Bria aa ey a] Wee eho pia see BRED yin Hovey pennies “tede SHU ean) Den restr ie vor ariinen BeGega teddy Vivrrayy fideney an porta it Wales: CONT aa 8 Nh ta it ee He iH ay way vite ria thf \ eupey AVE LDA Sate seen i lal Rea atenen ‘te yetas abs ‘ 4 ‘ 1 4 ' tye DRoConr ey yt) Tying ‘ shaved inegstey anil Ying seatyeaa gins : i> f . a 3 ebge trary) oan A ee errs Pa : 2H ” . STR er Sa raw) : net athe te ‘ H "4 Wah geg tying i Serie hae TVS VAAN aad beni dates vend d Fata os Syhataby raba@atsbatee Ore eet ea ‘ ROR a weber dae Things “34 4 y ‘ sty yfaka Heboae hatha esd es Hateryinigteds tate eebtDas ud > : ry - i on - bay oe aa 5 i 7 - =)" © a) & # 5 i ee Wt LA! Sad : ; : : © _ an cr 4 ; = =< Py ee a ws ‘ i ie tel @ ‘ é a Tee 3 ore a es are 7 ; 7 ’ > ay: - nish _ ri ; | ) : ’ : © aa * fi ar ‘ / = ~ " ; > ; | i \ Do pee Sk erat eee he St = ta LIBRARY OF PRINCETON : JUL 4-9 2018 THEOLOGICAL SEMINARY Digitized by the Internet Archive in 2022 with funding from Princeton Theological Seminary Library https://archive.org/details/apologeticsofchr0Oheth Works Publishey by T. & CT. Clark. Works RECENTLY PUBLISHED. 0) In demy 8vo, price 10s. 6d., THE DOCTRINE OF JUSTIFICATION. An OUTLINE OF ITs HIsToRY IN THE CHURCH, AND OF ITS EXPOSITION FROM SCRIPTURE, WITH SPECIAL REFERENCE TO RECENT ATTACKS ON THE THEOLOGY OF THE REFORMATION. By JAMES BUCHANAN, D.D., Professor of Divinity, New College, Edinburgh ; Author of rd as a Guide to Truth and an Aid to Faith.’ In demy 8vo, price 9s., AN EXPOSITION OF THE EPISTLE OF JAMES, In A SERIES oF DISCOURSES. By THE Rev. JOHN ADAM, ABERDEEN. In demy 8vo, price 10s. 6d., ECCE:E DE JU 8: EssAYS ON THE LIFE AND DOCTRINE OF JESUS CHRIST. ‘The production of a clever, sincere, religious mind...... The style is decidedly scholarlike, forcible, and pithy. London Review. ‘Finer sentences than those we have quoted, we make bold to say, are not found even in Jeremy Taylor. —Daily Review. In crown 8vo, price 4s., REPRE SENTATIVE RESPONSIBILITY: A LAw oF THE DIvINE PROCEDURE IN PROVIDENCE AND REDEMPTION. By Rey. HENRY WALLACE, Lonponperry. ‘The author shows a mind practised in philosophical analysis, and is fully abreast of all our recent literature on both sides of this difficult question.’ — Daily Review. In crown 8vo, price 5s., THE CHURCH: Irs Orrern, 1rs Hisrory, 1rs PRESENT POSITION. FRoM THE GERMAN or Drs. LUTHARDT, KAHNIS, anp BRUCKNER, Professors of Theology, Leipsic. ‘A finer theme for popular and instructive discourse it is not easy to have; and in the illustration of this theme there is much in this volume of suggestive truth, finely and impressively described.’—Freeman. Jn crown 8vo, price 4s., THE ROMISH DOCTRINE OF THE IMMACULATE CONCEPTION. TRACED FROM ITS SOURCE. By Dr. E. PREUSS, Principal of Friedrich-Wilhelm’s Gymnasium at Berlin. TRANSLATED BY GEORGE GLADSTONE. In crown 8vo, price 5s. 6d., THE FATHERHOOD OF GOD, AND ITs RELATION TO THE PERSON AND WoRK OF CHRIST, AND THE OPERATIONS OF THE Hoty Spirit. By tHE Rey. CHARLES H. H. WRIGHT, British Chaplain at Dresden. Works Publishey by C. & T. Clark. Just published, in Four Volumes 8vo, price 32s., THE COMPARATIVE GEOGRAPHY OF PALESTINE AND THE SINAITIC PENINSULA. BY PROFESSOR CARL RITTER, OF BERLIN. Translated anu Avapten for the Use of Wiblical Stuvents, By WILLIAM L. GAGE. ‘I have always looked on Ritter’s Comparative Geography of Palestine, comprised in his famous “ Erdkunde,” as the great classical work ‘on the subject; a clear and full résumé of all that was known of Bible Lands up to the time he wrote; and, as such, indispensable to the student of Bible Geography and History. This translation will open up a flood of knowledge to the English reader, especially as the editor is a man thoroughly imbued with the spirit of this noble-minded and truly Christian author’—A. Krrrit JounstTon, Esq., Geographer in Ordinary to Her Majesty for Scotland. : ‘One of the most valuable works on Palestine ever published.’—Rerv. H. B. TRISTRAM, Author of ‘The Land of Israel.’ : ‘By far the most important of Messrs. Clark’s publications is this very handsome and complete edition of Ritter’s Palestine. The great Berlin geographer can never be out of date; and though he did not live to complete his great work, by availing himself of the discoveries of recent explorers, yet the present editor has to a considerable extent supplied the deficiency ; and we may say that, among the voluminous products of the well-known Edinburgh press, few exceed this publication in importance and complete- ness. —Christian Remembrancer, Jan. 1867. ‘To clergymen these volumes will prove not less interesting than instructive and useful. Theological students will find in them the most exhaustive storehouse of facts on the subjects existing in the language, while upon all the moot points of Palestinian and Sinaitic geography they will meet with a condensed summary of all the arguments of every writer of note, from the earliest ages down to the period of the author’s death. In a word, these four volumes give the essence of the entire literature of the subject of every age and language. ..... The readers of these volumes have every reason to be satisfied with the result. ..... But it would be impossible to mention all the good things in these volumes. We must, however, say a few words upon Ritter’s magnificent monograph on the situation of Ophir, which we regard as one of the gems of the work. .... Ritter’s treatment of this apparently hopeless question is a masterpiece of mature scholarship and sound judgment. ‘The whole monograph is a model of its kind...... What we are now saying of the monograph on the situation of Ophir is, however, applicable to every- thing our author wrote.’—Spectator. ‘Mr. Gage has, with a perfect knowledge of the matter in hand, and by the use of a clear and lively style, produced a thoroughly readable book.’—Daily Review. ‘ By the publication of this geography of Palestine, Messrs. Clark have placed within the reach of a large number of students, clerical and lay, an exhaustive and comprehen- sive work on biblical geography, which will greatly facilitate the study of the sacred writings.’—Churchman. ‘It is superfluous to commend a work of so peerless a character ag this.’—British Quarterly Review. ‘ The translator has fulfilled his task admirably... ... The book is pleasant to read, and will be found very interesting, not only by biblical students, but by the public in general.’—Evangelical Magazine. NGO El Gus: —_—_—>——_- THE Publishers beg to state that the Volume now issued is composed. entirely of Lectures prepared by Dr. Hether- ington ; and read by him for several sessions to the Students attending the Free Church College, Glasgow. The conversion of these into Chapters and Sections has been deemed more suitable for general circulation; and © any alterations made on the Mss. are such only as have been rendered necessary by this change. The Rev. George Reith, of the Free College Church, Glasgow, has kindly revised the sheets for the press. EDINBURGH: PRINTED BY MURRAY’ AND GIBB FOR a. 3. (CL ACR K; LON DONG ike dat tig HAMILTON, ADAMS, AND CO. DUBLIN, . . . . . JOHN ROBERTSON & Co. THE APOLOGETICS OF THE CHRISTIAN FAITH BY THE LATE v WILLIAM M. HETHERINGTON, D.D., LL.D., PROFESSOR OF THEOLOGY, FREE CHURCH COLLEGE, GLASGOW. GHith aw Introductory Notice BY ALEXANDER DUFF, D.D., LL.D. EDINBURGH: T. & T. CLARK, 38, GEORGE STREET. 1867. Dai Py ele INTRODUCTORY NOTICE. ———
rn « Fy ‘ re 4 Sa # \
: UAE Bb RE aE: 1 Pe Ber ie pr errdd® tent Fy
ft Bi os
y, i ; i ‘ ‘ ‘ 4 ‘ " op: ’ » Tey ie a
i | 4 arte A a ae a ow Ly hriidor oe
4 [ 4 P Bal ¢ ; ‘ hd
< , : i! Mi: j ‘ * yi
; aa zi ial AF Phy t f / AT f gs j
ay if aah: oF i . ,
n 2 es RY GED toe ane ree geting iy ott Of 1 Oe
a; i
\ ; h ace" :
Sate | t. . f 4 =m
Oia attaniale | UTE MC a UR Ma a a)
- A a ¢
Sian as v ie hil y ,
ASR RMRICE BOULUD TO Bae 0 a ae Qj
Ms : } ne as ; , : '
he « oft , bl - Ly ¢. 4 ' “i
Ba dhe, ee AC ye ye eres TS ee
e 4 « é
WS ea “49 oor bay) \ ) tif : , : ; ciP
ey eae | ’ F pets Pen ca ab ae ; , : . ! cy fay] f 4%
e eK
* we 2 Se a ‘ ‘ | 5
‘ a*) '% 4 . 7 / = i
y i f i i ! e . : r
j eo. - = ie ‘ t ’ rf ? +
; 4 \Biray: fare Ss is SiS; Hy j 4 Z : t i ry ice
te ies Hi
~) Mpa dul
¢ ' ; e
\ |
Pies v y
‘2 i-e
ee ae b as
es > ae :
tay Peat ter (CyiA fait. ne DP Sah oF OR. F279
ga er: i als Mea: as eee
poner * PAL SMe: » ‘geld. ¢ SATE br os i
a : i. “A la > - nt .
zat i © . he ar ty ph j és ‘ { “
yeaah i od lo ont aie Dee ine
Ph Te ait op §4 us yi y, a
. J Di uy otf tae 04 Sui
CONTENTS.
DIVISION I.
NATURAL THHOLOG EY
CHAPTER I.
INTRODUCTION,
CHAPTER Il.
STATEMENT OF THE NATURE AND METHOD OF ARGUMENT RELATIVE TO
NATURAL THEOLOGY,
Sec. I. Primary Belief in a Supreme Being, Invariable and Universal,
II. The Three Divisions of Human Knowledge available to
prove the Reasonableness of this Belief,
CHAPTER III.
THE ARGUMENT A PRIORI,
Sec. I. Objections, ; :
II. True Character of the @ priort Wee eument Stated and Ex-
plained,
III. Theories of Dr. 8S. Clarke, Ties etc.,
IV. The Value of the @ priort Argument,
CHAPTER IV.
THE ARGUMENT A POSTERIORI,
Sec. I. Doctrine of Causation,
II. Doctrine of Adaptation—Design,
PAGE
XVill CONTENTS.
CHAPTER V.
ARGUMENT FoRMED BY COMBINATION OF A PRIORI AND A POSTERIORI
METHODS,
‘Sec. I. Different Theories of ae
II. The Will, Liberty, and Necessity,
III. Ethical Science, or the Science of Duty, pea in its ah
cation to Man in the Social State,
IV. Design in Man, ; 5
V. General View of Design in External yatare and in Max!
VI. Results of the Combined Argument,
CHAPTER VI.
GENERAL CONCLUSIONS TO WHICH NATURAL THEOLOGY LEADS
EXTENT AND LIMITS, i.
DIVISION ILI.
see hihi!
PAGE
77
79
89
101
114
125
137
REVELATION: EXTERNAL AND INTERNAL EVIDENCES.
PART I.—EXTERNAL EVIDENCES.
CHAPTER I.
INTRODUCTION,
Sec. I. Statement and Defence of the Argument: a Revelation Pro-
bable,
II. Further Argument that a Revelation is Pecneble Spc the
nature of the Human Mind,
III. The Necessity of a Divine Revelation,
CHAPTER Li
DrrecT AND PosITIVE EVIDENCE OF REVELATION,
Sec. I. Historical Veracity of the Bible,
IJ. General Principles of Historical Evidence,
Ill. Application of General Historical Principles to the Bible,
IV. Comparison between Sacred and Profane Records,
194
195
204
214
995
MIRACLEs,
Sec. I.
jue
. The Moral Character and Aspect of Miracles,
. The Condition and Circumstances of true Miracles,
. Examination of Hume’s Argument against Miracles, .
. Various Objections Stated and Answered,
. Greatest Special Instance: The Resurrection of Christ,
. Cessation of Miracles.
PROPHECY,
mec. 1.
if
. Characteristics of Prophecy,
CONTENTS.
CHAPTER III.
Miracles: Definition and Explanation,
The Possibility and Credibility of Miracles,
When? Why? Summary,
CHAPTER IV.
Nature of Prophecy: Definition and Explanation,
Relation between Miracles and Prophecy,
. Confirmation of the Evidence of itt
. Summary of the Evidence from Prophecy,
PART II.—INTERNAL EVIDENCES.
CHAPTER V.
CHRISTIANITY the TRUTH, .
Sec. I.
Lis
INTEGRITY AND AUTHORITY OF SCRIPTURE.
Adaptation of the Gospel to Man,
Moral and Social Results of Christianity,
DIVISION IIL
CHAPTER I.
THE CANON OF SCRIPTURE,
Sec. I.
Il.
The Canon of the Old Testament,
The Canon of the New Testament,
XIX
PAGE
237
238
247
258
269
281
292
302
313
325
325
335
344
346
356
368
369
378
XX CONTENTS.
CHAPTER II.
INSPIRATION OF SCRIPTURE,
Sec. I. Statement of Subject—Definition and Explanation,
II. Inspiration in accordance with God’s Dealings with Man,
III. Kind of Evidence Relevant and Sufficient to prove Inspi-
ration, s ‘ : : ; :
IV. Positive Proof of Inspiration—Scripture,
VY. History of Opinion relative to Inspiration,
VI. Objections of a Metaphysical Character, :
VII. Special Objections from Difficulties and Obscurities, .
VIII. Relation of Inspiration to the Interpretation of Scripture,
CHAPTER III.
AUTHORITY OF SCRIPTURE,
Sec. I. Scripture and Human Reason,
II. Scripture and the Office of the Holy Spir it,
Ill. Sufficiency and Perfection of Scripture,
Ae PE Ne Tex:
I. Instinct, Reason, Faith,
Il. Scepticism, Rationalism, Humanism,
III. Pantheism, Materialistic and Idealistic,
INDEX,
PAGE
413
413
424
433
445
455
466
476
488
499
499
509
520
531
542
549
557
DIVISION L—NATURAL THEOLOGY.
sac
CHAPTER I.
INTRODUCTION.
fe ecrrauT us suppose the question to be asked by some
| earnest and fair inquirer, “ What is Natural Theo-
logy, and what are its uses?” and let us assume the
position that it is our duty to answer that question,
so far as that may be in our power. It will at once appear
that, in order to obtain something like a clear and intelligible
conception to begin with, we must define the compound term
Natural Theology. The first half of that term—Natural—
must mean, what is in accordance with Nature. But this is not
enough ; for it may still be asked, What is Nature?
term metaphysical thinking; while, on the other hand, he was
profoundly conversant with physical science and its laws, and
felt that he could produce the & posteriori argument for the
being and attributes of God in full and irresistible strength.
For that reason, he was rather more than willing'to abandon
the & priori argument,—even to discountenance it,—that he
might pursue his own course unembarrassed, with all his giant
might. Yet there are minds as specially addicted to @ priort
thought, to whom that line of argument will be more convincing
than any argument based on the phenomena and the laws of
physical nature could ever be; and we are therefore inclined to
retain the & priori argument, and not only to retain it, but to
clear away from it all the misstatements and misapprehensions
which have been allowed to gather round it, and have abated
its clearness and its power. We may add, that the transcen-
eS — a a
:
CHAP. III.] THE ARGUMENT A PRIORI he
dental thinking of Germany can neither be understood nor
answered without some considerable attention to the department
of & priori thought; and as it is from Germany that most of
the recent insidious attacks on the Christian faith have come, we
think it our duty to meet the enemy on his own ground, and to
do what we can to foil him with his own weapons.
We have already referred to the philosophy of Descartes,
as giving direction to what is now generally designated sub-
jective philosophy; and we are inclined to make a few passing
remarks on that philosophy, because some have termed it the
basis of all & priori reasoning. The primary position of
Descartes was indeed the starting-point of modern metaphysics,
making the consciousness of the human mind the primary ele-
ment of all its knowledge. His position amounted to this:
that the very moment there are phenomena of any kind within
our consciousness, that moment the mind becomes cognizant of
its own existence ; and that were there no consciousness, there
would be no possible evidence of an intelligent principle.
Thought, thus understood, includes both the thought itself and
a thinking being—both a:subject and an ‘object. From this
natural division there arises the possibility of analyzing: both
mind and matter—psychology and perception. Our consciously
conceived ideas are thus subject to examination, and it becomes
of the utmost importance to obtain some criterion by which the
true can be distinguished from the false. This criterion Descartes
thought to consist in “clearness and distinctness.” This also
is essentially an appeal to consciousness. But this criterion he
applied also to the idea of God, in this manner: Clear ideas
are always objectively true, that is, there is a reality to which
they correspond : the idea of an all-perfect infinite Being is with-
out controversy clearly in my mind: this conception could not
have come from the finite and imperfect ; but I have that idea
incontestably and clearly: therefore, since I have the clear idea
of a God, a God must necessarily exist. Such is the argument
given by Descartes; but it is evident that it is not the argument ~
of Dr. Clarke. Descartes gave, however, also an ontological
argument inproof of the being of God, to the following effect :
The existence of God is implied in the very nature of the idea
we have of Him, as is the existence of a triangle in the con-
ception of a triangle. Necessary existence is contained in the
nature of the idea of God: therefore God necessarily exists.
5}
a8 NATURAL THEOLOGY. [DIV. I.
That there is in this attempted ontological argument a falla-
cious assumption of the point to be proved, is evident enough ;
but it is not evident that this argument is identical with that
which Dr. Clarke elaborated. The Cartesian ontological argu-
ment, as it is called, is not, in our opinion, truly ontological ;
for it is an attempt to reason from an idea, or concept, to a
_ reality, which is necessarily impossible,—unless, indeed, the
reasoner carry with him avowedly the consciousness of his own
existence, and the appeal to that consciousness as the connecting
link between the idea and the reality, which, however, Des-
cartes did not attempt todo. For these reasons, and for others
which might easily be stated, we do not admit the Cartesian
argument asa true & priori argument; and in a subsequent
part of our course we may take occasion to point out more
definitely the manner and position in which it received that
vitiating fallacy, by which it was perverted into an argument
on behalf of materialistic Pantheism.
Since the time of Descartes, the philosophical mind of the
Continent has been marvellously developed in all directions,
and has sought to explore every line of thought. In many
departments its success has been very great; but not so in its
use of a priori thinking to prove the existence and the attri-
butes of God. By some of the great German thinkers the
argument has been carried away into the regions of the ideal,
to such a degree that all possible knowledge of the real is
denied. By others, the subjective—the Igo, or the Me—has
been produced till it. has become the final sum, “the bright
consummate flower” of the universe,—the consciousness of the
Ego being regarded as God become conscious of Himself in man.
This is a strange Pantheism—a strange idolatry. It is a Pan-
theism, for all is God, and God is all; yet this All-God is man.
It is therefore an idolatry, yet a strange idolatry; for it is not
man deified, but God humanized, and yet God still. It is not
the ancient nature-worship or deified man-worship of earlier
heathen ages; but it is the hero-worship of idealized humanity.
To show how all this has sprung of extreme subjective philo-
sophy, deprived by its modern cultivators of at least one most
important element, and to point out why this all-important ele-
ment was left out, or thrown designedly out, will engage our
attention when we come to deal with some of the spurious forms
of thinking which come into collision with Natural Theology.
_ CHAP. TIL] THE ARGUMENT A PRIORI. 39
In England there has not been much done in the regions
of philosophico-theological disquisition since the time of Bishop
Butler, till of late. But that eminent man established some
points in the world of high and true thought which can never
be subverted, at least not in the British mind; and if not in
the British mind, ultimately not in the mind of the thinking
world.
The recently departed great Scottish philosopher, Sir
William Hamilton, not only maintained the renown of Scottish
thought, but gave to Scottish philosophy such additional clear-
ness, precision, and strength of thought and expression, as has
raised it to a position of ascendancy in the philosophic mind
throughout the world of thoughtful men. Yet even in his
philosophy may be traced a vitiating blank, similar in nature
to that which we hinted at with reference to nearly all conti-
nental philosophy. To this point also we shall subsequently
direct special attention.
The profound study of mental philosophy cannot cease to
engage the earnest attention of all meditative men. They will
think; they must think; and they cannot think long and
deeply without thinking of God—of that Supreme Being in
whom they live, and move, and have their being. ‘Their philo-
sophy must necessarily enter into the regions of Natural
Theology; and in that region may work, as it has formerly
wrought, wild havoc, unless it be calmly met, fairly encoun-
tered, its errors detected and removed, and all its true thoughts
received and dedicated to the service of revealed truth. ‘This,
we believe, both may be done and will be done, and that, too,
without much of the turmoil of controversy, or the noise of
boastful shouts of victory. Long has the secular mind been in
the habit of pluming itself on the calmness, serenity, and peace-
fulness of its philosophical disquisitions on all manner of sub-
jects, while it indulged in scornful complaint of the bitterness
of theological polemics. With what truth these self-lauda-
tions were employed, and these accusations uttered, we do not
think it at all necessary to say. But we shall endeavour to
avoid all unnecessary asperity of language, while with unhesi-
tating fearlessness we confront every opponent of what we deem
not only truth, but saving truth, and firmly prosecute our task
of refuting error and maintaining sacred truth and faith, not
merely on grounds that nature and sound reason furnish, but
40 NATURAL THEOLOGY. ; EpIVeED
also on the higher and holier grounds that God has vouchsafed
to reveal.
Before we pass from this brief disquisition repecting & priori
thought, and the various attempts that have been made to state
a true and conclusive @ priort argument for the being and
attributes of God, we think it right to say, that even though it
should be found utterly impossible to produce a true & priori
argument, our inquiries into subjects of such elevation and
dignity cannot fail to be of great mental value;-and if we duly
guard against the admission of any hostile and disturbing
elements into our minds, we shall be the better prepared for the
reception of the final and absolute a priori thinking contained
in the Bible—the thinking which has come direct from God
Himself. There is at the very least this peculiar value in
& priort or axiomatic thinking, that if its primary positions
cannot be proved, neither can they be refuted. It is impossible
for any man, by prosecuting axiomatic thinking, to become an
atheist, until he has succeeded in denying his own ewistence. He
must first annihilate himself; and as in doing so, or saying he
does so, he must also at the same time annihilate the thought
with the thinker, he ceases in the moment to be an atheist—he
is only a nothing, a nonentity: for axiomatic thinking enters
into depths far more profound and true than the shallow
superficialities of Atheism. In the heart of the human con-
sciousness it fixes its deep and ineradicable root of primary
investigation, and compels a man to stand face to face with his
own moral soul and nature, in its reverential feeling of responsi-
bility. ‘This is our impregnable position. Here we begin our
inquiry. If we shall find enough to convince us that there is
in man a spiritual essence united to a material body, which
renders him the very synthesis of mind and matter, we may
then think it no more strange that he cannot refuse to believe
the highest intuitions of his mind, than that he cannot refuse to
believe the plainest intimations of his senses, even though he
should not be able to demonstrate their truth in either case ;
and as he receives the evidence of his senses with most direct
conviction of their truth when he is in contact with external
nature, so he will receive the evidence of his mental intuitions
with most direct conviction of their truth when he is engaged in
spiritual converse with God. His true & priori demonstration
will be, when reason stands reverentially face to face with
CHAP. III.] THE ARGUMENT A PRIORI. 4}
faith, when the soul kneels humbly in fervent adoration before
its GoD.
SEC. IV. THE VALUE OF THE A PRIORI ARGUMENT.
<
Various statements have been already made explanatory of
the true nature of a true & priori argument; but as it may
conduce to clearness, it seems expedient to bring together into
one connected whole these explanatory remarks. _
No sooner has the element or principle of self-consciousness
been aroused in the human being, than he is constrained not
only to believe his own existence, but also to put certain im-
portant and primary questions to himself, such as, What am I?
Where am I? How came I to be, and to be here? These questions
suggest inevitably the three great and primary elements of all
our knowledge; viz., first, the idea of our own existence, or of
finite mind in general; secondly, the idea of external nature ;
and thirdly, the idea of the absolute and eternal, as manifested
in the conceptions of pure reason. We begin to think when we
begin consciously to observe; and in beginning to think, the
earliest form of thought must contain in it the consciousness of
self, and the perception of something which is not self. Many
an error may take place in our early attempts to expand,
apply, and understand these primary ideas, so as to form them
not only into a true knowledge, but into a true philosophy of
knowledge. We may puzzle ourselves long about the questions
concerning the trustworthiness of our senses, and the value of
our perceptions, in making us acquainted with external nature;
and regarding these questions scepticism has long exercised its
ingenious faculty for doubting, yet never really doubted the
actual existence of external nature, all the time that it was
arguing that no proof could be given of its existence. Not less
dificult may be, and has been, the task to satisfy the doubter
with proof of our own existence, although of course no man in
his senses ever really doubted the actual existence both of him-
self and of other men. Disputations on such points might be
allowed, so'long as they amounted to little more than the
intellectual amusements of idle men; but when they are em-
ployed to sap the foundations of Borah and religion, they
assume a dangerous character, and render it necessary to meet
them and examine their real nature and tendency.
~
42 _ NATURAL THEOLOGY. [DIV. I.
The greatest danger to morality and religion, however, has
always resided in the application of the sceptic’s sophistry to
man’s idea of the absolute and the eternal, as apprehended by
the conceptions of pure reason. If scepticism cannot banish
that great idea, it will try to transmute it into either an zdeal
Pantheism or a material Pantheism; and in either case there
can be no true foundation for morality and religion. And
here let it be noted, that while scepticism about the real, or
rather the proved, existence of man and nature cannot greatly
affect common morality, because men will believe in their
own existence and in that of external nature, despite all the
sophistry of all the sceptics; yet scepticism regarding the
existence of the absolute, the infinite, the eternal, has always
been readily received by many, and has always proved to be a
formidable foe to morality and religion, were it only by setting
men loose from all restraints imposed by the indefinite dread of
future retribution. Into the reason why scepticism so per-
tinaciously tries to preserve this ground, we shall inquire subse-
quently ; meanwhile we direct attention to the fact.
Now, it is with regard to this last-mentioned department of
man’s primary fountain of thought and knowledge, that the
& priort argument claims to be of special value. ‘There is a
necessary sequence in thought suggesting in every thought the
question, whether that thought was an absolutely primitive
thought, or whether it originated in a prior thought, prior state,
or prior being. This impels the mind to engage in tracing
every thought back, and back, and still further back, in search
of an absolutely first thought ; nor can it be satisfied till it either
ascertain that first thought, or become assured that it cannot
be ascertained. Nay, let it be frankly stated, that should the
inquiry be constrained to stop because the first thought cannot
be ascertained, the inquiring mind is no satisfied with such a
result; and while it stops, it does so with a feeling of disappoint-
ment at a result so unsatisfactory. It seems, then, that the
element of @ priori thinking is natural, and even necessary to
the human mind—the ultimate form of thought which it seeks
to attain. Man stands on the narrow isthmus of the present
now, between the two eternities, the past and the future. His
restless, indefatigable, wandering thoughts connect him with
both. The future he imagines he can conceive and may inherit,
because it seems easy to suppose that what now exists may
CHAP. III.] THE ARGUMENT A PRIORI. 43
continue to exist for ever. But back into the past, the dark
priority of an unbeginning eternity, from which his own begin-
ning sprang,—into that mysterious region he cannot pierce; and
yet he must attempt it, so fascinated is he with its unfathom-
able grandeur. There is, there must be, he thinks, an unbe-
ginning eternity: not an eternity of nothingness, for that affords
no actual beginning, or cause of beginning, to existing things ;
but an Eternal—a Being of whom eternity of existence is the
essential characteristic. Of any other thing or being I can ask, '
What was before it? Of such a Being I can say, He always
was, and always is, and always will be—Himself the First, the
Present, the Last, the ETERNAL.
This is & priori thinking; and while this kind of thinking
is absolutely an inevitable necessity for the human mind, with
its wonderful far-searching faculties and powers, the only ques-
tion is, Can this necessity of & priort thinking be reduced to
the form of an & priori argument? And if it can, how far
can it carry the inquiry relative to the being and attributes of
God? The chief objection which has been urged against the
& priori argument is, that it cannot be so stated as to carry the
conclusion of absolute being, without at least one assumption, or
postulate, which may be refused, and therefore that it cannot
prove absolute and necessary heines We have already cast
the & priort argument into several syllogistic forms. Let us
try another, as an illustration of our present reasoning on the
subject; premising only, that we hold ourselves entitled, from
the indubitable element of self-consciousness, to commence
with the idea, not of being merely, but of personality.
1The one postulate, it will be remembered, is, ‘‘ There zs finite being.”
When any man attempts to dispute or deny that postulate, he may be fairly
asked to explain what he means, or thinks he means. Does he mean to
dispute or deny his own existence, and yet think that he is thinking, and
not an existent thinker,—a thought perhaps, but not a thinker? No man
ever did, or ever could, either think or believe such an unintelligible ab-
surdity ; no man therefore ever did, or ever can, intelligibly dispute our
postulate, which accordingly takes the position of being itself a necessity
rather than a postulate. I am really anxious to press this thought; both
because many good thinkers, and fair and honest-minded men, shrink from
venturing to use the & priori argument, because it has got a bad reputation
from having been often misused, and still more often misunderstood ; and
also because, when thus left by the friends of truth, it falls into the hands
exclusively of the perverters of truth, by whom it is dexterously employed
in their fallacious reasoning. Being essentially axiomatic, it cannot be met
44 . NATURAL THEOLOGY. [DIV. I.
Axiom: All persons must be either self-existent or not self-
existent.
First term: Since all persons’ not self-existent must derive
their existence from a self-existent person, if there be
a person not self-existent, there must be a person self-
existent.
Middle term: I am a person not self-existent.
Conclusion: Therefore there is a self-existent person.
Now the only part of this syllogistic argument that can be
called an assumption, is the middle term, “I am a person not
self-existent.” Is this an illegitimate assumption? Can any
man that uses it deny it? Or can any one who hears it deny
it? If a man were so to deny it, as to say, “I am not a
person,” would any other man think it worth while to argue
with him? Or if he were to say, “ You cannot prove that I
am a person,” would any other man feel that his argument was
invalid, till he had proved the personality of the objector ?
The appeal to the principle of self-consciousness is direct and
absolute, and its answer equally direct and absolute, in the
case of every sane and honest mind; so that we are entitled
to repel the objection as a mere cavil, and to hold the argument
valid and conclusive. We thus pass immediately from the fact
of our conscious personal existence to the admission of a self-
existent person, as present to our reason, whenever we reflect,
as our own personality is to our own consciousness. Such, in
our opinion, is the conclusion to which a true & priori argument,
rightly understood and rightly stated, ought inevitably to lead
us, in the region of necessary thought and reason.
by any reasoning which ig not axiomatic; and therefore no process of
merely logical reasoning can be of the least avail against its lofty and im-
posing pretensions. It can be answered only by piercing still deeper into
the region of axiomatic thinking, reaching a basis more profoundly true,
and from that primary position destroying its dark sophistry. It is not
possible for any man honestly to doubt or deny his own existence, and on
the strength of that dishonest denial to denounce what he ventures to call
the unwarranted postulate of axiomatic thinking, ‘‘ There is finite being.”
The man who will perseveringly venture to deny this inevitable thought
may be demanded to state on what ground he does so. Does he presume
to do so, on the monstrous assumption that he himself is-dnfinite being, and
thence knows that finite being does not exist? Or does he deny that he
himself exists? The one postulate, as they term it, is not a postulate; it
is an absolute necessity of thought.
eee eee
CHAP. III.] THE ARGUMENT A PRIORI. a, Aaa
We might proceed to trace the power which this inevitable
& priort thinking and reasoning has displayed throughout the
world, and in all ages, in constraining mankind to believe in
the existence of a God, and to worship, in one way or other,
the God in whose existence they could not but believe. Every
man admits his own personality, nay asserts it,-and will not
consent to be regarded only as a thing, an animal, or a slave.
But what is personality? What is a person? ‘To be a person,
there must not only be individual will, the power of acting
from one’s own centre of being, with at least some measure of
freedom; but there must also be the perception of right and
wrong, good and evil,—that is, there must be a moral element.
A person, then, must be a rational intelligence, possessing the
high mental faculties of moral will and moral consciousness,
Nothing short of this can give a right and adequate idea of a
person. The idea of personality in its finite form implying
necessarily Personality Finite, must also imply the responsi-
bility of the derived and finite person to the Underived and
Infinite Person—the responsibility of man to God. Thence
must follow religion and religious worship. But while there
must be religion and religious worship, by the necessity of con-
sciousness and & priort thought, the kind of religion and religious
worship will depend on the idea which man entertains of God.
This, again, will depend on the mental and moral state, and
consciousness of men and nations, in the absence of revelation.
And as we are not at present in the region of revelation, so
far as our argument is concerned, we are entitled to say that
such as a nation is, such will be its religion and its gods. If
we could know with precision and certainty the mental, moral,
and social state of any people, we might tell what their religion
must be; and conversely, if we knew with precision the cha-
racter of the religion of any people, we might tell what must be
the mental, moral, and social state of that people. We refer
in passing to the Mohammedans, to the Hindus, to the Chinese,
to the Africans; and in each instance we see the congruity of
the religion with the character of the people: fierce and re-
morseless cruelty in those whose religious creed is also their
wild war-cry, “ The sword or the Koran ;” monstrous falsehood,
perfidy, and revenge, in those who worship monstrous gods, and
accept the huge fables of Hinduism; the despicable and atrocious
mingling of folly, fraud, and disregard of life, in those who
46 NATURAL THEOLOGY. [DIV. I.
follow the baseless system of Buddh; and the deepest degrada-
tion, crime, and misery, in those who place their religion in
the unintelligible incantations addressed to some Fetish. But
enough: the mere reference to such topics will serve to indi-
cate the power of & priori thinking, so far as it is thinking, or
superstitious instinct, so far as the principle acts, impulsively
and without thought, on mankind in every age and country.
It will readily be perceived that we attach more value to
both the & priort argument and to what we term @ priori
thinking, or axiomatic thinking, than is generally done. It will
also be perceived that, in our method of at once stating and
explaining this kind of reasoning, we are not exposed to the
accusation of passing illegitimately from the region of abstract
ideas into that of actual existence; because the true a priore
line of thought and argument is never in our method one of
abstract idea. It arises, we hold, necessarily out of the first
form of finite thought, self-consciousness, or the consciousness
of each person that he is a finite but a real existence; and it
carries with it most legitimately the conception of being, of
actual existence, into every other possible region of thought.
It needs no assumption which could be refused, no postulate
which might not be granted, in order to have a bridge from the
abstract to the real; for it is tétself that bridge: it is its own
assumption, its own postulate. And while we are not surprised
that the earliest advocates of the a priort argument failed to
span the chasm between the abstract idea and the actual reality,
and thus failed to carry the conviction of their cautious readers,
because the philosophy of mind was then but indefinite and
immature,—we are at the same time decidedly of opinion that,
by the addition of the modern improved and verified. philosophy
of mind, the & prior: line of reasoning may not only be restored
to Natural Theology, but may be made to afford one of its
most impregnable defences. In connection with this view, we
may state that, while carefully pursuing a recent very acute
metaphysical treatise on the Theory of Knowing and Being,’
we felt gratified to notice not only the tone of sincere respect
with which this very able and acute metaphysician always
wrote of religion, but also, and especially, were we gratified to
feel certain, that whatever havoc his reasoning might work
among metaphysical writings, it actually tended to produce a
1 By the late Professor Ferrier of St. Andrews.
CHAP. III.] THE ARGUMENT A PRIORI. AT
basis for the @ priort argument, by introducing a necessary
personality into all thought and all knowledge, thereby leaving
no chasm between the abstract ideal and the existing real or
concrete. We do not of course express any opinion relative to
the metaphysical value or soundness of the purely metaphysical
arguments and inferences contained in that work, though we
may have occasion to refer to some of them again; but we
regard it as at least an omen of good, when we find metaphy-
sical research tending to confirm the a priort argument in proof
of the being of the Infinite and Eternal Personal God.
To this extent, then, we think a true & priori argument,
regarded as the olution of a problem already believed, but
requiring to be solved, so far as that can be done by haiien
thought and reason, both can carry, and has carried, us in our
attempt to solve that problem. As certainly as man is an
existing, finite, self-conscious, moral, and personal being, so
certainly there is an existing, mand, intelligent, ovaly and
personal God, from whose eternal self-existence man derived
his finite existence, from whose infinitely wise and holy moral
being and character man obtained the finite, rational, and
moral nature by which he is distinguished, on whose abound-
ing and infinite goodness and protecting providence man is
ever dependent, and to whom, as the Author of our existence,
man is ever responsible.
These, certainly, are vast and most important conclusions
to which to be led by this line of argument, and they must be
admitted to be contributions of inestimable value to the science
of Natural Theology. They are also, as we hold, of adamantine
strength, and furnish a firm basis, so far as they go, on which to
erect that first and most important of all sciences,—the science
of eternal truth,—the science of our knowledge of God, and
of our relation to Him.
But we find, also, that this course of argument is almost ex-
clusively limited to the region of lofty thought, and has scarcely
anything to do with the vast realms of positive material exist-
ence which spread so universally around us. To the man whom
God has gifted with the power of recondite thought, this argu-
ment will always be peculiarly convincing; but to by far the
greater part of mankind it will be found of so abstract a nature
as to be absolutely beyond their powers of apprehension. The
language which we are constrained to use in stating and illus-
4§ NATURAL THEOLOGY. [DIV. I.
trating it, will generally seem to such persons unintelligible ;
and the thoughts which such language strives to embody, will
seem to them to have no meaning at all. Even such people,
however, may be able to perceive, that when the defender of
Christianity finds it necessary, or thinks it expedient, to meet
-the assailant in the regions of abstract thought, he is able to
traverse these shadowy regions with as firm and fearless a step,
and to use these abstract arguments with as much skill and
power, as can any of his antagonists. This may be of great value
to him, even though he should not be able to comprehend the
reasoning; for he may feel all the more confidence in the
plainer reasoning which he can comprehend. He may thus
actually share in the victory, although unable to take any part
in the conflict. And further, as the age in which it is our
lot to live is one of deep research, of great inquisitiveness,
and little characterized by reverence for anything that can
plead little more than hereditary and long-existent claims to
respect and credit, it is an age in which it is peculiarly neces-
sary for every Christian man, especially for every Christian
minister, to be able to take up every line of argument, and
thus meet every opponent on that opponent’s own chosen
ground. If continental theories about the Me and the not-Me
must and will be brought forward as something very new and
vastly profound, the defender of Christianity should be able to
use intelligently the same language, explore the thoughts which
it assumes to convey—perhaps means to conceal—take captive
the philosophy, so far as it 1s true, and employ it in the service
of true religion, not in the exposition of the gospel, which
admits not such foreign phraseology, but -in the science of
Natural Theology, where it may seem less unsuitable.
There is yet one thought which, before concluding this
section, we think it right to express. When we leave the sphere
of & priori thought and argument, and enter into one less ab-
stract, we have no intention to leave also behind us any of the
truths that we have acquired in that high sphere. We mean
to take them all along with us into every other region we may
have occasion to enter. When the mental philosopher has, by
means of his searching analysis, ascertained the true laws of
thought, and the fundamental principles of knowledge and
belief, he returns into more common regions of inquiry, and
employs the principles, the laws, and the skill which he has
‘
. CHAP. III J THE ARGUMENT A PRIORI. 49
acquired in the pursuit of all other knowledge. This gives
him immense power in every subsequent investigation, and en-
ables him to make great and rapid progress with the use of his
fine weapons and his well-trained mind. In like manner, it is
our intention to carry with us the well-proved results and well-
trained power of & priori thinking, and to make use of these
acquisitions in our future argument. We may find, that
though we have scarcely yet made any intelligent acquaintance
with external nature, and not a very full acquaintance with
even our own inner self-consciousness, we have nevertheless
obtained some knowledge of those forms and laws of thought,
into which all the intimations of external nature, and all that
our own self-consciousness can teach, must necessarily be cast.
We have felt ourselves placed in the dread presence of the one
holy, infinite, eternal, personal God, in no dim abstraction, but
in our own personality constrained to apprehend—not compre-
hend—His personality. And in our deep adoring awe and
reverential fear, we have been constrained to breathe the
humble prayer that He would vouchsafe to make Himself
more thoroughly known to us, and satisfy our already longing
souls with the gracious treasures of that highest knowledge.
Does not the reverential longing and adoring soul already
seem to hear,—as only supplicating souls can hear,—in its
deepest consciousness a solemn voice, which seems to say,
“The volume of nature is open before you—the widespread
volume of God’s works—go and peruse it: go, with the ideas
of your own self-consciousness, and of God, which you have
already partially acquired; go, with the light of those ascer-
tained intuitions shining around you and on your path; go,
with your perceptional faculties all awakened and enlightened,
to receive what it may impart ;—go thus, because God is before
you there, and because going thus you may expect that He
will there reveal Himself to you more fully, and thereby pre-
pare you for future revelations still more clear and glorious !”
Such a result of a priori thinking is indeed of inestimable
value.
CHAPTER IV.
THE ARGUMENT A POSTERIORI. 7
FEW preliminary sentences may be of advantage
for enabling us distinctly to apprehend the position
into which we have advanced, and the nature of the
argument into the consideration of which we are
now about to enter. The first position which we can possibly
occupy, or even conceive ourselves to occupy, is that given by
- self-consciousness. In this position a man may be rationally
conceived of as saying to himself, or as thinking, “ J am, I east,
and know that I exist,’ but nothing more. This would of itself
be merely the consciousness of existence, but would indicate
nothing as to the mode of existence. Considered in its most
abstract form, it would give nothing more than thinking being.
There is frequently a metaphysical fallacy admitted into this
very early position ; it is admitted or assumed that thought may
be conceived of without being. I do not mean without material
being, but without being at all, even immaterial being; and
from this follows the objection, that thought does not prove being.
I answer, Try to imagine thought without a thinker—thought
detached from all being, and in an illimitable void in which no
being, not even spirit, exists. We cannot; for if we try, we
find ourselves conceiving of thought as some invisible essence.
floating in the otherwise universal vacuum, and therefore actual
being even there, and rendering its own position not absolute
vacuity. Thought, then, asserts thinking existence ; and this is
primary and abstract consciousness.
But this primary self-consciousness is essentially activity. ~
From its position it can move in either of two directions, or
manifest or exert its activity in either of two directions. It
can employ its activity in inquiring into its own existence—
into its own forms of thought. It must do so, according to its
potency as a thinker; and in doing so, it inevitably inquires
into the nature and reason of its own existence: it asks whence
CHAP. IV.] THE ARGUMENT A POSTERIORI. OH:
and how that existence originated. It does not imagine itself
the earliest of beings—the primal existence; and therefore it is
anxious to inquire what was before it. Thus it plunges neces-
sarily into the very essence of & priori thinking,—of thinking
back, and asking what was before its own conscious existence,
—what are the daws of thought which constituted the forms of
thought. This necessary & priori thinking we have been already
engaged in attempting briefly to explore, for the important
purpose of ascertaining its intrinsic value, and the value of its
results,
The other region of thought, not less open to man, and
much more open to many men, is that which arises from his
sentient nature in contact with external nature, and calling into
action the power of reflex thought. This conjoint sensation
and reflection he calls perception, or, as some do, perception-of-
matter, using a compound term to imply the conjunction of
sensation and reflection, forming an irresistible conviction, that
what is thus brought before his intelligent nature is the reality
of existence external to himself. Having thus attained the
belief that external things affecting his organs of sensation have
given rise to these perceptions, and thus given him the know-
ledge of an external world with which he exists in contact,
meeting him at every point and pore of his sentient being,
calling into action every capacity of his percipient being, and
arousing every faculty of his intellectual being, he arranges all
the knowledge thus acquired, and with it fills all the forms
of thought of which he had previously become conscious. The
question then arises, Is this external world merely a produc-
tion of my own forms of thought, with which it so wonder-
fully agrees? Or has it an actual existence of its own, in no
respect dependent on me, though marvelously adapted to my
sentient, percipient, and intelligent nature? A very little re-
flection will suffice to convince every candid mind that it is not
in any way dependent on himself, since he cannot prevent its
existence making itself known to him often in conditions any-
thing but agreeable, yet which he cannot annihilate when he
pleases. It has, then, an existence of its own, quite indepen-
dent of him, yet wonderfully qualified to fill all his forms of
thought with correspondent realities. To what does it owe éts
ewistence ? This is the inevitable inquiry. And what infor-
mation can it suggest to me regarding the author of its exist-
o2 *« NATURAL THEOLOGY. ‘ [DIV. I.
ence? The question thus raised takes necessarily a different
direction from that in which the inquirer was formerly engaged.
He was then engaged among the laws of thought, in search of a
solution of the problem of necessary being. He is now about
to endeavour, by investigating existing nature, to ascertain the
character of its Author, at once and intuitively held to be that
Infinite Being in whose necessary existence he already believes.
This new mode of inquiry 1s termed the & posterior argument 5
and its course and purpose is, “ From nature, or, the universe,
viewed as effect, to reason back to the Author of the universe
regarded as CAUSE.”
It will easily be perceived, both that to many men the
& posteriori argument will be more attractive and intelligible
than the & priori can be, and also why this is and must be
the case. There is no small amount of both the faculty of
abstract thinking, and practice in the use of that faculty,
required in order to form an adequate conception of the a
priori argument. But the & posteriort method can be fol-
lowed and understood by almost any man, without more recon-
dite thinking than is required for the ordinary affairs of life.
Many will feel a strong repugnance to task their minds with
such arduous exercise of thought, but will attend with plea-
sure and advantage to information brought to them from the
fields of external nature. Yet these two forms of argument
ought not to be viewed in any other light than as equally valu-
able. One may be more available to one class of men, the
other to another. The one is not therefore more valuable than
the other in itself, but more suitable in its application to a
peculiar mental condition. We do not therefore admit that
the & posteriori argument is intrinsically better than that by the
& priori method; but we readily admit that it may be under-
stood by a greater number, and may relatively be of greater
general advantage to the majority of inquirers. By the
method which we have adopted, and are. pursuing, we avail
ourselves of both. Those who have adequately understood the
& priori course of thought and argument, will enter upon the
new line of investigation, both with minds already furnished
with forms of thought into which to receive the information
now to be acquired, and also with minds trained to high and
arduous inquiry. This may be a little further illustrated.
In his first and introductory book, Dr. Chalmers dwells
9
CHAP. IV.] THE ARGUMENT A POSTERIORI. Bae
pretty largely on what he denominates “the ethics of theo-
logy, as distinct from the objects of theology.” This disquisi-
tion is very valuable, chiefly as pointing out how the feeling
of responsibility may be so forcibly aroused and directed, by
means of the moral convictions and duties already existing in
the human mind, as to lay on us an imperative obligation to
direct our attention to the objects of theology. It shows, too,
that the fact of the distant and recondite nature of the inquiry
relative to the objects, does not in the least affect the obli-
gation, or the ethics. Now this disquisition answers some-
what to our discussion of the & priori argument, in its enforce-
ment. of the duty to study the subject. But there is this
advantage, as we think, in our method, that we not only have
had the duty very strongly enforced by the very nature of
the argument, but have also advanced far into the study itself.
We have obtained not only the conviction of our duty to enter
into a certain course of thought and investigation; but we
have already obtained the power of thought, the apparatus
of thinking, and some very important results of our prior
inquiries, as a permanent acquisition of those inquiries, and
a preparation for all that may yet be before us. We are quite
as strongly attracted to the & posteriori argument as any &
posteriori reasoner can be; but we do not come to that field of
investigation to find there our first intimations of the Divine
Being,—we come to seek further information relative to the
attributes and character of that Gop in the reality of whose
existence we already believe.
Still further and higher does the value of our previous
- acquisition reach. By our self-consciousness we obtain the
idea of personality,—that is, of moral will and consctousness.
By & priori thinking we legitimately carry the idea of per-
sonality into the idea of Gop, and conclude that man—moral
and conscious man—must stand in some personal relation to a
moral, intelligent, personal God. This even awfully solemn
and sacred idea we carry with us, as an ascertained certainty,
into all our investigations of the realm of nature. Man
already knows his own relation to God, so far, in the universe
of mind; and he now seeks to know his relation to the universe
of material being, with the further important inquiry, how both
he and nature stand in relation to God. The unreasoned but
also undisputed thought with which the mind usually com-
54 NATURAL THEOLOGY. . [DIV: I.
mences its inquiries in the region of nature is, “ God is, and is
everywhere. He made me, and He made also the world. I
cannot see Him; but I can see everywhere in nature the
manifestations of His power and wisdom. In every pheno-
menon of nature I perceive some attribute of God; and from
the character of these phenomena, I may infer to some extent
the character of the attributes, and hence the character, of the
Divine Being.” Entering on his inquiry, he may find in every
portion of his knowledge of nature the inevitable concurrence
of two elements,—the objective element, or fact, and the subjec-
twwe element, or reasoning, as existing in himself,—with a won-
derful harmony between them. He may therefore conclude
that the same God who made nature, made also his reason; and
thus he may regard himself as, what we have already termed
him, the synthesis of mind and matter, created both to know —
and to manifest God. But he may also miss his way to this
true and happy conclusion, as every sceptic and every ma-
terialist does. For as he began with the unreasoned though
undisputed postulate, “ God is,” and as that may be disputed,
and however reasonable cannot be proved by.& posteriort argu-
ment alone, he may find it impossible to advance beyond such
generalities as, the laws of nature—antecedence and sequence
—jinvariable antecedence and sequence — invariable laws —
fatalism. But if he has acquired and understood what the
d priort argument can legitimately teach,—his own personality
in moral will and consciousness, and the intelligent and moral
personality of God,—he cannot fall into the fathomless abyss of
fatalism, and may learn much in the & posteriori region relative
to the attributes and character of God.
There is another topic to which we wish to direct special
attention. When we use the term Nature, we are liable to
apply it only and exclusively to the external world—the material «
universe around us. But this is both an arbitrary and an
undue limitation of the term. In the term Nature we are
fully entitled to include man himself. Man is as truly an
object in nature as any naturally and materially existent object
of observation can possibly be. Every one deems it quite
legitimate to direct attention to the bee, for example, and to its
exquisite workmanship and wonderful instinct,—its habits of
consociation, and its social economy and government. But is it
not as perfectly legitimate to direct attention to man,—to his
CHAP. IV.] THE ARGUMENT A POSTERIORI. DOD
productions in art, science, and literature,—to his marvellous
mental faculties and powers,—to his social habits,—and to the
whole structure and economy of human society, laws, and
government? By doing so, we shall find that the sphere of
the & posteriori argument has become almost boundless, has
acquired an intensely increased degree of interest for us, and
is fraught with instruction full of the most vital importance.
Into this region Dr. Chalmers boldly entered, and from it drew
not a little of his most valuable contributions to Natural
Theology. Other authors have done the same, though with
immeasurably less skill and power. It may, however, be ques-
tioned, not whether this can be legitimately done,—for that we
hold to be unquestionable,—but whether it can legitimately
yield to Natural Theology, with ample certainty, the advantages
which Dr. Chalmers and others drew from it to that science,
unless it has been first impregnated with & priori thinking and
its results.
For example, there are no works in modern times, no works
in any age, which contain and present so complete a digest of
all human science, its laws, its reasonings, its necessary formal
arrangement, and its results, as the writings of Auguste Comte ;
and yet the conclusion at which he arrives is not a valuable
contribution to Natural Theology, but to what he terms Positive
Philosophy, or Positivism; in short, absolute Atheism. Yet, in
perusing the writings of Comte, it is impossible to refrain from
admiring the amount of knowledge which he displays of almost
every subject to which the human mind has ever addressed
itself, and very specially the deep acquaintance which he mani-
fests with human society in all its laws and all its phases—at
least as it exists in France—and even with regard to its religious
aspects. For he not only takes cognizance of religion as a
necessary element in the human mind, and a power in society,
but also traces, as he thinks, its origin, its successive develop-
ments, marks its present condition, and states what must be its
final results. It is plain, therefore, that the introduction of the
study of man and society into the & posteriort argument, how-
ever valuable it may be in the hands of some, will not neces-
sarily render it more pregnant with proofs of the being and
attributes of God, but may render it liable to be used in support
of Atheism, At a subsequent stage I shall attempt a statement
and refutation of the Positivism of Comte; meantime I can but
/
56 NATURAL THEOLOGY. [DIV. I
state, that to me it seems that the total absence of true a priori
thinking, and the consequent want of the results thereby pro-
duced, will sufficiently account for the fatal result of scientific
and human philosophy in the hands of Comte, and, with deep
regret we add, of his few followers in Britain—regret the most
profound that in Britain he could have even one follower. But
if the human mind begin its inquiries without any desire to find
a God, all its researches may but intensify its wilful blindness.
While we claim the right of carrying with us, and intro-
ducing into the domains of & posteriori investigation, the powers
and principles of thought already acquired and trained in the
& priori region, there is also another law of thought not neces-
sarily obtained alone in the & priori region, yet closely related
to it, which we must mention and explain before we proceed
to employ it. We can scarcely even begin our observation of
nature without perceiving change in the objects that come under
our observation. The first effect of this might only be to sur-
prise us. But when we perceive that, although changes are
incessant, they follow each other in accordance with some uni-
form order or plan, so that when one kind of change is perceived
we learn to expect it to be followed certainly by another of a
corresponding kind, somehow correlated to it,—this gives rise
to what is called our belief in the uniformity of nature. A great
deal of metaphysical and unmetaphysical argumentation has
been very unprofitably expended on this subject. Some explain
our belief in the uniformity of nature, by asserting that we do
so in consequence of an original law of the mind causing us
instinctively to believe in the uniformity of nature. Others
assert it to be the mere result of experience, and of course deny
that our belief is entitled to go beyond our experience. Every
one must feel that the latter cannot be the right explanation,
because every one knows that his belief in the constant uni-
formity of nature’s sequences far transcends his own experience.
Further, every one feels that he brings to his investigation
of the question, or to his observation of facts, an antecedent
expectation that these sequences will be uniform,—that there is
a constancy in nature’s operations,—and that he will seldom be
disappointed by trusting in the constancy of nature. How has
this antecedent expectation been formed? Is this one of the
necessary forms of thought, without the use of which we cannot
think orderly and rationally? Even if it were, how was it
re
CHAP. IV.] THE ARGUMENT A POSTERIORI. Ay
called into action, so as to be the antecedent expectation that we
always carry with us? This is no idle question, as we shall
find ere long. Can our & priori thinking help us here? We
have found that the primary element of our thinking is self-
consciousness; and that this element is probably roused, and
certainly kept in action, by the sensation of external resistance.
To this external resistance we consciously offer a corresponding
resistance, or employ it according to an internal and conscious
act of willi—a volition. Our own volition has just so much
uniformity as the experienced resistance has, so far at least as_
the external resistance elicits only an internal consciousness of
resisting. There may arise the volition to use the external
something in the way in which it seems to act. But this change
is in the internal volition, not in the external and physical
resistance. Such is the very earliest intimation which we can
have of nature; and it may induce us to form and entertain
the notion of a uniform constancy in the external world long
before we have learned to reason about nature, and sensation,
and perception. If this be so, then we bring from the very
dawn of consciousness, and from our earliest contact with nature,
so much of a dim perception of the constancy of nature’s posi-
tion in regard to the conscious self, as to lead necessarily to the
formation of a belief in the uniform constancy of nature. This
seems to us a more probable explanation of this very important
belief in the constancy of nature, existing and acting as an
antecedent expectation, and leading us on in our investigations,
than can otherwise be given. And when formed and in opera-
tion, it guides the experimental philosopher in all his inquiries,
and is itself strengthened and confirmed by every successful
experiment and new acquisition. It may afford also to the
mental philosopher, and to the student of Natural Theology,
the ground of a valuable inference in a very early stage of
their inquiries,—the inference, namely, that there is an inherent
harmony between man and nature, suggesting the great proba-
bility that the same God is the author of both man and nature.
The value of this idea in the region of a posteriort argument
cannot be over-estimated ; and it rescues us at the very outset
from the entangling sophistries of the sceptic.
We are here touching the border of the great vexed ques-
tion respecting Cause and Effect; but previous to the discus-
sion of this subject, we have already obtained so much acquaint-
58 | NATURAL THEOLOGY. | FI DIVEE
ance with certain primary laws of thought, as to be prepared
to enter upon it without much hazard of being led astray, or
losing ourselves in misty obscurities. We bring to the investi-
gation of the a posteriori argument nearly all the elements
necessary for the successful prosecution of all its departments ;
and that, too, without the necessity of spending much time in
preliminary disquisitions of a metaphysical character. So far
as these may yet meet us, and force themselves upon our notice,
we are provided with laws of thought by which they can be
mastered. Our self-consciousness is beyond the reach of dis-
pute. In that self-consciousness we have the elements of moral
will, and that, too, conscious moral will—a true personality.
We have also the certainty that God exists, and that He is
an intelligent and moral being. We have a considerably well
established belief, also, that our constitution, mental and physi-
cal, is in direct sympathetic and generally harmonious relation
with the constitution of an actually existing external universe ;
and as we know that our being is derived from God, we infer that
the universe with which we are in such sympathetic relation is
also derived from God, and that from our study of nature we
may expect to receive much precious information concerning
the attributes and character of that God who appears to be the
author of both man and nature.
Such is the state of mental preparation in which we pro-
ceed to the study of the & posterior’ argument.
SEC. I. DOCTRINE OF CAUSATION.
The & posteriori argument, regarded as a problem, may
be stated thus: “That the cause of nature and the cause of
mind is one and the same.” It is an endeavour to prove this,
by reasoning from the minor term of the proposition back to
the major—from the minor, or the effect of the universe, to
the major, or the Cause of the universe; or from nature, or
the universe, viewed as effect, to reason back to the Author
of the umiverse, viewed as cause. It proceeds, therefore,
throughout on the universal principle of causation.. This
principle is thus expressed in its axiomatic form, “Every
change must have a cause ;” and this implies a further ex-
planatory statement, that “every cause must be of such a
nature as to account for the character of the change.” From
CHAP. IV.] THE ARGUMENT A POSTERIORI. 59
x
this arises the possibility of reasoning in either of two direc-
tions, thus: “ From the character of the cause, we may infer
the character of the change;” or, “ From the character of
the change, we may infer the character of the cause.” The
latter of these is the form of the @ posteriori argument—the
term change being understood as implying effect, under the law
of causation. The full statement of the problem, then, is:
“F'rom the character of the effect to, ascertain, so far as the
effect extends, the character of the cause.” It will be observed
that we use the expression, so far as the effect extends, as cau-
tiously guardine*the proposition ; because, while the cause must
always be as great as the effect, it may be indefinitely greater ;
and we are not entitled to limit the cause to the exact boundaries
of the effect, as is fallaciously attempted by the opponents of
the & posteriori argument, when they assert that from a finite
effect we can legitimately infer no more than a finite cause,—
that from a finite universe we can infer no more than a /inite
God. We may admit that we cannot from a finite effect prove
an infinite cause ; but we are not legitimately required to deny
infinity, especially if from previous or other proof we have
reason to admit infinity. But this proof we have already re-
ceived from the & priori argument, according to which it
appeared, that from the fact of finite existence, given to us in
self-consciousness, we are entitled, or rather constrained, to
infer infinite existence. We have no need, therefore, to infer
more from the @ posteriori argument than its terms will warrant;
but we are not, on that account, confined within a limited and
defective conclusion.
The principle of causation, then, is this: Every effect, or
thing which begins to be, must have a cause. And as, under
this principle, every change must be regarded as an effect, we
feel that we are in a universe of cause and effect. By our
relation to the world, we perceive the universe of matter exist-
ing in space, and undergoing incessant changes. This is the
aspect of external nature, and it suggests to us causation co-
extensive with the universe. Internally, on the other hand,
we are conscious of our own existence, and of internal changes
of thought and emotion—of perception and of will. We long
to know whether there be a connecting link, which might prove
a common design between the external world and the internal
world, or the self-conscious being that we term the Mz. But
60 NATURAL THEOLOGY. 7 [DIV, I.
_the sophist attempts to arrest us even in this early stage, by
asserting that we cannot prove the reality of causation,—that
we never do, or can, know anything about cause,—that we
neither have, nor can obtain, any idea of power,—and that all
that we can ever know relative to change, either in the external
world or in the internal self, is the sequence of changes. He
further tells us that these sequences are invariable, both in
what we call nature and in what we call thought; that they
cannot spring from or be connected with any will, because will
is necessarily variable; and that therefore we ought to con-
clude that the universe of man and nature aré alike governed
by some invariable necessity—some inexorable destiny—and
that all is fatalism.
We are not, however, left at the mercy of the sophist’s
assertions. We turn to the self-consciousness within, to inquire
what information that bearer of sure evidence can give. It
has already given some information of great importance. Its
very first information made us at least partially acquainted both
with the world without us, and with our own internal self.
We had the sensation of some external resistance, and the con-
sciousness of a volition either to overcome, or to use it. We
perceived also that this volition, though entirely mental, had
the power of producing muscular action in our sentient bodily
frame, and thereby either overcoming the external resistance,
or seizing on it, and employing its action in obedience to the
conscious will. We thus obtain direct and immediate know-
ledge of one kind of causation; and we find that, so far from
its being absolutely invariable, it varies in exact accordance
with our own will. There is thus already formed so far within
us, some idea of a sympathetic relation between mind and >
matter, partly by the ready obedience which our own material
structure yields to the volitions of our own minds, and partly
by the equally ready obedience which external nature yields
to the power put forth by our bodily organization.'
? When the sceptic uses the argument that “ will is necessarily vari-
able,” we ought not at once to admit this assertion, but to try whether
it be not asophism. Do we find that will is so necessarily variable as he
assumes? Do we not, on the contrary, find that the variableness of will]
depends upon other mental elements, and on mutable conditions? If the
mind of any man be remarkable for wisdom and moral soundness of judg-
ment, he will rarely see any reason to be variable in his will ; for will is, or
Oe
CHAP. IV. ] THE ARGUMENT A POSTERIORI. ; 61
We have now begun to reason as well as to observe; and
as this combined action and reason has carried us out of the
sceptic’s first. assertion, “that we cannot prove the reality of
causation,”—inasmuch as we have acted causation, and know
that we have done so,—we proceed into the region of external
nature, to explore what may be learned in that wide sphere.
Let it be observed, however, that in carrying our observed
action and reason with us, we are now empowered to employ a
very important mental faculty; we mean the faculty of framing
analogies, and reasoning by analogy. This faculty is of more
- value, and is actually more employed, than many are aware.
It lies in the heart of all inductive reasoning, and is largely
employed by every man of inventive genius, by every discoverer
in any department of art or science. It consists essentially in
this, that our sensations and perceptions take notice of all
resemblances, both in single incidents or facts, and in com-
bined events or changes, with the latent idea that there is
some more comprehensive truth from which they both take
their form, and in which they are primarily united and inhere ;
and that, in perceiving these resemblances, we are led to con-
clude that the resemblance may go further than we have yet
perceived, and may produce events or changes analogous to
other already perceived events or changes. This mental idea
of analogy will require generally to be verified by experiment ;
but it often suggests the experiment, and thereby aids largely
ought to be, the mental volition put forth in accordance with the compre-
hensive reason and wisdom which perceives what ought to be done, and
under the direction of the moral faculty deciding what duty requires:
therefore, to the extent that these are sound, must the will be almost in-
variable. Add to this the thought, that the condition of a wise and good
man may be little, if at. all, dependent on circumstances, so that he may be
always free to act as reason and conscience dictate, and you will very
readily see that in his case variableness is not a necessary attribute of his
will. But carry this course of analysis to its ultimate point, and imagine
the will of a being infinite in wisdom, power, goodness, and truth, and you
will readily perceive, that so far from variableness being an essential cha-
racteristic of His will, it must necessarily be ‘‘ without variableness or
shadow of turning.” The sophism, then, is of a very common and puny
kind: ‘‘ Some will is variable, therefore all will is variable.” The will of
some ignorant, fickle, dependent man is variable ; therefore all will—not
only that of a man of wise, upright, independent, and decided character,
but also that of God—is variable. We need not surely further regard this
sophism.
62 NATURAL THEOLOGY. [DIV. I.
in extending our knowledge. It is also an ever-increasing
power, both in the extent and rapidity with which it prompts
to investigation, and in the confidence with which it enables us
to apprehend results, and very often. to anticipate them. All
science is full of this mental power, and very greatly indebted
to it; and in the case of some peculiarly gifted minds, it acts
like a peculiar intuitional foresight. We may add, that it
very readily lays hold of the idea of antecedent probability ;
and thus past experience and observed resemblance, combined
in the reasoning from analogy, aid man very greatly in acquir-
ing knowledge of the external world.
Let us employ this mental power a little, be way of
example. When we think of causation at all closely, we feel
ourselves inevitably impelled to regard it as capable of being
viewed in two very different aspects. There is physical causation,
and there is moral causation. The physical causation is analo-
gous to moral causation, but cannot be identical with it, because
physical causation cannot apply to mind, and moral causa-
tion cannot apply to matter, though they may illustrate each
other. Let us give them, then, distinctive names, and let us
call physical causation force, and moral causation motive. Mark
now how this division and the analogy enable us to explore
and apprehend nature. . We begin with man, and with mind
as we find it in man. By the aid of self-consciousness, we
know that though man is sentient and percipient of force, he
does not necessarily obey it, but resists or obeys according to
the inward dictates of his own mind. You must reason with |
him, or he must reason with himself, before he wills to act, and
then he acts or suffers as he wills; that is, a rational and moral
motive must be applied to his rational and moral mind before
he will act, and this is his true cause or motive.
But we look out on external nature, and on that depart-
ment of it which we call animated nature—the sphere of
sentient animal life. What is causation to that region of being?
Not rational or moral causation, not motive, as that was cause
to man, but something analogous to it—the application to its
sentient life of some external force, which excites a low kind of
volition or voluntary obedience to the force affecting its sentient
life, and producing such pain or pleasure as is enough to elicit
corresponding action. Further still we advance, carrying our
analogy with us, and enter into the region of vegetable life.
CHAP. IV.] THE ARGUMENT A POSTERIORI. 63
But this insentient life yet possesses what is termed rritability,
susceptible of receiving impulses from light, air, water, earth,
which it can absorb into its own organization. The only .
causation which we can now employ is that of force—the
invisible power which inorganic nature can exert on the irrita-
bility or susceptibility of root, fibre, and leaf ;—all this we can
so arrange and employ as to cultivate the vegetable world
as we please. Still further our research, guided by analogy,
or prompted by it and guided by experience, can extend. We
can perceive that there resides some latent force im even
inorganic nature, which not only acts on organic life, as we -
perceived in the vegetable world, but which can act on itself,
and that too with wonderful uniformity. Of this, crystallization
is a remarkable instance. Every distinct inorganic substance
in nature has its own specific crystal, which it will uniformly
assume in suitable circumstances. This latent force is its own.
We can neither give it, nor take it away. But we can put the
substance in such circumstances as will allow it to put forth
that latent force and assume its crystalline form. We can also
mark the specific operation of electric. and magnetic forces; and
we can so elicit and regulate them, as to render them subser-
vient to our own use in several very wonderful ways. Nor
do we suppose that we have yet ascertained all the forces or
unknown elements of physical causation that exist in nature,
or reached the limitation of their services to us in those that
we already so far know. Very much of all these discoveries
we owe to the almost intuitive faculty of reasoning from
analogy; and this faculty originated in self-consciousness, and
is related to 4 priori thinking,
I have made this brief digression, not to place a higher
value on & priori thought, but to show how a complete answer
may be given to the cavils of a cold and intellectual—yet not
very. mtellectual—scepticism. For you will observe that in all
these instances we have traced causation and found power,—a
causation which we could understand, and a power which we
could employ ; not a fatalistic causation, but a causation which
we could control, or neutralize, or vary, according to the dictates
of our own reason and will ;—a causation, therefore, which, in
its very susceptibility of being so used by reason and will,
showed its own derivation from the Supreme Reason and Will.
We find physical cause, as designated force, either active or
64 ‘ NATURAL THEOLOGY. ADIN
latent in all material nature, and in every elementary sub-
stance; and in these most latent conditions we still find it not
only existing, though invisibly and unknown essentially, but
also existing often in the greatest potency. We might well
imagine that, in its most invisible condition, yet greatest potency,
++ must be most subservient to mind when that mind possesses
adequate knowledge and power ; and thus we might believe
the God of nature to be most absolutely present among the
‘nvisible forces of nature, with them wielding the universe.
“Fe maketh the winds His messengers, and flaming fire His
servant.” We find force stimulating and promoting the growth
of insentient vegetable life; and we can guide and use it. We
still find force, but now in a higher form, giving impulse
to the sentient life of animals, and assuming somewhat of the
aspect of motive, yet not involving reason; and by employing
it as our reason directs, we can both impel and govern the
animal world. We can perceive that, in every rational human
being, there is an internal constitution similar to that of which
self-consciousness renders us cognizant; and we can therefore
know, that although in percipient rational life physical force
can affect the sensational frame, it cannot with any certain or
constant uniformity determine the conduct of the man; and
that if we wish to exercise any guiding influence on his conduct,
we must appeal to his reason,—we must use the only causation
which can have power with him,—we must produce a motive.
Even then we shall find that the motive sways him only when
his own will adopts it, and not further or otherwise than it does
so. Beyond this point we cannot at present legitimately pro-
ceed; but we may indicate that there is yet a higher power
that may be applied to man,—a purer and mightier causation :
the power and causation of motives not merely rational and
moral in the highest degree, but spiritual and divine, when
the Holy Spirit brings the gospel to bear on his spiritually
quickened and enlightened soul.
We have been traversing the realm of science, although
without making any special reference to it as science. But
now we mean to use it in illustration of our argument. What,
then, is science? Science is direct and spontaneous knowledge,
systematically arranged. The human mind, when beginning to.
observe, and think, and know, has as yet no science. But it
has what can and will produce science; for it has first the
CHAP. IV.] THE ARGUMENT. A POSTERIORI. 65
direct power of observing facts, and retaining the conceptions
of them in its memory; and it has next the spontaneous laws
of thought, by which it can classify and arrange them in
accordance with its own systematizing tendency. The know-
ledge thus obtained, classified and systematically arranged, is
entitled science. There may be long and extensive observa-
tion, commonly called induction,—much use of analogical
reasoning,—many an attempted classification,—before it can
become true science. And even when true, it may probably
never become complete; for there may be continually coming
into observation new facts that require to be added. But
when it has been established so as to unite both the laws of
thought, according to which men classify, and the observed
coincident relations of facts, in accordance with which they
require to be classified and arranged, then there is a true
and exact science. And when it has been thus accurately
elaborated, it is the same to all men by whom it is understood.
There are sciences of different kinds, because there are dif-
ferent objects in nature; but all sciences contain the laws
of human thought on the one hand, and the classified and
arranged objects of nature on the other. By means of sense
we perceive, by means of reason we arrange, all the phenomena
of nature; and the one link uniting the sense and reason of man
to the phenomena of nature is Science.)
This might be reasoned out and illustrated. to any length ;
but we forbear, believing that it will be readily understood
and admitted. We are, however, anxious to draw attention
to the position in which we now stand. We have achieved
science; and science is the union between man and nature—
‘ The application of this idea is shown in the happiest and most con-
vincing manner in the first lecture of The Testimony of the Rocks, in which
it is shown that man classifies all his knowledge, in consequence of his
mind possessing a native tendency to classify, or a native principle of
classification. But while this principle, implanted in him by his Creator,
impels him to classify, he finds, as he advances in his pleasing task, that
there already runs through all nature an aptness to be classified in certain
all-pervading principles and analogies, which concur in combining all
things under certain great leading principles, relations, and resemblances,
—intimating very clearly that the Creator Himself made all His works in
accordance with principles of classification,—that in this respect nature
itself proves that the mind of man is an image of the mind of God, and that
as Man is conscious of design, he cannot but gee design in creation, proving
it to be the work of an Infinitely. Wise Designing Mind—of Gop.
E
66 NATURAL THEOLOGY. [DIV. I.
between the subjective and the objective worlds. It unites the
intuitions of reason with the perceived phenomena of nature.
It contains portions of both elements, and thereby unites them.
If there were not a universal harmony between man and
nature, there could not be science. But there is science ;
therefore there is a universal harmony between them. The
objective universe of nature, and the subjective universe of
mind, are in reality only the separate elements of one and the
same universe: consequently, if we find the cause of the one,
we find the cause of the other,—the cause of, external nature
must be the cause of the moral world within us. This is the
conclusion we are already entitled to form,—a conclusion very
different from that to which sophistry tried to mislead us.
We are no doubt greatly indebted to science for aiding us
in reaching this conclusion by so direct and clear a path. We
may, however, add that men of science themselves frequently
miss this conclusion—not only in such instances as that of
Comte, but in the case of many others from whom better
things might have been expected. It may be worth while to
specify what we apprehend to be the reason of their aberration.
Some time since it was regarded as an indubitable philosophical
truth, that nothing more was to be found in nature but ante-
cedents and sequences, following each other with sufficient
uniformity to furnish ground for science, but never yielding
direct evidence of a real cause. The word nevertheless was
very convenient, and they used it, but generally with a warn-
ing to their readers that it was to be understood as meaning
nothing more than invariable sequence, because real cause was
not known in nature, and could not be known. They could
not therefore find any real cause in nature, for they did not
expect to find it—nay, denied that it could be found. It was
not possible, from such a defective premiss, to arrive at an
adequate conclusion. But they did use a term which implied
all that they denied, though they did not fully define that
term: they used the term force to indicate that unseen and
unknown, but real power, which was found to pervade all
nature, and to produce all its perceptible changes. . They
‘ estimated its power; they calculated the amount of that power;
they marked the laws of its operations; they calculated with
it; they used it as an absolute reality, and yet they would not
admit it to be a true physical cause. Were they afraid that,
OE EE
CHAP. IV.] THE ARGUMENT A POSTERIORI. 67
if they admitted a cause in nature, they would not be able to
deny a great First Cause—supernatural, supreme, divine? If
this was not their secret reason,—and we will not assert that it
was,—their conduct and reasoning were irrationally unscientific,
and had the miserable effect of leaving them in the grasp of
infidelity and fatalism—of that blind force which was to them
the unconscious God of their unconscious universe—the strong
inexorable destiny of unreasoning power, perhaps a material
Pantheism, or an unintelligible Idealism.
There has, however, of late a great and propitious change
taken place among our men of highest science. Few of them
would seek now to conceal the indications of nature that all is
full of cause, and lead the thoughtful observer of nature up to
the Cause of causes—to God. Many of them delight to make
their profound knowledge of science, and science itself, instru-
mental in illustrating the divine attributes—the power, the
wisdom, and the goodness of God, as manifested in the universe.
From all such right-minded scientific men we would confidently
anticipate the ready admission, that the use which we have made
of science in our argument is a correct and true one, and that
they delight to trace, in their own manner, the clear and daily
multiplying proofs that He who created the mind of man, and
sent him forth to study and interpret nature, is also the Creator
of the universe in which man has been placed, that he might
lend it his reason and his voice, and fill it with the anthem
of intelligent praise. Many eloquent passages precisely to this
effect might be quoted from the writings of Sir John Herschell,
Professor Whewell, Professor Sedgwick, Sir David Brewster,
and other men pre-eminent in science, to whose able and learned
works we gladly refer. But above them all in directness of
purpose, in deep searching investigation, in vividness of descrip-
tion, and in magnificent splendour of expression, would we
place the various geological works of the late Hugh Miller,
particularly in his latest work, The Testimony of the Rocks, in
which, despite the small detailed criticisms of some small critics,
we find what we venture to term the noblest and best contribu-
tion to Natural Theology, in the argument from design, that
has ever been produced.
68 NATURAL THEOLOGY. 7 [DIV. I
SEC. II. DOCTRINE OF ADAPTATION—DESIGN.
The most common mode of stating and prosecuting the @
posteriori argument is by means of what is termed design. By
the word design is meant, in its most simple sense, the adap-
tation of means to the accomplishment of some end. This, of
course, assumes that there is some end in view which is sought
to be obtained, and that the means likely to accomplish that
end are chosen and employed. This, again, implies mind
exercising thought and reason, with the deliberate intention and
the forecasting plan of employing means such as may produce
the desired result. It implies, further, the idea of power, and
the use of that power by the thinking and forecasting mind.
All this is contained in a full conception of what is meant by
the term design. Mind using matter for the accomplishment
of its own intentions, is what we mean when we speak of the
operations of designing mind.
The course commonly adopted by writers on the & posterior:
argument, is to contemplate nature as purely objective, and from
the observed arrangements to draw such inferences as may
seem valid under the ordinary laws of causation. According
to that method, we do not commence with the conception of
mind, and judge of its wisdom by our perception of the skill
with which the means have been chosen and applied; but we
mark the existing arrangements, and endeavour to discover
whether they are manifestly such as infer adaptation to an end
—and therefore infer that such an end was in view, and led to
that arranged adaptation—and that therefore there must be mind
designing, that is, with an end in contemplation, and adapting
suitable means for its accomplishment. This is the simplest
and most common conception of the a posteriort argument.
This is the method which has been adopted and employed by
Paley with consummate ability and skill, so far as clear state-
ment and convincing argument are concerned.
In order that the real and absolute value of the & posteriora
argument may be fairly tested, it must in the first instance
be restricted rigidly to the sphere of external nature,—the
objective world ; and all considerations drawn from the mental
constitution of man must be carefully excluded. We do not
mean to say that, in an earnest attempt to learn what we can
from nature regarding the attributes and character of its
CHAP. IV.] THE ARGUMENT A POSTERIORI. 69
Author, for the satisfaction of our own minds, we are not at
liberty to make use of every element within our reach,—as
men generally do; but we mean to say, that in order scientifi-
cally to construct and produce an argument intended to con-
vince possible gainsayers, we must keep strictly within the
proper limits of that argument. How much, then, can nature
actually teach us, under the ordinary laws of causation, even
limiting the idea of physical causation to the notion of force,
and excluding reflective thought drawn from self? This is
our present question.
By the very slightest observation of nature, we are con-
strained to admit the adaptation of means to an end,—even the
arrangement and use of forces to produce some result by their
means. But when we thus rigidly keep within the region of
nature alone, we are at once met by the specious objections of
the sophist. “I grant,” he may say, “that all things are im
conditions suitable to their nature; for otherwise they could
not exist, or at least could not perform their functions; but
while this manifests existing suitableness, it does not necessarily
prove designed adaptation. There may be in nature some
plastic power of prodigiously varied capacity for the produc-
tion of form and function. That power might have gone on
producing fishes, for example, on land, where they could not
perform their functions, and therefore could not exist, and are
not found existing. But when it produced them in the sea,
although without any more design than before, they would then
be in condition to perform their functions, and to exist. Their
actual existence can thus be accounted for without inferring
design ; and therefore I deny that their existence can prove
design.” This is no caricature: it is a fair specimen of the
reasonings of the school of the Positive Philosophy. But it is
adequately met and refuted, when we take into consideration
such complex facts as serial existences,—organisms which
require numerous inter-related and co-related adaptations, not
one of which could exist and perform its functions without
the co-existent presence of all the others, and not one of which
has the power to produce any other; or, the correlated groups
of vegetables, combining to form classification and order, based
upon their mutual relations, but none having the power to
impart that common relation, and so form the ground-element
of the group; or, the absolute and permanent mathematical
70 NATURAL THEOLOGY. ! "PA prvcre
ratios which are found to exist in many departments of nature,
regulating their constitution and action when so arranged, but
which arrangement has no power to produce itself. All these
observed facts in nature prove that there is more than the mere
performance of a function,—that there is a long, elaborate,
complex, and well-arranged preparation for the performance
itself, without which it would not be possible; and this is
ample and irresistible proof that there is in nature the adapta-
tion of means to a designed end. We hold, therefore, that
the argument is conclusive to that extent, and we set aside
unhesitatingly the objection of the founder of Positivism.
A different kind of objection is stated by those who seem
too much afraid of what they term “the doctrine of final
causes”? as very liable to encourage men to frame hasty con-
jectures, instead of following the more laborious path of strict
science. The “doctrine of final causes,’ rightly understood,
is precisely the argument from design. The term “final
cause’? means that there is some final object in view, the
attainment of which has caused the adoption and employment
of certain means for that purpose: it is termed jinal, because
it is the end ultimately in view; and it is termed a cause, on
account of the impulse which it gives to the mind, leading it to
frame and employ means for its attainment. It is employed
also in contradistinction to the term efficient cause, or that
active power or immediate agency by the operation of which
the result is directly produced. An efficient cause is true and
direct causation; but a final cause is the end in view, or design,
inducing the mind to choose, and also to employ, means adapted
to that end. Now, in the process of investigating nature, and
tracing the adaptation of means to an end, it is very possible
that men of ardent and hasty minds may leap to a rash
conclusion, assume an end before it has been proved to be
manifestly the end, and may misinterpret nature in order to
get something like proof of their own foregone conclusion.
Something like this was the custom generally of ancient
philosophy. ‘These ancient philosophers were much in the
habit of thinking out a system of nature,—imagining a series
of ends in view which nature had to accomplish,—and then
attempting to obtain from nature proofs or indications that
these were the very ends for the accomplishment of which
nature was so constituted. It is obvious enough that this was
—-i- ee
CHAP. IV.] THE ARGUMENT A POSTERIORI. 71
not to interpret nature, but to force an interpretation upon
nature; and that it might produce plenty of conjecture, but
could not give rise to science. So far as the danger of such a
process may be supposed still to exist, it is all right and well to
warn against it. But it would be an enormous abuse of such a
caution, to employ it against the legitimate use of tracing out
the proof of design, and thereby proving that mind governs
nature. Bacon expressed himself disparagingly regarding the
“ doctrine of final causes.” But he had to contend against the
misuse of that doctrine by the schoolmen of the middle ages ;
and thus understood and applied, his disparaging language 1s
neither too strong nor ill-directed. We are not, however, to
regard this as intended to cast discredit on the process by
which we may cautiously and correctly trace design in nature’s
adaptations.
The very same argument with which Paley begins his
celebrated treatise, may be used with regard to any of what are
called the productions of nature, from a leaf to a forest, from a
drop of water to the ocean, from a ray of light to the starry
heavens, from an insect to a man of the loftiest genius, a
Milton or a Newton. The illustration may be illimitable, but
the argument is one and the same. The direct conclusion must
always be, that the Author of all this is a mind—an intelligent,
designing mind—a mind possessing formative design, and form-
ing power adequate to its accomplishment.
It may be added, however, that though the argument, as
Paley left it, is as complete and conclusive as it can be, con-
sidered as argument ; yet the progress of science is continually
adding to its sphere of application, and modifying some of its
statements. For example, the finding of a stone on the heath
would not now admit of such a summary dismissal with a care-
less evasion of any answer, as it would have done in the time of
Paley. It might be picked up, examined closely, and seen to
be a specimen of some very remarkable geological formation.
In the hands of a Hugh Miller it might be made to tell of a
former world—of its strangely scaled and armed inhabitants—
of its vast and finely-constructed flora—of the manifold proofs
of design in the complicated structure of plant or animal therein
embedded, and preserved in the dark period of time long gone
by, as if for the very purpose of instructing future man, and
teaching him that the God in whom he himself lived, and
72 NATURAL THEOLOGY. (DIV. L
moved, and had his being, is the same “ Ancient of days”
who framed and ruled the earlier world on whose relics he is
gazing. This, however, would not be any real alteration of
the argument, far less any invalidation of it; but it would
be a new application of it, furnished by advancing science for,
its confirmation.
To resume and prosecute the argument itself, the inquiry
now rises: Nature indeed throughout is manifestly constructed
on a principle that shows adaptation of means to’ an end; but
what does this prove? When considered objectively, and
without any reference to our own self-consciousness and its
intuitions, does it prove the existence of God? The adaptation
of means to an end certainly proves mind, by proving design.
But as. the existence of a watch proves only skill and power in
the maker of it, out of previously existing materials, yet cannot
prove that he could have made the materials themselves; so
the adaptations in nature may prove amply the existence of
mind with skill and power enough to produce these adaptations,
but does not at least necessarily prove that this mind also gave
existence to the material employed in the construction of nature.
For anything that this argument has yet proved, or perhaps
can prove, matter may have existed eternally, incapable of
becoming a world of order and life by means of anything in
itself, but capable of being arranged into a world by a mind
possessing adequate intelligence and power. The existence of
matter cannot, we apprehend, be proved either to have been
eternal or not eternal; for there does not seem to be any
element for the proof of either within our reach. But when we
contemplate matter as it exists in the forms and adaptations of
nature, each of these forms and adaptations can be proved to
have had a beginning caused by a design. This may be proved
most easily by attending to the region of life, where each living
organism comes into being by reproduction, that is, by deriva-
tion from a parent, also a living organism, and never merely
from inorganic matter, showing the necessary existence of a
power greater than nature—a creative Parent. It might be
proved also by arguments drawn from the science of astronomy ;
for it may be shown that the forces which, by their steady co-
operation, keep the planetary bodies in their orbits, could not
possibly have placed them in the positions where these forces
produce at once motion and equipoise.
CHAP. IV.] THE ARGUMENT A POSTERIORI. . 73
From the study of nature, then, by the & posteriori argu-
ment alone, applied solely to the objective universe, we obtain
with clear certainty the conclusion that there is a great First
Cause, distinct from nature, and the cause of nature’s arrange-
ments; and that the first attribute of this cause 1s power—
absolute power over the physical creation.
At this point we find ourselves again in contact and colli-
sion with one of the kinds of scepticism. When we confine
our attention solely to the objective physical world, we find
power, both efficient and constructive: we find power adequate
to employ such force as is sufficient to originate all the motions
of all the universe, and this is efficient causation ; and we find
also power of such a character as to originate all arrangement
—designing and formative power. If we regard man’s physical
structure merely as physical structure, we find the same argu-
ment further illustrated, but nothing more. And as long as
we exclude man’s mental and moral constitution, we cannot
find more. Now this is precisely what: the sceptical reasoner
does. He rigidly excludes the human mind, its moral consti-
tution, and the constitution of human society, from his con-
sideration, and then he frames his conclusion from what
objective nature alone has furnished. Objective nature has
furnished the perception of power, and that, too, of designing
power, adapting means to an end. But it has not furnished
the concept of moral power, so long as man’s inner nature is
excluded from the consideration. The concept of mere design-
ing power gives rise very readily to the complex concept, “ laws
of nature,” by which an intelligible name is given to the mani-
fold indications of design that have been observed. These
“laws of nature” do well enough for physical science to reason
from, or reason with; but they seem to enable the man of
physical science to rest satisfied without rising to the idea of
any higher power. Not only so, but, as we have already seen,
he may employ them sophistically to neutralize or annihilate
the idea of causation. “ Laws of nature there unquestionably
are,” he says, “ for we can trace their uniform operation ; but
cause we cannot find.” Yet what is a law of nature in uniform
operation, but a uniformly operating cause ??
1 The phrase ‘‘laws of nature” may seem to demand a few remarks.
There are two different ways in which men are liable to misunderstand and
misuse this very common expression. They may use it to convey the idea
74 NATURAL THEOLOGY. [DIV. L
The discussion with the sceptical man of science might take
a somewhat different form. We might ask whether he regards
these laws of nature as having each a distinct substantive
existence of its own; or whether he regards them as somehow
inherent in some one vast comprehensive law-power existing in
nature. He will scarcely ascribe to each a substantive existence,
lest he should glide into a multiplex mythology, full of innu-
merable deities. But he may try to give some such explana-
tion of a great general law pervading all nature, and manifesting
its existence and power in special forms of law; and as these
special laws all operate with unchanging constancy, he must
conclude that the general law is also unchangingly constant.
That is, nature acts under the uniform influence of some
vast but unintelligent power—a destiny—a fate—a material
Pantheism.
He may, perhaps, turn boldly round and say, “ What other
conclusion can even your views of man and society yield?
You assume a God, and you worship Him; but what does that
that the laws of nature are the direct operations of God,—that there is no
power-in nature, and no causation, but the direct divine agency working
always and everywhere, and uniformly in the same manner throughout the
universe. This, which was the idea of Malebranche, has an aspect of great
sublimity,—seems to ascribe all glory to God in everything, from the revo-
lutions of suns and systems, to the attraction of atoms, and the twinkling
of gnats in the sunshine,—and has imposed upon many. But it leads
inevitably to a kind of grand-looking, idealistic Pantheism, and even then
to an absolute Fatalism, if it adopt the notion of an impersonal God. On
the other hand, if men give a physical meaning to the phrase, it must end
in either a materialistic Pantheism or a material Fatalism, which is neces-
sarily pure Atheism. But if men will earnestly analyze the phrase ‘laws
of nature,” they may find two different conceptions appearing, each of great
importance to a sincere inquirer. It may be possible to show, that when a
merely physical meaning is given to the term law, it can imply nothing
more than the ultimate fact to which an extensive induction may have led,
—the aggregate designation given to that ultimate element in which all the
subordinate elements of the wide induction seem to combine, as in their
proper root. In this sense it is not a power at all, but an ultimate fact,—
something like a mathematical axiom, with which or from which men may
proceed to reason. Or if a metaphysical meaning be given to the term,
it may be shown that in this sense all law resides in mind, must act in
conformity with the nature of mind,—must be the expression of design in
mind,—and may be the expression of an intelligent, conscious, moral,
personal mind; and the operations which it directs may be as uniform as
the will of that infinite mind, putting forth its agency in accordance with
infinite wisdom and goodness.
——
CHAP. IV. ] THE ARGUMENT A POSTERIORI. 75
avail you against the laws of nature? Does not one event
happen equally to the righteous and the wicked—to the man
who worships, and the man who worships not, when either of
them violates these inexorable and unchanging laws? They are
inevitable and unchanging; and they must be unintelligent
and unconscious, otherwise they might be termed unjust, if
not even malignant.”
This is perhaps the worst form that Scepticism, or Ration-
alism, or Secularism, or whatever name it bears, can take; and
it derives all its plausibility from its exclusive reference to the
objective material world. So long as it is allowed to keep itself
strictly within that region, and so long as we allow it to do so
by doing the same ourselves in our argument, it may be found
very difficult to meet this objection. But we are not bound to
do so. We have been using our reason all along, even in
attending to the sceptic’s argument; and he has been using his
reason in producing it. But reason, human reason, his and
ours, has its essence in self-consciousness, and has an absolute
and indestructible right to employ all the laws of thought that
self-consciousness can yield. Objective nature has proved to
us the existence of a designing power. But our own conscious-
ness was engaged in helping us out with that great inference—
even in giving the form of thought, without which the inference
could neither have been conceived nor have found expres-
sion. By the same consciousness, we know that design neces-
sarily implies mind—conscious mind—intelligent mind—mind
intending, willing, acting. We reject, therefore, the sceptic’s
conclusion, as inconsistent with our own consciousness—incon-
sistent with his own consciousness, if he will but attend to its
intimations—inconsistent with human consciousness in its most
comprehensive sense.
This answer we can confidently give to the reasoner of
sceptical tendency, and can appeal to a power within his own
being which he cannot dispute; or if he do dispute his own
consciousness, our argument ends—we cease to have common
ground for further discussion. But while we can silence the
sceptic, we may feel that his argument has raised an uneasy
feeling within us which we cannot so readily silence. We can-
not deny that there are constantly occurring in human life,
events of the most painfully perplexing kind. We see around
us the good man in a state of calamity and affliction, and the
4
76 NATURAL THEOLOGY. [DIV. I.
wicked man in a state of comfort and prosperity. We feel
within us a moral power persuading us to what is righteous, and
true, and just; but we do not readily and constantly comply
with its dictates, and we are tortured by remorse, and haunted
by the dread of punishment. We perceive that similar senti-
ments are entertained by our fellow-men, and similar conduct
pursued. We perceive, moreover, that there are no such irre-
gularities in the arrangements and operations of the physical
world ; that it is so constituted, that if we were always in ac-
cordance with what men term its laws, we might be always in
the enjoyment of welfare and happiness. This latter consider-
ation agrees with our conviction, that the cause of this world is
not a cause only, but a moral governor; yet still we feel that
our condition is one of inexplicable mystery, so far at least as
we have yet learned from nature. But this very objection, and
the nature of the topics which it suggests, constrain us to
direct our attention to the human element of the inquiry ; that
is, into a consideration of the mental and moral nature of man,
the constitution of society, and the addition which these con-
siderations give to the & posteriori argument. This considera-
tion both prompts and impels, nay, constrains us to have re-
course to the region of man’s moral nature; which, however,
is both legitimately within our present province, and has a right
to demand from us a full and attentive investigation.
CHAPTER V.
ARGUMENT FORMED BY COMBINATION OF A PRIORI
AND A POSTERIORI METHODS.
st CALL HOUT entering into any lengthened or minute
4e| examination of the human mind, as is done in the
study of Mental Philosophy, we may direct attention
to some of its main aspects and general principles,
so far as is necessary to introduce and apply the portion of our
argument on which we are now about to enter.
It is a very important fact-in our constitution, that in con-
sequence of the addition to one class of human faculties of
another of a higher order, even the lower class acquires both
expansion and elevation, and becomes subject to laws not other-
wise applicable to it. The merely intellectual or cognitive
powers of the mind, for example, do not of themselves give
rise to the sentiment or idea of right and wrong in any moral
sense. But when we direct our attention to a higher class of
human faculties, usually termed the active powers of the mind,
we find them all pervaded by an element of a new character,
which continually suggests the idea of rightness or wrongness,
and gives rise to the sentiment of approbation or disapprobation,
producing a result necessary to their beneficial existence and
operation. All the active powers of the mind tend to bring
man into contact with man; and that this contact may not be
incessant hostility, there must be some means of making it con-
cord. Hence it is apparent that we are entering another and a
higher region, and have now to do with nobler elements. But
if, before we explore this new region, we turn round and look
back, and down, on any previous survey of the human mind
that we have made, with regard to its sentient, percipient, and
- intellectual faculties, we shall find that, in consequence of the
union of intellectual and active powers in the same being, even
the intellectual faculties become subject to the laws that regu-
late the active powers, and can be regarded in this combined
78 NATURAL THEOLOGY. [DIV. I.
aspect with feelings of approbation or disapprobation. Ai here
whole man is now lifted into a moral region, and must be
viewed as a moral being.
But we can scarcely even begin to explore this moral region
of our nature without perceiving, that while the Desires and
Affections, to use the common terms (the conative in Sir W.
Hamilton’s language), prompt men to action, it is not to action
unrestrained,—not to action irrespective of consequences to
ourselves and others. Throughout their whole range they are
characterized by the presence of something which leads us to
regard their exercise as right or wrong in special circumstances,
and to regulate it accordingly. This is peculiarly perceptible
in the constant notion which we entertain respecting the pro-
priety of their limitations. The unrestrained indulgence of
any appetite, desire, or affection invariably calls forth the senti-
ment of disapprobation. This is not the case with regard to
the merely intellectual or cognitive faculties. The only limita-
tion which they sustain is that arising from their own weakness;
and though this may cause regret, it would never give rise to
the idea of demerit,—or rather, it excludes that sentiment.
But the idea of a limitation, to pass which excites the senti-
ment of disapprobation, suggests of necessity the idea of a
law fixing the limits which the indulgence of desires and affec-
tions ought not to pass. Limitation, thus viewed as fixed by
law, necessarily implies the existence of a faculty having
authority to determine these limits, and to regulate the entire
exercise of the active powers. Hence arise the ideas of duty,
moral obligation, and responsibility. To act in obedience to
these ideas is right; to violate them is wrong. This, however,
does not exhaust the idea or sentiment; for while we can con-
sider states of mind in themselves, apart from the actions to
which they prompt, we can also regard those states with appro-_
bation or disapprobation, viewed in their very nature and
essence, and without taking into consideration the idea of
limitation. Further, in the exercise of the moral faculty we
are conscious of a pleasurable or painful emotion, as we approve
or disapprove. Thus we arrive at the full conception of the
moral faculty, and we now perceive that its nature is to decide
respecting the rightness or wrongness, the merit or demerit, of
every appetite, desire, and affection; that it has Gathiiity to
determine the limits within which they shall be exercised, and
ae ee
“eS
CHAP. V.] THE TWO ARGUMENTS IN COMBINATION. 79
to regulate their whole course of order and action; and that all
its decisions are inherently accompanied or pervaded by the
emotion of pleasure when it pronounces the sentence of appro-
bation, or pain when it expresses disapprobation, both with re-
gard to our own conduct and that of others. There is yet one
preliminary remark which must be made: Although the moral
faculty takes cognizance of all states of mind, and passes its
decisions upon them all, and upon the actions to which they
impel, regarding them with very different and ever varying
degrees of approbation or the reverse, yet in its own operations
it must always be felt as one faculty,—not the combination of
many faculties, each acting in its turn, but One Faculty, having
a province of its own, taking cognizance of everything which
enters that province, and asserting a rightful supremacy within
that peculiar province.
SEC. I. DIFFERENT THEORIES OF MORALS.
It may be expedient to direct our attention very briefly
to some of the prevalent theories of morals which have been
promulgated by philosophers; keeping meanwhile in remem-
brance as distinctly as possible, that conception of the moral
faculty at which we have arrived. The moral faculty we
conceive to be, that one active power of the mind whose
nature it is to take cognizance of the distinction between right
and wrong, good and evil in all other states of mind, and in all
actions prompted by these states ; whose decisions have a neces-
sary and inherent authority, prescribing limits to, and regulat-
ing the actions of, all our appetites, desires, and affections, and
giving rise to the moral sentiments of duty, moral obligation,
and responsibility ; and in all whose actions there is inherent
the pleasurable or painful emotions of approbation or disappro-
bation. Let it be carefully marked, that the moral faculty
does not create the distinction between right and wrong, but
merely takes cognizance of it, discerns it, and declares it; and
that therefore its decisions, however authoritative, do not and
cannot form the ultimate standard of morality. That action,
or mental state, may very confidently be said to be right, which
the moral faculty approves; or still more confidently may be
said to be wrong to the individual himself, whose moral faculty
disapproves; but that action or mental state may be wrong,
80 NATURAL THEOLOGY. [DIV. I,
_which the moral faculty does not condemn. Any theory of
morals, therefore, framed from the unaided decision of the
moral faculty alone, may be both inaccurate and incomplete.
Had this consideration been more clearly and constantly before
the minds of moral philosophers, they might have avoided
many errors; and indeed their whole speculations on ethical
subjects must have borne a different aspect.
Various theories of morals, or statements of such leading
principle or principles as might be respectively the foundation
of a theory of ethics, have been propounded from time to time,
the chief of which are the following :
1. That Virtue, or moral rectitude, consists in living according
to nature (Stoic).
2. That what produces the greatest amount of happiness 1s
Virtue (Epicurean).
3. That the just medium between extremes is Virtue (the Aris-
totelian).
4. The Eternal Fitnesses of things, or abstract ideal Truth
(Cudworth and others). :
5. Utility, Prudence, Expediency, wisely adjusted Compro-
mise (Paley and others).
6. The Moral Sense, percipient of moral relations (Hutcheson
and others).
1. Right Reason, Judgment, Sympathy, Universal Benevolence
(Smith and others). |
8. The Love of Being, elevated into the Love of God (Jonathan
_ Edwards).
9, Conscience (Bishop Butler, Sir James Mackintosh, Dr.
Chalmers, and others).
It is not my intention to investigate and analyze these
various theories of morals at any length; but a few remarks
on the most important of them, and on the principles from
which they spring, may be beneficial. The three leading
theories of antiquity—the Stoic, Epicurean, and Aristotelian—
accordance with nature, love of happiness, and the just medium
—are all defective. The axiom that virtue is living in accord-
ance with nature has in it a portion of truth, for it recognises
constitutional principles as in themselves right and authori-
tative; and every person must be aware that a life spent in
CHAP. V.] THE TWO ARGUMENTS IN COMBINATION. 81
habitual violation of nature’s dictates must be wrong in itself,
and is productive of misery. But we need a definition of
nature. Does it mean the constitution of each several man ?
—that is too varied. Or of mankind in general ?—that is
both too vague and too limited. Or of the universe, including
the Deity, its Creator? To the knowledge of that we cannot
attain. We must therefore abandon that theory. We turn,
then, to the Jove of happiness. But here we are at once met
by the difficulty of finding any general harmony in the opinions
of mankind respecting happiness, wherein it consists. The
opinions of men respecting happiness are as varied as are their
tastes and habits. All men instinctively desire happiness ;_ but
their ideas of happiness are infinitely diversified, consequently
this can furnish no sure standard of morals,—nay, it can fur-
nish no criterion at all, nor any rule for the guidance of our
conduct, since each man’s taste and wishes would be his own »
peculiar rule. There may seem to be something more plausible
in the theory which takes for its basis the just medium between
extremes. But what are extremes? That may be the extreme
to one man, which is the ordinary course of conduct to another;
consequently there could be no correspondence and no medium
between the views which such men. would take. There is
needed for such a theory some mode of estimating extremes,
or rather, perhaps, some mode of fixing a medium,—the very
thing assumed,—the distance from which is the estimate of
extremes. That is, the theory has itself no basis, and there-
fore can never come into practical existence.
The more modern theories already enumerated may be
considerably reduced by being grouped together, and their
examination thereby simplified. The theory which would
make moral rectitude to consist in the Eternal Fitness of
things, has for its origin the Platonic theory, that all creation
was framed in conformity with ideas pre-existent in the Divine
Mind. Among these archetypal ideas there necessarily existed
a harmonious congruity, absolutely perfect. The perfection of
creation would therefore consist in its embodiment of these
ideas, and in the relations of existent or created things, corre-
sponding to each other as completely as did the relations of the
archetypal ideas in the Divine Mind. There is something
exceedingly grand, even sublime, in this theory, and it has to
some extent modified almost every modern system of morals.
F
82 NATURAL THEOLOGY. [DIV. I.
It forms the basis of the systems of Cudworth, Clarke, and
Price. It underlies and pervades the whole of the German
theories, from Leibnitz to Kant. Its influence is perceptible in
the systems of Malebranche, Butler, Paley, Hutcheson, Smith,
and even of Jonathan Edwards. But it lies open to one insur-
mountable objection—it cannot be so apprehended by man as
to furnish him with a rule of duty. Let it be granted that there
were in the Divine Mind from all eternity archetypal ideas, in
accordance with which He framed the universe ; and let it be
said that right and wrong implies the agreement or disagree-
ment between the created universe and these ideas, or even
between the relations of those created things which compose
the universe ;—still it will be impossible for any mind but that
of the Deity Himself to have a full and complete perception
of all these relations and their agreement: consequently the
eternal fitnesses of things, and abstract yet universal and immutable
truth, can be the standard of moral rectitude to no being but
the Creator. It might be added, that a misconception of this
great theory, and misuse of it, lies at the root of idealistic
Pantheism.
Another class of moral systems places the standard of
morality in what is variously termed The Good—The Summum
Bonum—Good upon the whole—The Beneficial—The Useful,
or Expedient. There is considerable plausibility and some
truth in these theories, which are all pervaded by that master
element which professes to have the production of good and
happiness for its object. But they, too, require an extent of —
knowledge of which a finite mind is not capable. There is
nothing of which we obtain greater certainty by almost daily
experience, than the fact that what at any given present time
we regarded as good, we may soon have reason to regret, or
even to condemn as evil. At no time are we able with certainty
to say that a wider range of knowledge or a more prolonged
view of future consequences may not change entirely our esti-
mate of what, with our present knowledge, we consider good.
What is right will always prove ultimately expedient ; but that
may seem expedient which is not right, and will ultimately
prove injurious. Further, let it be observed, that both the
theories which assume for their basis the eternal jitnesses of
things, and those that assume the good and the useful, are, after
all, conceptions of the intedlect, rather than of the moral faculties
CHAP. V.] THE TWO ARGUMENTS IN COMBINATION. 83
of the mind. Not only are they necessarily liable to error, as has
been shown; but even though their certainty were far greater
than it is or can be, they would not produce the distinctive
characteristics of morality. An error in knowledge, or even an
error in judgment, may call forth in a man’s mind the feeling
of regret that he did not know more, or judge more correctly ;
but it would not necessarily cause the painful emotion of self-
condemnation, which forms the characteristic element in the
consciousness of moral delinquency. From none of these
theories, therefore, nor from the general principles which per-
vade them all, can we derive the full idea of duty—of right
and wrong—of responsibility. A careful perusal of the various
works in which those theories are stated and advocated, might
be instructive with regard to moral perceptions and moral
sentiments, but could never enable us to frame a complete and
satisfactory standard of morality.
There is another class of moral theories which, in our
opinion, approach much nearer the truth—such as the moral
sense, sympathy, universal benevolence, the love of being. The
most direct notion that we can form of the term moral sense is,
that there is a faculty in the mind which has for its proper
function the perception of morality. The word sense must be
understood to be derived from the analogy of the bodily senses,
and to mean a faculty of a distinct and separate nature im-
planted in the mind, and thereby enabling us to perceive
morality. ‘Thus understood, the term conveys important truth ;
but it is necessary to guard against the perverse interpretation
which the ideal theory gives to this term, and by which the
primary meaning of the word sense, as implying a bodily capa-
city, is attempted to be fixed on the term moral sense. There
is another remark which must be made with regard to this term.
It does not very directly suggest the idea, that the operations of
the moral sense must be both emotional and authoritative ; yet,
fairly understood, it implies, or at least it does not contradict,
that idea. For if it be admitted to be an original faculty of
the mind, then all its operations must be authoritative, and all
its evidences and judgments intuitive, since, being original, its
existence and operations cannot admit of any other proof than
that of conscious existence ; and since its very nature is emo-
tional, the existence of its proper emotions is their own and
their only evidence. When we thus understand the moral
84 - NATURAL THEOLOGY. (DIV. I.
sense, or, as we prefer to term it, the moral faculty, we are
prepared to see in what manner sympathy, though not itself the
moral faculty, is well fitted to act as its ready handmaid. | For
the office of the moral faculty is to decide respecting the con-
duct, not less of others than of ourselves. By sympathy, we
are enabled to put ourselves in the condition of other men ;
and we thereby obtain a better position for judging both truly
and mercifully concerning their states of mind and actions,
than would otherwise be -possible.
Advancing in our investigation, the theory of universal
benevolence appears. The origin of this theory of morals seems
to have been the perception of the pleasurable emotion in acts
of moral approbation, and the love which instinctively springs
up in the heart towards those of whose conduct we approve.
That love accompanies most acts of moral approbation, every
one may ascertain from his own consciousness; but even here
there may be perceived a distinction. When we pronounce
any act to be just and right, we render it moral approbation ;
but the emotional feeling which accompanies it is not neces-
sarily Jove—it may be admiration merely. We may be correctly
said to admire a just or right action, and to love a good action.
The theory of universal benevolence does not therefore include
the entire province of the moral faculty ; consequently it can-
not furnish a true and adequate theory, far less a true standard
of morals. Further, as has been previously stated, the theory
of universal benevolence has never been found to have any prac-
tical existence among mankind; nor can it give to its decisions
the impress of authority. Even the philosophical writers who
promulgate this theory, while they demand for the principle itself
approbation, do not venture to brand the want of it with decided
disapprobation ; and not one of them has himself ever attempted
to exemplify its existence in his own conduct. Christians have
done so, because they were actuated by a higher motive ; but no
mere philosopher has ever realized that theory by acting on its
principle. ‘The theory of Jonathan Edwards approximates to
the truth in its consequences, but cannot possibly be operative,
and to the greater part of mankind is unintelligible. The love
of being, so far as any clear notion can be formed of such an
expression, is not inconsistent with the authoritative dictates of
revelation ; but could neither have been formed from the phi-
losophy of mind itself, nor can be so distinctly apprehended by
CHAP. V.] THE TWO ARGUMENTS IN COMBINATION. 85
the mind, as to become the basis of moral thought, or the rule
of moral conduct. I am inclined to conjecture, that Edwards
began by taking the Scripture standard, the love of God, and
then attempted to translate that into the form of a philosophical
principle, and to couch its statement in philosophical language.
If we may regard this supposition as a correct one, we: are
immediately put in possession of the explanation; but if we
regard it merely as a philosophical theory, we are surprised
that anything so vague could be produced by such a man,
The last theory which I shall briefly examine, is that of
Butler, who terms the moral faculty conscience. In explaining
his view, Butler is at pains to relieve it from the charge of selfish-
ness. The necessity for this will be at once apparent, when
it is borne in mind, that even the theory of universal benevo-
lence has been termed “ refined self-love.” Butler shows that
the fact of pleasure being conjoined with many gratifications
of appetite or desire, does not prove these appetites or desires to
be inherently selfish. The appetite of hunger craves food; and
there is gratification or pleasure in taking the food so craved.
But it is possible to conceive of the hunger appeased without
that peculiar, gratification; and it is certain that the simple
sensation of hunger has no respect whatever to the gratification
of the sense of taste. In like manner, every desire or affection
seeks its own object for the sake simply of obtaining it. Plea-
sure, no doubt, is experienced in the attainment; but that
pleasure formed no necessary part of the result sought directly
under the impulse of the desire. When we seek the gratifica-
tion or the good of another person, the obtaining of that result
gives us pleasure ; but the obtaining of that result was not the
object we had in view: nay, in truth, the less we have any
pleasurable result to ourselves in view, the more certain we are
to gain it. Intense hunger or thirst pays no regard to the
pleasure of the palate; but the hungry or thirsty man enjoys a
degree of pleasure from even bread and water, such as the most
thorough gourmand cannot even imagine. And the more en-
tirely disinterested that any benevolent action is, the more
exquisite is the gratification experienced by the generous bene-
factor. All these views of human nature tend to show, that
according to man’s original constitution, the mere desire of
selfish gratification is not, the ruling element of his nature ; and
although it were so, that no moral code or system could ‘be.
86 NATURAL THEOLOGY. [DIV. I.
deduced from these views, yet they tend to show, if not to prove,
that there was a pre-arranged suitability in man for the super-
addition of a moral faculty.
That moral faculty is CONSCIENCE. Its function is to survey,
and approve or disapprove, the several affections of our minds
and actions of our lives. In its own nature it is supreme, and
claims a rightful authority over all the faculties of mind and
principles of action. It expresses approbation or disapproba-
tion promptly and at once, without the lengthened inquiry
which the theory of fitness, or of utility, or even of universal
benevolence, would require. Its perceptions are intuitive, and
its judgments intuitive. Emotion is in all its acts. When it
condemns a man’s own deed, the painful feeling of remorse
arises ; when it approves, a placid feeling of unutterable delight
pervades the heart and mind. When it disapproves the mental
state and actions of another person, he is regarded with feelings
of aversion or indignation; when it approves, our emotions
towards the man are those of esteem and love. When it de-
clares respecting any contemplated action that it is might, we
feel it to be our duty to do that action. If it regards any action
with disapprobation, we are morally bound not to do that action.
It tells us what duty is—we thence feel moral obligation ; and
we further feel, that if we violate that duty, we shall be called
to answer for doing so: thence arises what we term responst-
bility. From this feeling of responsibility we cannot escape.
I may conceal a wrong desire, or a malevolent affection, from
every other human being; but I.cannot conceal it from myself ;
and conscience will call me to account, if I cherish in the
secrecy of my soul that wrong desire or malevolent affection.
Whenever any desire arises in the mind, being an active faculty,
it solicits the mind to act. But before the will can be put forth,
the intuitive decision of conscience pronounces it right or wrong.
If the will obey, and repel the promptings of desire, conscience
approves it, and there is peace and delight. But if the will
rebel against conscience, and comply with the desire, the sen-
tence of disapprobation is pronounced, and the punishment of
remorse is inflicted. Thus conscience asserts and indicates its
supremacy, even when it is unable to control the promptings of
desire and the rebellion of the wil.
1 There has been already allusion made to an important question which
might be here investigated, but shall be little more than re-suggested. The
CHAP. V.] THE TWO ARGUMENTS IN COMBINATION. 87
One reflection remains still to be made. Since conscience
is thus proved to be the supreme ruler of man’s action, so far
as anything in human nature can be a law to man, how comes
it that its authoritative dictates are so frequently violated ?
Does it not thus appear, that there exists in the mind of man
a conception or idea of moral rectitude far higher, purer, and
more true, than he can ever realize? Further, is it not matter of
every day’s observation, that, from the judgments by conscience
on the conduct of others, in cases where self-interest or passion
does not bias or overbear its dictates, there is produced what
may be termed a common conscience, which rules society with
even greater supremacy than it can the individuals that con-
stitute society? Again, we sometimes perceive a perverse
resistance to the dictates of conscience in corporate bodies, of
a kind and to a degree that no individual in those bodies
would venture to display alone, because the feeling of respon-
sibility has been lost or greatly weakened by its diffusion
over the corporate body. All these views tend to the same
point. All tend to prove that neither conscience itself, nor any
system that can be framed from its general dictates, can be the
standard of morality; and that conscience, though it claim supre-
macy as its right, is not able to enforce that claim. The con-
clusion is obvious. Man’s sovereign faculty has been dethroned.
Man is a fallen and enslaved creature. This even philosophy
might discern. This the word of God asserts and proves.
It is not my present purpose to dwell on the conclusion
to which we have thus come, either for the sake of explaining
or of enforcing it; but it may be useful to state briefly, and in a
succinct form, the results of our investigation respecting man’s
moral nature.
office of conscience, it is proved, is to distinguish between right and wrong ;
but what is that quality common to all right actions, on account of which
they are right,—and that opposite quality, on account of which wrong
actions are wrong? I have said that conscience does not create the dis-
tinction between right and wrong, but only discerns it, and then fervently
and authoritatively declares it. It will not do to say that actions are right
because conscience approves them ; for that would be reasoning in a circle,
and saying that conscience is the faculty which approves what is right, and
that that is right which conscience approves. Conscience itself, therefore,
is not the ultimate standard of morality. That standard is the will, the
law, the character of God; and conscience is the faculty which teaches the:
duty of conformity to that law.
88 NATURAL THEOLOGY. [DIV. I.
The idea of morality appears to be this: when we behold,
or mentally contemplate, any action performed by ourselves or
others, we immediately perceive something in the action which
we pronounce to be right or wrong. In this perception and
decision we are conscious of an emotion of pleasure or of pain
within our own inner being ; and we perceive the merit or de-
merit of the agent, and feel towards him the sentiments either
of love or of aversion. Neither the intimations which we re-
ceive from our bodily senses, nor the ideas furnished, by our
intellectual powers, call forth this idea of morality, or place
the mind in this moral state. The active powers of the mind
constantly tend to put man in positions in which there must
be some controlling power to regulate their action, and prevent
the incessant struggle which would otherwise arise between
man and man. No considerations of fitness, or prudence, or
utility, or even benevolence, can meet the necessity, because
all such considerations require a range of knowledge and a
compass of induction altogether unsuitable to the nature of
the office to be discharged. But we are conscious of the
existence within us of one high faculty which intuitively per-
ceives, and promptly and authoritatively decides, every question
that requires a moral decision, pronouncing this decision with
authority, and giving to it the sanction of the pains or pleasures
of emotional blame or approbation. This faculty we term
the Moral Faculty, or Conscience. It claims an imperative
supremacy; and “were its might equal to its right, it would
rule the world.” But it often cannot enforce its dictates.
Its decisions are liable to be overborne by impetuous passion or
rebellious will. It is a dethroned sovereign ; but it still retains
a sovereign’s character, and asserts a sovereign’s rights, almost
always inflicting punishment even where it failed to prevent
wrong. Were it utterly extinct, man would cease to be a
moral creature ; were it always obeyed, he would always do
right, and be happy. As it is, he is both moral and unhappy,
his violations of conscience being the main cause of his un-
happiness. Nothing can more clearly prove that man is a
fallen creature; and in a merely philosophical point of view,
the essence of his fall consists in conscience having lost its due
and rightful supremacy. Besides, since conscience, even in its
highest state, is not the standard of morality or the framer of
moral laws, but the percipient of morality and the interpreter
CHAP. V.] THE TWO ARGUMENTS IN COMBINATION. 89
of moral laws, it can be but a delegated sovereign, a vice-
gerent of a Higher Power, in whose character eternal and
immutable morality resides, and where will and law, embody-
ing that character, form the ultimate standard of morals. To
Him, therefore, must conscience apply for restoration to its lost
supremacy, and for such aid as may remedy the disorder and
misery of man’s fallen moral nature. Not otherwise can man
be rescued from degradation,—not otherwise can man be re-
stored and saved.
SEC. Il. THE WILL, LIBERTY, AND NECESSITY.
Our course of argument constrains us still to continue to
direct our attention to man; because, as we have already
found, it is impossible to prosecute our inquiry further into
nature, without taking self, or self-consciousness, with us,
modifying as it does all our inquiries, giving to nature its
interpretation according to the laws of our own being, and
often suggesting valuable topics of investigation into the cha-
racter of those laws which we perceive to be in operation. We
have already been led to make,some passing remarks on several
of the topics which will come under discussion in this section ;
but as they were then before us almost exclusively with refer-
ence to external nature, we did not think that to be the proper
place for anything like an adequate discussion of them. But
as we are now intentionally combining what. self-consciousness
tells us of man, with what we can learn from external nature,
we regard ourselves as. fully at liberty, and even required, to
make as much use of human nature as our limits will permit.
But let it be still borne in mind, that we are viewing man as a
part of objective nature, and placing him objectively before us,
that we may have some competent conception of what the
combined argument of nature and man, still an & posteriori
argument, can give us in our study of Natural Theology, pre-
paratory for the higher topic at which we shall in due time
arrive. It is scarcely necessary to remark, that we retain our
right to the free use of all that & priori or aaiomatic thinking
has fairly given.
While endeavouring to explain the moral faculty, we were
led to direct our attention particularly to that which seems to
be its essential element—its constant reference to actions, and
90 NATURAL THEOLOGY. [DIV. L
through them ultimately to those states of mind which prompt
to action. This necessarily leads to the inquiry respecting the
source of action in the mind itself, to what it is in any state of
mind that produces action. When we reflect on the operations
of our minds with regard to action, we are conscious of a pecu-
liar forthputting of the mind’s own energy, in consequence of
which a change is produced, either in the emotions of the mind
or in the operations of the body, according to the internal
energy so exerted. To this internal mental energy we give
the name Will (or volition).
Let us now look somewhat closely at the mental act which
we thus designate. Some bodily appetite, or some desire or
affection, arises in our complex frame and nature, and attracts
our attention. We either follow the impulse or we reject it; but
although the impulse arose from the natural appetite or desire
in which the mind was passive, the mind is active in exerting
its own energy, for the purpose of gratifying the appetite or
desire, or refusing that gratification. Or we may take a higher
view, in which the operations of mind are more directly contem-
plated. Reason places before us two or more courses of action :
we reject the one, and follow the other. We may have taken
into consideration the qualities of these courses of action, as
good or evil, beneficial or detrimental; but there is something
more implied, when we positively determine to exert our powers
in prosecuting the one rather than the other. In any and all
of such cases, the mind puts forth a peculiar power, to which
we give the distinctive appellation wiLL. This we regard as
a primary faculty of the mind—the very faculty of action.
But as it is the state of mind producing action of which the
moral faculty takes direct cognizance, and on which it pro-
nounces its sentence, we are thus brought to perceive that our
moral responsibility has an essential relation to the wil/—that
nothing can justly be called moral or immoral unless it be
voluntary.
Again, when we contemplate the idea of responsibility, we
at once perceive that it implies the power to act or not to act,
according to the dictates of the will. We invariably feel, that
when we can truly say of any action that it was compulsory,
that we could not possibly act otherwise, in consequence of
some constraint or restraint, we feel ourselves relieved in that —
instance from the feeling of responsibility. And the reason
CHAP. V.] THE TWO ARGUMENTS IN COMBINATION. 91
plainly is, that in any such case our own will was not consulted
or concerned, or was perhaps overborne by a power which it
could not resist. Hence we are led to the conclusion, that to
render any state of mind or action morally right or wrong, it
must arise from the free dictates of our own will, not under
any irresistible compulsion or restraint. And as the will is the
primary principle of action, we thus conjoin the ideas of moral
responsibility and free agency, which we regard as inseparable. |
Other ideas speedily arise as we proceed in our investiga-
tions. Perceiving that the decisions of the will were called
forth by the appetites, desires, affections, reasons, prospects,
hopes, and fears, which arose in the mind, we term these
motives, regarding them as principles, or primary elements of
mental motion, or calculated to excite the moving powers and
faculties of the mind. Too the motives thus contemplated we
ascribe some influence in eliciting the exercise of the will.
Some even assert that the will is always determined by the
strongest motive—an assertion which seems to me to be founded
on a misconception of both motive and will, particularly the
latter.
Further, we perceive that when the will determines, action
follows; and we put forth an energy which affects either the
operations of our minds, or the position of external things by
means of our bodily exertions willed into action, or both.
Hence seems to arise the idea of power, and our conviction
that we ourselves possess power, both over the states and
operations of our own minds, and over the functions of our
bodies, and thereby over things external to us. This idea of
power gives rise also to the idea of causation, or of cause and
effect; and from our consciousness of having the power of
producing change, we conceive that every change which we
observe must have been caused by some efficient power. It is
true that in abstract metaphysical reasoning we are unable to
detect power and causation, and find ourselves unable to pro-
ceed beyond the perception of constant or invariable sequence.
But while this may be all that mere metaphysical research can
prove, it does not exhaust the intuitive conception of the mind
produced by its own consciousness, which, notwithstanding
all metaphysical arguments, and equally among all mankind,
entertains the ideas of power and causation. The primary seat
of this power is in the will, as mind is the jirst efficient cause.
92 NATURAL THEOLOGY. [DIV. I.
Still further, the moral faculty asserts our responsibility for
our conduct. And in tracing out the conception of respon-
sibility, we find it inseparably connected with the belief of our
own free agency. But this leads ‘us to inquire in what free
agency consists; or how man can be a free agent, and yet every
event be foreseen and governed by God. This introduces one
of the most dark and difficult questions which the human mind
has ever attempted to investigate, and at the same time one of
the most important in its bearing upon both morality and
religion. The question is, How can man enjoy that. liberty
necessary to a free and responsible agent, and yet all things
that come to pass be predetermined and foreseen by God?
Into anything like a full discussion of this great question I
cannot here enter; but as I am convinced that some light may
be thrown upon it, even from a brief explanation of the various
ideas brought before us, and some arrangement of them when
so explained, I shall proceed to the attempt, with great diffidence
indeed, remembering by whom the question has been treated.
The leading term to be used is the wiLu. In that term, I
am persuaded, there is generally contained too much, from
which no small portion of the confusion wherewith the subject
is darkened has arisen. There are, as I conceive, two different
though kindred states of mind indiscriminately designated by
the term will. The one might be expressed by the word
willingness (voluntas), the other by choice or determination
(arbitrium) ; in Greek by 0cXw and Bovropa. The difference
between the two is shown by attending to the difference
between saying J am willing and I determine; the. one is —
essentially passive, the other is essentially active. In the state
of mind which I would express by the word willingness, the
mind receives an impulse from some motive placed before it,
applying to it and soliciting its consent. Should that consent
be granted, a more active state would follow, and the mind
would put forth its own inherent energies to realize the motive
thus presented. But in this a new idea is evolved, and the
mind directs its attention, not to the motive, but to its own act
and power. Should it not consent, it would still put forth so
much energy as might be required to repel the motive, and
refuse to produce external action; or the same result might
follow from the mere determination to withdraw attention from
the motive. This is the more active state which I would
CHAP. V.] THE TWO ARGUMENTS IN COMBINATION. 93
express by the word arbitrium, in which the mind exercises the
faculty of choice between two or more motives, courses of con-
duct, individual actions, desires, affections, or anything that
requires choice, or implies choosing before acting. Motives
act on the (voluntas) willingness, or percipient faculty, and
tend to elicit a feeling which would say, “I consent, I am
willing ;” but they can only solicit the arbitrium, the faculty of
choice, the true WILL, which says, “I determine.”
Motives must be carefully distinguished from efficient causes.
All appetites, desires, and affections are motives, but can all be
governed; all sensations are of the nature of motives, but can
be conquered ; all ideas of reward and punishment, all antici-
pations of advantage and disadvantage, of good and evil, are
motives, but can all be resisted. When we use the expression,
efficient causes, we ought continually to restrict its application
either to physical nature, and to the mechanical forces which
move and regulate it; or to those direct and spontaneous opera-
tions which mind puts forth voluntarily. If we give the name
cause to motives at all, we ought ever to remember that a motive
is a final cause,—that is, its operation is produced by the end, or
object to be accomplished, which it places before the mind.
When a man places before his.mind some object which cannot
be attained but after years of strenuous and steady exertion,
that object is the motive, or final cause, or end in view, for which
he chooses to make the necessary exertion; but mentally con-
sidered, the choice is the efficient cause of his conduct. But
when the action of a lever or a screw produces a change in
some portion of physical matter, we regard.the lever or screw
as the efficient cause.
And here it may be of advantage to observe, that this dif-
ference in these two great orders of causation arises out of the
inherent and constitutional difference between mind and matter.
The power, or efficient cause, which acts upon matter, requires, in
order to the certainty of the result, that matter shall be abso-
lutely inert, passive, without the power of motion in itself, and
therefore capable of receiving any motion impressed on it.
The power, or final cause, applied to mind, requires, in order to
the certainty of the result, a being who proposes to himself an
end, chooses means, and thus puts himself in motion. The
action or influence of motives depends, therefore, on the faculty
of choice in the mind of man. There cannot, therefore, be com-
94 NATURAL THEOLOGY. [DIV. I.
pulsion in any motive, because compulsion and choice are con-
tradictions ; and we have already seen that compulsion destroys
responsibility. We never apply moral judgment to any action
resulting from compulsion,—or in other words, in which there
is no choice: or were we to apply a moral judgment in such a
case, it would be to the antecedent, and not to the immediate
agency.
So far our path seems to be clear :—The will is the faculty
of choice ;—motives solicit but cannot compel it ;—moral causa-
tion presupposes the faculty of choice, and has its power not
on, but in that faculty. Hitherto we have found nothing in-
consistent with man’s free agency, and consequent responsibility.
This will also be found to be in perfect harmony with what
every man is taught by his own consciousness,—that he is a
free agent, and responsible.
But does not this imply such uncertainty as to render the
very idea of foreknowledge a moral impossibility? Not so, if
we rightly understand the terms employed, and the nature of
the inquiry. Mankind are so conversant with material exist-
ences and material laws, that they almost constantly apply
notions drawn from these to the nature and operations of mind,
and thereby fall into innumerable fallacies in reasoning, and
draw erroneous conclusions. The certainty of the results pro-
duced by efficient causes arises out of the adequacy of the physi-
cal force employed to produce these results, and the inertness of
matter. But hence men fallaciously apply what seems a cor-
responding course of reasoning respecting the certainty of the
results produced by jinal causes, and ascribe that also to power,
—and that, too, a kind of power similar to physical force, or
rather identical with it. But it should be borne always in
mind, that morality does not consist in power, but in will, or the
faculty of choice. It is in vain, then, to say that the influence
of motives is according to their power,—that the will always
acts according to the strongest motive. If the will were not
the faculty of choice, this might be the case; but since motives
can only solicit the percipient element of willingness, and may
be rejected by the faculty of choice, the true will, acting freely
according to its true nature, the result must ever be, not
according to the strength or value of the motive, but according
to the character of the faculty itself (by the term character I
here mean its relation to conscience). We daily see identical
CHAP. V.] THE TWO ARGUMENTS IN COMBINATION. 93
motives followed by very different results, not only in the con-
duct of different individuals, but in the conduct of the same
person when a change has taken place in his moral character.
This is easily explained when we look for the cause—the jinal
cause—not in the motives, but in the moral character of the
respective choosing faculties. It is altogether inexplicable
otherwise. In order, then, that foreknowledge may be possible,
we have only to conceive a Being to whom is known not only
motives, but also and especially the character of the minds of
moral agents. ‘To Him there can be no contingency, no chance,
no unforeseen event, not only because He pre-arranges all mo-
tives that solicit the willing and choosing mind, but because He
knows its whole character, and so adapts each final cause to each
mind that each man freely chooses what God had foreordained.
_ Iam very far from venturing to say that this is a sufficient
solution of the great difficulty, felt by all who have thought on
these deep subjects. Many a man will feel that he acts most
wisely when he contents himself with saying, that he cannot
solve the difficulty ; that he can believe each term of the pro-
position on its own evidence, and though he cannot reconcile
them, is willing to believe them reconcilable, and to wait till
in a higher stage of existence he shall receive more light.
That is, when we try to conceive of the Divine Being, we can-
not doubt that He foresees and pre-determines whatsoever
comes to pass; and when we question our own consciousness,
we feel that we are free agents, at liberty to act according to
the dictates of the will, or faculty of choice: We believe
each of those propositions to be true; and though we may not
be able to reconcile them, we are content to leave their recon-
ciliation to God and a future state of being. It might be
added, that our finite faculties are necessarily in themselves
unable to perceive at once both terms of any infinite truth,
in any other way than as a seeming contradiction,—the two
extremes of a circle meeting.
In the various treatises written on this deep and difficult
subject, there are other terms frequently employed,—such as
liberty and necessity, sometimes without any qualification, some-
times qualified as philosophical liberty and philosophical necessity.
By these qualifications the terms liberty and necessity are dis-
tinguished from their common use, and so restricted to the
exactness required in close reasoning. In common language,
96 NATURAL THEOLOGY. [DIV. I.
liberty means freedom from external force, or from the obliga-
tions and restraints imposed by unequal law, or mere caprice ;
but philosophical liberty relates only to the spontaneous determi-
nations of the will; and philosophical necessity implies that these
determinations are the necessary consequences of the constitu-
tion of the person and the circumstances in which he is placed,
or the motives brought before him. The idea of philosophical
necessity does not imply external constraint produced by effi-
cient causes, but rather the certainty and regularity of the
sequences of mind, in consequence of their nature and connec-
tion, so that our states of mind follow one another according to
certain mental laws, and arise with regularity in certain cir-
cumstances, rendering it possible to say, that the antecedent
state being known, there is a philosophical necessity (or certainty)
that this consequent, and not that, or any other indiscriminately,
will follow. With this explanation, I would not strongly con-
demn the theory of philosophical necessity ; but I by no means
regard it as giving an adequate view of the subject; or as
meeting the requirements of Natural, far less of Revealed,
Theology. It does not, and it cannot, account for the sudden
and great changes that frequently manifest themselves in human
character and conduct,—changes so decided as to render it
impossible to consider them the mere sequences of any ante-
cedent state of mind. Nor will philosophical liberty explain or
account for such changes, although it offers nothing against
their possibility. But they may all be satisfactorily explained
by the idea of a power (a divine mind) acting zn the will,
thereby enabling it to frame a new and unprecedented choice,
and to put forth a new energy, of a higher and nobler character
than it ever previously displayed.
This remark would lead us to look back and reconsider a
view already taken. When directing our attention to conscience,
we perceived that its high office is to declare respecting right
and wrong, and thence to tell us of duty, moral obligation, and
responsibility. In this office it comes inevitably into immediate
contact with the will. For, since the function of conscience is
to decide respecting states of the mind that prompt to action,
and since, before there can be voluntary action, there must be
volition, conscience must pronounce its judgment, not only
upon the motive, and upon the percipiency, but even the will,
the choice, before it becomes an act. When, therefore, motives
CHAP. V.] THE TWO ARGUMENTS IN COMBINATION. 9F
of any kind whatever solicit the will, and while it is preparing
to choose, conscience utters its approbation or disapprobation,
and tells even that proud faculty, the will, what duty requires,
what moral obligation enjoins, and what responsibility demands.
The will, then, is not without law; the arbitrium may not de-
termine arbitrarily ; the faculty of choice, however free, is not
at liberty to choose good or evil according to mere caprice.
Let the motives presented to it be as alluring or as urgent as
they may, conscience pronounces whether they ought to be
complied with or rejected ; and it is the duty of the will to obey
the dictates of conscience, to comply with the requirements of
duty, and not put itself under the power of motives. The full
import of this will be seen by adverting to a distinction already
drawn between voluntas and arbitriwm, Motives apply directly
to the voluntas, or percipient part of the will: conscience ad-
dresses itself ultimately to the arbitrium, or determining ele-
ment of the will... The freedom of the will consists in its
consenting to, or rejecting, the motives, according as they are
approved or disapproved by conscience! In this manner it
may be seen, that the freedom, rectitude, and power of the will,
must be exactly proportionate to the enlightenment, purity, and
truth of the conscience; and that the servitude, pravity, and
rebelliousness of the will, must be exactly proportionate to the
darkness, and corruption, and perversity of the conscience,
Hence we conclude, that a darkened and depraved conscience,
and a corrupt and rebellious will, form the great maladies of
man’s moral nature. And were we to pursue this line of
investigation, we might further prove, that, in this condition,
man’s will is under the power of motives, which are external
to himself and not under his own control; and that this renders
him the very slave of motives, and not the free subject of the
moral law of conscience, working within the will, and thereby
securing the free action of the « royal law of liberty,”—perfect
liberty, and perfect law. .
If the preceding view be admitted to contain anything like
The arrangement might be conceived of thus: 1. Desire, or emotion,
or motives; 2. Voluntas, percipient willingness, algo merely emotional ;
3. Act of the moral faculty, intimating approbation or disapprobation ;
4. Act of the arbitrium, or true will, or choice and power ; 5. Ultimate
act of conscience, in punishing if disobeyed, or rewarding if obeyed, by
remorse, or happiness.
G
98 NATURAL THEOLOGY. [DIV. I.
a true and intelligible account of the will, or faculty of choice
in man, as in my opinion it does, it will furnish an explanation
of some very obscure and difficult questions in moral philosophy.
The free agency and consequent responsibility of man will be
found to consist in the accordance between will and conscience.
The influence of motives will not be regarded as determining
the will, but as calling forth the moral action of both will and
conscience in their conjoint determination whether these motives
should be complied with or resisted. It will be seen also, that
*n this is one of the distinctions between man and the lower
orders of animated nature; for while they always obey motives,
man can either obey or resist them according to the decisions
of his higher nature. But it will likewise be seen, that the
will, though essentially free from the control and dominion of
motives,—of everything that can solicit its attention through
man’s sentient and intellectual nature,—is not without law ; that
conscience claims the right of directing the determinations of
the choosing faculty; and that.yet, when it complies with the
directions of conscience, it acts most freely, because it acts from
no compulsion from without, but from a congenial impulse from
within. And in the case of both conscience and will, there is a
direct recognition of an authority entitled to prescribe law to
both ;—law, to the supreme authority of which conscience her-
self appeals, whenever will refuses to listen to her dictates,—
this law to which conscience appeals, ought to dwell in the
inner being of the will itself, and to be its own ultimate law.
But what does this great thought suggest? Does it not suggest
that this inner law of will and conscience must be conformity
to the mind, and will, and character of the Supreme Author
and Ruler of our whole being? In compliance with that, we
must enjoy perfect liberty and perfect happiness. In our vain
endeavour to escape from it, we subject ourselves to the thral-
dom of motives, over the existence and the tendencies of which
we have no power. This is not the doctrine of philosophical
necessity ; yet it does not controvert the doctrine of divine
foreknowledge. The Divine Being, by whom we were called
into existence, cannot but know our inner nature. All motives
are at His command. If we comply with His divine will, obey
His law, and act in conformity to His character, the result
is certain; but if we refuse so to comply, we fall under the
power of motives, and the result is equally certain. When we
CHAP. V.] THE TWO ARGUMENTS IN COMBINATION. 99
obey Him, we conquer motives, and His will is done. When we.
disobey Him, motives conquer us, and yet His will is done. In
either case the result is certain, and can therefore be foreseen :
and yet our free agency is not otherwise impaired than as we
impair it by our own act, which still involves our responsibility.
It may be further seen, that in all this there is nothing
different from what takes place with regard to the other de-
partments of our complex nature. With regard to our sen-
sations and perceptions, these follow the laws of physical being,
and cannot be conceived of otherwise than as they are, being
in complete and amply proved harmony with the external uni-
verse, so far as we can become acquainted with it, as has been
shown by one of the ablest and clearest of modern thinkers.
Our intellectual nature is also equally obedient to the laws of
intelligent thought, which all operate necessarily, and according
to the constitution of our intellectual faculties. In like manner,
there are moral laws, bearing upon our capacity of recognising
right and wrong, good and evil, and of willing to choose the good
and refuse the evil; but in this, the very highest department
of our nature, these laws not only imply and recognise, but are
expressly directed in accordance with, the principle of freedom
to choose, and are therefore truly moral. Apart from the known
laws of sensation, perception, intellection, and morality, we
cannot conceive feeling, thought, and will; but these laws do
not impede, they constitute, freedom of thought or intellection,
and moral freedom, or the faculties of will and conscience, To
feel, think, and act in accordance with these laws, is what con-
stitutes our most perfect freedom, and our greatest happiness ;
because it is to act in accordance not only with the will of our
Creator, but also in accordance with our intuitive ideas of
duty and rightness—with the character of God. There can be
no action truly either moral or immoral, which is not voluntary;
but this does not exhaust the idea of morality. It must not
only be the voluntary act of the faculty of choice; it must
have been chosen in compliance with the sense of duty—the
conviction that it was good and right in itself, and therefore
ought to be done, and was therefore chosen and done. Here,
again, the harmonious and conjoint operations of will and con-
science are seen composing the moral liberty of man. When
the will chooses or rejects, not according to the solicitations of
motives,—not even according to the promised rewards or threa-
100 NATURAL THEOLOGY. [DIV. I.
tened punishments of law,—but according to the decisions of
conscience, then the action is morally right and good, and the
agent morally free. But when will rejects the decisions of
conscience, and follows the solicitations of motives, the action
is morally wrong, and the agent is morally enslaved—enslaved
by passion, prejudice, or crime.’ _
Liberty is not lawlessness ; it is the free exercise of the
laws of being, in accordance with the constitution and nature
of the agent. What we term the laws of sensation and per-
ception, are the operations of our sentient and percipient material
and mental being in connection with material nature, and the
intimations which we thereby receive when undiseased and
free. The free operation of our intellectual faculties is but
their exercise within their own province, and according to their
healthful constitutional capacities. This is their liberty, though
it be also their law.
By the addition of conscience, all these capacities and
faculties become the subjects of another kind of government—
a moral government. The acts of sense may be fallacious and
hurtful, if the sense be diseased. The acts of intellect may be
deranged, but their action, although insane, will be still intel-
lectual. And the acts of our moral nature, though they may
be in violation of its laws, are moral still, or, to use a more
common term, perhaps more suitable, they are then immoral—
vicious. The will may be solicited by any or by all the ~
departments of our lower nature, but its duty is to obey the
dictates of conscience, controlling all their solicitations. In its
liberty to obey conscience, consists its freedom, And conscience
1 All our natural faculties retain their primary nature, and act accord-
ing to it: each is still itself, and not any other. But in consequence of
the fall, they have all become misdirected, and have lost their due subor-
dination. They must retain each its own functions, operations, and pro-
vinees * the animal cannot think by feeding; the intellectual cannot feed
the body by thinking ; the reasoning cannot produce even mental action by
meditating ; the faculty that wills cannot produce deliberative judgment by
the exercise of its voluntary choice ; the most determined choice cannot
cause that to be morally right, which the moral faculty calls wrong ; and the
moral faculty cannot constrain the will to choose the right, when that
rebellious mental power has already denied it to be right, and is perversely
bent on the opposite. From the lowest to the highest, each should main-
tain its proper subordinate position, looking up to and obeying its superior;
conscience, the last and highest of all, looking up to and obeying God.
Thus would man at once glorify his Creator and be happy.
CHAP. V.] THE TWO ARGUMENTS IN COMBINATION. 101
is bound to perceive intuitively the right, the good, the lovely,
to decide accordingly, and to utter authoritative commands
even to the faculty of choice. But the will has thrown off the
due supremacy of conscience, and yet, in that rebellion against
its rightful lord, has enslaved itself to the impulses of those
motives which spring from lower sources. This is indeed
lawlessness, but not liberty. In this condition man is the slave
of nature, instead of wielding over it a free though delegated
sovereignty, responsible in its exercise to Him alone who is the
only Lord of the conscience.
To this conclusion, then, we have come by a fair and
legitimate investigation of the science of mind: That man is a
moral and accountable being,—moral and accountable through-
out all the range of all the faculties of his physical, intellectual,
and moral nature; that in the conjoint and harmonious opera-
tion of will and conscience consists his moral excellence,—
conscience pronouncing authoritatively what is right and good,
and will choosing and determining to act according to those
decisions; but that some dire calamity has befallen the human
race, in consequence of which conscience has lost its supremacy,
and even its clearness of intuitive perception of the good and
the evil, and will has rebelled against its dictates and put itself
under the control of the appetites of our lower nature. All
this we can perceive and prove without revelation; but any
remedy for this we cannot find. We groan beneath our heavy
moral bondage and degradation. We wished lawlessness, we
have lost liberty. We cannot recover our lost freedom by any
effort of our own: only by being born again can we again
become free-born. Hz only can restore our freedom by whom
we were at first created free.
SEC. III. ETHICAL SCIENCE, OR THE SCIENCE OF DUTY ;
VIEWED IN ITS APPLICATION TO MAN IN THE SOCIAL
STATE.
In a previous section I endeavoured to give some idea of
what many philosophers term the moral faculty, while I prefer
to give it the more common name of conscience. I may still
use the term moral faculty, as perhaps its strictly scientific
designation ; but I wish to be distinctly understood as attaching
to that term the full meaning which is usually given to that
102 NATURAL THEOLOGY. (DIV. I.
weighty word conscience. In the present section it is not so
much my intention to treat of conscience as a mental faculty,
or to inquire into its nature, as to view its operations and
results in the constitution of human society, forming what I
designate by the comprehensive name, T’he Science of Duty.
Nor is it the science of duty as it relates merely to human
society that I purpose to consider; but the science of duty and
man’s social state, as connected with the science of Natural
Theology, and as advancing our combined argument over the
extended sphere of observation now spread out before us. For
we cannot complete the investigation of our argument if we do
not consider man in his social condition, as well as in his indi-
vidual capacity ; in his relations to his fellow-man, as well as in
his relation to nature. Nay, in reality, the social sphere is the
more important of the two; because in it we see not only the
highest mental and moral powers of man brought out into
fullest and most developed action, but also we are constrained
to mark, in that state of developed action, an element which we
should not be able to trace with equal precision and certainty
in the individual,—an element which indicates with fatal dis-
tinctness and power the existence of some vast and disastrous
calamity which has befallen the human race, or some fearful
crime by which they have been involved in universal degrada-
tion and misery; rendering the construction of a true Natural
Theology either utterly impossible if omitted, or a matter of
the most urgently imperative importance.
If we retrace the survey we have already taken of human
nature, and mark what man is, we shall at once perceive that in
the very constitution of his mind there exists a necessity for
moral rules, to govern his appetites, affections, and desires. But
this appears most clearly when we view man as a member of
society, and perpetually holding such intercourse with his fel-
low-men, that without the guidance of moral rules he might be
incessantly inflicting or sustaining injury. _ From the very con-
stitution of man, therefore, as a rational and social being, he is
and must be also moral; and one of his most important studies
must necessarily be, the study of the science of duty,—a study
clearly pertaining to the domain of Natural Theology.
The question then arises, how man can learn the science of
duty. His intellectual faculties are so constituted as to enable
him to become acquainted with all around him. By their aid
a
CHAP. V.] THE TWO ARGUMENTS IN COMBINATION. 103
he can trace, to'a large extent, the relations of the whole of
external nature. And by the kindred relations subsisting be-
tween his own physical frame and external nature, he can avail
himself of the boundless resources with which the material
world is stored. The combined action of his intellectual facul-
ties, which we may term speculative reason, might give him a
very wide survey of what should be most conducive to his own
comfort and advantage. Yet when we attempt to conceive how
far the exercise of mere speculative reason could reach, we are
extremely prone to deceive ourselves, by ascribing to the possible
efforts of one mind what never has been produced except by
the mutual stimulus of many minds. There appears to be no
abstract impossibility in supposing, that the speculative reason
of a man bred up in a perfect solitude might proceed to the in-
vention of many of the arts of civilised life, and that at least
a succession of generations from such a man might arrive at
them all. Yet the fact is, that the tendency of man is not to
evolve a civilisation of his own accord, but rather to sink from
civilisation into barbarism, if left to himself. Leaving, how-
ever, that subject, and supposing the speculative reason to be
incessantly occupied in the investigation of the relations of
nature for the purpose of directing them to his own advantage,
what would be the result? There would be sedjishness, or the
desire and pursuit by each of what was conducive to his own
advantage ;—there might be what may be termed prudence, or
the calculating and cautious respect to the interests and self-
seeking desires of others which tended to warn him not to pass
certain limits in his dealings with his fellow-men ;—but out
of any possible amount of mere intellectual perceptions and
speculations on such topics, there could not possibly arise the
sense, the feeling, the principle of duty. There might be the
expedient,—there could not be the right: there might be the
perception of what would be certainly though remotely advan-
tageous, and for the sake of which present privations might be
endured, and present exertions made; but there could not be
the supreme conviction of the essential rightness of action or
endurance merely because-it was right, and from no prospect
of future advantage to himself.
We may also briefly inquire into the information furnished
by the active powers of the mind, as they are commonly called,
—the appetites, desires, and affections. It will be at once per-
104 NATURAL THEOLOGY. [DIV. I.
ceived that the very nature of these powers, or faculties, is to
prompt men to action; hence their usual designation, active
powers. The lowest class of these powers, the appetites, are not
otherwise necessarily moral, than by the necessity arising out
of their existence in connection with higher faculties, and in
a creature otherwise moral. The stimulus of our natural
appetites is necessary for securing the comfort and preservation
of our physical being; but even from our possession of higher
and intellectual faculties, we are called on to regulate our
appetites, so that the indulgence of them shall not impair the
exertions of the intellect. This consideration might lead to
prudential self-restraint, self-government, and some measure of
seli-denial, and might thereby produce at least the semblance
of morality; yet it would be only the semblance, for the essence
of all such procedure is still a regard to individual advantage,
which men endeavour to secure by the sacrifice of a present for
a future gratification, when convinced that we shall thereby
secure a greater amount of gratification on the whole. Apply
to such a course of conduct the idea of duty, and you will
perceive that you cannot make them coincide. Duty com-
mands to do what is right, because it is right, not because it is
prudent,—because it is right now, not because it may be
advantageous hereafter. The morality of self-restraint with
regard to our appetites, does not, therefore, arise out of our
possessing an intellectual nature, but out of our having a
moral nature; and though there may be many prudential regu-
lations based on intellectual considerations alone, they will be
found unable to ascend into those higher regions in which reside
the great principles of duty, moral obligation, and responsibility.
It might easily be shown, that as man is a social being, our
desires and affections do not and cannot terminate in self ; but
bring us into contact with other human beings actuated by
similar desires and affections, which the principle of sympathy
enables us almost immediately to realize. Sympathy has a
close relation to the moral faculty, though it is not itself that
faculty, as Adam Smith assumed, but acts as its unselfish
percipient element. We cannot, however, dwell on this topic,
but must proceed to what is more direct and important. Our
desires and affections pervade the. whole of our relations in
society. The very earliest position in which the human being
is placed, brings them into operation. ‘The family relation
CHAP. V.] THE TWO ARGUMENTS IN COMBINATION. 105
requires fidelity to the conjugal bond uniting husband and wife,
which is essentially a moral obligation. It requires, further,
the exercise of the parental affections, which are necessary for
the protection and the support of children. Thus it leads to
the desire of personal liberty, personal safety, and the possession
of property ; for without these the paternal affections cannot
have free scope. If a man has not personal liberty, he cannot
protect or support his household; if he has not personal safety,
he cannot secure the safety of those dependent on him ; and if
he has not security for the undisturbed possession of his pro-
perty, he cannot make his exertions available for the supply of
nature’s requirements.- Out of this primary relation there may,
therefore, naturally arise the conception of correlative natural
rights, which man claims to himself, and by parity of reason
must allow to others. We say must allow,—not may allow ;
because, without these, human society could not exist.
1. Out of these primary personal relations and natural rights
are evolved certain great primary ideas, or conceptions of prin-
ciples, which combine to form the social state. The first of these
arises from our perception of the benefits and the pleasures of
concord. ‘This has its earliest home in the household, where it
shows itself in that mutual love, which leads every member of
the family to seek the good of all the rest in preference to
what might seem his individual advantage. All desires that
centre and end in the individual have a dissociating tendency,
and lead to strife, dissension, and disruptive conflicts. That
society may be possible, therefore,—much more, that it may
be happy,—its regulating principle must be that of concord,
founded on mutual regard, or mutual love, or benevolence.
2. Further, as our intercourse with society increases, we find
the necessity of such a common understanding between man
and man as may enable us to depend upon each other’s words
and actions. Falsehood and deceit tend to break up society,
or to render its existence impossible. Hence we are constrained
to make every effort to secure such a harmony between inten-
tions and words, as to enable us, from a man’s words, to place
full confidence in the inward intentions which those words:
indicate. This coincident harmony between the mind and its
external indices we term truth; and we naturally desire, for
our own sakes and the welfare of society, that this moral
principle should be maintained. !
106 NATURAL THEOLOGY. [DIVE
3. Again, out of these primary personal relations and natural
rights there springs what we may term the idea of justice, the
object of which is to secure to every man what is his own. This
principle has for. its sphere to regulate the desire of property
according to what we may term fairness and liberality, as
contrasted with the ungenerous and grasping influence of
selfishness and covetousness.
4. We might thus, beginning with the family relation and
expanding that into the widening circle of society, elicit from
the constitution of the human being at least three great moral
principles—benevolence, truth, and justice; and we might
regard these as primary elements of morality, affecting all
mankind, and essential to the comfort and wellbeing of the
human race. But if we look still more closely into the con-
stitution of the mind, we shall find that we have not yet fully
explored its moral elements. For, as we have already observed,
though neither the bodily appetites nor the intellectual faculties
are themselves essentially moral, yet, when connected with
moral faculties in the same being, they acquire a moral charac-
ter, and are susceptible of moral rules. The control of the
natural appetites by the higher faculties of our nature may be
designated by the terms Temperance and Chastity. And as we
are conscious of the feelings of debasement and impurity when
the lower faculties are indulged to excess, and wrongfully, we
may give to the moral sentiment which demands their due
subjection the name Moral Purity. We thus conceive another
moral principle, having ‘for its domain the government of our
entire lower, animal, or sentient nature, with all its appetites
and desires.
5. Again, directing our attention to our intellectual nature,
we perceive the necessity of having all our intellectual powers
arranged and guided by such laws as shall regulate their
operations in a steady and uniform consistency. Without such
a systematic arrangement and uniformity of our intellectual
perceptions and pursuits, we perceive that the human mind
cannot make any truly valuable progress; nay, would be liable
to sudden aberrations little short of insanity. Hence another
general idea of fixed and regulating Jaw, as an indispensable
condition essential to moral progress, which is itself an essential
necessity and duty to man. And this general idea we may
designate Order.
CHAP. V.] THE TWO ARGUMENTS IN COMBINATION. 107
We thus obtain five primary principles of morality; viz.
benevolence, truth, justice, purity, and order. All these may be
deduced from the constitution of man, as an intelligent, rational,
and social being, and may be regarded as the primary principles
of natural and human morality. Let an appeal be made to
conscience on any or all of these principles, whether they be
necessary for its proper exercise, and we may confidently antici-
pate its response—that they are, each and all, essentially related
to it, included in its nature, necessary to its exercise, and
implied in the science of duty and in the domain of Natural
Theology.
Admitting, then, that conscience approves of the five great
moral principles thus enumerated, the next step is obvious :
they must be regarded as the essential rules of moral action,
or, in other words, as moral laws. They have all that is
requisite for the formation of laws: there is the conception in
the mind, the approbation of the conscience, and the consent
of mankind in general. But when we conceive of them as
becoming embodied in the form of law for the regulation of
society, we are enabled to perceive the importance of pure and
sound ethics to the welfare of the community. The law of any
nation cannot possibly rise higher, practically, than its morality ;
for it is in truth the embodiment of that nation’s morality,
reduced to rules for the government of society. It may often
happen that the law of a nation is morally defective ; and so
far the public morality of the nation may also be defective:
but should a juster view of moral obligation, and clearer con-
ceptions of what is morally right and good, be promulgated and
enlighten the public mind, the defective state of the law would
be seen, and it would be soon improved according to the stan-
dard of a higher and truer morality. Hence the duty of moral
culture, for two great ends—the enlightenment of the legislature,
and the enlightenment of the community. Either of these may
precede the other. The lawgiver may have far more true and
lofty conceptions of what is morally right and good than the
community can appreciate; and if he attempt to frame laws
in conformity with his own conceptions, he may find that the
community will reject them as visionary and impracticable.
Even Solon could say, “I have not given the Athenians the
best laws possible, but I have given them the best that they
can bear.” And an infinitely more wise Lawgiver could say,
108 NATURAL THEOLOGY. [DIV. I.
“Tt was because of the hardness of your hearts.” On the
other hand, the public morality of the nation may become more
enlightened and true than that of the legislature, in its admi-
nistrative function especially, and may strive to procure some
amendment of defective laws. This, too, may be for a time
resisted by the ruling powers; but that resistance cannot very
long continue to prevail against right, for morality must in the
process of time mould and regulate Jaw.
Moral principles, it appears, give rise to moral laws; and
moral laws embody and confirm moral duties and moral rights.
Our moral duties are thus rendered realities, which may be to
some extent enforced by the rewards and punishments of law ;
and our rights are realities, which may be protected in the same
manner. ‘Thus by the sanctions of law there must be continu-
ally going on a course of moral culture throughout the entire
community, to the extent at least of the morality embodied in
the laws of the country. The duties and rights thus realized
and enforced may be comprised under the following heads:
The Right of Personal Security, the Right of Property, the
Right of Contract, and Family Rights. The infringement of
any of these rights is a moral wrong, both against the individual
and against the national law, by which the individual is pro-
tected in their peaceful and secure enjoyment. Were we to
enter into an examination of these rights in detail, we might
easily show that they are all in perfect harmony with the
dictates of a sound and enlightened conscience. And we cannot
fail at once to perceive how much they are fitted to support the
general welfare, and to secure the harmony, peace, and happi-
ness of the social state of man. But our view will be defective
indeed if we do not also perceive that there are thousands of
minute particulars contained within the wide generalities of
public law, public morality, and public rights, the protection
and enforcement of which must of necessity depend on the
strength, purity, and faithfulness of individual conscience.
Law can but apply to the action, and cannot reach the state of
mind from which that action proceeded, and in which its moral
nature truly resides. Even though we were to regard national
law as embodied national morality or national conscience, we
must perceive that it can neither perform the functions nor
supersede the authority of the individual conscience. Hence it
must follow, that no reform of national laws, however important
CHAP. V.] THE TWO ARGUMENTS IN COMBINATION. 109
or extensive, can ever of itself secure the moral welfare of the
nation. That must be secured in the bosom of individuals and
families—in the enlightenment and purification of conscience
itself—in the infusion into the inner being of a law and a light
to which even conscience must do homage, and must find free-
dom and power in obeying.
There is another view that may be taken of the moral prin-
ciples already mentioned. We have pointed out their harmony
with the dictates of conscience, as well as their indispensable
necessity for the very existence of society. But when we look
closely at their operation in the case of an individual, we be-
come aware of a new and a very important aspect which they
assume. Conscience pronounces its sentence of approbation or
disapprobation upon any single principle, sentiment, or action.
But human life, though composed of pulsations and breathings,
is still a continuity ; and moral life, though composed of a suc-
cession of moral states, is still a continuous moral existence.
It is not the one action or sentiment, therefore, of which con-
science takes cognisance, and on which it pronounces sentence,
but the continuous moral existence of the man. And, to pro-
secute the analogy, as by the power of habit we acquire a
facility in the execution of any physical task, becoming expert
and skilful, so by the power of habit the mind acquires both
readiness and energy in the exercise of its faculties, and in the
reproduction of those emotions that prompt to action. The
habit of frequently contemplating and acting in accordance
with moral principles will naturally secure to those principles
easy access to the mind, and a calm, steady, and almost con-
tinuous influence over it. Thus the mind may acquire moral
habits and a moral character; and as these moral habits must,
of course, have for their essence the leading moral principles,
they may be designated by corresponding names. ‘There may
be, therefore, the habit of benevolence, of justice, of truth, of
purity, and of order; and these habits we would term Moral
Virtues. And as it is evident that some one of these moral
virtues may, and commonly will, predominate over the others
in the general tenor of a man’s life, so that predominating
virtue will give the distinctive name to his character, and he
will be called peculiarly a benevolent, a just, or a truthful man.
The very least consideration will show that a large proportion
of practical morality is included within the region of habit,—
110 NATURAL THEOLOGY. (DIV. I.
the region, that is, of the moral virtues, and their effect in
forming and moulding character.
The same subject might be investigated in the precisely
opposite direction. We might mark the violation of the great
principles of morality, which conscience condemns, and the law
punishes as crimes; and we might then trace the power of
habit in facilitating the recurrence of those states of mind
which prompted to the immoral actions. We should then per-
ceive, that habitual violations of moral principle were aptly
designated vices, and that their prevalence formed vicious
characters. But it is enough for our present purpose to have
indicated a course of inquiry, which the aspect of society
renders but too easy to prosecute.
One inference, or rather field of inferential argument, we
must, however, indicate. The power of habit in a moral point
of view, and the formation of character, virtuous or vicious,
according to prevalent habit, must be taken very largely into
account, when we endeavour to form an idea of man’s future
state. It even enters deeply into the argument to prove the
immortality of the soul. No power of metaphysical reasoning
or confusion will ever induce any man to believe that there is
not an essential difference between mind and matter. But if
mind, by its own operations, can contract habits and acquire a
permanent character, its separation from the body will leave it
with that character still; and not only so, but the same habit
will continue to deepen that character continually in a future
state, so that it must be terribly true, that “he who is filthy will
be filthy still,’ and eternity itself will but eternally increase his
wickedness and his punishment. A change of character must
take place in that stage of being in which alone character is
formed and matured, else it must never take place at all. And
the more cheering aspect of the inference must be equally true
and certain, and in the future state “he that is holy must be
holy still.”
It has been remarked, that the predominance of our prin-
ciple, and the habitual prevalence of its exercise in the conduct,
forms the character of the man. Let it be further observed,
that this is not a merit, but a defect in human character. The
man of benevolent character deserves and obtains moral appro-
bation on account of his benevolence; but his character would
be much more perfect were he equally distinguished by truth,
CHAP. V.] THE TWO ARGUMENTS IN COMBINATION. 111
justice, purity, and order. It is praiseworthy to have one
virtue ; but it would be more so to have every moral virtue in
equal exercise. No such man, however, exists,—no such man
ever did exist, except THE Man Curist Jesus. This excep-
tion, which I have almost unconsciously specified, points to the
manner in which one class of the evidences of Natural Theo-
logy is deducible from the moral nature of man. For that
argument proceeds upon the reality of moral principles in man,
as implied in the very constitution of his mind; whence the in-
ference appears inevitable, that these must be the attributes, in
absolutely infinite perfection and perfect harmony, of the divine
Creator Himself, otherwise they never could have been in man,
the creature.
We have briefly traced the leading elements and principles
of the science of duty, as manifested in the social state of man,
and essential to the very possibility of human society. But we
must take yet another view of the subject, if we wish to see it
fully. The moral principles already enumerated form the basis
of moral character in the individual, and of the moral laws of
society ; but they do not secure the moral conduct of the indi-
vidual, and they are insufficient for the task of preserving the
moral peace and welfare of society. All men recognise them
as right and good in the abstract, but no man regulates his con-
duct according to their dictates. All men wish others to be
guided by them, because all are constrained to admit that they
are right and good, and tend to promote the welfare and happi-
ness of society; but self-interest, and passion, and vice inter-
pose their pernicious influences, and all men, yielding more or
less to these evil agencies, commit in their own cases what they
condemn in the abstract, or in the case of others. And while
all men perceive, with various degrees of clearness, the benefit
of moral principles and virtues, and concur in passing laws in
accordance with their requirements ; yet all feel it to be neces-
sary to give to these the dread enforcement of the power of
inflicting punishment. It is a melancholy view of human
nature, but not more melancholy than true, that hwman law
has far more power to punish than it has to reward,—that, in
fact, its execution depends upon its power to punish, and not
upon its power to reward. Men seem instinctively to know,
and with tacit sullenness to admit, that it is much more likely
that the best laws which they can devise and frame will be
112 NATURAL THEOLOGY. [DIV. I.
broken, than that they will be obeyed. May not this be
regarded as the reluctant admission of man, that he is a fallen
creature,—that his own conscience cannot now govern him,—
and that law, instead of being merely the regulating influence
of internal principles, keeping his whole being in harmonious
action, is now an external power, employed to constrain or
punish what it cannot otherwise govern? ‘This is a melan-
choly conclusion; but it flows inevitably from the facts of
the case.
But even when taking this sad view of human nature, we
may obtain some encouragement from a kindred topic which it
suggests. The power of human law depends upon its punish-
‘ments more than its rewards. Yet the absolute power, the
power to punish, depends upon an element of a moral nature,
not mere physical force. This appears when we contemplate
a highly complicated state of society, in which the extreme
capabilities of life are explored, and often placed side by side.
Rank, wealth, refinement, and luxury are found possessed by
comparatively few, and almost in immediate contact with vice,
degradation, and misery too deep and fearful to be described.
If, in such a state of society, the enforcement of the laws that
protect person and property depended, either alone or chiefly,
on physical might, they could not be enforced an hour; but
the moral power of conscience comes to their aid, and even
those laws are generally obeyed against which all merely
physical interests would prompt the poor and the degraded to
rebel. It is thus that conscience continues to exercise its due
supremacy to so great an extent as still to be the guardian and
the ruler of society. Even statesmen and legislators are to
some degree aware of this great moral power, striving in
general to engage it on their side, and shrinking from anything
that would seem openly to outrage it, or weaken its influence.
The interests of society would be greatly promoted were legis-
lators wise enough to advance a little further in this direc-
tion, and to bend their energies to the incalculably important
office of endeavouring to promote the cultivation of sound,
pure, and elevated national morality. And how dark is the
omen for any land, where its rulers rest their power to govern
on their possession and employment of the means to deceive
and corrupt! Yet, even such acondition is not hopeless. The
general morality of the nation may be so much enlightened as
|
7
.
CHAP. V.] THE TWO ARGUMENTS IN COMBINATION. 113
to counteract the immoral agencies of rulers,—to improve both
the framing and the administration of national laws,—and. ulti-
mately to constrain governments to know that power must
depend on integrity, and that truth and rectitude are stronger
elements than deceit and corruption. But this can be the case
only where the nation possesses the means of obtaining a true
and pure moral culture, independent of the plans and arrange-
ments of its civil rulers.
The conclusion that ought to be drawn from the views
which have been taken, seems abundantly obvious. Both the
psychology of the individual human being, and the structure
of society, contain the most clear and conclusive proofs. that
man is a being of a moral nature,—that obedience to the dic- '
tates of his moral faculty is essential to his individual and social
welfare and happiness,—that disobedience to those dictates
involves him in misery, and exposes him to punishment: and
yet, that his moral nature must have sustained some signal
calamity, so great that he often cannot clearly distinguish what
duty requires, and when he does clearly perceive these require-
ments, he very often violates them, and exposes himself to the
punishments which either social law, or the law within his own
breast, sooner or later fails not to inflict. In vain do moralists
and speculative or philosophical statesmen attempt to frame
codes of law constructed on the idea of moral excellence which
conscience and speculative reason may unite to form. Plato
may imagine laws for the region of Atlantis, and Sir Thomas
More may conceive the moral government of Utopia; but the
enactment and execution of such laws must ever continue im-
practicable, so long as it is a mournful truth, that the human
mind is a fallen mind,—that the will is rebellious, the conscience
dethroned, and even reason and intellect warped and darkened.
Yet even such moral romances may subserve a higher argu-
ment. ‘They seem to prove that the human mind is essentially
moral; that even in its fallen and powerless condition, the moral
faculty asserts its right to rule; and that, fallen and degraded
as it is, it retains somewhat of its original majesty, and its’
aspirations after a purer and happier state than it now possesses,
or can by its own efforts obtain. Like Milton’s description of
the great fallen spirit,—
‘* His form had not yet lost
All her original brightness, nor appeared
H
114 NATURAL THEOLOGY. . 7 EDIV.