Sa 3S ie - 2S SS Sa Sa SSS SS = BR 45° .B35 1927 Williams, Norman Powell, 1883-1943 The ideas of the fall and of Arininal ein ‘this ¥ : 1 Digitized by the Internet Archive ’ | ~ In 2021 with funding from ® ) Princeton Theological Seminary Library | 7 | A | | ) ‘ 1 : archive.org/details/ideasoffallofori00will te THE IDEAS OF THE FALL AND OF ORIGINAL SIN Lene ei - ‘5 i {ia Roath Mac tO tea be ee re 1y CAA a Ay hae he “oh Lie iy aye , i 4 ¥ bate, fy Ay ANUS Whe : aT 7 \ Lei 4 \s at Cee Uh MLOa OM nya) © habe é THE IDEAS OF THE FALL AND OF ORIGINAL SIN A HISTORICAL AND CRITICAL STUDY BEING EIGHT LECTURES DELIVERED BEFORE THE UNIVERSITY OF OXFORD, IN THE YEAR 1924, ON THE FOUNDATION OF THE REV. JOHN BAMPTON, CANON OF SALISBURY BY NORMAN POWELL WILLIAMS, D.D., FELLOW AND CHAPLAIN OF EXETER COLLEGE, OXFORD Oa ¢ € g e A 3 4 aitia eAowevov® Qedg avatttos LONGMANS, GREEN AND CO. LTD. 39 PATERNOSTER ROW, LONDON, E.C.4 NEW YORK, TORONTO | CALCUTTA, BOMBAY AND MADRAS 1927 Made in Great Britain EXTRACT FROM THE LAST WILL AND TESTAMENT OF THE LATE REV. JOHN BAMPTON CANON OF SALISBURY ‘,.. I give and bequeath my Lands and Estates to the Chancellor, Masters, and Scholars of the University of Oxford for ever, to have and to hold all and singular the said Lands or Estates upon trust, and to the intents and purposes hereinafter mentioned ; that is to say, I will and° appoint that the Vice-Chancellor of the University of Oxford for the time being shall take and receive all the rents, issues, and profits thereof, and (after all taxes, repara- tions, and necessary deductions made) that he pay all the remainder to the endowment of eight Divinity Lecture Sermons, to be established for ever in the said University, and to be performed in the manner following : “I direct and appoint that, upon the first Tuesday in Easter Term, a Lecturer be yearly chosen by the Heads of Colleges only, and by no others, in the room adjoining to the Printing-House, between the hours of ten in the morning and two in the afternoon, to preach eight Divinity Lecture Sermons, the year following, at St. Mary’s in Oxford, between the commencement of the last month in Lent Term and the end of the third week in Act Term. “Also I direct and appoint, that the eight Divinity Lecture Sermons shall be preached upon either of the following Subjects—to confirm and establish the Christian vi EXTRACT FROM CANON BAMPTON’S WILL Faith, and to confute all heretics and schismatics—upon the divine authority of the holy Scriptures—upon the authority of the writings of the primitive Fathers, as to the faith and practice of the primitive Church—upon the Divinity of our Lord and Saviour Jesus Christ—upon the Divinity of the Holy Ghost—upon the Articles of the Christian Faith, as comprehended in the Apostles’ and Nicene Creeds. ‘Also I direct, that thirty copies of the eight Divinity Lecture Sermons shall be always printed, within two months after they are preached; and one copy shall be given to the Chancellor of the University, and one copy to the Head of every College, and one copy to the Mayor of the city of Oxford, and one copy to be put into the Bodleian Library ; and the expense of printing them shall be paid out of the revenue of the Land or Estates given for establishing the Divinity Lecture Sermons; and the Preacher shall not be paid, nor be entitled to the revenue, before they are printed. “Also I direct and appoint, that no person shall be qualified to preach the Divinity Lecture Sermons, unless he hath taken the degree of Master of Arts at least, in one of the two Universities of Oxford or Cambridge ; and that the same person shall never preach the Divinity Lecture Sermons twice.’ PREFACE PERHAPS the gravest of the intellectual difficulties which restrain men of thoughtfulness and goodwill from giving their allegiance to the Christian Faith is that which inheres— not in any one article or detail of our religion, not in its doctrines of the Triune being of God or of the two natures of Christ, not in Atonement, miracles, sacraments, or eschatology—but in its fundamental assertion that ‘ God is love.’ It is not that such persons find an intrinsic improba- bility or logical incongruity in the ascription of those qualities which we know in man as righteousness, benevo- lence, compassion, and love to the mysterious Ultimate Source and Ground of things; but rather that the assertion appears to them as irreconcileable with the facts of the world and of human life. ‘Is it possible,’ they ask, ‘ to believe that behind the cruel misfits, the senseless waste, the sordid ferocity with which organic nature, human and sub-human, is deeply marked, there really exists that dazzlingly perfect, that inconceivably glorious and blissful _ Being of whom Christian theology speaks ? Can we recognise in the infinite and eternal Energy, from which all things proceed, which seems with impersonal indifference to weave good and evil, love and hate, beauty and ugliness into the tissue of its phenomenal self-expression, the features of that loving heavenly Father whom Jesus claimed to reveal? Is it not more honest to admit that we are confronted by a morally neutral universe ; and, if we keep the conception of ‘‘God”’ at all, to regard the God of religion as limited, as less than the Absolute, though greater than ourselves— our ally, perhaps, in the work of harnessing the blind forces of nature, without us and within, to ethically valuable ends, but like men ultimately dependent for His being on the b Vill PREFACE inscrutable substrate of the world-process, which, for all we know, may in some unpredictable freak eventually crush both Him and us?’ For Christians, the faith that God is infinite in power, love, and holiness alike is guaranteed by His revelation of Himself, imparted in the first instance through the Hebrew prophets, consummated in Jesus Christ, and authenticated by the witness of the Spirit within the believer’s heart. Whatever use may be made of intellectual argument for establishing the probability of Christian theism, the con- viction of its certainty must always rest upon experience of a supra-rational kind: and such experience is normally acquired and communicated through the spiritual contagion which clings about the organised fellowship of redeemed people, the visible Church of Christ upon earth. To those who doubt the friendliness and the love of the Power behind the universe, the ultimate appeal of Christians must be “Come and see,’ ‘ gustate et videte, quoniam suavis est Dominus.’ Nevertheless, such an appeal, if it is to exert its full power, should be accompanied by some reasoned answer to the question ‘ How is the hypothesis of God’s infinite goodness and compassion to be reconciled with the actual state of His world ? ’ The answer given to this question by historical Chris- tianity consists in the doctrine of the Fall and of its consequences. The world is what it is despite the goodness of its Maker, because it has apostatised from its Maker. But, owing partly to the verdict of Biblical criticism upon the ancient stories with which this doctrine has for many centuries been connected, partly to the revolution effected by modern science in our conception of the universe and of the place of man within it, the idea of the Fall may be said to have been for some time past under a cloud; and such references as have been made to it by Christian thinkers, at least in areas of Christendom where heed is paid to science and Biblical criticism, have been hesitating and uncertain, except when they have involved its definite rejection. It seems, therefore, that there is room for a systematic study of the whole subject, such as is attempted in the following Lectures, a study which will not merely PREFACE 1X investigate the origins of the Fall-doctrine and trace the course of its development, but will seek to determine the extent of its acceptance by orthodox Christianity, and the degree of validity, if any, which it may claim before the bar of reason. Such a study has indeed been made on an imposing scale by Dr. F. R. Tennant, in three works, of which the latest was published some fifteen years ago—namely, ‘ The Origin and Propagation of Sin’ (Hulsean Lectures, 1902), ‘ The Sources of the Doctrines of the Fall and Original Sin’ (1903), ‘ The Concept of Sin’ (1912). These books constitute the first, and so far the only, attempt in English to subject the Fall-doctrine to a severely scientific examination in respect both of its origin and of its truth, and my obliga- tions to them will be obvious to the reader of these Lectures at every turn. Nevertheless, I have been impelled to essay the task again, partly because at various points I find myself in disagreement with Dr. Tennant’s interpretation of the historical data, and partly because, since the publication of his last-mentioned work, the speculative situation has been largely modified by the development of what is known as the ‘ new psychology,’ and also by the revival of a theory which at the time when Dr. Tennant wrote was not considered as a serious claimant to the attention of modern theologians, but which has been adopted as the basis of the constructive view set forth in the last of these Lectures— the theory, namely, of a transcendental, pre-human or pre-cosmic ‘ Fall.’ This revival is mainly due to Canon Peter Green’s book ‘The Problem of Evil’ (1920) and Dr. C. W. Formby’s ‘ The Unveiling of the Fall’ (1923) ; and I desire to acknowledge here the share which both of these books have had in moulding my own thought on the subject. Apart from these considerations, it has seemed worth while to endeavour to provide a treatment of the whole matter, both in its historical and in its dogmatic aspect, which should be included between the covers of one. book: though it must be confessed that the discussion of so vast and intricate a question, raising as it does almost every other problem both in theology and philosophy, does not lend itself to compression within the limits of eight % PREFACE Lectures; and, whilst rigidly confining myself, so far as was possible, to the examination of the Fall-doctrine proper, and abstaining from entering upon collateral fields of enquiry, I have found myself compelled to make full use of the privilege customarily conceded to a Bampton Lecturer, that of printing considerably more than was actually spoken in the pulpit of St. Mary’s. The apparent dispro- portion between the long and detailed study of pre- Augustinian thought in Lecture IV and the cursory notice of post-Reformation developments in Lecture VI is, I hope, justified by the use made of the former in the constructive part of the book. I desire to express sincere gratitude to those who have helped me in the preparation and revision of these Lectures with information and advice: first and foremost to the Rev. Canon Darwell Stone, D.D., who has found time amidst his innumerable employments to read the whole of the historical part of the book in typescript, and has freely placed the immense resources of his patristic learning at my disposal; then to the Rev. Canon Brightman, Fellow of Magdalen College, Oxford, to whom I owe the substance of Additional Note C (‘Congregational Confessions of Original Sin’) > to! Canon “D..-CSimpson;) Dupe eG Professor of the Interpretation of Holy Scripture in the University of Oxford; Professor Dr. Friedrich Loofs, of Halle ; Dr. Charles Singer ; Dr. A. Biichler, Principal of the Jews’ College; Canon T. A. Lacey’; and Mr. H. M. J. Loewe, University Lecturer in Rabbinic Hebrew at Oxford. It is doubtless unnecessary to add that these gentlemen are not to be considered in any way responsible for any of the opinions expressed in the book, or for any mistakes which may appear init. I must also thank the Ven. R. H. Charles, D.D., F.B.A., Archdeacon of Westminster, and the Delegates of the University Press for permission to make use of quotations from the English translations of apocalyptic documents contained in ‘ Apocrypha and Pseudepigrapha of the Old Testament’ (1913). N. P. WILLIAMS. OXFORD : January 1927. SMNOPSIS 7 OR iwC ON DONS PAGE LECTURE ].—THE BEGINNINGS OF FALL-SPECULATION I The Problem of Evil in general. No complete solution is possible ; but Religion ought to contain some indication of the direction in which the solution lies. Three classical answers to the question have in the past been given by Religion in its higher forms: (1) the theory of “unmoral monism,’ characteristic of Hindu thought, according to which Good and Evil are alike appearances—presumably necessary appearances—of an Absolute which transcends them both; (2) dualism, the view of later Mazdeism and Mani- cheism, which postulates co-eternal Powers of Good and Evil; (3) the theory of a ‘Fall’ and of ‘ Original Sin,’ in- herited by Christianity from Judaism, and standing in sharp opposition to the two former views. The purpose of these lectures is a critical examination of this last theory, both as regards origin and validity. General remarks as to the present position of the Fall- doctrine and of the conception of Redemption which is its inseparable corollary. We are faced at the outset by the fact that much diversity has prevailed within historical Christianity as to the exact form and contents of the ideas of the Fall and of Original Sin. Before endeavouring to evaluate them, we must first of all determine what precisely they are. It is impos- sible to assume without enquiry that any existing con- fessional formulary adequately embodies the whole mind of traditional Christianity on these points: and there are no detailed definitions of oecumenical authority. We must therefore endeavour to arrive at the irreducible essence of Fall-doctrine to which Catholic Christianity is committed by a comprehensive survey of the history of the doctrine, employing © the ‘Vincentian canon’ as a scientific—not as a authoritarian —criterion. The first six lectures will, accordingly, be histori- cal in nature, intended to ascertain the origin and fix the essence of these ideas, and the last two, theological or philo- sophical, devoted to a discussion of their validity. Our historical survey necessarily begins with the Old Testa- ment. The Paradise-story of Gen. ili. contains no idea of ‘ Original Sin’; it is, therefore, not the historical source of Xl SY NOPSISTOD ICON TENS PAGE the Fall-doctrine, which originated in the thought of post- exilic Judaism as the result of reflection on the empirical universality of Actual Sin. This observed fact suggested the presence of some inherent taint in human nature: the Jew’s intense conviction of the Creator’s goodness forbade the sup- position that such a taint could have belonged to human _ nature as originally created: it thus seemed necessary to postulate a ‘ Fall,’ or first sin. The necessity of a Fall having been thus arrived at by a priovt reasoning, search was made in the Biblical narratives for some event which could be identified with the first sin; this was found, at first, in the story of the lustful angels narrated in Gen. vi. The theory that human wickedness is due to the unnatural mixture of divine and human essences involved in the union of the ‘ sons of God’ and mortal women is elaborated in the Book of Enoch, and other apocalyptic literature. It breaks down, owing to its failure to explain post-diluvian sin, and is gradually ousted from its position as the popular Fall-story by the Adam-narrative of Gen. iii. Traces of it are, however, to be found even in New Testament documents. The fact that there has been this rivalry between the two Fall-stories, Gen. vi. and Gen. iii. (ending in the victory of the latter), confirms the conclusion that neither is the real basis of the doctrine: they are rather symbolic fagades, clothing a conceptual structure which rests upon spiritual experience and introspection. And the suggestion of Gen. vi., that the origin of sin is due to lust, represents the first emergence of a motif, which runs through much of Christian Fall-speculation and seems to have reappeared in recent psychology of the Viennese school. ADDITIONAL, Notre :A.—THE QRIGIN: OF THE ARTS) HIN PSEUDO-ENOCH AND AESCHYLUS : ‘ : ‘ 35 LECTURE “II——Tur -ADAM-STORY” AND THE’. EVIE IMAGINATION’ é , ; ‘ My ales, We now turn to the consideration of the story which finally became the official Fall-story of the Christian Church, that of Adam and Eve. It was pointed out in Lecture I that this story, in itself and for the mind of the Yahwistic writer, contained no doctrine of ‘ Original Sin’ and regarded ‘ the Fall’ merely as an exterior punishment, not as the acquisition of an interior taint or weakness. ‘This statement must now be justified. The story analysed. ‘Though capable of conscious com- munion with God, the first men are not conceived as being very much higher than the beasts, in respect of physical and material conditions. There is no doctrine of ‘ Original Righteousness’ ; but Adam and Eve, in their unfallen condi- tion, are not strictly ‘ non-moral,’ for they know of at least SYNOPSIS OF CONTENTS two duties—work and abstinence from the forbidden fruit. For the Yahwistic writer, their sin lay in the illicit acquisition of scientific knowledge ; cf. the myth of Prometheus. J isa pessimist ; he thinks that civilisation is a mistake, and that the increase of knowledge brings sorrow in its train. This naive original significance, however, was obscured for the Jews of the Maccabean period by the canonical status and inspired character attributed to the Book of Genesis ; hence, the religiously higher idea—that the essence of the first sin consisted in the conscious transgression of a known law—could be and was read into it. The pre-Christian development of Fall-speculation, now firmly anchored to the Adam-story, summarised : we notice in particular the growth of (a) the idea that man’s mortality is directly due to the first sin, and (b) the theory of ‘ Original Righteousness.’ The theory of the inquinamentum (which reappears in the New Testament), according to which Eve was the sole source of human sin and misery, Adam being guiltless. The two Fall-theories just discussed (that based upon Gen. vi., and its successful rival based on Gen. iii.) belong to popular religious thought. But, to gain a complete picture of the theological milieu into which Christianity came, and of the doctrinal background which the teaching of our Lord and His Apostles presupposes, we must consider the theory of the origin of evil held by official Rabbinical scholasticism—which is still held by the Jewish Church at the present day. This is the theory of the yéger ha-va‘, or ‘ evilimagination.’ Deriva- tion of this conception from the words of Gen. vi. 5. The‘ evilimagination ’ in pre-Christian literature, especially Ecclesiasticus. Further information about this idea may be derived from Talmudic sources. The conception of the yéger ha-ra‘ in the Rabbis would seem to be almost identical with that of ibidoin Jung,ifnotin Freud. Difference between this idea and that of ‘ Original Sin.’ The yéger implanted by God in each individual soul. This was the view of the official theology—as distinct from popular pietism. Butthe Adamic theory won such widespread support that the Rabbis had to take some account of it ; hence the idea of a forensic imputation of the first man’s demerit to his descendants, 7.e. the idea of ‘ Original Guilt,’ as distinct from that of ‘ Original Sin.’ This distinction, which will be of crucial importance for the understanding of Christian thought on the subject, explained. Two attempts to combine the popular theory of Adam’s Fall and ‘ Original Sin’ with the Rabbinical theory of the yecer ha-va‘—the Syriac Apocalypse of Baruch, and the Ezra- Apocalypse. Philo’s Platonism (really identical with what we described as the Hindu answer to the problem of the origin of Evil) forbids him to accept either the Fall or the ‘ evil imagination.’ Summary of the state of opinion within Judaism at the time when Christianity came into existence. The Fall- doctrine held 7m the Jewish Church, but not by the Jewish Xiil XiV SYNOPSIS OF CONTENTS Church as a whole. So far as the Elder Dispensation is con- cerned, it was never more than a ‘ pious opinion.’ Any claim to the position of a ‘ revealed ’ doctrine made on its behalf can only rest on the fact of its embodiment into the scheme of Christian doctrine. LECTURE IIJI.—THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE NEW TESTAMENT . : The foregoing Lectures have described the source and contents of the main theories as to the origin of Evil—the angel-theory, the Adam-theory, and the idea of the yéger ha-va‘— which prevailed within Judaism at the beginning of our era. We now have to face a crucial question: how was it that one of these theories (the Adam-theory) was taken over, to the exclusion of the others, by Christianity, and welded so firmly into the dogmatic structure of Christianity that succeeding ages have regarded it as a chief pillar of the Church’s Faith ? The question is somewhat of an enigma in view of the fact that the direct authority of Christ cannot be claimed for this doctrine, or indeed for any other theory of the origin of evil, though His teaching assumes that mankind is in sore need of redemption from sin. The only New Testament passages which definitely teach ‘ Original Sin’ and the Adamic theory of the Fall are con-. tained in the writings of St. Paul (Jude and 2 Peter seem to assume the ‘ angel-theory’). It is noticeable that St. Paul is at no pains to prove the Adamic theory : he takes it for granted, in parentheses and obizter dicta, which he could hardly have done unless he had known it to be common ground between himself and hisreaders. But, how could he have assumed it, in this almost casual manner, as the common intellectual property of all Christians, if it had not direct Dominical authority behind it? We must admit that the passage of the Fall- doctrine from Judaism into Christianity is involved in some obscurity ; but the following appears to be the most probable hypothesis : (a) That the earliest adherents of our Lord, being rough Galileans, and destitute of Rabbinical culture, would know nothing about the yéger ha-ra‘, but would be well acquainted with the popular apocalyptic literature : and would therefore be likely, in the absence of direct Dominical instruction to the contrary, to take the pseud- epigraphic theory of a Fall and Original Sin for granted, either in its ‘ angelic’ or its ‘ Adamic’ form. (bo) That our Lord, in accordance with His policy of assuming current Jewish theology wherever possible, tacitly acquiesced in this, and left His followers to decide for them- selves between the Fall-stories of Gen. iii. and Gen. vi. (c) That at first the Watcher-story enjoyed some popularity in Jewish-Christian circles: but that St. Paul’s PAGE 93 SYNOPSIS OF CONTENTS influence eventually dispossessed it in favour of the Adam- narrative, which thus became the official Fall-story of the whole Christian Church. If this is so, St. Paul would seem to have done Christianity a considerable service, in view of the unedifying developments of which the angel-story from its nature is capable. It is to be noted that although the Adamic theory as taught by St. Paul is mainly built upon the Biblical story, yet two passages in the Pauline corpus appear to presuppose the extra-Biblical legend of the inquinamentum (2 Cor. xi. 3 and 1 Tim. ii. 14) ; probably, however, this idea is merely used in the spirit of Philonic allegorism, to give point to practical exhortations. We now turn to the task of reconstructing the Apostle’s doctrine in detail. The /oci classici are to be found in Rom. v., Vi., Vil. ; I Cor. xv.; Gal. v. The relevant portions of these chapters imply that Adam’s sin communicated to his posterity (a) physical mortality, and (b) a condition of ‘ suppressed sinfulness,’ which is stimulated by knowledge of the Law to break out into sinful acts. The remedy for this condition is Baptism: analogies to this conception in contemporaneous paganism. St. Paul knows nothing of ‘ Original Righteous- ness’ or ‘ Original Guilt.’ The seat or nidus of the hereditary infection is the ‘ flesh,’ the ‘ body of this death,’ with its ‘ sinful passions.’ Is this conception based upon a Platonic or Oriental dualism ? But we have seen that the Fall-theory is necessarily the sworn foe of dualism. If a source other than St. Paul’s own experience must be found for the idea of the ¢dpdévnua tis capKds there is no need to go further than the yéger ha-va‘, with which the Apostle’s Rabbinical training must have made him familiar. A complete treatment of the problem of sin must endeavour to deal with the relation of evil in man to evil in Nature, orin the world outside men. Many subsequent theologians have shirked this question; but it is clear that the Apostle has faced it in his own private thoughts. Not human nature alone is permeated by Evil: the malign infection extends down- wards into the sub-human creation, which ‘ groans and travails together until now,’ and upwards into the supernatural sphere, where it inspires the hateful energies of a ‘ spirit-world at war with God,’ the malevolent ‘ world-rulers,’ ‘ principalities,’ and ‘ powers.’ For the content of these ideas St. Paul is indebted to the pre-Christian apocalyptists: but the form and the implications which he has imposed upon them are profoundly original. Summary. The doctrines which we are studying come to us on the authority of St. Paul and of the Church rather than on that of Christ: if, however, our final examination of them shows that they correspond to the facts of life, the circum- stances of their entry into Christianity will constitute no argument against them, and we shall be at liberty to conclude that, whilst not strictly Dominical themselves, they are never- theless implicit in the Dominical teaching as to the universal Xvi SYNOPSIS OF CONTENTS need of redemption. Though it gathers into a single system the ideas loosely scattered throughout the pre-Christian apocalyptists, the Apostle’s doctrine is yet somewhat vague and elastic, and therefore much more reasonable than some of the more rigid products of later theology. Despite a few rhetorical turns of phrase, no trace is to be found in his Epistles of the impossible paradox that we are morally culpable for possessing instincts which we cannot help possessing. Apart from the synthetic work just mentioned, and the final expul- sion of the Watcher-story, the most permanently significant of the Apostle’s contributions to the growth of the Fall- doctrine are (a) the close connexion established, or pointed out, by him between Original Sin and Baptism, and (b) his great conception of the unitary nature of Evil as pervading the three planes of life, sub-human, human, and superhuman, with its corollary of a final redemption embracing the whole realm of animate and created being. LECTURE IV.—THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH OF THE FIRST FOUR CENTURIES ’ : The Pauline teaching sketched in Lecture III was bound, when reflected upon, to raise certain great issues which have dominated the subsequent history of these doctrines. These issues are : ; (i) Is the Adam-story historic truth or allegory ? (ii) What was man’s unfallen condition—non-moral innocence, or ‘ Original Righteousness’ ? (iii) What exactly is the undesirable thing, state, or quality alleged to have been communicated by the first man to his descendants ? (iv) What was the mode of this donimini Cane physiological or merely social heredity, mystical or physical identity ? (v) What is the resulting state of human nature, with which Redemption now has to deal ? It must therefore be expected that the task of fixing the outlines of the really ‘ Catholic’ or universal doctrine will become more complicated as our research moves down the centuries. In order to determine what precisely has been believed ubique, semper, et ab omnibus, we shall have to enquire, not merely whether the Fall-doctrine was or was not held by the Christian Church during a given period, but also (if we decide that it was) what answers were returned to these crucial questions during the epoch under discussion. As these ideas are ultimately based upon religious experience, we shall find that the opinions held with regard to these five issues tend to group and combine themselves into two well- defined versions of the Fall-theory, corresponding to the ‘ once-born ’ and ‘ twice-born’ types of religious temperament. PAGE 165 SYNOPSIS OF CONTENTS XVil The more or less straightforward path followed by the evolution of the Christian Fall-doctrine after the Apostolic age is sharply bisected by the figure of Augustine, which stands as it were on the watershed between classical antiquity and the Middle Ages. The remainder, therefore, of our historical survey falls naturally into three sections, concerned respec- tively with Christian opinion before Augustine, with the teaching of Augustine himself, and with the subsequent Western developments of Augustinianism. The first of these sections, to which this morning’s lecture will be devoted, will be of peculiar importance for the task of settling what really has been believed ‘ everywhere, always, and by all,’ inasmuch as in the primitive, pre-Augustinian Church we may reason- ably expect to find nothing but the fundamental thought of historic Christianity on this subject, free from the ‘ personal equation ’ introduced by Augustine’s powerful individuality. Only two, exceedingly faint and doubtful, traces of these ideas are to be found in the ‘ Apostolic Fathers’; the Apologists are more explicit, but their teaching is ambiguous and confused. The first appearance within Christianity of the conception of ‘ Original Righteousness,’ and of the suggestion, destined to be elaborated by Duns Scotus, that the inherited infirmity consists in the lack of the supernatural endowments ofthe firstman. It would seem that, whilst St. Paul’s teaching was accepted, in a vague and general manner, by the Christian world, at least from the time of the canonisation of the Pauline corpus onwards, it was held very much in the background of the Church’s mind during the first post-Apostolic century : and that the hypothesis of a multitude of personal demons attacking the soul from without possessed much more vivid reality for the earliest Christians, as the explanation of evil suggestions, than the more abstract idea of a hereditary bias influencing it from within. The ideas of the Fall and of Original Sin emerged from this temporary eclipse as the result of the impact of Gnosticism upon the Church. Under the banners of this syncretistic movement, the two ancient foes of Jewish-Christian mono- theism—Hindu monism and Iranian dualism—once more advanced to the assault ; and, as in the Maccabean period, the Fall-theory was brought out of the Church’s armoury as the tried shield against any theories which imply the eternity or necessity of evil. The first systematic consideration of the subject is found in Irenaeus; the surprising modernity and reasonableness of his views on some of the five crucial issues. With the two greatest anti-Gnostic champions of the following century—Origen in the East and Tertullian in the West—the two classical types of Fall-doctrine begin to dis-¢” tinguish themselves. Some care must therefore be devoted | to the examination of these writers. Origen will naturally be considered first, as standing more directly in the succession of the earliest Greek-Christian thought. Origen’s two periods—the Alexandrine and the Caesarean. In the former, following the lead of Clement, he allegorises XVlil SYNOPSIS OF CONTENTS Gen. iii., in accordance with the exegetical methods traditional at Alexandria, reading into it the theory, borrowed from Plato’s Phaedrus, of a pre-natal fall of individual souls. ‘ Original Righteousness’ is thus affirmed, but referred to a transcendent and extra-temporal mode of existence, whilst ‘ Original Sin’ becomes a weakness rather than a disease, a ook privatio rather than a depravatio. In the latter, he takes a more gloomy view of ‘ Original Sin’ as a positive, quasi-physical pollution, to which, in some inexplicable way, guzli attaches; here the conception of ‘ Original Guilt’ creeps in by the side of ‘ Original Sin.’ This change of view is probably due to the fact that at Caesarea he became acquainted for the first time with the practice of Infant Baptism, which seemed to necessitate some doctrine of inborn depravity or guilt. He also shows signs of reverting to a more literalistic exegesis of Gen. iii., and, for the time, abandons the theory of individual pre-natal falls for that of a collective Fall of humanity in Adam. But in both periods alike he remains convinced that ‘ Paradise’ belongs not to the material but to the supersensible world. This is an idea which may prove fruitful in suggestions when we approach the constructive part of our task. The place of Tertullian in history as the father of Western and Latin theology, and the precursor of Augustine. The general texture and quality of his mind was unphilosophical, legalistic, materialistic. He is not prepared to predicate of unfallen human nature more than ‘integrity’ (which does not amount to ‘ Original Righteousness’) ; but he adheres to a rigidly literal interpretation of Gen. iii. The fundamental element in his presentation of the Fall-doctrine is the belief in the corporeity of the soul: from this is derived the ‘ Traducianist ’’ view of the propagation of souls, on which a crude form of the theory of ‘ seminal identity’ is based. It is strongly asserted that ‘ Original Sin’ is a positive corruption and not a mere infirmity: but there is no idea of ‘ Original Guilt,’ as Tertullian, unlike Origen, objects to the practice of Infant Baptism. The two types of Fall-doctrine destined to be characteristic of Eastern and Western Christendom—that which starts from the conception of ‘ Original Sin’ as a privatio and that which regards it as a depravatio—thus emerge in the writings of these two great third-century teachers. Further develop- ments in the East (Methodius, Athanasius, and the Cappa- docians) and in the West (Cyprian, Ambrose, Ambrosiaster— the two latter approximating to the full Augustinian doctrine) briefly summarised. Summary. From the evidence adduced it may be reason- ably concluded that the Fall-doctrine was very generally assumed in the Church of the first four centuries, on the authority of the Old Testament as interpreted by St. Paul. But it was not the centre of much discussion or interest; the demon-theory bulked more largely in the imagination of the ordinary Christian. Nor, in view of the fluidity of Christian SYNOPSIS OF CONTENTS XIX PAGE thought at this epoch, can it be said to have been strictly de fide. It was not embodied in the baptismal Creeds, or regarded as part of the Gospel or the ‘ deposit of Faith’; it was viewed rather as part of the prolegomena to the Gospel, taken over from Judaism. The sense in which the Fall- doctrine may be said to have enjoyed this vague general acceptance does not go beyond the simple teaching of St. Paul and, perhaps, of Irenaeus ; this view, which regards the Fall as a praevaricatio rather than a lapsus, and ‘ Original Sin’ as a weakness rather than an offence or pollution, is not uncongenial to the ‘ once-born’ type of religious experience and the sunny genius of Christian Hellenism. But the more gloomy and fanatical temperament of Northern Africa was already in search of a severer theory, appropriate to the “twice-born’ mode of feeling. The Augustinian version, which has dominated the West so completely that it is still thought by many to be the only Fall-doctrine, had not yet been constructed : but the materials for it were being accumulated. LECTURE V.—THE ‘ TWICE-BORN’ VERSION OF THE FALL-DOCTRINE FULLY DEVELOPED—AUGUSTINIAN- ISM : ; : 4 : ‘ : O15 Christian Doctrine, in its ‘ orthodox’ or ‘ historical’ presentation, is now conventionally divided into five great sections—the doctrine of the Trinity, of the Incarnation or the Person of Christ, of Grace or the Work of Christ, of the Church, and of the Sacraments. But in the primitive Church of the first four centuries, which claimed our attention in Lecture IV, Christian doctrine, so far as it had been formulated, consisted only of the first two of these sections—the doctrines of God and of Christ. Broadly speaking, the Church and the Sacraments were taken for granted as facts, and used rather than speculated about: and the problems which come under the head of the ‘ doctrine of Grace ’—Sin, Atonement, Justification—received only cursory attention, nor were any specific opinions in regard to them treated as de fide or insisted on as terms of communion. The Fall-doctrine in particular, though enjoying a vague general acceptance, was not thought of as part of ‘ the Gospel,’ and was largely obscured by the demonic theory. We have now to consider how ‘ the doctrine of Grace,’ carrying a rigidly systematised and ‘ twice-born’ version of the Fall-theory embedded in it, came to be added to the doctrines of God and of Christ as a third great section of the Christian intellectual scheme, as that scheme was con- ceived in the Western Church. This enlargement of the area of authoritative dogma was mainly due to the teaching and influence of St. Augustine. As the Fall-doctrine is based upon spiritual experience, it is desirable, at each crucial moment in its development, to examine the lives and temperaments of its greatest exponents, XX SYNOPSIS OF CONTENTS in order to lay bare the causes which have moulded their characteristic presentations of it. A brief review of Augustine’s earlier life discloses three main factors which naturally disposed him towards the sterner and more rigorous type of Fall-theory: (1) his own passionate, introspective, and ‘ twice-born’ genius, which had been deeply marked by the convulsions of sin, remorse, and instantaneous conversion ; (2) his contact with Persian dualism, the traditional foe of Jewish-Christian monotheism, in its Manichean form, which affected him first by attraction and then by repulsion ; (3) the tradition and temper of the North African Church, which made him heir to the more gloomy view of ‘ Original Sin’ first adumbrated by Tertullian. Augustine’s doctrine, which is the finished and classical expression of the ‘ twice-born’ view, took shape in his mind during the first ten years of his Christian and monastic life, as the result of his reaction from Manicheism, long before he had so much as heard of Pelagius. Its main points— “seminal identity,’ ‘ original guilt,’ ‘ original sin’ viewed as a depravation and not as a mere privation, the intrinsically evil nature of ‘ concupiscence,’ and the idea of fallen humanity as a massa peccati—appear in the treatise ad Simplicianum, as early as the year 397. Meanwhile, by a remarkable chance—or providence—the ‘once-born,’ strongly ethical type of religious temperament found a powerful representative in another monk, the Irishman Pelagius, whose evangelistic methods presupposed an absolute indeterminism and an optimistic view of human nature, which was eventually worked out by himself and his friends, Caelestius and Julian of Eclanum, into an explicit doctrine of man and of sin now known as ‘ Pelagianism.’ Down to the end of the fourth century the two monks, the Briton and the African, typifying and inculcating respectively the extremest forms of the ‘ once-born’ and ‘ twice-born’ views of sin and redemption, were unknown to each other; but the stage was being set for the great conflict between these two theories, which has not even yet come to a final decision. It will be convenient here to sketch the main principles of Pelagianism. It was not a ‘formal’ heresy—nor, at the date of its first appearance, was it a ‘ material’ heresy, as no officially defined Fall-doctrine was yet in being. It was rather an attempt to provide a rationalised, non-mystical explanation of the Scriptural texts relating to Adam’s trans- gression and the entrance of sin into the world. It started from the fundamental Christian idea of God as infinitely good, and from this deduced the immutable goodness of human nature. Hence Adam’s sin only injured himself directly, though it may be said to have injured his posterity indirectly in so far as it provided a bad example for their imitation. There is no physical propagation of any undesirable state or quality, not even of a privatio or weakness ; every individual represents at his birth a fresh start in the moral history of the SYNOPSIS OF CONTENTS race, and throughout the whole of his life retains absolute free-will, entirely undetermined by habit or character. So far as there is any transmission of evil from one generation to the next, it is merely through ‘social heredity,’ bad examples, customs, laws, and the like. Infant baptism confers positive graces, but not ‘ remission of sins,’ as infants have ex hypothesi no sins or sinfulness to be remitted; and the eschatological aspect of the problem, which now for the first time emerges in the question, ‘ What is the fate, after death, of those who die unbaptised ? ’ is dealt with, so far as infants are concerned, by the hypothesis of Limbo. The history of the Pelagian controversy summarised. The North African bishops, headed by Augustine, succeeded in forcing the stiff, ‘ twice-born ’ doctrine upon the West ; but their triumph was largely due to the secular arm of the Roman Government, and did not extend to the East, where the Pelagians found a natural ally in Theodore of Mopsuestia. Eventually the remnants of Pelagianism were involved in the downfall of Nestorianism ; but Canons 1 and 4 of Ephesus, which represent the only approach to a conciliar definition of oecumenical authority on this subject, noticeably abstain from an affirmation of Augustinianism, and content themselves with a cautious condemnation of Caelestius. A critique of Pelagianism. Whatever we may think of the methods employed to suppress Pelagianism, its disappearance was, on the whole, a blessing for Christianity. Though some of its positions are infinitely more reasonable and humane than the corresponding Augustinian tenets, it must yet be remembered that its vicious doctrine of unlimited indeter- minism abolished the essence of true religion by abolishing man’s feeling of dependence on God, and, by exaggerating every venial fault into a conscious mortal sin, turned Christianity into a joyless and legalistic Puritanism. This blessing was, however, dearly purchased by the triumph of Augustinianism. We must now examine this system in detail, as fully developed in St. Augustine’s anti- Pelagian writings. As in the case of the pre-Augustinian Fathers, our method will be that of considering St. Augustine’s answers to the ‘ five crucial questions’ defined in Lecture IV as naturally arising out of the Pauline doctrine. (i) The literal or allegorical interpretation of Gen. 111. After a momentary hesitation, Augustine decides for the former. (ii) Man’s unfallen state. The Rabbinical idea of ‘Original Righteousness’ is carried to the highest pitch, in order to intensify the heinousness of the Fall; Adam, unfallen, is canonised as the ideal athlete, philosopher, and saint. (iii) The exact nature of the disastrous legacy of the Fall. Augustine is the first to distinguish clearly between the vitium and the veatus of ‘ Original Sin ’"—in other words, XX1 XXIl SYNOPSIS OF CONTENTS between ‘ original sin’ as a psychological fact and ‘ original guilt ’ as a forensic status. Of these: (a) The vitiumconsists in ‘concupiscence,’ which is trans- mitted in and through parentage, and is in itself evil. (b) The reatus consists in legal responsibility for Adam’s transgression, based on the theory of “seminal identity.’ (iv) The mode of transmission. As will be seen from (iii) (a) and (b), Augustine alternates between ‘heredity’ and identity. He never makes up his mind as between ‘ Creationism ’ and ‘ Traducianism.’ (v) The resulting state of human nature. Mankind is a massa perditionis; but Augustine’s Platonism, for which all being, in so far as it is true being, is good, arrests him just short of the Calvinistic doctrine of total depravity, and mercifully blunts the edge of the antithesis between ‘nature’ and ‘ grace.’ Man was deprived of ‘ freedom’ by the Fall, but still possesses ‘ free-will’—an elusive and probably meaningless distinction. To these we must add : (vi) The eschatological issue, first brought out by the Pelagian controversy, ‘ What happens after death to those who die in original sin only, without having committed actual sin?’ Augustine has no hesitation in consigning this whole class, including unbaptised infants, to everlasting flames. A brief critique of the Augustinian doctrine. Its key- conceptions are three—Original Righteousness, Original Sin, and Original Guilt. As we have previously suggested, the first and third of these are intellectually indefensible, at any rate as Augustine phrased them and as they are embodied in the Western post-Augustinian systems: and his presenta- tion of the second seems strongly coloured by his early Manicheism. If, then, it were true, as is often assumed, that ‘ the Catholic doctrine’ of the Fall and of Original Sin is identical with the Augustinian doctrine, Catholic Christianity would indeed bein evil plight. But we have seen that Ephesus abstained from affirming Augustinianism; and no other Oecumenical Council has dealt with the matter. Augustini- anism cannot in any case claim to satisfy the test of semper ; but it will be well, for the sake of completeness, to enquire whether there was ever a time when it was accepted ubique et ab omnibus. This last question must, it would seem, be answered in the negative. The Christian East has never accepted the Augustinian version of the Fall-doctrine ; the Greek-speaking Church of the eighth century, as represented by St. John of Damascus, seems to leave the whole question shrouded in ‘reverential vagueness.’ We therefore conclude that ortho- dox Christians as such are in no way committed to the Augustinian position; and that the Church of the future is likely to look to the Greek tradition, which expresses the “once-born’ type of religious experience as its guide and SYNOPSIS OF CONTENTS Xxiil PAGE norm in this matter, though in any complete ‘ re-statement ’ of the Fall-doctrine room must be found for an expression of the permanent values disclosed by the rarer ‘ twice-born ’ type. ADDITIONAL NoTE B.—CANONS OF THE CARTHAGINIAN COUNCIL OF A.D. 418 : : : : ; Ok LECTURE VI.—THE TRIUMPH AND DECLINE OF THE AUGUSTINIAN DOCTRINE . i : ‘ 393 It was shown in Lecture V that the Augustinian version of the Fall-theory, never having been adopted by Eastern Christendom, does not satisfy the criterion of acceptance ubique, semper, et ab omnibus, and cannot therefore be described as ‘ the ecclesiastical doctrine’ or ‘ the doctrine of the Christian Church as a whole.’ It might, however, be urged that the non-acceptance of the Augustinian teaching by the East does not necessarily invalidate its claim to be ‘the Christian doctrine,’ inasmuch as the intellectual life of the Eastern Church was (not exclusively through its own fault) compara- tively stationary from the time of the Great Schism down to the nineteenth century; and that it is unfair to dismiss a theory which has so deeply affected the religious life of Western Europe, both in mediaeval and modern times, without having considered the developments which it received at the hands of some of the greatest Christian thinkers since the Patristic age, both Schoolmen and Reformers. Wedo not wish to argue the question of the true meaning of omnes, or to assume (for the purpose of these Lectures) any particular view as to the extent of ‘ the Church’; our desire is to arrive at conclusions which will possess as much objectivity and breadth of appeal as possible. We will therefore meet the hypothetical objector on his own ground, and examine the post-Augustinian history of Fall-speculation in Western Christendom, in order to decide whether or not, within this restricted sphere, the classical “twice-born’ theory can reasonably claim acceptance ab omnibus, and in the hope that this part of our historical survey may provide suggestions which may be of use in the con- structive part of our task. We need not consider the Semi-Pelagian controversy, which was concerned rather with the operations of ‘ grace’ than with the nature of the Fall: it is to be noted, however, that the second Council of Orange (A.D. 529), which brought this controversy to an end, contents itself with affirming a modified Augustinianism, which only predicates ‘ integrity’ of unfallen man, abstains from affirming ‘ Original Guilt,’ and asserts that whilst free-will was weakened by the Fall it was not destroyed. Little of interest is to be gleaned from the ‘ Dark Ages.’ Augustine continues to dominate the West down to the beginning of the scholastic epoch, though Anselm XXIV SYNOPSIS OF CONTENTS revives the idea that ‘ original sin’ consists mainly in the lack of ‘ original righteousness,’ and Abaelard repudiates ‘ original guilt.’ The history of mediaeval thought on this subject is the history of the gradual decline of the Augustinian view. This decline manifested itself in two forms, associated respectively with the Dominican and the Franciscan theologies, which must be separately explained. The Order of Friars Preachers was born in Provence, in the midst of the struggle between Catholicism and the Albi- genses or Catharists, who represented a recrudescence of Manicheism. In accordance, it would seem, with a law already noticed, that the invasion of Christendom by Oriental dualism stimulates in the Church a revival of interest in, and a tendency to intensify, the Fall-doctrine, Dominican thought was naturally inclined towards the strict Augustinian teach- ing. But, all unconsciously, it was constrained to modify Augustinianism in order to preserve it. The teaching of St. Thomas Aquinas may be taken as representative, and briefly summarised: as before, we arrange it under the heads of the * crucial issues ’ implicit in the Fall-doctrine. The Thomist position. (i) Man’s unfallen state. The Augustinian antithesis between ‘ nature’ and ‘ grace’ reappears as a metaphysical distinction between the natural and the supernatural orders. Hence the distinction between the donum super- naturale of ‘ Original Righteousness’ and man’s pura natuvalia is emphasised and sharpened. (ii) The nature of ‘ Original Sin’ The Fall was a fall from the supernatural to the merely natural plane. It follows that ‘ Original Sin’ consists in ‘ the lack of original righteousness,’ and, logically, the pura naturalia should be regarded as remaining unimpaired. St. Thomas, however, feels obliged to retain the Augustinian idea of ‘ concu- piscence’ as essentially evil, and hence he affirms that “ concupiscence’ constitutes the matter, and the ‘ defect of Original Righteousness’ the form, of Original Sin. Original Sin involves guilt. But baptism annuls the guilt of con- cupiscence, and leaves it as a morally neutral fomes peccati— an important modification of the Augustinian view. (iii) The mode of its transmission. The conception of “seminal identity’ is translated into terms of motion; Adam becomes an ethical primum mobile who ‘ moves’ his descendants towards sin by begetting them. (iv) The resultant state of human nature. The Augus- tinian position is, if anything, emphasised; freewill is verbally affirmed and constructively denied. (v) The eschatological corollaries of Original Sin. Augustine’s condemnation of the unbaptised to eternal torments is tacitly dropped, and the more merciful con- ception of Limbo substituted; this idea receives poetic consecration from Dante, Inferno, Cant.iv. Here we have SYNOPSIS OF CONTENTS a significant symptom of a tendency to revert to the earlier view of ‘ Original Sin’ as a privatio rather than a depravatio. The Franciscan position embodies a more definite and decided revolt against Augustinianism, and shows a tendency to return to the ‘ once-born’ view: of this, Duns Scotus may be taken as the typical representative. His characteristic opinions may be summed up as follows : (i) ‘ Original Righteousness’ was a provisional state, which would have been progressively confined by resistance to temptations ; this idea points in the direction of a return to the more primitive conception of the first man as un- developed. This involves a milder view of the Fall, of which the malice is expressly declared not to have been infinite. (ii) Hence ‘ Original Sin’ is a mere privatio consisting solely in the lack of ‘ Original Righteousness,’ and con- cupiscence is not sin at allin any sense. Scotus, however, cannot shake himself so far free from Augustinianism as to take the obvious next step of denying that this lack of * Original Righteousness’ involves guilt. (iii) Man, even as fallen, possesses full freedom of the will; and a position as to the necessity of ‘ prevenient grace’ is taken up which approximates to Semi-Pelagianism. (iv) Limbo is conceived as a state not merely of no pain but of positive pleasure. Closely connected with this minimising version of the Fall-doctrine are (a) the Scotist view of the Incarnation, which holds that the Son of God would have in any case assumed flesh, even if man had never fallen, and (db) the belief in the exemption of Mary from Original Sin—a belief which becomes the easier of acceptance the less ‘ Original Sin’ is made to mean. The allegiance of mediaeval thinkers was thus, broadly speaking, divided between the modified Augustinianism of St. Thomas and the almost anti-Augustinian view of Scotus. ? It will be convenient to complete the history of the subject so far as the Latin Church is concerned, before considering the views of the Reformers. The decisions of the Council of Trent represent a compromise between the modified Augus- tinianism, championed by the Dominicans, and the minimising view which the Jesuits had inherited from the Franciscans— a compromise which was strongly in favour of the latter. The subsequent condemnations of Baius and Jansen emphasised the anti-Augustinian direction of Roman thought on this subject, and the present Fall-doctrine of the Roman Church } would appear to be largely Scotist, with the Augustinian idea of | ‘Original Guilt ’ inconsistently adhering to it; the triumph} of Scotism was consummated by the definition of the} Immaculate Conception in 1854. The history of the Augustinian Fall-doctrine within Latin Christianity from Anselm to the present day might thus, on the whole, be graphically represented by a steadily descending curve. At the Reformation, however, and in the parts of XXV XXV1 SYNOPSIS OF CONTENTS Christendom affected by it, the curve of Augustinian influence suddenly soared up into a peak. Luther and Calvin were responsible for an ultra-Augustinian doctrine of Man and Sin, which is still popularly supposed to be the orthodox Christian view, which was the basis of some of the more unlovely aspects of Puritanism, and against which the conscience of England and America has now largely revolted. Reasons for the embodiment in Protestant theology of a rigid ‘ twice-born ’ anthropology: (1) the Reformation itself was a colossal re- \crudescence of the mystical, as opposed to the institutional, elements in St. Augustine’s thought, and therefore demanded a theory of man and sin which would make salvation ex- \clusively God’s work and eliminate human effort and merit ; (2) Luther himself, like St. Paul and St. Augustine, possessed the ‘ twice-born ’ temperament in a high degree. The Reformation made the Fall-doctrine, almost for the first time, a matter of popular and not merely of theological interest: compare many Calvinistic liturgical confessions, which require the congregation to accuse itself of ‘ original ’ as well as ‘ actual’ sin, with the Catholic Confiteor, which is a confession of actual sin only. The differences between Lutheranism and Calvinism on this subject were inconsiderable, so that it is possible to deal with the Protestant Fall-doctrine as a single body of ideas. The foundation of the Reformers’ position was the denial of the scholastic distinction between the donum supernaturale of ‘Original Righteousness’ and the pura naturalia. Adam’s supposed magnificent endowments were not conferred upon him by way of a superadded adornment, as the Schoolmen had taught, but belonged to him in right of his human nature. It follows that the Fall was a fall not from the supernatural to the natural plane (the scholastic teaching) but from the natural to a sub-natural plane. Hence the Fall was the most horrible catastrophe conceivable, and its result is to be found in the ‘total depravity’ of human nature, which the Re- formers depict in the blackest colours. All the actions of the heathen, even apparently virtuous actions, are really sins. The mere fact of the possession of ‘ concupiscence ’ is a mortal sin, apart from and prior to its actual indulgence. ‘ Original Guilt ’ is strongly affirmed, and, in the last analysis, ‘ Original Sin ’ is the only real sin that exists, all actual sins being merely epiphenomena revealing its malignant presence. It would seem, in short, that it is criminal in the sight of heaven to be born or to be a human being at all. It is hardly necessary to point out that this conception of human nature and sin rules out free-will: Luther is even more emphatic on this point than Calvin. But theism, rigid _, determinism, and the doctrine of ‘total depravity’ taken “together inevitably make God the direct author of evil; and this conclusion was accepted in set terms by Melancthon and Calvin, who thus appear to land themselves in precisely that unmoral Hindu monism which the Fall-doctrine was designed to resist—a curious revolution of the wheel of thought. SYNOPSIS OF CONTENTS XXVli PAGE The gloomy theory just described dominated Continental Protestantism for two centuries, but has now shared the fate of evangelical orthodoxy in general; the now dominant / system of Ritschlianism has no place for any kind of Fall” doctrine, Augustinian or other. The Anglican Articles were doubtless meant by their compilers to rivet a decided Augus- tinianism upon the English Church: but this interpretation was Challenged by Jeremy Taylor in the seventeenth century and Bishop Porteous in the eighteenth: and it would seem that the relaxation of the terms of subscription in 1865 has set the English Church free to handle the matter afresh. If we set these facts side by side with the largely non-Augustinian character of the present Roman Catholic Fall-doctrine, it will be seen that the classical expression of the ‘twice-born’ view has now all but disappeared from Christian thought, and therefore fails to satisfy the Vincentian canon, even within the restricted area of Western Christendom. ADDITIONAL NOTE C.—CONGREGATIONAL CONFESSIONS OF ORIGINAL SIN IN THE CHURCHES OF THE REFORMATION 443 LECTURE VII.—‘ ORIGINAL SIN’ RE-INTERPRETED . 447 As a result of the extended historical survey contained in the last six lectures, we are now in a position to attempt a definition of the ‘Catholic’ doctrine of the Fall and of Original Sin—understanding by the term ‘the Catholic doctrine ’ (as previously explained) the irreducible minimum of Fall-doctrine which has been disclosed by our examination of the history of Christian doctrine. This may be expressed in the form of seven propositions, as follows : (i) God is infinitely good, and therefore the world as He made it must have been purely good, including no element of evil at all. (We note that the idea of Creation is here presupposed.) (ii) The origin of evil is therefore to be sought in the voluntary vebellion of some finite and created will or wills, such rebellion having taken place prior to the appearance of the human species on this planet. (The ultimate ‘ Fall’ may, therefore, be conceived either in accordance with Origen’s suggestion of a pre- natal fall of individual souls, or as a pre-cosmic ‘ fall of the angels,’ such as was inferred by an uncritical exegesis from Rev. xii. 7 ff—the passage about the war between Michael and the ‘ dragon.’) (iii) Man, at his first entry into this world, was in moral and intellectual stature a babe, created frail, imperfect, ignorant, and non-moral, but endowed with self-consciousness and the power of self-determination, which constituted his starting-point for progress and upward evolution. XXVIl1 SYNOPSIS OF CONTENTS (The ‘irreducible residuum’ does not contain the Rabbinical and non-Scriptural idea of ‘ Original Righteousness,’ the abandonment of which abolishes the apparent conflict between the Fall-doctrine and the evolutionary view of human history.) (iv) The growth of man’s moral ideas brought in its train some action whereby man aligned himself with the revolting power, partially identified himself with the forces of Evil, and entered upon a path largely divergent from that straight upward voad which God had meant him to follow. (In other words, the first sin was not so much a‘ Fall’ as a failure to climb, or, more exactly, to climb as directly and perpendicularly as God desired. It will therefore be well to avoid using the term ‘ Fall’ with reference to the first human sin, and to keep it for designating the ultimate pre-cosmic revolt, whatever that may have been. The term ‘ Fall,’ again, is non-Biblical.) (v) Ever since this first transgression, human nature has displayed an inherent moral weakness or bias towards sin. (It is to be noted that this proposition abstains from asserting that the first transgression was the cause of the innate bias towards evil.) (vi) This innate bias or tendency towards evil is the effect and symptom of ‘ weakness of will,’ or defective control of the lower emotional and instinctive nature by the higher self. (We have already seen, in Lectures V and VI, that Catholic or universal acceptance cannot be claimed for the specifically Augustinian or Western ideas of ‘ seminal identity,’ ‘ Original Guilt,’ and the intrinsic sinfulness of “concupiscence’; all these ideas, consequently, go by the board. And the term ‘ Original Sin’ itself is non- Biblical, and inextricably associated with the idea of ‘Original Guilt’; we shall therefore avoid it for the future, and use instead the term ‘ inherited infirmity.’) (vii) This quality of ‘ weakness of will’ inheres in the human stock as a hereditary character transmitted from parent to offspring through biological and not merely through social heredity, Two corollaries which seem to follow from this general position should be mentioned: (a) the ‘inherited infirmity,’ being inherited and not wilful, cannot be thought of as deserving God’s ‘wrath’; (b) thereis much to be said for the Pelagian and scholastic conception of Limbo—the Augus- tinian idea that unbaptised infants deserve hell is in any case intolerable. Of these seven propositions, the first five deal with what is generally known as the ‘ Fall,’ and the last two with ‘ Original Sin,’ so called. But we have seen that the former idea was historically, and always must be, an inference from the latter. To-day, therefore, we will restrict ourselves to the task of deciding whether the ‘inherited infirmity’ is a psychological | reality or not, leaving more metaphysical questions as to the : origin of sin for our final lecture. SYNOPSIS OF CONTENTS What is meant by the statement that the will is ‘ weak’ ? This assertion is meaningless if the will enjoys unlimited freedom, and equally meaningless if it is absolutely determined. ‘Weakness’ must therefore imply the conception of ‘ partial determinism ’—or ‘ partial indeterminism,’ which comes to the same thing. This conception is intelligible enough; the only question is whether it is true or not. To decide this, we must examine the structure and working of human personality in the light of recent knowledge. An apology should doubt- less precede any fresh discussion of the world-old problem of ‘ free-will’ ; it may, however, be possible to speak, nove, non noua. We proceed to sketch, in summary form, that picture of the soul which recent psychology has built up, making free use of symbol and metaphor. (a2) The three areas of the soul—generally spoken of as ‘though they were three storeys in a building—the conscious, preconscious, and unconscious. The preconscious contains the ‘sentiments’ or ‘complexes,’ conglomerates of ideas and images which are charged with psychic energy and toned with feeling. The unconscious is largely unexplored, but may contain ‘ complexes’ which have been ‘ repressed ’ owing to their incompatibility with the dominant purposive organisation of the soul. (o) The instincts : these are paths or channels conducting the energy of the soul from its obscure source in the uncon- scious, either directly into action or into the ‘ complexes’ where it is stored until evoked by the appropriate stimulus. Whatever the correct number and classification of the primary instincts may be, there are three of special import- ance and power—those connected with the maintenance and assertion of the self, with sex, and with the ‘herd’; and the corresponding ‘ complexes’ constitute the chief springs of human action. The main outlines of this structure are universally admitted to be fixed by heredity ; if, therefore, there is such a thing as the ‘inherited infirmity ’ assumed by traditional theology, it should be discoverable somewhere in this framework. But the alleged ‘infirmity’ has to do with moral action; we must therefore scrutinise the ‘moral sentiment’ with some care. This is built upon the ‘herd-complex’; but two cautions must be borne in mind during our further investigation : (i) we are not now concerned with the question of hereditary criminality : this is a ‘ varietal character,’ and the ‘ infirmity ’ postulated by theology is generic and universal ; (ii) the same individual may belong to many ‘ herds’ and so possess many herd-complexes : the only herd-complex which interests us is that which centres in the idea of ‘human society.’ Inspection shows us that this is normally far weaker than either the ego— or the sex-complex; we therefore identify the ‘ inherited infirmity ’ of theology with ‘ inherited weakness of herd-complex.’ This is the privatio, revealed by the ‘ once-born’ type of religious experience, and exaggerated by the ‘ twice-born ’ type XX1X XXX SYNOPSIS OF CONTENTS PAGE into a positive depravatio; it does not, strictly speaking, amount to a tendency towards ‘sin’ as such, but rather to a tendency, experienced under al/ circumstances, towards action which under given circumstances is sin. But this negative conception of the ‘ inherited infirmity ’ implies no extenuation of the melancholy results to which it leads. The existence of a hereditary condition which tends to the indulgence of self-regarding and sensual impulses in despite of ‘conscience’ or the ‘moral sentiment’ would thus seem to have been verified. But this line of thought, if followed out consistently, proves too much for our purposes: for it lands us, not in ‘ partial determinism,’ but in a determinism just as ‘absolute’ as that which results from the older mechanistic view of the mind. In the preceding description of the vationale of conation and action, hardly anything was said about the conscious ego, which occupies—or rather is—the uppermost storey of the house of personality; and modern psychology, especially of the medical type, is largely epi- phenomenalistic, regarding the feeling of effort and struggle as an illusion, and consciousness as the passive mirror of events which it has had no share in causing. If we acquiesce in this tendency to ignore the conscious ego as a real factor in the causation of conduct, we shall have failed to vindicate what our historical survey has taught us to regard as the basic Christian doctrine of human nature; Augustinianism, having been driven from the field of theology by means of the Vincentian canon, will have returned in triumph with the assistance of Freud. The situation in regard to the question as to whether a true spontaneous causality, acting within limits fixed by heredity and environment, can be ascribed to the ego or not, has not essentially altered since Kant. Determinism is the necessary methodological postulate of science; but freedom is the no less necessary assumption of moral education, and, it may be added, of psycho-therapeutic practice as distinct from theory. Wedo not pretend to be able to solve a problem which is probably insoluble; but we may point out that determinism is only necessary to a psychology which studies the mind objectively and ab extra, whilst the consciousness of ability to exert or not to exert effort is, from the subjective and introspective point of view, a datum of immediate experi- ence. The doctrine of ‘ partial determinism,’ which, whilst admitting that conduct is the result of the interplay of stimulus, complex, and instinct, nevertheless claims that consciousness has, within limits, a real power of guiding the flow of psychic energy into this complex rather than that, and of gradually modifying the contents of the preconscious and unconscious by voluntary ‘sublimation,’ would seem to be the only one which does justice both to man’s moral and to his intellectual experience. ADDITIONAL Note D.—ORIGINAL SIN, ESCHATOLOGY, AND FOREIGN MISSIONS . ‘ : : ‘ 2 - 486 SYNOPSIS OF CONTENTS LEcTURE VIII.—THE ULTIMATE ‘ FALL’ : : We have seen that the belief in a ‘ Fall’ is now, and— despite the quasi-historical facade which has clung to it for twenty centuries—always has been, an inference from the fact of man’s ‘inherited infirmity,’ when considered in the light of the belief in the infinite goodness of his Creator: it is not a premise given by history. The doctrine of the Fall is logically dependent on the doctrine of ‘ Original Sin’ (so called), and not vice versa; it is a pinnacle, not a foundation, of the Faith. It follows that Catholic Christianity as such is committed to no more than the bare assertion that there was a Fall—that is, a primal rebellion of a created will againsty/ God; any attempts to fix the exact nature of this event belong to the realm of speculation. But, though this antece- dently contingent catastrophe, which our monotheistic belief and the fact of the ‘inherited infirmity,’ taken together, compel us to postulate, lies far back beyond the beginnings of recorded history, it may be possible to arrive at some dim conception of its nature by a Method of Residues, ruling out various hypotheses which appear to be inconsistent either with scientifically ascertained facts or with our fundamental axiom, which is the reality of the God revealed in the Bible and through Christ. When we have had occasion to mention the ‘ Fall’ hitherto, we have spoken of it as though it were an event in time, capable, if we only had the requisite knowledge, of being dated in a given year B.c. But a priovt reasoning, when applied to the reconstruction of past events in time, lies under a not undeserved suspicion. And as we have no evidence for a Fall other than what can be derived from a priori reasoning, it is natural to enquire in the first instance whether a temporal conception of the Fall is rigorously necessitated by our two premises, the goodness of God and the sinfulness of men. ., May it not be easier to conceive the Fall as an extra-temporal ' fact, the transcendental ‘ ground,’ rather than the historical ; ‘cause,’ of the ‘inherited infirmity ’ and of all other forms of concrete evil ? The simplest method of answering this question will be to examine the two classical attempts which have been made to lift the Fall out of the time-series—those associated with the names of Kant and Hegel. If these philosophic giants have failed to accomplish this feat, we may reasonably conclude that it is in the nature of things impossible. Kant’s discussion of the idea of the Fall is contained in his treatise, Die Religion innerhalb der Grenzen der blossen Vernunft. The empirical universality of evil is admitted, though it is regarded as an inseparable accident rather than as an essential constituent of human nature. It arises out of the adoption by man of ‘law-contradicting maxims’ (geselzwidrige Maxime) as motives of action in place of the maxims dictated by the morallaw. These law-contradicting maxims are suggested by the sensual nature, which, though not evil in itself, is the XXXli SYNOPSIS OF CONTENTS source of evil in so far as it demands satisfaction regardless of moral restraints. The fact that the sensual maxims do secure universal acceptance is explained by the supposition of an ‘inclination to evil’ (Hang zum Bosen). Thisisinborn. But Kant, taking the Lutheran theology of his country for granted, assumes that moral and religious experience informs us that we are blameworthy for possessing this ‘inclination to evil’; in other words, he assumes that religion as such is committed to the idea of ‘ Original Guilt.” The inbred propensity to evil must, accordingly, be somehow traceable to our own act. But he sees the impossibility of basing the (supposed) blameworthy hereditary condition upon the theory of ‘ seminal identity ’ with Adam: in the case of each individual, there- fore, it must be traceable to the individual’s own act, and each man must be the Adam of hisown soul. But we have possessed the inborn bias to evil from the moment of birth; how or when, then, did we commit the act which produced it? To solve this difficulty the dualism set up by Kant’s general metaphysical position between the phenomenal and the noitimenal selves is invoked. The ‘phenomenal ego’ is temporal and determined, and the ‘ noitimenal ego ’ is timeless and free. It is, therefore, to the latter that the fundamental act of wrong choice must be assigned. The ‘ Fall’ in the case of each individual is a ‘ timeless act ’ whereby his ‘ noimenal self’ adopts the ‘ law-contradicting maxims’ as principles of ;action. Instead of a single collective Fall in time, we have a multiplicity of individual and extra-temporal falls—an idea ‘which bears some resemblance to Origen’s earlier theory of a multiplicity of pre-natal falls. This conception, when stripped of technical terminology, is open to grave objections. Strictly speaking, a ‘ timeless act’ appears to mean nothing: for an ‘act’ must involve some change, if not in the world external to the agent, at least ; in the agent himself, and change implies succession and time. But if the word ‘ act ’ really means‘ state,’ we are left with the hypothesis of an eternal and presumably necessary evil prin- ciple existing in all notimenal selves, or all selves considered as notmenal, In other words, Kant’s theory seems to be either meaningless or Manichean. Hegel’s reinterpretation of the Fall-doctrine is expounded in the Philosophie der Religion, 3. Theil (Die absolute Religion), § II (Das Reich des Sohnes). It finds the source of evilin the separateness of the individual soul from the rest of the uni- verse—in other words, in individuality and self-consciousness, From this it follows that sin is a necessary phase of the soul’s evolution, and, though undesirable in itself, is less evil than innocence. We have already met with this theory ‘in the course of our historical review ; it is nothing other than a form of that Gnosticism which stimulated the revival and development of the Fall-theory by Irenaeus in the second century. It both involves and presupposes that conception of an unmoral and impersonal Absolute which lies at the root of the religious thought of India, but is totally irreconcileable SYNOPSIS OF CONTENTS XXXiil with the conception of God characteristic of Semitic religion and of the Bible. We conclude, then, that the instinct of the Maccabean } Jews was right, and that it is impossible to lift the Fall out | of the time-series without falling either into Manicheism or unmoral monism. Whether we like it or not, so much would j appear to be certain (given our premises), namely, that ‘ the Fall,’ whatever else it may have been, must have been an event in time. We now approach a second question raised by Kant, and by Origen before him, namely this: Is it necessary to suppose a single collective Fall, or will a multiplicity of individual falls suffice? The latter would have to be con- ceived as pre-natal, inasmuch as (according to the conclusion just reached) they would have to be in time and yet outside our present phenomenal lives. This theory of pre-natal falls enjoys a certain popularity in connexion with Theosophy, and it will therefore be worth while to examine its classical presentation as embodied in Julius Miller’s ‘ Christian Doctrine of Sin.’ This examination, however, reveals two fatal objections: (1) Miiller’s theory makes heredity to be a mere illusion, produced by a mysterious pre-established harmony of the pre-existing psychic monads; (2) it assumes an intolerably pessimistic (again, almost Manichean) view of this world and of human life as lived within it. We are, therefore, driven back upon the hypothesis of a single, collective Fall in time: Coleridge’s suggestion of a Fall of the race-soul presents certain attractions. This probably represents the furthest point in our regressive quest of the origin of evil that can be reached by a priori reasoning. We must, therefore, consider if the hypothesis formulated above can be given further substance and articula- tion by the consideration of a posteriort evidence provided by the history of the world and of our species as now known to us. Such evidence would seem to make it certain that the origin of evil cannot be found in ‘ the first human sin.’ For: (i) The continuity of man’s upward evolution, both physical and psychic, from the brute, makes it very doubtful whether there ever was a single action which could be described in an absolute manner as ‘ the first sin’; instinct can only gradually have given birth to conscious self- determination, and non-moral reactions must have shaded by imperceptible degrees into moral behaviour. (ii) Even if it were possible to fix upon some act of individual or group which could be labelled with certainty as the ‘ first known sin,’ this could not be identified with ‘ the Fall’; for (a) it must have occurred far too long after the emergence of man as a distinct zoological species to have affected the whole stock; (b) such an identification would presuppose thetransmissibility of acquired characters, ahypo- thesis which is far too uncertain to be built on with safety. In any case, sin presupposes the moral sentiment, and this,’ as we have seen, is the outgrowth of ‘ herd-instinct ’ ; it | follows that the ‘ first known sin ’ would be, not the cause, but ! ~~ XXXIV SYNOPSIS OF CONTENTS ho ~ the first known effect of that deficiency in ‘ herd-instinct ’ with which we have identified the ‘ inherited infirmity ’ of theology. The Rabbis were right when they said that Adam fell because he already had the ‘ evil inclination ’ within him. The cause of evil in man would thus seem to be historically prior to man. Can we assume that the defect of ‘ herd- instinct’ was simply inherited by man from his animal ancestors ? Apparently not: there is no reason for supposing that the ‘sub-men’ were less loyal to their packs or hordes than wolves or hyenas now. The fact is that the defect of herd-instinct in man is relative to the enormous growth of self- consciousness which distinguishes him from the brutes; the corporate instinct in him has not kept pace with the increasing demands of the complex societies which his expanding intellect has created. What is wrong with man is that he has just enough ‘ herd-instinct ’ for an anthropoid, but not enough for a man; he is suffering from arrested development of ‘ herd- instinct.’ But what arrested the development ? At present we can only assume that some unknown and positively malignant factor intervened in the crisis of the birth of the race. (It must be expected that our conclusions will become less and less precise, the further we penetrate back into the tunnel of the past.) Perhaps we may gain light upon the nature and source of this positive evil factor, which seems to have been revealed as lying behind the negative defect of ‘weakness of herd- instinct,’ if we consider man’s context—that is, the rest of organic nature. Evil in sub-human nature (which mainly takes the form of ‘cruelty’ or ‘selfishness ’) is positive and not merely negative, and objective in character, not subjective (z.e. to us, looking on as spectators, it appears as that which ought not to be, but to the beasts which work it in blind obedience to instinct it doubtless appears as natural). The cat has no qualms of conscience about playing with the mouse. Nevertheless we cannot but feel that we should not have created a universe containing the cobra and the bacillus of diphtheria, had we occupied the position of Demiurge; why, then, should God have doneso? The answer can only be that He did not do so; the evil which exists in organic nature, — apparently coeval with it and worked into its very tissue, cannot be due to the all-loving Creator. Weare thus led tothe hypothesis of a pre-cosmic vitiation of the whole Life-Force, at the very beginning of cosmic evolution: this, it would seem, and not the failure of primitive man to escape from already existing evil, is the true and ultimate ‘ Fall.’ Such a view of the Fall and its effects is much vaster and more awe-inspiring than that which makes it a purely human affair; and it proportionately increases the amplitude and magnificence of Redemption. To avoid both dualism and an infinite regress, we must suppose that the Life-Force corrupted itself—which means ” that we must conceive it as having been, at its creation, personal and free—a self-conscious anima mundt, like the ‘ only begotten universe-god ’ of Plato’s Timaeus. The Father of all Paar Manan SYNOPSIS OF CONTENTS XXXV PAGE things must have created this World-Soul good; but at the beginning of time, in some transcendental and incompre- hensible manner it turned away from Him and towards Self, thus staining its own essence and, perhaps, forfeiting self- consciousness, which it has only regained after aeons of myopic striving, in sporadic fragments, which are the separate minds of men. This interior perversion of its being—this orientation away from God, and in the direction of ruthless self-assertion— manifested itself in the struggle for existence, so soon as the anima mundi was able to express itself in organic forms at all ; it appears in the cruelty which ravages the animal world, in the unknown factor which hindered the due development of ‘herd-instinct ’ just when the anthropoids were becoming men, and in the mysterious outbreaks of fiendishness which we call ‘ criminality.’ The conception just outlined has some affinities with the thought of Plotinus, who makes the World-Soul the third member of his Trinity. But we diverge decisively from him in regard to two points, viz.: (i) the World-Soul for us is a created being, not an element in a part of, or a necessary emanation from, the Godhead; (ii) whereas Plotinus finds (what corresponds to) the ‘ Fall’ in the detachment of the human soul from the World-Soul, we find the Fall in the voluntary deviation of the World-Soul from conformity with the will of the Creator. Yet, though we cannot identify the created anima mundi with the eternal Logos of God, Who is the “express image of His substance,’ we must recognise an intimate; relation between the Life-Force of the universe and the Divine Person Who ‘ upholds all things by the word of His power.’, This relation was meant to consist in the penetration, inspira- tion, and guidance of the created by the Uncreated power ;. and the rebellion of the former has not banished the patiently | working influences of the latter. Before man was, the Spirit of Christ was striving with the evil in nature: and since the} emergence of man, the Word of God has worked in saint and sage to counteract the languor of the ‘inherited infirmity,’ finally assuming flesh as one of our own race to inaugurate the final act of salvation, whereby, in the perfected Kingdom of God, not only men, but superhuman and sub-human beings, and the basic World-Soul itself, will be redeemed from the bondage of corruption into the glorious liberty of the children of God. ADDITIONAL NOTES: E.—Dr. F. R. TENNANT’S ALTERNATIVE THEORY OF THE ORIGIN OF SIN ; : ‘ : : : 530 F.—FORMULARIES 4 4 ; : ; ' ; 537 G.—INFANT BAPTISM . : 3 : : : - 550 H.—PASSAGES BEARING ON THE FALL-DOCTRINE FROM PRE-AUGUSTINIAN WRITERS NOT MENTIONED IN Lecture -LVi).*: ; : : : : : 554 INDICES: I.— REFERENCES ¢ : : : ; : : 561 II.—AUTHORS ; ; . : 4 ° : ‘ 564 III.—SvuBJECTS ; ; 7 A A ; : : 568 + age AY aie light and knowledge—light upon the mysterious source and potency of Evil, and knowledge of its own wayward nature ; and whither should it look for light and knowledge but to Religion, its ancient kindly teacher, so long neglected during the days of prosperity, yet claiming still to be its heaven- descended guide? No complete solution of the problem of Evil is attainable with our present faculties, still less a logically perfect Theodicy, or vindication of the ways of God tomen: but Religion, if it is what it claims to be, must provide us at least with an indication, sufficient for the practical purposes of life, of the direction in which the solution lies. If we study the history of Religion, we shall find in it three classical answers to the problem of Evil, which in their most typical forms are known to us as evolved by the 1 ‘Rom. vil. 24. THE BEGINNINGS OF FALL-SPECULATION 5 creative thought of three races, each corporately gifted in a singular degree with that sensitiveness to the influences of the Divine and that thirst for immediate contact with and possession of Ultimate Reality which in the individual are the hall-marks of spiritual genius. Perhaps the most ancient of these reasoned answers is that which, ever since the composition and canonisation of the Upanisads,! has characterised the deepest philosophic and religious thought of the Hindu branch of the Aryan race; it consists in the affirmation that Evil is appearance, the inevitable con- comitant of individual, finite, and relative existence, and that the Absolute, the eternal One which is the timeless and changeless substrate of the fleeting phenomenal Many, lies as infinitely far beyond the opposition of good and bad as it transcends the distinction of personal and impersonal, and even the final antithesis of Being and Non-Being, in the incomprehensible depths of its all-embracing inanity. This view of God, the World, and Evil may be compendi- ously described as‘ unmoral’ or‘ praeter-moral’monism. As generally expounded in the Vedanta philosophy (that is, the system of thought which is partly contained in, and partly has been educed by commentators from, the Upanisads) it does not deny an imperfect and subordinate degree of reality to the phenomenal world,” but, as developed to its extremest pitch in the teaching of Buddhism, it involves as a necessary corollary the doctrine of Maya or illusion, that is, the belief in the complete non-reality and non-entity of phenomena, including the individual self. From this doctrine follows the profoundly pessimistic theory of redemption offered to mankind by the pure and lofty genius of Gautama—a theory which sees salvation only in the dissipation of the illusion of self-hood, with its con- 1 For the gradual revolution, marked by the growth of these books, and covering the period from the eighth to the sixth century B.c., which substituted the idea of the one supreme impersonal Being, called Brahman, for the animistic pantheon of the Vedas, see J. N. Farquhar, A Primer of Hinduism (1911), cc. IV, V (‘ The Philosophic Period ’) ; cf. also Hastings, ERE, art. ‘ Upanisads’ and P. Deussen, Philosophy of the Upanishads (Edinburgh, 1906). The most important Upanigads have been translated by F. Max Miller, Sacred Books of the East, vols. i., xv. 2 F. Max Miller, The Vedanta Philosophy, pp. 126-132. 6 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN comitant extinction of desire, and escape from the weary burden of Karma, achieved through successive cycles of reincarnation and death; and bids men concentrate their hope upon the supreme moment when the soul attains Nirvana by stripping itself of the last shred of individual passion and self-consciousness, and slides like a drop into the ocean of the infinite Nothing, which is the All. Second in order of time is the answer given by the other branch of the Eastern Aryan family, the Iranian Persians, in whose national religion, as elaborated by the Magi (though not as originally promulgated by Zarathushtra?’), the mysterious power of Evil, vaguely felt as all-pervasive, is personified as a malevolent God, Angra Mainyu or Ahriman, locked in Titanic conflict with Ahura Mazdah, the God of wisdom, goodness, and light. This is the answer of dualism, which regards Good and Evil, light and darkness, as equally rooted in the structure of reality, not as mere appearances, but as coaeval hypostases or substantive beings, existing from eternity in their own right, and dividing the realm of phenomenal being between them. So far as this Magian dualism was able to evolve a theory of redemption at all, it did not progress beyond the crude conception of an unexplained future victory of the good God over the oppos- ing power of evil, or of the ultimate collapse of the latter as 1 I here follow the great authority of J. H. Moulton, according to whose Early Zoroastrianism (1913), p. 201 ff., Zarathushtra’s own doctrine of evil, as expressed in the Gathas, ‘ amounted only to a strengthening of the Iranian doctrine of Truth as the highest virtue, with Falsehood as the sum of all evil. To that source of every wrong the Prophet attached a descriptive title, Angra Mainyu, which, however, he did not make into arealname. It seems a reasonable conjecture that the Magi commended their own dogma of a division of the world between good and evil powers— a mere relic of animism, which gave birth to a dreary ritual of apotropaic spells—by adapting the Gathic titles of Ahura Mazdah and Angra Mainyu’ (p. 202). A. V. Williams Jackson, on the other hand, thinks that Mazdean dualism is ultimately the product of Zarathushtra’s own genius (‘ Die iranische Religion,’ in Grundriss dey Iran. Philologie, ii. (1900), pp. 627- 631). In any case, however, the idea that there exists an evil Creator, independent of and hostile to the Good Spirit, is so thoroughly engrained into the later Avestan system as amply to justify the expression ‘ Persian’ or ‘ Mazdean’ dualism, which will frequently occur in the text ; see L. C. Casartelli, Philosophy of the Mazdayasnian Religion under the Sassanids, E. tr. (Bombay, 1889), pp. 50-54; and F. Cumont, Oriental Religions in Roman Paganism, E. tr. (Chicago, 1911), p. 151, ‘ Persia introduced dualism as a fundamental principle in religion.’ THE BEGINNINGS OF FALL-SPECULATION 7 brought about by the malignant natural forces which are its own creations and instruments.1 The means whereby man may assist Ahura Mazdah in his aeonian battle with Angra Mainyu, and prepare himself for eternal blessedness after death, consist in manthras or spells and purificatory rites of the most mechanical and materialistic description ; though the noblest form of the Iranian religion, Mithraism, deduced from the idea of the struggle between the good and the evil Gods, and of the obligation incumbent upon man to take an active part in the war on the side of good, an austere and exalted morality,? which, in the second and third centuries of our era made the religion of the ‘ unconquered Sun’ the most formidable rival of the religion of Christ, and all but secured for it the domination of Western Europe.® Last of all, opposed in the sharpest possible manner to both of these theories, and destined to wage for twenty centuries unremitting warfare upon them, emerges the third classical answer which Religion has given to the enigma of Evil: the answer which was born of the spiritual experience of the Semitic race, flowering in the lofty ethical monotheism to which the people of Israel ultimately attained, the answer which, against all views, whether monistic or dualistic, involving the eternity or necessity of evil, proclaims its temporal character and contingency. This answer is what we are accustomed to call the doctrine of the Fall and of Original Sin. As developed by the Christian Church, which claims to be Israel’s true representative and heir, it boldly asserts that Evil in all its forms—physical, aesthetic, intellectual, and moral—though to a certain limited degree and in certain spheres from a human point of view apparently inevitable, is yet from God’s point of view contingent ; that 1 Plutarch, de Is. et Osir. 47: €mevor 5é xpdvos etpappevos, €v @ Tov *Apes- pdviov, Aoumov émayovra Kal ALpov, b1d TovTwv avayKyn POapfvar wavTamace Kal adaviabfvar k. T. A. 2 Cumont, Oviental Religions, p. 157 f. ® In 307 A.D., six years before the liberation of Christianity by the Edict of Milan, the emperors Diocletian, Galerius, and Licinius met at* Carnuntum on the Danube, and dedicated a sanctuary there to Mithra, ‘the protector of their empire’ (fautori imperii sui) (Corpus Inscr. Lat. ITI. 4413; cf. Cumont, Monuments et textes relatifs aux mystéves de Mithra, i. p. 281). 8 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN it might not, and need not, have been at all; that its origin is to be found in the self-determined rebellion, in some ‘dark backward and abysm of time,’ of a finite, created will or wills against the all-holy will of the infinite Creator ; and that this remote primaeval catastrophe has marred the fair order of the universe and vitiated the stream of life in brute and man and whatever there may be of discarnate intelligence superior to man, in such a way that the tares of pain and ugliness and sin are, in the world as we know it, inextricably intermingled with the fair harvest which the creative fecundity of the Divine Spirit has brought forth in the wonders of nature and the triumphs of human achievement. This is the traditional Christian solution, or adumbration of a solution, of the problem of Evil. If it is true, it would appear to embody precisely that informa- tion as to man’s wayward nature and the relations in which he stands towards the moral order of the universe which he needs, and has never needed more than now, in order to re-shape his course in accordance with reality in a world of confusion and change. It may therefore be hoped that the critical examination of these doctrines in respect of their origin, content, and validity which the present lectures purpose to undertake will be justified, not merely by the theoretical interest which attaches to them in the mind of the professed theologian, but by their profound and intimate bearing, which affects theologian and layman alike, upon the possibility of a moral re-orientation of mankind. There is, however, a second reason, of no less weight for the reflective Christian, which, as I venture to think, justifies the choice of these mysterious doctrines as the subject of our enquiry. Even if the question of the source of evil were not suggested by the present condition of the world, it would still be pressed upon our attention by the exigencies of modern religious thought. There was a time when the scheme of orthodox dogma appeared to all as an unshakeable adamantine framework, reposing upon the two pillars of the Fall and of Redemption. These two complementary con- ceptions—that of the great apostasy, which defaced the image of God in man, and that of the great restoration through the Incarnation and the Atonement, which renewed it—were THE BEGINNINGS OF FALL-SPECULATION 9 universally taken for granted as the twin focal points which determined the ellipse of traditional theology: and the imagination of Christians loved to play around the paral- lelism of Adam and Christ—‘ the first man, of the earth, earthy,’ ‘the second man’ who is “ of heaven ’1—of the virgin Eve and the Virgin Mary,” of the death-bringing Tree of Knowledge and the life-giving Tree of the Cross. This idea of the double foundation of the Christian Faith is tersely summed up in Pascal’s aphorism—‘ Toute la foi consiste en Jésus-Christ et en Adam: et toute la morale en la concu- piscence et en la grace.’ * But the days when this conviction reigned unchallenged were days when most men believed that they dwelt in a comparatively small, geocentric universe, not more than five thousand years old, which had been con- structed in six literal days, and still contained the terrestrial paradise with its flaming Cherubim and its wonderful trees, concealed by divine power in some inaccessible region of the earth. Since then, the world in which we live has expanded like a wizard’s creation, at the touch of the magic wand of Science: the imagination is staggered by the illimitable leagues of interstellar space and the uncounted aeons of geologic time; biology proclaims the unbroken continuity of man’s descent from the brutes, and anthropology can find no room for the idea of his paradisal perfection. It is not too much to say that, whilst for professed and genuine Christians the second great pillar of the faith, the doctrine of Redemption, remains unshaken, founded upon direct fet. COT, XV. 47. 2 For the beginnings of this idea in the Christian Fathers of the second century, see below, Lecture IV, p. 174. 3 Cf. Iren. adv. haer. V, 19. 1, and also the second and third stanzas of the great Passiontide hymn Pange lingua (Venantius Fortunatus, 530- 609 A.D.) : ‘de parentis protoplasti fraude facta condolens quando pomi noxialis morte morsu conruit, ipse lignum tunc notavit, damna ligni ut solveret, hoc opus nostrae salutis ordo depoposcerat, multiformis perditoris arte ut artem falleret, et medellam ferret inde, hostis unde laeserat.,’ with the parallels quoted by A. S. Walpole, Early Latin Hymns, p. 168. 4 Pensées sur la Religion, Art. XVI, ii. 5 Cf. S. Thomas Aq., Summa theol. iia iiae, q. clxiv. a. 2, ad 5. 10 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN experience of the redeeming love of God in Christ, even they have the uneasy feeling that the first pillar, the doctrine of the Fall, has been irretrievably undermined, and totters on its base, no longer capable of bearing its former share of the super-incumbent weight. There are, indeed, those who urge that it is now a source of weakness rather than of strength to the fabric which it supported for so long, and should be razed to the ground. Whether this be so or not, it will be admitted that there is urgent need for a re-investigation of the question, and, if not for an abandonment of the tradi- tional doctrine, at least for a ‘ re-statement’ of it, in the strict and legitimate sense of that term. Before, however, we can approach the task of evaluating the doctrines of the Fall and of Original Sin, with an eye to the possibility of such re-statement, another, much more difficult and delicate, operation must be performed, namely, that of defining what precisely they are. It is noticeable that Dr. F. R. Tennant, in his monumental discussions of this subject, from time to time alludes to what he calls ‘ the ‘ecclesiastical doctrine ’ with regard to the Fall and Original Sin, without explicitly defining either the denotation or the connotation of this phrase A careful examination of the contexts in which the phrase occurs seems to justify the inference that it is meant to denote either the doctrine contained in the Thirty-Nine Articles, or else the highest common factor of the doctrines contained in the Anglican Articles, the Decrees of the Council of Trent, and the Confessions of Augsburg and Westminster.? 1 As, for instance, in The Origin and Propagation of Sin, 1902 (Hulsean Lectures), pp. 3, 4,5; Sources of the Doctrines of the Fall and Original Sin, 1903, Pp. 2, 104, 272, 274, 282, 299 (note 3), 343; art. ‘ Original Sin’ in ERE ix. pp. 558, col. b, 560, col. b, 564, col. a. 2 Itis, in fact, implied (Origin and Propagation, p. 5) that ‘ the doctrine of original sin’ (italics mine)—which presumably is the same thing as “the ecclesiastical doctrine ’—is for all practical purposes identical with the Augustinian teaching; and Appendix A, op. cit., p. 151, which is entitled ‘ The Doctrine of Original Sin in Christian Confessions,’ confines itself to extracts from the Thirty-Nine Articles, the Decrees of Trent, and four Protestant Confessions. It is remarkable that the teaching of the Eastern Orthodox Church is only alluded to in the vaguest possible manner (. . . ‘it would appear that on several points the teaching of the Greek Church with regard to the Fall and original sin is in agreement with that of Rome’); and yet the Holy Eastern Church by itself constitutes a fifth of Christendom. THE BEGINNINGS OF FALL-SPECULATION 11 If, however, we wish to consider the matter in a spirit of scientific impartiality, it will be impossible to assume, without previous enquiry, that any one of the types of teaching embodied in these Western and comparatively recent formularies, or even the highest common factor of them taken together, necessarily represents ‘ the ecclesias- tical doctrine,’ if this phrase be taken in its natural sense of ‘the doctrine of the Christian Church as a whole.’ Though it is not necessary for our present purposes to lay down any detailed theory of ‘ the Church’ or to fix its exact limits, we shall hardly be challenged if we assume that the Universal Church of God is something far more vast and spacious than the Church of England, the Church of Rome, the Lutheran or the Calvinistic communions, and that no existing con- fessional document is likely to contain more than a partial and provincial expression of its fundamental mind. But, when we enquire for an accurate index of that fundamental mind, a clear statement of the irreducible essence of Fall- doctrine to which historic Christianity as such is committed, we are faced by a remarkable absence of universally authori- tative definition. Neither the Nicene nor the Apostles’ Creed contains any direct allusion to the subject, nor can any positive and detailed information be gathered from the decrees of the undisputed Oecumenical Councils.1. The only means, therefore, which will enable us to collect and fix the diffused essence of the Christian doctrines of Man and of Sin must be found in a comprehensive survey of the history of these ideas, combined with an application of the canon laid down some fifteen centuries ago, by St. Vincent of Lerinum, that that alone is to be accounted truly Catholic which has been believed ‘ everywhere, always, and by all.’? Let me hasten to add that I propose in the first instance to employ this criterion, that of universal consent, as a means, not of establishing the objective truth of these doctrines, but merely -1 For a discussion of the significance which may be attributed to the censure pronounced upon the adherents of Caelestius by the Council of Ephesus, see Lecture V, pp. 354, 387. 2 commonitorium, ii. 6: ‘in ipsa item catholica ecclesia magnopere curandum est, ut id teneamus quod ubique, quod semper, quod ab omnibus creditum est. hoc est etenim vere proprieque catholicum, quod ipsa vis nominis ratioque declarat, quae omnia fere universaliter comprehendit.’ 12 ‘THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN of defining their exact content. When that content has been finally determined—when we know what the doctrines actually are—then, and not till then, can we address: our- selves to the task of deciding whether they correspond to the facts of nature and life or not. The first six lectures, therefore, of this course will be historical in nature, intended to ascertain the origin and fix the essence of these ideas, and the last two, theological or philosophical, devoted to a discussion of their validity and truth. THE PROBLEM IN THE OLD TESTAMENT As the Christian Church claims to be continuously identical with the ancient Israel, and as the Jewish Scriptures are embodied in the Christian Bible, our historical survey will naturally begin with the Old Testament ; by which term I understand, for the purposes of this lecture, the total corpus of Hebrew and Jewish literature contained in the longer or Septuagintal Canon, a definition which includes the books commonly called Apocrypha. The period of a thousand years over which the dates of these documents range may naturally be divided into three sub-periods, pre-Exilic, Exilic, and post-Exilic ; and it will be convenient to arrange our consideration of the growth of the Fall-doctrine in three corresponding sections. (a) It is not too much to say that the first of these periods, that which ends with the Babylonian captivity, contains no trace whatever of the existence of a belief in a ‘ Fall’ (as the term is used in technical theology) or in ‘ Original Sin’ ; the Paradise-story of Gen. iii, as we shall see in our next lecture, forms no exception to the truth of this statement.! It is not difficult to see why this must necessarily have been so. These ideas—especially that of a hereditary bias towards evil—even when held in the vaguest and most popular form, and without any scholastic exactness of definition, are yet of a somewhat artificial and abstract nature. They pre- suppose considerable powers of generalisation and induction from the facts of history and also of introspective self- 1 See Lecture II, p. 50 f. THE BEGINNINGS OF FALL-SPECULATION 13 analysis. Hence they are not likely to have arisen at a very early date in the history of the Chosen People. The idea of ‘ Original Sin,’ even in the crudest form, can only come into being as the result of meditation on the fact of Actual Sin ; it can only be born in the mind of one who has felt within him the fierce wrestling of conscience and desire, swaying to and fro in the agonies of the moral struggle. Now the idea of Actual Sin itself, in its precise sense of the free and deliberate transgression of a known moral law, does not belong to the earliest strata of human thought as revealed by anthropological research. The most primitive peoples known to us conceive of evil, not so much in its ethical sense as a value, or negation of value, affirmed of actions, motives, or the will or character which prompts them, but rather in a quasi-physical sense, as a subtle contagion, an impalpable foetor, which exhales from uncanny persons and things, from material substances, such as shed blood, corpses, and objects placed under a religious ban, or from organic pro- cesses such as those of generation, birth, and death. At this early stage of thought, there can be no question of a ‘ Fall’ or definite event giving rise to evil. For the distinction between bad and good mana, as inhering in uncanny things or persons, is not absolute, but relative to the circumstances of the percipient ; the emotions aroused by the uncanny are strictly ‘ambivalent,’ and may manifest themselves either as veneration or as horror.! As, therefore, there is no such thing for the savage as objectively or absolutely bad mana, the question of its origin does not and cannot arise. It is only by slow and painful degrees that the strictly ethical idea of good and evil has been educed from the 1 Cf. the double meaning of the Latin word sacer (‘ sacred’ and ‘ ac- cursed’). For detailed exposition of the meaning of mana, in its general- ised significance as a category employed by the science of Comparative Religion, see ‘ The Canception of Mana’ in The Threshold of Religion, R. R. Marett (1914); also the article ‘Mana,’ by the same author, in Hastings, ERE viii. p. 375. The idea of bad mana, owing to its vague- ness, and (as explained in the text) owing to its relativity, cannot be claimed as identical with the later and more artificial theologumenon of ‘ Original Sin’; but lingering traces of it seem to have worked sub- consciously in the minds of some Christian patristic writers on hamarti- ology, notably Origen and St. Augustine; v. infra, Lect. IV, p. 226, and cf. V, p. 366. 14 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN ambiguous notion of beneficent-noxious mana. Amongst the Greeks, the great tragedians allow us to see the process actually at work; the Antigone of Sophocles, for instance, contains both conceptions, the ethical and the quasi-physical side by side. The sin of Oedipus, which was ex hypothest unconscious and involuntary, is only a sin if evil is thought to be a substantive miasma or pollution inhering in a person, rather than a value which the mind attaches to his acts; whilst the heroism of Antigone is goodness in the modern or ethical sense, being obedience to those eternal laws of which she herself says: For their life is not of yesterday or to-day, but from all time, and no man knoweth when they first appeared. And, as with Greece, so it was with Israel. Like its neighbours, Israel started on its career with what may be called a merely zymotic theory of evil, which is clearly visible in the story of Achan and the Babylonish garment, and survives embalmed in much of the ceremonial of the Priestly Law.” It was the work of the great prophets of Israel’s classical period to dislodge this barbarous concep- tion from the national mind, to replace it by the spiritual and ethical idea, and to proclaim that the Lord requires nothing of man save ‘ to do justly, and to love mercy, and to walk humbly with his God.’ * But this was a task more than sufficient to absorb the whole even of their volcanic energies, and they would not have had time, even if they had 1 Soph. Ant. 456, 457: od ydp TL viv ye KaxXOés, GAN’ det ToTE Cf ratra, Kovoeis otdev €€ drov ’ havy. 2“ Exactly the same penalty is imposed for infringements of ritual (Ex. xxx. 33, 38; Lev. xvil. 4, 9, 14; xix. 8) as for grave moral offences (Lev. xviii. 29). Death is the penalty, alike for murder (Num. xxxv. 31) and for Sabbath-breaking (Ex. xxxi. 15; xxxv. 2). Purification from sin is prescribed after purely physical defilement, as through contact with a corpse, and even for a house which has been affected by leprosy (Lev. xiv. 49, 52; Num. xix. 12, 13, 19, 20 [the Heb. in these passages for cleanse, purify is properly to ‘free from sin’]). A sin-offering is also sometimes enjoined for merely ceremonial uncleanness (e.g. Lev. v. 2, 6; Num. vi. 9-11). ... The principle of ceremonial cleanness and un- cleanness, it may be noticed, was the point on which our Lord broke most decisively with the Mosaic law’ (S. R. Driver, art. ‘ Law (in Old Testament) ’ in HDB iii. p. 72. ® Micah vi. 8. THE BEGINNINGS OF FALL-SPECULATION 15 possessed the inclination, to raise the question of the origin of moral evil; whilst the hypothesis of an inbred tendency to sin, with the element of qualified determinism which it most always involve, would have been profoundly uncon- genial to them as apparently offering an easy excuse for continuance in evil-doing to the indolent and the hypo- critical. The insistence upon individual freedom and responsibility which lies at the roots of the prophetic teach- ing rises to its highest point in the rigid ethical atomism of Jeremiah and Ezekiel, as expressed in such sayings as: In those days they shall say no more, The fathers have eaten sour grapes, and the children’s teeth are set on edge. But every one shall die for his own iniquity: every man that eateth the sour grapes, his teeth shall be set on edge 2; and The soul that sinneth it shall die. The son shall not bear the iniquity of the father, neither shall the father bear the iniquity of the son; the righteousness of the righteous shall be upon him, and the wickedness of the wicked shall be upon him ?: —utterances which, if pressed to their logical conclusion, would seem to amount to a denial by anticipation of the later doctrine of Original Sin, at any rate in its pea Augustinian form. (0) In the course of our second period, that of the Exile, a change begins to appear in Hebrew thought on the sub- ject of sin. The great catastrophe had burnt the ethical teaching of the prophets deeply into the mind of Israel, had produced a poignant sense of sin, both national and individual, and had fostered a mood of sombre introspective- ness in which the soul seeks refuge within itself from the 1 The passage Jer. xvii. 9: ‘ The heart is deceitful above all things, and it is desperately sick ; who can know it ?’ does not affirm a radical evil in human nature; it is merely a practical aphorism, warning the prophet’s hearers that ‘ No man ever knows fully his neighbour’s thoughts and motives, nor whether he will remain faithful to his engagements’ (L. E. Binns, The Book of the Prophet Jeremiah, 1919, p. 140). 2 Jer. xxxi. 29; cf. Ezek. xviii. 2. 8 Ezek. xviii. 20. Although the whole of Ezekiel’s prophetic ministry falls chronologically within the period of the Exile (it may be dated 592- 570 B.C.) I have quoted this passage in my survey of the pre-Exilic period, because of its logical connexion with the teaching of Jeremiah. 16 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN disappointments of the unfriendly world without, only to be confronted by the spectacle of weakness and disharmony within. It would seem, however, that the first essays of the Exilic period in the task of explaining evil were prompted by the desire to mitigate, by elucidating, the fact of suffering or pain, and therefore approached the problem primarily on its physical side. The facile optimism of Deuteronomy, which regarded happiness as the unfailing reward of virtue, and suffering as the invariable punishment of sin, indissolubly linked together within the bounds of this present life, had been refuted by history 1; and, with the final adoption by Israel of a genuine monotheism, which regarded Yahweh, no longer as a local and limited tribal deity, but as the unique sovereign and creator of the universe, the problem of undeserved suffering called all the more insistently for a fresh solution. Abruptly challenging Mazdean dualism, which must have appeared as a simple and tempting solu- tion to many of the exiled Jews, the audacious thought of Deutero-Isaiah attributes evil to the direct appointment of God. ‘I am Yahweh, and there is none else. I form the light, and create darkness: I make peace, and create evil: I am Yahweh, that doeth all these things.’? Here there can be little doubt that both physical and moral evil are meant. But the genius of Hebrew religion, faithful to the lessons which it had learnt from the great pre-exilic prophets, could make no terms with a solution which by representing God as the author of evil sacrificed His righteousness in order to save His power. It was felt that somehow man, and not God, must be in the last resort responsible for evil, at any rate for the evil which appears in human history ; and the hypothesis of a direct causal relation between sin and suffering inevitably re-appeared, 1 It is here assumed, in accordance with the generally accepted ‘ criti- cal theory’ of the Pentateuch, that the composition of Deuteronomy was subsequent to the teaching of (the first) Isaiah, and cannot in any case be attributed to Moses; see p. 10, n. 5. 2 Isaiah xlv. 6, 7; cf. xxxi. 2, and Amos iii. 6. There are several earlier passages of the Old Testament in which Yahweh is represented as prompting men to particular evil actions (Ex. vii. 3; Judg. ix. 23; r Sam. ii. 25, xix. 9; 2 Sam. xxiv. 1); but Deutero-Isaiah would seem to be the first Hebrew writer to affirm the Divine authorship of evil as a universally valid proposition. THE BEGINNINGS OF FALL-SPECULATION 17 as in the discourses of Job’s friends and comforters. The author of Job rejects the naive theory of a necessary connexion between sin and suffering in this life; but, in the course of his meditations on this intractable problem, he is led to admit the empirical universality of sin to such an extent as to suggest something like an a friort necessity for it, rooted in the nature of man. And here we come upon the first dim traces of the ideas of which we are in search. ‘Can a mortal be just before God? or can a man be pure before his Maker?’ Or, again, ‘Who can bring a clean thing out of an unclean? Not one.’2 Or— even more emphatically—‘ What is man that he should be clean? And he that is born of a woman, that he should be righteous ? Behold, he putteth no trust in his holy ones ; yea, the heavens are not clean in his sight.’? ‘ How then can man be just with God? Or how can he be clean that is born of a woman ?’ 4 This is not yet a doctrine of original sin, but it is well on the way towards one. It would seem that the sinfulness which the author of Job admits to inhere in man is regarded by him as a necessary consequence of man’s finitude and creaturely character; there is no thought of a ‘ Fall’ from a supposed condition of original perfection. Moral frailty is the inevitable corollary of physical weakness and limita- tion. It is to be noted that ultimately this solution of the problem of evil is the same as the Second Isaiah’s, because, if sin is due merely to man’s physical frailty, the ultimate responsibility for it lies with the Creator who made him frail; and, indeed, the book of Job, for all its poetic sub- limity, is a self-confessed failure considered as a theodicy. It seemed as though Jewish thought was involved in an endless circle, perpetually finding itself drawn back into the position from which it most desired to escape, namely that which makes God the ultimate author of evil. There was 1 Jobiv. 17 (tr. Driver and Gray, ICC). 2 Job xiv. 4. Driver and Gray translate: ‘ Oh that a clean thing could come out of an unclean! not one can.’ Some critics regard this verse as a marginal gloss which has crept into the text: see op. cit., Philological Notes, p. 89. 3 Job xv. 14, I5. 4 Job xxv. 4. 18 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN only one way out of the difficulty. The conflict between the hypotheses of an inherent tendency to evil in man, and of the infinite goodness of God who created man, could only resolve itself by the assumption that human nature as it actually exists is not what God meant it to be, and that some historical catastrophe must be pos- tulated in order to account for this otherwise inexplicable fact. (c) This train of thought—in which the perception of the empirical universality of sin gives rise to a theory of inherited liability to sin, and this again when reflected on compels the assumption of a primal sin as its source—did not attain to complete definition and articulation until the third or autumnal period of Israel’s history, the age known by the great name of the Maccabees. It is not on that account to be lightly set aside or disparaged. What Pro- fessor F. C. Burkitt has called ‘ the heroic age of Jewish history ’ + had a providential function to discharge in fashion- ing and assembling much of the conceptual material which was to be built into the fabric of Christian theology, even before the birth of Christ, just as David before his death had accumulated timber and squared stones to be used in the construction of Solomon’s temple. We need only instance the doctrines of the Logos, of the heavenly Son of Man, of the Church and the Communion of Saints, of the Resurrec- tion and the Last Things, as ideas which our Lord and His Apostles did not create but took over as parts of an already existing theology. It was in the characteristic mind of this age, so strangely blent of touching piety and repulsive fanaticism, that the Jewish theories of the origin of evil assumed a relatively final shape. We cannot here attempt to reconstruct the state of religious thought and feeling during the obscure beginnings of this epoch ; it must suffice to quote three testimonies to the deepening sense of sin, with its reflex tendency to stereo- type and fix, by a kind of corporate auto-suggestion, the floating idea of hereditary sinfulness in the mind of the Jewish Church. These shall be taken from the hallowed and familiar words of three Psalms, dating from the Persian 1 Jewish and Christian A pocalypses, p. 15 (1913). = a ee a THE BEGINNINGS OF FALL-SPECULATION 19 and early Greek periods.! ‘If thou, Lord, wilt be extreme to mark what is done amiss, O Lord, who may abide it ? ’ 2 ‘Enter not into judgment with thy servant, for in thy sight shall no man living be justified ’’—two utterances which seem to show that the empirical universality of sin has already been elevated to the rank of a dogma. The next step, that of ascribing this universality of actual sin to the presence of a hereditary taint or weakness, is taken in the most pathetic of all outpourings of repentant grief, the 51st Psalm: ‘ Behold, I was shapen in wickedness, and in sin hath my mother conceived me’ 4—a saying which bears the same unmistakeable significance, whether an individual sinner or the personified community be regarded as the speaker. The time was ripe for the last step in the process, that of tracing the hereditary taint back to a primal sin, the uncaused cause or primum mobile of the whole disastrous concentration. Asa matter of fact, though in all probability the Psalmists knew it not, this step had already been taken. Already during the fourth century before Christ an unknown thinker had reasoned with himself to this effect—' Human nature everywhere contains an innate bias towards evil. This is clearly contrary to the intention of God, who must have created man in a state of goodness ; therefore, there must have been a primitive catastrophe, through which evil invaded human life from without, from the unseen world of spirits.’ This nameless philosopher, whose thoughts we have thus speculatively reconstructed, was the person designated in Hexateuchal criticism by the symbol R!*—in other words, the redactor who wove the Prophetic and Priestly strands of the Hexateuch into the single history which we possess to-day.° Oppressed by the need for a final and specific 1 This dating is taken from Briggs, The Book of Psalms, ICC. (1907) ; he assigns Pss. lh. and cxliii. to the Persian, cxxx. to the early Greek period. But the argument in the text will not be affected if all three are assigned to the Greek period. 2 Ps. cxxx. 3, RV., ‘ If thou, Lord, shouldest mark iniquities, O Lord, who shall stand ?’ eOlss Gxtili! 2. 4u. 5. 5’ Though no reader who is in any degree conversant with the present state of Biblical knowledge will require a detailed disproof of the Mosaic authorship of the earlier books of the Old Testament as they stand, it may 20 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN event to explain the origin of evil, he searched through the ancient traditions which lay before him, and fixed upon the mysterious legend of the fallen angels narrated in Genesis vi. This story, it would seem, was the first Jewish Fall-story, not in the sense that it is more ancient in origin than the Paradise-story contained in Genesis iii., but in the sense that it was the first to be fixed upon as containing an explana- tion of the origin of evil in man. To it, therefore, some words of explanation and criticism must be devoted. THE STORY OF THE FALLEN ANGELS The first eight verses of Genesis vi. are taken from the Yahwistic source, and have been placed in their present position to form an introduction to the Flood-story, which, as is well known, is composed of alternate sections of the Yahwistic and the Priestly narratives. In them we are told that certainly heavenly beings described as the bené nevertheless be well to state explicitly that in this and the following Lecture I assume the outlines of the ‘ four-document’ critical theory of the Hexateuch, elaborated in its present form mainly by Kuenen and Wellhausen. This, very briefly summarised, regards the Hexateuch as a composite structure, built up in the main out of four primary elements, namely, (1) the ‘ Yahwistic’ narrative, so called from its use of the divine name YHWH, and usually designated by the symbol J: this may be roughly dated c. 850 B.c.; (2) the ‘ Elohistic’ narrative, covering the same historical ground, but distinguished by its preference for the title, ’eldhim to denote God, and compiled, in all probability, about a century later than J; this is referred to by the symbol E (the conflate history of the world and of Israel into which these two narratives were compounded towards the end of the eighth century B.c. is known as JE, or the ‘ Prophetic History’); (3) the Book of Deuteronomy, the central portion of which is regarded by most critics as the basis of Josiah’s sweeping Reformation (2 Kings xxiii.), together with certain elements akin to Deuteronomy con- tained in other books, the whole being known as D ; (4) the great Priestly Document, which includes both an ecclesiastically coloured history and a collection of legal codes, and was reduced to its present form during and after the Exile (this is known as P). The final combination of JE, D, and P into the Hexateuch as we possess it may be assigned to the fourth century B.c. As both of the Genesis-passages which we shall have to examine are derived from J, it will not be necessary to go further into the refinements of Pentateuchal criticism, with regard to which much diversity of opinion still prevails amongst scholars (see The People and the Book, 1925, Essay V1). THE BEGINNINGS OF FALL-SPECULATION aq ha-’ elohim—the ‘sons of the gods ’+~(a trace of original polytheism which reveals the great antiquity of the narrative) saw the daughters of men that they were fair, and con- tracted marriages with them (vv. I, 2). In v. 3, Yahweh, beholding this action from heaven, is said to have uttered words which, as represented in the English versions, appear somewhat cryptic: ‘ My spirit shall not strive with man for ever, for that he also is flesh; yet shall his days be an hundred and twenty years.’* The fourth verse tells us of the nepiilim,® or giants, who existed upon the earth in those days, and also afterwards, whenever the ‘ sons of the gods ’ united themselves with women. The presumption is that these giants were sprung from the union between divine and human partners. They are further identified with the gibbovim or ‘mighty men’ of old, the traditional heroes of popular folk-lore. We are then told (vv. 5, 6) that Yahweh saw “ that the wickedness of man was great in the earth, and that every imagination of the thoughts of his heart was only evil continually ; and Yahweh repented that he had made man on the earth, and it grieved him at his heart.’ He consequently resolves to destroy the human race by means of a flood. Noah, however, finds favour in the sight of the Lord. As these verses stand, the only construction to be put upon them appears to be as follows: The ‘ sons of the gods ’ are divine beings, of an order inferior to Yahweh—or, to employ a later and more familiar term, ‘ angels ’*—-who gave way to lust, and committed sin by deserting their heavenly abode and mingling the divine essence with the 1 This translation seems to be necessitated by the presence of the definite article before pride. “Sons of God’ (AV., RV.) would pre- sumably be DION, 22, asin Job xxxviii. 7. 2 See below, p. 23, n. I. 8 For an account of these mythical beings (containing a large element of conjecture) see T. K. Cheyne in EB? iii. s.v. Nephilim. * Cf., much later, the use of DITION in Ps. viii. 5; ‘ Thou didst make him a little lower than the ’eldhim,’ and Briggs’ note 2” loc. (ICC., Psalms, vol. i. p. 64): ‘ We must think of the Elohim as comprehending God and angels, the latter being, in their historic origin, the ancient polytheistic gods, degraded to ministering servants of the one God Yahweh.’ 22 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN seed ofman. This unnatural action introduces the principle of evil into humanity: a principle which finds its first and most terrifying manifestation in the appearance of a mon- strous brood of Titans, who disturb the moral order of the earth by deeds of lawlessness. The chaos so created attains to such dimensions as to provoke the Creator to visit the earth with the Flood, so as to eliminate evil from the earth by drowning both the giants and other members of the human race who have been corrupted by their influence. As the narrative stands, it appears to imply the existence of a direct causal relation between the wickedness of the giants and the lustfulness of their angelic sires; this construction of the story, however, is not actually stated in the text, and careful examination seems to show that there is a perceptible ‘suture’ or join between vv. 4 and 5. Verses 5-8, giving the account of man’s wickedness, lead directly into the Yahwistic Flood-story ; but vv. 1-4, containing the legend of the angels, seem to come from a cycle of tradition which knows nothing of the Deluge; for in Numbers xii. 33 (a passage derived from JE) certain descendants of the nephilim, including the famous sons of Anak,? are said to have been still surviving in Palestine at the time of the invasion under Joshua, a statement which is obviously inconsistent with the supposition that the giants were all drowned in the Flood. And the words attributed to Yahweh in v. 3 seem inconsistent with the idea of a flood shortly to follow; for, if we follow the most probable hypothesis, their meaning may be paraphrased as follows: “ My “ spirit ” or essence ’ (that is, the divine essence which the ‘ sons of the © gods ’ have improperly introduced into the human stock by their unnatural alliances) “must not be allowed to remain intermingled for ever with the essence of mortal man, who is but flesh’ (z.e. not much more than an animal) ‘ and therefore is not entitled to the permanent enjoyment of the supernatural increase in knowledge and strength which participation in the divine essence brings with it. I will, 1 But G. Buchanan Gray (JCC., Numbers, p. 151) thinks that the words py>n3n-}9 PY 25, ‘ the sons of ‘Anaq are some of the nephilim,’ are a gloss, as they are not represented in the LXX. THE BEGINNINGS OF FALL-SPECULATION 23 accordingly, reduce the average duration of human life to a period of a hundred and twenty years, in order to ensure that the divine essence is worked out of the human race within a comparatively brief period.’1 Again, it would seem that Yahweh’s contemplation of so prolonged and cumbrous a method of eliminating from the human stock the divine element unlawfully introduced into it is quite inconsistent with the supposition that he was able, and intended, to destroy the whole human race en bloc by a sudden cataclysm within a few years. We therefore con- clude that the Angel-story comes from sources entirely different from those of the Flood-story, and that it was prefixed to the Flood-story by KR” in order to explain the universal wickedness which provoked the Deluge. In making it into a ‘ Fall-story’ it is probable that RJ” has mutilated it, in order to abolish mythological features which offended his moral and religious sense. THE ANGEL-STORY IN THE APOCALYPSES The use of this earliest Fall-story is illustrated by its elaboration in the most interesting of all pseudepigraphic 1 This very obscure and probably corrupt verse has been exhaustively discussed by J. Skinner (Internat. Crit. Commentary, Genesis, pp. 143 ff.). Its interpretation turns upon the meaning of the word ‘Ff (‘ my spirit’) and of the phrase HIND, which the LXX represents by od pi) Karapeivy and the English versions by ‘ shall not strive.’ The explanation adopted in the text is that given by Skinner, following Wellhausen (Die Composition des Hexateuchs u. dey historisch. Biicher des AT, 2nd edn. 1880, p. 305 ff.). It is not an objection to this view that the shortening of the lives of indi- viduals would not affect the characteristics acquired by the race through the divine-human unions ; for (assuming no further apostasies on the part of the ’eldhim-beings) the amount of the divine essence latent in the human stock as the result of the original transgression would, presumably, be conceived as strictly fixed, and, with the increasing numbers of the race, would be regarded as subject in each generation to a process of con- tinuous subdivision, so that eventually the quantity of it to be found in any given individual would be infinitesimal and so practically negligible. The reduction of the average life of the individual from nine centuries to a little more than one would be an obvious means of accelerating this process. 24 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN works—the Ethiopic Book of Enoch. This book is a literary patchwork embodying the whole or fragments of at least six separate documents, belonging to dates ranging between the end of the third and the middle of the first century B.c. The most important of these documents are (1) the Book of Enoch proper, comprising Chapters 12-36 of our present text, which may be dated in the neighbourhood of 200 B.C. ; (2) the fragments of the Book of Noah, which is at least earlier than the persecution of Antiochus Epiphanes ; (3) the Visions of Enoch, written about 165 B.c., in the midst of the Maccabean struggle, and contemporaneously with the Book of Daniel; and (4) the Similitudes, which appear to have been written between the years 94 and 64 B.c., during the reigns of Alexander Jannaeus and Alexandra. The most complete statement of the Fall-story as connected with the sin of the angels is contained in the fragments of the Book of Noah.* In this work the apostate angels are described by a term familiar to us from the Book of Daniel? as ‘Watchers ’"—that is, spirits who are conceived in their heavenly home as ceaselessly watching the Almighty, so as to be in perpetual readiness to execute His commands. We are told that they were two hundred in number, and that, having bound themselves by a mutual oath to carry out the projected rape, they descended upon the summit of Mount Hermon.’ The giants, who were their sons, are said 1 For citations from the text of this book, as well as from other apoca- lyptic writings which it has been necessary to mention in this lecture, I have used the translations contained in the monumental Apocrypha and Pseudepigrapha of the Old Testament, Oxford, 1913, edited by Dr. R. H. Charles. In giving references, I have followed the common custom of designating the Ethiopic Enoch as 1 Enoch, and the ‘ Book of the Secrets of Enoch,’ or Slavonic Enoch, as 2 Enoch. 2 1 Enoch vi-xi. 3 iv. 13, 17, 23. The Aramaic word is YY, ‘wakeful one,’ which LXX and Theodotion transliterate as efp; Aquila and Symmachus, however, render }*)}Y by éypyyopot, which appears to have become a technical term denoting the order to which the peccant angels belonged, as it appears in the Slavonic Enoch under the curious form ‘ Grigori’ (2 Enoch xviii. A text; the B text has ‘ Egoroi’; Charles, Apocr. and Pseudep. ii. p. 439). 4 1 Enoch, vi. 6. St. Hilary (fvact. in cxxxii. ps. [PL X. 521)) quotes this detail with some hesitation from the Book of Enoch, which he describes as ‘ nescio cuius liber.’ W. Robertson Smith (Religion of the Semites, 1914 edn., p. 446) suggests that the Watcher-story may have originally been a local legend connected with Mount Hermon. THE BEGINNINGS OF FALL-SPECULATION — 25 to have been three thousand ells in height. These Titanic beings, we are told, ‘ consumed all the acquisitions of men. And, when men could no longer sustain them, the giants turned against them and devoured mankind. . . . And as men perished, they cried, and their cry went up to heaven.’ } The engendering of giants, however, was not the only way in which the fallen Watchers introduced wickedness into the earth. They corrupted the human race by imparting to it knowledge which the Creator had not meant it to possess.? Here we detect the emergence of a motif which reappears in the second Fall-story, that of Adam and Eve, and is closely paralleled by the Greek legend of Prometheus—the idea being that God is jealous—ro @eciov wav dOovepov, as the Greeks put it 3—that the Creator grudges His creatures the possession of knowledge, and that all or many of their woes are due to its unlawful acquisition. Of the fallen angels, Azazél taught men the art of working metals, and of making knives, swords, and armour, and also instructed them in the manufacture of jewellery and cosmetics, arts which naturally led to the increase of homicide and impurity ; whilst the other angels reveal to men the sciences of magic, astrology, and astronomy.* Then, in Chapter 9, the Archangels Michael, Uriel, Raphael and Gabriel look down from heaven, and see the corruption and disorder which reign upon the earth. They complain to the Almighty, who charges them to deal with the situation in different ways. Uriel is com- manded to warn Noah of the approaching Deluge; Raphael is commissioned to bind Azazél, the leader of the rebel angels, hand and foot, and to bury him in a hole in the desert, piling upon him rough and jagged rocks, until the 1 ; Enoch vii. 4; viii. 4. The arrogance of the giants is also mentioned in 3 Macc. ii. 4; Ecclus. xvi. 7; Wisdom xiv. 6. 2 ix. 6: cf. also lxiv. 2 (Similitudes). 3 Herodotus i. 32, ili. 40: in these passages only material prosperity is conceived as the object of the divine ‘jealousy.’ Aristotle condemns this opinion, especially in so far as it attributes to God a dislike of human progress in knowledge: ei 67 Aéyovoi re of moinral Kal mépuxe POovetv ro Gciov, émt rovrov (1.e. in the matter of knowledge) ovpPaivew padrora eixds Kat dvotuxeis elvar mavras Tovs mepirrovs. GAA’ ovre TO Deiov POovepov evdexerar evar, GAAa Kal Kara Tv wapotmlavy TOAAG wevdovrar dovdoi x.7.A. (Met. A. ii, 10). 4 1 Enoch viil. 26 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN time is ripe for the last judgment, after which he is to be cast into eternal fire. The Lord’s charge to Raphael con- tinues— Heal the earth which the angels have corrupted, and proclaim the healing of the earth that they may heal the plague, and that all the children of men may not perish through all the secret things that the Watchers have dis- closed and have taught their sons. And the whole earth has been corrupted through the works that were taught by Azazél: to him ascribe all sin.’ 1 The commissions of the two other archangels seem to be derived from a different cycle of tradition, inasmuch as Gabriel is commanded to proclaim the destruction of the children of the Watchers through internecine strife—a command that seems incon- sistent with the hypothesis of a rapidly approaching Flood ; whilst Michael is bidden to bind one Semjaza, who in this version appears to be the leader of the apostates, in a ravine of the earth, there to await the last great assize. Such is the haggadic amplification of the story contained in Genesis Vi. I-4 as it appears in the fragments of the Book of Noah embodied in the Ethiopic Book of Enoch. A supplemen- tary detail is added in c. xv., belonging to the Book of Enoch — proper, in which the souls of the dead giants are said to have become demons who afflict mankind. It is very significant that the author of this document is well acquainted with the Paradise-story of Genesis iii. On one of his tours through the supramundane regions Enoch is shown the Garden of Eden with the Tree of the Knowledge of Good and Evil growing in the midst of it.2 His angelic guide explains that this is the tree of which Adam and Eve ate, which opened their eyes so that they knew that they were naked ; but it is noticeable that this event is mentioned merely as an interesting historical fact, and that no attempt is made to trace the origin of human wickedness to it. Evidently the Watcher-legend of Genesis vi. is the only Fall-story of which the Book of Enoch knows. A symbolic version of the Watcher-legend occurs in the third section of the Ethiopic Enoch, namely, the Visions, which must have been written in the very midst of the Maccabean struggle, almost contemporaneously with the ey DOCU X.17310- ox Se A. eae mmaini ttt ee THE BEGINNINGS OF FALL-SPECULATION 27 Book of Daniel. In the second ‘ Vision’ the history of the world from the creation of man to the foundation of the Messianic kingdom is told under the form of an elaborate animal story.1_ The apostate Watchers are symbolised by stars, the children of Seth, with whom they intermarry, by oxen, and the evil brood of giants who sprang from these unions by elephants, camels, and asses.2, The Watcher- legend is assumed once more in the Similitudes, which Dr. Charles dates between 94 and 64 B.c. Ince. lxvi-lxix. the emphasis is laid, not so much upon the lust of the angels as upon their transgression of the divine ordinance, in revealing to the human race secret knowledge which the Creator had not designed for it. As before, sorcery, metal- lurgy, and the manufacture of weapons occupy a prominent place among the forbidden arts in which the fallen spirits instructed man ?: the author of the Similitudes ingeniously adds the art of writing with ink and paper as one of the chief causes of human corruption for which the apostate Watchers were responsible. Such was the earliest and crudest form in which the doctrines of the Fall and of Original Sin obtained any wide currency amongst the Jews—the naive belief that the universal sinfulness with which mankind appeared to be infected flowed like a dark turbid river from a single fount, namely, the unholy unions of angelic and human beings narrated in Gen. vi. and the commixture of mortal and immortal essences effected thereby. No less crude was the theory of redemption dependent upon it. The world’s deliverance from sin was to be accomplished by purely external and mechanical means—the imprisonment of the Watchers, by God, or the Son of Man, in a lurid Gehenna, and the burning out of the body of the human race of the plague-spot which their lust had left behind, by the fires of an eschatological cataclysm. Doubtless we must attribute it to the distractions of the mortal conflict with the Seleucid power in which the Jewish Church-State was for nearly 1 + Enoch Ixxxv.-xc. Inc. lxxv., the creation of Adam and Eve, the murder of Abel, and the birth of Seth are related insymbolic terms, but there is no mention of the forbidden fruit or the expulsion from Paradise. 2 Ixxxvi. 3 Ixv. 6-8. 4°1xix.50;/10. 28 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN a generation involved, that an obvious internal difficulty exhibited by this artless theory was not at first perceived. The difficulty is this. Taking the story of Genesis vi., vil. literally, as the authors of Enoch took it (and ignoring the reference to the nephilim in Num. xiii. 33), we learn that all living beings, except Noah and his family and the animals preserved in the Ark, were destroyed in the Flood. Pre- sumably, therefore, the giants were drowned, and the whole seed of evil proceeding from the Watchers must have come to an end; so that the Watcher-story in no way accounts for the fact of post-diluvian wickedness. The author of the Visions seems dimly to feel this difficulty, because, after stating that the elephants, camels, and asses, who symbolise the giants, perished in the Flood, he goes on to state that the three bulls, who symbolise the sons of Noah, procreated after the Deluge—for no assignable reason—a heterogeneous brood of lions, tigers, wolves, dogs, hyenas, wild boars, foxes, squirrels, swine, and other unclean creatures.!_ These, of course, are the Gentiles or wicked races of the earth; but their appearance merely raises the problem of the origin of evil all over again, and leaves the apocalyptic thinker in the same condition of perplexity as before. The interpolator of the Book of Jubilees, the main body of which may be dated about the end of the second century B.C., attempted to solve the problem by asserting that post- Noachian wickedness was due to the ghosts of the drowned giants, who continued to haunt the world as earth-bound spirits.2, But the original author of Jubilees had already cut the Gordian knot by abandoning the Watcher-legend altogether, and fixing for his Fall-story on an entirely different passage of Scripture, namely, the Paradise-narra- tive of Genesis ii1., which eventually, owing to the influence of St. Paul, became the official Fall-story of the Christian Church.? This writer cannot, indeed, claim to be the first inventor of this idea, inasmuch as the sin of Eve is asserted to be the beginning of wickedness and the cause of death by the Son of Sirach, writing some eighty years previously.? 1+ Enoch Ixxxix. 10. ? Jubilees, vii. 26-39; x. 1-15. 3 iii. 17-35. 4 Ecclus. xxv. 24; for an examination of this passage see below, Lecture II, p. 54. THE BEGINNINGS OF FALL-SPECULATION = 29 But, from the Book of Jubilees onwards, during the course of the first century B.c., it is possible to trace the gradual suppression of the Watcher-legend by the Adam-story as the historical, or supposedly historical, explanation of the origin of human sin. THE EMERGENCE OF GEN. III. AS THE POPULAR FALL-STORY In the Testaments of the Twelve Patriarchs both stories seem to appear in this character. The Watcher-story appears in the Testament of Reuben, with a curious variant which makes the daughters of men take the initiative in seducing the angels,t and in the Testament of Napthali.? On the other hand, the Testament of Levi asserts that the redemption which the Messiah will bring will consist in the removal of the flaming sword which excludes man from Paradise, his restoration to the happy garden, and his being given to eat of the Tree of Life —a prophecy which seems to presuppose the identification of the ultimate ° Fall’ with the sin of Adam and Eve. In the Book of the Secrets of Enoch (often called the ‘ Slavonic Enoch ’) written, perhaps, contemporaneously with the life of our Lord, whilst both Fall-stories appear, all the emphasis is laid on the Paradise- story as narrating the origin of human wickedness in general, and the Watcher-legend is depressed to a comparatively subordinate role as the explanation merely of that particular episode in the history of human sin which was the occasion of the Flood. In the Book of the Wisdom of Solomon, which may be probably dated during the decade which followed the death of Christ,* there appears to be an incidental allusion to the Adam-story as the explanation of the cause 1 Test. Reub. v. 5-7. 2 Test. Napth. iil. 5. 3 Test. Lev. xvili. Io, II. 4 A. T.S. Goodricke, The Book of Wisdom, 1913, Introd. § 2. But it must be confessed that much diversity of opinion has prevailed amongst scholars as to the period of this book’s composition: Grimm dates it 150-145 B.c., Thackeray 130-100 B.c., Gregg 125-I00 B.c., Gfrdrer 100 B.c., Bousset under the Roman Empire, Farrar a.p. 40. For a full discussion of the question, see S. Holmes, The Wisdom of Solomon, introd. § 5 (in Charles, A pocr. and Pseudep. i. p. 520 f.). 30 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN of human mortality !; the Watcher-story is not mentioned. The Ezra-A pocalypse, commonly known as the Second or Fourth Book of Esdras, which dates from the last quarter of the first century A.D., seems to mark the complete dis- appearance of the Watcher-story, and the triumph of the Adam-narrative as the generally accepted Fall-story.? It need only be added, by way of epilogue to this earliest chapter in the history of the Fall-doctrine, that, when the angel-myth had finally ceased to be regarded as the inspired record of the origin of human sin, its somewhat carnal character gradually evoked, in the Israel of the Mishnic period, a strong repugnance to that literal, and, historically considered, correct interpretation of it which had hitherto held the field. The idea of sexual intercourse between celestial spirits and the daughters of men came to be abhorrent to the pious Jew; hence the bené ha-’elohim were rationalised into ‘ sons of the judges ’ or ‘ of the mighty,’ that is, purely human beings of princely rank,? and their sin was regarded merely as the first instance of seduction. In the Middle Ages, the literal interpretation was revived by the authors of the Oabbalah, and made the foundation of wild theosophical romances ®; but the main body of Judaism, which had ceased to believe in angels as more than poetical personifications of the divine attributes, adhered to the rationalistic view until recent times. The compara- tive study of religions, whilst restoring the literal interpreta- Ali, 23;).U. infra, Lecture 11,"p: 55. 2 uv. infra, Lecture II, p. 79. 3 See the references given in the Jewish Encyclopaedia, V. 333, art. ‘Fall of Angels,’ and R. H. Charles, Book of Jubilees (1902), pp. 33 ff., note. Symmachus embodies this interpretation in the text, rendering piidsen 3 as viol rdv Suvacrevdvtwv. 4 Philo, however, characteristically allegorises the story, interpreting the lustful angels as being in reality ‘ the wicked, who slip into the name of angels, not knowing the daughters of right reason, the sciences and virtues, but captivated by the mortal offspring of mortal men, even pleasures, the bearers of no genuine beauty, which is seen by the under- standing alone, but of a spurious gracefulness, through which the senses are deceived’ (de gigant. iv). But, as usual, the allegorical significance of the narrative does not exclude its literal truth (7bid. ii.). Josephus (Ant. i. 3. 1 ) reproduces the story without theological or other comment. 5 Griinbaum, Gesammelie Aufsdtze zur Sprach- und Sagenkunde (1901), PD. 70,70. THE BEGINNINGS OF FALL-SPECULATION = 31 tion of the phrase béne ha-’elohim, has now dispelled any lingering traces of belief in the historical character of the story, within as without the modern Jewish Church.+ It is easy enough to dismiss this queer old legend, this superseded and forgotten Fall-story, as at the present day totally devoid of interest, except for the Orientalist and the student of folk-lore. But the time which we have spent upon its consideration will not have been wasted, if in the course of the discussion two points, which will play an important part in our final constructive synthesis, have been made to stand out with clearness; and this lecture may appropriately conclude with a summary re-formulation of them. The first is this—that, considered historically and with regard to the circumstances of its origin, the theory of the Fall and of Original Sin does not rest upon the Paradise- story of Genesis iii. Its true foundations are psychological, based on bed-rock facts of ethical and spiritual experience —the consciousness of the moral struggle, and the feeling of a ceaseless strain and tension between duty and the clamorous appetites, which ever and anon burst victoriously forth into crude external expression, whilst reason looks on in helpless dismay andshame. Video meliora proboque, Deteriora sequor *: ‘ the evil which I would not, that I do’ ’: the state of things described in these almost proverbial sayings may be taken for granted, as requiring no explana- tion, by the unspiritual and the thoughtless; but, when deeply pondered and brooded over by pure, reflective, and sensitive minds, it generates a mental atmosphere in which the predicate of evil tends to become detached from outer acts and transferred to the inner dispositions, even to the very essence, of the soul—an atmosphere in which the con- ception of penitence becomes invested with a new and deeper meaning. The ordinary man may feel ashamed of doing wrong: but the saint, endowed with a superior refinement of moral sensibility, and keener powers of introspection, is ashamed of being the kind of man who is liable to do wrong ; 1 For the history of the Watcher-story, and of the Fall-story based upon it, within the Christian Church, see Lecture III, p. 113 f. 2 Ovid, Met. vii. 21. 3 Rom. vii. 19. 32 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN and, the more complete his mastery over the rebellious impulses of his lower nature, the greater is the distress which the mere existence of these impulses tends to cause him. The ordinary man, if he repents at all, repents merely of what he does, the saint repents of what he is: hence is derived the standing paradox of sanctity, the fact that the consciousness of sin actually deepens in and through the process of liberation from its malignant power, and that it is precisely the most spotless of men—with the arresting exception of One Whom Christians believe to be more than man—who have always proclaimed themselves to be the ‘chief of sinners.’ This attitude of repentance of one’s self, translated into intellectual terms, becomes a belief in some kind of ‘radical evil’ inherent in human nature. But human nature was created by God, and the passionate ethical monotheism which is the heart of Judaism and Christianity alike cannot endure the idea that God is the author of evil ; hence it was concluded that evil in man must be due to some spontaneous revolt against the Divine Law, some voluntary aberration from the path marked out for man by his Creator—in other words, to a ‘ Fall’ of some kind. The necessity of a ‘Fall’ being thus established nothing remained but to identify it with some ‘ fontal sin ’ of man’s infancy, and the unnatural marriages of Gen. vi. seemed at first to be the catastrophe required. Whatever we may think of the validity of this regressive chain of reasoning, from the facts of the moral struggle back to the idea of an inherited taint and from that again to the concep- tion of a primordial sin, it is clear that, inasmuch as the first Fall-story was that of Gen. vi., the doctrines of the Fall and of Original Sin cannot be regarded as standing or falling with the historicity of Gen. ii. The fact is that recent research, which has disposed of the claims of these stories to represent literal historic fact, has simultaneously disposed of the idea that the Christian doctrines of Man and of Sin are logically based upon them. If the Fall-theory rested upon moral and religious experience at the time of its first appearance, and if, as we have seen, the Watcher-story and the Adam-story were subsequently and successively applied to it as what we may call decorative after-thoughts or THE BEGINNINGS OF FALL-SPECULATION 33 supposed historical verifications, it follows that, in principle, it must still claim to be based upon moral and religious experience—and for us, who know these ancient stories to be no more than folk-lore, upon moral and religious experi- ence only. Hence the assertion which has sometimes been made, to the effect that the idea of the Fall has been refuted by ‘ Biblical criticism,’ would seem to be very wide of the mark. 2 7 D >” 2 , i GAN’ dv d€dwx’ evvorav e€nyovpevos a A \ / » / ot mp@ra pev BAemovres EBAeTIOV wary, Kdvovtes OUK GKoVOV, GAN’ dveiparwr adXiyKiot pwopdatcr Tov paxpov Biov 4 > A 4 ” a €dupov etx mavra, KovTe mALWOu gets Sdpous mpoceirous Haav, od Evrovpylav’ KaTtwpuxes 8° Evarov wor’ ajauvpor pvUpenKes avTpwv ev wvxots avnAlors. hv 8° oddev adrois ove xelwaros TéKap ovr’ avdeuwdous pos ovTe KapTipov Ogpous BéBatov, GAA’ drep yvouns TO av €mpacoov, €ate 84 adi avroAds eya dorpwv €deréa tds te Suoxpirous Svcets. 36 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN Kal pv dpb pov, éfoxov codiopdarwr, e€ndpov avrois, ypapparwv TE ovvévets, pynuny 0 andvrwv, fovoopynrop epydynv. Kkalevéa mparos ev Cuyotor xvadadra CevyAatar SovAevorra odypaciv 0’, dws Ovntots peylorwy Suddoxou Moe Onyicreoy yévow)’, vf’ appar nyayov diAnviovs immous, GyaA pa THs UTEepTAoUTOU xALOAs. BadacodrAayxra 8 ottis dAXos avr’ énod Aworrep’ nope vavtidwy oxyjpara. . . 7a Aouad pov KAvovoa Pavpudoer tAéov, olas Téxvas Te Kal mOpous Eunodunv..... I will speak, not chiding mankind, but expounding the kindness that I showed them in my gifts. For, at the first, men seeing saw in vain, and hearing they heard not, but like unto dream-forms they mixed all things in wild confusion all their days. Naught they knew of brick-built houses, turned to face the sun, or of the joiner’s craft ; they dwelt underground, like the tiny ants, in the sunless recesses of caverns. Nor was there any certain sign for them of winter, or bloomy spring, or fruitful summer, until I showed them the risings of the stars and their settings hard to be discerned. Number I found out for them, noblest of inventions, and groupings of letters, and memory of all things, creative mother of know- ledge. I first yoked beasts of burden, and made them thralls to collar and pack-saddle, that they might relieve mortals of their heaviest toils ; and to the chariot I harnessed docile steeds, the splendid appanage of luxurious wealth. Nor did any other devise the mariners’ canvas-winged wains that roam the sea.... Thou wilt wonder yet more, having heard the rest of my tale, what arts and contrivances I framed. He goes on to claim credit for having originated medicine, the art of divination, and (like Azazél) metallurgy :-— evepbe 5é yOovos Kexpuppev avOpwro.ow wdedAnpara, xaAKdv, aldnpov, apyupov, xpvaov Te Tis proevev av maporlev eLeupeiv epod ; ovdeis, odd’ olda, 1H pdrnv drvVaat OédAwv. Bpaxet S¢ pv0w wdvra avdAAnBdnv padbe, maoat Téxvat Bpototow ex ITpopnbéws. And who before me could pretend to have discovered the treasures hid beneath the earth, brass, iron, silver, and gold ? no one, I wot, unless he willed to babble foolishly. In one short sentence learn the whole story : all the arts came to mortals from Prometheus. (Prometheus Vinctus, 447-468, 476-7, 500-6.) In the Greek myth, knowledge is a blessing which the tyrant Zeus desires to withhold from men because he hates them ; in the Jewish story, it is, relatively to finite and imperfect beings, a curse from which the Lord would fain shield his children. II. THE ADAM-STORY AND THE ‘EVIL IMAGINATION’ Love is the source both of viriue and of sin ‘Neé creator né creatura mai,’ comincio ei, ‘ figliuol, fu senza amore, o naturale o d’animo; e tuil sai. Lo natural € sempre senza errore, ma l’altro puote errar per malo obbietto, O per poco o per troppo di vigore. Mentre ch’egli € ne’primi ben diretto, e ne’secondi sé stesso misura, esser non puo cagion di mal diletto ; ma, quando al mal si torce, o con pit cura o con men che non dee corre nel bene, contra il fattore adopra sua fattura. Quinci comprender puoi ch’esser conviene amor sementa in voi d’ogni virtute, e d’ogni operazion che merta pene.’ DaNTE, Purgatorio, xvii. gI-105. LECTURE If THE ADAM-STORY AND THE “EVIL IMAGINATION ’ Rom. v. 12: ‘Through one man sin entered into the world, and death through sin.’ Gen. vi. 5: ‘ And the Lord saw that the wickedness of man was great in the earth, and that every imagination of the thoughts of his heart was only evil continually.’ IT was assumed in our last lecture that the Paradise-story of Gen. ii., despite its traditional employment in later Judaism and Christianity as a basis for the doctrines of the Fall and of Original Sin, did not in the mind of the original compiler of the Yahwistic source either explicitly or im- plicitly contain these doctrines, in any of their developed or technical forms.1 This assumption must now be justified by a critical examination of that narrative which for many centuries was venerated by Christians as the literal historic record : Of man’s first disobedience, and the fruit Of that forbidden Tree, whose mortal taste Brought Death into the world, and all our woe.? The cadence of these stately lines should remind us of a preliminary warning, which despite its frequent repetition by commentators is not even yet superfluous, namely, that which bids us resolutely banish Milton from our thoughts. Probably most educated Englishmen who are not theological specialists still tend unconsciously to read the highly systematised doctrinal background of ‘ Paradise Lost’ into the artless simplicity of the primitive Scripture. But the student who is on his guard against the subtle influence which half-remembered poetic echoes may exercise upon tecture 1. pir; 2 Milton, Paradise Lost, 1. 1. 40 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN the mind will see at a glance that the splendour of Milton's mighty epic bears much the same relation to the original story of Gen. iii. as Michael Angelo’s basilica of St. Peter bears to its humble predecessor, the wattled oratory built by the earliest Christians upon the same site ; and it is the original story alone which has any significance at this stage of our enquiry. To discover this significance, we must be prepared to examine the narrative without presuppositions, and with a certain necessary independence of its familiar and hallowed associations. The Paradise-story examined. Approaching the story in this spirit, we naturally enquire first of all, What, in the mind of the Yahwistic author, was 1 If the following exposition of the Paradise-story, insisting, as it does, upon the imperfect conception of the moral character of God which is involved in the idea of His grudging His creatures the possession of knowledge, appears to any readers difficult at first sight to reconcile with belief in the authority of the Old Testament as ‘ written for our learning, that we through patience and comfort of the scriptures might have hope’ (Rom. xv. 4), I would ask the attention of such readers to the following words, which I am permitted to quote from a sermon preached by Dr. H. L. Goudge, Regius Professor of Divinity in the University of Oxford : ‘ There is a distinction which we must often remember as we read the Old Testament. It is the distinction between the original meaning of the words and the meaning which they now have for us. In early days the Jews were accustomed to treat their literature very freely. They com- bined old materials in a new way ; they corrected and added to what they found: and, as their interest in religion deepened, they put new and higher meanings upon old and familiar words. When the Christian Church took over the Old Testament from the Jews, it used a similar freedom. It did not, indeed, further alter the words which it found ; we read them to-day much as our Lord must have read them. But the fuller knowledge which the Church possessed enabled her teachers to find in the Old Testament a deeper meaning than even the Jews had found ; and it is with this deeper meaning that we are chiefly concerned to-day. What the words originally meant often matters little; what they mean as part of the Bible matters a great deal’ (italics mine). In accordance with the method explained in Lecture I, p. 12, the present portion of our enquiry is of a purely historical and scientific, not of a dogmatic or homi- letic nature ; and it is therefore concerned solely with the question what the Paradise-story originally meant, in the ninth century B.c., for the Yahwist writer when he selected it from a mass of Babylonian traditions for embodiment in his history of God’s dealings with man; it does not touch upon the question, what this story means now as part of the Christian Bible, for instructed members of the Christian Church. a ADAM AND THE ‘EVIL IMAGINATION ’ AI the condition of Adam and Eve! as first created? It is clear that the physical and mental state of the first man is not conceived as being very far exalted above that of the beasts, because the sole object of the creation of animals, according to the Yahwistic narrative of c. il. 18-25, is to provide Adam with a suitable companion, and the various existing species of brutes represent so many unsuccessful experiments made to this end by the Creator?; who, indeed, only hits upon the idea of building up a rib drawn 1<«Adam’ (ddham, OVS) is not really a proper name at all; it is the ordinary Hebrew word for ‘ man,’ homo. ‘ Eve’ is a proper name, but its Hebrew form is Hawwah (30, which in the LXX becomes Eda and in the Latin ‘ Heva’ or ‘ Eva,’ whence the English‘ Eve’). The Yahwist connects Hawwah with the verb /ayah (MN), to ‘ exist’ or ‘live,’ and explains that this name was conferred on the first woman by her husband “ because she was the mother of all living’ (iii. 20, which comes in rather oddly after the account of the first sin, and may be misplaced) ; but this etymology may well be an ex post facto invention, and it is not improbable that Hawwah may be a ‘ depotentiated’ Phoenician goddess of the underworld, as the name ym (HWT) occurs on a Punic tablet described by Lidzbarski, Ephemeris fiiy semit. Epigraphik, i. pp. 26 ff.; see also G. A. Cooke, North-Sem. Inscr., p. 135. To convey the full atmosphere of this primitive folk-tale, we should, perhaps, designate the two human actors in it as ‘Man’ (with a capital M) and ‘ Hawwah’ respectively ; but, as the use of ‘ Adam’ and ‘ Eve’ will be inevitable in those sections of our enquiry which are concerned with the Christian development of the Fall-doctrine, it seems best for the sake of verbal consistency to use them here. 2 In v. 18 Yahweh realises that solitude will be injurious to Adam, and resolves to make him a suitable mate. He therefore (v. 19) forms out of the ground ‘ every beast of the field and every fowl of the air,’ and brings them in succession to Adam ‘ to see what he would call them,’ 7.e. to see whether he would manifest his acceptance of any one of them as a life-companion by addressing it with some endearing epithet. The man apparently greets them in turn with ejaculations of a disparaging nature, each of which adheres to the particular animal which provoked it (for the primitive Hebrew, words are semi-material things which may become attached to living agents—compare the story of Jacob’s theft of the blessing designed for Esau) and becomes the animal’s permanent generic name (‘ whatsoever the man called every living creature, that was the name thereof’). See Skinner, Genesis, ICC., p. 67f.; the patristic idealisation of the passage is discussed in Lecture V, p. 361 f. It is hardly necessary to point out that this story, according to which man was created before the brutes, and was, in fact, for some appreciable time the only living organism in the world, is totally irreconcilable with the later narrative of P (i. 20-27), according to which man was only created at the close of the sixth day, after all the lower animals. 42 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN from Adam’s own body into a separate person when he finds that none of his sub-human productions prove congenial to a being endowed with reason. Manis thus a frail creature, child-like in his ignorance and simplicity, qualities which are manifested and symbolised by his nakedness. His home is Yahweh’s own private pleasaunce, set in the faery realm of ‘Edhen towards the sun-rising, shaded by the solemn love- liness of the primaeval forest, and watered by the perennial fount which feeds the four great rivers of the ancient world, Pishon, Gihon, Hiddeqel, and Euphrates1!; in its midst stand up two trees endowed with magical properties, the Tree of Life and the Tree of the Knowledge of Good and Evil. His days are spent in the light and pleasant labour of dressing and keeping *the Garden. Apart from this duty, one law only is imposed upon him—the prohibition against eating of the Tree of Knowledge, the taste of which, he is told, is fraught with instant death. This detail raises a question of considerable importance for the true understanding of the story—the question of the moral condition of Adam and Eve before the first trans- gression. It is clear that the story contains no formal doctrine of ‘ Original Righteousness,’ such as was later imagined in order to accentuate the malevolence of the first sin. But, on the other hand, the state of our first parents cannot be said to have been one merely of non-moral innocence: for they are conscious of at least two duties, those of doing a reasonable amount of work in the garden 1 Hiddegel is undoubtedly the Tigris; it seems most probable that Pishén and Gihon are the Ganges and the Nile respectively (the traditional identifications ; see Skinner, [CC., p. 64 ff.). A prosaic critic might find a difficulty in the fact that the Euphrates, the Tigris, the Ganges, and the Nile have not and never have had, a common source ; but the topography of Fairyland need not be taken too seriously. For an attempt to extract definite spatial determinations from these poetic fantasies, see F. Delitzsch, Wo lag das Paradies ? (1881). 2 That is ‘ guarding’: against what sort of dangers, in an unfallen universe, is not clear. $ It may be observed that the convention of describing and depicting the fatal fruit as an “ apple’ (which goes back at least as far as Venantius Fortunatus in the seventh century A.p., who speaks of the ‘ pomum noxiale ’—v. supra, p. 9, n. 3) is purely arbitrary. So far as the Yahwist visualised the magic trees at all, he must have thought of them as palms (like the sacred palms which appear in conventionalised form on many Babylonian sculptures) and of their fruit as dates. ADAM AND THE ‘EVIL IMAGINATION’ = 43 and of abstaining from the forbidden fruit. It would seem truer to say that they are conceived as being in principle moral and responsible agents, but exempted by their ignorance and by the primitive simplicity of their paradisal state from most of the painful conflicts between conscience and appetite which more complicated conditions of life necessarily involve ; they are in possession of the forms or categories of ‘ Right’ and ‘ Wrong,’ but their acquaintance with the content of these conceptions is imperfect and limited. | It is natural to enquire at this point ‘ If Adam and Eve are conceived in the story as possessed, even before their fatal act, of the knowledge of the distinction between right and wrong, what is meant by the description of the sinister Tree as “‘ the Tree of the Knowledge of Good and Evil” ?’ The answer to this question seems to lie in the fact that the Hebrew words for ‘ good’ and ‘ evil’ (¢6bh and va‘) do not necessarily or primarily signify moral good and evil: their fundamental meaning is rather that of ‘ good’ and ‘ evil’ relatively to the physical well-being of man, the expressions being transferred to virtue and vice only in so far as the consequences of these two states are advantageous or the reverse. In this phrase, therefore, ¢6bh and ra‘ may well be translated ‘ beneficial’ or ‘ useful,’ and ‘ noxious’ or ‘‘harm- ful,’ respectively. The knowledge, therefore, of ‘ good’ and ‘evil,’ that is of ‘ beneficial’ and ‘ noxious’ things, which Yahweh forbids his creatures to acquire, would appear to be what we should call ‘ scientific ’ knowledge rather than moral illumination. Hedoesnot wish them to know anything of the arts of civilisation, or of the sciences which make society and culture possible : he desires to keep them in happy, child-like ignorance, infinitely inferior to himself, but safeguarded from the sorrows which the increase of knowledge brings in its train. We shall see how this conception of the effects of the ill-omened tree lights up the whole story, as it appeared to the mind of the Yahwistic writer. Once more we are brought face to face with the Prometheus-moti/, which we have already noted as running through ‘ Enoch’s’ decoration of the Watcher-legend—the belief, that is, in a Divine jealousy which grudges man the possession of scientific 44 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN knowledge, and exacts stern punishment for its illicit acquisition. The main duty, therefore, of Adam and Eve, in their primal state, is to be ignorant : ‘ where ignorance is bliss, ’tis folly to be wise.’ Into this paradise of nescience there enters the sinister shape of the serpent, the most subtle of all the beasts of the field which Yahweh ’elohim had made, the incarnation of the irrepressible spirit of intellectual curiosity. There can be no doubt that in the mind of J it is the literal serpent that is meant (at this early date, it is to be presumed that only one? specimen of the serpent race was in existence, the primitive progenitor of all subsequent members of the tribe). In the text as it stands, there is no suggestion what- “ever that he is Satan in visible form or that he is indwelt by Satan, or that he embodies any personal principle of evil external to or other than himself. With treacherous affability, he engages our unsuspecting ancestress in con- versation. By adroitly exaggerating the extent of the divine prohibition (‘ Hath God said, Ye shall not eat of any tree of the garden? ’), he lures the too communicative woman into a discussion of the forbidden fruit and its properties: and points out (apparently with perfect truth, as we gather from the sequel) that the motives which have impelled her master to enact this prohibition are of anything but a disinterested nature, and that his warning as to the mortal effects of the tree is an empty threat. Yahweh is haunted by a jealous fear lest men, through the acquisition of scientific knowledge, should attain to a position of equality with himself, and he therefore endeavours to keep them in the dark by means of baseless menaces. Eve is deeply impressed by the uncanny creature’s knowledge of these high mysteries, and her longing for wisdom is rein- forced by the demands of natural appetite. She tastes the seductive fruit, and induces Adam to share her transgression. The immediate effects of the magic food are of a somewhat unexpected nature; the man and the woman become tSee' Lectures] pp. 251. 2 Or possibly two, if the Yahwist thought that sexual distinctions existed in the brute creation at this date ; in which case it may be presumed that the male serpent is here meant. But it is extremely improbable that our author had thought the matter out with this degree of minuteness, ——_—_—_— —-~ -. ADAM AND THE ‘EVIL IMAGINATION ’ 45 suddenly conscious of the facts of sex, of which, it would seem, they had hitherto been ignorant, with the concomitant sense of physical shame: which impels them to enwreath their bodies, hitherto innocently naked, with extemporised aprons of fig-leaves.1 Then an ominous sound falls on their ears—they hear the approaching footsteps * of the Creator, who, with the most naive anthropomorphism, is represented, like an earthly nobleman, as walking in his garden ‘in the cool of the day.’ Instead of running to meet him, as on the occasions of his previous visits, with the artless affection of children, the conscience-stricken pair hasten to hide them- selves in the undergrowth ; but are detected and summoned forth to give an account of this undutiful conduct. The man incautiously alleges his nudity as an excuse, thus betraying the fatal fact of his sin, with which he is imme- diately taxed. He confesses it, having no other resource, but, with unchivalrous cowardice, hastens to lay the blame on his wife, who in turn accuses the serpent; the latter, unable to transfer the responsibility to any fourth party, maintains a guilty silence. Then the judgment is pro- nounced. The light and pleasant labour of tending the fertile garden is to be exchanged by Adam for the heart- breaking task of wringing a scanty sustenance from a thorny and stubborn earth. The woman is punished for the unlawfully acquired knowledge of sex by subjection to the pangs of childbirth, which, despite its accompanying pain, the deepest instincts of her soul will drive her to desire ; whilst the serpent is deprived of the upright posture assumed to have been enjoyed by him hitherto, and is condemned to what our author evidently regards as a painful and igno- minious method of locomotion, to food of dust, and toa condition of perpetual feud with the human race. There follows the enigmatic sentence traditionally known as the Protevangelium, in which it is predicted that the seed of 1 It seems unnecessary to attribute (as apparently do St. Augustine, de civ. Det, xiv. 17, and Milton, Par. Lost, ix, 1o11 ff.) strictly aphrodisiac effects to the forbidden fruit. For the sex-motif in Fall-stories and Fall- speculation generally, see Lecture I, p. 34; II, pp. 58, 66. 2 The word Sp, rendered by the English versions as ‘ voice’ (‘ the voice of the Lord God walking in the garden’), should be translated ‘sound,’ as RV. marg.; see Skinner in loc. 46 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN the woman will crush the serpent’s head, whilst the serpent will crush or bruise his heel. The mystical interpretation of this saying as a foreshadowing of Redemption is well known, and, within the sphere of devotion, doubtless legitimate ; the critical student, however, cannot feel con- fident that the original significance of the passage is more than aetiological, designed to explain the instinctive mutual antipathy which exists between men and snakes. The primal curse having been thus pronounced, feelings of compassion seem, for a time, to come uppermost in the mind of the offended Deity ; for he condescends to manu- facture, apparently with his own hands, garments of skins } to replace the drapery of fig-leaves with which the guilty pair had clothed themselves. We are not told who slew the animals from which these skins were procured ; it may be surmised that a paragraph narrating the beginnings of animal sacrifice, or of hostility between the animals (other than the serpent) and man, has here dropped out of the record. Then the feeling of jealous alarm for his own position once more revives in Yahweh's breast. He suddenly thinks of the possibility that man, having acquired poten- tialities of scientific knowledge equal to that of his Creator, may take the further step of seizing immortality by tasting of the Tree of Life—a step which would make Adam Yahweh’s equal, and practically annul the judgment just pronounced against him.? To ensure effectually against this undesirable contingency, he expels the man and the woman from the garden, and places at its gateway the Cherubim and the whirling sword of flame, to bar for ever man’s access to the Tree of Life. This wonderful saga, both when read in the matchless English of the Authorised Version, and still more in the Homeric simplicity and directness of the Hebrew original, is instinct with a peculiar power and impressiveness, which is felt even by those for whom the story has no theological significance. And it may truly be claimed that, by removing 1 For the allegorisation of these ‘coats of skins’ by the Greek Fathers, v. infra, Lecture IV, pp. 229, 251, 275, 285. 2 v.22: ‘ Behold, the man is become as one of us’ (i.e. of the ’eléhim, Yahweh and his fellow gods) ‘ to know good and evil.’ ADAM AND THE ‘EVIL IMAGINATION’ = 47 the baroque magnificence with which the genius of Milton had gilded it, and bringing to light the brilliant, yet grave, archaic colouring of the authentic story, fresh from the Semitic world of the ninth century before Christ, modern criticism has rather enhanced than diminished the splendour of its literary and artistic appeal. It fulfils in a high degree the function assigned by one of our great teachers to the myths of Plato, that of evoking ‘ Transcendental Feeling ’ in a singularly pure and poignant form!: it speaks like solemn organ-music to the heart, awakening blended and formless emotions of adoration, awe, and penitence. From this point of view alone, it is impossible not to perceive the enormous superiority of the Adam-story of Gen. iii. to its earlier rival, the Watcher-story of Gen. vi., a superiority which is reflected by the measure in which the frieze of gorgeous pictures conjured up by Milton out of the former surpasses the weak and bombastic drama (‘ Heaven and Earth ’) founded by Byron upon the latter. And, on any showing, there can be no doubt that religion was the gainer by the victory of Gen. iii. It is not, indeed, necessary to discuss the question of its historicity before an audience such as this ; it has long since been recognised by educated Christians that the sunlight of Eden, which falls upon the magic trees, the talking serpent, and the man-like figure of the Creator, walking in his garden in the cool of the day, is The light that never was on sea or land.? A few words, however, devoted to the questions of its origin and significance will involve no waste of time, for they will confirm the judgment provisionally formulated in Lecture I, as well with regard to the Paradise-story as to the tale of the fallen Watchers, that these narratives are to be viewed as facades successively attached to, rather than foundations 1 See J. A. Stewart, The Myths of Plato, Introduction, 4 (p. 39). 2 In this connexion, it is perhaps worth noting that the Fall-story of Gen. vi. has widely been thought to have subconsciously inspired a line of Coleridge’s dream-poem, Kubla Khan: ‘ A savage place ! as holy and enchanted As e’er beneath a waning moon was haunted By woman wailing for her demon-lover.’ 8 Wordsworth, Stanzas on Peele Castle. 48 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN which carry the weight of, that theory of the origin of evil which is known as the doctrine of the Fall and of Original Sin. It may be said at once that archaeology so far has failed to discover the ultimate source from which J obtained the story, though a few uncertain parallels to one or other of its characteristic details have been discovered in Babylonian and Zoroastrian literature.t Nor does its internal criticism afford us much help in ascertaining the date and place of its origin. A careful examination of it raises difficulties to which no obvious answer is forthcoming. If Adam was allowed to eat of all the trees of the Garden, except only of the Tree of Knowledge, why did he not eat of the Tree of Life, and so secure immortality, before the ‘ Fall’? Why does the threat of instant death to follow upon the taste of the Tree of Knowledge fail to secure fulfilment, with the result that the serpent’s disparagement of the Creator’s good faith is apparently vindicated? And, lastly, what were the motives which actuated the animal tempter in his gratuitous interference with the happy condition of Adam and Eve? As the story stands, the serpent appears to come very badly out of the affair. He loses various gratifying privileges, and gains nothing whatever—a result which his demonic subtlety might reasonably have been expected to foresee. These inconcinnities suggest that the Paradise- story contains two narratives imperfectly fused—whether by J himself, or by an earlier writer, cannot now be determined. Sir James Frazer has suggested? that one story may have embodied a theme widely disseminated in the folk-lore of the African peoples, the idea that God sends a message to man informing him how to attain immortality, and employing some animal as his messenger—and that man’s present condition of mortality is due to the fact that the messenger spitefully falsified or suppressed the message. 1 See Skinner, [CC., pp. 90-93; and W. L. Wardle, Isvael and Babylon (1925), Cc. vii., ‘ Paradise and the Fall,’ which contains a criticism of the attempt made by S. Langdon to find a Babylonian version of the Fall- story in his Sumerian Epic of Paradise, the Flood, and the Fall of Man (1915). For a defence of Langdon’s theories, Wardle refers to an article by Mercer, in the Journal of the Society of Oriental Research, iii, 86-88— a reference which I have not been able to verify. 2 Folk-lore in the Old Testament (1919), i. 2 (Pp. 45-77). ADAM AND THE ‘EVIL IMAGINATION’ — 49 The other may have been based on another well-known legend, which accounts for the supposed immortality of the serpent by the fact that it periodically sheds its skin. It is conceivable that the original story may have combined these two ideas by telling how the serpent was commissioned by God to advise Adam to eat of the Tree of Life and so acquire immortality, and how through envy he perverted the divine message by persuading Adam to eat of the Tree of Death, and appropriated the gift of immortality by eating of the Tree of Life himself. This, however, remains no more than a brilliant conjecture. The origin of the story is thus obscure: but the significance which it bore for the minds of those who embodied it in the great Prophetic history of God’s dealings with man can be determined with much greater certainty. It has been already pointed out that the most important brima facie difficulties inhering in the story are cleared up if we assume that ‘ good’ and ‘evil’ in the name of the fatal Tree mean physical, not moral, good and evil respectively, and that the sin of the first men consisted in snatching the treasure of scientific and cultural knowledge which the Creator had not destined for them. This con- clusion is strikingly confirmed by the tenor of chapter iv., which narrates the first rude beginnings of culture, following immediately upon the expulsion from Paradise of the ancestors of the human race; for it is precisely with this growth of civilisation that the two first instances of human cruelty and ferocity are connected. The development of agriculture and of cattle-keeping, with its corollary, the discovery? of the only kind of sacrifice acceptable to Yahweh, brings in its train the first murder, that of Abel.? The discovery of the art of working in metals by Tubal-Cain 3 leads to the fatal invention of the sword, and there follows the repulsive scene in which Lamech is apparently repre- sented as brandishing the newly forged weapon, which he owes to the ingenuity of his son, before his wives Adah 1 If it be thought probable, as suggested above, that a paragraph narrating the beginnings of animal sacrifice has dropped out between iii. 20 and 21, for the words ‘ discovery of’ should be substituted ‘ acquisi- tion of the means of offering.’ 2 Gen. iv. 2-8. ® Gen. iv. 22. 50 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN and Zillah, and exulting in the bloody vengeance which he has taken for some trifling slight.1_ It would seem that, for J’s sombre philosophy of history, civilisation and culture are, on the whole, a disastrous mistake. The undertones of pessimism and world-weariness which pervade the early sections of his narrative are easily discernible by an ear attuned to the finer vibrations of an unstudied literary style, and it can hardly be doubted that he would have given a whole-hearted assent to the Preacher’s melancholy aphorism ‘ He that increaseth knowledge increaseth sorrow.’ ? It will be seen that for this writer the first sin was indeed a ‘ Fall,’ in virtue of its consequences, namely, the forfeiture of Paradise, the loss of the opportunity of obtain- ing immortality, and man’s resulting servitude to hard work and death. But the causal link between the primal trans- gression and man’s subsequent misfortunes is clearly of an external and, so to speak, mechanical nature: these misfortunes are represented as due, partly to the arbitrary decree of a jealous Creator, concerned to safeguard his unique prerogatives against a possible rival, and partly to the complicated conditions of social life inevitably engendered by the growth of ‘ scientific knowledge.’ There is not a word in the narrative to suggest that the first sin produced a reflex psychological effect upon Adam and Eve, or infected them with an znterioy corruption or infirmity cap- able of being transmitted by physiological heredity to their descendants: that is to say, there is not a word which implies the theological doctrine of ‘ Original Sin’ in any of its historic forms. The mysterious phrase which has been sometimes interpreted as imputing to Cain an innate bias towards evil (‘if thou doest not well, sin coucheth at the door ’—at the door of what, is not explained) is textually so corrupt that its original meaning is irrecoverable, and nothing can legitimately be built upon it?; even if it be 1 Gen. iv. 23. # Eccles! 1. 15, 3’ Gen.iv. 7. Itshould, perhaps, be added that the reading of LXX (ovx €av 6p0ds mpoceveyKys, 6pOds Sé w7 SreAns, Huapres ; Hovyacov—' If thou didst offer rightly, but didst not rightly divide [the oblation], hast thou not sinned ? be silent’) gives a sense which is perfectly intelligible, and may well be original; it represents Yahweh as insisting upon ceremonial ADAM AND THE ‘EVIL IMAGINATION’ § 51 insisted that these words must at least be understood as attributing an evil nature to Cain, the verse is entirely silent as to any inheritance of this by Cain from his parents, and in no way excludes the supposition that it may have been formed by unrecorded acts of free, but wrongful, self- determination committed prior to the murder of Abel. We can, indeed, read the story in the light of “ Original Sin,’ or read back the idea of ‘ Original Sin’ into the story— if we choose; but we must recognise that this can only be done by the employment of a mystical or allegorical, not a scientific, method of interpretation. In the narrative of Gen. iii. and iv. as it stands, the only ‘hereditary’ influences which play any part are such as fall under the general description of ‘ social heredity,’ which affects the individual from without, through the medium of laws, customs, insti- tutions, traditions, conventions, and fashions, and which is to be sharply distinguished from ‘ biological heredity,’ which determines the individual from within, through the invisible psychic characters borne by the fundamental germ-plasm from which he springs. THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE FALL-THEORY IN CONNEXION WITH THE PARADISE-STORY We conclude, then, that in the intention of J, the writer to whom we owe its embodiment in our Scriptures, the Paradise-story was meant to narrate what may be called a ‘ Fall,’ in an external or dramatic sense—that is, an act, of tBpis or presumption which brought the Golden Age to an end: but that it does not contain the idea of a moral infirmity or corruption transmitted by biological heredity, an idea which is the necessary basis of the doctrine of ‘Original Sin’ in all its forms. It must be remembered, however, that simple minds would find it difficult to distinguish clearly between ‘ social’ and ‘ biological’ heredity, in the sense defined above, and that the former conception correctness in every stage of the sacrificial action, not merely in the first. But, so understood, the verse ciearly contains even less sugges- tion of ‘ hereditary sinfulness ’ than it does in the Hebrew version. 52 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN might well be expected to melt insensibly into the latter, a transformation which would accomplish itself with especial facility in an intellectual world still subconsciously saturated, despite the work of the prophets, by the old conception of evil as a quasi-material contagion. It will be appropriate to subjoin a few words with regard to the steps by which this metamorphosis was actually effected. It was pointed out in Lecture I that the Fall-theory, in its earliest and vaguest form as a belief in a ‘ first sin’ of some kind which introduced an undefined poison into the stock of humanity, would seem to have been first connected with the Angel-story of Gen. vi., and that its attachment to the Adam-story was in the nature of an afterthought. It> must be frankly admitted that any attempt to reconstruct the process whereby the Fall-theory became firmly anchored to the Adam-story must necessarily be conjectural as regards its earlier stages, owing to the paucity of literary data for the period between Nehemiah and the Maccabees. We can affirm with certainty that the process did in fact take place, and that the Adam-story did, almost though not quite completely,! extrude the Angel-story from its position as the popularly accepted Fall-narrative, during the last two centuries before Christ: references to the pseudepigraphic passages which mark the stages of this silent revolution were given in our last lecture, and need not be repeated here. But it must be confessed that the pre-Maccabean beginnings of this process are at present veiled in obscurity. If, however, the provisional nature of all speculations as to the course taken by this development before the epoch at which it can be controlled through written evidence be borne in mind, it will be permissible to claim as much certainty as is possible under the circumstances for the following propositions : (1) The ruling idea of the original narrative, that knowledge is intrinsically disastrous, presupposes a very primitive and naive philosophy of life, and must have been obscured and forgotten by the time that speculation on the origin of evil began in earnest, after the Exile. It can hardly have survived the rise to power and influence of the Pee Lectureslit prin it 2 Lecture I, pp. 28-30. ADAM AND THE ‘EVIL IMAGINATION’ = 53 ‘wise men’ (hakhamim) and the tendency to hypostatise and almost to deify Wisdom (hokhmah). This idea once out of the way, the command to abstain from the fruit of a particular tree could be re-interpreted as a simple test of man’s obedience to his Creator, and the first sin could be viewed as deriving its significance and guilt merely from the fact that it was a deliberate transgression of a known law. In this way, we may suppose, the story was brought into harmony with strictly ethical ideas of God and goodness, and fitted to become the basis of a reasoned and logical Fall-theory. (2) It would seem that the first step in the construction of such a reasoned Fall-theory on the basis of the Paradise- narrative consisted in the affirmation of a causal connexion between Adam’s sin and the fact of human liability to death, that is, in the reading into the story of the hypothesis that man at his creation was endowed with the gift of immortality, but that this was withdrawn from him as part of the punish- ment for his transgression.! In fact, the Scriptural text says nothing of the kind: it implies, on the contrary, that man was created mortal, formed of the dust and destined to return to it, though he might have made himself immortal by eating of the Tree of Life, even after his sin; and that it was precisely in order to keep him mortal that Yahweh expelled him from the Garden and posted a cherubic guard to prevent his return. The point of Yahweh’s warning in ii. 17 as to the fatal consequences which would follow a breach of his command is, not that man would become mortal after being immortal, but that man, mortal by nature and fated sooner or later to return to dust, would suffer death forthwith as a punishment for his sin (‘7m the day that thou eatest thereof thou shalt surely die’) instead of living out his life to a ripe old age and being re-absorbed into his parent earth through a painless dissolution. It is the ruthless immediacy of the threatened death, not the mere fact of mortality (to which Adam was in any case subject by virtue of his creaturely nature), which constitutes the spear-head of the menace. It may be thought that the literal non-fulfilment 1 This theory seems to underlie the words of our first text, Rom. v. 12 ; v. infra, Lecture III, p. 126 f. 54 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN of this warning, on which we have already commented, ought to have presented as patent a difficulty to the Jews of the post-exilic age as it does to us. But it must be remembered that thinkers who approached the story of Gen. ii. and iii. in a spirit of uncritical devotion would find it easy to surmount this difficulty by supposing that, whilst the taste of the Tree of Knowledge was intrinsically fraught with death, its fatal operation was suspended for some nine centuries by a special exercise of Divine mercy, and only allowed to take effect after Adam had lived for the best part of a millennium. Hence the son of Sirach, writing in the first quarter of the second century before Christ, is already able to affirm a direct causal relation between the first sin and the fact of human death, though his misogynist tendency leads him to saddle Eve with the sole responsibility for our woes : From a woman was the beginning of sin, and because of her we all die. This aphorism cannot, indeed, be quoted as evidence for the existence in 180 B.c. of a doctrine of hereditary sinful- ness, as distinct from hereditary mortality ; for the recovery of the Hebrew original of this part of Ecclesiasticus has shown that the phrase ‘ From a woman was the beginning of sin’ only means that Eve’s sin was chronologically the first to be committed in human history, and does not imply that it was the cause of all subsequent sin.? It is probable, however, that the distinction between merely chronological and directly causal antecedence, even if consciously realised, would soon tend to become blurred in the non-speculative Jewish mind; and the idea of inherited mortality would draw to itself, by a kind of capillary attraction, the floating idea of inherited sinfulness, so that both alike would come 1 Ecclus. xxv. 24: a0 yuvatkos apx?) GuapTias, kal du’ adriy amoOvicKopev mavres. 2 The word apy stands for an origina] npn, which means ‘ temporal beginning ’ rather than ‘ efficient cause’ ; see Brown, Driver and Briggs, » Hebrew and English Lexicon of the O.T., s.v., p. 321. For the Hebrew text of Ecclus. xxv. 24, see JQR, xii. pp. 456 ff. (Schechter) ; Facsimiles of the Fragments of the Book of Ecclesiasticus in Hebrew (Oxford and Cambridge University Presses, 1901). ADAM AND THE ‘EVIL IMAGINATION ’ 55 to be regarded as direct consequences of the primordial sin of the first man. It can safely be affirmed that this process had been consummated, at least in some Jewish circles, by the beginning of the Christian era. Even if the famous saying of the Wisdom of Solomon: God created man for incorruption And made him an image of his own proper being ; But by the envy of the devil death entered into the world, And they that are of his portion make trial thereof 1} be interpreted as referring solely to physical death, the existence, at an epoch roughly coinciding with the life of Christ, of a fairly well-defined doctrine affirming that Adam’s sin was the cause of spiritual death in his descendants— that is, of an embryonic doctrine of Original Sin—is proved by its explicit assertion in the Book of the Secrets of Enoch, in a passage describing a vision of the lowest hell which unrolled itself before the eyes of the terrified patriarch. In this abyss, he says, ‘I saw all our forefathers from the beginning with Adam and Eve, and I sighed, and wept, and spake of the ruin caused by their wickedness ; Woe is me Sor my infirmity and that of my forefathers. And I meditated in my heart, and said: Blessed is the man who was not born, or having been born has never sinned before the face of the Lord, so that he should not come into this place, and bear the yoke of this place!’ ? Before we leave the consideration of the Adamic Fall- doctrine as it appears in the Jewish Apocalypses—if ideas so hazy and fluctuating as were those of Adam’s guilt and its melancholy inherited consequences in pre-Christian Judaism may legitimately be described as a ‘ doctrine ’— certain developments and variations of it, which were not without influence in the formation of Christian thought on 1 Wisdom ii. 23, 24: Ort 6 Beds Extisev TOV avOpwrov en’ adbapoia, Kal eikova THs idlas (dudTnTOS emroinoev adrov' Pbdvw S5é SiaBdAov Odvaros eiopAOev els Tov Kdopov, meipatovor dé avrov ot THs Exeivouv peptdos Ores. 2 2 Enoch c. 40. It will be noticed that these words leave a loophole for the idea of human free-will. Like the Christian second Council of Orange and the Council of Trent, the Slavonic Enoch holds strongly that the taint inherited from Adam and Eve is not so powerful as to destroy the individual’s responsibility for his own fate, 56 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN this subject, deserve to be briefly mentioned. The first and most important of these consists in the growth of an exalted theory of the state of unfallen man, which represents a striking departure from the picture of a frail and ignorant creature, not so very much higher than the beasts, contained in the text of Gen. ii. and ili. The belief that Adam before the ‘ Fall’ was, not merely in a position to acquire immor- tality, but actually immortal, naturally suggested the ascription to him of other physical, mental, and moral en- dowments of a supernatural kind, thus eventually giving rise to the idea of the original perfection of man, an idea known in its moral aspect to later Christian theology as that of ‘ Original Justice’ or ‘ Righteousness.’ The growth of this conception was assisted by two factors: firstly, the tendency already mentioned, to heighten the bliss of Paradise and the supposed virtues of its inhabitants in order to bring into stronger relief the wilful malice of the first sin and the disastrous nature of its consequences ; secondly, the popular diffusion of versions of the Paradise-story, parallel to but more riotously imaginative and fantastic than the com- paratively restrained presentation of it which secured admission to the Yahwistic document, and through this document to the text of canonical Scripture. It would seem that extra-Biblical traditions of this kind underlie the remarkable passage, Ezekiel xxviil. II-19, in which the prophet compares the future fall of the king of Tyre to an expulsion (presumably the expulsion of Adam) from the Garden of Eden ; and (if it be admitted that a direct com- parison of the Tyrian prince with Adam is here intended) by implication describes the first man unfallen, as an ‘anointed cherub,’ ‘ full of wisdom, and perfect in beauty,’ perfect in his ways from the day he was created until unrighteousness was found in him, dwelling in Eden the garden of God and on the holy mountain of God, clothed in garments sewn thick with jewels, and so completely exempt from physical pain that he could walk up and down ‘in the midst of the stones of fire.’1_ The doctrine of the + On the ‘ fire-walk,’ a religious practice, common to many nations, in which Adam is here said (by implication) to have been an expert, see J. G. Frazer, Adonis, Attis, Osiris, i. p. 114. ADAM AND THE ‘EVIL IMAGINATION’ = 57 ‘ original perfection ’ of man appears explicitly in the Book of the Secrets of Enoch, which describes the first man as “asecond angel, honourable, great, and glorious,’ ‘ appointed as ruler to rule the earth, and to have God’s wisdom,’ and endowed with the beatific vision so that he could see ‘ the angels in heaven singing the song of victory and the gloom- less light’ 1; for some reason, however, it is asserted that this condition of beatitude only lasted for five and a half hours.?, It is a reasonable conclusion that by the time Christianity came into the world the idea of man’s ‘ original perfection’ had become more or less stereotyped as the logical frius or presupposition of the Adamic version of the Fall-theory, in those areas of the Jewish Church where this theory prevailed. From the extra-Biblical versions of the Paradise-story, which it thus appears necessary to postulate, would seem to be derived a repulsive variant of the Adamic doctrine of the origin of sin, which regards the ‘ Fall’ as consisting in the seduction, in the restricted sense of that term, of Eve by the serpent, or by Satan appearing as the serpent; from which was later deduced a theory of the inherited taint as an inguinamentum, a gross physical pollution so communi- cated to her and through her to her posterity. The Slavonic Enoch expresses this view of the Fall quite frankly : On account of this (his expulsion from heaven) he (Satan) conceived designs against Adam; in such a manner he entered and deceived Eve. But he did not touch Adam.® 1 2 Enoch xxxi. (A text): cf. also the Book of Adam and Eve, i. 8. *27tno0ch, xxxit. (Ajtext), 3 It should be added that a fragment of the Book of Noah (1 Enoch lxix. 11) affirms the ‘ original perfection ’ of man, so far as righteousness and physical immortality were concerned, but attributes its loss to his intellectual development, stimulated by the instruction imparted by the fallen angels: ‘For men were created exactly like the angels, to the intent that they should continue pure and righteous, and death which destroys everything could not have taken hold of them; but Pas this their knowledge they are perishing.’ 4 v. infra, Lecture III, p. 122; Lecture IV, p. 227. 5 xxxi. 6. The words ‘into Paradise ’ which Professor Sokolov’s text adds after ‘ entered,’ are a patent gloss, designed to remove the obvious (and to later minds unedifying) significance of the passage: Morfill and Charles, The Book of the Secrets of Enoch (1896), p. 45. See Tennant’s full discussion, Fall and Original Sin, pp. 208, 209. 58 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN We observe once more the emergence of a motif, destined to exercise a powerful though largely hidden influence on the course of Jewish and Christian Fall-speculation, which we have already found strongly expressed in the Watcher- story, and less prominently in the Paradise-story (in connec- tion with man’s realisation of his nakedness)—namely, the idea that the first sin was a sexual one or in some way had reference to the instinct of sex.1_ It is noteworthy that the theory of the Fall here expressed exempts Adam from all responsibility for it; and it is impossible not to suspect that it may lie behind the cynical dictum of Ben Sirach, quoted above— From a woman was the beginning of sin.’ Strange though it may seem, we shall see in our next lecture that this hideous legend has shaped the form of two passages in the New Testament which allude to the first trans- gression.” A less revolting, though hardly more reasonable, embodiment of the sexual interpretation of the Fall is con- tained in the Apocalypse of Abraham,® a pseudepigraph of uncertain date, in which it seems to be implied that the first sin consisted in the physical union of Adam and Eve, who had apparently been meant by the Creator to live in per- petual continence. We may for the sake of completeness conclude this catalogue of apocalyptic variations upon and decorations of the Adamic Fall-theory by mentioning the idea, based upon the curse of Gen. iii. 17, 18, which doomed the earth to lose its primitive fertility and to bring forth thorns and thistles, that Adam’s transgression had cosmic consequences of a far-reaching nature : the Book of Jubilees asserts that in consequence of this event the animals lost the power of speech which they had previously possessed, and the Syriac Apocalypse of Baruch attributes to it the beginnings of pain of every kind. We have now briefly sketched the origins, and traced the pre-Christian development, of the Fall-doctrine proper —that is, of the theory (if the cloudy and confused trains of ideas running through the documents so far reviewed may 1 See Lecture I, p. 34; II, p. 45. 42 Cor) xi1/2,°5 $1 Lim, it) 14, See Lecture I11,'p, 122, % cc. xxiii, xxiv. (E. tr., G. H. Box, 1918, p. 69 ff.; G. N. Bonwetsch, Die Apok. Abrahams, p. 33 f.). ———————————————— Ee ee aa... ADAM AND THE ‘EVIL IMAGINATION ’ 59 be deemed to constitute a theory) which finds the origin of evil in a first transgression, producing in its perpetrators and their offspring a moral taint or infirmity which is con- ceived as transmissible by strictly physiological heredity. The Fall-doctrine however (understood in this precise sense) was by no means the only explanation of the origin of sin which was held within the Jewish Church at the time of the birth of Christ. It will have been observed that nearly all the evidence which we have adduced so far, of a date sub- sequent to the close of the canon of the Old Testament, has been drawn from the Apocalypses ; and these books, broadly speaking, represent the popular religious literature of Hasmonaean Judaism, unofficial tracts and flysheets designed to inflame patriotism, purify piety, and foster the hope of the Messianic deliverance from Gentile tyrants, which circulated amongst the unlearned masses of the people, and especially, it would seem, amongst the semi-outcaste population debarred by the necessities of its manual avoca- tions from the full observance of the Law, and known by the contemptuous name of the ‘am ha-’dre¢, the ‘ people of the earth.’ But, to obtain a complete picture of the intel- lectual influences which surrounded the cradle of Christian doctrine, and, as we shall see, had no small share in determin- ing the lines on which the Christian Fall-theory was destined to develop, we must consider the characteristic ideas, not merely of popular, unofficial, and unscientific pietism as represented by the Apocalypses, but of the official and technical theology as taught by the Rabbis. The conception of the psychological ground of sin which permeates this latter stream of Jewish teaching is that of the yéger ha-ra*, or ‘ evil imagination,’ a phrase drawn from the Scriptural passage (Gen. vi. 5) which I have used as the second of my two texts. This doctrine, whilst bearing some resemblance to that of ‘ Original Sin,’ has no place for the idea of a‘ Fall,’ in the strict sense of the term, an idea which may conse- quently be said to be peculiar to the apocalyptic or popular theology of sin. The all but complete disappearance of the apocalyptic scheme of ideas from the mind of Israel, due, partly to the conversion to Christianity of those Jews who held it, and partly to the apparent refutation of the glowing 60 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN millennial hopes which it embodied by the catastrophes of A.D. 70 (the destruction of Jerusalem by Titus) and of A.D. 135 (the overthrow of Bar Kokhba by Hadrian), has brought it about that the Fall-doctrine is now exclusively characteristic of the Christian, and the doctrine of the yécer ha-va‘ of the Jewish Church: and the theology of present-day Judaism is as devoid of any idea of a‘ Fall’ as it is of the belief in personal angels and devils. To the consideration of this Rabbinical idea of the ‘ evil imagi- nation,’ and of the various attempts which were made, previously to and contemporaneously with the rise of Christianity, to blend it with the Fall-doctrine proper the remaining part of this lecture must be devoted. THE DOCTRINE OF THE ‘ Evit IMAGINATION ’ Unlike the doctrine of the Fall, which, as we have seen, would appear to have been first constructed from data given by spiritual experience, and then successively read into two of the primitive stories embodied in Genesis, the doctrine of the yécer ha-rva‘ arose directly from the exegesis of a Scriptural passage. ‘ God saw that the wickedness of man was great in the earth, and that every imagination (y écer) of the thoughts of his heart was only evil continually * (Gen. vi. 5). Here the evil ‘form,’ or ‘ fashion,’ or ‘ im- agination ’ of man’s thoughts is regarded as a factor which provokes the Almighty to wrath; it is to be presumed, therefore, that man himself is responsible for its existence. A little later, however, in the same narrative we read (vill. 21) that, after the subsidence of the waters of the Flood, “Yahweh smelled a sweet savour’ arising from Noah’s sacrifice, and said in his heart ‘I will not again curse the ground any more for man’s sake, for that the smagination (yécer) of man’s heart is evil (va‘) from his youth.’ Here the “evil imagination ’ is clearly regarded by Yahweh as con- stituting an excuse for human depravity, from which it would seem to follow that it is something which is given in the essential constitution of man’s nature, an inherited infirmity of some kind which the individual cannot help ADAM AND THE ‘EVIL IMAGINATION’ 61 possessing. It was inevitable that an idea based equally upon both of these texts should be somewhat ambiguous. In the light of the first, the y écer ha-ra‘ might be regarded as the sinful habit which man, by the repetition of wrongful acts, impresses upon his own soul ; in the light of the second as a ‘form’ already imprinted upon him by the Creator.* But this very ambiguity may be said to have exercised a beneficent influence on the development of Jewish, and, later, of Christian dogma, inasmuch as it contained the potentiality of a doctrine of sin which would do equal justice to those elements of religious experience which assure man of the reality of his own free-will and to those which testify to the limitation of free-will by the sinister handicap of an innate moral weakness. Owing to the vast extent of the documentary evidence contained in the Rabbinical literature, it is impossible to do more than indicate, in the briefest manner possible, the main outlines of this important and interesting conception. The recent discoveries of parts of the original Hebrew text of Ecclesiasticus have revealed these outlines as already existing, with tolerable clearness of definition, in the thought of Ben Sirach. The most important passage is xv. II-I7, 1 «It is never doubted that God made the evil yé¢er, yet man is respon- sible for controlling and subduing it. The word itself suggested these two apparently contrary conceptions. The verb V¥° means to form, or fashion, and also, to form inwardly, to plan. It was used as the technical word for the potter’s work. It was frequently used of God’s forming of nature and of man, and also of his planning or purposing. The 1¥° of man could therefore suggest either his form, as God made him, his nature (so Ps. ciii. 14) or his own formation of thought and purpose, ‘‘imagination ’’ as the word is rendered in several Old Testament passages (Gen. vi. 5; viii. 21 ; Deniers 27> Nsaialvxxvi 13.77%, Coron xxvill./6,7.. xsIx405).5 Ln. Deut. Xxxi. 21, and probably Isaiah xxvi. 3, the word is used without the further definition “‘ of the thoughts,” ‘‘of the heart,’’ which 1 Chron. retains. The word had gained, therefore, in the Old Testament, a certain independence as meaning the nature or disposition of man, and this could be regarded as something which God made (Ps. ciii. 14) or as something which man works (Deut. xxxi. 21). It is evident that the word was fitted by Old Testament usage for further development in discussions of the origin of sin and the responsibility of man’ (F. C. Porter, The Yeger Hara, in the Yale Bicentenary Volume of Biblical and Semitic Studies, 1901, pp. 108, 109). See also C. Taylor’s note on ¥" (Sayings of the Jewish Fathers, 1897 edn., p. 37, n. 36). 62 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN which, as literally translated from the Hebrew, runs as follows : 11. Say not, My transgression was of God ; For that which he hateth he made not. 12. Lest thou say, He it was that made me stumble ; For there is no need of men of violence. 13. Wickedness and an abomination the Lord hateth ; And will not let it befal them that fear him. 14. For (?) God created man from the beginning, And put him into the hand of him that would spoil him, And gave him into the hand of his inclination (yé¢er). 15. If thou choose, thou mayest keep the commandment ; And it is understanding to do his will. If thou trust in him, thou shalt even live. 16. Fire and water are poured out before thee: Upon whichsoever thou choosest stretch forth thy hands. 17. Death and life are before a man: That which he shall choose shall be given him. In this the author directly raises the eternal problem of human wickedness in its relation to God’s all-disposing providence. He cannot allow man unlimited free-will, nor can he admit that God directly moves the human soul towards sin. His solution is to suppose that God has created two mutually antagonistic powers, the evil yéc¢er within the soul and the (Mosaic) Law without it, and that man possesses just enough freedom of choice to be able to surrender himself either to one or tothe other. These alter- native and mutually exclusive guides of life are symbolised in vv 16, 17 as the fire and water, the death and life between which the Israelite has to choose. This thought can be paralleled exactly by one of the most important Rabbinical sayings with regard to the yéger, the latter part of which seems to be a verbal quotation of 14c; ‘I created the evil yeécer; I created for it the Law as a remedy. If ye are occupied with the Law, ye shall not be delivered into its hand.’ # The second passage, in the Hebrew original of which the word yécer has been discovered to exist, is xxvii. 5,6. The 1 Schechter and Taylor, The Wisdom of Ben-Sira (1899), pp. Xxxi, xxxii, * Qiddushin 30>, ADAM AND THE ‘EVIL IMAGINATION’ 63 verbal form of these verses is in one or two details not absolutely certain ; but the following is, according to a high authority, textually most probable, and gives an intelligible and instructive sense : 5. A potter’s vessel is for the furnace to bake ; And, like unto it, a man is according to his thought. 6. According to the husbandry of the tree will be its fruit ; So the thought is according to the yécer of man. If this text be accepted as authentic, it throws a considerable light upon the providential function attributed by Sirach to the yécer ha-ra‘. The paraphrase of its meaning given by the same authority can hardly be bettered: ‘A potter’s vessel is both tested and made by the fire; so a man is tested by his inner thought, it is this that both tries and makes him (cf. Prov. xxii. 7). ... The husbandry of a tree, 2.¢. the digging and pruning, both tests the life of the tree and is the condition of its fruitfulness. So the thought- life of man is tested and developed by the yé¢er, which, like the fire of the potter’s furnace and like the labour of the husbandman, is severe and may prove destructive, but is essential to the making of a vessel and the growing of fruit. A man is tested and made, not by appearances or deeds but by his thought or reasoning, and his thought is tested and made to be of worth by the evil inclinations within him, that is, by moral struggle.’ } The third passage which may be quoted in this connexion is one which has not yet been recovered in the Hebrew, but in which the occurrence of the word yécer is established by the Syriac version. This is xxi. 11a, which is given in the English Revised Version as: He that keepeth the law becometh master of the intent thereof —an apothegm of doubtful meaning—but in the Syriac appears in a far more intelligible and significant form as: He that keepeth the law getteth the mastery over his yéger. It can hardly be doubted that this is the original sense : and, like the first of our quotations, it testifies to the existence, + PB. C. Porter, 0p. ctt., p. 142. 64 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN towards the beginning of the second century before Christ, of the belief, characteristic of later Rabbinical orthodoxy, in the ‘ evil impulse’ or ‘ imagination’ as a power rooted in the soul, prior to and independent of conscious choice, exerting from time to time an almost intolerable pressure in the direction of sin, yet capable of being tamed and sub- dued by the wholesome discipline of a rigorous observance of the Law.? It is true that after its first occurrence in the Book of Ecclesiasticus the term yécer disappears until the beginning of the Talmudic epoch. This, however, is due to the fact that most of the Jewish literature of the last two centuries before and the first century after the birth of Christ is only preserved in Latin, Greek, Ethiopic, or other non-Semitic languages; and as, at the moment that Hebrew texts become available once more, the idea of the yécer is found existing in full force, it is safe to assume that it existed during the period for which direct Hebrew or Aramaic evidence is lacking. And it is well known that the Mishnah and the Midrashim contain much material dating from times long anterior to those of their actual codification or composition in their present form. It will, therefore, be permissible to make a cautious use of Rabbinical and Tal- mudic data for the purpose of articulating and enriching the general picture of the doctrine of the yé¢er ha-ra‘ which we have constructed on the basis of the Sirach-passages, so as to be in possession of a roughly accurate idea of the degree of development which it had attained in Jewish thought at the beginning of the Christian era. It will be convenient to summarise the additional infor- mation which may be obtained from these later sources under the three heads of the Seat, the Nature, and the ultimate Origin of the ‘ evil imagination.’ (a) The Rabbis 1 Cf, also xxxvii. 3, ‘O evil imagination’ (& zovnpov évOdunpua, pre- sumably = Y} 7¥}) ‘whence camest thou rolling in To cover the dry land with deceitfulness ?’: and xvii. 31, which W. Bousset (Religion des Judentums im NTI, Zettalter, 1903, p. 384) restores as follows, after the Syriac version: ‘ What shines brighter than the sun? yet it becometh darkened. Soalso is it with the man who subdueth not his yé¢er ’ (‘seeing that he is flesh and blood ’ Bousset thinks may be a gloss). On this latter verse, see also R. H. Charles, Apocr. and Pseud. i. p. 312. ADAM AND THE ‘* EVIL IMAGINATION’ 65 are unanimous in placing the seat of the evil yécer in the ‘heart’ (lébh), that is, the inner self, the basal personality of man.t_ So intimately is the evil yécer connected with the ‘heart’ that the latter term can be treated as almost synonymous with the former: as when Ps. cix. 22, “My heart is wounded within me,’ is interpreted to mean that the Psalmist’s ‘ evil impulse’ has been wounded or slain, from which the Rabbinical exegete deduces the consequence that David is to be reckoned with Abraham, Isaac, and Jacob, over whom the yécer ha-va‘ had no power.” It has recently been suggested that the “ heart,’ in Hebrew psycho- logy, denotes precisely that obscure and profound region of the Self which underlies, yet continually influences, the sur- face play of thought and volition, and which modern writers have named the “ Unconscious ’—the dark and unexplored home of instinct, emotion, and impulse, which, using an inevitable spatial metaphor, we are accustomed to describe as situated below the brilliantly lit area of the conscious mind.* Whether a simple equation of the ‘ heart ’’ and the ‘Unconscious’ can be sustained—in view of the accepted opinion, voiced by Driver and other critics, that the pro- cesses believed by the Old Testament writers to reside in the heart were strictly intellectual, and that the emotions were associated by the Hebrews with the ‘reins,’ or kidneys— is a question which must be left to the decision of experts. But the ‘Unconscious’ of modern psychology includes thought as well as emotion, so that its connotation at least overlaps to a large extent, even ifit does not exactly coincide with, that of /ébh. Weshall therefore not be far wrong if we assume that in using the term ‘ heart’ to describe the seat of the evil impulse, the Jewish writers meant at least to orientate their readers’ attention in the direction of what we now know as the ‘ Unconscious’: and we shall see in a moment that such an assumption has the effect of illumina- 1 The question was raised, whether the ‘ evil imagination’ resides in beasts. Rabbi Nachman ben Isaac is of opinion that it does, because they bite and kick (Bevakhoth 614). Angels, however, are exempt from it (Lev. vab. 26; Bacher, Amor. ii. p. 419). * Baba bathvat74. It would seem that the doctrine of the Immaculate Conception is here anticipated, in reference to these four patriarchs. 8 K. E. Kirk, Some Principles of Moral Theology (1920), p. 145. 66 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN ting and clearing up the second of our three questions, namely, that of the nature of the ‘ evil imagination.’ (b) This question naturally subdivides itself into two further problems, namely, (1) What is the predominant meaning of the substantive yécer ? and (2) What is meant by the adjective ‘evil’? The first of these has already been dealt with up to a point, in the comments on Gen. vi. 5 and viii. 21, prefixed by way of introduction to this section of our enquiry. Etymologically, as we have seen, yécer should mean a fixed habit or disposition, and it is sometimes used in this sense. But, in by far the greater number of Rabbinical passages, it is clearly conceived, not so much as a static character but rather as a dynamic force, a strong current of emotional and conative energy which (if the use of a mis- cellany of metaphors may be allowed) can be resisted, fought, bridled, tamed, subdued, diverted into fresh channels, or harnessed to new purposes. The ambiguity is, however, perfectly natural and intelligible. When we think of a river, we may think either of its moving volume of waters, which, as instinct with dynamic energy, may operate turbines or demolish bridges: or else of the (relatively) fixed and permanent channel in which it flows, which may form the frontier separating parishes, counties, or empires. So what appears to be the element of innate sinfulness in human personality, which manifests itself with sudden and terrifying vividness in moments of temptation, may be viewed either as a dynamic uprush of psychic energy from the depths of the soul, or as the static channel, consisting of inherited psycho-physical dispositions, which directs this energy, harmless in itself, towards morally reprehensible ends. This ambiguity in the use of the substantive, which the official Jewish theology never succeeded in resolving, ex- plains an even more remarkable ambiguity in the use of the adjective. The yécer is evil, because it is perpetually pricking and prompting men to sin, and especially to sins against purity. (We note once more the appearance of the King Charles’ head which has obsessed so many speculators on the problem of evil in man.) Anger and idolatry are also conspicuous manifestations of the yécery ; and the pious Jew still entreats, in his morning prayers, to be guarded ADAM AND THE ‘EVIL IMAGINATION’ 67 from sin and temptation, and from the evil yéger.1 God Himself, according to some authorities, repents of having made the ‘ evil imagination’; ‘ It stands ill with the evil yecer, since even its creator calls it evil’?; ‘Woe to the dough, of which the baker himself testifies that it is bad!’ 3 Eventually the evil vécer was, in some quarters at least, identified with Satan ; ‘Satan, the evil yéger, and the angel of death are one.’* Yet, paradoxically enough, there is a certain amount of testimony to the essential goodness of the evil yécer. In expounding Gen. i. 31, “And behold it was very good,’ Rk. Samuel ben Nachman says ‘ Is the evil yé¢er then very good? Certainly, for without it man would not build a house, nor marry, nor beget children, nor engage in trade.’ ®> Another Rabbi, Simon ben Eleazar, teaches as follows : ‘The evil yécer is ike iron. From iron one may make all sorts of vessels if only he cast it into the fire. So one can make the evil yécer useful by the words of the Law.’ This is proved by Prov. xxv. 21: “If thou soothe thine enemy (the yécer) with bread and water (the Law), God will make it thy friend.’ ® This apparent antinomy is easily resolved if we understand the yécer as a fountain of conative energy, welling up from the ‘heart,’ that is, approximately, the sub- conscious self, intrinsically good, as having been created by God, and remaining good, so long as it finds its outlet in socially useful or legitimate activities, but becoming ‘ evil’ when allowed to overflow without restraint in the directions of sexual indulgence or ruthless self-assertion in defiance of the rights of God and one’s neighbour. The fact is that, in its quest for the source of evil in man, 1S. Singer, Authorized Daily Prayer Book, 4th edn., p. 7 (Morning Service), ‘ O lead us not into the power of sin, or of transgression or iniquity, or of temptation: Jet not the evil inclination have sway over us.’ It is impossible not to be struck by the similarity of these sentences to the language of the Lord’s Prayer as recorded by St. Matthew (vi. 9-13) ; v. infra, Lect. III, p. 98, n. 2, and see also Taylor’s discussion in Sayings of the Jewish Fathers (1897), Excursus V (‘ The Lord’s Prayer ’), p. 128. 2 Qiddushin 30b, 3 Num. vab. 13; Gen. rab. 34. 4 Baba bathva 164; Bacher, Amor. i. p. 354. 5 Gen. vab.9; Eccles. rab. 3,11; Bacher, Amor.i. p. 487 f. 6 Bacher, Die Agada dev Tannaiten, ii. p. 436; the same saying is also ascribed to R. Berachiah (Bacher, Amor. iii. p. 381 f.). 68 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN the official Jewish theology had stumbled upon, though it never quite succeeded in disentangling from confusing associ- ations, that central conception of modern psycho-analytic theory which is generally designated by the term /zbido. We may note in passing the remarkable fact that this conception should twice in the history of thought have been developed by men of Jewish blood, once in the Palestine of the second century before the birth of Christ, and again in the Vienna of the twentieth century after it. It must be added, for the sake of accuracy, that the idea of the yécer ha-ra‘ seems to be the equivalent of the idea of libido as defined by Jung, rather than of the strictly Freudian con- ception; for the yécer, though largely, is not exclusively sexual in nature. A definition drawn from an authoritative exposition of Jung’s psychology will make this clear: ‘(The libido is) a longing, a cosmic pressure or urge of the life-force manifesting itself in the human individual, the conation or striving which manifests itself not only in the reproductive instinct but in such physiological and psycho- logical phenomena as growth, development, hunger, and other human activities and interests.’ 1 It is, consequently, not surprising to find that, whilst the Rabbis occasionally insist upon the necessity for ‘ repressing ’ the ‘ evil impulse,’ the main tenor of their teaching finds the cure for it in what is now called ‘ sublimation,’ that is, the diversion of it into good and lawful avenues of expression, the chief of which are prayer and the exact observance of the Tévah. (Ideally, the observance of the Law is for the sincere and pious Jew, 1 From the introduction (p. xvii), by Dr. Beatrice M. Hinkle, to Jung’s Psychology of the Unconscious (E. tr. 1922). The whole passage, which I have epitomised in the definition given in the text, runs as follows: ‘ Be- ginning with the conception of /zbido itself as a term used to connote sexual hunger and craving, albeit the meaning of the word sexual was extended by Freud to embrace a much wider significance than common usage has assigned to it, Jung was unable to confine himself to this limitation. He conceived this longing, this urge or push of life as something extending beyond sexuality even in its wider sense. He saw in the term libido a concept of unknown nature, comparable to Bergson’s élan vital, a hypo- thetical energy of life, which occupies itself not only in sexuality but in various physiological and psychological manifestations such as growth, development, hunger, and all the human activities and interests. This cosmic energy or urge manifested in the human being he calls libido, and compares it with the energy of physics.’ ADAM AND THE ‘EVIL IMAGINATION’ — 69 not the enforced performance of a dull mechanical routine, but a joyful exercise, carried out with devotion and enthu- siasm, which provides an ample outlet and satisfaction for great volumes of emotional energy.) Yet the conclusion which might be expected to have been suggested by this remedial method, namely, that the yé¢er in itself is neither good nor evil, but morally neutral and colourless, was never attained by Jewish thought. Even at the present day it seems to be generally assumed that the yécer is essentially evil, though it may be endowed with a kind of artificial and adventitious goodness by being harnessed to good ends. In other words, Rabbinism never freed itself from what appears to us the self-evident fallacy of supposing that, because appetite under certain circumstances may lead to sin, it is therefore in itself sinful—a fallacy which, as we shall see in succeeding lectures, re-appears, with unfortunate results, in certain areas of Christian speculation with regard to the problem of sin. (c) The question of the ultimate Origin of the ‘ evil imagination ’ can be dismissed in a few words. The origin of the evil yéger is attributed by the Rabbis immediately to God: so immediately, in fact, that God is conceived, not as creating the yécey in man at the beginning of human history, and leaving it to be propagated by heredity, but actually as implanting it de novo in the soul of every indi- vidual member of the race at the moment of his or her conception (or, according to some authorities, birth?). This is the cardinal point which distinguishes the official and scholastic doctrine of the yéger ha-ra‘ from the popular and pseudepigraphic theory of the Fall—its denial that the ‘evil impulse’ in man is hereditary. According to the Rabbis, the individual sinner neither inherits the tendency 1 We are here simply concerned with theoretical principles, and it would, therefore, be out of place to raise the historical question as to how far this ideal was in fact realised during the centuries immediately pre- ceding and succeeding the Incarnation ; though it will be understood that a Christian author naturally assumes that there was ample justification for the attitude towards the Law and the halakhic tradition taken up by our Lord and by St. Paul. * Rabbinical theology in general holds to the ‘ creationistic ’ hypothesis of the origin of the soul: see F. Weber, System der alt-synagog. palastin. Theologie (Leipzig, 1880), pp. 219, 220. 70 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN to sin from his parents nor transmits it to his children ; he receives it into his soul directly from God at the first moment of his existence, as his parents individually received it before him and his children will receive it after him. It follows from this denial of the continuous transmission of the evil tendency that the existence of the yécer ha-ra‘ is in no sense due to Adam’s transgression ; on the contrary, Adam transgressed because the evil yécer had already been planted in him by his Creator. The disconcerting fact that, on this hypothesis, God is apparently made the author of evil, and the citadel of ethical monotheism in principle surrendered, never seems to have been adequately faced by the Jewish Church. REACTIONS, REAL AND SUPPOSED, UPON EACH OTHER OF THE PSEUDEPIGRAPHIC AND THE RABBINICAL THEORIES Such, then, were the two chief theories with regard to the origin of human sin which prevailed within the Jewish Church at the moment when Christianity came into the world—the popular and somewhat hazy theory of a primi- tive moral catastrophe and of some kind of hereditary corruption flowing from it, found in the Apocalypses, and the official, scholastic, and well-defined doctrine of an ‘ evil impulse’ planted by God in every human soul separately and individually which appears in the writings of the Rabbis. It would, however, be a mistake to exaggerate the division between the popular and the official theologies of Palestinian Judaism into an impassable gulf; the spiritual aristocracy of Israel, the class of the scribes and of the rigid observers of the Law, must have shaded downwards by imperceptible degrees into the lower strata of Jewish society known as the ‘ people of the earth,’ so that ideas could without great difficulty travel both up and down the scale; and, in so small a country as Palestine, it is to be expected that the two worlds of thought, the apocalyptic and the Rabbinical, would overlap and interpenetrate one another at a thousand points. Hence a full description of the immediately pre Christian state of Jewish opinion with regard to the origin ADAM AND THE ‘EVIL IMAGINATION ’ FY. and psychological ground of human sin must include some account of what appear to be half-conscious attempts to synthesise the two traditions, or at least to be instances of a tendency in one or other of these traditions to assimilate itself to its rival. A complete organic fusion of the Fall- theory and the yéger-theory was never attained by Judaism ; that was a task which Providence reserved for Christian thought. It is natural to classify the movements of thought just indicated under the two heads of (a) apparent approaches of Rabbinism towards the Fall-theory, and (0) leanings of the Fall-theory in the direction of Rabbinism, that is to say, in other words, developments of Rabbinical speculation with regard to Adam and his sin which seem to have been influenced by the apocalyptic vein of thought or at least by the extra-Scriptural traditions underlying it, and attempts made by the apocalyptic writers on their side to work the characteristic Rabbinical theology of sin into their presenta- tion of the Adamic Fall-theory. Of these movements, the former class deserves prior consideration, inasmuch as some scholars of weight have believed that they could trace, running through it, the gradual fixation and crystallisation, as it were, of two of the most important ingredients in that version of the Christian Fall-doctrine which was taught by St. Augustine—the ideas, namely, of ‘ Original Righteous- ness’ or ‘ Perfection,’ and of what we will take leave to call ‘ Original Guilt,’ a term which will be presently explained. With regard to the first of these ideas, that of the ‘Original Perfection’ of man, it is perfectly true that Rabbinical theology developed it to an even more extrava- gant pitch than did the apocalyptic writings quoted above.t The ‘ image of God,’ after which Adam was created, is made to include gigantic dimensions? (Adam is frequently said to have filled the whole world!), surpassing beauty of body, a degree of wisdom which almost suggests omniscience, an aureole of light eclipsing the radiance of the sun, powers of 1 vesupra, Pp. 56. 2 Cf. the following, from Gesprachen der drei Heiligen (Denkschriften der Akad. zu Wien, Bd. 24, S. 63): ‘quantum erat caput Adae? re- sponsio: tantum ut triginta homines in illud intrare possent.’ 72 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN vision which enabled him to see the total extent of the earth at once, and the right to command the services of angels for the purpose of ministering to his physical comfort.? These marvellous endowments were forfeited as the result of Adam’s sin, and the Shekhinah or divine glory withdrew itself from the earth. It would seem at first sight natural to conclude that Rabbinical thought must have regarded Adam’s descendants in a certain sense as having been injured by their first father’s transgression, inasmuch as they were born without the supernatural qualities which constituted ‘ Original Perfection’; and it is doubtless possible to see, implicitly contained in these fantastic speculations, the germ of the specifically Scotist doctrine of ‘ Original Sin’ which defines it as consisting solely in the ‘defect of Original Righteousness.’ 2 But there is no proof that such conclusions were ever drawn by the Jewish theologians in a formal and explicit way ; and the triviality which characterises. most of the haggadic amplifications of the Biblical Paradise-story strongly suggests that this narrative was never taken in earnest by the Rabbis as the explanation of the ultimate origin of sin, and that the belief in Adam’s ‘ original perfection’ never decisively crossed the frontier which separates the realm of romantic imagina- tion from that of serious theological thought. A similar conclusion appears to be inevitable with regard to the supposed presence of the idea of ‘ Original Guilt ’ in the official theology of Judaism during the epoch which immediately preceded the birth of Christianity. Though we have not met with this conception hitherto, it is one which plays an important part in the history of the Christian doctrine of Man and Sin, and the present will therefore be an opportune moment for defining it. It is the idea that the sin of the first man is legally imputed to his descendants (either because they are supposed to have been physically included in him when he sinned, or because they are arbitrarily regarded by God as having been represented or typified by him) in such a way that every individual 1 Quotations illustrating those beliefs have been collected by F. Weber, System der alisynagog. Theologie, pp. 214, 215. 2. See Lecture VI, p. 410. ADAM AND THE ‘EVIL IMAGINATION ’ 73 human being is born, not merely with the tendency to future sins latent in him, but subject to the personal guilt of and responsibility for the primal sin. It will be seen that this is a different idea from that of which we have hitherto been tracing the history, the conception of a hereditary bias towards evil, though it may be and in large areas of Christian thought has been closely associated with it; and it will be convenient in our future discussion to keep the term ‘Original Sin’ 1 for describing the innate tendency to sin, which is a fact, or alleged fact, of the psychological order, as contrasted with ‘ Original Guilt,’ which is a juristic or quasi-juristic conception. It is this latter idea which Ferdinand Weber asserts to be characteristic of Rabbinical theology in all its periods, including, as we must suppose, the immediately pre-Christian period. His words are: “There is a hereditary gut, but no hereditary sinfulness (Es gibt erne Erbschuld, aber keine Erbsiinde) ; Adam’s fall has brought death upon the whole race, but not sinfulness in the sense of a compulsion to sin; sin is the result of each individual’s personal decision, which experience shows to be in fact universal, but which, even after the Fall, is in no sense theoretically necessary.’? Here it is affirmed that the Rabbis—including, presumably, the Tanndim or “ Repeaters,’ who were the dominant school of our Lord’s day 3—whilst rejecting ‘ Original Sin,’ nevertheless accepted 1 Strictly speaking, of course, it is anachronistic to use the term ‘Original Sin’ in dealing with the ideas of any period prior to that of St. Augustine (see Lect. V, p. 327), as it is to employ the word ‘Fall’ to describe the first sin as conceived by writers earlier than Methodius of Olympus (see Lect. IV, p. 252, n. 4) ; but, in the case of both terms, we may plead that the anachronism is convenient and inevitable. “Ops Ct, Dp, 217.0 » Es gibtieme Erbschuld; aber keine \Erbstnde ; der Fall Adams hat dem ganzen Geschlecht den Tod, nicht aber die Sindigkeit im Sinne einer Nothwendigkeit zu sitindigen verursacht; die Siinde ist das Ergebnis der Entscheidung jedes Einzelnen, erfahrungs- gemass allgemein, aber an sich auch nach dem Fall nicht schlechthin nothwendig.’ 8 It may be of interest to set down here a list of the successive schools of divines which held sway during the classical period of Rabbinism. They were (1) The Sépherim, or ‘ Scribes,’ whose period lasted, roughly, from Ezra to the age of the Maccabees ; (2) the Zugéth, or ‘ pairs,’ so called because it is alleged that there were only two of them in office at a time, one being president, and the other vice-president, of the Sanhedrin—the word is formed from the Greek Cuydv, a yoke-pair; their period lasted from 74 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN the idea of ‘ Original Guilt.’ If this conclusion could be sustained, it would represent a fact of the highest importance for the interpretation of the New Testament doctrine of the Fall. Dr. Tennant has, however, shown that this sweeping assertion of Weber is, at the least, uncertain in the highest degree, in so far as it refers to immediately pre-Christian Rabbinism, in which alone we are interested for the purposes of the present enquiry.! It is, in fact, a precarious inference from the supposition, itself unproved, that the Tannaim believed Adam’s sin to have been the cause of mortality in his descendants. But, despite the fact that this latter doctrine was held by Ben Sirach ? and possibly by the author of the Book of Wisdom,’ there is no proof that it became at all common in the Rabbinical schools before the third century of our era. It is, moreover, affirmed, in opposition to Weber’s contention, by two eminent authorities * on the religion and theology of Judaism, that the generation of Rabbis nearest the time of Christ held for the most part an individualistic view of the connexion between sin and death, maintaining that each man’s death is due to his own sinful acts (which, as we have seen, are deemed to arise from his own culpable failure to control his yéger) and not to any ances- tral or racial sin. The empirical universality of death would thus be due merely to the empirical universality of actual sin, and not to any a priovz necessity or arbitrary Divine decree. It seems, therefore, safest to regard the attribution of a belief in ‘ Original Guilt’ to the Rabbis of the first centuries before and after the beginning of our era as an the Maccabees till Herod the Great ; (3) the Tanndim, or ‘ repeaters’—who flourished during the first and second centuries of our era ; (4) the ’Amédraim or ‘ interpreters,’ from c. 200 toc. 500 A.D. ; (5) the Sabérdim, or ‘ teachers,’ whose period coincides roughly with the sixth century a.D.; and (6) the Geonim, or ‘noble ones,’ who taught from 609 to 750 A.D. For further information as to these schools, see Oesterley and Box, Religion and Worship of the Synagogue, c. IV ii.; H. M. J. Loewe, art. ‘ Judaism,’ in ERE, vol. vii.; Oesterley and Box, Short Sketch of the Literature of Rab- binical and Mediaeval Judaism (1920), pp. 89-126. 1 Sources of the Doctrines of the Fali and of Original Sin, pp. 161-168. Ecclus, xxv. 24. Wisdom ii. 23, 24; see above, p. 55. Ginzberg, Monatsschrift fiir Geschicht eund Wissenschaft Judentums, Jahrg. 43, p. 153 f.; Schechter, Studies in Judaism, pp. 260 ff. Pe OO Dw ADAM AND THE ‘EVIL IMAGINATION’ = 75 anachronism ; and to assume that, within the sphere of the official theology, as it stood at this period, the hypothesis of a causal connexion between Adam’s sin and the deaths of his posterity only existed (so far as it existed at all) ina vague and undefined form, as a haggadic and mythopoeic motif rather than as a reasoned intellectual theory. It would seem, then, that the official theology of the Jewish Church in its immediately pre-Christian period only leaned towards the Adam-theory on its haggadic,. that is, its imaginative, romantic, and mythological side, and that it exhibited no real approximation to what we are justified in calling the pseudepigraphic doctrine in the sphere of intellectual concepts. The case, however, is different when we turn to the latest Apocalypses which have any bearing on our enquiry, namely, the Syriac Apocalypse of Baruch and the Second or Fourth Book of Esdras. These books - are of peculiar interest for our present purpose, because both the composition of their several elements and their final redaction as literary wholes are generally admitted to fall within limits marked by the dates 50 and 120 a.p.— that is to say, within a period roughly contemporaneous with the development of Apostolic Christianity and the writing of the New Testament ; and they therefore may be taken as first-hand evidence for the background of Jewish thought on the origin and ground of sin which is presupposed by St. Paul’s treatment of the subject. In them we shall find unmistakable evidence of the contacts and reactions between the scholastic and the popular opinions which must have been proceeding in the Jewish Church of our Lord’s day—evidence which in the former book takes the shape of 1 These documents have been edited, with English translation and full notes, by R. H. Charles and G. H. Box respectively, in Apocrypha and Pseudepigrapha of the Old Testament, vol. ii. (1913). Though the introduction to each contains a complete bibliography, it may be well to note here a few editions of importance: (1) (Baruch), R. H. Charles, The Apocalypse of Baruch (1896); Ryssel, in Kautzsch, A pokr. u. Pseudepigr. des AT, ii. 411 (1900); (2) (Esdras) R. L. Bensly and M. R. James, The Fourth Book of Ezra (the complete Latin version, including for the first time the missing fragment vii. 36-105, discovered by Prof. Bensly) ; Texts and Studies, iii. 2 (1895) ; Gunkel, in Kautzsch, Apokr. u. Pseud. ii. (1900) ; Bruno Violet, Die Esva-A pocalypse (Die griech. christl. Schrifist. der ersten dvet Jahrhund, Bd. 18, 1910); G. H. Box, The Ezva-A pocalypse (1912). 76 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN an emphatic repudiation of the Fall-doctrine, and, in the latter, of a more or less successful attempt to fuse it with the yécer-theory. Though it is certain that 2 Baruch and 4 Ezra (to employ the short titles under which scholars have agreed to designate these works) are closely related, in the sense that one was published as a conscious and deliberate reply to the other, there is at present no consensus of opinion on the question which came first ; and we shall therefore content ourselves with sketching the positions character- istic of these two books, without expressing any view as to which ought to be regarded as thesis and which as antithesis. As the Baruch-document represents what eventually became the permanent mind of post-Christian Judaism, it will be natural to examine this work in the first place, and to reserve 4 Ezra, which approximates more nearly than any other purely Jewish writing to the full Pauline doctrine of the Fall and Original Sin, for subsequent consideration. It is noteworthy that all the passages in 2 Baruch which deal with the origins of sin occur either in that stratum of it which Dr. Charles denotes by the symbol A® and assigns to the period prior to the destruction of Jerusalem, or in that designated by him as B?, the composition of which he places in the epoch of despair which succeeded the catastrophe of A.D. 70.4 But this difference of date between the two documents in question, even with the difference of world-outlook necessarily involved in it, does not affect their substantial identity of view with regard to the theology of sin,? and the relevant texts may therefore be considered together, without any attempt to group them chronologically. 2 Baruch admits, in accordance with the haggadic tendency noticed above, in our discussion of the Rabbinical inter- pretation of Gen. il., that Adam’s transgression was the starting-point of a long series of external or material disasters, in particular of physical death, or at least of its premature 1 Apocr. and Pseudepigy. ii. pp. 474 ff. * It should, however, be noted that in B? Adam’s sin is the cause of all death, it being apparently assumed that, but for the Fall, man would have been immortal; in A%, on the contrary, man was originally mortal, and Adam’s transgression is the cause only of its premature occurrence. ADAM AND THE ‘EVIL IMAGINATION ’ vas occurrence; this opinion finds expression in xxiii. 4: ‘ Because when Adam sinned, and death was decreed against those who should be born’ ; in xlvili. 42, 43: (42) O Adam, what hast thou done to all those who are born from thee, And what will be said to the first Eve who hearkened to the serpent ? (43) For all this multitude are going to corruption, Nor is there any numbering of those whom the fire devours ; and most conspicuously in lvi. 5, 6: (5) And as thou didst previously see on the summit of the cloud black waters which descended previously on the earth,? this is the transgression wherewith Adam the first man trans- gressed. (6) For (since) when he transgressed Untimely death came into being, Grief was named, And anguish was prepared, And pain was created, And trouble consummated, And disease began to be established, And Sheol kept demanding that it should be renewed in blood, And the begetiing of children was brought about, And the passion of parents produced,® And the greatness of humanity was humiliated, And goodness languished. It will be noticed that v. 6 contains what looks like an approximation to the later Augustinian doctrine of ‘ Original Sin,’ in the shape of a suggestion that the existence of sexual passion is due to Adam’s fall: this idea is further developed in vv. ro ff., where it is connected with the story of the lustful angels : For he became a danger to his own soul: even to the angels became he a danger. For, moreover, at that time when he was created, they enjoyed liberty. And some of them descended, eroce NOLe 2, p. 7G. 2 The reference is to Baruch’s vision, narrated in c. liii., in which the history of mankind from Adam to the Messiah is symbolised under the form of alternate showers of black and bright waters descending from a cloud. 3 Italics ours. 78 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN and mingled with the women. And then those who did so were tormented in chains. If these passages stood alone, we should be entitled to describe 2 Baruch’s views with regard to the significance of Adam’s sin as a compromise between the Rabbinical and the popular traditions, the consequences of the Fall being kept, in the main, on the purely external and mechanical level in deference to the former, whilst a single interior and psychological consequence—to wit, sexual emotion and activity—is taken over, in isolation, from the latter. It is noticeable that no attempt is made to utilise the idea of the yécer ha-va‘ in this connexion. But we have to set against the texts just quoted certain other passages in which the robust ethical libertarianism, almost amounting to what was known to later Christian theology as Pelagianism, of the Rabbis is strongly affirmed, and the popular Adamic Fall-theory is repudiated in explicit and energetic language. Those which bear most directly on the subject of our enquiry are XVili. I, 2, where Moses is said to have lighted a lamp for Israel (by promulgating the Law) but to have been imitated by few, the majority of Jews having chosen to ‘take from the darkness of Adam’ (that is, to imitate his sin) instead of rejoicing in the light of the lamp+4; and liv. 15 ff., which expressly states that Adam’s sin introduced premature death only, and in no way affected his descendants’ freedom of choice, in words characterised by such pointed vehemence that they can only be interpreted as a direct attack upon the Fall-theory : (15) For though Adam first sinned And brought untimely death upon all, Yet of those who were born from him Each one of them has prepared for his own soul torment to come, And again each one of them has chosen for himself glories to come. (19) Adam is not therefore the cause, save only of his own soul, But each one of us has been the Adam of his own soul. 1 Cf. John v. 35, in which a similar metaphor is applied to John the Baptist : éxetvos Fv 6 Avxvos 6 Kaidpevos Kal dpaivwr' dtpeis dé HOeAjoare ayaAdacbfva mpos wpav ev TH pwrti avrod. ' % Italics ours. ADAM AND THE ‘EVIL IMAGINATION’ = 79 The patent inconsistency of this teaching with that of lvi. 5 ff., quoted above, is a striking reflection of the divided opinions with regard to this subject which prevailed within the Jewish Church, just at the time when St. Paul was laying down, in measured yet unhesitating words, the outlines of that Christian Fall-doctrine which ever since has formed the presupposition of the Catholic redemptive scheme. With 4 Ezra we pass into a different atmosphere. This writer accepts the Rabbinical doctrine of the yécer ha-ra‘ ; but his experience of the actual sinfulness of Israel has led him entirely to reject its companion doctrine, that the Law is a sufficient remedy for the evil impulses connatural with the human soul, and that man can perfectly well obey the whole Law if he chooses so to do. Like St. Paul, though untouched by any spark of Christian faith or emotion, he has discovered that the Law produces only the ‘ knowledge of sin,’ not the power to overcome it, and that in him, or in his flesh, there dwelleth no good thing.! He arrives at an explanation of this saddening fact by fusing the Rab- binical and the pseudepigraphic theories, admitting that the evil yécer was planted (presumably by the Creator) in the heart of Adam at the moment of his creation, but sup- plementing this position by the implied assertions that its presence in him became fixed and habitual owing to the Fall, and that it is now hereditary in the human race, being communicated from Adam to the successive generations of his posterity by physical propagation. This, it will be seen, is for all practical purposes identical with the Pauline doctrine, save in so far as the Apostle abstains from affirming that the germ or potentiality of evil existed in Adam before the Fall; and even this latter idea can be paralleled in the teaching of St. Augustine, who finds himself obliged to postulate a minute but appreciable amount of “concupiscence’ in unfallen man, in order to explain the possibility of his being tempted at all.” The relevant passages may here be given at length : 1 Passages implying the empirical universality of actual sin are: Hi yeh as Avil. 40; 68 >) 'Vill, 35, ey pee Lecture V, p. 363; n.°3. @ 80 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN (a) For the first Adam, clothing himself with 4 the evil heart, transgressed and was overcome ; and likewise also all who were born of him. Thus the infirmity became inveterate; the Law indeed was in the heart of the people, but (in conjunction with) the evil germ ; so what was good departed, and the evil remained (ill, 21-23). (b) For a grain of evil seed was sown in the heart of Adam from the beginning, and how much fruit of ungodliness has it produced unto this time, and shall yet produce until sie threshing- floor come ! (iv. 30). (c) Then said he unto me: Even so, also, is Israel’ S portion ; for it was for their sakes I made the world; but when Adam transgressed my statutes, then that which had been made was judged, and then the ways of this world became narrow and sorrowful and painful and full of perils coupled with great toils (VILULL a2) (d) And I answered and said: This is my first and last word ; better had it been that the earth had not produced Adam, or else, having once produced him, (for thee) to have restrained him from sinning. For how does it profit us all that in the present we must live in grief and after death look for punishment ? O thou Adam, what hast thou done! For though it was thou that sinned, the fall 2? was not thine alone, but ours also who are thy descendants ! (vil. 116-118). In the first two of these passages the yécer ha-ra‘ is referred to as ‘ the evil heart,’ ‘ the evil germ,’ ‘a grain of evil seed’ ; it may be added that in another passage (vil. 92, which I have not quoted because it does not directly bear upon the questions of the origin and transmission of evil) the yécer is even more recognisably mentioned under the title of ‘the innate evil thought’ (cum eis plasmatum cogitamentum malum). The third passage cannot, perhaps, be claimed as going beyond the haggadic tradition generally received by the Rabbis, namely, that Adam’s Fall was the starting-point of material evil. But the transmission of the ‘evil heart ’ from Adam to his posterity would seem to be clearly implied in (a) and also in (d), the last sentence of 1 So the Syriac and Ethiopic versions: the Latin has ‘ bearing’ or ‘carrying’ (7.e. within him)—‘ cor enim malignum baiolans primus Adam transgressus et victus est.’ See Bensly and James, op. cit., p. 8. Box (Ezva-A pocalypse, p. 16, note im loc.) argues that the Latin baiolans represents a Greek dopéoas, which would be the equivalent of ‘ wearing’ or ‘ clothing ’ himself with the ‘ evil heart,’ as though it were a garment. 2 For a note on this word, see Lecture IV, p. 252, n. 4. ADAM AND THE ‘EVIL IMAGINATION’ = 8r which can hardly mean less than that Adam’s descendants in some sense have shared in his sin owing to their physio- logical connexion and continuity with him. It is impossible to read this Apocalypse, the last purely Jewish document to set forth the popular doctrine of an inherited interior weakness or disease, without feeling that a true organic synthesis of the two conceptions which the author of the main body of 4 Ezra somewhat mechanically juxtaposes lay all the time ready to his hand. From the standpoint of the dispassionate modern student, it must seem that it would not have been difficult to harmonise the official and the popular theories by taking advantage of the more reasonable form assumed by the scholastic doctrine in those passages of the Rabbinical writings which represent the yécer as being in itself a morally neutral libido ; and, whilst admitting that the yécer existed in Adam from the moment of his creation, to conceive the Fall as consisting in a mis-direction and fixation of this /zb1do upon an improper object, a fixation which became stereotyped in him and was transmitted by him to his posterity. I am not concerned at this stage of our enquiry to maintain that such a view is possible for us, but merely that it would have been possible for 4 Ezra. But the opportunity was missed, and the synthesis which seems for a moment to have trembled upon the verge of consummation was never consciously achieved. The crowning disasters of Bar Kokhba’s rebellion and its bloody suppression by Hadrian (A.D. 135) finally discredited the whole apocalyptic genre of literature and thought, which vanished into the limbo of forgotten things, taking with it (so far as Jewry was concerned) the half-developed ideas of the Fall and of Original Sin, and leaving the strict Rabbinical conception of the yéger ha-ra‘, as individually implanted by the Creator in each human soul and not hereditarily derived from any primaeval disaster, in sole possession of the field of Jewish orthodoxy. PHILO’s IDEAS WITH REGARD TO THE ‘ FALL’ It should be added, before we close our survey of the Jewish antecedents of the Christian Fall-doctrine, that little G 82 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN information of interest for our immediate purpose can be gleaned from the writings of Philo. His loyalty to the main tenor of the scholastic tradition leads him, in com- menting on the early narratives of Genesis, to reproduce the current haggadic ideas regarding the supernatural endowments, physical, mental, and moral, enjoyed by the first man,! and the material or external disasters which were involved in his expulsion from the happy garden.? But the idea of an internal psychological malady, trans- missible by physical heredity, and engendered by our first father’s fall, is totally absent from his writings. It is probable that his deepest thought with regard to the story of Gen. ili. is that which finds expression in the treatise de mundi optficio: in which the Fall-narrative is said to be an allegory (though this does not imply that it is not also a record of literal fact) portraying in symbolic form the processes which normally precede the commission of actual sin, Adam typifying the rational and Eve the sensuous element in human nature, whilst the serpent signifies the sinister power of carnal lust and pleasure.® It might have been expected that Philo, belonging as he did on his Jewish side to the world of official and Rabbinical theology rather than to the world of popular pietism in which the Apocalytic literature grew up, would have given an unfaltering allegiance to the idea of the 1 de mundi optf. 50 (Philonis Iudaet opera omnia, ed. C. E. Richter, Lipsiae, 1828, 1. p. 47; references to the volume and page of this edition are given in brackets after the references to the chapter or paragraph of Philo’s text): Adam év dxpdrw drérpiBev eddarpovia, and was in all things conformed to the will of his Creator ; ibid. 52 (i. p. 48): the naming of the animals was a proof of Adam’s supreme wisdom and sovereignty over the world (for the re-appearance of this idea in Christian thought, see Lect. V, p. 361); quaest. in Gen. i. 32 (vi. p. 266): ‘ protoplastorum autem animae ut a malo mundae essent et intemeratae, acutae omnino erant ad perceptionem cuiuscumque vocis ... illi vero quemadmodum corpus sortiti sunt nimis grande et proceritatem gigantis, necesse fuit ut prae se ferrent sensus etiam certiores, et quod his praestantius est, philo- sophicos intuitus auditusque. non enim frustra arbitrabantur nonnulli oculis illos praeditos esse, quibus potuerunt etiam eas quae in caelo sunt naturas essentiasque et operationes videre, quemadmodum et auribus culuscumque generis voces percipere.’ 2 de mundi opif. 60 (i. 54), an expansion of Gen. iii. 16-19; cf. de nobilit. 3, ad fin. (v. p. 262). 3 de mundi optf. 56 (i. p. 51 f.). ADAM AND THE ‘EVIL IMAGINATION’ 83 yécer ha-ra‘ as the ground or source of human sin. This idea does, indeed, seem to show itself, in a defaced and not easily recognisable form, as the totality of the ‘ passions’ (7a46n) which are described as ‘ rooted in the flesh’ 1 and as ‘evils connatural with our race’?; and it is possible that we might be able to perceive its authentic lineaments in passages of the Philonian writings where its presence has not so far been suspected, had the Hellenistic Jews been able to agree upon one single Greek equivalent for the term yécer.2 “But Philo was prevented from allowing this con- ception to attain its full Rabbinical development in his teaching by his great horror (which, as we have seen, the doctors of Palestinian and Babylonian Judaism do not seem to have shared*) of making God the author of evil. And, where his Rabbinism leaves him in the lurch, his Platonism emerges with redoubled power, and sets a masterful grip upon the reins of his speculation. He never attained to a single, internally harmonious explanation of the origin of sin; but there can be little doubt that the 1 guts ver. div. haer. 54 (ili. p. 59): vd0a yap kal £éva Stavolas Ta adatos Ws adnbds 7a On, capKos exrrepuKdta, mpoceppilwrrac. 2 ibid. 55 (iii. p. 60): 7a otpduta Kaxa Tod yévous judy. Philo is deeply conscious of the universality or practical universality of innate sinfulness ; cf. de vita Mosis, iii. 17 (iv. p. 215): mavrl yervnTt® Kal av omovdaiov 7, Tap’ Gaov HAGeEv eis yeveowv, cu dues TO Gpaprdvov eariv ; de confus. ling. 17 (ii. p. 204) : é€q’ adrep H poxOnpa dvors 8.” Eauris Badiler ; de mut. nom. 6 (iii. p. 166 f.): daerpa pév dort Ta KaTappuTaivorTa THY puxiy, dmep exvifpacar Kal admoAovoacba mavteAds ovK Eveotiv. amodeimovrat yap e& avaykns tavtt OvyT@ ovyyeveis Kifpes, ds Awdfoar pev eikos, avaipeOfvar 8 eiodtrav advvatov: de poenit. I (v. p. 215): TO pev yap pndev ovvddAws auapreir, tovov Deob, taxa Sé Kai Oeiov dvdpds : de sacy. Abel. et Caint 33 (i. p. 259) : ayevotov yap mabav 7 Kaxidv puyiv edpetv aonavidrarov. Notice in this last passage the comparison of humanity to a ¢vpaya, or lump of dough, which re-appears in St. Paul (Rom. ix. 21, 1 Cor. v. 7), Tertullian (‘ conspersio’— v. infra, Pp. 328, n. 3), Ambrosiaster (‘ massa,’ p. 310), and Augustine (p. 328). 3 For 18’ LXX has 8rdvora (Gen. viii. 21), d1aBovAov (Ecclus. xv. 14), Stadoyiopds (1btd. xxvii. 6), evOdpnua (ibid. xxxvii. 3); etc. 4 de decem ovac. 33 (iv. p. 280): Oeds Fv, edOds 5€ KUpios ayabes, povwv ayabdy aitios, Kaxod Sé oddevds; quaest. in Gen. i. 78 (vi. p. 290): ‘deus enim malorum nullo modo causa est’ ; ibid. i. 89 (vi. p. 296): ‘minime pro causa < corruptionis > habentes divinitatem, quae immunis est malitia et malis : sola enim bona prius largiri est eius opus’; ibid. i. 100 (vi. p. 304): “< deus est > causa sane non omnium sed bonorum tantum eorumque qui secundum virtutem sunt; sicut enim expers est malitiae, ita etiam nec causa’; etc. 84 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN predominant factor in his thought on this subject is the Platonic conviction (identical with what we have in Lec- ture I described as the ‘ Hindu’ or monistic solution of the problem 1) that evil is inseparably bound up with finite, relative and phenomenal existence. With this conviction naturally coheres another Platonic tenet, the belief in the pre-existence of the human soul; and it is therefore not surprising to find, in two passages at least,* inchoate adumbrations of a theory (such as had been imaginatively suggested by Plato himself in the Phaedrus, and as was destined to be elaborated nearly two centuries later by another great Platonist of Alexandria, Origen 3) of a prenatal fall of individual souls, drawn downwards from the tran- scendental plane, which is their true home, through a sensual craving for earthly and bodily life, and contracting the taint of evil from their voluntary self-imprisonment in envelopes of material flesh. This idea, according to which every human birth represents the voluntary fall of a pre- existent spirit from the heavenly sphere, has played a considerable part in non-Christian systems of religious belief, will meet us more than once in the history of Christian speculation on the origins of evil in man, and will claim a measure of respectful consideration when we approach our final task of determining what is the essential Fall-doctrine of the Christian Church. But it must suffice at this point to emphasise the fact that the theory of pre-natal falls was only hinted at, and never worked out in detail, by Philo, and cannot, therefore, be reckoned amongst the influences which contributed to the shaping of that doctrine regarding the Fall and Original Sin which we shall find in the pages of the New Testament. 1 v. supra, Lecture I, p. 5. 2 de somn. i. 22 (iii. p. 244); de gigant. 3 (il. p. 53). But in de confus. ling. 17 (ii. p. 265) the souls of the wise are said to have descended from heaven to earth ‘ because of their love of contemplation and learning.’ The theory of pre-existence is generally believed to underlie Wisdom viii. 19: ‘Now I was a child of parts, and a good soul fell to my lot; Nay rather, being good, I came into a body undefiled ’ (though A. T. S. Goodricke, The Book of Wisdom [1913], pp. 212, 381 f., denies this). But Pseudo-Solomon does not suggest that the incarnation of a pre-existent soul is to be regarded as a‘ Fall.’ Suv Lectuie LY, p. 2h Zp. 4 y. Lecture VIII, p. 507 ff. ADAM AND THE ‘EVIL IMAGINATION’ 85 SUMMARY AND CONCLUSION In view of the vague and elusive nature of the ideas respecting the origin and ground of sin which prevailed within the Jewish Church, as it stood on the eve of the Incarnation, it would seem desirable, even at the cost of some repetition, to conclude our survey of the pre-Christian history of the Fall-doctrine with a brief summary of the results so far attained. We have seen that this doctrine is entirely absent from the Old Testament documents of a date prior to the Exile, and that its origin is to be found in the feeling of sin, understood now in a strictly ethical and not in a quasi-materialistic sense, which that great cata- strophe inspired in devout and introspective souls. The dreary impotence which for the most part characterised the life of the restored community during the Persian and Greek periods impressed deeply upon the mind of the later Israel the idea of the empirical universality of sin. Reflection and self-analysis seemed to show, lying behind this fact, an innate sinfulness or tendency towards sin, deeply rooted in human nature. But this psychological phenomenon itself required an explanation. The piety of the common folk, which found expression in the apocalyptic literature, could not endure the supposition that human nature as it stands, with the evil impulse rooted in it, represents human nature as created by God; and was accordingly compelled to postulate a voluntary and deliberate declension of man from the moral ideal set before him by his Maker—in other words, a ‘ Fall.’ The ancient traditions of Israel were ran- sacked in order to discover an event which could be identified with this hypothetical ‘ Fall’; and the first supposedly historical incident which was selected for this purpose was the unnatural intermarriage of divine and human beings narrated in Gen. vi. 1-4. But the difficulty of accounting, on this hypothesis, for the persistence of evil after the Flood forced the later apocalyptists back upon the Paradise-story of Gen. iii. ; which seemed to provide an explanation of the origin of evil fitting the known facts of human nature and the supposed facts of human history much more closely than 86 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN that based upon the Angel-legend, and, in course of time, pushed this earlier Fall-story into the background. Both of these Fall-theories, as elaborated in the apocalypses, are shot through and interwoven with frequent traces of two diverse, though not necessarily discrepant, ideas as to the nature and mode of propagation of sin—one which regards it as bound up with man’s advance in knowledge, and one which finds it in intimate association with his sensual appetites, particularly with that appetite which subserves the continuation of the race. Meanwhile, the official theology of the Jewish Church, as represented by the scribes, the authoritative custodians of its traditional deposit, was developing a solution of the problem of evil and its origin on largely different lines. Having (it is not unfair to suggest) a somewhat colder, more intellectualised and philosophical, conception of God than that which underlay the passionate piety of the pseudepigraphic writers, they felt less difficulty about attri- buting, or appearing to attribute, the ultimate responsibility for the existence of evil to Him; and the robust ethical libertarianism 4 which they had inherited from the prophets made it impossible for them to allow the sinner a possible excuse for or palliation of his wrong-doing, such as he might have found in the theory of an involuntarily inherited pro- pension towards sin. Hence Rabbinical theology rejects altogether the beliefs in a ‘ Fall,’ and in a hereditary infirmity or taint, and substitutes the idea of the ‘ evil imagination,’ individually implanted by the Creator in every man at his conception or birth—a mysterious tumultuous force per- petually welling up from the depths of the soul and appearing in consciousness as an imperious hunger for self-assertion, self-expression, and self-gratification, especially within the sphere of sex. (In the stress which they lay upon this matter, the scholastic and the popular theories join hands.) This impulse has been placed by the Creator in man, not 1 This firm belief in free-will was held by the Rabbis side by side with an equally firm belief in the universality of the Divine prevision, as appears from the celebrated saying of R. ‘Aqibah ‘ Everything is foreseen, and free- will is given’ (Pirge ’Abdth, ili. 24; Taylor, Sayings of the Jewish Fathers, 1897 edn., p. 59). But Divine prevision, even if construed as predestina- tion, does not in itself imply a radical evil in man. ADAM AND THE ‘EVIL IMAGINATION’ 87 indeed with the avowed object of causing him to sin, but rather to be the necessary pre-condition of moral virtue, which is only attained through its subjugation, by means of the Law, and its consequent direction towards good and noble ends. We have already suggested that this concep- tion appears to be in essence identical with the libido of recent psychology, an idea which may prove useful when we approach the constructive part of our task. The Rabbis were, however, sufficiently far influenced by the movements of popular thought and by the vague body of extra-biblical legend floating around the figures of Adam and Eve to be willing to find a place, at least within the haggadic elements of their teaching, for the theory that the transgression of the first man, though not the source of human sinfulness, was nevertheless attended by many disastrous physical conse- quences affecting both himself and his descendants, and including the forfeiture of the supernatural perfections supposed to have been enjoyed by him in his paradisal state. The doctrine of ‘ Original Righteousness’ would thus seem to have been already present in the Jewish scholasticism which formed part of the intellectual milieu within which the Christian doctrines of Man and of Sin were first formu- lated ; and, though it would doubtless be anachronistic to attribute to the Rabbis an explicit belief in ‘ Original Guilt,’ or the imputation of Adam’s sin to his descendants, yet it can now be seen that the potentialities of such a belief lay dormant in the traditional mythology which treated the Fall as the origin of physical evil. At the beginning, therefore, of our era three main theories as to the origin of human sin were current within that Jewish Ecclesta into which Christ and His Apostles were born, namely : | (rt) The theory of the older apocalyptists, which finds the ground of moral evil in a hereditary taint introduced into the world by the unnatural angel-marriages of Gen. vi. (2) The theory of the later apocalyptists, which traces the source of inherited sinfulness to the transgression of Adam and Eve narrated in Gen. iii. Under this head we must distinguish between (a) that form of the theory which, confining itself to the interpretation of the Biblical narrative, found the first sin in Adam’s wilful transgression of a known divine command, 88 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN and (b) that based upon extra-biblical folk-lore, which regards the moral corruption of mankind as a consequence of the physical pollution of Eve by the serpent, or Satan. (3) The theory of the Rabbinical, that is of the official and scholastic theology, that the psychological basis of sin consists in an ‘ evil impulse,’ ‘imagination,’ or ‘ disposition,’ which is not hereditary, but implanted by the Creator in each individual separately at the moment of conception or birth. To these should perhaps be added (though, as already observed, it appears to have exercised no influence upon the earliest Christian thought) : (4) The view of Philo, according to which evil is a necessary quality of finite and relative being, and is communicated to human souls through their individual falls to the material plane from the transcendental sphere in which they are conceived as having existed before their births in time—a view which appears to be substantially identical with what we have described as the “ Hindu theory * in Lecture I. These diverse and in many ways discrepant conceptions constituted the pile of raw material which lay ready to the hand of the earliest Christian theology, at the moment when first it bent itself to the task of building up a doctrine of Man and of Sin to serve as the logical presupposition and prius of its redemptive and soteriological scheme. It may thus be claimed that a candid research into the origins and growth of the later or ‘ Adamic’ version of the Fall-theory has confirmed the conclusion which was pro- visionally formulated at the close of Lecture I, as the result of our investigation of the earlier or ‘ angelic’ version— namely, that the true basis of the pseudepigraphic doctrines of the Fall and of Original Sin (as of their scholastic rival, the doctrine of the yéger ha-va‘) is to be found in facts of inner spiritual experience, in particular the experience of moral struggle and failure and of penitence; these beliefs are rooted in psychology, not in history. The question may well be asked ‘Does not this conclusion dispose of their claim to be based upon a Divine revelation? ’: and the last words of this lecture shall be devoted to the presen- tation of a reply as definite as can be given at this stage of our argument without anticipating contentions which have yet to be developed. ADAM AND THE ‘EVIL IMAGINATION ’ 89 The nature of this reply must necessarily be determined by the conception of ‘ Revelation’ which is in the mind. of our imaginary interlocutor. If by ‘ Revelation’ he means a purely external, objective, and mechanical impartition to men’s minds of Divine truth in a finished and unalterable form, the answer must be in the affirmative; the facts which we have passed under review do indeed dispose of any claim which might be put forward on behalf of the Fall-doctrine that it rests upon such an outward, and, so to speak, tangible revelation. In all probability Man has lived upon this planet for not less than half a million years, and the Genesis-stories, in their present form, can hardly number thirty centuries of existence ; we cannot, therefore, regard them as based upon genuine reminiscences of the infancy of the human race. We have, moreover, seen that the Fall-doctrine came into existence as the result of human reflection upon the problem of human sin, and that it was not until after a century of experimentation with the Watcher-legend that the Paradise-story was finally chosen as the nail from which the inferred chain of the hereditary evil causality was to be suspended ; it is, therefore, equally impossible for us to accept that more refined form of the theory of an ‘ objective revelation’ underlying the Fall- doctrine which would see in the narrative of Gen. iii. an allegory directly dictated by the Holy Spirit in order to acquaint mankind with the forgotten first page of its own moral history. But, when we deny that this doctrine originated in an exterior or objective revelation, conveyed through oracle, vision, or supernaturally dictated text, and affirm that its immediate historical source is to be found in human specu- lation, we do not thereby exclude the possibility that it may be ultimately attributable to a Divine revelation of an interior or subjective kind. God fulfils Himself in many ways; and the praeparatio evangelica which, as heirs of the ancient covenant, we Christians discern in the pages of the Old Testament, was unrolled before the eyes of the Jewish Fathers zoAvpep@s Kat moAvtpotws,1 in many fragments and after many manners. Deep, searching, self-abhorring 1 Heb. i. 1. go THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN penitence, in which the whole theory is rooted and from which it draws its vitality, is in any case the gift of God ; and Christian believers should find no antecedent difficulty in the supposition that the same indwelling Spirit, who bestowed this poignant experience upon the noblest of the apocalyptic thinkers, may also, with delicate invisible touches, have so guided and shaped the course of their introspective meditations and reflections upon it as to educe from their tumultuous feelings a system of ideas—imperfectly defined and commingled for the time being with error and legend, yet containing a truer explanation of the origin of moral evil than any that the mind of man had hitherto evolved, and capable of purification during the following centuries in accordance with the mind of Christ and of ultimate incorporation into the majestic fabric of Christian belief. If this be a true account of the matter, and if the word ‘ Revelation ’’ may in this connexion be understood in the subjective sense indicated above, the doctrines of the Fall and of Original Sin may still claim to be founded in a Divine revelation, as surely as though they had been graven upon visible tables of stone or proclaimed in words of thunder from the smouldering steeps of Sinai. Whether, indeed, such a hypothesis may legitimately be applied to the origin of these doctrines cannot be cate- gorically decided until we have completed our final task of examining their permanent residuum, as it has emerged from the crucible of Christian thought, in regard to its psychological and metaphysical validity, and must depend upon the verdict at which we arrive in the course of our last two lectures. If we see reason to believe that these ideas embody the true explanation of the origin of evil, or an explanation as true as is attainable with our present faculties, we shall have no hesitation in assigning their ultimate source to the subtle, but none the less real, inspirations of the Divine ; if not, we shall conclude that they are mere human figments. Meanwhile, we may be content to observe that, as no consideration of a friort probability can be adduced which militates against the hypothesis of an interior and subjective revelation lying behind these doctrines, so also no a fosteriort evidence fundamentally incompatible with ADAM AND THE ‘EVIL IMAGINATION’ QI such a hypothesis has been disclosed by a careful survey of their pre-Christian development. He who would unravel their obscure and confused beginnings must necessarily handle, as we have already seen, much that is fantastic and even repulsive. But it is to be expected that in imperfect and undeveloped phases of revelation good and evil, truth and error, should be found lying side by side; and the searcher after Divine verity who is both qualified and pre- pared to discriminate between the gold of genuine spirituality and the mythological dross in which it is often to be found embedded, will not allow his judgment to be deflected by the repugnance which he will naturally feel towards the coarse or puerile details which occasionally disfigure the Fall-stories in some of their expanded haggadic versions. Whether or not he admits the validity of the logic which argues from actual sins to innate sinfulness, and from innate sinfulness to a primal fall, he will at least respect the experience which it endeavours to express, and will salute across the centuries the devotion and the penitence of the Maccabean saints, the holy and humble men of heart who waited for the consolation of Israel. III. THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE NEW. TESTAMENT The expense of spirit in a waste of shame Is lust in action; and till action, lust Is perjured, murderous, bloody, full of blame, Savage, extreme, rude, cruel, not to trust, Enjoy’d no sooner but despised straight, Past reason hunted, and no sooner had Past reason hated, as a swallowed bait On purpose laid to make the taker mad ; Mad in pursuit and in possession so ; Had, having, and in quest to have, extreme ; A bliss in proof, and, proved, a very woe; Before, a joy proposed; behind, a dream, All this the world well knows: yet none knows well To shun the heaven that leads men to this hell. SHAKESPEARE, Sonnet CXXix. LECTURE III THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE NEW TESTAMENT 1 Cor.xv.22: ‘For asin Adam all die, even so in Christ shall all be made alive.’ Our last two lectures have been devoted to the task of investigating the origin and defining the content of the ideas which were prevalent within the Jewish Church with regard to the origin of evil, at the moment when Christianity appeared on the stage of human history. These, it will be remembered, were the popular beliefs in ‘ Original Sin’ and in a ‘ Fall,’ identified at first with the sin of the fallen Watchers, but, in later Judaism, more often with the trans- gression of Adam—and the Rabbinical, scholastic, or official conceptions of the ‘ evil imagination’ and of the imputation of Adam’s sin to his descendants. We now have to face a grave and momentous question—how did it come to pass that one only of these theories (the popular and pseudepigraphic Adam-theory) was taken over, to the exclusion of the others, by Christianity, and welded so firmly into the dogmatic structure of our religion, that succeeding ages have taken it for granted as one of the central pillars and supports of the Church’s Faith ? THE TEACHING OF JESUS CHRIST It might naturally be supposed, by one who had never enquired very closely into the question, that the choice of this particular theory to constitute the official Christian explanation of the origin of evil and to provide a logical prius for Redemption was made by the supreme and final 96 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN authority of Christ. But it must be said at once that an examination of our Lord’s sayings as recorded in the Synoptic Gospels reveals no evidence for such a supposition. It is, of course, true that He assumes the empirical univer- sality of sin as a fact. Even for those who fail to catch the sombre undertones pervading all His teaching with regard to the relations of God and man, this ought to be sufficiently shown by the fact that His fundamental message, which He proclaimed at the outset of His public ministry in Galilee, and on which the rest of His exhortation was based, is to be found summed up in the solemn cry, re-echoing the words of the Baptist “ Repent ye, for the kingdom of heaven is at hand.’? Though this charge was addressed to the people of Israel alone, yet if interpreted in its context of contem- porary ideas it inevitably implies the strict universality of the need for repentance ; for from the Jewish point of view ‘Gentiles ’ were ex hypothesi sinners.* This universal need of repentance and forgiveness is most clearly assumed in the Parable of the Unmerciful Servant,? and the petition for forgiveness included in the Lord’s Prayer, and the Saying, preserved by St. Luke alone, with regard to the Galileans “whose blood Pilate had mingled with their sacrifices, and the eighteen upon whom the tower in Siloam fell—* Except ye repent, ye shall all likewise perish.’ * (The reference to the ‘ ninety and nine just persons who need no repentance ’ ® can hardly be other than ironical.) Three sayings can indeed be cited (two of which~at least are respectively derived from two of the earliest sources of the Synoptic Gospels, St. Mark and Q) which appear to take the further step of assuming, behind the empirical univers- ality of actual sin, some kind of sinful disposition naturally inherent in the human soul; these are (a) St. Mark vii. teMatt, 1V.)177) Markit) 15; 2 Even St. Paul, twenty years later, can allow himself to use the phrase ‘ We who are Jews by birth, and not sinners of the Gentiles’ (Gal. ii. 15). For a lurid description of the hatred and contempt felt by strict Jews towards all Gentiles as such, see Edersheim, Life and Times of Jesus the Messiah (1901 edn.), i. go-92. 3 Matt. xvili. 23-35. 4 Luke xiii. 2-5. 5 Luke xv. 7; cf. Matt. xviii. 12, 13. This interpretation clearly applies also to a similar saying, Matt. ix. 13: ‘I came not to call the righteous, but sinners.’ THE DOCTRINE IN THE NEW TESTAMENT 97 21, 22 (= St. Matthew xv. 19): ‘ For from within, out of the heart of men, evil thoughts proceed, fornications, thefts, murders .. . all these evil things proceed from within, and defile the man’; (b) Matt. vii. rr (= Luke xi. 13): ‘If ye then, beng evil, know how to give good gifts unto your children, how much more shall your Father which is in heaven give good things to them that ask him ?’ 4 and (c) Matt. xii. 33, 34: ‘ Either make the tree good and its fruit good; or else make the tree corrupt and its fruit corrupt: for the tree is known by its fruit. Ye offspring of vipers, how can ye, being evil, speak good things ? for out of the abundance of the heart the mouth speaketh.’ ? But the affirmations that this evil tendency or quality is transmitted by physiological heredity, and is ultimately derived from a primordial transgression—affirmations which we have seen to be necessary constituents of a ‘ Fall- doctrine ’"—are conspicuous by their absence. If, indeed, it is possible to connect the ideas underlying these sayings with current Jewish thought at all, the particular theory of which they are reminiscent would seem to be that of the yeécer ha-ra‘: for, as we have already seen, the ‘ heart,’ which in (a) and (c) is implicitly asserted to be the home of sinfulness, is again and again described by the Rabbis as the source of the ‘ evil imagination’: and it is possible that the phrase ‘bad’ (or ‘ evil’) thoughts (dvaroyropot kakot Mark; zovypot Matt.) in the first of these sayings may be a direct translation of an original yécer va‘.2 But this coincidence of thought and language cannot legitimately be pressed so far as to yield the further conclusion that our Lord held the distinctive position of the Rabbinical doctrine, namely that the ‘ evil imagination’ is, not inherited, but separately implanted by the Creator in the heart of each individual: and such a position would seem to be in sharp 1 This saying is assigned to Q by such representative authorities as Harnack, Sir John Hawkins, and Canon Streeter. St. Luke has ‘ holy spirit’ (mvedua ady.ov, without the article) for ‘ good things’ in the apodosis of the sentence. 2 The Lukan parallel is vi. 43-45, which, however, omits the question “ How can ye, being evil, speak good things?’ , and taketh with himself seven other spirits more evil than himself, and they enter in and dwell there, and the last state of that man becometh worse than the first. Satan asked to have you, that he might sift you as wheat. Ye are of your father the devil, and the lusts of your father it is your will to do. —simultaneously bearing in mind the total absence from our Lord’s discourses of any allusion to the Fall of Adam— and if we assume that, on the whole, the sayings preserved in the Gospels fairly represent not merely the content but (3) Matt. xii. 43-45 = Luke xi. 24-36: ‘ When is gone out of the man’... etc. (4) Mark iv. 15 = Matt. xiii. 19 = Luke vili. 12: ‘ Straightway cometh Satan, and taketh away the word which hath been sown in them.’ (5) Matt. xiii. 38-39 ‘ The enemy that sowed them’ (the tares) ‘ is the devil.’ (6) Mark viii. 33 = Matt. xvi. 23 (Peter addressed as ‘ Satan,’ a passage which presumably implies the diabolical origin of mean or unworthy thoughts). (7) Luke xxii. 31: ‘Satan asked to have you, that he might sift you as wheat.’ (8) John viii. 44: © Ye are of your father the devil . . .’ (9) John xii. 31, (10) John xiv. 30, and (rr) John xvi. 11 (Satan described as ‘ the prince of this world’). (12) John xvii. 15: ‘I pray not that thou shouldest take them from the world, but that thou shouldest keep them from the Evil One’ (for this translation of €« rod movnpod, see Westcott’s note iu loc.). The five Johannine passages are, of course, quoted not as verbally exact transcripts of individual Dominical Jogia but as generally reliable evidence for the trend of our Lord’s teaching in regard to this matter; see the statement of the position assumed in this section with regard to the Fourth Gospel, supra, p. 101 f. The list includes only sayings which trace the origin of moral evil to Satan ; if physical evil, such as disease, were also in question, the list could be considerably lengthened. The most impressive testi- mony to our Lord’s use of the Satanic hypothesis as the explanation of evil solicitations does not reach us in the form of a ‘ saying’ at all; itis the whole narrative of His own Temptation, which must be derived ulti- mately from Him. 112 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN the balance and proportion of His teaching—it is not unreasonable to suggest that we shall find ourselves con- firmed in the conclusion that the Fall-doctrine never re- ceived any explicit sanction from the lips of Christ Himself, such as that which He undoubtedly gave to the belief in the existence and activity of demons. It does not follow in the least that He condemned or rejected the Fall-theory: we are justified in presuming that, if He had disapproved of the possible holding of this doctrine by His followers, He would have denounced it in terms so direct and trenchant that they would inevitably have found a place in the primitive collections of His sayings which underlie our present Gospels.1 The argument from the silence of the Gospels is double-edged: it can be used as well to show that Christ did not explicitly condemn the doctrines of the Fall and of Original Sin as to show that He did not explicitly approve or promulgate them. But further than this we have no warrant for going. We must for the moment content ourselves with the only conclusion which can safely be based upon the evidence, namely that (to the best of our knowledge) our Lord said nothing either for or against any one of the theories respecting the origin of human sin which in His day prevailed amongst the Jews —save only in so far as a considerable number of His sayings may be taken to sanction the current belief in the existence of personal evil spirits. THE ‘ WATCHER’ AND ‘ ADAM’ STORIES IN THE APOSTOLIC WRITINGS It would seem, therefore, that the Gospels yield us no information with regard to this interesting question—how 1 Those who do not admit the assumption made here and also towards the end of the last paragraph must in logic renounce any attempt to grasp or to formulate the teaching of the historical Jesus as a coherent whole. But the validity of this assumption is guaranteed for the vast majority of students of the Life of Christ by the overwhelming impression which His recorded teaching produces of an internal harmony and unity so all- pervasive and satisfying that it cannot be attributed to chance or to sub- sequent redaction. a THE DOCTRINE IN THE NEW TESTAMENT 1713 was it that Christianity became committed to the Adamic version of the Fall-doctrine rather than to any other of the theories then current ? We must, accordingly, turn for light to the Epistles. The facts disclosed by an examination of these documents may be very simply summarised. The sole authority within the New Testament for the Adam- theory is to be found in the writings of St. Paul. The only passages which can be adduced as embodying this doctrine in one or other of its aspects are certain portions of the 5th, 6th, and 7th chapters of the Epistle to the Romans : the exposition of the parallelism between the two Adams, contained in 1 Cor. xv.; and the brief description of the inbred hostility between ‘ flesh’ and ‘spirit’ in Gal. v.+ It will be noticed that these Epistles all belong to the group recognised by Baur and the radical critics of Tibingen as ‘ pillar-Epistles,’ so that we may reasonably consider our- selves dispensed from the preliminary task of vindicating their authenticity : and also that they belong to the same period of the Apostle’s life, the period of the missionary journeys and the Judaistic controversy, so that we need not expect to find any pronounced development or change of opinion within them, and may assume that they express a single, internally harmonious view. The scope of our immediate enquiry is thus fortunately circumscribed and simplified. But it remains true to say that if we confine our attention to the New Testament, St. Paul, rather than Christ, is the teacher on whose authority these Jewish doctrines have descended to the modern world. A complete statement, however, of the data on which our judgment must ultimately be based should include the very striking and remarkable fact that, whilst the only 1 The sentence which has often been quoted from Eph. ii. 3 as a‘ proof- text’ establishing the doctrine of original sin—‘ we . . . were by nature children of wrath’ (yea réxva dvoet dpyis)—is now generally admitted to have no relevance to the matter, and is therefore not mentioned in the text. ‘ By nature’ (¢vce.) means no more than ‘ in ourselves,’ and ‘ children of wrath’ is a Hebraism meaning ‘ objects of the Divine wrath.’ All, therefore, that the text means is that Jews and Gentiles alike, prior to their acceptance of Christianity, were de facto actual sinners and as such deserving of God’s wrath: there is no suggestion of a here- ditarily acquired sinfulness antecedent to actual sin. See J. Armitage Robinson, St. Paul’s Epistle to the Ephesians, 1909, pp. 50 and 156. I I14 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN Fall-theory known to the Pauline corpus is that based upon : the story of Gen. iii., the Catholic Epistles present two clear traces of the influence of the Watcher-legend. The Epistle of St. Jude alludes to the ‘ angels which kept not their own principality but left their proper habitation’; these are described by implication as ‘ giving themselves over to fornication and going after strange flesh,’ for which reason they are declared in the true Enochian vein to be ‘ kept in everlasting bonds under darkness unto the judgment of the great day.’1 And the so-called Second Epistle of Peter, which is generally assigned to the second Christian century, speaks of ‘ the corruption that is in the world through lust ’ 2 —that is, the lust of the fallen angels, who are affirmed, as in the Epistle of Jude, to be ‘ cast down to hell and com- mitted to pits of darkness to be reserved unto judgment.’ 3 It is a striking testimony to the vitality of the older Fall- theory that a recrudescence of it should be found in a document written more than a century after the beginnings of Christian history. To these traces of the Watcher-story in the non-Pauline Epistles we must add the fact that it appears to have inspired St. Paul’s celebrated injunction that women are to be covered in the church ‘ because of the angels,’ 4 though his loyalty to the Adam-tradition prevents him from making any use of this earlier theory as the explanation of the ultimate origin of sin. The situation, therefore, which the Epistles reveal to us as existing within Christianity towards the end of the first generation is this. It is probable that the Watcher-theory, inherited from the Judaism of the second century B.c. through the Book of Enoch and similar works, still lingered in some Jewish-Christian circles. But the Adam-theory, derived from the tradition which expresses itself in Jubilees, 2 Enoch, and Wisdom, must have predominated within Jewish Christianity as within non-Christian Judaism. And it would seem to have been the only Fall-theory known within the borders of Gentile Christendom. This latter conclusion, paradoxically enough, can be shown from the small amount of space which is devoted to the subject— a point which needs a word of elucidation. RGU 0,17 ie OLer 1 As S02, Petersina as 4 t: Cort to. — ee THE DOCTRINE IN THE NEW TESTAMENT 115 Nearly seventy years ago Dr. Jowett, in his Commentary on the Epistle to the Romans, suggested that the small amount of space occupied in the New Testament by the texts implying the doctrine of a hereditary sinfulness flowing from Adam constituted a clear proof of the uncertainty and unimportance of this doctrine.t It would seem that in for- mulating this argument Dr. Jowett was still unconsciously dominated by the old artificial conception of Scripture as a systematic handbook of theology, a magazine of proof-texts, in which the importance of a particular subject can be measured by the amount of space devoted to its considera- tion. To-day, however, the interpretation of St. Paul’s writings is largely governed by an entirely contrary principle, which is based upon the psychology of letter- writing, and cannot be better stated than in the words of Professor Kirsopp Lake : Treat the Epistles as letters; and recognise that in letters the subjects discussed are not those on which all parties are agreed but those on which there is a difference of opinion ; so that the really central points [of the Christian Faith, that is] are not those which are supported by arguments but those which are assumed as generally believed.? Apply this principle to the two Epistles in which the Adamic theory is expressly mentioned, Romans and 1 Corinthians, and a clear result emerges. The problems upon which the Apostle lavishes a wealth of laborious dialectic, of glowing eloquence, or of mordant irony—such questions as the value of faith as compared with works, the function and nature of the Mosaic Law, the constitution of the resurrection body —are precisely those upon which Christian thought is not agreed, and in regard to which St. Paul has to wage a 1 op. cit. (1855 edn.), p. 162. ‘ How slender is the foundation in the New Testament for the doctrine of Adam’s sin being imputed to his pos- terity !’ (but it seems clear that Dr. Jowett is thinking not merely of ‘ Original Guilt’ but also of ‘ Original Sin’) ‘ two passages in St. Paul at most, and these of uncertain interpretation. The little cloud, no bigger than a man’s hand, has covered the heavens. To reduce such subjects to their proper proportions we should consider: First, what space they occupy tn Scripture’ .. . (italics ours), etc. 2 Earlier Epistles of St. Paul, p. 424, 116 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN stubborn fight for the triumph of his own view. But behind this array of hotly disputed questions it is easy to discern a solid nucleus of generally accepted ideas, or what St. Paul assumes to be such, which only come to the surface of his thought as it were accidentally, in unpremeditated interjections or passing allusions; or, if designedly men- tioned, are adduced, not as subjects of discussion, but as universally admitted premises to be used for the establish- ment of further truth. And to this residuum of beliefs which the Apostle assumes to be common ground to himself and his readers, it would appear that the Fall-doctrine belongs, precisely because of the cursory and casual nature of the allusions which are made to it. In neither of these Epistles does St. Paul make any attempt to prove the Adamic theory: on the contrary, he takes it for granted, in paren- theses and obiter dicta, as though it were a matter about which there was admittedly no dispute, and uses it to support or illustrate some further position—the universality of grace or the logical necessity for a resurrection. Nor is there any reason for supposing that Rome and Corinth were peculiar in this regard amongst the churches of the Gentile-Christian world. In the Roman letter, indeed, the Apostle’s quiet assumption of these ideas as indisputable truths is specially impressive in view of the fact that the Roman Christians were not his own converts and (at the time when he wrote to them) had never seen him in the flesh. If, therefore, the exegetical canon formulated by Professor Kirsopp Lake be valid, we are entitled to conclude that the Adamic Fall- doctrine was generally accepted throughout the churches of the Uncircumcision. It would save us some time and trouble at a later stage - in the enquiry ! if we could accept the principle that what St. Paul takes for granted and does not labour to prove must have been explicitly accepted by the totality of his readers, au pied de la lettre. But I must needs think that Professor Lake has, in the passage quoted, phrased the principle rather too absolutely, and that, in an unqualified form, it is as unreliable an instrument of interpretation as the opposite 1 See’ Lecture LV; *p.1177 ff. THE DOCTRINE IN THE NEW TESTAMENT 117 maxim which it has superseded, and of which we cited a characteristic expression from Dr. Jowett. As it stands, it ignores the fact that a man of masterful character and intense conviction, such as was St. Paul, is often prone to assume that his hearers, or readers, consciously agree with him, when in point of fact they are merely not prepared to contradict him. It appears to me that Professor Lake’s principle must be somewhat modified in the light of this psychological law, and that the utmost which can be safely inferred from St. Paul’s confident assumption of the Adam- doctrine is that no other theory of the origin of evil was in possession of the Gentile-Christian field at the time when he wrote. It is possible that some Corinthian and Roman Christians, who were by birth Hellenistic Jews or had been “God-fearers,) may have already been in possession of a belief in the Adamic theory, as the result of a study of Ben-Sirach, or the Book of Wisdom, but that we cannot tell ; it is also possible that many of those who had been converted directly from paganism to Christianity had never given a thought to the question of the ultimate origin of evil at all. The facility with which St. Paul assumes the Adam-theory merely proves that it was self-evident for him; so far as the Gentile-Christian world is concerned, we cannot infer more from his language than that no other theory was a serious rival to it. It would seem, then, that when St. Paul wrote 1 Cor. and Rom., rather less than thirty years after the death of Christ, the Adamic Fall-doctrine existed within the Christian Church. But it can hardly be said as yet to have been universally and consciously accepted by the Christian Church as such; there is some evidence which suggests that its older rival, the Watcher-theory, still lingered in Jewish-Christian circles, and it is possible that many Gentile Christians may, at this early date, never have heard of it. The question as to the effects produced on Christian thought by St. Paul’s unhesitating adoption of this doctrine in the two Epistles just mentioned must be reserved for discussion in our next Lecture.1 There is no trace in the New Testa- ment of the Rabbinical view that the bias towards evil SDE GOik: 118 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN is not inherited, but freshly implanted by God in every individual at birth.t A SUGGESTED THEORY REGARDING THE PASSAGE OF THE FALL-DOCTRINE FROM JUDAISM INTO CHRISTIANITY It must be observed, however, that this general and preliminary review of the Epistles has by no means solved, but rather accentuated, the problem of the precise way in which the Fall-doctrine passed over from Judaism into Christianity. In view of the solemnity with which St. Paul assures his Corinthian converts ‘ I received of the Lord that which I also handed on to you,’? the question becomes more insistent than ever, How could the Apostle have taken these doctrines for granted, especially in writing to Christians whom he had never seen, if they had not direct Dominical authority behind them? It would be a counsel of despair to suggest that Christ must have given instruction, of which no record has survived, on these mysterious subjects during the ‘Great Forty Days’ which intervened between His Resurrection and Ascension. We must frankly admit that the process by which the Fall-doctrine, or rather one parti- cular version of it, was inherited by the Christian Church from its Jewish mother is involved in some obscurity, and that we are moving in the realms of speculation ; but, if we bear in mind the fact that Christianity was conceived by its earliest adherents, not as a new religion intended to compete with Judaism, but rather as an improved form of Judaism—improved, that is, by the knowledge of the identity of the Messiah and the consciousness of the possession of the Spirit—it will not be difficult to frame a hypothesis which will amply account both for the silence of our Lord and for the confidence of St. Paul in regard to the Adamic doctrine of the origin of human sin. 1 James i. 13, 14 (‘ God cannot be tempted with evil, and he himself tempteth no man; but each man is tempted, when he is drawn away by his own lust [é€mv@uyia] and enticed’) may represent a Jewish-Christian attempt to retain the general idea of the yé¢er ha-ra‘ whilst repudiating the belief that its evil nature is due to God. Re COrs Xi 29)s C7 als0) 1) COL RV 53. THE DOCTRINE IN THE NEW TESTAMENT 119 Such a hypothesis, it seems to me, may reasonably be founded upon the fact that the original birthplace of Christianity, the scene of our Lord’s childhood, youth, and early manhood, the principal theatre of His public labours and the home of eleven of His apostles,t was Galilee. The remoteness of Galilee from the official centre of Judaism at Jerusalem, and perhaps the genial and smiling aspect of external nature, tended to develop amongst its sturdy peasantry a freer and more imaginative type of piety than that which prevailed in the neighbourhood of the capital, under the shadow of the Temple and the Rabbinical schools, upon the bare, rugged hills of Judaea ; and it is known that the religiously outcast stratum of Jewry, contemptuously described as the ‘am ha-’drec, the ‘ people of the earth,’ whose manual avocations debarred them from the full observance of the Law, lay thick amongst the population of this northern province. The assertion sometimes made, that the pseudepigrapha, and the apocalyptic genre of thought which they illustrate, were especially popular in Galilee cannot, indeed, be proved, but, in view of the circum- stances just mentioned, it would seem to be highly probable ; and Christianity itself must have at first appeared to be, even if in fact it was not, a movement for hastening the eschatological cataclysm which this literature had, with such a wealth of lurid imagery, described. Nothing, therefore, could be more natural than that the rough fisher- men and artisans who were the first to follow our Lord should have known and cared little about the learned speculations of the great scholars and divines of Jerusalem with regard to the yéger ha-va‘; nor is it less natural that, with minds steeped in the apocalyptic literature, they should have carried on into the new movement the ideas about a 1 Kerioth, the birthplace of Judas, was in the Negeb of Judaea. See Hastings DB. s.v. Kerioth. 2 For a description of the religious state of Galilee in the days of Christ, bringing out the theological and other differences between Galilean and Judaean piety, see A. Edersheim, Life and Times of Jesus the Messiah (1901 edn.), i. 223 ff. Cf. also E. Schirer, History of the Jewish People (E. tr. 1893), ii. 1, pp. 3-5; A.C. Headlam, Life and Teaching of Jesus Christ (1923), pp. 110 ff., and the works there referred to; A. Neubauer, Géographie du Talmud (1868), pp. 177-233, and Merrill, Galilee in the Time of Christ (1885). 120 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN primitive catastrophe and a consequent inherited corrup- tion which they had imbibed from Enoch, the Book of Jubilees, or the Testaments of the Twelve Patriarchs. Indeed, it is difficult to see any reason why they should have exchanged these ideas for others, in default of explicit instruction on the subject by the Master Himself. The only assumption, therefore, that need be made in order to obtain a satisfactory explanation of the passage of the Fall- doctrine from Judaism into Christianity is the very simple assumption which, as we have seen, is amply consistent with, if not necessitated by, the evidence of the Gospels— namely, that our Lord abstained from taking any steps to eradicate this belief from the minds of His disciples; in other words, that He tacitly acquiesced in the continued existence within His movement of the ideas of a ‘ Fall’ of some kind and of a hereditary corruption derived from it. If this hypothesis be correct—and I do not know of any other which covers all the facts—it would follow that these doctrines are not altogether devoid of Dominical sanction ; they must be deemed to enjoy at least such a measure of approbation as is involved in the fact of deliberate toleration. At any rate we may assume that the Twelve and the Galilean nucleus of the primitive community would continue to take the Fall-conception for granted, because they had no reason for not doing so. The newly converted Saul would thus find himself introduced into a community of which the leaders were Galileans, and therefore presumably believers in the Fall- theory. What his pre-Christian ideas on the subject of the origin of sin had been it is impossible to tell; he was doubt- less familiar with the Rabbinical stories about the disastrous physical consequences of Adam’s sin, and he may well have learnt ‘at the feet of Gamaliel’ the doctrine of the evil yécgey, an idea which, as we shall later see, the Apostle Paul did not altogether discard. But it is reasonable to assume that after his conversion he received some instruction in the essential ideas underlying the Christian movement, whether from Ananias and the Christians of Damascus, or at a later stage from the original Twelve. If, then, he found that the Fall-doctrine was very generally assumed in the THE DOCTRINE IN THE NEW TESTAMENT rar society which he had entered, that it was held by those who had known the Lord in the flesh, and that, if not strictly part of the Gospel, it was tacitly assumed as part of the setting of the Gospel, by many or most of those who ‘ seemed to be pillars,’ it would be the most natural thing in the world that he should himself adopt it without question, and use it in at least two of his letters as though it were an axiomatic truth undisputed by any Christian. The passage of the Fall-doctrine into Christianity may thus be considered to have been provisionally accounted for. But we have still to explain the immensely greater popularity, which ultimately became an exclusive dominance, within the Church of the Adamic theory of the Fall as con- trasted with the Angel-theory. It is clear that, as we have said, our Lord gave His followers no guidance whatever on this subject ; even if we suppose, as suggested above, that He consciously permitted a germinal theory of ‘ original sin’ to pass on into Christianity, it would seem that He left His Church to choose for itself between the two traditional Fall-stories. If we assume that the Epistle of St. Jude really comes from the pen of one of the Lord’s ‘ brethren,’ this supposition receives an almost startling confirmation : for the passage which we have already cited (v. 6) (cf. v. 14) would then prove that the inspiration of the Book of Enoch —and strongly suggest that the ‘angelic’ theory of the Fall—was accepted within Christ’s own family circle, pre- sumably without any protest on His part. But we have seen in Lecture I, that by the beginning of the Christian era the Adam-story had already attained to a position of pre- dominance over its earlier rival, even within the Jewish Church ; and, if any further reason be required at this stage for its later triumph within Christianity, it may plausibly be suggested that the deciding factor was the personal influence of St. Paul himself. We may well believe that the great Apostle’s keen spiritual and ethical perceptions were revolted by the unedifying emphasis laid on sexual sin by “the Watcher-story, especially as expanded in the Book of Enoch, and that its eventual dispossession in favour of the more austere and elevated Adam-story was not the least of the services which his genius rendered to the Christian Church. 122 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN We need not be deterred from attributing the final expulsion of the Watcher-theory from Christianity to the influence of St. Paul by the fact that he makes one, or, if the Pastoral Epistles be reckoned as completely Pauline, two allusions to a theory which is even more liable than the Watcher-story to the objection just mentioned, that is, the theory which exempts Adam from all responsibility for the Fall and finds the source of evil in a physical pollution or inquinamentum communicated to Eve by the tempter. The first and most certainly Pauline of these allusions is that contained in 2 Cor. xi. 2, 3: ‘I am jealous over you witha godly jealousy: for I espoused you to one husband, that I might present you as a pure virgin to Christ. But I fear lest by any means, as the serpent beguiled Eve in his crafti- ness, your minds should be corrupted from the simplicity and the purity that is toward Christ.’ If these two verses be considered together, the underlying thought is not difficult to discern. The second is that contained in 1 Tim. il. 14, in which the author gives as the reason for his objec- tion to women preachers the statement that ‘ Adam was first formed, then Eve; and Adam was not beguiled, but the woman being beguiled hath fallen into transgression.’ + It is noticeable that the word translated ‘ beguile ’ (é€azarav) is the same in both passages, being doubtless used with a certain implied nuance, very much like the English word ‘seduce.’ 2 Even if, however, we assume that both these passages alike come from the lips of St. Paul, there can be no doubt that nothing is further from his mind than the idea of seriously employing this unpleasant piece of haggadic mythology as the basis of his doctrine of sin: these two allusions to it are of the most cursory nature, conceived in the spirit of Philonic allegorism, and are merely intended to sharpen the literary form of his moral and practical exhortations. 1 For a full discussion of these passages, see H. St. John Thackeray, The Relation of St. Paul to Contemporary Jewish Thought, cc. ii. iii. (Pp. 50-57). 2 The use of this verb was, no doubt, suggested primarily by Gen. iii. 13, LXX—o dds jrarynoév pe, kal Edayor. But it is significant that anmaradv is twice at least used by LXX as =‘ seduce,’ in the narrower sense of the term (Exod. xxii. 16; Judith xii. 16). ee ee eee Se THE DOCTRINE IN THE NEW TESTAMENT 123 THE PAULINE DOCTRINE. (a) THE FALL The foregoing observations have, it may be hoped, explained—so far as it is possible to explain—the transit of the Fall-doctrine, and particularly of its Adamic form, from the Jewish into the Christian Church. We now approach a second and no less important task, that of examining the classical Pauline passages, with the object of reconstructing in detail what may be called the most primitive systematic presentation of the doctrine within Christianity; it is doubtless unnecessary to prove at length that the results of this enquiry must, in the nature of the case, have the most vital bearing upon our ultimate definition, of ‘ that which has been believed everywhere, always, and by all.’ The earliest passage in the Pauline writings which refers to Adam’s Fall is 1 Cor. xv. 21, 22: 21. For since by man came death, by man came also the resurrection of the dead. 22. For asin Adam all die, so also in Christ shall all be made alive. (The second allusion to Adam which occurs in the same celebrated chapter, vv. 45-49, does not refer to his trans- gression, but only to his ‘ okie ’ (buxekds, Which may be roughly translated ‘animal’) or ‘earthy’ (yoikds) nature or constitution—a nature which, it is implied, was given him at his creation,! and cannot therefore be regarded as a consequence of the Fall. These latter verses, accord- ingly, are irrelevant to the subject of our enquiry, and need not be further discussed.) The two verses 2I, 22 quoted above do not raise the question of hereditary sinfulness, and deal solely with the origin of physical death. This is asserted to be a direct con- sequence of Adam’s sin. The phrase ‘since by man came 1 Verse 45: ‘So also, it is written, The first man Adam became a living soul’ (éyévero . . . ets uyiv CSoav, quoted from Gen. ii. 7, LXX). Itis worth noting that the almost contemptuous terms in which the Apostle speaks of the first Adam’s constitution, as ‘ earthy’ and merely ‘* psychic’ or animal, suggest that he cannot have held any exalted doctrine of ‘ Original Perfection’ or ‘ Righteousness.’ 124 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN death ’ (v. 21) must refer to some one specific event marking the entry of death into the world, and this event can hardly be anything other than the primal transgression. And the words ‘ in Adam ’ (v. 22), modelled as they are on the pattern of the great phrase ‘ in Christ,’ 1 which pervades the Pauline writings from the earliest to the latest, cannot mean less than ‘ by virtue of their organic union or continuity with Adam,’ that is, in other words, ‘ by virtue of their descent from him.’ This passage, therefore, asserts that physical mortality is a universal hereditary consequence of Adam’s Fall. It will, however, be seen at once that this position does not go beyond that of the Wisdom of Solomon (‘ by the envy of the devil death entered into the world,’ ii. 24), a book with which St. Paul may well have been familiar? ; it appears to be assumed by the Apostle as by Pseudo-Solomon, that Adam was created, and but for his Fall would have remained, in a condition of immortality. To ascertain St. Paul's beliefs with regard to the ethical and psychological results of the Fall, we must turn to the Epistle to the Romans, which contains the palmary texts or loc classict upon which the whole subsequent development of the Fall-doctrine within Christianity has been founded. The first and most crucial of these texts is the celebrated passage Rom. v. 12-21, round the interpretation of which controversy has raged continuously, at least from the days of Origen onwards. In studying these obscure and tangled sentences we must bear in mind the fact that St. Paul is dictating his letter to the Roman Church; that dictation to a stenographer, although an easy and rapid method of composition, involves the inconvenience of inability to see at a glance what has just been dictated; and that con- sequently, in dictated prose, sentences are liable to remain incomplete, subordinate clauses are left hanging in the air with no principal sentence on which to depend, and essential 1 On this phrase see Deissmann, Die neutestamentliche Formel tn Christo Jesu, Marburg, 1892, and the note in Sanday and Headlam, ICC., Epistle to the Romans, on Rom. vi. 11. 2 Cf. the note in Sanday and Headlam, Romans (1905 edn.), pp. 267 ff. : ‘ The relation of St. Paul’s argument in chap. ix. to the Book of Wisdom’ ; and above, Lecture I, p. 29, n. 4, for the various dates which have been suggested for the composition of Wisdom. es 8 a S pl ie iy ans ——. ne eee ae THE DOCTRINE IN THE NEW TESTAMENT 125 links of thought are apt to remain in the author’s mind and never to appear on paper at all. Ordinarily such blemishes are remedied by a careful revision of the stenographer’s copy ; but the frequent anacolutha and inconcinnities which abound in St. Paul’s letters make it clear that he had no time for the processes of grammatical, stylistic or logical polishing, and that he usually contented himself with scrawl- ing a final personal message, in the large letters which may have been necessitated by defective eyesight,! at the end of Tertius’ manuscript, which was forthwith despatched, unrevised, to its destination. In order, therefore, to recon- struct in its fullness the series of ideas lying behind a difficult passage such as this, our exegesis must be prepared to supply a certain number of missing members by the judicious use of conjectural restoration. It will be convenient to consider the passage in two divisions (a) vv. 12-14 and (0) vv. 15-21; the first of these may now be given at length. 12. Therefore, as through one man sin entered into the world, and death through sin; and so death passed unto all men, for that all sinned : 13. For until the law sin was in the world: but sin is not imputed where there isnolaw. | 14. Nevertheless death reigned from Adam unto Moses, even over them that had not? sinned after the likeness of Adam’s transgression, who is a figure of him that was to come. It is clear from the context that St. Paul, when he began this section, had no idea of writing a formal dissertation on 1 Cf. Gal. vi. 11: tSere myAixous buitv ypdupacu Eypapa TH Euh xeupl. 2 The argument developed in the text depends upon the retention of this ‘ not’ (u) ; which has the all but unanimous testimony of the Greek MSS. behind it, and appears in TR., Vulg., WH., and RV. But there is some authority for its omission : Prof. Souter’s note (in his critical edition of the Revisers’ Greek Testament) runs as follows: p7 om. 424* * al. pauc. ‘IL (vt.d *) Orig. (Tert. Cypr. Victorin.) codd. uetusti ap. Ambst., quos sequitur ipse, codd. plur. ap. Aug., qui omnes uel fere omnes om. etiam kat. It will be noted that, with the exception of Origen, the corrector of 424, and the text of three other cursives, these authorities are all Latin. We may appeal with confidence to the maxim difficilior lectio potior in support of 7, as its omission (by making all who died between Adam and Moses guilty of actual sin) might easily have been thought by an unin- telligent scribe or translator to simplify the passage ; whereas its insertion into a text which did not contain it would be psychologically inexplicable. 126 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN the Fall; he may indeed have had no definite intention even of touching upon it. The first eleven verses of c. v. are of a purely practical and hortatory character, designed to impress upon his Roman readers the duty of cultivating in themselves dispositions of hope, interior peace, and confidence in God, and appealing to the immediate con- sciousness (which he assumes to be possessed by all Christians) of redemption through the atoning Blood of Christ and sanctification by the indwelling Spirit, as the all-sufficient logical ground of these virtues. It then occurs to him that the parallel between the first and the second Adams, the natural and the spiritual heads of the race, which (as we have just seen) he has already employed in I Cor. xv. to establish the congruity of an eschatological resurrection, may at this point be effectively re-used, in order to enhance the glories of Christ’s saving work by momentarily opposing to them the sombre consequences of Adam’s Fall, and so to deepen in the minds of his readers the sense of Redemption as a solid and reasonable basis for Christian confidence and peace. He accordingly begins his next sentence (v. 12) ‘ Therefore, as through one man sin entered into the world, and death through sin,’ intending doubtless to supply the words ‘so also through one man righteousness came into the world, and through righteousness life,’ or some similar phrase, to serve as its principal clause. Unfortunately, however, for the structure and symmetry of his sentence— though fortunately for our comprehension of his theology of sin—having once raised the question of the connexion between death and sin, he cannot resist the temptation to insert a parenthetic explanation of it into the ‘as’ clause; one idea brings up another by the chain of inevitable associa- tion, and the parenthesis expands to such a length that it overpowers the ‘ as ’ clause, and drives the principal sentence for the time being entirely out of his mind. What had, therefore, been intended merely as a passing allusion to the contrast between the typical acts of Adam and Christ and their respective consequences becomes in effect a short excursus on the subject of the Fall. For the immediate purpose of our enquiry we may neglect the disordered syn- tactical structure of these three verses, and treat their THE DOCTRINE IN THE NEW TESTAMENT 127 contents as a series of detached propositions which, taken together, will reveal to us in its main aspects the doctrinal idea which is in the Apostle’s mind. Examined in this way, the first two affirmations con- tained in v. 12 do not seem to present any: difficulty. Sin entered into the world (presumably from some external source, which may be identified with Satan or the serpent of Gen. iil.) through the transgression of Adam. Simul- taneously physical death entered into the world as an inseparable concomitant of sin. So far all is plain sailing. With the third affirmation we begin to get into difficul- ties. The Apostle continues ‘ And thus’ (that is, in con- sequence of the Fall) ‘ death passed abroad unto all men,’ in other words, was distributed or disseminated like a plague amongst all men, ‘ because all sinned’ (e¢’ & mavres yjpaptov).1 These words bring us to the central crux of this difficult passage. In what sense does he mean that all men ‘sinned’? Does he mean that, when Adam sinned, all men constructively or potentially sinned 7m him, because they were all contained in his loins at the moment when he sinned ? or, that in subsequent centuries all men actually did commit wrongful acts, thereby imitating the first man, although they were in no way obliged or hereditarily inclined to sin ? or is his fundamental thought merely this, that all men were in some vague sense “ sinful,’ in virtue of having a tendency to sin within them? The next verse (13) will throw light on this problem. The Apostle has just stated, with bald simplicity, that all Adam’s descendants ‘sinned.’ He has no_ sooner dictated these words than a difficulty occurs to his mind, arising out of one of his own leading ideas, namely, the correlative connexion of ‘sin’ and ‘law.’ He naturally assumes that the essence of ‘ sin ’ lies in the conscious trans- gression of God’s law? ; and when (as here) the influences 1 It is sufficient to refer to Sanday and Headlam, JCC., note in loc., for proofs that the phrase éd’ # simply means ‘ because.’ For remarks on Ambrosiaster’s misunderstanding of the inaccurate Latin rendering in quo, see Lecture IV, p. 308. fae Out. 1. 23, 25.11. vil. 16,22 f° 1: Lim, 1.8 ff. This assumption is formulated in so many words by the author of the First Johannine Epistle : 7 dyapria éoriv 4 dvopla (iii. 4). 128 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN of his Jewish ancestry and education are uppermost in his mind, ‘ God’s law’ for him becomes identified with the concrete historical Law promulgated by Moses. The question is therefore inevitably raised ‘ What about the people who lived between Adam and Moses ? ’—that is, between the ‘ Fall’ and the giving of the Térah, or—as we might express it in rough figures based upon the Old Testa- ment chronology, which St. Paul, of course, took for granted —between 5000 and 1200 B.c. ‘ They all died,’ he reflects, ‘therefore, they must have sinned in some sense’ (death and sin being inseparably connected) : ‘ and yet they cannot have sinned in the stvict sense of the term—they cannot have sinned in the precise way in which Adam sinned ’ (‘ after the likeness of Adam’s transgression ’) ‘ by wilfully breaking a known commandment, because, prior to the publication of the Decalogue, there was ex hypothesi no commandment for them to break. No law, no sin. In what sense, therefore, can the post-Adamic but pre-Mosaic generations be said to have “ sinned ”’ ? ’ To us at the present day the difficulty will doubtless appear entirely unreal, because we do not accept its root- assumption that a person who has never heard of Exodus xx. can have no idea of the moral law: but it is real enough for St. Paul. He is not, however, at a loss for a solution. If we may judge by the general tenor of the verses which follow (15-21), the answer to the problem which shapes itself in the Apostle’s mind is, that during the pre-Mosaic period the human race, though incapable of committing “sin ’ in the strict sense of the term, was nevertheless fene- trated and infected by the miasma of a vague and undefined abstract “ sinfulness.’ It would seem, in other words, that he invokes in his own thoughts the conception of ‘ original sin, in what the sequel will show to have been a somewhat nebulous form, in order to explain the universal domination of death at an epoch when, according to the Jewish view of the Decalogue as the sole embodiment of the moral law, 1 A similar puzzle with regard to the good deeds of virtuous Gentiles, based upon the assumption that Gentiles as dvopou, 7.e. ignorant of the Torah, must be zpso facto non-moral and incapable of meritorious action, is discussed in c. ii. 12-15. a eS, ee ae Se oe ee ee ene eee - —— THE DOCTRINE IN THE NEW TESTAMENT 129 ‘actual sin’ did not and could not exist. ‘ Until the Law sin (= “ original sin ’’) was in the world’ ; that is, the soul of man is conceived, as having suffered, before the giving of the Torah, from a kind of ‘ suppressed sinfulness,’ much as his body may suffer from a latent fever or imposthume. This conception, however, remains for the time being in the Apostle’s mind, and only reveals itself by degrees in the following section (vv. 15-21). At the moment, it occurs to him that he is in danger of being drawn into the quagmire of an interminable discussion as to whether ‘ sin’ which is merely an unconscious state really is sin or not; and he consequently extricates himself from this perilous ground as rapidly as possible. He hastily drops the whole problem of the moral condition of pre-Mosaic mankind, leaving the complicated string of clauses which he has begun in v. 12 as a hopeless anacoluthon, and reverts to the main thought from which he has been drawn aside by these subtle specula- tions, so that (in the course of vv. 15-19) the ‘as’ clause which begins v. 12 receives in substance, though not in form, the principal sentence with which he has forgotten to provide it. The abruptness of the transition, and the mutilated shape of the argument contained in vv. 12-14, leading up as it does to a conclusion which is not spoken, but only formulated in thought, will be graphically represented if we employ the modern typographical device of inserting a row of dots between the end of v. 14 and the beginning of v. 15. “ Death reigned from Adam unto Moses, even over them that had not sinned after the likeness of Adam’s transgression, who is a figure of him that was to come. . . . But not as the trespass,’ etc. If we assume that in the parenthesis which begins with v. 13 St. Paul is not really arguing with anyone in particular, but only thinking aloud, it will be easy to see that the dots stand for an unspoken thought, which may be formulated as follows : ‘ The solution, of course, lies in the fact that though the pre-Mosaic generations could not commit sinful acts, they were hereditarily constituted in a sinful state. But the question how a mere “ state,’ acquired by birth and not by the individual’s personal act, can be “ sinful,’”’ is too abstruse to be discussed now : I will therefore return to the K 9) 130 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN point from which I started, the parallelism between the first Adam and the last.’ This parallelism is now expounded in a series of com- parisons and contrasts, the verbal expression of which, however, is compressed by the seething uprush of the Apostle’s thought into a highly elliptical form which does not conduce to lucidity. It will be, once more, well to give the passage at length: I will, however, at this point desert the English Revised Version, and print a somewhat paraphrastic version of my own, in order to minimise its obscurity and render detailed commentary as far as possible unnecessary : 15. But the bounty procured by Christ’s atonement is not in all points analogous to the sorrowful legacy of Adam’s trans- gression. By the transgression of the one Adam mankind in its myriads died; but the kindness? of God, and the gift won by the kindness of the one Man, Jesus Messiah, have re- dounded to the welfare of mankind in its myriads ? in infinitely greater measure. 16. And the boon of salvation is not exactly parallel to the disastrous achievement of the one individual who sinned; for God’s Judgment began from the one (Adam) and ended in (universal) condemnation, whilst His free gift began with the myriad offences which called it forth, and has ended in (poten- tially universal) acquittal. 17. It is true that by the transgression of the one individual death became king of mankind, through the instrumentality of that one individual; but much more shall they who are receiving the abundance of God’s kindness and of His gift of righteousness reign as kings in life eternal through the one Man Jesus Messiah. 18. So then, as the first process, that of the propagation of sin, began from one transgression, infected all men, and involved them in universal condemnation, in like manner the second process, that of salvation, began from one verdict of acquittal, is designed to diffuse its beneficent operations amongst all men, and leads to God’s acquittal, which brings life. 1 Gr. xdpis : on this word, usually translated ‘ grace,’ see below, Pp. 233,07. 2 Gr. ot woAdol, ‘ the many,’ that is, the human race considered in its multiplicity. The AV. rendering ‘ many’ (without ‘ the’) is a mistrans- lation, which has been abused to support the Calvinistic doctrine of ‘ particular redemption.’ ee ee ee ’. - ee a —— THE DOCTRINE IN THE NEW TESTAMENT 1331 19. For as through the disobedience of the one man the myriads of mankind were constituted (xareord@yoay) sinners, so also through the obedience of that other One Man the myriads of mankind shall be constituted righteous. 20. And Law came into the process of human history as an afterthought, in order that the transgression might be multiplied ; but where sin was multiplied, God’s kindness superabounded, 21. In order that, as sin reigned in a world penetrated by death, so also the Divine favour might reign by means of right- eousness, leading men on to life eternal, through Jesus Messiah our Lord. We need not follow this complicated passage through all the changes which it rings upon the phrases ‘ the one’ and ‘the many,’ now comparing and now contrasting ‘ the one man, Adam, and ‘the many’ who were injured by his fault, ‘the one man’ Jesus Messiah, and ‘the many’ who reap the benefits of His Atonement. A broad general view of it is enough to show that here, at last, we have in fully developed shape, albeit stated without any scholastic pre- ciseness of definition, that momentous doctrine of the Fall and the Redemption as correlative conceptions, as twin pillars bearing up the fabric of Christian soteriology, which we saw in Lecture I to be distinctive of the orthodox or traditional presentation of our religion. It is clear that the transgression of Adam is conceived as standing in a causal relation to the subsequent death, sin, and condemnation of his descendants—nothing less than this can be meant by the word kareora@ycav (‘ were constituted’) in v. I9— though the exact nature of the link between this primal cause and its multitudinous effects is not expressly indicated. But we have already gathered from our consideration of I Cor. xv. 22, which may be regarded as a preliminary sketch or Vorstudie for this extended exposition of the idea of the two Adams, that St. Paul believed physical mortality to be a hereditary consequence of the first Adam’s fault; if, then, death and sin are inseparable associates (as is implied all through vv. 12-14), the Apostle must have held that sin also—in the vague sense of in- herent sinfulness or propensity towards evil—is hereditarily transmitted. This conclusion is confirmed by the fact that the last 132 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN two verses of this chapter (20, 21) are most easily explicable in accordance with the hypothesis adumbrated above, in connexion with vv. 12-14—namely, that the conception which is struggling for expression in St. Paul’s mind is that of a hereditary disease, somehow introduced into the human stock by Adam’s sin, existing in a suppressed form in the pre-Mosiac generations, but since the promulgation of the Decalogue manifesting itself in a perpetual irritation and stimulus towards wrong-doing. For, we are told in a brilliant and audacious paradox, the Law came in as an ‘episode,’ an afterthought, a temporary expedient which would not have been needed had there been no Fall, in order that the transgression might abound (v. 20) ; in other words, the Ten Commandments were given precisely in order that they might be broken as much and as often as possible. And this multiplication of actual sins was divinely ordained in order that God’s kindness might abound, that is to say, in order that God might be moved to bestow upon mankind the gift of redemption and the reign of divine kindness through Jesus Messiah our Lord. Whatever may be thought of this attempt to describe in human language the providential processes of the Mind of God, the doctrine of Man and of sin which underlies the whole passage vv. 12-21 should now be sufficiently clear. Man derived from Adam—we have been constrained to conclude, by physical heredity—the poison of suppressed sinfulness, which during four millenniums or thereabouts was unable to find its natural outlet in law-breaking, because there was no law to break. The Mosaic Law was then applied to mankind, as a sort of sharp, stinging fomentation, designed to bring this innate but suppressed poison up to the surface of the individual consciousness, so that it might discharge itself in the shape of actual sins. Sin, having been thus externalised and concretised, could then be dealt with by God on forensic lines, by means of a judicial atone- ment and acquittal. It would seem that at this point St. Paul assumes that ‘innate sinfulness’ is a thing too vague, subtle, and elusive for God to treat directly: He needs a tangible subject-matter, in the shape of Actual Sin, before He can set His restorative processes in motion. THE DOCTRINE IN THE NEW TESTAMENT 133 This curious assumption is, however, clearly bound up with the common Jewish idea that the moral law was uniquely and exclusively embodied in the Decalogue; we need not, therefore, devote further consideration to it now. It will be sufficient for the purposes of our historical enquiry if it has been shown that the language of this crucial passage explicitly asserts the existence of a causal relation between Adam’s sin and subsequent sin and death, and that the Apostle’s language is most easily explicable on the sup- position that there underlies it a half-thought-out idea of a hereditary spiritual disease, of an unconscious suppressed sinfulness, which when stimulated by the external impact of the Law, with its blunt, uncompromising series of commands and prohibitions, naturally wells up into the field of conscious volition. | It should be added that there is nothing in this passage which implies that ‘ suppressed sinfulness ’ actually involves guilt in the sight of God, previously to and independently of the commission of actual sin; and, indeed, the phrase in v. 13, ‘sin is not imputed where there is no law’! (apaptia dé odk eAXoyetTat pur) dvTos vopov), Would seem to deny by anticipation the later Augustinian conception of ‘original guilt,’ at any rate in the case of the pre-Mosaic men. If we may judge by his general usus loquendt, St. Paul shares the opinions of the ‘ plain man’ on this point. The word ‘ guilt,’ with the whole apparatus of forensic terminology to which it belongs, ‘ judgment ’ (xpiua), ‘condemnation’ (xardxpia), ‘ acquittal’ (dicaiwors), and the like, is only applicable to voluntary and responsible actions, that is, to actual sins: the ‘ inherited tendency to sin,’ or ‘ original sin,’ so called—if a fact—must be con- ceived as a disease, and medical terminology alone is appropriate in speaking of it. Neither here nor elsewhere does the Apostle make any attempt to explain how it is that a state for which we are not responsible manifests itself in acts for which we are, or why a guiltless malady should issue in symptoms to which guilt attaches—problems 1 These words might be paraphrased thus: ‘“ Original”’ sin by itself, which has not expressed itself in the breach of a known commandment, is not considered by God to be sin in the true sense of the term.’ 134 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN which have baffled the philosophers, theologians, alienists, and penologists of all ages. THE PAULINE DOCTRINE. (6) ‘ INHERITED SINFULNESS’ AND BAPTISM The process of unravelling St. Paul’s profoundest thought is necessarily difficult, and may, I fear, have been in the present instance somewhat tedious, to follow in detail. It will, therefore, be appropriate, before we turn to the con- sideration of a second and hardly less important division of the Apostle’s ‘ anthropology,’1 namely, his teaching with regard to the nature and seat of ‘ inherited sinfulness,’ to conform to the actual order of the Epistle to the Romans, and devote a few words to a more practical and more easily comprehensible aspect, or corollary, of the Pauline doctrine of Man and of Sin—that is, its conception of baptism. In the light of certain ideas which are familiar to us from the teaching of the Prayer Book offices and the Catechism, it is at least interesting to find that the discussion of the universal and hereditary ‘ sinfulness ’ of mankind (v. 12-21) is immediately followed by a deeply mystical passage (vi. I-11) in which the dominant thought is that of the saving effects of Baptism. We are at once reminded of the Nicodemus-scene in the Fourth Gospel (iii. 1-15) in which the words of Christ, as recorded by St. John, seem to speak of Baptism as the remedy for some implied and undefined defect inherent in human nature.2 As we have already seen, the modern critical study of St. John’s literary methods makes it difficult to be sure that our Lord Himself did actually point the sacramental moral of His exhortation as explicitly as the narrative represents ; but in the passage about to be discussed we have the ipsissima verba of the Apostle of the Gentiles, fixed and preserved for all time by Tertius’ shorthand as they fell from his very lips. I cannot 1 It need hardly be said that this term is here used in its theological, not in its modern scientific sense. 2 See above, p. 98 ff. Le NRL PELLAED IL LAGE NI LOL EA IEA ae ee 5 THE DOCTRINE IN THE NEW TESTAMENT 135 doubt that the key to the interpretation of vi. 1-11 is given us in the words of Professor Kirsopp Lake: Baptism is for St. Paul and his readers universally and un- questioningly accepted as a mystery or sacrament which works ex opere operato; and from the unhesitating manner in which St. Paul uses this fact as a basis for argument, as if it were a point on which Christian teaching did not vary, it would seem as though this sacramental teaching is central in the primitive Christianity to which the Roman Empire began to be converted. Given this hypothesis, which illuminates the relevant passages 2 of the Pauline writings as no other does or can do, and which can only be refuted on the basis of a priors assumptions as to what the Apostle ought to have believed —the articulation and sequence of St. Paul’s ideas about Sin and its remedy stand out with photographic clearness. Mankind inherited physical mortality and ‘ suppressed sin- fulness’ from Adam, who himself acquired them by his Fall. The promulgation of a Law which man had not the strength to obey stimulated this subconscious sinfulness to pullulate in a multitude of actual sins. In due season, whilst we were yet (actual) sinners, Christ died on behalf of the ungodly. Thenceforward, ‘ Faith,’ that is, unreserved mental, moral, and emotional self-surrender to Jesus as risen, Messiah, and Lord, procures for the believing soul ‘justification,’ or judicial acquittal from the burden of actual offences: and Baptism, which is the indispensable external expression and crowning moment of the act of Faith, mystically unites the neophyte to the Saviour, in whose death and resurrection, viewed sub specie aeternitatis as timeless facts, he sacramentally participates, and through the infusion of whose divine life he wins, as it would seem, the complete and final cure of the inherited disease of “suppressed sinfulness.’3 Faith, in short, brings ‘ release 1 Earlier Epistles of St. Paul, 1911, p. 385. Professor H. A. A. Kennedy’s attempt to disprove this hypothesis (St. Paul and the Mystery Religions, 1913, pp. 232 ff.) seems to me quite unconvincing; I may, perhaps, be permitted to refer to my observations on ‘ The Origins of the Sacraments,’ in Essays Catholic and Critical (1926), p. 389, 0. 7. RiGeal) 11192 Fes 07) COL Vil i exe 1, 2) xii rg Coliii. 12 5\hphiiva 5: 8 This idea—natural enough in the Church’s enthusiastic infancy— that the regenerated Christian is from the moment of his baptism onwards strictly incapable of sinning—reappears in 1 John iii. 9: ‘ whosoever is 136 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN from sin’ in the ‘ forensic,’ and Baptism in the ‘ medical,’ sense, of these words. Know ye not that all we who were baptised into Messiah Jesus were baptised into His death? So then we were buried together with Him through our baptism so as to share in His death. . . . For if we became incorporate with the likeness of His death, surely also we shall be incorporate with the likeness of His resurrection ; knowing this, that our old man was cruci- fied together with Him in order that the body of sin [.e. the physical nature of man in which, as we shall see, this hereditary disease of sin inheres] might be annulled or abolished, so that we should no longer be the slaves of sin.? There can, I venture to think, be no reasonable doubt as to the meaning of these words. Baptism is assumed by St. Paul to be a cathartic and therapeutic rite, the logical parallelism of which with some observances of the Greek and Oriental mysteries he would not have repudiated,? which unites the sick soul to the strong and stainless Redeemer- God, conferring upon it, through a mystical death and resurrection, the heavenly gifts of healing, purity, and inward peace. | It is one of the inevitable inconsistencies to which pioneers in any sphere of thought are liable, that this description of baptism as the infallible medicine which heals the disease of sinfulness and ‘annuls’ the ‘ body of sin’ should occur in a context which is devoted to imploring the Roman Christians to abstain from sin. It might well have begotten of God doeth no sin, because His seed abideth in him; and he cannot sin (od dvvarat duapraverv), because he is begotten of God’ ; cf. also v. 18. 1 Extracts from vi. 2-6, freely translated. The original Greek is appended: 7 ayvoetre ri door €BarricOnpev eis yprotov "Inoodv, eis Tov Oavatov adrot e€BanricOnuev; auveradynuev ody att@ dia tod Banrioparos eis Tov O@dvarov...e€i yap ovpudutor yeydvapev TH Opotwmmate rob Oavdrov avrod, GAAa Kal Tis avacrdcews €odpue0a* TobdTo yivdoKortes, GTL 6 Tadaos HUdv avOpwmos ovvectavpwbn, tva Katapynff ro oya ths duaptias, Tod pnKére SovAevew Huds TH Gpapria. The depth of St. Paul’s belief in the absolute efficacy of baptism is shown by the fact that Col. ii. rz re-echoes the thought of this passage, affirming the ‘ putting off of the body of the flesh’ to be a result of Christian initiation, which is again described as being ‘ buried with him in baptism.’ 2 I do not, of course, mean to imply that St. Paul’s ideas with regard to the Sacraments were derived from the Mysteries ; see above, p. 135, 0.1. ; THE DOCTRINE IN THE NEW TESTAMENT 137 been asked by an external critic of the first century A.D. ‘If the rite of Baptism has this immediate and all-sufficient effect in annihilating the power of innate sinfulness, why should it be necessary to urge baptised Christians to main- tain a high standard of moral life? How is it possible to reconcile the liability to backsliding which these exhorta- tions presuppose with the permanent and irrevocable effect which Baptism is assumed to produce?’ The answer, of course, is that it is not really possible, and that St. Paul at this early date had not fully thought out the implications of the fact of post-baptismal sin, which he is curiously loth to face. The logical difficulty in which he finds himself involved in exhorting people to refrain from sin who, on his own hypothesis, were incapable of committing it, was in a later age solved in theory by admitting that baptism did not destroy ‘ concupiscence ’1 ; and the practical difficulties which arose in connexion with the treatment of Christians who had sinned after baptism gave birth to the sacrament of penance, at first available only once in a lifetime for the post-baptismal offender, and then only to deal with one or more of the three capital sins, homicide, impurity, and apostasy, later expanding and ramifying so as to cover every type of sin and to be available as often as required.” When the Apostle wrote, however, these developments still lay in the future (the occasions on which he administered penitential discipline at Ephesus? and Corinth* would appear to him as purely exceptional events, which were not likely to recur before the Parousia): and he has therefore to content himself with the position ‘ You cannot, and therefore you ought not to, commit sin "—a reversed and 1 Cf. Article IX, ‘ this infection of nature doth remain, yea in them that are regenerated,’ etc.; conc. Trident. Sess. V. 5: ‘ manere autem in baptizatis concupiscentiam vel fomitem, haec sancta synodus fatetur et sentit,’ etc. (the whole passage is quoted below, Additional Note F, ‘ Formularies,’ p. 539). 2 For the details of this development, see O. D. Watkins, History of Penance (1920). A convenient summary of the development of Penance up to A.D. 400 may be found in Haslehurst, Penitential Discipline in the Early Church (1921). 8 Acts xix. 18: moAAoi re tTHv memictevKdtwv (1.e. of the baptised Christians) 7#pyovro é£opuodoyovpevor Kal avayyéAdovtes Tas Tpdkers addy (pre- sumably with a view to receiving some sort of absolution). Patol ves. 50h 21 Cor 4116 it. 138 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN negative form of the Kantian dictum ‘I ought, therefore I can,’ which the most superficial analysis will show to be a patent self-contradiction. The fact is, that he is on the verge of raising, though he does not actually raise, a philo- sophic problem which is implicit in the idea of Original Sin and of sacramental grace as the remedy for it, namely this: ‘Is it possible for there to be a presentation of the Fall-doctrine which will be sufficiently deterministec—which will lay sufficient emphasis on man’s hereditary weakness— to establish the need for “‘ grace,”’ in the technical theological sense,! and for sacraments; but will also be sufficiently libertarian to preserve the idea of man’s freedom and moral responsibility 2?’ But, interesting and important as this question is in its bearings upon modern religious life and thought, considerations of time compel us to defer its examination to the constructive part of this course, and to resume the thread of our main task, that of studying the Apostle’s conception of the state of human nature which in his view made baptism and all other elements in the redemptive process necessary. THE PAULINE DOCTRINE. (c) ‘ INHERITED SINFULNESS,’ ITS NATURE AND SEAT We have seen that St. Paul assumes the existence of a vague hereditary sinfulness, transmitted by Adam to his posterity, as the presupposition of Actual Sin and conse- quently of Redemption; and we have now to examine more narrowly his conception of this inherited infirmity or taint. It is probable that we shall gain most light on this point if we begin by investigating the question of the seat 1 That is, gratia sanctificans, which in the common usage of Western theology denotes positive Divine assistance given ab extra to the struggling soul; this is a different idea from that conveyed by the term ydpis as used by St. Paul, which means the sentiment of ‘ favour’ or ‘ loving- kindness ’—‘ graciousness’ rather than ‘ grace ’—-with which God regards His creatures. No doubt the practical consequence of God’s attitude of xdpis is His bestowal of gratia sanctificans ; but much confusion has been caused by the failure to realise that what St. Paul means by xdpis is not precisely the same as what St. Augustine means by gratia. THE DOCTRINE IN THE NEW TESTAMENT 139 of the congenital malady, that is, of the precise “ part ’? of human nature in which it resides and through which it is transmitted. A careful study of cc. vi. and vii. of the Epistle to the Romans will leave us in no doubt as to St. Paul’s view of the matter. The seat of hereditary sinful- ness is ‘ the flesh,’ that is, the strictly physical or animal nature of man. It is well known that the Apostle’s theory of human nature is trichotomous, dividing the domain of personality into three clearly cut areas, namely (a) the ‘flesh’ or the ‘ body,’ (0) the ‘soul’ (#vx7), the principle of organic life which we share with the animals, a concept which is the practical equivalent of Aristotle’s ‘ vegetative soul,’? and (c) the ‘spirit’ (avedua) which includes the highest intellectual, moral, and religious faculties.? And what distinguishes St. Paul’s ideas with regard to the subject of innate sinfulness from those of the other thinkers whom we have noticed up to this point, is the fact that he confines the seat of the inbred evil rigidly to the ‘ flesh,’ apparently exempting the ‘soul’ and the ‘spirit’ from any sort of inherent taint, and only conceding that they may be pol- luted as it were fer accidens, by the maleficent influences arising out of their physical substratum.* So we find that the effect of union with Christ in baptism is to “ annul,’ to ‘bring to nought,’ the ‘sinful body’ ® (vi. 6)—in plainer language, to paralyse, or rather to annihilate, sinful impulses assumed to be rooted in the body. More explicitly, the hidden sources of sin are described as ‘ the sinful passions which come through the Law’ ® (vii. 5)—in other words, the evil impulses stimulated into life, in a way which will 1 An apology is doubtless due for the use of this word; but it will be remembered that we are investigating ancient, not modern, psychology. 2 Cf. Eth. Nic. I. vii, 12: de anima 413 b 7. 3 See arts. ‘ Soul,’ ‘ Spirit,’ by J. Laidlaw, HDB; andcf. R. H. Charles, Eschatology, Hebrew, Jewish, and Christian (1899), pp. 409-15, for an elaborate, if occasionally arbitrary, analysis of St. Paul’s trichotomous psychology. 4 The perversion of the intellect by sensuality is the last stage of moral degradation ; the final punishment of the vicious Gentiles is to be abandoned by God eis dddxipov votv (Rom. i. 28), and, conversely, the ‘renewal of the intellect’ (dvaxaivwows rod vdos) is the final stage of post- baptismal sanctification (Rom. xii. 2). 5 +6 o@pua Ths duaprias. § ra mabjuata Tov dpapriav Ta Sia Tod vopov. 140 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN be presently explained, by the prohibitions and threatenings of the Law; and these are said, with reference to the unregenerate state in which both the Apostle and his readers once lived, to have been ‘ active in our members.’! As inherent sinfulness is thus connected with passion and impulse, it would seem that he would have spoken more accurately if he had affirmed the innate source of sin to lie in the dvx7 or “‘ vegetal soul’ ; we must, however, take his language as we find it; and his apparent determination to saddle ‘ the body,’ or ‘ the flesh,’ with the sole responsibility for being the home of sin, by its Arima facie inconsistency with his own trichotomous theory of human nature,? may well suggest that it is prompted by some unconscious psychological cause, lying deep in his personal idiosyn- crasy, rather than by considerations of the strictly logical order. . The Pauline theory, if such it may be called, regarding the nature and seat of ‘innate sinfulness,’ and regarding the psychological vationale of its externalisation in the shape of actual sins, under the stimulus of acquaintance with the Law, may be studied at length in vii. 7-25; in what appears from the directness and poignancy of its language (it is difficult to believe that its use of the first person singular is a mere literary device) to be a sketch of the Apostle’s own moral autobiography, a miniature analogue of the Confessions of St. Augustine. The passage deserves 1 éynpyetro ev tots péAcow Hydv. 2 The sharp contrast between ‘ flesh’ and ‘ spirit’ discussed later in the text seems to insist on a dichotomy rather than a trichotomy. According to W. Bousset (Religion des Judentums im NTlichen Zettalter, 1903, p. 381) the Jewish psychology of St. Paul’s day treated the terms “ spirit’ and ‘ soul’ as identical in meaning, thereby diverging from Old Testament usage, which had recognised a subtle difference of connotation between them, the former emphasising the element of Divine force which permeates and sustains all organic being, the latter laying stress on the separate psychic life of the individual organism (H. Schultz, ATliche Theologie®, 1896, p. 492 ff.). St. Paul’s normal use of the terms seems to accord with the practice of the Old Testament writers; he distinguishes sharply between 70 mvedpa and 7 pvx7y in 1 Thess. v. 23. But in writing the passages discussed above he may well have felt the dichotomous usus loquendi of his Rabbinical instructors to have been better adapted to the clear exposition of the point at issue than the trichotomous category which is more characteristic of his own thought. See, however, R. H. Charles, op. cit., pp. 412-13. ‘ * * £ 4 a Picea” ee came we SLA. ater? ener al ete THE DOCTRINE IN THE NEW TESTAMENT rar to be quoted at length, both because of its intense human interest and because of the light shed by it upon the difficult conceptions with which we are dealing. What shall we say then? Is the Law sin? God forbid. Howbeit, I hadnot known sinexcept throughthe Law. For I had not known desire, except the Law had said ‘ Thou shalt not desire? (wrongfully).’ But Sin, finding an occasion (or, starting- point), wrought in me through the Commandment all manner of (wrongful) desire ; for apart from the Law Sin is dead. Now I was alive apart from the Law once: but, when the Command- ment came, Sin revived, and [ died. And the Commandment, which was unto life (¢.e. meant by God to promote my true life), this I found to be unto death: For Sin, finding its occasion (or starting-point) through the Commandment, beguiled me, and through it slew me. So that the Law is holy, andthe Command- ment holy, and righteous, and good. Did then that which is good become death unto me? God forbid. On the contrary, Sin, that it might be shewn to de Sin, by working death to me through that which is good. . . that through the Command- ment Sin might prove to be superlatively sinful... (an un- finished sentence). For we know that the Law is spiritual: but I am a being of flesh * sold under the power of Sin. But that which I do I know not: for, not what I would, that do I practise ; but what I hate, that Ido. But if what I would not, that I do, I consent unto the Law that it is good. So now it is no more I that do it, but Sin which dwelleth in me. For I know that in me—that 1s, in my flesh—dwelleth no good thing: for to will is present with me, but to do that which is good is not. For the good which I would I do not: but the evil which I would not, that I practise. But if, what I would not, that I do—it is no more I that do it, but Sin which dwelleth in me. I find then the law,? that to me, who would do good, evil is present. For I delight in the Law of God after the inward man (or, so far as my inner self is concerned): But I see a different Law in my members, warring against the Law recognised by my intellect, and bringing me into captivity under the Law of Sin which is in my members. O wretched man that I am! who shall deliver me out of the body of this death? ... I thank God through 1 ovx émOuvpjoers—the first words of the Tenth Commandment as given in Exodus xx. 17 (LXX). 2 odpxwos: this word merely means ‘ made of flesh,’ and should be carefully distinguished from ocapxixdés, ‘ carnal’ in the bad sense, a distinction which RV. fails to recognise. See Grimm-Thayer, Greek- English Lexicon of the N.T., s. vv. 8 rov vouov must here, I think, mean‘ the general rule,’ or “ constraining principle’ ; see Sanday and Headlam’s note. 142 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN Jesus Christ our Lord.—So then I myself with the intellect serve the Law of God ; but with the flesh the Law of Sin.* The connexion of these verses with what precedes them is easily intelligible. The two passages on which we have just commented (v. 12-21 and vi. I-11) are, as we have seen, pervaded by the theory that mankind inherited a suppressed or latent sinfulness in virtue of its descent from the first sinner Adam, but that this hereditary taint did not manifest itself in actual wrongdoing until stimulated by knowledge of the Law. A somewhat obtuse imaginary critic is repre- sented as objecting that, if the effect of acquaintance with the Law is the commission of actual sin, the Law itself must be supposed to be in some way an evil power or agency (v. 7). The Apostle repudiates this suggestion with a stern ‘God forbid,’ but feels it necessary to provide against future misconceptions of the kind by clearing up, once and for all, the relations of ‘ suppressed sinfulness,’ the Law, and actual sin. He therefore proceeds to elucidate the nature of ‘ suppressed sinfulness’ (designated in these verses simply as “ Sin ’) by examining its operation on a small scale, within the compass of a single soul (in point of fact, as we have suggested, his own)—thereby reversing the procedure of Plato’s Republic, which endeavours to elucidate the nature of Justice in the individual soul by examining its workings on a large scale in the State. The parallel centres on the idea of the Law, the learning of which during childhood, from the lips of parent or hazzdn,? constitutes a moral Rubicon in the life of the individual, like that which its proclamation from Sinai constituted, as the Apostle believes, in the collective life of the race. If he had been acquainted with modern biological science, he might well have adapted one of its maxims to his purpose, and written ‘ (ethical and spiritual) ontogeny is the recapitulation of (ethical and spiritual) phylogeny,’ as the premise from which his exposi- tion is derived. 1 RV., somewhat modified and expanded. I have italicised the references to ‘ the flesh,’ ‘ the body,’ and ‘ the members,’ in order to make the underlying theory of the seat of sin stand out with clearness. * The synagogue attendant, or professional reader, who often acted as schoolmaster. oh ge oe ee ee ee ne a Oa ee ee eee SS a ee ee ee THE DOCTRINE IN THE NEW TESTAMENT 143 In three or four vivid words (v. 9) he sketches the golden age of earliest childhood, during which he was alive,! ‘in the purely physical sense,’ without the Law ; that is, during which he was a non-moral organism, swayed solely by instinct, ignorant of the Decalogue, and therefore incapable of actual sin. This state of innocence was brought to an end by the coming of the Commandment, through instruc- tion in the Law, which for the son of pious Jewish parents followed immediately upon the dawn of reason and moral responsibility. The effect of acquaintance with the Law was to rouse into venomous life the latent power of ‘ Sin’ (that is, “ original sin,’ or the sinful tendency) which during infancy had been slumbering within him, inert, like a frozen snake. Through some strange psychic chemistry, the stern warning ‘ Thou shalt not desire . . .’ provoked in his soul a passion of guilty desire to which he has hitherto been a stranger (v. 8) ; and, before he has had time to understand or adjust himself to the surging impulses which have broken out within him, he finds that he has committed some act which is condemned by the Law. It is difficult to avoid the impression that we have in vv. 8, 9 a generalised description of the psychic disturbances incidental to puberty and adolescence : though the language which describes an almost personified Sin as using the Commandment for a fulcrum whereby to push the tempted soul into spiritual death is equally applicable to the moral struggles of adult life. The idea which St. Paul endeavours to express by this picture of an awakened ‘ endopsychic’ demon of Sin utilis- ing the Law as a zoé or@ for accomplishing its fell designs, is that summed up in the proverbial phrases ‘ mitimur in velitum semper,’ “ Stolen fruits are sweetest.’ It is an idea which is, perhaps, rather less perplexing to us than it was to him: for we now know that the singular attraction exercised by the thought of forbidden conduct, merely because it is forbidden, over child-like and undisciplined minds, and it may be over others, arises from certain funda- mental facts of human nature. A modern neurologist 1 €lwv: Civ means to‘ be alive’ in a merely animal sense, Bidoxerv to ‘live’ a fully developed human, rational, and civilised life ; cf. the English words zoology, biography. 144 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN might describe these facts in physiological terms, pointing out that it is impossible for the thought of a given action to be suggested to consciousness without a concomitant stimulation, in however minute a degree, of the kinaesthetic area of the cerebral cortex: and that such stimulation in- evitably causes a discharge of energy, however infinitesimal in quantity, into the efferent nerves connected with the appropriate muscles, thereby producing a faint impulse towards the externalisation in act of the suggested thought. A psychologist, on the other hand, might prefer to speak of the ‘ phantasy ’ of a particular action as exciting the cognate ‘complex,’ and of this latter as thereupon tending to release its accumulated libido into the conational channels leading to the realisation of the ‘phantasy.’ But, in whichever way we choose to envisage the mechanism of conduct, whether psychologically or psycho-physiologically, it remains true to say that the idea of an action, once suggested to the mind, has a slight but distinct tendency to realise itself. The whole curative method associated with the names of M. Coué and M. Baudouin is built upon this principle. Now the Law, by the very fact of prohibiting a certain mode of conduct, necessarily suggests to the mind the idea of such conduct, and therefore cannot help arousing some degree of propension towards that which it is designed to forbid. And when the prohibited conduct happens to be the normal expression of one of the cardinal instincts of human nature, the clumsy threatenings of the Law may well evoke, from the mysterious depths of the unconscious self, mighty forces which are seemingly beyond the power of the conscious ego to bridle or repress. A merely ‘ideomotor’ impulse is doubtless too feeble and evanescent even to make itself felt in consciousness: but an ideomotor impulse reinforced by a flood-wave of animal appetite or elemental emotion inevitably passes over into action, unless dammed in by the barrier of habit or of intense volitional effort. Such spates of psychic energy, released in the way just described, are what the Apostle means by ‘ the sinful passions roused by the Law’; they constitute the ‘second Law’ (érepos vopos) Which hales us along as captives of the law of sin which is in our members. THE DOCTRINE IN THE NEW TESTAMENT 145 But the question still presses for an answer, With what precisely, in the Apostle’s thought, is ‘ Sin’ in the sense of these verses (that is, ‘ original sin’) to be identified? Is it simply another name for the natural appetites of the body ? or is it the exaggeration of appetite? Is it the psychic energy alluded to above, or the weakness of will which fails to tame its undisciplined uprushes ? We will, nevertheless, postpone these questions for a moment, in order to complete our review of the passage. Verse 13 attempts to account ex parte Det for the paradoxical fact that the revelation of the Law is found in experience to stimulate law-breaking, by suggesting that this has been providentially allowed in order that man may realise the full horror of Sin by seeing that it is capable of utilising the sanctities of the Law as the instrument of its detestable purposes. With v. 14, we pass into a tragic description of the conflict between reason and appetite which once racked the writer’s unconverted soul, a conflict in which appetite was continually victorious ; and the Apostle piles up rugged antithetical phrases (‘it is not what I would that I practise: but what I hate, that I do,’ and the like) to emphasise the complete dissociation which seemed to have taken place between his conscious ego and the control of his body. ‘ Sin,’ like some malignant secondary personality, has got possession of his limbs, and uses them as it thinks fit, quite regardless of the commands of his real self. This real self, the ‘inner man,’ or the intellect (vois), is strongly asserted to be morally sound, perfectly cognisant of the commands of the Law and per- fectly loyal to them; the whole blame for the aberrations of his actual conduct is laid upon ‘ the flesh,’ or ‘ the flesh ’ as controlled by ‘Sin.’ The state of interior schism thus depicted would seem to be exactly identical with what Aristotle terms dxpacia or ‘incontinence,’ the condition of the man who recognises the obligation of the moral law, but is too weak to conform to it, as distinct from the condition of the ozovdaios or ‘ good’ man, who both recognises and obeys the law, on the one hand, and that of the dxkdAaoros or ‘ profligate’ man, who both rejects the © law interiorly and disobeys it exteriorly, on the other.1 1 Eth. Nic. vii. I-10 (1145 a 15-1152 a). L 146 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN But it is described by the fiery Apostle in words of burning shame and remorse such as would have been quite unintel- ligible to the phlegmatic Stagirite. And the philosopher, unlike the Apostle, can only analyse the moral struggle, and cannot suggest any means of bringing it to a satisfactory end. The whole difference between the spirit of pagan Hellenism and the spirit of Christianity is summed up in the contrast between the cold aphorism with which Aristotle concludes his dissertation on the character of the ‘ incon- tinent man’ (‘ Those who are incontinent through habit are more easily curable than those who are such by nature ; for it is easier to alter a habit than to alter one’s nature ’ 1) and the exultant cry of the redeemed and converted Paul ‘T thank God through Jesus Messiah our Lord.’ It is not necessary to dwell for more than a moment upon two other well-known texts which should be noticed in any attempt to elucidate St. Paul’s conception of ‘ the flesh ’"—those, namely, which expound the characteristically Pauline antithesis of ‘ flesh’ and ‘ spirit,’ Rom. viii. 3-13, and what may be described as a rough preliminary study for this passage, Gal. v. 16-24. We observe that in the former of these texts it is not always certain whether the ‘ spirit ’ which constitutes the second member of the contrasted pair is meant to be man’s own spirit, or the Spirit of God ? ; but, whichever it is, the ‘ flesh’ with its physical appetites and cravings is conceived as standing in sharp opposition and hostility to it. The ¢dpovnua, the ‘mind’ or ‘ dis- position’ of the flesh—that is, the subconscious mental qualities revealed in its instinctive desires—is said to be death ; it is hostility towards God : it is not subject to the Law of God, nor indeed can be.? ‘The flesh desires con- 1 Ar. Eth. Nic. vii. 10, 4. (1152 a29): [edvardrepor] of 8x’ €Oc.apod axparets TOV pvoik@v’ pGov yap eos peraxivjoar dvcews. 2 As the autographs of St. Paul’s Epistles must have been written in uncials, our modern typographic device of denoting the Spirit of God by means of a capital initial letter was not available for his amanuensis : so that we can only judge in a given passage, whether 7d mvedua, used absolutely, means the Spirit of God or the spirit of man, from the general sense of the context. RV. is, I think, right in translating 70 avedya in Rom. viii. 4-9 as ‘ the spirit’ (= the human spirit) and in Gal. v. 16-25 as ‘ the Spirit’ (= the Spirit of God). ** Rom). vii. 7: THE DOCTRINE IN THE NEW TESTAMENT 147 trariwise to the Spirit, and the Spirit contrariwise to the flesh ; for these two powers are directly opposed to each other, so that you do not actually do what you wish to do (cf. Rom. vii. 15, “ not what I would, that do I practise ”’ etc.). . . . Now the works of the flesh are manifest, which are these, fornication, uncleanness, lasciviousness, idolatry, sorcery, enmities, strife, jealousies, wraths, factions, divisions, sects, envyings, drunkenness, revellings, and such like.’ ! ’ The ‘flesh,’ in short, is the seat or mzdus, not merely of the bodily appetites which may be summed up under the head of sensuality, but also of the self-assertive instincts which fall more naturally under the head of pride. All these hateful impulses, however, are believed, in accordance with the absolute view of the efficacy of baptism noted above, to have been destroyed once and for all, in Christians, by the mystic death through which they were united to the Saviour and initiated into the fellowship of the Church. ‘ Ye are not in the flesh, but in the spirit, ifi—as you know to be the case 2—the Spirit of God dwelleth in you.’% ‘ They that belong to Messiah Jesus have crucified the flesh with its passions and its appetites.’ 4 Our survey of the relevant passages of the Pauline writings has now placed us in a position to essay a solution of this most subtle and difficult of exegetical problems, the exact nature of ‘inbred sinfulness’ and of its relation to ‘the flesh,’ as conceived in the Apostle’s thought. It will clear the ground if we deal briefly, first of all, with a popular theory, not devoid of a superficial simplicity and attractive- ness, which sees in the famous antithesis of ‘ flesh’ and ‘spirit ’ a reproduction of the Platonic dualism of matter and mind,°* in which the former, when organised as a“ body,’ praliv. 19; 2 elmep, siquidem, appeals to an admitted fact. 3 Rom. viii. 9. = ral aVietA, 5 The most noteworthy exposition of this theory is that given by O. Pfleiderer, Paulinism (E. tr. 1877),i. 47-68. W. Bousset (fel. des Juden- tums, p. 386, 1903) isin general agreement with Pfleiderer : ‘ Wenn Paulus mvedua und odpé als zwei den menschlichen Willen unbedingt beherr- schende und diesen niederzwingende Machte anschaut, und wenn er die Wurzel der odp& doch wesentlich in dem leiblich-sinnlichen Wesen des Menschen sucht, so geht er damit seine Wege abseits von rabbinischer Theologie und bringt eine specifisch hellenische Auffassung an das Christ- entum heran.’ 148 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN is regarded as the impure clog or fetter which weighs down the heavenward strivings of the latter.1 It would not be difficult, did time allow, to rebut this contention by an extended demonstration of the intensely Hebraic character of St. Paul’s thought in general which certainly betrays no other trace of Platonic influence; and it would be even easier to set against it the passages in which the body is clearly conceived as a holy thing, created ‘ not for fornica- tion}; but forthe Lord,’ ? the temple) ofithe) Holy spin destined at the Last Day to be transubstantiated, by some celestial alchemy, into a ‘ body of glory,’ 4+ an ethereal envelope which will be the perfect instrument and vehicle of the immortal soul. But the simplest and, I venture to think, the most convincing reply to this suggestion is one which bases itself directly on the logical structure and interrelation of the ideas which form the subject-matter of our enquiry. It may be phrased as follows: We may admit that the passages just cited, which find the seat of sin in the body and its appetites, if considered by themselves and in isolation from the rest of the Apostle’s teaching, might appear to pre-suppose some kind of Platonic or Oriental dualism, were it not for the fact that the Apostle, in two classical texts (Rom. v. 12-19 and I Cor. xv. 21, 22), has left on record his conviction that the origin of evil, physical and moral, is to be traced, not to the essential constitution of human nature or of the material universe, but to the voluntary transgression of the first man—in other words, to the ‘ Fall.’ It is the idea of the Fall, with its necessary implication of the contingency and temporality, as opposed to the eternity and necessity, of evil, which makes all the difference; without the belief in the Fall, the doctrine of ‘ Original Sin’ 7s Manicheism. It is doubtless unnecessary to repeat the warning that we are not at the moment discussing the question of the Fall on its merits ; 1 This point of view actually appears in Wisdom, a book which is permeated by Alexandrine-Jewish Platonism: ‘ For a corruptible body weigheth down the soul, And the earthy frame lieth heavy on a mind that is full of cares’ (ix. 15). 4. rCor./ Wii 3. 3 zbid. 19. 4 t Cor. xv. 35 ff. THE DOCTRINE IN THE NEW TESTAMENT 149 that question belongs to the second or constructive part of our enquiry, in which we shall see that, from the purely intellectual point of view, there is much to be said for Manicheism ; we are only concerned now to emphasise the consideration, explained at length in Lecture I, that the Fall-theory and dualism are in principle, and always have been in history, mutually exclusive hypotheses. It follows that St. Paul’s emphatically asserted allegiance to the first is the surest proof that he cannot have held the second. There are those who would reply that strict logic was not the Apostle’s strongest point; that he may well never have had time to think the matter out with so much thoroughness as to become clearly conscious. of the con- tradiction ; and that the occurrence of a * Fall-theory ’ in Rom. v. 12 ff., and of:a ‘ flesh-theory ’ immediately after- wards, in cc. vi. and vil., merely constitutes one more instance of that power of simultaneously holding incom- patible theories, and of using each in turn as his dialectical exigencies require, which is most conspicuously displayed by his successive assumption of the predestinarian and of the libertarian standpoints, in the great Theodicy of Rom. ix.-xi. But the argument just advanced, that if St. Paul believed in a Fall he cannot have held any sort of dualistic theory, is based upon foundations which go far deeper than the canons of formal logic. Dualism, with its assertion of a realm of being (namely, matter) from which the will and power of the Most High are partially or entirely excluded, assumes a conception of God differing toto caelo from that ethical monotheism which was the supreme achievement of the Jewish Church, and a conscious relation to God fundamentally other than that possessed by the illustrious line of its prophets and saints. Dualism is treason to everything that is summed up in the Shema‘, the Apostles’ Creed of Judaism—‘ Hear, O Israel, Yahweh thy God, Yahweh is One.’ To suppose that St. Paul was capable of such treason is to suppose not merely a psychological but an ethical and spiritual impossibility. 150 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN THE ‘ MIND OF THE FLESH’ AND THE ‘Evit IMAGINATION ’ In point of fact, the student who remembers that St. Paul was before all things a ‘Hebrew sprung from Hebrews,’ 1 an ‘ Israelite,’? ‘brought up at the feet of Gamaliel,’ ? has not very far to look for the true answer to the question, What precisely was it that St. Paul believed to have been introduced into the human stock by Adam's sin, to reside in ‘ the flesh,’ and to constitute the psycho- logical ground of actual transgression? The various phrases which we have passed in review during our exposition of the chief relevant texts—‘ Sin,’ ‘ the old man,’ ‘ the sinful body,’ ‘ the body of this death,’ ‘ the sinful passions aroused by the Law,’ ‘the mind of the flesh —are all, I would submit, so many picturesque and paraphrastic names for the yécer ha-va‘. Indeed, it may be tentatively suggested that the last of these terms—the ¢povnya tis capKkos— almost amounts to a literal translation of the Hebrew phrase: we have seen that Hellenistic Judaism never fixed upon any one Greek word as the standing equivalent of yécer, and the dpdovnpna of Rom. viii. 6 would seem to come as near to its meaning as the word employed by the grandson of Ben Sirach, dcaBovAov (Ecclus. xv. 14). If the genitive ‘of the flesh’ may be taken as a Hebraism (=‘ fleshly’), the words 76 dpdvnpa THs capkos then represent ‘ the fleshly yécer;..and the corresponding phrase, ro dpdvnna Tob avevpatos (‘the mind of the spirit’), might be translated ‘the spiritual yécer’ ; so that the passage Rom. viii. 6, 7 would embody the first occurrence in Christian literature of the doctrine of the Two Yecavim, bad and good, which strive for the mastery within the soul of man.+ But, PPP Di ati. Se Oley chisel $< Acts xcxi."3. 4 This development of the yé¢ev-conception appears first in Test. x11. Paty., Test. Asser, I-IV. 6: ‘ Two ways hath God given to the sons of men, and two inclinations (8vo dSuaBovAua)’ ..., etc.; see the whole passage. The idea of the ‘ Two Ways,’ which is built upon that of the Two Ye¢arim, is found in the Didache, 1-6, and in the Epistle of Barnabas, 18-20. The Two Ye¢avim themselves reappear in Hermas, Mand. xii. (cf. Lecture IV, p. 172). THE DOCTRINE IN THE NEW TESTAMENT 151 whether this be so or not, it remains true to say that there are a thousand chances to one in favour of any explanation of a given Pauline concept which traces its genesis to Jewish, rather than Greek, Persian, or other Gentile sources; and that, in this particular instance, the idea of the ‘ evil imagination,’ as we have met with it in Rabbinical thought —of the turbulent stream of psychic energy perpetually boiling up from the depths of the soul and appearing in consciousness as sensual and self-assertive impulses—pro- vides us with precisely the category which we need in order to subsume into a unity the various aspects of inbred evil in man which are reflected in the Apostle’s passionate words. When, however, we suggest that the key to the Pauline doctrine of “ Original Sin ’ lies in the hypothesis that he has brought over with him into Christianity, from his Rabbinical training, the idea of the yécer ha-ra*, we must add that, in embodying it into his own system, he has stamped it with a threefold difference. (x) In the first place, he has permanently welded into it the idea of the Fall of Adam as its source, thereby creating that synthesis of the apocalyptic and the scholastic theories of the origin of evil, which (as we have seen) the author of 4 Ezra, writing in complete independence of Pauline and Christian influence, seems to have achieved a generation later. We may surmise that he had learnt of the yécer-theory from Gamaliel, and already held it prior to his conversion to Christianity, but that he only came to hold the Adamic Fall-theory as the result of intercourse with the original Apostles and other Galilean followers of our Lord. It is doubtless true that his combination of the two theories is more in the nature of a mechanical conjunction than of a complete organic fusion ; for, whilst implicitly affirming the yécer to be the effect—and not, as the Rabbinical theology asserted, the cause—of Adam’s transgression, he nowhere explains why a single act of wrongdoing should have had such a mighty reflex consequence as the birth of an interior power of evil, universally propagated by physiological heredity, and unconquerable save by supernatural assist- ance; the classical Fall-text, Rom. v. 12 ff., passes over this 1 See above, Lecture II, p. 79. 152 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN question in silence; nor, as we shall see, has this patent gap in his exposition ever been satisfactorily filled by any of his commentators or successors. But the Pauline blend — of the two Jewish traditions, the popular and the official, possesses a strength which cannot be attributed to either of them separately: it supplies intellectual reinforcement to the Fall-idea by giving it a more or less defined psycho- logical content, and it heightens the spiritual value of the yécer-conception by denying that God is the author of the ‘evil impulse,’ and so bringing the idea into full accord with ethical monotheism. Abstracting from the question of its objective truth—a question with which, as has often been said, we are not in this the first and historical stage of our enquiry concerned—we may attribute its survival in great measure to its association of ethical and religious value with a tolerable, though by no means excessive, “degree of conceptual precision. (2) The second difference which St. Paul has impressed upon the yécer-idea consists in the striking fact, already noticed, that—breaking away from the wusus loquendi common to the prophets and the Rabbinical theologians, and endorsed by our Lord Himself, according to which the seat of the evil power in man is the ‘ heart ’ 1—he insists again and again that the inbred disease resides in the ‘flesh,’ the ‘ body,’ or the ‘members.’ This is by no means a mere variant in terminology. In the rough and ready psychology of the Old Testament which lies behind all the Apostle’s thought and language with regard to these subjects, the ‘heart’ (lébh), paradoxically enough, is not a part of the ‘ flesh’ (badsar) : it is the whole personality, or perhaps rather that deep hidden part of the personality which we now call the Unconscious. The ‘ flesh,’ on the other hand, means the literal flesh, the organic tissue of which the body is composed: and as such it is for the Old Testament writers morally neutral. When, therefore, St. Paul transfers the seat of innate evil from the ‘ heart’ to the ‘ flesh,’ he is to be understood—so far as his words go—as exempting the mental and psychic life of man, even in its subconscious processes, from the infection of sin, and concentrating this 1 See above, Lecture II, p. 65; Lecture III, p. 97. THE DOCTRINE IN THE NEW TESTAMENT 153 almost exclusively in the physical body. Actually, he fails to maintain a sharp line of demarcation between body and mind or to keep inherited sinfulness strictly on the physical side of the line. But it is difficult to escape from the impression that his language in this connexion is dictated by the fact that (like many of his predecessors and also of his successors in the path of hamartiological speculation) he is in the main, perhaps unconsciously, thinking of ‘ sins of the flesh’ in the most restricted sense of the term; though, in the passage before noticed, Gal. v. 19, 20, he endeavours to correct the balance of his thought by expressly including amongst the ‘ works of the flesh ’ those sins which arise from cruelty and pride. (3) It must be noticed, in the last place, that for St. Paul the innate ‘impulse towards sin’ is unreservedly evil, and that he shows no traces of sympathy with that more humane view held by some of the Rabbis, who (as we saw in Lecture II) taught that the yéger is, considered in itself, a morally neutral libido: which, in the uninstructed man, may and generally does discharge itself in unlawful acts, but which is also the driving force behind all creative achievement, whether in the economic, the political, or the intellectual spheres, and which by the study of the Law can be completely ‘sublimated’ and diverted into socially useful channels. The Apostle will have none of this: for him sin, even as innate and potential, is “quite super- latively sinful’! (ka@’ daepBodrjv dpaptwdAds), and the Law, however long or intently it may be studied, quite impotent to subdue it (on the contrary, as we have seen, the Law merely stimulates the sinful impulse to fresh vigour) ; nothing less than the living power which flows forth from the Incarnation and the Atonement can quench the flames of temptation. ‘ That which the Law could not do—that in which its impotence was exhibited through (the power of Sin dwelling in) the flesh—God (actually did, namely this)—having sent His own Son in the likeness of sinful flesh and as a sin-offering, He condemned sin within (that very sphere of) the flesh (in which it had hitherto reigned without a rival).’2 So deep is St. Paul’s conviction a VEC OL uV il 1 37 2 Rom. viii. 3 (freely translated). 154 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN of the sinfulness of the sinful impulse, and of its intimate and subtle diffusion throughout man’s physical nature, that he is prompted to describe the stainless humanity of the Incarnate Son in a phrase which trembles on the verge of Docetism—‘ the Izkeness of sinful flesh.’1 Though, as will be argued later, the Augustinian doctrine of ‘ Original Sin ’ represents a one-sided distortion of the fundamental Pauline ideas, it cannot be denied that the Apostle’s language affords some excuse for those later Christian thinkers who saw in it an affirmation of the essentially sinful nature of “concupiscence,’ both in its general and in its specifically sexual significance. THE INFLUENCE OF ST. PAUL’S TEMPERAMENT UPON HIS DOCTRINE In the light of the facts reviewed in our previous Lectures, it will be clear that the special characteristics of the Pauline doctrine summed up under the last two heads (2) and (3)— that is, the affirmations of the intensely evil nature of the innate disease and of its close connexion with the physical organism—are idiosyncratic: they represent the stamp which the Apostle’s vivid and passionate temperament has impressed upon the materials combined by his genius. - Not merely has he driven out the Watcher-theory, and exalted the Adam-story to the position of the one and only Christian Fall-narrative ; not merely has he remedied the fatal weakness of the apocalyptic Fall-theories, which lay in the extreme vagueness with which the disastrous conse- quences of the primal sin were conceived, by formulating those consequences in terms of the scholastic yéger-theory ; he has embodied part of himself, of his living experience, in the great theologumenon which he has bequeathed to posterity. The finished, or relatively finished, product has been deeply coloured by the crucible in which it has been compounded. It will be appropriate to conclude our survey of the Pauline doctrine of Man and of Sin with a few words drawing out the significance of this fact. 1 Rom. Viii. 3. THE DOCTRINE IN THE NEW TESTAMENT 155 We have seen that all the theories with which we are immediately concerned take their rise from introspective reflection upon the experience of repentance. In the case of most religious men, repentance, and its corollary ‘ con- version ’—that is, the complete detachment of all impulses and desires, conscious or unconscious, from unworthy objects, and their complete concentration on the supreme good, however that may be conceived—are gradual ever- deepening processes, spread out over the whole life, and never, perhaps, consummated on this side of the grave. But in souls of a rarer mould, endowed with that highly sensuous temperament which is common to the voluptuary and to certain types of saint, the whole current of emotional and conative energy which ceaselessly wells up from the depths of the Unconscious may—through some minute and apparently accidental shock, physical or psychical—be in a moment diverted from one mental channel to another, and its manifestation in consciousness may be transformed from fleshly desire into the mystic thirst for God and good- ness, in the experience known as ‘ instantaneous conversion.’ It is no mere accident that the three great dominating figures in the history of the Christian Fall-doctrine—Paul, Augustine, Luther—belonged to this type, and passed through this experience. We shall have occasion again to examine the subtle influence exercised upon the more developed versions of the Fall-doctrine by the temperaments of their chief expounders ; it must suffice here to point out that the ‘ twice-born’ man (as William James has taught us to call him?) is usually an extremist, both as a sinner and as a saint; that the same emotional energy which before his conversion expressed itself in sensuality or sensual temptations usually appears after conversion as a fanatical horror and hatred of sensuality ; and that this horror of sensuality is apt to cover everything even remotely connected with the senses, so that the suddenly converted man is less capable of viewing the fact of bodily appetite calmly, and of distinguishing between natural impulse and its excessive or anti-social indulgence, than his ‘ once-born’ fellows. Such a one is prone to an ultra-ascetic and puritanical 1 Varieties of Religious Experience (1902), Lecture VIII. 156 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN condemnation of physical appetite as such, and specially of the sexual appetite ; it is noticeable, in this connexion, that St. Paul, in what may perhaps be described as a moment of unguarded soliloquy, expresses the wish that all men were celibates.1 It is to the Apostle’s ‘ twice-born’ tempera- ment, and to intensity of feeling rather than to reasoned theory, that we must ascribe the causes which prompt him to an occasional, and possibly incautious, use of words which appear to identify the hereditary tendency to sin with the natural appetites of the body ; though, as we have already pointed out, it is not difficult to correct the prima facie impression which these words might produce by counter- balancing them with other passages in which the body and its divinely implanted instincts receive their proper honour, and ‘ the flesh’ is given the neutral meaning which it bears in the Old Testament Scriptures. If we eliminate this accidental and temperamental colouring which clings to St. Paul’s language about ‘ the flesh,’ and endeavour to state the permanent essence of his conception of ‘ Original Sin’ in the terms which we may suppose that he would have used if he had been on his guard against the unconscious bias mentioned above, we shall be justified in describing the inherited moral disease as the hypertrophy, even the elephantiasis, of those non- rational and non-volitional elements in human nature which are summed up under the names of ‘ emotion,’ ‘ feeling,’ ‘instinct,’ ‘appetite. But the Apostle’s letters contain no word which definitely asserts that guilt is attached to the state of subjection to this disease. Even though, in a highly rhetorical passage, inbred Sin is said to ‘ prove itself superlatively sinful,’ this dictum must be understood in an abstract and proleptic sense, in other words, as implying no more than (a) that the inherited infirmity is, so to speak, aesthetically objectionable seen from God’s point of view, and (b) that it may be described as ‘ sin’ in a metaphorical and improper sense, in virtue of its tendency to produce actual transgressions; for only so can it be harmonised with the deeper, more deliberate, and more authoritative sentence, that where there is no consciousness of Law (as tyr Corevil.7. THE DOCTRINE IN THE NEW TESTAMENT 157 in the race between Adam and Moses, and in the individual before the dawn of reason) sin is not accounted to be sin (that is, does not involve guilt), St. Paul knows nothing of a mystical or pre-natal participation of Adam’s posterity in the sin of their first father, nor of the idea that inherited, and therefore involuntary, infection with ‘ concupiscence ’ is in itself deserving of punishment, even prior to and apart from actual offences ; in other words, he knows nothing of the conception of Original Guilt. THE CONTEXT OF EVIL IN MAN (a2) EVIL IN THE SUB-HUMAN WORLD It might well be supposed that the foregoing exposition, lengthy as it has inevitably been, would have exhausted the hamartiological doctrine even of so profound and original a thinker as the Apostle of the Gentiles. But the problem of evil in man presents yet a further aspect, with which we should expect a great Christian teacher to deal; and that is the problem of its relation to evil outside man, to evil as it exists, or may be thought to exist, in the planes of being which lie above and below him, in the world of sub-human nature, animate and inanimate, and in the world of super- human spirits. And we shall find that, unlike many lesser thinkers who have been content to ignore this question and to treat evil as though it were a purely human phenomenon, St. Paul has faced it in his private communings with God and his own soul. His explanation of the evil which prevails in Nature is enshrined in words of almost lyrical beauty and power, to paraphrase which would be a profanation : For I reckon that the sufferings of this present time are not worthy to be compared with the glory which shall be revealed towards us. For the earnest expectation of the creation waiteth for the revealing of the sons of God. For the creation was sub- jected to vanity, not of its own will, but by reason of him who subjected it, in hope that the creation itself also shall be delivered from the bondage of corruption into the liberty of the glory of the children of God. For we know that the whole creation groaneth and travaileth in pain together until now. 1 Rom. viii. 18-22. 158 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN Commentators are not agreed whether the mysterious reference to ‘him who subjected the creation to vanity ’ is meant to indicate Adam or the Creator; in any case, however, the meaning is that the woes of the animal creation are directly due to the Fall. The roots of this idea, as of the other elements which make up the Adamic theory, lie deep in the thought of the pre-Christian apocalyptists. The belief that Nature was corrupted by the Fall of Adam is derived ultimately from the primal curse pronounced, according to the Genesis-story, upon the earth—‘ Thorns also and thistles shall it bring forth unto thee’!; and this was expanded by the pseudepigraphic writers so as to include among the consequences of the Fall inclement seasons, earthquakes and all destructive or terrifying natural phenomena, the ferocity of the animal tribes. The Apostle reproduces this belief, but with an impressive difference. The apocalyptists had thought of the discords in Nature as evil merely from the point of view of man, as prejudicial to man’s comfort or physical well-being, as entailing fear, or pain, or death upon man. With amazing modernity of feeling, St. Paul merges himself in Nature, and looks at the terror of existence, if we may so say, from Nature’s point of view and through Nature’s own multi- tudinous eyes. The vanity and futility which mark the sub-human universe, the prodigal waste of life which the teeming generative forces of the world inevitably involve, procreating a million seeds to perish and decay for one that attains to full development, the ceaseless, silent, ruthless struggle for existence that underlies the smiling beauty of a summer landscape—these things appear to him as evil and God-defying in themselves, and not merely as perceived by, or in their relations to, man. ‘ He is one of those, like St. Francis of Assisi, to whom it is given to read the uncon- scious thoughts of plants and animals. He seems to lay his ear to the earth, and the confused murmur which he hears has a meaning for him. It is creation’s yearning for that happier state intended for it and of which it has been defrauded.’ 2 We cannot, indeed, in the light of modern knowledge, accept his naive theory that waste, and vanity, +(5EN Hallet GS. 2 Sanday and Headlam, op. cit., p. 212. THE DOCTRINE IN THE NEW TESTAMENT 159 and internecine hostility have been inflicted upon. sub- : human life as a sort of vicarious punishment for the sin of man; for we know that pain and death existed upon this planet millions of years before man was born. But.we may see beneath the Apostle’s words an intuition of the profound truths that man is organic to nature, inseparable from his context in the sub-human creation, and that evil in man is homogeneous with, and not explicable apart from, evil in the world at large. These vast problems cannot be adequately dealt with now; but we may confidently claim St. Paul’s authority in support of our modern faith That nothing walks with aimless feet, That not one life shall be destroyed, Or cast as rubbish to the void, When God hath made the pile complete,! and that, whether individual immortality be the destiny of the lower animals or no, the sub-human universe of sentient life can claim the ultimate fulfilment and perfection of its being from the justice and love of its Creator, with no less assurance, though with infinitely less of comprehension, than the favoured race of man.? THE CONTEXT OF Evit IN MAN (6) Evil IN THE WORLD OF SPIRITS Evil in man thus appears as set in a context or frame, of which one side is the unconscious evil with which the sub-hyman world is infected. The other side of this frame is constituted by the evil which St. Paul believes to exist on the superhuman plane, the ‘ spiritual powers of wicked- ness in the heavenly places.’ The Pauline demonology is in complete continuity and identity with that which we have already noted in the Synoptic Gospels, and like it 1 Tennyson, In Memoriam, liv. 2 Cf. the great description of the Messianic millennium in Isaiah xi. 1-9. G. A. Smith draws attention to the fact that ‘ Isaiah and Paul, chief apostles of the two covenants, both interrupt their magnificent odes upon the outpouring of the Spirit, to remind us that the benefits of this will be shared by the brute and unintelligent creation’ (The Book of Isaiah, 1889, vol. i. chap. x. III). * For a detailed treatment of this subject see O. Everling, Die paulin- ische Angelologie u. Daémonologie (1888). 160 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN reproduces the main characteristics of current Jewish opinion with regard to Satan and his aery host. The demons have the power of plaguing men with physical evils, such as the infirmity to which the Apostle alludes under the name of a ‘ stake in the flesh,’ and which he regards as a ‘messenger of Satan to buffet him’?; they foment dissension in the Church,? and contrive hindrances to St. Paul’s missionary plans *; they torment the faithful with sinful solicitations and temptations.® (It is to be observed that St. Paul’s extant letters do not contain any attempt to synthesise the theory which finds the origin of temptation in diabolic suggestions from without and that which regards it as rooted in sinful impulses, connatural with the flesh, welling up from within; doubtless it had not occurred to him that these views required harmonisa- tion.) But the chief théatre of their power is the pagan Graeco-Roman world lying outside the spheres both of Law and of Grace. They give reality and personality to the imaginary gods of heathendom, communicating their impure essence to their benighted votaries through the pagan Mysteries, even as Christ bestows the participation in His Body and Blood upon His worshippers through the Christian Eucharist ®; their power over this outlying domain of darkness and sin is so great that they are described as ‘ the princes of this age’ ’ who (through the agency of Pilate, the representative of the heathen empire) crucified the Lord of glory, and their chief is even styled ‘the god of this age.’ ® In the Epistle to the Ephesians, which, if not Pauline in authorship, is at least thoroughly Pauline in sentiment and thought, some of them are apparently identified with the ‘ world-rulers,’ ® the malignant 1 The Church can in a sense utilise this diabolical power for discip- linary purposes, by handing the excommunicate person over to Satan ‘for the destruction of the flesh, that the spirit may be saved in the day of the Lord Jesus’ (1 Cor. v. 5); cf. also1r Tim. i. 20. ee Wy Oa is.) ey. Bek O00 ths Bae ht 40y Dhessii...te- 5 r Cor. vii. 5; this conception would also seem to be implied in Rom. XVi. 20. Ora (Cor x20} 20. PPT COLA ..8, 8 2 Cor. iv. 4. ®° Eph. vi. 12; cf. also the reference to the orowyeia or elemental spirits, in Gal.iv. 9. For information about the xoopoxpdaropes in Gnosti- cism, see Edwyn Bevan, Hellenism and Christianity (1921), pp. 77 ff. THE DOCTRINE IN THE NEW TESTAMENT 161 planetary spirits who, according to the lore of the Gnostics, drawn from the astral cults of Babylonia, shed disastrous influence upon the destinies of men: others, of humbler rank, find their home in the lowest or sublunary firmament, through which they ride the midnight gales, under the leadership of the ‘ prince of the power of the air.’ } It is natural at this point to raise the question, How, in St. Paul’s view, had the evil spirits become evil? (We must assume that the ethical monotheism, in which, as a devout Israelite, he believed, would have prevented him from holding that they had been created evil by God, or that they were co-eternal with God.) Various answers were given by the Apostle’s Jewish contemporaries to this question. Josephus holds that the demons are the souls of wicked men departed.2. The apocalyptic writers who were influenced by the older Fall-tradition identified them with the fallen Watchers and the spirits of the dead giants their sons ; those who adhered to the newer Adamic theory doubtless believed in some sort of ultimate pre-mundane “fall of the angels,’ such as is described by the Slavonic Enoch in the following passage : And one from out the order of angels, having turned away with the order that was under him, conceived an impossible thought, to place his throne higher than the clouds above the earth, that he might become equal in rank to my [that is, God’s] power. And I threw him out from the height with his angels, and he was flying in the air continuously above the bottomless (abyss).4 It might be presumed a priori that St. Paul, as a believer in the Adam-tradition, would have given his allegiance to 1 Eph. ii. 2. For the idea that the earth’s atmosphere is the special haunt of evil spirits, cf. the passage 2 Enoch xxix. 4, quoted above, and the parallels adduced by Morfill and Charles, Book of the Secrets of Enoch (1896), note 7m loc. Abies f.Vit.. 6; 3: 8 So 1 Enoch vi.-xi., cvi. (fragments of the ‘ Book of Noah’); xv., xvi. (from the original ‘ Book of Enoch’). But it should be noted that the ‘ Similitudes’ distinguish sharply between the ‘ Watchers’ who fell in the days of Jared, and the ‘ Satans’ who are said to have corrupted them, and who must therefore be presumed to have become wicked them- selves at some earlier period (Ixix. 4, 5). 4 2 Enoch xxix. 4. M 162 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN this last view ; and in point of fact the language which he uses in 2 Cor. xi. 3 (the passage already quoted regarding the seduction of Eve by the serpent) and Rom. v. 12 (‘ through one man sin entered into the world ’—presumably from some already existing external source) presupposes a tempter who is already corrupt himself before he corrupts our first parents. It is therefore reasonable to conclude that in the Apostle’s thought there lies, dimly descried behind the historical, or supposedly historical, Fall of Adam, a much more ancient, remote, and mysterious ‘ Fall’ of conscious and intelligent beings, an ultimate and transcendental ‘Fall’ from which the malign infection of evil has percolated downwards through the transgression of Adam into the human stock, and through the Divine sentence consequent upon that transgression into the sub-human creation. Immense vistas of speculation are opened up by these audacious conceptions: but the attempt to penetrate them must be reserved for the constructive and concluding part of our enquiry. CONCLUSION We have thus seen that the doctrines of the Fall and Original Sin come to us on the authority of St. Paul and of the Church, rather than on that of Christ, though it is not unreasonable to claim for them at least as much Dominical sanction as is implicit in the fact of non-prohibition. It is possible that in the final lectures of this course we may be able to go further ; if our examination of these beliefs on their intrinsic merits shows that they correspond to the facts of human life, we shall be entitled to conclude that they represent the working out, into clear-cut and explicit form, of what is tacitly implied in our Lord’s undoubted teaching as to man’s universal need of salvation. Mean- while, it is impossible not to be impressed by the extreme humanity and reasonableness of the Apostle’s teaching, as compared with some of the more rigid products of later theology. Though he seems to assume the natural immor- tality of unfallen man,! he teaches no doctrine of ‘ Original 1 See above, p. 124. THE DOCTRINE IN THE NEW TESTAMENT 163 Righteousness’ or perfection; the Rabbinical fictions which represent Adam as surpassing the angels in glory, intellectual power, and conscious holiness are totally absent from his pages. Nor can his words be cited in defence of the idea of ‘ Original Guilt’; despite a few rhetorical turns of phrase, no trace is to be found in his Epistles of the irrational paradox, that we are morally culpable for pos- sessing instincts which we cannot help possessing. And blended with this Pauline thought, which is so reasonable precisely because so little defined, is the great conception which we may well be disposed to borrow, at a later stage, as the foundation-stone of a modern and constructive inter- pretation of the doctrines of the Fall and of Original Sin: the conception of the unitary nature of Evil as pervading the three planes of life, sub-human, human, and superhuman. It was St. Paul’s prophetic intuition which first saw clearly that moral evil in man is no unique and isolated pheno- menon, standing out with stark inexplicability in the midst of an otherwise moral and orderly cosmos; that it has upward connexions, joining it with the ‘ spiritual things of wickedness in the heavenly places,’ and downward rami- fications, running into the ferocious egotism and the diabolical cruelty which mar and ravage the infra-human world. The moral struggle in man is not a single combat waged within the narrow lists of the individual soul: it is part of a vast battle-front formed by the interlocked forces of Good and Evil, swaying to and fro in a conflict which is not indeed eternal (for to admit that would be a surrender to the ancient foe of dualism) but which is as old as Time and as wide as space, and which moves to the predestined climax of a Redemption in which not man alone, but the whole extra-human universe, in all its ordered hierarchical gradations from the highest discarnate intelligence + to the lowliest speck of animated tissue may be delivered, through the all-prevailing Blood of Jesus Christ, from the servitude of corruption into the liberty of the glory of the Children of God. 1 Col. i. 19, 20 asserts that the benefits of the Atonement extend even to the hostile spirit-world: ‘ For it was the good pleasure of the Father . . . through him to reconcile all things unto himself, having made peace through the blood of his cross ; through him, I say, whether things upon earth or things in the heavens.’ ¥ ey. 4 ; rua ee Ry ee oe 8) » Bs | te aa f 4.) beter tie Br ae ei 4 inte IV. THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH OF THE FIRST FOUR CENTURIES ” tM ta A / ‘ €oTw avayKns pha, Jeadv widiopa madaov, atdvov, mAaréeco. KaTeodhpnytapevov SpKots, Ss / > / / / a / evTé TiS GuTrAakinor dovw dira yvia pinvn Os Kk’ ErlopKov auaptyaas €mopdcon, Saipoves oltre paxpaiwvos reAdyaor Biovo, Tpis pv puplas Wpas amo paxdpwy aAdAnoba, dvopevovs travtota ba yxpovov eidea Ovntar, > / / 4 / apyaXéas Bidtovo petaAAdacovta KeAevous, aifépiov pev yap ade pévos movTovde SidKee / > > \ A > / a 9.07 > ‘ movtos 0° €s xOoves ovdas amémtuace, yaia 8’ és adyas Hhertov dacBovtos, 6 8 aif€pos euBadre Sivas, addXros 8 €€ aGANov SéxerTaL, atuyéovar Se mavres. a Nee \ A #28 \ / Ne ed / Tov Kal €yw viv etl, pvyas Oed0ev Kal adyjrns, velket pravoueve mlavvos. EMPEDOCLES. Zwei Seelen wohnen, ach ! in meiner Brust, Die eine will sich von der andern trennen ; Die eine halt in derber Liebeslust Sich an die Welt mit klammernden Organen ; Die andre hebt gewaltsam sich vom Duft Zu den Gefilden hoher Ahnen. GOETHE: Faust, Teil 1. LECTURE LV. THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH OF THE PIKRST BPOURIVEN TU RIES Rom. v. 19: ‘ As through the one man’s disobedience the many were made sinners, even so through the obedience of the one shall the many be made righteous.’ HITHERTO our research into the origin and growth of the doctrines of the Fall and of Original Sin has moved in an exclusively Semitic and Jewish environment. With the missionary labours of St. Paul, Christianity crosses from Asia into Europe, and the point upon which our historical research is focussed crosses with it. The transplantation of our religion from its Syrian birthplace into the Western and Aryan world, the world of Graeco-Roman culture, of science and philosophy, inevitably involved the subjection of its main constitutive ideas to a process of intellectual scrutiny, analysis, and discussion, out of which grew up the great fabric of Catholic theology, broad-based upon the foundations laid by St. Paul and St. John: and the ideas of the Fall and of the hereditary taint or weakness, vague and ill-defined as they had been in Jewish and primitive Christian thought, were now destined to share in this process, to shed the pictorial and mythological guise which they had hitherto worn, and, within the realm of Western Christian theology, to assume an armour of clear-cut conceptual forms, moulded in the furnace of acrimonious controversy. It is clear that the somewhat general and elastic doctrine of St. Paul described in our last Lecture was bound, when subjected to rigorous examination, to raise certain great issues which have dominated the sub- sequent history of these ideas, and it will facilitate the further course of our study if we define these issues at once. 168 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN They may be formulated in the shape of five questions, as follows : Firstly. Is the Paradise-story of Gen. iii. to be regarded as literal history or merely as an allegory symbolising ethical and spiritual truths ? Secondly. What was the condition of man before the Fall? Is this to be described as one of ‘ non-moral innocence, analogous to the state which we attribute to the animals ? or is it possible and necessary to assume that he enjoyed that exalted state of moral and _ spiritual perfection which is described, by those theologians who accept this hypothesis, as ‘ Original Righteousness’ ? Thirdly. What is the precise nature of the damnosa haereditas alleged to have been bequeathed, as the result of the Fall, by the first man to his descendants? Is ita positive infection or corruption, or merely a negative weakness ? Is it the fact of physical desire, or inability to control it? Is it merely a psychological state, involving liability to sin in the future, or does it also include a juridical status of responsibility for the sin committed by our first ancestor thousands of years before we were born ? In other words, what is ‘ Original Sin’ ? and does it include * Original Guilt ’ ? Fourthly. Assuming that Adam communicated ‘ Original Sin’ to his descendants, in what way is the mode of this communication to be conceived? Is it to be regarded as consisting in the entail of physiological heredity, or merely in the concatenation of example and imitation, such as is called ‘ social heredity’? Or are we to assume that Adam, when he fell, actually was the whole of humanity, mystically or literally, in such a way that, as we were in him, his sin is Our sin ? Fifthly. What, in the light of any conclusions which may be reached with regard to the foregoing issues, is the present state of human nature, with which Redemption now has to deal? Is it totally depraved and corrupted in all its faculties, or is the hereditary wound to be regarded aS a comparatively unimportant scratch ? or, if the truth lies somewhere between these two extremes, at what precise point is it to be fixed ° = THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 169 These are questions which are both momentous and subtle, and it must therefore be expected that the task of determining the outlines of the really ‘ Catholic ’ or universal doctrine will become more complicated as our research moves down the centuries. In order to decide what precisely has been believed ubique, semper, et ab omnibus, it will be necessary to enquire, not merely whether the Fall- doctrine can be said to have been held by the Christian Church as a whole during a given period, but also (if we conclude that it was) what answers were returned to these crucial questions during the epoch under discussion. It need not, however, be feared that the subject-matter of our research will swell to unmanageable dimensions. As the ideas of the Fall and of Original Sin, despite their apparent logical dependence upon the story of Adam and Eve, are really rooted in, and derive their long-continued vitality from, the facts of spiritual and ethical experience, in particular from the experience known as repentance, we shall find that the opinions held by Christian thinkers with regard to these five cardinal issues tend to group and com- bine themselves into two well-defined versions of the Fall- doctrine, corresponding to those two contrasted types of religious temperament which William James has con- veniently labelled as the ‘ once-born’ and the ‘ twice-born ’ respectively.t The ‘ once-born’ or ‘ healthy-minded’ man, whose religious life has unfolded itself in equable and passionless development, exempt from crises or storms, thinks of sin in the light of human freedom and responsibility, and tends to minimize, ignore, or deny the suggested element of inherited obliquity within his soul. So far as he concedes its existenceat all, it is for hima weakness, a lack or deficiency, not a corruption or an offence, and deserves the compassion rather than the wrath of an all-just Creator. But the ‘ twice-born’ man, the ‘ sick soul,’ the Augustine or the Bunyan blessed or cursed from birth with the mysterious heritage of neural and emotional instability, whose passions have been transformed, whose communion with God and peace of mind have been won through the paroxysm of an 1 This distinction has been already mentioned in connexion with St. Paul’s doctrine of sin: see above, Lecture III, p-155f. “se 170 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN instantaneous conversion, thinks of himself as a ‘ brand plucked from the burning,’ by no effort or volition of his own, and of his unconverted nature as saturated with moral evil and intrinsically hateful to God even before and apart from any particular or concrete transgressions of His law. That portion, therefore, of our historical survey which deals with the evolution of the ideas of the Fall and of Original Sin within Christianity after the Apostolic age will be largely devoted to the task of tracing the parallel growth and studying the mutual interactions of the two classical versions of the Fall-doctrine, to which these two types of spiritual experience have necessarily given birth. This post-Apostolic history falls naturally into three sections, concerned respectively with Christian opinion between St. Paul and St. Augustine, with the teaching of St. Augustine himself, and with the subsequent developments of Augustinianism. The figure of Augustine, probably the greatest man, next to St. Paul, whom the Christian Church has ever known, stands like a Colossus upon a mountain crest, marking the watershed between the ancient and the modern worlds, and casting its shadow far along the road by which the Fall-doctrine was destined to travel. But the overwhelming influence which the Doctor of Hippo exercised both upon the form and upon the content of these ideas, as upon the rest of Christian theology, at any rate in Western Europe, renders it all the more important, for our purpose of arriving at an accurate formulation of the deep under- lying mind of historic Christianity in regard to this subject, that we should give special attention to the thought of the primitive, pre-Augustinian Church, the Catholic Church of the first four Christian centuries. If, without inelegant abruptness, a second and entirely different metaphor may be employed to illustrate this great man’s place in the history of Christian thought, we will venture to suggest that a giant personality such as his might be expected to have the effect of warping and drawing out of proportion the thought of his age, much as the passage of a comet near the solar system has the effect of perturbing and distorting the orbits of the planets. But, in the writers of the epoch which preceded the transit of Augustine across the theological THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 171 firmament, we may be confident that we shall find nothing but the unruffled, uncorrupted thought of historic Chris- tianity, free from the tremors and oscillations which the gravitational influence of this majestic luminary might a priort be deemed likely to produce. THE FALL-DOCTRINE DURING THE SUB-APOSTOLIC AGE Without further preface, then, we resume the thread of our historical investigation, which now leads us into the obscure and dimly lighted region of the sub-Apostolic age ; by which term I mean for the purposes of the enquiry to denote the hundred and twenty years, more or less, which elapsed between the deaths of the chief Apostles, St. Peter and St. Paul (which probably took place in the year A.D. 64), and the birth of systematic theology in the writings of Irenaeus (c. A.D. 180). Our evidence for this period consists in the remains of the so-called ‘ Apostolic Fathers,’ and of the early Apologists (Aristides, Justin Martyr, Tatian, Theophilus). It is a striking fact, the significance of which will presently be discussed, that amongst the documents which have survived from the first ninety years after the deaths of the chief Apostles, that is which are of a date anterior to the works of Justin Martyr (who wrote c. A.D. 150-155), only one can be found containing an apparent allusion to the Adamic Fall-theory. This is the anonymous treatise known as the Efzsile of Barnabas, dated by Lightfoot as early as A.D. 70-79, but by the majority of scholars about A.D. 130,! in which it is asserted that there is a parallelism between the serpents which attacked the Israelites in the wilderness 2? and the serpent through which ‘the transgression’ (7) aapaPaows, the technical term em- ployed by later Greek theology for the ‘ Fall’ 8) was wrought in Eve. 1 See Harnack, Chronol. der alichristl. Littevatur (1897), 1. 410-428. Bardenhewer, Patrology (E. tr.), p. 24, following Hilgenfeld, dates it during the reign of Nerva, A.D. 96-98. 2 Numbers xxi. 6-9. 3 See below, p. 252 n. 4. x 172 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN ‘For the Lord caused all manner of serpents to bite them, and they died (forasmuch as the transgression was wrought in Eve through the serpent) that He might convince them that by reason of their-transgression they should be delivered over to the affliction of death.’ 4 But this passage stands by itself. Not a word can be quoted from Clement of Rome, the Teaching of the Apostles, the Epistles of Ignatius and Polycarp, or the earliest surviving Apology, that of Aristides, as evidence for the existence of a belief in the Fall of Adam as the fount of human sin. In short, it would seem true to say that (with the exception of the doubtful allusion just mentioned) no trace is found of the Adamic Fall-theory in what survives of the Christian literature written between the Epistle to the Romans and the works of Justin Martyr. It is further to be noted that this solitary allusion (if such it is to be deemed) to the Fall-theory based upon Gen. ii. is balanced by allusions to the two other Jewish theories regarding the origin of evil, one to each, occurring in the documents of this period. The canonical ‘Second Epistle of Peter’ (which is now admitted on all hands to be a polemical treatise, cast, in accordance with a literary convention common in the ancient world, into the form of a letter supposed to have been written by the martyred Prince- Apostle, and dating from c. A.D. 150) refers twice to the Watcher-theory?; whilst the Shepherd of Hermas (written not earlier than A.D. go or later than A.D. 140) appears in one passage ® to assume the doctrine of the yé¢er ha-ra‘ (émvOvpia wovynpa), which it asserts to be a‘ daughter of the devil.’ We will content ourselves for the moment with noting the fact that each of the three Jewish theories of the origin of sin can claim one reference in the scanty literary detritus which has come down to us from the dark period 1 xii. 5. énolncev yap Kupios mavta odw Sdxvew adtovs, Kal anébvnoxov, €mevd1) 7) mrapd Baous dua Too Odhews ev Eva éeyévero, va edéyEn adrovds or dia Thy mapaBpaow adrayv eis Ort Oavarov tapadoOjnaovrat. 23. 45 11.4. 3see Lecture 11], p.,114. 3 Mand. xii. ; this passage, in fact, contains a statement of the doctrine of the Two Yecarim (emOupia movnpa and émiOvpia dyaby)—an interesting instance of the way in which Rabbinical influences continued to penetrate the Christian Church long after its formal separation from Judaism. THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 173 between the deaths of the Apostles and the point at which the nascent Catholic Church begins to stand out in the light of comparatively full documentary evidence. When we pass this point, a change comes over the scene. The last thirty years of the ‘ sub-Apostolic age’ (c. A.D. 150-180) are marked by a constellation of three Apologists, Justin, Tatian, Theophilus; each of whom contains testimony to the existence of the Adamic doctrine, testimony which is perhaps vague enough when contrasted with the rigid confessional statements familiar to us, but which (at any rate in the case of the two last-named writers) wears an appearance of almost startling definiteness to one who approaches it fresh from the apparent blankness and incon- clusiveness of the records of the first ninety years. To these authors, therefore, our attention must now be turned. (1) Justin Martyr. This philosophic convert to Chris- tianity must be pronounced even by the most indulgent critic to be a singularly hazy and confused thinker. We need adduce no further proof of this than his interpolation of the ‘ host of good angels’ between the Son of God and the Holy Spirit in his enumeration of the objects of Christian worship.t_ We shall therefore be prepared to find that such passing allusions to the subject as are contained in his writings are marked by confusion of thought and lack of mental grip. There is no systematic treatment of the sub- ject, but there are scattered and incidental observations which, when collected, would seem to imply the presence in his thought of something like the Pauline doctrine. The empirical universality of sin is affirmed in the Dialogue with Trypho the Jew (c. 95) in which it is asserted that the whole race of man lies under a curse.2. Though the immediate grounds of the curse are subsequently defined as actual sins, it is natural to suppose that there is a connexion between the idea of the empirical universality of sin and the ideas expressed in the preceding chapter (94) in which Justin borrows the curious conceit of ‘ Barnabas’ with regard to the parallelism between the serpent which tempted our first parents and:the serpents which attacked the Israelites in the 1 1 Apol. 6. 2 ‘ ‘ ~ , > cA , ¢ a e€ ‘ ie ” Kat yap Tap yévos avOpwruv evpeOrjceTat UO KaTapay Ov. 174 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN wilderness, and affirms that the purpose of the Incarnation was to destroy the power of the old serpent, and to bring man salvation from his bites, which are evil deeds, idolatries, and other acts of unrighteousness. It would seem that the underlying thought implies some sort of causal connexion between the act of the serpent narrated in Gen. ili. and the present sinful condition of mankind, though this connexion is not of so stringent a character as to impair the reality of human free will. Inc. 88 of the Dialogue, the influence of the first man’s sin and the personal guilt of each of his descendants are set side by side, without any attempt at synthesis, in an allusion to— . .. the race of men, who from Adam had fallen under death and the deceit of the serpent, not to mention the individual responsibility of each member of the race who sinned on his own account.? But the Fall finds its predestined counterpart in the Redemption wrought by Christ ; and in c. 100 of the same treatise we meet for the first time the famous parallel of Eve and Mary, which was seized upon by Christian imagi- nation as a natural pendant to the Pauline comparison of Adam and Christ : He was made man of the Virgin, that by the same way in which the disobedience which proceeded from the serpent took its rise, it might also receive its destruction. For Eve when a virgin and undefiled conceived the word of the serpent, and brought forth disobedience and death. But Mary the Virgin, receiving faith and joy, when the angel Gabriel told her the good news that the Spirit of the Lord should come upon her answered, Be it unto me according to thy word.? Little or nothing is explicitly said as to the exact nature of the causal link between the first man’s sin and the sins of 1 ey: 4 ~ > A \ ~ e > 4 4 e , ovde TO yevvnOijvat avTov Kal oTavpwOfvar, ws evdens ToUTWY, UmépeveV, 3 +) e \ ~ / ~ ~ > 4 a > A a? A e A 4 A Ul GAN’ vmep Tod yevous Tod THV avOpwrwr, 6 amd Tob Addy bro Advatov Kal mAdvnv ~ > / \ > ~ THY TOD Opews EmENTMKEL, Tapa THY LOlav aitiay ExdaTov avTa@v movnpevaapevov. a / ” , “~ A 2 kal dua Tis tapfévov avOpwrov yeyovévar, va Kat 8” Hs 6500 7) amo Tod od \ 4 > \ Er \ Ps) AY v4 onl rf.) lot ‘ tA A , ews TapaKkon THY apxiv EAaBe, Kal dia tavTns THs 6800 Kal KatdAvow AaBn. / ‘ s w \ ” A 3 4 > A a ~ maplevos yap ovca Eva Kai apfopos tov Adyov tov amd Tod dhews avddaBoica / ” /, 8 aA mapakonv Kal Odvatov érexe’ miotw S€ Kal yapav AaBotaa Mapia % zapbévos % r / > ae Bi yA > a @ A , 23: cig | >? , evayyeACopevov avi T'aBpunA ayyédov ort mvetpa Kupiou én’ abriy emeAevoeTa.. . > / td od , ameKpivato’ yévo.Td pol KaTa TO phud cov, THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 175 his posterity. A phrase, indeed, which occurs in the first Apology (c. 10)—‘ the universally evil and manifold appetite which exists in each man’ 1—is reminiscent of the idea of the ‘ evil imagination.’ But it is possible that a vague and fugitive allusion to some kind of hereditary taint or flaw may be discovered in his exposition of the regenerating effects of baptism, in which we are told that man by birth is ‘a child of necessity and ignorance,’ but that by baptism he becomes ‘a child of choice and knowledge.’ ? It is evident that Justin regarded the sin of Adam as having had some kind of evil influence upon the race, but it is not clear whether he regarded this evil influence as having been propagated by way of physical or merely of social heredity. In other words, his ideas on the subject would seem to be considerably vaguer than those of St. Paul; and it is certain that the explanation of evil which interests him most, and occupies the forefront of his thinking on the subject, is to be found in his conception of the ‘ evil demons,’ who according to primitive Christian thought swarmed everywhere, speak- ing through the pagan oracles, working lying wonders, and obsessing the bodies and souls of men. Much more explicit and exhaustive treatments of the subject are to be found in the Apology of Tatian, the Syrian ascetic and student of the Gospels, and in the treatise To Autolycus of Theophilus, reckoned by tradition as the sixth Bishop of Antioch after St. Peter; both of which documents may be dated somewhere between A.D. 170 and 180. (2) Tatian tells us that man was created free and non- moral. He was not created good, for God alone is good by nature, but was created with a capacity for goodness ; and the assistance of the Spirit or the Logos (Christian theology 1 qq ev ExdoTw KaKiv mpos TavTAa Kal ToiKiAny dvoet EmOvplav. It is noteworthy that the ‘ evil demons’ are in this passage said to take the kak? emOupuia as an ally (ovupayos)—an anticipation of the familiar homiletic method of combining the theories which respectively attribute temptation to the suggestion of Satan and to the inbred fault of human nature. 21 Apol. 61. éaws ph avdykns téxva pyndé ayvolas pévwpev adda mpoaiptcews Kal emoTHuns. But see the whole passage, which appears in a vague and elusive way to bracket together ‘ physical’ and ‘ social’ heredity as grounds of the evil tendency in man. 3 ovatio contra Graeécos, 7. 176 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN is still not very clear as to the distinction between the two) was given him in order to help him to realise this capacity. As a result of his sint the guidance of the Spirit was with- drawn ; man became mortal, and was shut out from inter- course with God. Hence the human soul is afflicted by an inherent weakness which renders it susceptible to the assaults of the demons. This weakness, however, is not so grave as to destroy the power of self-determination and consequent responsibility, on which Tatian strongly insists. If we allow for the difference of times and the absence of technical terminology, this is almost exactly the doctrine of Duns Scotus, which finds the essence of ‘ Original Sin ’ in the lack of the supernatural gifts of grace enjoyed by the first man in his paradisal condition.2 (3) A similar pre- sentation of the subject is found in the Apology addressed by Theophilus to Autolycus.2 Man was created neither mortal nor immortal, but capable of either state. God gave him ‘ a starting-point for progress ’ (afoppx) tpoxomyjs), and if he had made good use of this he would have developed rapidly in the way of sanctification and intellectual per- fection, finally becoming refined into pure spirit and assimilated to the divine nature. His unfallen state is said to have been infantile and undeveloped,’ and it is on this basis that Theophilus explains the divine prohibition against man’s acquisition of knowledge. Knowledge in itself is good, but some kinds of knowledge are undesirable for children. If man had followed the upward path of development, as his Creator had intended, the ban upon the acquisition of knowledge might possibly have been removed at a later date. All the physical woes of human life are to be reckoned as the consequences of man’s expulsion from Paradise ; but there is no mention of a train of interior and psychological effects flowing from the sin which merited this expulsion. Again, however, as in the case of Justin, though both Tatian and Theophilus seem to accept the general 1 This is vaguely described as ‘ following that one of the angels who was wiser than the rest, because he was the first-created’ and ‘ regarding him as God.’ 2 See Lecture VI, p. 410. 3 ad Autol. ii. 24, 25. © 4 ibid. 25: 6 "Addp Ere vimos wv: cf. also dua 8é Kal emi mdciova, xpovov €BovrAeTo arAoby Kal axépatov diapetvar Tov avOpwrov vnmialovra, THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 197 teaching of St. Paul as to the entrance of sin into the world through Adam, it is nevertheless clear that the theory which really dominates their minds, and is instinct with the poignancy born of direct experience (real or supposed), is that of an airy multitude of demons which haunt the earth and the lower atmosphere, sometimes appearing visibly in the character of the pagan gods and perpetrating monstrous crimes, and always assailing the individual Christian with the invisible weapons of evil imaginations and thoughts. As we have before pointed out, the hypotheses of diabolical suggestion ab extva and of evil auto-suggestion ab intra, arising from an inherited inclination or predisposition of the soul towards sin, are by no means to be considered as mutually irreconcileable explanations of the fact of wrongful impulse ; but they are distinct, and at least potentially alternative, explanations ; and it would seem that in the minds of these three Apologists, typical, we need not doubt, of the Roman? and Syrian Churches of their day, whilst the second is formally believed, it is the first which is most intensely felt and which has the greatest share in determining Christian practice. All the writers of this epoch insist strongly upon the reality of man’s free-will.3 THE RELATION OF ST. PAUL’S TEACHING TO THE THOUGHT OF THE SUB-APOSTOLIC AGE At the close of the sub-Apostolic age it is natural to pause for a moment, in order, if possible, to discover an eeecture. LIT, p. 169, 2 After his baptism, Justin appears to have resided at Rome (Eus. H.E. iv. 11) and to have been martyred there (7b7d. iv. 16). 8 It may be added, for the sake of completeness, that the literature of this period contains three allusions, other than those discussed in the text, to the Paradise-story of Gen. ili.: namely, Epistle to Diognetus, 12 (a rhetorical allegorisation of Paradise) ; a saying of an unnamed‘ Presbyter ’ (that is, one who had been taught by Apostles) preserved by Irenaeus, adv. haer. 11. xxxiii. 2 (Harvey); and another saying of unnamed‘ Presbyters,’ ibid., V.v.1. None of these allusions, when examined, yields any testimony to the existence of a Fall-doctrine. Athenagoras, libellus pro Christianis, 24, 25 (ed. E. Schwartz, in Texte u. Untersuch. iv. 2) alludes to the Watcher- story of Gen. vi., but uses it merely as an explanation of the origin of the demons, whom he (doubtless following 1 Enoch) identifies with the lustful angels and the spirits of the giants their sons. N 178 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN explanation of certain remarkable phenomena disclosed by our survey of its literary remains. These are, firstly, the fact that—whereas St. Paul, writing to the Corinthian and Roman churches, in A.D. 52 and 56 respectively, seems to assume the Adamic Fall-doctrine with the greatest con- fidence, as an idea entirely familiar to his readers, and there- fore presumably to all Christians—no other trace of this doctrine (with the exception of the doubtful passage in ‘ Barnabas ’ mentioned above) is found in Christian literature until we come to Justin Martyr, nearly a hundred years later than the dates of 1 Corinthians and Romans ; and, secondly, the fact that when we have once passed the mysterious date c. A.D. 150, unmistakeable allusions to the Fall-doctrine begin to occur, and, as we shall see, are found in ecclesiastical writers with increasing frequency the further we descend the stream of the centuries. It is tempting to explain the (all but complete) silence of the first ninety years by the sugges- tion that this is merely apparent, due to the scantiness of the literary evidence ; and that, for all we know, the Expositions of Papias, the Apology of Quadratus, the Dialogue of Aristo of Pella, and other writings of this remote epoch which have perished through the lapse of time or the rage of persecutors, may have abounded in references to the sin of Adam and its disastrous results. But the historical causes—accident, persecutions, and the like—which have destroyed so many of the documents produced during this period, must clearly be deemed, precisely because from our point of view they were blind and fortuitous, to have operated with complete impartiality as between the ideas which may have been expressed in those documents. The doctrine of chances, therefore, compels us to assume that, on the whole, the proportion which the various ideas of the Faith bear to each other in such sub-Apostolic literature as actually survives does roughly represent the balance of the collective mind of Christendom as it existed during this epoch. If this be so, we are driven to the conclusions that the Church of the first three generations after the Apostles, whilst holding, in undefined and rudimentary form, the great beliefs in the Godhead of Father, Son, and Holy Spirit, in Christ’s death for man, and in the Divine power of the sacraments, had THE’ FALL-DOCTRINE: IN THE CHURCH 179 made little effort to grapple with the question of the ultimate origin of evil; that, so far as this question had been raised at all, Christians were still divided between the three views which had prevailed in the Jewish Church (namely, the Adam-theory, the Watcher-theory, and the doctrine of the yécer ha-va‘) ; and that St. Paul’s teaching, as contained in x Corinthians and Romans, had had comparatively little effect on Christian thought. The question becomes all the more insistent—If{ the Pauline doctrine was in practice ignored down to the middle of the second century, what was the unknown factor which at that time suddenly came into play, disseminating and popularising this doctrine in such a manner that within another two generations it had become the sole official and ecclesiastical theory of the origin and ground of sin ? In order to answer this question satisfactorily, it is necessary to find a hypothesis which will at once explain St. Paul’s confident assumption of the Fall-theory, its apparent eclipse for nearly a hundred years after the date of Romans, and its re-appearance in the writings of Justin Martyr and the later Apologists. To do this, we are con- strained to re-traverse some of the ground which was covered in our last lecture. It was there suggested that St. Paul derived this belief, along with the essential Christian message, from the elder Apostles and other Galilean followers of our Lord, who themselves may be supposed to have imbibed it, not so much from any direct teaching of the Master, as from the apocalyptic literature with which they had been familiar long before they met Him. If the Fall- doctrine came to St. Paul as part of the setting of the Gospel, on authority so impressive as that of the original friends and Apostles of Jesus, it is natural that he should have taken it for granted as an indisputable truth ; and, as we have seen, his own ethical and spiritual sense is a sufficient explanation of his emphatic preference for the ‘ Adamic’ as against the ‘angelic’ version of the theory. But it was pointed out at the same time that the fact of St. Paul’s taking this idea for granted in writing to Corinth and Rome does not neces- sarily prove that it was already accepted, consciously and explicitly, by all of his readers: it merely proves that no 180 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN other theory held an exclusive dominance of the field.t It is characteristic of men of sanguine and enthusiastic temperament, such as was the Apostle of the Gentiles, to assume that those consciously agree with them who are merely not prepared to contradict them. The most, there- fore, of which we can be certain with regard to the state of opinion in Gentile Christendom when St. Paul wrote his Epistles amounts to this—that the ‘Adam-theory’ was known to some Gentile Christians, and not denied by any. It may, however, be asked ‘ Even if this were the case at the moment when St. Paul wrote, should we not expect that the unhesitating assumption of the Adamic Fall-doctrine by so mighty a teacher as the Apostle of the uncircumcision, the Primate and Father of the Gentile Churches, would have had the effect of causing all his readers to give their allegiance to this doctrine at once, in submission to his inspired authority ?’ In reply to this question, it must be pointed out that St. Paul, when he wrote his letters, had no idea that he was writing ‘ Scripture,’ nor were those letters regarded as ‘ Scripture,’ though they were doubtless treated with the greatest respect and veneration, by their immediate recipi- ents. For the first century of its existence, the Christian Church possessed no ‘ Scriptures,’ recognised as such, other than the Scriptures of the Jewish Church ; the only ‘ Bible’ known to St. Paul’s converts, to the Apostolic Fathers, and to the earliest Apologists was roughly identical with what we should call the Septuagint Old Testament ?; and even with reference to a date as late as A.D. 120, it would be true to say that the whole conception of a ‘New Testament,’ composed of authoritative Christian writings, and claiming a canonicity and inspiration equal to that of the Law and the Prophets of the elder dispensation, still lay in the womb of the future. Hence it is not to be expected that a couple of obiter dicta, one of them couched in somewhat obscure language, would immediately leaven the whole of Christian 1 See above, Lecture III, p. 117. * See three articles by Sir Henry Howorth on ‘ The influence of St. Jerome on the (Biblical) Canon of the Western Church,’ JTS, July 1909, April 1910, Oct. 1911, THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 181 thought, or meet with instant comprehension and acceptance by the totality of Gentile believers. If it be remembered that the minds of St. Paul’s readers must have been super- saturated with the belief in demons as the immediate authors of all evil—a belief which would be reinforced, not merely by the influences of their pagan environment, but by many recorded sayings of the Lord Himself—it is easy to see that the Pauline teaching about Adam and the consequences of his sin would be likely, so far as it was noticed or com- prehended at all, to remain for some considerable time in the dim background or penumbra of the Church’s thought ; and that its gradual penetration into the central areas of that thought would naturally proceed at a very slow rate, until accelerated, towards the middle of the second century, by the canonisation of the documents in which it was embodied as part of the Pauline corpus, the second main constituent, after the Gospels, of the ‘ New Testament.’ It is, I would suggest, with this event—the formation of the Canon of the New Testament—that the sudden revival of the Fall-doctrine, after a period of apparent abeyance, is in the first instance to be connected. It will have become clear from the foregoing exposition that some occurrence of ecclesiastical or theological importance, the beginnings of which may be dated c. A.D. 140-150, 1s needed in order to explain the silence of Christian writers prior to that date, and the ever-increasing crop of allusions which springs up immediately after it; and the canonisation of the New Testament is precisely what we require. The exaltation of the First Epistle to the Corinthians and the Epistle to the Romans from the rank of venerable monuments of primitive devotion to that of divinely inspired oracles, co-ordinate with the Law and the Prophets, would implicitly carry with it the promotion of the Adamic Fall-doctrine from the status of a ‘ pious opinion’ to something like that of a revealed dogma: and it may well seem that, within the sphere of external or superficial causes, no further explanation need be sought. _ But no serious student of human ideas will need to be reminded that the procession of visible external happenings, controversies, definitions, and the like, which makes up 182 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN what is called the ‘ history of dogma’ (Dogmengeschichte) in the text-book sense of the term, is but the epzphenomenon, the surface ebullition and agitation which both veils and symbolises the play of mightier and more primary causes beneath, operating in the dim region of instinct and sub- conscious thought which must be assumed to lie at the base as well of a ‘ group-mind’ like that of the Christian Church, considered in respect of its corporate organic life, as of an individual human mind. It is not difficult, in the present instance, to descend from the outer to the inner, and to lay bare the deeper causes to which, in the last resort, the seemingly sudden popularisation of the Fall-doctrine which took place towards the end of the second century must be attributed. The formation of the Canon of the New Testa- ment, like the elaboration of baptismal creeds, and the universal adoption of monarchical, in the place of collegiate, episcopacy, was part of the half-conscious process whereby the still young and tender Church developed, as it were automatically, a hard protective shell or armour, doctrinal and institutional, to safeguard the principle of its life against the vast, creeping, impalpable menace of Gnosticism. This extraordinary movement—the forms which it assumed were too bewilderingly manifold, and its intimate essence was too chameleon-like and elusive, to justify us in describing it as a doctrine or a system—arose prior to the birth of Christianity and in purely heathen environments. But, immediately upon coming into contact with our religion, Gnosticism discovered a peculiar and, so to speak, parasitic affinity with it, adhering like a fungoid growth to the body of the ‘ Great Church’ and striving to penetrate it at every pore, deftly disguising itself in Christian forms, borrowing the names of Christ and the Holy Spirit, claiming, finally, to be the true and authentic version of Christianity, handed down by a secret tradition known only to an inner circle of adepts, and standing in sharp opposition to what it alleged to be the vulgar, ‘ psychic,’ or carnal version transmitted by the public tradition of the Apostolic Churches. The beginnings of these syncretistic infiltrations are already a source of anxiety to some of the New Testament writers: witness the Apostolic denunciation of philosophy, ex- THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 183 aggerated asceticism, and angel-worship directed to the Colossians,! and the Pauline, or deutero-Pauline, condemna- tion of ‘ Gnosis falsely so called.’ 2 It is impossible here to analyse the genesis of this primi- tive theosophy, or to disentangle the diverse elements, Mazdean, Babylonian, Hindu, Egyptian, which entered into its composition ; nor indeed are those scholars who have devoted long years of research to the subject of Gnosticism as yet agreed upon a single theory of its origin? The two facts which emerge with unmistakeable clearness from the welter of conflicting systems are these—(a) that the root- idea of Gnosticism, underlying equally all its multitudinous shapes, was cosmic pessimism, the conviction that evil is eternally and necessarily bound up with the existence of the universe of finite, relative, and material being, and (0) that its redemptive method was conceived as purely intellectual, mediated through the acquisition of esoteric knowledge. The basal pessimism of .the movement ex- pressed itself sometimes in a monistic world-theory, such as that of Valentinus, with its hierarchy of aeons or emanations bridging over the gulf between the Absolute and matter, sometimes in an explicit dualism, which maintained a Demiurge or evil Creator, co-eternal with the good God; of this latter tendency, Marcion, who identified the Demi- urge with Jehovah, the God of the Jews and of the Old Testament, is perhaps the most typical representative. But, whichever type of Gnosticism—monistic or dualistic—at any given moment confronted her, the instinctive reaction of the ‘Great Church’ towards it was always the same: she recognised intuitively that she was in the presence of the ancient and most deadly foe of that ethical monotheism which she had inherited from Judaism as the foundation and presupposition of the Gospel message. The lists were set for the next battle in the agelong struggle of the Asiatic 1 Col. ii. 16 ff. See Bishop Lightfoot’s commentary im /Joc., and his Introduction, § II, ‘ The Colossian Heresy.’ per big: vii20. 8’ The most recent survey of the data now available with reference to this vast problem seems to be the latest edition (1911) of W. Bousset’s Hauptprobleme dey Gnosis ; see also the articlesin PRE, vi. p. 728 (‘ Gnosis, Gnosticismus,’ G. Kriger) and ERE, vi. p. 231 (‘ Gnosticism,’ E. F. Scott). 184 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN philosophies which affirm the eternity and necessity of evil with the Judaeo-Christian belief in the supremacy of good and the consequent contingency of sin; and the inevitable effect of the pressure of Gnosticism upon the Church was to compel Christian thinkers to face the question of the ultimate origin of evil, and, we may reasonably surmise, » to force them back upon a neglected element in St. Paul’s teaching, namely, the doctrine of the Fall. As in the Maccabean period of the elder dispensation, so also at the close of the sub-Apostolic age, the doctrine that evil is not eternal or necessary, but traceable to a primitive self- perversion of finite wills—a self-perversion which ex hypothest need not have happened—was brought out of the Church’s armoury, where it had rested unused and almost unnoticed for a hundred years, to serve as the sure shield for safe- guarding the Biblical conception of God. We shall have occasion again in the course of our historical survey to note the significant fact that the invasion of Christendom by a wave of Oriental pessimism or dualism is usually followed by a striking development of Fall-speculation within the Church. Meanwhile, we may be content, so far as this stage of our enquiry is concerned, with the conclusion— paradoxical enough at first sight, yet fitting the known facts so accurately as to admit of little doubt, in the present state of our knowledge—that it was Gnosticism which indirectly saved St. Paul’s teaching with regard to the Fall and ‘Original Sin’: partly by its claim to be authentic Chris- tianity, which brought about the canonisation of the first Epistle to the Corinthians and the Epistle to the Romans, but mainly by its fundamental affirmation of the necessity of evil, which stimulated in the Catholic Church a revival of the only authoritative doctrine in which the idea of the contingency of evil was enshrined. THE VINCENTIAN CANON AND THE SUB-APOSTOLIC AGE If the preceding argument is well founded, our map of the route by which the Fall-doctrine found its way into accepted Christian teaching is now complete. The line of THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 185 that route, starting in the immediately pre-Christian pseudepigrapha, runs first through Galilee and the beliefs of our Lord’s earliest disciples and followers, then through the mind of St. Paul, as instructed by St. Peter and the original Apostles, then, from the letters of St. Paul, after they had been canonised and placed on a level with the Jewish Bible, into the speculations of the later second- century Apologists, and so into the developing fabric of orthodox Christian theology. We have already drawn atten- tion to the fact that the line does not, so far as we have been able to gather, run directly through the primary source. of specifically Christian doctrine, namely the teaching of our Lord Himself, but rather, if we may say so, leaves it somewhat to one side. But it was at the same time pointed out that this fact would not in itself militate against the right of the Fall-doctrine to be considered as a member of the system of Christian truth, if the constructive part of our enquiry were to justify its claim to be a necessary out- come of the experience of penitence and an inevitable inference from the Christian conception of God and of His relation to the world. Our review of the sub-Apostolic age has, however, raised another question, of a formal rather than of a material nature, which must be disposed of before our research can proceed upon its way. ‘If,’ it may be asked, ‘the object of your historical survey is to discover the precise maximum of Fall-doctrine which may be said to have been accepted by the Christian Church as a whole —and if the criterion of acceptance by the Church is that defined by the Vincentian Canon, namely, acceptance ubique, semper, et ab omnibus—is not a serious obstacle to further enquiry created by the conclusions which you have just formulated with regard to the sub-Apostolic age? For, according to those conclusions, the Church of the period between St. Paul and Justin Martyr had not yet decisively made up its mind between the three Jewish theories of the ultimate origin of evil, and was not in possession of any one universally accepted Fall-doctrine. The Adamic-theory, therefore, fails to fulfil the test embodied in the word semper ; and it would seem useless to proceed any further down the stream of history. If the Fall-doctrine as a whole 186 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN is ruled out of the sphere of ideas which have been accepted semper—that is, on your own hypothesis, out of the sphere of ideas to which the Christian Church as such may be said to be traditionally committed—by this disconcerting gap of a hundred years at the beginning of its Christian history, it will be waste of time to discuss its later developments.’ It is undoubtedly true that—despite its prima facie lucidity and convenience as a working ‘ rule of thumb “— the Vincentian Canon can easily be made to generate a host of logical puzzles, if severely analysed. And it may be admitted at once that if the terms ‘ everywhere,’ ‘ always’ and ‘ by all’ are to be tightly shackled together, so as to constitute one single criterion, instead of three loosely connected and potentially alternative criteria—and if the single criterion so obtained is to be rigorously pressed, in the strict and literal sense of each of its three component terms—the consequence suggested by the objector necessarily follows. But this mechanical method of construing the Vincentian test speedily reduces itself ad absuvdum ; for it would also rule out the canonicity of the New Testament itself, and compel us to assert that ‘ Catholic’ belief can only be said to recognise the Bible of the Jews, that is the Old Testament, as inspired, inasmuch as during the greater part of the sub-Apostolic age the idea of a ‘ New Testament ’ parallel to and of equal authority with the Hebrew Scriptures was unknown. And yet no reasonable person would deny that, if there are any principles to which the whole Church may be said to be committed (however ‘ the whole Church ’ may be defined), the authority of the New Testament is one of those principles. It may be added that such a rigorous interpretation of the Vincentian Canon would render it useless for the purposes of the modern critical student. of Christian doctrine ; for he could not employ it in this form without accepting the assumption, which it would then im- ply, that the essential ideas of historical Christianity must constitute a static, crystalline, lifeless system, incapable of growth or development in respect either of verbal ex- pression or of logical articulation—an assumption which is contradicted by the most patent facts of history, THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 187 and indeed was repudiated by St. Vincent of Lerins himself.? It will be clear that the sense in which we adopted, and propose to employ, the Vincentian Canon as a working standard is considerably more elastic than that presupposed by our hypothetical critic. We have already been at pains to point out that our use of this principle is meant, not to guarantee the objective truth of the ‘ Catholic’ doctrines of the Fall and of Original Sin—for that is precisely the question which we have reserved for discussion in our last two lectures—but merely to enable us to define their exact content. In any case, however, it follows from the fact of doctrinal evolution that the Vincentian test must always be employed with a certain spirit of accommodation, as a poorvBdwos Kavev or flexible rule,? continuously adapting itself to the differing stages of development which Christian thought and belief had reached at successive epochs of their history. The reasonable enquirer, who recognises that historic Christianity is a living growth, to be interpreted by means of biological rather than mechanical categories, will not expect to find all the lineaments characteristic of adult maturity present with equally sharp definition in the plastic vagueness of infancy; nor will he be surprised if the Christian ideas regarding human nature and the sinful tendency prove at their beginnings to have passed through an ambiguous or neutral phase, analogous to that disclosed by science in the foetal life of animals, a phase during which it would have appeared uncertain to an external observer which of two alternative characters the fully grown organism was destined to bear. Supposing, in short, that the Fall- doctrine is eventually shown to fulfil the tests of acceptance ubique and ab ommbus for the immensely greater part of the Church’s history, such an one will consider that the test of semper has been sufficiently satisfied if the idea in question was accepted at least by some members of the Church during 1 commonitorium, c. xxiii. ‘ sed forsitan dicit aliquis: nullusne ergo in ecclesia Christi profectus habebitur religionis? habeatur plane, et maximus.’ See the whole of this chapter, which treats of dogmatic development. *NAT Eth. Nic. v. X, 78 (1137 b. 30). 188 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN its infantile and formative age. Our description of Christ’s methods of instruction! will have prepared him for the fact that the history of Christian doctrine begins with a period of intellectual immaturity and (relative) indetermination, during which the general diffused mind of the Church was slowly clearing itself in regard to the question, which parts of the apocalyptic theology current in our Lord’s lifetime were so intimately presupposed by His explicit teaching that they must needs be regarded as smplicitly belonging to the essence of Christianity, and which parts deserved to be discarded as useless lumber or pernicious superstition.?, And, in the light of this fact, he will not quarrel with a slight glossatory expansion of the Vincentian formula which would make it read “ quod semper quidem ab aliquibus, iam pridem vero ubique et ab omnibus creditum est.’ That the Fall-doctrine must have been believed by some during the sub-Apostolic age is guaranteed by its occurrence in two of St. Paul’s chief epistles, which, though not yet formally canonised, can be shown from the fragments surviving from the literature of this age to have enjoyed great veneration and authority.* We shall, accordingly, deem that its claim to have been believed semper is not prejudiced by the fact that the Pauline teaching took a hundred years to sink into the general mind of the Christian society, and (humanly speaking) was only stereotyped as a fixed idea in that mind by the assaults of the rival doctrines (‘ unmoral monism’ and ‘ dualism’) which inspired the Gnostic movement. How, and when, it came to be accepted ab omnibus, we must now proceed to enquire. Lecture LL proof: 2 The belief in a millennial reign of the Messiah and His saints upon this earth is an instance of a Jewish apocalyptic idea which, though widely held by primitive Christians, including Irenaeus, Lactantius, Methodius of Olympus, and, for a time, Augustine himself (de civ. Dei, xx. 7), was eventually discarded by the collective mind of the Church as not contained or implied in our Lord’s teaching : it will be argued in the following pages that the belief in a‘ Fall’ of some kind is an instance of an idea of similar provenance which, on the contrary, has been recognised and accepted by the Church as tacitly presupposed by the Gospel message. ® See The New Testament in the Apostolic Fathers (Oxford, 1905). THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 189 THE DOCTRINE OF THE FALL IN IRENAEUS The Christian literature of the ‘ sub-Apostolic’ age, so far as we can judge from its surviving fragments and from notices of now lost works in Eusebius and other later writers, consisted in the main of occasional and unsystem- atic! compositions, written to deal with particular emer- gencies or to fulfil special purposes, homiletic, apologetic, or polemical. No synoptic treatment of the whole.body of Christian ideas is therefore to be found in what remains of it; the scope of the Apologies designed to vindicate the Faith in the judgment of the Roman Government and of the educated non-Christian public was limited by the natural unwillingness of the Church to disclose more than could be helped of her mysteries to profaneeyes; and it may, indeed, be doubted whether the great constitutive conceptions of our religion had as yet attained to a degree of fixity and definiteness sufficient to allow of their being formulated in any shape approximating to that of a text-book or Summa of dogmatic theology. But the increasing pressure of the Gnostic movement, which found its spear-head in the organisation of the first Christian schism, the powerful Marcionite Church, compelled the ‘ Great’ or ‘ Catholic ’ Ecclesia to follow up the measures of instinctive self-defence which we have already noted (the development of the Canon of the New Testament, of the baptismal Creeds, and of the universal Episcopate) by the production of more or less systematic expositions of orthodox Christianity, endeavour- ing to embody the whole contents of the Apostolic tradition and to exhibit them as a coherent corpus of truth. The first ecclesiastical writer to undertake the task of framing such an exposition was Irenaeus (c. A.D. 130—-Cc. 202), native of Asia Minor, pupil of Polycarp and other unnamed ‘Elders,’ and Bishop of Lyons in Gaul, whose great treatise 1 The lost Syntagma of Justin, as its name suggests, may have been “ systematic’ in the sense of possessing a logical order or arrangement ; but it is not likely to have been a work of ‘ systematic theology’ as the term is now used, inasmuch as its purpose would seem to have been rather that of refuting heresies than of formulating orthodoxy (Justin, 1 Apol xXvi. 8), 190 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN against Heresies may with probability be assigned to the period A.D. 175-185. Substantially the same doctrine as to the Fall and Original Sin is found in the work just mentioned and in the lately discovered Demonstration of the Apostolic Preaching,* though we may note that the latter embodies the Watcher- story 2 in a form which is clearly based upon r Enoch vii. I ; here, however, the sin of the angels isnot regarded as being itself the ‘ Fall,’ but is merely narrated as a consequence of the Fall, which, in conformity with the now all-powerful teaching of St. Paul, is identified with the transgression of Adam. The doctrine of Irenaeus in the main continues and develops that which we found hazily presupposed in Justin and more clearly stated in Tatian and Theophilus. The main points of the fundamental Pauline scheme, namely, that sin came into the world mediately or immedi- ately through the first man’s transgression, that there is a causal connexion of some kind between Adam’s sin and the sinfulness of his posterity, and that the infirmity or taint so attaching to human nature is cancelled and done away by baptism, are such commonplaces of his teaching that it is unnecessary to refer to individual passages. We may con- tent ourselves with noting the interesting fact that he repeats the famous parallel first drawn by Justin Martyr between the virgin Eve and the Virgin Mary,® adding to it 1 eis émiderEw Tod amooToAKod Knpvyparos. An Armenian translation of this long-lost work of Irenaeus was discovered at Eriwan in Armenia, by Dr. Karapet Ter-Mekerttshian, in 1904; the text with a German trans- lation was published by him in collaboration with Dr. Erwand Ter- Minassiantz, in Texte u. Uniersuch. xxxi. 1. An English translation, with introduction and notes, was published by Dr. J. Armitage Robinson in 1920 (S.P.C.K. ‘ Translations of Christian Literature’): I have used it for the quotations which occur in the text. The passages in this work which deal with the Fall are cc. 12-18, 31-33. BTCO LS: 8 Justin, Dial. 100 (see above, p. 174); Irenaeus, adv. haer. III. XXxXil. I, ‘eam quae est a Maria in Evam recirculationem significans’ ; V. xix. 1, ‘ et si ea inobediret Deo, sed et haec suasa est obedire Deo, uti virginis Evae virgo Maria fieret advocata’ (see the whole context of both these citations). All references to the adv. haer. in the following pages are given in accordance with Harvey’s edition of Irenaeus. Demonstration, 33, For it was necessary that Adam should be summed up in Christ, that mortality might be summed up and overwhelmed by immortality; and Eve summed up in Mary, that a virgin should be a virgin’s intercessor, THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH ror the second, equally celebrated parallel between the Tree of the Knowledge of Good and Evil and the Tree of Calvary ! ; and with summarising certain striking and original views which he holds with reference to three of the five cardinal issues formulated at the beginning of this lecture. It will be noticed that Irenaeus is the first author whose Fall- doctrine possesses a content rich and stable enough to necessitate the employment of these logical subdivisions of the subject, which can hardly be applied to the vague and unsystematised ideas of the writers reviewed so far. (i) The first of the cardinal issues is that of the literal historicity of the Adam-story. There can be no doubt that Irenaeus, like St. Paul and most of the Fathers, believed in the reality of a first man (he seems to recognise that ‘ Adam’ is not a proper name?) and of a first woman, called Eve. But, if the long fragment of a lost treatise of his preserved by Anastasius Sinaita,® a seventh-century writer, be genuine (as there seems no reason to doubt), he took a remarkably modern view of the story of the serpent and the forbidden fruit. The quotation of a few sentences will make this clear. How is it possible that the serpent which was created by God naturally devoid of speech and reason should utter reasonable and articulate language? If it spontaneously acquired for itself reason and discernment and understanding and the power to answer what was said by the woman, then there is no reason why any serpent should not do the same. But if they [pre- sumably the Ophites, against whom these words were written] assert that it was enabled to address Eve with a human voice by a Divine plan and dispensation, then they set up God as the author of sin. Nor, moreover, was it possible for the wicked and by a virgin’s obedience undo and put away the disobedience of a virgin.’ Cf. Tertullian, de carne Christi, 17, ‘ crediderat Eva serpenti : credidit Maria Gabrieli. quod illa credendo deliquit, haec credendo delevit.’ 1 adv. haer. V. xvi. 2; xvii. 4; Demonstr. 34. 2 adv. haer. II1.°xxxiii. 1. 8 Inconsidervationes anagogicae in Hexaemeron, X (PG LXXXIX, 1013B- 1o14C). Anastasius says that the passage was written by Irenaeus against the Ophites, the Gnostic sect which worshipped the serpent of Gen. iii. Harvey, who numbers the fragment XIV (vol. ii. of his edition, pp. 483-6), doubts its genuineness, but merely on the subjective ground that it deals too brusquely with Holy Scripture. 192 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN demon to bestow reason upon a nature devoid of reason, and so to summon an endowment out of non-existence into existence ; for he would never have ceased to converse with men, with a view to deceiving them, by means of serpents and beasts and birds, and so to lead them astray. He proceeds to apply a similar rationalising criticism to other details of the Fall-story, such as the serpent’s know- ledge of the Divine command, his accosting Eve in the first place instead of Adam, the weakness which Adam displayed in falling without a struggle. If we set this fragment side by side with the passages in the adversus haereses and the Demonstration in which the Fall is alluded to—noting that in most of these passages, whilst insisting upon the reality of our first parents’ transgression, he seems carefully to refrain from specifying its exact nature—we shall conclude that he must have taken the episode of the serpent and the fruit in a purely allegorical sense, as veiling some sin of which the character is unknown to us. It does not follow that he interpreted the rest of the Biblical history of Adam and Eve in the same way; from his treatment of Eve’s creation, the expulsion from Paradise and Cain’s fratricide, we should naturally infer that his view of these incidents was strictly realistic. Modern readers may, indeed, find it difficult to believe that Irenaeus does not mean to allegorise the whole story from beginning to end, when they come across expressions of ideas which he shared with and doubtless inherited from the Slavonic Enoch and St. Paul: namely that the ‘ Paradise ’ from which our first parents were ejected is situated outside the world which we know, on some transcendental super-terrestrial plane (described in terms of Rabbinical cosmology as the ‘third heaven ’!); that it is identical with the Paradise in which repose the spirits of just men made perfect, and that even in this life the favoured saint may be for a brief space caught up thither in mystic rapture, as was the Apostle of the Gentiles in the ecstasy which he has himself described.? 1 See 2 Enoch, viii (Charles, A pocr. and Pseudepigr. ii. p. 433 £.) ; 2 Cor. xii. 2-4. 2 adv. haerv. V. v. 1: mob obv éré0n 6 mpOtos avOpwros ; ev TH mapadeiow , ‘ / \ > A > v4 ? / 4 , dnrovdtt, Kabws yéypamta... Kai exetOev €€eBAHOn eis TOvde TOV Kdopov , A] ‘ , < 4 wn > / , A mapaxovoas. 6.0 Kat A€yovow ot mpeoBUrepa, Tov arogTdAwy padytal, Tods THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 193 But it must be remembered that Irenaeus lived long before the days of Copernican astronomy, and that, at a time when the firmament was believed by all to be a solid vault arching over the earth, the affirmation of a geographical Paradise situated in ‘ the third heaven ’—that is, somewhere above this vault—would not have appeared to his readers as meant to be other than a statement of objective fact. Hence the assertion that Adam, ‘ having disobeyed God, was cast out from thence into this world,’ 1 is to be taken quite literally. No doubt the conception of Paradise as placed at a vast distance above the terrestrial globe, which is not uncommon in the Greek Fathers, easily lent itself to a process of refine- ment and sublimation, which tended to transform the idea of a material and spatial garden into that of a metaphysical and transcendental state. We shall find this metamorphosis complete in Origen; but it would be an anachronism to read it into the thought of Irenaeus. (ii) The second of the great issues, in regard to which this pioneer of systematic theology has expressed a definite view, is the question of the condition of Man before the Fall. We have seen that St. Paul asserts nothing about Adam’s para- disal state, save in so far as he implies that it included the possession of free-will and physical immortality.2. Irenaeus strongly re-affirms the position of Tatian and Theo- philus, that unfallen man was an imperfect, undeveloped, and infantile creature,? thereby denying by anticipation petatebevtas exeice perateOfvar’ Sixaios yap avOpwois Kal mvevpatoddpots ‘ , e , vdah er AR TT ye aie , se ie ¥ xe HToLLdoOn 6 mapddeioos, ev @ Kal IIatAos amdatodos eioxopiobels AKovaEV appynTa phuata, ws mpos Huds ev TH mapdvTt, Kakel pevew Tovs petarebevras ews ouvtedelas, mpooysalopévous tiv ad0apaiay. Cf. also Demonsty. 12: ‘ And, that man might have his nourishment and growth with festive and dainty meats, He prepared him a place better than this world . . . and its name is Paradise’ ; 17: ‘ when they were put out of Paradise, Adam and his wife Eve fell into many troubles of anxious grief, going about with sorrow and toil and lamentation in this world.’ 1 adv. haer. V. v. 1, quoted above. * Lectoretil, iA. 3 adv. haer. IV. |1xii. This original imperfection of man is asserted to be a necessary consequence of his creaturely status: ta d€ yeyovdra (as opposed to the eternally self-subsistent Creator) xa0o perémerta yevéoews apxiy tdiav oye, Kata TOTO Kal vaTepetoAar Set adra Too meToLnKdTOS* ov yap novvavTo ayevyynra elvat TA vewaorl yeyervnueva’ Kalo dé py eoTW ayévvynta, Kara TovTo Kal votTepotvTa Tod Tedeliov. Kald Sé vedrepa, KaTa TobTO Kal VATA, KATA TobvTo Kal dovv7On, Kal adyvpvaora mpos TH TeAElay aywyrv. ws odv Hh UNTHP O 194 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN the doctrine of ‘ Original Righteousness.’ According to this great primitive writer, perfection, moral, spiritual, and intellectual, was not the original endowment of mankind, but the goal which it was intended to attain, presumably after long centuries of evolution. Human nature was indeed capable of immortality and incorruptibility ; but at the beginning it was not actually possessed of these gifts. It is true that man was created in the ‘ image and likeness ’ of God: but whilst the divine ‘image’ (ekwyv) is expressed in man’s flesh,? the divine ‘ likeness’ (dpotwoats) is developed in his soul gradually and slowly, through the possession of the Spirit and fellowship with God 8 ; it there- fore can have existed in the first man only asa germ. His ethical condition was one of innocence, not of virtue, inasmuch as he was unable to distinguish between good and evil.4 If it is permissible, with Harnack,® to refer the rhetorical question ‘ quemadmodum igitur erit homo Deus, qui nondum factus est homo? quomodo autem perfectus, nuper effectus?’® to man’s unfallen condition, it will be hardly an exaggeration to suggest that the Adam of Svvara TéAevcov mapacxetv TH Bpédher To EuBpwya, to S€ Ett advvaret tv adrod mpeaBurepav déEacbat tpod7jv' ovtTws Kal 6 Deds adros pev olds Te Hv mapacyeiv an’ apxyfis TH avOpwiaw To Tédevov, 6 S€ advOpwaos advvatos AaPeiv adtd* vHmos yap hv. This position is emphatically repeated in Ixiii. 1. Cf. also Demon- stration, 12: ‘ The lord (of the earth), that is, man, was but small; for he was a child ; and it was necessary that he should grow, and so come to his perfection’; ‘Man was a child, not yet having his understanding perfected ; wherefore also he was easily led astray by the deceiver.’ 1 adv. haer. IV. \xiii. 2: rod 5€ avOpamouv jpéua mpoKdnrovros (cf. the adopui mpoxonts of Theophilus) cat mpdos réAevov avepyouévov . . . €der dé Tov GvOpwrov mp@tov yevécbar, Kal yevouevov avéjoa, kai avfjoavta avdpwlFjvar, Kat avdpwlévra mAnOvvOjvar, Kat mAnOvvOévTa Evicydoa, Kal enoxtoavTa dofacbfva, cat Sdo€acbévra deity tov €avtos Seandryny (that is, God). The vision of God is that which ultimately produces df@apola or incorrupti- bility. Inthe Demonstration, however, man is said to have been physically immortal before the Fall (c. 15). Too great consistency must not be expected from the first systematic theologian. 2 adv. haer. V. vi. 1: ‘ perfectus autem homo commixtio et adunitio est animae assumentis Spiritum Patris, et admixta (? legendum admixtae) ei carni, quae est plasmata secundum imaginem Dei.’ 3 ibid. ‘cum autem spiritus hic commixtus animae unitur plasmati, propter effusionem Spiritus spiritalis et perfectus homo factus est ; et hic est qui secundum imaginem et similitudinem factus est Dei.’ 4 adv. haer. IV. Ixiv. 1. 5 History of Dogma (E. tr.), il. 270, n. 2. 6 adv. haer. IV. |xix. 2. THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 195 Irenaeus belongs, in respect of his moral status, to the category of hominidae or ‘ sub-men’ rather than to that of homo sapiens; but for the fact that his early home was in an extra-mundane ‘third heaven,’ he might pass for the immediate progenitor of the semi-human race of Neanderthal. If this primitive Hellenic-Christian concep- tion of man’s primaeval state had never been overlaid by the Rabbinical imaginations as to Adam’s supernatural per- fection and splendour, later Christianity might have been spared even the appearance of a conflict with Darwinism. In the light of this conception, it will not appear sur- prising that Irenaeus does not attach a very high degree of guilt or culpability to the ‘Fall.’ God Himself pities, rather than condemns, His frail, imperfect, inexperienced creature for succumbing to the wiles of a cunning and power- ful foe. Man’s first sin was one of thoughtlessness rather than of malice; the devil acquired power over him unfairly, by a trick.2 Closely connected with these ideas is the even more startling speculation that the Fall was in some ways positively beneficial to mankind. Viewed objectively, and in regard to its historical effects, it almost becomes what has been called a ‘ Fall upwards,’ inasmuch as it conduced to man’s fuller and richer ethical evolution; just as the individual learns the meaning of a ‘ bitter’ taste by actual sensation, so man learnt by painful experience that sin brings separation from God and spiritual death. This, 1 adv. haer. III. xxv. 2: ‘ eum enim odivit Deus, qui seduxit hominem ; ei vero qui seductus est, sensim paulatimque misertus est’; IV. Ixvi. 2: “eum autem, qui negligenter quidem sed male accepit inobedientiam, hominem miseratus est.’ 2 That is, by promising him equality with God, a gift which it was not in the devil’s power to bestow. adv. haer. III. xxxii. 2: ‘ primum enim possessionis eius vas Adam factus est, quem et tenebat sub sua potestate, hoc est, praevaricationem inique inferens ei, et per occasionem immortali- tatis mortificationem faciens in eum’; cf. V. 1. 1: ‘ quoniam iniuste dominabatur nobis apostasia.’ 3 adv. haer. IV. |xiv. 1: ‘ quemadmodum enim lingua per gustum accipit experimentum dulcis et amari, et oculus per visionem discernit quod est nigrum ab albo, et auris per auditum differentias sonorum scit, sic et mens per utrorumque experimentum disciplinam boni accipens, firmior ad conservationem eius efficitur, obediens Deo: inobedientiam quidem primum respuens per poenitentiam, quoniam amarum et malum est ; deinde ex comprehensione discens, quale sit quod contrarium est bono et dulcedini, ne tentet quidem unquam inobedientiam gustare Dei.’ 196 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN however, does not mean that God directly decreed the Fall, but merely that He foresaw and tolerated it (not willing to interfere with man’s free-will) and overruled its consequences for good ends. (iii) The third crucial issue which emerges in the writings of Irenaeus is the question of the exact nature of the causal link between Adam’s sin and the sinfulness of his posterity. The task of bringing to light the unexpressed assumptions underlying the vague language of a primitive writer is necessarily delicate and precarious ; but it must, neverthe- less, be attempted. So much, at least, would be generally admitted, that in Irenaeus we find (for the first time, if our analysis of St. Paul’s doctrine has been sound) that con- ception of the causal link which may be described as the ‘mystical identity ’ of Adam and his descendants—the idea being that Adam was in some undefined sense the represen- tative of mankind and that, therefore, the race was somehow - committed by his transgression to an attitude of defiance towards God, in much the same way in which a nation may be committed to a war with its neighbours by a speech or an act of its Prime Minister. This theory is nowhere formulated in express words ; but it appears in many turns of phrase and diction, as when he asserts that ‘men’ in general, or ‘we, transgressed God’s law and _ forfeited Paradise.2, Such a conception clearly contains the poten- tiality of a theory of ‘ Original Guilt,’ though this is not explicitly developed. It must, however, be pointed out that the theory—if such it can be called—of a merely ‘ mystical’ identity can only maintain itself in a mind which has not the time or is unwilling to probe very deeply into the problem. If it is 1 adv. haer. III. xxi. 1, 2. (God allowed Jonah to be swallowed by the great fish, not that he might perish, but that he might be delivered and glorify God the more: so also He permitted man to be swallowed by the author of the Fall, z.e. the devil, that man might learn not to consider himself like unto God.) Cf. also IV. Ixi. 2: ‘Deo quidem magnanimi- tatem praestante in apostasia hominis; homine autem erudito per eam, quemadmodum propheta ait: emendabit te abscessio tua; praefiniente Deo omnia ad hominis perfectionem, et ad aedificationem, et manifesta- tionem dispositionum.’ 2 ¢.g,in II]. xix.6; xxi.2; xxxiii.; V. xvi. 2; xvii. 1 ‘inquem peccaveramus in initio’ ; and many other passages. THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 197 seriously reflected upon, it must either relapse into meaning- lessness or transform itself into the theory of ‘ Seminal Identity,’ according to which Adam represented humanity precisely because, at the time of his Fall, he was humanity, the whole of his posterity existing seminally in his loins, and consequently sharing in his sin; just as (according to the writer of the Epistle to the Hebrews) Levi existed seminally in Abraham when he met Melchisedek, and consequently participated in Abraham’s payment of tithes to the mysterious priest-king.t The indefinite character of Irenaeus’ language debars us from attributing this theory to him in anything like that precise and fully articulated shape which it wears in the thought of Ambrosiaster and Augus- tine, some two centuries later. But I must needs think that a rude and inchoate form of it is implicit in his frequent use of the phrase ‘in Adam’ to describe the rationale of man’s subjection to sin and death.? I find it very difficult to affix any other significance to passages such as the following : (Christ was incarnate) that, what we had lost in Adam, that is, being after the image and likeness of God, we might recover in Christ Jesus.* In the first Adam indeed we offended (God), not performing His command; but in the second Adam we have been recon- ciled to him, having been made obedient unto death. But ‘ the grief of their wound’ is the grief of that wound by which at the beginning man was smitten in Adam, namely, Beaten. This conception underlies, and forms the logical prius of that view of redemption which is characteristic of Irenaeus, and is denoted by the term ‘ Recapitulation’ (avaxedadAaiwats). The passages in which this word and its cognates occur are somewhat obscure, and its usage is not absolutely invariable ; though that which the Redeemer ‘ recapitulates ’ or ‘ sums 1 Heb. vii. 9, 10. 2 I here diverge from Dr. Tennant, Sources, p. 289 f. 3 adv. haey. III. xix. 1. This passage contains a classical statement of the idea of ‘ Recapitulation,’ on which see the text above. 4V. xvi. 2: ev pev yap Td mpdrw ’Adau mpocexdpapev, pty ToujoavTes avtob Thy evroAjv' év S€ Td Sevtépw ?Addy aroxarynAddynper, bayjKoou péxpt Gavarov yevopevor. 5 V. xxxiv. 2: ‘ doloy autem plagae est, per quam percussus est homo initio in Adam inobediens, hoc est, mors... .’ =. 198 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN up’ is ordinarily ‘man’ or “ Adam’ or ‘ human life,’ yet Christ is said in one place to have ‘ recapitulated’’ Adam’s disobedience,! and in another the primal enmity of man towards the serpent.2. If, however, we neglect these two passages as employing the word in a somewhat abnormal sense, it is possible to draw out the sequence of thought which the great Gallican bishop has constructed by com- bining St. Paul’s parallelism between the first and the second Adams, drawn in two of his earlier Epistles,? with the hints contained in Eph. 1. and ii. as to a ‘ summing up’ (avaxedhadaiwois) of all things and a union of Jew and Gentile into ‘one new Man,’ in the Mystical Body of the exalted Christ * somewhat as follows. Adam, being in his paradisal state co-extensive with humanity, possessed the ‘image and likeness’ of God, and then lost it by the Fall: the subsequent multiplication of _ the human race is nothing other than the proliferation and | subdivision > of this original Adam into’ myriads of indi- vidual men, each, in consequence of the Fall, destitute of the divine image. Christ then came as the Logos, who is the perfect divine image, and as the second Adam, the Ideal Man or Son of Man, who sums up in Himself all the splendours which man’s unfallen state had potentially ° RAGAUARAEY.\N,. SURAT: 2 ibid. V. xxi. 2. ST COP XV a Olle vs SFO One Seyler ate 5 Nevertheless, although Adam as the universal of humanity splits up into a multiplicity of descendants, considered as a particular man he retains his own identity ; for Irenaeus is at pains to assert, as against Tatian, that (the individual) Adam has been saved (adv. haer. 1. xxvi. 1; II]. xxxvii.). 6 I here assume that the passages quoted above (p. 193, n. 3) which portray unfallen man as a ‘ babe,’ that is, a frail and undeveloped creature, represent Irenaeus’ real belief with regard to the state of man before the Fall—an assumption which involves the consequence that this Father cannot have attributed to our first parents more than a rudimentary form of the‘ image and likeness ’ of God, or more than a potential possession of perfection. Harnack, however, maintains (History of Dogma, E. tr., ii. 273) that the idea of ‘ Recapitulation’ presupposes the doctrine of ‘ Original Righteousness’ or ‘ Perfection,’ on the ground that what is summed up and restored in the Second Adam must be supposed to have had an actual and not only a potential existence in the First. I cannot follow him in deducing this momentous consequence from the mere word “ Recapitulation’; and, though adv. haer. Il]. xxxv. 1 explicitly attri- butes a ‘ robe of sanctity’ to unfallen Adam (‘ eam quam habui a Spiritu Sanctitatis stolam’), this is no more than a verbal inconsistency with Irenaeus’ general ascription of vymdryns to the first man, an instance of THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 199 possessed, and purposes to gather into Himself, by sacra- mental incorporation into His Mystical Body, the countless individuals into which the ancient protoplast has split up, thereby re-uniting humanity into one single organism, endowed with the image and likeness of God, as at the beginning. It is worth noting that Irenaeus make no effort to develop St. Paul’s teaching with regard to the flesh as the seat of the hereditary infirmity and the connexion of sin with physical appetite. This element in the Pauline anthropology is almost entirely 1 absent from his writings— a circumstance doubtless to be accounted for by the fear of Gnosticism, all forms of which (as we have seen) agreed in regarding the material world, and therefore the body, as essentially evil. THE BIFURCATION OF THE ‘ ONCE-BORN’ AND ‘ TWICE- BORN’ VERSIONS OF THE FALL-DOCTRINE DURING THE THIRD CENTURY Our study of these primitive Greek-Christian writers has thus revealed, gradually taking shape within the Catholic Church of the late second century, an interpretation of the Fall-doctrine which, whilst preserving the essential outlines of the Pauline teaching, wears a humane, reason- able, and curiously modern complexion. It does not, indeed, betray any suspicion that Adam and Eve may not which, indeed, occurs in the same section (‘indolem et puerilem amiserat sensum,’ 2b7d.). It may be added that Eusebius (H.E. v. 27) bears witness to the interest aroused by the question of the origin of evil at the end of the second century, and mentions a treatise written on this subject against the heretics (pre- sumably the Gnostics) by one Maximus. Nothing of this book now remains: the passage quoted by Eusebius elsewhere (Praep. Evang. vii. 22), which purports to be an extract from it, but is verbally identical with a section of the Dialogue of Methodius of Olympus on Free Will (Bonwetsch, Methodius, Schriften i. 15-38), has been shown by Dr. J. A. Robinson (Onigenis Philocalia, p. xl ff.) to be the work of the latter author. 1 A suggestion of itis found in adv. haer. III. xxv. 1, which, describing the immediate consequences of the Fall, tells us that Adam clothed himself with fig-leaves ‘ retundens petulantem carnis impetum.’ 200 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN have been historical personages. But it gives us a picture of primitive man as frail, imperfect, and child-like—a picture which is on the whole unaffected by the Rabbinical figment of Adam’s ‘ Original Righteousness,’ and is by no means incapable of harmonisation with the facts revealed by the science of to-day. It exaggerates neither the height from which, nor the depth to which, the first men are alleged to have fallen. It finds in the inherited disorder of our nature rather a weakness to be pitied than an offence to be con- demned ; and, in so far as man is conceived as being under a curse or enslaved by the power of evil, a large part of the blame for this is divided between his own folly and the malice of a personal Satan. As held by the Apologists, it would seem to have contained no hint of the conception of ‘Original Guilt ’—a conception which presents equal diffi- culties to a reasoned faith in the Divine justice, whether the supposed ‘ guilt ’ be regarded as accountability for the sin of a remote ancestor or accountability for the possession of instincts which we cannot help possessing. We must admit that (if our exposition of the theory of ‘ Recapitula- tion’ is correct) Irenaeus seems, in some passages, to have given what must be regarded as a wrong direction to the progress of Fall-speculation by interpreting the vague Pauline phrase ‘in Adam ’ in a sense which would assimilate it to the ‘in Abraham ’ of Heb. vii. 9, and would harden the undefined idea of our hereditary connexion with Adam into a stiffly realistic idea of our pre-natal existence in his loins. But this implied theory as to the link between Adam and his posterity is only used to account for our de facto lack of the Divine image, and the idea of our present personal responsibility for our first father’s primaeval sin appears hardly, if at all. This earliest patristic version of the Fall-doctrine, which we have reconstructed from the passing allusions of Justin, Theophilus, Tatian, and Irenaeus, is the natural product of the ‘ once-born ’ type of religious experience, which alone would seem to be characteristic of the sunny genius of Hellenic Christendom, at that time the sole laboratory of Christian theology ; and in some ways it might have been well if this version had continued to prevail without a rival. THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH or But a universal Church must embrace all nations and all types of religious temperament ; and the sterner and more terrifying elements of our religion had yet to receive their due recognition within the sphere of Christian anthropology. If the ‘ once-born’ temperament constitutes the ballast of the Church, the ‘ twice-born’ is, under God, its motive power; and both modes of religious feeling should be represented, through their appropriate intellectual expres- sions, in the final and balanced estimate of human nature which a fully reasoned theory of Redemption requires as its presupposition. The point at which the single rivulet of primitive Christian Fall-tradition bifurcated into two distinct, and in some important respects divergent, streams of doctrine—the one preserving the relative indefiniteness of the Pauline conceptions and the emphasis on human freedom characteristic of Hellenic optimism and sanity, the other flowing in specifically Western and Latin channels, and deeply coloured by the pessimism of the ‘ twice-born ’ religious temperament—lies in the early decades of the third century ; a review of which, in regard to its influence upon the developing doctrines of Man and of Sin, must form the next section of our narrative. The elemental force which stimulates the further growth of Fall-doctrine during this period is still the unquenchable determination of the: Christian society to safeguard the ethical monotheism, [ inherited from the ancient Israel, which was the heart of | its message and the mainspring of its life, against the slackening, but yet formidable, assaults of Gnosticism. The writers whose opinions now demand our study are the illustrious Platonists of Alexandria, Clement and Origen, leaders of Christian thought in the East, and the fierce Tertullian, father of the characteristic theology of the West. | It is in the Alexandrine and the African schools respectively that the two classical versions of the Fall-doctrine begin to appear differentiated from each other; and their teaching » must therefore be examined in some detail. The Eastern school has a prior claim to consideration, as standing in more direct continuity with the early Greek-Christian thinkers discussed above, and as having produced, in the speculations of Origen, some remarkable and _ brilliant 202 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN developments of the Fall-doctrine, which will require attention in due course. A few words must be devoted in the first place to certain traces of the Fall-theory which, as I believe, may be discerned in the writings of Clement of Alexandria, side by side with much which appears to deny or ignore it. CLEMENT OF ALEXANDRIA ON THE SIN OF ADAM These traces appear in two passages, which shall be reproduced at length. The first of them runs as follows: But contemplate for a moment, if you will, the Divine benefits bestowed upon us, looking back to their very beginning. There was indeed a time when the First Man sported in Paradise, free from all constraint, seeing that he was a child of God; but there came a time when he fell under the power of pleasure (for by the serpent pleasure creeping on its belly is in a figure signified, and earthborn wickedness, which is nourished up as fuel for the flames). So then the child was led astray by lusts, and grew to manhood in disobedience, and having disobeyed his father he dishonoured his God. What was the might of pleasure! man, who by reason of his simplicity had been free from constraint, was found bound with sins. This same man (rotvrov) the Lord then willed to loose from his bonds; and being Himself bound in flesh (a divine mystery), by this mystery worsted the serpent and enslaved the tyrant, even Death. And—the most as- tounding thing of all—that same man who had been led astray through pleasure, that same who had been bound by corruption, him the Lord shewed set free with hands unfettered. O mystical wonder ! the Lord is bowed down, and man raised up! and he who fell from Paradise receives as the prize of obedience some- thing greater than Paradise, namely, heaven itself.? 1 protrepticus, xi. 111 (ed. Dindorf, 1859): puxpov dé, ef BovrAa, avwHev wy x , > , € an | ees § \ > , ” / abper THv Oeiav evepyeciav. Oo mpa@rTos ore pev ev Tapadelaw Emale AcAvpEvos, > A , > ~ ~ Less \ ¢€ / ¢€ lod 4 > a e ~ : PT Emel TaLdiov Av Tob Oeod, Ore SE UrémimTEv HSovH—Odis adAnyopetrat HSov7 Ertl / ¢ s > a yaotépa eptovaa, Kakia yytvn, els tAas tpehouevn—mapHyeto emOvpias 6 mais > > lot avdpilopevos amreOcig Kal mapaKxovoas Tob matpdos Haxvvero Tov Oedv’ olov taxvaev ¢€ / ¢ > € / ” ¢ / € / / ~ d0vy ; 6 dv amddtnta AcAvpevos avOpwros auaptias nopéOn Sedepevos. Tav Seop@v Adcat TobTov 6 KUp.ios adOis HOEAnoEV, Kal capKi évdeHels, wvaTHprov Beiov, > ff ToUT@ TOV Odw ExELpWoaTo Kal TOV TUpavvoyv edovAWcaTo, TOV OdvaTov. Kal TO 2 mal a a ~ mapadofdratov, exeivov Tov avOpwrov Tov Hdov memAavnpevov, Tov TH POopa / / lot , dedepevor, xepaly AaAwpevars Eder~Ee AcAVEVoV. @ GavpaTos pvatiKod KéKALTAL \ ¢ la \ A Fug 2 ~ a ~ fev 6 KUptos, avéotn dé dvOpwmos, Kal 6 €x Tob mapadelaoov Tmeawy petlov brakojs GOAov ovpavods amoAapBaver. THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 203 In this passage we notice, first of all, the naturalisation within Christian thought of the allegorical method of ex- egesis borrowed from Philo, which we shall find used with such striking results by Clement’s great pupil and successor, Origen. Secondly, we remark that—continuing what has been the uniform teaching hitherto of those Christian teachers who have alluded to the subject at all—Clement affirms the condition of the first man to have been that of a child, characterised by imperfection and innocence; in other words, he knows nothing of the doctrine of ‘ Original Righteousness.’ Thirdly—and this is the point of greatest interest for our present enquiry—it is to be observed that the ‘man’ who was freed by Christ from the chains of sin and from bondage to corruption is emphatically, even though implicitly, asserted to have been identical with the ‘ man’ who had been seduced by pleasure ; that is to say, ‘ Adam ’ and the human race are identified as one entity. I venture to suggest that sufficient weight has not been allowed by previous students of the passage to the equation which it clearly presupposes between the universal ‘man’ and the individual ‘ first man.’ Such an allegorisation of the figure of Adam is by no means unnatural, because, as Origen later points out,? the Hebrew word Adam (’ddhdam, n78) is not a proper name at all—it is the ordinary word for ‘ man,’ homo. The paragraph is, of course, highly poetical in character ; but none the less it would seem clear that the underlying thought is that which we have already found in Irenaeus, the vague idea of a certain solidarity of mankind with Adam, which is capable of being expressed in terms of either ‘ mystical’ or ‘ physical’ identity, a solidarity which necessarily involves mankind in the bondage to ‘ pleasure,’ that is, to the sensual appetites, first incurred by its common father. This is at least a minimal doctrine of ‘ Original Sin,’ even though, as Dr. Bigg justly points out, it contains no suggestion of the idea of ‘ Original Guilt.’ 4 1 Cf. strom. iv. 23, 150 (Adam was only ‘ perfect’ in the sense that no specifically human characteristics were lacking to him): bid. vi. 12, 96 (Adam was created, not morally perfect, but capable of acquiring virtue). 2 See below, p. 229. 8 See Lecture II, p. 41, n. 1. 4 Christian Platonists of Alexandria (1913 edn., with some additions and modifications by F. E. Brightman), p. 112, n. 1. 204 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN The second passage contains an interesting speculation as to the exact nature of the first sin: it occurs in a context which is devoted to a defence of marriage against the attacks of the Gnostic Julius Cassianus, who had cited 2 Cor. x1. 3— ‘I fear lest, by any means, as the serpent beguiled Eve in his craftiness, your minds should be corrupted,’ etc.—to show that St. Paul disapproved of marital intercourse. For (human) generation is a created thing and a creation of the Almighty, who assuredly would never depress the soul from a better to a worse state. Nay, rather was it the case that the Saviour came unto us who had gone astray as to our minds, which had been corrupted as the result of the disobedience com- mitted by us, pleasure-loving as we were, against the command- ments; the first-formed man, perchance, having anticipated our season [that is, presumably, the season at which God willed that we, Adam’s posterity, should be begotten] and before the time of the grace of matrimony having experienced desire and committed sin (for ‘ every one that looketh on a woman to lust after her hath committed adultery with her already,’ not awaiting the season of the Divine Will).! Here it is suggested that the ‘ Fall’ may have consisted in the first stirrings of lustful appetite, which may have led to the premature union of Adam and Eve, before the time appointed by God for their marriage. (We notice once more the tendency to which attention has already been drawn, to assign a sexual character to the first sin.2) The passage is elusive in style: but there is clearly meant to be implied some connexion between the sensuality attributed to Adam in the last clause and the ‘love of pleasure’ which is, immediately before, said to be the source of our disobedience or actual sin. Is this connexion that of cause and effect, or merely that of type and antitype? If the latter, it would seem that the whole sentence about Adam becomes an irrelevant rhetorical flourish. But if a causal connexion 1 styom. iii. 15, 94: KTLOT?) yap 7 yéveots Kal KTicts TOO TaVvTOKpaTOpoS, ds odK dv mote €& ayewdvav eis Ta yeipw KaTdyo. uynv, GAN els Tovs © memAavnpevouvs Ta vonuata els Huds 6 owTnp adixeto, a 51) ex THS KaTa TAs evtoAds mapaxots epldapn piAndovovyvrwy judy, Taxa tov mpoAaBovTos Hud@v Tov Katpov TOO mpwromAdoTov Kal mpd Wpas THs Tod ydpouv ydpiTos dpexEevTos Kal Stapaptovros, Ste mas 6 PrenwV yuvaika mpos TO emiOvpoa. Won epolyevocer atTHv, ovK dvapetvas Tov KaLpov TOD DeAHpaTos. 2 Perhaps Clement may have borrowed the idea set forth in the passage under discussion from the Apocalypse of Abraham; see Lecture II, p. 58. THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 205 may be assumed, the whole argument at once falls into place, and aligns itself with the thought of the passage quoted above from the protrepticus. It may then be paraphrased as follows: ‘ St. Paul’s saying about the deception of Eve by the serpent cannot be quoted as a disparagement of conjugal union. This was ordained by God, and cannot therefore in itself be an evil thing. It is true that the serpent signifies bodily pleasure, and that the inordinate love of pleasure which lies at the root of our concrete sins flows from a primitive act of surrender to bodily pleasure committed by our first parents. But the wickedness of this act consisted not in its sexual nature, but in its frematureness ; and this judgment is based upon a permanently valid ethical principle, which is embodied in our Lord’s words recorded in Matt. v. 28. What He condemns is, not the appetite, but the unwillingness to wait for the time when the satis- faction of the appetite will have become legitimate.’ There is a third passage relative to the sin of Adam which deserves mention in this connexion, though its purport appears to be designed rather to refine away ‘ Original . ~ Sin,’ on what would later have been called ‘ Pelagian ’ lines, than to affirm it in the sense which we have found in the two places just discussed. This is a sentence occurring in the adumbrationes, or ‘ Outline Notes,’ on the Catholic Epistles,t which are recognised by most scholars as coming in substance from the hand of Clement. Commenting on 1 Printed in vol. ii. of Dindorf’s edition, pp. 479-489. These adumbra- tiones are generally believed to be a dogmatically expurgated Latin version, made by Cassiodorus, of the commentaries on 1 Peter, Jude, 1 and 2 John, contained in Clement’s now lost hypotyposes (émorumdces, = ‘ out- lines’). For discussions of them, see Zahn, Forschungen zury Gesch. des neutestamentl. Kanons, ili. (1884), pp. 79-103 ; Preuschen, in Harnack’s Gesch. der alichristl. Literatur, i. p. 306 f. Westcott, however, (art. ‘ Clement of Alexandria,’ DCB, vol.i. p. 564,) doubts whether the adumbrationes as they stand are the work either of Clement or of Cassiodorus, though he thinks that they may include important fragments of Clement’s Com- mentary; and Bigg (Christian Platonists, p. 112, n. 1), though not, apparently, raising any question about the authenticity of the adumbra- tiones as a whole, doubts the context in which the sentence ‘ sic etiam peccato Adae’ stands, on the ground that it goes on to lay down ‘ the doctrine of reprobation.’ I do not myself think that it does: but space forbids a discussion of the matter here. I have felt justified in quoting the sentence as Clement’s in view of the agreement of the majority of scholars. 206 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN Jude r1— Woe unto them! for they went in the way of Cain ’—he observes, according to the Latin translator, ‘Sic etiam peccato Adae subiacemus secundum peccati similitudinem.’ The fact that the Adumbrationes are no more than summaries of the Greek original makes it difficult to be certain of the precise sense intended by the author: but it seems clear that the phrase ‘secundum peccati similitudinem ’ is reproduced from Rom. v. 14 (‘ after the likeness of Adam’s transgression ’).4_ In view of its context, the only meaning which I can assign to the sentence is as follows: ‘ (The sinners denounced by Jude are said to have . gone in the way of Cain, that is, to have imitated the sin of Cain) ; and in the same way we all are subject to the sin of Adam, by imitating his sin.’ So interpreted, this aphorism would not directly deny the hypothesis of the solidarity of the race with its sinful parents; but it must be admitted that it looks very like an attempt to supersede the conception of ‘mystical identity ’ by that of ‘ social heredity,’ which regards Adam’s transgression as influencing his posterity towards evil only in so far as it provided a bad example for this imitation.’ | We have thus two passages in which the Adamic Fall- doctrine appears to be affirmed or implied, and probably one in which it is recognised, but recognised only in order to be rationalised away. But these passages, taken together, bear an exceedingly small proportion to the total contents of Clement’s surviving works ; and against them we must set the whole trend and predominant tendency of his general treatment of the moral life, which, in strict accord with Hellenic-Christian tradition, insists strongly upon the autonomy of the will,? and makes little allowance for the fact of the moral struggle. It would not be justifiable to 1 It is a probable inference from this sentence that Clement’s text of Rom. v. 14, like Crigen’s, did not contain the word y7 before auapryoartas : see Lecture III,’p. 125; m:,2: 2 The following curious passage should perhaps be mentioned in this connexion: Protvept. ii. 12: Aidvucov pawdAnv dpyialovar Baxxyou dpodayia THY tepopnviay ayovtes Kal TeAtcKovat Tas Kpeavoulas TOV ddvwv, aveaTeupevor tots odeow, eroAodvlovres Evav' Evav éxeivny, 8. hv 4 mAdvyn mapnKodovbnaev. Kal onpetov opyiwy Baxyix@v odis orl TereAcopevos. adtixa yoov Kata THY aKpLpA Tov ‘EBpalwy dwviv 76 dvona TO Evia dacvvdpevov épunveverat dduis 7 Onreva. 3 Cf. strom. ii. 14, 60; 15,66; and frequently. THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 207 assume that a belief in free-will is logically incompatible with the belief in any kind of inherited handicap ; and we have seen that both convictions were simultaneously held by the second-century writers reviewed above. But it cannot be denied that Clement’s expression of the former is emphatic and enthusiastic, whilst his admission of the latter is scanty and grudging. In the Fall-passages which we have noticed, he conveys the impression of one who is rendering lip- homage to an idea which has too much traditional and Scriptural authority to be totally discarded, but which is really alien to the general direction of his own thinking. The truth is that Clement’s own temperament is as defi- nitely and typically ‘ once-born’ or ‘ healthy-minded’ as Augustine’s or Luther’s was to be ‘ twice-born’?! ; and it may be doubted whether his feeling of the sinfulness of sin was not somewhat less intense even than that of the normal ‘“once-born’ religious man. Such a conclusion is at least suggested by a sentence which defines the causes of moral evil as consisting in the “ weakness of matter,’ that is of man’s material body, and the ‘involuntary impulses of ignorance.’? Hence, it is not surprising to find that in one place the conception of ‘ Original Guilt’ is rejected in scornfully explicit terms,? and that elsewhere words are used which, if taken at their face value, would deny even the mildest interpretation of ‘ Original Sin.’ 4 1 Compare Bigg’s phrase, ‘the blithe geniality of Clement, whose cloistered life seems never to have felt a storm’ (Christian Platonists, p. 168). 2 strom. vii. 3, 16: Kaxdv dé aitiay Kal BAns av tis dabeverav broAdBor Kal Tas aBovAnrous THs ayvolas Opyuds. 8 ibid. ili. 17, 100: Aeyérwoav Huiv mot emdpvevaev TO yevvynbév madiov, } 7Hs bro TH To ’"Adau tromémTwKev apav TO wndev evepyfoav .... Kal drav 6 AaBiéd cizn, Ev dpaprias cvvedndOnv cat év dvoplas exicono€ev pe ULATHP Lov, Aéyer pev mpodntiKds pntépa tiv Evav* adda Caévrwv Eta pyrnp éyévero, Kat ei €v dpaptia avveAnddn, aA od« adros ev aduaptia odd5é uy apuaptia adrds. “Let them tell us, where the newly born child committed fornication, or how a thing that has performed no action at all has fallen under the curse of Adam? ... And when David says ‘‘ I was conceived in sins and in iniquities did my mother bear me,” he is alluding in prophetic wise to Eve as his mother; but Eve became the mother of all living, and even if David was ‘‘ conceived in sin,” yet he is not thereby involved in sin, nor indeed is he himself sin.’ 4 strom. iii. 9, 64. Here the crucial passage Rom. v. 12 is quoted ; but Clement’s only comment on it consists in the assertion that death is produced by natural necessity, flowing from the Divine governance of the 208 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN The exaggerated optimism with which Clement regards human nature reflects itself in his failure to appreciate the saddening and perplexing facts of evil in the extra-human universe. Theapparently purposeless cruelty which ravages the animal world, which, as we have seen, so deeply affected the imagination of St. Paul,? and which has led many thinkers, both ancient and modern, to take refuge in dualism as the easiest explanation of the present state of sub- human Nature, seems to have made no impression upon him. And as he never realised the genuine weight and force of Marcion’s case against the monotheistic belief of the Great Church, he lacked the incentive to study and develop the one existing theory of the origin of evil which was capable of shielding that belief. Hence the great architec- tonic idea of the parallelism between and the mutual implication of the Apostasy and the Redemption, which had been sketched out by St. Paul and elaborated by Irenaeus, is all but absent from the pages of Clement ; and the doctrine of the Fall is little more than a useless excre- scence on his theology, only of significance in so far as the fact that he does not feel able to ignore it altogether may be regarded as testifying to the measure of acceptance which it had already won in contemporary Christian thought. ORIGEN AND THE ‘ TRANSCENDENTAL’ FALL-THEORY Far different is the place held by the Fall-doctrine in the writings of Clement’s famous pupil Origen, perhaps the mightiest doctor of pre-Augustinian Christendom, the austere and fiery spirit of whom it has been said by one of my most eminent predecessors in this Lectureship ‘ There has been no truly great man in the Church who did not love him a little.’ 3 universe. He proceeds (in 65) to say that Eve was called ‘ Life,’ because she was the mother of all, both of just and of unjust, ‘ each one of us justifying himself or again making himself disobedient’ (éxdorov mud €auTov OtKaobvTos } Eutradw ameO7 KatacKevalovtos). 1 Cf. R. B. Tollinton, Clement of Alexandria (1914), ll. p. 254; Bigg, Christian Platonists, p. 109. 2 Rom. vill. 18-25 ; see Lecture III, pp. 157 ff. 3 Bigg, Christian Platonists, p. 329. THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 209 In order to elucidate the successive phases through which his peculiarly daring and imaginative Fall-speculations passed, it is necessary to refer briefly to the circumstances of his life. Origenes Adamantius was born A.D. 185-6, under the Emperor Commodus, and died in his sixty-ninth year, in the reign of Gallus (A.D. 251-254).1 According to the generally accepted statement of Epiphanius,? he was a Copt, sprung from the native population of Egypt; his father was the martyr Leonides, and shortly after his eighteenth year he was appointed by the Bishop Demetrius to succeed Clement in the headship of the great Christian institution known as the Catechetical School of Alexandria. Until A.D. 231 his days were devoted to the vast encyclopaedic labours, critical, philosophical, and theological, which made him the dominant intellectual force in the Eastern Christen- dom of his day, and to the public exposition of the Scriptures in the lecture-room andin the church. The stern asceticism of his private life, which aspired to an unreserved conformity with the precepts of the Gospel, even to the extent of a literal acting upon the commendation of those who have “made themselves eunuchs for the kingdom of heaven’s sake,’ marks him as a typically ‘ twice-born’ Christian, standing in this respect at the opposite pole to his master Clement ; but this temperamental bias was to a certain extent corrected by the Hellenic sanity, balance, and sense of proportion with which he was imbued by his studies at the Museum, or University of Alexandria? ; and we shall see that the character of his Fall-doctrine has been largely determined by the interplay of his passionate African idiosyncrasy and the calming influences of the philosophic culture, with its ‘ once-born’ associations and tone, which he inherited from the Macedonian conquerors of his country. 1 Westcott, art. ‘ Origenes’ in DCB, iv. p. 98, calculates these dates from the statements of Eusebius, H.E. vi. 2, vii. 1 ; for slightly different estimates by other scholars (not, however, varying by more than a year or two) see Weingarten, Zeittafeln u. Uberblicke zur Kirchengesch. (1905), Pir. 2 haey. \xiv. 1: Aly’nrws 7H yever: a statement which is confirmed by the etymology of his name Origen (Qpryévns, ‘ sprung from the god Horus’). 8 According to Porphyry (ap. Eus. H.E. vi. 19), under Ammonius Saccas ; Bigg, however, disputes this (op. cit., p. 156, n. 3). P 210 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN In the year last mentioned, he fell foul of Demetrius, the bishop to whom he owed his appointment as head of the Catechetical School, owing to his uncanonical acceptance of ordination to the priesthood, whilst on a visit to Caesarea, at the hands of certain Palestinian bishops. Being con- demned and, perhaps, deposed from the priesthood! by Demetrius and an Egyptian synod, he quitted Alexandria ; and, as the churches of Palestine refused to recognise the censures of Demetrius, took up his abode at Caesarea, which, for the remaining twenty years of his life, was the scene of his multifarious literary activities. His writings conse- quently divide themselves into two well-defined groups, belonging respectively to the Alexandrine and the Caesarean periods of his life ; and, as we shall see, this chronological division corresponds to a significant difference of orientation in their treatment of the Fall-doctrine. (i) THE ALEXANDRINE PERIOD—THE ‘ PRE-NATAL FALL’ The most notable work of Origen’s first period is the great treatise ‘On First Principles’ (aepi dpydv, de principits), which contains what at first sight appears to be a unique and original version of, or at least substitute for, the Fall-theory. As this work marks the first appear- ance within Christianity of a line of thought which has in more modern times led to some striking speculative develop- ments, and which may well exert an important influence upon the final formulation of our constructive conclusions, it will be well to state the view of the origin of evil therein put forward with some degree of fullness.? 1 So Photius (bibliotheca, 118, [PG CIII. 398, 93a]), following the Apology of Pamphilus and Eusebius. 2 For the text of the de principiits I have used the critical edition of P. Koetschau (1913) in Die griech. christl. Schriftsteller der ersten 3 Jahrhun- derte, hervausg. von der Kirchenvater-commission dey kgl. Preuss. Akademie der Wissenschaften. Reference to this will show that I have relied upon Koetschau’s restoration of the Greek original, in places where Rufinus has apparently altered or suppressed what appeared to him doctrinally objectionable passages, from such sources as the anathemas of the Con- stantinopolitan synod of 543, and the Letter of Justinian to Mennas. I have also used the ‘ Berlin’ text of the commentary on St. John’s Gospel THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH a1r Unlike Clement, Origen is deeply sensitive to the inequalities, injustices, and miseries which are plainly manifest in human life, and may be dimly discerned in the superhuman and sub-human worlds. (We note the Pauline sweep and comprehensiveness of his envisagement of reality.) The Apostle tells us that one star differeth from another star in glory,! and for Greek thinkers of the third century (as still for Aquinas in the thirteenth 2) the stars were, Or were moved by, conscious minds; why should there be an apparently arbitrary inequality amongst these glorious beings? The diversities of human fortune present an even more perplexing problem. ‘Some are barbarians, some Greeks; and of barbarians some are more cruel and fierce, some more gentle. Some men live under admirable laws, some under laws which are contemptible or harsh, some are governed by inhuman and bestial customs rather than by laws. Some men from the moment of their birth are placed in a state of humiliation and subjection and are brought up in servile fashion, under the rule of masters, princes, or tyrants; others are reared in a more liberal and reasonable condition. Some are born with healthy bodies, some with congenital disease or defect. . . . Why should I enumerate the whole catalogue of human calamities and miseries, from which some are exempt, and in which others are involved ...?’3 The question of animal suffering is too embarrassing to be faced directly, and is dismissed with the curious observation that ‘ these things are secondary results, not primary causes.’ 4 To the question, Why is the world vexed by so many inexplicable inequalities and apparently undeserved suffer- ings ? dualistic Gnosticism had an easy reply: these things (E. Preuschen, 1903) and of the first four books of the contra Celsum (P. Koetschau, 1899). All quotations from other works of Origen are taken from Lommatzsch’s edition (Berlin, 1831). Bes GOT XVi'AT. 2 See the quotations given by P. H. Wicksteed, Reactions between Dogma and Philosophy (1920), pp. 73-76. 3 de princ. ii. 9 (Koetschau, p. 166 f.). £ So at least I understand Rufinus’ rendering ‘ cum haec non principalia sed consequentia accipi debere certum sit’ (ibid., Koetschau, p. 167), which presumably represents an original émei radra odk dpxas adda, axdAovba xpH vouifew, or some similar phrase. 212 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN are the work of the evil. Power co-ordinate and co-eternal with God. But Origen’s Christian monotheism decisively rules out such a solution. God is the creator of all that is, and His goodness forbids the supposition that He has inflicted unmerited pain on any of His creatures. The inequalities of fortune and opportunity, and the sufferings which are actually endured by men, must therefore be deserved ; and as ex hypothest these evils are congenital, and cannot have been deserved in this life, it follows that they must have been incurred by some transgression committed in a previous life. This is the logical basis of the theory of a pre-natal or extra-temporal ‘ Fall’ of individual souls, which represents the first conscious attempt of Christian theology to remove the origin of evil out of the phenomenal into the intelligible or supersensible sphere, and which may therefore be described as the earliest form of the ‘transcendental,’ as distinct from the ‘ historical,’ Fall- doctrine. Origen’s exposition of this audacious speculation starts from the assertion that in the beginning God, of His pure goodness, created a fixed number of intellectual essences (voepat ovata) or rational beings, as many as He could keep. under the control of His Providence. (The God of Origen is not unlimited; for if He were, He would be incomprehensible even to Himself.') All these immaterial and bodiless essences were created equal in goodness and like in status; for the Creator, being himself exempt from variety or changeableness, could have had no motive for producing a variety of creatures? ; and, in virtue of their identity of nature and operation, they constituted a Henad (évas) or Unity, a collegiate organism intimately inspired and illuminated by the Divine Logos.’ But, being created, they were necessarily capable of change ; and, being rational, they were gifted with freedom and the faculty of choice. This momentous endowment was used 1 de prince. ii. 9, 1 (Koetschau, p. 164, where a fragment of the Greek original, from which these statements are taken, is restored from Justinian, ad Mennam). 2 4i..9, 6. 3 ii. 8, 3 (Koetschau, p. 159). The affinities of this idea to the Gnostic conceptions of the Pleroma, the Ogdoad, Dodecad, etc., will be obvious. iA E-DOCERINRINS THE CHURCH” 2r3 by different groups of them in different ways. Some persevered in virtue and retained the status in which they were created ; others gave way to ‘ idleness, and weariness of the labour of preserving goodness’ (‘ desidia et laboris taedium in servando bono ’!) or to ‘satiety of the divine love and contemplation’ (kdpos rijs Jelas dydmys Kal Pewpias) ,? and fell from the supersensible world to various depths, so becoming enmeshed in matter to a greater or lesser extent and enclosed in corporeal envelopes’ of varying degrees of fineness and subtlety. The most rebellious sank to the deepest abyss, and became demons, clothed upon with ‘cold and dusky’ bodies; the less corrupted, whose love of God was cooled but not extinct, fell only as far as the earth-plane and became (human) ‘ souls’ (%vyai, fancifully derived from yvypds, cold’); those whose error was slightest descended only a little way from the Henad and became angels, Cherubim, principalities and powers in their various ranks, and the spirits animating the sun, moon, and stars. On earth, the fallen ‘souls,’ who are ourselves, immured in human bodies, are meant to dree their penance step by step — and to win restoration through chastisement and discipline. To such a pre-natal transgression, committed in the transcendental sphere, the Psalmist makes mystical allusion in the verse ‘ Before I was humbled, I went wrong: but now have I kept thy word’ *—meaning by the phrase ‘ before I was humbled ’ ‘ in my pre-natal life, before I was banished from the heavenly place, and confined in this humbling prison-house of flesh.’ 5 1 ii. 9, 2 (Koetschau, 165). 2 ii. 8, 3 (Koetschau, p. 159). 8 ii. 8 (Koetschau, p. 158). The derivation of guyy from véis, cooling, is also found in Philo, de somn. i. 6. apis, CS Vill, (CXIX.) 67, L2CX: 5 de princ. ii. 8 (Koetschau, p. 158). To yap eimety tov mpodyrny, mpiv ] TamewwOhvai pe, eyo éemAnupeAnoa, €& adrtis dyno THs Wuyis 6 Adyos, ws dvw ev ovpav@ éemAnupédAnoe, mplv 7 €v 7TH odpate TeTaTewHobau. The counter- argument from Scripture, based on St. Paul’s words about Jacob and Esau (‘the children being not yet born, neither having done anything good or bad,’ Rom. ix. 11), is parried by the arbitrary glossing of the phrase ‘cum ... neque aliquid egissent boni neque mali’ with the words, ‘ in hac scilicet vita’ (ii. 9, 7). 214 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN This, of course, is the exact theory of the origin of evil— at least of physical evil—which was hinted at by Philo,t and is apparently condemned by the Christ of the Fourth Gospel.2, Whilst in a general sense its source may be said to lie in Origen’s Platonism, it is impossible to fix with precision the particular writings which may have moulded his presentation of it. Perhaps the idea first came to him from Philo, and was impressed upon his mind by the great myth contained in Plato’s Phaedrus® In this, the pre- existent soul is portrayed as a winged charioteer, guiding a pair of unequally yoked steeds, the white steed of Reason, and his dark unruly mate of Desire. Ever and anon one.of these charioteers, as he follows in the train of Zeus, soaring upward to the heaven beyond the heavens, fails to curb the rebellious curvettings and prancings of the dark steed ; and is flung, like Phaethon, from the roof of the firmament down to this gross world of matter, shedding his wings as he falls, and becoming incarnate in the person of an individual man. Or we may find the immediate fount of Origen’s Fall-theory in the Myth of Er,* embodied in the Tenth Book of the Republic, in which the souls who are about to be born into this world freely choose their future lots, drawn from the lap of Lachesis. This splendid fantasy clearly displays the fundamental motif of Origen’s thought on this subject—namely, the determination to save God from the reproach of causing evil which les behind all Fall- theories and all other theodicies—in the heavenly prophet’s mystic cry, aitia éAopevov’ Beds avairios (‘ He who hath chosen shall answer for it: God is not answerable’). Ifthe question of the more remote affinities of Origen’s theory be raised, we may point out that the idea of the fall of the soul froma super-celestial state, acquiring various elements of im- purity from the planetary spheres through which it passes 4 See Lecture IT, p. 34, 2 John ix. 2, 3; see Lecture III, p. 98. As the relevant portion of Origen’s Commentary on St. John’s Gospel is no longer extant, we cannot tell how he evaded the difficulty which this passage must have raised for his theory. 3 Phaedrus, 246 A-257 A. 4 Republic, 613 E-621 D. On both of these myths see J. A. Stewart, The Myths of Plato. THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 15 on its downward way to be born in this world, was in the third century widely diffused, both within and without Gnosticism+: and Origen, like many other theologians since, may well have been unconsciously influenced by the very beliefs which he set out to refute. Living, too, in Alexandria, the great emporium and meeting-place of East and West, he may have been subtly affected by the Hindu belief in re-incarnation and karma, though he steadfastly refuses to admit more lives than three—pre-natal, present, and future.? But, whatever the exact sources from which this theory arose, one thing is clear. Origen has grasped, as no other before him and very few since, the all-important principle laid down in Lectures I and II, that the Fall-doctrine really rests upon an inference from the phenomena of evil con- sidered in the light of ethical monotheism, and not upon the Paradise-narrative of Gen. ili. He has realised that faith in the God of Christianity and ratiocination from observed facts form the only foundation on which a satisfactory theory of the origin of evil can be built, and that the story of Adam and Eve is not and cannot be more than a pictorial facade. Hence the exposition contained in the de principits makes no attempt to base itself upon the Adam-story ; which, in another connexion,? is emphatically declared to 1 See W. Bousset, Hauptprobleme der Gnosis, pp. 361-369, Exkurs IV, “ Der anthropologische Dualismus’ ; he gives copious references to ancient authorities, including Servius on Verg. Aen. vi. 714, Xi. 51, Varro, Macrobius, Porphyry, Proclus, the Corpus Hermeticum, and Pistis Sophia. Cf. also Lobeck, A glaophamus, i. p. 932 f. 2 Passages from Origen’s works expressly repudiating metempsychosis have been collected by Bigg, op. cit., p. 241, n. 1; see also P. D. Huet, Origeniana, ii. q. 6, §§ 18, 19. 8 de princ. iv. 3, 1 (Koetschau, p. 323): tis yodv vody éxwv oljcerat mpwrnv Kat Sevtépav Kal tpitnv Huéepav éamépay te Kal mpwtay ywpis Alov yeyovevat Kal aeAnvns Kal dotépwv ; tiv dé olovel mpdrnv Kal ywpls ovpavod ; tis 8° ottws HALos ws oinOAvat tpdrov avOpdrov yewpyod Tov Dedv mepuTevKEevat mapadevoov ev "Hdeu Kata avarodds, kat Evdov Cwfs ev adr@ memomKeévar 6patov Kal alcbnrdv, Ware b1a TOV GwyaTiKdy oddvTwy yevoduevov Tod KapTod To Civ avadapBavew* Kal mdadw Kadrod Kal movnpod peréxe Twa mapa TO peuachjoba 76 amd Tobde Tod EvAov Aap Bavdpevov ; eav Sé Kal eds TO devAvov €v 7@ wapadelow mepitaretv A€ynrar Kat 6 ’Adapy bao TO EvAov KpdrTecIu, ovK olwar Suotagew Twa rept Tod adTa TpomiKds Sia SoKovons toropias, Kal ov cwpLaTiKOs yeyevvnyéervns, pnv¥ew Tia pvoTHpia. ‘ What man of sense will suppose that there was a “‘ first,’ ‘‘ second,’’ and ‘‘ third day,’’ both 216 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN be a ‘seeming history,’ revealing ‘certain mysteries,’ of which the nature is not explicitly defined. If by these ‘mysteries’ he means, as would seem probable, his theory of the origin of evil, this declaration is an extreme instance of the power of that exegetical alchemy known as ‘allegorism’ to make anything mean anything; for this interpretation of the story generalises ‘Adam’ out of all recognition, and dissolves even the extra-mundane, but still concrete, Paradise of Irenaeus into a rarefied meta- physical abstraction. It must be observed, further, that he tacitly abandons (during this period), not merely the literal acceptation of the Adam-narrative, but what is the core of the Adamic theory, namely, the conception of a single collective Fall of humanity involved in or caused by its first parents’ fault. For this he substitutes a multiplicity of individual falls ; the souls which were to become men “ fell ’ independently and one by one. It follows from this that the unity of mankind, gua mankind, though real enough, is a consequence, and not an antecedent condition, of the ‘ Fall,’ or the ‘ falls’; it is the unity of those who have suffered the same misfortune before birth, and now find themselves clothed in the same “muddy vesture of decay.’1 Nevertheless, there is one exception to the rule that birth into this world is a proof of pre-natal transgression—the human soul of Jesus, which like all other human souls pre-existed in the transcendental sphere, preserved its purity intact, and descended voluntarily in order to form part of the human nature which the Logos evening and morning, without sun, moon, and stars? and the alleged “first day’’ without even a heaven? And who is so silly as to sup- pose that God literally ‘‘ planted a garden,”’ like a human farmer, in Eden towards the sun-rising, and that He made in it a visible and perceptible Tree of Life, so that one tasting of its fruit by means of his bodily teeth would receive (eternal) life? or again, that a man could receive (the knowledge) of ‘‘ good and evil”’ from having chewed the fruit of the Tree so called ? And if God is said to walk in the garden in the evening, and Adam to hide under the tree, no one, I imagine, will doubt that such words are meant to reveal certain mysteries metaphorically, through a seeming history, not one which happened in concrete fact.’ 1 The only original and essential unity in which, according to Origen, all men participate is the unity of all intellectual natures, the ‘ Henad’ alluded to above (p. 212). THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH a17 assumed at His incarnation! ; and the souls of a few of the greatest saints may also be assumed to have left the super- sensible world, not as the result of sin, but obeying a specific Divine command to co-operate in the regeneration of mankind.? Such is Origen’s earliest reconstruction of the idea of the Fall. The question still remains to be answered, What, in his view, were the results of the pre-natal transgression, other than the banishment of the peccant soul to this world ? It will be seen at once that the substitution of a series of individual and transcendental ‘ falls’ for a single ‘ Fall’ in time of a common ancestor entirely does away with any idea of an inherited bias towards evil (‘ Original Sin ’) or of an inherited status of guilt (‘ Original Guilt’). Given this hypothesis, it is impossible to speak of any sort of sinfulness as inherited : whatever moral infirmity or consciousness of guilt may inhere in the individual has been acquired by him, as the result of his own act, pre-natal or post-natal. As we have seen, the unity of the human race as such is, for Origen’s individualistic and atomistic anthropology, acci- dental, not essential? ; it is the result of sin, not the basis of sinfulness. It is impossible, therefore, to regard him as having held the doctrines of ‘ Original’ or racial sin or guilt, during the Alexandrine period of his career. It might have been supposed that—given the stability which the theory of Adam’s Fall as in some sense the cause of subsequent transgressions had by this time, in virtue of the Pauline teaching, attained within the Church—Origen would at least have felt obliged to provide a substitute for the idea of ‘ Original Sin’ in the shape of a conception of a pre-natally acquired bias towards sin. But no very clear expression of any such conception can be found in the 1 de princ. il. 6, 3 (Koetschau, p. 142: see the references and parallels given in the foot-notes) ; iv. 4, 4 (Koetschau, p. 353). 2 Such were Isaiah, Jeremiah, Ezekiel, John the Baptist (7 Joann. ii. 30 [Preuschen, p. 86f.]; this part of the Commentary was written before A.D. 231, according to Eus. H.E. vi. 24). We may perhaps compare the Lamaist idea of the successive incarnations of a series of Buddhas, for the purpose of teaching mankind the way of virtue. For a similar idea in Philo, see Lecture II, p. 84, n. 2. 3 See note on p. 216, above. 218 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN de principiis.1 (The idea, that the soul begins its life here in a ‘ cooler’ condition, relatively as to its love of God, than that which it enjoyed in the super-sensible sphere, is hardly definite or positive enough to be construed in this sense.) The traditional Hellenic and Stoic? belief in the absolute autonomy of the will, so-‘strongly characteristic of the primitive Greek-Christian writers—a belief which is all but irreconcileable with the hypothesis of an @ priom inclina- tion to wickedness—has really overpowered in his mind the authority of St. Paul, though he is, of course, quite unaware of the fact. So unqualified and inalienable is the power of self-determination in all conscious beings—angels, men, and flends—that the fiends may, if they choose, exalt themselves in the long run to human or angelic status, the angels may correspondingly degrade themselves, and men may either rise to the highest or sink to the lowest point in the scale of created being. Origen quotes, indeed, the Apostle’s words —— The flesh lusteth against the spirit,’ * but explains them away aS meaning merely that the bodily appetites do in point of fact furnish the occasion for and form the raw material of sinful impulse—that they are what a later age called the fomes peccatt, the ‘tinder of sin ’—though in themselves they are morally neutral.° If they are allowed to become hypertrophied, the devil may use them as a fulcrum for pushing us into sin, though even the devil's assaults do not impair the freedom of our choice.® The 1 Rufinus does indeed employ the term ‘ malitia’ to describe the state in which the fallen spirits find themselves (il. 9, 1) ; but his method of translation is so free and arbitrary that it would be unsafe to build too much upon this word alone. In any case, for Origen, as for subsequent Greek Fathers, evil is a negative concept, the mere privation of good (‘ certum namque est malum esse bono carere,’ zbid.). 2 For the pre-eminence of the Stoa as the champion of free-will, see Windelband, Geschichte der Philosophie (1892), p. 151, 3. 8 de princ. 1. 6, 2, 3 (together with this passage should be studied Koetschau’s footnotes, in which are collected summaries of Origen’s specula- tions on this point from the works of Jerome); iii. 1, 21. But this belief in an eternal indeterminateness of volition, with its corollary of an eternal possibility of sin, seems inconsistent with the idea of a necessary restitution of all spirits, which appears in iii. 6, 5, 6; a fact which illus- trates the fluid and provisional character of Origen’s thought on questions belonging to the ‘ fringe’ rather than to the central core of the Faith. a aa ha ® de princ. iil. 2, 2. begs ails p age THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH ar9 question why our bodily appetites ever should become hypertrophied is not discussed. It is difficult not to feel that in the de princrpiis the whole treatment of the problem of the ‘ moral struggle’ is superficial, and reflects, not the “twice-born’ fervour of Origen’s Coptic heart, but the ‘once-born’ serenity of his Hellenic brain.t Indeed, the structure of his earliest Fall-theory is, if we may so say, of a different composition and consistency from those versions of the traditional Judaeo-Christian doctrine which we have studied hitherto. They are the spontaneous precipitates, the “rationalisations,’ if you will, of crises of poignant feeling ; but this is an intellectual artefact, a cold philosophical hypothesis, divorced from penitential emotion, and designed rather to solve a cosmological than a religious or ethical difficulty. It is fair to add, in concluding our survey of Origen’s first theories in regard to the origin of evil and the pre- existence of souls, that he is at pains to emphasise the tentative and provisional nature of his speculations, and to disclaim any intention of putting them forward as dog- matically certain or as essential parts of the Faith. ‘ haec prout potuimus de rationabili anima discutienda magis a legentibus quam statuta ac definita protulimus.’ 2 (ii) THE CAESAREAN PERIOD—INFANT BAPTISM We now turn to the writings which date from the period of Origen’s residence at Caesarea in Palestine (A.D. 231— 2254). In them we shall find—juxtaposed, but by no means synthesised, with the highly ‘ once-born’ version of the Fall-theory sketched in our last section—another, more sombre and pessimistic, view, the unmistakeable product of the ‘twice-born’ elements in his strangely composite personality. According to a very probable hypothesis, first suggested by Bigg? and endorsed by Harnack,* the 1 Cf. Huet, Origentana, ii. q. 7, §§ I-11. 2 11.8, 5 ad fin.; cf. alsoi. 8, 4 (Koetschau, p. 105, II). 3 Christian Platonists, p. 246. 4 History of Dogma (E. tr. 1910), ii. p. 365, 0. 5. 220 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN emergence in his mind of a more thorough-going F[all- doctrine, adhering more closely to the Adam-story as inter- preted by St. Paul, and assuming a graver judgment on the weakness of human nature, was due to the fact that at Caesarea he became acquainted for the first time with a custom which is taken for granted by the Churchman of to-day, but which in the third century was not universally practised, or even universally known, amongst Christians— the custom of Infant Baptism. Exactly when and how this practice originated it is impossible to say with certainty. There is no recorded saying of Christ which can be quoted as referring to the age of the recipients of baptism; the Acts of the Apostles contain no clear evidence for the administration of the rite to persons other than those of adult age! ; the Epistles assume that the mystery of Christian initiation is normally imparted as the crown and consummation of a process of conscious faith in Jesus as Messiah, of repentance from sin, and of conversion from idols to serve the living God— in other words, that the neophyte is a person of full age and responsibility. On the other hand, none of the sacred writings contain any prohibition of the practice. It must be admitted that the New Testament neither approves nor condemns, but ignores, Infant Baptism 2; and that, if 1 It has been suggested that the “ households’ which are mentioned in the New Testament as having been baptised (as those of Lydia, Acts xvi. 15, the jailer at Philippi, 2bzd. 33, and Stephanas, 1 Cor..i. 16) may have included children ; but it is obviously impossible to be certain of this. 2 It is possible to surmise that St. Paul, even if he knew and approved of a custom of baptising the infant children of pagan or Jewish converts to Christianity, would at one period of his life have considered it unnecessary to baptise infants born to parents who were already Christian, or of whom one was a Christian ; see 1 Cor. vil. 14: ‘ For the unbelieving husband is sanctified in the wife, and the unbelieving wife is sanctified in the brother’ (v.e. her Christian husband): ‘ else were your children unclean, but now they are holy (dya).’ This passage may imply a belief that baptism so completely cancelled whatever disastrous entail was inherited from Adam that not only was the baptised person thereby made holy, but his or her subsequent children, even by a heathen spouse, were born in a condition of holiness. Hooker’s rejection of this interpretation (Eccl. Pol. v. 60, 6) seems to be based on dogmatic rather than critical grounds. It is not an argument against the attribution of such a view to St. Paul that according to it the spread of Christianity would eventually make baptism unnecessary and obsolete ; for at the date of the composition of 1 Cor., the Apostle was convinced that ‘ the time was shortened ’ (vii. 29) and the THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 221 nothing is lawful save what can be certainly demonstrated to have been sanctioned by one of the sacred authors, the Anabaptist has won his case. We may observe paren- thetically that even those who do not accept such a narrowly literal view of the appeal to Scripture, and rely on the auctoritas of the universal Christian society as legitimating a sacramental development which goes beyond what can be shown to have been the practice of the Apostolic Church, must feel that the custom of baptising unconscious infants (in virtue of the exclusive emphasis which it seems to lay upon the ex opere operato aspect of the sacred action, and the complete absence from it of the subjective and ex ofere operantis aspect) is not unattended by theoretical difficulties, such as do not arise in connexion with the normal administration of the other sacraments.t These difficulties will, however, be dealt with in the proper place.? For the purposes of our historical enquiry, it is sufficient to remark that, even if neither our Lord nor His Apostles directly authorised the administration of baptism to those who could not, in the nature of the case, experience either faith or repentance, the custom is one which, in the absence of any explicit prohibition, might well be expected to grow up at an early date and in many places, doubtless as the Parousia at hand, so that ex hypothest comparatively few children could be born under these favoured conditions. Ifsucha view of the hereditary efficacy of baptism was actually held in the Apostolic Church, it would, from the standpoint of later orthodoxy, have tobe classed with the com- panion beliefs in the validity of vicarious ‘ baptism for the dead’ (1 Cor. XV. 29) and in the impeccability of the baptised (see Lecture III, p. 135) as one of those mistaken but transient inferences from true principles which the student must expect to find in the initial stages of Christian theology. The probability that Christian baptism was, in some quarters, regarded in this way is increased by the fact that a similar view was taken, with regard to the baptism of proselytes, in the Jewish Church; cf. Yebamoth, 78a: ‘If a Gentile woman becomes a proselyte when she is with child, her son has no need for baptism ; for the baptism of his mother counts for him in the place of his own baptism.’ 1 Except in the case of absolution given to a dying person who is unconscious (Schieler-Heuser, Theory and Practice of the Confessional, 1906, pp. 646 ff.). It may be added that the same prima facie difficulties which attach to the custom of Infant Baptism attach also to the customs of Infant Confirmation and Communion, still retained by the Eastern Church. 2 See below, Additional Note G ‘ Infant Baptism,’ p. 550. 222 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN result of popular sentiment rather than of reasoned logic. It may well have been suggested to Jewish-Christian parents by the practice, vouched for by the Talmud as familiar to first-century Judaism,! of baptising the infant children of proselytes, and to Gentiles by the custom which permitted young children to be initiated into some at least of the pagan Mysteries.? It is in any case probable that the beginnings of Paedo- baptism run back into the Apostolic age, despite the fact that it is not mentioned in the New Testament ; Polycarp’s reply to the proconsul ‘ Eighty and six years have I been the slave of Christ ’® must imply that he had been baptised as an infant c. A.D. 69. Infant baptism is mentioned, possibly by Justin Martyr, and certainly by Irenaeus,‘ in the latter half of the second century, and it is strongly opposed by Tertullian ° at the beginning of the third : from the middle of the third the evidence for the recognition of its permis- sibility is continuous, and by the end of the fifth it has become universal and normal, as it is to-day in Christian countries. A careful study of the historical data, which we have only been able to summarise briefly here, will make it reasonably clear that in the practice of Infant Baptism we have a popular development of the earliest use of the sacra- ment, a development not at first deduced from theological principle or imposed from above by Church authority, but arising spontaneously from below, out of the subconscious 1 See the passages quoted to illustrate Matt. iii. 6 by J. Lightfoot, Hovae Hebraicae (1675), p. 219 f. 2 G. Anrich, Das antike Mysterienwesen, p. 55, gives instances, based mainly upon epigraphic evidence, of children of seven and ten years of age who had undergone initiation into several Mystery-cults: one such child is described as punfets Ere vijmios. 3 mariyrium Polycarpt, 9. 4 adv. haey. II. xxxiii. 2: ‘omnes enim venit per semetipsum salvare ; omnes inquam, qui per eum renascuntur in Deum, infantes, et pavvulos, et pueros, et iuvenes, et seniores.’ The passage from Justin, however, which is often quoted as a proof of the existence of the custom of baptising infants c. A.D. 150 (aoAAoi rwes Kal modAal éEnxovtobrar Kal éBdounKovTobrar, ot ex maidwy eualynrevOnoav 7H XprotH, adOopor Siayevovar, 1 Apol. xv. 6) is inconclusive: for é€uabnrevOnoav does not necessarily imply more than admission to the catechumenate, and é€x zaidwy does not mean ‘ from infancy.’ 5 de baptismo, 18; see below, p. 241. THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 223 instincts of the Christian society, eventually forcing its way into official recognition, and generating, at least in Western Christendom, a not inconsiderable body of doctrinal ideas in order to effect its own ex post facto justification. The point last mentioned is of crucial importance for the understanding of that part of the history of the Fall-doctrine upon which we are now entering. In treatises of systematic theology, the necessity of infant baptism is usually stated as an inference from the doctrine of Original Sin, and in the order of thought this may be so; but in order of time the practice was prior to, and largely stimulated the growth of, the doctrine, and not vice versa. Itis not the case that men said ‘ Infants are infected from the womb with a hereditary taint ; they must therefore be baptised as soon after birth as possible’ ; what they did say (after the custom, origi- nating, it would seem, in grounds of popular sentiment, had become thoroughly established) was: ‘ The Church actually does baptise infants as soon as possible after birth, and we cannot suppose that the Church does anything without good reason ; therefore, infants must be infected from the womb with a hereditary taint.’ Legem credendi statut lex orandt : there is no clearer instance of the control exercised by liturgical or devotional practice over the growth of dogma than that provided by the study of the relations between the custom of Infant Baptism and the doctrine of Original Sin. Thus it was, apparently, that Origen argued. If he had previously been unacquainted with the custom, the discovery that newly born, unconscious infants could be, and were, with the sanction of ‘ Apostolic tradition,’ + subjected to the same tremendous purificatory ceremonies as adults who had been stained with the darkest vices of the Graeco-Roman world, must have made a profound impression on his mind. Given the rightfulness of the practice (and this it never occurred to him to dispute) it was clear to him that some sort of positive sinfulness or defilement must be supposed to inhere in human nature as such, from the very moment of birth ; and it would seem that the idea of guilt pre-natally acquired by the soul—the only kind of pollution deducible 1 comm.in Rom. V.9 (Lomm. vi. 397) : ‘ pro hocet ecclesia ab apostolis traditionem suscepit, etiam parvulis baptismum dare.’ 224 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN from his theory of individual pre-natal ‘ falls "—through an act of which the exact nature, and even the bare commission, had ex hypothest been forgotten, now appeared to him far too shadowy and unsubstantial a ground for the introduction of personally sinless babes to the awful mysteries of Christian initiation. His restless mind, therefore, was fain to search in other directions for the required theoretical justification of paedo-baptism. He seems for a long time to have experimented with the idea of the quasi-material impurity, or ‘ bad mana,’ assumed by the Levitical law to infect the physiological processes of conception and child-birth and to need ‘ expiation ’ through the oblation of a pair of turtle-doves or of pigeons, one for a burnt-offering and one for asin offering. So, shortly after A.D. 231, he writes, in somewhat hesitating terms : Let us now investigate the question, why a woman who lends help to those being born into this world (z.e. a mother) is said to become unclean, not merely when she has received seed but when she has brought forth. Whence she is commanded to offer two young pigeons or turtle-doves for a sin offering . . . as though she required purification of sin, in that she lent help to the birth of a human being into this world . . . I do not venture to lay down any definite dictum in such matters, but I feel that certain occult mysteries are contained in these commands, and that there is some hidden and secret cause, why a woman who has conceived of seed and brought forth should be called ‘ unclean,’ and should be commanded, as though she had been guilty of a sin, to offer a sacrifice for sin and so to be purified. He goes on to point out that the child itself is unclean, according to Job xiv. 4, 5 (LXX),? and Ps. li. 5 (° Behold, I was shapen in wickedness ’). Dikeve xi. 2 For a note on the Hebrew version of this text, see Lecture I, p. 17. The LXX give 4 tis yap xafapos €otat ao puov ; GAN ovdeis, 5 édv Kal pla Huepa 6 Blos adrob émt ths yis—‘ Who shall be pure from defilement ? not so much as one, even though his life on the earth be but a day’ ; which Origen takes as proving the innate corruption of infants. The Hebrew is translated by Driver and Gray (ICC., p. 127) as follows: ‘ 4. Oh thata clean thing could come out of an unclean! not one (can). 5. If his (.e. man’s) days are determined, the number of his months is known to thee, and his limit thou hast appointed that he cannot pass ; 6. look away from him, and forbear .. .’ etc. If this is original, the LX X represents a mere misunderstanding. THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 225 We may add to these considerations the question, Why should baptism be given to infants (parvults) as is the use of the Church ? seeing that af there were nothing in infants which required remission and pardon, the grace of baptism would seem superfluous. He re-inforces this hypothesis of a mysterious sinfulness inherent in birth by the quaint argument that none of the saints was ever known to keep his own birthday as a feast, whereas Jeremiah and Job cursed the days of their entrance into this world.2. Here the pollution of birth is thought of quasi-juridically, as though it constituted guilt. But, a little further on in the same treatise the emphasis seems to shift, and the birth-stain seems to be treated as a predomi- nantly physical quality, from which the pre-existent human soul of Jesus alone was granted exemption at its incarnation, according to the text Wisdom viil. 20—‘ being good, I came into a body undefiled.’ Some years later, the stain derived from the processes of conception and birth has become in Origen’s mind purely physical; and, with considerable daring, as he himself admits (‘ temerarie forsitan videor dicere ’), he asserts that Jesus Himself was subject to it, and stood in need of purification with His Mother. In the Commentary on Romans, however, (after A.D. 244°) he returns to the more refined, if less intelligible, idea of the birth-stain as involving or amounting to sin, and appeals 1 in Lev. hom. viii. 3 (Lomm. ix. 318). 2 ibid. He also points out in this passage that the only persons mentioned in Scripture as having kept their own birthdays are the tyrants Pharaoh and Herod Antipas, both of whom polluted their celebrations with bloodshed, the former by hanging the chief baker, and the latter by beheading John the Baptist. 3 in Lev. hom. xii. 4 (Lomm. ix. 389 f.). 4 in Luc. hom. xiv. (Lomm. v. 134). This passage distinguishes carefully between sovdes and peccatum, the former of which is said to be transmitted by birth, the latter not. The paragraph significantly con- cludes (Lomm. v. 135): ‘ parvuli baptizantur in remissionem peccatorum. quorum peccatorum ? vel quo tempore peccaverunt ? aut quomodo potest ulla lavacri in parvulis ratio subsistere, nisi iuxta illum sensum, de quo paulo ante diximus ‘“‘ nullus mundus a sorde, nec si unius diei quidem fuerit vita eius super terram’’? et quia per baptismi sacramentum nativi- tatis sordes deponuntur, propterea baptizantur et parvuli, ‘“‘ nisi enim quis renatus fuerit ex aqua et spiritu, non poterit intrare in regnum coelorum.’’’ 5 Westcott, op. cit. 226 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN once more to the ‘ Apostolic ’ a of infant baptism as bearing this out.? Doubtless this line of thought represents one more re- emergence of that primitive subconscious tendency which we have already observed at work in previous hamartio- logical speculation, namely, the tendency to assume that all sex-activity is intrinsically dangerous and wrong,” and that the ground or origin of all actual sins is somehow to be found in it. This tendency, characteristic, as we have seen, of the ‘twice-born’ man, may be assigned to the Coptic, as distinct from the Hellenic, side of Origen’s personality. Two facts are in any case clear: (1) that the idea of the birth-stain never assumes complete fixity of outline: like the barbarous idea of ‘ bad mana,’ of which it is indeed merely a form, it wavers between the meanings of physical, ceremonial, and moral uncleanness; and (2) that in its more developed statements, it approximates to a doctrine both of ‘ original sin’ and of ‘ original guilt,’ such as is entirely absent from the writings of his earlier period. It is clear that this theory of a pollution of some kind necessarily inherent in and transmitted by the processes of generation and birth, if held apart from any view as to the origin of such pollution, lands us in pure and simple dualism, and involves the tacit surrender of the fundamental Christian conception of God to Gnosticism. Origen was therefore compelled to search for the ultimate fount of the sinfulness of sexuality or of generation—a broad universal fact (as he thought) which could hardly have been produced by a number of pre-natal or transcendental acts of individual souls—in some catastrophic happening upon the plane of matter; in other words, he was forced back upon the 1 comm.in Rom. V. (Lomm. vi. 397) : ‘ pro hoc et ecclesia ab apostolis traditionem suscepit, etiam parvulis baptismum dare; sciebant enim illi, quibus mysteriorum secreta commissa sunt divinorum, quod essent in omnibus genuinae sovdes peccati, quae per aquam et spiritum ablui deberent.’ 2 Origen’s ultra-ascetic, almost Manichean, views with regard to this matter are clearly shown both by his act of self-mutilation alluded to above (p. 209) and also by two passages, 7v Gen. hom. v. 4 ad fin. (Lomm. viii. 177), and 7m Num. hom. vi. 3 ad fin. (Lomm. x. 51), quoted by R. Seeberg, Lehrbuch der Dogmengesch. (1920), I. p. 538, n. 2. Tothese might be added de ovat. 31, 4 (Koetschau, p. 398). a ee ee ee Fag Oe Ee ee ee olga et On me i THE PALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 227 conception of a single historic ‘ Fall’ in time and in this world, and therewith upon a more or less literal interpre- tation of the Adam-story. At first, if the language of the Commentary on the Canticles is to be construed literally, he took refuge in that form of the Fall-doctrine based on Gen. iii. which may be called the theory of the :nquinamentum,} that is, the theory that Eve was seduced by the serpent and physically infected by him?; the same treatise contains a vaguer and less repulsive expression of the idea of ‘Original Sin’ in the statement that man’s free-will has been ‘ inclined to ignominy or wantonness’ by occasion of the ‘transgression’? (fvaevaricatio, which presumably represents an original wapaBaous*). The close study of the Epistle to the Romans, however, which was necessitated by the preparation of his great Commentary ® on that book, had the effect of diverting his mind into more characteristi- cally Pauline channels ; and throughout Comm. in Rom. V., which contains his exposition of the crucial passage Rom. v. 13-21, he accepts, in a general sense, the more normal Adamic theory as implied in the Apostle’s words. | It is noticeable that in his exegesis of this passage the word praevaricatio occurs frequently, and appears for all practical purposes to have assumed its technical meaning of ‘the Fall.’ The story of Gen. iil. seems to be taken quite literally (though the sex-motzf reappears in one passing allusion ®) ; and the propagation of sin from Adam to his 1 See above, Lecture II, p. 57; Lecture III, p. 122. 2 comm. in Cant. III. (Lomm. xv. 54 f.) : ‘ cervus quoque amicitiarum quis alius videbitur nisi ille qui peremit serpentem qui seduxerat Evam, et eloquii sui flatibus peccati venena in eam diffundens omnem posteritatis sobolem contagio praevaricationis infecerat ?’ Westcott (op. cit.) dates this treatise c. A.D. 240. Dr. Tennant’s description of it as ‘ one of (Origen’s) earliest works’ (Sources, p. 303, n. 2) seems to be founded ona confusion of it with an entirely different work, the much earlier Com- mentary on Canticles of which a fragment is preserved in Philocalia, vii. 1 (€x Tod eis TO dopa puKpod Topov Ov ev TH vedryte eypayer). 8 comm. in Cant. IV. (Lomm. xv. 72): ‘ . ut ostenderet inesse unicuique animae vim possibilitatis et arbitrii libertatem, qua possit agere omne quod bonum est. Sed quia hoc naturae bonum praevaricationis occasione decerptum, velad ignominiam vel lasciviam fueratinflexum. .. .’ 4 See below, p. 302. 5 Written after A.D. 244 (Westcott). 6 comm. in Rom. V. 9 (Lomm. vi. 397), where it is pointed out that Adam did not beget children until after the Fall: “nec Adam scribitur cognovisse Evam uxorem suam et genuisse Cain nisi post peccatum.’ 228 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN descendants is explained in terms of ‘ seminal identity,’ which we have already encountered in Irenaeus. Yet Origen the Biblical exegete has not altogether overpowered Origen the Platonist ; in his last-named character, he is reluctant to surrender altogether the half-mythological, half-metaphysical idea of an extra-mundane Paradise, and of the individual ‘ falls’ of pre-existent spirits. Hence, in commenting on Rom. v. 18 (‘ So then as through one trespass the judgment came upon all men to condemnation’) he writes : It is written that when Adam had sinned, the Lord God drove him out of Paradise, and set him in this earth, over against the Paradise of delights; and this was the condemnation of his sin, a condemnation which without doubt has extended unto all men. For all have been made to dwell in this place of humi- liation and in the valley of weeping ; whether because all who ave born from Adam were in his looms and were simultaneously with him cast out of Paradise, or whether, in some other ineffable way known to God only, each tndividual may be deemed to have been thrust out of Paradise and so to have received condemnation.? Here two alternative methods of conceiving a pre-natal and transcendental Fall are indicated: the first being the hypothesis of a collective pre-natal Fall of the whole race, contained in Adam, from the heavenly place; the second being the theory which has been already expounded in the de principius, that of a never-ending series of individual falls into this vale of tears, which is the world of matter. In his last work (the Tveatise against Celsus) he appears, though it is impossible to be quite sure of his meaning, to revert to his earlier theory, that of an immense number of 1 See above, p. 197. The parallel of Levi’s pre-natal existence in Abraham is used to support this theory (comm. in Rom. V. 1, Lomm. vi. 326): ‘si ergo Levi, qui generatione quarta post Abraham nascitur, in lumbis Abrahami fuisse perhibetur, multo magis omnes homines qui in hoc mundo nascuntur et nati sunt, in lumbis erant Adami, cum adhuc esset in paradiso ; et omnes homines cum ipso vel in ipso expulsi sunt de paradiso, cum ipse inde depulsus est.’ 2 comm. in Rom. V. 4 (Lomm. vi. 363 f.): . cum deliquisset Adam, scriptum est quod eiecit eum Dominus Deus de Paradiso, et con- stituit eum in terra hac contra Paradisum deliciarum: et haec fuit delicti eius condemnatio, quae in omnes homines sine dubio pervenit. omnes enim in loco hoc humiliationis et in convalle fletus effecti sunt: sive quod in lumbis Adae fuerunt omnes qui ex eo nascuntur, et cum ipso pariter eiecti sunt; sive alio quolibet inenarrabili modo et soli Deo cognito unusquisque de Paradiso trusus videtur et excepisse condemnationem.’ ‘ THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 229 individual pre-natal falls. This at any rate is a probable inference from the allegorisation of ‘Adam’ (O78 == homo, mankind in general) contained in the following passage : Concerning Adam and his sin those who have knowledge of _ these matters will philosophise to this effect, namely, that “Adam ’ in the Greek language signifies &vOpwmoc, ‘man,’ and that in what appears to be said about Adam < as an individual > Moses is really laying down scientific principles concerning human nature. For when the divine scripture tells us that ‘in Adam all die,’ and that all were condemned in ‘ the likeness of the transgression of Adam,’ it uses these expressions not so much of a single individual as of the whole race. And in the whole series of sayings which apparently apply to the individual Adam, it will be found that the curse of Adam is really common to all; and there is no woman who is not subject to the sentence pronounced on the woman < Eve >. And the ‘man’ who with the woman is cast out of Paradise, having been clothed in the ‘ coats of skins,’ which God made on account of the trans- gression (or ‘fall,’ mapé&aorg) of men for those that had sinned, conveys a certain ineffable and mystic meaning, far transcending Plato’s story of the descent of the soul which sheds her wings and drifts down to this world, ‘until she find some solid footing.’ This conception appears equally to underlie a later passage of the same work, in which the idea of the birth- stain described above, and here definitely stated to involve guilt and to need expiation, is asserted to be part of the revelation made to the prophets, and is connected, though in vague language, with the expulsion of ‘ Adam, that is to say Man’ from Paradise and his arrival in this terrestrial place of affliction.2 It would, accordingly, seem that the view in which Origen, towards the end of his life, finally came to repose represents a combination of his Alexandrian ‘ pre- natal fall’ theory with his Caesarean ‘ birth-stain’ theory. We may regard him, like Wordsworth, as concluding that the soul that rises with us, our life’s Star, Hath had elsewhere its setting, And cometh from afar ?: tc. Cels. IV. 40. (Koetschau, pp. 313 f.). The reference in the last sentence to the myth of the Phaedrus is unmistakeable. For the history of the allegorical interpretation of the ‘ coats of skins,’ see below, pp. 251, 275, 285, and J. H. Srawley, The Catechetical Oration of Gregory of Nyssa, P- 42, note on l. 14. era ces. .V1I.. 60, 3 Ode on Intimations of Immortality. 230 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN but we must add that the sense of sin which was rooted in the Egyptian side of his temperament compelled him to think of the soul, not as‘ trailing clouds of glory,’ but rather as falling to the earth like a meteor, glowing with the lurid and disastrous fires of pre-natal and extra-temporal guilt. It will have been seen that it is no more possible to educe a single thought-out scheme of Fall-doctrine from the writings of Origen than from those of his Greek-Christian predecessors, the Apologists, Irenaeus, Clement. The main interest, indeed, which his speculations bear for the purposes of our enquiry resides in the fact that in them we find, lying side by side and not yet articulated into coherent systems, the disiecta membra of both the chief versions of the Christian doctrine of man and sin, ‘ once-born’ or minimising and ‘ twice-born’ or maximising, which hence- forward were destined to compete for the allegiance of the Church. To the former, or Hellenic-Christian, version of the doctrine, belongs the tendency to allegorise the story of Gen. ili., and in particular to place ‘ Paradise’ in an extra- mundane ‘third heaven,’ which easily passes into the Platonic tdézos vontés or world of Ideas; the lenient description of ‘ Original Sin,’ if such it can be called, as a levis contagio,: a ‘ slight infection,’ which does not seriously impair the self-determining force of man’s free-will; the large recognition of ‘social heredity’ as a factor equally important with, or even more important than, physiological heredity, in the transmission of sin from generation to generation.2, To the latter or ‘ twice-born’ version, which we may describe as specifically ‘African’ (not merely because it reflects the native Egyptian elements in Origen’s 1 comm. in Rom. V. (Lomm. vi. 341): ‘ peccatum enim pertransiit etiam in iustos, et levi quadam eos contagione perstrinxit.’ 2 ibid. (Lomm. vi. 342 f.): ‘. . . ut hoc sermone omnes qui ex Adam praevaricatore nati sunt indicari videantur, et habere in semetipsis simili- tudinem praevaricationis eius non solum ex semine sed ex institutione susceptam. omnes enim qui in hoc mundo nascuntur non solum nutri- untur a parentibus sed et imbuuntur ; et non solum sunt filii peccatorum sed et discipuli. ibed. (Lomm. vi. 353): ‘ diximus quidem iam et in superioribus quod parentes non solum generant filios, sed et imbuunt ; et qui nascuntur, non solum filii parentibus, sed et discipulifiunt, et non tam natura urgentur in mortem peccati quam disciplina.’ THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 231 personality, but because those who were, as we shall presently see, its principal elaborators also dwelt on the southern shores of the Mediterranean), are to be assigned the tendency to assume the inherent sinfulness of sex, the idea that the inbred evil in human nature is in some way to be connected with physical generation, the belief that infants are born not merely with a bias towards evil but actually subject to some kind of pre-natal guilt, their own or Adam's, which needs absolution through the waters of baptism. It is true that some of the positions characteristic of the “ African ’ doctrine had already been worked out by a some- what earlier author, living nearer to the Pillars of Hercules, the fiery Tertullian; but nevertheless, if it is permissible to fix a definite point of time at which the bifurcation between the ‘ once-born’ and the ‘ twice-born’ presenta- tions of the Fall-doctrine tends to become clearly visible, that point may well be placed in the year A.D. 231, the date of Origen’s retirement from Alexandria to Caesarea, TERTULLIAN AND ‘ TRADUCIANISM ’ 1 From the Palestine of A.D. 250 the thread of our research now leads us some twelve hundred miles westwards, into the Roman province of Proconsular Africa, and some forty years backwards in respect of time, into the first decade of the third century. Hitherto we have been concerned with the earliest, predominantly ‘ once-born’ and ‘ minimising,’ development of the Fall-doctrine in the Eastern countries and the environment of Hellenic culture which together may be said to constitute the primitive matrix of Catholic Christianity ; but now our story touches for the first time the Occidental division of the Christian world, in which a sterner and gloomier presentation of the ideas of the Fall and of Original Sin has played so momentous a part. Of this great geographical and cultural unity within the Catholic 1 The brief account of Tertullian’s contribution to the growth of the Western Fall-doctrine contained in this section may be supplemented from P. Monceaux, Histoire littévaive del Afrique chrétienne, tom. i. (1901) ; G. Esser, Die Seelenlehve Tervtullians (1893); A. d’Ales, La Théologie de Lertullien (1905) ; J. Turmel, Tertullien (1905). 232 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN unity, Western Christendom, of which Roman and Anglican and Protestant still share in differing measures the spiritual and doctrinal heritage, the ultimate intellectual metropolis or parent-city is neither Rome nor Canterbury nor Geneva, but Carthage ; where Latin theology was flourishing whilst the local Roman Church was still almost purely Greek in language and thought, and where the work of hammering out the specifically Western conceptions of the Trinity, the Church, and the ‘ Doctrine of Grace’ was first begun. The earliest of the line of eminent teachers produced by North African Christianity was Quintus Septimius Florens Tertullianus, born c. A.D. 160, at Carthage, ‘the great craftsman who was the first to give its peculiar aspect and cachet to Latin theology.’1 As is well known, Tertullian was before his conversion to Christianity a lawyer and jurist, and it is possible that the Pandects of Justinian still preserve an excerpt from his legal writings.2 The influence of his juristic training upon the tone and character of his thought is luminously summed up by the writer just quoted, in the following words : Tertullian was no philosopher; speculation was always foreign to him, and he never thought of the Christian revelation as a new light which comes to enlarge our intellectual horizon or as a body of truth which invites our investigation. But he possessed the juridical sense in the highest degree. He was a lawyer who, before all things, saw in Christianity a Fact and a Law. It was the business of Christians to prove and to compre- hend the Fact—to interpret and, above all, to observe the Law. Relatively to us, God is a master and a creditor: we are His subjects and His debtors. The right method, therefore, of determining our relations with Him is to apply the principles of human legislative codes, and to carry into this application the severity which governs the calculation of our debts and of our civil rights—a method which can be employed with the exactitude which characterises the operations of commerce.? Despite the fact that only a comparatively short portion of his Christian life was spent within the communion of the 1 J. Tixeront, Histoive des Dogmes (1909) i. p. 329. 2 quaestionum libri viii, de castvensi peculio, ascribed to a jurist Tertullian, whom some identify with the African Father. See Dvgesta Iustiniant Aug., recogn. Th. Mommsen (1870), ii. p. 897. 3 Tixeront, op. cit., p. 330 (slightly abridged). THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 233 ‘Great Church’ (he was baptised some time before A.D. 196, adopted Montanist opinions c. 207, broke finally with the Church in 213, and, according to Jerome,? lived to an extreme old age), Tertullian may nevertheless be said to have constructed the mould in which the classical ‘ twice-born ’ or ‘ African’ presentation of the Fall-theory was destined to be cast. This mould, which was indeed broken and discarded when it had served its purpose,? but without which the Augustinian Fall-doctrine, still imagined by many to be the only Fall-doctrine known to traditional Christianity, could never have assumed its completed and logically rounded shape, was his ‘ traducianist ’ * psycho- logy : which may now be briefly summarised. Tertullian’s views with regard to the nature of the soul are expounded at length in the treatise de anima, which internal evidence shows to have been composed after his definite adoption of the Montanist position, but which none the less exercised a considerable influence within the “Great Church.’ He asserts that his psychology is based upon Holy Writ,® though claiming at the same time, in a curiously modern spirit, to have given attention to medical science in this connexion ®; and he expresses a vigorous contempt for the psychologies of philosophers, especially for the Platonic theories of metempsychosis and reminis- cence.? Nevertheless, it is clear that he was indebted both for his psychology and for his physiology to the Stoics, from 1 P. Monceaux, op. cit., p. 201 f. 2 de viris illustr. 53 (‘ fertur vixisse usque ad decrepitam aetatem ’). 3 c.f. below, Lecture VI, p. 413, n, I. 4 It is convenient to use this term as a description of Tertullian’s views regarding the origin of the soul; though, strictly speaking, it is anachron- istic, inasmuch as, according to Du Cange (Glossavium mediae et infimae latinitatis, ed. Henschel, 1887, s.v. tvadux), the term traduciani belongs rather to the controversies of the fifth century, being applied as a term of reproach by the Pelagians to the Augusiinians; the earliest instance of the term which he quotes is in Marius Mercator, lib. subnot. ix. 7, 14. 5 dean. 3. In giving quotations from this work I have used the text of A. Reifferschied and G. Wissowa, published in the Vienna Corpus Script. Eccles. Lat., vol. xx. 6 ibid. 2: ‘ sed et medicinam inspexi . . . sibi quoque hoc negotium vindicantem, quippe ad quam magis animae ratio pertinere videatur per corporis curam.’ He frequently cites the opinions of famous physicians, especially Soranus (6, 8, 15, 25, 44) and Hippocrates (15, 25). 7 «bid. 4, 23-24, 31-33. 234 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN whom he has borrowed his cardinal principle, that of the corporeality of the soul. It is permissible to suggest that, in Tertullian’s case, the legal mind, accustomed to deal with ‘ real property ’ and other tangible objects, discovered a special affinity with a philosophy which renders abstract ideas easier to handle by hardening them into ‘ bodies’ or quasi-material substances. Just as the Stoics had affirmed the Logos spermatikos, or ‘seminal reason,’ per- meating organic nature, to be, or to be immanent in, a material or quasi-material thing, a ‘creative flame’? or ‘fiery breath,’ ? that is, an exceedingly fine, rarefied, and imponderable gas, so Tertullian applies this conception to that which for him appears to take the place of the Logos spermatikos, namely, the ‘breath’ (flatus) of God, and develops it with narrow logic to a fantastic conclusion. In the beginning, we are told, God moulded man’s body out of clay, and breathed the breath of life itself, materialis- tically conceived, into his nostrils. The miraculous vapour poured into every nook and cranny of Adam’s body, filling it completely, and then congealing, as it were, into an ethereal substance occupying the same space as the fleshly body and fitting its lineaments and shape exactly, so as to bear its precise impress. This substance is the soul, an astral body somehow included within the skin of, and possessing the same volume as, the body of flesh and blood: it possesses a complete set of astral or ghostly limbs, whereby it really performs in the dream-world, during sleep, deeds lawful and unlawful, for which it will be held to strict account by God.* Hence it is that in Hades Dives, though disembodied, has 1 sip TexviKdv. 2 mvedua mupoedes: for the use of these terms by the Stoics, see the references given in A. Aall, Geschichte der Logosidee in der griech. Philosophie (1896), p. 118, n. 4. 3 dean. 9g: ‘ recogita enim, cum deus flasset in faciem hominis flatum vitae, et factus esset homo in animam vivam, totum utique per faciem statim flatum illum in interiora transmissum et per universa corporis spatia diffusum, simulque divina a spiratione densatum omni intus linea expressum esse, quam densatus impleverat, et velut in forma gelasse.’ 4 ibid. 45. The opinion that the soul is morally responsible for dream- actions is rejected by St. Augustine, de Gen. ad litt. xii. 15, and St. Thomas Aq., Summa theol. i. q. xciv. a. 4, ii. iiae. q. cliv. a. 5. ee ee eee ee ee a ee ee eer eens — s- THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 235 still a tongue, Lazarus a finger, and Abraham a bosom! ; and it is by their ghostly features—the exact counterparts of those that they wore in life—that the souls of the martyrs are recognised beneath the heavenly altar by the Seer of Patmos.2. Thesoul even has a colour; a Montanist sister saw, during one of Tertullian’s sermons, a vision of a soul, which was ‘ tenera et lucida et aerii coloris ’—‘ tender and shining and of the colour of air’ % (apparently resembling a great soap-bubble in human form)—a description which reminds us of the wraiths and ‘ materialisations ’ of modern spiritism. Nevertheless, though soul and body are two substances distinct in thought, in fact they interpenetrate and suffuse each other so subtly and intimately that man is a single unity,* resoluble into its constituent elements only by death. It is on the basis of this materialistic theory of the soul that Tertullian builds his explanation of the rationale of procreation. This, according to him, is essentially a process of fission, as well in regard to the psychological as to the physiological domain ; the paternal germ is not merely a portion of the progenitor’s body, but is (or is charged with) a definite quantity of his soul-stuff, which through the act of generation is diminished by so much.® When conception takes place, this detached fragment of the father’s soul shapes itself into a new soul, bearing all the hereditary characters inherent in the parental stock. It seems that the functions of the mother are regarded as being purely passive and receptive ; and, though Tertullian himself does not develop this consequence, the supposed biological law (now finally exploded by the discoveries of Mendel), that heredity only operates through the father,® will later be used by incautious apologists to show that a miraculous 1 de an. 7,9. ‘The same curious idea appears in Irenaeus, adv. haer. li. 55; see Grabe’s note, quoted by Harvey. 2 ibid. 8, 9. 8 ibid. 9. 4 ibid. 9: ‘ a primordio enim in Adam concreta et configurata corpori anima, ut totius substantiae, ita et condicionis istius semen effecit’; cf. also 36. 5 ibid. 27. 6 This ancient belief has been given a poetical expression by Aeschylus in Eumen. 658-661, where Apollo explains to the Areopagus that the con- nexion of son and father is very much more intimate and organic than that 236 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN conception was necessary in the case of Christ, in order to ensure the sinlessness of His human nature. Every human being is, therefore, a ‘ chip of the old block’ in an almost literal sense, with many, if not all, of his mental and moral qualities hereditarily pre-determined,! though a place is still left for free-will, which is here as elsewhere strongly asserted.? The first instance of this alleged reproduction by way of fission is to be found in the creation of Eve, who was made not merely out of a rib of Adam but also out of a portion of his soul-stuff.2 Though devoid of sexual accompaniments and carried out in a purely supernatural manner, this event was the type of all subsequent acts of generation, which represent so many subdivisions of the initial quantum of soul-stuff or condensed divine breath originally concentrated in Adam alone. Each individual soul now existing is, metaphorically speaking, a surculus or twig, cut from the matrix or parent-stem of Adam, and then planted out to of son and mother, in order to support his contention that Orestes was justified in slaying his mother in order to avenge his father : OUK €oTL LATHP KEKAnUEevoU TEéKVOU toxets, tpopos 5é€ KUpatos veoomdpov’ tixte. 8 6 OpdoKxwv, 7 8 amep Edvw Lévy €owoev Epvos, olor py BAdyn Oeds. It is found in the ‘ Hippocratic’ treatise wept yovijs, which Dr. Singer dates c. 380 B.c. (E. Littré, Hippocrates, tom. vii.), in Aristotle, de gen. animal. i.21 (729a 21), though here it appears as the theory that the male parent contributes the form or active principle and the female the matter, and in Galen (d. A.D. 199) de facult. natural. i. 4, de sanit. tuend. i. 2 ; Tertullian may have been influenced by the last-named. It was, however, rejected by the Epicureans; cf. Lucretius, de verum nat. iv. 1229-31 semper enim partus duplici de semine constat, atque utri similest magis id quodcumque creatur eius habet plus parte aequa. 1 dean 20: ‘et hic itaque concludimus omnia naturalia animae ut substantiva eius ipsi inesse et cum ipsa procedere atque proficere, ex quo ipsa censetur. Sicut et Seneca saepe noster: ‘‘ insita sunt nobis omnium artium et aetatum semina, magisterque ex occulto deus producit ingenia,”’ ex seminibus scilicet insitis et occultis per infantiam, quae sunt et intellectus. ex his enim producuntur ingenia.’ 2 ibid. 21, 22; cf. adv. Mayrcion. ii. 5, 6. 3 ibid. 36: ‘ ceterum et ipsam (sc. Evam) dei afflatus animasset, si non ut carnis, ita et animae ex Adam tradux fuisset in femina.’ Here ‘tradux’ must mean a‘ slip’ or ‘ off-shoot’ ; see below, p. 240, n. 2, fora note on this word. THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH . 237 grow by itself into a separate tree.t Tertullian’s biology here seems to approximate to the theory associated with the name of Weissmann, which exhibits the whole life-process of a species as a progressive sub-division of an original immortal germ-plasm, and heredity as the unfolding of characteristics which have not been acquired, but were always implicit in the primitive plasm. It is clear that this whole line of thought leads directly into the theory of “seminal identity,’ already hinted at by Irenaeus and Origen, according to which Adam was the sum of his own posterity,? and conversely, the human race as it now exists is an atomised or comminuted Adam: a position from which the step to an interpretation of the conventional Fall- tradition (as it may by this time be called) in terms of ‘ Original Guilt ’ would appear easy and tempting, at any rate to a thinker of ‘twice-born’ temperament. If all human souls are detached portions of the original soul (of Adam) which fell, they must bear with them, not merely the psychological effects of, but the moral responsibility for, the primordial Fall; they sinned ‘in Adam,’ and his trans- gression is their transgression, for they were he. So at least reason theologians, whose hypertrophied emotions have hurried them into a fanatically pessimistic estimate of human nature and human instincts. ‘ Traducianism, ‘seminal identity ’ and ‘original guilt’ constitute an apparently necessary sequence of ideas which is an effective ‘ rationali- sation ’ of, or conceptual disguise for, the keen feelings of shame and remorse with which the ‘ twice-born ’ Christian contemplates the life which he lived before his conversion.? - 1 ibid. 19: ‘ cuius anima velut surculus quidam ex matrice Adam in propaginem deducta et genitalibus feminae foveis commendata cum omni sua paratura pullulavit tam intellectu quam et sensu.’ 2 A curious argument for this theory is found in the language of Gen. i. 26, which almost in the same breath refers to ‘ man ” both in the singular and in the plural number: ‘ Let us make man in our image . . . and let them have dominion over the fish of the sea, etc.’ ; tbid. 27: ‘igitur ex uno homine tota haec animarum redundantia . . . nam et in ipsa prae- fatione operis unius, “‘ faciamus hominem,” universa posteritas pluraliter praedicata est—‘‘ et praesint piscibus maris.”’’ 8 It has been maintained (1) that ‘ traducianism’ is the necessary basis of any doctrine of ‘ Original Sin,’ the opposite hypothesis, that of ‘creationism’ (2.e. the view that each soul is, not the product of the father’s soul or the parents’ souls, but an immediate and ad hoc creation of 238 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN Did Tertullian himself take this momentous step, that of advancing from the idea of a hereditary bias towards evil derived from Adam’s fall (‘ Original Sin’) to that of a hereditary responsibility for Adam’s fall, which, as we shall see in succeeding lectures, is the chief differentia of the Augustinian version of the Fall-doctrine? Scholars are divided in opinion on this point, and it is not easy to give a decided reply. Itis certain that he held the idea of ‘ Original Sin,’ though his demonology, which was even richer and more luxuriant than that of his contemporaries, often tends to cross and blur the lines of his exposition of the Fall-theory. So, in the treatise which we have been considering, c. 39 tells us that the source of the evil with which pagans are tainted from their mothers’ wombs is the idolatrous cere- monial which surrounds childbirth, and conveys demonic infection to the newly born babe. From this kind of pollution the children of Christians are born free.1 Yet even they in due time? need regeneration by water and the Spirit ; for every soul is enumerated as being ‘in Adam,’ until that moment when it is re-enumerated as being ‘ in Christ’; and it is unclean, God), destroying the moral continuity and solidarity of the race; cf. the Jewish ‘ creationism ’ lying behind the doctrine of the yéger ha-va‘, Lecture II, p. 69, n. 2; and (2) that ‘ the traducian theory is the only one which modern biological knowledge supports’ (J. F. Bethune-Baker, Introduction to the Early History of Christian Doctrine, 1903, p. 304). I would suggest that both these contentions, in so far as they assume ‘ creationism’ and ‘traducianism’ to be mutually exclusive alternatives, are antiquated by the fact that our modern realisation of the immanence of God in all natural processes, combined with the recognition of what is called ‘ emergent evolution,’ has in principle abolished the cistinction between these two views. When water is experimentally generated in a laboratory by the combination of hydrogen and oxygen, we do not raise the question whether ‘ this water’ as such is to be regarded as the direct product of the combined gases, or whether we must suppose that mysterious proper- ties of ‘ aqueosity’ and ‘ thisness’ have been catastrophically imposed by God ab extva upon them; no more should we raise the disjunctive question whether the soul is the product of the parents or of God. ‘ Traducianism’ and ‘ creationism’ are no more than different ways of looking at the same fact. 1 This, Tertullian thinks, is the real meaning of 1 Cor. vii. 14 discussed above (p. 220, n. 2). 2 Tertullian deprecates Paedo-baptism; see below, p. 241. THE PALU-DOCTRINE, IN: THE CHURCH 2309 until it is so re-enumerated. But the soul is a sinner, because it is < in itself > unclean, not because it derives its disgrace from its alliance with the flesh. A little later we read : The evil, therefore, which exists in the soul, other than that which is built upon it by the visitation of the wicked spirit, is antecedent < to particular evil actions >, being derived from the fault of our origin (ex origints vitio), and is in a certain manner natural. For, as we have said, the corruption of nature is a second nature.” We are here very far away from the levis contagio of Origen’s more Hellenic mood 3 ; an equally severe judgment is pro- nounced upon fallen humanity in the treatise de spectacults : . . . that dread might of the envious angel, the arch-corrupter of the universe, has cast down man, the work and likeness of God, the lord of the whole world, from his ancient integrity, and changed into a state of rebellion against his Creator his whole substance, which had together with him been fashioned for PLORIAL Vests Yet neither of these passages contains any clear trace of the idea that we are justly culpable for having fallen ‘ in Adam ’ or for being fallen creatures. An incidental reference to the Fall, in the work de carnis resurrectione, is more suggestive of this idea : 1 de an. 40: ‘ita omnis anima eo usque in Adam censetur, donec in Christo recenseatur, tamdiu immunda, quamdiu (? non) recenseatur ; peccatrix autem, quia immunda, nec recipiens ignominiam ex carnis societate.’ The word ‘ nec’ at the beginning of the last clause has been added by Wissowa: but it seems necessary in order to save Tertullian from Manicheism: and as only one manuscript containing the text of the de anima survives (cod. Agobardinus, saec. ix.), such a restoration is not unjustifiable. Parity of reasoning suggests the insertion of ‘ non’ after ‘ quamdiu.’ 2 ibid. 41: ‘ malum igitur animae, praeter quod ex obventu spiritus nequam superstruitur, ex originis vitio antecedit, naturale quodammodo. nam, ut diximus, naturae corruptio alia natura est.’ 3 vu. supra, Pp. 230. 4 de spect. 2: ‘cum ipsum hominem, opus et imaginem Dei, totius universitatis possessorem, illa vis interpolatoris et aemulatoris angeli ab initio de integritate deiecerit, universam substantiam eius pariter cum ipso integritati institutam pariter cum ipso in perversitatem demutavit adversus institutorem’ (Wissowa’s text; but the repetition of ‘ pariter cum ipso’ must surely be a mere dittography). 240 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN When the Lord says that He is come to save that which was lost, what are we to understand by ‘that which was lost’ ? Undoubtedly man. Is man ‘lost’ as a whole, or only in part ? Surely as a whole, seeing that the transgression, which is the cause of man’s ruin, was committed both by an impulse of the soul, that is through concupiscence, and also by an action of the flesh, that is through the tasting < of the forbidden fruit >, has branded the whole man with the judicial record of his trans- gression, and therefore has deservedly filled him with ruin.? Here the ‘ elogium’ or ‘ judicial record’ of the sin of Adam seems to be understood as binding his posterity also ; and with this may be compared a passage of the de testumonio ammae : Finally, in every expression of annoyance, scorn, and ab- horrence thou dost utter the name of Satan, whom we call the angel of malice, the contriver of all error, the corrupter of the whole age ; by whom man was deceived in the beginning, that he should overstep the commandment of God; wherefore man was given over to death, and has made his whole race, drawing contamination from his seed, a stock or breed (¢vaducem) stained with his own condemnation ?: 1 de carnis vesurvect. 34: ‘in primis cum ad hoc venisse se dicit, uti quod periit salvum faciat, quid dicis perisse ? hominem sine dubio. totumne an ex parte? utique totum, siquidem transgressio, quae perdi- tionis humanae causa est, tam animae instinctu ex concupiscentia quam et carnis actu ex degustatione commissa totum hominem elogio trans- gressionis inscripsit atque exinde merito perditionis implevit ’ (Kroymann’s text, in Vienna Corpus, vol. xxxvil.). cf. also adv. Marcion.i. 22: ‘ homo damnatur in mortem ob unius arbusculae delibationem, et exinde proficiunt delicta cum poenis, et pereunt iam omnes qui paradisi nullam cespitem norunt’ (a sentence which, though it occurs in a context devoted to a criticism of Marcion’s theology, nevertheless appears to express Tertullian’s own point of view); and de resurrect. carnis 49: ‘ portavimus enim imaginem choici per collegium transgressionis, per consortium mortis, per exilium paradisi.’ 2 de test. animae, 3 (Wissowa): ‘ Satanan denique in omni vexatione et aspernatione et detestatione pronuntias, quem nos dicimus malitiae angelum, totius erroris artificem, totitts saeculi interpolatorem, per quem homo a primordio circumventus, ut praeceptum dei excederet, et propterea in mortem datus exinde totum de suo semine infectum suae etiam damna- tionis traducem fecit.’ The word ‘ tradux,’ which plays an important part in Latin speculation on this subject during the early patristic period, does not seem to have been satisfactorily dealt with by English commentators or translators, who take it as meaning, in a vague sense, either ‘ trans- mitter’ or ‘transmission.’ According to Lewis and Short’s Latin Dictionary (1922), its original meaning is a ‘ vine-layer’ or ‘ vine-branch’ trained for propagation, for which they quote Varro, Columella, Pliny THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 2ar in which the last phrase might easily be interpreted as meaning that every member of the race is born subject to the judicial sentence pronounced against Adam. Nevertheless, it is a striking fact that Tertullian objects to the custom of Infant Baptism, which, whether ultimately justifiable on other grounds or not, is an obvious practical inference from the doctrine of ‘ Original Guilt’; if infants are born subject to ‘ God’s wrath and damnation,’ and if baptism releases from this, it is clearly inhuman to delay the administration of the Sacrament to them for a second longer than is necessary. Tertullian, however, knows nothing of this line of reasoning, and thinks rather of the terrible danger of post-baptismal actual sin which haunts those who receive the rite without long and searching preparation, and mature purpose ; hence he vehemently urges the post- ponement of baptism in the cases of children and of un- married adults. ‘Why hurries the age of innocence to the remission of sins?’ + The conclusion must be that, though he may have been drifting in the direction of a conception of ‘ Original Guilt,’ he had not consciously arrived at it. It is probably safe to sum up this Father’s position in the statements (1) that he taught no explicit doctrine of * Original Guilt’; (2) that, however, he held a much more severe doctrine of ‘ Original Sin’ than any which we have hitherto come across, regarding the hereditary consequences of Adam’s fall as a positive corruption, not a mere weakness, a depravatio rather than a defrivatio ; and (3) that he shows at least a strong tendency to view this corruption junidically or forensically, as though it were a crime, rather than medically, as would be natural if it were a mere infirmity. and Tacitus. Du Cange (Glossarium, 1887 ed., s.v.) gives four meanings as current in later Latin, viz. (1) stirps vel propago, (2) origo (3) peccatum originale (4) propagatio. The first of these meanings seems to me most appropriate in this context. There seems to be no authority for the sense ‘transmitter.’ 1 de bapt. 18: ‘ itaque pro cuiusque personae condicione ac disposi- tione, etiam aetate, cunctatio baptismi utilior est, praecipue tamen circa parvulos . . . ait quidem dominus, “‘ nolite illos prohibere ad me venire.”’ veniant ergo, dum adolescunt; veniant, dum discunt, dum quo veniant docentur ; fiant Christiani, cum Christum nosse potuerint. quid festinat innocens aetas ad remissionem peccatorum ?’ R 242 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN ) It will be clear that this severe, ‘ twice-born ’ conception of the inherited bias towards sin, and the tendency to envisage it under specifically legal categories, when com- bined with the theory of the ‘ seminal identity ’ of Adam’s descendants with Adam himself, were bound eventually to generate the formal idea of ° Original Guilt,’ even if they did not generate it immediately upon their first juxtaposition. The central and distinctive elements in Tertullian’s Fall-doctrine have now, it may be hoped, been sketched with a degree of detail sufficient for our purpose. It will, however, be appropriate to add a few words regarding his views on some of the more peripheral of the ‘ five issues ’ enumerated at the beginning of this lecture as arising out of the Pauline ideas of the Fall and of ‘ Original Sin.’ There can be little doubt that he took the Genesis-story as a record of plain historic fact. There is no trace in his writings of the allegorical interpretation, which would have been peculiarly uncongenial to his juristic habit of mind, or of the character- istically Greek removal of ‘ Paradise’ into some extra- mundane sphere ; all his allusions to the subject are marked by the most naive literalism, and he seems to claim it as a privilege of Christians (and presumably also of Jews) that they alone are in possession of exact information about the origin of man. As regards his conception of man’s unfallen condition, it is noteworthy that, although holding a gloomy view of the consequences of Adam’s sin, Tertullian betrays no trace of the tendency, afterwards manifested by Augustine and his successors, towards heightening the ‘ original right- eousness ’ and ‘ perfection ’ of man to the greatest possible degree of exaltation, in order thereby to increase the depth and criminality of the ‘ Fall.’ His beliefs on this point do not differ substantially from the Greek-Christian theory of Adam's ‘ infantile condition’ or undeveloped innocence. Before the first sin, he tells us, man was ‘ innocent, a close friend of God, and the husbandman (colonus) of Paradise.’ 1 Adam's state is elsewhere described as one of ‘ integrity,’ 1 de patient. 5: the whole of this chaptér, which is too long to quote here, is devoted to an exposition of the Fall and its consequences as spring- ing from the fundamental sin of impatience. THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 243 which does not seem to imply more than the absence of any positive defect.1 It included, however, the gift of immor- tality ; ‘ if he had never sinned, he would never have died.’ 2 Tertullian’s view of the present condition of human nature, which is the object of Redemption, is more difficult to define with precision. We have already quoted passages in which he affirms that through the Fall man has perished as a whole, or in respect of the whole of his substance, that 1s, both in soul and body; and his ‘ traducianism ’ might be construed as involving the consequence that the seat or nidus of inherited evil extends over the whole personality, from its highest spiritual faculties down to its physiological instrument or basis—a position which seems to discard, at any rate in words, the Pauline antithesis between the disposition or ¢dpedvnua of ‘ the spirit,’ assumed to be good, and that of ‘ the flesh,’ which is ex hyfothest bad. Such a view might easily be pressed so as to become, in effect, the doctrine of the ‘ total depravity ’ of fallen human nature, as held by Calvin. Yet Tertullian himself never draws this conclusion, and indeed expresses opinions clearly inconsistent with it. Even after the Fall, he tells us, much that is good still survives in human nature; the natural goodness of the soul is overshadowed, not extinguished, by the corruption of nature, and reappears in its former beauty when the ‘ curtain of sin’ has been swept away by baptism. There is some good in the worst of men and some evil in the best.4 Moreover, free-will remains even in fallen man, so that real repentance and real change of life are possible under the impulsion of divine grace.® Yet all men alike are subject to ‘ concupiscentia,’ a term which is one of Tertullian’s most momentous legacies 1 de spect. 2, quoted above, p. 239, n. 4. 2 dean. 52: ‘ si non deliquisset, nequaquam obisset.’ 3 and ‘4 de an. 41: ‘ propterea nulla anima sine crimine, quia nulla sine bonisemine. proinde, cum ad finem pervenit, reformata per secundam nativitatem ex aqua et superna virtute detracto corruptionis pristinae aulaeo totam lucem suam conspicit.’ 5 ibid. 21: ‘... genimina viperarum fructum paenitentiae facient, si venena malignitatis expuerint. haec erit vis divinae gratiae, potentior utique natura, habens in nobis subiacentem sibi liberam arbitrii potestatem, quod adregovouov dicitur . . . inesse autem nobis 76 adrefovovoyv naturaliter iam et Marcioni ostendimus et Hermogeni.’ 244 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN to the Latin and Western theology of sin. ‘Concupiscentia’ is the standing translation, both in the Old Latin versions (as it would seem) and in the Vulgate, of émc@vpia, “ desire,’ as used by St. Paul! : and, as we have already seen, the Apostle’s conception of ‘ desire’ seems to be ultimately identical with the old yéger-conception of the Rabbis. Yécer, émOuvpia, “concupiscence,’ /ibido—these terms, representing a train of human thought which stretches from Ben Sirach through St. Paul and St. Augustine down to Freud, really denote the same fundamental psychological fact, though they contain varying implications of moral approval or disapproval of the fact. The Rabbinical theology could not make up its mind whether the yéger was in itself morally colourless, only becoming sinful per accidens, or whether it was essentially the yécer ha-ra‘, the ‘ evil impulse’: St. Paul was impelled by his ascetic and ‘ twice-born’’ temperament to choose the latter view, and in his writings ‘ desire’ (émOupia) almost invariably 2? bears a bad sense. Yet Tertullian, for all his African fanaticism, seems here to go behind St, Paul, and to revive the view of the more liberal Rabbis, that appetite in itself is ethically neutral. Those for whom the word “concupiscence ’ is bound up with Augustinian and scholastic associations will probably be surprised to find Tertullian declaring that concupiscence existed in Christ as perfect Man 8 ; and he asserts that there is a reasonable and laudable concupiscence which any Christian may have, ingenuously citing the Pauline dictum, in the Latin version familiar to him : “si quis episcopatum concupiscit, bonum opus concupiscit.’ 4 1 The Old Latin MSS. d e translate our Lord’s words in Luke xxii. 15, emOupia ercO¥pnoa, as “ concupiscentia concupivi’ ; but Vulg., apparently disliking the ascription of ‘ concupiscence’ to Christ, prefers ‘ desiderio desideravi.’ 2 The one instance of the use of the word in a good sense appears to be Phil. i. 23: rv émOuptay Exywr els Td Gvadocat. 3 de an. 16: ‘ ecce enim tota haec trinitas et in Domino, et rationale, quo docet, quo disserit, quo salutis vias sternit, et indignativum, quo invehitur in scribas et Pharisaeos, et concupiscentivum, quo “‘ pascha cum discipulis suis edere concupiscit’’’ (Luke xxii. 15; see n. 1, above). In | de cult. fem. ii. 2, however, ‘ concupiscentia’ is used specifically of sexual desire, in a bad sense. 4 y Tim. iii. 1: et tis €mucxomfs dpéyerar, Kadod Epyouv emOupet. Vulg., disliking the term ‘ concupiscere’ in this connexion, has ‘ si quis episco- patum desiderat, bonum opus desiderat.’ THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 245 After pointing out this liberal element in the thought of one who is popularly reputed to be the most fanatical of theologians (though indeed there are many parts of his writings which are humble, gentle, persuasive, and beautiful) it is disappointing to be compelled to add that Tertullian frequently enunciates that somewhat morbid view of sex to which, as we have shown, the ‘ twice-born’ temperament is inclined in its most exaggerated form. It is well known that (at least after his lapse into Montanism) he proclaimed sins of impurity to be the worst ofallsins, beyond the reach of any absolving power on earth,! and that his normal view of the married state ranked it as far inferior to virginity, and as an entanglement to be avoided by good Christians so far as was possible 2—though, as M. Monceaux drily remarks, ‘ ce grand ennemi du mariage était marié, naturellement.’? It would seem that a legal training provides no absolute guarantee for consistency either in theological theory or in practical life. It may be noted that Tertullian is the first writer to give us a phrase for the hereditary moral handicap, which, though it cannot be described as ‘ technical,’ yet has a technical suggestion and flavour about it—namely, the phrase originis vitium.* When we read these words, we seem to see the shadow of the tremendous term feccaium onginale already falling across the theological world; and we are no less conscious that we are moving in an atmosphere very different from that of primitive Greek-Christian theology, in which the thought of the consequences of Adam’s sin, or of his or ‘our’ expulsion from Paradise, is far too vague and indefinite to have demanded a single technical or quasi-technical term for its expression. 1 See especially de pudicitia. 2 In de exhort. cast. 9 he permits himself to write ‘ ergo, inquis, iam et primas, id est, unas nuptias destruis. necimmerito, quoniam et ipsae ex eo constant, quo et stuprum.’ 3 op. cit. p. 388. 4 de an. 41: ‘ malum igitur animae, praeter quod ex obventu spiritus nequam superstruitur, ex orviginis vitio antecedit, naturale quodam modo.’ 240 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN HISTORY OF THE ‘ HELLENIC’ AND ‘ AFRICAN’ THEORIES TO THE END OF THE FOURTH CENTURY Our historical research has now reached the middle of the third century of the Christian era, a point some two hundred years distant from the dates of r Cor. and Rom., which mark the first appearance of the Fall-doctrine in Christian literature. And it is now possible to discern, clearly differentiated from each other, the outlines of the two classical-versions, ‘ once-born’ or Hellenic and ‘ twice- born’ or African, of the somewhat indeterminate doctrines propounded or reaffirmed by St. Paul. It will conduce to lucidity if we pause for a moment in order to state and contrast these two presentations of the ideas in question ; . and the best method of doing this will be to summarise the answers given by the ‘ once-born ’ and ‘ twice-born ’ theories respectively to the ‘five crucial questions’ which were pointed out at the beginning of this lecture as implicit in the Pauline teaching. These questions, it will be remembered, were those (1) of the literal or allegorical interpretation of Gen. il., (2) of the original state of man before the Fall, (3) of the exact nature of the disastrous consequences flowing from the first man’s sin, (4) of the manner in which these consequences are perpetuated, whether by physiological or ‘social’ heredity, (5) of the present ‘condition of human nature, whether suffering from a grave depravatio or from a comparatively slight deprivatio. The ‘ Hellenic’ doctrine shows a strong tendency to allegorise the Paradise-story, or, at least, some of its details. It is inclined to construe ‘Adam’ etymologically, as merely the universal of ‘man,’ to remove ‘ Paradise’ into some extra-cosmic sphere which easily transforms itself into a purely metaphysical world of ideas or of noumena, and to interpret the eating of the forbidden fruit as a sym- bolic parable of sensual, sometimes of sexual, indulgence. At the same time, man’s Paradisal condition is not invested with fantastically exalted attributes of intellectual and moral THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 247 perfection! : he is conceived as a childish and imperfect creature, and his inexperience is sometimes taken as extenua- ting his Fall, which indeed is said to have had beneficial results in so far as it increased his knowledge of himself and of the world. The evil consequences of the Fall are con- ceived as expulsion from Paradise, subjection to the hard- ships of this world, and a certain moral weakness, due to loss of the assistance of the Logos or the Spirit, and some- times described as the loss of the ‘ likeness’ of God; the idea of ‘ Original Guilt ’ is, on the whole, conspicuous by its absence. These evil consequences are transmitted partly by ‘social heredity,’ children being influenced by the examples and instruction of their parents and by the fact of being born outside ‘ Paradise,’ partly, it would seem, by physiological heredity, in so far as the human race is vaguely thought of as organically united with Adam, its head and progenitor. It follows from this mild and minimising con- ception of the Fall-idea that the hereditary moral handicap of human nature is not depicted in very gloomy colours ; it is much more a deprivatio, a negation or absence of strength, than a positive depravatio, and even so far as it is conceived as a positive miasma, it does not amount to more than a levis contagio.2 The main source of sin lies in man’s free, self-determining will, and the main hindrance to a life of virtue consists in the invisible assaults of the demons, who, much more than any abstract ‘ Original Sin,’ are invoked as the explanation of evil desires, thoughts, and suggestions. The ‘ African’ doctrine, on the other hand, starts from a prosaically literal acceptance of the Paradise-story. On the question of man’s original state, it does not differ materially from the other version: the ‘ integrity,’ that is, ‘wholeness’ or ‘ completeness,’ which Tertullian predicates of Adam’s nature, is clearly not incompatible with the “childishness’ ascribed to the first man by Irenaeus. But, as we have seen, it shows a decided tendency to treat the 1 Except, perhaps, in Origen’s theory of pre-natal falls; but this, as we have pointed out, is rather a substitute for the Adam-theory than a version of it. 2 Origen’s phrase ; see above, p. 230. 248 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN inherited bias towards sin as a substantive and very grave disease or corruption, and to superadd to this, as part of the dreary legacy of the Fall, the idea of ‘ Original Guilt ’ or hereditary legal responsibility for the first transgression. These conceptions are closely bound up with the idea of the ‘seminal identity’ of the race with its first father as the true explanation of heredity. And they naturally lead toa severe and gloomy view of man’s fallen state, which, though not as yet accused of ‘ total depravity’ in the Calvinistic sense, is nevertheless regarded as involving the contamina- tion of both body and soul with the poison of congenital sinfulness. This scheme of ideas does not, indeed, amount to the full Augustinian position, for the beliefs in man’s ‘Original Righteousness’ or ‘ Perfection’ and in the prac- tical destruction of free-will by the Fall are still lacking ; but it will have become clear that the earliest thought of Christian Africa, as represented by Tertullian and by Origen (when writing as a Copt rather than as a Greek), contains the unmistakeable presage of what was to come. The remainder of this lecture will be devoted to a sketch of the development of these two types of Fall-doctrine during the rest of the pre-Augustinian period, that is, down to the end of the fourth century of our era—or rather to a sketch of the development of the ‘ African ’ theory, and to a record of the unprogressive oscillations of the ‘ Hellenic ’ theory. For, as we shall see, it is only in reference to the vigorous and prosaic West, with its predominantly ethical and practical interests, that we can speak of a ‘ develop- ment’ of the doctrines of human nature and of sin in the sense of an expansion of content and an ever-growing precision of form; the contemplative and metaphysically minded East tended rather to fix its gaze upon the eternal verities of the Being of God, upon the idea of the unchanging, impassible Logos and the mysteries of His relation to God and of His assumption of flesh, and it devoted little energy to the elucidation of the Fall-doctrine, contenting itself for the most part with repeating the unsystematised state- ments of the early Greek-Christian writers whom we have already noticed. Nevertheless, we must not expect to find THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 249 the doctrines generally characteristic of East and West divided by a rigid geographical frontier. In a supra-racial body like the Great Church of Catholic antiquity the currents of living thought are bound to intermingle ; the colours of the theological map, though their main masses are distinct, tend to overlap and run into each other like those of a badly executed aquatint. Hence we shall have occasion to note the presence of ‘ twice-born,’ almost Augustinian, traits in the teaching of some fourth-century Greek Fathers, and of a “ once-born ’ element in the thought of one or two Latin writers : though these overlappings will not prove sufficiently extensive to invalidate the application of the adjectives ‘Hellenic’ and ‘ African’ to the ‘ once-born’ and ‘ twice- born’ theories respectively. It will be natural in the first place to complete our survey of Greek-Christian thought with regard to the origin of sin down to the close of what may be called the primitive and formative period of Fall- speculation, and then to retrace our steps in order to carry the story of the more vital and clear-cut Western theory down to the same point ; concluding this lecture with an attempt to indicate the bearing of the results so far attained upon the fundamental question ‘ What statements regarding the origin and ground of sin may reasonably claim to have been held in the Christian Church ubique, semper, et ab omnibus 2’ a THE ‘ HELLENIC’ THEORY DOWN TO THE END OF THE PRE-AUGUSTINIAN PERIOD (rt) Methodius of Olympus. The history of Eastern thought with regard to the questions of the primal sin and its consequences, as with regard to other and even pro- founder questions, between the middle of the third and the end of the fourth century, is in great measure the history of alternating reactions against and regressions toward the characteristic positions of Origen. Both of these tendencies manifest themselves in the writings of Methodius, bishop of Olympus in Lycia (or according to some authorities, 250 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN of Patarat), who is said to have suffered martyrdom Cc. A.D. 3II, in the persecution of Maximinus Daza. Despite this author’s relative obscurity, a study of his Fall-doctrine forms the necessary introduction to the Greek-Christian anthropology and hamartiology of this period, not only because his life roughly covers the interval between the generation of Origen and that of Athanasius, but also because his relation to later Eastern orthodoxy is not unlike that of Tertullian to the thought of Ambrose and Augustine in Western Christendom ; for, in both cases, the main ideas afterwards set forth by the great classical writers of the fourth and fifth centuries—the golden age of creative theological thought—already appear, in germinal and confused form, amidst the less mature speculations of their third-century predecessor. The principal tenet of the Origenistic system to which Methodius objects most strongly is its conception of the relations of souland body: this is attacked inan intolerably diffuse dialogue, laboriously imitating the Platonic model, though without any tincture of the Attic master’s wit and charm—the dialogue de vesurrectione. In the course of this work he takes occasion to denounce the allegorical interpre- tation of Gen. ili., the idea of a supra-mundane Paradise, the hypothesis of a number of pre-natal falls, and the contention that evilin the human soul is due to its immersion in the world of matter 2—that is, the whole ‘ Transcendental Fall-theory ’ which we have seen to be characteristic of Origen’s Alexandrine period. He asserts emphatically that Paradise is a definite area of this world’s surface, ingeniously pointing out that if it had been located above the firmament 1 See Bardenhewer, Patrology, pp. 175 ff., and the articles ‘ Methodius’ in DCB (Salmon) and PRE (Bonwetsch). The standard editions of this Father’s works are (a) G. N. Bonwetsch, Methodius von Olympus (1891), i. Schrifien ; [this does not appear ever to have been completed, and has now been largely superseded by] (b) Methodius (1917), edited by the same scholar, in Die griech. christl. Schriftsteller der erst. drei Jahrhund. For the purposes of this section I have used the text as given in the latter work, which is cited as ‘ Bonwetsch (b).’ A brief but excellent summary of his general doctrinal position will be found in F. Loofs, Leitfaden zum Studium der Dogmengesch. (1906), pp. 224 ff. 2 de vesury.i. passim. For the sources from which the text of this work has been reconstructed, see Bonwetsch (b), Einleitung, pp. xxxiv-xxxvii. THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH a25rz the four sacred rivers, which according to Gen. ii. ro ff. take their rise in it, must necessarily have poured down from the skies in a single mighty cataract, which would have washed the earth away altogether.t The earlier Greek exegesis 2 of 2 Cor. xi. 2-4 (‘I know a man in Christ . . . sucha one caught up even to the third heaven. And I know such aman... how that he was caught up into Paradise,’ etc.) is repudiated, and the passage is explained as referring to two separate raptures, which translated the Apostle in spirit to two distinct places, the ‘third heaven’ above this sublunary world, and ‘ Paradise’ within it.2 And he de- votes interminable pages to confuting Origen’s allegorical interpretation of the ‘coats of skins,’ wherewith God clothed Adam and Eve after the Fall, as fleshly bodies— an interpretation which for some reason he seems to find peculiarly exasperating. So far as the first of the ‘five cardinal issues’ implicit in the Fall-doctrine is concerned, Methodius, though an Eastern of Easterns, stands for the characteristically ‘African’ view, and affords a good example of that theological overlapping of East and West which the reader has already been warned to expect. With regard, however, to three of the other issues (the primal condition of man, the rationale of the process whereby the consequences of the first sin are transmitted, the resul- tant state of human nature) the opinions of Methodius are specifically ‘ Hellenic’ and in line with the teaching of the early Apologists and of Irenaeus. He tells us that Adam was overcome by evil whilst still imperfect, and expresses this idea by the fanciful assertion that, whilst the protoplast was still a clay image, moist and soft from the Creator’s hands, the streams of sin overflowed and dissolved 1 de vesurr. i. 55 [Bonwetsch (b), p. 313]: mpa@rov yap 6 mapddetoos, dbev kat €£eBAnOnpev ev TH mpwroTAdoTH, ex TavTNs €oTl THs ys TpodjAws Téz70s e€alperos . . . SiAov amo Tod Kal Tov Tiypw Kat tov Eddparnv Kai tovs Aourods TroTapovs Tovs éxetOev mpoxeopevous evtadba daiveadar Tv pevpdtwr Tas duexBodas eis tiv Kal? Huds yareipov emuxkdvlovras. ov yap amd THv odtpavav dvwbev Katapdoocovrar xedpevor’ mel 00d UreaTH av 4 YH OyKoVv TodobTOV GIpdws e€ dyous katadepdpevov UrodeEacbat Udatos. Su supra, p..192, 1. 2% 3 ibid. [Bonwetsch (b), p. 313 f.] 4 These ‘ coats of skins’ seem to have exercised a curious fascination over early Christian writers ; see above, p. 229, n. 1, and below, p. 275, 0. 4. 252 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN him.! It would be rash to extract any minutely detailed meaning from this highly imaginative metaphor: but it at least suggests that the conception of unfallen man as a ‘babe’ (vjmos) which we have seen to be characteristic of the earliest Greek-Christian thought on this subject still dominates his mind, and that the belief in the ‘ Original Perfection ’’ and ‘ Righteousness’ of man is still below the intellectual horizon of Eastern Christianity. This conclusion may appear at first sight to be somewhat discounted by the fact that Methodius revives the ‘ recapitu- lation’ theory of Irenaeus in a form so extreme that it asserts the Logos to have been personally united with the first Adam as with the second, thus hardening the Pauline parallelism of Adam and Christ into an all but absolute identity 7; and in one passage at least he affirms that man was originally immortal, and not merely capable of im- mortality, physical death being introduced in order that man might not live for ever in a state of sin. We notice also what appears to be the first instance, in any Christian writing which can be regarded as a systematic discussion of the subject,* of the application of the significant term 1 symposium ili. 5 [Bonwetsch (b), p. 31]: €re yap mnAovpyovpevor Tov "Addu, ws EoTw eimetv, Kat TyKTOV GvTa Kal Vdapy, Kal pHndérw POdcavTa diknv dotpdxov Th adOapoia Kpatawiivac Kal drometpwOfvar, Vdwp wamep KataderBopern Kal Kataordlovoa Si€Avcev adrov 1) dpapria. 2 symposium iii. 4 [Bonwetsch (b), p. 30 f.]: dépe yap qyets emroxepmpeda, m@s opbodd—ws avyyaye tov ’Adday es tov Xpiorov, od pdvov avdrov TUTOV HyovpeEvos elvat Kal elkdva, GAAG Kal adTo TobTo Xpiorov Kai adrov yeyovevat dud, TO TOV mpd aidvwy els adTov eyKatackHya Aoyov. According to Victorinus Afer, on Gal. i. 19 (PL VIII. 1155 B), this idea was held in an even cruder form by certain Judaising Christians, ‘quiad dominum nostrum Iesum Christum adiungunt iudaismi observantiam: quamquam etiam Jesum Christum fatentur: dicunt enim eum ipsum Adam esse, et esse animam generalem, et alia huiusmodi blasphema.’ 5 ibid. ix. 2 [Bonwetsch (b), p. 116]: qv yap judy Kal mpdocbev drrwtos HaKnvy adda dia tiv mapaBaow ecarevOn Kat €xAOn, Tod Oeod TO dudprnua Avoavtos Oavarw, iva wn aavdtws dpaptwrds 6 dvOpwmos wv, Sdons ev adT@ THs apaptias, aiwriws Kataxpitos yev7x0n. For the development of this idea by Gregory of Nyssa, see below, p. 280. 4 It is true that the word casus is used to describe Adam’s transgression in the Latin version of 4 Esdras (Bensly, vii. 118, ‘ non est factum solius tuus casus sed et nostrum,’ quoted above, in an English translation, Lecture II, p. 80) ; and that in Hilgenfeld’s conjectural restoration of the lost Greek text from which the Latin version was made (Messias Iudaéorum, Leipzig, 1869, p. 67) this word is represented by mr@ya. If this restora- THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 253 ‘Fall’ (zr@pa) to the sin of Adam.! This term is entirely non-scriptural in this connexion, the word used by St. Paul being wapafPaots, a ‘ stepping aside’ from the path marked out for man by God; and it was destined later to have momentous consequences in the way of fostering a belief in ‘ original righteousness,’ inasmuch as the conception of a ‘ Fall’ implies an exalted condition previously enjoyed by the being who ‘ fell,’ an implication from which the Biblical and early Patristic word zapdBaois is entirely free.? It is fair, however, to observe that the term has not yet assumed the technical sense of ‘ the Fall,’ but is employed rather in the general sense of a ‘calamity’ or ‘ disaster.’ We may accurately sum up the ideas of Methodius with regard to man’s original state by saying that he adheres in the main to the position of Irenaeus, though there are not wanting in his works faint premonitions of the coming invasion of Christian thought by the Rabbinical figment of Adam’s supernatural perfection. tion were certain, we should have to conclude that the use of mr@pa in this connexion runs back at least into the second century A.p. (The Greek version of 4 Esdras must be prior to Clement of Alexandria, as it is quoted by him, Strom. iii. 16; see G. H. Box, The Ezra-A pocalypse, p. xi.) But there is no proof that casus is a translation of mrdpa, ‘ fall’; it may equally well have been used to translate a vaguer term like oupdopa, ‘disaster.’ Violet and Gressmann (Die Apok. des Esra und des Baruch, Gniech. Chrisil. Schriftst. XXXII. p. 99, note im Joc.) think that casus must represent mr@ya, and that a7dpya must have represented an original NgBN ; but, even so, this latter word need mean no more than ‘ ruin’ in a general sense (see Brown, Driver, and Briggs, Hebrew and English Lexicon of the O.T.., s.v. Sp», p- 658). Note that Wisdom x. 3 has wapdmrwua for Adam’s sin; but this word cannot be pressed to mean much more than mapdBaos. In the New Testament arpa invariably means ‘ corpse’; see Moulton and Geden, Concordance, s.v. It is, however, curious that Hippolytus, de antichristo 64 (Griech. Christl. Schriftst.,;ed. H. Achelis, p. 44), after quoting Matt. xxiv. 28, ‘ wheresoever the 77@ya is, there will the eagles be gathered together,’ observes mrdpa S€é yeyevnrar ev mapadeiow’ exet yap *Addap anatndels mémtwKxev: a use of the word which at least points the way towards its later technical use. 1 symposium iii. 6 [Bonwetsch (b), p. 32]: . . . cuvvéBn mapeAnArvbdra tiv évrodnvy dA€Opiov mrdpa Kat Sewdv meceiv, eis Odvarov dvacrouyewwbévra. * For observations on the use and significance of the parallel Latin words, praevaricatio (= mapdBaos) and lapsus (= mt@pa), see below, Pp. 302. 254 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN The question of the exact nature of the sinister legacy of the Fall, which had hardly been faced by Eastern theology up to this point, receives for the first time, in the treatise known as the Banquet of the Ten Virgins,1 what is in effect a philosophical answer, albeit expressed in a somewhat confused form—an answer which was destined to be further elaborated by the great Greek Fathers of the fourth century. This answer describes the evil principle introduced into human nature by the Fall as dopa, a word which was doubtless suggested in the first instance by its use in Rom. viii. 21 to describe the effects of Adam’s transgression upon sub-human nature. This word is usually translated ‘corruption’; but in the writings of Methodius and his successors, saturated as they were with the influence of Greek philosophy, a better rendering would be ‘ disinte- ration’ ?; for ‘ corruption’ conveys an inevitable sug- °. Es Sb gestion of a change which is offensive to the senses or (metaphorically) to the conscience, whereas ¢@opa used in philosophical context is an aesthetically colourless term, a connoting, at least in Aristotle, no more than the modern term ‘ katabolism,’ that is, the break-down of a highly organised structure into its components or into simpler combinations of them. No doubt as used by Plato the term possesses associations of a severer kind, which may well have been in the mind of this Father (Methodius platomzans *): for, in Platonic thought, yeveoits and @Oopa, ‘coming-to-be’ and ‘ passing-away, are charac- teristic of the world of matter, which is erroneous, mani- fold,’ self-contradictory, and evil.® But, whether the term 1 symposium iii. 7 [Bonwetsch (b), pp. 33 ff]. * This rendering is confirmed by the fact that the inbred infirmity of man’s nature is also described as advappooria ‘ disharmony’ (symp. il. 7), and (by implication) as 70 dvacro.yewwOFvac—‘ being resolved into its component elements,’ zbid. iii. 6 [Bonwetsch (b), p. 32]. 3 It is true that St. Basil once alludes to dvawdia as arising from ¢Oopa (hom. Quod Deus non est auctor malorum, 5) ; but the highly metaphorical context makes it clear that ¢@opa is not used in its philosophical sense. * Loofs, Lettfaden, p. 225. (Professor Loofs has been good enough to inform me that this phrase was suggested to him by the title of A. Jahn’s work, S. Method1 opera et S. Methodius platonizans, Halle, 1865.) 5 For ¢0opa in Aristotle, see the treatise mepi yevécews kal dOopas, 3149-338» (edited by H. H. Joachim, under the title ‘ On Coming-to-be and Passing-away,’ 1922). It is clear that for Aristotle the term ¢@opa THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 255 is employed with the Platonic or the Aristotelian nuance, it does not suggest, as the word ‘ corruption ’ does, a quality or a process which naturally awakens horror or disgust in the mind of the beholder: and it is therefore reasonable to assume that the state of ¢fopa produced in man by the Fall would have been deemed by Methodius to be regret- table indeed both in itself and in its effects, but not per se morally censurable or involving those who suffer from it in personal guilt, any more than hereditary phthisis or colour- blindness can be imputed to those who suffer from them as morally censurable offences. It is, in other words, probable that he would have been very far from agreeing with the Augustinian position that the mere possession of ‘ con- cupiscence ’ is in itself a sin.t Though Methodius himself does not give any clear explanation as to what he means by the ‘ disintegration ’ to which man has been subjected by the Fall, it has seemed worth while to reconstruct its probable significance at this point: for, as stated above, this author is the herald of the fourth-century Greek Fathers, some of whom employ the conception as the basis of that presentation of Christ’s redeeming work which unsympathetic critics have labelled “ethico-physical’ or “ physical-materialistic ’—that, namely, which concentrates the believer’s attention on the idea of the union of the ‘ disintegrated ’ soul with the Logos, Who through the sacraments—especially that of the Eucharist— floods it with His own essence, which is true Being, thereby arresting its tendency to relapse into non-being and restoring it to full and concrete existence. Formally, this conception is Platonic rather than Aristotelian, in so far as it assumes that evil is non-ens; but we may surmise that what covers what may be roughly called clean kinds of disintegration, such as the melting of ice. And, even in Plato, yéveots and d0opa are corre- lative and equally necessary characteristics of the material world, the latter not being more essentially evil than the former. In later Greek- Christian usage, the original, purely physical meaning of ¢@opa and its secondary, ethical meaning became hopelessly confused; this confusion is specially evident in the ‘ Aphthartodocetic’ controversy at the beginning of the sixth century (see R. Draguet, Julien d@ Halicarnasse et sa controverse ,avec Sévérve d Antioch, Louvain, 1924, pp. 100 ff.). 1 For this, see below, Lecture V, p. 373, 0. 2. 256 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN Methodius and his greater successors were really trying to express by the term ¢0opa is ‘ weakness of will-power,’ the defect which the modern psychologist describes by the bastard neologisms ‘ aboulia ’ and ‘ psychasthenia.’ In any case, however, our author is a convinced adherent of the continuous ‘ Hellenic’ tradition that the inherited infirmity does not seriously prejudice the essential freedom of the will, which in the treatise de autexusio is said to be possessed by all members of the human race in the same measure as by Adam at his creation }—a dictum which, if it had been uttered a century later, might have been described as explicitly Pelagian. The foregoing exposition of Methodius’ Fall- apergiae will, it may be hoped, have placed in the reader’s hand the main guiding threads which run through the hamartio- logical teaching of his great fourth-century successors— Athanasius, and the Cappadocian triad, Basil the Great, his brother Gregory of Nyssa, and their friend Gregory of Nazianzus. Their writings deserve a specially careful examination, inasmuch as in them the primitive ‘ once- born’ version of the Fall-doctrine attained as much fixity of outline and definiteness of articulation as it was destined to attain before Augustinianism descended on the Western Church like a flood, and Eastern thought had been drawn off into the sterile intricacies of the Monophysite, Monothelite, and Iconoclastic controversies. Though these illustrious doctors were by no means unconscious of the pervasive influences of Manicheism (the third great wave of Oriental dualism which was now beginning to assail the faith of Israel), the focus of their attention was occupied by the great Trinitarian and Christological problem, and they were not © able to spare more than a place in the penumbra of their thoughts for the question of the origin of sin. Much of our 1 de autexus. xvi. [Bonwetsch (b), p. 186]: adreEovauov 5€ tov mpdtov avOpwrov yeyovevar A€yw, TouTéaTiv EdeVOepov, ad’ od Kal of duddoxor Tod yevous THv Opolay é€Aevbepiay exAnpwoavro. It may be noted that this treatise is penetrated by the master-motive which, as we have seen, lies at the root of all Fall-speculation, viz. the desire to safeguard the infinite goodness and power of God both against monism and against dualism ; but, in this work at least, Methodius seems to forget the Fall-doctrine altogether, and to seek the way of escape between the Scylla of the Indian and the Charybdis of the Persian doctrine in unlimited indeterminism. THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 257 reconstruction, therefore, in the following section will have, as before, to be pieced together out of incidental allusions and obiter dicta ; we shall not expect to find perfect precision of language or coherence of thought; and we shall be prepared for the occasional emergence of an idea or an expression which seems more akin to the ‘ African’ or ‘twice-born ’ mode of feeling than to the sunny genius of Christian Hellenism. It is doubtless unnecessary to repeat the warning that the ‘ African’ and the ‘ Hellenic’ versions of the Fall-doctrine, as systematically set out above, though generally representative of the two main tendencies of hamartiological thought in the pre-Augustinian Church, are yet in the nature of composite photographs, which arrive at the expression of an ideal type by the elimination of individual and irrelevant detail. gol ae A daestuseii Ds (ALD. §20%, 7102°,373)..., Chough St. Athanasius does not deal with the question directly, it would seem probable that he held a partially allegorising interpretation of Gen. ii.; for his writings contain few allusions to the details of the story, and one well-known passage describes the Fall of man as consisting, not so much in the physical manducation of a particular fruit as in the aversion of his mind, through slothfulness, from that beatific contemplation of divine things for which he had been created.t This idea is presumably inherited from Origen, but with a difference ; for it does not appear to have been coupled by Athanasius with the idea of pre-natal existence or of a purely metaphysical or ‘intelligible’ Paradise. He once, indeed, asserts that ‘ Paradise’ was ‘ tropically,’ or metaphorically, so called by Moses; but in the same breath he alludes to it as a ‘ place’?; and, as Adam is 1 ¢. gentes 3: ovTw pev ody 6 Snwovpyos, Wamep EtpnTat, TO THY avOpwimwv yévos KaTeoKevace, Kai pévew HOEAncev’ of Sé avOpwro. KaToALywpHaavrTes TOV KpeiTTOvwv, Kal OKVHCaYTEs TEpl THY TovTwWY KaTdAnp, TA eyyuTépw pwaAAoV éauTdv elyrynoav. éyytrepa dé tovTos Av Td GHpa Kal at to’Tov aicOyoets* d0ev tHv pev vontdv anéotynoav éavT@v Tov vobv, éavtods dé Katavoety np£arto. eis €auTdv émibupiay erecav, Ta idta mpoTiunoavtes THS mpds TA Beta Bewpias : see also the preceding chapter. (For the text of St. Athanasius I have used the Benedictine edition, Patavii, 1777.) 2 ibid. 2, ad fin.: . . . ouvdsaitaa8ar trois dyious €v TH THY vonrdv Oewpia, qv elyev ev éxeivw 7O tomm, Ov Kat 6 ayios Mwiofs tpomiKds tapddevcov Wvomacer. Ss 258 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN conceived as being endowed with a body,! even in his paradisal state, it is natural to conclude that the ‘ place’ is conceived as located somewhere within this concrete universe, whether above the earth, as Irenaeus thought, or upon it, as Methodius maintained. It is probably safe to assume that, like the former of the authors just mentioned, he accepted the idea of a first man and woman quite literally, but would have been prepared to rationalise some of the more naive features of the story. Unlike Irenaeus, however, he holds that the protoplast was anything but a ‘ babe,’ inasmuch as Adam is credited with intellectual, moral, and spiritual powers of the highest order. His purity of heart endowed him with the vision of God, a vision so far-reaching that he could contemplate the eternity of God’s essence and the cosmic operations of His Word.? His mental sight was turned away from ‘ bodies,’ and directed upwards. Harnack has collected the expres- sions ‘imagination concerning God,’ ‘ knowledge,’ “ percep- tion,’ ‘comprehension,’ ‘contemplation’ of ‘divine things’ or of ‘the intelligible world,’ ‘contemplation concerning God,’ an ‘inward grasp of knowledge as to the Father,’ 3 which are used by Athanasius to describe the eagle-like, un- wavering intensity of the first man’s gaze upon the splendour of God. Besides all this, he was endued with immortality and safeguarded from disintegration into his native nothing- ness by his intimate union with the Logos *—an idea which we have already encountered in the writings of Methodius, though Athanasius does not follow his predecessor in the strange fancy of making the first Adam apparently as much an incarnation of the Divine Word as the second. The anthropology of this great Father thus marks a definite breach with the primitive Hellenic tradition which conceived the protoplast as frail, unformed, and innocent or morally neutral, ‘capable of both’ good and evil,® and the definite 1 ¢. gentes 3, quoted above. 2 «bid. 2. 5 davracia mepl Oeot, yrdats, Katavdnois, KardAniyis, Oewpia trav Oelwv, Gewpia t&v vontadv, Bewpia rept tod Oeod, Ewora ris eis marépa yricews (History of Dogma, E. tr., 1897, ili. p. 273). 4 d ¥ ‘ : bf 5 8 4 A 4 / , A / é wnucayn. 4, 5; Cj. especially 5: ova yap Tov ovvovta TovTois Lloyov Kal 7 Kata dvow Pbopa rovTwr ovK Hyytle. 5 uv. supra, pp. 175, 176, 193. THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 259 beginning of that naturalisation of the ideas of Adam’s ‘ original righteousness’ and ‘ perfection ’ within the sphere of Christian thought, both Eastern and Western, which was the outstanding event in the history of the Fall-doctrine during the fourth century of our era. It is in the highest degree noteworthy that Athanasius, in exalting the primitive state of man, draws in effect that very distinction between (a) the qualities belonging to the first man merely in virtue of his human nature as such, and (b) the resplendent supernatural qualities bestowed on him by a special act of Divine grace, which was destined to play a great part in the later development of the ‘ African’ Fall-doctrine, and to be expressed by the mediaeval School- men as the distinction between Adam’s pura naturalia and the donum superadditum of ‘ original righteousness.’4_ Man, like all other members of the created universe, was made out of nothing: hence human nature can never continue in one stay, always tending to slip back into nothing. To counteract this inherent instability of man’s being, God bestowed upon him ‘a further gift’? (a phrase which is roughly equivalent to donum superadditum), namely His own ‘image, which is none other than the indwelling of the Logos, the ‘image of the invisible God,’ * and a special ‘grace’ ® (another word which calls up Augustinian associa- tions in the mind of the modern reader). It is carefully explained that this supernatural grace was bestowed on man from without, catastrophically, and was by no means bound up with or involved in his physical constitution as man.® ® 1 See Lecture V, p. 363; Lecture VI, p. 4or1. 2 de incarn. 4: €oTt pev yap Kata dvow avOpwaos Ovntos, are 8H €€ ovK OvTow yeyovws. 3 ibid. 3: mAéov te yapilopuevos adrots. 4 Col.i.15. The idea that the ‘image of God’ in man 7s the indwelling Logos is clearly expressed in the following passage: epi 5€ adrod (sc. Tod Xpictobd) oti pdvos eikav aGArAnOwi} Kat dvoet Tod Tarpds Eat. et yap Kal kat eixova vyeyovapev Kal eik@v Kal boa beob expnwarioaper, GAN’ od ou” EavTovs maw, aAda dia Thy evoukjoagay ev jpty eikova Kal aAnOA Sd€av Tod Geod, qTis €oTW 6 Adyos avrod, 6 81° yas vorepov yevduevos oap£, tavryv 7H KAjoews € EXO ev THv xapu (oY. ill. c. Avian. 10 ad fin.). 5 deincarn. 3: mpoAaBav jadadicato vou Kai Témm THY Sobcicay adtots xdpwv. 6 ov. il. c. Avianos, 68: 6 pévtot dvOpwros Tovotros eyiveto olos Av Kal 6 "Addap apo ris mapapdacews, e£whev AaBwv tHv xdpw Kal pw} cvvnppoopEernv Exwv avThY TO owpate. 260 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN According to Harnack,? this bodily and sensuous con- stitution of man is all that Athanasius means by mere human nature; our higher faculties, intellectual and spiritual, belong to the donum superadditum, which is the ‘image of God.’ Hence the first sin was a Fall, not from a natural to an unnatural state, but rather from a state which was supernatural to one which was merely natural—another conception which we shall meet again in the thought of some Western Schoolmen.? It may thus be said that Athanasius, despite the touches of anticipated Augustinianism which we have noted, regards the direct consequences of the Fall as being in the nature of a deprivatio rather than of a depravatio. The ‘ depriva- tion’ however involves a ‘ depravation,’ in so far as the loss of the ‘image of God’ (that is, of the indwelling of the Logos) releases the connatural tendency of man’s being to lapse into non-entity, in other words, renders him liable to ‘disintegration’ or ¢0opa.2 This word, at least in the fourth-century Greek Fathers, includes the ideas of physical mortality and of that obscuration of man’s intellectual powers which rendered him an easy prey to idolatry and the worship of daemons 4; but its primary meaning seems to be metaphysical. Round the conception of ‘ disintegra- tion ’ coheres the whole scheme of ideas, the emergence of which was predicted in our discussion of Methodius, and which needs no further explanation at this point—the idea of evil as non-being (by which, verbally at least, God is saved from the charge of originating evil, as He cannot have originated the non-existent: this device was subsequently employed in the theodicies of Gregory of Nyssa,° Augustine, ® 1 op. cit. ill. p. 272. eemee Lecture Vi, peor: 8 For the ideas expressed in this and the preceding sentences, compare de incayn. 4: % yap mapaBaats Tis evroAjs eis TO KaTa dvaw adtods eméaTpe dev, iva WoTep OvK OvTES yeydvactY OUTWS Kal THY Els TO p17) Elvar POopaV dropetvwor T@ Xpovw elKdTws. 4 It would seem that the idea of a progressive intellectual decadence in man resulting in idolatry was derived by Athanasius and his successors from Rom. i. 18-end. Wecannot, however, go at length into the interest- ing question of the influence exercised by this passage on later thought, as exigencies of space compel us to limit the scope of our survey very strictly to the history of the Adam-theory. 5 uv. infra, p. 278. & Lecture: Vi) p.371* THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 261 and Thomas Aquinas !)—and the idea of redemption as consisting chiefly in the reunion of the perishing soul with the Logos, Who infuses into it the streams of His own strong and stainless being, thereby arresting the process of ‘ disintegration,’ and eventually exalting the soul to what is daringly described as actual ‘ deification.’2 This latter conception is summed up in the famous paradox ‘ He (the Logos) became Man in order that we might be made God’ 3 ; a sentence which points backwards to the words ascribed to St. Peter ‘ that through these (the promises) ye may become partakers of the Divine nature, having escaped from the “ disintegration ’’ which is in the world through sinful appetite ’ *—and forwards to the glowing lines of Newman : And that a higher gift than grace Should flesh and blood refine, God’s presence and His very Self And essence all-divine.® In all three cases, though the Eucharist is not expressly mentioned, it is permissible to surmise that the sacramental idea is in the background of the writer’s mind. ® There does not appear to be any trace of the idea of ‘original guilt’ in the thought of Athanasius. His occasional statements that ‘we’ sinned, or perished, in contexts bearing on the Fall of man, might seem prima facie to imply a belief in some kind of participation by Adam’s posterity in the responsibility for his sin ; but it is, I think, 1 Lecture VI, p. 405. 2 Complete ‘ deification’ will, apparently, not be accomplished until the resurrection : see the passage oy”. ili. c. Avian. 33, quoted below (p. 262, 12). 3 de incayn. 54: avros yap evnvOpmmnoev, iva juets OeomornPSpev. Com- pare or. ii. c. Avian. 70: ov adv 8€é madw €BeoroinOn Kticpat. avvadbels 6 avOpwros, et un Oeds Av GAnOwos 6 vids; or”. iii. c. Avian. 25: domep viol Kal Geot 51a tov ev yuiv Adyov: and many other passages. See A. Robertson, St. Athanasius On the Incarnation (E. tr.), p. 93, D. 2. euzeteter tA. 5 Dream of Gerontius. 6 The Eucharistic setting in which the idea of ‘ deification’ was held by the mind of Athanasius is clearly shown in the following sentence : otk avOpmmov Té Twos peTéxovTes owpatos adAAA atrob Trot Adyou capa AapBavovres Peoto.otpeda (ad Maximum philosophum epistola, 2 ad fin.). Cf. St. Ignatius’ conception of the Eucharist as the ¢dppyaxov abavacias, Eph. 20. 262 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN more natural to interpret such expressions merely as desultory symptoms of the subconscious influence of the ‘ Recapitulation ’-theory in its vaguest and least rigorous form. No explicit statement is made as to the manner in which the consequences of the Fall are transmitted from generation to generation: but the emphatically realistic idea of ‘ disintegration ’ which Athanasius holds in common with Methodius must surely presuppose physiological, and not merely ‘ social,’ heredity as the means of its propagation. The opinions of Athanasius with regard to the last of the ‘ five cardinal issues,’ the present condition of ‘ fallen ’ man, though severe, are yet, on the whole, of the ‘ Hellenic ’ and ‘once-born’ type. We are told that the débdcle of human nature, that is, its collapse into nothingness, which was brought about by the Fall and the withdrawal of the sustaining power of the Logos, was a gradual and long- drawn-out process, which is not even yet complete ; for it is implied that man still retains the ‘ image of God’ (that is, the indwelling of the Logos) in so far as he still possesses faculties of knowing and reasoning, and free-will It is even asserted that sinlessness is both theoretically and actually possible, some of the saints, such as Jeremiah and John the Baptist, having been pure from every kind of sin.” 1 Cf. de incayn. 12, in which it is contended that even before the Incar- nation men might have improved their state by receiving instruction from the law, the prophets, and other holy men. ‘The vivid simile at the begin- ning of c. 14, in the same treatise, of the picture overlaid by dirt, implies that the ‘image of God’ still existed in human nature, only overlaid by sin to such a degree that it had been ‘ made invisible’ (zapadavicbeica). 2 The passage in which this statement occurs is worth quoting at length, as it contains Athanasius’ leading ideas relative to the Fall, Sin, and Redemption assembled together. > ‘ ‘ lol 6 , lo A / ” \ 8 A a 2 cpa d > ei yap Ta THS YedtyTos TOG Adyou Epya pH Sia Tod adpartos eyiveto, ovK b] ¢ 4 , > A ~ av €JeomornOn 6 avOpwros. Kal madwy, et Ta idia THs CapKds OdK edEyeTO TOD A , ? n DY Q 60 > cat > \ v4 ec om” é > > Laer g ‘ oyouv, ovK av NAevdepwbn mavTeAds azo TovTwy 6 avOpwmos’ GAA’ ei dpa mpdos > e lal / »” = dAlyov wev averraveTo, Ws mpoet mov, maALw Sé Evevev 7) duwaptia ev adT@ kal 4 0 opa, 4 > \ an »” > v2 / A aA Worep emt THv Eumrpoober avOparwv yéyove, Kab TOTO SeixvuTa. moAAol yodv 4 7 A \ ‘A ¢€ dytou yeyovaci kat Kkabapoi rmaons duaprias’ "lepeutas §é xaléx KotAlas € , rf) * \ ai / ” i. > , b] > , 924 aA aA nyiacbn’ Kal Iwdvvns Ete kvopopovpevos eoKipTycev ev ayadXudoe emt TH Pwvh a , / . ‘ y s+ 2 , THs QYeordkov Mapias’ Kai ouws ‘€Bacirevoev 6 Odvatos amd "Addu péxpe : , oo 4 ‘ Nace , 2 Ps = Mwocéws, kal emt Tovs py apaprnoavtas emi TH Sporwpate THs mapaBdoews >AS , ’ \ ¢ Mv 7) \ Chae. fa) \ \ A ‘ du.’ Kal odrws Euevov oddev HrTOov of dvOpwrror Ovynrol Kal POaprol, SexTLKol A ? / A , cal ~ A tT&v (Siwy ris dv¥cews Tabdv. viv dé rot Adyou yerouévov avOpamou, > / A ~ A / ~ ~ Kal LOvomoLovpevovu Ta THS GapKos, OVKETL TabTa Tod GwmaTos anTETAL, Sid TOV > > ~ f A ié ‘ LAN e > ? ~ \ > , 4 4 Ce €v avT@ yevopevov Adyov’ a um avTov pev aviAwrat, AouTov Sé of avOpwror 2 THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 263 It is natural to append to our account of Athanasius’ Fall-doctrine some words with regard to his younger contemporary, (3) Cyril of Jerusalem (A.D. 315-386). This Father’s writings contain exceedingly few allusions to the ideas of a primitive catastrophe and of an inherited taint. He tells us, in one place, that Adam’s sin was the cause of physical death1; he is prepared to use the idiom which makes the first person plural the subject of verbs referring to the Fall,? and he admits that our nature is ‘ wounded,’ ® that is, affected by a hereditary bias towards sin. But he is no less emphatic in asserting that we are personally sinless at birth,* and that man possesses the fullest possible freedom of choice, which is not really hampered by the suggestions of the devil or the storms of appetite ®; and his references to the ‘remission of sins’ imparted in baptism make it clear that he is thinking only of actual personal sins and of adult baptism, and that the idea of ‘ original guilt ’ is completely absent from his mind.® As in the case of so many other Greek-Christian writers, it is evident both that the Fall- tradition is for him too much of an authoritative reality ovKeTL KaTa Ta dia maOn pevovow aywapTwdAol Kal vexpol, aAAa KATA THY TOO — Adyou Sdvapw avaordyres, GOdvaroe Kal ddOaprou del Srapevovow (or. iii. c. Arian. 33). Together with this should be considered a passage in o7. il. c. Avian. 61, which is of interest (a) because it affirms the universality of the destruction involved by Adam’s sin, thus appearing to contradict the statement just cited as to the sinlessness of many of the saints, (bd) because it contains an emphatic assertion of the idea of redemption by way of quasi-physical (7.e., presumably, sacramental) incorporation with the human nature of the incarnate Logos: éed2) mdvtwv tdv avOpadmav amoAAvpevwv Kata THY TapdBaow Tod °’Addau, mpwHTn Tdv dAdwy éodOy Kal HArcvbepadOn % exeivov cap, ws adtob tot Adyov odua yevopuérn, Kal doumov Hpmets Ws cdvcowpot TUYXdVOVTES KaT’ exetvo owlopeda. er Cab. XM1, 2. 2 ibid. ii. 5: doAdAapev dmarnbevtes . . . TemTwHKapev . . . ETUPADONwev ait iiAs 8 ibid. xii. 7: péyrotov Fv TO Tpatua THs avOpwmrdrnTos, ad Toda Ews Kegadrys odk tv ev avT@ OXroKAnpia. 4 ibid. iv. 19: mplv wapayévynrat els TévdSe TOV Kdopov 7 uy}, OddSey NuapTer (probably a repudiation of Origen’s view)’ dAQ’ €Advres dvapaptynrot, viv ek Mpoaipécews apapTavoper. 5 ibid. iv. 21: adregovards éorw % pvyn’ Kal 6 dudBodAos 7d pev droBddAXeuw dvvaTa, TO Oé Kal dvayKdoat Tapa Tpoatpeow ovk Exes THY eEovaiav. wmoypader oot mopvetas Aoyrouov' av OéAns, edéEw* eav p1) O€Ans, ovdK d€Fw. Ve PAtpid. iil. 12, 15, xVii.)37. 264. THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN to be completely discarded, and also that it has never been assimilated into the texture of his thought, which remains strongly indeterministic throughout. (4) St. Basil of Caesarea (b. A.D. 330, d. 379). The writings of the greatest of the Cappadocian Fathers contain some clear and unmistakable affirmations of, or allusions to, the Adamic Fall-doctrine in its most general sense,! side by side with assertions of human free-will so vehement and unqualified as to seem logically incompatible with that doctrine. His position with regard to the question of the origins and ground of sin is thus typically ‘ Hellenic,’ both in its inconsistency and in its libertarianism ; and, but for the testimony which it bears to the rapid growth of the idea of ‘ original perfection,’ might have been described as entirely free from any traits of the kind which we have designated as ‘ African’ or ‘ twice-born.’ The most extended discussion of the subject which St. Basil has 1 The following are the passages alluded to (all quotations are taken from the Benedictine text, S.P.N. Basilit Caesar. Capp. archiep. opera omnia, ed. D. Julianus Garnier, Parisiis, 1722—hereinafter cited as ‘Garnier’ or ‘G’): (a) hom. in ps. xxix. 5 (G.i. 129 A): Kadds pev yap nenv Kata tHv dvow: (notice that Basil does not, apparently, accept Athanasius’ distinction between human nature as such and the donum supevadditum) aobevis dé dia 7d €€ EmtBovdAfs Tod dodews vexpwOHvar TH TapanTwHpate : (b) hom. in ps. cxiv. 3 (G. i. 202 A): quets Fuey more Evdokor emi THs TOb mapadeicov dtaywy fs, eyevopeba 5é ddo€ou Kal TaTewwol dia THY ExTTWOW : (c) hom. in fam. et sicc. 7 (G. ii. 70 D): as yap ’"Adap xaxds dayav tiv dpaptiav mapémepisev (presumably by physical heredity) ; (zd) hom. de humilit. (G. ii. 156 D, E)—a strong assertion of man’s original glory and perfection, from which he was cast down by the devil by the hope of a feigned glory ; (ec) hom. de venunt. saec. 6, 7 (G. 1. 207 D, 208 C)—these passages, however, are allusions to the story of Gen. iii. rather than affirmations of the Fall-doctrine ; (f) de spir. sancto, 15 (G. iii. 28 C): 9 Tod Oeod Kai owripos Rudy sreEpi Tov avOpwrov oikovopia avdKAnats €oTw ano THs EKTTMOEWS. (g) ep. 261 (ad Sozopolitanos) (G. iii. 402 A, B)—a general but quite definite assertion of the doctrine of the Fall in order to vindicate the reality of the Incarnation against those who attributed a ‘ celestial body ’ toour Lord. ‘Thereis an interesting touch of ‘ anticipated Augustinianism’ in the use of the word ¢upapa, ‘lump,’ to describe mankind considered as included in Adam (v. infra, p. 310, n. 2, p. 328, n. 2): tls dé xpeia THs ayias mapbévov, et pt ex Tod dupdwartos Tod "Addy euedrAev 7 Oeopdpos cap§ mpocdauBavecbat ; THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 265 bequeathed to posterity—though, as we shall see, even this does not amount to very much—is to be found in the Homily quod Deus non est auctor malorum,’ a title which bears witness to the fact, often emphasised in these Lectures, that the Fall-doctrine is fundamentally an exercise in theodicy-making. A brief summary of this discussion will sufficiently indicate the general tenor of his thought upon a matter to which he has evidently devoted but little sustained attention. After some introductory remarks upon the evils which God permits to afflict mankind, and the difficulties which these raise against the belief in the divine governance of the world and of human history, the preacher begins his treat- ment of the subject by distinguishing sharply, much as a modern philosopher might, between physical evil (that is, in the last resort, pain) and moral evilor sin. Weare not here concerned, nor does space permit us, to examine his vindi- cation of the justice of God in regard to the terrible chastise- ments, such as storms, floods and earthquakes, with which from time to time He visits offending communities or sections of the human race. These things, according to St. Basil, are relatively evil; sin alone is absolutely evil; and the root of sin is emphatically asserted to be free-will,” ‘ seeing that it is in our power either to abstain from evil or to be wicked.’ If this unqualified autonomy can really be attributed to the human will, one half and that the most important half of a complete theodicy has already been constructed, and nothing more remains to be said on the moral side of the problem of evil. But Basil appears to be uneasily conscious that the facts of human nature are not quite so simple as unlimited indeterminism supposes them to be; at any rate, he adds two arguments which, on the extreme libertarian hypothesis, are logically superfluous, 1 Garnier, ii. 72-83. 2 op. cit. 3 (Garnier, li. p. 74 A): dpx} yap Kat pila ris dpaprias rod ed? nuiv Kal 7d adre€ovaror. 3 ibid. 5 (p. 76 E). 4 Later on in this Homily (7, Garnier, p. 79 D, E) Basil gives the correct reply to those who impugn the righteousness of God on the ground that He might have made us moral automata and did not—the reply, namely, that the possibility of moral action involves freedom of choice and therefore freedom to go wrong. 266 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN namely, (rt) the contention already adduced by Athanasius, that evil is a privatio, supervening upon ‘ mutilations of the soul,’ 1 and therefore a negation or non-entity—and that the Creator cannot be supposed to have created that which does not exist ; (2) that a good Creator cannot in any case be the author of anything save that which is good, a contention which is confirmed by the Scriptural record. ‘And God saw all that He had made, and, behold, it was very good.’ Nevertheless, he is forced to admit that evil does exist empirically, even though it may be ‘ non- existent’ metaphysically?; and he poses once more the question—already answered, if extreme indeterminism be allowed—‘If God is not the first cause of evil, who or what is ?’ The reply is again ‘ Human free-will,’ but this time with a difference. For the freedom which is now in question seems to be, not the freedom which we possess or think ourselves to possess at the present moment, but rather the complete capacity for self-determination with which the soul in its unfallen condition was once endowed.* There follows an exceedingly vague and elusive statement of what appears to be in essence Origen’s first or ‘ Alexandrine ’ Fall-theory, that which postulates a great number of pre- natal falls. We are told that ‘the soul’—by which is apparently meant each individual soul—was created for the contemplation of God and of eternal beauty ; that it allowed itself to be overcome by satiety ° and a kind of drowsiness, 1 ob. cit. 5 (p. 78 A): orépnots yap ayafod earl 76 Kaxdv: ibid, (p. 78 B): ovTw Kal TO Kakov ovK ev tdia wmdpge e€otlv, GAAA Tots THS uxAs TmnpwWmacuv emcrylveTat. As was suggested above, in our discussion of Methodius (p. 255), the idea of the anhypostatic character of evil naturally leads to an interpreta- tion of ‘inherited sinfulness ’ as weakness, or a defect of will-power, issuing in failure to control the natural impulses in accordance with the dictates of reason, rather than as a positive propension towards wrong-doing as such ; and this conception of ‘ weakness’ as the result of the Fall is actually expressed by St. Basil in quotation (a), supra, p. 264, 0. I. 2 Gen. i, 31. 3 op. cit. 5 (p. 78 C): dAda pny eote 76 Kakodv, Kal 4 evépyera Selxvvat moAv Kata tod Biov mavtds Kexvuevov. mdbev odv adT@ TO elval, et pHTE dvapxov €ort, dno, unre mEeTolnTaAL ; 4 op. ett. 6 (p. 78: E). 5 xédpos (ibid. 6, p. 79 A): the word is used by Origen (v. supra, p. 213). ee ye inet 2 ee THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 267 so conceiving the desire of carnal pleasures, which caused it to slide down from the heavenly sphere and to be mingled with flesh. Hardly, however, has St. Basil formulated this position before he seems to be attacked by misgivings with regard to the wisdom or justifiability of identifying himself so explicitly with the teaching of one so suspect by many members of the Church, albeit so beloved by himself,? as Origen: and he consequently decides to redress the balance of his discourse by subjoining a statement of what had by this time almost become the ‘ orthodox ’ theory, in the following words : There was a time when Adam lived on high, not locally, but in respect of the direction of his will [this is evidently meant to repudiate both a supra-mundane, but yet concrete, Paradise, and also the idea of human pre-existence on the plane of the intelligible world] when, only just endowed with life, he raised his eyes to heaven; and, rejoicing exceedingly in those things which he saw, he was filled to overflowing with love for his Benefactor, who had freely given him the enjoyment of eternal life, had made him to repose amidst the delights of Paradise, had granted him a princedom like unto that of the angels and a share in the food of archangels, and had made him a listener to the Divine Voice. And besides all this, he was shielded by God and enjoyed all His good things. Never- theless, being soon sated with all these things, and being as it were impelled to insolence by his satiety, he preferred that which appeared pleasant to the eyes of flesh above the intelligible beauty, and counted the satisfying of his belly more precious than the spiritual joys. So then, being forthwith outside Para- dise, and outside that blessed manner of life, he became evil, not through necessity, but as the result of folly.® 1 For Origen’s own statement of this theory, v. supra, pp. 212 ff. 2 It will be remembered that we owe the Philocalia to the collaboration of Basil and Gregory of Nazianzus. 3 op. cit. 7 (Garnier, p. 79 B, C): fv more 6 Addy dvw, 0d romm GAAG TH mpoapece, ote dptu puxwhels Kal avaPrAas mpds odpavoer, weprxapyns Tots Spwpevois yevopevos, brepayanayv tov evepyéTrny Cais pev aiwviov amdAavow xaproduevov, Tpudais Sé mapadeicov evavarravoarra, apyny dé SdvTa Kata Thy THY ayyédwv, Kat dpyayyéAots adrov tovjoavra Opodiarov, kal duvAs Oelas dxpoaTHy’ éml maou tovtos brepacmilduevos Tapa eob, Kai dmoAatwv Tav adrod ayabdar, Taxyd mdvtwy avaTAndels Kal ofov €£vBpicas 7 Kdpw, 76 Tots capKivors 6POadpois davév tepmvov Tob vonTos mpoetiunce KdAXovs, Kal Thy TAnspoVvIY THS yaoTpos Tov mvevpaticav amodatvoeww Tiyswrépav ebero. eéw pev ed0ds qv Tod mapadetoov, £w Sé ris paxaplas éxelvns Staywyfs’ odK e& dvdyKys Kaxds GAN’ €€ dBovdAlas yevdpevos. 268 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN This passage clearly asserts a high view of ‘ original righteousness’ and ‘ perfection, 1 and it is consequently not surprising to find elsewhere ? in the writings of St. Basil instances of the use of the word ‘ Fall’ (ékardats, m7 Gpa) in this connexion. We naturally expect, after such an exordium, some explanation of the consequences flowing from the ‘ folly’ of the first man. But the Adam-theory, as here set forth, remains a torso, running down into vague- ness ; the only statements suggestive of a connexion between the acquired sinfulness of the protoplast and the sinfulness of his descendants are to be found in the employment from time to time of an idiom which we have already noted in Greek writers on this subject, namely, the use of the first personal pronoun plural in expressions referring to the Fall. ‘We’ are said to have drawn death upon ourselves as the result of an evil disposition?; the Tree of the Knowledge of Good and Evil was fair to look upon in order that ‘ our’ obedience might be tested ®; the devil has become our adversary on account of the Fall (z7@pa) which happened to ‘us’ of old as the result of our insult (to God).® Such expressions may naturally be construed, both in Athanasius and in Basil, as symptomatic of the subconscious influence of the Kecapitulation-theory. But it is clear that the conviction which our author really holds with his whole heart and which springs out of the depths of his own vital experience is the virile ethical belief in the fullness of man’s free-will. The Fall-doctrine comes to him from without, on the authority of Scripture and ecclesiastical tradition, and it is accepted by him in a minimising form, we need not doubt sincerely, but yet superficially ; it has not gripped his emotions or even the whole of his intellect, and he has made little effort to harmonise the uncompromising liber- tarianism natural to his own Hellenic temperament with the measure of determinism which even a minimal statement of the Fall-doctrine must logically involve. It may be noted that this Father adds a curious 1 Cf. quotations (a), (0) and (da), supra, p. 264, n. I. 2 e.g. de spir. sancto 15; hom. in ps. cxiv. 3. 3 uv. supra, pp. 196, 261. 4 hom, quod Deus non est auct. mal. 7 (Garnier, p. 79 C). 5 ibid. g (Garnier, p. 81 A). 6 ibid. 9 (Garnier, p. 81 D). THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 269 hypothetical decoration to the idea of Adam’s ‘ original perfection,’ when he tells us that, although unfallen man had no need of clothing, nevertheless, if he had persevered in virtue, a lucid aureole would have formed itself about him, more beauteous than the daedal hues of the flowers and more brilliant than the light of the stars, which would have been an angelic garment bestowed on him as the reward of his perseverance by the hand of the Creator himself.4 From the writings of St. Basil we pass by a natural transition to those of (5) his younger brother, St. Gregory of Nyssa (b. c. A.D. 335, d. c. 395).2. Though it cannot be said that this acute psychologist and brilliant rhetorician did much to fix the changeful and elusive lineaments of the “ Hellenic ’ Fall-doctrine, he nevertheless deserves the credit of having devoted much more attention and interest to the subject than any of the Greek-Christian writers whom we have reviewed so far, with the exceptions of Irenaeus and Origen ; and his works contain a wealth of material for the reconstruction of the opinions and speculations regarding the origin of sin which were current in Eastern Christendom during the age immediately prior to that of St. Augustine. It will conduce to clearness if in summarising the ideas held by this Father we employ once more the five-fold scheme of ‘cardinal issues’ defined at the beginning of this Lecture as arising directly out of the Pauline doctrine of the Fall and of its consequences for man. (1) It is clear that, following his master Origen, Gregory was a partisan of the allegorical, as opposed to the prosaically literal, interpretation of Gen. iii. We need only refer to the phrases used by him in the oratio catechetica— ‘... all the matters whereof Moses treats in more or less historical form, placing before us 1 hom. quod Deus non est auct. mal. 9 (Garnier, p. 81 D). 2 For more extended discussions of St. Gregory’s doctrines of Man and of Sin, see the following: Gregorit Nyss. doctrinam de hominis natura et tllustravit et cum Origeniana comparavit E. W. Moller, Halle, 1854; A. Krampf, Der Urzustand des Menschen nach der Lehre des hl. Gregor von Nyssa, 1889; Fr. Hilt, Des hl. Gregors von Nyssa Lehre vom Menschen, 1890; J. Riviere, Le dogme de la rédemption, 1905, Ppp. 151-159, 384-386, 420, 422. Quotations from the ovatio catechetica are given in accordance with Dr. J. H. Srawley’s text (The Catechetical Oration of Gregory of Nyssa, Cambr. Patristic Texts, 1903) ; for quotations from other works, I have used Migne (PG XLIV-XLVI). 270 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN doctrines in the guise of a narrative’... ‘nowit is sucha doctrine which Moses sets forth unto you in more or less historical form and by means of riddles; yet the teaching which these riddles contain is plain and manifest.’ * Thorough- going allegorism is for him, as for Origen, a means of escape from servitude to the letter of the Paradise-story into the free atmosphere of philosophical speculation, in which the Fall-theory can be developed in accordance with what we have seen to be its true nature, as a hypothesis framed by reason to account for the actual existence of evil whilst safeguarding the infinite power and goodness of God. (2) The question, what was Gregory’s view of the original state of man, is much more obscure and complicated. It can, however, be considerably simplified if we abandon the attempt to harmonise all his allusions to the subject, and recognise that two somewhat different theories of ‘ original perfection,’ involving correspondingly diverse theories of the nature and effects of the Fall, appear in his writings. The earliest of these attempts to articulate the Fall-theory is to be found in the treatise de hominis opificro (‘ on the making of man’) which may be dated c. A.D. 380; the later is contained in the oratio catechetica, written c. A.D. 385. A brief survey and comparison of these two views will both help to complete our picture of the various tendencies which the ‘ Hellenic’ Fall-speculation of this period was elastic enough to include, and also suggest ideas which may prove to be of use in our final evaluation and re-formulation of the basic Christian doctrines of human nature and of sin. (a) ‘ Original perfection’ and the Fall in the treatise ‘On the making of man.’ The first of these trains of thought finds its nominal starting-point in the words of Gen. i. 26, 27. (26) ‘ And God said, Let us make man in our image, after our likeness: and let them have dominion over the fish of the sea. . . ,’ ‘or. cat. 5: Oca rept todtwy taropikdtepov 6 Mwogs diebepyerau, ev Sinyjnoews elder Sdypara Hutv mapatibépevos. 2 ibid. 8: 1d dé ToLvotrov Sdypa iotopixwTepov pev Kal 8c’ aiveypdrwv 6 Mwofs byiv éxriberar, aAnv ExdndAov Kat 7a aiviypara ri SiSacKadAlay Eyer. 3 de hom. opif. 16-18. THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 271 etc. (27) ‘And God created man in his own image, in the image of God created he him ; male and female created he them.’ This text is made, by a somewhat forced exegesis, to yield the theory of a double creation of man, or (in other words) of the creation of the human race as involving two distinct and separate Divine acts. The first of these acts brought into existence ‘man’ as such, that is, the idea or universal concept of humanity. This archetypal or ideal ‘man’ was made ‘in the image of God,’ and was con- sequently endowed with all possible moral and intellectual excellences, including the completest freedom of self- determination ; and, though at the beginning numerically one, and contained in one body,? he included in himself the potentiality of all subsequent individual men. His nature was entirely free from irrational passions and appetites, more particularly from the sexual appetite ; and if he had never fallen, he would have propagated himself in the same manner as the angels, presumably (though Gregory does not say this, and disclaims exact knowledge of the angelic mode of procreation) by some kind of fission. Nevertheless, though made in the image of God, he was distinguished from God by his creaturely status, which involved instability and mutability; for God alone is uncreate and immutable. This mutability inherent in man carried with it the possibility of sin: and, though God did not predestine man to sin, He foresaw that in point of fact he would sin,? and would consequently forfeit the power of 1 de hom. opif. 16 (PG XLIV. 185 C): ovrws ofuat Kabdrep ev evi cwpatt GAov TO THS avOpwrdTHTOS TANpwUGA .. . TEeproxeDFvat. 2 The view set out in this paragraph must be carefully distinguished from Origen’s theory of the pre-natal existence of individual human spirits, which is emphatically repudiated by Gregory of Nyssa. (de an. et resurr. [PG XLVI, 112 C].) This passage does not mention the name of Origen, doubtless owing to Gregory’s pietas towards him, and appears to be nominally directed against the idea of a pre-natal fall as expounded in the myth contained in Plato’s Phaedrus (v. supra, p. 214); but to con- demn the theory of the Phaedrus myth is to condemn the theory of Origen’s Alexandrine period. Another repudiation of this view occurs in de hom. opif. 28 (PG XLIV. 229 B). 8 Cf. Milton, Paradise Lost, iii. 116: ‘ They themselves decreed Their own revolt, not I. If I foreknew, Foreknowledge had no influence on their fault, Which had no less proved certain, unforeknown.’ 272 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN reproducing himself after the manner of the angels. In view, therefore, of the foreseen, though not fore-ordained, catastrophe of the Fall, and to preserve the possibility of the numerical increase of mankind, God subdivided the one archetypal man into ‘male’ and ‘female’: that is, He added to man’s original intellectual nature those sexual organs and appetites which are the instruments of genera- tion in the sub-human brutes. ‘Hence also’ (he adds) ‘the great David, pitying the misery of man, mourns over his nature with such words as these, that ‘‘man being in honour knew it not’’ (meaning by “ honour ”’ the equality of the angels) ; therefore, he says, “‘ he is compared to the beasts that have no understanding, and made like unto them.’ ! For he truly was made like the beasts, who received in his nature the present mode of transient generation, on account of his inclination to material things.’? This partial degradation of man, through his subdivision and ‘sexualization’ (if this coinage may be pardoned) in view of a foreseen Fall, is the second act of creation, described in Gen. 1. 27 ‘ male and female created he them.’ The assumption of an animal nature and of sexual feelings by man necessarily carried with it (according to this author) the assumption of other appetites and passions, such as pride, ferocity, greed, and timidity. All these evil impulses came into human nature concomitantly with sex and because of sex, so that man became a Janus-like creature, with two faces, one bearing the ‘image of God,’ the other the image of the brutes. Nevertheless, free-will can bridle these passions and harness them to good ends, thus trans- forming the dispositions from which they arise into heroic virtues ; this had actually been done by Moses and other saints of the elder Covenant.2 On the other hand, free- will may accept and endorse the animal passions, and set the intellect to work at the excogitation of lawless and fantastic means of satisfying them, so that monstrous crimes, unknown to the brute creation, result. Yet Gregory seems to recognise, in a startlingly modern spirit, that all 1s ex lit 3) (1xX )i 2 de hom. opif. 17, 5 (PG XLIV. 189 D). 3 ibid. 18, 8 (PG XLIV. 193 D). THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 273 so-called ‘evil passions’ in man are exaggerations, or perversions, of instincts which in themselves are necessary for the continuance of animal life upon the earth; anger, for instance, is the perversion of the self-assertive instinct, timidity of the self-preserving instinct, and so on. The affinities of this conception with the Rabbinical idea of the yecer ha-ra‘, and with the doctrines of more recent psycho- logy of the psycho-analytic school, do not need to be emphasised. Gregory’s earliest version of the Fall-doctrine, yee does not regard the connatural disorder of the human soul as a direct consequence of the Fall: it is, rather, a direct consequence of man’s endowment by God with a bodily, and more particularly with a sexual, nature, in view of his divinely foreseen Fall. This position represents an exceed- ingly subtle and original revision of the traditional doctrine, and cannot now be considered on its merits: it must suffice to note its key-conceptions, some of which, as we shall see, were discarded by our author in his later presentation of the doctrine, that which appears in the oratio catechetica. These key-conceptions are: (i) The attribution of ‘ original perfection,’ not to the first sexually differentiated pair of human beings, but to the archetypal Man, the universal of humanity; this idea may well be derived from the hypothesis of a single pre- existent Adam tentatively Re in Origen’s Commentary on the Epistle to the Romans! : (ii) The conviction that sex is an intrinsically evil, or at least undesirable and regrettable, phenomenon—an instance of the appearance of a specifically “‘ twice-born ’ or “ African ’ trait in an otherwise thoroughly ‘ Hellenic’ scheme of thought. The emergence of this familiar piece of morbidity will cause no surprise to anyone who remembers the ascetic tendencies common to the three Cappadocians, or who has read the terrible indictment of marriage contained in Gregory’s treatise de virginitate.? 1 vy. supra, p. 228. 2c. li. (PG XLVI. 325 ff.). Like Tertullian, Gregory of Nyssa was a married disparager of marriage : his wife was named Theosebia (see S. Greg. Naz. ep. cxcvii, ed. Paris. ii. p. 162, written to console Gregory of Nyssa on T 274 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN (iii) The ultra-‘ Hellenic,’ almost Pelagian, belief that free-will is capable—apparently by itself—of taming the passions, and that sinlessness was actually achieved by a few men even before the coming of Christ.} (b) ‘ Original perfection’ in the Catechetical Oration. The chief prima facie objection to the scheme of ideas just described is that, in so far as it regards sin as a natural consequence of our animal constitution, and attributes our animal constitution to a specific creative act of God, it appears to make God the ultimate first cause of sin— the very conclusion which the Fall-doctrine was originally designed to destroy, but into which it tends, when care- lessly handled, to convert itself. Five years later, how- ever, Gregory had been driven by the silent but persistent pressure of Manichean dualism to realise the true issues at stake. ‘All through the oratio catechetica’ (says Dr. Srawley) “Gregory has the Manicheans in view.’? What we have called the theodicy-making motive dominates his later pre- sentation of the Fall-doctrine. ‘Seeing that man is the work of God, who out of His goodness brought this living creature into existence, no one can rationally suppose that he, whose constitution has its source in goodness, was created by his Maker in a state of evil.’ 3 In the light of this principle, the whole theory of a double creation and of a distinction between the one arche- typal man and the two sexually differentiated beings, Adam and Eve, is tacitly dropped, and there is substituted for it what was now becoming, in both East and West, the normal view—that, namely, of a single glorious protoplast, belonging both to the intelligible and to the sensible world, her death ; Nicephorus, H.E. xi. 19, ed. Fronto Ducaeus, 1630, li. p. 1373 Tillemont, Mémoires, ix. p. 252, thinks that she was a deaconess, as well as a priest’s wife). 1 Cf. the opinions of St. Athanasius on this point, supra, p. 262. 4 op. ctl. Pp. 27, 1.5. 3 or. cat. 5 (Sr. p. 25, 15): €zrevd%) yap Beod Epyov 6 dvOpwmos, Tod 8° ayabérnra to Cdov roito mapayaydvtos eis yéveow, ovK dv Tis evrAdyws, od 4 airla THs cvotdcews ayabdrns €otl, TodTov év Kakots yeyevfolaL Tapa Top METOLNKOTOS KADUTOTTEVCELEDV. THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH) 275 the meeting-point of spirit and matter, the ruler of the earth, immortal and impassible, ‘ revelling in the manifestation of Deity even face to face.’? Inflamed with envy by man’s splendid prerogatives, the archangel who governs the earth and its surrounding sphere resolved to bring him to naught? ; and, being unable to work man’s ruin by force, he persuaded him by guile to renounce his communion with God, and so to infect his whole being with a fatal weakness. Gregory illustrates this conception by a quaint yet significant simile, comparing the malevolent Spirit to one who, not having sufficient strength of lung to blow a lamp out, mixes water with the oil and so reduces the flame to a feeble flicker 3 ; a simile which implies that the image of God in man is obscured but by no means destroyed. [From the error of the protoplast flow all human ills, including physical mor- tality (the ‘ coats of skins’ of Gen. ili. 21 are explained as symbolising the sensuous and irrational nature with which mortality is necessarily bound up, but not bodies as such *) ; and the God of Christianity is thus vindicated against the indictment of the Manicheans. We may note that in Gregory, as in other fourth-century writers, an exalted con- ception of man’s primal state finds its logical consequence in an occasional use of the word ‘ Fall’ to denote the first transgression. ® 1 or. cat. 6 (Sr. p. 36, 8): adris Kata mpdowmov tis Oeias eudavelas KaTaTpupav. 2 Note that in the Catechetical Oration the real and ultimate ‘ Fall’ is that of the angel of the earth, who became the devil. 8 ibid. 6 (Sr. p. 36, 15). 4 ibid. 8 (Sr. p. 43, 2 ff.), where Gregory draws attention, in an eminently critical spirit, to the difficulty of supposing that animals were literally killed and flayed for the purpose of providing these garments. The explanation which he gives seems to represent, like so much else of greater importance in fourth-century Eastern thought, the resultant of the forces of attraction towards and revolt against Origen (v. supra, p. 249). Cf. de an. et resurry. (PG XLVI. 148 D), where the ‘ skin’ is expounded as typifying ‘ the form of the irrational nature, wherewith we were clothed, when we had been made familiar with passion,’ and de virg. 12, where it is identified with the ‘ mind of the flesh’ (¢pdvnua tis capxds). For earlier discussions of this point, v. supra, pp. 229, 251, 275. 5 Cf. or. cat. 8 (St. p. 51, 22): } rod mem@TwKOTOS Gvdpbwas: ibid. 15 (Sr. p. 63, 11): 6 &y 7H wrwparte avOpwmos; de vita Moysis (PG XLIV, 337 D): Adyos ris eotw ex matpixfs mapaddcews TO MuoTOV Exwv, 6s dat, Teaovons huav eis Gpwapriavy THs dvcews, 7 Tapideiv Tov Oedv THY TTAGLY 276 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN (3) What, in Gregory’s view, was the exact nature of the disastrous legacy of the primal catastrophe ? According to the treatise On the making of man, it was nothing other than our irrational, sensuous, appetitive, and emotional nature itself. But, as we have already pointed out, to brand appetite, instinct, and emotion as evil, as things which had better not have been, is to leave the door ajar for the entrance of Manicheism. We may suppose that it was the realisation of this fact which impelled Gregory in the Catechetical Oration to affirm emphatically that the seat of evil lies in the power of choice though even in this work there are not wanting traces of his earlier view.2, To modern readers it may seem that it would not have been very difficult to clear up the confusion which enwrapped the question of the precise nature of the flaw or disharmony in man’s psychic structure by saying boldly: ‘ appetite is in itself good, or at least neutral; but appetite permitted to indulge itself without limit or government becomes fer accidens bad ; it is the business of the will to keep appetite in order ; but, owing to the Fall, the will is weak, so that it is not always capable of opposing a firm inhibition to the clamorous demands of the appetites for satisfaction, with the result that they often break out into action contrary to the dictates of reason and conscience. Hence, the radical flaw of human nature may be defined as “‘ weakness of will’’.’ He comes near to this position, when he tells us that ‘human nature is weak relatively to the doing of good, in that it was once for all amapavontov. or. cat., however, also employs the words zapartpomm, ‘turning aside’ (8, Sr. p. 49, 16), and wapoAcAdvew, ‘ to slip aside’ (8, Sr. Pp. 5I, 10), which seem to express the older idea of the first sin as a mapaBaois, a divergence from the line of progress which God had meant man to pursue. 1 op. cit. 7 (Sr. p. 40, 4): Kakov yap oddev é€w mpoaipécews ef” EavTod xetrat (in other words, moral evil is alone xaxov) ; cf. also c. Eunom. ii. 13 (PG XLV. 545 B): yap mapaxot mpoaipécews 03 awpatos auaptia éaotiv’ tdvov yap puxfs mpoaipecis, ad’ Fs maoa tis pPicews avudopa thy apyxiy éoxev (‘for disobedience is a sin of will, not of body; for will is a property of soul, from which all the disaster of our nature had its beginning’). For this line of thought, see St. Basil, hom. quod Deus non est auctor malorum (discussed supra, p. 265). 2 ibid. 8 (Sr. p. 45, 7): T@ atoOnriKd péper, TH kata 76 o@pd dnc, THs Kaxias Kataptxbeions (‘ wickedness being intermingled with the sensuous part cof our nature>, that part I mean which is connected with the body ’). a, THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 2977 hamstrung by wickedness.’} But he never succeeds in reaching a clear distinction between appetite and the illicit indulgence of appetite ; he sticks fast at precisely the same point at which the Rabbinical artificers of the yé¢er-doctrine had stuck. Doubtless in both cases the failure to advance may be attributed to defective terminology, inasmuch as neither the Hebrew nor the Greek language contains a word which exactly expresses the idea of Will as the power, not merely to choose, but to enforce the choice in the teeth of rebellious inclinations by the exertion of effort. In view of this imperfection of his psychological termi- nology, it might have been expected that Gregory would fall back upon the metaphysical or quasi-metaphysical concep- tion of ‘ disintegration,’ which we have already noted in Methodius and Athanasius. This, however, he leaves on one side. Two fragments, indeed, of the scheme of ideas 1 de ovat. domin. 4 (PG XLIV. 1164 C): adodevas % dvOpwrivn dvats mpos 76 ayabdv eorw, amak bia Kakias exvevpiobeica. (The context consists of a series of eloquent variations on.this theme.) Cf. also or. cat. 15 (Sr. p. 63, 10): édet7o yap Tod latpevovtos 4 dvois nudv aobevyoaca; ibid. 16 (Sr. p. 69, 9), where the ‘impulse towards wickedness’ is called an dppwotnpua or ‘ ailment’ of our nature. 2 v. supra, Lecture IIT, p. 609. 3 Biblical Hebrew does not contain a word for ‘ Will,’ in the sense defined above: py seems to mean rather ‘ goodwill,’ ‘ favour,’ ‘desire,’ or ‘ pleasure’ (see Brown, Driver, and Briggs, Hebrew and English Lexicon of the O.T., s.v., p. 953). And Dr. A. Biichler, than whom no one can speak with more authority, informs me that the equivalent of ‘ will’ in this sense is not to be found, so far as he knows, in Rabbinical Hebrew. He suggests, indeed, (in a letter to me) that the term yéger hattobh (‘ the good impulse,’ which in later Rabbinical literature is said to contend with the yéger ha-va‘ within the soul of man) comes to very much the same thing ; but the‘ goodimpulse,’ or‘ disposition,’ being ex hypothest directed towards good ends, cannot be taken as simply identical with the bare power of exerting effort to overcome inclination, for this latter power may be exerted to overcome conscientious scruples or good inclinations, as in the case of Shakespere’s Hubert (King John, Act IV, Scene 1) : ‘If I talk to him, with his innocent prate He will awake my mercy which lies dead : Therefore I will be sudden, and dispatch.’ The Greek language is no better off in this regard. mpoaipeos is defined by Aristotle as Bovdeutixn dpeéis THv ef’ Hutv (Eth. Nic. ili. 3, 19)— a definition which implies that in mpoaipeous ‘ appetite’ and ‘ deliberation ’ are harmoniously united ; and @éAnyua is defined by St. John of Damascus (orth. fid. ii. 22, quoted by Suicer, Thesaurus, s.v.), in substantially identical terms, as dpefis Aoyixy Te Kai Cwriki wdvev HpTnuErn TOV hvaiKkdv. P| 278 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN which coheres round this term appear in the Catechetical Ovation. He several times takes occasion to point out that evil is a ‘ privation,’ absence, or negation of good, not a thing-in-itself existing in its own right ; and bases on this the conventional anti-Manichean contention that God is not the author of evil, as it would be absurd to describe Him as the author of that which does not exist.1_ And the idea of the ‘ deification’ of human nature through sacramental incorporation into the Incarnate Logos is expressed with almost startling realism and definiteness, in a chapter? which sets forth a doctrine of Eucharistic ‘ transelementa- tion ’® which is hardly, if at all, distinguishable from the later ‘ transubstantiation.’ But the disease which is to be healed by this ‘ deification’ is here described, not as a mere negative tendency to relapse into nothingness, but as a substantive ‘ poison’ * which can only find its antidote in the reception of the Body of Christ. We seem, in short, to be here confronted with a momentary emergence of the characteristically ‘ African ’ tendency to conceive the results of the Fall as involving a positive defravatio, and not a mere deprivatio. The only comment that can usefully be made upon this will be a repetition of the familiar reminder that too much consistency must not be expected from the pioneers of scientific theology. It is of great importance to note that Gregory, in harmony with the strongly marked tendency of the ‘ once-born’ and ‘Hellenic’ line of thought, repudiates the idea of ‘ Original Guilt.’ Ample proof of this statement is supplied by the whole tenor of the treatise On the untimely deaths of infants ° ; in which the question of the future destiny of babes who die 1 Op. Cit. 7. SLCC B 3 ibid. 37 (Sr. p. 152, 6): tabra dé didwor 7H THs edAoyias Suvdyer mpos Exeivo pEeTAaTOLxELWoas THY paivopevar tiv dvaw. See Srawley’s note 2x loc., and D. Stone, History of the Doctrine of the Holy Eucharist, i. pp. 71 ff., 103 f. 4 OnAnTHpcov (Sr. p. 142, 4). 5 de tnfantibus qui praemature abripiuntur (PG XLVI. 161-192). That the infants contemplated in this treatise are unbaptised infants is not indeed expressly stated, but follows (1) from the presumption that no doubt could have arisen in the mind of any primitive Christian about the salvation of baptised infants, and (2) from the fact that Gregory seems to be almost unconscious of the existence of the custom of infant baptism ; v. infra, Pp. 279. THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 279 without baptism is handled with the completest apparent unconsciousness of any idea that a newly born babe is as such subject to God’s wrath or stained with any kind of ‘sin.’ + Gregory's humane and reasonable suggestion of some state analogous to what was later called the limbus puerorum, as the solution of this problem,? stands in the most vivid contrast to the heartless fanaticism with which Augustine condemns unbaptised little ones to eternal fire, and is the surest warrant that he was completely out of sympathy with the theory which impelled the Doctor of Hippo to this gruesome conclusion. It is, indeed, remark- able that (for all his devotion to Origen) Gregory seems to ignore the custom of infant baptism with the theories which had grown out of it, and to maintain the primitive point of view according to which the normal recipients of baptism are adults, and the sins which are forgiven through the sacrament are the actual sins committed by the neophytes in their past lives. The only work dealing at any length with the theology of baptism which Gregory has bequeathed to us declares that the new-made Christian ascending from the baptismal font is as free from accusations and penalites as the new-born babe >—a statement which is a formal 1 Note the first appearance of a sixth ‘ crucial issue,’ which will in our subsequent discussions have to be considered together with the five defined at the beginning of Lecture 1V—namely, the eschatological issue, ‘ What is the future fate of those who die subject to the consequences of the Fall, without having in this life consciously obtained redemption through Christ and in His Church ?’ 2 This view is developed in a rhetorical and elusive passage too long to quote (op. cit., PG XLVI. 177 A-180 D), the gist of which is that the soul of an infant who has died before attaining the age of reason will enjoy a beatitude proportionate to its capacities, very much less than that to which the adult saint may look forward, but nevertheless true beatitude ; it is suggested that such child-spirits may progressively grow in the know- ledge of God until they eventually attain to full mental and spiritual maturity. * For references v. infra, Lecture V, p. 377, n. 1. 4 Gregory does not condemn even hardened adult sinners (much less innocent babes) to never-ending hell ; for his usual teaching makes ‘ hell’ merely a temporary purgatory, which will end in the universal droxatdoraas or restoration in which he had learned from Origen to believe ; see Barden- hewer, Patrology, p. 303 f. 5 in baptism. Christi (PG XLVI. 579 D): os yap ro evOdToKov madiov eAcvbepov eotw éyKAnudtav Kal TyLwpidv, oUTwWS Kal 6 THS avayervicews mais ovK Exet mepi Tivos amoAoynHaerat, Bacwixh Swped Tadv evdvrav aPpeleis. 280 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN contradiction of the doctrine of ‘ Original Guilt,’ and may even be thought to undermine the necessity of infant baptism itself. (4) Although Gregory nowhere attempts an explicit definition of the manner in which the ‘ weakness’ or ‘ ail- ment’ of human nature is transmitted from generation to generation, we may conclude with reasonable certainty that Gregory regarded the transmission as taking place by way of biological, and not merely of ‘social,’ heredity. This conclusion would seem to be an inevitable inference from the use of the first person plural in verbs referring to the Fall (an idiom which, as in previous writers, betrays the subconscious influence of the idea of ‘ recapitulation ’), from Gregory’s ‘traducianist’ conception of the origin of the soul, } and from the phrases which declare sin, or the impulse to sin, to be knit up with man’s constitution, especially with his bodily constitution.? It is indirectly confirmed by the statement, apparently based upon a suggestion of Methodius, that man was made subject to physical death in order that his spiritual nature might be freed from inherent sinfulness and become capable of receiving the resurrection body, just as an earthenware vessel into which some malicious person has poured molten lead must be broken up before the alien matter can be removed and the fragments recompounded into a new vessel. We may glance in passing at the curious fancy that the multiplicity of mankind is itself an evil, and that it would have been better if the archetypal man had continued to subsist in his pure intellectual unity and uniqueness °; this, however, is an irrelevant piece of un- 1 de hom. opif. 29 (PG XLIV. 233 D ff.). 2 e.g. ov. cat. 35 (Sr. p. 134, 15): dv adv éxdveral mws 6 avOpwmos THs m™pos TO Kakov ovupdvias: de vita Moysis (PG XLIV. 336): Tov THY GuapTHTLKHY Hudv dvow TeptBadAdpevov: ibid. (756): 6 Kowwvdv THs pvoews TOb Adap, kowwvadv b€ kal THs exmtTdaews: in ps. (PG XLIV. 609) : 7) Gwapria 7 cuvarroTiKTopern TH dvoer. For the connexion of con- genital wickedness with the body, v. supra, p. 276, n. 2. C) USSUPTA, Di 252 Tas. $vorviicaine (Sricp. 44919): 5 Such is the apparent implication of a sentence in de an. et vesurr. (PG XLVI. 157 A): 6 yap mp&ros ordxvs 6 mpatos avOpwros Fv "Addy (Gregory is fancifully embroidering upon St. Paul’s comparison of the resurrection of the body to the growth of corn from the seed, in 1 Cor. xv). GAN everd) TH TAS Kakias claddm eis TARIOS H Pdats KaTepeplao4y THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 281 digested neo-Platonism, which bears no organic relation to Gregory’s other speculations upon evil in man. (5) The resulting state of human nature, infected as it is by ‘ weakness’ and the ‘impulse to sin,’ is one of dis- integration and destruction. Yet, though the objective and ex opere operato aspects of Redemption, and, by impli- cation, the presupposed need and helplessness of man, are brought into strong relief by the vividly realistic conception of ‘ deification’’ through the Eucharist, in which Gregory’s soteriology culminates, no diminution is admitted in the fullness of man’s endowment of free-will. Whatever the strength of our innate propension towards evil, it is not so strong that we cannot overcome it if we choose ; whatever the power of sacramental grace, it does not dispense us from the necessity of spiritual effort in order to its fruitful appropriation. We may conclude this review of Gregory’s speculations about human nature and congenital sinfulness by drawing attention to the tentative and provisional character which he expressly attributes to them. ‘Some such explanation as the following have we received from the Fathers ’ 1—“‘ we, imagining the truth as far as we can by means of conjectures and similitudes, do not set forth that which occurs to our mind authoritatively, but will place it in the form of a theoretical exercise before our kindly hearers’ *?—‘ here, again, the true answer, whatever it may be, can be clear to those only who, like Paul, have been initiated into the mysteries of Paradise; but ourv answer is as follows’? x. tT. A. The idea that multiplicity as such is evil appears in Plotinus, Enn. vi.6,1: Gp’ €ore 70 7AHV0s andaracts Tob Evds, Kal 4 ameElpia amdoTaAcLS mavtTeAns TH 7TARVos avdpiOpov elvar, Kal dua TobTO KaKov 7 amretpia Kal ypeis Kaxol, orav mANOos ; 1 ov. cat. 6 (Sr. p. 28, 15): Tovotrdv twa Adyov mapa tTav maTrépwr dvedeEdueOa: this formula reminds us of the phrase with which Plato’s Critias introduces the Myth of Atlantis—éeyw dpdow madadv axnxows Adyov ov véov avopds (Timaeus, 21 A). 2 de hom. opif. 16 (PG XLIV. 185 A): pets Sé, nabds é€ore Suvaror, dua oToxaopav Tivwv Kal eikovwv davtacbevtes THY aAnOevav, TO Emi vobv €ADov ovuK amodavTikas exTiOépeba, GAN’ ws ev yupvacias etder Tots edyvmpoor TaY aKkpowpevwy mpoobjcoper. 8 ibid. 17 (PG XLIV. 188 B): aAd ev rovtos wddw 6 pH adndijs Adyos, cotis moTe My TUyXavEL, Lovous GV Ein SHAos Tots Kata IIabAov Ta TOb mapadeicov 47 >e punOetow amoppnta’ 6 dé yyeTEpos TOLObTEs €oTLY. 282 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN —these are the formulae with which he introduces the subtle though unsystematised ideas which have been summarised above. The Adam-tradition exists, and he admits its general claim upon his allegiance; but the philosopher’s stone of allegorism enables him to transmute its pictorial details into metaphysical or psychological concepts, and he uses this power with great freedom. It is clear that there is as yet no question of a stereotyped ecclesiastical dogma. (6) St. Gregory of Nazianzus (b. A.D. 329, d. c. 390). Before we finally leave the field of unsystematised and incoherent speculations presented by the writings of the Greek Fathers, and turn to the swift, consistent, and logical development of the ‘ African’ or Western version of the Fall-doctrine, the third remaining doctor of the Cappadocian group claims our attention—Gregory of Nazianzus, ‘ the Theologian’ far excellence as Eastern Christendom has loved to style him, and the intimate friend of the brothers Basil and Gregory of Nyssa, whose thoughts with regard to the origin and ground of sin have just been reviewed. Like his predecessors, this Father has bequeathed to us no single treatise dealing with the subject of our enquiry, and his ideas about the Fall and its consequences have to be gathered from incidental allusions scattered through works dealing with other doctrinal questions. It cannot be claimed that his doctrine exhibits any advance upon that of his two friends, in respect either of definition or of synthesisation; its interest lies partly in the testi- mony which it bears to the existence and solidity of a ‘“once-born’ and non-Western type of Fall-theory, or Fall-speculation, during the last pre-Augustinian century, and partly in its employment as a spear-head, not so much against theological dualism (its traditional foe) as, in the more restricted area of Christology, against the Apollinarian tenet of the imperfection or incompleteness of the Lord’s human nature. This peculiar Christological bearing imposed by Gregory upon the Fall-doctrine will be explained in the course of our survey of his allusions to the doctrine—a survey which may follow the familiar THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 283 land-marks of the ‘ five crucial issues,’ or such of them as emerge in his writings.? A convenient starting-point for our study of this Father’s opinions on the subject of our enquiry is provided by a passage occurring in the last of his sermons, preached, after his retirement from the see of Constantinople, at the village of Arianzus, one Easter Day not long before his death.? The purpose of this discourse is to glorify the Resurrection of Christ by exhibiting it in its context, as a supreme moment in the whole process of God’s dealings with His universe and with man. The first portion of it, therefore, is devoted to the topics of Creation and the Fall. The preacher distinguishes sharply between the creation of the ‘intelligible world,’ the world, that is, of Platonic Ideas or eternal values, and that of the ‘sensible’ or phenomenal world. He continues : Mind, then, and sense, thus distinguished from each other, had remained within their own boundaries, and bore in them- selves the magnificence of the Creator-Word, silent praisers and thrilling heralds of His mighty work. Not yet was there any mingling of both, nor any mixture of these opposites, tokens of a greater wisdom and generosity in the creation of natures; nor as yet were the whole riches of goodness made known. Now the Creator-Word, determining to exhibit this, and to produce a single living being out of both (the invisible and visible natures, I mean), fashions Man; and taking the body from already existing matter, and placing in it a Breath taken from Himself (which the Word knew to be an intelligent soul, and the image of God), He placed him on the earth as a sort of second world, a microcosm,? a new Angel, a mingled worshipper, fully initiated into the mysteries of the visible creation, but only partially into those of the intelligible creation *—king of all upon earth, but subject to the King above ; earthly and heavenly ; temporal and yet immortal ; visible and yet intelligible ; midway between greatness and lowliness; in one person combining spirit and 1 Quotations are taken from the Paris edition of 1840, ‘ post operam et studium monachorum O.S.B. e congreg. 5S. Mauri’ ; references to the volume and page of this are given in brackets. 2 ov. xlv. (i. 845) in sanctum Pascha. ‘The Benedictine editor dates this Oration c. A.D. 385. 8 ofdv twa Kdopmov ETepov, ev puxp@ peyav. The idea may have been suggested by the account of the creation of man in Plato’s Timaeus. 4 endntyy THs Oparis Kticews, wvoTnv THs voouperys. 284 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN flesh, spirit because of God’s favour, flesh because of his exalta- tion . . . a living creature, governed by God’s providence here, but in process of translation to another sphere, and—to crown the mystery—in process of being deified through its natural inclination towards God! ... Him [that is, Man] God placed in Paradise—whatever that Paradise may have been 2—having honoured him with the gift of free-will, in order that good might belong to him as the result of his choice, no less than to Him Who had provided the seeds thereof, as a husbandman of immortal plants, that is, perhaps, of Divine concepts, both the simpler and the more perfect —naked in his simplicity and in his inartificial way of life, and devoid of any covering or defence ; for such it was fitting that the original man should be... Now the Tree [of Knowledge] was Con- templation * (as I see the matter), which can be safely climbed only by those who are of a more perfect and settled character ; but it is not good for those who are simple-minded and of a somewhat greedy appetite, just as perfect (7.e. solid) nourishment is not profitable for those who are yet tender and stand in need of milk. But when by the envy of the devil and the caprice of the woman (that caprice which she both suffered, as being the more tender, and inspired, as being the more persuasive)—alas for my weakness! for that of my first father 1s mine °>—he forgot the commandment which had been given to him, and was worsted by the baneful taste; and for his wickedness was banished at once from the Tree of Life, from Paradise, and from God, and was clothed with the coats of skins, 1 lHov evrabba oixovopovpevov, Kat dAdaxod peOordpevov, Kal, wépas Tob pvotnplov, TH mpos Gedv vevoer Geovpevov. 2 Garis mote hv 6 Tapadevaos odTOs. 3 dutdv abavdtwv yewpyov, Jeiwy évvordy tows, THv Te GTAOVOTEpwY Kal THY TEAEWTEPwY, The comparison between ideas and growing plants is one which seems naturally to suggest itself to the mystical genius; cf. Keats, Ode to Psyche : ‘ Yes, I will be thy priest, and build a fane In some untrodden region of my mind, Where branchéd thoughts, new-grown with pleasant pain, Instead of pines shall murmur in the wind’ ; and Francis Thompson, The Hound of Heaven: “ And now my heart is as a broken fount, Wherein tear-drippings stagnate, spilt down ever From the dank thoughts that shiver Upon the sighful branches of my mind.’ 4 Oewpia yap hv TO putov. 5 ded ris euts aobeveias’ eu yap 7 Tod mpomaropos (a phrase which contains a suggestion of ‘ Original Guilt’; v. infra, p. 289, n. 2). THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH) 285 that 1s, perhaps, the coarser kind of flesh, which is both mortal and impatient of control.” A cursory survey of this passage will show that in it our author raises the first of the ‘ cardinal issues,’ that of the allegorical as opposed to the literal interpretation of the Scriptural narrative. Closer investigation, however, reveals the fact that this first issue is not presented to the reader in clear-cut isolation, but is intertwined with the second— namely, the question of the original state of man. At first sight, a single consistent scheme of ideas, based upon an allegorical exegesis, and displaying clearly marked affinities with Origen’s later or ‘ Caesarean’ presentation of the Fall- doctrine, seems to run through the passage. The expression “whatever that Paradise may have been’ suggests that the ‘garden ’ is not to be interpreted as a literal plot of ground, but as an exalted state? ; and, in view of the sublimation of the flowers of Eden into ‘ Divine concepts,’ this state can hardly be other than a transcendental state of existence on the plane of the intelligible world. With such an interpre- tation of the Paradise-story coheres the ascription of super- human and angelic prerogatives to the primal man, and the allegorisation of the Tree of Knowledge as ‘ contempla- tion’; though it is to be noticed that Gregory seems here to have introduced an ingenious variant into the Origenian scheme (doubtless in order to make type and antitype correspond more exactly), representing the first sin as consisting, not in man’s turning away through ‘ satiety ’ from privileges of contemplation which he already possessed, but in his premature grasping at privileges which he did not possess and for which he was, even in his primitive glory, not sufficiently prepared. The explanation of the ‘ coats of skins’ given here is in a general sense cognate with the 1 rods Seppativous audievvuTa yitavas, laws TY TmaxvTépav odpKa: Cf. carmen de anima 115 (il. p. 248) : Sepparivous dé xiTa&vas Edéacaro odpxa Bapetay vexpodopos. 2 op. cit. 7, 8 (slightly abbreviated). The translation given above is largely based on that of C. G. Browne and J. E. Swallow (Select Library of Nicene and Post-Nicene Fathers, 1894). I have italicised phrases of special doctrinal interest. 3 Cf. carmen de anima, 105 (ii. p. 246): fw 5” odpavin wéAerar mapddevoos Eporye. 286 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN explanations given by Origen and Gregory of Nyssa ; though the Nazianzene’s statement that these garments may sym- bolise ‘ a coarser flesh ’ implies that unfallen man possessed flesh of some kind, presumably of a more subtle, tenuous, or ethereal consistency. Nevertheless, the three notable allegorisations to which we have drawn attention (of the plants of Paradise, the Tree of Knowledge, and the ‘ coats of skins ’) are introduced with expressions of hesitancy (‘ perhaps’ and ‘as I see the matter’); and there are other statements which seem to presuppose a more literal view of the Scriptural narrative. We are told that man was placed ‘on the earth,’ though ‘in process of translation to another sphere’; that he was only ‘ partially initiated’ into the mysteries of the ideal world ; that he was naked of covering and defence, and led a simple and artless life. Mention is, moreover, made of the detail of his temptation by the woman. All this is strongly reminiscent of the earliest Greek presentation of the Fall-theory, as we found it in Tatian, Theophilus, and Irenaeus, according to which man as originally created was a ‘ babe,’ ‘ capable of either good or evil,’ but possessed of a ‘starting-point for progress.’ The conclusion to which we seem to be driven is that Gregory’s thoughts on this subject represent a purely mechanical and inconsistent juxtaposition of the earlier pre-Origenian, and of the later or post-Origenian tendencies of Hellenic Fall-speculation— of the primitive theory which views the first sin as the failure of an infantile being to pursue the upward course of develop- ment which God had marked out for him, and of the later conception, which vaguely emerges during the fourth century, of an archetypal man or collective race-spirit who falls from an exalted, possibly a metaphysical, Paradise. It should be noted, however, that Gregory Nazianzen, like all the great Greek Fathers of the fourth and succeeding centuries, unequivocally condemns Origen’s first or ‘ Alexandrine ’ view, that of the pre-natal life and sin of the individual soul? ; and few candid students will fail to be 1 Cf. p. 271 ff. (Gregory of Nyssa). 2 Or, XXXVii. 15 (i. p. 655). The name of Origen is not mentioned, but the theory is condemned as Aiav Gromop Kal obK ExxAnavaoTiKdr. THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH = 287 impressed by the instinctive repulsion with which the under- lying mind of the Christian society rejected a theory which was felt to be an infiltration from alien sources, despite the extreme fluidity and indeterminateness of its own Adamic tradition. Gregory's language with regard to the third issue, that of the precise nature of the sorrowful legacy of the Fall, is tantalisingly vague. We are told that as the result of Adam’s transgression mankind has become subject to a ‘newly sown curse,’ ! to death, to sin, to a “ heavy yoke ’ of toil and trouble 2 ; but, for the most part, no effort is made to define the undesirable thing, quality, or status, of which trouble, death, and sin are the symptoms. There seems to be only one passage which gives us even a momentary glimpse into his real mind with regard to this point; it occurs in the poem entitled A sorrowful song on the calamities of hits own soul, and forms the conclusion of a lamentation over the internal conflict between reason and appetite which torments the author—a lamentation which may be described as the substance of Rom. vii. 7-24 hammered out into somewhat pedestrian elegiac couplets. We will venture upon the following metrical rendering : Often our earth owns the sway of the Mind: yet, captive unwilling, Often the Mind in its turn follows the might of the Flesh. Yea, though it yearn for the good, it accomplisheth that which it hateth, Mourning its direful fate, held in calamitous thrall, Mourning our ancient father’s offence, and the sin of our mother, Word that she spake in guile, mother of frenzy distraught : Mourning the impious lie of the crooked bloodthirsty serpent, Who in the crimes of men taketh his fiendish delight ; Mourning the fatal Tree, and the fruit bringing ruin to mortals, Taste whereof setteth man e’en fore the gates of the grave, 1 carmina, i. (poemata theologica), sect. i. 8 (de anima), line 128 f. (ii. p. 248) : toin mpwroydvoto vedamopos HAvOev arn devAotow pepdmecow, d0ev ordyus €BAdatyoe. 2 ibid. ii. (poemata historica), sect. ii. 1 (ad Hellenium), line 345 f. (ii. p. 1014) : ovx dArts, orte Bporotor Bapdv Cuydv Ayaye mparn apxeyovov Kaxin, Kal dutov avdpoddvor ; 288 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN Nakedness shameful of limbs, and banishment dreary from Eden, Far from the Tree of Life, heaping dishonour on loss.} It is clear that our author here conceives the Fall to be the historical cause of the moral struggle within himself ; in other words, that the legacy of the Fall is to be identified with inordinate or hypertrophied appetite, as indeed St. Paul had already taught by implication in the chapter which is the basis of these lines. But the term ‘ hypertrophied,’ as applied to appetite, must necessarily be relative to some norm or standard, and the ‘normal’ amount of appetite must, presumably, be that which is capable of being con- trolled by the will. ‘Hypertrophy of appetite’ is thus merely a synonym for ‘atrophy of will’; the phrases represent different aspects of the same psychic fact, as ‘convex ’ and ‘ concave’ represent different aspects of the same geometric fact. We may therefore claim that the underlying conception revealed in these lines is that of the inherent infirmity of human nature as consisting in “ con- genital weakness of will’—the same conception which Methodius and Athanasius had endeavoured to express under the figure of metaphysical ‘ disintegration.’ Did Gregory hold the theory of ‘ Original Guilt’? Certain phrases occurring in his works seem at first sight to imply that he did. These phrases include some very definite and forcible assertions of our unity and solidarity with the Adam who fell: typical of them is the following : 1 carmina, li. (poemata historica), sect. i. 45, lines 95-107 (il. p. 922) : GdAXoTte pev Te vow xods Sduvarar' adAdote 8 adte oapKl voos KpaTteph EomreTar ovK €Oédwy. GAAa 7d prev mobeer, Td ye BéATEpov' 46 atvyéer Sé Epdwv, SovAoov’ynv pvpeTrar apyadenv, maTpos T apxeydvoto mAdvynv, Kal untpos adAtTpHy mappacw, NMETEpNS NTEpa papyoovns, Kal oxoAoto SpaKxovtos atdabaXov aipoBdporo weddos, 6s avOpmrwv Tépmerar autAakias, Kal Evrov, 76€ dutotio Bpotav SynAjpova Kapmov yedoiy 7 odrAopevnv, Kai POavdro.o mvAas, yUpvwow perewv te mavaicyea, Kal mapadeicou 75€ putot Cwis pibw dripotarny. It may perhaps be claimed for the versions of Gregory’s lines given in the text that they are not more prosaic than the originals. THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 289 we were re-created, not an individual here and there, but all of us who partook of the same Adam, who were deceived by the serpent, were slain by sin, were saved once more by the heavenly Adam, and by the Tree of shame were brought back to the Tree of Life, from whence we have fallen.? Together with this may be grouped many other instances of the use of the first person plural (‘ we’) and even of the first person singular (‘ I’) 2—in verbs expressing the idea of the primal sin. The impression created by these turns of phraseology, that Gregory was at least inclined to play with the idea of ‘ Original Guilt,’ is to a certain extent reinforced by passages which speak of the human race as ‘condemned’ for Adam’s fault. But against these references we must set his treatment of infant baptism, any consideration of which must always force the question of the reality of ‘ Original Guilt’ to the front: the crucial passage is, again, to be found in one of his poetical compositions. He tells us that God has provided many helps for our fickle and wayward nature : Whereof the Laver is one, fount of grace ; for, e’enas the Hebrew Children escaped the destroyer, by virtue of blood’s dread anointing Cleansing the posts of the doors, what time all the first-born of Egypt Fell in the self-same night of alarm, so also meseemeth 1 OY. XXXili. 9 (i. p. 609): adta ra ypiorod 7aOn, du” Ov aveTrAdoOnpev, odx 6 pev, 6 8 ov, mavtes S€é of Tod adrod "Adam petacydvtes, Kal bm Tot 6dews mapadoy.obevtes, Kal TH apaptia Oavatwhévtes, Kat dia TOD emovpaviov "Adayu avaowévres, Kal mpos To EvAov THs Cwhs éemavaybevtes, 81a Tod EvVAov THs atupias, ev dmomeTTwKapev. 2 e.g. OY. X1X. 14 (i. p. 372),a paragraph in which every sentence contains thisidiom ; ov. xxii. 13 (i. p. 422): éeyphv yap, émerd7 Oedrns Wvwrat, Svatpetobas THY avOpwrdTnTa, Kal mept TOV vody avonTtaivew Tods TaAAa addous, Kal 7 6Aov pe aodlecfa, dAov mtaicavta Kal Kataxpibévra ex THS TOO mpwromAdoTov mapakons (a piece of anti-Apollinarian sarcasm; v. infra, p.291 f); ov. xlv. 8 (i. p. 851) : ded THs eufis aobevelas’ eur yap 4 Too mpomdropos (quoted above, p. 284, n. 5); ib7d.9 (i. p. 852): petéAaBov ris efkdvos (sc. Tob Geob) Kat ovK epvAata: ibid. 12 (i. p. 854) : meadvras Huds ex THs auaptias TO am apy%s. 3 e.g. OY. XXXvii. 4 (i. p. 665): Kal ef yeBous KaTEKpLVE, TOOW UGAXov TO xptorov mabeiy edixaiwoev: and or. Xxxix. 13 (i. p. 685) : ovrws 6 véos "Add tov madav avacdonta, Kat AvOG TO KaTaKpLLA THS oapKos. Notice also the word xaraxpiOévra in or. xxii. 13 (quoted above). U 290 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN Here is the Seal of God our defender, for innocent infants Only a Seal, but for grown men a Seal and a Remedy potent.+ The significance of the last two lines will be translucently clear, and doubtless, to those who have been accustomed to assume that Augustinianism is Catholicism, somewhat startling: for the poet draws a sharp distinction between the effects of Adult and those of Infant Baptism, affirming the former to include both dedication to God and remission of sin, but the latter to consist in dedication only—which is precisely the position maintained by the Pelagians in the next century.2_ Evidently our author knows nothing of the idea that newly born babes are, simply in virtue of their human nature, born guilty of the sin of Adam. This con- clusion is reinforced by the fact that, like his friend and namesake of Nyssa,? he decides the ‘ eschatological issue ’ (which, as we have seen, was now beginning to emerge) by means of the hypothesis of Limbo *—another idea which was advocated by the Pelagians, and as strenuously denounced by the Africans.® It will therefore be safest to assume (as in the case of Athanasius, Basil, and Gregory of Nyssa) that the phrases mentioned above, which identify ‘ us’ 1 caymina, i. (poemata theologica), sect. i. 9 (de testamentis et adventu Christt), lines 87-92 (ii. p. 252) : av é&v Kal Noetpoto Bpotots ydpis* ws yap dA€eOpov ‘EBpaiwy moré maides bréxpuyov aipate ypioTa, TO Aids exdOnpev, 67 dArETO Tpwroyéeve Aros Aiyvmrov yeven vuKtl pif, Os Kal Emouye adpnyis ade~txdxoro Beod 7d8€, vnmiadyots pev od¢pnyis, de€opévorce 8’ adkos Kai odpnyis apioryn. (I do not understand the lengthening of the last syllable of vuxri in line 90, but give the line as it stands in the Paris edition.) 2 v. infra, Lecture V, p. 345. 3 vu. supra, p. 279. 4 or. xl. 23 (i. p. 708): rods dé (that is, those who have not been able to receive baptism 61a vymidrnra—this implies that there were still some parts of the Church where paedobaptism was unknown—or through some other involuntary cause) pyre dofacOjcecbar pjnre KoAacbjcecbar mapa Tod duxaiov KpiTod, ws doppaylorous ev atovipous Sé, dAAa wabdvras paAdov thy Cnpiav (1.e. the lack of baptism) 7 dpdcavras. 08d yap darts od KoAdcews agévos, 45n Kal Tynfs’ Womep obd€ Gots od Timfs, 7Sn Kal KoAdcews. I use the term Limbo in the text as a convenient anachronism for expressing the idea of a future state which is one neither of punishment nor of glory. 5 vw. infra; Lecture, V} p.348,2D. 2. THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 2o1 with Adam, are no more than highly rhetorical assertions of the theory of ‘ Recapitulation.’ It will have become clear in the course of our review that the idea of ‘ Original Guilt "—if considered in abstraction from its psychological grounds in the self-condemnation of the ‘ twice-born’ saint or converted rake—may be said to have two main logical antecedents, namely, the conception of ‘ Recapitulation ’ (which, if pressed, easily converts itself into ‘ seminal identity ’), and the belief that baptism is always ‘ for the remission of sins,’ even when administered to unconscious infants. But we have seen that Gregory did not hold the latter view: and, if allowance be made for the vivid modes of expression natural to an Asian orator, there will be no reason for supposing that he had in his own mind pressed the former to its logical conclusion. Gregory, then, though not a believer in ‘ Original Guilt,’ is an enthusiastic ‘ recapitulationist.’ In the light of this fact his opinions with regard to the fourth and fifth of the cardinal issues become easily intelligible. The means whereby ‘ weakness of will’ is transmitted cannot, for a believer in ‘ Recapitulation,’ be anything other than physio- logical heredity.1. And his characteristic opinion with regard to the present state of human nature is this—that man’s intellect (vots), as well as his will, emotions, and physical constitution, has suffered deterioration through the Fall. It is here that he brings the Fall-doctrine to bear upon the Apollinarian controversy. Adam sinned with his mind first of all, in that he mentally denied the supreme claim of God’s command upon his loyalty and obedience. Hence, in virtue of Adam’s ‘ recapitulation’ of humanity within himself, the human mind as such became in some undefined manner subject to the consequences of the Fall. Gregory never faces the question, What precisely are the consequences of the Fall in the purely mental sphere? but we may suppose that he means in a general sense error and delusion. In order, therefore, that man as a whole might be redeemed, it was necessary that the Saviour should assume human intellectual faculties together with the rest LOY euLOos 292 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN of man’s nature! ; ‘ for that which was not assumed could not have been healed.’ 2 We need only point out, without commenting upon, the fact that the conception of redemption here pre-supposed appears, as in the writings of Athanasius and Gregory of Nyssa, to be that of union with the Incarnate Logos, and ultimate ‘ deification,’ through sacramental reception of Him in the Eucharist. This is not, indeed, expressly stated : but it is difficult, if not impossible, to see how the assumption by the Logos of a human vois could have the effect of Redeeming the vots of mankind in general, unless the final ‘recapitulation’ of our race in Christ is conceived as con- summated through the sacramental incorporation of its wayward and sinful individuals into Him. It may, indeed, be said that healing and sanctification through sacraments constitute the goal to which the medical way of conceiving ‘innate sinfulness’ favoured by Greek thought naturally leads, just as juridical absolution and ‘ justification ’ are the end which the forensic conception more congenial to the Latin mind presupposes. iL HEP DEVI STARIGHTS : If Gregory of Nazianzus died in A.D. 390, as seems most probable, the end of his life may be regarded as roughly synchronising with the beginning of Augustine’s Christian career ° ; so that the consideration of his writings forms the natural terminus ad quem for the present section of our enquiry. We may appropriately pause at this point, before taking up the thread of the ‘African’ or ‘ twice-born’ development of the Fall-tradition, to explain our deliberate 1 The classical passages for this anti-Apollinarian use of the Fall- doctrine are to be found in the two Epistles to Cledonius, epp. ci., cil. (ii. p. 83 ff) ; cf. also ov. xxii. 13 (i. p. 422), a partof which is quoted above (p. 289, n. 2), and carmen de se ipso, line 167 ff. (ii. p. 874) : réuvovar 8’, ws fedv ov, Kat Beot péyay Bporov (i.e. ‘ exalted humanity’) dvow tibévtes, ws dvov "Adam memtwkoros. 2 ep. ci. (ii. p. 87): 76 yap ampdcdrnmrov, abepdmevtov’ 6 Sé Hrwra TO 6G, rodro Kai owerar: a celebrated epigram which Tixeront (op. cit. ii. p. 115) justly describes as a ‘ sentence lapidaire.’ 3 Augustine was baptised in A.D. 387. THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 203 omission of any mention of a theory which may well appear at first sight to form an integral part of the subject-matter of our research, and which exercised a powerful influence over Christian soteriology for a thousand years—the theory, namely, that by virtue of Adam’s sin the Devil acquired legal or quasi-legal rights of property over mankind, rights which the justice of God forbade Him to disregard and which consequently had to be bought out in some way or other. On this was founded the popular view of the Atonement, which saw in the death of Christ the payment of His life as a “ransom’ to the Devil, designed to induce the latter to surrender his commercially conceived interest in the posses- sion of human souls. The soteriological scheme so consti- tuted can claim the support of many illustrious teachers, belonging both to Eastern and to Western Christendom, amongst whom may be enumerated Irenaeus (its apparent originator *), Origen (though he may not have regarded it as much more than an elaborate metaphor), Basil, Gregory of Nyssa, Tertullian, Augustine; though sturdy protests were raised against it by the otherwise unknown author Adei- mantius, Gregory of Nazianzus, and John of Damascus.? We have left this once popular theory on one side—not so much because of its bizarre and mythological nature, or of the childishly immoral idea to which it gave birth, that of a trick played by God upon the Devil in offering him Christ’s Humanity as his prey without telling him that it veiled the Godhead—nor yet because of the fact that 1 Detailed histories of the growth of this theory may be found in H. Rashdall, The Idea of Atonement in Christian Theology (1919), pp. 243 ff., 259, 303 ff., 311, 313, 332; J. Riviére, Le dogme de la rédemption, I. (Essat d étude historique) (1905), cc. xxi-xxiv. See also A. Ritschl, Rechifertigung und Verséhnung (1882),i. pp. 16-19, and A. Sabatier, La doctrine del expiation et son Evolution historique (1903), p. 47 ff. 2 Rashdall (op. cit. p. 245) suggests that this theory may have been derived by Irenaeus from the doctrine of Marcion. According to the latter “it was because, by bringing about the death of Jesus, the God of the Jews —the generally just but not benevolent Demiurge—had violated his own laws, that it became just for the true and benevolent God to set man free from the Demiurge.’ Rashdall adds ‘ Irenaeus simply substituted the devil for the Demiurge.’ The dualistic affinities of the conception are in any case obvious. 3 So Rashdall (p. 259, n. 1). 4 For references, see the works of Rashdall and Riviere, mentioned above. 294 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN Anselm’s Cur Deus homo eventually drove it from the field of Christian thought, so that, whether or not it was ever believed ubique, it cannot even assert a claim to fulfil the test of semper ; but rather because it is completely unknown to the New Testament. Though our Lord speaks of men as subject to the domination of evil spirits,| He gives no countenance to the monstrous notion of the Devil’s ‘ rights’ ; the power of Satan is always regarded by Him as a lawless usurpation. Nor does He anywhere connect the beginnings of such usurpation with the sin of Adam; if the simile of the “house swept and garnished’ may be pressed, He affirms them rather to be due to the folly or weakness of the individual. The theory is merely a mistaken inference from the use of the word ‘ ransom’ in Mark x. 45, and forms an apt illustration of the dangers involved in riding a metaphor to death. It is a parasite on, and not an organic branch of, the genuine and Pauline Fall-tradition, only deserving of notice in so far as its tenacious vigour is an index of the vitality inherent in the trunk to which it clings ; and we need not, therefore, complicate our history by taking further account of it. | (0) THE ‘ AFRICAN’ THEORY DOWN TO THE END OF THE PRE-AUGUSTINIAN PERIOD In accordance with the plan outlined above, our story now returns to the West and to the third century A.D., with the object of tracing the development of the more severe or ‘ twice-born’ version of the Fall-doctrine, from the ‘ point of bifurcation’ between the two presentations of this doctrine marked by the writings of Tertullian and Origen, down to the end of the pre-Augustinian period. The writers whose opinions will claim attention in this section of our narrative are Cyprian, Lactantius, Hilary of Poitiers, Ambrose, and the anonymous commentator on the Pauline Epistles known by the sobriquet of “ Ambrosiaster.’ The evidence provided by the first three of these writers may be summed up in a few sentences, whilst the last two will require a somewhat more detailed treatment, in view 1 vy. supra, Lecture III, p. 110 f. THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH = 295 of their position in time as the immediate precursors of Augustine, and of the peculiar influence which they (in par- ticular Ambrose, as the bishop who instructed and baptised Augustine) appear to have exercised upon his thought. (x) St. Cyprian (beheaded A.D. 258). The extant writings of this illustrious prelate and martyr, the third + great African lawyer to embrace Christianity, contain half a dozen or so of references to Adam’s sin and its melancholy consequences, which, whilst generally in accord with the views of Tertullian, Cyprian’s ‘master,’ 2 add no fresh developments to them. There is, however, one passage of great significance, which represents the first explicit emer- gence of the idea of ‘ Original Gwilt’ as the theoretical justification of infant baptism. We have spoken above of the stimulating influence exerted by this custom on the growth of a doctrine of birth-sin or birth-pollution ? ; and we have noted the fact that Tertullian’s elaboration of the doctrine of ‘ seminal identity,’ on the basis of his ‘ tradu- cianist ’ psychology, naturally pointed in the direction of a theory of all Adam’s descendants as hereditarily invested with the legal responsibility for his Fall, a responsibility which to the mind of a juristic theologian might seem to constitute the ‘pollution’ apparently presupposed by infant baptism. But Tertullian, hecause of his dread of increasing the possibility of ost-baptismal sin, strongly objects to paedobaptism, and hence never explicitly develops the idea of Original Guilt. Cyprian, disregarding on this point the authority of ‘the Master,’ took a step which has proved momentous for Western thought con- cerning birth-sin and baptism when he wrote his fifty-sixth Epistle, in the name of himself and of a Council of sixty-six bishops, to a certain bishop Fidus, who had thought that the baptism of an infant should be delayed until the eighth day after its birth, on the analogy of the Jewish rule regarding circumcision. Cyprian urges that, on the contrary, baptism 1 The first two were Minucius Felix and Tertullian. 2 Jerome tells us (de vivis ill. 53) that Cyprian used to spend some time every day in reading the works of Tertullian, demanding the volume from his secretary with the words ‘ da magistrum.’ 3 vu. supra, p. 220 ff. 296 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN should be administered as soon as possible after birth ; the passage of immediate interest for our purpose runs as follows : Assuredly, if the remission of sins is given even to the worst offenders and to those who have previously sinned much against God, when afterwards they have believed, and if no one is for- bidden the reception of baptism and of grace, how much more ought an infant not to be forbidden, who being newly born has committed no sin, save that being carnally born according to Adam he has by as first birth contracted the infection of the ancient death ? and, indeed, an infant approaches to receive the remission of sins more easily through this very fact, that the sins which are remitted unto him are not his own but another’s.+ Here it is clearly taught (a) that to be carnally born as a descendant of Adam involves participating in a hereditary infection by sin, (0) that the sin in question, which is remitted in baptism, is not the newly born’s own, but the sin of ‘ another ’—that is, presumably, of Adam. The thought of the passage is obviously confused, and oscillates illogically between what we have called the medical and the forensic ways of regarding sin 2; but such a confusion, as we shall see, is inherent in the idea of Original Guilt. It is certainly curious that the transgression of Adam, the guilt whereof is said to be forgiven to infants in baptism, should be described in the plural number as feccata ; but the phrase is no doubt chosen in order to avoid admitting an essential difference between the spiritual effects of infant baptism and of adult baptism, both alike conveying the vemissa peccatorum ; and if challenged on the point, Cyprian would doubtless have contended, like Augustine later,? that Adam’s primal sin 1 ep. |xiv. (Hartel’s text, in Vienna Corpus Script. Eccl. Lat. Til. 2): ‘porro autem si etiam gravissimis delictoribus et in Deum multum ante peccantibus, cum postea crediderint, remissa peccatorum datur et a baptismo adque (= atque) gratia nemo prohibetur, quanto magis pro- hiberi non debet infans qui recens natus nihil peccavit, nisi quod secundum Adam carnaliter natus contagium mortis antiquae prima nativitate con- traxit, qui ad remissam peccatorum accipiendam hoc ipso facilius accedit quod illi remittuntur non propria sed aliena peccata.’ This passage was read out, with great rhetorical effect, by St. Augustine, in the anti-Pelagian sermon preached by him on June 25, 413, in the‘ basilica Maiorum’ at Carthage (serm. ccxciv. ; cf. de gestis Pel. 25). 2 Cf. pp. 133, 241. The passage quoted above almost, but not quite, falls into the absurdity of alluding to the ‘ remission’ of an ‘ infection.’ * See Lecture V, p..364. THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 297 included within itself several distinct sins, such as pride, greediness, disobedience, and others. (2) Lactantius. Curiously enough, the fourth great member of the African succession of jurists turned theo- logians, Lucius Caecilius Firmianus Lactantius (b. c. A.D. 250, d. 325), represents, in regard to the development of Fall- speculation, an abrupt reversion to an ultra-° Hellenic ’ and “minimising ’ position comparable to that of the Alexandrine Clement. This is, perhaps, the more surprising because Lactantius appears to possess a good share of the fanati- cism characteristic of the African Church, the general tone of his treatise de mortibus persecutorum, in which he narrates with evident gusto the miserable ends of the Emperors who had oppressed the Church, being strongly reminiscent of the conclusion of Tertullian’s de spectaculis, the famous passage in which the father of African theology anticipates with glee the sight, which he expects to enjoy at the Last Day, of pagan kings and philosophers writhing in eternal flames.? Nevertheless, though in his systematic defence and exposi- tion of Christianity, divinarum institutionum libri vir, he duly narrates the substance of the Scriptural Fall-Story, he noticeably refrains from attaching any theory of ‘ Original Sin’ to it, and attributes only external and mechanical consequences to the Fall, such as man’s loss of physical immortality and of Paradise.2 His own view of the ground of human sin is that man is naturally prone to evil because of the earthly or physical elements in his nature ; and though he uses the actual phrase depravatio naturae , the depravatio is illogically regarded as inherent in the necessary conditions of man’s being.? He does not appear to face the 1 Gibbon’s comments on this passage (Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire, ed. J. B. Bury, ii. p. 27) are well known, and not unjustifiable. 2 op. cit. li. 13 ; see also epitom. div. inst.27. div. inst. ii. 15 contains an original version of the ‘ angel-story’ of Gen. vi. which asserts that the “sons of God’ were sent to earth by the Lord Himself, in order to be guardians of the human race, but that through their sin they became daemons themselves and begat daemons. 8 de iva det, c. xv. (ed. Brandt, Corpus Script. Eccl. Lat. XXVIIT) : “sic et nos ex duobus aeque repugnantibus conpacti sumus, anima et corpore: quorum alterum caelo adscribitur, quia tenue est et intractabile, alterum terrae, quia conprehensibile est: alterum solidum est et aeternum, alterum fragile atque mortale. ergo alteri bonum adhaeret, alteri malum, 298 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN fact that this position makes the Creator ultimately respon- sible for man’s sin.! The theology of Lactantius is in general somewhat eccentric and defective—he was better at attack- ing Paganism than at expounding Christianity—and it would therefore be unjustifiable to cite his words as evidence for a supposed reaction against the Fall-theory at the end of the third or the beginning of the fourth century. As in the earlier case of Clement of Alexandria, it is probably truer to suggest that even a scanty and (so to speak) grudging mention of the Adam-story, by an author whose charac- teristic positions demand the uncompromising maintenance of free-will, is an unconscious testimony to the amount of general acceptance which the Fall-theory had obtained ; though this doctrine is alien to his whole way of thinking, it is now too firmly rooted in Christian tradition for him to be able to ignore it altogether. (3) St. Hilary of Poitiers (d. A.D. 368). However this may be, it is at least certain that we have no evidence for any further development of the specifically ‘ African’ Fall- doctrine until we come to the writings of Hilary of Poitiers, in the fourth century. At this point our narrative leaves Africa, the original home of the ‘ twice-born ’ doctrine, for Western Europe, not to return until we come to consider the final formulation of this doctrine by the last and greatest of the African doctors, St. Augustine himself. The passing allusions made by Hilary to Adam’s sin and its consequences are, on the whole, in line with Tertullian’s doctrine, with the alteri lux vita iustitia, alteri tenebrae mors iniustitia. hinc extitit in hominibus naturae suae depravatio, ut esset necesse constitui legem qua possent et vitia prohiberi et virtutis officia imperari.’ (This position is described as ‘ illogical’ in the text, because a ‘ depravation’ implies a previous good state of that which has suffered the depravation.) Cc. xviii. contains an expression of the same idea—‘ sed ideo procedit in vitium, quia de terrena fragilitate permixtus non potest id quod a deo sumpsit incorruptum purumque servare.’ Lactantius, in fact, shares the view which we have already found in the Book of Job (see Lecture I, p- 17) and shall find again in the writings of Dr. F. R. Tennant (see Additional Note E.), the view, namely, that man’s moral weakness is simply due to his creaturely nature, and that there is no more to be said on the subject. 1 See Additional Note E (‘ Dr. F. R. Tennant’s Alternative Theory of the Origin of Sin’), p. 530. THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 299 important exception that ‘ traducianism ’ is emphatically repudiated. The vwitium originis® (we notice that this phrase, taken over from Tertullian, has now become all but technical) is not transmitted directly from the soul of the progenitor to the soul of the offspring, but is acquired by the newly created soul through its union with the flesh 3 ; hence the flesh is the seat of ‘ Original Sin,’ a theory which represents a return to the strictly Pauline view. But, though the mould in which the idea of ‘ seminal identity ’ had been shaped into consistency and toughness is thus discarded, the idea itself stands fast ; and there are two or three passages which seem to imply that the human race was in Adam, or was Adam, when he fell—such as the following ‘in unius Adae errore omne hominum genus aberravit.’* It is, however, clear that this Father took no very great interest in the theology of the Fall and its conse- quences, and the aggregate amount of space occupied by his few incidental allusions to the subject is almost infini- tesimal in comparison with the length of his great treatise on the Holy Trinity and of his polemical writings against the Arians. Not as an elaborator of the Fall-doctrine, but as the ally of Athanasius and the champion of the Nicene Christology in the West, did Hilary earn the titles conceded him by both East and West of Doctor and Confessor of the Church. (4) St. Ambrose (bishop of Milan, A.D. 374-397). This great man is popularly conceived as illustrious through practical rather than through intellectual gifts—as a powerful administrator, a zealous pastor, a princely prelate, a friend and on occasion a severe monitor of emperors, an organiser 1 tvact. in cxviil. ps., litt. iv.: ‘anima, quae alterius originis est, terrae corporis adhaesisse creditur’; de tvin. x. 20: ‘cum anima omnis opus Dei sit, carnis vero generatio semper ex carne sit’; ibid. 22: ‘ nunquam ab homine gignentium originibus praebetur.’ 2 tract. in cxviii. ps., litt. xiv. 20: ‘natura quidem et origo carnis suae cum detinebat : sed voluntas et religio cor eius ex eo in quo manebat oviginis vitio ad iustificationum opera declinat.’ 8 So I understand the difficult passage comm. in Matthaeum, X. 23, 24. 4 ibid. xviii. 6; the context contains what appears to be the first instance of the application of the Parable of the Lost Sheep to the Fall of man. Cf. also tract. in cxxxvi. ps. 5: ‘ quisquis ergo in crimine primi parentis Adae exsulem se factum illius Sion recordabitur .. .2; 2bid. 7: ‘qui in Adam extorres se factos esse caelestis Ierusalem meminerunt.’ 300 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN of liturgical worship, rather than as a learned doctor or subtle theologian. It is doubtless true that no one original en- richment of Christian thought can be placed to his credit : but the part which he played in the elaboration of the ‘maximising’ version of the Fall-doctrine was of no little importance, inasmuch as in his mind the cardinal elements of this version were for the first time assembled and held side by side, though not yet wrought into a single coherent unity. Though his writings do not contain a systematic treatise on the doctrine of the Fall (the book de paradiso is rather a mystical commentary on the whole narrative of Gen. ii. and iii. than an exposition of the ‘ Fall’ in particular), yet his numerous allusions to the subject when collected together give us an ultra-‘ African’ type of Fall-theory, which may not unreasonably be described as Augustinianism before Augustine. If we remember that it was in great part the attraction of Ambrose’s majestic personality which drew Augustine through his great spiritual crisis to Catholic Christianity, and the hand of Ambrose which baptised and anointed him,! we shall find it difficult not to believe that the brilliant young neophyte must have drunk in Ambrose’s teaching on the Fall together with the rest of his dogmatic exposition of the Faith, through private catechetical instruction or through the homilies which the great bishop was accustomed to deliver in the basilica of Milan and to which the not-yet-converted Augustine listened entranced. If this is so, the place occupied by Ambrose in the history of the ‘maximising’ Fall-doctrine may be defined as that of the workman who collected the materials out of which the more gifted master-builder Augustine constructed the finished edifice. Ambrose is the first of the Latin Fathers to teach in unequivocal terms the doctrine of the ‘ Original Righteous- ness’ or ‘ Perfection’ of man, an idea which seems to be the necessary starting-point of the ‘maximising’ Fall- theory, considered as a logical scheme; for only if the , original state of man be made one of unqualified perfection and bliss is it possible to represent the primal transgression 1 Cf. S. Aug. Conf. v. 13,14; vi. 4; ix. 5; c.Iulian.i. 4,10; op. imp. c. Iulian. i. 2. THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH - 301 as a sin against the fullest possible ight, as an act of wanton, unmotived, inexcusable malice, and therefore as invested with an infinite degree of guilt. He tells us that Adam in Paradise was a ‘ heavenly being,’ 1 ‘ breathing ethereal air,’ ? like unto an angel,? exempt from the cares and weariness of this life,” resplendent with celestial grace and accustomed to speak face to face with God,* endowed from the moment of his creation with that perfect balance of reason, will, and appetite ° which fallen man can only recover by painful effort and the continuous assistance of the Holy Spirit.® It is a remarkable fact that this Rabbinical figment was, | as we have already pointed out, being propagated by Gregory of Nyssa in the East just about the same time that Ambrose appeared as its champion in the West ’7: and it would seem probable that the same ultimate cause lay behind both of these happenings, namely, the invisible pressure of the second great wave of Oriental dualism which was then silently flooding Europe, Manicheism. We have already, in speaking of Gnosticism, called attention to the reaction which the impact of dualistic theories tends to stimulate within the Church: the affirmation of the co-eternity of good and evil inevitably drives the mind of the Christian society back upon the principle implied in its fundamental 1 in ps. cxvili. expos. serm. xv. 36: “‘ Adam cum in paradiso esset coelestis erat.’ 2 ibid. iv. 5: ‘ beatissimus auram carpebat aetheream, curas vitae huius et taedia nesciebat.’ 3 de parad. ix. 42. 4 in ps. xlilil. enarr. 75: ‘in conspectu Dei erat Adam, in paradiso vigebat, coelesti gratia refulgebat, loguebatur cum Deo.’ 5 expos. ev. sec. Luc. vii. 142: ‘ quod utique tunc facit, cum caro in naturam regressa vigoris sui agnoscit altricem, atque ausu deposito contumaciae moderantis animae coniugatur arbitrio: qualis fuit cum inhabitanda paradisi secreta suscepit, antequam veneno pestiferi serpentis infecta sacrilegam famem sciret.’ 6 Note that Ambrose follows the exegetical tradition (for which v. supra, pp. 192, 251) which identifies the ‘ Paradise’ of Gen. iii. with that of 2 Cor. xii. 2: im ps. Cxvili. expos. serym. iv. 2: ‘ denique eiectus de paradiso, hoc est, ex illo sublimi et caelesti loco ad quem raptus est Paulus sive in corpore sive extra corpus nesciens.’ ? It may be noted that Ambrose, unlike Augustine, had an excellent knowledge of the Greek language, and was much influenced by Origen and Basil : it is possible that he may have derived the idea of “ original perfec- tion’ directly from the Cappadocians. 302 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN monotheism, that of the absoluteness and necessity of good and of the contingency of evil, a principle which since the Maccabean age has been embodied in the Fall-theory. And doubtless it was the peculiar vigour and compactness of the doctrines of Mani,! as contrasted with the vagueness and variety of the systems collectively known as Gnosticism, which impelled Gregory of Nyssa in the East, and Ambrose in the West, all unconsciously to accentuate the idea of the Fall by prefixing to it the idea, borrowed from Jewish legend, of a state of paradisal ‘ perfection,’ which goes far beyond the conception of that ‘infancy’ which was attributed by the earliest Greek-Christian writers to the ancestors of the race. It is interesting, however, to note that (if a passage in one of Ambrose’s letters is to be taken as containing his permanent thought on the subject) man’s ‘Original Righteousness’ was not, in this Father’s view, destroyed at one blow by the first transgression, as Augustine and Calvin were later to maintain ; it became progressively diminished in each succeeding generation of Adam’s descendants and eventually died out altogether, in much the same way that the attractive force of a magnet holding a series of iron rings becomes weaker in each ring that is added to the series.’ The influence of this significant addition of ‘ Original Righteousness’ to the growing fabric of the ‘ African’ theory is reflected in a terminological tendency exactly analogous to that which we have noted in the writings of the Cappadocian Fathers—the tendency, namely, to speak of Adam’s sin not merely as a ‘ transgression ’ (praevaricatio, which literally means ‘ walking crookedly,’ and is an almost exact rendering of the Scriptural and primitive term mapapacts) but as a ‘ Fall,’ or lapsus.2 We have already 1 For an authoritative summary of Manicheism, based upon the latest researches, see F. C. Burkitt, The Religion of the Manichees (Donnellan Lectures for 1924). * ep. xlv. 14: cf. St. Athanasius, de incarn. 12 (commented on above, p. 262). ) 8 Cf. hexaemeron vi. 42: ‘secundum hunc imaginem (sc. Dei) Adam ante peccatum: sed ubi Japsus est, deposuit imaginem caelestis, sumpsit terrestris effigiem’; de excessu fratr. sui Satyri, ii. 6: ‘ lapsus sum in Adam ’ (see below, p. 305, n. 4, for the rest of the passage) ; in ps. cxviii. expos. XXlil. 30: ‘ suscipe me in carne, quae in Adam Japsa est’; apol. THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 303 pointed out that the idea of a failure on the part of man to pursue an upward line of moral progress marked out for him by his Maker is very different from the idea of a fall from a pre-existing condition of moral and spiritual per- fection ; and it is hardly necessary to add that the former conception of the primal catastrophe is not contradicted by the information given us by science with regard to the origin and primitive condition of our race, whereas. the latter would seem in the light of modern knowledge to be purely mythological. It is fair to observe that the use of the term ‘fall’ (that is, of the verb Jab: and its cognate sub- stantive /apsus) in this connexion is not predominant in Ambrose ; and it is not until the close of the patristic period that /apsus takes the place of praevaricatio as the technical designation in Latin of the primordial sin. The allusions in St. Ambrose’s writings to ‘ Original Sin,’ in the sense of the inherited bias towards evil, are so numerous that it is impossible to do more than summarise their general import.1 The phrase ‘all we men are born under sin’? gives the key-note of his thought on this matter ; and the ‘ sin,’ or ‘ danger of sinning,’ ? which dogs man’s path from his birth is described as ‘ the iniquity of our heels, which compasseth us about... of that heel which was bitten by the serpent, and causes us to go limping ’ 4 —as the net in which Adam enveloped his whole posterity,° or the chain with which he bound the human race ®—as the inheritance of a vitxum * (Tertullian’s and Hilary’s word)— as the entailed curse, which makes our flesh to be sin. But the question, what is the precise psychological account to be given of this vitzum, or curse, is left in judicious vagueness. David, xi.: “ nec conceptus iniquitatis exsors est, quoniam et parentes mon carent lapsu’; apol. David alteva, iii. 19: ‘ post primi hominis labsum’; de paradis. xiii. 62: “ vitio uxoris lapsus est’; de " Cain et Abel,i.: ‘ Adam et Evae lapsus.’ 1 Some of these passages were collected by St. Augustine, de pecc. orig. xli. * de poenitent. I. iii. 13 : ‘ omnes homines sub peccato nascimur.’ 3 in ps. xlvili. enarr. 9. i Teleee ney 5 in ps. CXVili. expos. 47; ep. Ixxiii. 9. 6 ep, Ixxiato, 7 in ps. xlili. enarr. 75. 8 in ps. CXVill. expos. 21. 304 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN When he does raise it, he shows the influence of that curious vein of subconscious feeling which we have noted as running all through the history of the Fall-doctrine, a feeling which may be described as a horror or phobia of sex. It is not surprising to discover traces of this feeling in the writings of so prominent a champion of virginity and asceticism ; and the reader will doubtless remember what has been said above concerning the tendencies of the ‘ twice- born’ temperament in regard to the matter.1 Hence in one passage” he toys with the repulsive notion, already suggested by Origen,®? of a ‘bad mana’ inherent in the physiological processes of conception and birth ; and in the same passage he implies that sexual intercourse is itself sinful, so that we are ‘ born in’ the ‘sin’ of our parents. This leads on to the lamentable suggestion that the miraculous birth of Christ was necessary in order to the avoidance of the physical or quasi-physical pollutions inherent in normal birth. Full use is made of the familiar proof-texts, Ps. li. 5, ‘ Behold, I was shapen in wickedness,’ and the Septuagintal mistranslation of Job, ‘ There is no one free from defilement, not even if his life has been but a day upon the earth.’* Nevertheless, the wound of man’s nature, whatever its kind and seat, does not abolish free- will or reponsibility ; and it is impossible not to appreciate the manliness and common-sense of Ambrose’s declaration, “Let him not fear the danger of heredity, who desires to hold the standing-ground of virtue.’ ® In view of the general character and tone of Ambrose’s Fall-doctrine as indicated by these preliminary observations, we shall naturally expect to come across some strong affirmations of ‘ Original Guilt.’ It is true that the context of the passage last cited contains a declaration that ‘ the iniquity of our heels,’ which is identified with the sin of Adam or its inherited results, will not be laid to our charge at the Day of Judgment—a declaration which is clearly tantamount to a denial of our personal responsibility for the first sin.® But we may set against this isolated utterance 1 See Lecture III, p. 155. 2 apol. David, xi. 3 vu. SUPYa, P. 224. 4 vu. supra, Pp. 224, Nl. 2. 5 in ps. xlviil. enarr. 9. 6 ibid. THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH = 305 other passages which with equal clearness affirm this idea, together with its logical foundation of ‘ seminal identity.’ In the writings of the great bishop of Milan the theory that we all were in Adam and were Adam, and therefore fell in his Fall, or ‘sinned in’ him, attains to conscious and explicit formulation. There is no mistaking the significance of such passages as this: ‘ Assuredly we all sinned in the first man, and by the inheritance of his nature there has been transfused from that one man into all an inheritance of guilt. . . . So then Adam is in each one of us; for in him human nature ttself sinned.’ (We notice in this last clause the first appearance of a refined form of the theory of “seminal identity,’ which sublimates the concrete individual Adam into the abstract universal of ‘humanity,’ and regards this universal as having somehow ‘sinned’; this is a thought which runs through the whole subsequent history of the Western theology of sin and redemption, finding its latest expression in Dr. R. C. Moberly’s great work on the Atonement.?) Equally striking utterances of the same view are the following: ‘Adam existed, and in him we all existed. Adam perished, and in him all perished ’?; and ‘ In Adam I fell, in Adam I was cast out of Paradise, in Adam I died; how may God recall me, unless He find me in Adam, justified in Christ, even as I was rendered subject to guilt, and the destined prey of death, in the first Adam?’* Here the full implications of Irenaeus’ ‘ recapitulation ’-theory are drawn out with a plainness from which its original author would, perhaps, have shrunk.® It is one of the many paradoxes 1 apol. David alteva, 71: ‘ nempe omnes in primo homine peccavimus, et per naturae successionem culpae quoque ab uno in omnes transfusa successio est . . . Adam ergo in singulis nobis est. in illo enim conditio humana deliquit, quia per unum in omnes pertransivit peccatum’ ; cf. also ibid. 69: ‘ cui se fateatur noster David non solum in se ipso, sed etiam in primo homine peccasse, dum praecepta divina temerantur.’ 2 R. C. Moberly, Atonement and Personality (1904), p. 88 f. 3 expos. ev. sec. Luc. vil. 234: ‘ fuit Adam, et in illo fuimus omnes ; periit Adam, et in illo omnes perierunt.’ 4 de excess. fratris sut Satyri, ii. 6: ‘ lapsus sum in Adam, de paradiso eiectus in Adam, mortuus in Adam; quomodo revocet, nisi me in Adam invenerit, ut in illo culpae obnoxium, morti debitum, ita in Christo iustifi- catum ?’ 5 uv. supra, p. 197. 306 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN revealed by a close study of the history of dogma, and one of the many facts which warn us against an over-rigid classi- fication of primitive Christian thinkers, that the idea of ‘Original Guilt,’ which became the most characteristic constituent of the African and Latin presentation of the Fall-doctrine should have been suggested in the first instance by a theologian so typically Hellenic in thought and feeling as the great second-century bishop of Lyons. Like Hilary, Ambrose finds himself able to hold the theory of the identity of the race with its first father, whilst discarding the ‘ traducianism ’ which in Tertullian’s thought had supported and reinforced this theory. So far as Ambrose is concerned, we may safely attribute this phenomenon to the fact that (as we have just suggested) the identity of mankind with Adam is ceasing, in his mind, to be a merely material or ‘ seminal ’ identity, and is becoming a logical or metaphysical identity; following, we may suppose, the lead of those Fathers who had recognised that the Hebrew ’Adham merely means ‘ man,’! he seems to think of Adam as (so to speak) the Platonic Idea of man, as hypostatised ‘human nature,’ conditio humana. It would not be germane to this historical portion of our enquiry to raise the question whether the statement that a hypostatised class-concept ‘ sinned,’ and so infected the particulars sub- sumed under it with sin, is ultimately intelligible or not. It is hardly necessary to add that in the thought of Ambrose the divinely appointed remedy for the hereditary disease of human nature is baptismal regeneration. We may note that in the treatise de mysteriis * he seems to ad- vocate the curious view that ‘ original guilt’ is remitted by the liturgical washing of the neophyte’s feet after baptism, or at least that this was effected in the case of the Apostles through the washing of their feet by our Lord, as narrated in St. John xiii. 1-11. Though they have no bearing on the logical structure 1 uv. Supra, PP. 192, D. 2, 203, 229. 2 de myst. vi. 32: ‘ mundus erat Petrus, sed plantam lavare debebat ; habebat enim primi hominis de successione peccatum, quando eum sup- plantavit serpens, et persuasit errorem. ideo planta eius abluitur, u# hasreditaria peccata tollantuy; nostra enim propria per baptismum relaxantur.’ THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH = 307 of Ambrose’s Fall-doctrine, we may notice here two mytho- logical decorations of the Adam-story which occur in his works, and which illustrate the fact that even after two centuries of gradual crystallisation the tradition was still plastic enough to admit of haggadic additions at the will of each of its exponents. The first is the curious idea that Adam, after his expulsion from Paradise, was banished to a ‘ castellum,’ to do penance for his sin! ; he is also said to have been clothed with skins and not with silk, for the same reason, the skins being apparently conceived as a kind of hair-shirt.2, The second is a belief which still survives as an artistic convention ; this is the idea that Adam was buried on the hill which was afterwards to be consecrated by the Passion of the Son of God, immediately under the spot upon which the Cross was destined to be reared, an idea from which has sprung the familiar custom of portraying a skull as lying at the base of the Cross,.in painted or sculptured representations of the Crucifixion.* It is fair to add that this is only mentioned as a possible opinion. This drapery of folk-lore which clings about the developed Fall-doctrine, even in the last half of the fourth century A.D., shows that the pseudepigraphic and Rabbinical Jewish writings still exercised a certain influence upon Christian thought, and that the sentimental ties which had bound the Catholic Church to its Jewish mother were even at this date not completely severed. (5) ‘ Ambrostaster.’ This writer* clearly indicates by his comments on Rom. v. vi. vii. that he accepts the idea of ‘ Original Sin’; but he has only one sentence which (apparently) implies the idea of ‘ Original Guilt.’ The sentence to which we refer is, nevertheless, of the most 1 in ps. CXVill. expos. 23; 1n pS. XXXVI. enarr. 20. 2 de poemttent. II. x1. 99. 3 ep. Ixxi. 10; im Luc. x. 114. Maldonatus, commenting on Matt. XXVil. 33, gives a list of other Fathers who held the same opinion. Louis Ginzberg (Monatsschrift fiir Gesch. u. Wissensch. Judentums, xliii. 69 ff.) has shown that this story is a Christianised version of the Jewish legend that the body of Adam was compounded from dust gathered on the future site of the altar of burnt-sacrifice. 4 For a discussion of the question of his identity see A. Souter, A Study of Ambrosiastey (Cambridge Texts and Studies), 1905, which contains a full bibliography. 308 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN crucial importance in the development of the ‘ twice-born ’ Fall-theory, because Ambrosiaster thereby provided, per- haps unwittingly, the doctrine of ‘ Original Guilt’ with what it had hitherto lacked, namely, a Scriptural proof-text to be its formal basis: the ignorance of Greek now prevalent in the West, and the consequent inability of many Latin theologians to read the actual words of the New Testament, effectually screened the fact that the supposed proof-text rested upon a blunder in translation. Its relevant portions run as follows: In whom, that is, in Adam, all sinned. The Apostle said “in whom’ in the masculine gender (7 quo) although he is speak- ing about the woman, for this reason, that his reference is to the whole race of man, not to the particular sex . So then it is plain that all have sinned in Adam as in a lump (guast in massa) ; for all the children whom Adam begat, having been himself corrupted by the woman (tpsa) through sin, have been born under sin. From him there- fore all are sinners, because from him are we all; for Adam lost the gift of God when he transgressed, having become un- worthy to eat of the tree of life, so that he died. The cardinal error in this sentence les in the mis- translation of St. Paul’s phrase eg’ @ mavtes 7papror, * for that allsinned ’ (R.V.), as though it were ev @ mavres juaprov, ‘in whom, sc. the “one man’”’ just mentioned, all sinned.’ Ambrosiaster is, of course, relying on a Latin version which renders ef’ 6 as 1” quo, a translation which has been per- petuated in the Vulgate. This rendering is inexact and ambiguous enough in all conscience, but it does not compel us to assume that quo is masculine ; a reader who possessed only the Latin version, without any knowledge of the original Greek, and read it without any preconceived ideas as to “Original Guilt,’ would probably understand im quo as equivalent to quod or quantum, ‘in so faras all sinned.’ In any case the words unum hominem are too far distant from 1 comm. in Rom. v.12: ‘in quo, id est, in Adam, omnes peccaverunt. ideo dixit 7m quo, cum de muliere loquatur, quia non ad speciem rettulit, sed ad genus. manifestum itaque est in Adam omnes peccasse quasi in massa ; ipsa enim per peccatum corruptus, quos genuit, omnes nati sunt sub peccato. ex eo igitur cuncti peccatores, quia ex eo ipso sumus omnes ; hic enim beneficium Dei perdidit, dum praevaricavit, indignus factus edere de arbore vitae, ut moreretur.’ THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 309 the relative guo to be its grammatical antecedent. Ambrosi- aster has therefore bequeathed to Western Christendom as the supposed Scriptural foundation of its characteristic doctrine of ‘ Original Guilt’ a gratuitous misunderstanding of a faulty rendering of what St. Paul actually wrote. The fatal legacy was received only too gladly : Augustine quotes this passage, mistranslation and all, as from the writings of ‘sanctus Hilarius, 4 who is undoubtedly ‘Ambrosiaster.. Nor has its malign influence even yet come to an end: I have in my possession a Roman Catholic pamphlet? in which the words of Rom. v. 12 are quoted in defence of the idea of ‘ Original Guilt,’ in the form‘ . . . in whom all have sinned,’ without the slightest apparent consciousness that St. Paul wrote nothing of the kind. It is, indeed, doubtful whether Ambrosiaster himself really intended to place on this clause (7m quo omnes pecca- verunt) the sense which Augustine took him to intend, and which has been adopted without question, on Augustine’s authority, by so many later writers in Western Christendom. For, in commenting on v. 14 of the same fifth chapter of the Epistle to the Romans, he lays down a principle which logically seems to exclude “ Original Guilt’ altogether. His text of this verse runs ‘ sed regnavit mors ab Adam usque ad Moysen, in eos qui peccaverunt in similitudinem praevari- cationis Adam’; which, it will be noticed, like Origen’s text, pre-supposes a Greek original not containing the word py before duaptjoavras.? This reading, right or wrong, clearly connects the incidence of death with the commission of actual sin; and Ambrosiaster expounds it to mean that only actual sin deserves the ‘second death,’ or Gehenna. 1c, wu. epp. Pelag., IV, iv. 7. By ‘sanctus Hilarius’ Augustine apparently means Hilary of Poitiers: but this is almost certainly mistaken. Souter (op. cit., pp. 161 ff.), following Dom Germain Morin, concludes tentatively that the ‘ Hilarius’ who is to be identified with ‘ Ambrosiaster ’ is Decimius Hilarianus Hilarius, a distinguished Christian layman who was proconsul of Africa in 377, praefectus urbi in 383, praefectus praetorio Italiae in 396, and praefectus urbi for the second time in 408. 2 Original Sin, by the Rev. C. C. O’Connor (Catholic Truth Society), p. 22. F. X. Schouppe, S.J. (Elementa Theologiae Dogmaticae, tom. i. tract. 7, c. 3, 2, § 195) appears to rely on this traditional mistranslation ; but Pohle-Preuss (God, the Author of Nature, 1912, p. 249) have grave doubts about it. 3 For a note on this reading, v. supra, p. 125, N. 2. 310 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN Moreover, like most Latin writers after Tertullian, he repudiates ‘ traducianism.’? It is, therefore, possible that by the assertion that all men ‘sinned in Adam, as in a lump’ he may merely mean that they ‘ became sinners’ or “acquired a sinful tendency’; in other words, he may intend to affirm merely ‘ Original Sin,’ and not “‘ Original Guilt.’ But the idea of ‘ Original Guilt’ had by this time become so popular, and the apparent discovery of a Scrip- tural basis for it was so welcome, amongst thinkers who knew no Greek, that critical considerations of this kind do not seem to have occurred to any of Ambrosiaster’s readers ; and his mistranslation of 颒 & wavtes 7japrov took its place in the armoury of controversial arguments for the ‘ twice-born’ version of the Fall-doctrine. This momentous error, andthe emergence of the conception of fallen humanity as a sinful massa,2 or ‘lump,’ bring us up to the very threshold of Augustinianism ; where it will be appropriate to pause, and survey the ground which has been covered in this lecture. CONCLUSION It must be confessed that the section of our journey which has just been completed very considerably exceeds in length those which have preceded it ; but it may be hoped that the cardinal importance for our enquiry of the Church’s pre-Augustinian infancy will have justified a somewhat detailed examination of this period. We are now in a position to attempt answers to the two main questions formulated at the beginning of this lecture as necessarily arising out of our historical method of determining what is ‘the ecclesiastical doctrine’ of Man and of Sin—namely : (xr) Can it be said that the ideas of the Fall and of Original Sin were held universally within the Christian Church—that 1 comm. in Rom. vii. 22: ‘ si enim anima de traduce esset et ipsa, et in ipsa habitaret peccatum, quia anima Adae magis peccavit quam corpus: sed peccatum animae corrupit corpus . . . in anima autem si habitaret , numquam se cognosceret homo: nunc autem cognoscit se, et condelectatur legi Dei.’ * This term may have been suggested by the use of dvpaya (Vulg. “massa ’) in Rom. ix. 21. THEePALE-DOCTRINE IN: THE CHURCH. + 31x they were believed ubique, semper, et ab omnibus—during this period? and (2) if they were, can any given set of solutions of the ‘five crucial problems’ implicit in the Adamic Fall-theory claim a similar degree of oecumenical acceptance ? (1) To answer this question with exactness, we must distinguish between the doctrine of the ‘ Fall,’ that is, the belief that there has been some great prehistoric moral catastrophe which has separated man from God, and the doctrine of ‘ Original Sin,’ that is, the affirmation that the ground of this separation lies in man’s consequent infection by a hereditary weakness or taint which is interior or psychological in nature. It may reasonably be concluded from the evidence which we have adduced from the greatest teachers of the pre-Augustinian Church (to which, if space allowed, might be added more cursory references to the subject by writers of lesser importance?) that the doctrine of the Fall was accepted, in a vague and general way, by most Christians of this period, at least from the canonisation of St. Paul’s Epistles onwards : and we have shown reason for dismissing the contention that the uncertainty which appears to have reigned in the Church with regard to this matter destroys the claim of the Fall-doctrine to fulfil the second of the Vincentian qualifications, that of acceptance semper. Though in all probability the rank and file of the Christian society took little interest in the matter,? and though the thought of the consequences of Adam’s sin would seem to have possessed little vividness or reality for their imagina- 1 See Additional Note H, p. 554, ‘ Passages bearing on the Fall-doctrine from pre-Augustinian writers not mentioned in Lecture IV.’ * This popular lack of interest in the subject seems to be reflected in the Apocryphal Gospels, which are the products of vulgar and non- theological Christianity, both Catholic and heretical. In the whole of Dr. M. R. James’ convenient collection of these documents (The A pocryphal New Testament, 1924) there appear to be only three references to the Fall of Adam, one of which occurs in the ‘ Book of John the Evangelist’ (op. cit. p. 189 f.), a Bogomil work which in its present form is not earlier than the twelfth century, and is therefore of no value as evidence for primitive Christian opinion ; the other two occur in the‘ Questions of Bartholomew ’ (pp. 173, 178), which may represent the ‘ Gospel of Bartholomew’ mentioned by Jerome (praef. in comm. super Maitt., Vallarsi, vil. 2), and, if so, is a version of a pre-Augustinian writing—but this is highly doubtful see James, p. 166). 312 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN tions in comparison with the idea of invisible daemons swarming around them and instilling subtle suggestions of evil into their minds—an idea which came to them with the direct authority of our Lord’s own words—they would at least not have denied the teaching of Rom. v. 12-21; it is not conceivable that, after the recognition of St. Paul’s letters as Scripture, any member of the Church would have asserted that the Apostle was mistaken when he connected the universal prevalence of death and sin with the trans- gression of the first man. The question whether the idea of ‘ original sin,’ in the sense defined above, enjoyed an equal measure of explicit acceptance is prima facie more disputable. It was shown in Lecture III that the language of Rom. v. vi. vii. is most naturally and easily comprehensible on the supposition that St. Paul meant to weld together the Fall-theory of the apocalyptists and the yécer-theory of the Rabbis, and to exhibit the ‘ evilimpulse ’ as the legacy of the primordial sin. If this is so, the Pauline teaching is that the disastrous entail of the Fall involves, not merely physical mortality, but evil consequences of an interior, psychological, and spiritual nature. But the Apostle’s obscure and com- plicated sentences, in which he is struggling to express ideas which are not completely articulated or defined even in his own mind, though they would seem to be penetrated by this assumption of the psychological character of the main legacy of the Fall, do not contain any express affirmation of it; and hence it was possible for a tendency to manifest itself in some quarters towards construing the consequences of the first sin as of an external or mechanical kind, as consisting in the circumstance that since the Fall men have been born outside Paradise, or subject to some commercially conceived obligation or servitude to the Devil. Neverthe- less, a reasonable interpretation of the Vincentian Canon will allow for temporary misunderstandings and local failures to grasp the full inwardness of these vast and mysterious ideas ; and the conceptions of ‘ banishment from Paradise ’ and ‘ legal servitude to the devil’ may well be regarded as superficial and mythological rationalisations of that pro- found and poignant experience of self-condemnation, which THE FALL-DOCTRINE IN THE CHURCH 313 is the heart of true penitence and the foundation of the whole Fall-doctrine. (2) The ideas of the Fall and of ‘ Original Sin,’ in a broad general sense, may thus be taken on the whole to satisfy the Vincentian test (interpreted in that elastic sense which does not exclude doctrinal development) so far as the first four centuries of Christian history are concerned. But it will have become clear in the course of our exposition that neither of the two classical versions of the Fall-doctrine— neither the Hellenic, ‘ once-born,’ and ‘ minimising,’ nor the African, ‘ twice-born,’ or ‘ maximising’ version (which includes as a characteristic constituent the formidable con- ception of ‘ Original Guilt ’)—enjoyed oecumenical accept- ance during this period. Neither the one nor the other can claim to have been believed ubique, semper, et ab omnibus down to the point which our narrative has reached. This fact would seem by itself to dispose of the common assump- tion that the African theory is ‘ the ecclesiastical’ or ‘ the Catholic’ doctrine, in an exclusive sense. Given the Vincentian criteria of Catholicity, it is clear that the title of the ‘ Catholic’ doctrine can only be claimed by the common substratum, or the highest common factor, of the Hellenic and the African views. And this highest common factor is nothing more or less than the teaching of St. Paul—that ‘Adam’ sinned (however ‘Adam’ is to be construed, whether as archetypal idea, race-spirit, or historic individual) and that in consequence all men inherit a congenital inordi- nation of appetite or debility of will (whichever mode of expression be preferred), with liability to physical disease and death. It may be predicted, without improper antici- pation, that at the end of the historical portion of our enquiry we shall not see reason to revise the provisional judgment to which our study of the first four centuries of Christianity has led us, that the genuinely ‘ Catholic’ doctrine of the Fall and of Original Sin is simply and strictly identical with the New Testament doctrine. It should be added, in order to complete our picture of the mind of the Church with regard to this subject during the pre-Augustinian epoch, that none of the writers who have been reviewed so far asserts that the Fall-doctrine belongs to 314 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN the essence of the Christian message, that is, to ‘ the Gospel ’ or ‘ the Deposit of Faith.’ The ideas of Adam’s sin and of its gloomy consequences would seem rather to have been placed in the not very precisely limited category of indis- pensable prolegomena to Christianity, contained in the Jewish sacred books. Itisa significant fact that no mention of these doctrines occurs either in the local baptismal creeds of the period or in the great oecumenical symbol of Nicaea. It was reserved for Augustine to declare that they belonged to ‘ the very foundations of the Faith.’ 2 1 By this is meant, of course, the Creed as promulgated by the Council (‘N’), though the statement is equally true of ‘ C,’ the so-called Niceno- Constantinopolitan symbol. The phrase ‘ who for us men and for our salvation came down from heaven’ does not, so far as its verbal form is concerned, necessarily mean more than that the object of the Incarnation was to redeem us from actual sin. 2c. Iulian. i. 6, 22: ‘hoc autem unde nunc agimus ad ipsa fidei pertinet fundamenta.’ Ve THE ‘TWICE-BORN’ VERSION OF THE FALL-DOCTRINE FULLY DEVELOPED— AUGUSTINIANISM GAN’ ef dvOpwmot aKovrTés Elot KaKOL Kal ToLOdTOL Ody EKdVTES, OUT av TLS TODS adixobvras aitidoaito, ovre Tods maayortas ws 4.’ adtovs tadra mdcxovras. cf bé 57) Kal dvayKn ovtw KaKods yivecOat cite b70 THs hops cite THs apxis Sidovons 7d axdAovbov evredbev, dvaixds odtws. ei dé 57) 6 Adyos adds €oTW 6 TOWWY, TAS ovkK doiKa ovTws; GAAd Td peév GkovTes, OTL Guaptia aKovotov' Todro dé ovK dvaipet TO avtods Tovs mpaTrovTas map’ avta@v elvar, AAA’ ért adrol mrototar, dia TOOTO Kal avTol GuapTdvovow* 7 0d’ av GAws Huaprov p17) avTOL Ot moLodyTES OvTES. PLOTINUS* “ancien fo: ‘Tis the faith that launched point-blank her dart At the head of a lie—taught Original Sin, The Corruption of man’s heart. BROWNING: Gold Hair; a story of Pornic. LECTURE V THE ‘“TWICE-BORN’ VERSION OF THE FALL-DOCTRINE FULLY DEVELOPED— AUGUSTINIANISM Rom. vii. 22, 23: ‘ For I delight in the law of God after the inward man: but I seea different law in my members, warring against the law of my mind, and bringing me into captivity under the law of sin which is in my members.’ In our last lecture it was shown that the primitive pre- Augustinian Church, whilst holding the doctrines of the Fall and of an inherited taint or weakness in a vague and undefined shape, did not regard these ideas as constituting parts of the ‘ Gospel,’ that is, of the revelation of Himself made by God through Christ. They are nowhere described as essential elements of the Canon, Rule, or Deposit of Faith. For the Church of the first four centuries, ‘ the Faith’ was that which was contained in the baptismal Creeds, consisting mainly in the doctrines of God and of Christ. But this central nucleus of the Faith, though in- vested with a unique majesty and authoritativeness, was never regarded as standing alone: it was set in a frame or context of presuppositions and corollaries, less definite and clean-cut, but not less generally accepted. To the category of presuppositions or prolegomena belonged the ideas which Christianity had inherited from Judaism, the belief in the unity of God, in the inspiration of the Old Testament scriptures, and that which forms the subject of our present enquiry, the belief in the first sin and its disastrous legacy ; to the latter, the category of corollaries or consequences, belonged the as yet undeveloped doctrines of the Church, the Ministry and the Sacraments, things 318 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN which for the most part 1 were taken for granted as facts, and used rather than theoretically analysed. In other words, the central body of Trinitarian and Christological ideas which constituted ‘the Faith’ was surrounded by a fringe or penumbra of less defined ideas, which had not yet formed the subject-matter of authoritative definition, and in regard to which individual speculation was as yet un- trammelled, or limited only by the words of Scripture. This rudimentary organisation of Christian thought con- trasts vividly with those later systems of theology which are most familiar to ourselves, which contain, as integral parts of a defined and coherent whole, not merely the two great original sections dealing with the doctrines of God and of the Incarnation or of ‘the Person of Christ,’ but three further sections, to all appearance equally authori- tative, devoted to the doctrines of Grace or of ‘ the Work of Christ,’ of the Church, and of the Sacraments—additions which represent the gradual expansion of the sphere of dogma proper by the progressive embodiment into the central nucleus of large tracts of the penumbra. Hence the doctrines of the Fall and of Original Sin now appear to the student of Christian thought as permanently em- bedded in the main fabric, forming as they do the founda- tion of that segment of it which is known as ‘ the doctrine of Grace’; they are now very generally regarded as dogmas of the Christian Church, constituting parts of its essential message just as truly as the ideas of the Incarnation, or the Second Coming. It would be premature to express any opinion now with regard to the validity and desirability of this development ; our immediate task is to reconstruct the way in which it came to pass. The development of the third section of Christian doctrine, the doctrine of Grace, carrying within it the doctrines of the Fall and of Original Sin, is associated with the name of Augustine, whom we have already observed as it were from a distance, standing on the frontier which separates classical antiquity from the 1 It is true that the ‘ holy Church’ is mentioned in the Old Roman Creed, ‘ remission of sins through the holy Church ’ in the African Creed of the third century, and baptism in the Jerusalem Creed of ¢. A.D. 348: but no specific doctrine about these things is defined. AUGUSTINIANISM 319 Middle Ages, and of whom it has been strikingly said that the miserable existence of the Roman Empire in the West would seem to have been providentially prolonged into the fifth century solely in order that Augustine might arise within the shelter of its domain, in order to discharge his predestined task of infusing, through his writings, the thought and culture of the old world into the rude and barbarous vitality of the new. The history of Christian thought, like that universal history of which it forms a part, is in great measure the history of its creative spirits; and though the plan of our enquiry, seeking to determine that which has been believed ubique, semper, et ab ommibus, necessarily involves the laying of a special emphasis upon the continuous life of the Church and the unbroken self-identity of that diffused corporate consciousness of the Christian society which is the real bearer of its traditional ideas, this conception needs to be perpetually balanced by the recognition of the part played in dogmatic development by the fresh bursts of spontaneous energy which spring from great individual personalities. One such creative personality we have noted in St. Paul, who laid down the lines on which Christian anthropology was to develop. Another has been marked in Origen, the Platonist of Alexandria, some of whose speculations may provide useful material when we come to the constructive part of our task. But the end of the ancient world and the beginning of the Middle Ages was marked by the figure of an even greater Platonist, greater, that is, in the immediate effect which his life and writings produced upon the thought of Christendom. Origen’s influence during his life affected only part of the East and did not extend into the West; and, three centuries after his death, his most daring speculations were repudiated, and he himself was branded as a heretic, by Justinian’s ecclesiastical henchmen, But Augustine from his obscure seaport on the North African coast swayed the whole Western Church as its intellectual dictator, a position from 1 See Fr. Diekamp, Die origenistischen Streitigketten im sechsten Jahr- hundert und das fiinfte allgemeine Concil, Minster, 1899; L. Duchesne, L’Eglise au vieme siécle (1925), p. 171 f. 320 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN which he has not even yet been deposed, and the mighty energies of his mind and spirit initiated reverberations which affected every sphere of thought. According to Eucken, he was the greatest of purely Christian philosophers, whose fame not even Thomas Aquinas can rival. Like his great master Plato,? he was gifted with the resplendent imagination and the flow of gorgeous imagery which spring from the union of poetic and philo- sophic genius, and he wielded a passionate yet lucid style, which at times could rise, as in the Confessions, to heights of almost dithyrambic power; the derisive nickname of ‘Punic Aristotle’ 3 bestowed upon him by his opponent Julian of Eclanum falls harmlessly to the ground in so far as it may be thought to have implied a disparagement of his literary skill, whilst it admirably describes the encyclo- paedic range of his intellectual interests. He fused Neo- Platonism and Christian theism into a far more intimate and organic synthesis than had been effected by the Alex- andrine Fathers, educing therefrom a vast cosmic picture of the ordo naturarum stretching continuously, in hierarch- ical gradation, from that Divine nature, which is the supreme and unchangeable Good, down to the lowest level of irrational and inanimate natures, a picture of Being not less magnificent than the Plotinian, but unlike it, portraying God as personal and Matter as real.4 He expounded the argument, cogito, ergo sum, before Descartes,°® and the relativity of Time before Kant.® His Confessions represent the most penetrating achievement of Christian 1 R. Eucken, Die Lebensanschauungen der grossen Denker*, p. 216. 2 Cf. E. Norden, in Die Kultur dey Gegenwart (1905) i. 8. p. 394. 3 “ Aristoteles Poenorum’ (op. imp. c. Iul. ili. 199) : ‘ philosophaster Poenorum ’ (ib7d. v. 11). 4 A brilliant study of St. Augustine’s metaphysic will be found in T. A. Lacey, Nature, Miracle, and Sin (1916), Lectures II and III. 5 de civit. Dei, xi. 26: ‘nulla in his veris Academicorum argumenta formido, dicentium, quid, si falleris ? si enim fallor,sum. nam qui non est, utique nec falli potest: ac per hoc sum, si fallor’; cf. de vera rvelig. 73; solilog.ii.1; de lib. arbitr. ii. 3. 6 de civit, Det, xi. 6: ‘ quis non videat quod tempora non fuissent, nisi creatura fieret, quae aliquid aliqua motione mutaret ?’ zbid.: ‘ procul dubio non est mundus factus in tempore, sed cum tempore’; conf. xi. 26: ‘inde mihi visum est nihil esse aliud tempus quam distentionem—sed Ccuius rei, nescio, et mirum, si non ipsius animi,’ and the whole of 27. AUGUSTINIANISM 321 antiquity in the domain of introspective psychology. His treatise ‘On the City of God’ created the science of the philosophy of history, and by its workings in the mind of Charlemagne may well have helped to bring that strange romantic phantom, the Holy Roman Empire, to the birth.! In Christian theology, he developed the Western conception of the Triune Being of God to a point on which no sub- stantial advance has since been made, and by his influence on Pope Leo the Great helped to determine the final formula- tion of the Chalcedonian Christology. But more remarkable than any single one of these mental achievements is the general domination exercised for centuries by his spirit, ideas, and manner of thought over the religious life of Western Europe, a domination which has not even yet entirely passed away. Through the doctrine of the Church and the ministry, as articulated by him to meet the exigencies of the Donatist controversy, and through the doctrine of Grace, as elaborated against the Pelagians, his genius played a foremost part in fixing upon Western Christendom that predominantly institu- tional and practical bias, which, reinforced by racial antipathies, inevitably tore it loose from the enfeebled Byzantine East (temporarily in the schism of Photius, and finally in the catastrophe of A.D. 1054), and shaped it into a self-contained organism, a mighty theocratic empire of souls, the Latin Catholic Church of the Middle Ages.? Yet, all through the mediaeval period, within the bosom of the most imposing ecclesiastical system which the world has ever known, Augustine the predestinarian mystic was silently contending with Augustine the hierarch, and the Reformation of the sixteenth century was in great measure the posthumous rebellion of Augustine against Augustine. 1 Charlemagne ‘ delighted in the books of St. Augustine, and specially in those that bear the title ‘“‘ Of the City of God’”’’ (Einhard, Vita Carol, 24, quoted by B. B. Warfield, ERE ii. p. 222). 2 Cf. H. Reuter, Augustinische Studien (1887), vii. (( Zur Wurdigung der Stellung Augustins in der Geschichte der Kirche’), p. 499: ‘ (Er hat) durch sein geniales litterarisches Schaffen, durch die Wucht der Person- lichkeit, in so epochemachender Weise auf das theologische Denken in Occidente eingewirkt, in demselbe nachgewirkt, dass man sagen darf, die spatere Trennung desselben von dem Oriente sei wider seine Absicht dennoch von thm vorbereitet.’ Y 322 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN From Augustine the leaders of the Protestant revolt in- herited the overwhelming sense of God’s universal causality, of the impotence of human nature and the emptiness of human merit, which in logic makes all sacramental and institutional religion otiose: and in Augustine, too, is to be found that lofty conviction of the divine mission of the institutional, visible Church, which nerved Loyola, Borromeo, and Peter Canisius to roll back the flood of rebellion against the Papacy beyond the Alps and the Rhine. The two main camps into which the Reformation sundered the mediaeval Western Church continued to take the authority of Augustine for granted, as second only to that of the inspired writers. The Preface ‘ Of Ceremonies ’ in our own Prayer Book enquires, with rhetorical passion, ‘What would St. Augustine have said ...?’ as though a dictum from him would constitute a final solution of any ecclesiastical dispute. The doctrines of Grace set forth in the Canons of the Council of Trent, in the Thirty Nine Articles, in the Inustitutio of Calvin, in the Augsburg Con- fession, are so many modified and competing versions of Augustinianism.t As in St. Paul’s interpretation of the Old Testament Abraham was the spiritual father of circum- cised and uncircumcised Christians alike,? so in the genealogy of Western religious thinkers Augustine is the ancestor both of the Ultramontane and of the Evangelical? ; and it is no wonder that his version of the Fall-doctrine has stamped itself so deeply upon the imagination of his descendants that it is still very generally believed to be the only Fall-doctrine. There could hardly be a greater contrast than that which is presented by the fortunes of Origen, exiled, largely repudiated during his lifetime and anathematised after his death, and those of Augustine, for centuries the unchallenged master of Western theology. Yet it may now be said, without undue anticipation, that one of the conclusions 1 See Lecture VI. 2AIOMs 1 Val Bes 3 See Reuter, op. cit. vii. pp. 497-513. This author, however, finds more of the Catholic than of the Evangelicalin Augustine ; cf. the following two judgments: (a) ‘ Augustin gilt auch mir als Begrinder des rdmischen Katholizismus im Occidente’ (p. 497); (0) ‘ fragmentarisch, aber wirklich Evangelisches ist in Augustin ’ (p. 513). AUGUSTINIANISM 323 which will emerge from our historical review will be that in regard to the particular subject-matter of our enquiry, the ‘once-born’ or ‘ Hellenic’ scheme, as worked out (however imperfectly and confusedly) by the Greek Fathers of the fourth century on the basis of Origen’s speculations, represents not merely the maximum of doctrine to which historical Christianity as such can be said to be committed, but also the only type of Fall-doctrine which is capable of reconciliation with modern knowledge: and that the characteristic elements in the ‘twice-born’ or ‘ African’ theory, as completely elaborated by Augustine, possess neither oecumenical authority nor intrinsic reasonableness. The greater part of this judgment has been already estab- lished in the preceding lecture ; its remainder must now be vindicated by what, in view of the vast field to be covered, will necessarily be a relatively brief and summary sketch of Augustine’s teaching with regard to human nature and the origins of sin.4 AUGUSTINE'S EARLY LIFE AND TEACHING As was observed in the case of Origen, any attempt to estimate the value of a great thinker’s work must begin with some indication of the most important facts of his life. Augustine was born in A.D. 354 at Tagaste,? a small town in Proconsular Numidia, as the son of Patricius, a citizen of curial rank, at that date still a pagan, and his Christian wife Monnica, who has been canonised by the piety of subsequent generations as a pattern of Christian motherhood. He was 1 The incomparable wealth of documents at our disposal makes it impossible to give anything like an exhaustive list of references and quotations in the course of this highly compressed review, and we shall, therefore, confine ourselves to printing a few of the more important or interesting. The reader desirous of more detailed information must be referred to the monumental works of G. J. Vossius (Historiae de contro- versits quas Pelagius eiusque reliquiae moverunt, lib. vii, 1655) and Petavius (De Pelagiana et semi-Pelagiana haeresibus, 1644); cf. also J. Turmel, Le dogme du péché originel dans St. A. (Revue d’histoive et de littérature religieuse, Vii. p. 128). 2 Now Souk-Aras, ‘ & vingt-cinq lieues de Bone’ (Portalié, in DTC, col, 2268). 324 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN made a catechumen in his youth, but, owing to Monnica’s dread of the responsibilities which full membership of the Church would impose upon his passionate nature, was not baptised. At the age of sixteen he became a student at Carthage, where his sensuous temperament hurried him into the immoral connexion described in the second book of the Confessions1; and, three years later, his restless intellect, which had already begun to busy itself with the problem of evil, became enmeshed in the toils of that superficially attractive solution which, as we have seen, always has been and must be the deadly foe of Christian monotheism, namely, dualism ; which manifested itself at that time and place in the form of Manicheism. For nine years? he re- mained in a prison of his own creation, morally shackled by the liaison to which we have alluded, and intellectually fettered by the terrible theory of an eternal and indestructible principle of evil, of equal power with God Himself. It would seem that though during this period he accepted dualism as the starting-point for his enquiries into the origin of evil, he never arrived at any completely satis- fying conclusions; and that his status in regard to the Manichean sect was that of a ‘hearer,’ or catechumen, attached to it in the hope of eventually obtaining full enlightenment concerning the questions which tormented him, and not that of the ‘ elect ’ or fully initiated members.? The double stress to which Augustine was subjected during this period—the moral agony involved in fighting a losing battle with his own animal passions, and the mental strain of a seemingly futile search for the truth as to the 1 It was then that the celebrated prayer was uttered—‘ da mihi castitatem, sed noli modo’ (Conf. viii. 7, 17)—the cry of a divided person- ality. Loofs’ suggestion (PRE, ii. p. 261, art. ‘ Augustinus’) that con- cubinage was then tolerated by the Church, and that Augustine’s conduct was therefore not as reprehensible, from the point of view of de facto Christianity, as he himself believed it to be, appears to rest on a misunder- standing of the 17th canon of the Council of Toledo, held in a.p. 400 (Hardouin, i. 992) ; see Portalié, op. cit., DTC, col. 2269. 2 That is, from 373 to 382, the date of his departure from Africa— “novem totos annos’ (de moribus manich. 19). 3 On the two grades of membership in the Manichean Church, see F. C. Burkitt, Religion of the Manichees, pp. 44 ff. Augustine was later accused of having been a priest of the sect (c. litt, Petil. iii. 20). AUGUSTINIANISM 325 origin of evil—constituted the psychological conflict which eventually gave birth to his characteristic doctrines of Grace. At the age of twenty-eight he abandoned the formal profession of the Manichean creed, on discovering that Faustus of Milevis, the archpundit of the cult, who had been held up to him as an inspired teacher capable of solving all his difficulties, was nothing but a pretentious quack. There followed his sojourn in Italy and his contact with Ambrose,” whose life and teaching induced in him the con- viction that the Catholic Christianity of his boyhood was in possession of the key to the intellectual problem, without, however, communicating to him the means of solving the moral problem, that is, of regaining control over his sensual appetites. We need not recount again the world-famous story of the spiritual crisis which gripped him in the garden at Milan,® of the childish voice chanting the sentence folle lege, tolle lege, of the solemn words which met his eye as he opened the New Testament—‘ Not in rioting and drunken- ness, not in chambering and wantonness, not in strife and envying ; but put ye on the Lord Jesus Christ, and make not provision for the flesh, to fulfil the lusts thereof.’4 With the perusal of these words the long-repressed complex in his subconscious mind was broken up, the powerful stream of sexual feeling which had for so long stormed and fretted against, and every now and then by sheer force broken through, the repressing activities of the moral censorship, was diverted into a new channel, and henceforward fertilised his whole life with a passion for God—‘ the beauty so ancient yet so new,’ *—expressed under the form of ascetic mon- asticism. His new-found Christianity ®° was deepened and 1 Conf. v. 3-6. Other reasons contributed to bring about his secession, notably the scandalous lives of the Manichean ‘ elect’ (de moribus manich. li, 18-20), 2 v. supra, Lecture IV, p. 300. This period covers the years 383-386. 3 Conf. viii. 12. SOM. Si Tock As * Conf. x. 27: ‘sero te amavi, pulchritudo tam antiqua et tam nova, sero te amavi.’ ‘ T assume that the narrative of the Confessions may be taken ‘ at its face value,’ and that the theory advocated by M. Gourdon (Essai sur la conversion de St. Augustin, 1900), according to which the experience in the Milanese garden was a conversion to philosophy, not to Christianity, need not be seriously considered ; see Portalié, op. cit., col. 2273, 4. 326 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN philosophically formulated in dialectical converse with his friends at the sylvan retreat of Cassiciacum, where doubtless his private leisure was devoted to the further exploration of those ‘ books of the Platonists ’1 (probably the Emneads of Plotinus, in Victorinus’ Latin translation) with which he had already become acquainted at Milan. The year 387 witnessed his baptism by Ambrose, the death of Monnica, and his return to Africa, where he began that monastic life? for which the newly transfigured instincts of his nature craved, and which later caused many of the religious orders of the mediaeval Church, friars, eremites, and canons regular, to claim him as their spiritual father and legislator.? Four years before the close of the century he became bishop of Hippo Regius, the modern Bona, a small seaport on the Mediterranean coast which his name has immortalised for ever. It is not necessary for our present purposes to carry this sketch of his biography any further, inasmuch as his theology of grace, with its core of anthropology, was already complete in essentials by the time of his consecration to the episcopate, long before he had heard the name of his great opponent Pelagius. We note here a fact which must be borne in mind when we approach our final evaluation of the Augustinian ideas—the fact that they represent that version fof the Christian theory of the origin of evil into which his powerful and ardent spirit was naturally drawn in its recoil from the Iranian theory of an eternal dualism.) Augustine’s conception of the Fall and its consequences was the pro- duct of a reaction,/not against Pelagianism but against Manicheism,) thus constituting the most impressive and celebrated instance of the law which seems to determine the movements of Christian opinion with regard to the subject of our enquiry—the law, namely, that contact with dualism stimulates the mind of the Church towards a fresh accentua- 1.Conf, vii: 9.3 vill. 2. 2 At first in the home which he had inherited from Patricius at Tagaste, then at Hippo in a house attached to the church, and finally in the episcopal residence itself. 3 The so-called “ Rule of St. Augustine’ is an adaptation of a letter (ep. ccxxi.) of general direction and guidance, which he wrote in a.D. 423 to a community of women at Hippo. AUGUSTINIANISM 327 tion of the Fall-doctrine ; and it would seem to have been worked out in comparative peace, not under the stress of controversy, during the first ten years which immediately succeeded Augustine’s conversion. We find it, mildly phrased but already complete in essential outline, in the first book of the treatise de diversis guaestionibus ad Simplicianum, a work written in A.D. 397 to explain certain difficult passages of Scripture for the benefit of Simplician, Ambrose’s successor in the see of Milan.1 f Augustine here asserts that ‘sin,’ which for the moment seems to be synonymous with ‘ concupiscence * (the passage under discussion is Rom. vil. 7-25, in which, as we have already seen,? duapria and émOupia appear to be more or less convertible terms) originated in the transgression of Adam.* This ‘sin’ has become ingrained into human nature and is transmitted by physical heredity.*/ Here for the first time in the history of Christian thought we meet the epoch-making phrase originale peccatum, meaning a sinful quality which is born with us and is inherent in our con- stitution. But this sinful quality, it is clear, is conceived by Augustine to be ‘sin’ in the fullest sense of the term, albeit involuntarily acquired, for it deserves ‘ punishment,’ ® and therefore involves guilt ; and a little later we find the actual term oviginalis reatus, ‘ original’ or ‘ connatural’ ‘guilt.’® The guilt in question, however, appears at this early stage of Augustine’s thought to be, not so much the supposed 1 In later years Augustine was accustomed to appeal to this work as evidence for the continuity and consistency of his teaching with regard to Grace throughout his episcopate ; see de don. persev. xxi. 55; de praedest. sanct, iv. 8. *eLeecure TIT, p. 142 f: 3 ad Simplic. 1. q. I, 4: ‘sane quod ait, peccatum revixit adveniente mandato, satis significavit hoc modo aliquando vixisse peccatum, id est notum fuisse, sicut arbitror, in praevaricatione primi hominis, quia et ipse _ mandatum acceperat.’ 4 ibid. 10: ‘ quod si quaerit aliquis unde hoc scit, quod dicit habitare in carne sua non utique bonum, id est peccatum: unde nisi ex traduce mortalitatis et assiduitate voluptatis? illud est ex poena originalis peccatt, hoc est ex poena frequentati peccati. cum illo in hanc vitam nascimur, hoc vivendo addimus.’ 5 ibid. 10: ‘ ex poena originalis peccati.’ ® zbid. 20 (quoted below, p. 328, n. 3). 328 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN hereditary responsibility for Adam’s transgression,’ as the guilt of having ‘ concupiscence’ in usatall. Itisin any case certain that originale peccatum in Augustine always includes the idea of ‘ original guilt’; and we shall, therefore, for the purposes of this lecture suspend the popular use of the English term ‘original sin’ as meaning merely the bias or tendency towards sin )(which Augustine denotes by con- cupiscentia), and employ the phrase as the strict equivalent of originale peccatum. By virtue of its intimate saturation with ‘ concupiscence ’ and ‘ original guilt,’ the human stock constitutes a single massa peccati or ‘lump of sin’ (this terrible phrase was presumably suggested by Ambrosiaster’s words ‘ all have sinned in Adam as in a lump’?) which as such is justly doomed to everlasting death.* The freedom of the individual will is indeed nominally preserved *; but inasmuch as in unregenerate man the will is invariably determined by ‘ sin,’ that is, by an inborn aversion from the Creator and propension towards creatures, this freedom appears to be little more than a phrase. 1 So far as we have found traces of the idea of ‘ original guilt’ in pre-Augustinian writers, this is the form which it seems to have taken. 2 comm. in Rom. v. 12, quoted above, Lecture IV, p. 308, n. 1. 3 ad Simplic.i.q.2, 16: ‘sunt igitur omnes homines (quandoquidem, ut apostolus ait, in Adam omnes moriuniur, a quo in universum genus huma- num origo ducitur offensionis Dei) una quaedam massa peccati, supplicium debens divinae summaeque iustitiae, quod sive exigatur sive donatur nulla est iniquitas’; 20: ‘ tunc facta est una massa omnium, veniens de traduce peccati et de poena mortalitatis . . . concupiscentia carnalis de peccati poena iam regnans, universum genus humanum tamquam totam et unam conspersionem, oviginali veatu in omnia permanante, confuderat’ (‘ con- spersio’ here means ‘ dough’ or ‘ paste,’ as in 1 Cor. v. 7 Vulg., where it represents ¢uvpaya, Tert., adv. Marcion. iv. 24, et al., and carries on the metaphor of massa). The following variants of the phrase massa peccati, as applied to fallen mankind, have been collected by the learned Benedictine, Dom O. Rottmanner (Der Augustinismus, p. 8): massa Ppeccatorum, lutt, iniquitatis, ivae, mortis, damnationis, offensionis, massa tota vitiata, damnabilis, damnata. 4 ibid.i.q.1, 11: ‘ velle enim, inquit, adiacet mihi, perficere autem bonum non invenio, his verbis videtur non recte intelligentibus velut auferre liberum arbitrium. sed quomodo aufert, cum dicat, velle adiacet mihi ? certe enim ipsum velle in potestate est, quoniam adiacet nobis ; sed quod perficere bonum non est in potestate, ad meritum pertinet originalis peccati . . . quod non vult malum, hoc agit, superante concupiscentia, non solum vinculo mortalitatis, sed mole consuetudinis roborata.’ 21: ‘liberum voluntatis arbitrium plurimum valet, immo vero, est quidem ; sed in venumdatis sub peccato quid valet ? ’ AUGUSTINIANISM 340 In God’s resultant dealings with the human race His mercy and justice are equally exhibited. Out of the massa peccatt His mercy selects a fixed number of souls, who through no merits of their own are brought to baptism, ‘justified’ (which in Augustine’s terminology means ‘sanctified ’), and saved.. The rest of mankind is left by His justice in the ‘ lump of sin,’ rolling on its way unhindered to the bottomless pit. The equity of this procedure, which glorifies a small body of arbitrarily chosen favourites, and abandons all other human beings (who are ex hypothesi not more deserving of damnation than the fortunate objects of predestination) to their fate, is defended partly by the consideration that the lost have in any case no right to complain, inasmuch as they only get what they have deserved (by ‘ original guilt ’), and that the predestined have every reason to be satisfied with the arrangement, so far as it affects themselves 1: partly by an appeal to mystery and to the transcendental nature of the workings of the Divine Mind.* ‘ How unsearchable are his judgments, and his ways past finding out!’ It will be recognised at once that we have now reached the fully rounded, logically coherent expression of that ‘African’ or ‘ twice-born’ type of Fall-doctrine which in our last lecture was seen, slowly assuming definite shape and consistency, in a succession of Latin writers reaching from Tertullian to Ambrosiaster. Considered as a formal dog- matic scheme, it purports to be based upon the well-known Scriptural texts which we have already met with in previous 1 ad Simplic. i. q. 2,22: ‘ debitum si non reddis, habes quod gratuleris : si reddis, non habes quod queraris ’—an epigram in which, we may surmise, the reprobate would find but cold comfort, if Augustinianism represented objective fact. Cf. also de praedest. sanct. viii. 16: ‘ cur autem fides non omnibus detur, fidelem movere non debet, qui credit ex uno omnes isse in condemnationem sine dubitatione iustissimam: ita ut nulla Dei esset iusta reprehensio, etiam si nullus inde liberaretur.’ 2 1bid.i.q.2,16: ‘atque ita tenacissime firmissimeque credatur, idipsum quod Deus cuius vult miseretur et quem vult obdurat, hoc est, cuius vult miseretur et cuius vult non miseretur, esse dlicuius occultae atque ab humano modulo investigabilis aequitatis, , nisi remittantur. sed quomodo manent, si praeterita sunt, nisi quia praeterierunt actu, manent reatu? sic itaque fieri e contrario potest, ut etiam illud’ (sc. malum concupiscentiae) ‘ maneat actu, praetereat reatu.’ 4 de nupt. et conc. i. 20, 21: ‘propter hanc’ [sc. concupiscentiam] ‘ergo fit ut etiam de iustis et legitimis nuptiis filiorum Dei, non filii Dei sed filii saeculi generentur: qua et ii qui genuerant, si iam regenerati sunt, non ex hoc generant ex quo filii Dei sed ex quo adhuc filii saeculi . . . ex hac igitur concupiscentia carnis quod nascitur, utique mundo non Deo -nascitur: Deo autem nascitur cum ex aqua et Spiritu renascitur. huius concupiscentiae reatum regeneratio sola dimittit, ac per hoc generatio trahit.’ 368 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN propagated from parent to child in and through the act of generation, would seem to have relieved Augustine of the necessity of deciding between the ‘creationist’ and the ‘traducianist ’ views of the origin of the soul; for it is equally compatible with either. His personal inclinations pointed in the direction of ‘ creationism’; but he found it difficult to explain why God should have created so many millions of souls in a state of innocence, only to be infused into bodies which He knew were bound to pollute them with concupiscence.t Moreover, the Pelagians, it would seem, were ‘creationists’ to a man: hence, when charged by them with holding ‘traducianism,’ Augustine shows a distinct reluctance to repudiate the accusation.? His final position with regard to this point seems to have consisted in an affirmation of its indifference, provided that the reality of the innate disease and of its hereditary transmission were firmly maintained.? (v) So oppressive and overwhelming is the tyranny of fleshly appetite over fallen man, that he cannot even begin to raise himself out of the mire of sinfulness without the help of God’s prevenient grace. This position would seem logi- cally to involve the negation of human free-will; and from time to time Augustine uses phrases which can only be construed in this sense.4 The condition of man after the Fall is described as subject to a peccatum habendi dura necessitas.» Yet Augustine strenuously refuses to admit that our fallen race does not still possess free-will, and in order to preserve a nominal freedom in man he is driven to make use of shifts and expedients which, with all due respect for his mighty intellect, it is difficult to regard as more than mere verbal jugglery. In reply to Julian he admits that the libertas which Adam possessed in Paradise has perished ; this /zbertas is defined as freedom to remain in Paradise and 1 de anima et eius orig. i. 6, 13. 2 Cf. de pecc. merit. et rem, iii. 5; c. 11. epp. Pel. iii. 26; op. 1mperf. c. Tulian. 11.178; iv. 104. 3 ¢, Iulian. Pel. v. 17: ‘ista fides non negetur, et hoc quod de anima latet aut ex otio discitur, aut sicut alia multa in hac vita sine salutis labe nescitur.’ 4 e.g. enchir. 30: ‘amissum est liberum arbitrium’; de perfect. iust. hom. 9: ‘ poenalis vitiositas subsecuta ex libertate fecit necessitatem,’ 5 de perfect. iust. hom. 9. . AUGUSTINIANISM 369 acquire the gift of immortality. But although freedom (ibertas) has perished free-will (berum arbitrium) still exists; and this elusive and all but incomprehensible distinction between ‘ freedom’ and ‘ free-will’ is defended, not by metaphysical arguments, but by an exposition of the metaphorical language employed by St. Paul in Rom. vi. 20 with regard to the condition of unregenerate man: ‘ When ye were enslaved to sin, ye were free in regard to righteous- ness.’ The confusion introduced into Augustine’s con- ception of free-will by his determination to use St. Paul’s image, borrowed from the Roman law of slavery, as though it were a metaphysical or psychological definition, is com- plete. The will of fallen man is free, but in point of fact it always freely chooses evil under the overwhelming influence of concupiscence, or of the devil’s power.? We are free to do what we like, but we are not free to like what we ought to like. This interpretation of ‘freedom’ is justified by the consideration that if freedom means the power to choose either good or evil God Himself is not free, nor will the blessed in Heaven be free, because they will be subject to the beata necessitas non peccandr.* It is not necessary to go into this very abstruse and difficult conception of freedom any further, inasmuch as it is clear that Augustine, whether consciously or not, is Se, 4t. epp,. Pel, 3: 5. 2 Cfeibids it, 0. 8 Cf. op. imperf.c. Iulian.i. 100, 102; de civ. Det, xxii. 30: ‘ Deus ipse numquid quoniam peccare non potest, ideo liberum arbitrium habere negandus est ?’ and the whole context. The answer to this argument surely is that God is not free, in the sense in which freedom is predicable of human beings still1m via, in the state of probation ; if He were, it would be an imperfection in Him, and He would in fact not be God. The same consideration would also apply to the blessed, who are comprehensores in patria: their blessedness is based upon the fact that they cannot now fall, in other words, upon the fact that they are not ‘free.’ The discussion of the whole matter, both by Augustine and by some of his successors, is vitiated by a failure to distinguish between three senses of the word ‘freedom,’ viz. (a) physical, in which it connotes absence of external - constraint : in this sense, God undoubtedly is free, and man may or may not be, according to circumstances ; (b) metaphysical, in the sense of interior indetermination ; in this sense, God and the saints are not free, but man in the state of probation is ; (c) metaphorical, in the sense of * freedom from sin ’ or from concupiscence ; this actually means a fixed interior determina- tion towards good, in other words, it implies the exact opposite of freedom in sense (0). 2B 370 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN really trying to run with the hare and hunt with the hounds. He wants to keep freedom in order to preserve man’s responsibility for actual sin, and yet he wishes to throw it overboard in order to provide scope for irresistible grace. If we disregard verbal subtleties and concentrate our attention on realities, we shall find that the Augustinian system implies the negation of free-will in any except a highly recondite and unnatural sense of the term. Mozley’s words can hardly be bettered : (Augustine) explained the corruption of human nature to mean the loss of free-will; and this statement was the funda- mental barrier which divided the later from the earlier scheme and rationale of original sin. The will, according to the earlier school, was not substantially affected by the Fall. Its circum- stances, its means and appliances, were altered, not itself; and endowed with spiritual aids in Paradise, deprived of them at the Fall; re-endowed with them under the Gospel, it retained throughout these alterations one and the same essential power, in that power of choice whereby it was, in every successive state of higher or lower means, able to use and avail itself of whatever means it had. But in Augustine’s scheme the will itself was disabled at the Fall, and not only certain impulses to it with- drawn, its power of choice was gone, and man was unable not only to rise above a defective goodness, but to avoid positive sin. He was thenceforth, prior to the operation of grace, in a state of necessity on the side of evil, a slave to the devil and to his own inordinate lusts.? As a result of the Fall, therefore, according to Augustine, the nerve of the human will is severed, and concupiscence rages unchecked. Yet Augustine is not prepared to draw from these facts—or supposed facts—their logical conclusion, which would seem to be the Calvinistic doctrine of the ‘ total depravity ’ of human nature. We may surmise that it was 1 Augustinian Doctrine of Predestination, p. 125 f. 2 A well-known passage, de nat. et grat. 42, appears at first sight to exempt the Blessed Virgin Mary from this law, and has been quoted as an anticipation of the doctrine of her Immaculate Conception: ‘ excepta igitur sancta virgine Maria, de qua propter honorem Domini nullam prorsus, cum de peccatis agitur, haberi volo quaestionem : unde enim scimus, quid ei plus gratiae collatum fuerit ad vincendum omni ex parte peccatum, quae concipere et parere meruit, quem constat nullum habuisse peccatum ?’ Yet, at their highest interpretation, these words do not appear to do more than suggest that Mary may have been safeguarded, by a special grace, from actual sin. AUGUSTINIANISM 371 his Platonic monism which, perhaps subconsciously, re- strained him from formulating this final corollary of the ‘twice-born ’ version of the Fall-doctrine. For the Platonist all being, in so far as it is true being, is good; and every- thing that exists is either God or derived from God. Even the nature of the devil, gua created nature, is good; he is only evil as it were per accidens, because of the perversion of his will.t Hence evil—even the evil of original sin—is nothing positive: it isa defect of goodness, the absence of virtue, just as darkness is not a substantive thing-in-itself but merely the absence of light.2 These are ideas which we have already encountered in the great Greek Fathers of the fourth century,? and which need not be commented on now, save by the observation that their logical effect would necessarily be to blunt the edge of the antithesis between ‘nature’ and ‘ grace,’ which arose out of Augustine’s own specifically ‘twice-born’ experience. If this suggestion does actually represent the interior workings of Augustine’s mind, it would not be the first time that the harsh judgment of human nature generated by the fervid emotions of an African Fall-speculator had been mollified by the genial influences of his Hellenic philosophical background: Origen is an instance of the same phenomenon.* At any rate, it is noteworthy that Augustine, in the opening chapters of the treatise On nature and grace, explicitly admits that ‘ all the good qualities which human nature, even as fallen, still possesses in its constitution, its life, its senses, its intellect, it has from the most high God, its creator and artificer’ >: 1 de civ. Det, xix. 13: “ proinde nec ipsius diaboli natura, in quantum natura est, malum est ; sed perversitas eam malam facit.’ 2 Cf. de nat. boni 17: ‘non ergo mala est, in quantum natura est, ulla natura; sed cuique naturae non est malum nisi minui bono’; enarr. in ps. vil. 19: ‘non quod aliqua sit natura tenebrarum. ommnis enim natura, in quantum natura est, esse cogitur. esse autem ad lucem pertinet : non esse ad tenebras. qui ergo deserit eum a quo factus est et inclinat in id unde factus est, id est in nihilum, in hoc peccato tenebratur.’ 3 Lecture IV, pp. 255, 260, 266, 278. 4 ibid. p. 209. 5 de nat. et grat. 3. As against Julian, he repudiates the idea that human nature is essentially, not merely accidentally, evil: ‘non dixeram naturam humanam malam non esse sed malum non esse: hoc est, ut planius loquar, non dixeram vitiatam non esse, sed vitium non esse’ (op. imperf. ili. 190). 372 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN and, in the section of the Retractations dealing with this book, he claims to have upheld grace ‘ not indeed in dis- paragement of nature, but as that which liberates and controls nature.’ } (b) We now pass to the question of the results of the Fall as viewed under the legal or forensic category, that is, to the question of ‘ original guilt,’ of the inherited taint considered as veatus rather than as vitvum, together with the allied question of the mode of transmission or communica- tion of such guilt. It is curious and noteworthy that, whereas the transmission of original. sin, considered as vitium, is said to take place by way of biological heredity (the act of generation being the nexus which conveys the fatal legacy of concupiscence from parent to child), the communication of original sin, considered as reatus, from Adam to his posterity is explained in accordance with the theory of ‘seminal identity.’ No doubt it is possible to harmonise these two conceptions of the mode of trans- mission, but Augustine makes no effort to do so. When ‘original guilt’ is in question, the latter theory is affirmed in the stiffest and most uncompromising fashion. Adam, by his wilful transgression, incurred infinite guilt and was therefore justly doomed to eternal damnation. But, at the moment when he committed his sin, he included within , himself, in a strictly physiological sense, the whole of the ~ human race, all the countless myriads who were to proceed from his loins ; or, if the more metaphysical way of phrasing the matter be preferred, Adam was the universal of human nature, and as such subsumed in himself all the particular men who have since been born. Consequently, all men sinned ‘in Adam,’ in the sense that at the moment of the Fall they were all infinitesimally minute portions of the Adam who sinned, or particulars included in the universal nature which sinned: their personalities and wills were all implicit in Adam’s personality and will. The possibility of such pre-natal participation in an ancestor’s act is demon- strated by the instance of Levi, who was yet in the loins of Abraham when the latter paid tithes to Melchisedek, and who must therefore, in the mind of the author of the Epistle 1 yetract. il. 42. C—O ee ee ee ee) a AUGUSTINIANISM 3/0 to the Hebrews, be deemed to have ‘seminally’ shared in the payment of those tithes.1 It follows, according to Augustine’s logic, that all human beings are born subject to the penalty of eternal hell for a sin which they are alleged to have pre-natally committed in Adam’s loins: and this appalling sentence is duly executed upon all except those whom the inscrutable decree of God’s predestination singles out from the ‘mass of perdition,’ brings to the absolving waters of baptism, and endows with the grace of final perse- verance. The Doctor of Hippo repeatedly and vehemently insists upon the ‘justice’ of this arrangement whereby millions of the human race are condemned to an eternity of torture as the punishment of a crime for which they have ex hypothest no personal responsibility whatsoever.? This macabre doctrine runs through the warp and weft of Augustinianism like an endless black thread. Though the passages in Augustine’s works which embody it are innumerable, it may nevertheless be worth while to quote two of the most gloomy and powerful. The first contains its foundation, the theory of ‘seminal’ or ‘ metaphysical identity ’ God indeed created man upright, being Himself the author of natures, not of vices. But man, having of his own free-will become depraved, and having been justly condemned, begat a posterity in the same state of depravation and condemnation. For we all were in that one man , seeing that we all were that one man (omnes enim fuimus in illo uno, quando omnes fuimus ille unus*®) who fell into sin through the woman, who was made of him before the sin. Not yet had we received those individually created and distinct shapes, in which we were as separate individuals to live; but there was a seminal nature, from which we were to be propagated; and, this having been vitiated by sin, tied with the chain of death, and justly con- demned, it follows that man would be born from man in no other condition .4 1 Heb. vii. 9, 10; quoted in op. wmperf. c. Iulian. i. 48. 2 It should be noted that original sin, according to the Augustinian conception, really contains two distinct kinds of original guilt, viz. (1) the guilt of having ‘sinned in Adam,’ and (2) the guilt of possessing con- cupiscence, which is both pecegium and poena peccait. 3 Cf. Ambrose’s phrase ‘fuit Adam, et in illo fuimus omnes’ (expos. ev. sec. Luc. vii. 234, quoted above, p. 305, n. 3). 4 de civ. Det, xiii. 14. 374 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN The second illustrates the superstructure, that is, the theory of original guilt : Banished after his sin, Adam bound his offspring also with the penalty of death and damnation, that offspring which by sinning he had corrupted in himself, as in a root ; so that whatever progeny was born (through carnal con- cupiscence, by which a fitting retribution for his disobedience was bestowed upon him) from himself and his spouse—who was the cause of his sin and the companion of his damnation—would drag through the ages the burden of original sin, by which it would itself be dragged, through manifold errors and sorrows, down to that final and never-ending torment with the rebel angels. ...So the matter stood; the damned lump of humanity (totius humani generis massa damnata) was lying prostrate, nay, was wallowing, in evil, it was ever falling head- long from one wickedness to another ; and, joined to the faction of the angels who had sinned, it was paying the most righteous penalty of its impious treason. It is, perhaps, better not to speculate with regard to the amount of unhappiness which these ideas must have brought to sensitive souls between the time of their first promulgation and that of the final eclipse of Augustinianism by Darwinism in the nineteenth century. Two corollaries of the Augustinian doctrine of original sin remain to be noticed. The first of these is the theory which denies the possibility of virtue, good works, or merit in the unbaptised, a theory which appears to survive in the thirteenth of our Thirty-Nine Articles, in the intensified form of the assertion that works before justification ? ‘ have the nature of sin.’ Inasmuch as human nature, apart from grace, is so deeply depraved, it is impossible for the heathen to possess genuine virtue, though they may perform actions which in Christians would be the symptoms of genuine virtue. ‘ regards heathen morality as bad 1enchirid. 26, 27. * This phrase is taken from the title of the Article: it is, however, fair to mention the fact that the text of the Article only condemns ‘ works done before the grace of Christ and the inspiration of his Spirit,’ which might, verbally at any rate, be taken to mean works other than good works: though in that case the body of the Article becomes a sonorous platitude. 3 In the beautiful treatise de spiritu et litera, which reveals only the noblest and most humane side of Augustine, he admits that the good deeds of the heathen may be praised ‘ merito recteque’: but he adds, as though AUGUSTINIANISM 375 at the foundation, and therefore as hollow, false, and only seeming morality itself.’ 1 God forbid [he exclaims against Julian] that we should admit the existence of true virtue in anyone except he be righteous. And God forbid that we should admit anyone to be truly righteous, unless he lives by faith: ‘ for the righteous lives by faith.’ Who then of those who wish to be thought Christians (except the Pelagians alone, or perhaps you alone even amongst Pelagians) will apply the epithet of ‘righteous’ to an infidel, to an impious man, to one sold into the power of the devil ?— even though such a one should be a Fabricius, a Fabius, a Scipio, a Regulus, names by which you thought that I could be brow- beaten, as though we were debating in the old Senate-house at Rome ! 2 Hence even continence and chastity are no virtues when displayed by the ‘impious,’ that is, non-Christians. The Scriptural basis of this position appears to consist solely in a scrap of the Epistle to the Romans, torn from its context and expanded into a general principle which the Apostle would never have recognised as his own: ‘ What- soever is not of faith’ (that is, according to Augustine, specifically Christian faith) ‘is sin.’* Though he did not himself declare the virtues of pagans to be sflendida vitia, this phrase, coined by his disciples of a later day, is fearing that he has conceded too much, ‘ quamquam si discutiantur quo fine fiunt, vix inveniuntur quae iustitiae debitam laudem defensionemve mereantur’ (§ 48). In the following passages Augustine appears (some- what inconsistently with his general position) to recognise the possibility of real virtue outside the Church, though such virtue is solely the gift of God: ep. cxliv. 2 (Polemo, a pagan, said to have renounced drunken- ness) ; de patient. 23 (schismatic martyrs will, in view of their martyrdom, be treated more leniently in the final judgment); de grat. Christi 25 (Ahasuerus changed by God’s interior operation from fury to gentleness). 1 J. B. Mozley, Augustinian Doctrine of Predestination, p. 127. ecad uitam. Jel. iv 17, 8 ibid. ad fin. 4 Rom. xiv. 23, cited in de gestis Pel. 34; c. Iulian. Pel.iv.24. The true meaning of the phrase, in relation to the vegetarian controversy which the Apostle is discussing, has been well summed up by Sanday and Headlam (ICC., p. 393, note in Joc.) in the sentence ‘ Weakly to comply with other persons’ customs without being convinced of their indifference is itself sin’ ; it has no reference to the ordinary conduct of non-Christians. 376 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN not very far from expressing his real thought on the point.? The second corollary which deserves mention is the doctrine of the necessary damnation of all persons dying unbaptised, including personally guiltless infants. This follows inevitably from the conception of the massa damnata, which (with the exception of the company of predestined souls arbitrarily picked out of it for exaltation to eternal life) steadily gravitates, under the inexorable pressure of the divine justice, towards the bottomless pit. At one period of his life, indeed, Augustine appears to have shrunk from the full rigour of this pitiless dogma. In A.D. 415 we find him writing to Jerome for help. Teach me [he begs] what I am to teach, teach me what I am to hold, and tell me, if souls are individually created for all the individuals who are this day being born, when (? where) do such souls sin in the little ones, that they should need the remission of sin imparted by the sacrament of Christ . . . ? or, if they sin not, by what justice of the Creator are they so bound to another’s sin, so soon as they are infused into their new-begotten members, that damnation seizes upon them, unless help is brought to them through the Church? especially in view of the fact that it is not in their power to secure being helped by the grace of baptism. So many thousands of souls which at the deaths of infants depart from their bodies without the pardon bestowed by the Christian sacrament—with what equity can they be damned, if, newly created, by no previous sin of their own but solely by the will of the Creator, all these individual souls were infused into the individual bodies for the animation of which He created and gave them ? ? Jerome excused himself, on the ground of want of leisure, from giving an answer to these questions, which are indeed unanswerable. The fact that Augustine never- theless maintained this inhuman theory down to the last days of his life is a melancholy illustration of the way in which the best of men may allow the kindly instincts of 1 The phrase is probably an inference from de civ. Det xix. 25: ‘proinde virtutes, quas sibi habere videtur [sc. mens veri Dei nescia], per quas imperat corpori et vitiis ad quodlibet adipiscendum vel tenendum, nisi ad Deum retulerit, etiam ipsae vitia sunt potius quam virtutes.’ 2 ep. clxvi. Io. It will be noticed that in this passage Augustine assumes ‘creationism’: but the difficulty is equally pressing on the “traducianist ’ hypothesis. : AUGUSTINIANISM 377 human nature to be overridden by the demands of a fanatical logic. The Augustinian doctrine on this point is vividly ex- pressed in a woodcut which is prefixed to tom. x. of the Benedictine edition of 1700, the volume containing the anti-Pelagian treatises. This woodcut is meant to illustrate the passage op. imperf. c. Iul. 1. 39. It depicts the interior of a church in baroque style. On the right of the picture is the baptistery, where a bishop is plunging a naked infant into the font; this infant is evidently one of the elect, for the Holy Spirit is represented as a dove descending upon him in a stream of supernatural glory. Parents, sponsors, acolytes stand around in various attitudes of edification. On the left is the nave of the church ; here another christen- ing party is seen, suddenly halted with expressions and gestures of horror and dismay, just before the entrance to the baptistery : in their midst, a nurse holds the corpse of an infant, who was being brought to baptism, but has that very moment unexpectedly died (of convulsions, or what not) on the very verge of receiving the Sacrament of re- generation, and whose soul must therefore be presumed to have gone straight to hell, in virtue of original sin. The picture is surmounted by a scroll, bearing the inscription “Unus assumitur et alter relinquitur; Quia magna est gratia Dei, et verax iustitia Dei’ (taken from the passage in question: the context adds ‘sed quare ille potius quam ille >—inscrutabilia sunt iudicia Dei’). When the whole theory is so horrible, it is perhaps a small matter that it appears to assume a purely mechanical view of the efficacy of infant baptism. Augustine must, indeed, be allowed whatever credit may attach to the fact that at various times during the main period of his theological activity he expresses the opinion that the punishment of unbaptised babes, albeit eternal, will be of the mildest kind.1 No hint of this qualification, however, is shown by his last utterance on the subject, in the unfinished work against Julian. Here he speaks of the 1 de pecc. merit, et vem, i. 21: enchirid. 23 (xcilil), with reference in general to those who die in original sin only, without having committed actual sin; c. Iulian. Pel. v. 44 (‘ damnatio omnium levissima’). 378 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN ceremony of insufflation, or breathing on the face of the catechumen, which still survives in the modern Roman ritual of baptism; and he tells us that this ceremony is performed in order that the devil, in whose power the little one is born (as being ‘ guilty’ through the contagion of original sin), may be cast forth, and the child transferred to the power of Christ. But, he adds, if the little one is not so delivered from the power of darkness, he remains under it. Why (he naively enquires) should it be a matter of wonder that the little one is doomed to eternal fire with the devil, seeing that he is not permitted to enter the kingdom of God ? 1 Before proceeding to the task of disentangling what appear to be the permanently valuable elements in the Augustinian doctrine of man and of sin from those which are morbid or irrational, it will be well to indicate the arguments upon which the doctrine was formally based. (It is doubtless unnecessary to re-emphasise the distinction between the psychological ground of Augustinianism, con- sisting in its author’s ‘ twice-born’ temperament, and the logical premises from which it was nominally deduced: and it will be understood that to recognise Augustine’s theological case for his doctrine as being ultimately an ex fost facto “rationalisation ’ of a peculiarly vehement type of emotional experience in no way reflects upon his personal sincerity and good faith in putting it forward.) These arguments, which recur again and again throughout the vast mass of Augustine’s anti-Pelagian writings, do not when collected amount to very much. The ‘ appeal to Scripture ’ consists in ringing the changes on the four or five proof-texts with which we are already familiar—the Psalmist’s cry ‘ Behold, I was shapen in wickedness’ 2; the Septuagintal mistrans- lation of Job xiv. 4, 5 ‘ Who shall be free from defilement ? not one, even though his life be but a day upon the earth’ 8; the Johannine Christ’s affirmation of the necessity of a new birth through water and the Spirit as a condition of entrance 1 op. imperf. c. Iulian, iii. 199. wild Suc bad bigs 3 For the true text see Driver and Buchanan Gray, Job (ICC.), 1921, Doel oye AUGUSTINIANISM 379 into the kingdom of God?! ; the phrase ‘ children of wrath ’ from Eph. ii. 3; and the text which Augustine believed to be his trump card, the clause from Rom. v. 12 (lat.)—‘ in quo omnes peccarunt,’ misinterpreted in accordance with Ambrosiaster’s fatal blunder as ‘in whom (sc. Adam) all have sinned.’2 The slenderness of the Biblical foundation upon which Augustine’s terrific dogma is reared will be realised when it is pointed out that of his five proof-texts three are mistranslations. The ‘ appeal to tradition,’ in so far as it is not a mere assertion, bases itself upon an alleged consensus of the Fathers: but it is impossible not to observe that the Fathers whom Augustine cites are for the most part Western, and that the list of authorities which may be compiled from his various references is a fairly exhaustive catalogue of upholders of the specifically “‘ twice-born ’ view, no account being taken of the Apologists or of the Alexand- rines.2 This, however, does not prevent him from triumph- antly exclaiming to Julian ‘ You are refuted on every side ! so great testimonies of the Saints are clearer than daylight.’ 4 Thirdly, we have the argument which has played so great a part in this discussion from the time of Origen downwards, drawn from the actual practice of the Church in administer- ing baptism to infants, with exsufflations, exorcisms, and renunciations of Satan; all of which, it is contended, would be futile if the newly born infant were not in some sense guilty of Adam’s sin. Lastly, and more reasonably, Augustine bases his theory upon the actual state of man, 1 St. John iii. 5. 2 For remarks upon Ambrosiaster’s misunderstanding of 7” quo, itself a faulty rendering of 颒 @, see Lecture IV, p. 308f. Typical instances of Augustine’s use of this mistake to support the idea of our ‘ seminal identity ’ with Adam are serm. ccxciv. 15; c. 11. epp. Pel. iv. 7 (here he quotes Ambrosiaster’s comment, ‘manifestum in Adam omnes peccasse quasi in massa,’ as from ‘sanctus Hilarius’); de pecc. merit. et rem.i. 11. The correct translation which the Pelagians gave of éd’ @, viz., propter quod, was denounced by Augustine, despite his imperfect acquaintance with Greek, as importing ‘sensum alium novum atque distortum et a vero abhorrentem ’ (c. Lulian. Pel. vi. 75). 8 Augustine cites in favour of his general scheme of Fall-doctrine Irenaeus, Cyprian, Hilary, Ambrose, Ambrosiaster, Reticius of Autun, Jerome: amongst Eastern writers, Gregory. of Nazianzus, Basil, John Chrysostom. 4c. Iulian. Pel. i. 30: ‘convinceris undique: luce clariora sunt testimonia tanta sanctorum.’ 380 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN the immensity of misery, mental and physical, in which he is overwhelmed. There are inexplicable catastrophes of nature, earthquakes and eruptions, bringing pain and death to thousands of innocent people, there are the sufferings of little cnildren ; which even include, so he tells us, the horrors of demoniacal possession. All this mass of apparently meaningless and inexplicable woe points, according to our author, to the presence of a profound hereditary guilt, derived from the beginning of the race and prior to the responsibility of any individual. AN EVALUATION OF THE AUGUSTINIAN DOCTRINE In view of the more shocking and repulsive aspects of Augustine’s doctrine of original guilt, as set out above, many will doubtless think it superfluous to subject his system to any reasoned or detailed criticism at all. It is nevertheless possible, within the compass of a few words, to distinguish between the permanently valuable and the worthless elements in his thought on this subject. The doctrine which we have just sketched may be summed up in three great conceptions, those of ‘ original righteousness,’ ‘ original sin’ considered as vitium, and ‘ original sin’ con- sidered as veatus (that is, ‘ original guilt’). I venture to submit the judgment that the first and third of these con- ceptions, in their strict Augustinian form, are worthless from the point of view of modern thought, but that the second contains large elements of permanent truth. We need not spend much time upon Augustine’s conception of ‘ original righteousness.’ Even if it were possible to treat Gen. Iii. as being a literal record of historical facts, Augustine’s idealised picture of the superhuman qualities of the first man goes far beyond the language of the Scriptural text, and beyond that conception of man’s first condition as one of ‘infancy ’ which appears in the earliest Greek Fathers ; and it will hardly be disputed in the light of what we now know about the primitive history of man, that his picture of a “Golden Age’ and of an earthly Paradise tenanted by a saintly couple belongs to the realm of mythology. Nor is it So Ne a eS Oe Re Eee Pees ies ns se a Bs — AUGUSTINIANISM 381 necessary to do more than point out the absurdity of the theory of ‘ original guilt,’ which asserts that human beings are held responsible by an all-just Judge for an act which they did not commit and for physiological and psychological facts which they cannot help. At this time of day it is hardly necessary to bestow the compliment of a serious refutation upon the theory of ‘ seminal identity.’ Nor can any verbal manipulation of the ‘ universal’ of human nature make it just to punish a man for a sin alleged to have been committed several millenniums previously by another man. Those (if there are any such) who demand a formal disproof of the belief that what is ex hypothesi an inherited psycho- logical malady is regarded by God in the light of a volun- tarily committed crime may be referred to the scathing satire of Samuel Butler’s ‘ Erewhon.’ + Augustine feels the force of such objections as these, with which the Pelagians were not.slow to press him: and hence he is fain to shelter himself behind the mystery which shrouds all the operations of the Divine Being, availing himself to the full of two convenient texts from the Epistle to the Romans?2: ‘Nay but, O man, who art thou that repliest against God?’ and ‘How unsearchable are his judgments, and his ways past tracing out!’ and appealing to the conception of an ‘ occult justice’ in God, which may vindicate the apparent arbitrariness of His predestination, and may differ as far from ordinary human justice as God Himself differs from man. A _ typical expression of this conception is to be found in the following passage : By how much divine justice is loftier than human justice, by so much is it more inscrutable, and by so much it differs from human justice. . . . Think on these things, and forbear to set God the Judge in comparison with human judges, that God whom we must not doubt to be just even when He does what seems to men unjust, or what, if it were done by a man, would actually be unjust.* 1 T do not know whether Butler had ever read the treatise de correptione et gratia, in which Augustine maintains that it is reasonable to rebuke men for defects for the possession of which they are not responsible: but Evewhon might have been written as a reply to it. Ge 20 and ‘xi. 33: 3 op. imperf. c. Iulian. ili. 24. 382 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN Such a position lies open to the unanswerable retort made by John Stuart Mill to a similar ‘appeal to mystery’ advanced in this pulpit, in the Bampton Lectures of sixty- six years ago: ‘I will call no being good [or just] who is not what I mean when I apply that epithet to my fellow- creatures ; and if such a being can sentence me to hell for not so calling him, to hell I will go.’1 On the other hand, Augustine’s analysis of original sin, in the sense of the vitium or inbred disease of human nature, would seem to be marked by psychological acuteness and truth. We need not go all the way with him in his practical denial of free- will to recognise the subtlety of his analysis of the moral struggle, and the aptness of his division of the rebellious forces within the citadel of man’s soul into ‘ pride,’ the hypertrophied instinct of self-assertion, and ‘ concupiscence,’ representing mainly, though not exclusively, the ungovern- able instinct of the race to perpetuate itself even at the expense of a particular individual’s suffering? We have seen that Augustine’s conception of the inherited infirmity, merely as such, does not appear to go beyond the Pauline conception, save in so far as his perverse view of sex is concerned: and his borrowing from Platonism of the anhypostatic notion of evil points ultimately to the idea of original sin as a deprivatio rather than a depravatio, a defect or absence of good rather than a positive evil substance,® a weakness of will rather than a corruption of appetite. No Christian thinker in his senses will maintain that Augustinianism is a heresy. Yet a theological opinion may be profoundly erroneous without being either formally or materially heretical ; and, if the contention of these lectures has been sound, at least two-thirds of the classical version of the ‘ twice-born’ doctrine of man and of sin deserve the former note. If Augustine’s doctrines of the Fall and of 1 J. 5S. Mill, An Examination of Sir Wiliam Hamilton’s Philosophy, 1865, p. 103, replying to H. L. Mansel’s Bampton Lectures, ‘ The Limits of Religious Thought,’ 1858. A 2 See Harnack, History of Dogma, E. tr. 1898, v. p. 211: and cf. infra, Lecture ViLip 481; 3 Augustine, very justly, claims this point as decisively differentiating his conception of evil from the Manichean: op. imperf. c. Iulian. iii. 175. 4 Cf. Lecture VII, p. 483. AUGUSTINIANISM Lee original sin—with their mythological conception of the physical, moral, and mental stature of the first man, with their logically incoherent notion of original guilt, their fanatical denial of the possibility of virtue outside the Church, and their horrible corollary of the necessary damna-~ tion of unbaptised infants—were really ‘ the ecclesiastical doctrine,’ that is, the doctrine of the Church, as both friends and opponents have, at least in Western Europe, hitherto assumed it to be; if the whole fabric of orthodox dogma were really based upon this one-sided theory of human nature, seamed as it is with so large a vein of mythology and split by a colossal self-contradiction ; we should be obliged to conclude that the prospects of defending historical Christianity in the coming generation were of a singularly unpromising kind. Pelagius was right when he affirmed that these questions were not, strictly speaking, parts of the Faith! ; but Augustine was also right when he said that they belonged to the foundations of the Faith? ; and no structure can stand if the rock on which it is built is reduced, by a process of attrition or molecular disintegration, to a heap of dust. If Catholic Christianity presupposes $tatements about human nature and about the origin of sin which are intellectually indefensible and morally revolting, then all is over with it) If its axioms have been refuted, it is waste of time to investigate the conclusions which follow from them. If the key position of the Christian trenches has already been stormed, the endeavour to hold the rest of the line is but useless effort. These considerations have been our justification for the extended review to which we have subjected the genetic history of these doctrines— a review which has been designed for no other purpose than to furnish us with the materials for returning an answer to the question ‘Is ‘“‘ the ecclesiastical doctrine ”’ identical with the Augustinian doctrine?’ or, in other words, ‘Is the Christian Church, as such, committed to Augustinianism ? ’ In view of the gradual development of this doctrine, side by side with the vaguer and less severe ‘ Hellenic ’ view A USSUPIES Dy 335,114 3: 2 v. supra, Lecture IV, p. 314, n. 2. 384 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN (which, as we have seen, is the more primitive, as being traceable well back into the second century), it may appear unnecessary even to raise this question: and, indeed, it may now be claimed that whatever pretensions to satisfy the central test of the Vincentian triad, that of acceptance semper, were asserted by Augustinianism have now been decisively dispelled Yet it is theoretically possible—and it has sometimes been the case—that an idea which cannot be discovered in the earliest epochs of Christian history has nevertheless at a later date diffused itself so intimately through the mind of the Great Church as to acquire at least a plausible title to the honour of acceptance ubique et ab omnibus. Such an idea could not, indeed, be affirmed to be an integral part of the Faith: but, if its universal accep- tance were extended over many centuries, it might be deemed to have acquired a certain prerogative or auctoritas, which, if the idea in question were reasonable, might well serve to commend it to Christian thinkers, and, if it were absurd or unreasonable, would correspondingly discredit the cor- — porate judgment of the Christian society. It will therefore be pertinent to conclude this lecture by enquiring ‘ Did Augustine, either during his lifetime or after his death, succeed in making his characteristic opinions an integral part of orthodoxy, as orthodoxy was understood during the remainder of the period of “ undivided ”’ Christendom, down to the schism of A.D. 1054 2? Did he rivet the theories of “original righteousness’’ ‘‘seminal identity’’ and “ original guilt’ into the fabric of orthodoxy as firmly as Athanasius had riveted the Homoousion ?’ These questions may be answered in a few words. 1 A typical instance of such pretensions is to be found in c. Iulian. Pel. vi. 39: ‘ nihil de hac re iam tunc sentiens . . . nisi quod antiquitus discit et docet omnis ecclesia.’ Curiously enough, the original author of the ‘Vincentian Canon’ (which, on our shewing, deprives the specifically Augustinian doctrine of any claim to oecumenicity) thinks that it con- firms the idea of ‘ original guilt’; he enquires rhetorically ‘ quis ante prodigiosum discipulum eius (sc. Pelagii) Caelestium reatu praevari- cationis Adae omne humanum genus denegavit obstrictum ?’ (S. Vine. Lir. commonit. 62). The obvious retort is ‘quis ante Ambrosium et Augustinum affirmavit ? AUGUSTINIANISM 385 THE EXTENT TO WHICH THE AUGUSTINIAN DOCTRINE WAS ACCEPTED BY THE WORLD-CHURCH The assent of the Universal Church to a doctrinal proposition may be manifested either by some formal and official act or by tacit acquiescence and general though informal adoption. The only. official acts which could conceivably be construed as committing the Great Church to the specifically Augustinian points of ‘ original righteous- ness’ and ‘ original guilt’ are (a) the (alleged) world-wide subscription, enforced by the sword of the Emperors, of the Catholic episcopate to the ¢vactoria of Zosimus, and (0d) the condemnation of ‘the partisans of Caelestius’ by the Council of Ephesus. (a) The few surviving fragments ? of the tvactorta contain little of doctrinal import : it may, however, be assumed that it was drafted in such a way as to enforce at least the main points of the Augustinian position, including ‘ original righteousness’ and ‘original guilt.’? Ecclesiastical his- torians have hitherto taken for granted the assertion that Julian of Eclanum and his eighteen associates stood alone in refusing subscription to it.4 This statement appears, how- ever, to be open to question. The sole testimony for a literally universal acceptance of the ¢vactoria is found in the writings of Marius Mercator,® an ecclesiastically minded 1 The confirmation of an unspecified synod of Carthage, which may or may not be that of a.pD. 418, by can. 2 of the Council 7x Trulio (Hardouin iii. 1660 C) can hardly be interpreted as signifying an official adoption of Augustinianism by the Eastern Church. 2 These were collected by P. Coustant, epistolae Romanorum pontificum, 1721, tom. i, col. 994-998, and are reprinted in PL XX. 693 f. 3 It is possible that, as Coustant (op. cit. col. 996, reprinted in PL col. 694 B) suggests, Augustine may be referring to the tvactoria in the passage de an. et eius orig. xii. 17: ‘novellos haereticos Pelagianos iustissime conciliorum catholicorum et sedis apostolicae damnavit auctoritas, eo quod ausi fuerint non baptizatis parvulis dare quietis et salutis locum etiam praeter regnum coelorum.’ If this is so, the Pope followed the Africans in their condemnation of limbo. 4 Duchesne, however (Hist. ancienne de I’ Eglise, iii. p. 264, n. 1), seems to feel some doubt on the subject. 5 common. iii. 1: ‘illa beatae memoriae episcopi Zosimi epistola, quae tractoria dicitur . . . quae et Constantinopolim et per totum orbem missa subscriptionibus sanctorum patrum est roborata; cui Iulianus et reliqui complices subscribere detrectantes . . . depositi . . .{sunt.’ 2c 386 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN layman who made opposition to Pelagianism and Nestori- anism the main business of his life. It is a prio not at all inconceivable that Marius, in accordance with the usual Western tendency to forget the existence of Eastern Christendom, and the usual tendency of enthusiasts to assume that the absence of any active protest against their opinions is the equivalent of a positive approval of them, may well have supposed that the ¢vactoria had been accepted throughout the East merely because no Eastern had taken the trouble to denounce it publicly. Zosimus, it would seem, addressed his letter to the chief Patriarchal sees, expecting their occupants to secure the signatures of their subordinates: but we have no evidence (other than the general assertion of Marius Mercator just mentioned) to show how far this was actually done. Doubtless the tvactoria was duly signed wherever the imperial government was in a position to bring civil coercion into play: but the Syriac- speaking Churches at least, which cherished a theological tradition favourable to Pelagianism,! and which, moreover, were rooted amidst a population seething with suppressed nationalistic and anti-imperialist feeling, would hardly be likely to welcome a document emanating from the Roman Pope and enforced by the sword of the Roman Emperor. It is difficult to believe that Theodore of Mopsuestia could have signed the tvactoria, in view of the fact that only a few years after its publication we find him taking the Pelagian exiles under his personal protection. Nor is it likely that the Churches of Asia Minor and Syria, which looked to Theodore as their intellectual guide and teacher, would have subscribed to a formulary which was destructive of their own point of view. It is at least possible that Marius Mercator’s assertion as to the universal acceptance of the tractoria is an enthusiastic over-statement of the fact that it was universally received in the West and in Egypt, and not overtly denounced in Asia Minor, Syria, and the far Eastern Churches. (6) The encyclical of Zosimus, however, though it cannot be proved to have secured strictly oecumenical acceptance, represents the apogee and high-water-mark of the power 1 v, supra, p. 349 f. AUGUSTINIANISM 387 and influence of the Augustinian ideas. But the studiously vague and cautious condemnation of Caelestius pronounced by the Council of Ephesus shows that thirteen years later the Easterns, even those of Cyril’s party, were not by any means willing to give their whole-hearted allegiance to the theories which had triumphed in the West; nor can the language of the letter addressed by the Council to Pope Celestine, informing him that it had renewed the condem- nation pronounced by his predecessors against Pelagianism, be taken as more than a very general and complimentary approval of the anti-Pelagian attitude of Rome; it would not be reasonable to extract from it an explicit commenda- tion of every detail of Zosimus’ letter, even if we knew what this contained. The first and fourth Canons of this Council,1 which censure those who ‘ hold the opinions of’ or ‘ side with ’ Caelestius, cannot be construed as an approval of the characteristic positions of Augustine: they can hardly be made to affirm more in the positive direction than that there was a Fall, and that it had hereditary consequences in the shape of a transmitted bias towards sin. How far can the Augustinian Fall-doctrine be deemed to have secured the tacit acquiescence, as distinct from the credal or conciliar endorsement, of the undivided Church ? In view of the overwhelming triumph of Augustinianism in the West, this question is, in effect, an enquiry how far Augustinianism succeeded in penetrating the East, and in superseding or suppressing the vaguer, more liberal ‘ once- born’ tendency which we have seen to be associated with the Hellenic-Christian thought of the first four centuries. It is difficult to give any very precise answer to this question, for the reason that after the Council of Ephesus, and the secession of the Syrian and Persian Churches which sym- pathised with Nestorius and by consequence with Pelagius, the remainder of Eastern Christendom seems to have lost all interest in the matter. During the last five centuries of the ‘ undivided’ period, the dominant doctrinal issues in the East were the Christological question, the questions of the two natures and the two wills, and that of the veneration 1 The text is given in Additional Note F, p. 537, ‘ Formularies, I. Oecumenical’; and see above, p. 354. 388 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN of icons, not the Western disputes about Adam, sin, and grace. In the scanty references made to the subject by the Greek-Christian writers of this epoch, we note the appearance of the term ‘ ancestral sin’ (ayapria mporaropurn *) which is now used in the dogmatic theology and formularies of the Eastern Orthodox Church as the equivalent of ‘original sin’; but whether in the sixth and seventh centuries it included the idea of ‘ original guilt’ or not it is impossible to say. There is no doubt that the Monophysite Christology tended to be associated with an Augustinian type of Fall-doctrine,? just as Nestorianism had been logically linked with Pelagianism 4; but it would be unsafe to dog- matise with regard to the proportion borne by this tendency to the other factors which went to make up the kaleidoscopic picture of Byzantine theology. It is instructive in this connexion to read through the treatise On the Orthodox Faith written by the last of the great figures of Eastern theology, St. John of Damascus (?680-?760). This work contains much detailed exposition of the doctrines of the Trinity and the Incarnation, and, indeed, of various cosmological and physiographical theories which we should regard as having nothing to do with the Faith at all; but the Damascene’s language on the subject of the Fall and of its consequences is rhetorical and vague to the last degree.® There is some use of the traditional phrases regarding man’s ‘ servitude to the devil,’ and the ‘ disintegration’ (f@opa) of his being ; but it is impossible to extract from the Damascene’s pages any doctrine more precise than that of St. Paul, and the specifically Augustinian conceptions are nowhere to be found. 1 Cf. Olympiodorus (saec. vi), fragmenta in Ievemiam, in c. xxxi. 30 (PG XCIII. 689 D): % rot’ Adau auapria d1eAMobaa eis ro EOvoS Kat emt TOs py) duaptnoavras HAGev ds elev 6 amdaTOA0s’ yxpioTod odv GuyYwpHaavros TaUTHY dia Tob AovTpob THs adecews, ExalapicOyn ev %) mpoTraTopiKH dpaptia, Exacros dé TOV olKelwv apapTnudrwy bméxet Adyov: Maximus Confessor (sa@ec. vii), ep. ad Marinum (PG XCI. 136A): dtya Tov KUpiov elvar THs mMpoTaTopiKHs auaptias ws dvOpwrov. 2 See Additional Note ‘ Formularies, III Eastern Orthodox’ (p. 542). 3 See A. Draguet, Julien @ Halicarnasse, mentioned above, p. 254, n. 5. 4 v. supra, Pp. 349. 5 The chief references to the subject are contained in lb. ii. cc. Io, 11, 12 (a reproduction of St. Greg. Naz., or. xlv, quoted above, Lecture IV, p. 283), 30: lib. iii. r: lib. iv. 13 (in Michael Lequien’s edition, Paris, 1712, tom. li. p. 267 E). AUGUSTINIANISM 389 So far as this writer is concerned, Augustine, Pelagius, Caelestius, and Julian might never have existed at all. In view of such facts as these, we shall be safe in formu- lating the statement that from the Council of Ephesus down to the Great Schism of A.D. 1054 a modified Augustinianism + was dominant in the West, and a state of complete vague- ness and confusion with regard to the Fall-doctrine prevailed in the East. Augustinianism, though the most widely spread version of the doctrine, never enjoyed an exclusive dominance: it cannot be said to have ever attained to acceptance in a literal sense ubigue et ab omnibus. Not even in a modified and secondary sense of the term, there- fore, can it claim to. be ‘the ecclesiastical doctrine’ par excellence. Nevertheless, it cannot be denied that the original perfection and righteousness of Adam were taken for granted by practically all Christians between the fifth and the nineteenth century: though Gregory of Nyssa’s re-interpretation of the subject of ‘ original righteousness ’ as the ideal or archetypal man, not the concrete individuals Adam and Eve, stood on record as indicating a possible solution of the coming clash between the monotheistic religious consciousness, which demands that the works of an infinitely good God must themselves have been good as originally created by Him, and the scientific understanding, which can find no crevice in the smooth continuity of man’s evolution from the brute into which an epoch of Paradisal perfection could be interpolated.? CONCLUSION Meanwhile, the fact that we must needs reject the ideas of ‘ original righteousness ’ and ‘ original guilt ’ as Augustine formulated them involves no disparagement of the spiritual greatness of this heroic saint and doctor, nor does it imply 1 From A.D. 529 onwards, the canons of the second Council of Orange, with the statement which concludes them (Hardouin, ii. 1098 A sqq. ; Denzinger-Bannwart, Enchiridion, §§ 174-200) may be taken as represent- ing the norm of this ‘ modified Augustinianism ’; see Lecture VI, p. 397, and Additional Note ‘ Formularies, 11. Western and Roman,’ p. 537. 2 v. supra, Lecture IV, p. 271; and infra, Lecture VIII, p. 526, n. 1. 390 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN any contempt for the highly specialised type of experience in which these ideas were rooted. In the history of Christian thought we have at every turn to distinguish between the kernel and the husk, between the permanent facts of the life of the soul and the intellectual form which in a given epoch is used to body them forth. Augustine’s belief in the Golden Age, in the unalloyed bliss of Paradise, in the super- natural glories of unfallen human nature, has been banished by modern knowledge from the domain of historic possi- bility. Butitisstilla splendid symbol of the ideal of human nature as God meant it to be and as it exists in the treasure- house of the divine ideas, a symbol cast in a gorgeous pic- torial form and projected upon the misty background of the primeval past. The idea of original guilt, of the inheritance of responsibility for the first sin, is one which is inconsistent with our notion of justice; and the affirmation that there is a mysterious kind of divine justice, which has little in common with what. we understand by the term ‘ justice,’ has now ceased to have any meaning for us. Yet as the husk of ‘inherited racial guilt’ splits asunder, it reveals the infinitely true and precious—though humbling and not easily comprehensible—idea of that voluntary and sym- pathetic self-identification with the sins of the community which was attributed by the Jewish scriptures to Nehemiah 4 and Daniel,? and was achieved in fullest measure by our Lord Himself upon the Cross. These are ideas which cannot be neglected in future speculations on this mysterious sub- ject. The mighty structure of Augustinianism has in great part collapsed; but it contains precious materials which may well be used for the new fabric which is to replace it. As the marble columns which had served to rear the pedi- ments of the ancient temples were utilised by the men of Augustine’s day to adorn the glittering naves of the new Christian basilicas: so the characteristic doctrines of Man and of Sin evolved through storms of controversy by the “twice-born ’ type of religious genius, though rejected as theological truths, may none the less survive as devotional values, enriching and fertilising the common life of the * Nehem, 1,6, °7; 2 Daniel ix. 20. AUGUSTINIANISM 391 Church, which must in the main reflect the experience of the ordinary and ‘ once-born’ man, with the tears and the penitence of the Saints. ADDITIONAL NOTE B Canons of the Carthaginian Council of a.p. 418, dealing with the Fall and Original Sin (Hardouin, i. 926, 927; Denzinger- Bannwart, Enchiridion Symbolorum etc., 1913, p. 47, §§ IOI, 102). can. I. placuit omnibus episcopis . . . in sancta synodo Carthaginiensi constitutis : ut quicunque dixerit, Adam primum hominem mortalem factum, ita ut sive peccaret sive non peccaret moreretur in corpore, hoc est de corpore exiret non peccati merito, sed necessitate naturae, anathema sit. can. 2. item placuit, ut quicunque parvulos recentes ab uteris matrum baptizandos negat, aut dicit in remissionem quidem peccatorum eos baptizari, sed nihil ex Adam trahere originalis peccati, quod lavacro regenerationis expietur, unde sit consequens, ut in eis forma baptismatis in remissionem pecca- torum non vera sed falsa intelligatur, anathema sit. quoniam non aliter intelligendum est quod ait apostolus: fer unum hominem peccatum intravit in mundum, et per peccatum mors, et ita in omnes homines pertransiit, in quo omnes peccaverunt, nisi quemadmodum ecclesia catholica ubique diffusa semper intel- lexit. propter hanc enim regulam fidei etiam parvuli, qui nihil peccatorum in se ipsis adhuc committere potuerunt, ideo in peccatorum remissionem veraciter baptizantur, ut in eis regeneratione mundetur, quod generatione traxerunt. can. 3. [This is the canon, which, as Duchesne notes (v. supra, p. 348, n. 2), has been suppressed in most collections of canons, presumably because it condemns the idea of limbo.] item placuit, ut si quis dicit, ideo dixisse Dominum, im domo patris met mansiones muliae sunt, ut intelligatur, quia in regno coelorum erit aliquis medius aut ullus alicubi locus, ubi beati vivant parvuli, qui sine baptismo ex hac vita migrarunt, sine quo in regnum coelorum, quod est vita aeterna, intrare non possunt, anathema sit. nam cum Dominus dicat, mist quis venatus fuerit ex aqua et spiritu Sancto, non intrabit in regnum coelorum, quis catholicus dubitet participem fore diaboli eum, qui coheres esse non meruit Christi? qui enim dextra caret, sinistram procul dubio partem incurret. [On the authorities for this canon, see Hardouin’s note, 1. 927 B.] hi aul OE it ade iS she be, 1 Atal VE. THE TRIUMPH AND DECLINE OF THE AUGUSTINIAN DOCTRINE God made this whole world in such an uniformity, such a correspondency, such a concinnity of parts, as that it was an Instrument, perfectly in tune: we may say, the trebles, the highest strings were disordered first ; the best understandings, Angels and Men, put this instrument out of tune. God rectified all again, by putting in a new string, semen mulieris, the seed of the woman, the Messias: And onely by sounding that string in your ears, become we musicum carmen, true musick, true harmony, true peace to you. If we shall say, that Gods first string in this instrument, was Reprobation, that Gods first intention was for his glory to damn man; and that then he put in another string, of creating Man, that so he might have some body to damn; and then another of enforcing him to sin, that so he might have a just cause to damne him ; and then another, of disabling him to lay hold upon any means of recovery: there’s no musick in all this, no harmony, no peace in such preaching. JOHN DONNE. LECTURE VI. THE TRIUMPH AND DECLINE OF THE AUGUSTINIAN DOCTRINE Rom. ix. 18. ‘So then he hath mercy on whom he will, and whom he will be hardeneth.’ It was shown in our last lecture that the sombre and pessimistic version of the Fall-theory, which springs from the characteristic experience of the ‘sick soul’ or the ‘twice-born’ type of religious man, which received its chief development in the stern and fanatical atmosphere of the North African Church, and which was wrought into a rounded, coherent, and classical doctrine by the genius of St. Augustine, though victorious all along the line in the field of Western Christendom, yet exercised only a super- ficial influence on the mind of the Christian East; which, on the whole, remained faithful (at least until the seven- teenth century) to that milder view of the presuppositions of Redemption which we found in the writings of the earlier Greek Fathers, more particularly in those of Irenaeus, Origen, and the Cappadocians. It follows that, for those who recognise a palmary and normative authority as residing in the mind of the primitive undivided Church, the question “What is “‘ the ecclesiastical doctrine ’’—the doctrine accepted by the Christian Church as such—in regard to the origin and nature of the inherited tendency to sin?’ has been conclusively answered. The doctrine of the Undivided Church as a whole can only be taken to be the highest common factor of the maximising and minimising versions of the Fall-doctrine held by its Western and Eastern areas respectively ; and this highest common factor is evidently identical with the lesser of these quantities, that is, with 396 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN the minimising theory. If, then, we were at liberty to assume without question the validity of that appeal to the witness of Christian antiquity as a whole which is implied in a literal interpretation of the word semper, as it occurs in the Vincentian formula, and which is in many quarters assumed to be the corner-stone of the specifically Anglican position, the purely historical part of our enquiry might well end at this point. But it will be remembered that, in our first lecture, at the very outset of our review of the development of the Fall-doctrine, we deliberately renounced this liberty, and undertook to employ the Vincentian Canon solely as a scientific, and not as an authoritarian test, in order that our conclusions as to the amount, or the kind, of Fall-doctrine which is necessarily pre-supposed by the Christian religion as such might be invested with as much objectivity and breadth of appeal as possible. Given this method of employing the formula ubique, semper, et ab omnibus, it might very plausibly be urged that the term omnes should not be interpreted in a grossly literal, mechani- cal and numerical sense, so as to include all Christians without exception, no matter how ignorant and unpro- gressive many of them may be: but that it should rather be restricted to designating the intellectually vital and fruit- ful areas of Christendom, which until recently were con- fined to Western Christendom, Catholic and Reformed. It would follow from such a contention that the non-accept- ance of the Augustinian teaching by the primitive and mediaeval East did not necessarily invalidate the claim of this teaching to be ‘ the Christian doctrine,’ inasmuch as the intellectual life of the Eastern Church was (not ex- clusively through its own fault) comparatively stationary . from the time of the Great Schism down to the seventeenth century ; and that it would be unfair to dismiss a theory which has so deeply affected the religious life of the Western nations, including our own, without having considered the forms which it assumed in the thought of some of the greatest Christian teachers who have flourished since the Patristic age, both Schoolmen and Reformers. It would be irrelevant to our purpose, and would confuse the develop- ment of our argument, if we allowed ourselves to be drawn DECLINE OF AUGUSTINIANISM 397 into a discussion of the true meaning of ubzque and omnes ; and an enquiry which aspires to scientific impartiality can- not afford to expose itself to the suspicion of having neglected fields of thought which are of the highest interest in them- selves, and might conceivably yield considerations of such a nature as to induce us to revise or modify the adverse verdict which in our last lecture was passed upon the classical expression of the ‘ twice-born’ theory. The present lecture will, therefore, be devoted to an examination of the post- Augustinian history of the Fall-doctrine in Western Europe, designed with the object of deciding whether or not, within this restricted sphere, the ‘ twice-born’ theory can reason- ably claim acceptance ‘ by all,’ in the sense of all, or nearly all, intellectually alert and progressive Christians. Our historical review need not pause to consider the Semi-Pelagian controversy, which, though the direct sequel of the great duel between Augustine and Pelagius noticed in our last lecture, was concerned rather with the opera- tions of ‘ grace’ than with the nature and results of the Fall: we may note, however, that the Second Council of Orange, which brought this controversy to an end, contents itself with affirming a modified Augustinianism, which only predicates ‘integrity’ of unfallen man, abstains from affirming ‘ Original Guilt,’ and makes the important assertion that whilst free-will was weakened by the Fall it was not destroyed.! Little of interest is to be gleaned from the so-called ‘ Dark Ages’ ; of the four great writers whom — the Western Church produced during this period, Gregory the Great, Bede, Alcuin, and Scotus Erigena,? the first three were largely absorbed in pastoral, historical, juristic, and liturgical interests, and made few original contributions to the progress of thought, whilst the last named did little more than emphasise that Platonic aspect of patristic thought for which evil is mere non-entity. The Doctor of Hippo continued to dominate the West down to the begin- ning of the thirteenth century, though Anselm in discussing original sin lays all the stress upon our lack of Adam’s 1 For the relevant Canons of Orange, see Additional Note F, ‘ Formularies, (II) Western and Roman,’ p. 537 f. 2 See H. Bett, Johannes Scotus Evigena, 1925, pp. 65-70. 398 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN original righteousness,! and Abaelard repudiates ‘ original guilt.’2 It is not until the rise of Scholasticism that signs of an onward movement can be detected in the some- what stagnant waters of Western-Catholic anthropological thought. The development of Scholasticism is intimately bound up with the history of the great mendicant Orders of the thirteenth century, notably with that of the Friars Preachers, founded by Dominic Guzman, and that of the Friars Minor, which owes its origin to the life and personality of Francis of Assisi. In regard to the doctrines of man and of sin, the theologies characteristic of these two illustrious Orders exhibit differences which may without undue fancifulness be traced to the differing circumstances of their origins. In the previous lectures of this course, we have had more than once occasion to emphasise the fact that the doctrines of the Fall and of original sin were evolved in the first instance by that ethical monotheism which is the heart both of Judaism and of Christianity, as an intellectual self-defence against the attacks of Oriental dualism ; and this character, that of being in essence a protest against dualism, has clung to them all through their history. They were first shaped in the minds of the Maccabean Jews by the desire to save the unique sovereignty and holiness of Jehovah as against the evil God of Mazdeism. St. Paul and St. Irenaeus re- affirmed them as against the second historic wave of West- ward-surging dualism, that which we know as Gnosticism. Augustine perfected his scheme as a bulwark against the third invasion of dualism in the form of Manicheism. And it may be suggested that the strongly Augustinian tone of Dominican thought on these subjects is due to the fact 1 de conceptu virginalt, 22, 27 (see also Thomasius, DG. ii, pp. 152, 153, 163-5). ~ 2 in ep. ad Rom. (Opera, ed. Victor Cousin, 1859, ii. pp. 238 ff.). 8 An excellent summary account of the evolution of the Fall-doctrine during the scholastic period may be found in Gustav Ljunggren, Det Kristina Syndmedvetandet intill Luther, Uppsala, 1924, pp. 236-265. This book is written in Swedish, and there appears to be no English, French, or German translation : I have only been able to use it through the kindness of the Rev. G. C. Richards, D.D., Fellow of Oriel College, Oxford, and Vicar of the University Church, who has been good enough to supply me with a translation of the pages referred to. DECLINE OF AUGUSTINIANISM 399 that the Order of Preachers was founded by a saint of stern if heroic character, in Languedoc, in the very midst of a life-and-death struggle between Catholic Christianity, as it then existed, and a fourth invasion of Eastern dualism, that which is known as the ‘ Albigensian’ or ‘ Catharist’ movement, which was in great part based upon a recrude- scence of the doctrines of Mani.! But the Order of Friars Minor was born, not from the crisis of a fierce battle with semi-heathen heresy, but rather from the pure impulses of love towards God and man which flowed forth from the humble and gentle nature of the foverello himself, the “minstrel of the Lord,’ and spouse of the Lady Poverty, ‘Sweet Saint Francis of Assisi,’ as Tennyson calls him : He that in his Catholic wholeness used to call the very flowers Sisters, brothers—and the beasts—whose pains are hardly less than ours.? Given a founder whose character was marked by an almost feminine tenderness towards the sufferings of mankind and by that intuitive sympathy with sub-human nature which hitherto we have noted in St. Paul alone of Christian saints, it is not a matter of surprise that the theologians of this Order should have championed a comparatively anti- Augustinian and all but Semi-Pelagian anthropology, in which the sharpness of the distinction between ‘ nature’ and ‘grace’ tends at least to be blunted, and the human will is restored to its dignity as essentially free, though weakened by the Fall. It will conduce to clearness if we first of all survey briefly the modifications introduced by St. Thomas Aquinas, the “ Angel of the Schools’ and the typical repre- sentative of the Dominican theology, into the hitherto dominant Augustinian scheme, and then set side by side with the Thomist doctrine a brief sketch of the Franciscan point of view, as depicted in the works of one of the most famous sons both of St. Francis and of Oxford, the ‘ subtle Doctor’ Duns Scotus. 1H. J. Warner, however (The Albigensian Heresy, 1922), denies the historical derivation of Catharism from Manicheism. 2 Locksley Hall Sixty Years After. 400 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN THE THOMIST POSITION The results of an analysis of the specifically Augustinian Fall-doctrine may be summarised by the statement that it can be reduced to seven fundamental ideas. These are (1) an exalted conception of Adam’s original righteousness and perfection ; and the ideas (2) of the infinite malice of the first sin, as being the ethical suicide of a saint; (3) of ‘original sin’ as a vitvwm, consisting in the tyranny of con- cupiscence ; (4) of ‘ original sin’ as guilt (veatus), inhering in each and every member of the human race in virtue of the race’s seminal identity with Adam; (5) of the trans- mission of original sin, considered as a disease, in and through the act of generation, which is itself intrinsically sinful, owing to the concupiscence which accompanies it, though it is condoned by God in the case of the baptised ; (6) of the practical abolition of free-will which thus results, though, as we have pointed out, Augustine strenuously maintains freedom—at least in name; and (7) of the necessary and rightful damnation of the whole of Adam’s posterity, including infants, with the exception of those who are arbitrarily predestined to be recipients of baptism, justification, and the ‘ gift of final perseverance.’ We will take these points one by one, and note the modifications introduced by the Angelic Doctor. (1) In essence the Augustinian conception of man’s original state is left unchanged. It is, however, to be noted that the category which Augustine had employed to define . this conception is subjected to a certain measure of recon- struction. This leading category of Augustinianism is the antithesis between ‘nature’ and ‘ grace,” which, in the thought of St. Thomas, is made necessary instead of con- tingent, becomes logical rather than ethical, and instead of being restricted to the domain of human nature is made to apply to the whole realm of created being. It thus appears as the celebrated scholastic distinction between the natural and the supernatural orders or planes of being, or, in modern phrase, between ‘ nature’ and ‘ supernature.’ This distinc- tion has the effect of sharpening the difference between the qualities of human nature considered in itself—the qualities DECLINE OF AUGUSTINIANISM ~ = 4or ‘known in scholastic terminology as Adam’s pura naturalia, which God, so to speak, was under the necessity of conferring upon him if He was going to make a ‘ man’ at all—and the supernatural splendours of ‘ original perfection,’ with its perfect sanctity and its mighty intellectual powers,! which God was under no necessity, logical or otherwise, to bestow upon man, but which represents a donum indebitum—a purely gratuitous piece of munificence on the part of the Almighty. Even if man had remained endowed solely with the pura naturalia, and had never received the splendid present of ‘ original justice,’ he might, St. Thomas tells us, have attained to a certain natural knowledge of God by speculating upon His works. With infinite generosity, however, the Creator destined His creature to a much more wonderful destiny. He raised him at the first moment of his creation to the supernatural plane, and designed to lead him upward, along an ever-ascending pathway, to the supernatural knowledge and possession of Himself in the Beatific Vision. If Adam had stood firm under the tests imposed upon him, his spiritual and physical evolution would have progressed so rapidly that he would have been enabled to transcend death and to ascend to his eternal abode without the necessity of physical dissolution. We need not now discuss the ingenious refinements with which this revised Augustinianism was decorated, or follow out the chain of syllogisms by which Aquinas determines, to his own satisfaction, what would have been the moral, social, physical and economic condition of mankind if Adam had never fallen.2 It is enough to note that St. Thomas takes an essentially optimistic view of human nature in itself, even apart from the added splendours of the super- natural endowments enjoyed by Adam. Man in himself is not a mere animal, but a citizen of the divine kingdom, who, by the special favour of his Almighty Sovereign, was created a prince at his birth. (2) The infinite malice of the first sin is assumed, without much argument, on the authority of St. Augustine ; and its prime effect is conceived of as being the instantaneous fall of man, fvom the supernatural plane to which he had been 1 Summ. theol. i. qq. xCiv, xcv. 2 ibid. i. qq. xcvii-ci. 20 402 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN raised, to the natural plane on which he would have lived but for the gratuitous exaltation involved in the bestowal of the donum supernaturvale. To continue the metaphor indi- cated above, the prince who has offended his sovereign is punished indeed, but not by outlawry or execution; he merely forfeits his princely rank and privileges and reverts to the status of a bourgeois. This has an important bearing upon (3) the nature of original sin considered as a psychologi- cal flaw, or disease of the soul. It means that ‘ original sin,’ viewed under the ‘ medical’ or ‘ therapeutic’ category, is to be formally defined as the ‘ lack of original righteousness’ (defectus originalis iustitiae), but not of any of the pura naturalia, a definition which makes it a mere negation, and as such not, apparently, a very tragic matter; the inheritor of modest means, who, having been presented with a colossal fortune by a munificent benefactor, then loses the fortune by misconduct, without forfeiting his original patrimony, would appear prima facie to be at least no worse off than he would have been if he had never received the fortune. At this point, however, the influence of Augustine makes itself felt, and St. Thomas feels compelled to affirm that although original righteousness is no part of the endowment of man as man, yet the loss of it, when it has once been possessed, introduces a certain disorder into the faculties of human nature. The pura naturalia are not destroyed; but their due harmony and proportion are disturbed and disarranged. This thought leads St. Thomas back into the Augustinian conception of original sin, psychologically considered, as consisting in ‘ inordinate concupiscence’ ; and he produces what does not appear to be more than a verbal reconciliation of his own position with that of his master by asserting that the material element in original sin is concupiscence, but that its formal element is the defect of original justice 1— 1 St. Thom. Aq. de malo, q. iv. a. 2: ‘ et ideo cum carentia originalis iustitiae se habeat ex parte voluntatis, ex parte autem inferiorum virium a voluntate motarum sit pronitas ad inordinate appetendum, quae con- cupiscentia dici potest, sequitur quod peccatum originale in hoc homine vel in illo, nihil est aliud quam concupiscentia cum carentia originalis iustitiae, ita tamen quod carentia originalis iustitiae est quasi formale in peccato originali, concupiscentia autem quasi materiale’; cf. also in I Sent., dist. xxx. q.i. a. I. DECLINE OF AUGUSTINIANISM 403 a position which appears to be an apt illustration of the scholastic method of using and illustrating traditional ideas as though they were hard metallic counters or symbols which can be grouped together in an infinite number of permutations and combinations, but may not be subjected to the acid of logical criticism or analysis. St. Thomas is thus enabled to show that original sin is a corruption of human nature, not merely a lack or deprivation of gifts or graces which it formerly possessed. (4) and (5). In loyalty to the dominant tradition of the West he maintains that original sin involves guilt ; but the Augustinian conception of seminal identity is modified by him in a curious manner, by being clothed with a dynamic, as opposed to a static, form. Instead of saying that Adam was the sum of his descendants, or that the whole human race 7s Adam, he invokes the conception of motion, and asserts that Adam ‘ moves’ all his descendants by begetting them.1 Adam thus becomes a kind of ethical frimum mobile, having initiated the process of sinful motion consisting in concupiscence and subsequent generation,? a process which goes on, as though in accordance with a kind of Newtonian moral law, for ever, until brought to a standstill by an opposing force. This opposing force is sanctifying grace, communicated through baptism, which abolishes the guilt of original sin, but leaves concupiscence still in existence, no longer as sin but as the fomes peccati—a pregnant phrase— the ‘ tinder of sin,’ the raw material of emotion, impulse, and instinct, which in the baptised is fer se morally neutral, but which may be worked up into forms which constitute sin.* Formally, this position does not go beyond the Augustinian statement that baptism annuls the veatus of concupiscence but leaves the actus still in existence +: but the phrase fomes peccatt was the herald of a coming revolution in thought with 1 Summa theol. i. iae. q. xxxi.a.3: ‘ unde et culpa originalis traducitur ad omnes illos qui moventur ab Adam motione generationis.’ 2 St.Thomas adheres to the Augustinian position that the concupiscence which accompanies the act of generation has the effect of staining the resul- tant offspring with original sin; cf. de malo, q.iv.a.2: ‘vis generativa per decisionem corporalis seminis operatur ad traductionem peccati originalis simul cum natura humana.’ 3 But see the preceding note. # Lecture V, p. 367. 404 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN regard to bodily appetite and its relation to sin, a revolution which, when completely accomplished, will have swept away the last relics of the ultra-ascetic view of human nature imposed upon the Western Church by the ‘ twice-born’ temperament of the Doctor of Hippo. The admission that concupiscence, in itself, and apart from the consent of the will, is not sin in the baptised, must, on any other than a grossly mechanical theory of the efficacy of baptism, ulti- mately involve the admission that it is not sin in the unbaptised, in other words, that in itself it is not ‘ sin’ at all. (6) It remains to consider St. Thomas’ view of the present state of fallen human nature, with the accompanying question of free-will. Here again his position is fundamentally Augustinian. God is the prime cause of all motions, without exception, and therefore of the motions of the human soul— even those which we call free. St. Thomas is, therefore, like St. Augustine, a metaphysical determinist. From this point of view no change was introduced by the Fall—man Was just as much a puppet in the hands of God after as before the primeval catastrophe.t Nevertheless, psycho- logical freedom is maintained, so far as words go, though it is difficult to see how this can be reconciled with what is said about the unchecked domination of concupiscence in unre- generate human nature. We are told that it is impossible for an adult who dies in original sin, that is without having been baptised, not to have committed actual sins of a mortal quality as well. And after, as before, the Fall, man is solely and exclusively dependent on grace in order to be able to perform any good action; the only difference made by the Fall was a difference in the divine distribution of grace. Before the Fall grace, both ‘ habitual’ and ‘ actual,’ was given in full measure to all mankind, that is, to Adam and Eve, who were then the only representatives of mankind. After the Fall we get the paradoxical position that the reprobates receive what is called ‘ sufficient ’’ grace, of which 1 Summa theol.i. q.1xxxili.a.2: ‘Deus . . . est prima causa movens et naturales causas et voluntarias. etsic.t naturalibus causis, movendo eas, non aufert quin actus earum sint naturales, ita movendo causas voluntarias, non aufert quin actiones earum sint voluntariae, sed potius hoc in eis facit ; operatur enim in unoquoque secundum eius proprietatem ’ ; and ¢f. ibid, i. iilae. q. X. a. 4, quoted below. DECLINE OF AUGUSTINIANISM 408 they never avail themselves, whilst the predestined receive “ efficacious’ grace, which they never resist. Yet, despite its imprisonment in the iron framework of an all-pervasive divine causality, the will remains ‘ free’ ; in other words St. Thomas asserts that psychological freedom can subsist simultaneously with metaphysical necessity. If he is asked how this can be, he takes refuge in mystery. He tells us ‘ As it behoves divine Providence to preserve, not to pervert, the natures of things, God will move everything according to the requirements of its nature . . . So God moves the human will in such a manner that its motion remains con- tingent and not necessary,’1 and with this prima facie contradiction in terms he leaves the question. When pressed by the objection that this universal divine causality inevit- ably makes God the author of sin, he escapes by means of the time-honoured verbal device of asserting that sin is a defectus, a mere vacuity or privation which as such cannot be due to the operation of the first and supreme Being.? (7) The last point which demands consideration in treat- ing of the Thomist republication of Augustinianism is the eschatological issue. What is the destiny reserved in the next world for those who die in original sin only, without having committed actual sin? For St. Thomas this means, What will be the fate of unbaptised children ? because, as already pointed out, he cannot conceive of a non-baptised adult who is free from actual mortal sin. The humanity of Aquinas shrank from the ruthless severity of Augustine, who condemned unbaptised infants to eternal punishment (even though of the ‘ mildest kind’)*: hence he takes refuge in the Pelagian conception of a limbus puerorum. For the purpose of justifying this conception, original sin is regarded solely on its negative side as being the lack of original righteousness. This lack of man’s Paradisal sanctity has as its corollary in the next life lack of the Beatific Vision. But this is not in the strict sense of the term punishment. The inhabitants of Limbo, which for other mediaeval thinkers includes both the limbus puerorum, the eternal home of 1 Summa theol. i, iiae. q. X. a. 4. 2 1bid. i. iiae. q. Ixxix. a. 2. 3 v. supra, Lecture V, p. 327. 406 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN unbaptised infants, and the limbus patrum, in which the saints of the Old Testament dwelt before the descent of Christ into Hades, and in which the souls of virtuous pagans still are confined, never having received through Baptism the capacity for the Beatific Vision, do not feel the lack of it as in any way painful; and consequently their state may well be one of natural happiness. They may even know God through His works as intimately as Adam might have done if he had never received the endowment of original righteous- ness. They would no more complain, or consider it a grievance that they do not possess the Beatific Vision, than a horse or a dog complains that it is not a highly educated or cultured man. In fact, they may very well remain in blissful ignorance that there is such a thing as the Beatific Vision at all. It is true that a more sombre conception of this state has received a poetic consecration in the immortal verse of Dante, who identifies Limbo with the first circle that surrounds the abyss of Hell, but paints it as a realm of pensive melancholy rather than of agonising pain : Here, as mine ear could note, no plaint was heard Except of sighs, that made the eternal air Tremble, not caused by tortures, but from grief Felt by those multitudes, many and vast, Of men, women, and infants. Then to me The gentle guide: ‘ Inquirest thou not what spirits Are these which thou beholdest ? Ere thou pass Farther, I would thou know, that these of sin Were blameless ; and if aught they merited, It profits not, since baptism was not theirs, The portal to thy faith. If they before The Gospel lived, they served not God aright ; And among such am I. For these defects, And for no other evil, we are lost ; Only so far afflicted, that we live Desiring without hope.’ 4 1 Inferno, iv. 25-42: ‘ Quivi, secondo che per ascoltare, non avea pianto, ma’che di sospiri, che l’aura eterna facevan tremare : e€ cio avvenia di duol senza martiri, ch’avean le turbe, ch’eran molte e grandi, d’infanti e di femmine e di viri. DECLINE OF AUGUSTINIANISM 407 Yet even this dun region contains an enclave of passion- less tranquillity, approximating to happiness, which is ten- anted by the poets, sages, and heroes of pagan antiquity. Dante and Vergil are led through the dreary wood, by the spirits of Homer, Horace, Ovid, and Lucan, to a place depicted as: | . . . a mead with lively verdure fresh. There dwelt a race, who slow their eyes around Majestically moved, and in their port Bore eminent, authority : they spake Seldom, but all their words were tuneful sweet .. . There on the green enamel of the plain Were shown me the great spirits, by whose sight I am exalted in my own esteem... . . . . [he master of the sapient throng, Seated amid the philosophic train. Him all admire, all pay him reverence due. There Socrates and Plato both I mark’d Nearest to him in rank, Democritus, Who sets the world at chance, Diogenes, With Heraclitus and Empedocles, And Anaxagoras, and Thales sage, Zeno, and Dioscorides well read In nature’s secret lore.? Lo buon maestro a me: “ Tu non dimandi che spiriti son questi, che tu vedi ? Or vo’ che sappi, innanzi che pit: andi, Ch’ei non peccaro; e s’egli hanno mercedi, non basta, perché non ebber battesmo, ch’é porte della fede che tu credi ; e se furon dinanzi al Cristianesmo, non adorar debitamente Dio ; e di questi cotai son io medesmo. Per tai difetti, non per altro rio, semo perduti, e sol di tanto offesi, che senza speme vivemo in disio.”’ ’ (The translations given in the text are taken from Cary’s version, first published in 1814.) 1 Inferno, iv. 111: ‘ ... prato di fresca verdura. Genti v’eran con occhi tardi e gravi, di grande autorita ne’ lor sembianti ; parlavan rado, con vocisoavi... Cola diritto, sopra il verde smalto, mi fur mostrati gli spiriti magni, che del vederli in me stesso n’esalto ... Vidi il maestro di color che sanno seder tra filosofica famiglia. 408 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN We shall have occasion again to treat of the conception of Limbo as the eschatological corollary of Original Sin apart from Actual Sin, and need not devote more time to the examination of its specifically Thomist form: it will suffice for our present purpose to point out that its adoption by St. Thomas, after its stern rejection by St. Augustine, is the most striking instance of the fact that, even in the minds of the African Doctor’s most loyal disciples, the rigidly ‘ twice- born’ anthropology had to be perceptibly softened in order to be preserved at all.? THE SCOTIST POSITION The Franciscan version of the Fall-doctrine represents a more definite and decided revolt against Augustinanism and shows distinct affinities with what we have designated as the primitive, ‘ once-born,’ and ‘ Hellenic’ view. In accordance with the method previously explained, we take the opinions of John Duns Scotus as typical of his school.? Tutti lo miran, tutti onor gli fanno; quivi vid’ io Socrate e Platone, che innanzi agli altri piu presso gli stanno ; Democrito, che il mondo a Caso pone, Diogenes, Anassagora e Tale, Empedocles, Eraclito e Zenone ; e vidi il buono accoglitor del quale, Dioscoride dico.’ 1 The full Augustinian doctrine was, however, embodied in the great text-book of mediaeval canon law, the Decretum of Gratian: Pars iii, dist. 4, c. 3: ‘ firmissime tene, et nullatenus dubites, omnem hominem qui per concubitum viri et mulieris concipitur cum originali peccato nasci, inpietati subditum mortique subiectum . . . firmissime tene, non solum homines ratione utentes, verum etiam parvulos, qui sive in uteris matrum vivere incipiunt et ibi moriuntur, sive iam de matribus nati sine baptis- matis sacramento ... de hocseculo transeunt, sempiterno igne puniendos ; quia etsi peccatum propriae actionis nullum habent, originalis tamen peccati dampnationem carnali conceptione ex nativitate traxerunt.’ 2 Scotus’ interpretation of the doctrines of the Fall and of Original Sin is expounded at length in qguaestiones in ii. lib. sentent., distinct. xvii.— xxxill. (Paris edition, 1893, tom. xiii. pp. 61-332). It will be understood that the sketch given in the text only endeavours to pick out some of his more characteristic points, and does not attempt to review the whole discussion. Except where otherwise indicated, the reference ‘ dist,’ denotes one of these distinctiones. DECLINE OF AUGUSTINIANISM 409 So far as words go, the exalted Augustinian conception of ‘ original righteousness ’ is preserved in this scheme; the idea of the Paradisal perfection of man was at this date too deeply rooted in Christian thought to be frankly discarded. It is, nevertheless, modified to a certain extent. ‘ Original justice’ is asserted to have been a donum supernaturale, which had the effect of producing a perfect harmony and balance between the various faculties and functions of the human soul, a harmony involving the due subordination of appetite to reason. This harmony, however, was not absolutely stable, even in Paradise; for the experience of successful resistance to temptation was needed in order that human nature might be confirmed in grace. Until he had been tempted once, Adam’s blissful condition bore a pro- visional character. If he had triumphed on the first occasion when he was tested, he would have acquired a more solid and permanent habit of virtue ?; and the same rule would have applied, if he had not fallen, to each of his descendants. Each member of the human race subsequently born would have been tested once, and, if triumphant, would have been confirmed in grace. It may be suggested that Scotus shows signs of a desire to return, so far as was possible within the bounds of mediaeval Western orthodoxy, to the primitive, second-century conception of man’s unfallen state as being one of ‘infancy’ (vymorys), though including a ‘ starting- point for progress’ (adopux mpokomfs). Congruous with this is the affirmation that the ‘immortality’ enjoyed by 1 dist, xxix. (Paris edn. tom. xiii. p. 272): ‘ potest dici ergo quod si originalis iustitia habuit illum effectum, facere scilicet perfectam tran- quillitatem in anima, quantum ad omnes potentias, ita quod natura inferior non inclinaretur contra iudicium superioris, aut si inclinaretur quantum est ex se, posset tamen a superiori regulari et ordinari sine diffi- cultate superioris et sine tristitia inferioris, cum hoc non habuerit potentia facta in puris naturalibus, necesse est ipsam ponere donum supernaturale, quo sit ista tranquillitas perfecta in anima.’ Bydtshi xx qu T(opmett ip WEL) a0.) .. pater ‘primus’ inisset’ con; firmatus, si primae tentationi restitisset, in ista iustitia,’ etc. 8 dist, xx. q. I (pp. 115 ff.). This ‘confirmation in grace’ would, however, not have conferred the state known as non posse peccare, which is only possible for comprehensores (i.e. the blessed who possess the Beatific Vision), but only the privilege quod non peccat vel peccabit, which alone is appropriate to viatores (i.e. those still living on this earth in a state of probation). 410 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN unfallen Adam consisted, not in the impossibility of dying, but in the possibility of not dying.t Corresponding to this somewhat modified conception of original righteousness we have a milder estimate of the degree of wickedness involved in the Fall. The root of Adam’s sin, according to Scotus, was not (as in Augustine’s view) an incomprehensible, unmotived impulse to defy his Creator, but the very natural, and, as it were, pardonable defect of ‘immoderate desire for the affection of his wife ’ (‘mmoderatus amor amicitiae uxoris), and the wish not to be separated from her even after her sin, a wish that under the circumstances almost inevitably transformed itself into the will to do that which was not lawful (voluntas explendi illud quod non licuit).2 As the primal sin sprang from so human and genial a source, it is a gross exaggeration to describe its ‘malice’ as ‘infinite’?; and the foundation has been removed, on which the Augustinian conception of fallen mankind as corporately constituting a massa damna- tionts is built. The same tendency to soften the harsh outlines of the Augustinian system appears most noticeably in the discussion of original sin in its character of vitium, that is, of a psychological disease. For Scotus, the essence of original sin consists only in the ‘ lack of original justice ’ (carentia originalis wustitiae), and does not consist in con- 1 dist, xxix,,5 (p. 274) cf. dist. xix, 2-(p. 103)., This, howeverj is precisely St. Augustine’s position : v. supra, Lecture V, p. 361, n. 2. 2 dist. xxi. q. 2 (p. 139): “primum autem peccatum Adae non fuit ex immoderato amore sui, sicut fuit primum peccatum Angeli. . . primum ergo peccatum hominis non potuit esse immoderatus amor sui, sed... immoderatus amor amicitiae uxoris. nam dicit Augustinus quod noluit contristave eam, quam credebat sine suo solatio contabescere, et a se alienatam omnino interive, ut habetur in littera. c. illo: ex quo manifeste. patet ergo quod non fuit amor concupiscentiae vel libidinis, quia ille nondum fuerat ; ex isto autem amore inordinato peccatum gravius sequebatur, scilicet voluntas explendi illud quod non licuit, puta praeceptum de esu pomi violare.’ 8 ibid. (p. 141) : Adam’s sin arose from an excess of love for his neigh- bour (i.e. Eve); ‘ergo sequitur quod peccatum hominis primi non fuit quantum ad hoc gravissimum, imo dico quod multa peccata fiunt modo a multis quae sunt graviora, ita quod si Adam debuisset fuisse damnatus pro illo, multo minorem poenam sustinuisset.’ On p. 143 will be found an apportionment of the guilt of the Fall, such as it was, between Adam and Eve: ‘ Adae peccatum accidentaliter fuit gravius peceato Evae : formaliter tamen, per se mere, et praecise in se, peccatum Evae fuit gravius.’ DECLINE OF AUGUSTINIANISM AII cupiscence at all?; this is one of his capital divergences from St. Thomas. Concupiscence, indeed, is said to be ‘natural,’ as being merely the necessary reaction of the sensitive part of the soul to intrinsically desirable objects.? It would seem probable that the Subtle Doctor is here using the word in its etymological sense, as signifying merely ‘desire as such,’ not ‘inordinate desire’?; and we may fairly set the name of Duns Scotus by the side of Julian of Eclanum, as the name of one of the few Christian thinkers who have firmly grasped the idea of the moral neutrality of physical appetite. It might have seemed that the affirmation of the innocence of concupiscence would naturally bring in its train the further consequence of a denial of original guilt or veatus, at any rate of the guilt which on Augustinian principles attaches to a nature infected with concupiscence. Here, however, the courage of the Franciscans would seem to have failed them. Frankly to throw over the conception of original guilt would have seemed to the thought of the Middle Ages to involve the condemnation of the practice of 1 dist. xxx. q. 2 (p. 293): ‘ peccatum originale non potest esse aliud quam ista privatio (sc. originalis iustitiae) ; non enim est concupiscentia, tum quia illa est naturalis ev dist. 29, tum quia ipsa est in parte sensitiva, ubi non est peccatum secundum Anselmum,’ etc. 2 He draws this very distinction between these two senses of the word in dist. xxxii. 7 (p. 311), and admits that in the latter sense ‘ concupis- centia est materiale peccati originalis,’ thus coming verbally into accord with St. Thomas. It is, however, not unreasonable to regard this admis- sion as a mere passing act of lip-homage to Augustinianism, and to hold that Scotus’ real mind is expressed by a significant silence in dist. xxxi. q. unica. Here he is commenting on Sent. i1., in which the Lombard quotes and endorses a passage from St. Augustine, expressing in its crudest form the theory that original sin is transmitted from parent to child through the concupiscence accompanying the act of generation. This passage deserves to be quoted in full: it runs: ‘quia, dum sibi invicem vir mulierque miscentur, sine libidine non est parentum concubitus; ob hoc filiorum ex eorum carne nascentium non potest sine peccato esse conceptus, ubi peccatum in parvulos non transmittit propagatio, sed libido; nec foecunditas humanae naturae facit, homines cum peccato nasci, sed foeditas libidinis, quam homines habent ex illius primi iustissima con- demnatione peccati. ideo beatus David, propter originale peccatum quo naturaliter obstricti sunt filii irae, dicit ‘‘ in iniquitatibus conceptus sum, et in peccatis concepit me mater mea’’’ (de fide ad Petrum, 2). Scotus passes this unpleasant citation over without a word, evidently dissenting from it, though the combined authority of St. Augustine and of the Master of the Sentences is too great to be explicitly repudiated. A412 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN infant baptism. Once more the actual practice of the Church, as in the fifth century, exercised an irresistible influence over the development of thought. The Church actually does baptise newly born infants, and we cannot suppose that the Church has acted wrongly or without good reason ; therefore infants, even of a day old, stand in urgent need of baptism. But, in the ‘ Nicene’ Creed, we profess our belief in ‘ one baptism,’ which is ‘ for the remission of sins.’ There are not two different kinds of baptism, one of adults conveying remission of sins, and the other of infants conveying no remission of sins ; therefore, infants are baptised ‘ for the remission of sins,’ and must accordingly be supposed to have some real sin, in the sense of guilt, which can be remitted. Adequate historical knowledge regarding the growth of the custom of paedo-baptism, and regarding the relation of the Constantinopolitan (the so-called ‘ Nicene ’) Creed to the original ‘ Nicaenum’ might have made this chain of reasoning seem very much less than cogent.t Such knowledge, however, was not at Scotus’ disposal: and hence he endeavours to explain original guilt under the some- what unsatisfactory category of ‘ debt.’ God entrusted man in Paradise with the gift of original righteousness, and man has lost it; hence man, collectively considered, is in a condition of ‘indebtedness’ to God, because he has lost the treasure with which his Father had endowed him. It is this condition of indebtedness which descends from genera- tion to generation, and is forensically regarded as involving ‘guilt’ in the sight of God.2 The possibility of such inheritance appears to be based upon a theory of ‘ seminal 1 See Additional Note G ‘ Infant Baptism’ (p. 550). 2 dist, xxxii. 7 (p. 311): ‘peccatum originale est . . . formaliter carentia iustitiae originalis debitae, et non qualitercumque debitae, quia acceptae in primo parente et in ipso amissae, cui correspondet poena damni dumtaxat ex praemissa criminis transgressione proveniens’ ; 9 (p. 312): ‘ ex illa collatione (sc. originalis iustitiae) facta patri, filius est debitor iustitiae sic datae’; but see the whole distinctio. The ‘ debt’ of original justice is remitted (or, in other words, the inherited guilt of having lost the supernatural endowments of unfallen human nature is pardoned) by God through baptism, and for it is substituted the obligation to possess the ordinary Christian virtues: ibid. 13: ‘ideo in baptismo cum redditur gratia, simpliciter dimittitur illud peccatum (sc. originale) . . . solvitur enim debitum habendi istud donum (sc. originalem iustitiam), et commutatur in debitum habendi aliud donum.’ DECLINE OF AUGUSTINIANISM 413 identity,’ which, however, only has reference to man’s body; for Scotus’ ‘creationism’ forbids him to assume that Adam’s soul included all subsequent human souls at the moment when he fell. } It has been suggested before that the theory of a material identity of the human race with Adam can hardly be held by a philosophically trained mind except in the form of the theory of logical or metaphysical identity ; and, as Scotus himself was a logical Realist, the idea that we, or at any rate our bodies, were ‘in Adam’ is not difficult for him. But the Nominalism which was characteristic of other Franciscan thinkers, by denying the real objective existence of universals, implicitly denied that Adam was the universal of humanity, and thereby cut at the root of the idea of original guilt, in so far as this implies the pre-natal acqui- sition of responsibility for Adam’s sin. The antinomies in which later Franciscan schoolmen found themselves involved by the attempt to justify some sort of defecated Augustinianism on a purely Nominalist basis were such as could only be solved by the application of the sceptical principle, which, by a singular irony, was the final intellectual product of the Ages of Faith—that propositions may be true in theology which are false in philosophy, and vice versa.? 1 dist. xxxi. 2 (p. 299): ‘contraximus istud peccatum in quantum fuimus in Adam secundum rationem seminalem ... hoc autem fuit secundum corpus, non secundum animam; anima enim non est ex traduce.’ 2 Cf. the following observations on Occam’s Fall-doctrine: ‘As a church-theologian, Occam was obliged to maintain this conception [that of original sin], and likewise also the traditional definition of it as the defect of original righteousness. But from the standpoint of the possible . . . it in no way appears, according to Occam, that man is under obligation to possess a supernatural gift in addition to his natural equipment. Original Sin is no real loss in man’s nature: it is the ideal imputation of Adam’s sin with regard to all his descendants. It simply means that the race of man, by virtue of God’s potentia ordinata and by reason of another’s trespass, has been included in a sentence of condemnation. There is no question here of a man’s own sin. It is axiomatic with the Nominalists that there is no veal connexion between Adam and the vest of humanity. These theses show with the greatest plainness what a tremendous gulf separates this doctrine of original sin from the motives which led to its first formulation by Augustine. In effect we have only the empty formulae left, now that that which formerly gave them life is gone. The doctrine is a locus theologicus, which is without any other raison d@étve than that which is imposed upon it by ecclesiastical tradition. How little understanding 4I4 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN We pass to the consideration of the present state of fallen man according to the Scotist conception. The Franciscan doctrine is naturally determined by the fundamental position that the essence of original sin consists in no positive corruption of human nature, but merely in the lack of certain splendid endowments which human nature once possessed. Hence the Franciscans are able to maintain a real and not merely nominal freedom of the will. For Scotus the will is free, both in the psychological sense of freedom from exclusive determination by habit and character, and also in the metaphysical sense of freedom from exclusive determination by an all-embracing divine causality. Both these positions have interesting consequences, which may be pointed out without straying too far from the main path of our enquiry. The concession of psychological freedom to fallen man necessitates the admission that he can perform morally good works of a natural order, even prior to the reception of grace. These works of merely natural virtue must, it is explained, be sharply distinguished from super- natural actions, for which grace is necessary ; but they are nevertheless truly moral, and so far are pleasing to God. They may even merit the bestowal of grace de congruo or de condigno, that is, as a congruous or as a deserved reward —a position which is naturally distasteful to the severe Augustinianism of the compilers of our Thirty-Nine Articles 1; and Scotus emphatically repudiates the idea that the virtues of the heathen are no more than ‘ splendid vices.’ The metaphysical freedom which Scotus attributes to the human soul is reconciled with the universality of divine causation by the supposition of a pre-established harmony Occam has of the original import of the doctrine is shown in his mode of treating concupiscence . . . Concupiscence or fomes is to him entirely of sensual nature, a merely bodily defect. It is simply to be compared with bodily diseases, and like them must be supposed to rest on an unequal distribution of the ““humours”’ in man. To fomes he assigns also the whole circle of the vegetative life ; hunger, thirst, sleep, etc., are results of the same, inasmuch as it is not possible to controlthem. In this last sense neither Christ nor the Virgin Mary was free from concupiscence. [Thus Occam returns to the position of Julian, which once roused Augustine’s vehement indignation].’ G. Ljunggren, op. cit. p. 248f. (tr. G.C. Richards). 1 It.is strongly condemned in Art. xiii. DECLINE OF AUGUSTINIANISM 415 between the eternal decrees of God and the results of human choice. I have, here and now, perfect freedom to choose between two alternatives, A and B. If I decide for B, I am perfectly free in so doing, and bear the full responsi- bility for my choice : nevertheless, in eternity God foresaw that I should choose B, and ratified my decision by anticipation in His divine counsels, designing the rest of human history on the assumption that B would actually be my choice; hence the Franciscans are able to approxi- mate very closely to semi-Pelagianism in regard to the function of prevenient grace. This modified version of the traditional Western presenta- tion of Christian anthropology naturally culminates in an exceptionally mild view of its eschatological corollaries, that is, in a view of Limbo even gentler than that of St. Thomas. Scotus is compelled by tradition to describe those in Limbo as ‘damned’ !; but their damnation is, it would seem, of an exceedingly pleasurable and soothing kind. Those who are lost merely because of the original sin of their nature, and are free from actual or personal sin, have no pain or sadness of any kind; they are exempt both from the poena sensus, the torments of unending flames, and from the poena damnz, the penalty of the loss of God.? Though they will not have the Beatific Vision of God in His intimate essence, it is probable that they will know God through His works, perhaps as perfectly as He can be so known; and this knowledge will give them a certain positive pleasure. Scotus quotes Bonaventura as saying that Augustine spoke excessive— with exaggeration ’—in denying the intermediate state postulated by the Pelagians in the case of the virtuous or sinless non-baptised.4 So far as the conception of Limbo is concerned the Franciscan theory won all along the line in the Middle Ages. The few rigid Augustinians, like Gregory of Rimini (d. 1358), who clung 1 dist. Xxxili. 2 (p. 328) : ‘ damnati pro solo peccato originali.’ 2 1hid. 2 (p. 329). 8 ibid. 3 (p. 330): ‘ videtur probabile concedere quod omnium naturaliter cognoscibilium possunt naturaliter cognitionem habere excel- lentius quam aliqui habuerunt pro statu isto, et ita aliqualem beatitudinem naturalem de Deo cognito in universali poterunt attingere.’ * dist. xxxiii. 4 (p. 331). 416 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN to the idea of positive torments to be inflicted on unbaptised infants, were scoffingly nicknamed tortores infantium. It was reserved for Calvin to revive this part of the Augustinian teaching in its full horror. Two further consequences of the Scotist doctrine should be mentioned for the sake of completeness—one which has reference to the person of the Redeemer, and the other to that of His Mother. It is naturally difficult for those who minimise the seriousness of the Fall to suppose that such a tremendous event as the Incarnation was contingent upon it. Franciscan thought on this subject is funda- mentally out of sympathy with the idea expressed in the famous phrase of the Exultet: ‘O certe necessarium Adae peccatum! O felix culpa, quae talem et tantum meruit habere redemptorem!’ Hence comes the characteristically Scotist view that the Incarnation would in any case have taken place, even if there had been no Fall, and that it was purposed by God from all eternity as the crowning moment of human history.t And the purely negative or depriva- tional notion of original sin, as consisting solely in the absence of certain supernatural graces, made it easier to believe that those graces were as a special privilege conferred upon the Mother of Christ in order to make her body and soul a fitting habitation for the Divine Word.? Harnack’s dictum, however, that it is easy for Roman Catholics to affirm the immunity of Mary from original sin, because original sin means nothing to them, is an obvious exag- geration,? which ignores the fact that the post-Tridentine 1 A classical presentation of the theory of the absolute purpose of the Incarnation is found in Westcott’s essay ‘ The Gospel of Creation ’ (Epistles of St. John, 1883, pp. 273-315). 2 j. Turmel (ERE vii. p. 166, art. ‘ Immaculate Conception’) reverses the relation of cause and effect suggested in the text, and thinks that popular enthusiasm for the feast and the idea of the Immaculate Conception compelled official theology to mitigate its conception of original sin, and in particular to drop the belief in the inherent sinfulness of concupiscence. On strict Augustinian principles, the Immaculate Conception is ruled out, as the soul of Mary would have been automatically infected with original sin by the concupiscence which ex hypothesi must have attended her generation by Joachim and Anne. St. Bernard, as is well known, had strenuously opposed the introduction of the feast (ep. ClorxtV PEC ILNe X L Lig ao ne 3 History of Dogma (E. tr., 1899), vil. p. 100, n. I. DECLINE OF AUGUSTINIANISM 417 Latin doctrine of the inherited wound of human nature is more stringent than the Scotist, though not so severe as the Thomist or the Augustinian teaching.t And it is also fair to point out that the difference between St. Thomas and Duns Scotus in regard to the privilege of Mary turned, not upon the question whether Mary after her birth was exempt from original sin—for both admitted this—but upon the question whether this exemption was conferred on her at some unknown moment during her intra-uterine life, as the Angelic Doctor affirmed,? or in the very first instant of her existence, that is, at the moment of her conception, as the Subtle Doctor maintained. The foregoing summaries of the anthropological thought 1 It will be appropriate to append here a few words with regard to the bearing of our discussion upon the Roman doctrine of the Immaculate Conception of the Blessed Virgin Mary. The Bull Ineffabilis Deus, dated Dec. 8, 1854, affirms that ‘ the doctrine which holds, that the most blessed Virgin Mary was in the first instant of her conception, by a singular grace and privilege of Almighty God, in view of the merits of Christ Jesus, the Saviour of the human race, preserved immune from all stain of original sin (ab omni originalis culpae labe praeservatam tmmunem) has been revealed by God and is therefore by all the faithful to be firmly and constantly believed ’ (Denzinger-Bannwart, Enchiridion, § 1641). As the definition is promul- gated by Roman authority, it presumably presupposes the present Roman conception of original sin, which (as pointed out in the text) is somewhat severer than the Scotist doctrine, inasmuch as it includes not merely the guilt of being devoid of original righteousness, but also the guilt of having sinned ‘in Adam.’ Immunity ‘from all stain of original sin’ must therefore mean, inter alia, immunity from original guilt. From the stand- point of the thesis developed in these lectures, it follows that the main objection to the doctrine of the Immaculate Conception is—not so much the fact that no trace of any such belief can be found in the New Testament or in the Christian writers of the first four centuries, but rather—the fact that (if our contentions have been sound) the idea of responsibility for pre-natal participation in Adam’s sin is both mythological and irrational. If, as we have argued, ‘ original guilt’ is merely an Augustinian nightmare, it is meaningless to assert that Mary was ‘ immune’ from it. 2 The doctrine of St. Thomas on this subject is contained in summa theol. iii. q. xxvii, ‘ de beatae Mariae virginis sanctificatione.’ This doctrine is (a) ‘ rationabiliter creditur quod beata Virgo sanctificata fuerit antequam ex utero nasceretur’ (a. 1); (bd) ‘sanctificatio beatae Virginis post eius animationem’ (a. 2); (c) ‘per sanctificationem in utero non sublatus beatae Virgini fomes secundum essentiam, sed ligatus’ (the ‘fomes’ is, of course, concupiscence) ‘postmodum vero in ipsa conceptione carnis Christi, in quo primo debuit refulgere peccati immunitas, credendum est quod ex prole redundaverit in matrem, totaliter fomite subtracto’ (a. 3). 2E 418 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN of the two leading doctors of the Middle Ages will, it may be hoped, have made it clear that the history of our subject during the scholastic period is the history of the gradual decline of rigid Augustinianism. In the eleventh century the first blows were struck at its supremacy by Anselm, who introduced the conception of the ‘lack of original righteousness ’ as a prime constituent of original sin, thereby paving the way for the substitution of the idea of hereditary weakness for that of hereditary wickedness, and by Abaelard, who was the first to challenge the idea of original guilt. St. Thomas and the Dominicans stood for a modified type of Augustinianism, in which the lack of original righteous- ness is described as the ‘ form,’ and concupiscence as the ‘matter’ of original sin. Scotus and the Franciscans developed a still further modified version of Augustinianism (if such it can be called) in which original sin for all practical purposes comes to consist solely in the lack of original righteousness, and concupiscence ceases to be in any real sense sinful. Naturally such a highly artificialand abstract notion as that of the mere non-possession of certain splendid endowments, which were believed to have for a brief space belonged to the remote ancestor of human kind, had little power to weigh upon men’s consciences or even to excite their intellectual interest: and if the Franciscan and Nominalist tendency to whittle the Fall-doctrine down to nothing had continued, the whole of Augustine’s work in regard to these ideas might have been undone, even within the sphere and period of mediaeval Catholicism. It is a striking fact that the comprehensive commentary on the ‘Sentences’ written by Pierre d’Ailly1 ignores the whole subject of originalsin. The short-lived Augustinian reaction associated with the names of Bradwardine and Wycliffe had comparatively little effect on the general thought of Europe. What really gave Augustinianism a new lease of life was the Reformation. It will, however, conduce to clearness if for 1 Pierre d’Ailly (1350-1420) was successively chancellor of Notre Dame de Paris, bishop of Cambrai, bishop of Orange, and cardinal. He played a leading part in the ‘ Conciliar ’ movement at the beginning of the fifteenth century. For a study of his life and writings, see P. Tschackert, Peter von Ailli, Gotha, 1877. The statement in the text is made on the authority of Ljunggren, op. cit., p. 249. DECLINE OF AUGUSTINIANISM 419 the moment we ignore this cataclysmic event, and continue the story of the gradual decadence of Augustinianism within Latin Christianity down to modern times. THE COUNCIL OF TRENT The discussion of these doctrines between the theologians of the two great mendicant Orders was largely an affair of the study and the schools. The questions involved did not affect practical life in any way,! nor were they of interest to the laity or to such of the clergy as were not theological experts. They belonged to the same world of discourse as the interminable controversies with regard to angels, whether they occupy space or not, whether one angel can occupy the same space as another, whether the thought of angels is discursive or intuitive. But the Reformation, challenging as it did the whole fabric of mediaeval Church life and thought, had the remarkable effect of dragging the doctrines of the Fall and of original sin out from the cloister and the lecture-room into the market-place, and of making them issues of the greatest interest and importance for the religious life of hundreds of thousands of ordinary people.? Hence, when the Latin Church, after the defection of the Northern nations, took stock of itself, and proceeded to reorganise itself on a military basis, like a besieged city, with 1G. G. Coulton, however (Five Centuries of Religion, vol. 1, 1923, p- 145), thinks that the gloom of the severe Augustinian doctrine helped to stimulate the growth of the cultus of the Blessed Virgin, the thought of whose intercessory powers provided men with some mental relief from the prospect of probable damnation. * This popularisation of the Fall-doctrine is illustrated by the liturgical confessions of sin embodied in many Protestant Church Orders, which require the congregation to accuse itself of original as well as of actual sin : for a collection of such confessions, see Additional Note C, ‘ Congregational Confessions of Original Sin in the Churches of the Reformation’ (p. 443). The enormous growth of interest in original sin which these formulae manifest can be gauged if they are compared with their mediaeval pre- decessor, the Catholic ‘ confiteor Deo omnipotenti, beatae Mariae semper virgini, omnibus sanctis . . . quia peccavi nimis cogitatione, verbo, et opere, mea culpa’ which is a confession of actual sin only. It may be noted that the Confessions contained in the daily Offices and Communion Service of the Church of England, though showing literary relationship with the Continental confessions, abstain from mentioning original sin. 420 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN a stern discipline designed to safeguard its life against the attacks of its enemies, it was necessary that these doctrines also should be reduced to a stiff, defined form, in order to keep the reforming influence at a safe distance. Conse- quently what is still the official doctrine of the Roman Church on these subjects was formulated at the Council of Trent, despite the nervousness of the Emperor Charles V, who would much have preferred that the Council should have left such thorny topics alone. The Dominicans were repre- sented at the Council by Catterino and de Soto, two of the most learned theologians of their order ; but it is remarkable that we hear very little of the Franciscans. The Order of Friars Minor had fallen upon evil days, having produced no great theologian since William Occam. It was at this period distracted by the schisms between the Capuchins and the Conventuals; and the mantle of Duns Scotus, as the upholder of the anti-Augustinian position, had fallen upon the newly founded Society of Jesus. The decisions of the -Souncil were contained in the Decree concerning original sin, (Cession 5, affirmed on June 17, 1546, and the Decree con- cerning Justification, Session 6, affirmed on January 13, 1547.1 The former consists of five canons verbally repeating the first two canons of the second Council of Orange, and containing also a long passage taken from the second canon of the second Council of Carthage, which had condemned Pelagius and Caelestius in A.p. 418. These facts sound as though the Tridentine decision ought to have been a triumph for Augustinianism. Actually, the result was a compromise which cannot have satisfied either party completely, as a brief analysis of it will show. We will take the cardinal points at issue seviatim. (1) ‘ Original righteousness.’ Adam is said to have been ‘constituted’ in holiness and righteousness. The Council is silent on the subject of his supposed intellectual attainments. (The word ‘consti- tuted’ is obviously meant to avoid raising the question whether Adam was created in original righteousness, as the Dominicans asserted, or created in a state of pure nature and subsequently endowed with supernatural holiness, as 1 For the text of the relevant portions of these documents, see Additional Note F, ‘ Formularies (Il), Western and Roman,’ p. 538. DECLINE OF AUGUSTINIANISM 421 the Franciscans maintained.) (2) Original sin considered as vitium. Here the Council is studiously vague, contenting itself with repeating the indefinite affirmation of the second Council of Orange, to the effect that by the Fall Adam was changed for the worse, in both body and soul, and that he injured his posterity and not merely himself. (3) Original sin considered as veatus, that is, ‘ original guilt.’ This is emphatically affirmed. Canon 3 (of the Decree concerning original sin) seems to imply the theory of ‘ seminal identity,’ though its language is very vague. Canon 4 asserts that infants have sin, which must be expiated in the laver of regeneration. Canon 5 usesthe actual phrase vreatus pbeccatt originalis, and asserts that something undefined, which has the true and proper nature of sin, is abolished by baptism. (4) With regard to the state of human nature which has resulted from the Fall, the Council affirms that concupiscence is not sin but merely the fomes or tinder of sin and that it is left in the regenerate ad agonem, for them to struggle against. It is declared also that man’s free-will was by no means extinguished, but rather attenuated and warped so that apart from grace men cannot rise and free themselves from the chains of sinful desire. It will be seen at once that these positions represent a compromise between the Dominican and the Jesuit points of view, in which, on the whole, the Jesuits get very much the best of the bargain. The Dominicans secure the affirmation of original guilt in terms which go a long way beyond the debt theory of Scotus. The anti-Augustinian party, on the other hand, secures a strong affirmation of the reality of human free-will, the denial of concupiscence as in any real sense sin, the exemp- tion of the Blessed Virgin Mary from the scope of the decree affirming the universality of original sin, and the denial of the Augustinian position that the good works of non- Christians are sins. It may therefore be said that Triden- tine orthodoxy on this subject is, on the whole, Scotist, with one unassimilated fragment of pure Augustinianism, namely, the conception of original guilt, adhering awkwardly to it. The subsequent history of these doctrines in the Latin Church may be passed over in a few words. The main controversy between the Dominicans and the Jesuits tended 422 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN to veer away from anthropology and to become more and more entangled in the question of ‘ grace,’ with which, as was pointed out in Lecture V,! we are not immediately con- cerned. Mention must be made, however, of one attempt to revive the full Augustinian scheme within the Roman communion—an attempt which by its failure and suppression had the indirect effect of accentuating the Scotist and anti- Augustinian character of Latin orthodoxy on these points. This is associated with the name of Michael de Bay, or Baius.2 Baius, a professor at the University of Louvain, who had attended the Council of Trent as a theological expert, denied the scholastic distinction between the donum supernaturale of original righteousness and the pura naturalia (thereby asserting that Adam’s splendid gifts of mind and soul belonged to the essence of human nature, and so increasing the guilt of his fall), and also reaffirmed the Augustinian position that the mere presence of potential concupiscence in a newly born infant is in itself a deadly sin.? The condemnation of these two propositions,* amongst many others gathered from the works of Baius, exerted, so to speak, a reflex influence on the current teaching of Roman theologians. The distinction between mere human nature and the ‘ supernatural gifts ’ was sharpened and stereotyped ; and in practice the idea of original sin came to be interpreted in the Scotist manner, as a mere deprivation of these super- natural gifts, with only some slight deordination of the proper relations of reason and appetite as its result. The idea of original guilt is still retained in words, but it is explained in such a way as to evacuate the term ‘ guilt,’ and the forensic terminology which naturally coheres with this conception, of all real meaning. To illustrate this, we need * Pp. 337: * Born 1513, died 1589: the forerunner of the more celebrated Cornelius Jansen. 8’ These two positions, as will be explained below, constituted the differentia of the version of the Fall-doctrine characteristic of the Reforma- tion. Baius was, in effect, endeavouring to naturalise the Protestant anthropology within the sphere of post-Tridentine Latin Catholicism. See Vacant-Mangénot, DTC., art. ‘ Baius.’ 4 By the Bull of Pius V, Ex omnibus afflictionibus (1567). For the principal propositions condemned, see Denzinger-Bannwart, Enchiridion, §§ roo1 ff.; notice especially 1021, 1023, 1025-27, 1047, IO5I. DECLINE OF AUGUSTINIANISM 423 only quote a recent authoritative statement of the Roman Catholic point of view, contained in the volume of essays called ‘ God and the Supernatural.’1 Speaking of the term “uncleanness ’ as applied to original sin, the writer on ‘ The Problem of Evil’ says: No physical defilement nor uncleanness of nature as such does the Church intend by such language, but simply and solely birth into a nature-self deprived of the supernature which should have completed it. Thus is the personal innocence of the new- born babe, its innocence in the natural order, compatible with a guilt of its nature in relation to the supernatural order. Thus also is it dear to God because substantially united to Him as its natural ground and end, yet ‘a child of wrath’ in its separation from Him and aversion from Him as its supernatural end.? He adds in a footnote: ‘ Yet surely such language as “ child of wrath” or “hateful to God” should not be used of naturally and personally innocent children without careful explanation of its highly technical and non-natural sense.’ In this part of our enquiry we are concerned rather to record the movement of ideas than to criticise them. It is impos- sible, however, to refrain from observing that if the term ‘guilt ’ can only be applied to original sin in a non-natural sense it would seem much better that it should not be so applied at all. AUGUSTINIANISM AND THE REFORMATION It will thus be seen that within Latin Catholicism, which still constitutes the greater part of Western Christendom, the influence of St. Augustine’s characteristic Fall-doctrine has steadily declined during that whole period of its history which may be regarded as beginning with the rise of Scholas- ticism and as ending with the definition of the doctrine of the Immaculate Conception by Pius IX. If the fluctuations in the degree of power exercised at different epochs by a given doctrine over the minds of men could be represented 1 Ed. Fr. Cuthbert, O.S.F.C. (1920). a Pil 5O: 424 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN under the form of a mathematical graph, we should see the index-point of Augustinian dominance rising to its zenith shortly after the death of St. Augustine himself, continuing at this exalted level across an area denoting some six cen- turies, beginning to fall at the point corresponding to the teaching activity of St. Anselm, and descending in a gradual and elongated curve down to the period of the Reformation. Here our chart would have to be doubled, in order to con- form to the religious partition of Europe effected by that event ; and we should notice the remarkable fact that, whereas in the Latin section of the chart the line of Augus- tinian influence continues to sink, until it reaches its nadir at the canonisation of Alfonso Liguori, in the Reformed section it rushes steeply and suddenly upwards, like the edge of the Matterhorn’s silhouette, and for more than two centuries preserves an elevation equal to that which it maintained within those divisions of the single chart which we suppose to symbolise the period known as the “ Dark Ages.’ In other words, we are at this stage of our enquiry brought face to face with a colossal recrudescence of the rigidly ‘ twice-born ’ anthropology, combined with a remorseless accentuation of all its sternest lineaments—a process which has given birth to that puritan doctrine of original sin still so largely believed to be the primitive, Christian, and Biblical doctrine. The details of this process, and the merits of its results, now demand examination. It is natural in the first instance to raise the question, why the Reformers should have felt it necessary to draw up an elaborate system of doctrines with regard to these abstruse and mysterious subjects at all? The Reformation proclaimed itself to be a return to Gospel simplicity, a revolt against the subtleties and quiddities of the Schoolmen, a rediscovery and republication of the pure and undefiled Christianity of the New Testament: why, then, could its leaders not have been content with the very general, loose, and undefined teaching of St. Paul? Why did they feel it necessary to bequeath to posterity the interminable definitions with regard to predestination, the Fall, original sin, grace, and free-will, which crowd the pages of the innumerable formularies produced in the sixteenth and DECLINE OF AUGUSTINIANISM 425 seventeenth centuries ? What constrained them to impose upon their followers anthropological schemes, no less com- plicated and far more gloomy than anything that appears in the pages of St. Thomas or St. Bonaventura? The answer to these questions is partly historical, partly psycho- logical. The Fall-doctrine of the Reformation grew from a double root, of which one fibre was embedded in (a) the hitherto dominant Augustinian dogma, whilst the other sprang from (0) the personal idiosyncrasy of the revolting leaders, Luther and Calvin themselves. (a) In our last lecture it was pointed out that the thought of St. Augustine, considered as a whole, is permeated by two dominant elements which have never been finally fused or synthesised, the predestinarian element, which regards salvation as the direct work of God upon the individual soul, a work to which the saved man contributes little or nothing, and the institutional or hierarchical element, according to which the Christian works out his own salvation through the devout use of the Sacraments, within the warmth and shelter provided by a great and august society.1_ During the Middle Ages it was the ecclesiastical and sacramental element in Augustine’s teaching which, as embodied in the mighty theocratic fabric of the Western Catholic Church, exercised the most powerful influence over the lives of ordinary men, and his predestinarianism was little heard of outside the lecture-room and the cloister. But the mystical craving for immediate, personal, unhampered access to the Divine— the longing which impels the solitary soul to overleap all external, ecclesiastical, and liturgical forms, and to wing her way in a flash to the arms of her solitary God—was still working underground, in the dim subconsciousness of the Teutonic nations: and in the Reformation it found a volcanic and earth-shattering expression. Hence it was, humanly speaking, inevitable that the Reformers, nourished as they had been on the thought of St. Augustine, and repre- senting as they did that individualistic method of envisaging the Godward impulse which had determined his predesti- narian teaching, should, in their revolt against his institu- tionalism, have revived, with unbalanced enthusiasm, his 1 vu. supra, p. 321f. 426 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN “twice-born’ anthropology ; that their declaration of war upon the Mass, penance, the cultus of the saints, pilgrimages, monasticism, and other external works and forms, should have been accompanied by the promulgation of a theory of man and of sin which was designed to rule out human merit, and to make salvation exclusively God’s work, and which therefore was obliged to presuppose the lowest possible view of unredeemed human nature. (5) To these considerations we must add the fact that both Luther and Calvin appear to have possessed that ‘twice-born’ religious temperament indicated by the experience of instantaneous conversion, whether complete or incomplete, or by experiences analogous thereto. There seems no reason for discrediting the story of the voice which sounded in Luther’s ears, pronouncing the words ‘The just shall live by faith, when as a young Austin Friar he had ascended half of the Scala Sancta at Rome on his knees!; and, though this phenomenon took years to work its full effect in Luther’s mind, it would seem not unjustifiable, from the standpoint of human psychology, to class it with the ‘ Saul, Saul’ of the Damascus road or the ‘ Tolle, lege’ of the Milanese garden. Calvin, too, was visited by a similar experience in his youth, though of this no details are known.? It is not too much to claim that temperament alone would have guided the great Reformers into the paths of a severe and gloomy anthropology, even had they not been intellectual heirs of mediaeval theology, with its overwhelming tradition of the African Doctor’s immemorial authority. 1 This incident occurred during Luther’s stay in Rome, Dec. 1510- Jan. 1511. The version of the story assumed in the text is that given by Luther’s son Paul, who says that he had it from his father. The Reformer himself, however, in a sermon of Sept. 15, 1545, alludes to the incident, merely describing his experience as a sudden feeling of doubt whether the system of indulgences was true. Dr. J. Mackinnon (Luther and the Reformation, 1925, i. p. 144, n. 78) thinks that the two versions of the story are incompatible, and that Luther’s own account must be accepted in preference to his son’s; it appears to me, however, that there is no real incompatibility, and that the Reformer may well have preferred in the pulpit to employ an indefinite mode of allusion to his experience, whilst feeling free to narrate it in detail in the privacy of his family. 2 Calvin, in librum psalm. comment., praefatio (ed. A. Tholuck, Berlin, 1836, 1. p. ix). DECLINE OF AUGUSTINIANISM 427 The differences between Lutheranism and Calvinism in regard to the doctrines of man and of sin are inconsiderable, so that it is possible to state the Fall-theory characteristic of the Reformation as a single dogmatic scheme. This scheme was based upon a position which seems curiously dry, abstract, and unreal to us to-day, but which was in the sixteenth century defended by the Reforming leaders with the most passionate fervour: it consists in the denial of the scholastic distinction between the donum supernaturale of Original Righteousness assumed to have been received from his Creator by unfallen man and his pura naturaha, that is, the qualities belonging to him merely in right of his human nature.4 It will be remembered that this dis- tinction made possible a comparatively mild view of the Fall, at any rate for the Franciscan Schoolmen: a citizen who is elevated to princely rank and then deposed from it is not necessarily worse off than he was before his elevation. But, for the reasons just mentioned, the Reformers were determined to paint the present condition of fallen human nature in colours as gloomy as possible. Hence the mag- nificent endowments supposed to have been possessed by the first man are affirmed to have been, not superadded adornments, but essential constituents of human nature as God originally created it; and their loss means, not merely that human nature has been stripped of some adventitious splendours, but that it has been wrecked and confounded in its inmost being. The Fall was not 1 Cf. the position of Baius, mentioned above, p. 422. Though this dispute between Latin Catholic and Protestant theologians (whether the splendours of ‘ original righteousness’ were a donum indebitum, 1.e. a separable accident of the protoplast’s nature, as the Catholics maintained, or an essential quality thereof, as the Protestants contended) may seem to us mow purely academic, yet (as Ritschl, Rechtfertigung u. Versdhnung?, lii. p. 308, acutely points out) it was vividly symptomatic of the divergence between the mediaeval Catholic and the Protestant Weltanschauungen. For the Protestant view implies that the idea of Christian perfection was included in the idea of human nature itself as conceived in the Divine mind : from which it follows that man should seek his perfection along strictly human lines (as a citizen, husband, father, etc.). Whereas the Latin Catholic opinion, that ‘ original righteousness ’ was a donum supernaturale, catastrophically imposed upon man’s pura naturvalia, involves a super- naturalism according to which human perfection can ultimately be found only in the vita angelica of monasticism. 428 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN a fall from supernature to mere nature, as the Schoolmen had taught, but from mere nature to sub-nature. Man is not a citizen, who, after receiving a princedom from the generosity of his sovereign and forfeiting it by his own fault, has reverted to his former bourgeois condition; he is a citizen who has degraded himself by his own act to the status of an outlaw or a felon. This view of the nature of original righteousness, with its corollary as to the infinite ruin wrought by the Fall, gives rise, by a logic which we might regard as inexorable if we did not know that the conclusion has really determined the premises, to the doctrine of human nature generally known as that of ‘total depravity.’ Though the essence of this doctrine is common to both the great schools of Reformation thought, certain differences manifest themselves in the expositions which Luther and Calvin give of it. It may be said at once that the Lutheran doctrine on this point is by far the more pessimistic and severe. According to the strict Lutheran conception, human nature by the Fall was deprived of one of its essential faculties—the faculty of knowing, loving, and serving God. The God-apprehending powers of the human soul were totally extirpated. The so-called ‘ Synergist’ Lutherans, under the leadership of Victorinus Strigel, endeavoured to mitigate the harshness of this doctrine by maintaining that the moral and religious faculties were not so much permanently destroyed as tem- porarily paralysed. This view was, however, hailed by the majority of Luther’s followers with shouts of vituperation, as being grossly Pelagian, and was condemned by the ‘Formulary of Concord,’ one of the official documents of the Lutheran Church, which says ‘ They also are likewise repudiated and rejected, who teach that our nature has indeed been greatly weakened and corrupted because of the Fall of the human race, but nevertheless has not alto- gether lost all goodness relating to divine and spiritual things. . . . For they say that from his natural birth man still has remaining somewhat of good, however little, minute, scanty and attenuated this may be.’2 It is true that the 1 J. A. Mohler, Symbolism (E. tr., 1847), pp. 79, 80. 2 solid. declar. i. de pecc. orig. § 23. DECLINE OF AUGUSTINIANISM 429 Confession of Augsburg leaves man some little power of fulfilling what it calls ‘ civil justice,’ that is, duties enjoined by purely political or secular morality; but this power has no reference to spiritual or supernatural virtue, of which fallen man is totally and absolutely bereft. To quote once more the emphatic language of the Formulary of Concord, fallen man as such possesses no more power of loving God or turning towards Him than a stone, a tree-trunk, or a piece of mud.? From this position, in the thought of Luther himself an even more startling consequence follows. It seemed self-evident to him that original justice and original sin must be exactly equal and parallel. He seems, by a curious piece of confused thinking, to infer from this premise the consequence that the annihilation of the moral and religious faculties of the soul must have been followed by the substitution in their place of similar, but contrarily orientated powers—what might be called immoral and irreligious faculties? Hence we are led to the idea of original sin as a substantive thing or hypostasis—an idea which the Reformer expresses in crude phrases, such as these: ‘It is the essence of man to sin,’ ‘ original sin is that very thing which is born of a father and a mother,’ “Man, as he is born of father and mother, is with his whole nature and essence not merely a sinner but sin itself.’ * It is difficult to avoid the conclusion that Luther has plunged headlong into the abyss of Manicheism, on the verge of which Augustinianism had always trembled but into which it had never, up to this moment, actually fallen.° His followers did not indeed go so far ; but the conception of original sin as a positive malignant power, and not a mere deprivation, 1 conf. August., art. xviii.: ‘ de libero arbitrio docent quod humana voluntas habeat aliquam libertatem ad efficiendam civilem iustitiam, et diligendas res rationi subiectas.’ —~ * solid. declar. ii. de lib. arb. § 24: ‘ antequam homo per Spiritum Sanctum illuminatur . . . ex sese et propriis naturalibus suis viribus, in rebus spiritualibus nihil inchoare, operari, aut cooperari potest, non plus quam lapis truncus aut limus.’ 8 Mohler, op. cit., i. p. 85. 4 These expressions were collected by J. A. Quenstedt (Theologia didactico-polemica, Wittenberg, 1601, ii. pp. 134 f.). 5 The Formulary of Concord, however, expressly condemns the Manichean theory that evil is a substance (solid. declar. 1. § 27). 430 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN is unequivocally expressed by the Formulary of Concord in words which may be quoted here : Moreover, it is affirmed that original sin in human nature is not merely that total lack or defect of virtuous powers in spiritual things which pertain unto God; but also that into the place of the image of God which has been lost there has succeeded an intimate, grievous, most profound and abyss-like, inscrutable _and indescribable corruption of the whole nature and of all the powers of man, most chiefly of the superior and principal faculties of the soul, a corruption which infects the mind, intellect, heart, and will. Wherefore after the Fall man receives from his parents by heredity a congenitally depraved impulse, filthiness of heart, depraved concupiscences and depraved inclinations.4 — This sweeping condemnation of human nature as it stands previously to the operations of divine grace raised once more the old enigma of the apparent virtues and good works of non-Christians. Generally speaking, the theology of the Reformation, in regard to this point as to others, obediently follows the lines laid down by its master, Augustine. The supposed ‘ good deeds’ of Jews or pagans are really sins: for, given the doctrine of “ total depravity,’ all that issues from unregenerate human nature is necessarily sinful.2 So the Apology for the Confession of Augsburg asserts : ‘it is both false and an insult to Christ, to assert that men do not sin when they fulfil the commandments of God, apart from grace ’ ® (and grace ex hypothest is only bestowed upon members of the Christian Church). This position is developed, and based upon the familiar proof- text discovered in the Epistle to the Romans by the 1 solid. declay. i. 11 : ‘ praeterea, quod peccatum originale in humana natura non tantummodo sit eiusmodi totalis carentia seu defectus omnium bonorum in rebus spiritualibus ad Deum pertinentibus, sed quod sit etiam, loco imaginis Dei amissae in homine, intima, pessima, profundissima instar cuiusdam abyssi, inscrutabilis et ineffabilis corruptio totius naturae et omnium virium, inprimis vero superiorum et principalium animae facultatum in mente, intellectu, corde, et voluntate. itaque iam post lapsum homo haereditario a parentibus accipit congenitam pravam vim, internam immunditiam cordis, pravas concupiscentias et pravas inclinationes.’ 2 Cf. Calvin, instit. christ. vel. li. 3, title: ‘ ex corrupta hominis natura nihil nisi damnabile prodire.’ 3 apol. conf. Aug. li. § 29: ‘ falsum est et hoc et contumeliosum in Christum, quod non peccent homines facientes praecepta Dei sine gratia.’ DECLINE OF AUGUSTINIANISM 431 ingenuity of Augustine,? in the following sentence of the same formulary: ‘Seeing that contempt of God and doubt concerning His word, His threats, and His promises are rooted in the nature of man, men truly sin even when they perform good works apart from the Holy Spirit: for they perform such works with an impious heart, as it is written, _ whatsoever 1s not of faith 1s sin.’ 2 Thus the whole of human nature and the sum of man’s moral aspirations and efforts, apart from Christianity, are stigmatised as corrupt and worthless in the sight of Almighty God. Compared with this crude and violent version of the dogma of ‘ total depravity,’ Calvin’s doctrine on the same subject assumes from time to time a comparatively humane and reasonable form. There is one sentence of the Institutio which in words denies the idea of total depravity, in con- nexion with this vexed question of the virtues of pagans, which, he tells us, have been ordained by God ne hominis naturam in totum vitiosam putemus, lest we should think that the nature of man is altogether depraved.? And the psychological analysis of the various faculties of human nature which occurs in the second book of the Institutes contains a singularly generous tribute to triumphs won by the human intellect, even apart from the grace of Christianity, in the spheres of secular ethics, of philosophy, of political and social science, of the liberal and mechanical arts. He exclaims, with patent sincerity, “How many good things the Lord hath left to human nature, even after it had been despoiled of the one true good!’® Yet against this liberal and enlightened view we have to set many passages which merely repeat the gloomy doctrine of Luther. Even in Ay ROM. xiv. 23°; see Lecture!V )p.'374 f- 2 abol. conf. Aug. uu. § 38: ‘cum igitur haereant in natura hominis contemptus Dei, dubitatio de verbo Dei, de minis et promissionibus, vere peccant homines etiam cum honesta opera faciunt sine Spiritu Sancto, quia faciunt ea impio corde, iuxta illud, guicquid non est ex fide peccatum est.’ 2 instit i. 3; 3- 4 ibid. ii. 2, 13-16. 5 ibtd. ii. 2,15: ‘ergocum homines istos, quos scriptura yuyiKxods vocat, usque eo fuisse pateat in rerum inferiorum investigatione acutos et per- spicaces, talibus exemplis discamus quot naturae humanae bona Dominus reliquerit, postquam vero bono spoliata est.’ 432 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN the case of the virtuous pagans, such as Camillus, who appears to have been a stock example of non-Christian virtue, he suggests that their apparently good deeds must have been due to one of two causes—either to hypocrisy, or merely to the sovereign will of God, mechanically im- pinging upon them ad extra and restraining them from acts of external vice without healing the interior corruption of their souls... Many passages can be quoted which in fact affirm the idea of total depravity, despite the verbal denial of it which we observed just now. The whole of human nature is saturated with ‘ concupiscence,’ which is in itself mortally sinful, even before and apart from the consent of the will.? Man is covered from head to foot with sin as with a flood.® Infants bring their own damnation with them from their mothers’ wombs ; the moment they are born their natures are odious and abominable to God.‘ It is not necessary to devote many words to the question of original guilt, because, as will have been seen, this idea is implicit in the Augustinian theory, whole-heartedly accepted by both of the great Reformers, of the intrinsic sinfulness of concupiscence, that is, of any kind of appetitive movement - or impulse towards action forbidden by the law of God, even though such movement be not endorsed and even though it may be resisted by the conscious will. This is fortified by its connexion with the theory of ‘seminal identity ’ or of the physical solidarity of the race with Adam, which appears explicitly at any rate in Calvin,® and seems ae 1 instit. ii. 3, 3: ‘ita sua providentia Deus naturae perversitatem refraenat, ne in actum erumpat: sed non purgat intus.’ 2 ibid. ii. 1, 8: ‘ qui dixerunt esse concupiscentiam, non nimis alieno verbo usi sunt, si modo adderetur . . . quicquid in homine est, ab intellectu ad voluntatem, ab anima ad carnem usque, hac concupiscentia inquinatum refertumque esse, aut, ut brevius absolvatur, totum hominem non aliud ex se ipso esse quam concupiscentiam.’ 3 ibid. li. 1, 9: ‘ totum hominem quasi diluvio a capite ad pedes sic fuisse obrutum, ut nulla pars a peccato sit immunis.’ 4 gbid. il. 1, 8: ‘ atque ideo infantes quoque ipsi, dum suam secum damnationem a matris utero afferunt, non alieno, sed suo ipsorum vitio sunt obstricti. nam tametsi suae iniquitatis fructus nondum protulerint, habent tamen in se inclusum semen : imo tota eorum natura quoddam est peccati semen: ideo non odiosa et abominabilis Deo esse non potest.’ 5 ibid. ii. 1,6: ‘ certe habendum est, fuisse Adamum humanae naturae non progenitorem modo, sed quasi radicem, atque ideo in illius corruptione DECLINE OF AUGUSTINIANISM 433 to underlie a position which is common to both the great schools of Reformation divines, namely, that in the last analysis original sin—the sin of universal human nature as such, apart from the actual sins of individuals—is the only real sin that exists. Actual sin is regarded as being merely an epiphenomenon—a loathsome efflorescence of which the foul root is the inherent sinfulness of humanity. The sin of Adam, which is the sin of mankind, is regarded as a perennial fountain of filth and uncleanness which is perpetually bubbling up in black streams of perverted and degraded impulse, manifesting itself not merely in those acts which the moral law stigmatises as sinful but in all the daily, hourly, momentary acts, even though in appear- ance innocent or virtuous, performed by the unconverted man—a doctrine which, if seriously accepted, would make this life indeed a prison-house, a penitentiary, and a vale of tears. On this showing, it would seem to be criminal in the sight of Heaven to be a human being at all. The prolegomena to the Gospel would appear to have been well summed up in the gloomy aphorism of the Spanish dramatist Calderon: ‘ The greatest crime of man is that ever he was born.’ The last department of the Reformation doctrine which claims consideration, a department which is closely con- nected with the belief in the ‘ total depravity’ of man, is that concerned with the freedom of the will. It may be briefly stated that both great schools of Reformers carried the speculations of Augustine to their logical conclusion in the shape of a_relentless..and_iron determinism. In regard to this matter, again, the Lutherans are more emphatic and more violent even than Calvin and his followers. The title of Luther’s treatise against Erasmus, de servo arbitrio, leaves room for no mistake as to his con- clusions. Two quotations from this work will be sufficient : ‘Accordingly this doctrine is most chiefly needed and merito vitiatum fuisse hominum genus’: ‘ ipse (sc. Adam) peccando non sibi tantum cladem ac ruinam ascivit, sed naturam quoque nostram in simile praecipitavit exitium. neque id suo unius vitio, quod nihil ad nos pertineat : sed quoniam universum suum semen ea in quam lapsus erat witiositate infecit.’ 2¥ ae We 434 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN salutary for the Christian to know that’God foresees nothing contingently, but that He both foresees, determines, and actually does all things, by His unchangeable, eternal and infallible will. By this thunderbolt the whole idea of free- will is smitten down and ground to powder’ (hoc fulmine sternitur et conteritur pemtus lberum arbitrum). ‘ All things which we do, even though they may seem to us to be done mutably and contingently . . . in reality are done under the stress of immutable necessity (necessario et ammutabiliter) if regard be had to the will of God.’ 2 It is to be noted that the Formulary of Concord gives express sanction to this treatise. Calvin’s doctrine is identical with this, though he attributes real freedom of the psycho- logical order to Adam before the Fall. Yet even this psychological freedom conceded to unfallen Adam is not metaphysical freedom—a conception which is strictly im- possible for Calvin, as it had been for St. Thomas and St. Augustine, in virtue of the irresistible, all-embracing, ineluctable omnipresence of the divine causality. For him, as for his great predecessors, the will of God is the direct and immediate cause of suffering or unhappiness in the world ; there is no room for secondary or contingent causes. Though it is not our purpose to enter into the deeper and vaster problems of predestination, it will be seen how inevitable was the consequence which made the arbitrary, inscrutable will of God the ground of an absolute double predestination—of the elect to eternal life and of the reprobate to eternal loss—a grim conclusion from which the Lutherans always shrank. This overwhelming, almost suffocating doctrine of the absoluteness of God, which can find room for not the faintest motion of spontaneity on the part of His creatures, has been summed up by one who will not be suspected of any prejudice against Calvinism, the late Dr. Fairbairn, in the sentence: ‘Calvin was as pure, though not as conscientious or consistent, a Pantheist as Spinoza.’ 4 1 ob. cit., parsi, § 10 (opera lat. D.M. Luth., ed. Ien., 1567, i. fol. 165). 2 ibid. (op. lat. ed. Ien. i. fol. 165 verso). 3 solid. declar. il. § 44. 4 A.M. Fairbairn, The Place of Christ in Modern Theology, 1893, p. 164. DECLINE OF AUGUSTINIANISM 435 The denial of human freedom and the reference of all effective causality to the will of God naturally raised for the Reformers, as it had raised for the Schoolmen, the question of the extva-human origin of evil. It will be seen at once that any system of rigid determinism possessing a theistic basis can only escape from making God the direct author of evil by the unsatisfactory device of asserting that God cannot have originated that which does not exist.1 Hampered, doubtless, by the tendency already noted in Luther, to conceive evil as a positive hypostatic substance, the Reformers were slow to avail themselves of this way out, and hence, strange though it may seem, one or two of them do not hesitate to attribute evil to the direct causality of God. Melancthon, in the edition of his com- mentary on the Epistle to the Romans published in the year 1525,2 makes the following assertion: ‘ Not merely does God permit His creatures to act, but He Himself is the proper agent in all things that happen; so that as men confess that the conversion of Paul was God’s proper work, so they ought to confess both that morally indifferent actions, such as when men eat, are God’s works, and also actions which are bad, like David’s adultery’; he goes on in the same strain to assert that the treachery of Judas was just as much an act of God as the conversion of St. Paul. These conclusions were, however, so revolting to the general mass of Lutherans that they found no support, and the responsibility for the origin of evil was transferred to Satan, with whom it was left—no attempt 1 Cf. supra, Lecture IV, p. 260. 2 The passage has disappeared from later editions, and is known to us only through its preservation by Melancthon’s pupil, Martin Chemnitz (loc. theol., ed. Leyser, 1610, pars i, p. 173): the original is ‘ nos dicimus, non solum permittere creaturis ut operentur, sed ipsum omnia proprie agere, ut sicut fatentur proprium Dei opus fuisse Pauli vocationem, ita fateantur opera Dei propria esse, sive quae media vocantur, ut comedere, sive quae mala sunt, ut Davidis adulterium: constat enim Deum omnia facere, non permissive, sed potenter, id est, ut sit eius proprium opus Iudae proditio, sicut Pauli vocatio.’ Chemnitz excuses this audacious dictum on the ground that the extreme libertarianism which then prevailed (doubt- less under Franciscan influence) in the Schools was calculated to provoke equally extreme utterances on the other side. Can. 6 of the Tridentine decretum de tustificatione is directed against this utterance of Melancthon : see Additional Note F, ‘ Formularies,’ p. 540. 436 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN being made to investigate the question how Satan became evil. The Calvinists, however, were dominated by a more rigorous logic, and possessed to a greater extent the courage of their convictions.1 If the origin of evil, as it exists at present, be traced to the Fall, the question arises ‘What was the cause of the Fall?’ and for Calvin there , could be only one answer—the will of God. Calvin’s pre-» destinarianism is, therefore, of what is called the ‘ supra- lapsarian’ kind; that is, it assumes that the decree which arbitrarily destined certain elect souls to salvation and con- demned the rest of mankind to perdition, was made by God in eternity, before the Fall, and that the Fall itself was preordained as the means of procuring the infection with sin of those destined to be damned. Calvin leaves us in no doubt as to his tremendous meaning. Such a dictum as the following speaks for itself: ‘ Man falls, the providence of God so ordaining’?; and, alluding to the sovereign, pre-temporal decree of God which he regards as the direct cause of the Fall of man, with all its consequent misery and horror, ending in the eternal ruin of the greater portion of the human race, he observes: ‘It was in truth a horrible decree, I confess: but none can deny that God foreknew the final fate of man before He created him, and that He foreknew it precisely because it was appointed by His own ordinance.’ *® How this terrible doctrine can be reconciled with the love of God Calvin nowhere explains; it is harmonised with His justice by the familiar Augustinian expedient of postulating a peculiar, mysterious and ‘ occult ’ kind of Divine ‘justice’ which has little or nothing in common with what we know as human justice.* Critics 1 For quotations from Zwingli appearing to make God the author of sin, see Mohler, op. cit. i. p. 54 ff. ; for the opinions of Beza, zbid. i. p. 60 fff. 2 instit. lili. 23, 8: “ cadit igitur homo, Dei providentia sic ordinante, sed suo vitio cadit.’ 8 ibid. iii. 23, 7: ‘decretum quidem horribile, fateor: infitiari tamen nemo poterit quin praesciverit Deus quem exitum esset habiturus homo antequam ipsum conderet, et ideo praesciverit quia decreto suo sic ordinarat.’ 4 Cf. ibid. iil. 23, 8: ‘si enim praedestinatio nihil aliud est quam divinae iustitiae, occuliae quidem, sed inculpatae, dispensatio . . . iustis- simum quoque esse interitum quem ex praedestinatione subeunt aeque certum est.’ DECLINE OF AUGUSTINIANISM 437 who are not satisfied with this arbitrary device are silenced by a convenient quotation from St. Paul—‘ Nay, but, O man, who art thou that repliest against God? Shall the thing formed say to him that formed it, Why hast thou made me thus? Hath not the potter power over the clay, of the same lump to make one vessel unto honour, and another unto dishonour?’! It is conceivable that the Apostle might have expressed himself in less absolute terms had he foreseen the use to which his words were destined to be put; but that is a question which cannot be discussed now. Meanwhile, it is not unfair to conclude this summary of the Augustinian anthropology, as republished and developed by the leaders of the Reformation, with the remark that in the hands of Melancthon and Calvin, at least, who make God the ultimate author of evil, it would seem to have transformed itself into precisely that unmoral Hindu monism—that belief in a God, or an Absolute, who transcends the distinction between good and evil—which, as we saw at the beginning of this enquiry, is one of the Fall-doctrine’s two traditional foes: a curious revolution of the wheel of thought.? THE ANGLICAN DOCTRINE We have now reviewed the history of the Augustinian Fall-doctrine between the fifth and the sixteenth centuries, and have failed to discover any considerations calculated to induce us to revise the unfavourable judgment which was passed upon it in our last lecture. Neither the Schoolmen nor the Reformers seem to have succeeded in placing the ideas of Original Righteousness, “ seminal identity,’ Original Guilt, and the intrinsic sinfulness of ‘ concupiscence’ in a more Rom: ix. 20, 21. 2 It should be added, however, that the chief Protestant Confessions explicitly and strongly condemn the view that God is in any sense the author of sin: the more extreme oditey dicta of individual Reformers quoted in the text are meant to illustrate the subconscious tendencies and the logical implications of their thought, and are not cited as representing the official mind of the Lutheran and Calvinistic Churches, for which see Additional Note F, ‘ Formularies’ IV and V, pp. 543-548. 438 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN favourable light ; on the contrary, the former proved able to defend these conceptions only by modifying them or by taking refuge in mystery, whilst the latter appear to have achieved nothing beyond bringing out into fuller relief all their more irrational and horrifying features. As for the suggestion in which this Lecture’s argument found its starting-point, that the ‘ twice-born’ doctrine has a prima facie claim to be considered as having fulfilled the Vincentian test, inasmuch as it has been accepted by all the intellectual vital and progressive areas of Western Christendom, that has been sufficiently refuted by the gradual decline of Augustinianism within the Latin communion, and by its almost complete disappearance, consummated within the last hundred years, from the thought of Continental Protestan- tism. In a rapid and summary review such as the present (which is all that the vastness of the period to be covered and the necessity of compressing our discussion within the limits of a single lecture permit), it is impossible to do more than allude to the great break-up of traditional evangelical orthodoxy in the Continental homes of the Reformation, due to the collapse of the belief in the literal inerrancy of the Bible—a break-up in which the ultra-Augustinian Fall- doctrine of the Reformers, based as it was believed to be upon the historicity of Gen. iii, was swept away with the rest of the Protestant scholastic system. The philosophic attempts of Kant and Hegel to restate what they considered to be the permanent essence of the doctrine must be reserved for con- sideration in our final lecture. Only the barest mention can be made of Schleiermacher’s attempt to save the form of the idea of original sin whilst abandoning its content, by explain- ing ‘hereditary sin’ (Evbsiinde) in terms of ‘social,’ as opposed to biological, heredity ?: or of the explicit sub- stitution of a communal sinfulness (gemeinsame Sinde, Gesammisiinde) handed on by example and tradition for the idea of a weakness innate in the individual, by Albrecht Ritschl,? whose recasting of the whole dogmatic system of Christianity presents the latest and the clearest illustration 1 pp. 497-500. 2 Der christliche Glaube*, §§ 66-67 (Berlin, 1842, pp. 361-436). 3 Rechtfertigung und Verséhnung?, iii. 5 (Bonn, 1883, pp. 304-357). DECLINE OF AUGUSTINIANISM 439 of the mutual co-inherence and interdependence of the Pelagian doctrine of man, the Adoptionist or Antiochene doctrines of Christ, and the merely ‘ exemplarist ’ doctrine of redemption. The circumstances, however, under which we are gathered together demand that a few concluding words should be devoted to a particular version of the Western Fall-doctrine which has hardly been mentioned hitherto, namely, the doctrine of the Church of England. This is contained in the IXth Article of Religion ‘ Of Original, or Birth-Sin,’ in the Xth ‘ Of Free will, and in the XIIIth, ‘ Of works before justification.’ These were all included in the original 42 Articles drawn up in 1553 by Cranmer at the instigation of the Council of Edward VI, at a period when the influence of the Swiss Reformers was at its height. The Tridentine doctrines of Sin and Justification which have been considered in this lecture were promulgated in the year 1546. It follows that Cranmer and his collaborators must have been well acquainted with them, and that the ultra-Augustinian affirmations contained in the Articles were meant to be direct contradictions of the doctrine put forward at the Council of Trent. It is, therefore, not surprising that a superficial perusal of these formularies should seem to Justify the celebrated dictum of William Pitt, that the Church of England possessed a Popish liturgy and Calvinistic Articles. A closer study, however, will disclose the fact that whilst these Articles would seem to have been drafted in such a way as to be patient of a Calvinistic interpretation, they cannot be said of necessity to contain more than a fairly strong affirmation of those Augustinian conceptions with which our historical survey has made us familiar. So much is indeed certain. In Article IX we find at least one side of the characteristically Augustinian conception of original guilt, namely, the idea that we are in some inexplicable way responsible for being born with disordered natures ; and it is asserted that this hereditary corruption and fault of human nature, which ex hypothesi we cannot help, as found in every person born into this world deserves God’s ‘ wrath and 1 Cf. Lecture V, p. 349 f. 440 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN damnation.’1 There can be little doubt that in the original intention of the compilers these tremendous words carried with them the terrible consequences of the necessary damna- tion of the heathen and of unbaptised infants? ; and the gloss with which Dean Church attempts to soften their formidable import—a gloss which in effect amounts to this, that original sin itself may be said in the abstract to deserve God’s wrath and damnation, but that its individual posses- sors do not necessarily deserve anything but His compassion 3 —whilst no doubt practically convenient, as making it easier for men of the twentieth century to consent to a formulary drawn up in the sixteenth, seems to be rather an evacuation than an explanation of the ‘ literal and grammatical’ sense of the Article. The same Article contains the statement (attributed to ‘the Apostle’) that concupiscence and lust hath of itself the nature of sin ; which, if it means anything at all, would seem to be a re-affirmation of the Augustinian doctrine of the intrinsical sinfulness of one of the elementary 1 Cf. the formula prescribed in the Book of Common Prayer for the reception of a privately baptised child into the congregation (‘ The Ministra- tion of Private Baptism of Children in Houses’), in which the infant is described as ‘ born in original sin, and in the wrath of God.’ 2 It may be noted, however, that Hooker (Eccl. Pol. V. 1x. 6) is inclined to think that the unbaptised children of Christian parents may possibly be saved. 8 The reference is to a letter, in Life and Letters, p. 248: ‘ The fact of what is meant by original sin is as mysterious and inexplicable as the origin of evil, but it is obviously just as mucha fact. There is a fault and vice in the vace, which, given time, as surely develops into actual sin as our physical constitution, given at birth, does into sickness and physical death. It is of this inherited sin in our nature, looked upon in the abstract and without reference to concrete cases, that I suppose the Article speaks. How can we suppose that such a nature looks in God’s eyes according to the standard of perfect righteousness which we also suppose to be God’s standard and law? Does it satisfy that standard ? Can He look with neutrality on its divergence from His perfect standard ? What is His moral judgment of it as a subject for moral judgment ? What He may do to cure it, to pardon it, to make allowances for it in known or unknown ways, is another matter, about which His known attributes of mercy alone may reassure us ; but the question is, How does He look on this fact of our nature in itself, that without exception it has this strong efficacious germ of evil within it, of which He sees all the possibilities and all the conse- quences ? Can He look on it, even in germ, with complacency or indiffer- ence? Must He not judge it and condemn it, as in itself, because evil, deserving condemnation? I cannot see what other answer can be given but one, and this is what the Article says.’ DECLINE OF AUGUSTINIANISM 441 instincts of mankind, though a loophole is left for those who cannot accept this Manichean opinion in its full rigour by the use of the ambiguous phrase ‘ the nature of sin,’ ratio peccati.1 Article XIII contains another, somewhat hesitating, re-affirmation of a position common to both St. Augustine and the Reformers, namely, that works done before justifica- tion, which ‘spring not of faith in Jesus Christ,’ are not pleasing to God and, in fact, ‘ have the nature of sin.’ There can be no doubt that this Article was meant to traverse the teaching of the Council of Trent that the virtuous actions of pagans are not sins; but on this point, at any rate, there are very few modern Christians who in their heart of hearts do not agree with Trent. We have already pointed out the intellectual and moral antinomies which these propositions, taken at their face value, necessarily involve. In an age, however, of passionate feeling and of unquestioning accept- ance of St. Augustine’s authority these difficulties were not likely to occur to anyone ; and circumstances with which we are all familiar have brought it about that these obsolete positions are still embedded in the doctrinal standards of the English Church. Nevertheless, even before the publication of Tract 90, with its exposition of a benignior interpretatio, which may be employed as a kind of intellectual shoe-horn for accommodating the stiff formularies of the past to the living religious experience of the present, protests had been raised both in the seventeenth and in the eighteenth centuries against the severity of these doctrines. The idea of original guilt, which, as we have suggested, is both the most charac- teristic and the least defensible element in the whole Augustinian scheme, involving as it does the assertion that a newly born infant deserves eternal damnation on the mere ground of the fact that it is a human being, was manfully combated by the illustrious Jeremy Taylor; a single quota- tion will make his position clear : And truly, My Lord, to say that for Adam’s sin it is just in God to condemn infants to the eternal flames of Hell, and to say that concupiscence or natural inclinations before they pass into 1 The Augustinian view of sex finds a striking expression in the opening exhortation of the Marriage Service, as contained in the Prayer Book of 1662. 442 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN any act would bring eternal damnation from God’s presence into the eternal portion of devils, are two such horrid propositions that if any Church in the world should expressly affirm them, I, for my part, should think it unlawful to communicate with her in the defence or provision of either, and to think it would be the greatest temptation in the world to make men not to love God, of Whom men so easily speak such horrid things. Considerations of this nature prompted the application addressed by Dr. Porteus, subsequently Bishop of London, together with several other distinguished divines, in the year 1772 to Archbishop Cornwallis, asking him to consult with the episcopate whether a revision of the Articles could not be carried out, with the object of eliminating what appeared prima facie to be their more Calvinistic features. The Archbishop replied that he and his brethren, having considered the matter, were unanimously of the opinion that nothing could be done—a conclusion which was dictated in all probability rather by practical caution than by theological conviction. The relaxation, however, of the terms of clerical subscription to the Articles, which was effected by the combined authority of Convocation and Parliament in the year 1865, has had what is in practice the same effect as a revision of their text, and it is safe to say that no minister of the national Church at the present day conceives himself as being committed to the statements that newly born infants deserve damnation, that those impulses which subserve the perpetuation of the race are inherently sinful, and that the virtuous acts of non-Christians are all crimes. Nevertheless, although practical difficulties in connexion with subscription have solved themselves, it is not a good thing that any branch of the Universal Church should continue to be cumbered with obsolete formularies inherited from the past which are in practice repudiated by the thought and conscience of the present ; and it may, therefore, not be presumptuous to suggest that it would be well if the 1 Works (London, 1822), ix. p. 373. From ‘ An Answer to a letter written by the Rt. Rev. the Lord Bishop of Rochester, concerning the chapter of Original Sin in the ‘“‘ Unum Necessarium.’”’’ Taylor’s own views about original sin, which approximate to the Scotist position, are developed in the Unum Necessarium, or The Doctrine and Practice of Repentance, cc. vi. vil. (Works, ix.). DECLINE OF AUGUSTINIANISM 443 Doctrinal Commission, which has been entrusted by the two Primates of England with the task of endeavouring to secure a greater unity of fundamental belief amongst members of the Church of England, would turn its attention to this particular area of Christian doctrine, and endeavour to arrive at formulations which might ultimately be substituted for the crude assertions which have come down to us out of the passions and conflicts of the sixteenth century. Revision of the Liturgy, as Porteus saw a century and a half ago, must involve as its logical corollary revision of the Articles, and in some ways the latter is the more important task of the two. If and when it is undertaken by ecclesiastical authority, it must surely include the task of presenting Christendom with a carefully balanced statement of Christian anthropology which does not go beyond the positive contents of Revelation and is free from all contradiction with the teachings of modern science and the deliveries of a tolerant and enlightened conscience. By her unique position in Christen- dom, seated as she is in the West, and heiress to the treasures of both Latin and Teutonic thought, yet united by ever- growing bonds of sympathy and mutual knowledge with the Christian and Hellenic East, by her splendid intellectual tradition, which combines unswerving loyalty to the historic revelation of God in Christ with the most tremulous sensitiveness to new light, through whatever windows it may pour in—the English Church possesses both the power and the opportunity to wrestle with this ancient problem anew, and to win one of those triumphs in the world of thought which are only less glorious than her invisible achievements in the sphere of grace. ADDITIONAL NOTE C CONGREGATIONAL CONFESSIONS OF ORIGINAL SIN IN THE CHURCHES OF THE REFORMATION I. Origins. Strassburg, 1537 (F. Hubert, Die Strassburger liturgischen Ordnungen, im Zeitalter der Reformation, Gottingen, Ig00, p. 92): Almechtiger, ewiger got vnd vatter, wir bekennen 444 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN vnd veriehen, das wir leyder inn siinden empfangen vnd geporen seind wnd daher geneygt zu allem argen vnd treg Zuvaliem Suten.. 4. Calvin, La maniére de faive priéres, 1542 (Alfred Erichson, Die Calvinische und die altstrassburgische Gottesdienstordnung, Strassburg, 1894, p. 16): Seigneur dieu pere eternel et toutpuissant nous confessons sans feintise deuent ta saincte majesté, que nous sommes pouures pecheurs, conceuz et nez en iniquitez et corruption, enclins a mal faire, inutiles a tout Dich yen: II. Development. III. (x) Calvin, Precum ecclestasticarum formula (B. J. Kidd, Documents of Cont. Reform, p. 615): Domine Deus Pater aeterne et omnipotens, agnoscimus et ingenue profitemur apud sanctam majestatem tuam, nos miseros peccatores esse, conceptos, et natos in iniquitate et pravitate, ad nequitiam proclives, ad omne autem bonum opus inutiles ... (2) Valerand Pullain, Liturgia sacra seu Ritus Ministerw an ecclesia peregrinorum Francofordiae ad Moenum (A. L. Richter, Die evangelische Kirchenordnungen des 16. Jahrhun- derts, 1. p. 150) : Domine Deus Pater aeterne et omnipotens agnoscimus et fatemur ingenue apud sanctam majestatem tuam peccatores esse nos miseros, adeoque a prima origine, qua concepti et nati sumus, tam ad omne malum esse pronos quam ab omni bono alienos. .. . (3) Laski (Jo. a Lasco) Forma ac ratio tota Ecclesiastict Mimistertt, in peregrinorum, potissimum uero Germanorum, Ecclesia instituta London in Anglia, 1551, p. 66: Omni- potens aeterne Deus misericors Pater . . . Etenim praeter- quam quod in peccato concepti ac nati, omnis boni prorsus expertes, pleni omni iniquitate sumus. .. . In English Puritanism. (1) English exiles at Geneva (Calvin’s Common-Prayer Book, or the Service, Discipline and Form of the Common Prayers, & Adminstration of the Sacraments us’d in the English Church of Geneva, in The Phenix, Vol. i. p. 214), and J. Knox, Book of Common Order, 1564 (The Liturgy of the Ch. of Scotland, or John Knox’s Book of Common Order, London, 1840, p. 1): O Eternal God and most merciful Father, we confess and acknowledge here before thy divine Majesty, that we are miserable Sinners, conceiv’d and born in Sin & Iniquity, so that in us there is no Goodness ; for the Flesh evermore rebelleth against the Spirit, whereby we continually transgress thine holy Precepts and Command- ments, and so purchase to ourselves, through thy just Judgment, Death and Damnation. IV. DECLINE OF AUGUSTINIANISM 448 And Book of Common Order, p. 6. If thou shouldst begin to reckon with us even from our first conception in our mother’s womb, thou canst find nothing at all in us but occasion of death and eternal condemnation ; for truth it is that first we were conceived in sin, and in iniquity was every one of us born of our mother. . . (2) A booke of the forme of common prayer, 1584 (‘ The Puritan Liturgy ’; in P. Hall, Fragmenta liturgica, 1. p. 25): O eternal God, and most merciful Father, we confess and acknowledge here before thy divine majesty, that we are miserable sinners, conceived and born in sin and iniquity, so that in us there is no goodness. (3) Disciplina Ecclesiae sacra, c. 1588 (in F. Paget, Introd. to the Fifth Book of Hooker's Eccl. Pol., p. 301): sequatur precatio continens confessionem generalem reatus peccati originalis et actualis : et poenae ob utrumque ex lege debitae. (4) A Directory for the Publike VV orship of God T hrough- out the Three Kingdoms, London, 1644 (P. Hall, Rekquiae hiurgicae, iil. p. 25): the minister . . . is to endeavour to get his own and his hearers’ hearts to be rightly affected with their sins, that they may all mourn . . . by proceeding to a more full confession of sin... to this effect :—To acknowledge our great sinfulness: First, by reason of original sin ; which (beside the guilt that makes us liable to everlasting damnation) is the seed of all other sins, hath depraved and poisoned all the faculties of soul and body, doth defile our best actions, and (were it not restrained, or our hearts renewed by grace) would break forth into innumerable transgressions, and greatest rebellions against the Lord, that ever were committed by the vilest sons of men. (5) Exceptions of the Ministers, 1661 (Cardwell, Con- ferences, 309): The Confession is very defective, not clearly expressing original sin. (6) The Reformation of the Liturgy, 1661 (‘ The Savoy Liturgy,’ by Baxter; in P. Hall, Reliquiae liturgicae, iv. p- 15): .. . we confess that we are vile and miserable sinners, being conceived in sin; by nature children of wrath, and transgressors from the womb. (7) Evyodoywov: a Book of Common Order (Scottish Church Service Soc.), 1877, p. 48: O Lord our God, eternal andj almighty Father, we acknowledge and confess before thy holy majesty, that we are miserable sinners; born in iniquity, prone to evil; unable by ourselves to do that which is good... . At Cologne. Hermann von Wied of Cologne, fia ac simplex deliberatio, 1545 (the italicised words are added in the Latin to the 446 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN German of 1543), p. xciv: Omnipotens aeterne Deus, Pater Domini nostvt Iesu. Christt, Creator rerum omnium, tudex cunctorum hominum, agnoscimus et deploramus nos in peccatis conceptos et natos ideoque ad quaevis mala pronos et abhorrentes a wevis bonis. . . . V. In Sweden. E. Yelverton, The Mass in Sweden (Henry Bradshaw Soc., 1920). 1531: Mass of Olarus Petri, p. 33: I, poor sinful man, who am both conceived and born in sin, and ever afterwards. ... 1576: Mass of John III, p. 85: Confiteor tibi Deo Patri omnipotenti, me miserum peccatorem in peccatis conceptum et natum nimis peccasse in vita mea... 1602: Communion Office of Charles IX, p. 131, as 1531 above. 1917: Modern Mass, p. 157: I, poor sinful man, who was born in sin, and ever afterwards &c. VII. ‘ORIGINAL SIN’ RE-INTERPRETED To consider the world in its length and breadth, its various history, the many races of men, their starts, their fortunes, their mutual alienation, their conflicts; their ways, habits, governments, forms of worship; their enterprises, their aimless courses, their random achievements and acquirements . . . the greatness and littleness of man, his far-reaching aims, his short duration, the curtain hung over his futurity, the disappointments of life, the defeat of good, the success of evil, physical pain, mental anguish, the prevalence and intensity of sin, the pervading idolatries, the corruptions, the dreary hopeless irreligion, that condition of the whole race, so fearfully yet exactly described in the Apostle’s words, ‘ having no hope and without God in the world ’—all this is a vision to dizzy and appal; and inflicts upon the mind the sense of a profound mystery, which is absolutely beyond human solution. What shall be said to this heart-piercing, reason-bewildering fact? I can only answer, that either there is no Creator, or this living society of men is in a true sense discarded from His presence ...I argue about the world; 7zf there be a God, since there is a God, the human race is implicated in some terrible aboriginal calamity. It is out of joint with the purposes of its Creator. Thisisa fact, a fact as true as the fact of its existence ; and thus the doctrine of what is technically called original sin becomes to me almost as certain as that the world exists, and as the existence of God. JoHN HENRY NEwMAN: Apologia pro Vita Sua, c. V. LECIURE VIL: “ORIGINAL SIN’ RE-INTERPRETED Matt. xiii. 52: ‘ Therefore every scribe who hath been made a disciple to the kingdom of heaven is like unto a man that isa householder, which bringeth forth out of his treasure things new and old.’ IT is natural for the traveller who has slowly climbed a long and precipitous ascent, to pause on reaching the mountain crest, and look back upon the road by which he has come; and it is no less appropriate that, at the end of our historical survey, which has led us through twenty-five centuries of Jewish and Christian history, we should sum up in retrospect the results which our enquiry has yielded, before pushing on into the almost untrodden region of abstract speculation and construction. We have seen that the doctrines of the Fall and of Original Sin were born in the minds of the Maccabean saints as the fruit of the experi- ence of penitence, and that they were designed to safeguard this experience against interpretations which were ultimately destructive of ethical monotheism, especially against the Iranian explanation of evil as the work of a second and malevolent God, and the Hindu theory of evil as a necessary moment in the finite self-expression of an impersonal and non-moral Absolute. Thus a vague and wavering con- ception of a primitive moral catastrophe and of a train of disastrous hereditary consequences flowing from it slowly arose in later Judaism, clothed itself with the Paradise- story of Gen. ill. as its supposedly historical integument, passed on into Christianity with, it would seem, the tacit permission of the Master Himself, and was stereotyped by St. Paul as the official Christian explanation of the origin of evil in Nature and in man. The impact of successive waves of Oriental dualism stimulated the Christian Church 2G 450 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN to clarify and articulate the ideas which it had adopted as the presuppositions of its redemptive scheme. But, as this development advanced, two distinct versions of the Fall- doctrine began to define themselves, corresponding to the two differing emotional forms which penitence assumes in the experience of the ‘ once-born’ and ‘ twice-born’ types of religious man. The former of these versions wears a milder character, appropriate to the sunny genius of Christian Hellenism, recognising as it does the good that survives even in fallen man; the latter, elaborated into rigid severity by the fanaticism of Northern Africa, and condemning human nature as largely or entirely depraved, was riveted on Western Christendom by the genius of St. Augustine, exaggerated into fantastic and repulsive forms by Luther and Calvin, and until recently was generally believed by Englishmen to be the only traditional Fall- theory. But the Augustinian theory never took captive the mind of the Christian East, and even in the West its millennial domination has now passed away. The right of the highly specialised ‘twice-born’ dévot to force his despairing estimate of human nature upon the sober majority of ‘once-born’ Christians is now universally denied; and the primitive, Hellenic, ‘ once-born’ version of the Fall-doctrine now stands clearly revealed as the basic or residual Christian belief, the only scheme of ideas regarding human nature and sin which commits its adher- _ ents to nothing that cannot truly claim to be Scriptural, Oecumenical, and accepted ‘ everywhere, always, and by all.’ We now turn, in conformity with the plan set forth at the beginning of this enquiry, to the constructive task of verifying and elucidating these ideas, and of correlating them, so far as is in our power, with the modern universe of philosophic thought. It has been frequently pointed out during the course of this discussion that the belief in the Fall as a historical event, though for long believed to rest upon the testimony of an inspired and inerrant record, is in reality an inference, a logical construction based upon the observed fact, or what was believed to be such, of ‘ original sin,’ together with the revealed fact of the infinite power and goodness of the Creator ; in the order of thought, ‘ORIGINAL SIN’ RE-INTERPRETED 451 therefore, as distinct from the order of time, original sin comes first, and the Fall last. It will conduce to lucidity if we follow the order of thought, devoting the present discourse to a consideration of the validity of the idea of original sin as a psychological hypothesis, reserving the idea of the Fall, with its deeper theological and metaphysical implications, for our final lecture. There is, however, one task which must necessarily be dealt with at the outset, if the argument of our two con- cluding lectures is to be presented with the highest degree of perspicuity ; and that is the task of formulating, with greater precision than has been possible hitherto, the traditional theory which is now to be put to the test. Before we can verify in the facts of human psychology that which on the basis of the Vincentian Canon we have found to be the most truly ‘ catholic’ or universal doctrine of human nature, it will be necessary first of all to state it in extenso, as a single coherent theory, collecting together into an ordered whole various fragments and aspects of it which have from time to time emerged in the course of our historical review. As this minimising, ‘ once-born’ Fall- doctrine has never been officially formulated, but merely exists, as it were, in solution, or like radium, diffused as a common element through a heterogeneous series of chemical compounds, but nowhere discoverable in isolation, it will be understood that this formulation does not lay claim to more than approximate accuracy. We must, therefore, occasionally assume the liberty to supply a few minor links or logical connexions which the structure of the theory seems to demand, but for which no specific patristic or con- ciliar texts can be quoted. In the light of what has been already said with regard to the real basis of the Fall-doctrine in spiritual experience, and its relatively accidental con- nexion with the Paradise story of Gen. ili., we shall confine ourselves to a formulation of the intellectual essence of these ideas, carefully avoiding the use of pictorial terminology drawn from the Adam-story, so as to avoid exposing our- selves to the suspicion of substituting legend for logic. It will be convenient to include in this summary a statement of the doctrine of the Fall, that is of the origin of human 452 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN evil, which, as already explained, is reserved for exhaustive consideration in our final lecture, as well as the statement of that with which we are immediately concerned in this lecture, namely, the doctrine of original sin, so that we may have before our minds a synoptic view of the whole intel- lectual fabric constituted by these ideas. The full signifi- cance borne by the substitution of the milder for the more gloomy version of Christian anthropology will be brought out with greater clearness, if in the course of this formulation we indicate once more the chief Augustinian or ‘ twice- born’ positions which, if our argument so far has been well founded, must now be decisively repudiated, both on the ground of their lack of genuinely universal acceptance, and also on that of their incompatibility with the facts of modern historical knowledge and with a real belief in the infinite goodness and justice of God. This basic essence of Fall-doctrine, which may be regarded as the highest common factor of the various competing versions of that doctrine which have from time to time been current within the orthodox Christian world, can be conveniently summarised in the form of seven distinct propositions, of which the first five taken together constitute the doctrine of the ‘ Fall,’ in the strict sense, and the remaining two that of ‘ original sin,’ so called. These propositions are the following : (1) God is infinite, not merely in power but in love and goodness, and therefore the world of created being as He made ut must have been purely good, including no element of evil at all. (We note in passing, though it is impossible now to go into the subject at length, that the idea of the Fall necessarily presupposes the idea of Creation, and would be quite incapable of harmonisation with any theory implying that the universe of finite being is an eternal or necessary mode of God’s self-expression. ) (2) The origin of evil ts therefore to be sought 1n the voluntary rebellion of created and finite wills, such rebellion—and here we touch upon a point of considerable importance—having taken place prior to the appearance of the human species on ths planet. In other words, the ultimate Fall, which is postulated in order to avoid an infinite regress, is conceived “ORIGINAL SIN’ RE-INTERPRETED 453 as being extra-terrestrial ; and this extra-terrestrial char- acter of the primal catastrophe may be imagined either in accordance with the view, hinted at by Origen, of an extra-temporal Fall of the race-soul from a transcendental Paradise, or in accordance with the more popular theory of a ‘fall of the angels,—not that which has hitherto claimed our attention, the descent of the lustful ‘ Watchers ’ to earth, as narrated in Gen. vi., but a much more ancient, pre-human revolt of spiritual beings against their Almighty Lord, such as was imagined at the beginning of our era by the author of the Slavonic Enoch,? was read by Christian imagination into the Apocalyptic vision of the celestial conflict between Michael and the dragon,? and is familiar to English readers in the magnificent Homeric vesture which the genius of Milton has imposed upon it.* (3) Man, at his first appearance on this planet, was im moral and intellectual stature a babe, created frail, imperfect, ignorant and non-moral, but endowed with self-consciousness and the power of self-determination, which constituted, in the penetrating and memorable words of Theophilus, an adoppr mpokomys, a starting-point for progress and upward evolution. Here, for the first time, the theory decisively joins issue with Augustinianism. It involves the complete abandon- ment of the belief in the view technically known as the “original righteousness’ or ‘ perfection’ of the first men. The Talmudic theory of the “ protoplast,’ as endowed with Olympian strength and beauty, with all the gifts of philoso- phical subtlety and scientific and theological erudition, and with a character of settled virtue and sanctity—a theory which does not possess the slightest foundation in Scripture —is frankly relegated to the limbo of discarded fables. We cannot stay to enlarge upon this point; but it is permissible to point out how enormously the repudiation of ‘ original righteousness’ as an alleged phase of human history ° eases the strain of the prima facie discordance A mtv. supra, Lecture IV, ps 225. 2 v. supra, Lecture III, p. 161. Pekev: xii: 7, 8. 4 Paradise Lost, v., Vi. 5 For a discussion of the question whether the conception of ‘ original righteousness’ might not be re-used in an extra- or pre-human connexion, see the next Lecture, p. 526. 454 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN between traditional theology and modern science as to the origins and primal condition of man. With an avowed return on the part of theology to such a picture of primitive man as was sketched by Irenaeus,! the conflict between the Fall-doctrine and the evolutionary view of human history would largely disappear, and the atheist lecturer of Hyde Park would find one of his favourite dialectical weapons smitten from his hand. (4) The growth of man’s moral ideas brought in its train some action, or system of actions, whereby man aligned himself with the rebellious power, showed that he had partially thrown in his lot with the forces of evil which were already at work in the universe, and entered on a path largely divergent from that upward career of spiritual evolution which God had meant him to follow. Here again we note a significant divergence from the Augustinian and traditional Western view. Augustinianism, positing the doctrine of ‘ original righteousness,’ assumes that man was placed at his creation on the summit of the mountain of perfection, and that the first sin was tantamount to an instantaneous, headlong “ Fall,’ over a sheer precipice, into the abyss of sin and damnation. The view, however, which we are now endeavouring to articulate, represents primitive man as born at the bottom of the mountain, as refusing to follow that path which led most directly to its summit, and as preferring to follow a tortuous route of his own devising, which, whilst leading generally upwards, has plunged him into many bogs and crevasses, and involved him in many unnecessary hardships and miseries. A fully developed systematic theology might continue the metaphor by pointing out that the road of man’s own choice has, so far, not led him much higher than the foothills or lower slopes of the peak which he would fain ascend, that a Guide has come to meet him and restore his footsteps to the right track, but that the only short cut from the lower to the higher path must of necessity now lead through ‘ the grave, and gate of death,’ on the further side of which alone complete perfection is to be attained. Such a theory does not deny that the record of human 1 uv. supra, Lecture IV, p. 193 f. ‘ORIGINAL SIN’ RE-INTERPRETED 455 history has, on the whole, been that of a slow millennial ascent from low and brutish beginnings to our present state ; its upholders are only committed to the proposition that the direction of this progress has not been so direct and unswerving as it might have been, and was meant by God to be—that the graph of man’s moral and intellectual development, slowly climbing through half a million years at an almost imperceptible angle to the horizontal, with sierra-like undulations of advance and set-back, like those which mark the temperature chart of a feverish patient, stands in the strongest possible contrast to the steep, upward-rushing line of intellectual, spiritual, and moral growth which represented God’s original design for His creature. Given this point of view, it would seem very | desirable that the word ‘ Fall,’ which occurs nowhere in the — Bible, which does not appear to be older than Hippolytus | or Methodius,! and which is almost inextricably bound up— in the popular mind with the idea of ‘ original perfection,’ should be used as little as possible in connexion with the sin of man. (In our next lecture? we shall consider the question whether it is possible to believe in anything corresponding to the supposed pre-human rebellion of the angels, an event to which the term ‘ Fall’ would be more appropriately applied.) When man alone is in question it would seem more appropriate to employ the term which we have seen to be both historically and logically associated with the primitive or ‘ once-born’ theory, that is, ‘ trans- gression’ (zapdBaois, praevaricatio), in the sense of a ‘stepping-aside’ from the straight or proper path. The hypothetical ‘ first human sin,’ or the first human action which we should have been justified in classing as ‘ sin,’ had we been able to observe the history of our remotest ancestors,? | should thus be regarded not so much as a‘ Fall,’ but rather | as a failure to climb—to be exact, a failure to climb as directly and perpendicularly as God had desired. In any case, however, and whatever may be thought with 1 y, supra, Lecture IV, p. 252, n. 4. aA 52 7 3’ On the question whether it is possible to assume a historical event which could be absolutely described as‘ the first human sin,’ v. infra, p. 514 f- 456 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN regard to the question of terminology, it is clear that this mode of conceiving the first human sin entirely rules out Augustine’s contention that it was characterised by infinite malice and a correspondingly infinite guilt. We shall agree with Irenaeus that the primal sin of man was in a sense pardonable ! ; and it is a possible speculation that, as being the sin of a frail, imperfect, and ignorant creature, so far from being the greatest, it was really the least of the crimes which have stained the history of human kind. (5) Ever since this first human transgression, our nature has displayed an inherent moral weakness or bias towards sin. This proposition is modelled on a phrase in which Justin Martyr formulates his primitive and undeveloped conception of the Fall-theory.2 It will be noted that it abstains from asserting that the first human transgression was the direct cause of the innate bias towards evil which _ has revealed itself since, and leaves open the possibility that the Jewish Rabbis may have been right when they said that Adam sinned because the ‘ evil inclination’ was jalready rooted in him.? It is true that this modified and ‘cautious assertion does not solve the question how the evil which was already at work in the universe managed to find, or to retain, a foothold in human nature: but it does not raise a difficulty which is inherent in the Augustinian theory and even in the language of St. Paul, if rigidly interpreted—the difficulty, namely, of understanding how a single wrong act could have such illimitably ruinous results, especially if, as we have just suggested, it was of a comparatively venial nature. It is true that under the complicated conditions of our modern world a single false step may wreck a whole life; but that is largely due to the clumsiness and inhumanity of our present social conventions ; and even they do not involve the penalisation of the sinner’s unoffending posterity until the end of time. We shall find in our concluding lecture that we are relieved of many other difficulties by the liberty, which the primitive doctrine 1 uv. supra, Lecture IV, p. 195. 2 dial. c. Tryph. 88... tod yévous rob tdév avOpdmwv, 6 amd Tod "Adap b76 Odvatov Kai mAdynv Thy Tod Odews EmemTwKeLr: the whole passage is quoted above, Lecture IV, p. 174, n. I. * Lecture II, p. 70. ‘ORIGINAL SIN’ RE-INTERPRETED 457 allows us, to regard the sin of the protoplast as being not a Fall but a failure—not a wanton plunge into crime but rather a wilful neglect to emancipate himself from tendencies already existing in him, which he both could and should have overcome. For the sake of clearness it may again be observed that the five propositions just formulated are concerned with the idea of the Fall or ultimate origin of evil,.and have therefore received only cursory comment. We now approach the last two of our seven theses, which, taken together, embody the primitive, Hellenic, or ‘ once-born’ version of the idea of ‘Original Sin,’ and therefore claim a more detailed and exhaustive examination. The sixth proposition may be formulated as follows: This innate bias or tendency towards evil is the effect and symptom of ‘ weakness of will,’ or defective control of the lower emotional and instinctive nature by the higher self. The question of the exact nature of the inherited infirmity is one in regard to which the area of agreement between the thought of Eastern and Western Christendom is exiguous and ill-defined. Of one thing we can be certain: historical Christianity as such is not committed to the assertion that | X “ original sin,’ so called, is sin in the strict sense of the term. ' The word sin either means a conscious act carried out with full purpose and deliberation in defiance of a known law of God, or it means nothing at all. It is therefore, strictly speaking, a solecism to apply this term to a pre-determined state, independent of conscious volition, which is alleged to belong to unconscious infants. We must, accordingly, admit that the term ‘ original sin,’ eccatum originale, which (like the term ‘ Fall’) has no Scriptural authority, which we have seen to be the legacy of Augustine’s semi-Manichean view of human nature, and which is inextricably bound up in the popular mind—as, indeed, it was meant to be—with the idea of ‘ original guilt,’ is a singularly unfortunate and misleading expression. It should be beneath the dignity of theology to use a term of which the prima facie meaning has to be elaborately explained away on every occasion of its use; if our religion is to regain its ancient power in an age which demands remorseless clarity of thought and 458 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN fearless sincerity of expression, it cannot afford to disregard a maxim dictated by common sense, namely, that if a term cannot be used in a given connexion without a non-natural interpretation, it had better not be used in that connexion at all. I propose, therefore, during the remainder of these lectures, to substitute for the word ‘sin,’ in speaking of the hypothetical flaw in human nature, the word ‘ infirmity,’ which avoids the implication irresistibly conveyed, and meant to be conveyed, by the Augustinian phrase, namely, that we are morally culpable in the sight of God for possessing natures which we had no share in choosing and which we cannot help possessing. It is hardly necessary to point out that, with the term ‘ original sin,’ we discard all those Augustinian and Western theories which have historically been bound up with it—the idea that physical appetites, especially the sexual appetite, are inherently sinful, that we are morally guilty because we were born without the imaginary splendid endowments enjoyed by the first man in Paradise, that we were physically parts of Adam at the moment when he ate the forbidden fruit and are therefore justly deemed to have eaten it ourselves. To this list of obsolete words and conceptions may be added the time- honoured but ambiguous term ‘ concupiscence,’ which for seventeen centuries has wavered, with more than Protean elusiveness, between the meanings of ‘ physical appetite in general,’ “inordinate physical appetite,’ and ‘lust,’ and through the interminable confusion thereby engendered, has amply earned the sentence of perpetual banishment from the realms of exact theology. If our argument so far is well founded, we may claim that this particular area of the ground—the question of the exact nature and seat of the inbred tendency to sin—has thus been cleared of a great quantity of obsolete intellectual structures, and now presents a fair open site for the erection of a more solid and permanent fabric, composed of the materials supplied by the universal Christian tradition and cemented together by the best modern thought. But the question has not yet been answered, What are those materials ? in other words, What is the psychological account given of the ‘ inherent flaw ’ by the basic and truly ‘ORIGINAL SIN’ RE-INTERPRETED 459 ‘Catholic’ tradition, as distinct from, though doubtless underlying, the specifically Latin and Western view of “hereditary sin’? If we examine those Greek theologians of the early centuries, in whose writings, as we have already seen, the essential Christian doctrine of human nature and sin appears in its purest and most unadulterated form, we find no unanimous, clear-cut answer to this question. Tatian+ and Theophilus? regard the inborn defect as consisting in the loss of the special assistance of the Holy Spirit, assumed to have been enjoyed in full measure by unfallen man; Origen, in his Caesarean period, reverts for a time to the barbarous conception of bad mana, supposed to be inherent in the processes of generation and child- birth ?; Athanasius takes refuge in the Platonic identifica- tion of Being and the Good, and explains the bias towards evil as a tendency inherent in the soul to disintegrate and relapse into non-being *; Gregory of Nyssa, in a well-known passage of the Catechetical Oration, describes the condition of unregenerate man as ‘ weakness,’ ‘ a state of prostration,’ ‘failure to attain to life,’ ‘lack of participation in the Good,’ ‘ imprisonment in darkness.’ ® But no single psycho- logical conception can be extracted from these heterogeneous statements ; and in general it must be observed that the Greek Fathers prefer to employ, in describing that unre- generate condition of human nature which is the necessary presupposition of any theory of Redemption, the somewhat different, if not alternative, idea of servitude to a personal devil, which both afforded greater scope for glowing rhetoric and also cohered with the then popular view of the Atone- ment as the temporary payment of Christ’s life to Satan in ransom for captive humanity. To ascertain, therefore, what is the common underlying element which is the basis, of all views of the ‘ inherent infirmity ’"—to fix that highest common factor of all the competing theories as to the nature of the moral flaw, which alone can claim acceptance ubique, semper, et ab omnibus—we must recur to the teaching of the great Apostle who laid the foundations of Christian Heecture LV, p.175. 2 ibid. p. 176. 8 ibid. p. 224. 4 ibid. p. 260. 5 or. cat. 15 (Sr. p. 63). ¢ Lecture IV, p. 292 f. 460 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN anthropology, whose authority was unquestioningly claimed by all those representatives of Christian thought who have handled the subject, from Justin Martyr down to Baius and Quesnel. St. Paul’s doctrine was examined at length in our third lecture, and may therefore be summarised here in a single sentence: the ‘inherent infirmity’ of human nature consists in the discord between ‘ flesh’ and ‘ spirit ’ which may be described in modern terms as ‘ weakness of will-power,’ defective control over the emotional impulses, or imperfect power of inhibiting the spontaneous flow of psychic energy along the channels of the primary instincts. We shall consider presently how far this conception is ultimately intelligible and true; for the moment, it is sufficient to insist that the only ‘ Catholic’ conception of that inherent infirmity which has been misnamed ‘ original sin ’—the only common element and foundation underlying the various systems which we have reviewed—is simply identical with the Pauline conception: and St. Paul’s conception can be crystallised in the phrase ‘ inherent _ weakness of will.’ On this point, the result of our long historical research has been to show us that tradition and dogmatic development, broadly interpreted, have added absolutely nothing to the language of Scripture, despite the well-nigh nineteen centuries which have elapsed since the Epistles to the Galatians and Romans were first written. The seventh and last proposition may be formulated as follows: This quality of ‘ weakness of will,’ or defective control of appetites, inheres in the human stock as a hereditary char- acter transmitted from parent to offspring through biological and not merely through what ts called social heredity, so that its elimination from human nature is outside the power of man’s unaided efforts. If man’s will is hereditarily weak it must be supposed to be too weak to will effectually the abolition of this weakness. Man can no more raise himself morally without the help of external assistance, technically known as ‘ grace,’ than he can lift himself physically without some external fulcrum or point of support. Yet this does not mean that the human will is non-existent, or completely paralysed ; the general, diffused mind of Christendom on this point would seem to have been well summed up in the Se ee a. “ORIGINAL SIN’ RE-INTERPRETED 463 Tridentine assertion that “ free-will, although weakened and ,/ attenuated, is by no means extinguished ’ by the Fall. It is doubtless not necessary to adduce detailed evidence in order to show that historical Christianity has, rightly or wrongly, committed itself to the hypothesis of biological as contrasted with merely social heredity, as the means whereby the ‘inherent infirmity ’ is transmitted from generation to generation; the general condemnation of the views of Caelestius pronounced by the third Oecumenical Council amounts at least to the affirmation of physiological heredity in some sense, and to some extent, even though, as we have seen, it cannot be interpreted as a positive approbation of the whole Augustinian scheme.? As formulated in this way the doctrine of ‘ inherited / infirmity ’ would seem to be a merciful, rather than a rigor- istic conception ; as compared with the unlimited indeter- minism of Pelagius it makes a deliberate allowance for! human frailty and to a certain extent diminishes, though it/ does not abolish, man’s responsibility for actual sin.? It affirms, indeed, that man is accountable for wilful sin, in other words, that he deserves censure or punishment, but it couples this with the assertion that he does not deserve quite as much censure or punishment as he would have deserved had he not been handicapped by this inherent weakness of the higher self. The idea of man’s inherited frailty does not, indeed, amount to the assertion that from God’s point of - 1 decret. de tustif., cap. I (quoted p. 540). 2 Lecture V, p. 387. 3’ The fact that the doctrine of ‘ original sin’ (in the sense of ‘ original infirmity,’ and apart from the idea of ‘ original guilt ’) is a merciful doctrine, which tends to extenuate rather than to exaggerate man’s responsibility for actual sin, may be illustrated by a dictum of Molinos: ‘ When thou fallest into a fault, do not trouble or afflict thyself for it. Faults are effects of our frail nature, stained by original sin. Would not he be a fool who during a tournament, if he had a fall, should lie weeping on the ground and afflict himself with discourses upon his misadventure ?’ (quoted by W. R. Inge, The Philosophy of Plotinus, ii. p. 151). It is Pelagianism which by its theory of unlimited indeterminism exaggerates the malice of actual sin to an intolerable degree (see Lecture V, p. 357). The con- ventional criticisms directed against Pelagianism on the ground that it “ minimises the sense of sin’ are totally wide of the mark, if ‘ sin’ be given its normal and natural meaning of ‘ actual sin’ ; on the contrary, it is the idea of the ‘ inherited infirmity ’ which (as I should contend, healthfully) minimises a ‘ sense of sin’ which might otherwise become morbid. 462 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN view tout savoir, c’ est tout pardonner, but it does carry with it ‘the implication that tout savoir, c’est beaucoup pardonner. It steers a middle course between the extreme positions of Augustine and Pelagius, asserting against the former that the occurrence of sin is not inevitable, and against the latter that it is in every age, and under every combination of circumstances, highly probable. It will be well to complete this sketch of the universal basic essence of the Christian Fall doctrine, as extracted by our historical method from the materials provided by Scripture and tradition, by indicating two consequences which seem to follow irresistibly from it. The first is this: that with the disuse of the phrase ‘ original sin ’ as describing the inherited infirmity of man’s nature it is desirable also to discard all phrases which imply that this involuntary weakness, which is ex hypothesi simply given in the conditions of human birth and existence and for the possession of which the individual cannot reasonably be held responsible, is in itself, and quite apart from any actual ~~sins to which it may lead, the object of the Divine ‘ wrath.’ The conception of God as regarding the newly born but still unbaptised infant with ‘ wrath,’ that is, presumably, with anger and hostility, is indissolubly bound up with those Augustinian conceptions of seminal identity and original guilt which we have already seen reason to reject ; and it is well known that the phrase of Eph. ii. 3, ‘ children of wrath,’ merely means persons guilty of actual sin.t It is doubtless true that all attributions by theologians of human emotions to the Divine Being represent the language of conscious anthropomorphic metaphor ; and that they are nothing but symbols, imperfectly describing the permanent attitude of God, which is implied in His character, towards the various actions or states of His creatures ; and it cannot be doubted that the present condition of human nature, contrary as it is to His holy will, must, if we are to use this human and almost materialistic language at all, provoke in the Divine nature a reaction which can only be described as one of abstract disapproval. But such an attitude falls far short of anything that could be appropriately described by the 2 Lecture 41) ports, tee ‘ORIGINAL SIN’ RE-INTERPRETED 463 metaphor of ‘ wrath.’ It would seem truer to say that God regards the nature of the newly born infant, containing, as on this hypothesis it does contain, the seeds of moral failure and possibly of tragedy, with sorrow and compassion, not with resentment or vengeful indignation: these are terms which should be kept to express His attitude towards wilful transgression, towards ‘ sinning with a high hand,’ towards the conscious adoption of the maxim of Milton’s Satan, ‘Evil, be thou my good.’ In this matter we shall be con- tent, if we decide that the whole theory is well founded, to follow the customary language of the Greek Fathers, and speak not so much of the ‘ wrath’ of God as provoked by human nature, prior to human actions, but rather of His plilanthropia, the loving-kindness which impelled Him to send His Son to seek the sheep that was lost and by ‘a higher gift than grace ’ to restore the disordered faculties of human nature to that harmony, health, and peace which in the beginning He meant them to possess. The second of the corollaries to the Fall-doctrine, as just restated, is concerned with the eschatological problem first raised by the two Cappadocian Gregories,? and forced into prominence by the Pelagians, namely, the question ‘ What becomes in the next world of those who die in original sin ’ —or, aS we prefer to phrase it, ‘ subject to the inherited infirmity ’“—‘ without having committed actual sin?’ It is unnecessary to say that the view which we have sketched provides no justification whatever for Augustine’s condem- nation of all such persons to eternal flames. If I may in passing express a personal view on a mysterious and terrible subject, which it is impossible here to examine at length, I would suggest that the total elimination of the idea of hell from our religion must eviscerate and emasculate it, and annul much of its power to chain the tornadoes of human passion. But the only conception of hell which is morally or intellectually tolerable is one which regards it as the sinner’s own free choice, as the freely willed culmination of a deliberate course of self-degradation and of conscious rejec- 1 Paradise Lost, iv. 110. 2 v. supra, Lecture IV, pp. 279, 290. 3 Lecture V, p. 346. 464 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN tion of God and goodness.1 As for the destiny of those, whether infants or adults of infantile mind, who pass into the next world, never having rejected God because they have never known Him, nothing has been revealed, and we must be careful not to be wise above that which is written. But, if it is permissible to give the rein to speculation at all, there is, I would suggest, much to be said for the conception of Limbo, which, according to the merciful Scotist interpreta- tion, is a state of natural beatitude, representing the utmost perfection of which its tenants are capable; these tenants, unbaptised infants, virtuous pagans, and the like, are conceived as feeling no regret for their lack of the Beatific Vision of God, either because they know themselves to be incompetent to enjoy it, or because they are ignorant that it is possible.2 Some such hypothesis as this, enlarged in a manner consonant with the generous tendencies of modern Christian thought in regard to the future destiny of non- Christians, might form a theoretical justification for the Church’s practical insistence upon the all-importance of the evangelisation of the heathen, and upon the urgency of bringing infants to baptism as soon as possible after their birth.? If there are many mansions in the house of God, it would seem not improbable that the forms of life and con- sciousness which inhabit them may display a variety as 1 For an eloquent exposition of the idea of hell on these lines, see F. von Higel, Essays and Addresses on the Philosophy of Religion (1921), 7, “ What do we mean by heaven ? and what do we mean by hell ?’ 2 v. supra, Lecture VI, p. 415. The conception of Limbo has inspired a modern French lyric, Casimir Delavigne’s Les Limbes, in which, however, the negative aspect of this state—that is, deprivation of the Beatific Vision —is emphasised at the expense of its positive aspect, that of ‘ natural beatitude’: cf. this stanza : ‘ Loin de Dieu, 1a, sont renfermés Les milliers d’étres tant aimés, Qu’en ces bosquets inanimés La tombe envoie. Le calme d’un vague loisir, Sans regret comme sans désir, Sans peine comme sans plaisir, C’est 1a leur joie.’ Milton utilises Limbo as a convenient receptacle for ‘ embryos’ and ‘ idiots,’ friars, scapulars, rosaries, and papal bulls (Paradise Lost, iii. 445 ff.). 3 See Additional Notes D, ‘ Original sin, eschatology, and foreign missions,’ p. 486, and G, ‘ Infant Baptism,’ p. 550. ‘ORIGINAL SIN’ RE-INTERPRETED 465 inexhaustible and multitudinous as is provided by the spectacle of animate nature on this planet ; and the problem presented by the dwarf, the crétin, the imbecile, and other stunted or helpless types of human flotsam and jetsam, may be lightened if we allow ourselves to imagine that such beings are capable of a perfection of their own, and may grow into a mode of existence like that of the ethereal choir of child- spirits, the cloud of selige Knaben, whom Goethe has painted in the final scene of the second part of Faust, and on whose lips he has placed the blissful song : Sag’ uns, Vater, wo wir wallen, Sag’ uns, Guter, wer wir sind ; Gliicklich sind wir, allen, allen, Ist das Dasein so gelind ! 4 Time, however, does not permit us to pursue these fascinating speculations further, and we must return to the idea of ‘ original infirmity,’ which is the main subject of this lecture. Though the whole drift of our argument has been towards a denial of the authority and validity of the specifi- cally Western versions of the Fall-doctrine, we have already admitted that one passage in one particular Western formu- lary appears very accurately to embody the fundamental and truly Catholic essence of this idea, namely, the first chapter of the Tridentine decree ‘ concerning Justification ’ which, borrowing a phrase from the Second Council of Orange, affirms that in unregenerate human nature ‘ free-will is by no means extinguished, although weakened in its strength and warped’ (liberum arbitriuan minime exstinctum, viribus licet attenuatum et inclinatum).2 The kernel of the whole idea, which comes to light when the wrappers of Augustinian and scholastic accretion are stripped away, consists solely in the conception of an inherent ‘ weakness of will,’ which to a certain degree diminishes,? but does not by any means 1° Tell us, father, whither float we: tell us, good father, who we are. Happy are we, to all of us existence is so delicious !’ 2 Conc. Trident. Sess. VI, decret. de tustificat., cap. 1 (Denzinger- Bannwart, Enchiridion, 1913, p. 266): cf. conc. Avausic. II, can. 25 (Denzinger-Bannwart, p. 84). 3’ Cf. F. H. Bradley, Ethical Studies (1876), p. 42: ‘ violent emotion may make it impossible for the person to keep two courses before him and decide—impossible to separate himself from the strain put on him, so as 2H 466 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN abolish, moral responsibility. (It may be observed in paren- thesis that the responsibility with which we are dealing here is strictly individual responsibility ; the question whether there is any such thing as racial responsibility belongs to that complex of deeper and more metaphysical problems which cluster around the idea of the Fall.) The phrase ‘ weakness of will’ which we have employed hitherto belongs to the vocabulary of the so-called ‘ plain man,’ and is doubtless an unsatisfactory instrument of exact thought: if analysed, however, it would seem to disclose two ideas underlying it, namely that of volition, as involving effort, and that of this effort as impeded, or opposed, by non-volitional factors. We are, therefore, justified, without spending time in a more minute analysis, in translating this conception of ‘ weakness of will’ into philosophical terminology as the conception of ‘partial determinism,’ or ‘ partial indeterminism,’ which comes to the same thing, though the former expression is perhaps preferable as bearing a positive connotation. ‘ Such a doctrine would clearly stand in an equal opposition to absolute or rigoristic determinism and to absolute or anarchic libertarianism. It would, if intellectually defensible, repre- sent the safe middle channel between a Scylla which devours morals anda Charybdis which drowns Science. The result of our historical survey has, in fact, been to suggest that the only doctrine of human nature which is necessitated by the Vincentian canon involves one particular answer to the world- old enigma of free-will, and it is inevitable, therefore, that our ensuing discussion should be to a certain extent con- cerned with this all-too-hackneyed theme. No one who possesses any acquaintance with the history of the discussion of free-will can be under the delusion that he has anything new to say on the subject—his only justification for touching upon it must le in the hope that he may be able to speak either to resist it or to identify himself with it. In such cases the agents can not collect themselves so as to will, and though with knowledge, yet with pain and feeling of guiltiness, as in a dream, they perform some act which is abhorrent to them, and which they impute to themselves as guilt, but which (provided always their fault has not led to it) the sober onlooker may be unable to impute to them, in their character of a moral agent.’ The last clause, in my opinion, is an overstatement of the case. ‘ORIGINAL SIN’ RE-INTERPRETED 467 nove, non nova—to lay before his hearers not fresh con- siderations but the familiar arguments envisaged from a novel point of view. It was pointed out just now that the hypothesis of ‘partial determinism, which is presupposed by the irre- ducible residuum of the doctrine of so-called original sin, finds two competitors in the field: the rival theories of absolute indeterminism or libertarianism, and of absolute deter- minism. It is not necessary for us to spend any time in refuting the former theory ; the question was fought out as long ago as the fifth century, and the criticisms which were formulated against the views of Pelagius in our fifth lecture would appear to have a permanent validity as against his modern successors. If any further argument be needed it may be briefly pointed out that absolute indeterminism, by making all human action unpredictable, entirely destroys the possibility of the moral sciences—psychology, pedagogy, criminology, politics, economics, and ethics. Nor need we pay much attention to that slightly modified form of absolute libertarianism which admits the external determination of the will by the influences of environment but refuses to acknowledge its interior determination by heredity, and, like the Pelagians of old, finds the medium through which evil is transmitted solely in what is called ‘ social heredity.’ Such a theory, even if it had not been sufficiently refuted by the teachings of biology, as summed up in a phrase associated © with the name of Galton ‘ the all-importance of nature in comparison with nurture,’ would seem to be untenable on the simple a priori ground that Society is made up of human beings and is not a mysterious abstract hypostasis existing apart from or above them. Social heredity is merely the epiphenomenon of biological heredity : bad laws only exist because there have been bad legislators; and to lay the blame of man’s moral deformities upon ‘ Society,’ conceived as something other than and apart from its members, is a fallacy analogous to the political delusion which imagines that it is possible to throw the expense of extravagant schemes upon an imaginary entity known as ‘the State’ without increasing the burden of the individual taxpayer. The most formidable antagonist which confronts our 468 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN minimising doctrine of the ‘ inherited infirmity ’ is absolute determinism. In the present condition of thought it is the partial freedom of the will, not its partial determination, which needs defence. By a paradoxical revolution of thought, the residual doctrine of original sin has become the last citadel and refuge of the idea of the freedom of the will ; whilst, on the hypothesis of absolute determinism, all the fiendish cruelties of the Inquisition, the Jacquerie, or the Soviet, all the nauseous abnormalities which crowd the pages of Krafft-Ebing 4 or Havelock Ellis,? with their minor roots and ramifications which extend into the subconscious selves of us all, must be regarded as necessary, inevitable, predetermined manifestations of a principle of moral evil, saturating the whole body of mankind and making the general sum of human nature into a massa perditions which would more than merit Augustine’s most lurid and terrifying descriptions. The classical nineteenth-century discussions of the problem of free-will, such as those of Bain, Mill, and Leslie Stephen, presuppose that now antiquated view of the mind which regarded it as a piece of clockwork set in motion by the insertion into it of hard, metallic objects, known as ‘motives.’ With the remarkable development of the study of human personality which has taken place during this century the problem has assumed a new aspect. Both the leading schools of psychology—the school which studies human nature as revealed in moral behaviour and political conduct, and the more specifically medical school which draws its data from the study of mental pathology—agree in regarding the soul, or psyche, as an organism; living and growing and displaying the fundamental characteristic of organic life, that of perpetual self-adaptation to environ- ment; and, despite certain inevitable differences of emphasis and proportion which flow from the different interests and objects of the academic and the medical psychologists, there is a very large measure of agreement as to the general picture of the soul, its essential fibre and structure, which results from recent research and discovery. 1 Psychopathia sexualis, New York, n.d. 2 Studies in the Psychology of Sex, Philadelphia, 1923. “ORIGINAL SIN’ RE-INTERPRETED 469 It is inevitable that such a picture should be built up of metaphors, which may sometimes assume such a materialis- tic complexion as to give the impression that we are dealing with mythology and not with science; and it is no less inevitable that the outlines of the picture should be invested with a vague, fluctuating, and dreamlike quality, so that we seem to be looking not at realities but at some phantasma- goric dance of shadows, such as that which played and leapt upon the walls of Plato’s cave. But psychology is not the only science which is under the necessity of employing pictorial thought-forms and categories moulded in the furnace of imagination ; and if metaphor is frankly recognised for what it is, there is no reason why it should lead us astray. With this caution in mind we may now proceed to out- line that composite portrait of the soul which seems to have resulted from the two branches of psychological research _ just mentioned. The soul is a living organism; and in material organisms, such as form the subject-matter of the biologists’ study, a clear distinction can be drawn between the structure or tissue of the organism and the vital energy, which informs and builds up this structure and is in turn determined by it as regards the modes and channels of its discharge. In the soul we can similarly distinguish between structure and energy ; and it will conduce to clearness if we devote a separate examination to these two factors in psychic life. The structural plan of the soul is marked out by the frontiers, vague and undefined yet intensely real, between its three areas, which are commonly known as the conscious, the fore- or pre-conscious, and the unconscious. It is usual and convenient to speak of these areas as though they were vertically superimposed one upon another like storeys in a building, a usus loguend: which we will here follow ; and, as we are concerned with the present and normal condition of human personality and not with its genetic history, we will briefly describe the contents of these storeys in an order contrary to that of their chronological development, begin- ning with the latest addition to the fabric, the attic or garret which is tenanted by, or rather which 7s, consciousness, and working gradually downwards to the obscure and unexplored 470 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN basement of the Unconscious which rests, perhaps, upon the living bed-rock of God. For our purpose the most important fact to notice about this top storey, which we call the Conscious Self, is that it is furnished with certain wide and spacious windows, which are the senses, and which are never completely closed, even during sleep. Through these windows there beats in a per- petual blizzard of sense-impressions, derived mainly from the outside world, but including also a not inconsiderable num- ber which originate in the body and which, taken together, constitute what is known as the coenesthesia or sum of the organic sensations. This flux of sense-impressions, per- petually pouring in through the windows of the Soul, is flung into the broad framework of the subject-object relation, sorted out and built up into percepts by means of the forms of perception and the categories of the understanding, and organised, with a never-ceasing readjustment of content, perspective, and proportion, into a continuously flowing, cinematographic representation of the objective world. The details of this process belong to the subject-matter of epi- stemology or the theory of knowledge and do not, therefore, interest us now; the important fact for our purposes con- sists in the no less perpetual drain of the impressions, images, percepts and concepts, after they have played their part in the diorama of consciousness, through what, if we are to keep to our metaphor, must be imagined as a series of cracks .~ or holes in the floor, into the storey immediately below, the area of the preconscious, which is the domain of Memory. Here these discarded elements are caught, held suspended, and organised into more or less coherent conglomerates by the force of the vital energies, of which more will presently be said, welling up from the obscure depths of the Uncon- scious. These constellations of ideas and images, which are often charged with strong emotional feeling much as a thundercloud is charged with electricity, which hover, as it were, in the preconscious area just below the threshold of the Conscious, and which exert, as we shall see, the most powerful reflex influence upon the field of consciousness, are called by one school of psychologists ‘sentiments’; by Dr. Jung, however, they are known as ‘complexes’; and ‘ORIGINAL SIN’ RE-INTERPRETED 471 there is yet a third method of terminology which describes them as ‘ sentiments’ when occupying their normal position in the preconscious and as ‘ complexes’ only when repressed or driven down into the deep prison of the Unconscious. This hierarchy of ‘complexes’ (we adopt the term in Dr. Jung’s sense) which occupies the preconscious area, constitutes what is generally known as ‘ character’ in its more obvious and perceptible aspects, though in the con- ception of character we have to include ‘sentiments’ or complexes, which have been repudiated by the whole self, conscious and preconscious, as incompatible with external facts or with the conscious organisation of its purposes, and repressed in the manner just explained. The lowest room of all, the region of the Unconscious, is almost entirely unexplored, and only reveals its contents by vague and uncertain glimpses in the dream. All that we know about it can be summed up in this—that its obscure recesses contain the fountain of that mysterious energy or life-force which penetrates and vitalises the whole superincumbent structure, that it houses the uneasy and rebellious prisoners known as “repressed complexes,’ and that the exit from it is guarded against any possibility of their escape by a kind of psychic Cerberus known as the ‘censorship,’ whose lair is on the landing between the unconscious and the preconscious, and which is a metaphorical personification of the intellectual, social, and moral dispositions and conventions which forbid the emergence into consciousness of ideas and impulses felt to be inconsistent with its dominant organisations. These divisions, however, only represent part of the structure of the soul ; if we utilise the metaphor of a building, they represent the horizontal elements in it, the floors or storeys, and we have yet to consider certain highly important vertical elements which pierce through the various floors at right angles to them; or, if we prefer the metaphor of a woven tissue or fabric, what we have considered so far con- stitutes merely the warp of human personality, consisting of the various grades of consciousness, and we have now to consider the weft, consisting of the cross-threads of Instinct, running up from the selvedge of the Unconscious through the preconscious, the ends of which are gathered, ravelled and 472 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN matted together, in manifold and bewildering intricacy, in the sentiments or complexes. Perhaps it would be well, for the sake of clearness, to drop metaphor for a moment, and to take as the basis of our exposition the austerely scientific language of Dr. W. McDougall’s definition. He describes an instinct as ‘an inherited or innate + psycho- physical disposition which determines its possessor to perceive, and to pay attention to, objects of a certain class, to experience an emotional excitement of a particular quality upon perceiving such an object, and to act in regard to it in a particular manner, or at least to experience an impulse to such action.’2 It will be seen from this that an instinct is not Energy ; it is rather an arrangement of the psychic structure which determines the course which Energy takes upon a given occasion in order to discharge itself. If we may now relapse into what has already been indicated as inevitable, the use of metaphor, we may say that an instinct is a path, a channel, a pipe, or a wire, into which the funda- mental energy of the soul is attracted by the impact of a given stimulus. Strictly speaking, therefore, it is inaccurate to speak of the Instincts as being the efficient causes of action. The efficient cause of action is psychic energy, that which the medical psychologists have named /ibido, which we shall have occasion to discuss presently. Nor, in the light of this conception of the instincts as paths or channels is it appro- priate to speak of them as ‘ strong’ or ‘ powerful.’ What we know as an ‘imperious’ instinct should rather be described as one ‘ of high conductivity,’ if we think of the fundamental energy of the soul as something analogous to electricity, or as a ‘deeply graven channel,’ which attracts into itself a great volume of lbido, if we think of the energy under the metaphor of a fluid. It is not necessary for us to come to any conclusion on the disputed question of the exact number of the fundamental instincts. As is well known, Dr. McDougall enumerates twelve—Flight, Pugnacity, Repulsion, Curiosity, Self-assertion, Self-abasement, Parental instinct, the reproductive instinct, the instinct towards 1 T have italicised these words in order to draw attention to their importance for our enquiry. 2 An Introduction to Social Psychology, 18th edn., p. 29. ‘ORIGINAL SIN’ RE-INTERPRETED 473 feeding or self-maintenance, Gregariousness, Acquisition, and Construction.!_ Medical psychologists, on the other hand, seem to recognise only three fundamental instincts: those directed towards the preservation of the ego or self, towards conformity and homogeneity with the herd to which the individual belongs, and that directed towards the reproduc- tion of the species ; in other words, what are generally known _ as the ‘ ego-,’ the ‘herd-,’ and ‘sex-’ instincts. We need not go into the question whether Dr. McDougall’s twelve fundamental instincts are differentiations of the psycho- therapist’s three, or whether the psychotherapist’s three are compositions built up out of Dr. McDougall’s twelve. It is sufficient for our purpose to know that, piercing the psychical structure perpendicularly upwards, there is a web of pipes, channels, or paths, which is innate and given by heredity, which guides and determines the uprush of the fundamental energies of the soul, and which can, at least in thought, be separated out into three divisions or sets directed towards the maintenance and development of the self, the preser- vation of harmony between the self and the herd, and the perpetuation through the individual of the life of the race. We have now to consider the way in which the funda- mental energy, or force of the soul, flowing along one or other of these fixed, innate paths or channels, appears in con- sciousness as volition and in the external world as action. ‘’ It would seem that in the adult individual, in so far as he is adult in personality, the instincts do not discharge the vital energy directly into action. If and when they do, we are accustomed to say that the person in question is acting like a child, or an animal. Purely automatic actions, sometimes described as purely instinctive, whereby a given stimulus instantaneously causes a given external reaction, are characteristic only of organisms in which self-consciousness does not exist. The growth of self-conscious personality involves the growth of the sentiments, or complexes, stored in the preconscious area, which are continually being built up and charged with energy by the life-force transmitted to them through the instincts. In the adult individual, there- fore, an instinct is not, or ideally should not be, directly 1 op. cit. c. iii. —- aw 474 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN connected with the mechanism of muscular innervation leading to act; it is, on the contrary, a pipe or a channel which ends in the complex or sentiment, which must be conceived as a kind of reservoir or accumulator, lying just below the threshold of consciousness, containing the poten- tiality of action in the shape of psychic energy, or libido, which is being perpetually conducted to it by the channel of the appropriate instinct. Ifwe may employ yet another type of metaphor, we may think of the complex as a kind of sponge made up of associated ideas and images, which is kept in a state of perpetual saturation with psychic energy by the pipe of the appropriate instinct ending in it. The account of action and conation which results from this general conception may be formulated as follows. A ~stimulus enters the conscious area, either from above, through the windows of sense, or from beneath, dragged up from the preconscious by the machinery of association. The appearance of the stimulus in consciousness calls the appro- priate complex or sentiment into activity, and one of two things happens: either the stimulated complex discharges the psychical energy stored in it into the usual conative channels, from which it emerges as muscular innervation, and a bodily action follows ; or the stimulus simultaneously or after an infinitesimal interval excites another complex . inhibiting the action of the first. When this latter con- wae tingency occurs, the particular rivulet of energy which has been dammed up and refused an outlet into action may return upon itself, still further saturating the appropriate complex, and increasing its potential explosiveness; or it may be drained off and go to reinforce some other sentiment which is not debarred from finding practical satisfaction. In this way combative energy may be side-tracked and find a harmless outlet in competitive games and sport, and reproductive energy may be diverted and utilised as motive power for artistic creation or philanthropic activity. When the individual is able to resolve the conflict between the sentiments by starving the weaker sentiment—that is, by depriving it of the psychic energy which keeps it in being, and by using up this rejected energy in some other form, harmonising with the general organisation of his complexes— “ORIGINAL SIN’ RE-INTERPRETED 475 he is said to have achieved ‘sublimation.’ Too often, however, a mind, which has no comprehension of itself and its workings, takes a short and superficially easy cut to interior peace by thrusting the rebellious complex, still alive and charged with vital energy, down into the oubliette of the Unconscious, from which it often emerges as a neurosis or pathological symptom, disguising itself in some fantastic or irrational form in order to evade the vigilance of the ‘censorship.’ EL EMouaes Such, then, is the portrayal of conation and action which _is given in the modern picture of human personality. Action | means the release of stored-up energy by a complex in response to an appropriate stimulus ; abstinence from action means the inhibition of a weaker complex by a stronger ; and interior conflict, such as is manifested in the ‘ moral struggle,’ represents the overlap and collision of two com- es which must end either in the ‘ sublimation ’ or in the ‘repression ’ of the weaker. This simple scheme—percep- i of stimulus, excitation of complex, discharge of energy —represents, of course, the simplest type of conscious action ; but the most elaborate and complicated concatenations of mental procedures, directed towards the most ideal and abstract ends—the activities of a general working out a strategic design, of a statesman planning and executing a great measure of social reform, of a scientist or philosopher pursuing a train of abstruse research or speculation—can ultimately be dissected and resolved into such elementary reactions of complex to stimulus, though the true character of these conational units, if the phrase may be allowed, is often disguised by the high degree of co-ordination and integration which they have undergone. The conduct of the most subtly organised and highly moralised personalities can, in theory, be exhaustively explained on these lines, given liberty to postulate a sufficiently numerous hierarchy of ‘ sentiments,’ fed with power, not merely by the primary instincts but by a multiplicity of secondary and derivative conduits carved out for itself by the elemental energy of the soul, like the network of minor watercourses which link up with labyrinthine intricacy the main channels enclosing and dividing the delta of a great river. 476 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN Having now before our eyes what may be described as a cross-section photograph of the Self, displaying the interior mechanism of conduct to view, we naturally enquire if in this structure, the main outlines of which, as we have seen, are given solely by heredity, we can recognise any lacuna, any misfit or dislocation, corresponding to the ‘ inherited infirmity ’ alleged by theology to inhere in human nature. It must be emphasised, for the sake of clearness, that the ‘infirmity ’ of which we are in search is a strictly moral infirmity ; it would complicate our task to an impossible extent if we took account, at this stage, of pathological and morbid phenomena which no one would regard as bearing an ethical character. And a moral infirmity must, pre- sumably, mean an infirmity of the moral ‘sentiment’ or ‘complex,’ resulting in a tendency for it to be overborne by complexes more highly charged with psychic energy and endowed with a more pleasurable affective tone. We must, therefore, examine with some care the psychologist’s account of the moral sentiment, inasmuch as in it, or in the primitive instincts which have contributed to its formation, we shall either find—or not find—the fundamental flaw which Catholic Christianity declares itself to presuppose. The ‘moral sentiment’ is capable of pure and lovely efflorescence in ideal loyalties, self-sacrificing heroisms, and self-transcendent yearnings for the Absolute and the Infinite, in Whom the world of eternal values, like the world of ultimate truths, finds its supporting pillar and stay. Yet this interior power, which has been adored by poets and thinkers under the name of ‘ Conscience’ or ‘ Duty,’ ‘stern daughter of the voice of God,’ is, from the psychologist’s unsentimental point of view, an artificial and secondary construction, built upon one of the three primary, or at any rate most massive and dominant complexes, that which consists of ideas and images clustering round the idea of the ‘herd.’ It is, doubtless, unnecessary to urge a cultured audience not to allow itself to be prejudiced against the — information which psychology has to give us in this con- nexion by the apparent brutality of this technical term, or by the postulation of a lowly basis for our most exalted feelings ; ‘a rose by any other name would smell as sweet,’ ‘ORIGINAL SIN’ RE-INTERPRETED 479 and a diamond sparkles none the less brilliantly because it is made of the same carbon as a lump of coal. The ‘ herd- complex,’ then, with its various roots and ramifications, constitutes the field in which the ‘ inherited infirmity,’ if it is a reality, is to be found. We must, however, delimit this field with some minute- ness before proceeding to its investigation. It would clearly be waste of time to analyse the higher developments of the “moral sentiment,’ or to trace the process whereby, in ethically gifted individuals, the partial fusion of the ego- and the herd-complexes gives birth to an autonomous moral ideal, independent of external or social sanctions. Nor are we concerned with the weird and monstrous aberrations of the specifically criminal temperament, such as formed the subject-matter of the studies of Nordau and Lombroso— the temperament in which the ‘ moral sentiment ’ is either non-existent or so much atrophied as hardly to be recog- nisable. It is, indeed, tempting to identify ‘ original sin,’ so called, with criminality ; and such an identification was implied in the half-serious, popular and journalistic cliché which attributed the atrocities committed in the late war to a ‘double dose of original sin’ in their perpetrators. It would certainly seem that criminal dispositions are trans- missible by heredity ; the progress of statistical research may prove that in certain strains of mankind they behave as Mendelian dominants; and it is probable that a reason- able system of applied eugenics might do much towards their elimination from the human stock.!. We shall certainly not be able to ignore the question of criminality when we approach our final: problem, that of the ultimate origin of evil. But we cannot simply identify it with the ‘ inherited infirmity ’ of which we are in search; for the innate flaw or wound of human nature, which Christian tradition pre- supposes, purports to be, not a varietal factor borne by 1 In so far as ‘ eugenics’ is a genuine science, no Catholic Christian can claim to have a conscientious objection to it : if and in so far as it is an art, it does not seem possible to find limits for its scope other than those dictated by the inalienable rights and dignity of the individual. Such limits would clearly rule out both the system of State-breeding suggested by Plato in Republic V, and also the‘ sterilisation of the unfit’ enjoined by the law of certain American States. 478 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN particular individuals or stocks, but a generic quality, existing in all men (with one, or, as some hold, with two exceptions), inhering deeply in the fundamental plasm of the race, beyond and below the reach of eugenics, psycho- therapy, manipulation of the endocrine glands, or of any remedial agency other than the delicate and viewless ° influences of God’s redeeming grace. We must therefore neglect the superficially more interesting qualities of the ethical genius and the ethical degenerate, and dig deep, in quest of the alleged ‘ inherited infirmity,’ into that instinctive structure which is the basis of human personality in saint and criminal alike. The ‘ herd-complex,’ then, as it exists, not in the ethically highest or lowest types of mankind, but in the generalised average of humanity, is the starting-point of our search. But here, again, a further limitation has to be added. Civilised man belongs to many herds, and his preconscious mind therefore contains many herd-complexes of greater or lesser strength, built up round the ideas of his school, college, regiment, social class, trade, political or religious party, and so on; these structures tend to generate in the surface mind feelings of esprit de corps, party loyalty, “class-consciousness, and other quasi-moral emotions familiar to us all. But the particular herd-complex which forms the core and substratum of the moral sentiment clearly cannot be identified with any one of the minor conglomerates just mentioned, though it may on occasion draw upon the energy with which they are charged. It can be found only in that deep-lying psychic structure which coheres round the idea of ‘society’ as such, and which, from the standpoint of the morphology of personality, must be regarded as the proximate source of specifically ethical impulses and conations, no matter whether ‘society’ be narrowly conceived as the individual’s own clan or totem- group, or broadened out so as to include the whole human race or the whole fellowship of conscious beings. In the religious man, indeed, the perfected moral sentiment is largely fused and identified with the mass of ideas, beliefs and emotions which grow out of his conception of God ; but an. examination of this loftiest efflorescence of ethical feeling ‘ORIGINAL SIN’ RE-INTERPRETED 479 would lead us away from our immediate task, which is to uncover its ultimate roots. And these roots lie in the idea of ‘society,’ ‘the community,’ or ‘the herd.’ Whatever metaphysical explanation of the pure forms or categories of ‘ right ’ and ‘ wrong’ may commend itself to the specula- tive reason, it is a mere statement of historical and psycho- logical fact when we assert that the concrete content of _ morality, as it exists at any given time, is defined for the individual by the exigencies of the herd, and mediated to his consciousness through the pressure of the herd-tradition upon him. The ‘ social complex,’ then, created and maintained by “herd-instinct,’ is the basis of the ethical sentiment ; and all interior moral conflicts are due to incompatible conations arising from this on the one hand, and either from the ego- complex or the sex-complex on the other. Sometimes, indeed, the moral sentiment may be able to utilise the ‘ energy latent in the ego-complex—or, in less technical terms, morality and self-interest may combine to inhibit some sensuous impulse; and a little imagination will show that an alliance between the moral sentiment and the sex-complex, to oppose the dictates of mere selfishness, is not by any means unknown. But—and here we come to the real point of this long excursion into the realm of analytic psychology—experience decisively shows that the “society ’ complex, in isolation and devoid of allies, is no match for the powerful systems of thought and feeling cohering round the ideas of the self and of sex—a fact which is indicated in the restrained words of Dr. McDougall: ‘ We have to recognise that the desire that springs from the completed moral sentiment is usually of a thin and feeble sort in comparison with the fiercer, coarser desires that spring directly from our instincts and from our concrete sentiments.’1 If we ask why the desire, which issues from the moral sentiment into consciousness, is normally of this ‘thin and feeble’ character, the answer must be that the moral sentiment emits only a thin and feeble desire, because it itself is only charged with psychic energy of a thin and feeble quality. Just as a powerful electric spark cannot be 1 ODe Ctl... 1X Pp. 229. 480 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN obtained from a weak battery, so a strong conational effort cannot issue from a complex endowed with a relatively small quantum of that libido or life-force which is the driving- power behind actions of every kind, volitional and non- volitional alike. And this weak saturation with psychic energy of the social complex can only be due to the weakness of the herd-instinct, which feeds it; which, in the meta- phorical and symbolic language necessary for the purposes of this enquiry, is a narrow and constricted gutter carrying only a thin trickle of the forces of the soul; whereas in comparison with it the two other elemental instincts, those concerned with the maintenance of the self and the per- petuation of the race, must be imagined as broad and deeply cut canals, which take fierce swirling volumes of the vital impulse. (The ultimate psychological fact, therefore, which ,. gives rise to an interior ‘ moral struggle’ ending only too often in the defeat of the social or ethical principle, is the weakness or shallowness of the ‘ herd-instinct,’ relatively to the two other primary instincts of human nature. And this unsatisfactory proportion which the three cardinal instincts bear to each other is, it must be remembered, nothing acquired or artificially constructed ; it is simply given by heredity, in the total make-up of human personality with which we are born. It would seem therefore that we need search no further, and that at this deep level in the struc- ture of the soul, beneath the area of the preconscious and lying in the obscure recesses of the Unconscious, we have unearthed that precise weakness or interior dislocation of man’s being which historical Christianity has steadfastly affirmed to exist, and which forms the presupposition of its redemptive and sacramental scheme. In the light of this identification of the ‘ inherited infirmity’ with congenital weakness or shallowness of ‘herd-instinct,’ it is easy to understand the psychological vationale of the traditional language employed by Christian ascetic theology in regard to the forms assumed by ‘ innate sin’ as it gradually grows within the growing soul. In this traditional language it is often said that all actual sins spring from one or other of two roots—namely, Pride and Sensuality ; and that these again run back into Self-love “ORIGINAL SIN’ RE-INTERPRETED A481 as their ultimate source. And ‘ Self-love’ is nothing but a positive manner of describing the same fact which psycho- logy, in agreement with the most primitive Christian modes of thought, conceives as a negation, an €AAewws or deprivatio, as deficiency in that ‘ herd-complex,’ that sym- pathy or love, that corporate or social feeling which all men do possess to some degree (for otherwise they would not be moral beings at all), but which, in normal human nature, as transmitted to us by birth and as it stands prior to moral and religious educative influences, is strong enough only to hamper and not to master the tendency of the life-force to rush impetuously down the channels of the self-asserting and the race-perpetuating instincts. ‘Pride’ is merely a name for the exaggeration of the ego-complex, and ‘ sensu- ality ’ for the hypertrophy of the cluster of ideas and images connected with sex; and what we have already noted as the somewhat excessive preoccupation of Jewish and Christian anthropology ! with ‘ concupiscence’ in the more restricted sense of that ambiguous term is doubtless due to the somewhat greater depth and capacity of the latter instinct as compared with the former. It would not, indeed, be difficult to paraphrase the classical descriptions of the inbred taint and the moral struggle given us by the masters of the spiritual life in terms of the three dominant com- plexes. It would be a task of the highest intellectual interest (though considerations of time prevent us from undertaking it now) to work through the great Pauline passage, Rom. vii. 7-25, which we studied in Lecture III, translating it into the terminology of modern mental science, rendering ‘ the sin that dwelleth in me ’ as ‘ the innate weak- ness of my herd-instinct,’ ‘ the law of my mind’ as ‘ my completed moral sentiment,’ and the “ law of sin which is in my members’ as the ‘ powerful complexes perpetually fed with psychic energy by my animal instincts’; whilst the cry of despair ‘ who shall deliver me from the body of this death ?’ would represent the crisis of psychic pain born of the clash of conflicting conations; and the victorious 1 See Lecture I, p. 34; Lecture, II, pp. 58, 66; Lecture III; p. 153; Lecture LV,-pp. 226, 245, 273, 304; Lecture V, p. 360;° Lecture, V1) PP. 403 Daz; 4IT nz: pay 482 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN reply ‘I thank God through Jesus Christ our Lord’ would be the exulting song of a soul which had won its way to interior harmony and peace by the sublimation of the rebellious complexes into the mystic aspirations of a great ideal love. Yet when, in accordance both with the most primitive Christian thought and the most modern psychological re- search, we define the inherited wound of human nature in negative terms as a deficiency, a lack, a privatio, we must not be supposed thereby to minimise the deadliness and the horror of the results to which it leads in human action. To realise in full the objective evil of what, considered sub- jectively, is nothing but a defect, a gap, a blank, a minus quantity, we need only borrow the method used by Plato for the detection of righteousness, and study that enlarged and generalised portrait of the soul which is presented by the state or the nation in its corporate bearing towards other states or nations. It is instructive to review that world- wide society constituted by the unity of our race, in which peoples are the individuals, and humanity as a whole is the ‘herd’ to which the individual owes allegiance. The history of peoples, in their relations one with another, is marked by an almost complete absence of collective “ herd- instinct’ and by the unrestrained dominance of the ‘ ego- instinct ’ in its most brutal and least disguised form. The events of the last decade lend a melancholy confirmation to words recently written, not by any Augustinian or Calvinistic divine, but by a thinker whose theological impartiality will nowhere be disputed, Mr. Bertrand Russell. “Men’s collective passions are mainly evil; far the strongest of them are hatred and rivalry directed towards other groups. Therefore at present all that gives men power to indulge their collective passions is bad. That is why Science threatens to cause the destruction of our civilisa- tion.’? It would be difficult to find a more apposite commentary upon our Lord’s own grave and awful saying: ‘From within, out of the heart of men, evil thoughts proceed .. . thefts, murders . . . coveting, wickednesses, deceit . . . an evil eye, railing, pride, foolishness: all these evil things proceed from within, and defile the man.’ ? 1 Icarus (1924), p. 63. 2 Mark vii. 21 f. “ORIGINAL SIN’ RE-INTERPRETED 483 It may thus be reasonably claimed that the existence of a hereditary psychic factor which tends to promote the indulgence of self-assertive and sensualimpulses in despite of ‘conscience,’ or the ‘ moral sentiment,’ is a hypothesis which finds ample verification both in ordinary daily life and in the scientific study of human personality. But, it may be objected, this line of thought, if followed out consistently, proves too much for our purposes: for it lands us, not in ‘ partial determinism,’ but in a determinism just as absolute as that which results from the older mechanistic view of the mind. In the preceding description of the vationale of conation and action, hardly anything was said about the conscious ego, which occupies—or rather is—the uppermost storey of the house of personality : and modern psychology, especially that of the medical type, is largely epipheno- menalistic, regarding the feeling of effort and struggle as an illusion, and the ‘I’ as the passive mirror of events which it has had no share in causing. The logical result of such a view, when combined with a recognition of the fact which we have described as man’s congenital deficiency of herd-instinct, would be (as we have pointed out above 3) something very like the ‘ twice-born’ view of human nature characteristic of Latin and Western Christendom: some elements at least of Augustinianism, having been driven from the field of theology by the Vincentian Canon, would have returned in triumph under the aegis of Freud. We have already indicated what seems to us the inconsistency of Augustinianism with a genuine belief in the goodness and justice of God, and in the moral account- ability of man. But we do not forget that this doctrine has nevertheless been held by some of the greatest saints and doctors of the Universal Church, that it is not without roots in the teaching of St. Paul, and that the type of character which has been nourished by it is, at its best, virile, austere, and noble. Whatever may be the case in logic, it is at least psychologically possible for an orthodox Christian to | be a rigid determinist. It is, therefore, no part of the contention of these lectures that Augustinianism is a heresy. We have maintained that the ‘ once-born’ or ‘ Hellenic’ 1 p. 468. 484 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN doctrine represents the maximum to which historical Christianity is, as such, committed; but if any individual orthodox Christian believes that he has grounds for going further and adopting the ‘ twice-born’ view—if he thinks that man can be justly held accountable by God for acts which are completely determined by heredity and environ- ment, and that the potter may justifiably wreak vengeance on the pots for being of the shape into which he has himself moulded them, or allowed them to be moulded—it would seem that, so far as the auctoritas of Scripture and tradition is concerned, he is well within his rights in so thinking and believing. It is not, accordingly, necessary for our purposes to embark at this juncture upon an extensive vindication of free-will: and it will suffice to conclude this lecture with the briefest possible summary of the present position of the problem. The situation in regard to the question whether a true spontaneous causality, acting within limits! fixed by heredity and environment, can be ascribed to the ego or not, has not essentially altered since its treatment by Kant. Determinism is the necessary methodological postulate of 1 The mere feeling of freedom is not always veridical : sometimes we are most completely determined when we believe ourselves to be most free. The smooth, unimpeded interaction of the psychic organisations sketched in the text is not in itself freedom: freedom is only realised when the conscious ego, the transcendental self, deliberately takes control of the situation, with clear knowledge of itself, of its instinctive impulses, and of the effort which it is putting forth in order to guide or restrain them. What appears to be substantially this point has been expressed by Bergson in his own characteristic language, and connected with his peculiar philosophy of time and duration, in the following passage: ‘ Il y aurait donc enfin deux moi différents, dont l’un serait comme la projection de autre, sa représentation spatiale et pour ainsi dire sociale. Nous atteignons le premier par une réflexion approfondie, qui nous fait saisir nos états internes comme des étres vivants, sans cesse en voie de formation, comme des états réfractaires 4 la mesure, qui se pénétrent les uns les autres, et dont la succession dans la durée n’a rien de commun avec une juxtaposition dans l’espace homogéne. Mais les moments ot nous nous ressaisissons ainsi nous-mémes sont rares, et c’est pourquot nous sommes vavement libres (italics ours). La plupart du temps, nous vivons extérieure- ment & nous-mémes . . . nous vivons pour le monde extérieur plutét que pour nous; nous parlons plutét que nous ne pensons; nous ‘‘ sommes agis’’ plutét que nous n’agissons nous-mémes. Agir librement, c’est reprendre possession de soi, c’est se replacer dans la pure durée’ (Les données immédiates de la conscience, 1908, p. 178). “ORIGINAL SIN’ RE-INTERPRETED 485 the scientist and the statistician; but freedom is the no less necessary assumption of the teacher and the judge, an assumption which is largely employed in psycho-therapeutic practice as distinct from theory.1 We cannot hope with our present faculties to attain a complete logical synthesis » of the dictates of the theoretical reason, which repudiates the idea of an uncaused causality, with those of the practical | reason, which demands it ; but it remains true to say that determinism is only necessary to a psychology which studies the mind objectively and ab extra, whilst the consciousness of ability to exert or not to exert effort is, from the sub- jective and introspective point of view, a datum of immediate experience. In the light of these considerations, it may: _ reasonably be claimed that the doctrine of ‘ partial deter- /” minism ’—which, whilst admitting that conduct is the result of the interplay of stimulus, complex, and instinct, nevertheless affirms that consciousness has, within limits, a real power of guiding the flow of psychic energy into this complex rather than that, and of gradually modifying the contents of the preconscious and unconscious by voluntary ‘ sublimation ’—would seem to be the only one which does justice both to man’s moral and to his intellectual experience. If this be so, we have in the treasure-house of Christian tradition that true conception of human nature, its power and its weakness, which contains the key to the world-old problems of social regeneration and reform. No readjust- 1 The restrained words of an eminent psychotherapist may be quoted in this connexion: ‘ . . . one finds such a distinguished neurologist as Dejerine saying in his book on psychotherapy that belief in freedom is essential to the more successful application of the methods of psycho- therapy. He claims, practically at any rate, that we must believe in freedom if we are to hope to influence our patients on the mental side. Without going so far as that, I am inclined to say that a belief in freedom, in self-determination, on the physician’s part, strong enough to sustain or originate a similar belief in the patient’s mind, is a very important factor in mental cure’ (William Brown, Mind and Personality, 1926, p. 47). 2 Cf. O. Tansley, The New Psychology (1922), p.296: ‘ The fundamental postulates of the new science of the mind, the doctrines of psychic deter- mination and of the derivation of the springs of all human action from instinctive sources, are essential as working hypotheses. But this science need not commit itself to the conclusion that the play of instinctive forces exhausts the meaning of the human soul, any more than biology need commit itself to the conclusion that the play of chemical and physical forces exhausts the meaning of life itself.’ 486 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN ment of governmental or economic machinery, no perfection of scientific or hygienic efficiency, will in itself avail to bring the Kingdom of God upon earth one step nearer, apart from a ‘change of heart’ in the individual member of society. The essential condition of such a change, which is the co-operation of human freedom and Divine grace, stands written for all time in the great saying of the Apostle, ‘Work out your own salvation with fear and trembling,’ recognising and using to the full the God-given endowment of self-consciousness, self-determination, and individual autonomy, yet remembering, in humble acknowledgment of the connatural flaw of human nature, that it is God, Who alone can ‘ order the unruly wills and affections of sinful men,’ ‘ that worketh in you both to will and to work, for His good pleasure.’ ADDITIONAL NOTE D ORIGINAL SIN, ESCHATOLOGY, AND FOREIGN MISSIONS One of the master-motives which spurred on the great missionaries of the last four centuries, both Catholic and Evan- gelical, to their heroic labours amongst the heathen was a burning desire to snatch as many souls as they could from the eternal perdition assumed to await all non-Christians as such in the next world, in virtue of ‘ originalsin.’ In other words, Augustinianism and its concomitant eschatology lay at the root of the apostolic zeal manifested alike by a Francis Xavier and a Henry Martyn: and these ideas still seem to appear in the missionary inter- cession printed in the well-known devotional manual Sursum Corda (1906, p. 121): ‘O God of all the nations of the earth, remember the multitudes of the heathen, who, though created in Thine image, are perishing in darkness and ignorance ’—where there is little point or force in the word ‘ perishing’ unless it means ‘ perishing eternally.’ Ifthe contention embodied in these lectures is correct, this particular incentive to missionary effort has ceased to exist. But the conception of Limbo, in some form or other, as a possible destiny of the spiritually undeveloped, may still provide a non-Augustinian Christianity with a satis- factory, though not so dramatically appealing, substitute. The 2, Philais Dey 73: ‘ORIGINAL SIN’ RE-INTERPRETED 487 desire to lead the child-like members of the human family up to far higher planes of spiritual vision and power than any to which they could have attained, apart from Christ and His Gospel, either in this life or the next, may well prove to be an evangelistic motive more truly inspiring than that which springs from the crude eschatology of Augustinianism. It may be added that the missionary cause would not suffer by a reverent unwillingness on the part of Christian thinkers to define too narrowly the category of those who may be incapable of the highest beatitude, or by a refusal to draw too sharp a line between Limbo and ‘ purgatory.’ The words of a previous Bampton Lecturer are specially pertinent in this connexion : “Few among us would desire to bar the gates of heaven against the Unitarian Channing, against the Buddhist ascetic, against even the naked savage who on his sea-swept coral reef, forsaken as he may seem of God and man, is yet just and grateful and kind to wife and child. Yet few would think that for these maimed souls no instruction is needed, that the mere rending of the veil can make tolerable the splendour which it reveals. We believe in the many stripes and the few. We believe that star differeth from star in glory, and in these words lies all that any sober- minded man has ever maintained.’ } 1 Bigg, Christian Platonists of Alexandria (1886), p. 299. VIII. THE ULTIMATE “FALL? O martyred Spirit of this helpless Whole, Who dost by pain for tyranny atone, And in the star, the atom, and the stone, Purgest the primal guilt, and in the soul ; Rich but in grief, thou dost thy wealth unroll, And givest of thy substance to thine own, Mingling the love, the laughter, and the groan In the large hollow of the heaven’s bowl. GEORGE SANTAYANA., In my folly often I wondered why by the great foreseeing wisdom of God the beginning of sin was not letted: for then, methought, all should have been well. . . . But Jesus answered by this word and said ‘ Sin is behovable, but all shall be well and all shall be well and all manner of thing shall be well.’ JULIAN OF NORWICH. LECTURE. VIII. THE ULTIMATE ‘FALL’ Rev. xii. 7, 8: ‘ There was war in heaven: Michael and his angels going forth to war with the dragon ; and the dragon warred, and his angels; and they prevailed not, neither was their place found any more in heaven.’ In our last lecture we dealt with the question of what has been called ‘ Original Sin,’ and defined the nature of the inherited infirmity, declared to exist in human nature, by the basic doctrine of traditional Christianity as held “everywhere, always, and by all.’ We saw that our moral consciousness, the interplay of ‘ thoughts accusing or else excusing one another’? (to use St. Paul’s vivid phrase), necessitates the assumption that in an ideal human per- sonality the ‘herd-complex’ would form an adequate counterweight to the ‘ ego-complex ’ and the ‘ sex-complex ’ and also to the aggregate of them taken together, so that the soul would enjoy a condition of perfect equilibrium or poise on which conscious free-will could play, reinforcing now one and now another of the dominant psychical structures and controlling, modifying, or inhibiting the flow of vital energy into them. And we saw further that the congenital weak- ness or disorder of human nature consists precisely in this, that such an equilibrium does not, in point of fact, exist ; that, owing to the weakness of the herd-instinct which feeds it, the herd-complex, and by consequence the moral senti- ment which is built upon it, does not possess anything like the amount of vital energy necessary to place it on equal terms with the two other primary complexes, so as to preserve that equilibrium of the empirical self, or ‘ me,’ 1 Rom. ii. 15: petaéd addAdAndAdv rdv Aoyiopdv Karnyopovvrwv H Kal amoAoyoupevwv. 492 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN which the transcendental self, or ‘I,’ needs in order to be able to function with freedom. Hence the conscious ego is in the position of an organist condemned to play upon an instrument in which certain very powerful stops are liable to speak of their own accord and at the most inappropriate moments; or, in less metaphorical language, free-will, though not destroyed, is weakened and hampered, in comparison with what it ought to be, by the present con- ditions of human nature, and the self-regarding and race- perpetuating instincts tend to have things all their own way. We now approach the final problem—namely, the question how this state of affairs came into existence; that is to say the problem of what is known to traditional theology as the ‘ Fall.’ It was observed in our first lecture, at the very beginning of our historical review, that the hypothesis of a ‘ Fall’ is essentially an inference from the facts of human weakness and sin, considered in the light of the infinite holiness of God.! It is not a premise given by history—a fact which would have been quite sufficiently proved by the existence in Judaism and Christianity for three hundred years of two alternative Fall-stories, even if Biblical criticism and natural science had never shown that the Paradise-story which ultimately triumphed is just as devoid of historical character as the ‘ Watcher ’-story which it superseded. The recog- nition of this fact must compel a certain readjustment of what has been, at least in Western Christianity, the traditional view as to the interior structure, if the term may be allowed, of the fabric of Christian doctrine. It was pointed out in our first lecture that mediaeval Christians, at least, thought of the Faith as borne up by the twin pillars of a historic Fall and a historic Redemption, both vouched for by written records of divinely guaranteed accuracy and authority—as leaning upon the Tree of Death which stood in the midst of the Garden of Eden, and the Tree of Life which was planted upon the summit of Calvary. If the argument developed in this course of lectures has been sound, the first pillar is to be found not so much in the 1 Lecture I, p.19; and cf. the passage from Cardinal Newman’s A pologia pro Vita Sua printed at the beginning of the last lecture. THE ULTIMATE ‘ FALL’ 493 idea of the Fall as in the idea of ‘ original sin,’ so called, and the basis of this pillar consists in a certain kind of religious experience—namely, the experience of penitence—and not in history. I do not mean to imply that the idea of the Fall ought to be discarded, or that it does not correspond to any reality—I am only concerned to point out that, in view of its inferential character, it must for the future be con- ceived not as a column which supports the Christian Faith, but rather as a pinnacle which is supported by it. It might thus seem as though there were not very much to be said about the Fall beyond the mere assertion that, if God is infinitely good, He cannot be the author of evil, and that the facts of human nature therefore compel us to assume something corresponding to a Fall; and indeed, when once the literal historicity of Gen. ii. has been given up, that is all that can be affirmed to be of faith—at any rate for Christians other than those of the Latin communion. But because the idea of the Fall is a pinnacle and not a column, it does not follow that it is of no structural importance. A pinnacle need not be a mere ornamental excrescence ; it may exert a downward thrust which plays an important part in the system of stresses ensuring the stability of the fabric to which it belongs. It has, in fact, been recently ascertained in connexion with St. George’s Chapel at Windsor that the gravitational pressure of a row of heavy pinnacles is necessary in order to enable its buttresses and columns to resist the lateral pressure of its flattened and floriated vault, and that the threatened collapse of this venerable fabric is largely due to the incautious removal of these same pinnacles, a century ago, on the ignorant assumption that they were nothing but unnecessary adorn- ments.t We will therefore make no apology for endeavour- ing to dispel the mists which surround this particular pinnacle, that is, for devoting our final lecture to the task of arriving at a conception of the Fall which may be congruous both with the essential contents of traditional Christianity and also with the deliveries of human reason. It will be remembered that the fundamental Christian doctrine of the Fall, as distinct from that of Original Sin, 1 This was written in 1924. 494 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN was in our last lecture condensed into the form of five pro- positions, which it will be well, for the sake of clearness, to repeat at this juncture. They were as follows: (1) God is infinite, not merely in power but in love and goodness, and therefore the world of created being as He made it must have been purely good, including no element of evil at all. (2) The origin of evil is therefore to be sought in the voluntary rebellion of created and finite wills, such rebellion having taken place prior to the appearance of the human species on this planet. (3) Man, at his first entry into this world, was in moral and intellectual stature a babe, created frail, imperfect, ignorant and non-moral, but endowed with self-consciousness and the power of self-determination which constituted a starting-point for progress and upward evolution. (4) The growth of man’s moral ideas brought in its train some action, or system of actions, whereby man aligned himself with the rebellious power, showed that he had partially thrown in his lot with the forces of evil which were already at work in the universe, and entered on a path largely divergent from that upward career of spiritual evolution which God had meant him to follow. (5) Ever since this first human transgression, our nature has displayed an inherent moral weakness or bias towards sin. These are the propositions which must now be vindicated if the doctrine of the Fall is to be preserved as a member of the Christian dogmatic scheme. It will be noticed that they are all couched in a strictly historical form. As they stand, they purport to describe real events which occurred in past time, which would, presumably, be capable, if we only had the requisite knowledge, of being assigned to specific dates B.c. We are all familiar with the conventional form which the sequence of these alleged events has assumed in popular religious thought and scholastic theology, and which has been shaped into a vast cosmic drama in the mighty epic of ‘ Paradise Lost.’ The revolt of Lucifer, setting up the standard of revolt against the Most High in the regions of the North, the hurling of the apostate angels from the crystal battlements of Heaven, the desire to fill up the gaps left in the ranks of His servants by the defection of the rebellious PEO UTARIN AH EAN TTE ¢ 495 spirits as being the motive which prompted the Almighty to create Man in His own image and likeness, and the tempter’s assault upon our first parents as prompted by a craving for revenge upon the triumphant Deity—these are but the pictorial and mythological husk in which the kernel of the doctrine of the ‘ Fall,’ as expressed in the five more abstract propositions given above, has been for many centuries con- cealed. Such beliefs are only worth mentioning now for the sake of helping us to realise the total and utter absence of any sort of serious evidence for them. We have already pointed out that the Paradise story of Gen. iii. was not meant to narrate a ‘ Fall’ in the theological sense of the term, and it may be added that the Scriptural texts which have been adduced as testifying to the fall of the angels have even less relevance to their supposed subject-matter. The battle between Michael and the Dragon, narrated in the twelfth chapter of the Christian Apocalypse, has too many parallels in pagan mythology to be regarded as a literal revelation of pre-mundane history !; the reference to the fall of ‘ Lucifer,’ that is, the Day-Star, made by some prophet of the Exile, whose work has been embodied in the Book of Isaiah, is merely a metaphorical description of the collapse of the Babylonian power”; and even our Lord’s saying, reported in St. Luke’s Gospel, ‘ I beheld Satan fallen as lightning from Heaven,’ ® clearly refers not to any pre-cosmic expulsion of the revolting spirits from the abode of God, but to the triumph just gained over the demons by His seventy disciples through a successful series of exorcisms. There is therefore as little a fostertovt evidence for the fall of the angels as there is for the Fall, or rather the failure, of Man ; and if the scheme contained in our five propositions, or any part of it, is to be sustained at all, it can only be upon the basis of purely a priori reasoning. At this point we are faced by the consideration that the use of the a priov1 method for establishing historical con- clusions lies under profound, and not undeserved, suspicion. 1 For a list of these parallels, and a searching investigation of the origins of the myth, see R. H. Charles, The Revelation of St. John (ICC., 1920), vol. i. pp. 305 ff. * Isaiah xiv. 12. 3 Luke x. 18. 496 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN The argument ‘Such and such a thing ought to have hap- pened, and therefore it did happen,’ has been so often refuted by the critic’s pen or the archaeologist’s spade that our modern intellectual conscience will not allow it so much as a hearing until all other possible alternatives have been decisively disposed of. Before, therefore, we can even begin to consider the hypotheses of a pre-mundane revolt and a failure of man to avoid complicity in this revolt we must give careful consideration to the previous question, which is this : Is it necessary to find the source of evil in a historical event at all? If, for the time being, we use the term ‘ Fall’ asa convenient label for designating that unknown % in which the origin of evil lies hid, is it necessary to interpolate the Fall into the historical time series, and to describe its relation to empirical evil under the category of ‘ cause and effect’ ? May it not be simpler to regard the Fall, in this symbolical sense, as standing towards the actual sins of man in the relation of ‘ ground’ to ‘ consequent,’ and as con- stituting a timeless, transcendent and metaphysical fact, rather than a phenomenal and historical event? The shortest and most convenient method of answering this question will be to examine the two classical attempts which have been made by two of the most subtle and powerful of philosophical intellects to remove the idea of the Fall from the plane of history into that of metaphysic, in order to ascertain whether they fulfil the essential function of the Fall-doctrine, for the discharge of which it was first devised and in which alone we, as Christians, are interested—namely, that of saving the infinite goodness of God by relieving Him from the direct responsibility for the creation of evil. These two restatements or reinterpretations of the traditional Fall-doctrine form part of the systematic attempts made by Kant and Hegel to salve what seemed to them the permanent essence of religion from the wreck in which a destructive Biblical criticism and the remorseless rationalism of the Aufkldrung seemed to have involved German evangelical theology. Should we conclude that neither of these giants of thought has succeeded in lifting the idea of the Fall out of the phenomenal plane, we shall be entitled to assume that the task is inherently impossible, and that—for good or for THE ULTIMATE ‘ FALL’ 497 evil—the propositions which were formulated above must be taken au pied de la lettre, as purporting to describe historical events lying, infinitely remote from us, in the ‘dark backward and abysm of time.’ Kant’s discussion of original sin is contained in the first section of his treatise entitled ‘ Religion within the bounds of Mere Reason.’1 This treatise is concerned mainly with religion on its soteriological side, that is, in its aspect as a way of salvation, and its main divisions are concerned with the entry of the evil principle into human nature, the struggle between the good and evil principles, and the eventual triumph of the good principle.2. The argument of the first of these sections is based upon the empirical universality of sin, which Kant proves from the not very considerable store of information at his disposal with regard to the habits of savages. He does not regard badness as constituting part of the essence of human nature, but rather as an inseparable accident. Badness is not given in the concept of man, but it is de facto so widely spread that it can be predicated of man generically. Though Kant is distinguished amongst philo- sophers by his contempt of psychology, he makes some show of analysing human nature in order to throw light upon the seat of the evil principle, and it is noteworthy that in describing what he calls ‘ the animal nature of man,’ which is the substratum and foundation of his strictly human and moral being, he designates as its primary psychical con- stituents, precisely those three instincts with which our last lecture is so largely concerned, those, namely, which are directed towards the maintenance of the self, the propagation of the race, and the maintenance of harmony between the self and the society to which it belongs—in other words, what we now call the ‘ herd-instinct.’4 It would seem at first sight as though this analysis might lead to results 1 Die Religion innerhalb der Grenzen der blossen Vernunft (Kant’s sémmi- liche Werke, ed. Rosenkrantz and Schubert, Leipzig, 1838, x. pp. I-244). 2 The first of these sections (‘ Von der Einwohnung des bésen Princips neben dem guten, oder, Uber das radikale Bose in der menschlichen Natur’) has been translated into English by T. K. Abbott (Kant’s Critique of Prac- tical Reason, and other works on the Theory of Ethics, 1883, pp. 325-360). 3 p. 36 f. (paginal references are given to Rosenkrantz and Schubert’s edition). epee, SX * 2K 498 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN congruous with, and likely to illuminate, the conclusions which were reached in the last lecture. Unfortunately, however, Kant is obsessed by his conception of the Good as a Law, eternal and supersensible, which, in Troeltsch’s phrase,? is the ‘ focus’ of the intelligible world, which, like the axioms of mathematics, carries its own authority within itself, and neither requires nor is capable of genetic explanation or logical proof: and his argument in consequence tends to move in the rarefied atmosphere and amongst the bloodless abstractions of metaphysics rather than upon the solid ground of ascertained psychological fact. This Law is communicated to man by the ‘ categorical imperative’ of conscience, and Virtue, or moral goodness, consists in the adoption by the individual man of the ‘ maxims,’ or concrete universal commands, in which this law expresses itself, as the motives which determine the voluntary choice of the will. As we have seen, however, moral badness is, according to Kant, universally characteristic of mankind, manifesting itself in three stages or degrees which appear to represent three chronologically successive phases of the individual’s growth. The first degree of moral badness is designated as ‘frailty’ or ‘weakness’ (Gebrechlichkeit), in which man recognises the authority of the good maxims but is unable to follow them, owing to the strength of his sensual nature. This condition seems to correspond exactly to Aristotle’s akpacia which, as we saw, is the moral state described by St. Paul in Rom. vii.2 This is succeeded by the second degree of moral evil, which is ‘impurity’ (Unlauterkeit), in which the individual does indeed conform his conduct to the dictates of the good maxims but from motives other than the only moral motive—namely, the pure desire to obey the moral law precisely and solely because it 7s the moral law. The third and final stage of moral badness, which Kant describes as ‘ depravity ’ (Bosartigkeit), ‘ corruption’ (Verderbtheit), or ‘perversity ’ (Verkehrtheit), is reached when the individual experiences a conscious inclination to adopt as the motives of his conduct maxims which are positively contrary to the moral law (gesetzwidrige). When this state is reached human nature has displayed, in fully developed form, what he a, BREDA O57. 2 Lecture III, p. 145. THE ULTIMATE ‘FALL’ — 499 describes as the innate ‘inclination to evil’ (Hang zum Bésen) or ‘ radical evil.’ These law-contradicting maxims arise out of the sensual nature of man, that is, out of the three primary instincts, egoistic, reproductive, and social. These are, indeed, not bad in themselves—Kant has no sympathy with the Augustinian idea of the essential wicked- ness of normal sex-feeling—and only become relatively bad when the desirability or necessity of their indulgence is exalted into a ‘maxim,’ endowed with such authority that it overrides the maxims arising out of the moral law. This inclination to evil, or tendency to adopt maxims dictated by the sensual nature in preference to those provided by the moral law, is expressly identified by Kant with ‘ original sin,’ as understood by the only theology with which he was acquainted—namely, that of Prussian Lutheranism—though the fact that he uses the curious phrase peccatum originarium + instead of the more usual feccatum originale suggests that his familiarity with the official theology of his country was not much more intimate than his acquaintance with the interior of its churches. So far this exposition of the problem appears to be not unreasonable, though, in the light of modern psychology, we shall naturally demur to the exceedingly abstract and trans- cendental account of the moral law which it embodies and to the attempt to represent the ‘ herd-instinct ’ not as the basis of the moral sentiment, but as something essentially separate from, and independent of, it. These, however, are not fatal objections and need not prevent us from pursuing the immediate object of our enquiry, which is that of examin- ing Kant’s conception of the Fall—that is, the source or ground of the inclination to evil. We must now draw atten- tion to a further element in Kant’s doctrine of original sin, which appears to have been simply taken over from Lutheran- ism without much effort to examine its intrinsic merits, to wit, the idea of ‘ original guilt.’ Never having examined the monuments of Christian antiquity for himself, and taking the Confession of Augsburg for granted as the authoritative formulation of Christian anthropology, in much the same way that Anglican divines have been apt to take the Thirty-nine * p. 34. 500 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN Articles for granted, Kant assumes that we are respon- sible for possessing an evil inclination, and justly deserve censure because of it. But we can only be censured for that which proceeds from the exercise of our own free-will. He therefore arrives at the frankly self-contradictory definition of original sin as a radical evil, inborn in human nature, which is none the less acquired by ourselves. It is doubtless true that the contradiction implicit in this definition is merely the reflection of the antinomy which we discover in our own moral experience, which both presents us with the idea of inborn evil as stronger than our own moral instinct and at the same time afflicts us with the consciousness of responsibility and guilt for every actual sin that we commit. From a philosopher, however, who purports to explain religion within the bounds of mere reason we naturally demand a resolution of this antinomy, and it is in Kant’s attempt to resolve it that we come face to face with his conception of the Fall. The antinomy, we learn, between (a) the consciousness of an irresistible evil inclination and (b) the practically necessary postulate of freedom and responsibility, rests upon the dualism between the phenomenal and the noiimenal self. The phenomenal self, which is the sum of the actual contents of conscious- ness, the totality of the feelings, ideas and volitions which occupy the field of conscious experience, is part of the phenomenal world. It is completely immersed in the time- series, an indisseverable portion of the causal nexus which stretches from eternity to eternity. As such, it is rigidly and utterly determined, and from the point of view of pure reason, which can only legitimately function within the phenomenal sphere, freedom is an illusion. But from the point of view of the practical reason, which is the guide of our moral life, freedom is an indispensable regulative principle which must consequently be assumed to belong to the notimenal self. The contents of consciousness, indeed, are empirical, belonging to the world of sense and change, but consciousness itself, or rather the transcendent ego which is conscious of these contents, belongs to the world of things in themselves, which are the unknown causes of 1 p. 33f. THE ULTIMATE ‘FALL’ 501 phenomena. From this it follows that ‘ original sin,’ or the adoption of sensual maxims as the guiding principles of conduct, is due to a timeless, transcendental act of the notimenal self, and that for Kant is ‘ the Fall’ ; or perhaps it would be more accurate to say that these transcendental acts committed by our noiimenal selves constitute the Falls of man. For the philosopher of K6nigsberg, like Origen in his Alexandrine period,? abandons the idea of one single collective or representative Fall of all humanity, and finds in each man the Adam of his own soul. We will only observe in passing that this emergence of Origenistic ideas after fourteen centuries of obscuration by Augustinianism is not without significance ; though, to avoid the charge of going further than the facts warrant, we must subjoin the quali- fying statements that there is no reason for supposing that Kant had ever read Origen, and that the views of the later thinker differ from those of the earlier in this important respect—that Origen’s Falls, though pre-natal, are strictly in time, whereas Kant’s belong to the intelligible world, in which the form of perception known as time has ex hypothes1 no validity. Such is the first classical attempt to remove the Fall out of the sphere of History into the plane of transcendental truth, and to interpret it as the metaphysical ground rather than the temporal cause of the innate sinfulness of man. Daring as the attempt is, the criticisms to which it is open will be obvious. The conception of a ‘ timeless act’ is one which seems to involve a contradiction in terms—at any rate if the word ‘ act’ be used in that sense which it bears in ordinary usage. For it would seem that an act of the will necessarily implies change, if not in the external world, at least in the agent; it at least involves the idea of a transition on the part of the agent from a previous condition, either of inertia or of differently directed activity; anda transition is a change, and change involves time. The scholastic conception of the being of God as purus actus can hardly be adduced to support or illustrate the conceivability 1 p. 34: ‘ Jene (der Hang zum Bosen) ist intelligibile That, bloss durch Vernunft ohne alle Zeitbedingung erkennbar.’ 2 Lecture IV, pp. 210-219. 502 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN of a timeless act on the part of the human noiimenal self ; because an act which is both an action and a state, an évépyeta axwyotas in which eternal activity and eternal repose are transcended and synthesised, can only be affirmed (if it can be affirmed at all) of the Absolute and Infinite Being Himself, and is not thinkable of the finite and relative selves of men, even when regarded sub specie aeternitatis as members of the intelligible world. If, then, we desire to penetrate deeply into the significance of Kant’s language, so as to elicit from it a meaning which we can make real to ourselves, we seem shut up to one or other of two alterna- tives: either the ‘timeless act’ is merely the intelligible aspect of man’s concrete acts of evil-doing, the fact of actual sin seen, as 1t were, from above by God or by some hypo- thetical supra-temporal observer ; or the term ‘ act’ must in this connexion be taken to be simply equivalent to the term ‘state’ or ‘condition.’ If we choose the former alternative, we are forced to conclude that Kant has totally failed to perform the feat which he has undertaken, namely, that of exhibiting to us the ground of actual sin ; for a mere ‘aspect’ cannot be the ground of the substantive reality of which it is an aspect, and it would seem that on this inter- pretation his alleged ‘explanation’ of the ‘evil heart’ which is present within man reduces itself to a mere feat of terminological jugglery. If, however, we take the term ‘act’ to be simply the equivalent to the word ‘state,’ we are led to conclusions which are at first sight equally disap- pointing, though they contain a lesson which will in the long run prove a helpful contribution towards the development of our argument. If actual or ‘ derivative’ sin (peccatum derivativum) is the baneful efflorescence in time of an eternally evil state of the soul, it must not be forgotten that the ‘ categorical imperative’ of duty also springs from the timeless essence of the notimenal ego. It would seem, therefore, that evil and good exist side by side as eternally necessary principles in the intelligible world, to which the human soul in its higher aspect belongs. In other words, a very few logical steps have landed us in a highly refined philosophic Manicheism. Kant’s attempt to lift the Fall out of the temporal order either amounts to nothing at all, THE ULTIMATE “FALL” 503 beyond mere verbal gymnastics, or it involves us in precisely that Iranian dualism which is intolerable to the Christian who starts from the Biblical idea of God as infinite both in power and in goodness. It is possible that this conclusion might not have appeared particularly disastrous to Kant, inasmuch as for him God, like Freedom and Immortality, is merely a regulative principle, which the necessities of the moral life compel us to assume as a working hypothesis, but which cannot merely on that account be certainly known to correspond to any reality. But, for the Christian, to whom God is a luminously self-evident fact of immediate experience, whose yearnings are summed up in the words of the Psalmist, ‘ Whom have I in heaven but thee ? and there is none upon earth that I desire in comparison of thee ’ 1— and for whom it would be impiety to admit the existence of an evil power co-ordinate and co-eternal with God, these speculations will stand condemned as soon as they are formulated or uttered. We pass to the consideration of the second great classical attempt to provide religion with a purely metaphysical, as opposed to a historical, conception of the Fall. This is expounded, not systematically but by way of frequent allusion, in the third part of Hegel’s Philosophy of Religion.? The problem of the moral struggle which, as we nave seen, is the fundamental psychological fact which has given birth to all doctrines of ‘ original sin,’ ‘ radical evil,’ or ‘ inherited infirmity,’ is expressed by Hegel in his common dialectical form of a superficially contradictory pair of propositions. The thesis runs ‘ Man is good by nature’; there is in him at least the promise and potency of harmony and interior peace. Corresponding to this we have the antithesis ‘Man is by nature bad’ ; in actual life we see that hé follows his passions and impulses even when he knows that their indulgence is harmful to himself. The synthesis is obtained by referring the inherent goodness of man to his notion or essence, and his badness to the conditions of concrete existence upon this 1 Ps. xxiii. 24. 2 Philosophie der Religion, 3. Theil (Die absolute Religion), § II (Das Reich des Sohnes): G. W. F. Hegel’s Werke, Berlin, 1832, Band xii. pp. 204 ff. 504 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN planet. In the words of Dr. J. E. McTaggart, ‘ Hegel’s doctrine of Original Sin is that man in his temporal existence on earth has in his nature a contingent and particular element, as well as a rational and universal element, and that while his nature is good in respect of the second it is bad in respect of the first.’ Now this necessary evil which belongs to man’s concrete nature appears to be inherent in his existence as man at all; for, although the ‘ notion’ of man is good, it is only good potentially, and in order that this notion may realise itself it must necessarily pass into a condi- tion of separation from, and consequently opposition to, the absolute system in which, as notion, it inheres. Hence the natural or animal condition of man prior to education and moral discipline—a condition usually described as ‘ inno- cence ’—is evil precisely because it is natural; and, indeed, innocence on this showing is the greatest evil of all. Actual sin is indeed wrong, because it represents a deliberate purpose to remain in the animal stage after the possibility of a higher development has dawned upon the individual man ; but it is less evil than innocence, which means ‘ incapability of moral choice.’ To choose wrong, therefore, is, according to Hegel, better than not to choose at all, and the choice of right is, apparently, only possible after and by means of previous choice of wrong. The advance from innocence to virtue can only be through sin, because ascent from innocence can only be obtained by means of knowledge, and knowledge reveals the possibility of sin. A quotation will make this conception as plain as it is capable of being made. It is knowledge which first brings out the contrast or antithesis in which evil is found ; the animal, the stone, the plant, are not evil. Evil is first present within the sphere of knowledge; it is the consciousness of independent Being, or Being-for-self relatively to an Other, but also relatively to an object which is inherently universal in the sense that it is the notion or rational will. It is only by means of this separation that I exist inde- pendantly for myself, and it is in this that evil lies. To be evil means, in an abstract sense, to isolate myself.? 1 Studies in Hegelian Cosmology (1901), p. 232. 2 op. cit. (Berlin edition, xii. p. 216): ‘ Die Erkenntniss ist erst das Setzen des Gegensatzes, in dem das Bose ist. Das Thier, der Stein, die Pflanze ist nicht bése, das Bose ist erst innerhalb des Kreises der Erkennt- THE ULTIMATE (RALRL© 505 Despite the elusive phraseology in which it is enshrined, this sequence of thought seems fairly clear. Evil is due to knowledge, and a pre-condition of knowledge is that separa- tion of the individual man from the rest of the universe which is involved in his coming into being at all. But moral evil is nevertheless not so objectionable as mere innocence; for a man who has committed sin has, in the words of Dr. McTaggart, ‘ at least started on the only road which can eventually lead him upwards.’ 4 It is not surprising to find that Hegel, whilst considering that the Paradise-story of Gen. i. embodies a profound truth, regards the so-called Fall there narrated (or supposed to be narrated) as having been in reality a successful climb. When the Tempter promised man knowledge as the result of sin, he told the exact truth. ‘ The Serpent says that Adam will become like God, and God confirms the truth of this, and adds His testimony that it is this knowledge which constitutes likeness to God. This is the profound idea lodged in the narrative.’* For Hegel, then, the creation and the fall of man are identical ; they are simply different ways of describing the same event, and the ‘ Fall’ is also an ascent, for sin is the only road which ultimately leads to virtue. It is hardly necessary to observe that this treatment of sin is diametrically opposed to the Scriptural and Christian teaching, which regards wilful sin as infinitely hateful and loathsome. For the Christian no truly valuable end ever has been attained, or can be attained, by means of sin, which could not have been better attained without it. The acceptance of Hegel’s presentation of the Fall-doctrine would have the effect of transforming Christianity into Gnosticism ; for he presupposes precisely that conception of a non-moral and impersonal Absolute, including both good and evil as moments in its infinite non-entity, which is the niss vorhanden, es ist das Bewusstsein des Fiirsichseins gegen anderes, aber auch gegen das Objekt, was in sich allgemein ist in dem Sinn des Begriffs, des verninftigen Willens. Erst durch diese Trennung bin ich fiir mich und darin liegt das Bése. Bdésesein heisst abstrakt, mich’ ver- emzeln).\\.' tC; 4 op: ctt. p. 234. 2 op. cit. p. 217 (freely translated and compressed). 506 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN basis of Hindu religious thought: and his conception of Redemption bases it upon knowledge.1 Whilst then Kant, if interpreted seriously, leads us straight into the arms of one of the ancient foes of Jewish-Christian monotheism—namely, the dualism of Persia—Hegel hands us over to its other secular antagonist, the non-moral monism of India ; and we are therefore entitled to conclude that the feat which both claim to perform—namely, that of lifting the Fall out of the time-series into some timeless metaphysical plane, whilst yet leaving the rest of the Christian religion essentially intact—is one of which the achievement is in the nature of things impossible. In the world of thought, as in that of action, ‘ Things are what they are, and their consequences will be what they will be. No amount of dialectical ingenuity can nullify or even soften the inexorable rigour of the issue, as it was perceived by the Jews of old with the clearness which comes not of speculative power but of passionate religious devotion. If God is infinite in power, dualism is intolerable, and if infinite in goodness, monism not less so; the origin of evil must therefore be sought in the world of created being, and within the sphere of time? and contingency. We conclude, then, that the attempts made by the two giants of German philosophy, Kant and Hegel, to provide us with a ‘ Fall’ which shall be neither temporal nor con- tingent are, from the point of view of the believer in the Christian God, the God of the Bible and of Jesus, worthless. But a theory which proves to have no intrinsic value may possess an accidental and adventitious importance as a floating cork or straw, revealing the direction of some deep natural current of thought, which invisibly and impalpably determines the conscious speculative tendencies of a given period. I called attention just now to the fact that Kant’s theory of the radical evil in human nature, as grounded upon an incalculable number of wrong decisions made on the 1 op. cit. p. 217: ‘ Die Erkenntniss ist das Princip der Geistigkeit, die aber, wie gesagt, auch das Princip der Heilung des Schadens der Trennung ist.’ 2 On the question whether the Fall-theory involves belief in the ultimate reality of Time, v. infra, p. 523 N. 2. THE ULTIMATE ‘FALL’ 507 supersensible plane by our noitimenal selves—in other words, on millions of separate and individual ‘ falls "—-was reminis- cent of the hypothesis put forward by Origen in his first or Alexandrine period, the hypothesis of a series of individual pre-natal falls.1 I do not know of any evidence for supposing that Kant had ever read Origen, and it is probable that there is no direct relation of dependence between the earlier and the later thinker. But this reproduction by Kant of one aspect of Origen’s thought, fortuitous though it may have been, is symptomatic of much. It means that with the collapse of what had hitherto been the all-powerful Augustinian doctrine, which had for thirteen centuries banked up the stream of Fall-speculation, the main current of thought on this subject tended to find its way once more into the old and long dry channels which had been pro- visionally cut out for it some sixteen centuries previously by the genius of Origen. It is not too much to say that if a single phrase be required for summing up the really pro- gressive and valuable movements of Christian anthropology and hamartiology which took place during the nineteenth century, that phrase must be ‘ Away from Augustine, and back to Origen.’ This tendency shows itself with even greater clearness in what is perhaps the most exhaustive and laborious treat- ment of the Christian doctrine of sin which has ever been published, the monumental treatise written some seventy years ago by the learned Lutheran divine, Dr. Julius Miiller.? Miller realised that there is no strictly historical evidence for the Fall, and that the belief in such an event can only be based upon a priori reasoning, which starts from the fact of the moral struggle. Like Kant he finds the root of original sin in the fact, or supposed fact, that whereas the tendency towards sin is universal, ‘interwoven with human nature and, as it were, rooted therein,’ yet we feel ourselves, and really are, responsible and culpable for its existence. (It will be noticed that Miiller is prevented by his Lutheran orthodoxy from breaking decisively with that indefensible 1 See Lecture IV, p. 2io ff. 2 EK. tr., The Christian Doctrine of Sin, 2 vols., Edinburgh, 1852. 508 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN Augustinian conception of original guilt, which has done so much to confuse and discredit the clear, reasonable, and fundamentally Christian idea of the inherited infirmity.) In order to solve this contradiction, which need never have existed but for Augustine, he follows the guidance of Kant, taking over the dualism which the latter had established between the phenomenal and the notimenal selves. He sees, however, the two difficulties which were raised just now in our critical examination of the Kantian theory— namely, the unintelligibility of the idea of a ‘ timeless act,’ and the lack of any logical ground for the universality of the supposed extra-temporal wrong decision. He therefore endeavours to emend the Kantian theory so as to eliminate both of these flaws. He gets rid of the difficulties inherent in the idea of extra-temporal falls by (in effect) putting the Falls back into the time-series. It is true that so far as words are concerned he strenuously denies that he is doing this ; but it is impossible to attach any other significance to his description of the fall of the individual soul as occurring in a mode of existence which precedes life on this planet. If words have any meaning at all, the tell-tale prefix ‘pbre-’ obstinately resists all attempts to strip it of its tem- poral reference, and we must suppose that the heavenly or noitimenal life from which man has descended, though doubtless in every other way of a transcendental and incomprehensible nature, is nevertheless as completely en- closed in the framework of temporal succession as is the life which we now live in this vale of tears. The second difficulty, that of accounting for what appears at first sight to be the remarkable coincidence that all men have in point of fact made a wrong decision in their pre-natal lives, is accounted for on strictly Origenistic lines. Origen’s solu- tion of this problem, which was noticed in our fourth lecture, and which cannot be denied the merit of considerable 1 Cf. op. cit. ii. p. 400: ‘ This were now a manifest contradiction, if there were not (timelessly) preceding our earthly temporal existence of our personality, as the sphere of that self-decision, by which our moral condi- tion from the beginning is conditioned’; p. 4o1: ‘ the recognition of a primitive fall preceding the individual time-life.’ I have not been able to verify these passages in the original, but I assume that the translator has not done Miller an injustice. TOBE UIA TE RATT 4 509 ingenuity, is this: all men are fallen, and have the tendency towards evil in them, precisely because only those spirits who fell in the heavenly sphere were banished to earth and became incarnate, as human beings. Perhaps it would be more exact to say that only those spirits who sinned venially in the intelligible world become incarnate as men: for Miiller is disposed to believe in the real existence of devils, who must presumably be regarded as spirits who sinned more grievously than those condemned to inhabit human bodies, and who, therefore, have been banished to an even lower plane of existence (a thoroughly Origenistic idea). The spirits who did not make a wrong decision continued, and presumably still continue, to exist in the heavenly sphere as angels. In other words, we are not fallen because we are men; on the contrary, we are men because we are fallen ; and this accounts for the universality of the fallen condition. Miiller’s Lutheranism makes him nervously anxious to disclaim all sympathy with Origenism, but the differences which he discovers between his own theory and that of the Alexandrine thinker do not appear to be of any great moment. He also endeavours, quite unnecessarily from the point of view of logic, to find room for something like a historical fall of Adam and Eve; but, as the supposed historical sin of our first parents must, in accordance with his main theory, be attributed to pre-creational trans- gressions on their part, the story of Gen. i. is really, though he will not admit it, nothing but an otiose excrescence upon the main fabric of his theory. The theory we have just sketched will doubtless appear to many as unnecessarily elaborate and fantastic, and as partaking equally with the old-fashioned scheme of a fall of _ Lucifer, succeeded after an indefinite interval by a fall of Adam, in the nature of mythology. But the theory of a pre-natal Fall of individual souls is not one that can be dismissed at first sight as inherently improbable. It enjoys at the moment a certain measure of popularity as being an element in the fashionable cult of theosophy. A well-known philosophic teacher has declared that, in his opinion, there are no arguments for the immortality of the soul after death which would not equally well establish its pre-existence 510 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN before birth.1 The hypothesis of a number of individual pre-natal Falls certainly seems fully capable of performing that essential function of the Fall doctrine which is its only vaison ad étrve—namely, that of relieving God from responsi- bility for the origin of evil. It is true that the weight of such auctoritas as may be deemed to belong to the language of Scripture, and the almost unanimous consensus of Christian antiquity, is on the side of a single, collective, and racial Fall rather than an undefined number of individual falls ; and, if we were to conclude that this latter conception represents the most probable account of the origin of evil in man, we should necessarily be obliged to revise the defini- tions which we gave of ‘original sin’ in Lecture VII, and substitute for the word ‘ inherited,’ as a qualification of the substantive ‘weakness of will’ or ‘infirmity of herd-complex,’ the adjective ‘innate.’ But the theory of individual falls has never been explicitly condemned by any authority which English Churchmen can recognise as having a right to the august title of oecumenical. It will therefore not be waste of time if we devote a few words to the task of examining this theory in regard to its intrinsic merits. When we are faced by the hypothesis of a pre-natal existence, our first impulse is to ask ‘ What, precisely, is conceived as pre-existing ?’ It is natural to assume that the advocates of this hypothesis mean to assert that the entire human spirit, endowed at least in potentiality with the whole structure of ‘instincts’ and ‘ sentiments’ which was described in our last lecture, pre-existed. But much of this instinctive structure is connected with the functions of the physical organism, and would be meaningless and purposeless apart from it. And all of it, in the generalised form under which we sketched it, is ordinarily assumed by psychology to be given by heredity; the old controversy between creationism and traducianism which we noticed in our review of patristic opinion has for all practical purposes ended in the victory of the latter.2 If this assumption 1 Dr. J. E. McTaggart, Some Dogmas of Religion (1906), ch. iv.‘ Human pre-existence,’ p. 113. For other supporters of or sympathisers with the doctrine in recent times, see W. R. Inge, The Philosophy of Plotinus (1918), it; D.3ts a°v. supra, Lecture ITV, p.'237 n. 3. TARE ULTIMATE. PAL 511 of psychology corresponds to fact—and in the absence of direct evidence to the contrary it is reasonable to assume that it does—we can only conclude that nothing of the soul existed before its birth into this world except a pure form, empty of any content, an ego which possessed merely the potentiality of self-consciousness without any self of which to be conscious. It is difficult to see how such a naked and vacuous pre-existent ego, with no instincts to control, and no sentiments to resist or modify, could ‘ sin’ at all, or how such an abstract pre-existence differs from that merely ) ideal existence in the thoughts of God which will be con- ) ceded to all souls even by the most convinced supporters — | of a historic Adam. It would, then, seem that, if we are to\, make the conception of a pre-natal sin intelligible at all, we must regard the pre-existent soul as a monad or atom of soul- } stuff, containing the potentiality of its fully developed adult | structure, much as the acorn contains the germ and potency’: of an oak. This, of course, means that the conception of heredity in every department of life is a pure illusion, and that the apparent transmission of such qualities as (to quote two instances at random) mathematical genius or moral imbecility from parent to child is really due to a ‘ pre- established harmony ’ between the developmental capacities of a pair of successively incarnate monads. This is no doubt a thinkable theory; it is always possible to substitute a pre-established harmony for direct causation in all spheres of thought, from the most abstract and ideal down to the most brute and mechanical, given sufficient determination and ingenuity ; just as it would probably still be possible to explain the apparent movements of the heavenly bodies in accordance with the Ptolemaic astronomy, given unlimited liberty to employ an indefinite number of cycles and epi- cycles. But, though such a hypothesis is not inherently impossible, it becomes inconceivably cumbrous and com- plicated the moment any attempt is made to explain human history in accordance with it; and it is not illegitimate to suggest that William Occam’s ‘razor,’ which cuts at the root of all unnecessary multiplication of entities, will prove to possess an equally trenchant edge when turned against the indefinite multiplication of causalities. 512 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN It may be further urged against this theory that it involves a view of human life and conditions of existence on this planet so profoundly pessimistic as to make us doubt whether the hypothesis of pre-natal falls has not already tumbled into that abyss of Manicheism, on the edge of which, as we have already seen, the doctrine of original sin is perpetually trembling. According to the Hebrew Scriptures the world, as God made it, is good, and a pleasant thing it is to behold the sun ; but according to the ‘ pre-natal’ theory, this life is a purgatory and a tearful prison-house, in which the soul expiates a sin of which she no longer possesses even the bare memory; and it is difficult to see how Christian parents could rejoice that a man is born into the world if they were under the necessity of regarding their new-born offspring as a small culprit who had just been banished from the intelligible sphere in consequence of some gross defiance of the majesty of God. Whilst, therefore, we are not prepared to pronounce dogmatically that Origen’s first theory as revived by Julius Miiller is inherently impossible, or directly unorthodox, its melancholy implications and its complicated structure justify us in leaving it on one side, and in searching for some theory which will both be free from these objections and also will be more harmonious with the general tenor of Scripture and tradition, and with our instinctive consciousness of the essential, and not merely accidental, unity and solidarity of the human race. For the sake of clearness we will briefly resume the substance of our argument up to this point. We saw that the collapse of the rigid Augustinian system naturally brought about a reversion, conscious or unconscious, to the Origenistic method of dealing with the problem of the Fall, and a concentration of interest upon the ultimate trans- cendent origin of evil rather than upon the first of its mani- festations in human history, the so-called Fall of Man. But our examination of the theories propounded by Kant and Hegel showed that for believers in the Biblical and Christian idea of God, which I have assumed, without apology, all through these lectures, even this ultimate fall must still be conceived as a member of the time-series ; for any attempt ‘to lift the ultimate origin of evil out of Time THE ULTIMATE ‘FALL’ 513 plunges us into the gulfs either of dualism or of unmoral monism. And we have just seen reason for regarding the hypothesis which polarises the Fall into an indefinite multiplicity of pre-natal individual falls as open to grave suspicions of the same nature. Of the conceptions, there- fore, which have emerged in the course of our enquiry, that which seems to offer the most attractive field for our explora- tion is the conception of a collective fall of the race-soul of humanity in an indefinitely remote past.1_ But this tentative adumbration of a conclusion probably represents the most we can extract with safety from the purely a priovz trains of reasoning of which we have made use so far; and at this juncture it will be well to change our method of approach to the problem, and see if body and substance can be given to this attractive vision by means of a posterior: evidence, derived from an examination of the world as we actually know it to be, in the light of that Darwinian revolution in thought and knowledge which the eyes of the great German philosophers were never destined to see. If, then, we turn our backs on the fascinating but mysterious realm of metaphysics, and bend our gaze upon that vast evolutionary panorama in which the history of this planet and of our race has been depicted by the genius of modern science, we shall naturally concentrate our attention, first of all, upon the facts which have now been ascertained about the origin of man, in so far as they are relevant to our purpose. In this connexion, it is unnecessary to do more than repeat an observation already made, namely, that Augustinianism, with its theory of a Paradisal condition of original perfection, cannot possibly be dove- tailed into the picture of a gradual ascent from gross and brutish beginnings which is given us by geology and biology.? 1 Coleridge seems to hint at some such theory when he speaks of a ‘ Spiritual Fall or Apostasy antecedent to the formation of Man’ (Azds to Reflection, London, 1836, Aphorism X, p. 285). 2 Mr. H. J. T. Johnson (Anthropology and the Fall, 1923), writing from the Roman Catholic standpoint, does not attempt to adduce any positive evidence for the hypothesis of ‘ original righteousness,’ and is content to argue that science has not disproved the essential positions of Latin theology with regard to the state of the first men, positions which for him are based upon revelation. But, in the last resort, his only ground for thinking that the alleged ‘ revelation’ 7s arevelation is the authority of the Roman Church. 2L 514 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN Few Christian thinkers will now attempt to identify the protoplast of Augustine’s imagination with the original owner of the Piltdown skull, none with fithecanthropus evectus. In so far as the traditional Christian doctrine of man involves any affirmation about the historic state of the first men at all, it is clear that the only version of this doctrine which has the faintest chance of surviving in the modern world is that taught by the primitive Greek Fathers, which regards the protoplast as a babe, a frail, undeveloped, ignorant creature, and views the first human sin rather as a praevaricatio—a stepping-aside from the true line of upward progress—than as a /apsus or fall from a high level of moral and intellectual endowment.t But this conception of a ‘ first sin ’’ needs somewhat closer examination than we have hitherto been able to devote to it. It is very doubtful whether, if we could travel back into the past, on some Time- machine, like that imagined by Mr. H. G. Wells, and observe the whole history of the origins of our race—from a point in Time at which it was certain no human creature existed upon the earth at all, to the point (let us say) at which the race of Neanderthal finally disappeared before the conquering march of the men of Cromagnon—we should be able to lay our finger upon any one single event which could be described as a ‘first sin’ at all. The idea of sin presupposes the existence both of self-consciousness and of a developed moral sentiment, built up upon that primitive ‘ herd-instinct’ of which the deficiency constitutes the innate infirmity ; and the development of both of these cardinal facts, self- consciousness and the moral sentiment, must have been such a slow, gradual and continuous process, that even if we possessed the fullest knowledge in regard to its actual course it would still appear entirely arbitrary to draw a line across it and label all acts disapproved of by the ‘ herd’ as non- moral accidents on one side of the line, and as moral offences or ‘sins’ on the other. We can only say that there was a time, doubtless to be counted by aeons, during which the moral consciousness had not dawned on this planet, and that there was—and now is—an age of responsibility, and con- scious ethical obligation. But in regard to the question 1 v. supra, Lecture IV, pp. 253, 302. THE ULTIMATE ‘ FALL’ 518 how the former age passed into the latter, we can only confess ourselves to be totally ignorant; and all analogy suggests that the transition was mediated, not by a sudden flash of moral illumination, succeeded by a single act in which man turned his back upon the new light, but rather by a period of twilight during which the lineaments of the animal slowly melted into the human, the faint glow of potential self-consciousness which smouldered in the brains of our simian ancestors grew in brightness, consistency, and firmness, and the gregarious impulse which had kept the ancient hunting-pack together gradually flowered in the idea of acommunal law and in a rudimentary sense of ethical and tribal obligation. It might be urged as a counterbalancing consideration that the continuity of evolution in no way prejudices the real distinctness of the main stages passed through by the evolving organism, a distinctness which is self-evident if a pair of such phases be mentally held together for purposes of comparison. The process whereby the child grows into a boy, the boy into an adolescent, the adolescent into a man, manifests this precise quality of smoothness and unbroken continuity. It is impossible, except for legal purposes and on the basis of arbitrary convention, to point to a single date in the calendar at which a given individual ceases to be a youth and becomes a man. But, nevertheless, common sense affirms that there is a time after which it is reasonable and necessary to treat a given individual as being, in point of fact, an adult man, though it may not be possible to say exactly when he attained to this status or how long he has enjoyed it. Soit might be urged, with regard to the human race as a whole, that—however long the crepuscular period of semi-humanity and semi-bestiality may have lasted— there must have been a definite date at which it would have been possible for an extra-terrestrial observer to say ‘ Now, at least, whatever it may have been before, this race of advanced biped mammals must be regarded as having become fully self-conscious and morally responsible.’ It would, therefore, be theoretically possible, if we possessed the requisite knowledge, to lay our finger upon some primi- tive action, and say ‘ This, at least, may be certainly desig- 516 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN nated as a moral offence, no matter whether any previous human actions deserve to be so designated or not.’ Even if, however, we admit the theoretical possibility of arriving at some human action which could be labelled, not indeed as the ‘ first sin’ but as the ‘ first known sin,’ such an action must still have occurred far too late in the history of the physical development of our species to be regarded as a ‘ fontal sin’ or as the source of subsequent weakness or corruption. For the possibility of ‘sin,’ as St. Paul has taught us, presupposes the existence of a moral law to sin against !; and the birth of a moral law, consciously recognised as such, must have taken place many thousands of years after the emergence of man as a distinct zoological species. Even if the ‘ monophyletic’ theory of the origin of humanity (that is, the view which regards the whole of man- kind as descended from a single pair of ancestors) be true, it - is impossible to suppose that the first sinner was one of this hypothetical original pair. We must assume that hundreds of generations were born and died upon this planet whilst the dictates of herd-instinct were crystallising into custom, and tribal custom was hardening into law. By the time that the ‘ first known sin’ became possible, the human family must have multiplied and ramified over a great area of the earth’s surface; and the ‘first known sinner,’ if it were possible to establish his identity, must have been, not the original father of mankind, but merely one amongst thousands of brethren and cousins, whom he could only infect by example and not by heredity. Moreover, even if we take into consideration the somewhat fanciful sup- position that the descendants of this primeval sinner may have intermarried with the descendants of his ex hypothest sinless or non-moral brethren, in such a way that the whole body of mankind eventually became polluted by the ever- widening stream of moral infirmity flowing forth from him, we have still to reckon with the fact that such a theory pre- supposes the transmissibility of acquired as distinct from congenital characteristics—a supposition of which the possibility is strenuously disputed by Weismann and his school, and which therefore cannot be regarded as forming 1 Rom. v. 13: ‘ sin is not imputed when there is no law.’ THE ULTIMATE “FALL: 517 a secure foundation for a modern presentation of the theological Fall-doctrine. All these considerations combine to suggest that the first known human sin, even if we could ascertain what precisely it was, would not contain the explanation of subsequent sins ; like them it would refer us beyond itself; it would be not the cause but the first known effect of the ‘ hereditary infirmity.’ In other words, the first human sin, or the first human action which an extra-terrestrial observer could have certainly designated as sin, was not ‘ the Fall ’—it was merely the first result in human history of ‘ the Fall.’ This is a conclusion upon which the three lines of thought which we have been examining—the tendency or direction revealed by the residual (or ‘ Hellenic’) Christian doctrine when stripped of its Augustinian accretions, the movement of metaphysical speculation from Kant to Coleridge, and the general trend of modern empirical and scientific knowledge as — to the origins of man—converge with impressive unanimity. The origin of evil must lie in some catastrophe much more ancient, remote, and mysterious than the first homicide, rape, or theft committed by a palaeolithic savage. If we take ‘Adam’ as a pictorial designation for the hypothetical first human sinner,! we shall see that the Rabbis and the author of 4 Ezra were perfectly right when they said that Adam sinned because he had already got the yé¢er ha-ra‘— the ‘ evil inclination ’"—rooted in him. Cor enim malignum baiulans primus Adam transgressus et victus est. All that basic Christian thought requires us to affirm, and all that modern knowledge permits us to affirm, of the first speci- fically human creatures that trod this earth, is not a Fall but a failure—a failure to ‘move upward, working out the beast,’ a failure to rid themselves of the anachronistic ‘ ape and tiger ’ strain in their blood, a failure to emancipate them- selves from the fatal flaw of deficiency in ‘herd-instinct ’ or gregarious feeling, the flaw of which their developing intellects had made them progressively conscious. It is natural at this point to raise the question whether 1 But see below, p. 526, n. 1, for another possible way of utilising the pictorial concept of ‘ Adam.’ Rt acizra, 111.:21. 518 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN the innate deficiency of herd-instinct on which we have fixed as the root of moral weakness, and which would appear to have been characteristic of man from the moment when he first becomes recognisable as a strictly moral and responsible agent, is to be regarded as having been inherited directly from his pre-human ancestors. There seems no reason for returning an affirmative answer to this question. ‘There is no evidence to show that the hominidae or anthropoid animals, who were the immediate progenitors of the human race, were any less loyal as individuals to the hunting-packs or hordes in which they were associated than the hyenas or the wolves of the present day. The fact is that when we speak of ‘defective herd-instinct,’ we mean ‘ defective ’ relatively to the exacting, penetrating and intimate demands of the modern herd, whether we think of this as Church, or State, or civilised society in general, or the whole world of moral beings summed up in God. What is wrong with the average man, as distinct from the criminal, on the one side, and the saint who has won his way to settled and permanent virtue, on the other, is that although a member of a complex society, which claims the allegiance of his innermost thoughts and feelings, he yet possesses only so much strength of herd-instinct as was sufficient to enable his sub-human ancestors to fulfil the simple and elementary requirements of the primitive horde. Hence, in every age of human development the innate weakness of herd-instinct is relative to existing social conditions, and its immediate origin is to be attributed, not to a deprivation of something which man once possessed, but rather to an arrested develop- ment. Whereas self-consciousness and intellectual power have during the ages increased enormously in scope and clearness, thus revealing more and more opportunities of indulging the instincts connected with self and sex, there has been no corresponding development of the social instinct, or of the moral sentiment which should grow out of it. We can therefore enlarge and enrich our definition of the inherited infirmity by describing it as ‘ arrested develop- ment’ of the herd-instinct. And this conclusion takes us a step further back in our investigation of the origins of evil in man. We must postulate some unknown factor or agency TAEY ULTIMATE RAI’ 519 which interfered to arrest the development of corporate feeling, just when man was becoming man, some mysterious and maleficent influence which cut into the stream of the genetic evolution of our race at some point during the twilit age which separates pre-human from human history. It would seem, then, that the negative pre-condition of sin in man, the pvivatio or mutilation which we have found to consist in relatively defective or atrophied herd-instinct, points to a positive or substantive power which at the moment we can only describe as an unknown ~ representing evil, or the potentiality of evil, as it existed in the nature of things before man was. This provisional conclusion may appear disappointingly vague ; but it must be expected that the more deeply we penetrate into the tunnel of the past and the further we leave behind the daylight of recorded history, the more general and indefinite our judgments are bound to become. The history of man’s immediate ancestors is involved in such obscurity that it throws no light upon the nature of this positive evil factor, and it would seem as though our exploration had been brought to a standstill by a blank wall. If, however, we follow the lead given by the prince and master of all Christian Fall-speculators, the Apostle St. Paul, we shall, I think, be able to find a way round the obstacle It was shown in our third lecture that, for St. Paul, evil in man is closely connected with the pain and suffering and waste of life which reigns in sub-human nature.1 The Apostle, indeed, regards the former as the direct cause of the latter, echoing the Jewish speculations which had sought to explain evil in nature by the naive supposition that the Almighty deliberately infuriated the previously tame and gentle animal tribes in order to provide an uncomfortable environment for man as part of the punishment for his sin. This conception, in its literal form, is impossible for us because we know that the strong preyed upon the weak, that ‘tooth and claw’ were ‘red with ravin,’ and that the ‘ dragons of the prime . . . tare each other in their slime,’ millions of years before our race was born. But it is perfectly possible, and, indeed, necessary, + p. 157: 520 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN given our modern view of man as organic to Nature, to assume a real connexion of a collateral rather than a directly causal nature, and to regard the unknown factor, which intervened in the crisis of the birth of man and held back the natural, proper, and God-designed development of ‘ herd- instinct,’ as being one with the mysterious power which vitiates the whole of sub-human life with cruelty and selfishness. Further light, therefore, though of a dim and wavering kind, may be shed upon the problem by the consideration of extra-human or sub-human evil. The concrete forms assumed by evil amongst our humbler kinsfolk present certain superficial contrasts with the manifestations of sin in man. We cannot accuse them of defective ‘ herd-instinct,’ because great numbers of sub- human species consist of solitary individuals, and are not gregarious at all. Andin those which are associated in packs or herds the gregarious instinct, so far from being defective or atrophied, seems nicely calculated in amount and degree to subserve the necessary purposes of the corporate life, rising in the marvellous complexity of some insect com- munities, such as those of ants, bees, and wasps, to a degree infinitely transcending the most self-effacing patriotisms ever dreamed of by man, and to a point at which the indi- vidual, though physically distinct from its fellows, is psychically no more than a cell in a single self-determining organism. Nor, if we neglect certain comparatively rare phenomena,? does it seem possible to discover in the animal world the type of evil known as sexual; broadly speaking, that remains the shameful prerogative of self-conscious man. The evil that exists in the animal world appears rather to consist in a ruthless egotism which asserts the right on the part of the individual or the species to live at the expense of others, which expresses itself in ferocity and occasionally in what appears to us as unnecessary cruelty. We can only bring this quality under the general head of ‘lack of herd- instinct ’ if we extend the denotation of the term ‘ herd’ to include the totality of organic life, which would be a some- what unnatural expansion of its meaning. It therefore 1 See the authorities quoted by E. Westermarck, The Origin and Development of the Moral Ideas (1908), ii. p. 456, n. I. THES SaIMA TRO opALTY 521 seems better to describe the manifestations of evil in sub- human nature as characterised by the common quality of selfishness, which is the negation of love. Here, it would seem, we have come to close quarters with the unknown mysterious agency, which had dominated the world for aeons before man was, and which suddenly and inexplicably asserted itself, as against the upward-striving powers which co-operated in the making of man, in the very crisis of his birth, partially repressing and strangling that instinct towards fellowship and social harmony of which the due development was necessary in order that his personality might attain to that perfect poise and proportion which the Creator meant it to possess. Employing the indefinite language which is all that the obscurity of the subject allows, we seem to see, lying behind all forms of evil, human and animal alike, a single, deeply lying principle which manifests itself mainly amongst the brutes as the ruthless self-assertion of one herd against another, but in man, with his developed self-consciousness and his more intense individuality, as the self-assertion of the individual against the herd, a principle which we can only designate by the inadequate titles of selfishness, lovelessness, and hate. The question may be raised at this juncture, whether it is legitimate to employ terms such as these, which contain a note of moral censure, in speaking of the behaviour of sub- human organisms. It might be objected that we spoke of man’s non-human ancestors, and indeed of man himself during the early stages of his history, as a distinct zoological Species, as non-moral, a mere bundle of instincts devoid of that governing power which we know as self-consciousness and free-will, and which alone makes possible strictly moral _and responsible action ; and it may be questioned whether we have the right to use such a term as ‘ evil’ in this con- nexion at all. The answer to these questions seems to lie in the consideration that not all evil is sin. We apply the term ‘evil’ to all phenomena which our moral conscious- ness tells us ought not to exist, but we only describe such phenomena as ‘ sins’ if they are due to conscious, voluntary action, if, that is, they are the expressions of evil volitions, which alone can be termed ‘sins’ in the strict sense of the 522 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN word. And, superficially regarded, this consideration may appear to relieve the problem of evil in nature of some of its oppressive weight. There is much evil amongst the brutes, but (with the possible exception of some of those higher animals which, through their domestication by man, seem to have acquired the germ of a moral faculty) they are free from sin. The cat which tortures the mouse by playing with it ; the wasp which deftly stings the living caterpillar in the chief ganglia of its spinal cord, so as to keep it, paralysed, as a store of fresh food for her young; the microbe which destroys a life that might have been the source of un- numbered blessings to the human race; and that most uncanny manifestation of the spirit of evil in nature—the insectivorous plant, which with cold and Mephistophelean ferocity disguises its death-dealing petals in the form of more innocent blossoms so as to allure and entrap its unwary victims: all these perform functions which are evil in the sense that they rouse the detestation of the refined moral consciousness in man; but they are free from guilt, they commit no sin, because they are but blindly following the fundamental law of their being. , Yet the problem is only lightened in appearance, for the guiltlessness of the brutes merely emphasises the apparent guilt of Nature, which has made them what they are. If savagery and cruelty are the expressions of a fundamental law, how evil must be that law, and how deep its discordance with the will of the all-loving Creator revealed by Christ, Who clothes the lilies of the field, and without Whom not one sparrow falls to the ground. If we face the facts candidly, we must admit that no one of us, if he had been in the position of Demiurge, would have created a universe which was compelled by the inner necessity of its being to evolve the cobra, the tarantula, and the bacillus of diphtheria. How, then, shall that God, the infinite ardours and pulsations of Whose love bear the same relation to our weak emotions of sympathy and fellow-feeling as the infinity of His wisdom does to our dim and limited knowledge, have done so? The answer can only be that He did not do so; that He did not create such a universe ; that, in the words of the most ancient scriptures of our monotheistic faith, in the beginning PEE \ULTIMATE BALL 523 ‘God saw every thing that he had made, and, behold, it was very good.’1 To explain evil in Nature, no less than in man, we are compelled to assume a Fall—a revolt against the will of the Creator, a declension from the beauty and glory which God stamped upon His work at the beginning. And, to account for the vast and intimate diffusion of evil, selfishness and hate amongst all the multitudinous tribes of living creatures, we must place this ultimate Fall, which the argument contained in the first part of this lecture compels us to regard as an event in Time, at a point before the differentiation of life into its present multiplicity of forms and the emergence of separate species. We must summon to our aid the great conception first elaborated by the Stoics under the title of the ‘ Logos Spermatikos’ or ! “seminal reason,’ and more recently reformulated, in the © light of modern biological conceptions, by M. Bergson under ! the name of the élan vital, the Life-Force which is the’ immediate ground of our own being as of that of all the multitudinous creatures of the universe. If we can assume that there was a pre-cosmic vitiation of the whole Life-Force, when it was still one and simple, at a point of time? prior to its bifurcation and ramification into a manifold of distinct individuals or entelechies, we shall be in possession of a conception which should explain, so far as explanation is 1 Gen. i. 31. Unfortunately we cannot add, with Goethe’s archangels (in the Prologue to the first part of Faust) : “ Und alle deine hohen Werke Sind herrlich wie am ersten Tag.’ 2 It may be asked at this point ‘ Does such a transcendental Fall- doctrine necessitate the assumption of the ultimate reality of Time?’ The answer would seem to be in the negative. The doctrine of the Fall does, indeed, imply that the created universe is in Time; it may, indeed, be taken to involve the assumption that there is what may be called for human purposes an ‘ absolute’ Time or duration, of which the times relative to different percipients or groups of percipients are imperfect and distorted copies. But such an ‘ absolute Time’ would only be absolute within the realm of created being ; it could have no reference to the eternal Essence of God, Who is the supreme and timeless Reality. The version of the doctrine of the Fall suggested above does not, therefore, involve the attribution of a higher degree of reality to Time than to the created world of which Time is a dimension; it ascribes no more than a phenomenal reality to either; and it is amply consistent with the Platonic and Augustinian position that the world was created, not in Time, but together with Time. 524 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN possible, the continuity and homogeneity of evil throughout all ranks of organised life, from the bacillus up to Man. This remote and mysterious event, and not the compara- tively recent failure of primitive man to escape from already existing evil, would then be the true and ultimate ‘ Fall.’ Such a view of the primeval catastrophe and its effects is vaster, more solemn and more awe-inspiring than that which regards the Fall merely as the affair of our species, and it proportionately increases the scope, the amplitude, and the magnificence of redemption. This conception of the Life-Force permeates much of the cosmological speculation of modern times, appearing as it does not merely in the system of M. Bergson but in the thought of Schopenhauer, as a blind Will or uzsus which is the underlying reality of the universe, and attains to self- consciousness in the minds of men. It follows that theology would be acting in accordance with many precedents pro- vided by the great creative epochs of its own past history if it were, as we suggest, frankly to borrow this conception for the purpose of elucidating and placing on a secure intellectual basis the preliminary assumptions which lead up to the central body of its redemptive scheme. The Catholic Church, which within the first thirty years after Pentecost took over from Philo the great metaphysical conception of the Logos, to be employed as the foundation stone which supports the majestic dome of Trinitarian and Christological dogma, need feel no antecedent difficulties about borrowing this smaller fragment from the philosophy of the present day, to be used in the reconstruction of that outlying porch or narthex in the temple of Christian thought which is con- stituted by the doctrines of Man and of Sin. Such a sub- stitution of the idea of a corruption of the whole cosmic energy at some enormously remote date for the idea of a voluntary moral suicide of Man in comparatively recent times would be no greater a revolution than that which was effected by St. Anselm, when he substituted a satisfactional theory of the Atonement for the view which regarded the death of Christ as a ransom paid to the Devil—a view which had behind it the venerable authority of a thousand years of Christian history. THE ULTIMATE ‘ FALL’ 528 If, however, this conception of the Life-Force is to form part of our reconstructed anthropology, it must be used with a difference. We must make an important addition to it which may, at first sight, appear somewhat startling ; and that is this—we must conceive it as having been at the beginning, when it first sprang forth from the creative fecundity of the Divine Being, free, personal, and self- conscious. This follows from the conception of its rebellion against God which, as we have seen, is required by the necessities of our theodicy. It is impossible to think of an impersonal force as rebelling against a Creator of infinite wisdom and power. In the case of Man, indeed, we often see the mighty natural forces which he has harnessed for his convenience escaping from his control and running amok in blind destructiveness. But such disasters are due to the limitations of Man’s knowledge or of his powers of attention. We cannot save God’s goodness at the expense of His wisdom, or regard the Creator in the light of an inexpert electrician who has inadvertently released a powerful current into channels which cause it to burn and destroy instead of lighting and warming. The necessities of safe- guarding the Biblical conception of God, no less than the intellectual obligation to avoid an infinite regress, compel us to place the origin of the perversion of the Life-Force in some point of spontaneity, some uncaused cause, lying within its own being ; and the moment that we have done this, the moment that we have attributed to it an uncaused causality, we have made it personal. Hence, if our revised Fall-doctrine is to be intelligible at all, the ‘ Life-Force’ becomes for us the World-Soul, the ‘ only-begotten Universe ’ of Plato’s Timaeus, which, for its excellence, was able to be company to itself and needed no other, being sufficient for itself as acquaintance and friend.t Like the Attic Moses, we must assume that God, the Father of all things, created this conscious Life-Force or anima mundi, replenished (with the potentiality of) all mortal and immortal creatures, living and visible, containing all things that are visible, the image of its Maker, most mighty and good, most fair and perfect.2, And here, rather than with regard to any sup- 1 Timaeus, 34 B. 2 tbid. 92 C. 526 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN posed condition of palaeolithic man, the idea of ‘ original righteousness ’ may be usefully employed. The World-Soul, then, was created good ; but, our theory must continue, at the beginning of Time, in some transcen- dental and incomprehensible manner, it turned away from God and in the direction of Self, thus shattering its own interior being, which depended upon God for its stability and coherence, and thereby forfeiting its unitary self- consciousness, which it has only regained, after aeons of myopic striving, in sporadic fragments which are the separate minds of men and perhaps of superhuman spirits. It is not necessary to assume, with Plotinus and Gregory of Nyssa, that the existence of our limited and imperfect conscious- ness represents a f7s-alley, an unsatisfactory substitute for the one first-created world-consciousness ; if speculation may be carried so far, we may surmise that the cosmic consciousness was meant from the beginning to develop within itself smaller individual consciousnesses without in any way prejudicing its own unity, and so that if it had developed in accordance with the plan pre-ordained by its Creator, it would have been the ideal society or community, endowed with a corporate mind which would have trans- cended, without mutilating or repressing the minds of its 1 It will not have escaped the reader’s notice that the speculative re- construction of the Fall-doctrine suggested in the text bears certain resemblances to that expounded by St. Gregory of Nyssa in de hom. opif., and commented on in Lecture IV, pp. 270 ff. Our ‘World-Soul’ corresponds to his ‘ archetypal man,’ numerically one and endowed with original perfection ; though of course the World-Soul must be conceived as including the potentiality of all life, supra- and sub-human as well as human. On occasions when the use of pictorial language is pedagogically desirable, there seems no reason why the World-Soul should not be described as ‘ Adam,’ ‘ the Man,’ DN: the assertion of the ‘ original righteousness ’ of ‘ Adam’ would thus cease to be a mere Rabbinical figment, and would become a mythological way of expressing a necessary inference from ethical monotheism. The Greek fancy of an extra-terrestrial or even metaphysical‘ Paradise’ (v. supra, pp. 193, 216) might also be re-utilised in an allegorical presentation of our theory. And, like Gregory, we regard the break-up of the intellectual unity of the general Soul as due to the Fall, though (as stated above) we are very far from regarding multiplicity as in itself evil, and have no sympathy with his semi-Manichean view of sex. The affinity of our conception with the ideas of Origen will be obvious ; and the last paragraph of this lecture suggests the kind of ‘ Recapitulation ’-theory to which it would naturally lead up. La OLEATE PATE 527 individual members. On this supposition it would seem natural to suppose that the Fall wrecked the unity of the world-consciousness, reducing the cosmic soul to a stream of blind and internally discordant effort, and delaying for _ millions of years the appearance of conscious individual personalities. In our own infirm wills and circumscribed intelligences, and in the efforts which our race has made to develop sympathy and fellowship through families, tribes, nations, and the still shadowy and embryonic World-State or League of Nations, we may trace the instinctive strivings of the dissociated World-Soul to recover, in all its noonday brightness, the unitary self-consciousness that it had at the beginning. However this may be, we can at least feel sure that this interior self-perversion, which we have hypothetically attributed to the collective Life-Force which was God’s primal creature—this orientation away from God and in the direction of ruthless self-assertion—would necessarily mani- fest itself in a development of organic life permeated through and through with the spirit of selfishness, manifested in ferocious competition and in a bloodthirsty struggle for existence. It might a priov have been expected to appear in the cruelty which ravages the animal world, in the unknown maleficent factor which hindered the due de- velopment of herd-instinct just when the anthropoids were becoming men, and in the mysterious ebullitions of pure fiendishness which, within the sphere of responsible human action, are known as ‘criminality.’ If, in harmony with later Jewish and primitive Christian thought, and with the consensus of those who are known as‘ spiritual experts’ in every age of the newer dispensation, we are prepared to admit the existence of evil discarnate intelligences, it would doubtless follow that the malevolent nature of such , beings was to be regarded asthe outcome of the pre-mundane* Fall of that World-Soul, of which they, equally with men and beasts, would be the offspring. A place could thus be found in this provisional scheme for the idea which has been expressed in mythological form as the Fall of Lucifer and the apostate angels ; though on this showing the fall of the angels would be parallel to and collateral with the fall, or 528 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN rather the failure, of Man, and need not be (though we know too little about these matters to deny that it may have been) its direct cause or chronological antecedent. For such a hypothesis it may be claimed that, if we are prepared to make allowances for the vagueness and the indefiniteness of its outline, and for the many lacunae which the imperfection of our knowledge, and the uncertainty of a priori speculation, render inevitable, it explains better than any other existing theory the existence and the wide diffusion of evil in a universe which, as Christians, we believe to have been created by an all-powerful, all-wise, and all-loving God. And for those who recognise that a religion which claims to be ‘ Catholic’ or universal, in an intensive, as well asin an extensive, sense, is thereby endowed with the right, and subject to the duty, to make use of categories and thought- forms drawn from any source for the elucidation of its fundamental ideas, it will not appear an objection to this view that it has certain affinities with the thought of the great Neo-Platonist and mystic Plotinus, who makes the World-Soul, the divine fuy7, the third member of his Trinity. But, in the light of the Christian revelation, we are con- strained to diverge decisively from him with regard to two points. Inthe first place, the World-Soul for us is a created being, not an element in, a part of, or a necessary emanation from, the Godhead. This position is so _ self-evidently involved in those Biblical conceptions of God as Creator and as infinitely good, which have been taken for granted all through this discussion, that I need not dilate upon it further. Secondly, whereas Plotinus seems to find the origin of evil in the wilful self-detachment of the human soul from the World-Soul,1 we find the Fall in the voluntary deviation of the World-Soul from conformity with the will of the Creator; and we cannot but feel that if Plotinus and Origen had possessed our modern realisation, induced by the scientific study of nature, of the vast diffusion of evil outside of, and apart from, the realm of specifically human life, they would have been constrained to agree with us in enlarging 1 Cf. Enn. i. 8, 4, ad fin. For Plotinus’ not always consistent views with regard to the descent of the soul, and its relation to the Universal Soul, see W. R. Inge, The Philosophy of Plotinus, i. p. 254. 7 THE ULTIMATE ‘ FALL’ 529 the subject of the Fall, that is, the personal being who fell, beyond the confines of Man, individually or collectively regarded, until it becomes conterminous with the totality of organic life. Yet though for us the World-Soul is erring and sinful, created and not divine, we are constrained by the historic Christian revelation to recognise a certain profound and intimate connexion between the created Life-Force of the universe and the eternal Logos of God, the express image of His substance, Who upholds all things by the word of His power and in Whom all things consist. This connexion was meant to consist in the continuous penetration, inspiration, and guidance of the created anima mundi by the Almighty and uncreated Logos: and the rebellion of the former has not banished the patiently working, healing, and refining influences of the latter. Even in marred and vitiated Nature much goodness still survives; many of the dumb beasts may well put our arrogant race to shame by their gentleness, their humility, their love of their offspring, their devotion to their human masters. Such facts as these may embolden us to believe that, long ages before man was, the Spirit of Christ was at work in the world, sustaining the blinded Life-Force, which otherwise would have lapsed into nothingness, fostering within it the potentialities of good- ness and love, combating those elements which made for selfishness and cruelty, and leading it slowly and gently | back towards the recovery of its original harmony, peace, - and unified self-consciousness. And when the cosmic Soul had so far progressed along the upward path as to be able to find expression in Man, the eternal Logos was present in his birth, assisting and inspiring the growth of reason, will, and social or gregarious feeling. Nor, when our race had finally failed to extricate itself from the pre-existing stream of selfish tendency, and was seen still to bear within it, deeply stamped upon its fundamental plasm, the lack of love and weakness of social instinct which were the legacy of the primal Fall, did the immanent Word of God withdraw from it His interior inspiration: the long line of pre-Christian prophets, saints, and sages, in whom the fire of man’s highest aspirations has shone with clear and steady flame, 2M 530 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN testifies to the benign and pervasive influences of that Light which lighteth every man, as it cometh into the world. In the fullness of time, the gracious Power which had guided man so far deigned to enter into an even closer bond with our race, and through it with the fallen World-Soul, by uniting humanity to His divinity : And so the Word had breath, and wrought With human hands the creed of creeds. Yet not by mere example, or by ‘loveliness of perfect deeds’ alone did He design to heal the inherited weakness of human nature, but also by forming a sacramental society which would be the extension of His personal being, within which the defect of love, of social feeling, of gregariousness, of ‘herd-instinct "—it matters not how it be named—might be remedied through the direct transfusion into our souls of His own self-sacrificed life. This is the point to which our revised formulation of the doctrines of the Fall and of Original Sin has naturally led us, and at which we may well be content to leave it. In the completion of the eternal Christ Who all in all is being fulfilled—in that summing up and recapitulation in Him, not only of all humanity but of all forms of created being, in their count- less hierarchical gradations, whether things on earth or things in heaven—all individual spirits will have grown to their full stature, the perfection of their fellowship will express itself in the redintegrated consciousness of the general Soul, the Redemption which is the predestined sequel of the Fall will be for ever consummated, and the regenerated universe, in all its multitudinous members, will know the full meaning of the mystic paradox—‘ O felix culpa, quae talem et tantum meruit habere Redemptorem.’ ADDITIONAL NOTE E Dr. F. R. TENNANT’S ALTERNATIVE THEORY OF THE ORIGIN OF SIN ‘To the evolutionist sin is not an innovation, but is the survival or misuse of habits and tendencies that were incidental to an earlier stage in development, whether of the individual or the DR. TENNANT’S THEORY 531 race, and were not originally sinful, but were actually useful. Their sinfulness lies in their anachronism: in their resistance to the evolutionary and Divine force that makes for moral develop- ment and righteousness.’ 1 These words, quoted by Dr. Tennant from an address delivered to the Church Congress of 1896 by Archdeacon J. M. Wilson, contain nothing which we desire to contradict: though the argument of Lecture VII has endeavoured to supplement them by exhibiting ‘ the evolutionary and Divine force that makes for righteousness ’ as manifested in the growth and development of ‘herd-instinct,’ social feeling, and love. Dr. Tennant, however, (if I have rightly grasped the argument; of his third and fourth Hulsean Lectures,) appears to consider | these words to be, not a statement, but the solution of the problem of the origin of sin. In so far as the empirical uni- versality of sin is a fact, he finds the explanation of this fact in the chronological priority of feeling, impulse, and instinct to conscience in the historical order both of the race’s and of the individual’s evolution. The moral consciousness experiences difficulty and pain in disciplining appetite and impulse, because the moral consciousness itself is a late arrival in the house of human personality. This I take to be the gist of his third lecture, expressed in such a sentence as this: ‘ The foundation from which we start is the fact already asserted of the race and now to be repeated of the individual, that we are natural before we are moral beings, and that the impulses of our nature are in full sway before the moral consciousness begins to dawn’ ? (italics ours). The result of this temporal priority of instinct to the ethical sense is that sin must be regarded as ‘ something empirically inevitable for every man’ though by no means ‘theoretically, or on a priori grounds, an absolute necessity.’ 3 The temporal priority of instinct to conscience is, of course, a fact. But it appears to me that two criticisms may be made upon the contention that this fact constitutes an adequate explanation of a second fact—namely, the empirical universality and practical inevitability of sin. The first criticism is, that this contention ignores the possibility that the two facts in question , may be collaterally related, as effects of the same cause, and ~ need not necessarily stand in a direct causal relation. If there is an evil principle infecting organic life, including human life, it may both have delayed the development of the moral will, 1 Quoted, Origin and Propagation of Sin (Hulsean Lectures) (1902), p. 82. Except where otherwise specified, paginal references given in this Additional Note are to this work. 2 op. cit. Pp. 93. 8 p.110. But, if ‘ empirical inevitability ’ is a fact, must it not be the index and epiphenomenon of an underlying ‘ theoretical necessity’ ? Such at any rate appears to be the assumption of physical science within its own sphere. 532 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN and ensured that the moral will should be relatively weak when at length it did develop. In any case, there seems no a priori reason why temporal posteriority of development should involve weakness ; an omnipotent God presumably might, and could, so have ordered matters that the moral consciousness, when it did appear, should have sprung into existence endowed with the fullest control and power over the animal impulses, like Athene springing fully armed from the head of Zeus. This latter consideration naturally leads to our second criticism, which is that, even if it could be proved that the late emergence of the moral consciousness necessarily involved its practical weakness, Dr. Tennant’s position does not logically -»exempt the Almighty from the responsibility of causing evil, as the Fall-theory (except when combined with ‘ supra-lapsarian ’ predestinarianism +) does. (No theodicy, indeed, that human ingenuity can elaborate will ever exempt Him from the responsi- bility of permitting evil: because He obviously does permit it.) For, on any other than a Deistic view of God’s relation to the world and to human souls, the temporal priority of instinct to conscience, which is alleged to be the source of man’s observed proneness to evil, must (if the Fall-theory be excluded) be attributed to the Divine appointment; that is to say, we must conclude that the will of God immanent in organic evolution has brought man into existence with a secret flaw in his soul which sooner or later betrays him into actual sin. If man’s nature is a ‘ chaos not yet reduced to order,’ and if the hypothesis of a ‘ Fall’ of any kind be ruled out, we can only suppose that man started his career as a ‘ chaos’ because God willed that he should so start; and if this his ‘ chaotic ’ condition involves the “empirical inevitability ’ of sin, then God must be deemed to have laid the foundations of human nature in such a way that sin inevitably results. One sentence in the fourth Hulsean Lecture seems expressly to accept this consequence. ‘ What introspection really discovers is an internal conflict between nature and nurture, natural desire and moral end’: (so far we entirely agree; but the sentence continues) ‘and this is the inevitable condition of human life and the expression of God’s purpose’ 2 (italics ours). If an arrangement which involves the “empirical inevitability’ of sin be really ‘the expression of God’s purpose,’ the human race may well say to its Maker, in the words of FitzGerald: Oh, Thou, who Man of baser Earth didst make, And who with Eden didst devise the Snake, For all the Sin wherewith the Face of Man Is blackened, Man’s Forgiveness give—and take ! 3 1 v. supra, Lecture VI, p. 436f. tn CE 3 Rubdiydt of Omar Khayydm, lviii. DR. TENNANT’S THEORY 533 This consideration is of such importance for the comprehension of the Fall-theory, and also (as it appears to me) so decisive against the sufficiency, from a theistic and Christian point of view, of Dr. Tennant’s ‘ alternative hamartigeny,’ that I make no apology for insisting upon it at some length. ‘ Anachronisms,’ or ‘ chronological misfits,’ are not accepted by the mind as self- caused or self-explanatory, i in any department of human affairs. If an antiquated law or-institution lingers on in the State after its original usefulness has departed, needlessly causing friction between classes or wasting the resources of the community, we do not record the judgment ‘ This is an anachronism, and there is no more to be said’; on the contrary, our comment is ‘ This is an anachronism, and the Government, or Parliament, is very much to blame for not having abolished or reformed the law or institution in question when the conditions which originally justified it ceased to exist.’ The idea of an ‘ anachronism’ seems logically to involve the idea of some conscious agent’s (more or less) culpable neglect of his duty as its cause, though the more harmless the anachronism, the less culpable the neglect which has produced it. Now it is a not uncommon practice to apply the term ‘ anachronism’ to certain vestigial and now useless structures in man’s physical organism: Dr. Tennant himself instances ‘the troublesome wisdom tooth and the dangerous caecum.’*+ If the term ‘anachronism’ is seriously ‘ used in this connexion, it implies a teleological view of the universe as its background, and prima fa jacié involves a note of censure, or quasi-censure, on the power or powers responsible for the continued existence of the ‘anachronistic’ structure— a power which may for the moment be vaguely described as‘ ‘Nature’ (natura naturans). When disease arising from such a source brings pain or death to some dear one, the most im- passive philosopher may well experience a moment’s indignation against the apparent negligence of ‘ Nature,’ whose irresistible pressure compels men to adopt changed modes of life, without simultaneously effecting the necessary modifications of their physiological organism. The thoughtful believer in Christian theism will naturally de- mand an explanation of the existence of such cruel anachronisms in a world which he has been taught to believe was created and is sustained by an all-loving and merciful God; he will no more take them for granted, as self-explanatory, than the his- torical student takes political anachronisms for granted. Our own explanation has been generally indicated in Lecture VIII ; to the poet who cries ‘ Are God and Nature then at strife?’ we answer ‘ Yes, to a large extent; because of the pre-mundane rebellion against God of that which men have called the Logos 1 The Concept of Sin (1912), Pp. 147. 534 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN Spermatikos, the World-Soul, natura naturans, the élan vital, the Will to live.’ Underlying all the evil in physical nature we suppose vitiated streams of the disintegrated Life-Force, par- ticular entelechies or idées-forces (to quote Fouillée’s pregnant term) which owing to the primal catastrophe have become forces of sloth, of cruelty, or of death. Such a view at least relieves ‘God of the responsibility for the origination of physical evil, though not from that of originating its possibility and tolerating its actuality. But it appears that Dr. Tennant’s view does not claim to do so much. Speaking of the relative independence vis-a-vis of God and of its fellow-creatures which he attributes to the human self, he observes ‘ It is compatible with solidarity in sin and penalty, and does not necessitate that the ills of the creature are events wholly external to the life of the Creator, though indeed their sins are—so that “‘ the Creator has fashioned suffering in which He Himself has no share and of which He is independent.” ’ 4 The sentence is vaguely expressed; but, if we are justified in arguing from its verbal form, it would seem to imply that ‘the ills of the creature’ (physical ills are presumably meant) are at least partly included in ‘the life of the Creator,’ in a way in which men’s sins arenot. And, a little further on, it is suggested ‘that physical evils, though not ‘ direct expressions of the will of God,’ are yet ‘necessarily incidental’ to His ‘plan of realising His end,’ or ‘inevitable bye-products of the. . . course of nature.’2 But is it possible to relieve God of responsibility for ‘necessary,’ even though ‘ incidental,’ consequences of His own plan? Surely it would not have been beyond the resources of Omniscience to devise another plan, which would not have mecessarily involved such consequences as cancer or syphilis? ‘In human justice a man is held to intend the necessary, reasonably foreseeable, and foreseen consequences of his acts, even though he may urge that the idea of such consequences was not the motive which prompted the acts or a ‘ direct expression’ of his will: and a'theodicy can hardly be conducted on laxer principles than those which prevail in earthly courts. I venture to suggest that, so far as physical evil is concerned, Dr. Tennant despite ‘the subtlety and brilliance of his dialectic has not really succeeded in evading the ancient dilemma ‘ Ezther there has been a “‘ Fall”’ of some kind, ov God must be deemed to be the author of evil,’ and that though he refuses to admit the fact, he is really impaled upon its latter horn. But if physiological anachronisms of such a kind that they produce disease or death must be regarded either as the conse- quences of a ‘ Fall’ or as the products of the Divine will, there is at least a strong presumption that the same holds good of the PDT 20) 0 Ace Dp $2.0 S45 DR. TENNANT’S THEORY 535 psychological anachronisms which predispose man to sin. They must be due to some cause: that cause ex hypothesi does not lie in the will of the individual man who suffers from them—the bully in whom the combative instinct is endowed with a degree of strength, which would have been appropriate and useful in a Pleistocene anthropoid but is useless and dangerous in a member of modern civilised society, has clearly not willed this anachron- istic quality of hisnature. And what cause of such anachronisms can be or ever has been suggested, by believers in monotheism, other than the will of God or a primal rebellion of some created will or wills against the will of God? Those who reject both of these alternatives are surely under an intellectual obligation to produce a third explanation: and this it appears to me that Dr. Tennant has failed to do. Dr. Tennant has laid Theology at large under an immense obligation by the courage with which, following in the steps of Julian and Scotus, he has proclaimed the moral neutrality of/ appetite (the fomes peccati) as such, thereby sweeping away at one blow the endless confusions which clustered round the word “concupiscence’; and by insisting that the word ‘sin’ means, not a psychological state nor yet a forensic status, but an act committed with full and conscious deliberation in defiance of a known law. To criticise the constructive views of one who can claim the credit of such far-reaching and permanently. valuable achievements may well appear to many minds in the light of presumption. Yet I must needs think that the argu- ment of Dr. Tennant’s third and fourth Hulsean Lectures, eloquent and persuasive though it is, obscures the real logic of the matter, which, I suggest, is perfectly simple. So far as sin is capable of a genetic explanation at all, there are four possible explana- tions and four only: namely (1) monism, (2) dualism, (3) Pelagian- ism, (4) the theory ofa‘ Fall’ ofsome kind. Dr. Tennant rejects the fourth, and, even more emphatically, the second of these! ; but I venture to think that, when rigorously analysed, his own explanation will be found to amount, not to a fifth theory, but to an inconsistent combination of the first and third (monism < and Pelagianism). When he tells us that an ‘inevitable condi- tion of human life,’ which involves the ‘ empirical inevitability of sin,’ is ‘ the expression of the Divine purpose,’ 2 he is speaking as a thoroughgoing monist; when he removes the Divine; control from a great part of the world-process, and describes | many events as having no teleological import? and as mere: ‘incidental results’ or ‘ bye-products’ of the Divine plan, he at least approximates to the Deistic view of God which is 1 p. 135. Seu LBs 8 p. 130: ‘. .. the incidental nature of much that happens in God’s world, and from which teleological import is excluded.’ ’ 536 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN inseparable from the Pelagian view of man?!; when he asserts that ‘the actuality of sin is derived solely from the individual will influenced by its social environment’ ? and that ‘ the con- tents of man’s moral life and the quality of his character are ... the results of his own determination according to his opportunities,’ 2it is difficult to interpret his words otherwise than as expressing the complete indeterminism and the ethical atomism on which the thought of Pelagius and Julian was based. Nevertheless, there is one sentence in the fourth Hulsean Lecture which, if allowed its fullest meaning, seems to concede the whole principle for which we have been contending. ‘ Man’s condition denotes, on our theory of sin, a fall [italics ours] from the divine intention, a parody of God’s purpose in human history, though not a fall from an actual state of original righteousness.’ 4 With regard to the last clause, it need only be said that we have already repudiated the idea of the original righteousness of the first concrete human individuals as unhistorical. But the statement that man’s present condition denotes a ‘fall’ from God’s intention presumably means that the idea of Man, as conceived in the Divine mind from all eternity, included the idea of a perfect moral character; that ‘original righteousness,’ though its attribution to any generation of our remote semi- brutish ancestors is mythological, may yet be ascribed to the Ideal or Archetypal Man as existing in the intelligible world ; and that the human race, as we know it in the world of time and sense, represents a grave declension or ‘ fall’ from the eternal pattern of manhood laid up in the heavens. Two logical steps forward (neither of them very difficult) from this position would bring Dr. Tennant into complete accord with the general Fall- conception vaguely adumbrated by Gregory of Nyssa, and set out in our last lecture. The first of these steps consists in the hypo- . statisation and personalisation of the archetypal Idea, and in the - reference to its conscious self-determining activity of the cause of the declension from perfect righteousness manifested by the human race as we know it ; the second, in expanding the content of the Idea so that it becomes the Idea not of humanity alone but of all organic life, so that its self-perversion accounts not merely for the tendency to evil in man but for the equally oppressive and saddening phenomenon of evil in sub-human nature. The justification of these steps will be found stated at length in Lecture VIII, and need only be summarised here by pointing out (a) that unless the relation between the perfect Idea and the degenerate particulars be conceived, as we have suggested, under causal, contingent, and temporal forms, it can only be conceived under the timeless category of ‘ ground and 4° See Lecture’ Vi,\p.13 56: ? 2 DHIT 7 *ips T19. : Dura FORMULARIES 537 consequent,’ which would involve postulating a principle of evil necessarily inherent in the Idea itself, and thus making God the direct author of evil; (5) that the evolutional continuity between man and the brute requires that evil in both should be brought under the head of a single explanation. It is, perhaps, not temerarious to suggest that a full recognition of the implications of the phrase ‘a fall from the divine intention’ would entirely eliminate whatever divergence may be thought to exist between the ‘evolutionary view’ and the ‘ecclesiastical doctrine’ (understood in the historical and Vincentian sense of the term, and construed as we have suggested) regarding the origin and ground of sin. ADDITIONAL NOTE F: FORMULARIES [Only such texts are printed as are strictly relevant to the Fall- doctrine. ] I. OECUMENICAL Council of Ephesus, A.D. 431. can. I. et rus 6 wntpomodirys rijs émap- xlas, amooraryicas THs aytas Kal olxovperkhs avvodov, mpocelero TH THs Gmooracias ovvedpiw, 7) peTa TotTO mpooTebein, ) Ta Kedcoriov édpovyncev 7 Ppovicer, ovTos KaTa THY THs émapxias emuoxoTwv SiamparrecOal Te ovdayds dvvarar, maons exkAnoaoTiKfs Kowwvias éevretbev 75n bro TIS avvddov exBeBAn- févos, Kal avevépyntos bmdpywv. . . . can. 4. ei d€ twes amoorarnoaey TOV KAnpiKdv, Kal ToAujoaey 7 Kat” idtay 7) Snpocta ta Neoropiov % ta Kedeoriov dpovica, Kai tovrous eivat KaOnpnuevous, b70 THs ayias avvddov SediKaiwrar. {[Hardouin 1. 1621 D; Denzinger-Bannwart, Enchiridion, §126; W. Bright, Canons of the First Four General Councils, 1892, p. xxvii f.] II. WESTERN AND ROMAN 1. Canons of the Second Council of Orange, A.D. 529 can. I. Si quis per offensam praevaricationis Adae non totum, id est secundum corpus et animam, in deterius dicit hominem commutatum, sed animae libertate illaesa durante corpus tantummodo corruptioni credit obnoxium, Pelagii errore deceptus adversatur scripturae dicenti: anima, quae peccaverit, ipsa morietur [Ezek. xviii. 20]: et, nescitis quoniam qui exhibetis vos servos ad oboediendum servi estis e1us, cut oboeditrs ? [Rom. vi. 16]: et, a quo quis superatur, evus et servus addicitur [2 Pet. 10): 538 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN can. 2. si quis soli Adae praevaricationem suam, non et eius propagini asserit nocuisse, aut certe mortem tantum corporis, quae poena peccati est, non autem et peccatum, quod mors est animae, per unum hominem in omne genus humanum translisse testatur, iniustitiam Deo dabit, contradicens Apostolo dicenti: per unum hominem peccatum intravit in mundum, et per peccatum mors, et ita 1m omnes homines movs pertransiit, in quo omnes peccaverunt [Rom. v. 12]. can. 8. si quis alios misericordia, alios vero per liberum arbitrium, quod in omnibus, qui de praevaricatione primi hominis nati sunt, constat esse vitiatum, ad gratiam baptismi posse venire contendit, a recta fide probatur alienus. is enim non omnium liberum arbitrium per peccatum primi hominis asserit infirmatum, aut certe ita laesum putat, ut tamen quidam valeant sine revelatione Dei mysterium salutis aeternae per semetipsos posse conquirere .. . can. 13. arbitrium voluntatis in primo homine infirmatum nisi per gratiam baptismi non potest reparari: quod amissum nisi a quo potuit dari non potest reddi.. . can. I5. ab eo quod formavit Deus mutatus est Adam, sed in peius per iniquitatem suam. ab eo quod operata est iniquitas mutatur fidelis, sed in melius per gratiam Dei. illa ergo mutatio fuit praevaricatoris primi, haec secundum Psalmistam mutatio est dextrae excelst (ps. Ixxvi. II]. can. I9. natura humana, etiamsi in illa integritate in qua est condita permaneret, nullo modo se ipsam creatore suo non adiuvante servaret : unde cum sine Dei gratia salutem non possit custodire, quam accepit, quomodo sine Dei gratia poterit reparare quod perdidit ? From the doctrinal statement appended to can. 25. ac sic secundum supra scriptas sanctarum scripturarum sententias vel antiquorum patrum definitiones hoc Deo propitiante et praedicare debemus et credere, quod per peccatum primi hominis ita in- clinatum et attenuatum fuerit liberum arbitrium, ut nullus postea aut diligere Deum sicut oportuit, aut credere in Deum, aut operari propter Deum quod bonum est, nisi eum gratia miseri- cordiae divinae praevenerit. 2. Council of Trent Sessio V (June 17, 1546). Decretum de peccato originals. I. si quis non confitetur, primum hominem Adam, cum mandatum Dei in paradiso fuisset transgressus, statim sancti- tatem et iustitiam, in qua constitutus fuerat, amisisse, in- currisseque per offensam praevaricationis huiusmodi iram et indignationem Dei atque ideo mortem, quam antea illi com- FORMULARIES 539 minatus fuerat Deus, et cum morte captivitatem sub eius potestate, qui mortis deinde habuit imperium, hoc est diaboli, totumque Adam per illam praevaricationis offensam secundum corpus et animam in deterius commutatum fuisse: anathema sit. 2. si quis Adae praevaricationem sibi soli, et non eius propagini asserit nocuisse, et acceptam a Deo sanctitatem et iustitiam quam perdidit, sibi soli et non nobis etiam eum perdidisse ; aut inquinatum illum per inoboedientiae peccatum mortem et poenas corporis tantum in omne genus humanum transfudisse, non autem et peccatum, quod mors est animae ; A.S., cum contradicat Apostolo dicenti: per unum hominem peccatum intravit in mundum etc. [Rom. v. 12]. 3. si quis hoc Adae peccatum, quod origine unum est, et propagatione, non imitatione, transfusum omnibus inest uni- cuique proprium, vel per humanae naturae vires vel per aliud remedium asserit tolli quam per meritum unius mediatoris Domininostrilesu Christi) 2 A.S. oi 4. Si quis parvulos recentes ab uteris matrum baptizandos negat, etiam si fuerint a baptizatis parentibus orti, aut dicit in remissionem quidem peccatorum eos baptizari, sed nihil ex Adam trahere originalis peccati, quod regenerationis lavacro necesse sit expiari ad vitam aeternam consequendam, unde fit consequens, ut in eis forma baptismatis in remissionem peccatorum non vera, sed falsa intelligatur: A.S., quoniam non aliter intelligendum est id, quod dixit Apostolus: per unum hominem peccatum intravit in mundum etc. [Rom. v. 12], nisi quemadmodum Ecclesia catholica ubique diffusa semper intellexit. propter hanc enim regulam fidei ex traditione Apostolorum etiam parvuli, qui nihil peccatorum in semetipsis adhuc committere potuerunt, ideo in remissionem peccatorum veraciter baptizantur, ut in eis regeneratione mundetur, quod generatione contraxerunt.1 mist enim quis renatus fuerit ex aqua et Spiritu Sancto, non potest introive in regnum Det [John iii. 5]. 5. si quis per Iesu Christi Domini nostri gratiam quae in baptismate confertur reatum originalis peccati remitti negat, aut etiam asserit, non tolli totum id, quod veram et propriam peccati rationem habet, sed illud dicit tantum radi aut non imputari : A.S. ... manere autem in baptizatis concupiscentiam vel fomitem haec sancta Synodus fatetur et sentit, quae cum agonem relicta sit, nocere non consentientibus sed viriliter per Christi Iesu gratiam repugnantibus non valet; quin immo quz legitime certaverit coronabitur [2 Tim. 1i.5]. hanc concupiscentiam, quam aliquando Apostolus peccatum [Denzinger refers for this to Rom. vi. 12 ff.] appellat, sancta Synodus declarat Ecclesiam catholicam nunquam intellexisse peccatum appellari, quod vere 1 This canon is practically identical with can. 2 of the Carthaginian Synod of A.D. 418 ; see above, p. 391. 840 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN et proprie in renatis peccatum sit, sed quia ex peccato-est et ad peccatum inclinat. si quis autem contrarium senserit: A.S. declarat tamen haec ipsa sancta Synodus, non esse suae in- tentionis, comprehendere in hoc decreto, ubi de peccato originali agitur, beatam et immaculatam Virginem Mariam Dei genitricem,* sed observandas esse constitutiones fel. rec. Sixti Papae IV sub poenis in eis constitutionibus contentis, quas innovat. [Hardouin x. 27 C ff.; Denzinger-Bannwart, § 788 ff.] Sessio VI (Jan. 13, 1547). Decretum de tustificatione. cap.1. de naturae et legis ad tustificandos homines imbecillitate. primum declarat sancta Synodus, ad iustificationis doctrinam probe et sincere intelligendam oportere, ut unusquisque agnoscat et fateatur, quod, cum omnes homines in praevaricatione Adae innocentiam perdidissent ... usque adeo servi evant peccato [Rom. vi. 20] et sub potestate diaboli ac mortis, ut non modo gentes per vim naturae sed ne Iudaei quidem per ipsam etiam litteram legis Moysi inde liberari aut surgere possent, tametsi in eis liberum arbitrium minime exstinctum esset, viribus licet attenuatum et inclinatum.? [Hardouin x. 33 C; Denzinger-Bannwart, § 793. | Canones de iustificatione. can.5. siquisliberum hominis arbitrium post Adae peccatum amissum et exstinctum esse dixerit, aut rem esse de solo titulo, immo titulum sine re, figmentum denique a satana invectum in ecclesiam: A.S. can. 6. si quis dixerit, non esse in potestate hominis vias suas malas facere, sed mala opera ita ut bona Deum operari, non permissive solum sed etiam proprie et per se, adeo ut sit pro- prium eius opus non minus proditio Iudae quam vocatio Pauli: A.S. (This canon is directed against the dictum of Melancthon, mentioned above, p. 435.) [Hardouin x. 40 E; Denzinger-Bannwart, §§ 815, 816.] For the relation of the foregoing definitions to the drafts submitted to the Council by the ‘ private congregations,’ see J. Waterworth, Canons and Decrees of the Council of Trent, 1848, Ppp. XCili—c. 1 Cf. St. Aug. de nat. et grat. 42, quoted above, Lecture V, p. 370, n. 2. 2 uv. supra (p. 538), canons of the second Council of Orange, statement appended to can. 25. ee —————— ee ee ae —- Fs Se Oe FORMULARIES 541 III. EASTERN ORTHODOX 1. Confessio Orthodoxa. (ap. E. J. Kimmel, Monumenta jidet Eccl. orient., 1850, p. 83 ff.) quaest. xxii. “ But seeing that man, whilst he was yet in the state of innocency, forgat the commandment of God, and plucked and tasted of the forbidden fruit: for this reason was he stripped of the honour which he had from the moment of creation, during the time of his innocency, and driven forth from Paradise. Wherefore he became such an one as the Prophet describes: ‘““ Man being in honour had no understanding, but was compared unto beasts void of reason, and was made like unto them ”’ (Ps. xlix. 20): and he heard the sentence “‘ Earth thou art, and unto earth shalt thou return ”’ (Gen. ili. I0).’ quaest. xxiii. ‘ Of what kind was the state of man’s innocency, or purity and sinlessness ? ’ Answer. ‘There are two kinds of innocency and integrity : the first is a voluntary departure from sin, as when a man after the daily and habitual exercise of vice by his own choice renounces sin; the second is a simple ignorance and inexperience of sin . due to tender age or to other causes. With this latter kind was the innocency of Adam to be compared before his sin, joined as that innocency was with every perfection and innate righteous- ness, both on the side of intellect and on the side of will; in his intellect was included every kind of knowledge, and in his will every kind of goodness and virtue. And seeing that Adam had a most perfect knowledge of God (in accordance with that measure which was granted unto him for that time, and in accordance with that which was seemly), for this very reason that he knew God, he also knew all other things in God.’ [This is proved by the incident of his naming the animals, which he was able to do because he possessed a perfect knowledge of the nature and disposition of each, due not to scientific investigation but to meditation on God and His goodness.] ‘As for his will, this was always subject to reason; though he always retained his liberty, and though it was always in the power of man either to sin or not to sin, as the Scripture saith [Ecclus. xv. II-17, 20, quoted at length]. In this state, therefore, of innocence and sinlessness man was like unto the angels. But so soon as he had fallen through the transgression, forthwith in the same place of Paradise, being endued with the state of sin, he became mortal [Rom. vi. 23]. Then forthwith, the perfection of his reason and intellect having been lost, his will also became more inclined to evil than to good. And in this way the state of integrity and innocency passed into a state of sin, man having already experi- enced evil; and man who had once been perfect was so much 542 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN humbled, that he may now say with David, ‘‘ I am a worm, and no man”’ [Ps. xxii. 6].’ quaest. xxiv. ‘ Are all men subject to the same sin? (efvar Taxa Grou of dvOpwrot broxeipevor cis THY adTiy dpapTiva;) Answer. ‘As all men were in Adam during the state of innocency, so also from the moment that he fell all fell in him (sro. €opadav ¢is adrév) and remained in the state of sin. Where- fore they are subject not only to sin, but also to punishment because of the sin [Gen. 11. 17; Rom. v. 12]. Wherefore also we are conceived in our mothers’ wombs and are born with this sin, as the holy Psalmist saith [Ps. li. 7]. And this sin is called Ancestral [zporaropixov—or ‘original’]; firstly, because man was defiled by no other sin before it. Though the devil was already corrupted by his own sin; and at his instigation this which is called “‘ ancestral sin’’ began to germinate in man, that sin to which Adam became subject and all we who descend from him. Secondly, because no man is conceived except in sin.’ 2. Dosithet Confessio (ap. Synod. Hierosol., Kimmel, Op.\cit., Dp. 425 Tf.) decretum vi. (Kimmel, p. 432 f.). ‘We believe that the first man was created by God and fell in Paradise, when, neglecting the divine command, he obeyed the deceitful counsel of the serpent ; and that thence has flowed in succession the ancestral sin (tiv rpotatopixny dpaptiav) ; so that no one is born according to the flesh who does not bear this burden and perceive the fruits thereof in this present world. And by the “ fruits’? and the “ burden ’”’ we mean, not sin, such as impiety, blasphemy, murder... etc.: for many of the Patriarchs and Prophets, and myriads of others of those both who lived in the shadow of the Law and in the truth of the Gospel, and the divine Forerunner, and especially the mother of God the Word, the ever-virgin Mary, had no share in these or like sins; but we mean those things which the divine justice sends upon man as a penalty on account of the transgression, such as the sweat of toil, tribulations, bodily infirmities, the pains of childbirth, a toilsome life during this pilgrimage, and finally bodily death.’ [Note that this formulary appears to restrict the consequences of the Fall to external and physical evils. ] 3. The Longer Catechism of the Russian Church. (R. W. Blackmore, The Doctrine of the Russian Church, 1845, p. 60) Q. ‘Why did not the first man only die, and not allas now?’ A. ‘Because all have come of Adam since his infection by sin, and all sin themselves. As from an infected source there FORMULARIES 543 naturally flows an infected stream, so from a father infected with sin, and consequently mortal, there naturally proceeds a posterity infected like him with sin, and like him mortal.’ [The definitely Augustinian tone of the sections quoted from the Confessio orthodoxa of Peter Mogila is notable, and contrasts strongly with the vagueness which had previously characterised Eastern thought on this subject. It is doubtless to be attributed to the wave of Latinising influence which swept over Eastern theology in the middle of the seventeenth century, as a reaction from the Protestantising tendencies of the unfortunate Patriarch Cyril Lucaris ({1637). To judge by the sketch of modern Greek theology given by F. Gavin (Some Aspects of Contemporary Greek Orthodox Thought, 1923, Lecture III, § 3, ‘ The Fall,’ § 4, ‘ Original Sin,’ pp. 165 ff.), the current hamartiological teaching of Eastern divines, as represented by two such eminent scholars as M. Androutsos and M. Dyobouniotis, is still strongly coloured by ‘Augustinianism; though Gavin (p. 168) quotes Damalas as deeming ‘concupiscence’ to be morally indifferent, whilst Androutsos rejects the Augustinian disparagement of the good works of the heathen (Gavin, p. 167).] IV. LUTHERAN (In this and the following section it has not been possible to print more than a few typical texts, owing to considerations of space. | 1. Confession of Augsburg, A.D. 1530 art. i. de peccato origins. item docent, quod post lapsum Adae omnes homines secundum naturam propagati nascantur cum peccato, hoc est, sine metu Dei, sine fiducia erga Deum, et cum concupiscentia, quodque hic morbus seu vitium originis vere sit peccatum, damnans et afferens nunc quoque aeternam mortem his qui non renascuntur per baptismum et Spiritum Sanctum. damnant Pelagianos et alios qui vitium originis negant esse peccatum, et ut extenuent gloriam meriti et beneficiorum Christi, disputant hominem propriis viribus rationis coram Deo iustificari DOSSErn.. [F. Francke, libri symbolict eccl. Lutheranae, 1. p. 13 f.; B. J. Kidd, Documents of the Continental Reformation LEQEE L202. | 2. Schmalkaldic Articles, A.D. 1537 pars ii, I. de peccato. I. hic confitendum nobis est, ut Paulus Roman. v. affirmat, peccatum ab uno homine Adamo ortum esse et introisse in 544 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN mundum, per cuius inobedientiam omnes homines facti sunt peccatores, morti et diabolo obnoxii. hoc nominatur originale, haereditarium, principale, et capitale peccatum. 2. huius peccati fructus postea sunt mala opera, in decalogo prohibita, ut sunt diffidentia, incredulitas, falsa fides sive xaxomotia, idololatria, sine Dei timore esse, praesumptio seu temeritas, desperatio, caecitas seu excaecatio, et ut summatim dicam, Deum non agnoscere, non curare; deinde mentiri, nomine Dei abuti, peierare, non orare, non invocare, verbum Dei contemnere vel negligere, parentibus immorigerum esse, occidere, lascivire, furari, decipere etc. 3. hoc peccatum haereditarium tam profunda et tetra est corruptio naturae, ut nullius hominis ratione intelligi possit, sed ex scripturae patefactione agnoscenda et credenda sit (Ps. li, Rom. v., Exod. xxxiii., Gen. iii.).. quapropter meri sunt errores et caligines contra hunc articulum scholasticorum doctorum dogmata, quibus docetur : 4. post Adae lapsum hominis naturales vires mansisse integras et incorruptas, et hominem naturaliter habere rationem rectam et bonam voluntatem, sicut philosophi docent : 5. et hominem habere liberum arbitrium faciendi bonum et omittendi malum et e contra omittendi bonum et faciendi malum, etc. [Francke, 1. p. 20 f.] 3. The Formulary of Concord, A.D. 1577 I. Epitome, c. 1. de peccato originals B. Affirmativa I credimus, docemus, et confitemur, quod sit aliquod discrimen inter ipsam hominis naturam, non tantum quemadmodum initio a Deo purus et sanctus et absque peccato homo conditus est, verum etiam qualem iam post lapsum naturam illam habemus, discrimen, inquam, inter ipsam naturam, quae etiam post lapsum est permanetque Dei creatura, et inter peccatum originis, et quod tanta sit illa naturae et peccati originalis differentia, quanta est inter opus Dei et inter opus diaboli. II credimus, docemus, et confitemur quod summo studio hoc discrimen sit conservandum, propterea quod illud dogma, nullum videlicet inter naturam hominis corrupti et inter peccatum originis esse discrimen, cum praecipuis fidei nostrae articulis de creatione, de redemptione, de sanctificatione et resurrectione carnis nostrae pugnet, neque salvis hisce articulis stare possit. . . _ FORMULARIES 545 III vicissim autem credimus, docemus atque confitemur, peccatum originis non esse levem, sed tam profundam humanae naturae corruptionem, quae nihil sanum, nihil incorruptum in corpore et anima hominis, atque adeo in interioribus et exteriori- bus viribus eius reliquit. sicut ecclesia canit ‘lapsus Adae vi pessima humana tota massa, natura et ipsa essentia corrupta, luce cassa ’ etc. {Francke, i. p. 20 f.] II. solida declaratio, c. 1. B. I et primum quidem constat, Christianos non tantum actualia delicta et transgressiones mandatorum Dei peccata esse agnoscere et definire debere, sed etiam horrendum atque abominabilem illum haereditartum morbum, per quem tota natura corrupta est, inprimis pro horribilt peccato, et quidem pro principio et capite omnium peccatorum, e quo reliquae transgressiones tamquam e radice nascantur et quasi e scaturigine promanent, omnino habendum esse. et hoc malum aliquando D, Lutherus pbeccatum naturae, item fpeccatum personae appellare solet, ut significet, etiamsi homo prorsus nihil mali cogitaret loqueretur aut ageret (quod sane post primorum nostrorum parentum lapsum in hac vita humanae naturae est impossibile) tamen nihilominus hominis naturam et personam esse peccatricem, hoc est, peccato originali quasi lepra quadam sfiritualt prorsus et totaliter in intimis etiam visceribus et cordis recessibus profundissimis totam esse coram Dei infectam, venenatam et penitus corruptam ; et propter hanc corruptionem atque primorum nostrorum lapsum natura aut persona hominis lege Dei accusatur et condemnatur, ita ut natura filii irae, mortis et damnationis mancipia simus, nisi beneficio meriti Christi ab his malis liberemur et servemur. [Francke, ii. p. 84 f.] V. REFORMED 1. Confessio Helvetica prior, A.D. 1536 7. Von dem menschen. Der mensch, die volkomnest bildnus gottes uff erden, under allen sichtbaren creaturen, die edleste und furnemste, der ist uss lib und seel zusamen gesetzt. Der lib ist todtlich, die seel untodtlich, diser mensch als er von gott recht und wol geschaffen war, ist er durch sin eigne schuld in die sund gefallen und hatt das ganz menschlich geschlecht mit ihm in solichn fall gezogen, und solicher arbeitsalikeit underwurflich gemacht. 2N 5,46 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN 8. Von der eerbsiind. Dise eerbsucht aber und urspringenliche sund ist das ganz menschlich geschlecht dermasen durchgangen, und hetts der- masen verwust und vergifft, dz dem menschen, der ein kind des zorns und fyend gottes worden war, niema denn gott durch Christi helffen oder widerbringen mocht, und was in ihm guts uberbliben ist, dz wirt durch taglich mangell und prasten fur und fur geschwacht, das es zi eergeren geratet, dann die krafft der sund und des prestens in uns trifft fur, das weder die vernunfft dem, dz sy erkendt nachkomen, noch der hochverstand das gottlich funckli pflanzen und furbringen mag. [H. A. Niemeyer, Collectio confesstonum in ecclesiis reformatts publicatarum, Lipsiae, 1840, p. 106 f.] 2. Confessio Belgica, A.D. 1561 XIV. De hominis creatione, lapsu et corruptione. credimus Deum ex limo terrae hominem ad imaginem suam, bonum, iustum et sanctum creasse, qui proprio arbitrio suam voluntatem ad Dei voluntatem componere et conformem reddere posset. verum cum in honore esset nescivit, et excellentiam suam non cognovit : sed seipsum sciens et volens peccato et per consequens morti ac maledictioni subiecit: dum diaboli verbis et imposturis aurem praebens mandatum vitae transgressus est, quod a Domino acceperat ; seque a Deo, vera ipsius vita, penitus subduxit, atque abalienavit, vitiata omnino atque corrupta per peccatum ipsius natura: quo factum est, ut morti tum corporeae tum spirituali sese obnoxium reddiderit, improbus atque perversus effectus fuerit, atque in omnibus viis et studiis suis corruptus, et praeclara illa dona omnia amiserit, quae a Deo acceperat: adeo ut non nisi exiguae illorum scintillae et vestigia exilia illi relicta sunt, quae tamen sufficiant ad in- excusabiles reddendos homines .. . idcirco quaecunque de libero hominis arbitrio traduntur ea merito reiicimus, cum homo sit servus peccati: nihilque ex se possit, nisi datum sit illi de coelo. XV. De peccato originals. credimus Adami inobedientia peccatum, quod vocant originis, in totum genus humanum diffusum esse. est autem peccatum originis corruptio totius naturae et vitium haereditarium, quo et ipsi infantes in matris utero polluti sunt: quodque velut noxia quaedam radix genus omne peccatorum in homine pro- ducit, estque tam foedum et execrabile coram Deo, ut ad universi generis humani condemnationem sufficiat. meque vero per baptismum penitus aboletur aut radicitus evellitur, quando- quidem ex illo tanquam ex infausta ac corrupta scaturigine De FORMULARIES 547 perpetui rivuli assidue exoriuntur et effluunt ... hinc ergo Pelagianorum errorem damnamus, qui hoc peccatum originis nihil aliud esse asserunt quam imitationem. (Niemeyer, pp. 368-70. ] 3. Confessio fider Gallicana, A.D. I561 Article IX Nous croyons que l’homme ayant esté créé pur et entier et conforme a l’image de Dieu, est par sa propre faute descheu de sa grace qu'il avoit recue, et ainsi s’est aliéné de Dieu .. . en sorte que sa nature est du tout corrompue: et estant aveuglé en son esprit et dépravé en son cceur, a perdu toute integrité sans en avoir rien de residu. .. . Article X Nous croyons que toute la lignée de Adam est infectée de telle contagion, qui est le péché originel et un vice héréditaire, et non pas seulement une imitation, comme les Pelagiens ont voulu dire. . . . Et ainsi que en la personne d’iceluy (sc. Adam) nous avons esté dénués de tous biens, et sommes trébuchés en toute pauvreté et malédiction. Article XI Nous croyons aussi que ce vice est vrayement paché: qui suffit a condamner tout le genre humain, iusques aux petis enfants dés le ventre de la mére, et que pour tel il est reputé devant Dieu, mesmes qu’aprés le baptesme c’est toujours péché, quant a la coulpe, combien que la condamnation en soit abolie aux enfans de Dieu, ne la leur imputant point par sa bonté gratuite : outre cela, que c’est une perversité produisant tousiours fruicts de malice et de rebellion, tels que les plus sains, encore quils y résistent, ne laissent point d’estre entachez d’infirmitez et de fautes, pendant qu’ils habitent en ce monde. Article XII Nous croyons que de cette corruption et condamnation générale, en laquelle tous hommes sont plongez, Dieu retire ceux lesquels en son conseil éternel et immuable il a éleus par sa seule bonté et miséricorde en nostre Seigneur Jesus Christ, sans con- sidération de leurs ceuvres, laissant les autres en icelle mesme corruption et condamnation, pour démontrer en eux sa iustice, comme és premiers il fait luire les richesses de sa miséricorde. .. . [Niemeyer, pp. 316-318.] 548 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN 4. The Westminster Confession, A.D. 1647 Chapter VI. Of the Fall of Man, of Sin, and of the Punish- ment thereof. I. Our first parents, being seduced by the subtilty and tempta- tion of Satan, sinned in eating the forbidden fruit. This their sin God was pleased, according to his wise and holy counsel, to permit, having purposed to order it to his own glory. II. By this sin they fell from their original righteousness and communion with God, and so became dead in sin, and wholly defiled in all the faculties and parts of soul and body. III. They being the root of all mankind, the guilt of this sin was imputed, and the same death in sin and corrupted nature conveyed to all their posterity descending from them by ordinary generation. IV. From this original corruption, whereby we are utterly indisposed, disabled, and made opposite to all good, and wholly inclined to all evil, do proceed all actual transgressions. V. This corruption of nature during this life doth remain in those that are regenerated; and although it be through Christ pardoned and mortified, yet both itself and all the motions thereof are truly and properly sin. VI. Every sin, both original and actual, being a transgression of the righteous law of God and contrary thereto, doth in its own nature bring guilt upon the sinner, whereby he is bound over to the wrath of God and curse of the law, and so made subject to death, with all miseries spiritual, temporal, and eternal. [P. Schaff, The Creeds of the Evangelical Protestant Churches, 1877, p. 615 f.] (A.D.'1553 ; 1562 5) 1571) ARTICLE IX VI. ANGLICAN. De peccato originale peccatum originis non est (ut fabulantur Pelagiani) in imita- tione Adami situm, sed est vitium et depravatio naturae culuslibet hominis ex Adamo naturaliter propagati, qua fit, ut ab originali iustitia quam longissime distet, ad malum sua natura propendeat, et caro semper adversus spiritum con- Of Original or Birth Sin Original Sin standeth not in the following of Adam (as the Pelagians do vainly talk), but it is the fault and corruption of the Nature of every man, | that naturally is ingendered of the offspring of Adam ; where- by man is very far gone from original righteousness, and is of his own nature inclined to FORMULARIES cupiscat. unde in unoquoque nascentium iram Dei atque damnationem meretur. manet etiam in renatis haec naturae depravatio ; qua fit ut affectus carnis, Graece ¢povnpa capkés, (quod alii sapientiam, alii sen- sum, alii affectum, alii studium carnis interpretantur) legi Dei non subiiciatur. et quanquam renatis et credentibus nulla propter Christum est con- demnatio, peccati tamen in sese rationem habere concu- piscentiam fatetur Apostolus. 549 evil, so that the flesh lusteth always contrary to the spirit ; and therefore in every person born “into wathis soworled aot deserveth God’s wrath and damnation. And this in- fection of nature doth remain, yeainy them) thatwareienhe- generated ; whereby the lust of the flesh, called in the Greek, dpdvypa capxés, which some do expound the wisdom, some sensuality, some _ the affection, some the desire of the flesh, is not subject to the Law of God. And although there is no condemnation for them that believe and are baptised, yet the Apostle doth confess, that concupiscence and lust hath of itself the nature of sin. ARTICLE. X De libero arbitrio ea est hominis post lapsum Adae conditio, ut sese naturali- bus suis viribus et bonis operibus ad fidem et invoca- tionem Dei convertere ac prae- parare non possit; quare absque gratia Dei, quae per Christum est, nos praeveniente, ut velimus, et co-operante, dum volumus, ad pietatis opera facienda, quae Deo grata sint et accepta, nihil valemus. Of free will The condition of Man after the fall of Adam is such, that he cannot turn and prepare himself, by his own natural strength and good works, to faith, and calling upon God: Wherefore we have no power to do good works pleasant and acceptable to God, with- out the grace of God by Christ preventing us, that we may have a good will, and working with us, when we have that good will. ARTICLE XIII Opera ante tustificationem opera quae ffiunt ante gratiam Christi et Spiritus eius affatum, cum ex fide Jesu Of Works before Justification Works done before the grace of Christ, and the Inspiration of his Spirit, are not pleasant 550 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN Christi non prodeant, minime Deo wagrata) ssunteys © neque gratiam (ut multi vocant) de congruo merentur; Imo cum non sint facta ut Deus illa fieri voluit et praecepit, peccati rationem habere non _ dubi- tamus. to God, forasmuch as they spring not of faith in Jesus Christ, neither do they make men meet to receive grace, or (as the School-authors say) deserve grace of congruity ; yea rather, for that they are not done as God hath willed ee and commanded them to be done, we doubt not but they have the nature of sin. ADDITIONAL NOTE G INFANT BAPTISM THE ceremony of baptism, as known to the Apostolic Church, seems to have formed the central act of a process which may be described as ‘Christian Initiation.” This began with ‘Repentance’ (presumably manifested by an oral confession of sin), was consummated by the immersion of the catechumen in the living waters of a spring or river, symbolising the washing away of sin, and concluded with the imposition of hands, which imparted the gifts of the Spirit. As we have pointed out in the text and elsewhere,! the New Testament references to Initiation assume that its recipients are adults, and that the dispositions required in them are those of conscious and deliberate renuncia- tion of sin and idols, and of personal faith in and allegiance to Christ. Thus conceived, the rite illustrates vividly the true principles of ethical sacramentalism, which demand not merely the due performance of a sacred act by the minister but the right response of heart and will on the part of the worshipper, and which regard the objective opus operatum as ineffective unless met and completed by the subjective opus operantis. It will be clear from this account of the original institution of baptism that the custom of baptising unconscious infants, which, as we have suggested, seems to have grown up spon- taneously on a basis of popular feeling, and not of any reasoned theory, and which has now for many centuries been the normal means of entrance to the Christian Church, involves two very serious difficulties: (1) the apparent incongruity of administer- ing a sacrament, the purpose of which is declared both by its symbolism and by the language of Scripture to be the ‘ washing away of sins,’ to beings who ex hypothes1 cannot have committed 1° The Origins of the Sacraments,’ in Essays Catholic and Critical, 1926, pp. 369 ff. INFANT BAPTISM 587 any sins; (2) the exclusive emphasis which the practice appears to lay upon the opus operatum, in view of the presumption that unconscious infants are incapable of repentance or of personal faith in Christ. It might in fact be contended, that if the epithets ‘ magical’ and ‘ mechanical’ can be applied to any parts of the traditional sacramental system at all, it is the custom of infant baptism first and foremost to which they ought to be affixed ; and such a contention might be thought to derive some force from the curious stratagems employed by the Jesuit missionaries in North America to enable them to baptise dying infants amongst the heathen surreptitiously (by unobservedly flicking a few drops of water over the infant’s face, and simul- taneously whispering ego te baptizo, etc., whilst apparently engaged in conversation with the parents), for the purpose of adding as many souls as possible to the Kingdom of God. We have already pointed out that the first of these diffi- culties stimulated the growth of the idea of ‘original guilt,’ or guilt of nature, as its own solution. If, however, the history of the Fall-doctrine has been correctly portrayed in Lectures I to VI, this idea is no part of the body of revealed Christian truth, but a mere human figment: and in whatever way it be conceived—whether as the guilt of having sinned ‘in Adam,’ of being destitute of the splendid endowments alleged to have been originally possessed by Adam, or of being infected by ‘concupiscence ’—it is equally irrational, as involving the self-contradictory assertion that we are held ‘ guilty’ by God in respect of facts for which we have ex hyfothesi no personal responsibility whatsoever. If, then, the insistence of the historic Church upon the permissibility, and indeed necessity, of infant baptism is to be justified, some theoretical basis for this custom other than the idea of ‘ original guilt ’ must now be found. It is necessary at this point to distinguish between the fact (assuming it to be a fact) of, and the veasons for, the necessity, or at least high desirability, of the baptism of infants. That infants may and should be baptised is a proposition which rests solely upon the actual practice of the Church; as in the fifth century, the sole argument for the fact is simply this: ‘The Church does baptise infants, and we cannot suppose that the Church has acted wrongly or without good cause in so doing.’ It is not possible here to enter into such vast questions as the nature of the stewardship which the Church holds in regard to the methods and conditions of administering the sacraments, the amount of liberty which our Lord may have intended to leave to His Church in regard to developments or variations of sacramental usage, or the degree of auctoritas which attaches to a custom which has come to be accepted by the whole, or 1 See F. Parkman, The Jesuits in North America, i. pp. 185 f., 206 f. 552 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN practically the whole, of the Christian society. It must suffice to state that in the author’s view the argument a praxi ecclesiae is the only, but also a sufficient, ground for affirming the legitimacy and laudability of Paedo-baptism: and that those who do not trust the instincts of the historic Church to the extent which this argument requires should in logic either abandon the custom altogether or interpret it solely as a picturesque and dramatic method of registering the name of the infant as an honorary member of the Christian society. Those, however, who are prepared on this ground to accept the proposition that infant baptism is permissible and desirable, will still demand some explanation as to why it should be desirable. If the theory that ‘ original guilt’ is thereby remitted be ruled out, and if, nevertheless, the baptism of infants be regarded as strictly sacramental and grace-bestowing, and not as merely symbolical, there appears to be no explanation of its efficacy other than that hinted at by St. Gregory of Nazianzus in the words already quoted : vnmiaxous ev odpnyis, deEopevorcs 8’ dkos Kal odpnyts apiorn * and developed by Julian of Eclanum in the suggestion that whilst infants, not being vez, do not need venia, they are never- theless capable of receiving ‘inluminatio spiritualis, adoptio filiorum Dei, municipatus Jerusalem caelestis, sanctificatio, atque in Christi membra translatio, et possessio regni caelorum.’ ? We must frankly regard baptism as having two sets of effects, negative and positive, sin-remitting and strength-bestowing. And we must conceive of the baptism of adults as fraught with both kinds of operation, in that it both remits men’s actual sins and imparts to them the germ of the supernatural life ; whilst the baptism of infants involves only the positive operation of making its recipients members of the Church and of Christ, capable of receiving the influx of grace which, when their Initia- tion has been completed by Confirmation, will assist them gradually to overcome that ‘inherited infirmity’ which daily experience shows, so far from being abolished by the opus operatum of baptism, to remain ‘ yea, even in them that are regenerated.’ It would follow from such a view of infant baptism that the idea of its efficacy cannot be dissociated from the influences of a Christian upbringing and of life within the shelter of Church membership, and that the indiscriminate baptism of children, with regard to whom no guarantee exists that they will be trained as Christians, is both useless and to be deprecated as a cheapening of the Sacrament. 1 carmina i. § i. 9, 22, 91, 92 (quoted above, p. 290, n. I). 2 op. imperf. c. Iulian. i. 53. INFANT BAPTISM 553 Nevertheless, though part of the efficacy of infant baptism must be conceived as prolepiic, in that by admitting its recipients to the Christian society it makes it possible for them in future years to imbibe the graces which flow from a supernatural environment, the actual practice of the Church clearly assumes that the administration of the rite has its own immedzate efficacy ; for otherwise there would be no reason for baptising dying infants, who ex hypothesi have no prospect of being brought to Confirmation or of being trained up in Christian virtue within the fold of the Church militant here in earth. We must, then, believe that through the act of the Christian society, represented for the time being by the minister of the Sacrament, the begin- nings of the Christ-life are planted in the infant soul, even though there may appear to be no conscious effort to prepare for or to appropriate them. Those who find this a hard saying may be asked to weigh well the words of Fr. C. C. Martindale, S.J. : ‘Less and less objection should be taken to the Catholic baptism of children or the weak-witted, in proportion as modern psycho- therapy proves how very deep and active is the sub-consciousness of those who, like children or seeming “‘idiots,’’ have their superficial consciousness very undeveloped or ill-controlled,’ and “ Even in those whose wits do not seem capable of coping with the natural life of man, the germ of the supernatural may yet take root.’ } The question may be raised, as it was raised in the fifth century,” ‘ How can such a view of the rationale of infant baptism be reconciled with the clause of the Oecumenical Creed which affirms ‘“‘one baptism for the remission of sins’’?’ If it were an admitted principle that the meaning of the clauses of the Creed must be determined in complete abstraction from their history, this question would possess a certain amount of force as an objection to the explanation of Paedo-baptism indicated above. Butno such principle has been formulated by any person or body with any claim upon our intellectual allegiance, and the Council of Chalcedon, which first conferred official authority upon the ‘Creed of the 150,’ did not append to it any com- mentary or any canons to govern its exegesis. It is therefore reasonable to assume that the true meaning of this clause is its historical meaning—that is, the meaning which it bore in the minds of those who first drew it up. Now it is well known that this clause does not occur in the original Nicaenum, which ended with the words ‘and in the Holy Ghost’ and the anti- Arian anathemas. According to the generally accepted theory of Hort, it is of Jerusalemitic origin, as indeed is the main body of our ‘Nicene Creed’; which represents the baptismal creed of 1 God and the Supernatural (1920), p. 285. 2 See Lecture V, p. 345, 554 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN the Mother Church of Christendom, revised (perhaps by Cyril of Jerusalem in A.D. 362-364) by the insertion into it of phrases drawn from the real Nicene Creed (1.e. that actually approved by the Council of Nicaea). The true meaning of this clause must, then, be the meaning which it would have borne for Cyril and for the Church of Jerusalem in the middle of the fourth century. And there can be no reasonable doubt that the thought in their minds was that of baptism as administered to adults according to Apostolic and primitive usage, preceded by ‘Repentance’ and immediately followed by ‘Confirmation ’ and first Communion: a glance at Cyril’s catecheses tlluminan- dorum and catecheses mystagogicae is enough to show that adult baptism was for him and his flock the normal form of baptism. When, therefore, we repeat this clause in the Creed as a part of the Eucharistic Liturgy, what we affirm is our belief in baptism as anciently administered to adults, for the washing away of actual sins, and as still so administered, habitually in the mission field to converts from heathenism, and rarely in Christian countries: we neither affirm nor deny the legitimacy of infant baptism, which is a collateral development from the original idea and institution of baptism, and which depends for its authority not upon any credal or conciliar formula, but upon the actual practice of the Church and the semi-articulate instincts of the general body of Christendom. ADDITIONAL NOTE H PASSAGES BEARING ON THE FALL-DOCTRINE FROM PRE-AUGUSTINIAN WRITERS NOT MENTIONED IN LECTURE IV (1) Latin Writers NOVATIAN (flor. c. A.D. 250) de trinitate1. [PL III. 914 A] (physical mortality the result of the Fall) post quae hominem quoque mundo praeposuit et quidem ad imaginem Dei factum: cui mentem et rationem indidit et prudentiam, ut Deum posset imitari: cuius etsi corporis terrena primordia, caelestis tamen et divini halitus inspirata substantia : quem, cum omnia in servitutem illi dedisset, solum liberum esse voluit. et ne in periculum caderet rursum soluta libertas, mandatum posuit, quo tamen non inesse malum fructu arboris doceretur, sed futurum, si forte ex voluntate hominis de con- temptu datae legis praemoneretur. nam et liber esse debuerat, 1 See A. E. Burn, Introduction to the Creeds (1899), pp. 104 ff, PRE-AUGUSTINIAN PASSAGES 555 ne incongruenter Dei imago serviret: et lex addenda, ne usque ad contemptum dantis libertas effraenata prorumperet: ut et praemia condigna et merita poenarum consequenter exciperet, suum iam habens illud, quod motu mentis in alterutram partem agitare voluisset: ex quo mortalitas, invidia utique, in ipsum redit ; qui cum illam de obedientia posset evadere, in eamdem incurrit, dum ex consilio perverso Deus esse festinat: cuius tamen poenam nihilominus indulgenter temperavit, dum non tam ipse quam labores eius maledicuntur super terram. COMMODIAN (? ¢c. A.D. 250) instructiones adversus gentium deos. [PL V. 201-262] XXXV. de ligno vitae et mortis Adam protolapsus, ut Dei praecepta vitaret, Belias tentator fuit de invidia palmae ; contulit et nobis seu boni seu mali quod egit, dux nati [ ? ] nativitatis, morimur indeque per illum, ex divino ipse ut recedens exsul a verbo. XLVI. catecuminis in baptismo tibi genitale solox lavatur [‘ genitale solox’ means ‘ancestral filth,’ 7.e., presumably, ‘original guilt.” For the word ‘solox,’ v. PL, footnote 1m loc., or Du Cange, Glossarium med. et inf. lat. (Henschel-Favre), s.v. But B. Dombart, Commodiant carmina, in Corp. eccl. script. Lat., 1887, p. 66, emends the line so as to read— in baptismo tibi genitalia sola donantur. ] PACIAN OF BARCELONA (flor. A.D. 360-390) sermo de baptismo. [PL XIII. 1089 c ff.] accipite ergo, dulcissimi, homo ante baptismum in qua morte sit positus. scitis certe illud antiquum quod Adam terrenae origini praestitutus sit : quae utique damnatio legem illi aeternae mortis imposuit; et omnibus ab eo posteris quos lex una retinebat haec mors in genus omne dominata est, ab Adam usque ad Moysen ... interea nos omnes sub peccato tenebamur, ut fructus essemus mortis: siliquarum escis et pecorum custodiae destinati, id est, operibus immundis, per malos angelos, quibus dominantibus nec facere licuit nec scire iustitiam. .. . Adam postquam peccavit, ut retuli, dicente tunc Domino, terra es, et in terram tbis, addictus est morti. haec addictio in 556 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN genus omne defluxit. omnes enim peccaverunt, ipsa iam urgente natura, sicut apostolus dicit: quia per unum hominem peccatum introivit, et per delictum mors, et sic in omnes homines devenit, in quo omnes peccaverunt. dominatum est ergo peccatum, cuius vinculis quasi captivi trahebamur ad mortem, mortem scilicet sempiternam. AURELIUS CLEMENS PRUDENTIUS (A.D. 348-Tafter 405) apotheosis, 909-931 (A strongly ‘ Western’ or ‘ twice-born’ view of the Fall and its results is expressed, but ‘ traducianism ’ 1s repudiated.) haec prima est natura anima, sic condita simplex, decidit in vitium per sordida foedera carnis. exin tincta malo peccamine principis Adae infecit genus omne hominum, quod pullulat inde, et tenet ingenitas animarum infantia in ortu primi hominis maculas, nec quisquam nascitur insons, vitandus tamen error erit, ne traduce carnis transfundi in sobolem credatur fons animarum sanguinis exemplo, cui texta propagine vena est. non animas animae pariunt, sed lege latenti fundit opus natura suum, quod parvula anhelent vascula vitalisque adsit scintilla coactis. quae quamvis infusa novum penetret nova semper figmentum, vetus illa tamen de crimine avorum ducitur, inluto quoniam concreta veterno est. inde secunda redit generatio et inde lavatur naturae inluvies, iterumque renascimur intus perfusi, ut veterem splendens anima exuat Adam. quae quia materiam peccati ex fomite carnis consociata trahit, nec non simul ipsa sodali est incentivum peccaminis, inplicat ambas vindex paena reas peccantes mente sub una peccandique cremat socias cruciatibus aequis. (2) Greek Writers. EPIPHANIUS (c. A.D. 315-1403) GET A a IL Le reT S| [Adam before the Fall was innocent and simbple.] amAobs Te Hv Kal dkakos, odK Gvoud TL KeKTNMLEvos Erepov, od Sdéns, od yroduns, od Biov diaxpicews erixAnow Kexrnpévos, } ’Adau pdovov KAnbels, 76 épunvevdpevoy avOpwros, PRE-AUGUSTINIAN PASSAGES 557 haer. lii. 2. [PG XLI. 957 A] [Against the Adamian sect, who held their meetings in hypocausts or subterranean heating-chambers.—Adam and Eve before the Fall were not tormented by heat or cold. | "Addu yap Kai Eva odx év broxavorw olkw tiv Slarav elyov, obre ev droypd Twt vremelovto, ote Kpvos adrods eddprov’ Hv Sé adrois djp Kxabapdraros, Kal mdons evxpacias edrdxtws ex Oeod pepepnuévos, ovre amnvdrnre wuxplas TETOVMMEVOS, OUTE andeoTaTH EeKmUpwmcer Kavawvos emnypTynuevos’ Siaira Se duBpoola pdda ex Beod wemompevn’ 6 xa@pos éréraxto, Oupndias Kal edlwtas mEeTONpevos. Kal ove plyet UmémiTTOV OvTE KavawnL, ws Edy. haer. \xix. 52. [PG XLII. 282 D, 284 a] [free choice the source of sin, both in Adam and in ourselves.] [fhe Word co-operated with the Father and the Spirit in the creation of the universe] iva Setéy, 671 76 attiov THs T00 "ASdp, mapaBdcews ovK a6 TOD TETAAKEeVvaL, OVSE ATO TOO TETOLNKEVaL TO GpapTés 7) TO THS TapaKohs €axev, add’ amo idlas mpoawpécews . . . od yap & yéyovey ev 7H avOpadmw, eis Tobro ex Tod Snpwoupyod Tob avaitiov THs TOO Aday dpuaprias Tod apaprety yéyove, kat 61a todro qpaptrev’ GAda 76 abrefovoiov adr emédwxe, Kal aitios éavT@ Exacros yiverat dpaprias. haer. Xxxvii. I, 3 (ed. K. Holl, ap. Gr. Chr. Schr., ii. p. 51) [A vague connexion between the disobedience of Adam and Eve and the idolatry of their descendants seems to be implied. | , \ 3 e ~ A A ” A A > A 3 / 4 A Kalamep yap €& vbrapxis tos wept Evav cai rov "Adap Hadtyoev, ovTw Kal viv, KpUTTwY €auToV ev TE TH TapovTe Kal ev TH ypovw THv "lovdaiwv aype tis ~ “A ~ / tod Xpiotob mapovoias. elta Kal mpoBawdvtrwy tav xpdvwv Aixvous Gvras Tods avOpwmmovs TH Sv adrob ex ths mapaxons AndOcion Bpwoes Ett brovofevwv Kai A A / epeOilwy eis mepiccotépay amdarnv amd Tod Ovtos Oeod ddiorynot. ... amd yap A ~ Aa , A Tob €vods Kat GAnOiv0d Oeot amoorjcas avtrovs , \ , Ye / > ea A 4 , eldwdrodarpeias Kal moAvOetas BAdogynpov Kevodwvriav. . . . ovK Tv O€ alTLos povos © pavopevos TOTE Odis, GAA 6 ev TH Oder Odus AadArjoas (dypi Sé 6 SiaBodros) Kai lo A ; ¢ THY axonv Tob avOpwmov tapdéas Sia THs yuvatkds. Kal ovdé TO EvAoV Hv Guaprtia (Beds yap ovddév movnpov durever), yrdow dé éverroince 7d EvXov Tod cidévat > /, ‘ ~ A chee, | A \ 2 , e 7 3 A A A t4 ayalov re kal datAov. Kal odyt dia 70 eidevar 6 Oavaros, aAAa dia THY TapaKojr. A A A ¢g A / > kal yap 4) 7aca Tob €xOpod tére avoKevi ovx Evexev TO Bpwparos yéyovev, adda Aa A , A €vexev TOO epydoacba avrots tiv mapaxonyv. Oley mapaKxovaarTes TOTE TOD pev / mapadeloou Ewer yivorrat, émitiyunbevres SixaioTaTa. .. . haer. \xx. 3. [PG XLII. 344 4] [Adam did not lose the image of God by his Fall.] tA / > ‘ > >? , >? a >? \ 4 GAdoe . . . O€dovar A€yeww Tore pev elvar TO Kar elkdva ev TH “Addy, Ews eo b] a / \ / > ‘ ~ 5A \ > , 4] A E.) > bo be Gre ev mapaxoh yéyove Kal Bexpwxev amo rob EvAov, Kal e€ewabn ad’ od dé ? , > 4 \ > bee A \ AXA , bd \ a > Q , Q pats e£ewaOn, amwdAece TO KaT ElKOva. Kat TOAAH Tis EoTl THY avIpwrwv pvooToOLa $ ” rua ¥2 a ¢ ” ¢ ols ov xpi) ovdé mpos wpav el€at, ovTE ToUToLS, OUTE ExELVOLS TOis OVTWS 7 OUTw ~ > ‘ > >? /, cA A Aéyovaw aAN elvar pev morevew ev TH avOpwmmw TO Kat’ Eikova, €v TavTt dé padora, kat ody adds. 558 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN Joun CuRYSOSTOM (A.D. 344-1407) in c. i. Genes. hom. xvi. [PG LIII. 126 f.] ; ; ; ; [Man’s paradisal state was devoid of pain.] > , ld / e 4 ~ > , ~ aA evvonady por paKapiorntos v7epBodny, mAs avatepor Hoav TOV owpaTiKdv ~ ~ A 4 amdvrwy, THs Kabamep Tov ovpavoy OUTW THY YHV @kovuy, Kal Ev O@paTL TUYXAVOVTES ~ , ‘ / MM > 7 wv € , Ta TOV cwpdtwv ovx Uiéuevov’ ovTE yap oTéyns, OTE Gpddgov, ovTE ‘partion, ~ +) , \ > € aw b} , A ~ ovre dAdov ovdevds Tav ToLovTwy edéovTo. Kal ovxY amTADs, OVSE Elk ToObTO € ~ 7 , € , 4A > 7 6 A AA b) ~ , Hiv emeonunvatro 4 Oeia ypady, GAX’ iva pabovres tHv dAuTov avtav Tavrnv , A > A e > aA , Siaywyiv, Kal Tov avwduvov Biov, Kal tHv ayyeAuKny, ws eEimeiv, KaTaoTaOL, nw ¢€ A > > A / A €reoav LOwpev pera TatTa TovTwWY amavTwWY EpHuovs adTods YyeEvopévous, Kal a ? > , tA 4 Kabamep amo troAAfs mAovTov mepiovaotas eis eAaxtoTny meviay KatevexOevras, lol , A “a / TH padupia avray 70 wav emuyparbwpev. ep. ad Olymp. ii, 3. [PG LII. 574] (The Fall of Adam condemned the whole human race.] i A 4 C.F A A € ld 3 Ud A A A A 4 Ore yap Huaprev 6 Adda Tv GpapTiay exeivny THY xadeTV, Kal TO KOLVOV / / / / , li andvrwy avOpwmmwv Katedixace yevos, WOXOw TOTE KaTEdiKaleToO. in c. 1. Genes. hom. ix. [PG LIII. 79] [As a result of the Fall man lost his empire over the animals.] Tapa yap THv apxnv ody oUTW Ta TMpaypaTra SLeKELTO, GAA’ eSedolKer Kal Erpepe 7a Onpia, kal Uméxumte TH SeamdTH. €7rE1d7) Sé THs Twappyoias efémece Sia THY mapaKkory, Kal TA THS GpxAs HKpwrnpiacbyn ... . Ews pev yap elxe THY Tpos TOV feov mappnatav, doBepos Kat trois Onpiois Fv émerd7) 5é mpocéKpovae, Kal Tovs €axdtous Ta&v auvdovrAwy ededoixer AouTov. in Matt. hom. xxviii. 3. [PG LVII. 353] [The souls of children are not evil, and are in the hand of God. ? 4 \ ” 4 > a¢ a ~ Wa cd aA aA , ovdé€ yap ev uxynv amoppayetcay Tob awpartos evtat0a mAavGabar Aowrov. 7, A A € ~ /, e aA Sixatwy yap yuxal ev yeipt Oeod' ef Sé at Tay Sdixalwy, Kal at tov waldwr Q > A / ovde yap exetvat Tornpat. in Matt. hom. lviii. [PG LVIII. 569] [Our Lord’s calling a child to Him proves that child-nature, and therefore human nature as such, 1s not an evil thing. | eldes ms aAw Huds mpos Ta Pvoixa KatopOwpara exkadeirar, Serxvds Ort €K Tpoaipecews Tatra KaTopOoby Suvarov, Kal tv Tovynpav Maviyaiwv émoropiler Avtrav; ef yap movnpov 4» vais, Tivos evexev exetOev THs didocodias Ta mapadelypata €Aket; mardiov dé por doxet ofddpa tradiov é€v TH pwéow orhoat, TOv raddv andvrwy TovTwv amynAAaypevov. 70 yap ToLwodTov madiov Kal amovolas kal dofopavias Kai Backavias Kai didoverkias Kal mavrwy THY ToLvovTwY amHAAaKTAL maddy x. T. A. PRE-AUGUSTINIAN PASSAGES 559 in ep. ad Hebr. c. vil. hom. xii. [PG LXIII. 99] [The human will, though free, 1s prone to evil.] 2. ... mpoatpeois, moAAds Seyouevn petaBodAds, kal viv pév trodro, viv dé €xeivo aipovpevn’ o€uppemis yap adtn mpos Kakiay. [Grace co-operates with, but does not ‘ prevent,’ our wills.) 3. ov mpopOdver Tas juerépas BovdArjaers, tva pi AvpHnvytat 70 adte§ovorov Hyadv. Grav dé ypeis EAdpeba, tote TOAARY elodyer Tiv BojnPeay wiv (the position later known as ‘ semi-Pelagianism’: cf. de verb. apost. habentes eundem spiritum, i. 5 [PG LI. 276]). ovre yap 6 Beds, odre 4 Tob mvevparos xdpis THY HuETEpav mpopOaver mpoaipecw* aAda Kael peév, avapever S€ Wore ExovTas Kal BovdnOévras oixobev mpocedbciv’ elra emerdav mpoceAPwpev, tore THY Tap’ €avTod mapexer ovuppaylav dmacap. in ep. ad Rom. hom. x. 2,3. [PG LX. 477 1.] (A ‘ minimising’ discussion of the classical N.T. Fall-passage. St. Paul says ‘ As through the one man’s disobedience the many were made sinners,’ etc. [Rom. v. 19]. But it seems unreasonable that one man should be deemed to have sinned, because another has disobeyed: therefore, by ‘ sinners’ the Apostle must mean ‘ liable to the penalty of sin,’ 1.e. death. Even so, however, it 1s difficult to see why mankind should be liable to death for Adam’s sin: the A postle states the fact, but is silent as to the reason for 1t.) @otep yap dua THs mapaxoys Tod évos avOpdrov apaptwdAol KateotdOynoav ot moAAot x.7.A. Kat Soxet pev Enrnua od puxpov Exew 7 elpnuevov’ dv dé Tis axpiB@s mpooexn, Kal totro edKoAws AvOyoeTrar. ti mor odv €ore TO CyrHpa 5 70 Aéyeww 81a THs mapaKkohs TOO évds GpapTwdAods yevéaBar ToAAOVs. TO per yap dpaptorros exeivov Kal yevopevov Oyntod, kal todvs €€ avrob Tovovrous elvar, oddev dmeukos’ TO O€ €k THS mapaKoys exelvou ETrepov dpaptwdAdv yevécbar, moiay av dxodovbiay axotn ; evpeOjoeTar yap ovTw unde Sixnv ddetAwy 6 ToLobToS, Et ye [7) olkobev yéyovev duaptwAds. ti ovv €otw evtadda 76 “Apaptwadot ; eyot dSoxet 7O brevOvvor KoAdoer Kal KaTadedixacpevor Oavarw. Ore pev odv Tob "Ada amobavdvTos martes eyevopueba Ovntol, cadds Kal dra ToAADY EderEe* 70 SE CnTovpevor, Tivos Evexev TOOTO yEeyorver. GAN’ otKétt TodTO mpooTibnaw: ovdé yap a’T@ mpos TO Tapov aurTEdct mMpds yap *Iovdatov 7 payn tov apdiBddAdrovta Kal KatayeAdvra THs 81a Tob Evods Sixacoovrys’ . . . . Sidmep adinow dAvrov. [In any case, our mortality is not such a very great evil: for the thought of death restrains us from many sins, and, if there had been no death, the martyrs could not have won their crowns. ] Sen im a “Kath, ' a, INDICES I. SCRIPTURAL, PSEUDEPIGRAPHIC, AND RABBINICAL REFERENCES. (a) OLD TESTA- MENT GENESIS : PAGE 1. 20-27 AlN. 2 any. 272 3, 31 Ag as 3: li. 18-25 eat? £! a»? IQ, 20 - 361 f: iia. : - 40-51 NE Gibson | PEQCI 2 LV. 2-Sa) Eh eae Eee : z 49 vi. 1-8 . 20-23 ae 2 23.1 eS j f 60 Viil. 21 A : 60 Exopus vil. 3 : 16 7”. 2 xxil. 16 LXX 122 n. 2 LEVITICUS Mie: : 224 NUMBERS MAN OOZe uh ares xxi. 6-9 I7i %.2 JUDGES 1Xq, 29 iG”: 2 t SAMUEL li. 25 16. 2 xix. 9 16”. 2 2 SAMUEL XXiv. I 16 ”.2 NEHEMIAH 176.67 4 Ae B00 Jos PAGE 1V 717 : eee? XIV. 4 : oleae ty: »? 4, 5 224, 304, 378 XV. 14, 15 Py, XXV. 4 : : LZ XK VIL 21”. 1 PsALMS Vili. 5 ; 21 n. 4 muax.53 LXX Zoe li. 5. 19, 224, 304, 378 1b 9. vb P72 ae am 503 ix, 22 A s 65 Cxix. 67 213 (ie. @ 6, oh, ee An fe) Gxt 2. bs , I9 PROVERBS XV Gedy hl eke 1 OF, ECCLESIASTES i. 18 2 SSO ISAIAH Xi. I-9 159 7”. 2 pO. 2.4 Keg 16 7. 2 ES Fy 2 ; 16 JEREMIAH XVii. 9 15 ”.1 Keel eso +: 3 15 EZEKIEL Vill ae 15”. 2 2? 20 I5 XXVili. II-I9Q . 50 DANIEL 1x:'20 A 14 $90 561 Amos PAGE lil. 6 16 ”. 2 MicaH 14”. 3 2 ESDRAS v. wmfra, under (c), Pseudepigrapha, 4 Ezra JUDITH X11. 16 122”. 2 WISDOM xs ‘ ECCLESIASTICUS XV. II-I7 a8) 02 43-45 Ti0”.1I KU SSi3oy LL... 1 xXVersiir 107 ” 19 °, 97 XV. 23-35 OO MIA 98 n. I ee < OO xxii. 29 ff. 107 xxiv. 28 252: 4 St. MARK a. 15 96 2.1 iv. 15 TIO N. I Wilsod ts 107 Aes din 97, 482 Vlil. 33 Ito ”, I <6 98 2.1 xii. 24 ff bike 9 XV. 45 294 St. LUKE Vl. 43-45 - 97 %. 2 x. 18 495 > 4 a + on OF »» 24-36 IIo”. 1 xiii. 2-5 Bapvne a) XV. 7 g6 A iis 107 KUL 244 Wot, Pi a A030 106 MNS Las a uteent LO. d ST. JOHN ill. I-2I. 08 ff. 2? 5 ‘4 378 iv. 44 103 ”. I vi. 63 at ALO# vlil. 44 TIO #%. 1 TK 719 98, 214 xii. 25 Se LOS Hk TAY ot 110 ”. I xiii. 16 103 2.1 ee 230 103 ”.1 xiv. 30 IIO 2.1 XV. 20 103 ”.1 XVIEL eae ALO tis S », 2-14 eLOF XVii. 15 IIo”. 1 Acts Vin TS G57 220, te 1 Pb Oyen Gs. 137 2. 3 ROMANS WEG Me. i) ZOOM A iil, 12-15 128”. 1 a T5 491 AM ek Le he it 322 PAGE Vv. I2-21 124-134, 335 ”. I », 12 364, 379 ee Bs) A SL eS vi. I-II 134-138 Zo 369 vii. 5 139 ry 725 140-1 46, 327, 481 ” 8 459 n.1 », 18-24 335 2. I >? 19 * > 31 EX eg ee Vili. 3 153, 154 Oy, : tab 2» 9 : 147 », 18-22 157-159 IX 213”. 5 », 20, 21 437 Tee 381 Nay! eat S10 %. 2 xi033 381 Xill.v2¢, La 325 XIV. 23 375, 431 I CORINTHIANS i. 16 220 ”. I li. 8 160 Vv. 5 Se LOO 7 328 Nn. 3 vi. 13 148 2 819 148 Vil. 5 Ae OO See | 220 n. 2, 233%. 1 SaeeO 21 CeEOO Xl. 10 ieeks Sap as4 kl oO XV. S122 (t23 1, » 22 335 ”. 1 An Zo 220 nm. I ones Aude . 148 aE 211 »» 45-49 123 » 47 9 2 CORINTHIANS li. II 160 iv. 4 160 eG Ixv. 6-8 . d 2 ERA 5 1617%.°3 pee O40 ee 7, » I! 57 %. 3 Ixxxv.—xc. AO Tee Ixxxix. I0 rd eee GVit ; I6I 7. 3 2 ENOCH PAGE viii. P TO2/%.. 1 Xviil. (A text) 24 7. 3 oe abd AA oie LOL XENIAG wee 57 REX (AS Texty ae 5 7 xiae. : : 55 4 EZRA lll. 2I-23 . 80 lv. 30 80 Vil; Lin 2 80 », 16-118 80 LLU Cumin 252 2. 4 JUBILEES iil. 17-35 . Mit eo vii. 26-39 Tiled. Des He <1 ed TEsT. ASSER i.-iv. 6 150 2. 4 Lest. Lev. XVill. IO, II fal eX Test. NAPTH. EBS : he A TEST. REUB. Vv. 5-7 : we O 563 (d@) RABBINICAL DOCUMENTS BABA BATHRA PAGE 16a . ; uM OT 17a) - - OS BERAKHOTH Olaw 652.1 GEN. RAB. Cyan, . Sa OT S40 : 2 OF ECCLES. RAB. see Bip : ae OF LEV. RAB. 2 Ola 65”. 1 NUM. RAB. Ty 3 : i OF PIRQE ’ABOTH ill. 24 86 n. I QIDDUSHIN 30b . 62, 67 YEBAMOTH 78a . 220 nN. 2 202 AUTHORS. AALL, A., 234 ”. 2 Abaelard, Peter, 398 Adeimantius, 293 Aeschylus, 35, 235 ”. 6 d’Ailly, Pierre, 418 d’Alés, A., 231 ”. I Allen, W. C., 98 1. 2 Ambrose, St., 299-307, 373 ”. 3 ‘ Ambrosiaster,’ 307-310, 328, 379 %. 2 Anastasius Sinaita, 191 Androutsos, M., 543 Anselm, St., 294, 397 Aquinas, St. Thomas, 9 u. 5, 234 nN. 4, 400-408 Aristotle, 625) nse) 180, \145 /-1., 235 2. GO, 254 #. 5, 277 %. 3 Athanasius, St., 257-262 Athenagoras, 177 ”. 3 Augustine, St., 170, 234 ”. 4, 293, 300, 309, 314, 317 ff., 430f. BACHER, W., 65 ”. I, 67 un. 4, 5, 6 Baius, Michael, 360 7. 3, 363, 422 Barnabas, Epistle of, 150 ”. 4, I71 Basil, St., 254 ”. 3, 264-269, 276 ”.1, 293 Bensly, R. L., 75 ”. 1 Bergson, Henri, 484 ”. 1, 523 Bernard, St., 416 ”. 2 Bethune-Baker, Dr. J. F., 237 n. 3 Bevan, Dr. Edwyn, 160 x. 9 Beza, Theodore, 436 n. 1 Bigg, Dr. C., 203, 205 ”. 1, 207 ”. I, 208, 215 . 2, 219, 487 Bindley, T. H., 351 2. 3 Bonaventura, St., 415 Bonwetsch, G. N., 58 2. 3, 250 . I Bousset, W., 64 ”. I, 140 ”. 2, 147, 183 ”. 3, 215 4. 1 Box, Dr. G. H., 75 . 1, 80 mu. 1, 252 n. 4 Bradley, F. H., 465 ”. 3 Bright, "Dr. »W., 332 %. 12, 4996. 353 Nn. 2, 4 Brightman, Canon F. E., x Brown, Dr. W., 485 ”. 1 Brown, Driver and Briggs, 252 n. 4, 277 %. 3 Buchler;*Dr. A.,°277 7..3 Bull, Bishop, 361 Buonaiuti, E., 330 . I, 366 ”. 3 Barkitt, Dro F.C. (1Sjng02 wee 324 %- 3 % Burn, Dr. A. E., 5547.71 Burney, Dr. C. F., 100 u. I Bury; J: B...332) 2a Butler, Samuel, 381 CaLvin, John, 322, 426, 431 f., 434, 436 f. Casartelli, L. C., 6 ”. 1 Caspari, C. P., 357 ”. 1 Cassian, John, 350 x. 3 Chapman, Dom John, O.S.B., 99 Nn. 2 Charles, Dr. R. H., 24 . 1, 64 . 1, 75 %. I, 139 %. 3, 495 ”. 1 Chemnitz, Martin, 435 . 2 Chrysostom, St. John, 558 f. Church, Dean, 440 Clement of Alexandria, 202-208 Coleridge, S..1.,.47°%. 2, Sig caren Commodian, 555 Cooke, Dr. G. A., 41 2. 1 Coulton, G. G., 419 ”. I Coustant, P., 385 nn. 2, 3 Cumont, F.,.6 #. 1;7 2". 2,38 Cyprian, St., 295 f. Cyril of Alexandria, St., 351 #. 3 Cyril of Jerusalem, St., 263 DANTE, 406 f. Deissmann, A., 124 ”. I Delavigne, Casimir, 464 n. 2 504 ee a oe a ee ee INDEX OF AUTHORS Delff, 100 Deussen, P., 5 ”. I Didache, 150 n. 4 Diekamp, Fr., 319 u. I Diognetus, Epistle to, 177 n. 3 Dositheus, 542 Draguet, R., 254 ”. 5, 388 n. 3 Driver, Dr. S. R., 14 . 2 Du Cange, 233 ”. 4, 240 ”. 2, 555 _ Duchesne, L., 319 ”. I, 347 ”. I, 348 nn. I, 2, 354 2%. 3, 385 nN. 4. Dyobouniotis, M., 543 EDERSHEIM, A., 96 7. 2, IIQ 7”. 2 Ellis, Havelock, 468 Epiphanius, 556 f. Erichson, Alfred, 444 Erigena, Scotus, 397 Esser, G., 231 ”. I Eucken, R., 320 u. I Everling, O., 159 7. 3 FAIRBAIRN, A. M., 434 ”. 4 Farquhar, J. N., 5 ”. 1 Formby, Dr. C. W., ix Frazer, Sir James, 48, 56 7. I GALEN, 235 7. 6 Gavin, F., 543 Gibbon, 297 ”. I Ginzberg, Louis, 74 ”. 4, 307 n. 3 Gloucester, Bishop of (Dr. A. C. be Headlam), 108 ”. 3, 119 ”. 2 Goethe, 465, 523 ”. I Goodricke, A. T. S., 29 ”. 4 Gore, Bishop, 99 ”. 2, 350 Goudge, Dr. H. L., 40 n. 1 Gratian (decretum of), 408 n. I Gray, G. Buchanan, 22 7. 1 Green, Canon Peter, ix Gregory of Nazianzus, St., 282-292, 293, 345 . 2, 552 m. I Gregory of Nyssa, St., 260, 269-282, 301 f., 343, 389, 526 Gregory of Rimini, 415 HARNACK, A. von, 97 ”. I, 171 %. I, 194,) 108, #2.) 6," 219, (258,200, 347 %. I, 382 ”. 2, 416 Hawkins, Sir John, 97 n. I Hegel, 503-506 Hermas, 150 #. 4, 172 Herodotus, 25 7. 3 Hilary of Poitiers, St., 24 m. 4, 298 f. Hilgenfeld, 171 ”. I, 252 ”. 4 Hilt, Fr., 269 ”. 2 565 Hippocrates, 233 7. 6, 235 n. 6 Hippolytus, 252 7. 4 Holmes, S., 29 ”. 4 Hooker, Richard, 220 n. 2, 440 n. 2 Howorth, Sir Henry, 180 n. 2 Hubert, Fr., 443 Huet, P. D., 215 ”. 2, 219 ”. I Higel, Baron F. von, 464 n. 1 IenaTius of Antioch, St., 261 2. 6 Inge; WK. 4G%. 1-3) 51019.) Ly 528 n. I Irenaeus, 9 ”. 3, 177 ”. 3, 188 un. 2, 189-199, 247, 293, 305 Jackson, A. V. Williams, 6 2. I James, Dr. M. R., 75 m. I, 311 u. 2 James, W., 155, 169 Jerome, St., 295 ”. 2, 31I ”. 2, 376 John of Damascus, St., 277 x. 3, 293, 388 . Johnson, H. J. T., 513 2. 2 Josephus, 30 ”. 4, 161 Jowett, Dr. Benjamin, 115 Julian of Eclanum, 341 mn. 1, 2, 343 ”. I, 356 Jung, C. G., 68, 470 f. Justin Martyr, 105 m. I, 173-175, 456 Justinian, the Emperor, 210 %. 2, 232 KANT, 497-503 Keats, 284 n. 3 Kennedy, Prof. H. A. A., 135 ”. 1 Khayyam, Omar, 532 Kidd, Dr.) Be}. say ient Kirk, K. E., 65 2. 3 Krafft-Ebing, 468 Krampf, A., 269 ”. 2 Lacey, Canon T. A., x, 320 ”. 4 Lactantius, 188 n. 2, 297 f. Lake, Prof. Kirsopp, 105 m. I, 115 ff., 135 Langdon, S., 48 ”. 1 Laski, John, 444 Leporius, 350 ”. 3 Lidzbarski, 41 x. I Lightfoot, J., 98 ”. 3, 222 n. I Lightfoot, Bishop, 171, 183 ”. I Ljunggren, G., 398 nv. 3, 413 1. 2 Loewe, Hi Mf... %)73 nig Lombard, Peter, 411 Loofs, Prof. F., 250 ”. 1, 254 ”. 4, 824 n. I, 347 nN. I 566 THE FALL AND Lucretius, 235 ”. 6 Luther, Martin, 426, 428 f., 433 f. McDovea.t, Dr. W., 472 f., 479 McTaggart, Dr. J. E., 504, 505 Maldonatus, 307 x. 3 Mansel, H. L., 382 n. 1 Marett,( Dr. iK- R13 Marius Mercator, 349, 385 f. Martindale, C. C., S.J., 553 Martyrium Polycarpi, 222 n. 3 Maximus Confessor, 388 . 1 Melancthon, Philip, 435 Methodius of Olympus, 188 n. 2, 249-2560, 277, 280 Mill, John Stuart, 382 Milton, John, 39, 45 wm. I, 27I nN. 3 Moberly, Dr. R. C., 305 Mogila, Peter, 541, 543 Mohler, J. A., 428 ”. 1 Molinos, 461 ”. 3 Moller, E. W., 269 n. 2 Monceaux, P., 231 ”. I, 245 Montefiore, C. G., 98 x. 2 Morfill and Charles, 57 ”. 5, 161 n. 1 Morin, Dom Germain, O.S.B., 309 n. 1 Moulton, J. H., 6.1 Mozley, J. B., 362 . 3, 370, 374 f. Miller, F. Max, 5 un. 1, 2 Miller, J., 507-509 47> NEWMAN, Cardinal, 261 Nicephorus, 273 7. 2 Norden, E., 320 n. 2 Novatian, 554 f. Occam, William, 413 x. 2 Oesterley and Box, 73 n. 3 Olympiodorus, 388 x. I Origen, 208-231, 247 ”n. I, 2, 266f., 209,° 271 RAZi2IO MN 4) ZO5 A250, 293, 304, 371, 453, 5°97 PAcIAN of Barcelona, 555 Papias, 99 Parkman, F., 551 ”. I Pascal, 9 Pelagius, 334 f., 337-346 Petavius, 323 ”. I Pfleiderer, ‘0.7147 Philo Judaeus, 30 7. 4, 81-84, 524 Photius, 210 ”. I, 349 ”. 2 Plato, 84, 214, 525 ORIGINAL SIN Plotinus, 280 n. 5, 326, 526, 528 Plutarch, 7 ”. 1 Pohle-Preuss, 309 7. 2 Porphyry, 209 n. 3 Porter; -F.\G., 65 #.°15163 Porteus, Bishop, 442 f. Prosper of Aquitaine, 350 n. 3 Prudentius, 556 Pullain, Valerand, 444 QUENSTEDT, J. A., 429 n. 4 RASHDALL, H., 293 mn. I, 2, 3, 4 Reuter, H., 321 n.2;322 "ig Ritschl, A., 293 ”. I, 427 ”. I, 438 Riviére, J., 269 ”. 2, 293 ”. I Robertson, Dr. A., 261 2. 3 Robinson, Dr. J. Armitage, 113 n. 1, T9O #%. 1, 198 ”. 6 Rottmanner, Dom O., O.S.B., 328 nN. 3 Rufinus, 210 ”. 2, 211 ”. 4 Russell, Bertrand, 482 SABATIER, A., 293 ”. I Sanday and Headlam, 124 mn. I, 2, 127 N. I, LAI ”. 3,258, 37514 Schechter, S., 74 ”. 4 Schechter and Taylor, 62 n. I Schleiermacher, Friedrich, 438 Schopenhauer, 524 Schouppe, F. X., S.J., 309 ”. 2 Schirer, E.; 1199.12 Scotus, Duns, 176, 408-418 Seeberg, R.; 226 2325347 not Shakespere, 277 ”. 3 Singer, S.,.67 ”. I Skinner,.,J., 23.1, 41 %u2/A2 sek 45:-%. 2, 48 2.1 Smith, G. A., 159 ”. 2 Smith, W. Robertson, 24 n. 4 Sophocles, 14 Soranus, 233 7. 6 Souter, Prof. A., 125 ”. 2, 307 #. 4, 334 %. 1 Stawley, «Dr: *]. *H:,/;220uaee 269 n. 2 Stanton, V., 100 ”. 2 Stewart, J. A., 47 Stone, Dr. Darwell, x, 278 n. 3 Streeter, Canon’-B. 0Ha107# sme, 00 %..1, IOI #.£1,°106 92 Suicer, 277 n. 3 swete, Dr. H..B., 349 niepegsr nn. I, 2 Symmachus, 30 #. 3 INDEX OF AUTHORS TANSLEY, O., 485 7. 2 Tatian, 175 f., 198 . 5 Taylor, C., 61 ”. I, 98 n. 2 Taylor, Jeremy, 441 f. Tennant, Dr. F. R., ix, 10, 57-7. 5, FACRLO Zou 21h 227) M2, 297) eas; 539-537 Tertullian, 231-245, 293, 295 Thackeray, H. St. John, 122 2. I Theodore of Mopsuestia, 349, 351 Theodotion, 24 ”. 3 Theophilus, 176 Thompson, Francis, 284 n. 3 Thucydides, ror Tillemont, 273 n. 2 Mixcront, | :, 232. %%.'1,13,,292 #r 2} 363 Nn. 3 Tollinton, R. B., 208 n. 1 Turmel, J.; 231 #.'1, $23 4. 1, 363, 416 nu. 2 VENANTIUS Fortunatus, 9 ”. 3 Victorinus Afer, 252 n. 2 567 Vincent of Lérins, 11, 187, 384 n. 1 Violet and Gressmann, 252 ”. 4 Vossius, G: 3777329) 7.°5 WARNER, J. H., 399 u. 1 Waterworth, J., 540 Watkins, O. D., 137 Weber, F., 69 n. 2, 73 Westcott, Bishop, 209 m. I, 416 n. I Westermarck, E., 520 m. I Wicksteed, P. H., 211 n. 2 Wied, Hermann von, 445 YELVERTON, E., 446 ZAHN, Dr. Theodor, 205 n. I Zosimus, Pope, 348, 385 Zwingli, 436 . 1 III. SUBJECTS. ABSOLUTE, the, 5, 505 actus concupiscentiae, 367 Adam and Christ, parallelism of, 9, 126 ff. Adam, alleged intellectual powers of, 361; allegorised as universal of ‘ Man,’ 203, 229, 306; colossal stature ascribed to, 71; mortal by nature, 53; perfect sanctity ascribed to, 362; said to have been buried on Calvary, 307; said to have been ultimately saved, 198 n. 5 Adam-story, adoption as Fall- narrative, 29 f., 51 f.; original significance of, 40-51 African theology, harsh character of, 330 Ahura Mazdah, 6 Albigenses, the, 399 ‘am ha- ave¢, 59, 70, 119 ‘ Ambrosiaster,’ identity of, 309”. I Anachronisms, 533 ‘ Ancestral sin,’ 388, 542 Angels, pre-mundane Fall of, 161 f., 453, 495 Angel-story of Gen. vi., 20-29, 30, 77, 114 Angra Mainyu, 6 Antioch, Christology of, 349 ff. Aphthartodocetic controversy, 254 n. 5 amokatdoracs, 279 ”. 4 Apollinarianism, 282, 291, 292 2.1,2 Apologists, Fall-doctrine in, 173- 177 Appetite, hypertrophy of, 156, 288; moral neutrality of, 60, 153, 276, 343 Aquinas, St. Thomas, 400-408 Archetypal Man, the, 271, 526, 536 Arts, origin of the, 25, 35, 49 Augustine, St., ancestor both of Latin Catholicism and of the 568 Reformation, 321 f.; conversion of, 325; life of, 323-326 ; person- ality and achievements of, 319 ff. Augustinianism, 360-384 Aureole of light, would have been bestowed on Adam but for the Fall, 269 BAPTISM, 99, 104, 134 ff., 306, 3606 f., 421 Baptism of infants, 219-226, 241, 279, 289, 295, 344, 379, 412, 559-554 Bar Kokhba, 81 Birth-stain, conception of, 224 ff. CAELESTIUS, 333, 337, 347; 353, 357 %. 3, 385, 387 Canon of the New Testament, 181 Carthage, Synod of (A.D. 411), 347 Carthage, Synod of (A.D. 418), 348, 391 ‘ Categorical imperative,’ 498 Celestine I., Pope, 387 ‘Censorship,’ the, 471 ‘Coats of skins,’ allegorised by the Greek Fathers, 229, 251, 275, 285 Complexes, 471, 474, 491 ‘Concupiscence,’ 34, 137, 154, 240, 243 £., 342, 351, 365, 402, 4II, 422, 432, 458 Congregational Confessions of Original Sin, 419 ”. 2, 443-446 Consciousness, 470 Conversion, instantaneous, 155, 331, 426 Corruption (see also ‘ Disintegra- tion ’), 254 Council 7m Trullo, the, 385 n. I Creed, Nicene, 314, 553 Creed,‘ Niceno-Constantinopolitan,’ 314, 345, 412, 553 Ca: ae : : INDEX OF SUBJECTS da quod iubes, 336 Damnation, eternal, original guilt, 372 f., 486 ‘Deification’ through the Eucharist, 201, 202itae. 295; 202 Deism, 356, 535 f. Deposit of Faith, the, 313 f., 317 Determinism. See Free-will Devils, personal, belief in, 108-112, 159 ff., 175, 527 ‘ Devil’s rights, the,’ 292 ff. ‘ Disintegration,’ 277, 288, 388 donum indebitum, 401, 427 n. 1 donum superadditum, supernaturale, 363, 422 Peas +O, 147. 1..° 253; .20T,7 320, 398 exmTa@ous (see also ‘ Fall,’ the term, history of), 268 élan vital, 523, 534 Entelechies, 523 Ephesus, Council of, 353 f., 385, 389 ‘ Ethico-physical’ theory of salva- tion, 255 Eucharist, the, 278. See also ‘ Deifi- cation’ through the Eucharist Eugenics, 477 ‘Eve,’ origin of name, 41 ”. I Evil, anhypostatic theory of, 255, ZOO 260002955" 87t57. 405) at tributed to God’s appointment, 16, 17, 435, 532 Evolution, 530 f. “exemplarist ’ soteriology, 352 Exorcism, 379 Exsufflation, 379 Fatt and Redemption, mutual implication of, 8, 131, 208 Fall, Anglican doctrine of the, 437- 443; Hegelian interpretation of, 503 ff.; collective pre-natal, 228, 513 ”. 1; individual pre-natal, theory of the, 84, 208-219, 266, 508-512; inferred from existence of evil, 18, 19; infinite malice of, 364; of man, the, compara- tively venial, 195, 410, 4560; the, source of bodily death, 123; the, source of physical evil, 76 f.; the term, history of, 252 . 4, 275, 455; the ultimate, 524 ff. ; timeless conception of, 501 Fall-doctrine, the, crucial issues implicit in, 168, 246, 359; ‘ Hellenic ’ and ‘ African ’ versions of, 200 f., 246 ff.; its penalty of 569 adoption by the Church, 118-121 ; residual minimum of, formu- lated, 452-461 Fall-story, allegorical interpreta- tion of, 192, 216, 269 f., 285, 360 Flesh, the, 139 f., 145, 146-149 Flesh, the mind of the, 150 ff. fomes peccatt, 218, 403 Foreknowledge, Divine, 271 Fourth Gospel, the, 98-105 Free-will, 176, 218, 256, 263, 264, 274, 281, 328, 341, 355 £., 368 ff, 404, 433 ff., 467 ff., 483 ff. GALILEE, 119 Gnosticism, 182-184 Gospels, Apocryphal, 311 ”. 2 Grace, 138 ”. I HAaBit, tyranny of, 341 Heart, the, as seat of the yécer, 65, 152 Heathen, good works of the, 374, 414, 439, 432, 441 Herd-complex, the, 476 ‘ Herd-instinct,’ 479, 514 Heredity, believed to operate through the father only, 235 f. ‘ Heredity, social,’ 51, 343, 467 Hexateuch, critical theory of, Ig”. 5 hominidae, 518 Honorius, the Emperor, 348 f. Human nature, sin of, 305 ‘IMAGE and likeness’ of God, 194, 262 Incarnation, absolute purpose of, 416 ‘Incontinence,’ Aristotle’s concep- tion of, 145 ‘Infancy,’ man’s primitive state one of, 41, 176,193; 1900 %a) G, 242, 252, 286, 409 Infants dying unbaptised future destiny of, 279, 376 ff., 405 ff., 415 f., 440 ‘Infirmity, hereditary,’ 458, 461, 465, 480 inquinamentum, legend of the, 57 f., ay, Instinct, 471 ff. JEALousy of man, attributed to God, 25, 43 Jerome, St., 376 Jesus Curist, teaching of, 95-112 B79 Karma, 6, 215 Kingdom of God, the, 106 lapsus, 303, 514 Law and sin, 127 f. Law, Mosaic, a remedy for the yecer, 62, 79 libido, 68, 153, 472, 480 Life-force, the, 523 Limbo, 279, 290, 346, 348 n. 2, 385 ”. 3, 405 ff., 415, 464, 486 Livania, 338 Logos, the, 252, 258, 259 ”. 4, 292, 529 ‘Logos Spermatikos,’ 523, 533 f. Maat, the, 6 Man’s moral weakness due to his creaturely nature, 17, 297, 532 ff. Mana, 13, 224, 355 Manicheism, 256, 274, 301, 324f., 429 Marcion, Marcionism, 183, 189 Marriage, regarded as inferior to virginity, 156, 245 Mary, the Blessed Virgin, Immacu- late Conception of, 370 ”. 2, 417; parallelism between Eve and, 9, 174, 190; sinlessness of, 370 massa, 308, 310 massa peccati, perditionis, etc., 328, 3390 Mazdeism, 6 Mill, John Stuart, 382 Missions, foreign, 486 f. Mithraism, 7 Monism, unmoral, 5, 84, 183, 437 Monnica, 323 Monophyletism, 516 natura natuvans, 534 Nature, sub-human, evil in, 157 ff., 519 ff. ‘ Nature and grace,’ 371, 400 ‘ Nature and supernature,’ 400 Neanderthal man, 195, 514 nephilim, the, 21 f. Nestorius, 353 f. Neurosis, 475 Nicodemus, 98 Nominalism, 413 non posse peccare, 362 n. 2 Noimenal self, the, 502 ‘“OccuLT justice,’ ascribed to God, 329 NH. 2, 381, 436 ‘Once-born ’ temperament, 169 THE FALL AND ORIGINAL SIN Origen, life of, 209 f. ‘ Original Guilt,’ 72 ff., 207, 289 f., 295, 304, 307 f£., 372, 411, 440, 551 ‘Original Righteousness and Per- fection,’ 56 f£., 71; 258, 300) 85 360 ff., 409, 420 f., 453, 513 ”. 2 ‘ Original Sin,’ 73, 433, 457; as de- fect of Original Righteousness,’ 170,307 1. 41Owaro ‘ originale peccatum,’ 327 oviginalis veatus, 327 Orosius, 348 mapapaots, 171, 227, 455 Paradise, extra-mundane concep- tion of, 192, 250 f., 267; meta- physical conception of, 230, 267, 285 Patricius, 323 Paul, St., teaching of, 123-162 Pelagian controversy, the, 347-354 ‘ Pelagian Paradise,’ the, 340 Pelagianism, 332-347 Pelagius, his commentary on the Pauline Epistles, 334 ”. I, 335 ”. 1 Penance, Sacrament of, 137 Phaedrus, myth of, 84,214,271 7.2 Philo, yéc¢er in, 82 f. d0opa, 254, 388. See also ‘Disinte- gration’ dvpapa, 83 n. 2, 264 N. 1, 310 %. 2 pithecanthropus erectus, 514 Platonism, 83, 148, 254, 371 posse non peccare, 362 praevaricatio, 227, 302, 455, 514 Pre-conscious, the, 470 Predestination, 329, 434 Prophets, Hebrew, 14 f. Psychotherapy, 485 pura naturalia, 259, 363, 422 Q, 97 ”. I, 105 ‘RADICAL evil,’ Kant’s conception of, 499 f. Realism, logical, 413 veatus concupiscentiae, 367 ‘Recapitulation’ in Athanasius, 262; in Gregory of Nazianzus, 291; in Gregory of Nyssa, 280; in Irenaeus, 197 f. ; in Methodius, 252 Reformation, the, 423-426 Revelation, modes of, 89 f. Rigorism, Pelagian, 357 Rufinus, 339 INDEX OF SCHLEIERMACHER, 438 Scotus, Duns, 408-418 Selfishness, 521 “Seminal identity,’ 197, 237, 299, 395, 372, 421 Sentiments, the, 470 f., 473 Serpent, the, in Gen. ili., 44 f., 48, I9I Sex-motif in Fall-speculation, 45, 50) 177, 100; 204, 220, 227, 271- 273, 304, 340 #. I, 366, 411 nm. 2 Sin, actual, universality of, 17, 19, 96; foetal, 98 ». 3; ‘ medical’ and ‘ forensic ’ ways of regarding, 133, 292, 296, 365; cf. 73 Sinless saints in the Old Testament, 262, 342 “Sons of the gods.’ story of Gen. vi. Soul, materialistic conception of, 234 f.; structure of, 469 ff. splendida vitia, 375 Stars, believed to be animate, 211 ‘ Sublimation,’ 475, 485 “ Suppressed sinfulness,’ 132 f., 142 Supra-lapsarianism, 436 See Angel- Tannaim, 73 Theodicy, 265, 525 Thirty-Nine Articles, 10, 439 Time, reality of, 523 . 2 ‘ Total depravity ’ of human nature, 428 ff. SUBJECTS tvactoria, epistula, 348, 385 f. Traducianism, 233 ff., 280, 368 tradux, 240 n. 2 Tree of Knowledge, the, 43 Tree of Knowledge and Tree of the Cross, parallelism of, 9, 191 Trent, Council of, 419-421 “Twice-born’ temperament, 169, 331 571 155, UNconscious, the, 471 VINCENTIAN Canon, the, 11, 184- 188, 310 ff., 384, 396 vitium originis, 239, 245, 299 ‘WATCHERS,’ the, 24 ‘Watcher - story.’ story of Gen. vi. Will, the, 277; weakness of, 256, 460, 465 World-Soul, the, 525 fff. Wrath, God’s, 113 ”. 1, 462 f. See Angel - yerer ha-va‘, 59-70, 97, 150, 343, 517; created by God, 69; in what sense evil, 66 f. Zosimus, Pope, 348 Printed in England at Tux BALLANTYNE PRESS SPOTTISWOODE, BALLANTYNE & Co. Lrp. Colchester, London & Eton ~ DATE DUE DEMCO 38-297 “ Princeton Theological Seminar il 2 0101 Ment WHIM TE es SS —— Sa SS os ae eae econ