the possibility of error. 1 This line of thought is repeated by the Neo-Platonists, by Spinoza et al., and is unavoidable if Being is valid as the criterion of “ things being.’? Compare Kant, Kr. d. v. Vern., Kelirb., 471 £. 2 vy. 59 ff., especially 61: odd¢ mor’ qv 008 gorat eel viv éoriv Suou wav év Evveyes. 8 v. 96: od8€ ypdvos éoriy }} Carat GAO TapeK Tod eovros. This is di- rected perhaps against the cosmogonies, perhaps against the chrono- logical measure of cosmic devélopment in Heracleitus. 4 vy. 78. THE METAPHYSICAL CONFLICT 61 All plurality, all qualitative difference, all origination, all change or destruction are shut out by true Being. In this respect Parmenides has constructed the concept in perfect clearness and sharpness. But this abstract ontology among the Eleatics nevertheless took another turn through some content definitions obtained from the inner and outer world of experience. ‘This oc- curred in the two directions resulting from the way in to which thought refers in its naive conception as if it “Were_i necessary content, is corporeal actuality. Therefore the Being of Parmenides was identified with the absolutely corporeal. The polemic against the atrephance of not-Being got a new uepent) in this way. The dp coin- cides with the wAéov, the yu) dv with the cevdy; and the Eleatics taught that there is no empty space. There- fore Being is indivisible, immovable, and excludes not only qualitative change, but also all change of place. This absolute corporeality is therefore not boundless (arededryTov), but is Being? that is complete in itself, unchangeably determined, self-bounded, like a perfectly rounded, changeless and homogeneous sphere.’ 1 vv. 80, 85; twirdy 1 ev rwiT@ Te pévov Kal éwuTd Te KeiTat. 2 y. 88f. Doubtless Parmenides antagonized the Milesian teaching of the dme:pov in all its possible affiliations. But it is utterly unnecessary to think that the opposition of mépas and dmeipoy presupposes the num- ber investigations of the Pythagoreans. There is not the slightest trace of this in Parmenides. Inversely it is not impossible that the opposition of the Eleatics against all predecessors made the dual con- cept so important that the Pythagoreans inserted this among their fundamental antitheses. Doubtless the purely Greek representation influenced Parmenides, in which the measurable and self-determined and never the measureless and undetermined was regarded as perfect. Melissus seems (§ 20) to have neglected this point, and thus to have approached the theory of Anaximander. 3 vy. 102 f. 62 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY On the other hand, however, there was again for Par- menides no Being which was not either consciousness or something thought: twirov & éorl voeiv te Kal obvexév éote vonua (v. 94), As for Xenophanes, so also for Parmenides, corporeality and thought perfectly coincide in this cosmic god, this abstract Being: 10 yap mAéov eat) vonua (v. 149). We can designate, therefore, the Eleatic system neither as materialistic nor idealistic, because these terms have mean- ing only when corporeality and thought have been previously considered as different fundamental forms of actuality. The Eleatic theory is rather an ontology which in regard to its con- tent so completely took its stand at the naive point of view of the identification of corporeality and thought, as really to exalt it to the dignity of a principle. More prominently in the teaching of Parmenides than in that of Xenophanes does the peculiar result appear: that the principle, gained by conceptual reflection out of the need of knowing the real world, proves itself entirely unsuitable for the purpose. This Eleatic concept of Being could explain so little of the empirical world that Parmenides had to deny the existence of that world. All plurality and’ diversity, all coming into existence, existing and passing out of existence, are only illusory appearance, —false names that mortals have given to true Being.’ The Eleatic found the origin of this appearance in sense-perception, of whose illu- sory *character he gave warning. He did not seem, however, to realize the circle involved in his reasoning. Although, from an entirely opposite principle, he explained in a sharper epigrammatic way than Heracleitus, how the truth can be sought only in conceptual thought but never in the ly. 98f. The conjecture évap instead of dvoy’ (v. 98, Gladisch) is invalidated by, among other things, the circumstance that Sophistry and Eristic, which were deveroped from Eleaticism, frequently spoke of the plurality of names for the one thing that is (§ 28). 2. 54 fF. THE METAPHYSICAL CONFLICT 63 senses. His ontology is a perfectly conscious rationalism that shut out all experience and denied all content. Nevertheless Parmenides believed that he could not do without a physical theory, possibly because he felt the de- mands of his scientific society in Elea. So the second part! of his didactic poem gave a kind of hypothetical and problematical physics which stands out of logical connec- tion with the ontology of the first part. But on the other hand the “ Human Opinions” about the many changeable things offered to sensation were not simply reproduced, but were transformed, as they would necessarily have to be, according to his presupposition, if in general plurality motion and change were to be recognized as real. lo this pig A I ap seer aera nage Som is thought * as actual side by side that which is; and that out of the reciprocal Setton-of the BFS are derived multiplicity and the process of individual Becoming. The ‘he physical theory_of Parmenides was a dualism, a theory of op opposites. Although ir thts—reepect Te reminds us strongly of Heracleitus, the agreement with him is still more apparent in the making whatever really is as the equivalent of the light, and whatever really is not as the equivalent of the darkness.2 When therefore this pair of opposites was identified with the thin and thick, the light and the heavy, the fire and the earth, the reference was to Anaximander. Yet, on the other hand, there was full recognition of the Heracleitan teaching, which had set fire over against all the other elements as the forming and determining ele- ment. If Parmenides did not herein also point out the relation between these two opposites as that of an active 1 y. 18-30; 83-7; 110 f. 2 On this point later Atomism, which was more logical than even Parmenides himself in physics, regarded not-Being, i. e., empty space, as actual. By. 122 £. 64 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY and a passive principle, nevertheless Aristotle was justified (Met., I. 8, 984 b, 1), inasmuch as for Parmenides the fire, which possesses Being, certainly had the value of an ani- mating, moving principle over against the darkness as a thing not possessing it. Of the particular theories of Parmenides which have been handed down in a very fragmentary condition, there is not much to remark. With him also the principal stress was aid upon metaphysics. The little information that exists proves that he tried with considerable art to develop the dualism which he derived from his general ontology, and that he even descended to details which he made it his duty * to explain in all their bearings. In some particulars he subjoined existing theories to his own without making any actual advance in physics. His astronomical ideas agree so thoroughly with those of the Pythagoreans, with whom he doubtless came in contact, that one must admit the dependence of the Eleatics upon the Pythagoreans in astronomy.? As to the origin of man, he held the same view that Anaximander held before him and that Empe- docles held after him. Otherwise, excepting some remarks about procreation, etc., only his theory of sensation has come down to us. In this he taught, like Heracleitus, that of the two fundamental elements contained in man, each is susceptible to that which is related to it in the external world. The Warm in a living man senses the fiery connec- tion-in-things (Lebenszusammenhang), but even also in the corpse, the cold, stiff body feels what is like it in its surroundings. He expressed the opinion that every man’s ly, 120 f. 2 Compare, for details, Zeller, I. 525f, That Parmenides here showed not the least knowledge of the so-called number-theory, is another proof of the later origin of this philosophical teaching of the Pythagoreans, whose mathematical and astronomical investigations obviously preceded their metaphysical. See § 24 THE METAPHYSICAL CONFLICT 65 ideas and intuitions are determined by? the mixture of these two elements in him. There is no ground for doubting the genuineness of the report of Plato? that Parmenides in his old age went to Athens, where the young Socrates saw him. ‘The statements of the dialogue Parmenides, which presents the fiction® of a conversation be tween Parmenides and Socrates, are not wanting in probability. According to this, Parmenides was born about 515. He came from a distinguished family, and his intercourse with the Pythagoreans is well attested. On the other hand, however, his acquaintance with Xenophanes * is also well proved, together with whom he directed the activity of the scientific association in his native city, Klea. Parmenides exercised a decided in- fluence on the political life also of this newly founded city,® and is in general represented as a serious, influential, and morally high character.”. His work was written about 470 or somewhat later. It was in answer to that of Heracleitus, and at the same time it inspired the theories developed somewhat later and almost contemporaneously by Empedocles, Anaxagoras, Leu- eippus, and Philolaus (Chap. III.). It is in verse, and shows a peculiar amalgamation of abstract thought and plastic poetic fancy. The greater portion of the preserved fragments came from the first and ontological section of the poem, which was perhaps also called zepi dvcews. Besides Karsten and Mullach, Am. Peyron (Parmenidis et Empedoklis fragmenta, Leipzig, 1810) and Heinr. Stein (Symb. philologorum Bonnensium in honorem F. Ritschleti, Leipzig, 1864, p. 763 f.) have collected and discussed the fragments. Compare Vatke, Parmenidis Veliensis doctrina, Berlin, 1844; A. Biumker, Die Einheit des P’schen Seins (Jahrb. f. kl. klass. Philol., 1886, 541 f.). 20. Whereas Parmenides made a no inconsiderable con- cession to the customary idea of the plurality and change of things, at least in his construction of an hypothetical 1 vy. 146 f. 2 Theetetus, 183 e. 3 Parmenides, 127 b; Sophist, 217 ¢. 4 Diog. Laert., IX. 25; Strabo, 27, 1, 1. 5 Arist. Met., I. 5, 986 b, 22. 8 Diog. Laert., IX. 23, according to Speusippus. 7 Plato, Theet, 188 e: compare Soph., 237 a; Parm., 127 b. 5 66 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY physics his friend and pupil Zeno of Elea proceeded to refute even this customary point of view, and thereby to establish directly the teaching of his master concerning the unity and unchangeableness of Being. The habit of abstract thinking, which was raised to a pre-eminence by Parmenides, manifested itself here in the way in which his pupil turned entirely from the earlier physical tendency of science. Zeno was no longer concerned in apprehending or understanding empirical reality. He was interested only in the conceptual defence of the paradoxes of his teacher. In seeking to discover, therefore, the contradictions which inhere in ordinary opinions regarding the plurality and mutability of things, he employed in a more partisan spirit than Parmenides arguments not based on subject matter or empirical fact, but only those of formal logic. This appeared primarily in the form of the proof, — first systematically and expertly used, as it seems, by Zeno. By the continuous repetition of contradictory disjunc- tives, he sought to deny exhaustively all the possibilitics of comprehension and defence of the assailed thought, until it was at last brought into obvious contradictions, On account of this keen application of the apparatus of logic, which lets the entire proof seem to be controlled by the law of contradiction, we may suppose that Zeno first had a clear consciousness of formal logical relations: Aristotle even called him the inventor of dialectic.? All the difficulties that Zeno by this method found in the ideas of multiplicity and movement refer to the infinity of space and time, and indeed partly to the infinitely large, partly to the’infinitely small. These difficulties simply prove in the last instance the impossibility of thinking exclusively of continuous spatial and temporal quantities 1 Zeller, IT*. 538, for unimportant and even trivial notes which seem to controvert this, and for the most part rest upon misconceptions. 2 Diog. Laert., VIII. 57. THE METAPHYSICAL CONFLICT 67 as analyzed into discrete parts, —of thinking of the in- finity of the perceptive process. Upon this ground the difficulties of Zeno could find no conclusive solution until the very real and difficult problems resting on them were consid- ered from the point of view of the infinitesimal calculus. Compare Aristotle, Physics, in many places with the comments by Simplicius. Bayle, Dict. hist, et crit., article Zenon; Herbart, Einleitung in die Philos:, § 139 ; Metaph., § 284 f.; Hegel, Gesch. d. Phil., Complete Works, Vol. XIII. 312 f.; Wellmann, Zenon’s Beweise gegen die Bewegung und ihre Widerlegungen, Frankfort a. O., 1870; C. Dunan, Les arguments de Zénon d'Elée contre le mouvement, Nantes, 1884. The proofs advanced by Zeno against the multiplicity of what really is, were two, and they were concerned in part with magnitude, in part with number. As_regards- magnitude, whatever possesses Being must, if it be many, be on the one hand infinitely small and on the other infinitely great : infinitely small because the aggregation of ever so many parts, of which every one, being indivisible, has no magnitude, can result also in no magnitude; infinitely great because the juxtaposition of two parts pre- supposes a boundary between the two, which, as something real, must itself likewise have spatial magnitude, but on this account must again be parted by boundaries from the two minor portions of which the same is true, etc., etc. —xkouin, as regards number, whatever possesses Being must, it it be supposed to be many, be thought as both limited and. unlimited. It must be limited because it is just as many as it is, no more nor less. It must be unlimited because two different things possessing Being must be separated by a boundary which as a third must itself be different from these, and must be separated from them both by a fourth and fifth, and so ad infinitum.” + 1 The second part of the argument is essentially the same in both proofs, and was called by the ancients the argument ék d:xoropias, in 68 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY It is probable, and also chronologically quite possible, that these proofs were even at that time directed against the begin- nings of Atomism (§ 23). They are intended to show that the world cannot be thought as an aggregation of atoms. Consist- eut with this view is the further circumstance that Zeno’s polemic was made against the idea of mutability of what pos- sesses Being only in the sense of xivyats, not in the sense of aAAoiw- ows (qualitative change). Atomism affirmed xiyyois, and denied qualitative change. There is, in addition, a third argument against the plurality of Being, which Zeno seemed rather to indi- cate than todevelop. This is the so-called Sorites, according to which it is inconceivable how a bushel of corn could make a noise when the single kernels make none. This argument became effective in the polemic against the atomists, who sought to derive qualitative determinations from the joint motion of atoms. Presumably against atomism there was directed another argument of Zeno, which dealt neither with the plural- ity nor the motion of what possesses Being, but with the reality of empty space, which was the presupposition of move- ment to the atomists. Zeno showed that if what possesses Being should be thought as in space, this space as an actuality must be thought to be in another space, etc., ad infinitum. On the other hand, the application which Zeno made of the categories of infinity and finiteness, of the unlimited and limited, appears to suggest a relationship to the Pythagoreans, in whose investigations these ideas played a great rédle. § 19; § 24. The contradiction involved in the conception of motion Zeno tried to prove in four ways: (1) By the impossibility of going through a fixed space. This means that the infinite divisibility of the space to be passed through will not allow the beginning of motion to appear thinkable. (2) By the impossibility of passing through a space that has movable limits. This supposes the goal, which is to be reached in any finite time, to be pushed away, though perhaps ever so little. An example of this is Achilles, who cannot catch the tortoise. (3) By the infinitely small amount of motion at any instant of time, since the body in motion during any which dichotomy is used not in the logical but in the original physical sense, THE METAPHYSICAL CONFLICT 69 individual instant of time is at some definite point, 7. e. at rest. He used the resting arrow as an example. (4) By the relativity of the amount of motion. A motion of a carriage appears to differ in amount according as it is measured in its process of separation by a stationary carriage or by one in motion in the opposite direction. Little is known about the life of Zeno. If one holds that the exact chronological reports in the dialogue of Parmenides are fictitious and the statements of the ancients about the é«kyy are doubtful, nevertheless it is certain Zeno can have been scarcely a generation younger than Parmenides. One will not make a mistake if one places the length of his life at sixty years, between 490 and 430. He was, then, the contempo- rary of Empedocles, Anaxagoras, Leucippus, and Philolaus, and it is easily possible that he held fast to Parmenides’ doctrine of Being in its conceptual abstractness in direct contrast to the remodellings of it by these men. His well-attested évJy- ypaupa was composed in prose, and, to suit his formal schema- tism, was divided into chapters. In these the single irobéces found their reductio ad absurdum.’ If the presentation of these in accordance with their polemic nature had the form of question and answer,” then this is probably the beginning of the philosophic dialogue-literature which later developed so richly.® Of lesser significance* was Melissus of Samos. Not a native Eleatic, he was also not a complete and consistent supporter of Parmenides’s doctrine of Being. He was somewhat the junior of the Eleatic, and lived on into the time of the eclectic tendency in which the opposing the- ories began to fade out (§ 25). In the main, to be sure, he thoroughly defended the Eleatic fundamental principle, and in a manner obviously antagonistic to Empedocles, Anaxagoras, Leucippus, and in part to the Milesian physics. 1 Plato, Parm., 127 c ff.; Simpl. Phys., 30 v, 139, 5. 2 Arist. wept cop. éAéyy-, 10, 170 b, 22. = Diog. Laert., IIT. 48. 4 Arist. Met., 1.5, 986 b, 27; Phys., I. 3, 186 a,8. mepi co. eAcyx. 5, 167 b, 13. 70 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY Yet he stood with his doctrine of the infinity of the One in so striking a contrast to Parmenides, and in such obvious harmony with Anaximander, that he appears as a real intermediary between the two, The form of his arguments shows the influence of the dialectic schematism of Zeno. Melissus tried to prove in these that (1) what really is, is eternal because it can arise out of neither what is nor what is not; (2) that what really is, is without beginning and end, temporally and spatially, i. e. infinite (dzrecpov) ; (8) that what really is, is single, since several things that really are, would limit one another in space and time; (4) that what really is, is unchangeable, motionless, and condi- tionless, because every change involves a kind of origina- tion and ending, and every movement presupposes empty space which cannot be thought as possessing Being. It is thus clear that Aristotle correctly found the conception of the & in Melissus to be more materialistic than in Parmen- ides. What Melissus won by such an approximation to the Milesian physics, when he still denied every change to Being, is not clear. His theory appears, therefore, to be a compromise without any strong principle. Melissus, son of Ithagenes, was a navarch, under whom the Samian fleet conquered the Athenians in 442. His personal relation to the Eleatics has not been explained. His Svyypaypa (epi dicews OF wepi rot dvros, Simplicius and Suidas) was writ- ten in prose. Compare F. Kern, Zur Wiirdigung des M., (Stet- tin, 1880); A. Pabst, De M. P. fragmentis (Bonn, 1889); M. Offner, Zur Beurtheilung des M. (Arch. f. Gesch. d. Philos., IV. 12 f.). The polemic of Zeno gave clearest expression to the fundamental principle o é i Tito - 6 thought out logically and consistently the conceptually necessary concept of Being, Which in itself alone did not suffice for the apprehension and explanation of the empiri- cally actual. The Heracleitan thests that the essence of EFFORTS TOWARD RECONCILIATION ma things is to be sought in an orderly process of perpetual change, stood opposed to it. Zeno’s argument was purely ontological. It recognized only the one increate and un- changeable Being, and denied the reality of multiplicity and Becoming without also explaining their appearance. The argument of Heracleitus was entirely genetic. It seized upon the process itself and its permanent modes with- out satisfying the need of connecting this process with an ultimate and continuous actuality, The concept of Being is, however, a necessary postulate of thought, and the pro- cess of occurrence is a fact not to be denied. Consequently, from the opposition of these two doctrines, Hellenic philos- ophy gained a clear view of the task which in an indefinite way underlay the very initial conception of the dpy7. This task was from Being to explain the process of phenomenal change, 8. EFrorTs TOWARD RECONCILIATION. The above problem gave rise to a number of philosophi- cal theories which are best designated as efforts toward reconciliation between the thought motifs of the Eleatic and Heracleitan schools. Since all the arguments aim at so modifying the Eleatic idea of Being that from it the or- derly process of occurrence in the Heracleitan sense may seem conceivable, they are at once of a metaphysical and physical character. Two ways were open for the solution of this problem: one led from Parmenides, the other from Heracleitus. The inadequacy of the Eleatic concept of Being to explain empirical plurality and change was due essentially to its qualities of singleness and spatial immobility. If these characteristics, however, were given up, those of non- Becoming, indestructibility, and qualitative permanence could be more strongly maintained in order to explain pro- 72 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY cess and change by means of a plurality of objects pos- sessing Being (Setenden), with the help of spatial motion. The theories of Empedocles, Anaxagoras, and the Atomists moved in this direction. Common to them all was the pluralism of substances, and the mechanistic method of explanation, in virtue of which origin, change, and destruc- tion were supposed to be derived merely from the motions of these substances unchangeable in themselves. These theories were in extreme antithesis to the hylozoistic monism of the Milesians in particular. On the other hand, these three systems were distinguishable from one another partly as to the number and quality of the sub- stances that each assumed to exist, partly as to the rela- tionships of substances to motion and moving force. The insufficiency of the Heracleitan theory consisted, however, not in establishing the concept of the rhythm of the pro- cess of occurrence, but in retaining nothing else of what really is, as entering into these changes. Heracleitus had recognized no one of the empirical materials, and no abstract noumenon, and consequently nothing as Being. If now Parmenides showed that thinking undeniably pre- supposes something that really is, one would be forced to try to vindicate the character of Being for the relations and connections which Heracleitus had retained as the sole permanence. This the Pythagoreans attempted to do with their peculiar number theory. These four efforts toward reconciliation sprang accordingly simultaneously out of one and the same need. Their represen- tatives were nearly contemporaneous. From this fact are explained not only a number of the similarities and affinities in their doctrines, but also the circumstance that they frequently, particularly in polemics, seem to have referred directly to one another. This is at the same time a proof of the lively scien- tific interest and interchange of ideas in the middle of the fifth century through the entire circle of Greek civilization. The ‘efforts toward a reconciliation” used as a basis for associating these philosophers here is fairly generally recognized EFFORTS TOWARD RECONCILIATION 73 for the first three, although on the one hand Anaxagoras is usually set apart by himself (Hegel, Zeller, Ueberweg), be- cause we have overestimated his doctrine of the vots. On the other hand, Atomism (Schleiermacher, Ritter) has naturally been classified with Sophistry. Compare, respectively, § 22 and § 23. Yet, from the time of the Pythagoreans until now, Strumpell alone has preceded me in this proposed view. Brandis treats indeed the Pythagoreans for the first time before the Sophists, but as a tendency independent of the others. 21. The first and most imperfect of these attempts at reconciliation was that of Empedocles. He proceeded expressly from the thesis of Parmenides that there can be no origination and destruction as such. In his effort to explain apparent origination and destruction, he said that every origination should be regarded_as a combi- nation, and every destruction a separation of the original elements.!_ He called the original materials the feSopara mavrov, and he does not seem to have employed the later customary expression, crotyeta. The predicates of “ unori- ginated,” “imperishable,” ‘ unchangeable,” belong to the elements. They are eternal Being; and the manifold and change of single things are supposed to be explained by spatial motion, by virtue of which they are mixed in differ- ing relations to one another. Accordingly, Empedocles should apparently be accredited with the priority of forming this conception of the element that has been so powerful in the development of our science of nature. It is the conception of a material, homoge- neous in content, qualitatively unchangeable, and liable to changing states of motion and to mechanical division He got this conception, nevertheless, in the attempt to make the concept of Being of Parmenides useful in the explana- tion of nature. Much Jess happy, although historically 1 Plutarch, Plac., I. 30 (Doz., 326) vows o8evds dor drdvrav Ovnrav ovd€ Tis odAOpevou Oavdroto redevTH, GAAG povov wikis Te SuddAakis Te peyevTODV éoti, puots Sei rois dvopdCerat dvOpamorow. 74 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY quite ‘as effective, was the point of view which Empedocles formed of the number and essence of these elements. He adduced the well-known four: earth, air, fire, and water. The choice of four fundamental elements was the result of no systematic conception on the part of Empedocles, in the way that Aristotle, by whom this theory was established and made the common property of all literature, later made them a fundamental part of his system. As it appears, it was the result of an impartial consideration of the previous philosophic theories of nature: water, air, fire are to be found as elements among the Jonians; and earth in the hypothetical physics of the Ele- atics. That Empedocles? placed fire over against the three other elements, and thus returned to the two divisions of Heracleitus (§ 19), reminds us of this latter. Nevertheless the number of elements as four has in it something arbitrary and immature, as likewise appears from the superficial characterization that Empedocles gave to each singly? Empedocles to all appearances was not able to say how the different qualities of particular things were derived from their combining. Quantitative relationships and states of aggregation might appear to be thus derived, but not particular qualities. Consequently Empedocles seems to have had only the former in mind when he so described the process of combination and separation, that therein the protruding parts of one body were supposed to press into the pores, i. e. into the interstices,’ of another body. Empedocles seems to be referring to the former also in his defining the relationship and the strength of the recip- rocal attraction of empirical things by the stereometrical. similarity between the emanations of one substance and the pores of another. As to the qualitative difference 1 Arist. Met., I. 4, 985 a, 82; De gen. et corr., II. 8, 830 b, 19. 2 Zeller, I4. 690. 3 That this acceptation presupposed a discontinuity of the original matter, and hardly was to be thought without the presupposition of empty space, which he with the Eleatics denied (fr. v. 91, Arist. De celo, IV. 2, 809 a, 19), appears to have furnished no difficulty to Empedocles. EFFORTS TOWARD RECONCILIATION 75 between individual things, he taught only in very general terms that this difference depends on the different masses in which all or only some of the elements exist in combination. But the more that Empedocles claimed the character of the Parmenidean Being for his four elements, the less could he find in them an explanation of the motion in which they must exist according to his theory of union and separation. As pure changeless Being, the 2 elements could not move them- selves, but only be moved. To explain the world, the theory needed further, then, beside the four elements, a cause of motion or a moving force. Here, in the statement of this problem, appears first completely Empedocles’s opposition to the hylozoism of the Milesians. He was the first in whose theory force and matter are differentiated as separate cosmic powers. Under the influence of Parmenides he had accord- ingly so conceived the world-stuff that the ground of motion could not be found in it itself. So, in order to explain the cosmic process, he had to find a force different from the stuff and moving it. Although Empedocles introduced this dualism into the scientific thought of the Greeks, it appeared fiot in sharp conceptual, but in mythical-poetic form; for he designated the two cosmic forces which caused the com- Se ee bination and separation of the primitive substances, as Love and Hate. pee pee The personification, which Empedocles moreover, as like- WEE-PaMemes In his didactic poem, extended to the ele- ments, was mythical and poetic; so also the representation inadequate because stated in terms of sense and not developed to conceptual clearness, was of the same character. Indeed, it is not certain from the passages in which his principles (dpya/) were enumerated as six in all, whether or not he thought of the two forces incidentally as bodies (Arist. De gen. et corr., I.1, 314 a, 16; Simpl. Phys. 6 v, 25, 21), which as such were mingled with the other substances. Obviously he formed no sharp idea of the nature of the actuality and the effi- ciency that belong to Love and Hate. There is the additional 76 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY fact that the duality of forces not only was called forth by the theoretic need of representing the different causes in the opposed processes of cosmic union and separation; but it was also occasioned by considerations ‘of worth, in which Love is the cause of Goodness and Hate of Evil (compare Aristotle, Met., I. 4, 984 b, 32). The view of Aristotle is supported by the predi- cates which Empedocles (fragment v. ne f.) attributes to giddorns and veikos. Fro res itions Empedocles derived an exe _ planation of the cosmic process, not indeed conceiving each individual occurrence as ever and always arising from a universal law of combination and separation, but yet satis- fying the demands of the Heracleitan philosophy by the assumption of a perpetual cyclic process of development. He taught, namely, that the four elements, that he assumed as alike in their mass, change out of a state of perfect mingling and equality, separate by the action of the vetxos, and become completely sundered ; that then from this state of separation they pass back through the influence of the dirérns to their original absolute intermixture. There re- . sults from this a cycle of four continuously dissolving cosmic states: (1) that of the unlimited supremacy of Love and of the perfect unification of all the elements, which is called by Empedocles c¢aipos and also designated as 7d év or eds ; (2) that of the process of successive separation through the constantly growing preponderance of veixos.; (8) that of the absolute separation of the four elements through the sole supremacy of Hate; (4) that of the process of succes- sive recombination through the increased predominance of girOrns. Compare Arist. Phys., VIII. 1, 250 b, 26. It is clear that_a world of individual things can appear oply . the second and fourth stages of the cosmic process, and that Buel a world is character me by the opposition and ict__be e See and_separating principles. eas is the place of the éitan fundamental principle in the Empedoclean aanenton of the cosmos. On the other EFFORTS TOWARD RECONCILIATION 77 hand, it can be said that the two parts of the Parmenidean didactic poem appear no longer in the opposition of Being and Appearance, but in the relationship of changing cosmic states. The first and third phases are acosmic in the Eleatic sense; the second and fourth are, on the contrary, full of the Heracleitan. moA€Los. All that we have of the particulars of the theory of Empe- docles seems to teach that he regarded the present state of the world as the fourth phase, in which the elements that have been separated by Hate are reuniting through Love into the Sphairos. At least in reference to the formation of the world he taught that the separated elements have” “beet brought through Love mto the whirttie-motion tat —> is in the process of uniting them. Originally the air en- compassed the whole like a Sphere, and by virtue of this motion fire broke out from below. The air was pressed below and into the middle, was mixed with the water into mud, and then formed into the earth. The two hemi- Spheres originated in this way: one was light and fery; the other dark, airy, and interspersed with masses of fire, which on account of the rushing of the air in rotatory motion around the earth created day and night. —— eee t In particular, Empedocles showed — not without dependence on the Pythagoreans— highly developed astronomical ideas concerning the illumination of the moon from the sun, concern- ing eclipses, the inclination of the ecliptic, etc., and also many interesting meteorological hypotheses. — Empedocles had an .especial interest in the organic world. He regarded plants as primary organisms and as having souls like ‘animals. He compared in isolated remarks the formation of fruit with the procreation of animals, their leaves with hair, feathers, and scales; and so one finds in him the beginnings of a comparative mor- phology. Also numerous physiological observations of his are preserved. But especially are there biological reflec- 78 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY tions, in which he in some measure in the spirit of the present theory of adaptation explained, although with fanci- ful naiveté, the existence of the present vital organisms by the survival of purposeful forms from things that on the whole were aimlessly created.1 Empedocles did not except man? from this purely me- chanical origination, and he constructed a large number of interesting single hypotheses in respect to his physiological functions. The blood plays an important réle in this theory. It was to him the real carrier of life, and in it he believed he could see the most perfect combination of the four elements. It is of especial interest that he conceived the process of perception and sensation as analogous to his universal theory of the interaction of elements. He ex- plained this process as contact of the small parts of the perceived things with the similar parts of the perceiving organs, wherein the former were supposed to press upon the latter, as in hearing; or the latter upon the former, as in sight. Since then, in general, such interaction was to his mind the more close, the more nearly similar were the emanations and pores, he established the principle, there- fore, that all external things are known by that in us which is similar to them. Herein was involved to some degree the idea that man is a microcosm, the finest admix- ture of all the elements. Hence it followed for Empedocles that all perceptual knowledge depends upon the combination of elements in the body and especially in the blood, and that the spiritual nature depends on the physical nature. Just on this 1 Aristotle has brought this thought into abstract expression, and it contains the whole modern development theory in nuce. Phys., II. 8, 198 b, 29; Gov pev obv Gravra cuveBn Somep Kav ei everd Tov éeyevero, Tatra pev €owOn, dd Tov a’rouarov auaTdvra emutndeiws, doa dé pu) ovTws, dro ero kai dwodAvtat Kaddrep *EpmredoxXjjs Aéyet, ete. 2 He appears to have made good use of the tales about the centaurs. EFFORTS TOWARD RECONCILIATION 79 account, moreover he could deplore incidentally, as_Xeno- phanes deplored, the limitation of buman knowledge ; an and could assert, on the other hand, with Heracleitus and Par- menides, that true knowledge does not_grow out of sense perception, but only out of reflection (vociv) and reagon (vods).* Empedocles of Agrigentum, the first Dorian in the history of philosophy, lived probably from 490-430. He came from a rich and respectable family which had been partisans for the democracy in the municipal struggles. Like his father, Meton, Empedocles distinguished himself as a citizen and statesman, but later he fell into the disfavor of the other citizens. In his vocation of physician and priest, and with the paraphernalia of a magician,? he then travelled about through Sicily and Magna Grecia. Many stories circulated into later time concerning his death, like that well-known one of his leap into Atna. In this religious réle he taught the doctrine of transmigration and of an apparently purer intuition of God, like that of the Apollo cult. These teachings, which were not consistent in content with his metaphysico-physical theories, show, however, much the greater similarity to the teaching of Pythagoras (§ 12). Pythagorean- ism he certainly knew, and indeed his entire career suggests a copy of that of Pythagoras. When we consider his political affiliations, it is improbable that he had any close connectio with the Pythagorean society. Empedocles stood comparatively isolated, —save his acquaintance with the teachings of Hera-: cleitus and Parmenides, the latter of whom he presumably knew personally. Nevertheless he seems to have been affili- ated with a yet larger body in that he is characterized as one of the first representatives of rhetoric.? He had even con- nections with the so-called Sicilian school of rhetoric (or ora- tory), in which are preserved the names of Tisias and Korax as well as that of Gorgias, whom they antedate.* Only wepi diceus and xaGappot are the writings of Empedocles that can be authenticated. The preserved small fragments are especially collated by Sturz (Leipzig, 1805), Karsten (Amsterdam, 1838), and Stein (Bonn, 1852). Compare Bergk, De prooemio, E, Berl., 1 Fr, v. 24; 81. 2 Thus he pictured himself in the beg:aning of the Songs of Purifica- cation (xa@appoi). 8 Diog. Laert., VIII. 57; Sext. Emp. Adv. math., VII. 6. 4 See below, § 26. 80 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY 1839; Panzerbieter, Beitrige zur Kritik und Erlduterung des E.- (Meiningen, 1844); Schliger, H. quatenus Heraclitum secutus sit (Eisenach, 1878). —O. Kern, E. und d. Orphiker (Arch. f. Gesch. d. Ph., I. 498 f.). 22. “Older in years, younger in works than Empedo- cles,” 1 Anaxagoras brought the movement of thought, which had been begun by Empedocles, to an end in one direction. He, like Empedocles, was convinced that we do not use language correctly when we speak of origination and destruction, since the mass of the world must remain unchangeably the same. On this account apparent origi- nation and destruction are better designated as combina- tion and separation (cvyxpiois sive cdppstis). Whatever enters into combination or whatever suffers separation was to him, also, a plurality of original substances which he called ypjuara or orépwata. Thus far he agreed with his predecessor. But he took decided exception to the arbi- trary assumption of Empedocles that there are only four elements, since it is impossible to explain the qualita- tive distinctions of empirical things by the union of these four elements. Since the Parmenidean idea of Being excludes the new creation and destruction of qualitative determinations, and demands qualitative unchangeable- ness for the totality of primitive materials, Anaxago- ras argued that there are as many qualitative ypyyara, different from one another, as there are qualitative deter- minations in empirical things. The things of which we are sensible are composite, and they are named according to .the primitive material that prevails in them at any par- ticular instant? Their qualitative change (dAXolwats) consists in the fact that other primitive materials enter into the combination or some are excluded from it. 1 Arist. Met., J. 8, 984 a, 11. 2 Fr. 14. 3 Arist. Phys., I4. 187 b. EFFORTS TOWARD RECONCILIATION 81 The ypuara must, according to this, be thought as divis- ible ;* and in antithesis to the perceived things, which con- sist of heterogeneous components, we must designate as xpjwata all those substances which fall into homogeneous parts, however far they be divided. Therefore Aristotle designated the o7épyata of Anaxagoras as opuolopepi), and in later literature they go under the name of homoio- meriai. Consequently, what Anaxagoras had here in mind was nothing other than the chemist’s idea of the element. The utter inadequacy of data on which Anaxagoras could depend appears in the development of his theory. For since observation had as yet not been directed to chemical, but only to mechanical analysis, the constituents of ani- mals, such as bones, flesh, and marrow, as well as metals, were chumerated as elements. Further, because the philosopher possessed no means of fixing upon a deter- mined number of elements, he declared them to be num- berless and differing in form (édéa), color, and taste. When Aristotle in several places (see Zeller, I*. 875 f.) cites only organic substances in Anaxagoras as examples of the ele- ments, he is speaking more out of his preference for this field than of an inclination on the part of Anaxagoras to refer inorganic matter to the organic. There is not the slightest trace to be discovered in Anaxagoras’ cosmogony of a qualita- tive distinction between the organic and the inorganic. In particular, what we may call his teleology is not by any means confined to the organic. As regards the motion of these substances, Anaxagoras also separated the principle of Being from that of Becom- ing, but in an entirely different way from what we find in Empedocles. The poetical and mythical form of this thought he stripped off; but at the same time, instead 1 In remarkable dependence on ‘Parmenides, Anaxagoras neverthe- less makes a polemic, like Empedocles, against the acceptance of empty space (Arist. Phys., IV., 6, 213a, 22), and at the same time also against the finite divisibility of matter postulated in the concept of atoms. 6 82 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY of reflecting like Heracleitus upon the antagonistic pro- cesses of motion, he emphasized again the unity of the cosmic process. Since Anaxagoras, as is the case with all naive conception, could think of the actual only as material stuff, he had to seek among the numberless xpjpata for one which is the common cause of motion for all the others. This primitive dynamic material or motion-stuff was conceived by him.as having life within itself, after the analogy of the Ionian cosmic matter. It moves the others from within itself. Its nature, however, was inferred by Anaxagoras from the character of the world of perception that it brought into being. This world presents itself as an ordered, purposeful whole, and the forming force must also be orderly and purposeful. Therefore after an analogy? to the principle actively working in living beings, Anaxagoras called it the voids, the reason, or, as it may best be translated, the thought- stuff (Denkstoff). Far from being an immaterial princi- ple, the “spirit” is to Anaxagoras corporeal matter, but indeed in a state of exceeding refinement. It is the “lightest,” the most mobile, the only matter that moves itself. It represents the Adyos, both in the macrocosm and in the microcosm. As regards the form and move- ment of the eosmic process, it has all the functions of the Heracleitan fire. The order (xécos) and purposefulness of the empirical world, on which Anaxagoras depended in his assertion of the vos Staxoouav 74 wdv7a, was not noted by him so much in single terrestrial things as in the great relationships of the universe, in 1 Aristotle in Physics, VIII. 5,256 b, 24, proved only that Anaxagoras has called the vois the draéfs and dytyfs. The predicate dxivyros is only an inference of Aristotle. The mobility of the vods and its implications in single things is clearly set forth in passages like Stob. Ecl., I. 790 (Doz., 392), and Simpl. Phys., 85 recto, 164, 23. 2 Arist. Met., I. 8, 984 b, 15, kaOdep ev rois (dors. EFFORTS TOWARD RECONCILIATION 83 the regular revolutions of the heavenly bodies.1. His monism and the teleological method of his presentation rested on astro- nomical considerations. Compare W. Dilthey, Hinleitung in d. Geisteswissenschaften, V.201 f. He sought in a purely natu- ralistic way a physical explanation, and was not in the smallest degree concerned with religious matters. If he, as is very doubtful, called ? the vods God, yet this would only have been a metaphysical expression, as it had been among the Milesians. The doctrine of the vods was taken by Aristotle very much in the sense of an immaterial spirituality, when in the well-known passage (Met., I. 3, 984 b, 17) Aristotle placed the doctrine of Anaxagoras as that of the only sober philosopher among them all. In the Hegelian interpretation, which even to-day is not outgrown, Anaxagoras is placed at the close of the pre-Sophis- tic development on account of his alleged discovery of the ‘¢ Spirit.” It sounds so fine when in this philosophy of nature _ the world principle becomes ever more ‘ spiritual” in passing from water through air and fire until finally the ‘* pure Spirit” has been as it were distilled from matter. But this ‘* Spirit” is likewise only living corporeality, i. e., that which moves itself. Anaxagoras with his vots is scarcely a step nearer the immate- rial than Anaximenes with air, or Heracleitus with fire. On the other hand, we must nc+ fail to recognize that in this character- ization of the moving principle Anaxagoras, in a still more em- phatic manner than Empedocles, had taken up the factor of a judgment of value into his theoretic explanation. Admiration of the beauty and harmony of the world dictated to him the acceptance of a thought-stuff arranging the universe according to a principle of order. This vods, therefore, stands over against the other ele- ments. It alone is in itself pure and unmixed. It is sim- ple, and possesses through its “‘ knowledge” a power over all other material stuff. It plays somehow asa stimulus upon the other substances, which are mixed by it. It participates temporarily to a greater or less degree in the particular things thus originating. For, like all matter, it 1 Simpl. 33 rerso, 156, 13; mdvra duexdopnce voos kal THY TEeptxapnaty ravrqy, fv viv meptyopet ta Te dotpa, kat 6 iAtos Kal ceAqyn Kal 6 ajp Kai 6 aiip of drroxpwwdopevor. 2 Cicero, Acad. II. 37, 118 ; Sext. Emp. stdv. maih., IX. 6. 8 Fr. 7 and 8. 84 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY also is quantitatively divisible and qualitatively unchange- able. Remaining essentially identical with itself, it is dis- tributed in different proportions in single things. Anaxagoras used this thought-stuff only to explain on the one hand the beginnings of motion, and on the other such single processes which he could not derive from the mechanism of the once for all awakened cosmic motion. What these processes in particular are, we cannot? ascer- tain from the reproaches made against Anaxagoras.3- So far as our knowledge goes, the application that Anaxagoras has made of his vod; theory to explain the cosmic process is limited simply to this, — that he ascribed to the ‘‘ order- ing” thought-stuff the beginning of motion, and that he then conceived the motion to go on mechanically by impact and pressure between the other primitive materials in a manner planned by the vods. Connected with this is the fact that Anaxagoras denied a plurality both of coexisting and successive worlds, and that he aimed to describe only the origin of our present world. Consequently in distinc- tion from his predecessors he spoke therefore of a temporal beginning of the world. Preceding this beginning is a state of the most perfect mingling of all substances, reminding us of the Sphairos of Empedocles. In this mingling all ypxjara, with the excep- tion of the vods, are so minutely distributed that the whole possesses no particular character, This idea reminds us on the one hand of Chaos, on the other of the arepov of Anaximander. In his delineation of this idea, we have the fact that he taught that the mixtures of dif- fering xpyjuara let only those qualities come into perception in 1 How misjudged the meaning is, is clear, for Anaxagoras conceived his voids as a divine being. 2 It is highly improbable, according to Theoph. Hist. plant., III. 1, 4, that it concerns the genesis of the organism. 8 Plato, Phado, 97 b; Arist. Met., I. 4, 985 a, 18. EFFORTS TOWARD RECONCILIATION 85 which the components are all harmonized. He also in this way conceived the four elements of Empedocles as such mix- tures of primitive matter.’ Absolute mixture has no quality ; 6400 mavta xpyyata Av is the beginning of the writing of Anaxagoras, In this Chaos the primitive thought-material first created at one point? a rotatory motion of great velocity. This, be- ing extended in broadening circles, led to the formation of the orderly world, and is further being continued on account of the infinity of matter. By this rotation two great masses are first differentiated which were characterized by the opposi- tion of Bright, Warm, Pure-light, and Dry, as against Dark, Cold, Dense-heavy, and Moist, and are designated by Anaxa- goras as aiOyp and ajp.2 The latter is pressed into the centre, and condensed into water, earth, and stones. His ideas of the earth show him to have been essentially influenced by the Ionians. We regarded the stars as dissipated frag- ments of earth and stone that have become glowing in the fiery circle. He saw in the great meteor of Aegospotamoi a confirmation of this theory and at the same time a proof of the substantial homogeneity of the world. Anaxagoras’s astronomical view shows highly developed, many-sided ideas and inferences, which rest in part upon his own studies. He explained eclipses correctly ; and while he allowed to the sun and moon altogether too small dimensions, they were nevertheless very great compared to their perceptual size. Accordingly Anaxagoras was convinced that, as in Chaos, so in all individual things developed from it, the combina- 1 Arist. De gen. et corr, 1. 1, 814 a, 24; Zeller, I*. 876. 2 Presumably Anaxagoras assumed this point to be the pole star: see H. Martin, Mémoires de U Institut, 29,176 f.; see Dilthey, op. cit. 8 These antitheses remind us more of the Ionians than of Parmenides. In respect to the manifold of the mixture and the determination of the qualities, they stand in Anaxagoras obviously between the piyya and the Empedoclean elements. 86 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY tion of the cosmic elements is so fine and intimate that something at least of each one is everywhere. Thus the organic omépyara develop as plants and animals on the separation of the water and earth, which separation was caused by the heavenly fire. But the vods, as the vitalizing principle, stands in intimate relations with these, and its in- dependent power of motion was doubtless introduced here by Anaxagoras as the cause of functions that are not mechani- cally explicable! He, too, seems to have given especial attention to sense perception, which, however, he derived, in entire opposition to Empedocles, from the reciprocal action of opposites influenced by the feeling of aversion. Accord- ingly perceptual knowledge acquired in this way is only relative.2 In contrast to it, the truth is found solely through the Adyos, through the participation of the individual in the world reason. Anaxagoras originated in Clazomenee in the circle of Ionian culture, from which apparently he got his rich scientific knowl- edge and his pronounced positive and pbysical interest. His birth is (Zeller, I‘. 865 f., against Hermann) to be placed at about 500. We do not know about his education, particularly how he could have been so powerfully influenced by the Eleat- ies. He was of wealthy antecedents, and was regarded as an honorable gentleman, who, far away from all practical and polit- ical interests, ‘‘ declared the heaven to be his fatherland, and the study of the heavenly bodies his life’s task,” — a statement in which, side by side with the presentation of a purely theo- retical ideal of life, is to be noted the astronomical tendency which also characterized his philosophy. About the middle of the century Anaxagoras, then the first among philosophers of renown, removed to Athens, where he formed a centre of scien- tifie activity, and appears to have drawn about him the most notable men. He was the friend of Pericles, and became in- 1 To this the objection of Aristotle applies, that Anaxagoras did not distinguish the principle of thought (vois) from the animating (be- seelenden) principle (vy). (De an., I 2, 404 b.) This objection certainly did not arise from immanent criticism. 2 Arist. Met., IV. 5, 1009 b, 25; Sext. Emp., VII. 91. EFFORTS TOWARD RECONCILIATION. 87 volved under the charge of impiety in the political suit brought against Pericles in 434. He was obliged in consequence of this to leave Athens and go to Lampsacus. Here he founded a scientific association, and while high in honor he died a few years later (about 428). The fragments of the only writing preserved of his (as it appears) wept ¢icews (in prose) have been collected by Schaubach (Leipzig, 1827) and Schorn (with those of Diogenes of Apollonia, Bonn, 1829); Panzerbieter, De fragmentorum Anaz. ordine (Mciningen, 1836); Breier, Die Philosophie des An. nach Aristotles (Berlin, 1840); Zévort, Dissert. de la vie et la doctrine d’.A. (Paris, 1843); Alexi, A. u. seine Philosophie (Neu-Ruppin, 1867); M. Heinze, Ueber den voos des A. (Berichte d. Stichs. Ges. d. W., 1890). Archelaus is called a pupil of Anaxagoras, but appears, nevertheless, to be so much influenced also by other theories that he will be mentioned in a later place. The allegorical interpretation of the Homeric poem, which in part is ascribed to Anaxagoras himself (Diog. Laert., II. 11), in part to his pupil, Metrodorus, has only the slightest relation to his philosophy. 23. The philosopher who desired to abandon the arbitrary theory of the four elements of Empedocles, was obliged, in order to oppose to it a consistent theory, to assert either that the qualitative determinations of things are all pri- mary, or that no one of them is. The first way Anaxagoras chose; the Atomists the second. While in their explana- tion of empirical occurrence they also postulated a plurality of unchangeable things having Being, they had the boldness to deduce all qualitative distinctions of the phenomenal world from purely quantitative differentiations of the true essence of things. This is their especial significance in the history of European science. It has been customary in the history of philosophy to treat the theory of the Atomists in inseparable connection with the pre-Sophistic systems. This is explained from the fact that all direct knowledge fails concerning the founder of this theory, Leucippus and his doctrine, and that the teaching of the Atomists lies before us relatively complete only in the form that Democritus developed it. But between Leucippus and Democritus is an interval of certainly forty years, and this lies in that epoch of most strenuous mental labor, — which epoch 88 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY. witnessed in Greece the beginnings of Sophism. Leucippus is the contemporary of Zeno, Empedocles, and Anaxagoras, but Democritus is the contemporary of Socrates, and, in the works of his old age, of Plato. It is also consonant with this differ- ence of years that the fundamental thought of the Atomists in the form of the metaphysical. postulate of Leucippus arose from the Heracleitan-Parmenidean problems; but also that the development of that postulate, which Democritus gave to these problems, was for the first time possible upon the Sophistic theories as a basis, especially those of Protagoras (§ 82). To these changed temporal conditions there is the further corre- spondence in the fact that those theories of the Atomists, which we can refer to Leucippus, remained entirely in the compass of the problems confronting his contemporaries, Empedocles and Anaxagoras. On the other hand, the theory of Democritus gives the impression of being a comprehensive system, like that of Plato. Therefore the reasons from the point of chronology and from that of the subject matter require the beginnings of Atomism in Leucippus to be separated from the system of Democritus, which was conditioned by the subjective turn given to Greek thought. We must make this discrimination, however difficult it may be in details. Accordingly in this place is to be developed only the general metaphysical basis of Atomism, which has grown out of Eleaticism.' It was therefore on the one hand a complete misconception of the primal motives, but on the other a legitimate feeling — although defended entirely falsely in connection with precon- ceived notions — with which Schleiermacher (Gesch. d. Philos., Complete Works, III. 4a, 73) and Ritter after him (G@esch. d. Philos., 1.589 f.) sought to classify the Atomists with the Sophists. In Leucippus Atomism arose as an offshoot of Eleaticism. The theory of Democritus, however, far from being itself Sophistic, presupposed the theory of Protagoras. The suggestion of this relation may be found in Dilthey, Hinleitung in die Geistes- wissenschaften, I. 200. Leucippus, the first representative of this theory, stands in the most marked dependence on the Eleatic teaching. To his mind also, Being excluded not only all origination and destruction, but all qualitative change. Likewise Being coincides with the corporeal, that is, the gy with the 1 As to the perfect certainty of ascribing this to Leucippus, see Zeller, Tt, 843, n, 1. EFFORTS TOWARD RECONCILIATION. 89 mréov. By virtue of this coincidence Parmenides had felt compelled to deny the reality of empty space, and therefore also that of plurality and motion. Should now, however, as the interest of physics demanded, plurality and motion be recognized as real, and a scientific apprehension of the actual again be rendered possible, then the simplest and most logical method was to declare} that “ Non-Being,” the Void (16 xévov), did nevertheless exist. The aim of this assumption, however, is simply this: to make possible plurality and mobility for that which really is. Thereby it becomes possible to create a world of experience from the “ Void” and the multiform “Full” moving in the “Void,” to construct that world from that which has no Being and from a multiplicity of those things that have Being. A categorical physics thus appears in place of the hypothetical physics of Parmenides, and in place of a problematical appears an assertorical and an apodeictic physics. But while Leucippus departed from the Parmenidean concept of Being only so far as seemed absolutely neces- sary to explain plurality and motion, he still clung not only to the characteristic of unchangeableness (un-Becoming and indestructibility), but also to the thoroughgoing qualitative homogeneity of what possess Being. In oppo- sition to Empedocles and Anaxagoras, Leucippus therefore taught that all these varieties of what possess Being are homogeneous in quality. He agreed entirely with Par- devoid of all specific qualities. According to the Hleatics, all distinctions are due only to the permeation of that which really is not, by that which really is. So, on the one hand, to Leucippus distinctions between individuals 1 Democritus seems to be the first to have made the pointed remark : Pe) paAov 7d Sev H 76 pydev eivar, “das Ichts set um nichts mehr real als das Nichis.” Plut. Adv. col. 4, 2 (1109). 90 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY. ‘ that really possess Being exist only in those qualities due to their limitation through that which really is not; viz., empty space. These are the distinctions of form and motion. On the other hand, each of the changeless sub- stances possessing Being must be thought as a corporeality, homogeneous in itself, a continuum and therefore indivisi- ble. Being, which is moved in empty space, therefore con- sists of innumerable, exceedingly small bodies. Leucippus called these Atoms (drouot), every one of which is, like the Being of Parmenides, unoriginated, indestructible, un- changeable, indivisible, and homogeneous in itself and with all other Being. The single cosmic-Being of Parmenides was broken up into an infinite number of small primitive elements which, were they not separated by empty space, would constitute a single element in the sense of Empe- docles, and indeed would be the absolute qualitativeless éy of Parmenides. Of all the transformations of the Eleatic teaching, that of Leucippus is characterized by a striking simplicity, and by keen logical limitation to that which is indispensable to a professed explanation of the phenomenal world. At the same time it is “clear that the Atomism which became later so important in the development of scientific theories did not grow out of experi- ence, or observations and the conclusions built upon them, but directly out of the abstractest metaphysical concepts and absolutely universal needs for the explanation of actuality. Up to this point the Atomistic theory has been regarded as a variant of the Eleatic metaphysic, arising from an interest in physics. But, on the other hand, Leucippus is so far under the influence of Ionian monism that he does not seek the cause of motion in a force different from the stuff, but he regards spatial motion itself as a quality, immanent in the stuff. The corporeality that is homoge- neous in all atoms did not, in his mind, possess the power to change itself qualitatively, that is to say, dAXolwows; but it did possess «/vnows, an original underivable motion that EFFORTS TOWARD RECONCILIATION. 91 is given in its own essence. In fact, Leucippus seems to have understood by this term not so much that of heavi- ness, — fall from above downward,— but rather a chaotic primal condition of bodies moving, disorderly, among each other in all directions (§ 82). At all events, the Atom- ists held this original state of motion as uncaused and self-evident. So we can see in their view the perfect synthesis of the Heracleitan and Eleatic thought: all homo- geneous elements of Being are thought as unchangeable, but at the same time as in a state of motion that is self- originated. This is the extent to which the beginnings of Atomism may with certainty be ascribed to Leucippus. It is an attempt to explain the world by atoms in original motion in empty space. The purely, mechanical part of the theory, that the world was formed by collision, lateral and rotatory motion, likewise presented itself to the founder of Atomism in the same form in which Democritus later developed it. It is not so easy to explain, however, how Leucippus solved the more difficult and delicate question regarding the manner in which the various empirical qualities arose from these complexes of atoms; that is to say, the transformation of quantitative into qualitative differences. Of his answer we know nothing. The sub- jective method which Democritus applied to it was not as yet available to the founder of Atomism, since this method grew out of the investigations of Protagoras. Whether Leucippus! was content with setting up this origination 1 To my mind, there is no foundation for the belief that Leucippus in his doctrine of the aic@nrd employed the antithesis of pice: — rope; from its significance and following all tradition, this antithesis is So- phistic. The inference rests upon the obviously late and inaccurate note in Stobeus, Ecl., I. 1104 (Doz., 397 b, 9) from which it might also be adduced that Diogenes of Apollonia was an Atomist. It is certain that Leucippus, as an Eleatic, denied sense qualities as real. For some later 92 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY. of the qualities out of the quantitative relationships only as a metaphysical postulate; whether he explained these qualities, like Parmenides, simply as vain show and illu- sion; or whether he in an uncertain manner, like Empedo- cles, derived all other material from the four elements and their mixtures, so that he too sought to refer empirical things back to the different form and size of the combining atoms, —how far, in fact, he in general passed from the metaphysical principles to the specific development of the physical theory, — concerning all this it is doubtless too late to determine. From the allusions in his theory, and from the very uncertain reports from the extant literature, it is only safe to say that probably Leucippus was younger than Parmenides, considerably older than Democritus and contemporary with Empedocles and Anaxagoras. It is hardly possible to decide between the differ- ent reports, whether his residence was in Miletus, Elea, or Abdera. Since however his pupil (éraipos) Democritus doubt- less was an Abderite, and came from ascientifically active circle which we cannot! possibly suppose to be that of the Magi, alleged to have been left behind by Xerxes, we may assume that a scientific activity was developed in Abdera in the second half of the sixth century, which city attained its highest glory under the influence of the colonists from Teos. Leucippus was its first representative of any significance.? Protagoras appears to have originated in the school of Abdera at a time between the two great Atomists (§ 26). That Leucippus put his thought in writing is not entirely certain, but is probable. Nothing of his work remains, however. In any event, even early in anti- quity, there was uncertainty about the authorship of what had been ascribed to him.* Theophrastus ascribed * to him the péyas didxoomos Which went under the name of Democritus. It is reporter this denial is identical with the assertion of their subjectivity (vépq). Parmenides himself best teaches us how little this equivalence was possible for a pre-Sophistic thinker. 1 Zeller, T+. 763. 2 Diels. Aufsdize Zeller’s Jubilidum, p. 258 f. 8 De Xen., Zen., Gorg., 6, 980a, 7; év Tois Aevkimmou xadovpévors Adyors. 4 Diog. Laert., IX. 46. EFFORTS TOWARD RECONCILIATION. 93 strange that in the memory of succeeding times and indeed in modern time (Bacon, Alb. Lange), even as in antiquity (Epicu- rus), he has been entirely overshadowed by Democritus.* 24. “ Between these and in part already before them,” 2 the Pythagoreans sought finally to apply their mathematical studies to the solution of the Heracleitan-Eleatic problem (§ 12). However in this respect the Pythagoreans form no perfectly homogeneous whole. It appears rather that within the society, corresponding to its geographical extension and its gradual disintegration, the scientific work divided on different lines. Some Pythagoreans clung to the development of mathematics and astronomy; others busied themselves partly with medicine, partly with the investigation of different physical theories (con- cerning both see § 25) ; others finally espoused the metaphysical theory, which so far as we know was constructed first by Philolaus and is usually designated as the number theory. Philolaus, if not the creator, at least the first literary repre- sentative of the ‘t Pythagorean philosophy,” was an older con- temporary of. Socrates and Democritus, and cannot, at any rate, be set farther back than Anaxagoras and Empedocles. Indeed he is presumably somewhat younger than the latter two. Of his life we know nearly nothing, and we are even not sure whether he was a native of Tarentum or Crotona. Also that he, like other Pythagoreans about the end of the fifth century, lived for a time in Thebes, is inferred with uncertainty from the passage in Plato, Phedo, 61. Nearly as doubtful is his supposed authorship of the fragments that are preserved under his name. They have been collated and discussed first by Bockh (Berlin, 1819). From the investigations of Fr. Preller (article Philolaos in Ersch und Gruber Encykl., UI. 23, 370 f.), V. Rose (De Aristotelis librorum ordine et auctoritate, Berlin, 1854), C. Schaar- schmidt (Bonn, 1864), Zeller (Hermes, 1875, p.175f.), they may be assumed in part to be genuine, but they must be very cau- tiously introduced into the discussion of the original number theory. 1 Zeller, I4. 761, 843. Compare E. Rhode, Verhandl. der Trierer Philol.-Versuchungen, 1879, and Jahrbiicher fiir Philologie u. Pddagogik, 1881, 741f. Diels, Verhandlungen der Stettiner Philologie Vers. 1880. 2 Arist. Met., I. 5: év d€ rovrots kai mpo TovTwy of Kadovpevor Ivdayo- peta TOV pabyparey dyyduevot Kr. 94 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY. Along with Philolaus are mentioned, in Italy Clinias of Taren- tum,} in Thebes Lycis the teacher of Epaminondas, and Eurytus the pupil of Philolaus, a citizen of Crotona or Tarentum. Eury- tus in turn had as pupils Xenophilus of Thracian Chalcis, the Phiiasians Phanto, Echecrates, Diocles, Polymastus.? From Cyrene Prorus is mentioned. In Athens Plato brought forward the two Pythagoreans, Simmias and Cebes, as witnesses of the death of Socrates. Almost mythical are the Locrian Timeus? and the Lucanian Ocellus. The philosophic teaching of any of these men is not in any way certainly known. With the disso- lution of the Pythagorean League in the fourth century the school became extinct. The doctrines of the last significant personality in it, Archytus of Tarentum, merged, so far as our knowledge goes, into those of the older Academy (§ 38). + A collection of all the Pythagorean fragments is in Mullach ; Ritter, Gesch. der pyth. Philos. (Hamburg, 1826); Rothen- bitcher, Das System der Pythagoreen nach den Angaben des Aristoteles (Berlin, 1867) ; Alb. Heinze, Die meta. Grundlehren der dilteren P. (Leipzig, 1871), Chaignet, Pythagore et la philos. Pythagorienne, 2 vols. (Paris, 1873); Sobezyk, Das pyth. Sys- tem (Leipzig, 1878); A Doering, Wandlungen in der pyth. Lehre (Arch. f. Gesch. d. Philos., v. 508 f.). As to the Pythagorean teaching, only that can-be regarded as genuine which Plato and Aristotle report, together with the concurrent portions of the fragments transmitted in such ques- tionable shape. In the Pythagorean society mathematical investigations were pursued for the first time quite independently, and were brought to a high degree of perfection. Detailed views concerning the number system, concerning the series of odd and even numbers, of prime numbers, of squares, etc., were early instituted. lt is not improbable that they, applying arithmetic to geometry, came to the conception embodied in the so-called Pythagorean theorem. Herein must they have had a premonition of the real value of number-relations in that they represent number as the ruling 1 Jambl. De vita Pyth., 266. 2 Diog. Laert., VIII. 46. 3 The writing bearing this name and concerned with the soul of the world, usually published in Plato’s works, is certainly a later compendium of Plato’s Timeus. EFFORTS TOWARD RECONCILIATION. 95 principle in space. Their number theory was strengthened by the results attained by them in music. Although later reports include? much that is fabulous and physically impossible, there can nevertheless be no doubt that the Pythagorean harmonic shows an exact knowledge of those simple arithmetical relations (first of all, the string-lengths) out of which musical melody arises. To this may be added that the regular revolution of the stars, — of which they made especially careful observations, and which are indeed the standard for all time measurements, — made the world- order (x ‘EdAdOos 76 rputaveloy ths codias. Here the need of cul- ture developed most actively among the lesser citizens, here learning began to have political and social power, and here the supremacy of culture was personified in Pericles. Thus in science also Athens absorbed into itself the scat- tered beginnings of Greek civilization. Anaxagoras had lived for a long time in Athens. Par- menides and Zeno probably visited Athens, and Heracleitanism was represented there by Cratylus. All important Sopbists 1 See Windelband, Praeludien, p. 56 f. 2 Xen. Mem., I. 6. 8 Gorg., 420 ¢. 4 Eth. Nik., IX. 1, 1164 a, 24. 5 See Grote, Hist. of Gr., VIII. 493 f.; Zeller, Té4. 971 £ THE GREEK ENLIGHTENMENT. 111 sought and found here honor and glory. With them began the Attic period of ancient philosophy, its most magnificent period. The Sophists are, accordingly, first and foremost the bearers of the Greek Enlightenment. The period of their activity is that of the expansion of scientific culture. With less ability in independent creation, the Sophists devoted their energies to revising and popularizing existing theories. Their work was first directed, with an eye to the people’s needs, to imparting to the mass of people the results of science, Therein lay, along with their justification, also the danger to which the Sophists succumbed. Zogicrys meant originally ‘‘a man of science” in general. Then, as Protagoras? claimed for himself, it meant ‘‘ a teacher of science” and of political virtue; later, expressly, a paid teacher of rhetoric (see below). The opprobrium attached to the word Sophist at present is due to the polemics of Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle, which have unfavorably dominated history in its judgment of the Sophists, until Hegel (Complete Works, Vol. XIV. 5f.) made prominent the legitimate moment of their work. Since then, this has attained a complete recognition (Brandis, Hermann,” Zeller, Ueberweg-Heinze), but on the other hand has been exaggeratedly emphasized by Grote (History of Greece, VIII. 474 f.). Compare Jae. Geel, Historia critica sophistarum (Utrecht, 1823); M. Schanz, Die Sophisten (Gottingen, 1867) ; A. Chiapelli, Per la storia della sophistica greca (Arch. f. Gesch. d. Ph., III.) ; the fragments in Mullach, II. 180 f. The difference between the earlier and later Sophists (Ueber- weg) is well founded, since in the nature of the case at the be- ginning the serious and legitimate aspects of the movement were more prominent, while later on appeared the vagaries of the members and the menace of their doctrines to society. This development was so necessary, the consequences were so certainly determined by the precedents, and this distinction is on that account only go relative, that it, particularly for a brief presentation, will not be adopted as a basis of subdivision. — Plato’s dialogue Protagoras gives in its clear characteriza- tion of the principal personages an exceptionally vivid pic- 1 Plato, Protag., 318 d. 2 Hermann, Gesch. u. Syst. d. plat. Philos., 1.179f., 296 f. 112 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY. ture of the entire movement of the Sophists. In spite of the general polemic character of this work, the better aspects of Sophism are not entirely obscured. The most derogatory characterization of the Sophists is given in the dialogue Sophist transmitted under Plato’s name. ‘The Aristotelian conclusions agree with this dialogue in the main (Met., III. 5; VII. 3). The worst is the definition wept cop. édéyx. I. 165 a, 21; eons yip 4} codpiorixy pawvopern copia otca 8 ob+ Kai 6 coduorijs Xonwatiarhs dd hawoperns copias GAN’ odk ovo7ns. The popularizing tendency of Sophistry found an emi- nent representative in Hippias of Elis. A brilliant poly- histor, he dazzled his contemporaries in all sorts of mathematical, zodlogical, historical, and grammatical learn- ing. At the same time, however, as the dialogue Hippias Major shows, he aimed by his somewhat colorless moral teaching to achieve a cheap success with the masses. It was very much the same with Prodicus of Iulis on the island of Ceos, of whose shallow ethics an example is preserved in the well-known Heracles at the Cross Ways. The strength of Prodicus lay in synonymy. See L. Spengel, Swaywy? rexvav (Stuttgart, 1828) ; J. Mahly, Die Sophist Hippias von Elis (Rheinisches Museum, 1860 f.) ; F. G. Welcker, Prodikas der Vorgtnger des Socrates (in a smaller work, II. 393 f.). Both were about of an age, and somewhat younger than Protagoras. Nothing further is known concerning their lives. Hippias, who prided himself on his memory and his great learning, was pictured as one of the most conceited Sophists. Prodicus was treated by Plato with playful irony on account of his pedantic pains in word-splitting. For Socrates’ relation to him, see § 27. The instruction that the Sophists were called upon to give had to adapt itself to a specific purpose. Democracy had gained ascendency in Athens and most other cities, and the citizen was brought by duty and inclination into active participation in public affairs. This evinced itself particu- larly in oratory. With the higher culture of the masses, 1 Hermann, Gesch. u. Syst. d. plat, Philos., I. 179 £., 296 f. THE GREEK ENLIGHTENMENT. 113 the greater were the demands upon those who by the power of the spoken word wished to win influence in the state. The youth who attended upon the teaching of the Sophist desired to be trained by him into a cultured and eloquent citizen of the state. So the Sophists found their chief task in scientific and rhetorical instruction for publie life. The instruction consisted on the one hand in technical and formal oratory, and on the other in that learning which appeared especially important for any par- ticular end they had in view. Therein lay not only the social-historical significance of the Sophists, but also the tendency of all the inlependent investigations through which the Sophists have furthered science. Gorgias of Leontini and Protagoras of Abdera may be regarded the most eminent representatives of this phase of Sophism. For the characterization and criticism of Sophism as a tech- nique of education in statecraft, one ought to consult especially Plato’s dialogue, Gorgias. Concerning the relation of the Sophists to rhetoric, see Fr. Blass, Die attische Beredsamkeit von Gorgias bis Lysias (Leipzig, 1868). As a typical expres- sion of these attempts of the Sophists which embraced also legal oratory, may be taken the utterance of Protagoras that he would pledge himself to? rov #rtw Adyov KpeitTw Toveiv, — an expression, to be sure, which called forth the crushing criticism of Aristophanes, who in the Clouds imputed it to Socrates. A more reliable fact about the life of Gorgias is that he was in Athens in 427 as head of the embassy from his native city (Thucyd., III. 86). His life has been set by Frei (Rh. Mus., 1850, 1851) in the time from 483 to 375. He made a great impression in Athens by his eloquence, and exercised a distinct influence upon the development of rhetorical style. He spent his protracted old age in Larissa in Thessaly. The genuineness of both of his preserved declamations (ed. Blass, Leipzig, 1881) is doubtful. His philosophical treatise bore the title rept picews } wept Tod py dvros (see below). His con- nection with the Sicilian school of oratory (Corax and Tisias), and therefore also with Empedocles, is undoubted. His con- nection with the Eleatics appears equally certain, from the argu- 1 Arist. Rhet., II. 24; 1402 a, 23. 8 114 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY. mentation in his writings. Compare H. E. Foss, De -G. LZ, (Halle, 1828); H. Diels, Gorgias und Empedocles (Berichte der Berliner Akademie). Alcidamus of Elea, Folus'of Agrigentum, Lycophron, and Protarchus ? are named as pupils of Gorgias. Protagoras, doubtless the most important of the Sophists, was born in Abdera in 480 or somewhat earlier. It can be assumed that he was not distant in his views from the school of Atomists in that city. Considerably younger than Leucippus, and about twenty years older than Democritus, he formed the natural connection between the two (see §§ 23, 31). With keen insight into the needs of the time, and much admired as a teacher of wisdom, he was one of the first to make an extended tour of the Grecian cities. He was in Athens many times. In 411, and during the rule of the four hundred, he was there for the last time, and was accused of atheism. He was con- demned, and upon his flight to Sicily was drowned. The titles (Diog. Laert., [X. 55) of his numerous writings, only a very few of which are preserved, prove that he dealt with the most varied subjects in the domain of theory and practice. Com- pare J. Frei, Questiones Protagoree (Bonn, 1845); A. J. Vi- tringa, De Prot. vita et philos. (Gréningen, 1851). Lately Th. Gompertz (Vienna Session Reports, 1890) has identified a Sophistic speech with the Apology of Medicine in the pseudo- Hippocratic writing, rept réyvys, and has noted its not fully undoubted connection with the teaching of Protagoras. Antimerus of Mende, Archagoras, Euathlus,? Theodorus the mathematician, and in a wider sense Xeniades of Corinth also are to be regarded as pupils of Protagoras. Eminent citizens of Athens, like Critias, probably Callicles, or poets like Evenus of Paros, etc., stood in a less intimate connection with the Sophists. The practical and political aim of their instruction com- pelled the Sophists to turn aside from independent nature study and metaphysical speculation, and to content them- selves with the presentation, in popular form, of such the- ories only when they were called for or appeared effective. 1 Plato, Gorg. 2 Plato, Phileb. 8 Plato, Theetetus. 4 Many, like Gorgias, rejected this as perfectly worthless. See Plato, Meno, 95 c. THE GREEK ENLIGHTENMENT. 115 The. peculiar task in teaching men how to persuade drove them, on the other hand, to interest themselves more thor- oughly in man, especially on his psychological side. Who- ever endeavors to influence man by speech must know something ofthe genesis and development of his ideas and volitions. (While earlier science. with naive devotion to the outer world had coined fundamental concepts for its knowledge of nature, Sophistry, so far as it adopted the methods of science, turned to inner experience, and com- pleted the incomplete earlier philosophy by studying the mental life of man. In this essentially anthropological tendency, histry turned philosophy on the road to ej) This new kind of work began first with language. The efforts of Prodicus in synonymy, those of Hippias in grammar, were in this direction. Protagoras was especially fruitful in this respect. Persuaded that theory without practice was as little useful as practice 2 without theory, he connected the practical teaching, to which Gorgias seems to have limited himself, with philological investigations. He concerned himself with the right use of words,’ in their genders, tenses, modes,’ etc. Compare Lersch, Die Sprachphilos. der alten, 1.15 f.; Alberti. Die Sprachphilos. vor Platon (Philol., 1856) ; Prantl, Gesch. der Logik, I. 14 f. Similar small beginnings in logic appeared, in addition to those in grammar. That teachers of oratory should 1 What Cicero (Tuse., V. 4, 10) said of Socrates, that he called philosophy down from heaven into the cities and houses, is equally true for the entire Greek Enlightenment, for the Sophists as well as for him. 2 Stobzeus Florilegium, 29, 80. 8 Plato, Phedr., 267 c. 4 Diog. Laert., IX. 53, in which he distinguished edywAn, éparnotss ddxpyars, and. évro\7. 116 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY. reflect how a thing was to be proved and controverted, is obvious. It is also easily credible (Diog. Laert., 1X. 51 f.) that Protagoras had his attention drawn to the nature of contradictory propositions, and was the first to teach the method of proof (ras pos Tas Oéoeus érryetpjoes). Appar- ently formal logic sprang up here as an art of argumen- tation, proof, and contradiction. Of how far it was developed in details by the Sophists, we unfortunately know absolutely nothing.? We are better informed concerning their general view of human knowledge. The less the Sophist championed earlier metaphysical and physical learning, and the more he entertained his hearers by his clever opposition to it, and the more vividly again instruction presented to the consciousness of the rhetorician the possibility of proving different things of the same object, so much the more con- ceivable is it that these men lost faith in any universally valid truth or in the possibility of any certain knowledge. Their preoccupation with the theory of knowledge led, as things were, by a psychological necessity to skeptici&m. This skepticism is the theoretical centre of Sophistry. That this degenerated among the younger Sophists into frivolous argumentation should not lead to the misconception of the scientific seriousness with which the negative epistemology was developed, especially by Protagoras. On the other hand, it was an unhistoric interpretation for those in modern time, fol- lowing Grote’s example, to celebrate Protagoras as the founder of Positivism: E. Laas, Idealismus und Positivismus, I. (Berlin, 1880) var. loc. ; W. Halbfass, Die Berichte des Platon u. Aristoteles tiber Protagoras (Strassburg, 1882). Opposed to 1 That the Aristotelian logic was not without precedents, literary or in the form of practical exercise, may be taken a priori as extremely probable. Tow far these precedents reached cannot be determined from the very few indications from extant literature (see particularly Plato’s (?) dialogue Sophist). This lack of evidence is one of the most regrettable deficiencies in the history of Greek science. Compare Prantl, Gesch. d. Log., I. 11 f. THE GREEK ENLIGHTENMENT. 117 this is P. Natorp, Forschungen zu Gesch. des Erkenntnissprob- lems, p. 1 f., 149 f. Compare Fr. Sattig, Der Protagoreische Sensualismus in Zeitschr. f. Philos. (1885 f.). The chief source for the epistemology of Protagoras is Plato’s dialogue, Theetetus. Yet it is a question how far the presentation developed in this may be referred to Protagoras himself. The teaching of Gorgias is in part preserved in the psendo-Aristo- telian De Melisso, Zenone, Gorgia, c. 5 and 6 (§ 17); and in part in Sext. Emp. Adv. math., VIL. 68. In order to establish his skeptical belief about human knowledge, Protagoras made the eternal flux of Hera- cleitus his point of departure. But he emphasized still more than Heracleitus the correlation, in which every single thing does not so much exist, as momentarily come into existence, through its relation to other things. From the disavowal of absolute Being it followed that qualities of things arise only out of the temporary effect of things on one another. Quality is the product of motion,! and in- deed, as Protagoras in a purely Heracleitan manner sect forth, always of two corresponding motions but in opposite directions. One of these was designated as activity, the other as passivity.? It follows that in general it can never be said what a thing is, but at most-what it becomes in its changing relation to other things,’ and the Protagorean cor- relativeness contained a still greater significance in apply- ing this general theory of motion to the theory of human perception. Whenever a thing affects one of our senses, 1 Jt is not clear from the Theetetus whether and how Protagoras discussed the substratum of the xivjots. Even if he did not with -Heracleitus deny it, yet he regarded it at any rate as incognizable. It is conceivable that the Abderite Protagoras developed this theory in ° compliance to the demands of Atomism, in which shape Democritus later received it (§ 32). 2 Theet., 156 f. 8 Similarly the skeptical statements of Xeniades appear to have been conceived. Compare Zeller, I+. 988. 118 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY. in which the motion proceeding! from the object meets a reacting motion of the organ, there then arises in the sense organ the perceptual image,? and simultaneously in the thing, the quality corresponding * to the image. Therefore every perception teaches only how the thing appears in the moment of slags for the perceiver, and indeed for him alone. Now for Protagoras, sense perception was regarded as the only source of knowledge and of the entire mental life Therefore there was for him no insight into the Being of things over and above those relations; no idea of what things mighthe in themselves abstracted from perceptual relations. eater is everything for each individual ® just what it appears to him; but it is such only to that indi- vidual, and, more exactly, only for his momentary state of perception.) ' The well-known statement ® has this meaning : TavTov. Lemeara perpov avOpwros, TOV pee ovTwv @s éort, tov 5é wn dvtwv ws ovK got. 1 The ability of the different objects to influence the different sense organs appears already to have led Protagoras to his theory of the different velocities of movements of the objects. See Theet., 156 c. With this reduction of the qualitative to the quantitative, Protagoras stood entirely in the school of the Atomists (§§ 23 and 82). ? Under this term the sensations and also the feelings are classified in the Thecetetus (156). 8 That the aic@yrov in reality arises with the aleOnots, is an addition presumably of those who had extended and applied the theory of the Abderite (according to the Theetetus), For such an assertion carries one far beyond the bounds of skepticism. This cannot apply to Democritus. 4 Whether and how Protagoras has proved and explained this view (un dev etvar ray yoy mapa ras aicOnoes, Diog. Laert., IX. 51) is not known. In the light of the earlier Rationalisn (§§ 18-23) this sensa- tionalism seems somewhat unwarranted. It is presaged in the physio- logical psychology of the later nature philosophy (§ 25). 5 The explanation of Thewtetus (152 a) does not permit the dvéparos in this well-known sentence to refer to the genus. See Arist. Met, X. 6, 1062 b, 13. 6 Theatetus, 152 a; Sext. Emp. Adv. math., VII. 60. THE GREKK KNLIGHTENMENT. flv As Protagoras based his philosophy upon that of Hera- cleitus, so Gorgias founded his upon that of the Eleatics. The formen{ had concluded that to all opinion there is attached a relative, but to none an absolute, truth ;)\ the latter sought to demonstrate in general the impossibility of knowledge. While, however, the practical investiga- tions of Protagoras enriched philosophy in the succeeding systems of Plato and Democritus, the argumentation of Gorgias was developed in a captious and sterile dialectic. Gorgias showed: (1) Nothing is. That which is not, can- not be, and even as little can that which is. For that which is, cannot be thought either as unoriginated and imperish- able or as originated and perishable; neither can it be thought as one or as many, nor indeed finally as moved, without being involved in obvious contradictions, The arguments of Zeno are everywhere re-employed here _ (§ 20). Moreover, that which is and that which is not to exist simultaneously, is impossible (against Heracleitus ?). (2) Were there something, it would not be knowable ; for that which is and that which'is thought must be differ- ent, — otherwise error would be impossible.t (8) If there were knowledge, it could not be communicated, because communication is possible only by means of signs, which are different from the thing itself. There is no warrant that there is a like apprehension of these signs by different individuals.? F owsoever seriously and scientifically the theories of ‘Skepticism were held, even by Protagoras, they neverthe- less led to the demoralization of science, and resulted finally in a frivolous diversion in daily life.) Gorgias had found 1 This dialectic is more finely spun out in the dialogue of the Sophist. 2 One is almost inclined to regard: these paradoxes of this anti-philo- sophical rhetorician as a grotesque persiflage of the Eleatic dialectic. At all events, this last is inevitably and fatally involved in its own toils. 120 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY. that every predication of a subject is doubtful,’ if indeed there is any difference whatever between subject and pred- icate. He therefore called in question synthetic judgments. Protagoras himself doubted the reality of mathematical knowledge.? Euthydemus, in the spirit of this relativism,3 said that anything is suitable to everything; one cannot err, for what is spoken exists also as a something thought.! One cannot contradict himself; if he appears to, it is only because he is speaking of a different thing, and so on, Since the majority of the Sophists did not take truth seri- ously from the beginning, their entire art amounted to a dispute with formal adroitness pro et contra over anything whatsoever, and to equipping their pupils in this facility. Their principal aim was accordingly to be able to confuse the listener, to drive him into making absurd answers, and to refute one’s opponent. Protagoras also wrote dvTiAoylas and cataBddrovres 3° and the practice of the Sophists, especially in later time, in trying to be sensational, consisted simply in that art, which is called Eristic. Plato’s Huthydemus describes with many playful witticisms the method of Eristic by the example of the two brothers Euthydemus and Dionysidorus, and Aristotle has taken the pains to arrange systematically these witticisms in the last book of the Topics (rept coguorixay édéyywv). The greater number of these witticisms are puns. The ambiguity of “the words, of the endings, of the syntactical forms, etc., are in the main the basis of the witticisms (Prantl, Gesch. d. Log. I. 20f.). The great favor with which these jokes were received in Greece, and espe- 1 Sophist, 251 b. 2 Arist. Met., IT. 2, 998 a, 8. 3 ray mpos Te ctvar THY ddnOecav. Sext. Emp. Adv. math., VII. 60. * Here the ambiguity of the copula also plays a part. Lycophron proposed to omit the copula. 5 The proposition that “man is the measure of all things” is cited as the beginning of this work, and at the same time as the beginning of a work, called d\7Geca, which perhaps formed the first part of it, THE GREEK ENLIGHTENMENT. 121 cially in Athens, is explained by the youthful inclination to quibble, by the southron’s fondness for talking, and by the ome of reflective criticism upon familiar things of daily However, this facetious method was unpromising for the serious progress of science. On the other hand, the con- yictionless attitude of mind that the Sophists designedly or undesignedly encouraged became a direct menace in its application upon that domain in which, as their entire effort showed, they were alone deeply interested, — the ethico-political. Since the time of the Seven Wise Men (§ 9), the content of moral and civil laws and obedience to them had been a common subject for reflection. But the growing individualism, the inspired activity of the Periclean age, and the anarchy of the Athenian democracy for the first time brought into question through the Sophists the justification of these norms. Since here also the individual man with his temporary desires and needs was declared to be the measure of all things, the binding power of the law became as relatively valid as theoretical truth had been. See H. Sidgwick, Zhe Sophists (Journal of Philology, 1872, 1873); A. Harpf, Die Ethik des Protagoras (Heidelberg, 1884) ; and the general literature concerning the Sophists and particu- larly that concerning Socrates. Of the profounder investigations in which the more important Sophists were largely engaged, almost nothing is preserved save individual remarks and striking-asser- tions. At most there is the myth of Protagoras in the dialogue of that name (320f.). Perhaps the first half of the second book of the Republic refers also to something of the same sort. Per- haps the Sophists suffer in this domain, as in theory, from the fact that we are instructed concerning them only from their opponents.” The most important point of view which the Sophists in this respect set up appeared in their contrast of the natural 1 There is also a fragment found by Fr. Blass (Univers. Schrift. Kiel., 1889) in Jamblichus, Protreptice orationes ad philosophiam, ch. 20, who attributed it to the Sophist Antiphon. 122 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY. and social condition of man. From reflection upon the difference and change not only of legal prescriptions but also of social rules,! the Sophists concluded that at least a greater part of these had been established by convention through human statute (Oécex sive vou); and (a only such laws were universally binding as were established in all men equally by nature (dice). _The natural therefore appeared to be of the greater worth, — more nearly per- manent and more binding than the social. Natural law seemed higher than historic positive Iaw,) The more se- rious Sophists endeavored then further “to strip off from natural morality and natural Jaws the mass of convention- alities: Protagoras? taught that justice and conscience (Sinn and aises) are the gifts of the gods, and are common to all_ men; but neither this nor the assertion of Hippias, that {law ” violently drives? man to many things that are contrary to “ atute ele up any thoroughgoing and neces- sary opposition between the two legislations. But the more the theory of the Sophists conceived of “nature” as “human nature,” and as “human nature” limited to its physical_impulsive, and individual aspect, so much the more did law” appear a detriment and a limitation of the nat- ural man.}] Archelaus, the pupil of Anaxagoras, declared that social differences do not arise from ‘ Nature.” They are conventional determinations (od voces adda vouw).! Plato® has Callicles develop the theory that all laws are created by the stronger, and these laws, on account of need of protection, the weaker accept. He® puts into the mouth , 1 Compare Hippias in Xen. JJem., IV. 4, 14f. 2 In his myth reproduced by Plato. 8 Plato, Prot., 337c. Similarly, but somewhat more brusquely, Cal- licles expresses himself in Plato, Gorgias, 482 f. * Diog. Laert., IT. 16. 5 Loe. cit. . 6 Republic, 1, 888, THE GREEK ENLIGHTENMENT. 123 of Thrasymachus of Chalcedon a naturalistic psychology of legislation, according to which the ruler in a natural body politic would establish laws for his own advantage. In this spirit Sopbistry contended, in part from the point of view of “natural right,’ in part from that of absolute anarchy, against many existing institutions:' not only as the democratic Lycophron against every privilege of the nobility, or as Alcidamus against so fundamental a prin- ciple of ancient society as was slavery, but finally even against adl custom and all tradition.2 The independence of individual judgment, which the Enlightenment pro- claimed, shattered the rule of all authority and dissipated the content of social consciousness. In the attacks which already science in its more serious aspects had directed against religious ideas, it is obvious that religious authority also would be swept away with the flood of the Sophistic movement. All shades of religious freethinking are met with in Sophistic literature : — every- thing, from the cautious skepticism of Protagoras, who claimed? to know nothing of the gods, to the naturalistic and anthropological explanations of Critias 4 and Prodicus® as to belief in the gods, and even to the outspoken atheism of a certain Diagoras ® of Melos. 27. Against the destructive activity of the Sophists ap- peared the powerful personality of Socrates, who stood indeed with his opponents upon the common ground of the Enlightenment, and like them raised to a principle the inde- 1 To some extent with positive propositions whose authors, according to Aristotle (Pol., II. 8 & 7), were Hippodamus and a certain Phaleas. 2 Compare Arist. Pol., I. 3, 1253 b, 20. 8 By reason of the vagueness of the object and the brevity of human life; compare Diog. Laert., IX. 51. 4 Compare the verse in Sext. Emp., IX. 54. 5 Cic. De natura deorum, I. 42, 118. 6 Compare Zeller, I*. 864, 1. y S 0 4 124 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY. pendent reflection concerning everything given by tradition and custom. Gut at the sane time he was unshaken in the conviction that through reflection a universally valid truth could certainly be foun Sperry aii’ Nev in air geigo\ . The reports of Xenophon,’ Plato, and Aristotle are the chief sources of our knowledge concerning Socrates. The remarkably different light that is cast from such different men upon this great personality makes him stand ont in plastic distinctness. Xenophon saw more of the sober, practical, and popular side of the life and character of the man. Plato, on the contrary, beheld the height of his imagination, the depth of his spiritual being, his elevating influence on youthful and highly gifted minds. See S. Ribbing, Ueber das Verhiiltniss zwischen d. xenophontischen u. d. platonischen Berichten tiber d. Persénlichkett u. d. Lehre d. Sokrates (Upsala, 1870). Xenophon’s representation, so far as the author’s knowledge goes, is one of historic fidelity, but it was strongly under the influence of Cynic party prejudice. Plato’s writings, however, place in the mouth of Socrates less often Socrates’ teachings (only in the Apology and the earliest dialogues) than the consequences that Plato has drawn out of them. Aristotle’s teaching is everywhere authoritative as re- gards the teachings of Socrates; for, following Socrates by some- what of an interval, and uninfluenced by personal relationship, he was able to set in clear light the essential features of Socrates’ scientific work. H. Kochly, Sokrates u. sein Volk (in Acad. Vortr. u. Red., I. 219 f.); E. v. Lasaulx, Des Sokrates Leben, Lehre und Tod (Miinchen, 1857); M. Carriére, Sokrates wu. seine Stellung in der Gesch. des menschlichen Geistes (in Westermann’s Monats- heften, 1864); E. Alberti, Sokrates, ein Versuch tiber ihn nach den Quellen (Gottingen, 1869); E. Chaignet, Vie de Sokrate (Paris, 1868); A. Labriola, La doctrina di Sokrate (Neapel, 1871); A. Fouillée, La philos. de Sokrate (Paris, 1873); A. Krohn, Sokrate doctrina e Platonis republica illustrata (Halle, 1875) ; Windelband, Sokrates (in Praeludien, p. 54 f.); K. Joél, Der echte u. der wenophontische Sokrates, I. (Leipzig, 1892). 1 The Memorabilia are essential for our consideration of this (see A. Krohn, Soc. u. Xen., Halle, 1874). So is the Symposium. The question as to the priority of the Symposium of Xenophon or the Symposium of Plato is not yet fully decided in favor of the former, but is of Inte accepted. Compare Ch. V. Compare Sander, Bemerkungen zu Xeno- phon’s Berichten, ete. (Magdeburg, 1884). THE GREEK ENLIGHTENMENT. 125 Socrates was born in Athens a little before 469,! the son of Sophroniscus, a sculptor, and Phenarete. He learned the trade? of his father, and discriminatingly absorbed the various elements of culture of his time, without applying himself to properly erudite studies. Acquaintance with the methods of instruction of the Sophists awoke in him the con- viction of the dangerousness of their tendencies. Against them he felt himself called by divine direction? to a serious examination * of himself and his fellow-citizens, and to un- remitting labor in the direction of moral perfection. He was moved by a deep religious spirit and an exalted moral sense in his investigations. He shared with his contem- poraries an immediate interest in these investigations; and his own peculiar activity, which began in Athens as early as the commencement of the Peloponnesian war,° rests upon these. He belonged to no school, and it was foreign to his purpose to found one. With spontaneous feeling, he sought on the broad public field, which Athenian life offered, intellectual intercourse with every one. His extra- ordinary exterior,® his dry humor, his ready and trium- phant repartee brought him into universal notice. His geniality, however, and the fine spiritual nature which lay hidden in his astonishing shell,’ the unselfishness which he manifested unstintedly toward his friends, exercised an irresistible charm upon all the remarkable personalities of the time, especially upon the better elements of the Athe- 1 He was at his death (399) over seventy years old. 2 Concerning a piece, later on pointed out as one upon which the young Socrates was said to have wrought, see P. Schuster, Ueber die Portrdts der griech. Philos. (Leipzig, 1877). 3 Plato, Apol., 33 c. # é£erdtew éuavrdv kal rovs GAdovs: ibid., 28 e. 5 The production of the Clouds, 428, attests his popularity. ® The humorous characterization of his own Silenus shape is in Xeno- phon’s Symposium, 4, 19 f. 7 Compare the beautiful speech of Alcibiades in Plato, Symposium, 215 £. 126 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY. nian youth. While he in this way obeyed higher duty to the neglect! of home cares, in free fellowship a circle of admirers formed itself around him in which especially the aristocratic youth were represented in men like Alcibiades. He held himself as far away from political activity as pos- sible, but the unavoidable duties of the citizen of a state he performed with simple integrity.? At the age of seventy Socrates was accused of “ cor- rupting the youth and introducing new gods.” The charges arose. originally from low personal motives,’ but became serious through political complications,* in that the aristo- cratically inclined philosopher, as the most popular and active “ Sophist,’ was to be made answerable for moral degeneration by the democratic reactionary party. Not- withstanding he would have been freed with a small pen- alty °if he himself had not offended ® the Heliasts by his candid pride in his virtue. The execution of the sentence of death was delayed thirty days by the Aewpia to Delos, and Socrates disdained in his loyalty 7 to law the flight so easily possible to him. He drank the cup of hemlock in May,® 399. 1 Concerning Xantippe, whose name has. become proverbial, see K. Zeller, Zur Ehrenrettung der Xan. (in Vortrag und Abhandlung, I. p. 51 f). ? He made three campaigns, and showed himself, as prytanis, just and fearless against the excited minds of the masses (see Plato, A pol., 82 f.).. ® The accusers Meletus, Anytus, and Lycon acted out of personal animosity, unless they were men of straw (K. F. Hermann, De Soc. accu- satoribus, Gottingen, 1854). 4 See Grote, History of Greece, VIII. 551 f. 5 The verdict of “ guilty” was carried only by a majority of three or thirty ; the sentence of death had a much larger majority (more than eighty). ® The Apology of Plato may be taken as authentic in its essentials. 7 Compare Plato’s dialogue, the Crito. § In respect to the external circumstances of the day of his death, Plato’s dialogue, the Pheo, is certainly historical, although Plato in it THE GREEK ENLIGHTENMENT. 127 An instructor in philosophy, in the strict sense of the term, Socrates did not have. He called himself (Xen. Symposium, 1, 5) atrovpyés. But apparently he had become familiar with many of the scientific theories, especially with those of Hera- cleitus and Anaxagoras, not only through the discourses of the Sophists but through his own readings. (Compare K. F. Her- mann, De S. magistris et disciplina juvenili, Marburg, 1837.) The process of development portrayed in the Phedo is scarcely historical, but can be looked upon as a sketch of the Platonic theory of ideas. (Compare Zeller, II*. 51.) Xenophon, as well as Plato, makes Socrates meet persons of every position, calling, and political complexion in his conver- sations. His relation to young men was an ethically pedagogical and morally spiritual ennoblement of the Grecian love for boys. Among the men who made his popular philosophical method their own are to be named: Xenophon, who stood very near to the Cynics (compare F. Diummler, Antisthenica, Berl., 1882, and Academica, Giessen, 1889) ; also AXschines (not the oy who wrote dialogues in the same spirit (K. F. Hermann, De isch. Socratict religutis (Gottingen, 1850); and the almost mythical shoemaker Simon (see Béckh, Simonis Socraticis dialogi, Heidelberg, 1810, and E. Heitz in O. Miiller’s Lit- teraturgeschichte, I1?. 2, 25, note 2). The legal measures against Socrates are epen to the most different constructions. The old view that the philosopher was ruined through intrigues of the Sophists may be regarded as given up.and also the conception originated by Hegel (Complete Works, II.560 f., XIV. 81f.), according to which, as in a tragedy, Socrates was the champion of the higher Idea, and was ruined by his unavoidable crime of offending the established laws. These great antitheses play no part in the trial. It appears, rather, that through personal and political intrigues Socrates became a sacrifice for the discontent which the democratic reaction fostered against the entire Enlightenment. Although presumably unin- tentionally, nevertheless Aristophanes did a decided injury to the philosopher in his caricature of him in the Clouds," in that he stamped him in the public mind as a type of precisely those Sophistic excesses which Socrates fought most vigorously. (Compare H. Th. Rétscher, Aristophanes und seine Zeitulter, goes far beyond Socrates in his theory of the immortality of the soul (compare Apol., 40 c) not only in his presentation of evidence, but as to his personal conviction. 1 Compare especially H. Diels, Verh. d. Stet. Phil. Vers., 1880, 106 f. WD) oS 5, opA Lay rare > di Sas 128 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY. Berlin, 1817; Brandis, in the RA. Mus., 1828; P. W. Forch- hammer, Die Athener und Soc., Berlin, 1837; Bendixen, Ueber den tieferen Schriftsinn, ete. (Husum, 1838.) The theory of knowledge of the Sophists had led in all its parts to a relativism of individual opinions. The effort, on the other hand, for a stable and universally valid knowl- edge formed the central point of the activity of Socrates) The éavctiun was set in antithesis to the dofa: by him; yet the éruatyun is not a complete, erudite possession to be handed down, but an ideal to be striven for in work in com- mon with other men. , Fr. Schleiermacher, Ueber d. Wert des Sokrates als Philos. in Ges. Werk, IL. 2, 287 ff. Socrates did not try, therefore, to impart knowledge or to give purely formal instruction, but to engage in a mutual seeking for truth. The basis of this was the conviction that such a norm of truth existed paramount to individual opinion. Therefore his activity found its necessary form in the dialogue, the conversation in which, through the exchange of opinions and through mutual criticism of these, that should be found which is recognizable by all. While the Sophists studied the psychological mechanism by which opinions come to be, Socrates had faith in a law of reason that determines the truth His whole endeavor was only a continuous invitation to his fellow-citizens to help him in this search. His confession of his ignorance! signified this, while he also at the same time herein intimated? his failure to attain his ideal of copia. Yet he demanded the same measure of self-knowledge? also from others, For 1 Plato, Apol., 21f.; Symp., 216 d, 2 Compare Plato, Symp., 203 f. In this connection the term procodpia wins, as contrasted with the more pretentious codia (coduoris), its pecu- liar meaning, ‘‘striving for knowledge.” See Ueberweg, p- 2. ® Compare the oracular yuOO ceaurdv, Xen. Mem. IV. 24f.; Plato, Apol., 214. THE GREEK ENLIGHTENMENT. 129 nothing more dangerous blocked the way of wisdom than that conceited affectation of wisdom which the Sophistic half-education developed in the majority of minds. There- fore his conversation analyzed with exasperating logic the opinion which at the outset he elicited from others, and in this superior manipulation of the dialectic consisted the Socratic irony.) But after removing this impediment Socrates, in leading the conversation, sought to draw out gradually what was common to the participants. In the persuasion that serious reflection could find such a common thought, he “delivered” the slumbering thought from the mind; and this art he called his maieutic.? The method of the Socratic investigation corresponded, in point of content also, to this external schema. Cie set the concept as the goal ® of scientific work over against the sin; single ideas given by individual perception. When therefore Socrates in general~ aimed-at definition, he came into contact with the efforts of the Sophists * who had busied themselves in fixing the meanings of words. But he on his part went much deeper, in the hope of grasping>0' C3 the essence of fact and the law governing single cases and >’ relationships by the application of this universal principle. So Pp h. In making the answer to the particular question from which the conversation proceeded depend ® on the general defini- tion to be sought, he was making man conscious of the law of logical dependence of the particulars upon the universal, and exalting that law to the principle of the scientific methd,) In the search for universal concepts Socrates still 1 Plato, Rep., I. 337 a. 2 With reference to the profession of his mother; Plato, Thecet., 149 f. 8 Arist. Met., XII. 4, 1078b, 17: rd épitecOa xa@ddov. The tech- nical expression for the concept is, in this connection, Adyos. * Particularly with Prodicus, with whom his relations were uniformly friendly. 5 Xen. Mem., IV. 13. 130 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY. remained strongly fixed in the habits of naive reflection. For the inductive procedure, the introduction of which is accredited to him,! consisted in the comparison of arbitra- rily collated particular cases, by means of which, however, a complete induction could not be guaranteed. But, never- theless, the Socratic method was a distinct advance over the entirely unmethodical generalizations, which earlier think- ers had drawn from single observations or thought motifs, It began, moreover, to set a methodical treatment in the place of ingenious fancies. P. J. Ditges, Die epagogische Methode des 8S. (Cologne, 1864); J. J. Guttmann, Ueber den wissenschafilichen Stand- punkt des S. (Brieg, 1881). Examples of the Socratic method are to be found in the Memorabilia of Xenophon and in most of the dialogues of Plato. Socrates did not advance to a defi- nite formulation of methodical principles, but his entire activity has given them distinctly the character of an inspired insight. The realm to which Socrates applied this method of the inductive definition of concepts included — as in the case of the Sophists — essentially the problems of human life. For, as his search for conceptual truth was rooted in the strength of his moral conviction, science and moral self- culture were to him in the last instance identical. The universally valid truth, which he said was to be found by means of conversation, is the clearness and certainty of moral consciousness. The limitation of philosophy to ethics, and on the other hand the establishment of scientific ethics, passed even in antiquity as the essential characteristic of the Socratic teaching. (See Zeller, Il*. 132 f.). Neither the poetic license, with which Aristophanes (in the Clouds) made of him a star-gazer, nor the passages in the later Platonic dialogues (Phe@do and Philebus), in which a teleological nature-philosophy is put into his mouth, nor, finally, the very homely utilitarian theory, presumably after- ward revised ? by the Stoics, which the Memorabilia makes him 1 Arist. Met., lc. 2 See A. Krohn, Xen. u. Soc. (Halle, 1874). THE GREEK ENLIGHTENMENT. 131 develop, — none of these can have weight against-the very defi- nite expressions of Xenophon (M@em., I. 1,11) and Aristotle (Met., I. 6, 987 b, 2). On the other hand, his aversion to natural science was not in the spirit of Skepticism, but due to the deficiency of science in ethical value. A universal faith in the teleological arrangement of the world and in a Providence over mankind remained side by side with this aversion. See con- clusion in Plato’s 4pology, in Euthyphro, etc. In this specific ethical turn, Socrates followed, however, a psychological principle, which expresses the rationalistic character of the Enlightenment in its purity. J¢ ts the formula of the identity of virtue and knowledge In the complicated relationships of civilized life the habitual ob- servance of national conventions had become insufficient. In the confusion of public life, where one thing was com- mended here, another there, every one felt that he needed knowledge and judgment for making correct decisions. In the increasing competition in civilization the well-in- formed? man proved himself to be the abler in all depart- ments of life. Socrates expressed himself most clearly as to this condition, when he, applying the case to morals, declared that true virtue consists in knowing, and that right knowing leads always of itself to right acting. Thereby to know the Good was elevated to the essence of morality and reflection to the principle of living. (Philosophy, as Socrates understood it, was the independent meditation of reasoning man upon that law of goodness valid for all alike. | Knowledge is a moral possession, and the common striving for it he designated as a process of mutual help- fulness? under the name épws. On the other hand, this 1 See Xen. Mem., III. 9, 4. 2 Ibid., 9, 10 ff. 8 This is the Socratic concept cf %pws, whose extreme importance appears in the fact that not only Plato and Xenophon, but also other friends within the Socratic circle, have written about it. Compare Brandis, Handbuch, II. 1, 64. 132 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY. point of view involved a deterministic and intellectual con- ception of the will, which makes moral excellence depend- ent upon intellectual culture, and in general the decision of will exclusively dependent on the clearness and ripeness of the insight. When he asserted that all evil action pro- ceeds only out of a deficient insight,’ this is the same as proclaiming entirely in the spirit of the Enlightenment that knowledge is the ethical ideal. For Socrates all other virtues accord with the fundamental virtue, éwiotnun? and possessing this all the others are attainable and teachable. The process begun at the time of the Seven Wise Men was completed in these definitions of Socrates ; and the norms of universal consciousness, after they had for a time been imperilled by individual criticism, during the wild anarchy of opinions were again found by rational re- flection and by the recognition of the universal validity therein involved. The question of the teachableness of virtue is treated in a most engaging dialectic in the dialogue Protagoras, while the other dialogues of Plato’s earliest period have for their common theme the reduction of the single virtues to the fundamental virtue of knowledge. These are Huthyphro, Laches, Charmides, and Lysis. Compare F. Dittrich, De S. sententia virtutem esse seientiam (Braunsberg, 1868) and particularly T. Wildauer, Die Psychologie des Willens bet Sokrates, Platon und Aris- toteles, Part I. (Innsbruck, 1877). Besides, the determinism of Socrates stands in a close relation to his eudszemonism (see below). For the proposition that no one will freely do wrong is founded upon the same basis with that proposition that if one has recognized what is good for him it would be impossible for him to choose the opposite against his own interest. Com- pare Xen. Mem., 1V. 6, 6; Arist. Magn. Moral., I. 9, 1187 a, 17. In the realm of ethics, moreover, Socrates stopped at this most general suggestion without developing syste- 1 Xen. Mem, ITI. 9. 2 In Xenophon one still finds the word codia for this ; see Mem., ITf. 9. THE GREEK ENLIGHTENMENT. 133 matically that kind of knowing ( Wissen) in which vir- tue was said to consist. For the distinctive trait of the activity of Socrates was that he never lost sight of the given conditions. Therefore the question, “ What then is the Good?” always became the question as to what is the Good in a particular respect and for a particular indi- vidual ;1 and the answer was always found in the suitable, in that which perfectly satisfies the striving of man and makes him happy. According to the grosser? interpreta- tion of Xenophon, Socrates’ ethical theory was utilitarian- ism, and the value of virtue founded on knowing sank to the prudential cleverness of acting in every case according to correct knowledge (Hrkenntnis) of expediency. The finer presentation of Plato refers, however, this dpPéAiuov, which is assumed as identical with caddy and dyaGov, to the health of the soul,*? to its furtherance toward a true state of perfection. In both cases, nevertheless, intellectual virtue is identified with happiness. Right action, toward which insight guides, makes man happy. The fundamental conception of ethics in Socrates is thoroughly eudemonis- tic, and ancient philosophy did not pass beyond this point. Compare M. Heinze, Der Huddmonismus in der griech. Philos. (Leipzig, 1883) ; Zeller, 114. 149 f. In all particulars the Socratic morals remained essentially within the compass of Greek social-consciousness.6 It sought to find a basis in the 1 Mem., IIT. 8. 2 In whose writings, in one passage, it would appear that Socrates agreed in morals with the relativism of the Sophists: Mem., HI. 8, mdvra dyaOa kai kadd eort mpos & dv eb exp, axa S€ kal aloypad mpos 4 dv Kaka@s. * Particularly note the representation of the Phedo. 4 Xen. Mem., IV. 1, 2. 5 To be excepted is only the prohibition of doing evil to an enemy. If here the contradiction between Plato’s and Xenophon’s representa- tions is irreconcilable, we are inclined to rezard Plato’s report as the true one: for the Crito, which treats this prohibition as one already long 134 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY. ‘reverent recognition of divine law and established usage. Par ticularly Socrates himself, the model of noble and pure morals, gave high place to civic virtue, to submission to the laws of the state. In the state, however, he would have not the masses, but the good and intelligent, rule (Xen. Mem., IIL.9, 10). Socrates personally supplemented his indifference to metaphysical and physical theories by a deep and religious piety, which led him to believe in the rule of the divine es- sence in nature and in human life. He likewise supple- mented the rationalistic one-sidedness of his ethics by his unswerving faith in obedience to the divine voice, which he believed he heard in himself as dacudvov. Likewise in the development of: this thought, Xenophon, pro- vided the extant form of the Memorabilia comes from him, stood at the point of view of commonplace utility, while Plato’s Apology represents faith in Providence in a high ethical light. In Socrates the rejection of nature knowledge comes about from the fact that such knowledge contains trifles that waste our time.’ On the other hand, there was the interest of piety, which led ? him to require a teleological view of the cosmos. It is im- probable that he gave an‘exhaustive development of it, because (Mem., J. 4, and IV. 3) Socrates usually was most prudently reserved on such questions. Even Monotheism he by no means emphasized sharply. He speaks mostly of ‘‘ the Gods,” both in Xenophon and Plato, and no enemy ever once charged him with disavowing ‘‘ the Gods.” ® Concerning the Saudvoy, compare Ueberweg, I+. 107, and Zeller, II4. 74, Regarded on the whole, the activity of Socrates, in that he set up the ideal of reason as against relativism, was an attempt to reform the life morally by means of science. The success of his teaching led among the best friends of recognized in the Socratic circle, though indeed at variance with popu- lar opinion, clearly belongs to the earliest writings of Plato. 1 Xen. Mem., I. 1, and IV. 7. 2 Ibid., I. 4, and IV, 3. ® He was reproached with introducing a new divine being, and his enemies appeared to be aiming especially at the damcnov. THE GREEK ENLIGHTENMENT. 135 the philosopher to the highest achievements of ancient culture. The principle of reflective introspection, however, which was thus victoriously awakened, and the enthusiasm with which Socrates turned his meditations from the charm of external existence to the value of the intellectual life, were in the Grecian world a new and strange thing. At this point of view the philosophy embodied by him detached itself from its background of culture and took other shape. 28. Under the name ‘Socratics” a number of schools are usually grouped, which, founded by men of more or less close association with Socrates, stepped forth, directly after his death, with opinions that belonged in their direction and content entirely to the Greek Enlightenment. If we look, nevertheless, more closely, we see that these men and their teaching have a much nearer relationship to the Sophists 1 than to Socrates; and that, especially in the development of these schools, the “Socratic element,” which to some degree was still present in Euclid, Antisthenes, and Aris- tippus, vanishes more and more from sight. These so- called “Socratic schools” should rather be viewed as branches of Sophism which were touched by the Socratic spirit. There were four such schools: the Megarian and the Elean-Eretrian, the Cynic and the Cyrenaic. Among these the Cynics stand nearest to Socrates. K. F. Hermann, Die philos. Stellung der dlteren Sokratiker u. threr Schulen (in Ges. Abhandl., Gottingen, 1849, p. 227 f.) ; Th. Ziegler, Gesch. d. Ethik, I. 145. The founder of the Megarian school, Euclid, believed in his ability to give content to the Eleatic concept of Being, by identifying it with the Socratic concept of the Good. Yet no victory over the abstract sterility of the Parme- nidean principle was won by this method. For even if 1 Aristotle calls (Me?., II. 2, 996 a, 33), for example, Aristippus a Sophist, and with justice. 136 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY. Euclid defined! the Good as the one ever immutable? Being, which is given? different names by men; even if he characterized the different virtues only as the changing names of the one unchangeable virtue, that is, of knowing, which was thus identified with Being as among the Eleatics ; even if he thereby refused‘ reality to all concepts other than to that of the Good; — nevertheless all this led neither to the construction of an ethics nor to an enrich- ment of theoretical knowledge, but gave evidence of a con- tinuation of unfruitful dialectic in the direction of Eleatic Sophistry. The Megarians, therefore, accomplished noth- ing in the realm of ethics. The only one of them to whom political teachings are ascribed was Stelpo, the later head of the school, who, however, in this respect had entirely adopted the views of the Cynics. In metaphysics the Megarians were satisfied with the assertion of the unity of that which possesses Being, and with an indirect proof of that assertion resembling the Eleatic argumentations. In this spirit Diodorus Cronus added ® to the arguments of Zeno new ones which were indeed less significant and far more captious. In these the impossibility of constructing a continuum out of a sum of discrete quantities again played the chief role. There was a similar tendency mani- fested in the investigations of the Megarians concerning the categories of modality. For the assertion that only the actual® is possible, and the famous proof (xupsetwv) 7 of Diodorus Cronus —that the unactual, which has demon- 1 Diog. Laert., VII. 161. 2 Cicero, Acad., II. 42, 129. 8 Diog. Laert , IT. 106. 4 Ibid.: compare Euseb. Prep. ev., XIV. 17. 5 Preserved in Sext. Emp. Adv. math., X. 85 f. ® Arist. Met., VIII. 8, 1046 b, 29. ™ Compare Cicero, De fato, 6,12f. Later philosophers, particularly Chrysippus, have definitely declared their positions with reference to this argument. THE GREEK ENLIGHTENMENT. 137 strated itself through its unactuality to be impossible, may not be called possible — point only in a rather abstract way to the refutation of Becoming and change.! Compare F. Deycks, Die Megaricorum doctrina (Bonn, 1827) ; Henne, Ecole de Mégare (Paris, 1843); Mallet, His- toire de Pécole de Mégare et des écoles d'Elis et d’ Erétrie (Paris, 1845). We can only speak in general of the dates of the life of Euclid of Megara, one of the oldest and truest friends that, Socrates had. He was not much younger than Socrates, yet he considerably outlived him, and opened after the death of the master his hospitable house to his friends. About this time a school formed itself around him, and it appears to have re- mained intact through the fourth century. Of the most of those who are mentioned as adherents of this school, we know only the names. Particulars are reported only of Eubulides of Miletus, the teacher of Demosthenes, of Diodorus Cronus, of Jasus in Caria (d. 307), and especially of Stilpo, who was a native of Megara (Diog. Laert., 11. 113 f.). Stilpo lived from 380 to 300, and aroused universal admiration by his lectures. He linked the Megarian dialectics to the Cynic ethics, and deci- sively influenced thereby his chief pupil, Zeno, the founder of Stoicism. His younger contemporary was Alexinus of Elis. The most important controversial question arising in refer- ence to the Megarian school concerns the hypothesis set up by Schleiermacher (in his translation of Plato, V. 2, 140 f.) and opposed by Ritter (Ueber d. Philos. der meg. Schule, Rhein. Mus., 1828) and Mallet (loc. cit. XXXIV. f.), accepted by most others, including Brandis and Prantl, and defended by Zeller (14. 215 f.). This hypothesis is to the effect that the represen- tation of the theory of Ideas in the dialogue, the Sophist (246 b, 248 f.), refers to the Megarians. If one is convinced that this dialogue is genuinely Platonic, it is difficult to provide for this theory of Ideas. For to presuppose any kind of an other- wise unknown school (Ritter) as the author of so significant a 1 Since Aristotle cites the proposition as Megarian, that only the actual is the possible, it can scarcely have arisen from the polemic against the Aristotelian categories dvvayis and évépyera. But possibly the later Megarians, for example Diodorus, developed it in this direction. Compare Hartenstein, Ueber die Bedeutung der megarischen Schule fir die Geschichte der metaphysischen Probleme (in Hist. philos. Abhand- lungen, 127 f.). 138 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY. system as that of the dowpara eidy, is forbidden because Aristotle (Met., I. 6; Nic. Hth., I. 4) designated Plato distinctly as the inventor of the same. It is certainly very far from having any place in the Socratic schools. But the teaching is even as little consistent with what has been at other times confidently ascribed to the Megarians as with the teaching of any one of the other schools. In no place is there a single indication of it. It stands in so abrupt opposition especially to the abstract theory of Being of the Megarians, that we do not avoid the difficulty by taking for granted a gradual development within the school.* On the other hand, it may be shown that the description? which the dialogue, the SopAist, gives of this theory of Ideas, agrees completely and even verbally with that phase of the Platonic philosophy expressed in the Sympostum.? There is, accordingly, nothing left but either accept Plato as opposed to an earlier phase of his own teaching and its ido, or to find the author of this criticism of the Platonic philosophy in an Eleatic contemporary of Plato. (For details, see Ch. V.) In neither case can the theory of Ideas treated in the passage in the Sophist, nor the developed theory of knowledge connected closely with it and completely Platonic in character, be ascribed to the Megarians. This theory in the Sophist amounts to a sensuous knowledge of yéveous, or a knowledge of the corporeal world plus a conceptual knowledge of otcia, which is a knowl edge of the non-corporeal Ideas. The only remaining feature worthy of comment in regard to the Megarian school is its development of the Sophistic art of Eristic. Its abstract theory of unity involved a skepticism regarding all concrete knowledge and a nega- tive trend in its instruction. The prominent fact in re- 1 Zeller seems to believe (II*. 261) that the Euclidean theory of Ideas was given up in the course of the development of the school to satisfy the theory of unity. Since the latter theory had been given from the very beginning in the form of Eleaticism there must then be expected conversely a gradual division of the Eleatic One into a plural- ity of Ideas and this is precisely what Plato accomplished. 2 See E. Appel, Arch. f. Gesch. d. Ph., V. 55 £. 8 In this connection there is hardly an allusion to Ideas as causes of the phenomenal world. Zeller, [4. 316. The ovoia as airia is first intro- duced in the Phedo, Philebus, and the latter parts of the Republic. See Ch. V. THE GREEK ENLIGHTENMENT. 139 spect to Euclid is that he in polemics followed the method! of neglecting proofs and even premises, and leaped directly to the conclusion by means of reductio ad absurdum. Stilpo accepted the Sophistic-Cynic assertion, that according to the law of identity a predicate different from the subject cannot be ascribed to the subject. The younger members, Kubulides and Alexinus,? got their notoriety by inventing the so-called “ catches.” These are questions put in such a way that no one of the possible disjunctive answers can be given without involving a contradiction. See Prantl, Gesch. der Logik, I. 33 f.; Diog. Laert., II. 168, enumerates seven of these ‘* catches,” —the Liar, then three practically identical ones, the Concealed, the Disguised, and the Hlectra, and further the Horned Man, and finally the Heap (Sorites) and the Bald-head, which positively and negatively suggest the acervus of Zeno (§ 20). As was the case with the Sophistic witticisms, these were in the main reducible to verbal ambiguities. The lively interest that antiquity had in them was almost wholly pathological. Still less significant was the Elean-Eretrian school, which was founded by Phedo, Socrates’ favorite scholar, in his native city Elis. Later it was transferred by Menedemus to his home, Eretria, where it died out about the beginning of the third century. It appears to have taken a similar line of development as the Megarian school and Phedo agreed with Euclid? in all essentials. Menedemus, who received instruction in the Academy and from Stilpo, co- operated with Stilpo in turning the school toward Cynic ethics. Both schools merged finally, like the Cynic, in the Stoa. 1 Diog. Laert., II. 107. 2 Whose name was facetiously perverted into ’Edeyfivos: Diog. Laert., II. 109. , 8 Presumably he had received powerful influence from Euclid dur ing his stay in Megara. 140 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY. Compare Mallet (see above); L. Preller, Phadon’s Lebens- schicksale und Schriften (Ersch und Gruber, III. 21, 357 f.) ; v. Wilamowitz-Mollendorf (Hermes, 1879). Pheedo, when very young, was taken into captivity by the Athe- nians, and not long before Socrates’ death he was, at the insti- gation of Socrates, freed from slavery by one of his friends. The genuineness of the dialogues ascribed to him was early very much in doubt. At any rate, as little from the literary activity of this school is preserved as from that of the Megarians. Menedemus, who is said to have died soon after 271 at the age of seventy-four, had (Diog. Laert., II. 125 f.) raised himself from a very low position to one of considerable authority. It is now impossible to determine whether his apparently loose and transitory relation to the Academy was a fact. Only the names of the other members of the school are preserved. 29. Notably more important are the two schools existing immediately after Socrates and not uninfluenced by his ethical doctrine. In these, the Cynic and Cyrenaic, the opposition as to both moral and social conceptions of life took definite form. They had in common an indifference for theoretic science and a desire to concentrate philosophy upon the art of living. Common also was the origin of their philosophy from the Sophistic circle ; and they found partial support in the formulations of Socrates. They were, however, diametrically opposed in their conception of the place of man and his relation to society. This re- mained a typical opposition for the whole ancient world. Both theories as the result of the cultural and philosoph- ical impulse given by the Sophists reveal the disposition of the Grecian world toward the value which civilization possesses in its control of individual impulses. This com- mon problem put the same limits upon their endeavors in spite of their different conclusions. The Cynic school was called into life by Antisthenes of Athens, and maintained its popularity on account of the original character, Diogenes of Sinope. Among its more distant followers may be named Crates of Thebes, his wife Hipparchia, and her brother Metrocles. THE GREEK ENLIGHTENMENT. 141 Antisthenes, born about 440, was not a full-blooded Athenian. He had entered the Sophistic profession of teaching as the pupil of Gorgias, before he came under the influence of Socrates, whose active admirer he became. After the death of Socrates he founded a school in the gymnasium Cynosarges, which he administered for quite a time. Of his numerous writings (Diog. Laert., VI. 15 -f.) only a few fragments are preserved, — collected by A. W. Winckelmann (Zurich, 1842). Compare Chappuis, Antjsthéne (Paris, 1854); K. Barlen, Antisthenes u. Platon (Neuwied, 1891); K. Urban, Ueber die Erudhnungen der Philos. des Antisthenes in den platonischen Schriften (Konigsberg, 1882); F. Dimmler, Antisthenica (Halle, 1882) and Akademika (Giessen, 1889); E. Norden, Beitrdge z. Gesch. d.gr. Ph., 1-4. Diogenes, the Swxpdrys pawdpevos, fled as a counterfeiter from his home to Athens, and ornamented his proletariat and queer existence with the wisdom of Antisthenes. He claimed to put the theory of his teacher consistently into practice. In old age he lived as tutor in the house of Xeniades in Corinth, and died there in 823. Compare K. W. Gdttling, Diogenes der Kyniker oder d. Phil. des gr. Proletariats ( Geschich. Abhandl., 1. 251f.) ; K. Steinhart (Zrsch u. Gruber, I. 25, 301 f.) Crates of Thebes, nearly contemporary of Stilpo, is said to have given away his property in order to dedicate himself to the Cynic life. His rich and nobly connected wife followed him into a beggar’s existence. Anecdotes only are preserved concerning his brother-in-law, Metrocles. Cynicism continued later as a popular moralizing instruction ; for example in Teles, whom v. Wilamowitz-Méllendorf treats (PAilol. Untersuchungen, IV. 292 f.), and whose fragments have been published by O. Hense (Freiburg, 1889). Later do we find Cynicism in Bion of Borysthenes, whose sermons greatly influenced later literature (Horace), as upon the other hand the satires of the Pheenician Menippus, which breathe the Cynic spirit, influenced Varro. See Zeller, Il°. 246, 3. As only the Good was Being for the Megarians, for the Cynics virtue appeared to be the only legitimate con- tent and purpose of life. With similar Eleatic one-sided- ness they remained averse to all other ideals and disdain- ful of them. They taught indeed, like Socrates, that virtue consists in knowing, and yet they emphasized the practical 1 Compare R. Heinze, De Horatio Bionis imitatore (Bonn, 1889). 142 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY. side, that is, right action, and especially the consistent carrying out of moral principles! in life. They like- wise attributed only so much value, therefore, to scien- tific investigations as those investigations serve ethical purposes. , It is to be added that in its epistemology also this school stood entirely upon the ground of Sophistic skepticism. It indeed sounds to some degree Socratic for Antisthenes to demand ? the explanation of the permanent essence of things by definition. Yet in his development of this pos- tulate he fell back upon the opinion of Gorgias that of no subject can an attribute differing in any way from it be predicated. He made it equivalent to the statement that only identical judgments are possible? Accordingly only the composite are definable ;* all simple things, on the other hand, can be indicated ® only by their peculiar individual names, which, however, do not explain the essence of the fact itself. Thus their theory of knowledge reduced itself to bare skepticism ; and it also manifested itself in Antis- thenes adopting the Sophistic teaching that a contradic- tion is wholly impossible.® 1 Even in the character of Antisthenes this consistency, this serious and strict adherence to principles, was the central point. Diogenes intended assuredly to outdo him in this respect. 2 To him belongs the definition Aoyos éariv 6 76 ri Hy } Core OnAGY. ® That the place in the Sophist, 251 b, refers to Antisthenes, Aristotle teaches in Metaphysics, 1V. 29, 1024 b, 32. * Compare Aristotle, ibid., VII. 8, 1043 b, 24. 5 The logically central truth of the Cynic teaching appears in the Platonic statement (Theet., 201 f.). This truth is that the ultimate terms (ra mpéra) by which all else may be defined are themselves not definable or reducible to something else. This opinion is closely joined with that which looks upon these last elements of concepts as the arotxyeia, by which all things are really constituted. This is a view which in a certain sense sounds like the homoiomeriai of Anaxagoras, and also like the Platonic theory of Ideas, 6 Arist. Met., IV. 29, 1024 b, 34. THE GREEK ENLIGHTENMENT 143 This purely Sophistic limitation of knowledge to nomenclature had taken on as a most obvious nominalism a distinct polemical tendency against the theory of Ideas. The old tradition placed in the mouths of Antisthenes and Diogenes rough and coarse ridicule of the Platonic theory (rpdmeluv bpd, tpamelornta 3’ odx 6p, Diog. Laert., VI. 53; compare Schol. in Arist., 66 b, 45, etc.; Zeller, II®. 255); for these leaders of the Cynics only single things existed in natura rerum. The class concepts are only names without content. At the same time it is evident that, since the essence of a thing did not seem to them logically determinable, they claimed that it was producible only in sense perception. Thus they fell into the coarse materialism which regards a thing as actual only as the thing can be held in the hand. Presumably this fact is meant in the Sophist, 246 a; Theetetus, 155 e, Phado, 79 f. Compare Natorp, Forschungen, 198 f. So much the more was the science of these men limited to their theoretically meagre doctrine of virtue. Virtue, and it alone, is sufficient to satisfy all strivings for happi- ness. Virtue is not only the highest, but the only good, — the only certain means of being happy. Over against this spiritual and therefore sure possession, which is protected against all the changes of the fateful world, the Cynics despised all that men otherwise held dear. Virtue alone is of worth; wickedness alone is to be shunned ; all else is indifferent (ddudpopov).! From this principle they taught the contempt of riches and luxury, of fame and honor, of sense-pleasure and sense-pain. But with this radical con- sistency, which ever grew sharper with them, they also despised all the joy and beauty of life, all shame and con- ~ yentionality, family and country. The obtrusive moralization of these philosophical beggars appears mainly in their coarse witticisms; and very many anec- dotes relate to Diogenes. There is very little of serious inves- tigation in their moralizing. Antisthenes appears to assert the worthlessness of pleasure, perhaps against Aristippus, and to have sought to demonstrate that man with such a conviction, even if it be not entirely right, would be proof against the 1 Diog. Laert., VI. 105. 144 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY slavery of sense pleasure.! In Diogenes this disgust of all external goods grew to the philosophical grim humor of a prole- tarian, who has staked bis cause on nothing. Irrespective of the mental culture to which, so far as it concerns virtue, he ascribed some worth,? he contended against all the devices of civilization as superfluous, foolish, and dangerous to virtue. Most dubious in all this was the shamelessness of which the Cynics were guilty, and their intentional disregard of all the con- ventions of sexual relations; similar too was their indifference to the family life and to the state. For the cosmopolitanism in which Diogenes took pride* had not the positive content of a universal human ideal, but sought only to free the individual from every limitation imposed upon him by civilization. In particular, the Cynics fought against slavery as unnatural and unjust, just as already the Sophists had fought. On the other hand, it must not remain unnoticed that Antisthenes,® in defiance of the judgment of Greek society, declared that work is a good. Cynicism finally reckoned also religion among the adiadopa. All mythical ideas and religious ceremonies fall under the class of the conventionally determined, the unnatural, and are excusable only because they may be regarded as allegorical expressions of moral concepts. Positively the Cynics represented an abstract monotheism which finds in virtue the true worship of God. The fundamental purpose of Cynicism in all these deter- minations is to make man entirely independent. The wise man to whom virtue, once gained§ is a permanent’ pos- session, stands in his complete self-sufficiency ® over against 1 See Arist. Eth. Nic., X. 1, 1172 a, 31; on the contrary, Plato (Phileb., 44 b) can hardly be regarded as referring to Antisthenes (Zeller, IT4. 308, 1). It is probable that places like the Republic, 588 f., refer to Democritus. See below, § 33 and § 31. 2 Diog. Laert., VI. 68, and elsewhere, 3 From Diogenes on, the Cynics had wives -and children in common. (Ibid., 72.) This is only one of the instances that they manifested of a levelling radicalism (in distinction from Plato). 4 Loc. cit. 68: see ibid., 11, 38, 72, 98. 5 Ibid., 2. ® Tt can also be teachable, but more through practice than through scientific instruction. Jbid., 105 f., 70. 7 Xen. Mem., 1, 2, 19. 8 Diog. Laert., VI. 11 f. THE GREEK ENLIGHTENMENT 145 the great mass of fools. His reward is the perfect inde- pendence in which he is equal! to the undesiring gods. In order to be as independent of external goods as possible, he reduces his needs to those most external. The less one needs, the happier? one is. ‘The Cynic Wise Man feels himself free from society also; he sees through its preju- dices; he despises? its talk; its laws and its conventions do not bind him. The independent lordship of the vir- tuous Wise Man does not need civilization and casts it aside. (The Sophistic opposition of vcs and vopos is constructed into a principle, and all human limitation by statute is unnatural, superfluous, and in part corrupting. From the midst of the fulness and beauty of Greek civiliza- tion, the Cynic preaches the return to a state of nature which would avoid all the dangers of civilization indeed, but would forfeit all its blessings. ’ 30. The joyous wisdom of the life of the Cyrenaics formed the completest antithesis to the morose seriousness of the virtue of the Cynics. The leader of this school was Aristippus of Cyrene, a man of the world, who once belonged to the Socratic circle, but at other times led a wandering life as a Sophist. Through his daughter Arete his conception of life passed down to his grandson, the younger Aristippus. Soon after this the school branched out with the special interpretations which men like Theodorus the atheist, Anniceris, and Hegesias gave to the Aristippian principle. Among later representatives Euemerus is to be mentioned. 1 Diog. Laert., VI. 51. ? See the self-description of Antisthenes in Xenophon’s Symposium, 4, 34f. In this respect Cynicism showed that Eudamonism is logically absence of need. From the eudemonistic point of view, then, the goal is the renunciation and suppression of all avoidable desire. 8 Thus Diogenes accepted the designation of xiwv, which was origi- nally a witticism in reference to the seat of the school, the gymnasium, Cynosargus. 10 146 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY The years of the birth and death of Aristippus cannot be very exactly determined ; his life included from thirty to forty years in the fifth and fourth centuries (435-360). When he was young he was influenced to come to Athens by the fame of Socrates, and often during the course of his life did he return to that city. That he for some time lived in Syracuse in the court of the older and younger Dionysius, that he probably met Plato there, cannot well be doubted. The founding of his school in his native city, the rich and luxurious Cyrene, occurred prob- ably at the end of his life, since all the known adherents to the school were considerably younger than he. Compare H. vy. Stein, De vita Aristippi (Gottingen, 1855), also his Geschichte des Platonismus, IL. 60f. The technical development of the theory } seems to have been completed by the grandson (yrpodisaxros), of whom nothing further is known. Theodorus was driven out of his home, Cyrene, soon after the death of Alexander the Great. He lived in exile for some time in Athens and at the court of Egypt, but he returned finally to Cyrene. Anniceris and Hegesias (eo. Odvaros) were contemporaries of Ptolemeus Lagi. Hegesias wrote a treatise the title of which Cicero mentioned as ’Azoxap- tepov ( Tusc., I. 34, 84). Euemerus, probably of Messene (about 300), set his views forth in what were well known to antiquity as the lepa dvaypady. Compare O. Sieroca, De Huemerus (Konigs- berg, 1869). The smaller fragments are in Mullach, II. 397f. Compare J. F, Thrige, Res Cyrenesium (Copenhagen, 1878); A. Wendt, De philos. Cyrenaica (Gottingen, 1841); Wieland (Aristip., 4 vols., Leipzig, 1800f) also gives a graceful and expert exposition. In his theory of life, Aristippus followed closely the teaching of Protagoras,? just as Antisthenes followed the direction of Gorgias. Indeed he developed the relativism of the Protagorean theory of perception to a remarkably valuable psychology of the sense feelings. Sense percep- tion instructs us only as to our own states (7rd0m),? and is 1 According to Eusebius, Prep. ev., XIV. 18, 31. Compare, besides, Zeller, II*, 344. 2 Which was communicated to him perhaps by his fellow-citizen, the mathematician Theodorus (compare Plato, Theetetus). 8 Sext. Emp. Adv. math., VII. 191 f. THE GREEK ENLIGHTENMENT 147 not concerned with the causes of those states (Ta qezozy- xoTa Ta wd0n). The causes are not recognizable; our knowledge directs itself only to the changes of our own essence, and these alone concern us. Sensations, since they are a consciousness of our own condition, are always true.1 In this spirit the Cyrenaics assumed an attitude of skeptical indifference to natural science. They followed Protagoras in the individualistic turn of this theory when they asserted that the individual knows only his own sensations, and common nomenclature is no guarantee of similarity in the content of the thought. That these epistemological investigations of the school of Aristippus were used for a basis of their ethics but did not evoke their ethics, is proved for the most part by the subordinate posi- tion which they received in the later systematizations of the school. According to Sextus Empiricus (Adv. math., VII. 11), the treatment at this time was divided into five parts: concern- ing good and evil; concerning the states of the soul (rd@n) ; concerning actions; concerning external causes; and, finally, concerning the criteria of truth (zicres). However, the fundamental problem of the Cyrenaics (as of the Cynics) was that concerning the real happiness of man, and they emphasized simply the included moment of pleasure or displeasure in those states of mind to which knowledge is limited. As, however, Protagoras had re- ferred the theoretic content of perception to differing cor- poreal motions, the Cyrenaics sought to derive also the affective tone of the same from the different states of motion of him perceiving. Gentle motion (Acia Kivnots) corresponds to pleasure (jSov7}), violent (tpaxeta) to dis- 1 Sext. Emp. Adv. math., VII. 191f.; farther, Diog. Laert., II. 92. 2 Sext. Emp. op. cit. 195. 8 Eusebius, loc. cit.; Diog. Laert , IT. 86f. Likewise the exposition in the Philebus, 42 f., which brings this teaching directly into connection with the mdvra fei, presumably refers to Aristippus. Compare Zeller, IIt, 352. ; 148 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY pleasure (aévos), rest from motion to absence of pleasure and pain (dydovia kai amovia), Since now these three possibilities include the whole range of stimuli, there are only two, perhaps three 7d@y: pleasant (75éa), unpleasant (adyewva), and the states of indifference between them (7a peraéd).1 Since, however, among these three possible states, pleasure alone is worth striving for, 7d0v7 is the only goal of the will (7éAos), and accordingly is happiness or the Good itself. Whatever gives pleasure is good. Whatever creates displeasure is bad. All else is indif- ferent. The question concerning the content of the concept of the Good, which was not really answered by Socrates, was answered by these Hedonists, in that they declared pleasure to be this content, and indeed all pleasures, whatever their occasion,” to be indistinguishable. By this only the single momentary state of pleasure is meant. The highest, the only good, for these Hedonists was the enjoyment of the moment.? From these presuppositions the Hedonists concluded, with entire correctness, that the distinction of value between single feelings of pleasure is determined not by the content or the cause, but only by the intensity of the feelings. They asserted that the degree of intensity of the bodily feelings is greater than that of the spiritual feelings.* ‘The later Cyrenaics, particularly Theodorus,® came therefore to the conclusion that the Wise Man need not regard himself restricted by law, convention, or indeed religious scruples, but he should so use things as to serve his pleasure best. Here, again, the Sophistic antithesis between vonos and pious * is repeated, and the natural individual pleasur- able feeling is taken as the absolute motive of action. Still more pronounced than in the degenerate phases of Cynicism appeared here the egoistic, naturalistic, and individualistic trait which is basal in the common problem of both theories. On the other 1 Sext. Emp. op. cit. 199. 2 Plato, Philebus, 12d. 5 See A. Lange, Gesch. des Mater., p. 37, 2 ed. 4 Diog. Laert., II. 90. 5 Ibid., 99. ® See ibid., 93. THE GREEK ENLIGHTENMENT 149 hand, Anniceris? sought later to temper this radicalism, and to ennoble the desire for pleasure by emphasizing the enjoyment of friendship, of family life, and of social organization as more valuable. At the same time he did not lose sight of the egoistic fundamental principle, but only carefully refined it. With this turn in its course, however, the Cyrenaic. philosophy merged into Epicurean hedonism. Virtue was, accordingly, for Aristippus identical with the ability to enjoy. The utility of science consists in di- recting men to the proper satisfaction. Right enjoyment is, however, only possible through reasonable self-control (dpovnars).2 Requisite insight for this frees us from preju- dice, and teaches us how to use the goods of life in the most reasonable way. Above all else it gives to the Wise Man that security in himself by which he remains proof against weakly yielding to influences of the outer world. It teaches him, while in enjoyment, to remain master of himself and his surroundings. The problem for both Cynic and Cyrenaic was the attainment of this individual inde- pendence of the course of the world. The Cynic school sought independence in renunciation ; the Cyrenaic in lord- ship over enjoyment, and Aristippus was right when he said that the latter was more difficult and more valuable than the former? In opposition to the Cynic ideal of re- nunciation of the world, the Cyrenaic drew, as his picture of the Wise Man, that of the perfected man of the world. He is susceptible to the enjoyment of life, he knows what animal satisfactions are, and how to prize spiritual joy, riches, and honor. In elevated spirit he scrupulously makes use of men and things, but even then never forgets himself in his enjoyment. He remains lord of his appe- tites; he never wishes the impossible, and even in the few happy days of his existence he knows how to preserve vic- toriously the peace and serenity of his soul. 1 Diog. Laert., IT. 96; see Clemens Alex. Sirom., lL 417, 2 Diog. Laert., II. 91. 8 [bid., 75. 150 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY With these qualifications (reminding us of Socrates), Aris- tippus went beyond the principle of momentary enjoyment of pleasure when he, for example, explained activity as repre- hensible if, on the whole, it yields more unpleasurableness than pleasure. He recommended on this same ground that there be universal subordination to custom and law. Theodorus then went still further, and sought to find the 7éAos of mankind, not in individual satisfaction, but in serene disposition (yap). This is also already a transition to the Epicurean conception. If the principle that only educated men know how to enjoy happily verified itself in the temperament and circumstances of Aristippus, his school on the other hand drew another irresistible consequence from the hedonistic principle, viz., pessimism. If pleasure is said to give value to life, the greater part of human- ity fails of its purpose, and thus life becomes worthless. It was Hegesias who dissipated the theory of Aristippus with this doc- trine. The desire for happiness cannot be satisfied,? he taught. No insight, no opulence, protects us from the pain which nature imposes on the body. The highest we can reach and even as téAos strive for is painlessness, of which death most certainly assures us.2 The particular ethical teachings of Hegesias ap- pear more nearly like the precepts of the Cynics than like many of the expressions of Aristippus. The isolation of the individual shows itself in the hedo- nistic philosophers in their indifference to public life. Aristippus rejoiced that in his Sophistic wanderings no interest in politics infringed upon his personal: freedom.‘ Theodorus® called the world his country, and said that patriotic sacrifice was a folly which the Wise Man is above. These all are sentiments in which the Cynics and Cyre- naics agree almost verbally, and in these the decline of Greek civilization was most characteristically expressed. Religious beliefs are among the things which the Hedonists shoved one side with sceptical indifference. Freedom from religious prejudices seemed to them (Diog. Laert.., II. 91) to 1 Diog. Laert., IT. 98. 2 Tbid., 94 f. 8 The lectures of Hegesias mesovdvaros are said to have been for- bidden in Alexandria because he spoke too much cf voluntary death. Cicero, Tusc., I. 34, 83. 4 Xen. Mem., IL. 1, 8 f. § Diog. Laert., IT. 98. MATERIALISM AND IDEALISM 151 be indispensable for the Wise Man. It is not related, however, that they set up in any way in opposition to positive religion another conception. Theodorus proclaimed his atheism quite openly. Euemerus devised for an explanation of the belief in gods the theory to-day called after him, and often accepted in modern anthropology id many forms. According to this theory, the worship of the gods and heroes is developed from a rever- ence of rulers and otherwise remarkable men. (Cicero, De nat. deor., I. 42, 119; Sext. Emp. Adv. math., IX. 17.) 5. MATERIALISM AND IDEALISM. DEMOCRITUS AND PLATO. The Greek Enlightenment had impeded the progress of natural science by destroying the naive confidence of the Greek in the validity of human knowledge. Science was being utilized for practical life, and was in danger of losing its dignity and the independence which it had just achieved. On the other hand, the prevailing interest of the period in psychology had widened the circle of scientific work. Logic and ethics had thus been added to physics, — to use the classification of the ancients. Conceptions of the psychical aspects of life now stood side by side with those of its physical aspects. Man had become conscious of his share in the construction of the idea of the world. The essence of scientific research was found to consist in the examination of concepts and the fundamental proposition of science had its formulation in the law of the domina- tion of the particular by the universal. At the same time, however, the principle was seen that science could never give Satisfaction if it disregarded the connection between human life, as teleologically determined, and the objective world, The subjective moment had been sundered in its devel- opment from the objective, and consequently placed in a { 152 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY certain opposition to it. In the mutual interpenetration of the two, and in the tendency of these principles to coalesce, did Greek science find the profoundest deepening of its conceptual life and the greatest broadening of its practical life. From the Peloponnesian war ‘until Philip of Mace- don, when the political life of Greece was already approach- ing dissolution, science created its comprehensive systems, and perfected itself in its ripest undertakings, which are associated with the three names Democritus, Plato, and Aristotle. ; In the first place, as preparation for the final synthetic statement of Aristotle, appeared the two metaphysical sys- tems which expressed the greatest opposition possible within the realm of Greek thought: the materialism of Democritus and the idealism of Plato. Both appeared at that culmination point of Greek culture when the flood of Greek life was passing over to its ebb; the Democritan system was about three decades before the Platonic, and in a remarkable degree independent of it. ‘Each system developed its doctrine on a broad episte- mological basis, and each is related both positively and negatively to the Greek Enlightenment. Both were met- aphysical systems of outspoken rationalism. Hach in ‘complete exposition compassed the entire range of the scientific interest of the time. Finally, in both became defined those opposed philosophical views of the world which have not been reconciled up to the present time. But there are just as many differences as there are simi- larities. Although agreeing with Plato as to the Protago- rean theory of perception, Democritus turned back—ta the wold rationalism of the Eleatics, while Plato created a new ideal Eleaticism out of the Socratic theory of the concept. Democritus may therefore appear less progressive and less original in this respect than Plato, but we must remember that as to their general metaphysics thg principle of phys- MATERIALISM AND IDEALISM 153 ics dominated the Democritan system, and the principle of ethics the Platonic system. Ethics was incidental in the former system, while in the latter physics was the incident. In every direction the theory of Democritus shows itself to be an attempt to perfect the philosophy of nature by the aid_of the anthropological theories of the Enlightenment, while Platonism was developed as an original recreation out of the same problems. The historical fate of both these philosophies was also determined by this relationship, for the materialism of Democritus was pressed into the background from the beginning, while Plato became the determining genius of future philosophy. The great significance, which — in this exposition in distine- tion from all previous ones — is given to Democritus by making him parallel with Plato, is required solely by historical accuracy. A similar view was, for that matter, very common among the writers of antiquity. Asa matter of chronology Democritus, who lived between 430 and 860 (§ 31), was about twenty years younger than Protagoras and ten years younger than Socrates. Although he never came under the direct personal influence of the latter, yet it must be taken for granted that a man to whom in all antiquity Aristotle alone was comparable in learning, had not studied the scientific work of the Sophists in vain. To treat him entirely among the pre-Sophistic thinkers, as is customary,’ would be justified only if no traces of the influence of the En- lightenment are seen in him. We hope to show the contrary in the following exposition of his theory. But, however, this ex- position will not support the attempt to stamp the Democritan theory as a kind of Sophistry, as Schleiermacher and Ritter have made it. Thestrong bias of judgment and vagueness of treat- ment that has arisen from this interpretation is sufficiently repudiated by Zeller (I*. 842 f.). The points of view and theo- ries in Sophistie literature of which Democritus certainly did make use, were arranged by him synthetically in a unified met- aphysic, but such a metaphysic lay far outside the horizon of the Sophists. On the other hand, it is to be entirely admitted that even this materialistic metaplysic played a relatively 1 Most unfortunate in this connection is the arrangement of Schwegler- Kdstlin, where the Atomists (as also Empedocles and Anaxagoras) were treated before the Eleatics. 3 ed. p. 51 f. 154 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY unfruitfal part in rejuvenating ancient thought. For ancient thought took a Platonic tendency, and therefore we have been very imperfectly taught concerning the Democritan theory. But the case is entirely different when we consider the whole European history of science. Since the time of Galileo, Bacon, ‘and Gassendi, the Democritan teaching has become the funda- mental metaphysical assumption of modern natural science, and however sharply we may criticise this theory, we cannot deny its significance (Lange, Geschichte des Materialismus, 2 ed., I. 9 f.). Just in this, however, consisted its historical equality with Platonism. One of the most striking facts of ancient literature is the apparently perfect silence that Plato maintained concerning Democritus.!_ This was discussed many times in antiquity.? The neglect is not possibly explained as hate or contempt.* Plato was very much interested in men like the Cynics and Cyrenaics whose manner of thought must have been far less in sympathy with his own than that of Democritus, — with men whe must have appeared to him far less significant intellectually. That Plato knew nothing of Democritus is chronologically a matter of greatest improbability. If we also admit that Democritus on account of his long journeys entered * comparatively late upon his literary activity, yet the amount of his literary work requires that its beginning be set distinctly before Plato’s first works, and much the more before Plato’s later works: when Plato wrote the Symposium, Democritus was seventy-five years old. The more remarkable is it that Plato, who otherwise refers to, or at least mentions, all the other early philosophers, ignores not only Democritus, but also the Atomic teaching.® It must therefore 1 The name Democritus occurs nowhere in Plato’s writings, and there is nowhere a mention of the Atomic doctrine. When Plato speaks of materialism (compare above), he cannot possibly have Democritus in mind. 2 Diog. Laert., IX. 40. 8 As early as Aristoxenus there appears to have been related the foolish story of the designed burning of the Democritan books by Plato. Diog. Laert, op. cit. 4 The time of the composition of his puxpds didkoouos, Democritus himself (Diog. Laert., LX. 41) places at 730 years after the destruction of Troy (see Zeller, I*. 762), i. e. about 420. 5 It is significant that both the Sophist and the Parmenides — whether they be dialogues written by Plato or originating from the Pla- tonic circle —do not mention Atomism, although there were present MATERIALISM AND IDEALISM 155 be concluded, at all events, that Atomism — the writing of Leucippus being doubtful — had found no favor within the circle of Attic culture. It therefore appears conceivable that the Athenians were?’ entirely indifferent to the essentially scientific nature-investigations of Democritus at the time of the Sophists and Socrates. In Athens one worked at other things, so that Plato even later also made no mention of the writings of the great Atomist in developing his own nature-theories. ‘That he was not really acquainted with them appears to become more and more doubtful. R. Hirzel has pointed out two places (PAil., 43 f.; Rep., 583 f.) where references are made to Democritan ethics ( Untersuchungen zu Cicero's philos. Schriften, I. 141 f.). P. Natorp has assented to this (Yorschungen, 201 f.), but he has few results in following up ‘‘ the traces of Democritus in Plato’s writings” (Arch. f. Gesch. d. Philos., I. 515 f.). 1t would be more satisfactory to seek negative and positive relations to Democritus in Plato’s later metaphysic (Philebus) ? and in his philosophy of nature dependent on it (Zimaus). Compare be- low the references in the remarks to § 37. 81. Democritus of Abdera, the greatest investigator of nature in antiquity, was born about 460. He was first attracted to scientific research in the school of Leucippus, probably about the time when Protagoras, who was some twenty years his elder, also belonged to that circle. Hav- ing the liveliest sense for individual investigation in natu- ral sciences, he travelled extensively for many years. This led him through Greece, for a longer time into Egypt, and over a greater part of the Orient. The exact time of his return and the beginning of his literary activity, however, must remain a subject for conjecture, and his death can important occasions for it in the Sophist in the discussion of Being, and equal occasions in the Parmenides in the dialectic over the One and the Many. 1 In any case the expression of Democritus (Diog. Laert., X. 36) is characteristic : #AOov eis "AOnvas Kai otris pe Cyvoxev. At the time of the Sophists of the Peloponnesian war, no one, not even Socrates, had the spirit for serious investigation into the nature studies of Democritus. 2 H. Usener (Preussisches Jahrbuch, LIII. p. 16) has already given much attention to this (Philebus, 28 f.). 156 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY only be approximately set at 360. He settled in his home in Abdera. He became highly honored there, and he lived surrounded by those who prosecuted their researches under his direction. He remained distant and apart from the Attic circle of culture, in which little notice was taken of him, but he may have been in occasional intercourse with the physician Hippocrates, who spent his later years in Larissa. The life of Democritus is fixed by approximately safe data, from his own statement (Diog. Laert., IX. 41) that he was forty years younger than Anaxagoras, and from the statements he made concerning the time of the composition of his ptxpds dudxoopos (§ 30). The acquaintance of Democritus with the teaching of both his countrymen, Leucippus and Protagoras, is entirely assured by the testimony of antiquity and the character of his philosophy. He doubtless knew the Kleatics as well, and one possessed of his great erudition could hardly be ignorant of most of the other physicists. Traces here and there in his system show this. He did not accept the number theory of the Pythagoreans. The friendly relationship to the Pythago-° reans, attributed to him,' can have reference only to his mathe- matical? researches, and perhaps in part to his physiological and ethical undertakings. He also appeared to be very familiar with the theories of the younger physicists. But more impor- tant for his development of the Atomic theory were, on the one hand, his own very extensive and painstaking researches, and, on the other, the theory of perception that he obtained from Protagoras. Whether he gave much attention to the theories of the other Sophists, is still doubtful. They were entirely alien to his metaphysical and scientific tendency. But the thorough- ness of his anthropology, the significance that he laid on meta- physical and ethical questions, and the single points which he found valid in them, prove, nevertheless, that he was not unin- fluenced by the spirit of his time from which he was otherwise somewhat isolated. All these circumstances assign to him the place of one who through the subjective period of Greek science was the banner bearer of the cosmological metaphysic; and in consequence of his partial acceptance of the new elements was 1 Diog. Laert , IX. 38, 2 He prided himself particularly on his mathematical knowledge (Clemens Alex. Strom, 804 a). MATERIALISM AND IDEALISM 157 the finisher of the system. He did not receive the slightest influence from his great contemporary Socrates. The duration of his travels was at all events considerable, and his stay in Egypt alone is given as about five years. He certainly came to know the greater part of Asia.? He got nothing philosophical from his travels, especially since his thought habitually avoided everything mythical. Nevertheless, his gain in breadth of experience and in the resulis of his col- lections was only the greater. His return to Ahdera after his journeys was the beginning of his teaching, and his literary work may be dated, in view of the extent of these travels, not before 420. Presumably he continued his work into matura vetustas (Lucret. De rer. nat., III. 1039). Wis fellow-citizens honored him with the name codia. He seems to have been little interested in public affairs, and he reached the great age * of ninety or, according to some, of one hundred and nine years. His intimacy with Hippocrates (§ 39), which is not improbable in itself, has been the occasion for the forgery of letters between the two (printed in the works of Hippocrates). Geffers, Questiones democritee (Gottingen, 1829); Papen- cordt, De atomicorum doctrina (Berlin, 1732); B. ten Brink, Verschiedene Abhandlungen in the Philologus, 1851-53, 1870; L. Liard, De Democrito philosopho (Paris, 1873); A. Lange, Geschichte des Materialismus, I’. (Iserl., 1873) p. 9 f. The literary activity of Democritus was certainly very great. Even if a part of the works which Thrasyllus had arranged in fifteen tetralogies, whose titles are preserved in Diogenes Laertius (IX. 45 f.),— even if this part was wrongfully ascribed to him (for Diogenes mentions there 1 Diodor., I. 98. 2 Strabo, XV. 1, 38. 3 It is little probable that Democritus appeared publicly with his theory, especially with his discussion of definitions, before the beginning of the activity of Socrates (about the time of the beginning of the Peloponnesian war). The passage in Aristotle (De part. anim., I. 1, 642, 26), is not to be taken to mean with ctrtainty a chronological rela- tionship of the two philosophies, especially when compared with Meta- physics, XII. 4, 1078 b, 17. It signifies only that among physicists and metaphysicians Democritus first treated definition, although only ap- proximately; while the direction of the scientific thought of Socrates was turned to ethics. 4 In reference to the numerous anecdotes about the “laughing phil- osopher,” see Zeller, I*, 766. 158 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY titles of spurious writings), yet there remains a magnificent number besides. In the genuine works all departments of philosophy, mathematics, medicine, metaphysics, physics, physiology, psychology, epistemology, ethics, esthetics, and technics are represented. Since the writings themselves do not lie before us, the question of their genuineness must be decided on the score of greatest probability. The ancients were proud of the works of Democritus, — which by the way were written in Ionian dialect, — not only for the wealth of their contents, out of which Aristotle took so much for his scientific writings, but also on account of their highly perfected form. They placed him in these respects by the side of Plato + and other great litterateurs.? They admired the clearness of his exposition? and the effective power ‘ of his buoyant style. The loss of these writings, which appears to have hap- pened at some time from the third to the fifth century after Christ, was the most lamentable that has happened to the original documents of ancient philosophy. While the work of Plato has been preserved in its complete beauty, there remains of that of his great antipode only a torso that can never be completed. Compare Fr. Schleiermacher, Ueber das Verzeichnis der Schriften des Dem. bei Diog. Laert., Complete Works, Division III., Vol. TIL. p. 293 f.; Fr. Nietsche, Betirige zur Quellenkunde und Kritik des Diog. Laert., p. 22. The Fragments with annotations by Mullach, I. 330 f. (par- ticularly Berlin, 1843) ; W. Burchard, Demoerttt philosophie de. sensibus fragmenta (Minden, 1830), Fragmente der- Moral des Abderiten Democritus (Minden, 1834) ; Lortzing, Ueber a. ethi- schen Fragmente des Democritus (Berlin, 1873); W. Karl, Democritus in Cicero’s philos. Schriften (Diedenhofen, 1889). The insecurity in early time in reference to the writings of the Atomists can be seen in the fact that while Epicurus seems to have called in question the existence of Leucippus (Diog. Laert., X. 13), the school of Theophrastus ascribed the péyas didkoopos 1 Cicero, Orat., 20, 67. 2 Ibid., De orat., I. 11, 49. 8 Ibid., De divin., II. 64,133. 4 Plutarch, Ques. conv., V. 7, 6, 2. MATERIALISM AND IDEALISM 159 to Leucippus (Diog., IX. 46). Compare E. Rhode and FH. Diels, in Verhand. der Philologischen Versuchungen, 1879 and 1880, and the former in Jahrbuch f Philologie, 1881. The ethical writings, which V. Rose (De Arist. libr. ord., p. 6 f.) holds as entirely ungenuine, can be taken in part as genuine (Lortzing), especially wept evOupins. Concerning this last writing and the use Seneca made of it (De animi tranquillitate), see Hirzel (in Hermes, 1879). 382. The metaphysical principles of the Democritan teaching were given above in the Atomism of Leucippus (§ 23): space and numberless_self-moving, qualita- tively similaratgms. These atoms differ only in form and size, and in their union and separation all events are to be explained. Their _motions- were accepted as self-evident ; but the dAdrolwars, the qualitative characteristics of the per- ceived thing, and the change arising from its motion must remain as inexplicable for Leucippus as for the Eleatics. Here Democritus entered armed with the perception theory of Protagoras. The perceived qualities of things arise as products of motion. They belong not to things as such, but are only the manner in which the subject perceiving at the time carries on its representation. They are, therefore, necessary signs of the course of the world, but they do not belong to the true essence of things. In contrast to abso- lute Being, that is, atoms and space, only a relative reality belongs to the sense qualities, But this relative reality of the images of perception was supposed by Democritus to be derived from absolute reality —the Heracleitan from the Eleatic world. The realm of the relative and the changing had been known by Protagoras as the subjective, as only the world of representation. But the objective world, which the Sophist with skeptical indifference had thrust aside, re- mained still for Democritus the corporeal world in space. When he thus tried to derive the subjective process from atomic motions, Atomism became in his hands outspoken materialism. 160 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY The peculiar significance of Democritus in the history of Atomism seems to lie more in this materialism than in his com- prehensive detailed investigations. He scarcely changed history in any way in its fundamental cosmological principles; but the careful development of anthropology, which we cannot atter all ascribe to Leucippus, is clearly his chief work. The unifying principle of Atomism, as it has been devel- oped into a system by Democritus, is the complete develop- ment of the concept of mechanical necessity in nature. Democritus, as well as Leucippus, designated this as dvdy«n, or in the Heracleitan manner as ejuapuevn. Every actual event is a mechanics of atoms; possessing originally a motion peculiar to themselves, they get impact} and push by contact with one another. Thus processes of union and separation come about and these appear as the origin and destruction of things. No event is without such a mechan- ical cause.2 This is the only ground for explaining all phenomena. LEvery teleological conception is removed a limine, and however much Democritus in his physiolog referred ‘to the wonderful teleology in the structure and. functions of organisms, nevertheless he apparently saw therein little reason or cause for such teleology in point of fact. Outspoken antiteleological mechanism is obviously the prin- cipal reason for the deep chasm which continued to exist be- tween Democritus and the Attic philosophy, even at those points concerning which Aristotle recognized the value of the investi- gations of Democritus, — the chasm which divided the teaching of Democritus from that of Aristotle. This was the reason that after the victory of the Attic philosophy, Democritus lapsed into oblivion until modern science declared in favor of his principle and raised him to recognition. A highly significant moment in 1 Since empty space which has no real Being cannot be the bearer of motion, the transit of motion from one atom to another is possible only through contact, and ‘‘actio in distans ’’ is excluded. When the latter seems to occur, it is explained by emanations, as in the working of the magnet (as in Empedocles). 2 Obd€ev ypipa pdrny yiyverat, GhAd mavra ek Adyou Te Kal bn” dvdykns. MATERIALISM AND IDEALISM 161 the human apprehension of the world, and one never to be left out of account, came hereby to clear and distinct consciousness, and ruled all Atomism as a methodical postulate. The charge raised by Aristotle (Phys., II. 4, 196, 24) and before him by Plato (Phileb., 28 d) and lately repeated (Ritter), that Democri- tis made the world one of chance (durduarov, rixn) rests upon the entirely one-sided teleological use of this expression. Com- pare Windelband, Die Lehren vom Zufall, p. 56f. The Atoms are to be primarily distinguished from each other by their form (cynya or idéa), and there are an in- finite number of forms. The difference of size? is referred in part? to their difference of form.4 Motion dwells within the atoms, as a necessary irreducible function by which each atom, lawless in itself, and each one for itself, is in process of flight in empty space. Where, however, several of them meet, there arises an aggregation. The shock of meeting causes a vortex, which, when once begun, draws more atoms into itself from the space surrounding it. In this whirl Like find Like. The coarse heavy atoms collect in the centre, while the finer and more volatile are pressed to the periphery. The motion of the whole mass has a balanced revolution however. With reference to the indi- vidual objects constructed ° in this way, the order, position, 1 Jt is most characteristic that the idéa, the term that appears in Anaxagoras, equally appears in Democritus and Plato for absolute real- _ ity. Of course in a different sense Democritus wrote (Sext. Emp. Adv. ‘math., VII. 137) a separate work, repi iSeav. 2 At all events, the atoms were thought of as so small that they were imperceptible. ; 3 Yet in this the different reports do not fully agree, in that occasion- ally péyeOos and oyjya seem co-ordinated, and atoms of similar forms are assumed to be of different sizes. See Zeller, I4. 777. It is, however, not impossible that Democritus had in mind atom-complexes for such cases. 4 Which, as the only ground of difference, is often quoted. See pas- sages in Zeller, I*. 776, 1. 5 Diog. Laert., IX. 31 f. £6 Arist. Met., 1.4, 985 b, 13. In this place under rd dv is to be under- stood the thing possessing Being constructed out of atoms. For rdfis and 11 162 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY and form of the atoms which constitute them, are the de- termining factors. The real qualities of a perceived thing are spatial form, weight, solidity, and hardness. Weight? depends on the mass of matter, with an allowance for the interstices of empty space. Solidity and hardness de- pend on the nature of the distribution of matter and empty space. These are the primary? qualities which belong to the things in themselves. All others belong to the things only so far as they affect the perceiving subject. The secondary qualities are not therefore signs of things, but of subjective states.2 Democritus considered color, taste, and temperature as belonging to the secondary qualities, and he based their subjectivity on the difference of the impression of the same object upon different men.* In this theory of the subjectivity of sense qualities (for de- tails, see below) Democritus carried out the suggestions of Protagoras. His principle of relativity especially shows this. His polemic against Protagoras was prompted by the fact that he held, like Plato, side by side with the theory of the relativity of sense perception, the possibility of a knowledge of absolute real- ity. On this account, even as Plato, he battled against the Pro- tagorean theory, in which every perception in this relative sense déors could not be marks of distinction between the single atoms, but only between the complexes. Compare De generatione et corruptione, L., 314 a, 24, in which things are distinguished by the atoms, and their rdéis and ééo.s. Finally, both of the latter moments (order and position) deter- mine the ddAoiwars, the qualities of particular things. 1 Heaviness (@dpos) in Atomism very often clearly signifies approxi- mately the same as movableness, i. e. the degree of reaction in pressure and impact. The direction of the movement in fall is included by the term in Epicureanism. 2 The expressions “ primary and secondary qualities” have been in- troduced by Locke. The Democritan distinction had been previously renewed by Galileo and Descartes. Descartes reckoned solidity among the secondary qualities, but Locke placed it back among the primary. 8 aan ris alcOncews dddovovperns: Theoph. De sens., 68 £. 4 Ibid. MATERIALISM AND IDEALISM 163 must be called true. Compare Sext. Emp. Ady. math., VIII. 56, VIL. 139; Plutarch, Adv. col., 4, 2 (1109). Democritus also added to his recognition of the subjectively relative the assertion of the objectively absolute. Reality, however, con- sists of space and geometrical forms of matter, and herein is his relationship to the Pythagoreans. Compare V. Brochard, Pro- tagoras et Démocrit (Arch. f. Gesch. der Philvs., I. 368 f.). Every place of the meeting of several atoms can there- fore become the beginning of a vortex movement that is ever increasing in its dimensions, and proves to be the point of the crystallization of a particular world. On the one side it is possible that the small worlds thus formed may be drawn into the vortices of a larger system and become component parts of it, or on the other hand that they may shatter and destroy each other in some unfavorable col- lision. Thus there is an endless manifold of worlds, and an eternal living-process in the universe, in which the single worlds arise and again disappear through purely mechanical necessity. As to the form of our own world-system, Atomism taught that the whole swings in empty space like a ball. The out- ermost shell of this ball consists of compactly united atoms, and the interior is filled with air, while in the middle, like a disc, rests the earth. The process of separation of what is stable and what is flowing, is taking place still in the earth. The stars are like the earth, except that they are much smaller bodies. Their fires are kindled by the rota- tion of the whole world, and are nourished by the vapors of the earth. Democritus said that the ‘sun and moon are of large dimensions, and he spoke of the mountains of the moon. Both sun and moon were originally independent atom-complexes. They have been drawn into the terres- trial system by its revolution, and they were in that way set on fire. We cannot here go into the detailed description which the Atomists made of this division of the elements, as brought about 164 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY by the vortex movement; see Zeller, I*. 798 £. Nevertheless, the interpretation still championed by Zeller, 1°. 874 f., and earlier the universal interpretation, has been shaken by A. Brieger (Die Urbewegung der Atome, etc., 1884, Halle; compare De atomorum Epicurearum motu principali, M. Hertz, p. 848), and by H. C. Liepmann (Die Mechanik der Democritischen Atome, Leipzig, 1885). ‘This earlier interpretation was that the Atomists regarded the original motion of the atom in the direction of the fall, i. e. downwards as perceived by the senses. Though the ancient commentators thus brought the motion of the atoms into connection with Bapos (compare above), yet the movement down- wards was not expressly mentioned as absolute. Democritus could easily designate in the vortex system of atoms the opposi- tion. between centripetal and centrifugal directions as xérw and avo, Accordingly he could have investigated the effect of the “heavy” in the vortex without teaching the conception of the Epicureans that ‘¢ weight” is the cause of motion. Atomism has been apparently very much confounded with this in later time. However in the sources (probably academic) which Cicero (De fin., 1. 6, 17) uses, there is the express state- -ment that Democritus taught an original movement of the atoms in infinito inant, in quo nihil nec summum nec infimum nec medium nec extremum sit. Epicurus, on the contrary, degraded this teaching in assuming that the fall-motion is the natural one for bodies. The turbulenta atomorum concursto, on the other hand, here (20) was made a charge against Democritus, Plato (Tim., 80 a, xwovdpevoy mypmedas kal draxtws) appears to me to signify this, and doubtless refers here to Atomism. Com- pare Aristotle, Dz ceelo, III. 2, 800 b, 16. In his matured rep- resentation of endless space, it is remarkable that Democritus took a point of view in astronomy that was even for his time very antiquated. He did not think of the shape of the earth as spherical. He affiliated closely throughout with Anaxagoras, never with the Pythagoreans. With this exception his single hypotheses, especially his peculiar meteorological and physical hypotheses, make us recognize in him the thoughtful man of research and the penetrating observer. We find him collecting many kinds of particular observations and explanations even in biology, which Aristotle and others later used. He agreed with Empedocles as to the origin of organisms (§ 21). The most important of the elements was thought by Democritus to be fire. It is the most perfect because it is the most mobile. It consists of the finest atoms, which are MATERIALISM AND IDEALISM 165 smooth and round? and the smallest of all. Its importance consisted in its being the principle of motion in organisms,? and hence it is the soul-stuff.2 For the motion of fire atoms ts psychical activity. Upon this principle Democritus built an elaborately developed materialistic psychology, which in turn formed the fundamental principle of his epistemology and ethics. Fr. Heimsoeth, Democritus de anima doctrina (Bonn, 1835) ; G. Hart, Zur Seelen- und Erkenntnislehre des Democritus (Leip- zig, 1886). It is evident that the theory of fire in Democritus goes hack to Heracleitus. Fire plays, however, in Atomism the same réle in many respects as the mind-stuff vods in Anaxagoras. This is especially true in his explanation of the organic world. Fire is indeed not the element that is moved by itself alone, but it is the most movable element, and it imparts its motion to the more inert material. It must be understood, from these refer- ences and relationships, that Democritus also thought that the soul and reason were distributed through the entire world, and that they could be designated asthe divine.’ Yet it is certainly a later explanation which attempts to find in his theory a world- soul like the Heracleitan-Stoic world-soul. The isolation by the atomists of the motion of the separate fire-atoms has no reference to a unitary function. In physiology Democritus considered the soul atoms to be disseminated throughout the entire body. He supposed that between every two atoms of the material of the human body is a fire atom.® Thereby he concluded that soul-atoms of differ- ent size and motion are associated with different parts of the body. He accordingly located the different psychical functions in different parts of the body, — thought in the brain, percep- tions in the different sense organs, the violent emotions (épyy) in the heart, and the appetites.in the liver. The fire atoms were supposed to be held together in the body by the breath, so that the diminution of the breath in sleep and death leads to the diminution or nearly entire destruction of the psychical life. The spiritual individuality of man is also destroyed at death. The peculiarity of the Democritan psychology consisted in the fundamental hypothesis that the life of the soul and 1 Arist. De colo, III. 4, 303 a,14. 2% Ibid. Dean., I. 2, 404 a, 27. 8 Compare Zeller, It. 814. 4 Arist. loc. cit. 405 a, 8. 5 Cicero, De nat. deor., I. 48,120. © Lucret. De rer. nat., III. 370. 166 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY its entire qualitatively determined content has its final explanation in the quantitative difference of the motion of atoms. The life of the soul is really also only an atom- motion, although the very finest and most nearly perfect of all motions! This doctrine attempted to elaborate the differex inds of atomic motion which form true essence of the different psychical functions. This shows itself in the first place in his theory of pere ceptign. Since, for example, the influence of external things upon us, which is manifested in perception, is possible only by contact according to a mechanical principle,? sensation can be induced only by emanations of these things pressing upon our organs. The sensitive fire-atoms found in these organs, are thus set in a motion, which precisely is the sensa- tion.2 Indeed Democritus, with support from the theory of Empedocles, concludes that in every organ the stimulating motions corresponding to its atomic constitution become perception, when a similar motion meets‘ them from the soul atoms of the organ. Democritus developed these theories for sight and hearing in particular. It is particularly im- portant for his entire theory that he called the influences emanating from objects “small images” (eiwAa), in his dis- cussion of sight. 1 That Democritus did not actually deduce the qualitative from the quantitative, but only had assertions and good intentions about it, is quite obvious. It is of course unattainable ; and this shows the impossibility of a logical completion of the materialistic metaphysic. That he, however, sought to work it out systematically, makes him the father of materialism. 2 Therefore touch is the fundamental sense; compare Arist. De sens., 4, 442 a, 29. This conception reappears in the “ new psychology,” — an interesting fact of historical development. 8 Theoph. De sens., 54 £. * Ibid. 56. Developed in respect to the ear. Here is also the modern conception concerning the specific energy of the sense-organs, as dependent on the peripheral end-organs being suited to the reproduction of different motions. This is approximately the thought of Democritus. MATERIALISM AND IDEALISM 167 Democritus agreed entirely with Protagoras in his as- sessment of the epistemological value of these sensations. Since, then, the motion thus called forth is conditioned not only by the transmitting media+ but also by the indepen- dent action of the fire atoms, sensation is no true expres- sion for the nature of perceived things. Therein consists the subjectivity of sense perception and its inability to give true knowledge, and sense does not therefore truly repre- sent the atoms and their connection inempty space. Sense yields only qualitative determinations, like color, taste, and temperature. Democritus associated the formulation of this thought with the Sophistic contrast of the law of na- ture and the law of man: vou@ yAvKd Kai vow TiKpoY, vow Oepyov, vop@ ~uypov, vouw xpoun . éren 5é AToua Kai Kevov.2 Thereby to sense experience objective truth is denied.‘ Sense experience yields only an obscure view of what is actual. True knowledge >—viz., of the atoms, which are not perceptible to our senses, and of likewise imperceptible empty ee can be attained only by thought. This rationalism, which in a typical manner stands in contrast to the natural science theory of sense perception, arose out of the metaphysical need of the Protagorean theory of perception, and went beyond it. For a very instructive parallel between 1 Theoph. De sens., 50. 2 The Heracleitan-Protagorean moment of this theory lay in this counter-motion particularly. 3 Sext. Emp., VII. 135. Compare Theoph. De sens.; 63. He like- wise traced the human nomenclature for things back to @éais. See Zeller, I+. 824, 3. 4 The occasional strictures about the limitations of human knowledge (Diog. Laert., IX. 72; see Zeller, I*. 823 f.) are, as also in Empedocles, to be considered only in this relation. It seems all the more true, since Democritus expressly taught that there might also exist for other things other methods of perception than those of man. This was con- sistent with his whole theory. See Plutarch, Plac., IV. 10 (Doz., 399). Compare below. 5 Sext. Emp. Adv. math., VII. 139. 168 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY Plato and Democritus, see Sextus Empiricus, Adv. math., VIII. 56. Thisrationalism of Democritus corresponds, in fact, entirely to that of the old metaphysic and the nature philosophy. The only difference is that here in Democritus it is not only asserted, but it is also based upon an anthropological doctrine. -It is further to be observed, and it is also of value in drawing a parallel with Plato (Natorp, Forschungen, 207), that Democritus yvepn yvyoin refers to space and the mathematical relations pos- sible in space. It must remain undecided how far connections with the Pythagoreans are to be supposed. Democritus, at all events, is as far distant as the Pythagoreans and the Academy from a really fruitful application of mathematics to physics in the manner of Galileo. But, finally, thought itself, which grasps the truth of things, is nothing else than a motion of atoms, and in so far is like perception! Furthermore, since thought, as all kinds of motion, can arise only from mechanical causes, Democritus saw himself driven to the conclusion that the vonos as well as the alcOnous presupposes” impressions of elS@Aa from the outer world upon the body. In view of the documents that lie before us, it is only supposititious ? how Democritus more exactly represented to himself the process of thought. It is certain‘ that he traced dreams, visions, and hallucinations to e/éwAa as their causes. These are also ideas introduced indeed through bodily im- pressions, but not by the customary path of perception 1 Although in itself not equivalent on the higher planes, It is like- wise dissimilar to all the functions of the fire atoms. 2 Plutarch, Plac., IV. 8 (Doz., 395). 3 Zeller (I*. 821, 2) thinks that, Democritus did not attempt such an in- vestigation concerning the psychological principle in order to establish the preference of thought to perception. Zeller’s view seems improbable, in the first place, on account of Democritus’ elaboration elsewhere of his epistemological and psychological doctrine; in the second place, on account of the importance of the matter for his whole system; finally, because of the traces of such undertakings in his preserved fragments. Compare G. Hart, Zur Seelen- und Erkenntnislehre des Dem., p. 19. 4 Plutarch, Quest. conv., VIII. 10, 2; Cic. De div., II. 67, 187 f. MATERIALISM AND IDEALISM. 169 through the organs of sense. Democritus is so far from holding these images as purely subjective that he ascribes to them rather a kind of presentient truth.2_ He looks upon the process distinctly after the analogy of the sense of sight as the name eSwAa shows. eiéwda, finer than those influencing the sense, create a correspondingly finer motion of the soul atoms, and thus arises our dream knowledge. If now Democritus regarded thought as the finest motion of the fire atoms, he must have looked upon the finest e/SwXa also as the stimuli of that motion, viz. those ef6#Aa in which the true atomistic form of things is copied. Thought is accordingly an immediate knowledge of the most minute articulation of actuality, the theory of atoms. These finest e/SwAa remain ineffectual to the greater portion of humanity compared to the gross and violent stimulations to the sense organs. The Wise Man, however, is alone sensitive * to them, but he must avert his attention from the senses® in order to conceive them. Compare E. Johnson, Der Sensualismus des Demokrit, etc. (Plauen, 1868) ; Natorp, Forschungen, 164f. To designate De- mocritus as a sensualist is only justified by the fact that he thought * It does not appear from the preserved passages exactly clear whether Democritus in his explanation of dreams thought that the eidoAa press in during sleep without the help of the sense organs; or that they were those that had pressed in during wakefulness, but on account of their weakness had first come into activity during a state of sleep. Perhaps he had both conceptions. 2 According to Plutarch (op. cit.), the dream is able to reveal a strange life of the soul to the dreamer. 3 Thought in analogy to sense of sight; pointed out first by Brandis (Handbuch, I. 333 f.) and abandoned by him (Gesch. d. Entw., I. 145); analogy revived by Johnson. This analogy is to the effect that thought is an immediate inner perception or the intuitive conception of absolute reality. 4 Compare the somewhat dark passage, Plutarch, Plac., IV. 10: Anpoxptros mAeious eivat aicOnoets mept Ta Goya (Ga Kal wept Tois coors kal epi Tous Geove. © See Hart, op. cit. p. 19 f. 170 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY that the ground of the stimulation and the functioning of thought is analogous to that of (sight) perception. The distinguishing characteristic of Democritus is, however, this, that thought could go on without the help and therefore to the exclusion of sense-activity. Therefore he is an outspoken rationalist.1 These passages in which it is apparently ascribed to Democ- ritus that he drew conclusions trom govomeva concerning the vonré (Sext. Emp., VII. 140; Arist. De an., I. 2, 404 a, 27), prove only on the one side that he undertook to explain phenom- ena from atomic movement: 7@ aAXAowodo Gut rored 76 aicOdverGat (Theoph. De sens., 49). On the other side these passages show that he tried to have the theories verify themselves through their ability to explain phenomena, and to derive appearance from absolute actuality. Adyou mpds riv aicPyow épodroyovmeva Aéyorres (Arist. De gen. et corr., I. 8, 325 a). 83. The Ethics of Democritus, like his epistemology, has its roots in his psychology. Feelingand desire are xuycess, motions of the fire atoms. As, however, he established in theory this difference of value, — that only obscure recog- nition of phenomena takes place in the gross stimula- tions of the senses, and that insight into the true form of things is solicited by the gentlest movement of thought, — so in practice he applied the same distinction. As in meta- physics knowledge is the réAos,2 in ethics happiness (ed3au- povia) is the rédos. In the attainment of this happiness there is also here the fundamental difference between ap- pearance and truth. The joys of sense deceive, and only 1 Just as all pre-Sophistic philosophers (Heracleitus, Parmenides) are found to have their epistemological rationalism united with a distinct- ively sensualistic psychology of thought. Compare Windelband, Gesch. d. Philos., § 6. 2 Or ovpos, fr. 8 and 9. With this establishment of a unifying prin- ciple for the ethical determination of value, Democritus stood uniquely by the side of Socrates. Practically he differed from Socrates but little. Compare Ziegler, Gesch. der Ethik, I. 34. Fortunately, ibid. 36, there is an allusion indicating that Democritus’ pupil, Anaxarchus, was called Evdatpovds. 8 The opposition of véuzos and ducts prevails also here. Only through human convention (vdy) desires are of value. The Wise Man lives here ¢icet. MATERIALISM AND IDEALISM 171 those of the spirit are true. This fundamental thought shows itself through all the ethical expressions of Demo- critus as a principle fully parallel to his epistemological principle. Also here he held the principle as authoritative that violent and stormy! motions disturb the equilibrium of the soul, i. e. disturb the fire atoms. Such motions bring with them a state of agitation of the senses. Therefore, in spite of their apparent momentary pleasure, such motions lead in reality to lasting dissatisfaction. Fine and gentle motions of thought have, on the contrary, true pleasure in themselves. Compare Lortzing, Ueber die ethischen Fragmenta Demo- crits (Berlin, 1873); R. Hirzel in Hermes (1879, p. 354 f.); F. Kern, in Zeitschr. fiir Philos. u. philos. Kritik (1880, supple- mentary part); M. Heinze, Der Huddmonismus in der griech. Philos. (Leipzig, 1873). The attempt to reduce all qualitative to quantitative relations, which very properly gives a unique place in ancient philosophy to the Democritan atomism, becomes the capstone of his ethics. The puxpai xwyoes contain true happiness in the moral as well as in the intellectual world, and the peydAae are disturbing and deceptive. For particulars, see especially G. Hart, op. ctt., p. 20 f. If then the value of the psychical functions is made dependent in both directions upon the intensity of atomic motion, and indeed in inverse ratio, then it is difficult not to think of the similar purpose in the hedonism of Aristippus, who made the same distinction, in a coarser way to be sure, in estimating the value of the delights of the senses. It must remain undecided whether Democritus directly influenced the Cyrenaics, or whether there had been a common source for the two in the doctrine of Pythagoras. The pleasures of sense are relative. They have a phe- nomenal 2 but not an actual value, viz., the value belonging 1 Fr. 20 (Stob. Eel., I. 40). 2 Plato, Rep. 584 a. The above representation is supported prima- rily by Plato’s Republic, 583 f., and Philebus, 43 f., whose references to Democritus appear to Hirzel and Natorp to be certain (see above). In both instances it is remarkable to see the exposition colored by medical expressions and examples which probably belong to the writing of Democritus (sept evOupins). 172 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY to duos. Sense pleasures differ like the perceptions in different individuals, and depend on circumstances. Every sense pleasure is conditioned only by the cessa- tion of unpleasurable feeling in the desire concerned, and therefore loses its apparently positive character. True happiness consists in peace (jovyia) of the soul, and Democritus generally uses edduuia to designate it. But he also uses many other expressions, as d0auGia, drapafia, adavpacia, dppovia, Evpyetpia,” especially eveoto. He has for it a very happy simile of a calm of the sea (-yaAnvn). By every excess? of excitation thought is aroused to adroppoveiv* and feeling to stormy unrest. The right condition of gentle harmonious motion of the soul-atoms is possible only through intellectual knowledge. Out of this flows the true happiness of man. In these definitions the content of the ethics of Democ- ritus is fully on a level with the ethics of Socrates. The ethics of Democritus intimately connected the social worth of man with his intellectual refinement. The ground of evil is lack of cultivation.® Happiness therefore con- sists not in worldly goods,® but in knowledge,’ in the har- monious leading of the life, in a life of terhperance and self-limitation.2 The social worth of a man is to be esti- mated® by hig mental calibre and not by his actions; and he who acts unjustly is more unhappy than he who suffers unjustly.° Everywhere he regarded the peace of man to be within himself (evecté). He looked upon the with- drawal from the sense-desires and upon the enjoyment of the intellectual life as true happiness.“ 1 Fr. Mor. 47. 2 Both the last terms have a Pythagorean sound. 3 Fr, 25. 4 Theoph. De sens., 58. 5 Fr, 116. 6 Fr. 1. 7 Fr. 136. 8 Fr. 20; compare 25. 9 Fr. 109, 10 Fr, 224. 1 It must remain uncertain to what extent Democritus distinguished MATERIALISM AND IDEALISM 173 The numerous single sentences which have been preserved from Democritus suit entirely the quality of this noble and high view of life. Since they all, however, have been transmitted in a disconnected way, it can no longer be determined whether and how they have a systematic derivation from the developed fundamental principle. In particular is to he emphasized the high worth that Democritus places in friendship,’ and on the other hand his full understanding of the importance of civil life, from which he seems to have deviated only in reference to the Wise Man? with a cosmopolitanism analogous to that of the Sophists. Yet there remains here much that is doubtful. Democritus maintained an attitude of indifference to religious belief, which was consistent with his philosophy. He ex- plained the mythical forms, in part by means of moral alle- gories,? in part by nature-myth* explanations. He accepted, in connection with his theory of perception, essentially higher an- thropomorphous beings imperceptible to the senses, but influential in visions and dreams. He called these demons efdwAa, an ex- pression employed elsewhere in his epistemology for the emana- tions from things. They are sometimes benevolent, sometimes malevolent.® The school at Abdera disappeared quickly after Democritus died. Even in its special undertaking, it performed,® after the leader fell, scarcely anything worth mentioning. Its philosophi- cal tendency, however, became more and more sophistie,’ and thereby led to Skepticism. Metrodorus of Chios and Anax- archus of Abdera, the companion of Alexander on his Asiatic campaign, are the notable names. Through the influence of Pyrrho, a pupil of Metrodorus, the Abderite philosophy became Skepticism, and the contemporaneous Nausiphanes formed the connection between it and Epicureanism. between the perfect happiness of the Wise Man won through the yyoin yvoun, and the peace of the ordinary man obtained by temperance and self-control. Compare Th. Ziegler, op. cit., who wishes to put into a similar relationship both of the chief ethical writings, wept et@vyuins and tmoOnjxat. 1 Fr. 162 f. 2 Fr, 225. 3 Clemens, Cohort., 45 f. 4 Sext. Emp. Adv. math., IX. 24. 5 Ibid. 6 The astronomical tenets of Metrodorus seem to indicate a relapse into Heracleitan ideas. Compare Zeller, I*. 859. 7 For the theoretical skepticism of Metrodorus, compare Eusebius, Prep. ev., XIV. 19, 5. Whatever is reported of the ethical tendency of Anaxarchus reminds one of Hedonism, and Cynicism as well. 174 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY 34. Democritus’ consummation of the metaphysics of science by means of materialistic psychology formed in the total growth of ancient thought only an early dying branch. The principal tendency of Greek thought perfected itself nearly contemporaneously in the ethical immaterialism of Plato at the centre of Attic civilization. The same ele- ments of the earlier science, which were fundamental to the theory of Democritus, were combined afresh and in an entirely different manner in the Platonic system under the influence of the Socratic principle. Heracleitus, Parmeni- des, Anaxagoras, Philolaus, and Protagoras furnished the material for the theory of Plato, but it was worked over in an entirely original manner from the point of view of con- ceptual knowledge. Plato, the son of Aristo and Perictione, was born in Athens in 427, and came from a distinguished and pros- perous family. Endowed with every talent physical and mental, he received a careful education, and he was familiar at an early age with all the scientific theories that interested Athens at that time. The political excitement of the time made the youth desire a political career. The Peloponnesian war was raging, and during its progress the internal and external affairs of Athens were becoming more and more precarious. On the other hand, the rich artistic development of the time was irresistibly attractive, and Plato was led to try poetry in many of its forms. Both Plato’s political and poetic longings appear to follow him in his entire philosophy: on the one side in the lively, al- though changing interest that his scientific work always shows in the problems of statecraft, and on the other in the artistically perfected form of his dialogues. But both are subordinate to his entire absorption in the personality and teaching of the character of his great master Socrates, whose truest and most discriminating pupil he remained for many years, MATERIALISM AND IDEALISM 175 Of the general works concerning Plato and his theory there are to be named W. G. Tennemann, System der plat. Philos., 4 vols. (Leipzig, 1792-5) ; Fr. Ast, Platon’s Leben u. Schriften (Leipzig, 1816); K. F. Hermann, Gesch. u. Syst. der plat. Philos. (Heidelberg, 1839); G. Grote, Plato and Other Com- panions of Socrates (London, 1865) ; H. v. Stein, Sieben Biicher zur Gesch. des Platonismus (Gottingen, 1861 f.) ; A. E. Chaignet, La vie et les écrits de Plato (Paris, 1871) ; A. Fouillée, Za philo- sophie de Plato (4 vols., 2d ed., Paris, 1890). The nearest pupils of Plato, especially Hermodorus, dealt with his life; also the Peripatetics, Aristoxenus and others. The expositions of Apuleius and Olympiodorus (published in Cobet’s edition of Diogenes Laertius) have been preserved. Besides there is a life of Plato in the Prolegomena (printed in Hermann’s edition of the Platonic writings). The collection of spurious letters printed with his works is a very untrustworthy source. Only the seventh among them is of any worth. K. Steinhart has published a life of Plato (Leipzig, 1873), which ranks well among the new works. On his father’s side, Plato had the blood of the Codrus family in his veins, and on his mother’s he traced his lineage back to Solon.! He himself was called after his grandfather, Aris- tocles, and is said to have been called Plato for the first time by his gymnasium teacher on account of his broad frame. For the determination of the year of his birth, the statements of Her- modorus are decisive (Diog. Laert., III. 6), that when he went to Euclid at Megara in 399, immediately after the death of Socrates, he was twenty-eight years old. That his birthday was celebrated in the Academy on the seventh Thargelion emanates possibly from the Apollo cult, to which many of the early myths about the philosopher seemingly are referable. That Plato was early remarkable in every physical and musi- cal art is entirely in agreement with every part of the picture of his personality. The particular accounts about his teachers (Zeller, II*. 394) throw no light on his own scientific significance. His early acquaintance with the Heracleitan Cratylus is attested by Aristotle.2 At what points of time in his development the teachings of the other philosophers whose influence is traceable in his works were known to him, cannot be ascertained. Early in his career Heracleitus, the Eleatics, Protagoras and other Sophists, and later® Anaxagoras and the Pythagoreans were authorities for him. 1 It is improbable that his family was poor, as many later writers would have it. His style of life indicates the contrary. 2 Met., I. 6, 987 a, 32. 8 Indeed, relatively late: see below. 176 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY Plato was hostile to the democracy, as_was consistent with the traditions of his family and the political-views of his teacher, Socrates. Yet his political inclinations, as he-has—laid-them do-vn in his works, diverge.so far from historic-aristocracy that his complete abstinence from public life in his native city appears highly conceivable. That he concerned himself in his youth, as was the custom, with epic and dramatic poetry, is not to be doubted, notwithstanding the uncertainty of the particular tra- ditions about it. Concerning the time when he became acquainted with Socrates, an acquaintance that certainly eclipsed all the early interests of the youth, there is nothing very definite to be said. If he were then, according to Hermodorus,! twenty years old, there remained very little room for his poetic attempts, which ceased when he began philosophy. It is probable that Plato had formulated the content of the separate conversations in the earliest dialogues during Socrates’ life.? After the death of Socrates, Plato went first, with other pupils of the master, to Euclid at Megara. He soon after began a journey which took him to Cyrene? and to Egypt, and he seems to have returned to Athens from this journey about 895. Here he apparently already began, if not his teaching, yet the part of his literary work in which he opposed the different tendencies of the Sophists. About the end of the first decade of the fourth century, he began his first tour to Magna Grecia and Sicily, which not only brought him into personal touch with the Pythagoreans, but also led him to the court of the elder Dionysius of Syracuse. Here he was in close intimacy with Dion, and was thereby drawn into the strife of political parties which ruled the court, Matters became dangerous for him, for the tyrant grew hostile and treated him as a prisoner of war. He delivered Plato over to the Spartan ambassador, and the 1 Diog. Laert., III. 6. 2 The statement concerning the Lysis, ibid. 35, is in itself by no means improbable. ® His intimate relations with the mathematician Theodorus, the pupil of Protagoras (see 7'heetelus), are somehow connected with his stay in Cyrene; possibly also his essentially polemic relation to Aristippus. MATERIALISM AND IDEALISM 177 latter sent the philosopher to the slave-market of A®gina, where a man from Cyrene bought his freedom. About 387 Plato returned to Athens, and founded his scientific society soon after in the Academy, a gymnasium. Here, to a con- tinuously increasing band of friends and youths, he imparted his philosophic theories, sometimes in dialogues, sometimes in longer discourses. The only data for this part of his life which are not reported alike everywhere in the sources have probably been given their definitive statement by Zeller, II*. 402. It is probable that Plato’s Wanderjahre, from the death of Socrates until his failure in Syracuse, were not without interruption, and that he mean- while had already begun his instruction at Athens, although to a small circle, and not yet to the closed and organized Academy. The literary activity of Plato in the interim (395-91) was essen-. tially only a defence of the Socratic doctrine, as Plato conceived it and had begun to develop it against Sophistry, which was flourishing more than ever. Whether or not Plato left his home a second time for political reasons, during the Corinthian war, when Athens was again ruled by the democracy,? is uncertain. He probably at that time attempted in Syracuse, perhaps in collusion with the Pythagoreans, to bring his political principles into vogue by the exercise of influence upon the tyrant. For the treatment which he experienced at the hands of Dionysius, who seems to have threatened his life, is hardly to be explained by any mere unpopularity of his ethical parrhesia, but is, on the contrary, natural enough if Plato entered politics. At first Plato probably taught in the Socratic manner by con- versation, and he sought to construct concepts with the help of his pupils. But the more his own opinions became finished, and the smaller the organization of the Academy grew in numbers, the more didactic became his work, and the more had it the form of the lecture. In the successive dialogues the work of the inter- locutor becomes fainter and less important. Later Aristotle and the other pupils published lectures of Plato. The philosopher allowed himself only twice to be induced away from his teaching in the Academy, which teaching 1 That about this time public attention turned again to Socrates, is shown by the circumstance that even then the rhetorician Polycrates published an attack upon Socrates. See Diog. Laert., II. 39. 12 178 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY lasted the entire second half of his life; and then only through the hope of fulfilling his political ideals. After the death of the elder Dionysius, he sought, with the help of Dion, to influence the younger Dionysius. He had no success in the first attempt in 367, and the third Sicilian journey in 861 brought him into great personal danger again. In this journey his special effort was to reconcile Dion and Dionysius the younger. Only the energetic effort of the Pythagoreans who, with Archytas at their head, repre- senting the power of Tarentum, seems to have saved him. Plato died in 847, in his eightieth year. He was revered by his contemporaries, and celebrated as a hero by posterity. He was a perfect Greek and a great man, — one who united in himself all the excellences of bodily beauty with intel- lectual and moral power. He also ennobled the esthetic life of the Greeks with a depth of spirituality which assured to him an influence for a thousand years. The political character of the second and third Sicilian journeys is beyond doubt, but that does not preclude the supposition that Plato at that time, in his intercourse with the Pythagoreans, was pursuing his scientific work. At any rate, the number theory exercised an increasing but scarcely a healthy influence on part of the development of his philosophical thought. On the other hand, his influence on the Pythagoreans was very fruitful. The reports of the ancients as to the length of life and the time of death of the philosopher differ only a little. They are easily reconciled in the statement that Plato died in the middle of the year 347. It is also said that he died suddenly in the middle of a marriage feast. The report of Cicero — scribens est mortuus — signifies only that Plato was still laboring to perfect his works at the time of his death. The aspersions upon his character in later literature arose from the animosities of the scholastic controversy. They are refuted, however, by the respectful tone with which Aristotle always spoke of Plato, even when he was battling against his theory. It is not entirely impossible that in later time, when Aristotle went his own way and Plato became more Pythagorean in his mysticism, that the relations between the two became less close and somewhat in- harmonious. MATERIALISM AND IDEALISM 179 We.can get the most.reliable picture of Plato from his own writings.-.They show in their author the realization of the “Socratic ideal} his scientific investigations “are tarried on “with all the seriousness of a moral endeavor seeking its own fulfilment. The serene beauty of his compositions ‘and the perfect purity of his diction reveal the artist who from the heights of the culture of his time gives to the thought of that time a form that transcends the time. With the exception of the Apology, they are dialogues in which the conversation and the deciding word, if a decision is reached, fall in by far the majority of cases to Socrates. In reference to their content, only a few of the dialogues have a fixed plan of philosophical research. Rather, almost always threads of thought were spun from the chief prob- lem in any direction and followed to the end. On that account the dialogues are not scientific treatises, but works of art in which scientific “‘ experiences ” are reproduced in an idealized form. One remarks this esthetic character in Plato’s use of myths, which appear usually at the beginning or end of an investigation, where Plato cannot or will not develop his thought conceptually. The story form of the argument enhances its poetic power. By the term ‘ experiences,” which are elaborated in Plato’s dialogues, we do not mean so much the conferences which the poet philosopher employed or devised as the outer scenery of his works, but the discussions in which he himself led in the circle of his riper friends.1_ Such a dialogue as the Parmenides bears even the character of being the esthetic résumé of actually fonght out word-battles. The Platonic authorship of these is extremely doubtful, but they must have originated in the Pla- tonic circle. The actually occurring conversation is idealized and universalized in these dialogues, being placed in the mouth of Socrates and other persons, some of whom had already died. Plato shows here his imagination by his selection and 1 This certainly happened later also, when scholastic teaching and practice had place in the Academy, in which teaching the preserved dizreses and definitions may have been used. 180 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY adornment of the situations under requirements of fiction, in which situations these conversations purport to have taken place; by the plastic characterizations of the champions of various theories, in which he uses frequently the effectual means of persiflage ; and also by the delicate structure of the conver- sation, which forms itself into a kind of dramatic movement. Countless allusions, of which only a very few are understood by us, apply to the historical persons figuring i in the dialogue, and in part perhaps to the companions of Plato. In the- undoubtedly genuine Platonic dialogues, Socrates is made the speaker of Plato’s own views. ~The “Only excep-.. tions are tle latest, Zimceus and Critias,and the Laws. In ~ the first two the reason for this exception is that Plato deals only with the mythical and not with sure knowledge. In the Las the head of the school has become an authority and. speaks as such. Usually the dramatic scenery in the first dia- logues is much more simple and less ornate; in the works of his d«urj, the scenic effect is fully developed; in the Philebus, on the contrary, and in the other later works, it sinks back again to a schematic investiture. ‘The conversations are partly ‘give and take,” partly repetitions whereby sometimes the chief dialogue.is. introduced into the discussion of. another dialogue. Although the earlier dialogues follow, on the whole, the secdnd principle, and the later the first, yet these principles are not safe criteria for the chronological succession? of the dialogues. The reports of antiquity that Plato divided ? philosophy into dialectics, physics. and ethics can refer only to his method in the Academy. This division in the dialogues can be made neither directly nor indirectly. On the whole, epistemological, theoretical, metaphysical, ethical, and sometimes physical mo- tives are so interwoven that while here and there the one or the other interest predominates (in Zhectetus the epistemological and theoretical ; in-the Republic the ethico-political), never does a conscious sundering of the realms of the problems take place. This belongs moreover to the poetic rather than the scientific character of Plato’s literary workmanship. Concerning the myths of Plato, compare especially Deuschle (Hanau, 1854) and Volquardsen (Schleswig, 1871) ; concerning the general character of Plato’s literary activity, see E. Heitz (O. Miller’s Literaturgeschichte, II. 2, 148-235). 1 In Theetetus this innovation is made, and reason is given for it (148 b,c). The Phedo also, which was certainly a late dialogue, and the probably later Symposium returned to the older method. 2 Cicero, Acad., I. 5,19. Compare Sext. Emp. Adv. math., VII. 16. MATERIALISM AND IDEALISM 181 There is no ground for supposing that any one of the writings of Plato has been lost. On the other hand, the transmitted collection contains many that are undoubtedly questionable and ungenuine. We may take the following as certainly Platonic: the Apology, Crito, Protagoras, Gorgias, Cratylus, Meno, Theetetus, Phedrus, Symposium, Phedo, Republic, Timaus , and also probably Philebus and the Laws. The following are certainly not genuine: Alci- biades IL, Anteraste, Demodorus, Aziochus, Epinomis, Eryzias, Hipparchus, Clitophon, Minos, Sisyphus, Theages, and the small studies epi S:caiov and trepi aperns. Among the doubtful, Parmenides, Sophist, and Poltticus are of special importance. The criterion of their genuineness is chiefly the testimony of Aristotle, who mentions many of the writings with the name of Plato and title of the book, many only with either name or title, many without certain reference to Plato. To a canon established in this way, there are to be added writings that Plato himself cites, or whose form and content make them Plato’s. Just as important as the question of the genuineness of the writings of Plato, is the question of their order and con- nection. The chief controversy over the order of the writ- ings is between the Systematic and Historical theories. The Systematic theory, advocated by Schleiermacher and Munk, finds a plan in the whole of Plato’s writings, — a consistent system organized at the beginning. Hermann and Grote advocate the Historical theory, which makes each dialogue a stage in the development of Plato’s thought. Beside the general reasons for the Historical theory, there are the nu- merous variations in the establishment, development, and application of the fundamental thesis, --a thesis which is clearly present although undergoing transformation. In both directions the body of the Platonic writings presents one of the most difficult problems of antiquity, — insolv- able in some particulars; yet time has brought about a 182 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY pretty complete agreement concerning the more important ones. The works of Plato were arranged and published in antiquity by Aristophanes of Byzantium partially in trilogies, and by Thrasylus in tetralogies. In the Renaissance they were excel- lently translated into Latin by Marsilius Ficinus, and printed in Greek text at Venice in 1518. Further publications of the works are those by Stephanus (Paris, 1578) which has been cited, the Zweibriicken edition (1781 f.), that of Imman. Bekker (Berlin, 1816 f.), Stallbaum (Leipzig, 1821 f., 1850), Baiter, Orelli, and Winkelmann (Zurich, 1839 f.), K. Fr. Hermann (Leipzig, Teubner, 1851 f.), Schneider and Hirschig (Paris, 1846), M. Schanz (Leipzig, 1875 f.). Translations with introductions: Schleiermacher (Berlin, 1804 f.), Hieron. Miller and Steinhart (Leipzig, 1850 f.), V. Cousin (Paris, 1825), B. Jowett (Oxford, 1871), R. Bonghi and E. Ferrai (Padua, 1873 ff.). The most nearly complete and comprehensive picture of the special literature which is not to be reproduced here and also concerning the single dialogues, is given by Ueberweg-Heinze, I’. 138 f. The chief writings on the subject are as follows: Jos. Socher ( Ueber Platon’s Schriften (Munich, 1820); Ed. Zeller, Plat. Studien (Tiibingen, 1839); F. Susemihl, Prodromus plat. Forschungen (Gottingen, 1852); Genetischen Entwickelungen der plat. Philos. (Leipzig, 1855-60) ; F. Suckow, D. wissensch. u. kiinstlerlische Form der plat. Schriften (Berlin, 1855); E. Munk, D. natiirliche Ordnung der plat. Schriften (Berlin, 1856); H. Bonitz, Platonische Studien (3 ed., Berlin, 1886) ; Fr. Ueberweg, Untersuchungen tuber Echtheit und Zeitfolge plat. Schr. (1861, Vienna) ; G. Teichmiiller, D. plat. Frage (Gotha, 1876); Ueber die Reihenfolge der plat. Dialoge (Leipzig, 1879) ; Litterar. Fehden im vierten Jahrh. vor Chr. Geb. (Breslau, 1881 f.); A. Krohn, Die plat. Frage (Halle, 1878) ; W. Ditten- berger (in Hermes, 1881); H. Siebeck, in Jahrbuch f. klas. Philologie (1885); M. Schanz (Hermes, 1886); Th. Gomperz, Zur Zeitfolge plat. Schriften (Wien, 1887); E. Pfleiderer, Zur Lisung der plat. Frage (Freiburg, 1888); Jackson, Plato’s Later Theory of Ideas (Jour. of Philol., 1881-86) ; F. Diimmler, Akademika (Giessen, 1889) ; K. Schaarschmidt, D. Samm. der plat. Schr. (Bonn, 1866). With reference to all the different factors, the Pla- tonic writings group themselves somewhat as follows :? 1 To which there have been added lately, but with little success, some philological statistics. MATERIALISM AND IDEALISM 183 (1) The Works of Plato’s Youth. These were written under the overpowering influence of Socrates ; in part dur- ing Socrates’ life, in part in Megara immediately after his death. To this group belong Lysis and Laches, and, if they be genuiue, Charmides, Hippias Minor, and Alcibiades L ; so, also, the Apology and both the apologetic dialogues, Crito and Euthyphro. Lysis (concerning friendship) and Laches (concerning cour- age) have purely Socratic content. Hippias Minor is also Socratic, and for its genuineness we have Aristotle’s authority in Metaphysics, IV. 29,1025 a. This treats the parallel between Achilles and Odysseus from the point of self-conscious virtue. Charmides (concerning moderation) and the rather unskilful and incoherent Alcibiades I. are doubtful. The Apology and Crito (concerning Socrates’ fidelity to law) are usually placed after the death of Socrates. Included in this class is Huthyphro (con- cerning piety), which also has entirely the character of an apology. Huthyphro criticises the charges of impiety made against Socrates by proving that true piety is the Socratic virtue. It is not impossible that the latter three were written about 395, during Plato’s residence at Athens, and were an answer to the renewed attacks upon the memory of Socrates.* (2) The Disputations concerning Sophistical Theories. In these appear now, besides his criticisms of the Sophists, indications of his own philosophy. These works are sup- posed to have been written or begun in Athens in the time between the Egyptian and Sicilian journeys. They are the Protagoras, Gorgias, Euthydemus, Cratylus, Meno, and Thecetetus. Presumably there belong to this period the first book of the Republic and the dialogue concerning justice. These dialogues, with the exception of the Meno, are entirely polemic and without positive result. They form a solid phalanx against Sophism, and show the falsity and insufficiency of its doctrines one after another: the Protagoras, by the investiga- tion concerning the teachableness of virtue, which Plato shows 1 Compare above. Further evidence of this is the manner in which sev- eral dialogues (Gorgias, Meno, and Thectetus), which for other reasons are known to belong to that time, contain allusions to the trial of Socrates. 184 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY to be presupposed by the Sophists, but incompatible with their fundamental principles ; the Gorgias, through a criticism of the Sophistic rhetoric, in contrast with which genuine scientific cul- ture is celebrated asethe only foundation for true statecraft; the Huthydemus through the persiflage of eristic; the Cratylus by a criticism of the philologic attempts of the sophistic contemporaries; the Theatetus, finally, in a criticism of the epistemology of the different schools of Sophists. Protagoras, dramatically the most animated of Plato’s dia- logues, heads this series as a masterpiece of fine irony. It is doubtful whether Gorgias followed it immediately, for there is a great difference in the fundamental tone of the two. Yet it is entirely natural that the artist, Plato, in the second dialogue, in which he takes a much more positive position, should adopt a more serious tone, and should give a more intensely spiritual expression to his political ideal of life. The Huthydemus and Cratylus, which perhaps, therefore, are to be placed before the Gorgias, follow the Protagoras, the irony: mounting to the most insolent caricature. If Hippias Major is taken as genuine, it belongs in this class, for it contains Plato’s criticism of the sophistic art of Hippias. Yet it is probable, rather, that the Hippias Major was the pro- duction of a member of the Academy who was fully familiar with the Platonic teachings. The dialogue concerning justice is a polemic against the Soph- ists, and, indeed, against their naturalistic theory of the state. This dialogue forms at present the first book of the Republic, and was possibly its first edition (Gellius, Moct. Att., XIV.3.3). It resembles throughout in tone the writings of this time, which fact does not obtain as to the chief parts of the Republic. Also the first half of the second hook of the Republic (until 367 c) seems to be a copy of a Sophistic speech called Praise of Injustice. In the Meno the Platonic epistemology had its first positive expression, even if it is only an exposition developed by sugges- tions, and stated after the manner of the mathematician. The Pythagorean influences, which are also found in the Gorgias. do not oblige us to put the Meno in the time after the first Italian journey. It is remarkable that the Thecetetzs, so soon after the youthful enthusiasm with which the Gorgias had proclaimed (174 f.) the vocation of the philosopher to be statesmanship, advocated * so pessimistically the retirement of the philosopher 1 The opinion shared by Th. Bergk (Fiénf Abh. 2. Gesch. d. gr. Phil. u. Astron., Berlin, 1883), that this dialogue should be put as late as the fourth decade of the fourth century, cannot be reconciled with its content. MATERIALISM AND IDEALISM 185 from public life. Yet the explanation of this may be that Plato began the Thecetetus in Athens, and completed it after or upon his journey; for the dialogue refers to a wound that Thesetetus received in an encounter during the Corinthian war. His clash with the tyrant and his wily and adroit flatterer (Aristippus ?) is consistent with his experiences at this time. There is per- haps a connection between this and the change of form, which makes it necessary to place the dialogue at the end of this series. (3) The Works of the Most Fruitful Period of Plato’s Activity. These are the Phedrus, Symposium, and the chief part of the Republic. In the same period were probably written the Parmenides, Sophist, and Politicus, which cer- tainly came from the Platonic circle. The Phedrus may be viewed as Plato’s program delivered upon his entrance (386) into active teaching in the Academy. Philosophically it contains the fundamental thoughts of this period in mythical dress: the theory of the two worlds (§ 35) and the triple division of the soul (§ 36). In the contention between Lysias and Isocrates he takes the latter’s part, but de- clares thereby (276) that he prefers the living conversation to the written word. If Plato concentrated from now on his powers in oral instruction, it is natural that he should appear not to have published any work in the two following decades. Not until immediately after the Phaedrus did he give the fullest expression to his entire teaching in the ‘* love speeches ”* of the Symposium (385 or 384). The most superb of all his artistic 1 The exposition of these thoughts lies so essentially in the direct line of the Platonic philosophy that it does not seem necessary to seek their inspiration in the appearance of a work of Xenophon. Xeno- phon did not have the slightest occasion to treat the ‘‘ love-speeches ” by the side of the Memorabilia as a separate work, as he manifestly did treat them. It is rather probable that after Plato idealized the evening feast (for there is undoubtedly some historical ground for the description) in his own way, Xenophon felt compelled to give an ac- count of the facts. His additions were especially to the thoroughly prac- tical conception, which Socrates developed, as to the relations of the sexes. In addition to these practical reasons there are also verbal and - historical grounds for placing Plato’s account prior to that of Xeno- phon’s rather than the opposite. Compare A. Hug (Philol., 1852), and Rettig (Xen.’s Gastmahkl, Greek and German, Leipzig, 1881). 186 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY products, it represents in every respect the acme of his intellect- ual power. In the elegance of its rhetoric and in the character- ization of single individuals carried out to verbal detail, it is surpassed by no work. Upon the background of the cosmology, suggested in the Phadrus and clearly developed here, it pictures the épws as the living bond of the Platonic society. The Menexenus has the same general tendencies as the Sym- posium and the Phedrus, but it was probably written not by Plato, but by one of his pupils. It boasts somewhat proudly at the end that Aspasia has many more beautiful speeches like the given funeral-oration. During the time of literary silence that immediately followed, Plato appears to have been going on with his great life work, — that one, among all his works, which presents the most serious critical and historical difficulties. This is the Republic. As it lies before us, it is wanting in an intellectual and artistic unity in spite of its subtile, often all too intricate, references and cross- references. All attempts to establish such a unity fail. Follow- ing the fruitless dialogue concerning justice, which forms the first part of the work (first, according to the present divisions, which were indeed traditional early in antiquity), there comes, after the insertion of a species of sophistic discourse, the conver- sation with entirely new persons concerning the ideal state, and concerning the education necessary for constructing a state by which the ideal justice may be realized. Thus there appear two perfectly unlike parts welded together, but the second and greater (Books II.-X.) is by no means a decided advance in thought. In particular, the diatribe taken up again at the beginning of the tenth book against the poets, stands abruptly in the way between the proofs that the just man in the Platonic sense is the happiest man on earth (Book IX., 2d half, 588 f.) as well as after death (Book X., 2d half, 608 ¢) It is particularly striking that whereas the teaching abont the ideal state and the education peculiar to it restricts itself entirely to the limits set forth in the Phedrus and Symposium, we find an intervening section (487-587) which not only expresses the teaching of Ideas as the highest content of this education in the sense stated in the Phedo and developed in the Philebus, but also develops in a more extended way the different metaphysical teachings of the later period. These and other single references, which cannot be followed out in this place, show that there are three strata in the Republic: (1) the dialogue of early origin concerning justice (Book I., possibly including appendix, 857-67) ; (2) the outline of an ideal state as the realization of justice, originating at the time of his teaching, that followed the Phedrus and Symposium MATERIALISM AND IDEALISM 187 (Books II.-V.), and the entire conclusion from Ch. XII. (Book 1X.) ; (8) the theory, dating from the time of the Phedo and Philebus, of the Idea of the Good, and the critique of the consti- tutions of the state (487-587). As Plato grew older, he sought to weld these three parts into one another. To accomplish this, he now and then worked over the earlier portions, but he did not succeed in bringing them into a perfect organic union. In accepting a successive genesis of the whole, the simplest ex- planation is given of the insertions, which appear still further within the different parts in polemic justification. These in- sertions are attempts to meet objections that had in the mean time been raised orally or in writing. In the course of the discussion of the theory of Ideas in the Academy, there appeared difficulties in the way of their devel- opment. The Parmenides and Sophist were written especially to express these objections and to discuss them. ‘The Parme- nides with a dialectic which drew its formal and practical argu- ments from Eleaticism, tears the theory of Ideas to pieces without reaching a positive result. The contemptuous tone and the boyish immature réle which is clearly given to the Socrates- Plato, stands in the way of regarding this as Plato’s criticism of himself. Probably an older member of the Platonic circle, who was educated in Eleatic sophistry, is the author of this dialogue. The Parmenides does not give to Socrates, but to Parmenides, the deciding word, and it bears entirely the Eleatic character of sterile dialectic.? The question about the genuineness of the Sophist and the Politicus is more difficult. That both have the same author can be inferred from their form. On the one hand, in both, as in Parmenides, not Socrates but a friend and guest, who is an Eleatic, leads the conversation ; on the other hand, there is the pedantic and somewhat absurd schematism, with which, by a continuously progressive dichotomy, the concept of the Sophist and statesman is attained. It is therefore impossible to ascribe one dialogue to Plato and the other not to him, as Suckow has attempted. The two stand or fall together. It might he pos- sible to divine an intended caricature of the philosopher in certain externals that are in other respects wholly un-Platonic, but the contents of both forbid this. The criticism of the theory 1 Jf Philebus, 14 c, refers to Parmenides, the notable way in giving up the investigation of é and woAAd is rather a reason for regarding the Parmenides as a polemic that had been rejected. This is better than to let both these dialogues stand or fall together, as Ueberweg prefers (I. 151, 7th ed.). 188 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY of Ideas which is contained in the Sophist (compare § 28) might be conceived, perhaps, as Platonic self-criticisin, although weighty reasons are also against it. But the manner in which it solves the discovered difficulties is not Platunic.t So the Politicus contains many points of view which agree with Plato’s political convictions. It is, however, not probable that the philosopher tried to treat the same problem in a book other than the Republic, especially siice the Politicus sets up other teachings which differ on important points. Convincing reasons are therefore adduced tor seeking the authorship of both in a member of the Academy with strong Eleatic sympathies.” It is singular enough that the divergence of both from the Platonic teaching lies exactly in the direction of the metaphysics and politics of Aristotle,? who entered the Academy in 367. About this time the dialogue Jo may have originated, which indeed makes use of Platonic thoughts in its distinction between poetry and philosophy, but cannot be safely attributed to the head of the school. (4) The Chief Works on Teleological Idealism. These were written in the time before and after the third Sicilian journey. They are the Phedo, Philebus, the correspond- ing parts of the Republic (487 f.), and in connection with these the fragment of Critias and the Zimeus. The characteristic of this period is the introduction of Anaxa- gorean and Py thagorean elements into the theory of Ideas. The central concept is the Idea of the Good... The introduction of these elements finds its full perfection in the Phado, which was written presumably shortly before the third Sicilian journey. | 1 In the passage of Phedo (101 d), Plato explains the problem of the Sophist and also of Parmenides as relatively indifferent problems, compared to the importance of the establishment of the theory of ideas. 2 Who perhaps was prevented by death or other cause from the third proposed dialogue (@:Adcopos). That the trilogy seems to be connected as to its external framework (which is moreover very much wanting in fancy) with the conclusion of the Theetetus, is not decisive for the Platonic authorship. 8 The way in which he mentions both dialogues, I cannot recognize as proof of their genuineness, in spite of the conclusions of Zeller (II. 457 £.). MATERIALISM AND IDEALISM 189 As if conscious of the dangers to be met, Plato gives to this dia- logue the tone of a last will and testament to the school. Asa delightful counterpart to the Symposium, he pictures the dying Wise Man as a teacher of immortality. After this journey, the philosopher? reached the zenith of his metaphysics in his investigations concerning the Idea of the Good, which are embodied in the dialogue Philebus. All the thoughts? that are expressed there, are to be found again in the less abstract presentation in the middle part of the Republic,§ which was designated above as its third stratum (487-587).4 Plato has then, as an afterthought, brought into external rela- tionship the incomplete sketches of his philosophy of history (Critias), and likewise his mythical theory of nature (Timeus) with the scenic setting of the Republic (supposably finished at this time). (5) The Laws. This is the work of his old age. This sketch of a second-best state originated at the time when Plato in his Aoyou ayparrou entirely went through the theory of Ideas with the Pythagorean theory of numbers in mind. The exposition passes over here into senile formality, although still worthy our admiration. The present form of the work pro- ceeded from Plato even in its details, although the manuscript was said to have been published first by Philip of Opus after the death of Plato. The same scholar had edited the epitome of the Laws, which under the title of Epinomis was received in the Platonic circle. 35. The episte j,—metaphysical_doctrix as the theory of Ideas, forms the central point in the 1 The new course that Plato certainly takes, shows itself in the peculiar fact, that in the Philebus expressions like gpas and dvdyynors have lost the specific sense which the earlier dialogues have given them. 2 Among others, the treatment also of the concept of pleasure which might be claimed to belong to Democritus. (See above.) 8 In this part a number of pedagogical and political discussions appear to have been sprinkled, which already could have belonged to the earlier sketch of the ideal state and supposably did belong to it. The details cannot be given here. 4 This interpolated piece begins with a discussion. In this discus- sion the experiences, which the philosopher underwent with the young tyrant at Syracuse, are made use of detail by detail. 190 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY Platonic philosophy. The root of this inspired conception KGSTEPISIO'S attempt to transcend the Protagorean doc- trine of relativity, whose validity for the world of sense and perception he recognized. By the help of the study of concepts after the Socratic method he tried to attain a safe and a universally valid science of the true essence of things, The final motive of this theory was, however, the ethical need of winning true virtue by true knowledge. The subjective point of departure ! was, for Plato as for Socrates, the conviction of the inefficiency of customary virtue. The virtue of custom, resting upon convention and prudential considerations, is unconscious of its fundamen- tal principle, and is exposed to the insecurity of change and opinions. Plato showed to Sophistry? that it with its pleasure theory took the popular point of view for its own, and he found the reason for this in the fact that Sophis- try renounced all real knowledge, and therefore could find no fundamental basis for virtue. In this sense Plato? Z purposely agreed with the Protagorean theory about the value_of sense inions based_on it. ( de was vigorous in asserting the relativity of such knowl- edge, and its inability to give us the true essence of things. pir precisely for that reason the ethical need drove Plato beyond Sophistry, and led him to fight Protagoras the more energetically with Protagoras’ own relativism. If there be virtue of any sort, it must rest on other than relative knowledge, which alone the-Sophists considered. But Socrates had, to the mind of Plato, shown us the way through conceptual science to this otlier knowledge which is independent of all accident of perception and 1 Especially Meno, 96 f£. Compare Phaedo, 82 a, and the Republic in different places. 2 Chiefly in the Gorgias. 8 All the points of view of the Sophistic epistemology are discussed thoroughly in the Thecetetus. MATERIALISM AND IDEALISM 191 opinion. The methodical development of this postulate was called by Plato the Dialectic! Its object is on the one hand to find individual concepts (cuvaywyn), and then to establish the mutual relations of these concepts by division (Staipecis, Téuve). Plato used the Socratic induction in the main.in finding the concepts, and supplemented tliis by hypothetical discussions in testing and verifying the con- cepts. These hypothetical discussions-draw out all the consequences from the constructed concept, and thus bring it to the touchstone? of fact. The dividing of these class concepts is the method which was introduced anew? by Plato with the intention of exposing the logical relations between concepts; and therefore connected with this pro- cess of dividing there are investigations concerning the compatibility and incompatibility of concepts, i. e., concern- ing the principle of disjunction.* As the last goal of dialectic, there appeared withal A LOGICAL SYSTEM OF CON- cepts, arranged according to their relations of co-ordina- tion and subordination. Herbart, De Plat. systematis fundamento, Vol. XIT. 61 f.; 8. Ribbing, Genetische Darstellung von Platons Ideenlehre (Leipzig, 1863-64) ; H. Cohen, Die plat. Ideenlehre (Zeitschr. J. Vélkerpsych. u. Sprachwissench. 1866); H. v. Stein, Sieben Bucher zur Geschichte des Plat. (Gott., 1862-75, 3 vols.) ; A. Peipers, Untersuchungen tiber das System Plat., Vol. I. (The epistemology of Plato, examined with especial reference 1 Phedr , 265 f.; Rep., 511 £; ihid., 533.: Phileb., 16. 2 Meno, 86; Phed., 101; Rep., 5384. The Parmenides similarly (135 f.) ; but applies the Platonic principle in the spirit of the fruitless antinomy of the Eleatic Sophists. 8 Phileb., 16. 4 Particularly Phed., 102 f. 5 In their method, the Parmenides, Sophist, and Politicus stand entirely on Platonic ground by their happy and logically sharp turns. The application, however, that they make of the method seems a juve- nile attempt at independent development rather than an ironical auto- caricature by Plato. 192 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY to the Thewtetus) (Leipzig, 1874); Onotologia platonica (Leipzig, 1883). The Protagorean doctrine of relativity is for Plato not only an object of polemic, but, as in the case of Democritus, is an inte- gral part of his system. This will become more evident as we proceed. Skepticism of the senses is the mighty corner-stone of both these systems of rationalism. On the other hand, the ethical point of view of Plato carried with it the attitude — and herein that of Democritus was also one with it — that it could not ascribe to the Sophistic doctrine of pleasure even the worth of a relatively valid moment. ‘This was at least the doctrine in the first draft of the theory of the Ideas, although later, especially G oo Plato’s conception was in this somewhat changed Direct, logical, or methodological investigations were not yet made by Plato, at least not in his writings. On the contrary, one finds numerous isolated statements scattered through his dialogues. In practical treatment the synagogic method out- weighs by far the dieretic. Only the Sophist and Politicus give examples of the dieretic method, and these are indeed very unfortunate examples. Hypothetical discussions of concepts, however, grew to a fruitful principle in the scientific theories of the Older Academy (§ 37). These concepts include a kind of knowledge that is very different in origin and content from that founded on per. ception. In perception there comes into consciousness the world of change and appearance. Conception gives us the permanent Essence of things (ovcia). The objective con- ' tent of conceptual knowledge is the Idea. If true knowl- edge — thus Plato followed the Socratic ideal — is supposed tq be given in the concepts, then this must be a knowledge of what really is.1 As, therefore, the relative truth of sense perception consists in its translating thé changing relations that spring up in the process of Becoming, so the absolute truth of conceptual knowledge (that of Dia- lectic) consists in the fact_that it conceives in the Ideas \ the true Being, independent of every change. So two dif- \ ferent worlds correspond to the two ways of knowing: a 1 Theet., 188; Rep., 476 f. MATERIALISM AND IDEALISM 193 world of true reality, the Ideas, the object of conceptual knowledge ; and a world of relative actuality, the things that conte anti go, the objects 0 5 e predicates of the Eleatic Being belong therefore to the Idea as the object of true knowledge, adré xa’ airo pel” avtov wovoedes dei dy ;? it is unchangeable, obSé wor’ ovdauij ovdauas aGrXowaow ovdcpiav évdéxeras.® The perceivable individual things, on the contrary, constitute the Heracleitan flux of continuous origination, change, and destruction. The fundamental principle of the metaphysical epistemol- ogy of Plato is this: Two worRLDs must be distinguished,! one of which és and never becomes, the other of which be- comes and never ts ; one is the object of the reason (vonats), the other is the object of sense (alcOno.). Since, now, the objects are as completely separated (ywpis) as the’ methods of knowing are distinct, the Ideas stand as incor-, poreal forms (doopara e/dn) in contrast to material things, which are perceived by the senses. The Ideas, which are -never to be found® in space or in matter, which indeed exist. purely for themselves (edAsepuvés), which are to be grasped ® not by the senses but only by thought, form an intel- — ligible world in themselves (romos vontds). A rational ° theory of knowledge requires an immaterialistic meta-_) physics. This immaterialism was the peculiarly original creation of Plato. Where in the earlier systems, not excluding that of Anaxagoras, the discussion turned upon the spiritual as the distinctive principle, nevertheless the principle always appeared as a peculiar kind of corporeal actuality. Plato, on the other hand, first discovered a purely spiritual world. The theory of Ideas is, therefore, an entirely new mediation of the Eleatic and the Heracleitan metaphysic, employing the 1 This view is stated most clearly in Timeus, 27 f., 57f. Compare Rep., 509 f., 533. 2 Symp., 211. ® Phedo, 78. ; 4 Tim., 27d. 5 Symp., 211. 6 Rep., 507; Tim., 28. 13 194 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY opposition between the Protagorean and Socratic theories of knowledge. Precisely for this reason, in the Theetetus, Plato brought the Sophistic theory of perception into closer relation- ship to the wdvra fet than the Sophist himself had brought it. On the other hand, the close relationship of the Socratic episte- mology to the Eleatic doctrine of Being had already been recog- nized by the Megarians (§ 28). The positive metaphysic of Plato may be characterized, therefore, as immaterialistic Eleati- cism.’ Therein consists its ontological character (Deuschle). It cognizes Being in Ideas, and relegates Becoming to a lower form of knowing. The neo-Pythagorean-neo-Platonic conception was an en- tire misunderstanding of Plato. According to this concep- tion, Ideas possess no independent actuality, but are only thought-forms supposed to exist in the divine mind. Through the neo-Platonism of the Renaissance, and even down to the beginning of this century, this interpretation of Plato obtained. Herbart was of great service in his opposition to it (Hinleit. in d. Philos., § 144 f.; Vol. I. 240 f.). Consistent with the theory of two worlds, as the central point in Platonism, is the manner in which Plato repre- sented our cognition of Ideas in particular. The primary function of the Ideas is to set forth the logical character of the class concepts, to reveal the com- mon qualities (7d xowdv) of the particulars which the class concepts comprehend, They are, in the Aristotelian phraseology, the év él woAAdv.2 But Plato regarded the process of thought, not as analysis, nor as an abstraction by comparison, but as rather a synoptic intuition? of reality presented in single examples. The Idea cannot be con- / tained in its perceived phenomenon. It is of another sort, and cannot'be found in appearance. In other words, ma- terial _things do_not include the Idea, but are only the “1 The relative pluralistic character of the theory of Ideas is in con- trast to original Eleaticism. It did not, as in the earlier attempts at mediation, arise from the need of an explanation of Becoming, but from the circumstance that conceptual knowledge can and must refer toa manifold of independent content-determinations. 2 Met., I. 9, 990 b, 6. 8 Phedr., 265; Rep., 537. MATERIALISM AND IDEALISM 195 copies or shadows! of it. Therefore the perceptions can-. not include the Ideas as separable integral parts, but are, on the contrary, only the occasions for the apprehension of that Idea that is similar to the perceptions but not identi- cal with them. Since the Idea cannot be created by re- flection, it must be regarded as an original possession of the soul which the soul remembers when it sees its copy in the_sense world. The recognition of the ideas is dvd- pono? In the mythical representation in the Phewdrus, Plato presupposes that the human soul has gazed upon the Idea with its supersensible faculties, — those related to the world of Ideas, — before its entrance into earthly life, but it remembers them only upon the perception of correspond- ing phenomena. Thereby out of the painful feeling of astonishment at the contrast between the Idea and its phenomenon is created the philosophic impulse, the long- ing love for the.supersensible Idea. This love is the épws,3 which conducts it back from the transitoriness of sense to the immortality of the ideal world.* There is an interesting parallel between the intuitive character, which the recognition of I in Plato possesses, and the youn yvnoin of Democritus. In Plato also analogies to optical impressions predominate. Both Democritus and Plato have in mind immediate knowledge of the pure forms (idéa.), the abso- lutely actual ® which is attained wholly apart from sense percep- 1 Rep., 514 £.; Phedo, 78. 2 Meno, 80 f.; Phedr., 249 £.; Phedo, 72 f. 3 Phedr., 250 f., and especially Symp., 200 f. 4 The theory of the gpws takes on thereby in the Symposium a more uni- versal aspect of beholding the living principle of all Becoming (yéveors) in the desire for the Idea (ove/a), and so prepares the way for the teleo- logical interpretation of Ideas. 5 One has the same right to speak of “ sensualism ” in Plato as in Democritus. Both explain true knowledge of the dvrws 8v as the recep- tion of the {3a by the soul, not as an act of sense perception, although as illustrated by the analogy to optical perception. 196 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY tion. The exposition of this teaching appears in Plato (Phedrus. and Symposium) in mythical form. For since it is a question of the time-process of the knowledge of the eternal, of the genesis of the intuition of the Absolute, a dialectic presentation is not possible. Since the Ideas are hypostasized class-concepts, in their first draft there are for Plato as many Ideas as there are class concepts or general names for different perceptual things. There are, therefore, Ideas of all that is in any wise thinkable,! — Ideas of things, qualities and relations, of products of art and nature, of the good and of the bad, of the high and of the low2 The later dialogues (Sympo- sium, Phoedo, Timeus) speak only of such Ideas as have an inherent value, such as the good and the beautiful; of such as correspond to nature products, like fire, snow, etc. ; and, finally, of mathematical relations, like great and small, unity and duality. Aristotle reports that Plato in later time did no longer recognize Ideas of artifacts, negations, and relations, and that he held, in place of these, essentially nature class-concepts.2 An exacter determination of the circle within which the philosopher, especially in different periods of his development, extended or wished to extend his theory of Ideas, cannot be made. In general the chronological order of the dialogues indicates that Plato originally constructed a world of Ideas according to his logical and epistemological view of class concepts. In the course of time, however, he came more and more to seek in this supersensible world the highest values and the fundamental onto- logical forms, according to which the sense world of Becoming is modelled. From the world of Ideas there thus arose an 1 Rep., 596. 2 For particular proofs, consult Zeller, II. 585 f. The dialogue Parmenides proves with fine irony to the “ young Socrates’? that he must accept also the Ideas of hair, mud, etc. (130f.). In as late a writing as the middie part of the Republic, Plato used the Ideas of bed, etc , to illustrate his theory. ® Met., XI. 3, 1070 a, 18, MATERIALISM AND IDEALISM 197 ideal world. The norms of value thus took the place of class concepts. The ethical motive became more and more influen- tial in his philosophy, as appears also in what follows. The more thoroughly the theory of Ideas in their first draft distinguished the two worlds from each other, the more difficult it became to determine the relation of the things of sense to their respective Ideas. The characteristic of this relation most frequently given in the dialogues Meno, Theetetus, Phedrus, and Symposium, and likewise in the Phedo, is similarity. This is consistent with the thought which the philosopher developed in those same dialogues concerning the origin of concepts; for similarity forms the psychological ground through which,! stimulated by percep- tion, the recollection of the Idea is said to come. Similar- ity,? however, is not equivalence. The Idea never appears fully in the things, and accordingly Plato designated the relationship of the two as puiunows*. The Idea is thus » regarded 5 as the original (Urbild) (rapdSerypa), the sensed object as the copy (Abdild) ( #9 J atrtov ovx dy ror’ etn airtov. 202 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY things. This thought was peculiar to the first draft of the theory of Ideas, and it got new support and significance in Plato’s tendency toward Pythagoreanism which set the perfect and imperfect worlds in opposition to each other. The more, however, the world of Ideas became the ideal world, the perfect Being or the kingdom of Worth, the less could it be viewed as the cause of imperfection in the world of sense. The world of imperfection could rather only be sought in the thing that has no Being. For the sense world as eternally “ becoming” has part not only in that which has Being (the Ideas), but also in that which has no Being (uy 6v).1 Empty space? was re- garded as having no Being by Plato as by the Eleatics. Plato moreover regarded empty space, like the Pythago- reans, as in itself formless and unfashioned, and precisely for that reason as pure? negation (ordpyow) of Being. But the formless is capable of all possible forms, and retains them by virtue of mathematical determinations. In this sense the Philebus4 makes the Pythagorean fundamental opposition a part of his teleological metaphysic, in that he defined as the two first principles of the world of experi- ence the dzrepov (endless formless space) and the épas (the mathematical limitation and formation of that space). Out of the union of the two the world of the individual things of sense appears, and the fourth and highest prin- ciple forms the basis of this “mixing.” This principle is the aria, the Idea of the Good, or the cosmic reason, the vous. 1 Rep., 477 a 2 That the py dv which is designated in the Philebus as the dme:pov and in the Timeus (§ 37) as deEapevn, exuayetov, etc., is space, Zeller has proved (III%. 605 £.; see also H. Siebeck, Untersuchungen, 49 f.):. On this account the word “matter” has been avoided, lest it imply its unavoidable subordinate meaning, “ unformed stuff.” ‘‘Unformed stuff,” the day of Aristotle, had not yet had its meaning determined by Plato. 3 Compare Arist. Phys., I. 9, 192 a, 6. * Phileb., 23 £. MATERIALISM AND IDEALISM 203 Mathematics, whose importance for the dialectic has been emphasized above, had an ontological importance also in Plato’s, system. Mathematical forms are the link by means of which the Idea sliapes, space teleologically into the sense world. 1 Here for the-fit {the position which the philosopher assigns this science in connection with his epistemology. Mathe- matics is a knowledge not of the phenomenal world but of the permanent world. For that reason in the carlier dialogues it seems to have been used only for dialectic ? purposes. Its objects, however, especially geometrical objects, have still something of sense in them, which distinguishes them from the Ideas in the later evaluation of the Ideas. Therefore mathematics belongs, according to the schema of the Republic (309 f., 523 f.) not to the Sdééa (the knowledge of yéveots), but to vdnors (the knowledge of oiofa). Within oicia it is to be distinguished as Sidvoia from the peculiar émioryjuy, the knowledge of the Idea of the Good. Mathematics appears, then, in the education of the ideal state as the highest preparation for philosophy, but only as preparation. Concerning Plato as a mathematician, his introduction of definitions and the analytic method, see Cantor, Geschichte der Mathematik, I. 183 f. In his latter days Plato borrowed from the Pythagorean number theory the principle by which he hoped for a systematic presentation and articulation of the world of Ideas. Logical investigations? toward this end were given up as soon as from the teleological principle the Idea of the Good had been placed at the head. The Pythagorean method of developing concepts according to the number series commended itself to him. In adopting this method, Plato 1 A good parallel exists also here between Plato and Democritus, although in the latter’s theory in the place of the teleological airia of the Philebus stood the dvayky (% Tov dAdyou kai ein Svvayis Kal Ta omy ervxev, Phileb., 28 d), and although the xévoy and the oyrpara (the ?8éae of Plato) produce the sense world. In view of this, one can see in the exposition in the Philebus, 23-26, a reference to Demo- critus, whose teaching this dialogue appears to have used in other places (§ 33). 2 The Meno shows how we can know Ideas by geometrical examples (Pythagorean doctrine). 8 Sophist, especially 254 f. 204 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY also symbolized single Ideas by ideal numbers. The ele- ments of the Ideas are the dzrespov and the zrépas in analogy to the principles laid down for the sense world in the Phile- bus. The dzrepov has here the significance of “ intelligible space.” ! Out of the & which he identified? with the Idea of the Good, he derived all other Ideas, as a graded series of conditioning and conditioned (aporepov Kai borepov). Traces of this senile attempt are to be found in the Philebus and the Laws. In other respects we are instructed only by Aristotle concerning these dypanta Sdypata: Met., I. 6, XII. 4 f.; compare A. Trendelenburg, Plat. de ideis et numeris doc- trina ex Arist. ilustrata (Leipzig, 1826), and Zeller, II*. 567-f. 86. Measured by its first motive, Plato’s theory of Ideas is an outspoken ethical metaphysic. Consequently Ethics was the philosophical science which he chiefly and most fruitfully built upon. Among the Ideas that the dialectic undertook to develop, social norms had a prominent place. The immaterialism of the double-world theory necessarily involved an ascetic morality that was very uncharacteristic of Greek thought. The Thectetus,? for example, sets up an ideal of retirement from the world for the philosopher who, since earthly life is full of evil, finds refuge as quickly as possible in the divine presence. The Phedo* further develops this negative ethics in all its details. It pictures the whole life of the philosopher as already a dying, a puri- fication of the soul from the dross of sense existence. The soul in the body is, as it were, in prison, and it can free itself only by knowledge and virtue. This view, which is particularly like that of the Pythag- oreans among the ancient moral theories, took in the metaphysical theory of Ideas a special form, by virtue of which the psychological basis was created also for 1 Compare H Siebeck, Untersuchungen, 97 f. 2 Aristox. Elem. harm., II. 30. 8 172,176 £. * 64 £, MATERIALISM AND IDEALISM 205 the positive ethics of Plato. In the theory of the two worlds the soul must take a peculiar intermediary position, —a theory that could be developed not without difficulties and contradictions. On account of its ideal character the soul must be capable of conceiving the Ideas, and on this account must be related to them! The soul belongs to the supersensible world, and should have all the qualities of that world, — non-origination, indestructibility, unity, and changelessness. But since it is the carrier of the Idea of life? and as cause of motion is itself eternally movable, it isnot identical to the Ideas, but very similar to them.? Therefore for Plato it had pre-existence and lasted beyond the earthly body. Yet in that changeless timelessness of Being which belongs to the Ideas it has likewise only a share, since it also belongs to yéveous but it is not identi- cal with the Ideas. On the other hand, the Socratic prin- ciple required that the soul’s goodness and badness must not be attributed. to external fate, but to the soul itself.* Since its essence, related as it is to the world of Ideas, cannot be answerable for a bad decision, its higher nature must be considered as deformed by the temporary incli- nations of the senses. Hence the theory of the three “parts” ® of the soul. This theory, although represented mythically in the Phedrus (consistent with its subject matter), became in the Republic an entirely dogmatic basis of ethics. There is the part that is related to the Ideas, the directing, reasoning part (qycwovxov, AoyioTiKov). Then there are the two passionate (affektvolle) parts. One is the nobler: it is the strong activity of will (@uu0s, @upo- evdés). The other, less noble, consists of sensuous appetites (érvOupntixov, diroxypyparov). These three parts appear in the Phedrus and the Republic as the Forms (ei) of 1 Phedo, 78 f. 4 Tbid., 105 d. 3 Suotorarov; ibid., 80 b. 4 Rep., 617 £. 5 bid. 611 £. 6 Phaedrus, 246 £. 206 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY activity of the soul in its unity. Hence in the Phedrus, also, the soul that is described there as a unity, unites in itself in the next life all the functions that in the dialogues are ascribed to its three parts." The myths of the Timeus for the first time expressly speak of the wépy, of which the soul is composed, and treat the parts as separable, in such a way that one part, the vods,? is immortal, the others mortal, Jas. Steger, Plat. Studien, III.; Die plat. Psychologie (Innsbruck, 1872); P. Wildauer, Die Psy. des Willens, II. (Innsbruck, 1879); H. Sieheck, Gesch. der Psy., I. 1, 187 £.; Schulthess, Plat. Forschungen (Bonn, 1875). Plato’s psychology was by no means only a result of his theory of nature, but was a metaphysical presupposition for it, resting upon ethical and epistemological motives. This is shown in the beginning of the myth in the Zimeus. Pre- existence is supposed to explain our knowledge about Ideas (by évauvnots), and on the other hand to explain our guilt, on account of which the supersensible soul is bound in an earthly body (see myth in Phedrus). The post-existence of the soul, on the other hand, makes possible not only the striving of the soul to reach beyond earthly life after a completer identification with the world of Ideas, but above all it makes possible moral recompense. Thereupon Plato illuminated this teaching every- where by mythical representations of judgment at death, of wanderings of souls, ete. (see Gorgias, Republic, Phaedo). Con- sequently, however weak the proofs may be which Plato had adduced for individual immortality, yet his absolute belief in it is one of the chief points of his teaching. Of the arguments on which he founded this belief, the most valuable is that wherein he (Phedo, 86 f.) contended against the Pythagorean definition of the soul as the harmony of the body by the proof of the soul’s substantial independence through its control over the body.? His weakest argument is that in which the Phedo 1 In the Phedrus that previous determination of the soul is ascribed to the sense appetites, which explains the errors of earthly life. In the Pheedo, the fortunes of the soul after death are made dependent on the adherence of its sensuality. Pre-existence and post-existence are ascribed in both cases to the whole soul. 2 Tim., 69 f. 8 The Mendelssohn copy of the Phedo (Berl. 1764) especially raises this point in the spirit of the philosophy of the Enlightenment. MATERIALISM AND IDEALISM 207 sums up and crowns all the other arguments: a dialectic sub- reption from the double meaning of the word é@dvaros, in which the soul is explained as immortal because it can exist in no other way than as a living thing (Phedo, 105 f.).. Compare K. F. Hermann, De immortalitatis notione in Plat. Phadone (Marburg, 1835); id. de partibus anime immortalibus (Gitt., 1850); K. Ph. Fischer, Plat. de immortalitate anime doctrina (Erlangen, 1845); P. Zimmermann, Die Unsterblichkeit der ee in Plat. Phed. (Leipzig, 1869); G. Teichmiiller, Studien, I. 107 f. The relationship of the three parts to the essence of the soul is very difficult, and is not made perfectly clear. Plato main- tains clearly, on the whole, the unity of the soul, but only in a few places particularly emphasizes it. On the one hand, the Phedrus makes all the three parts belong to the essence of the individual, in order to make conceivable the fall of the soul in its pre-existence. On the other hand, it appears as if both the lower parts originated in the union of soul and body, and on that account again were stripped off entirely from the true essence of the soul (vots) after a virtuous life (Rep., 611; Phedo, 83). The abrupt and direct opposition of the two worlds made this troublesome point in his system (Rep., 435 f.). So also the specific psychological meaning of the three parts, whose origin is made clear by ethical evaluation, is undetermined. In spite of some similarities, this division is in no wise identical with the present-day psychology and its customary triple division into ideas, sensations, and desires. For the aic@yoas did not, according to Plato, belong to the Aoyoredy, but must, although he has not expressly stated it, be ascribed to both the other parts. On the other hand, there belong to the vois not only the knowledge of Ideas, but also the virtuous determination of the will, which, according to Socrates, corresponds to that knowledge. We come nearest to the Platonic thought when we think of the life of the soul as ordered into three different degrees of worth. Each degree has its own theoretic and practical functions in such a way that the lower functions may exist without the higher, but the higher appear — at least in this life—in con- nection with the lower. So plants have émiOupyrixdv (Tim., 77; Rep., 441); animals have Ouoedés in addition to emeBypantursy 5 and men have, besides these two functions, the AoywrriKov- The yots is localized in the brain, @vpds in the heart, and érOupio in the liver.? : In the application of this to ethnography, he claimed for the 1 Agreeing with Democritus. 208 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY Greeks the excellence of Aoy:orixdy (Republic, 435 e), allowed to the warlike barbarians of the north the predominance of Ovuds, and to the weak barbarians of the south that of émGupia. Upon the basis of this psychological theory, Plato went beyond not only the abstract simplicity of the Socratic theory of virtue, but also the ascetic one-sidedness of his own first negative statements. That moral conduct alone makes man truly blessed 1 in this or the other life,? is his fundamental conviction. But even if he was inclined to find this true happiness only in the most complete perfec- tion of the soul, in which happiness the soul is a sharer in the divine world of Ideas; and even if therefore he refused 2 as unworthy of the soul every utilitarian principle of con- ventional ethics, yet he recognized other kinds of happiness as justifiable moments of the HigHEst Goop. These kinds of happiness are all which, in the entire sweep of the soul’s activities, appear as true and noble joys. The Philebus4 develops such a graded series of goods. Plato contended also, in this dialogue, against the theory that would find the rédos® only in sense pleasure. But against the view of those who explain all pleasure as only illusory, he held fast to the reality of a pure and painless sense-pleasure,® and he contended against the one-sided view that sought true hap- piness only in insight.” But while he on the other hand recognized the legitimacy of intellectual pleasure, he laid claim to it not only for rational knowledge (vovs), but also for correct ideas in every science and art.® Above all this, however, he set the participation in ideal evaluations and 1 Rep., 353 f. 2 Compare entire conclusion of Rep., Books IX., X. 8 Rep., 362; Theet., 176; Pheedo, 68 f. 4 See Laws, 717 f., 728 £. 5 As already seen in Gorgias. 6 Supposably Democritus. 7 These statements could be aimed just as well against Antisthenes, Euclid, or Democritus (Phileb., 21, 60). 8 Phileb., 62 £. MATERIALISM AND IDEALISM 209 their actualization in individual activity.1 All the beauty and vitality of Greece was amalgamated here in the tran- scendental ideal of the philosopher, and a similar union of the two sides of reality was already suggested in the series of objects which the Symposium? develops as the working of the épws. A. Trendelenburg, De Plat. Philebus consilio (Berlin, 1837) ; Fr. Susemihl, Ueber die Giitertafel im Philebus (Philol. 1863) ; R. Hirzel, De bonis in fine Philebi enumeratis (Leipzig, 1868). However, Plato founded the development of his theory of virtue in a still more systematic way upon his triple divisions of the soul. While his first dialogues took pains to reduce the single virtues to the Socratic cides of knowl- edge, the later dialogues proceeded upon the theory of the distinct independence and the respective limitations of the particular virtues. In so far ‘as the one or the other part of the soul preponderates in different men according to their dispositions? are they suited to developing one or another virtue. For every part of the soul has its own perfection, which is called its virtue and is grounded in its essence. Accordingly Plato constructed a group of four cardinal virtues which at that time were beginning to be frequently mentioned in literature. There is the virtue of wisdom (codia) corresponding to the #yenovsxor ;_ that of will-power (avdpia), corresponding to the @uyoedés ; that of self-control (swppocvvn), corresponding to the érvOupnriov. Finally, since the perfection of the whole soul consists® in the right relations of the single parts, in the fulfilment of the soul’s particular task through every one of these parts (ra éavtod mpatrew), and in the regulative control of 1 Phileb., 66 £. 2 Symp., 208 f. 3 Rep., 410 f. 4 Rep., 441 £. 5 In the entire Republic the ascetic thought of stripping off the lower parts of the soul is entirely put aside. 14 210 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY reason over the two other parts,! so we have as a fourth virtue that of an equable arrangement of the whole. This last is called by Plato dccaroovvy.? The last term, which is scarcely understandable from the point of view of individual ethics, arises from the peculiar derivation which Plato has given to these virtues in the Republic. Loyal to the motive of the theory of Ideas, the Platonic ethics sketched not so much the ideal of. the individual as that of the species; it pictured less the perfect man than the perfect society. The Platonic ethics is primarily social ethics. It does not treat of the happi- ness of the individuals, but that of the whole,? and this happiness can be reached only in the perfect state. The ethics of Plato perfected itself in his teaching of the ideal state. K. F. Hermann, Die historischen Elemente des platonischen Idealstaates (Gesch. Abhandi., 132 f.); Ed. Zeller, Der plat. Staat in seiner Bedeutung fiir die Folgezeit (Vortrdge und Abhandl., I. 62f.); C. Nohle, Die Staatslehre Plat.’s in threr geschichtlichen Entwickelung (Jena, 1880). Whatever* may be the natural and historical origin of the state, its task is the same everywhere, according to Plato: viz., so to direct the common life of man that all may be happy through virtue. The task can be accom- 1 Since already awpocvvy is possible only through the right rule of the appetites, cwPpocdvn and Sixavoovvn are not mutually exclusive. Compare Zeller, II8. 749 f. 2 The most usual verbal translation, justice, concerns only the politi- cal, not the moral spirit of the case. Righteousness does not fully state the Platonic meaning. * Precisely on that account the philosopher must share in public life, even if he would find his happiness only in his turning from the earthly and in his devotion to the divine. See above; also Rep., 519 f. 4 The first book of the Republic develops critically the views of the Sophists on this point. How far in the representation of the genesis of the state, given in the second book (369 f.), positive and negative analogies appear, cannot be discussed here. MATERIALISM AND IDEALISM 211 plished only by ordering all the relations of society accord- ing to the principles of man’s moral nature. The perfect state is divided into three distinct parts, like the soul of man. There are the producers, the warriors, and the admin- istrators. The great mass of citizens (Sjyos; yewpyol Kai Snutovpyot), corresponding to the émiuyntixov or pido- xpyuarov, are entrusted with providing for the material foundation of the life of the state by caring for its daily needs ; and they are prompted to make this provision by their own sensuous appetites. The warriors and officials (émixoupot), corresponding to the Ovpoeds in the unselfish fulfilment of duty, have to guard the state externally by repelling invasion, internally by executing the laws. The rulers, finally (dpyovres), corresponding to Aoeyortixov or nyepovexov, determine, according to their insight, the legis- lation and the principles of administration. The perfection however of the entire state— its “virtue” —is justice (Stxatoavvn),) that every one may get his right. Justice consists in these three classes having their proper distribu- tion of power, while at the same time every one fulfils his own peculiar task. Therefore the rulers must have the highest culture and wisdom (codgia), the warriors an undaunted devotion to duty (avdpia), and the people an obedience which curbs the appetites(cappocvvn). The constitution of the ideal state for Plato is an aristoc- racy in the strictest sense of the word. It is a rule of the best, —the wise and virtuous. It places all legislation and the entire direction of society in the hand of the class of the scientifically cultured (¢sAdcodor).2, The task of the 1 Therefore the corresponding virtue of the individual, the ethical equilibrium of the parts of his soul, is designated by the same name. 2 Thus must the celebrated sentence (Rep., 473 d) be understood. There will be no end to the sorrow of man until the philosophers (the scientifically cultured) rule or the rulers are philosophers (are scientifi- cally cultured). 212 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY second class is to execute practically the orders of the highest class, and to maintain the state and preserve its interests both internally and externally. The mass of mankind have to work and obey. Since, however, the object of the state does not consist in the securing of any merely outward benefit, but in the virtue of all its citizens, Plato demanded that the individ- ual should merge himself entirely in the state, and that the state should embrace and determine the entire life of its citizens. Plato thus went beyond the political principle of the Greeks. The development which this idea found in the social organization of the vodteia was restricted, nevertheless, to the two higher classes, which were taken together under the name of “ guardians” (¢vAa«es). For the mass of the dios there is accessible no virtue founded on knowledge, but only the conventional virtue of society, which is enforced by the strict execution of the laws and attained through utilitarian considerations. The Platonic politics leaves therefore the third class to itself. In its desire for acquisition, this class is moved by a fundamen- tally sensuous motive; and it performs its duty when by its labor it furnishes the material foundation for the life of the state,and yields to the guidance of the “ guardians.” But the prenatal and present life of the “ guardians” are to be controlled by the state. Impressed by the importance of the propagation of the species, Plato would not leave marriage to the voluntary action of the individual, but de- cided that the rulers of the state should provide for the right constitution of the following generation by a fitting choice of parents! Education of the youth in all depart- ments belongs to the state, and gives equal attention to bodily and spiritual development. In the latter it pro- gresses from folk-lore and myths through elementary instruction to poetry and music, and thence through math- 1 Rep., 416 b. MATERIALISM AND IDEALISM 213 ematical training to interest in philosophy, and, finally, to the knowledge of the Idea of the Good. In the different steps of this education, which is the same for all the chil- dren of the two higher classes, those children are pruned out by the state officials that no longer seem to show fitness of disposition and development for the higher'tasks. Dif- ferent grades of officials and warriors are thus formed from these. This sifting process leaves ultimately the élite, who succeed to the position of archons and dedicate their lives partly to the furthering of science and partly to the admin- istration of the state. Herein are the two upper classes a great family ; every form of private possession is renounced,! and their external wants are cared for by the state support, which is furnished by the third class. The Platonic state was accordingly to be an institution for the education of society. Its highest aim was to pre- pare man by the sensible for the supersensible world, by the earthly for the divine life. The social-religious ideal is that which floats before the philosopher in his methodical delineation of the “ best” state. As all the higher interests of man will be included by this social community of life, so the philosopher believed that the state should have exclu- sive control not only of education and science but also of art and religion. Only that art shall be allowed whose imitative? activity is directed upon the Ideas, especially the Idea of the Good.2 The Greek xadoxdyaOia consisted in the evaluation of everything beautiful as good. Plato reversed the order of this thought by establishing only the good as the really beautiful. In the same way the ideal state accepts in the main the myths and the culture of the Greek state religion as educational material for the third class of society, and partly also for the second class, espe- cially in childhood. But the state expunges from the \ Rep., 416 b. 2 Tbid., 313. 8 [bid., 376 f. 4 [bid., 369 f£. 214 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY myths all things immoral and ambiguous, and permits their use only as the symbolical representations of ethical truths. The religion of the philosophers, however, consists in sci- ence and virtue, of which the highest goal is the attainment of likeness to the Idea of the Good, — the Godhead. Plato did not conceive his city as an imaginary Utopia, but in all earnestness as a practicable ideal. He employed therefore in many particulars, especially in social arrangements, numerous features of the then existing Greek states, and he preferred, natu- rally enough, the stricter and more aristocratic ordinances of the Doric race. ‘Though he was convinced that out of the existing circumstances his ideal could be realized only through force,! yet he had none the less faith that if his proposal were tried, he would bestow upon his citizens lasting content, and would make them strong and victorious against all foreign attack. In the incomplete dialogue, Critias, the philosopher tried to develop this thought,— that the state founded on culture should show itself superior to the Atlantis, the state founded on mere ex- ternal power. An idealizing of the Persian wars probably floats before him. The description is broken off at the very beginning, and there is wonderful similarity in the picture of the Atlantis to the institutions of former American civilizations. As to details, we should make a comparison of the Republic with all of Plato’s other writings. The Politicus offers many similar thoughts, but with the interweaving of much that is foreign, and it has predilection for monarchical forms of govern- ment. It deviates from the Republic, especially in its theory of the different kinds of constitutions, contrasting three worse forms with three better.2 The kingdom is contrasted to the tyranny, the aristocracy to the oligarchy, the constitutional to the lawless democracy. Inexact sketches are drawn of the seventh, or best, state in contrast to these. In the Republic,® Plato used his psychology to show how the worse constitutions come from the deterioration of the ideal states. These are the timocracy in which the ambitious rule, the predominance of the Ovpoedés ; the oligarchy in which the avaricions rule, the pre- dominance of the éribuuyrixdy 3 the democracy or realm of uni- versal license ; and, finally, the tyranny or the unfettering of the most disgraceful arbitrary power. The aristocratic characteristics of the Platonic state corre- spond not only to the personal convictions of Plato and his 1 Rep., 540 d. 2 Polit., 302 £. 3 Rep., 545 f. MATERIALISM AND IDEALISM 215 great teacher, but are developed necessarily from the thought that scientific culture can be obtained only by the very few. In scientific culture is the highest virtue of man, and his only title to political administration (Gorgias). Likewise, the exclu- sion of all non-intellectual labor from the two directing classes is consistent with the universal Greek prejudice against the proletariat. However, it is justified by Plato in the reflection that all true labor presupposes love for its task, or brings love with it; and accordingly, that all manual work necessarily lowers the soul to the sensuous, and makes distant its supersensible goal. From the same motive came the exclusion of family life and private possessions. It is misleading to speak here of a communism. The community of wives, children, and goods is expressly delimited to the two higher classes. ‘This was not to satisfy a claim for universal equality, as was the case in the naturalistic investigations of radical Cynicism, but, on the contrary, to prevent private interest from interfering in any way with the devotion of the warrior and ruler to the welfare of the state. It is, in a word, a sacrifice made to the Idea of the Good. The peculiar character of the ethics of Plato, and at the same time its tendency to go beyond actual Greek life, consisted in the complete subordination of the individual life to the purpose of the political whole. In contrast to the degenerating Hellenic culture the philosopher held an ideal picture of political society, which could first actually be when the Platonic thought predom- inated: that all earthly life has value and meaning only as an education for a higher supersensible existence. To a certain - extent the hierarchy of the Middle Ages realized the Platonic state but with the priests in place of the philosophers. Other moments of the Platonic ideal — for example, the control of science by the state — have been realized also to some extent in the public measures of some modern nations. Concerning Plato’s theory of education see Alex. Kapp (Minden, 1833); E. Snethlage (Berlin, 1834); Volquardsen -(Berlin, 1860) ; K. Benrath (Jena. 1871); concerning his atti- tude toward art, K. Justi, Die esth. Elemente in der plat. Phi- los. (Marburg, 1869) ; concerning his attitude toward religion, F. Ch. Bauer, Das Christliche des Platonismus (Tiibingen, 18738). Compare, also, S. A. Byk, Hellenismus und Platonismus (Leipzig, 1870). Similarly Plato’s ethics also experienced as disadvan- tageous a later transformation in the Laws as his theoretic 216 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY philosophy in the lectures of his old age. In pessimistic! despair? as to the realization of his political ideal, the phi- losopher attempted to sketch a morally ordered community without the controlling influence of the theory of Ideas and its devotees. In the place of philosophy, on the one hand religion presented itself in a form much nearer to the national mode of thought, and on the other mathematics with its Pythagorean tendencies to music and astronomy. Philosophical culture was replaced by practical prudence 3 (dpovncts), and precise conformity to law and the Socratic virtue by a moderate dependence on ancient worthy cus- toms. Thus the state in the Republic changed, when it appeared in the later writings, into a mixture of monar- chico-oligarchic and democratic elements, —the ideal power into a compromise with historical conditions. Moreover, all this is set before us in a long-winded, unconcentrated presentation, which seems to be wanting the last finishing touches and the final redaction.* Just because the Laws give details of contemporaneous life, they are of high antiquarian, even if of very little philosophical value. They represent so great a deterioration, not only from the theory of Ideas, but from Plato’s entire idealistic thought, that the doubts which have been wisely put aside again as to their genuineness are yet entirely conceivable. Compare Th. Oncken, Staatslehre des Arist., 197 f.; E. Zeller, II*. 809 f.; the five essays by Th. Bergk, concerning the History of Greek Philosophy and Astronomy (Leipzig, 1883); E. Praetorius, De legibus Plat. (Bonn, 1884). 87. The epistemological dualism of the theory of Ideas allowed and demanded a dogmatic statement concerning ethical norms of human life, but no equivalent recognition 1 Laws, 644. The conviction as to the badness of the world grew up here to the extent of a belief in an evil world-soul, which works against the divine soul. Compare § 37. See Laws, 896 f. 2 Ibid., 739 £. 8 Ibid., 712, in exact antithesis to Rep., 473. 4 Ibid., 746 £. MATERIALISM AND IDEALISM 217 of nature phenomena. For although Plato had fully deter- mined that the tasks of metaphysics lay in regarding the Ideas and especially the Idea of the Good as the cause of the sense-world, that world nevertheless remained to him as before a realm of Becoming and Destruction. According. to the premises of his philosophy, this realm could never be the object of dialectic or true knowledge. The point of view of the theory of Ideas presupposes a teleological view of nature, but it offers no knowledge of nature. In his latter days, complying with the needs of his school, Plato drew natural science also within the realm of his research and theory, — which science he in the spirit of Socrates had earlier entirely avoided. He, nevertheless, remained always true to his earlier conviction, and empha- sized it with great clearness and sharpness at the beginning of the Zimeus, in which the result of these investigations was set down.! This was to the effect that there can be no émiotnun of the Becoming and destruction of things, but only siotis: no science, but only a probable conclusion. He claimed therefore for his theory of nature, not the value of truth, but only of probability. The presentations in the Timeus are only eixdtes wdOor, and, however closely related to his theory of Ideas, they nevertheless form no integral part of its metaphysics. Aug. Béckh. De Platonica corporis mundani fabrica (Heidel- berg, 1809) ; Untersuchungen iiber das kosmische System des Plat. (Berlin, 1852) ; H. Martin, Htudes sur le Timée (2 vols., Paris, 1841). Plato’s philosophy of nature stands, then, not in the same, but in a very similar relationship to the metaphysic of his theory of Ideas, as the hypothetical physics of Parmenides to his theory of Being. In both cases it seems to have been a regard for the needs 1 Tim., 28 £; which discussion, 27 d, begins with the recapitulation of the theory of the two worlds. The relation of the philosophy of nature to the theory of Ideas is characterized most exactly by sentence 29 c; ért wep mpos yéeveoty odcia, Todro mpds mictw ddjGea. 218 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY and wishes of the pupils that occasioned their descending from interest in permanent Being to an experimental interest in the changeable. Plato designated expressly this play with the cixdres pd0oe as the only permissible diversion from his dialectic, which was his life-work (Tim., 59 ¢.). Although a critical and often, indeed, polemical consideration of existing opinions ap- peared here, the formal moment of which Diels (Au/s. z. Zeller- Jub., 254f.) made of great importance in Parmenides, Plato took account of the fact that a school that had a school-membership of the organization and range of the Academy could not hold itself indefinitely aloof from natural science, and that such a school would be obliged finally to come to some terms or other.? While, however, upon the basis of the theory of Ideas a perfect knowledge of the comparative worth of the individual, society, and history could be obtained, yet the determination of the reality of nature through the Idea of the Good was not to be developed with equal certainty as to details. Suppose, then, physics and ethics to be the two wings of the Platonic edifice, the ethical wing is like the main portion of the edifice in style and material; the physics is, however, a lighter, temporary structure, and is merely an imitation of the forms of the other. That which pressed upon the philosopher and was treated by him with careful reserve was, remarkably enough, made of the greatest importance by his disciples in later centuries. The teleological physics of Plato was regarded through Hellenistic time and the entire Middle Ages as his most important achieve- ment, while the theory of Ideas was pressed more or less into the background. Relationships to religious conceptions are chiefly accountable for this, but still more the natural circum- stance that the school had an especial fondness for the more tangible and useful part of his teaching. This explains why already Aristotle (De an., I. 2, 404 b, 16) contended against the myths of the Timcus as though they were serious state- ments of doctrine. The basis for the myths of the Zimeus is the metaphys- ics of the Philebus. The sense world consists of infinite space, and the particular mathematical forms which that space had taken on in order to represent the Ideas. But conceptual knowledge cannot be given of the efficacy of these highest purposes. Consequently the Zimeus begins 1 Concerning the influence of Eudoxus, see H. Usener, Preuss. Jahrb., LITI. 15 f. MATERIALISM AND IDEALISM 219 by personifying this efficacy mythologically as the world- forming God, the Snysovpyés. It is purposeful force; it is good, and because of its good-will has made the world.} In the act of creation it had in view the Ideas, those pure unitary forms of which the world is a copy.2. The world is therefore the most perfect, best, and most beautiful,’ and since it is the product of divine reason and goodness, it is the only world. The perfectness of the one world which is reasserted with especial solemnity at the end of the Timcus. is a necessary requisite of the teleological basis of thought. The denial of the opposite proposition, that there are numberless worlds (Tim., 31a), appears as a polemic against Democritus, especially in connection with what immediately precedes (30 a). According to Democritus’ mechanical principle, the vortices arise here and there in the midst of chaotic motion, and out of these the worlds arise. According to Plato, the ordering God forms only one world, and that the most perfect. That, however, this world corresponds not perfectly with the Ideas, but only as closely as possible, is due to the second principle of the sense world, to space into which God has built the world. Space is known neither by thought® nor sense. It is neither a concept nor percept, Idea nor sense object. It is the yu7 éy or what possesses no Being, without which the évtws év could not appear, nor the Ideas ® be copied in sense things. It’ is the Evvaitiov in comparison to the true airsoy; and so also the things formed in it in the individual processes of the world are Evvairia.® They forma natural necessity (avdyxn) ° beside 1 Tim., 29 c 2 Ibid., 30 ¢. 8 The teleological motive of the teaching of Anaxagoras, which was accepted already in the Phedo, forms one of the fundamental teachings of the Timeus. 4 Tim., 30 a, 46 c. 5 Tbid., 52. * Which are midway between Being and not-Being. Rep., 477 £. 7 Tim., 68 e, meaning a second kind of airia. 8 Ibid. 46; Phedo, 96 f. 9 Tim., 48 a, another term used completely in Democritan sense. 220 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY the divine reason, which necessity under certain circum- stances stands in the way of the teleological activity of the divine reason. Space! (yapa, Té7ros) is that wherein the cosmic process comes to pass (éxelvo év @ yiyvetat) which takes on all bodily forms (dvcus Ta rdvta capata dexopuévn, also the % Se£auevy or brodoyy Ths yevéoews), and is in- determinate plasticity (duopdov éxuayeiov). Out of this Nothingness ? God creates the world. The identity of Platonic ‘‘ matter” of the tpirov yévos (Tim., 48 f.) with empty space is most certainly proved by his con- struction. of the elements out of triangles (see below), in which connection the philosopher identified the mathematical body immediately with the physical body. See also J. P. Wohlstein, Materie und Weltseele im plutonischen System (Marburg, 1863). The cosmos must also, as the most perfectly perceivable thing, possess reason and soul. The first task of the de- miurge in the creation of a world is the creation of a world- soul. As the life-principle of the All, the world-soul must unite in itself its Form-determining capacity, its motion and its consciousness, The world-soul is the mean between the unitary (the Idea) and the divisible (Space), and possesses the opposite qualities of sameness (radrév) and change (Oarepov). It holds in itself all numbers and dimensions. It is itself the mathematical form of the cosmos, is distrib- uted by the demiurge into harmonious relations, in which: distribution an inner circle of changing motions and an outer circle of uniformity (the place of the fixed stars and planets) is to be distinguished. The latter is again divided proportionately within itself. By means of these circles, each moved according to its own nature, the world-soul is supposed to have set the entire cosmos into motion. By means of this motion, permeating the whole and returning # to itself, the world-soul created in itself and in individual 1 Tim , 49 f. 2 Compare the claims of Democritus. 8 Tim., 85 £ 4 Ibid., 37. MATERIALISM AND IDEALISM 291 things consciousness, perception, and thought. The most perfect kind of knowledge, however, is the circular move- ment of the stars, which continually returns to itself. The particulars of this extremely imaginative description of the Tima@us are obscure, and have been subject to controversy (see Zeller, II? 646 ff). The tendency toward the number theory of the Pythagoreans as well as toward their astronomy and harmonics is unmistakable. In the division of the world- soul, with which the divisions of the astronomical world are identical, harmonic proportion and arithmetical means play the chief réle. The important thought is that with this general division of the mass and motions of the cosmos, a perpetual definiteness of form (wépas) belongs to space, which is a com- panion principle of the depov in the Philebus (§ 35). The mathematical was therefore not for Plato entirely identical with the world-soul; but it was in the most intimate connection with it, and was in a similar intermediary position between the Ideas and the sense world. The characteristic of the Platonic theory of motion is that it referred all motions of individual objects to the teleologically determined motion of the whole. It thus was in antipodal opposition to Atomism, which considered motion to be an inde- pendent function of single atoms. It is remarkable that the Timeus emphasizes many times (Zeller, II®. 663, 3) the con- nection, nay the identity, between motions and intellections. The “right idea” is referred, for example, to the Oarepov, to irregular motions ; rationai knowledge, on the other hand, is re- ferred to ravrov, the uniform, circular motions (Zim., 87).1 It is also here characteristic that all particular acts are referred to the universal functioning power of the world-soul. Thus to the world-soul is lacking the characteristic of personality. The further mathematical formation (7épas) of empty space is accomplished in the individual things, which have been introduced by the demiurge into the harmonious sys- tem of the world-soul; and, firstly, in the formation of the elements (ctoyeia). Besides an artificial deduction of their fourfold number,? which introduced air and water as the two 1 Tf in these theories any use is made of Democritus —which I re- gard by no means improbable — his teachings have, at any rate, received an independent treatment. 2 Tim., 31 f. 222 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY means between fire and earth, Plato! gave a stereometrical development from these four elements, which development, as among the Pythagoreans, presents the four regular bodies as the fundamental forms of the elements. The tetrahedron is the fundamental form of fire; the octa- hedron, of the air; the icosahedron, of the water; the cube, of the earth. He conceived, however, these funda- mental bodies as constructed out of planes, and indeed of right-angle triangles which are sometimes isosceles, and sometimes of such a nature that the catheti stand in the ratio of one to two.2, With this construction the transfor- mation of space into corporeal matter seemed to be con- ceived. From the different magnitudes and numbers of these indivisible plane-triangles® were next derived with clever fancifulness the physical and chemical qualities of individual stuffs, their distribution in space, their mingling, and the continuous motion in which they exist. Plato also believed that the individual elements and stuffs are in a determined part of space according to the predominating mass, to which the scattered parts then strive to return. It is not entirely clear how he introduced the relationships of weight into this thought. At any rate, he had been sensible of the fact that the direction from above downward cannot be re- garded as absolute; but that in the world-sphere only the two directions, to the centre and to the periphery, exist. Plato’s astronomical views differ from those of the Py- thagoreans essentially in his acceptance of the stationari- ness of the earth. According to his theory, the earth rested like a sphere in the middle of a spherical-shaped world-all. Around the “diamond” axle of this world with daily revolution from east to west swings in the outermost periph- 1 Tim., 58 f. ‘2 The square is constructed aut of the former; the equilateral tri- angle, of the latter. 8 Which accordingly take the place of the droya and cynpara of Democritus. MATERIALISM AND IDEALISM 2238 ery the heaven of the fixed stars, in which the single stars are conceived as “ visible gods” in continuous per- fect movement upon their own axes. That revolution is communicated to the seven spheres, viz., the five planets, the sun and the moon. ‘These intersect the first circle (of the fixed stars) in the direction of the zodiac. The planets, sun and moon, have, however, within their orbits their own reverse movements of differing velocity. The last proposition as an astronomical explanation of the apparent irregularity of the movements of the planets, remained for a long time authoritative. The methodical principle lying at its basis has been strikingly formulated by Plato or his followers in the question: tivwy irorebacay épadov Kai teray- peo kuycewv SiacwOy Ta Tepl Tas KATES TOV TAQVHMEeVWY paLYd- peva (comp. Simplicius with Aristotle, De colo, 119). The theory of motion in the 7imceus concludes with a detailed account of the psycho-physical process of percep- tion.2, It is concerned with establishing those conditions of motion of external objects and of the body which call forth the motions of the soul, its sensations and feelings.? With great pains in this connection the investigations of the physiologists, just as the theory of Protagoras,* were adjusted to the teleological theory of motion. Since the subjective moment is, moreover, separated from the objec- tive in aie @nots, the nature philosophy confirms the episte- mological point of departure which the Theetetus had illu- minated. Finally, by way of appendix, the Zimeus gives a sketch of a theory of diseases and their cures, and thus yields to the encyclopedic demands of the Platonic school. 1 Tim., 40 a. 2 Ibid., 61f. For details, see H. Siebeck, Gesch. der Psych., I, 1, 201f. 3 In this respect the exposition of the Timeus is supplemented by that of the Republic and the Philebus, while it develops empirically the theoretical principles of the Theetetus. 4 And perhaps much also which belongs to Democritus. 224 HISTORY OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY 6. ARISTOTLE. A career of nearly forty years in teaching gathered a large number of superior men around Plato, and gave to the operations of his school, in its treatment of ethico-his- torical and scientific medical studies, that comprehensive- ness of which indications appeared in his later dialogues.t To the stately number of men that belonged to the school more or less closely, empirical research owed much valu- able enrichment in the immediately succeeding time, but philosophy gained at their hands scarcely anything worthy of mention. Only the one man, Plato’s greatest pupil, who it is true did not remain in the ranks of the Academy, but founded a school of his own, was called to bring to completion the history of Greek philosophy with his won- derful system of thought. This man was Aristotle. The history of the Academy is generally divided into three and perhaps five periods: the Older Academy, which lasted about a century after the death of Plato; the Middle Academy, which filled out the -second century, in which period we distin- guish two successive schools, that of Archesilaus and that of Carneades ; the New Academy, which extended to neo-Platonism, and in which the dogmatic movement advocated by Philo of Larissa is to be distinguished from a later eclecticism of Anti- ochus of Ascalon. The two later phases belong to the syncretic skepticism of Greek philosophy. For general comparisons, see H. Stein, Sieben Biicher zur Gresch. d. Platonismus (3 vols., Git- tingen, 1862-75). 38. The so-called Older Academy stood entirely under the influence of that less healthy tendency which the Platonic philosophy in later time had shown theoretically toward the Pythagorean number theory and _ practically toward a popular and religious system of morals. Speu- sippus (d. 839), the nephew of Plato, took charge of the 1 See H. Usener, Ueber d. Organisation d. wissenschafilichen Arbeit im Alterthum (Preuss. Jahrb. 58, 1 ff.); E. Heitz, D. Philos. schulen - Athens (Deutsche Revue, 1884). ARISTOTLE 295 school after Plato, and Xenocrates of Chalcedon followed Speusippus. To the same generation belonged Heracleides of Pontic Heraclea and Philip of Opus. The astronomer Kudoxus of Cnidus and Archytas of Tarentum, head of the Pythagoreans of that time, stood in a loose relation to the Platonic school. The following generation of the school yielded to the spirit of the time, and turned essentially to ethical investigations. Polemo of Athens was then head of the school, from 814 to 270, and since his gifted pupil, Crantor, died before him, Crates of Athens became his successor. An exact description of all the Academicians of this time is in Zeller, I]*. 836 f.; F. Biicheler, Acad. philos. index Hercula- nensis (Greifswald, 1869). Our knowledge concerning the dif- ferent tendencies within the Academy arises from the fact that after Plato’s death, as Speusippus had been designated by Plato to succeed him as scholarch, Xenocrates and Aristotle left Athens. ‘The former was afterward chosen to lead the school; the latter somewhat later founded a school of his own. Judging by what has come down to us about Speusippus, he was a vague and diffuse writer. Diogenes Laertius (IV. 4 f.) gives a list of his writings, and these touch upon all parts of science. The most appear to have been tzopurijpara in reference to his career as a teacher. It was these that Aristotle had in mind in his frequent and mostly polemical references to Speusip- pus.