SE Ee Se ua aHEALEL — eo —— a me) © = a se we =e > es # — —- —{Atayireteansieiersesenasstere ste serv ames tneueseupastupunpainyaintesabasncasertaes sess scoseecnereeene seseeeeen tases eaaeerroraeemomnreeseneens orgies Tie nt te ecient Sgr eens Homey pt gente eae tae Phatereeg +. <> 4k ed ~ , Y MORAL THEOLOGY Vol. 6é &¢ DOGMATIC THEOLOGY BY FRANCIS J. HALL, D.D. A series of ten volumes, each complete in itself, designed to constitute a connected treatment of the entire range of Catholic Doctrine. i i. Introduction to Dogmatic Theology. Authority, Ecclesiastical and Biblical. The Being and Attributes of God. The Trinity. Creation and Man. The Incarnation. The Passion and Exaltation of Christ. The Church and the Sacramental System. The Sacraments. Eschatology. Indexes. MORAL THEOLOGY BY THE Rey. FRANCIS J. HALL, D.D. PROFESSOR OF DOGMATIC THEOLOGY IN THE » GENERAL THEOLOGICAL SEMINARY, NEW YORK CITY>, ey AND THE Rev. FRANK H. HALLOCK, D.D. PROFESSOR OF OLD TESTAMENT AND SEMITIC LANGUAGES IN SEABURY DIVINITY SCHOOL, FARIBAULT, MINN. LONGMANS, GREEN AND CO. §5 FIFTH AVENUE, NEW YORK 39 PATERNOSTER ROW, LONDON, E. C. 4 TORONTO, BOMBAY, CALCUTTA, AND MADRAS 1924 COPYRIGHT, 1923, BY LONGMANS, GREEN AND CO. MADE IN THE UNITED STATES HBredicated WITH HIS GRACIOUS PERMISSION TO THE RIGHT REVEREND WILLIAM WALTER WEBB, D.D. BISHOP OF MILWAUKEE AND AUTHOR OF THE VALUABLE MANUAL “THE CURE OF SOULS” Digitized by the Internet Archive in 2022 with funding from Princeton Theological Seminary Library https://archive.org/details/moraltheologyOOhall PREFACE I HAD intended, after finishing the production of my series of ten volumes in Dogmatic Theology, to add as sequel thereto a work on Moral Theology, a subject which I taught in the Western Theological Seminary for some twenty years. Various reasons, however, threatened greatly to delay my completion of this work, when my scholarly friend and former pupil, Dr. Frank H. Hallock, offered to help me in preparing existing material of mine for immediate publication. I was the more ready to accept his kind offer because of the numerous letters which I was receiving, urging the present need of some kind of handbook of Moral Theology. Accordingly, Dr. Hallock has taken my Western Seminary Syllabus, has slightly enlarged it, amended it, and brought it up to date, and has filled in the footnotes—an arduous undertaking. I have in turn gone over the footnotes and, with occasional slight amendments of both text and notes, have added to the bibliographical matter. I am also responsible for the opening chapter on “The Study of Moral Theology.” With grateful thanks to Dr. Hallock for his most valuable help, I express my earnest hope that our vil Vili PREFACE book may help on the revival so much needed of the study of Moral Theology. It is, of course, a mere handbook, and does not remove the need of more adequate treatises. LO Pils & 6Or een ® w CONTENTS CHAPTER I THE STUDY OF MORAL THEOLOGY Part I. Introductory PE ROUIVALOLITILELES Eeyore eee ee Uae Ua eg Tce . Onesided Tendency of Ethical Literature.......... Pieurrent Utilitariany LGGAlSs ce ue og ail ie ie Part II. Survey of Moral Science . Its Several Branches: Practical Aspect............ . Legalistic and Ascetic Elements. 0) .0..003655 . The Place of Psychology...... TOM Onge Nhat teeta Part III. Some Snares . In Distinguishing Venial and Mortal sin.......... . In Judging the Guilt of Relapses................. . In Teaching the Need of Sacramental Confession... CHAPTER II INTRODUCTION AND HISTORY . Definitions eoeepeveoeveeere ee epee eovnee sree ed eeooeoe ene eone@ Part I. Ancient Pagan Ethics 37 CONTENTS x PAGE Sa) Greek Ethics o's lela visteie t mauelemre. alee: petenue arnt oar 24 §)\5)) Greco-Roman Ethics. hogs oie emais ern ea aeane 30 Part II. Christian Ethics $6.) New departures.) ‘sa cys cleiebile eels Cy ene ieee 32 S 7) Patristic: Ethics ny ion wo aa ee aataretrar onare 27 $5. Scholastic Behics, Jee Oc nel ae eat ea AI $0. Later; Roman Ethics.) (ace gama cise eee 44 Sto.|' Protestant Ethics .:.!0. eed eens Ue mines aie tae 46 Part III. Modern Ethics Sir. Hobbes to Hume oy eee hee 47 §12:\Precipitations after umesr nie aay hha 50 §13. Epitome of Ethical Systems..... a ncd es phga Waa we) OnL lel onan ate CHAPTER III MORAL PHILOSOPHY OR SYSTEMATIC ETHICS St) Assumptions... ee ra. rete iegia cieievehk ane 60 Part I. The Agent §'2.\ The Intellectual Faculties f073 (isa eee ae 62 $3: The Emotions) ui uiet Aa) Cuan aman oe ee 68 Sep ane WTA OTT OEM er VANS Un ti iMag) Ay Nhat 69 8) 6. The Body s Ve ue Dare ae a acco ea Ra Oa ca 75 $!'6,' Man’s: Moral History dupe ua aus ee wen ee 76 Part II. The End § 7. Ends of Moral Conductom uy ima, ae oa cua aan 77 88) Motivese. ge IO Aa a en at ae Gee 80 Part III. The Act 8.9. The Morality’ of Actions (vie mie ls cn aera 83 $10. Acts Classified iit i) i Cn nl TE nS cD a lia 86 Sir. Virtues and) Vitese Join Ole Wily ae ine 89 §12, ‘The Practice of Religion. (Ann cunaiaeuaie ss wue g2 602602602 6072602607 602COR Cony Qui > Wh H CONTENTS xi CHAPTER IV MORAL THEOLOGY PROPER: LAW Part I. The Law of God PAGB - Definition of Moral Theology Proper............. 95 UME WW IL an Law OL. Gr0du ice int ielsa aa aele wt 97 POVLELDOC Ob) ETERCINON Uys wana wat ianier stint 99 Part II. The Law of Reason PAINOtviciias Obligations. rarer Pen a ie 100 Pr OOCIAL CDG AtIONS it's slaaaeitad cele puree te were IOI Part III. Superimposed Moral Law . The Decalogue and Christ’s Summary............ 102 Le First Commandment vii Genie 45 6 beaver eu 105 The: Second Commandment wwii eee oe 106 A neuLnird AcommaAndiment cgay ee Uy 107 ‘he; Fourth Commandment .s 0.) aes cS 109 POG UAC COM MANGMeNG. wi c)hslslee fies ke whe seleib ois i12 Moi a COMMAnOMenL sce A aie eats 117 THeimevench, COmMManCMeNnt ww y juny nual wie II9 Matte signi i Commandmenty sii) signs ca syle do e's 122 Wise MINDEN COMmMMaAnamMent ye Wire cle ok gat male hace 124 PRVOCMLENEN COMMMANGMENL, . galsicy decimate gc uray ie 126 CHAPTER V SACRAMENTAL OBLIGATIONS ne acramien tatty Crenetats suis clas si die eee oars ete 129 BAAN hd LESSER LAT erate eb ehaihl celal) Wid tate drm a Rodd oa ewe 131 PPALONTIETIALION | un mene Rack Ce vrata hte tanita 20 133 POL COMMUNION Vs Sere Ce NS car nas Tas PR EMIALICOW cre ts ons ai ites CUM Ian Eccles stad la. '8 tara otc mane 137 POLO AIT GET SI hoot ae Caters shale WOMAN cy ati’ "ob a a natal 142 METROUY UNI AVITEOTIY © tie hrenate ea iG. se raia rary bie nie vie a areal ats 146 SITET OLFLHE ICR Shite so Gite nyt Waly Sa eee dala ara ea 150 €OR 00? 60200? 60760200? x“ Ari PW DH we CONTENTS CHAPTER VI OTHER OBLIGATIONS Part I. Notable Duties PAGE PLAY ET ain ss aie. oul pinibiace's <3 gmie Wie Strout ite en noes 152 » PASTING 2. so saoo esd lala oe ale SP MG ene Ren Tet err eae 154 Almsgiving< 3.055.452 spine ees ova emer n cena 155 Part IT. Civil Obligations SOUECO) Se he ee a en ae 157 LUTE ele nb getaue ce ep wala teehee ole tie ean ein ee 158 Part III. Soctological Obligations ; in General, Socialism.3 7c) nen ss eee eee ee 160 . Industrialism .):* : (awit os sceieick sc eieee ieee en en eee 163 Contracts 3555.5) ) ctoleale ica i aieleeti eerie da cae ee cae nn a at 164 Economic Laws, 0.0 ie vin cuivanty ee aaienias kee ee 165 Incidental Questions, (2 Wiese) esesee oie abe ween 168 Part IV. Obligations Voluntarily Incurred OP VOWS ee ae a tie fear oy Aner ehee eae mae 172 Of vocation Orilife workie i. ia veo ea ae Les CHAPTER VII EXPEDIENCY AND EXAMPLE . Non-legalistic Obligations: The Call to Perfection.. 175 ») Virtues and @iaracter [ao Ge ain ub ey gine mete hares 176 »/ Christian i Manneras iy ven eiius, E ican As ce Gaon tenet a 178 , Expediency: Permissions sc uxeiis. cts) eel sia eine es 179 COunsels oe ee i aaah igi tee Statens 181 Example 27 Or c's eile Guk CWI tseN a went Ger ee aaa 185 6096006072 00? 002402 C02 COW CO? 09002609 002 COP OO2COR Ont anAnRWD H oo“? Dur & w ia e CONTENTS CHAPTER VIII THE SACRAMENT OF PENANCE PE ACASUIGEDY for, eel ici eieise so hae are ate hen gh Ras ue 4 The Requirements of this Sacrament............. The Duty and Profit of Confession............... eualincations of the Priest so. ywieg sacle domes ole . The Mode of Hearing Confessions...............- PEIPTCELORAtIONS Atte huis a uiee hamiG male mene dee ek Mr ypestOlye CMIteNtS es sche visi roe ae sieime aera bee Sirk Confessions of the Sick and Dying... ..seeesreeee CHAPTER IX SIN PPL IOUIM ONG Cs ce See ee res Pe Poptare dtd iomrey Weatnnai PEC ATACLErIstics: ANGOTIFIN . Se ass see ace als Were PEINLOTERT AOC) VEDIAL ITE ae ou lari erec nme tial ate Temptations and Occasions of Sin...........0.02- PIS ITIS OE INL triatey ite yet tee ae ane ete Late aN Tyee mele seven Capltalisingayy cue eee ke sy . Sins that Cry to Heaven for Vengeance........... Lhe.Sin against.the Holy Ghost... yoko Bibtiograpiical, INGeK aw. vases asic eee He sas DUOC INUCK si ils tor sia anny F te wine Gilato teed PAGE 189 IQ 200 203 209 210 214 220 a ee a ‘ig Sy ANS RR oO gana Rican a LTV OARH UR A REM Rene CANTER US Wh) + ee Neos ah \ ey Wert uoy a, wat es hi ui Past VN Tah TE a AME CEA HH eh hye aie Al aay ml om Hise At p ' Hi My FO a ON ee ae Ve ; ah team bik aly a0 H Ve RON NAL iy ih, EM UNA a Kee Ohta ¢ 4 wt La vw RURAL ae it ” ‘ F 1 \ an) y# yy Sa aS abe oa) LAM patty eh yeah Oe NA TY We hae Witiie BURA uD) Hs SE RY Ra ‘ MORAL THEOLOGY CHAPTER I THE STUDY OF MORAL THEOLOGY I. Introductory § 1. One of the most encouraging incidents of the catholic revival in the Anglican communion is the renewal of interest in Moral Theology which is grad- ually extending among the Anglican clergy. This interest, however, is far from being as yet what it should be, and its development is retarded by a very serious lack of literature in the subject adapted to Anglican conditions and needs. Quite a few con- tributory productions of value have appeared in recent years; but constructive manuals of systematic and comprehensive nature, suitable for the general guidance of priests in dealing with souls, are not in evidence. They are greatly needed; and the imme- diate urgency of this need explains our publication of this comparatively brief handbook, without the long delay that would be required for its full elab- oration. 2 THE STUDY OF MORAL THEOLOGY § 2. The general tendency of moral writers outside the Roman Communion has been to deal almost exclusively with the more pressing problems of indus- trial and social life, and beyond that field to confine their attention to ethical theory. Moreover, in ethical manuals of to-day the claim of supernatural religion to be the true organizing principle of life and character in this world is very generally ignored. This is a very serious omission. Its natural result is that current practical ideals are largely of exclu- sively humanitarian and utilitarian types—as if man were his own end, and general human welfare in this world the organizing aim of all human duty. The larger Christian meaning and purpose of human effort, whenever it is sought to be reénforced, is stig- matized as an interimsethic, or as “‘other-worldiness”’; and is lightly put aside as antiquated and unhelpful to those who would face the problem of this twen- tieth century—the problem, that is, of making this a better world to live in, here and now. The supreme duty towards God, if discussed at all, is re-defined as consisting in helping our neighbours, in promoting their earthly well-being. That to do earthly good to our neighbours, or to serve them as opportunities occur in matters of tem- poral welfare, is an integral and vital part of Christian duty cannot rightly be denied, of course. Christ Himself has set us an example in going about doing good, and so far as modern practical idealism repre- sents in this direction a recovery of Christian sense INTRODUCTORY 3 of responsibility to do physical works of mercy, and a call to promote the present welfare of all classes of society with the aid of improved social science, it ought to obtain our entire approval and enlist our earnest practice. § 3. None the less, the swing of the pendulum has been excessive, and the central and organizing principle of Christian ethic has been driven out of sight in the utilitarian idealism referred to. Doing present good, healing the sick and so forth, was cer- tainly an inevitable adjunct and promotive factor in what Christ came to do. But the purpose which brought Him into the world was to bring men to eternal life—into living touch with God forever. His immediate good works were undertaken as revela- tions of His love and as adjuncts of His main design— to facilitate the turning of men to God. The Gospel evidence of this is abundant, and while the Catholic Church has never ceased to include temporal benefi- cence among Christian duties, it has consistently retained Christ’s standpoint and aim as the organizing principle of its ethical teaching. This world is our school for the life which is to be enjoyed hereafter. It is the sphere of probation and discipline; and present happiness, even of the great- est number, cannot be made the controlling aim of all earthly endeavour, the supreme standard of refer- ence in determining duty, without shifting the moral centre from where God has placed it, and conse- quently altering in fatal ways the righteousness 4 THE STUDY OF MORAL THEOLOGY which we are set to cultivate. It dethrones God and reduces Him to a mere agent for human purposes and human comfort. A true moral science places God at the centre, as our chief end. Whatever we are and for whatever end we came to be are determined wholly by God’s will and purpose in making us; and He made us for Himself, to be His friends forever. Accordingly, He has so made us that no temporal good, no purely human fellowship, can satisfy us in the long run. God does indeed will that we should attain to hap- piness; but He has so determined our nature that no abiding happiness is possible if we seek it otherwise than through life with Him. This means that our chief end does not lie unqualifiedly in seeking and promoting happiness, but in making the happiness which we seek and promote to consist in the life with God and His saints for which we are made. So it is that religion, or the cultivation of true relations with God, is no mere aid to natural goodness, but is the central element of righteousness, the ele- ment that organizes all obligations and ideals what- soever around our chief end. Apart from its prac- tice the natural virtues—virtues though they truly are—fail to be linked up with their higher and heavenly complements, with the way to life and the light that reveals that way. Problems of present distress are treated as if they were the ultimate ones; and the remedies sought to be applied serve as con- cealments of the real situation instead of means of INTRODUCTORY 5 recovery for the journey to God. It is idle to set over against this the widespread neglect by catholic Christians of the utilitarian branch of their duties, as if this justified giving such duties the paramount place. A reformation of this neglect is rightly demanded, but to make this world’s social welfare the controlling standard of moral obligation is to subvert the teaching of Christ and to revert to paganism. Moral Theology should measure all obligations in the light of their bearing on eternal life; and when this is done practically the true and abiding welfare of mankind will be promoted effect- ively and in the manner that God wills. §4. An adequate and justly proportioned moral science, suitable for the conditions under which Angli- can priests have to labour, has yet to be developed— a development that will make no important headway so long as our moral writers postpone experimental effort in producing really constructive treatises. The ideal treatise of which we dream cannot come except as the sequel of pioneer efforts and numerous imper- fect manuals. In the meantime, our clergy are under obligation to study Moral Theology, if they are to serve as intelligent pastors and guides in and out of the confessional, and not to be reckless exploiters of indi- vidualistic judgments, judgments unrelated to the cumulative experience and consentient opinions of their predecessors from the beginning. Where shall they turn? 6 THE STUDY OF MORAL THEOLOGY First of all they need to study Holy Scripture, espe- cially the New Testament, as a storehouse of deter- minative data—the moral teaching of Christ and His Apostles, the cases in which their teaching received significant application, and the ideal of Christian conduct and character there exhibited. Then they need to study the post-apostolic moral teaching, precepts and discipline of the Catholic Church, tracing it carefully through the ages to the present day. This study, along with the biblical, will provide the materials of Moral Theology and afford many determinative hints both for constructive ordering of moral science and for pastoral judgment. Above all it will go far to save the student from one- sidedness, whether of ecclesiastical provincialism or of modern utilitarianism. The great ethical classics should receive attention, especially Aristotle’s Nichomachean Ethics and St. Thomas’ Summa Theologica, Part II, which more than any other ethical treatises have created the terminology of moral science. To St. Thomas we owe the accepted definition of many moral concepts, and to leave him out is like leaving Hamlet out of Shakespeare’s drama of that title. Again, we cannot pass over the study of Roman Catholic treatises. In them alone do we find large and constructive treatments of the whole subject. These treatises have defects, and are adjusted to ecclesiastical conditions other than ours; and some of their defects will be indicated in these pages. But SURVEY OF MORAL SCIENCE 7 nowhere else can we find complete handling of many questions which we have to face somehow in dealing with souls. Finally, an adequate study of moral science must include a reckoning with modern ethical literature of the contributory type, both Anglican and other— the modern manuals of Ethics (mostly theoretical) and Anglican contributions from such writers as Bishop Gore, T. B. Strong, K. E. Kirk, F. G. Belton and others mentioned in our footnotes. In particu- lar, the modern industrial situation has to be faced, and some knowledge needs to be gained of law, eco- nomics, sociology and psychology. Surely the sub- ject of moral science is large; but its largeness ought not: to conceal the imperative need of mastering it as well as we can. IT. Survey of Moral Science § 5. The several branches of Moral Theology in general are as follows: (a) Moral Philosophy, the principal content of modern ethical manuals, con- cerned with ethical theory and the definition of the fundamental ethical concepts; (b) Moral Theology Proper, giving a logically connected account of all Christian obligations, in the light of the law of both God and man and of the terms of the Christian cove- nant; (c) Casuistry, concerned with problematical cases of conduct, and with the principles which should guide a priest in dealing with individual souls; (4) 8 THE STUDY OF MORAL THEOLOGY Ascetic Theology, or the science of Christian progress towards perfection; (e) Mystical Theology, con- cerned with the supernatural experiences of those who in this life attain to occasional enjoyments of union with God approximating that which is pledged to the faithful in Heaven. It is to be noticed that the study of moral science has a practical aim, an aim which cannot be fulfilled by concerning ourselves exclusively or chiefly with ethical theory. Sound ethical theory, which means theory that reckons seriously with the supernaturally revealed Christian faith and covenant, is indeed indispensable; but it should be regarded as intro- ductory only, and should be applied in a coherent treatment of the whole range of Christian obligations, Godward and manward, of supernatural religion and of good morals in the usual sense of that phrase. The widespread assumption that no such science is needed, even for Christian pastors, is hopelessly mis- taken. Without it the range of duty is inadequately understood by the clergy; and the problems that con- tinually arise in the guidance of souls are apt to be handled crudely and determined badly, with oblivi- ousness of established principles and precedents in the Church of God. Moral Theology Proper, its supple- ment of Casuistry, and its complement of Ascetic Theology are plainly necessary, therefore, for the equipment of priests. § 6. I have called Ascetic Theology the ‘‘comple- ment’ of Moral Theology Proper. The realization SURVEY OF MORAL SCIENCE 9 of this is needed if we are to avoid a serious danger, one not wholly escaped in Roman moral treatises. I mean the danger of setting up two standards of Christian vocation and duty, the legalistic and the ascetic. The distinction between sinlessness and positive perfection is indeed real and important; and therefore the separate treatment of Moral The- ology Proper, concerned mainly with distinguishing between the sinful and the non-sinful, and of Ascetic Theology, concerned with growth in heavenly virtue, is justifiable and convenient. The former science, coupled with Casuistry, is for the judicial equipment of priests in the tribunal of Penance; while the latter is for their equipment in guiding souls in the way to God that has still to be travelled by those whose sins are being forgiven and forsaken. But no penitents, however backward in spiritual culture, should be allowed without corrective enlight- enment to acquiesce finally in the notion that the avoidance of sin is the only obligation imposed upon them by their Christian vocation. All Christians are called of God to positive perfection—not indeed as immediately attainable, but as the appointed goal towards which they are under obligation by God’s grace to direct their efforts. In saying this I do not forget that backward souls have to be dealt with very patiently, and that in a vast number of cases they cannot be expected in this worldly stage of progress wholly to escape from the legalistic concep- tion of Christian duty. My point is that their ulti- 10 THE STUDY OF MORAL THEOLOGY mate escape from it is a sine qua non of their entrance into the joy of God. A merely sinless creature is not fit for full divine communion and fellowship until perfected in the positive graces of character which Christ has exhibited for our attainment. So it is that, limited in scope though it be, no Moral Theology Proper is rightly studied and applied except from the background of the fuller conception of Christian obligation which is unfolded in Ascetic Theology. For this reason, brief as this manual is, we have given our seventh chapter to a short summary of the higher side of Christian responsibility. § 7. The work of the Holy Spirit and His opera- tions of supernatural grace in the hearts of Christians are necessarily presupposed and allowed for in Moral Theology. But the work of grace is not subversive of human nature and freedom and of the natural laws of human conduct. The purpose of grace is to assist and uplift human nature on its own lines and to sanctify it. But in those aspects of conduct and development of character which are susceptible of observation the laws of human nature hold their own, and their investigation is a useful adjunct of Moral and Ascetic Theology. This means that the Psychology of behaviour and of sainthood is a legitimate and fruitful line of study; and works like those of Joly, on the one hand, and James, on the other, furnish important contributions to our science. But in admitting this we ought not to forget an important limitation of psychological SOME SNARES I science. Like other natural sciences it is concerned exclusively with natural factors; and the self- coherence and apparent self-sufficiency of its descrip- tion of the laws that control the natural functioning of our spirits should not blind us to the evidences that the higher level of sanctity in which such functioning occasionally results is not explained by natural factors alone. Psychology describes the course of nature that is involved in saintly development; but that it should pursue such a course, and with such a result, is due to supernatural grace and to lines of self-dis- cipline which such grace alone makes possible and successful. Valuable as knowledge of the natural or psychological factors of moral behaviour is to a priest, Psychology for his purpose is a handmaid rather than the mistress of his moral science. III Some Snares § 8. The danger of acquiescing in a double standard of Christian obligation, above referred to, is not the only one that attends the study and application of moral science. The distinction between venial and mortal sin is plainly made in Scripture, and is very necessary for practically judging the gravity of sins both in the tribunal of Penance and in self-examina- tion. A momentary loss of temper is not to be treated as having the degree of guilt which is to be ascribed to deliberate and wilful murder; and if we would not drive men to despair, we ought not to deal 12 THE STUDY OF MORAL THEOLOGY with their lighter sins as if immediately fatal to the spiritual life. ) But serious danger, none the less, attends the rather common habit of making the technicalities of venial and mortal sin take the place of careful and discriminating judgment. ‘The distinction referred to is qualitative, and in its application requires consider- ation not only of the gravity of matter or the act as such, but also the degree of knowledge, deliberation and wilfulness of the sinner. Sins of invincible ignorance, of sudden impulse, and of weakness in unusually severe temptation, are not invariably to be reckoned as mortal because of the gravity of their matter; nor are the small sins, materially considered, to be treated as venial when they are committed and clung to with deliberate, malicious and obstinately impenitent wilfulness. To forget this, and to neglect careful consideration of the subjective as well as the objective elements of sins, invites one or other of two serious consequences: (a) of driving struggling souls to despair by undue severity of judgment, treating sins as mortal when they are really venial; and (0) of lightly estimating sins of relatively light matter, as if necessarily and invariably venial, when perhaps they are forms of deadly malice and guilt. The distinction between venial and mortal sin is often set forth before simple folk in a way that encour- ages the notion that one need not worry at all about venial sins—a very dangerous notion indeed, and one very apt to be encouraged by unqualified assurances SOME SNARES 13 that venial sins need not be recalled and mentioned in the confessional. It is of course true that an exact enumeration of all one’s sins, however minute, is neither possible nor necessary. But the inference frequently made by simple minds that venial sins need not be repented of, and therefore are not neces- sary matters of contrite self-examination and con- fession im genere, is hopelessly false and apt to be fatal in its consequences. All sins of every degree need to be repented of by implication at least, and to suppose that besetting sins, even though venial, can safely be forgotten in confession is a very precarious opinion. § 9. Another snare that needs careful avoidance is that of an undiscriminating judgment as to the state of those who fail wholly to abandon, or even visibly to reduce the frequency of, sins that have been ostensibly repented of. Besetting sins by long con- tinuance modify the subjective aptitudes of the mind and will, and seriously reduce the power of avoiding their repetition; and this is as true of the graver forms of sin as of lighter ones. The power of grace is lim- ited after all, and the entire removal of the danger of relapse into previously well-established habits of sin is not to be looked for in this world. Such relapses may indeed reveal the insincerity of repentance, or a malignant carelessness that is very serious indeed. But they may be due entirely to weakness, and may leave unaltered a growing dissociation of the peni- tent’s fundamental aim and attitude from the 14 THE STUDY OF MORAL THEOLOGY habits not yet overcome. The genuineness of repentance may indeed be brought under just suspicion by the lack of visible amendment of sinful habits, but the suspicion should be aban- doned if there is*evidence of the sinner’s growing detestation of his sinful habit, grounded in increasing love of God. Of course, relapses have to be attended to with great care; and the penitent should be urged to avoid the occasions which his previous habits make dangerous, and to cultivate by every means in his power the growth of his love of God and of his hatred of his sin. Never should a case be abandoned as hopeless, so long as opportunities of spiritual care remain. § ro. A further snare is encountered in hasty con- clusions as to the necessity and obligation of resorting to the sacrament of Penance. The conventional teaching that this sacrament is necessary for salvation in case of mortal sin is too precise and sweeping to be accepted without qualifications, and is not prim- itive. Obviously the necessary conditions of salva- tion are not more numerous to-day than in the apos- tolic age. The most that can be said unqualifiedly is that, when adequate contrition and repentance are | practically impossible without resort to Penance, that sacrament is necessary; and the Church’s experi- ence justifies the further teaching that this impossi- bility is apt to exist when the soul has been hardened by the graver degrees of deliberate and wilful sin. SOME SNARES 22 Furthermore, the Church has authority to impose such disciplinary rules in this direction as its experi- ence dictates. But the doctrine that adequate contrition secures divine forgiveness in any case is undoubtedly biblical and ecumenical, and the disciplinary requirements referred to have not been precisely set forth except provincially and variously. Anglicans are bound only by the requirements of Anglican discipline, which leave the determination of personal need and obligation in this matter to individual judgment. Whatever may be our opinions as to the merits of this peculiarity of Anglican discipline, it should be clear that Anglican priests may not impose disciplinary requirements upon their people which the Anglican province does not impose. What they both may and ought to do is to make clear to those under their spiritual care the great value of sacramental confes- sion, and the grave danger that failure to make use of it may in many instances mean failure truly to repent. Summing up what has here been said on the snares that beset the study and application of moral science, these snares arise mainly from the careless use of the technicalities of Moral Theology. ‘These are neces- sary for scientific purposes, and are true when taken with the important proviso that moral principles are larger than the rules which are deduced from them, and are insusceptible of exclusively technical consid- eration. Similarly, moral states of the soul are not 16 THE STUDY OF MORAL THEOLOGY rightly estimated and judged unless their qualitative nature is carefully borne in mind. Rules are helpful, but they do not obviate the need of exercising a dis- criminating judgment in each case. CHAPTER II INTRODUCTION AND HISTORY § x. “Ethics is the science of Conduct. It con- siders the actions of human beings with reference to their rightness or wrongness, their tendency to good or to evil.” 1 It concerns itself largely with the attempt to define the meaning and content of such terms as “‘good,” “‘right and wrong,”’ “obligation,” “duty,” ‘‘conscience.”’ While Ethics, or Moral Philosophy,” is often confused with Moral Theology, there is a distinction between them. The latter is the science of the Will of God with relation to the conduct of men; and is distinguished from Moral Philosophy in that one rests upon divine revelation, the other upon the processes of human reason. Ina wide sense Moral Theology is the science of human duty and conduct considered in the light both of nature and of supernatural revelation. As Ethics usually deals only with the former of these factors, it is comparable to Natural Theology; while Moral 1J.S. Mackenzie, Manual of Ethics, p.1. But it is often treated philosophically, and is then the philosophy of conduct and of duty, rather than the science of them. 2F. J. Hall, Creation and Man, pp. 237-248. 17 18 INTRODUCTION AND HISTORY Theology, including both, may be compared to Dogmatic Theology. Moreover, as usually handled, Ethics is theoretical, philosophical rather than sci- entific, so as to be distinguished from Moral Theology proper as the philosophy of a thing is from its science, and is, therefore, properly called Moral Philosophy.! A science is described as theological in so far as it treats of its subject-matter in relation to God, and moral science is called Moral Theology because it treats of conduct and character in relation to divine purpose and government. No moral science can be adequate, or even sound, which fails to reckon with the revealed will of God and with true religion. This will appear in the historical sketch of ethical systems which will occupy the greater part of the present chapter. The term “‘moral’? comes from the Latin mos, moris, which means custom, or practice. The cor- 1 They are thus distinguished in this treatise. See ch. ili, init. 2Cf. the German term Sittenlehre. ‘‘Customs were not merely habitual ways of acting; they were ways approved by the group or society.” Dewey and Tufts, Ethics, p. 1. Their origins appear when men first begin to live in groups, the earliest being the family. Cf. Dewey and Tufts, op. cit., ch. ii; F. H. Giddings, The Principles of Sociology. Sometimes the clan takes the place of the family, as when husband and wife are of different clans and the wife and children remain with the wife’s clan, to which the husband is only a visitor. Custom, taboo (the thing to be avoided) or ritual (the way the thing prescribed is to be done) gradually, but slowly, emerge to the point where conscience becomes a deciding factor. Dewey and Tufts, op. cit., chh. iv-v. The earlier state is that of customary morality, when dress and the manner of wearing the hair are on a par with marriage regulations and laws regarding murder. This customary INTRODUCTION 19 responding term ‘‘ethics” comes from the Greek 700s, which means custom, or character, and #6:xés, which means that which pertains to conduct or char- acter, and is closely related to 0s, signifying custom. As has been said, the data of Moral Theology are taken from both natural and revealed sources—in particular from our general experience of human nature and conduct, and from that which is made known to us of the character, operations, will, and purpose of God. A sound and adequate moral science assumes that the catholic faith and religion are true, and that it is man’s duty to be guided by the light which that religion affords.! stage gradually passes over to the reflective, but a great mass of custom always remains. See H. Rashdall, Is Conscience an Emotion?, Lec. ii, on the transi- tion from emotional to rational ethical judgments. While allowing for the predominance of the emotional, which E. Westermarck, Origin and Development of the Moral Ideas, thinks wholly explanatory, Rashdall holds that far down in the social life we may find glimmerings of the rational. But conduct never advances to the state where it is based upon rational motives alone, where there is no impelling desire to be reckoned with, nor is it desirable that it should. There is room for both. Rashdall, op. cit., pp. 118-119, “‘The practical morality of a man like Kant was as defective on one side as that of St. Francis was on another. A more rational morality would per- haps have induced St. Francis to recognize that he had no right to give away his father’s property to the poor, that cleanliness is not necessarily inconsistent with godliness, and that it is better to take care of one’s health and live to the age of seventy than to neglect it and die at forty-five. A more emotional morality might have led Kant to visit his crazy sister as well as to support her pecuniarily out of respect for the Categorical Imperative.” 1Qn Ethics as related to other branches of philosophy, see J. S. Mackenzie, of. cii., pp. 23-24; A. Alexander, Christianity and Ethics, 20 INTRODUCTION AND HISTORY I. Ancient Pagan Ethics § 2. An historical survey of the more important types of ethical theories is desirable before under- taking a more systematic treatment of our subject.! The most significant of the ancient gentilic systems are Buddhism, Confucianism, and the Greco-Roman.? Buddhism was taught by Gautama, born in India about 560 B.c. Impelled by pity for human sorrows he sought to show a way of escape from them. This way consists of knowledge of the cause and of the remedy. Ignorance brings desire, which induces clinging to existence and involves pain. Suffering pp. 14-21; Geo. H. Palmer, The Field of Ethics, passim. Pro- found metaphysical problems lie back of the study of Ethics and appear from time to time in its course. Limitations of space, and of the purpose of this work, have obliged us almost entirely to neglect them. J. G. Hibben, The Problems of Philosophy, ad rem, may be read with profit. 1 On the hist. of Ethics, see H. Sidgwick, Hist. of Ethics; Hastings, E.R.E., s.vv. ‘Ethics,’ “Ethics, Rudimentary,” “Ethics and Morality” (series), and for the various systems; A. B. Bruce, The Moral Order in Anc. and Modern Thought; J. Martineau, Types of Ethical Theory; W. E. H. Lecky, Hist. of European Morals; W. Wundt, Ethical Systems; H. H. Scullard, Early Christian Ethics in the West; Schaff-Herzog Encyc., s. v. “Ethics,” IL (with fuller bibliog.); and the Histories of Philosophy, esp. F. Ueberweg. 2¥For still earlier beliefs and practices, see S. A. B. Mercer, Relig- tous and Moral Ideas in Babylonia and Assyria; Growth of Religious and Moral Ideas in Egypt; also a series of articles by the same author in the Journal of the Society of Oriental Research, vols. 1-V. These articles contain matter dating from as early as 3850 B.c., and show much more advanced standards than would generally be expected. ANCIENT PAGAN ETHICS 21 is remedied by the final destruction of desire, and, in the meantime, by the acceptance of the eight-fold way of right as a guide for life: (a) insight; (0) thoughts; (c) words; (d) deeds; (e) behaviour; (f) striving; (g) remembering; () self-suppression.! Five prohibitions are given: (qa) not to kill any living thing; (6) not to seize the property of another; (c) not to touch another man’s wife (monks not to touch any woman); (d) not to speak untruth; (e) not to drink anything intoxicating. The ideal man is the wise man who practices apathy. These ways and prohibitions are for those who have not entered the higher way of abandonment of home and of all desire. The goal is Nirvana—the state of salvation, in which no re-births occur, and which merges in an impersonal blessedness. Buddhism has no god, no sacrifice, and no sense of sin or need of salvation therefrom; but in popular practice Buddhists are polytheists. The defects are: (a) an erroneous account of pain, which, in fact, does not come from desire but from natural causes and from perverted desire; (6) lack of sense of sin; (c) absence of a genuine religion and of dependence upon God; (d) denial of personal im- mortality, and consequent lack of a goal of develop- ment; (e) pessimistic inertia, nullifying progress; (f) an aristocratic confinement of its higher blessings to the few; (g) intellectual pride. In practice Bud- 1 These are interpreted by Prof. Rhys Davids, Sacred Books of the East, vol. II, p. 144 (abridgement in J. H. Leuba, A Psychological Study of Religion, p. 286). 22 INTRODUCTION AND HISTORY dhism has gendered immorality. Even its boasted altruism has reference to humanity at large con- sidered in the abstract. The Western systems of Theosophy and Christian Science contain Buddhistic elements with Christian additions; they are hybrid systems, vitiated by the Pantheism which underlies Indian thought, and are really non-moral; they foster a pseudo-spirituality and a blinding self- satisfaction.? § 3. Confucianism? was founded by Confucius (551-478 B.c.). It presupposes a state religion and one which has no determinative creed. Propriety, convention, and precedent rule. Virtue is described as consisting of knowledge, magnanimity, and valour. Worship is directed towards (a) heaven; (0) non- human spirits; (c) dead ancestors; especially the last. Confucius eschewed dogmatism about the super- human, tolerating and ignoring popular superstitions. He based all upon the law of human nature and upon duties to men. ‘The worship of heaven was reserved for the emperor, as representing the people, who are to worship their ancestors. The family is the centre of his religion, and filial piety is the essence of virtue. 1H. Rashdall, Conscience and Christ, pp. 264-271, has a good crit- fcism of the attempts sometimes made to equate Buddhistic and Christian theology and ethics, 2See P. V. N. Myers, History as Past Ethics, ch. v; J. Legge, Religions of China. Curious correspondences between early Chinese and Greek thought in ethics and in metaphysics are shown by Aubrey L. Moore, Essays Scientific and Philosophical, ch. ix. ANCIENT PAGAN ETHICS 23 Taoism and Buddhism are tolerated, subject to ancestor worship and filial piety. Human nature is good and, if followed, will lead men aright. This involves social relations and functions between: (a) sovereign and subject; (6) husband and wife; (c) parent and child; (d) elder and younger brother; (e) friend and friend. These are natural relations and involve four rules: (a) serve the sovereign; (6) serve parents; (c) serve elder brothers; (d) set an example to friends. ‘The sum is reciprocity,” but it is shown by observing rules of propriety. ‘These were elab- orated and were fixed by convention and by precedent. The result was a purely legalistic and external system which could not reform mankind. It cultivated con- ceit, a low morality, and stagnation.! The inspiration of Chinese morality comes rather from Buddhism than from Confucianism. Lao-Tse, born about 604 B.c., met Confucius in 517 B.c. He saw the futility of Confucian ethics and sought to remedy it by urging a revolt from civilized conventions in favour of the virtues of primitive sim- plicity and the cultivation of mystical wisdom, but his effort was abortive. 1 Ethics, as everything else in China, has been stationary. P. V.N. Myers, op. cit., p. 7, “It is largely because Europe has been con- stantly getting a new conscience that its history has been so dis- turbed and so progressive, just as it is largely because China has had the same Confucian conscience for two thousand years and more, that her history has been so uneventful and unchanging.” ‘Taoism is pantheistic and may be compared to Nietzscheism, see P. V. N. Myers, op. cit., p. 57, note 3. 24 INTRODUCTION AND HISTORY § 4. Greek ethical developments! properly began with Socrates, who may be called the “father of moral philosophy.” Previous to his career we have only the fragmentary sayings of the so-called “wise men of Greece.’ Physical and metaphysical ideas had predominated. The Sophists had thrown all funda- mental principles into confusion and, in fact, made virtue the same as self-interest.” Socrates, 470-399 B.C., was the noblest of pagan prophets, and rose to as high a level as was possible apart from revelation.2? It is noteworthy that he 1A, Alexander, op. cit., pp. 35-44; Dewey and Tufts, of, cit., ch. vii; T. B. Strong, Christ. Ethics, pp. 26-34. 2H. Sidgwick, Hist. of Ethics, pp. 13-22; R. A. P. Rogers, A Short Hist. of Ethics, Greek and Modern, pp. 31-34. The leaders of the Sophists were Protagoras of Abdera (nat. c. 480 B.c.) and Gorgias of Leontini (mat. c. 483 B.c). The first of these made ethics sub- jective. Carried to its conclusion his system was anarchical, imply- ing that each may do what he likes without reference to the good of others. The teaching of the second leads to skepticism, as there is no objective standard of truth and goodness. 3H. Sidgwick, op. cit., pp. 22-34; R. A. P. Rogers, op. cit., pp. 34-36; B. Rand, The Classical Moralists, ch. i. He ignored meta- physics, natural science and mathematics, and made the study of moral man and his duties as a citizen central in education. He was skeptical as to the possibilities of knowledge in other fields. He is certain that the one thing that man can know is himself. Hence his motto ‘Know thyself,’ which does not refer to physiological or psychological knowledge but to ethical. His chief claim to fame lies in the emphasis he puts upon the authority of conscience; but his teaching must be carefully distinguished from that of Kant on the categorical imperative. The latter leads one to do his duty without inclination for it; whereas according to Socrates the desire for hap- piness is fundamental, and coincides with duty; for only the ful- filment of duty brings happiness and is worth striving for. His end ANCIENT PAGAN ETHICS a thought himself to be inspired by a good demon. He undertook the mission: (a) of establishing the objective value of truth, goodness, and beauty; (0) of making men see their ignorance; (c) of turning them to self-knowledge. His method was a critical definition of accepted ideas and their amendment by induction. His chief principles are: (a) there is a God, a future life of the soul, future responsibility, and absolute good; (b) virtue and happiness coincide and are based upon wisdom and knowledge, especially self-knowl- edge.| These emancipate the will by turning it towards the good.” Plato, 427-347 B.c., introduced metaphysical and psychological additions to the thought of Socrates and may be described as the flower of his teaching, while Aristotle was its fruit.2 As with Socrates, knowl- was practical. ‘‘The quest of Socrates was for the true art of con- duct for an ordinary member of the human society, a man living a practical life among his fellows.” Sidgwick, op. ci#., p. 39. His system contains the germ of all the chief Greek ethical systems. The difficulty of interpreting him fully is shown by the variety of schools that profess to follow him, the most important of these ethically being the Cynics, founded by Antithenes, and the Cyrenaics, founded by Aristippus. He wrote no books on ethics. The outcome of his speculations was the stimulation of thought, and the attempt to give exact expression to this thought begat the several schools from which, broadly speaking, the Stoics and Epicureans later on developed. 1“ Knowledge is virtue,” cf. Plato’s Protagoras. This involves practice rather than mere intellectual knowledge, and rests upon the hypothesis that ‘‘no man is knowingly vicious.” 2-H. Sidgwick, of. cit., pp. 21-32. 3H. Sidgwick, op. cii., pp. 34-50; R. A. P. Rogers, of. cit., Pt. I, 26 INTRODUCTION AND HISTORY edge is the essence of virtue, especially knowledge of pure reason, of ideas, of principles intuitively seen in their internal sense. Ideas are the true realities, and are the eternal types of which mundane things are passing impressions.! Pleasures are to be distinguished because they are often contrary. ‘The true ideal is to know and attain to the summum bonum, which is likeness to God who is the absolute good. As this cannot be embraced in its unity, it is to be sought in the manifold by rational understanding of truth, beauty, and virtue. Man’s perfection lies in resemblance to God. Virtue is the harmony of the soul, vice its deformity. Virtue is essentially one, but may be distinguished under ch. ii; Wm. De W. Hyde, Five Great Philosophies of Life, ch. iii; B. Rand, of. cit., ch. ii (a very useful source book). Among modern writers who have felt in an especial degree the influence of Plato, Carlyle represents the stronger side, Emerson (in whom the Neo- Platonic predominates) the weaker. Plato’s chief ethical work is the Republic. It seeks to determine the nature and worth of justice and the means whereby it is to be realized in the State. The Philebus should also be read for the sake of its inquiry into the nature of good to the individual. 1W. Wundt, Ethical Systems, vol. II, p. 10, says, “ Plato’s phi- losophy rests wholly and entirely on an ethical basis.” Also p. 11, “When Plato, perhaps influenced more by the Socratic life than by the Socratic doctrine, rises to the principle that it is better to suffer wrong than to do wrong, he can no longer avoid the conviction that the good and the pleasurable do not necessarily coincide. It would, however, be intolerable to suppose a permanent conflict between pleasure and good. There is thus no way out of the difficulty save by the opposition of permanent to transitory pleasure; and, since the former is unattainable in the life of sense, it must be sought in a supersensuous existence.” ANCIENT PAGAN ETHICS 27 four heads in relation to the faculties of the soul: (a) of the reason, prudence or wisdom; (8) of the pas- sions, fortitude or courage; (c) of the appetites, tem- perance; (d) of the harmony of all, justice! These are the so-called Cardinal Virtues? of Christian Ethics, and are found in the later Jewish writers, in the works of St. Ambrose, who first applied the term “Cardinal,” of St. Augustine, and of all moral writers since. He argued at length for the immortality of the soul;3 but the Christian idea of the immortality of the entire man, resurrection from the dead, lay outside of all pagan thought. In common with all Greek writers Plato treated ethics as political, and regarded the individual as subordinate to the state. There are certain defects in his system: (a) knowl- edge and theory is elaborate, but power is wanting; (6) it is an ethic for philosophers, not for men in gen- eral; (c) the problem of evil was not faced, but was 1He attempts a psychological distinction of the faculties of the soul, Adyos, Ouuds, éwiuula, reason, emotion (not an accurate translation as we have no equivalent word), and desire. The proper fulfilment of the function of each leads to virtue. 2Of the Cardinal Virtues Justice is fundamental. “For the intelligence it consists in the correctness of thought (codla, pirocodgla) ; for the will, in courage (dvdpla); for the sensibility, in temperance (swppoctvn). Wisdom is the justice of the mind; courage, the justice of the heart; temperance, the justice of the senses. Piety (6o.6rys), is justice in our relation with the Deity. It is synony- mous with justice in general.” A. Weber, Hist. of Philosophy, p. 99. Cicero terms justice “the mistress and queen of all virtues.” * See especially the Phedo. 28 INTRODUCTION AND HISTORY thought to reside in the corporeal, in that which was becoming, and was thought to be without remedy. Aristotle, 384-322 B.c.,| separated ethics from other sciences and began his work with a discussion of the summum bonum, which he found in man’s welfare, not in God, and regarded as political, this. resting upon his well-known description of man as a political animal. The end of conduct is the welfare of the state, not of the individual. The Greek has no more duties to the barbarian than he has to the wild beast.2, The summum bonum consists in happi- ness, which is defined as a perfect practical activity of soul in a perfect life. Mere pleasure, as such, is neutral, depending for its relation to happiness upon the use made of it. Virtue is founded in natural sentiments and in habits which issue in 700s, a moral character2 These are of two kinds: (a) moral vir- tues, which are developed by acts and the habits caused by them; (6) intellectual virtues, which per- fect the moral. Practically speaking, the essence of virtue is moderation or a mean between two ex- 1H. Sidgwick, op. cit., pp. 50-71; R. A. P. Rogers, op. cit., Pt. I. ch. iti; J. E. C. Welldon, Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle; B. Rand, op. cit., ch. iii. 2P. V. N. Myers, op. cit., p. 169, ‘The relationships and activities of the Greek as a citizen, and not his relationships and activities as a husband or father or business man, determined his chief duties. Conscience was very little involved in that part of his life which lay outside the civic sphere. It was solely as a member of a city com- munity—that he could live the truly moral life and attain the highest virtue.” 3 He was the first to use the term “‘ethics.’’ ANCIENT PAGAN ETHICS 29 tremes, the via media... The importance of the will is emphasized as contrasted with knowledge. The evolutionary view of sin may be traced back to Aristotle, for he regarded sin as a necessary stage on the way to goodness, or as goodness itself in so far as it had not yet proceeded from potency to act. There- fore it was a mere imperfection, or a less good? In general, in Greek ethics human nature was con- ceived as essentially good; and morality was mainly secular as contrasted with that of the Hebrews. Hence it advanced beyond the static religion.4 Greek ethical theories gave form and system to those of the Church, but Christianity itself gave the spirit which 1A, Weber, op. cii., p. 132, ‘‘Courage, for example, is a virtue, and as such the mean between timidity and foolhardiness; liberality is the mean between avarice and prodigality.” R. A. P. Rogers, op. cit., p. 72, has a good illustration of this important point of Aristotle’s teaching: Excess Mean Defect Rashness Courage Cowardice Licentiousness Temperance Apathy Extravagance Generosity Miserliness Bad temper Good temper Servility Flattery Courtesy Rudeness The middle column is printed so as to suggest that the mean is often nearer one extreme than the other. 2W. Wundt, op. cif., vol. II, pp. 19-20, “Aristotle was the first to recognize the will as the specifically ethical function within the general domain of reason; and for him, accordingly, moral virtue consists, not in right knowledge, but in the good will, which is indeed dependent upon reason, but not identical with it.” 3 Metaphysics, XIX, 4, 7d kaxdv adrd 7d Surdwer dryabby, 4Cf. Aubrey Moore, in Lux Mundi, Essay ii. 30 INTRODUCTION AND HISTORY made them living and realizable. This is often over- looked when the debt of Christianity to Greek ethics is magnified, or the statement made that Ambrose is Cicero with a Christian veneer. Christianity brought a new motive power into morality, united the virtues in the spirit of love, and attached a new value to personality. § 5. In Greco-Roman Ethics, Platonic and Aristo- telic efforts brought to birth two opposed systems, the Stoic and the Epicurean, emphasizing respectively virtue and happiness.! The Stoic system? was founded by Zeno, 340-260 B.c. Among his followers, more or less consistent, were Cleanthes, Chrysippus, Panztius, Posidonius, Pompey, Cicero, Seneca? Epictetus, and Marcus Aurelius. From the standpoint of the pious heathen the Stoics were men of lofty virtue. They held that virtue is the only true good, the swummum bonum and the ultimate source of all happiness; but even virtue must be sought in a disinterested manner, for its own sake, not for that of consequent happiness. The rule of virtue is to live according to nature, which means according to enlightened reason. Hence only phil- osophers can follow this way. Indifference is the proper attitude to observe towards the circumstances 1 On the Roman moral systems in general, see P. V. N. Myers, op. cit., ch. xi; H. Sidgwick, op. cit., pp. 70 ff. 2'Wm. De W. Hyde, op. cit., ch. ii; R. A. P. Rogers, op. cit., Pt. I, ch.v; Wm. Wundt, op. cit., vol. II, pp. 25-28. ? On the relation of Seneca to St. Paul, see Bp. Lightfoot, Ep. to the Philippians, App. 2. ANCIENT PAGAN ETHICS 31 of life—health, fortune, honours, pleasures. All these are parts of the system of things, adiaphora, that is, indifferent to the wise man. Fortitude under all cir- cumstances is the sovereign rule; and all human passions are regarded as the sources of evil. They are not merely to be restrained, as Aristotle taught, but to be eradicated entirely. The chief defects of the system are: (a) arrogant self-sufficiency; (0) aristocratic indifference to the common people; (c) apathy, which is fatal to genuine moral progress; (d) immorality, growing out of the principle of adiaphora; (e) inevitable resort to suicide when the evils of this life become unbearable.! On the good side it emphasized the power of the soul to live its own life, rising superior to misfortune and suffering, and the authoritativeness of duty. Epicureanism ” had for its chief promoters Epicurus, 342-271 B.c., and Lucretius, a Roman poet of the second century B.c., and, later on, it was popularized by Horace. The summum bonum was happiness,’ 1Cf. the terse advice of Marcus Aurelius to one who found life hard, “If the house smokes, go out of it.” 2R. A. P. Rogers, op. cit., Pt. I, ch. iv; Wm. De W. Hyde, op. cit., ch. i. It is based upon an atomistic materialism, and has regard to physical and psychical, rather than moral or spiritual, well-being. It is best exemplified in Toto Melema of Geo. Eliot’s Romola. J. 5S. Mill bases his system upon it, but incorporates elements from all other systems, so that his presentation becomes a hodge-podge of contradictory elements. 3W. E. H. Lecky, Hist. of European Morals, vol. I, p. 14, gives the Epicurean canons, “The pleasure which produces no pain is to be embraced. The pain which produces no pleasure is to be avoided. 32 INTRODUCTION AND HISTORY which was interpreted to mean pleasure in action and in repose, the latter being the more complete. The Epicureans found no standard higher or more authoritative than the agreeable; but it is to be noted that pleasure of the soul is placed above that of the body. Virtue means wisdom (¢povyots, or insight) in seeking the forms of happiness which will not end in disappointment. Both systems inculcate the cardinal virtues of Plato, although the Stoics interpreted them ideally and the Epicureans from a purely hedonistic stand- point; but both lack power and adequate motive. The Epicureans inevitably gravitate towards Hedon- ism, or pleasure of the moment, ‘Let us eat and drink, for to-morrow we die.” Il. Christian Ethics § 6. The Holy Spirit alone enables men to arrive at a sound moral philosophy.! He does this through The pleasure is to be avoided which prevents a greater pleasure, or produces a greater pain. The pain is to be endured which averts a greater pain, or secures a greater pleasure.” Wm. Wundt, op. cit., vol. II. p. 29, ‘‘While, like the Stoics, they emphasize repose of mind as an essential condition of happiness, the evil to be avoided is not, as with the Stoics, passion, but pain. Not apathy, but ataraxia, painlessness, is extolled as the blessed state. Thus, while, for the Stoics, virtue, since it consists in control of the passions, is a good to be sought for its own sake, and from whose possession true happiness first arises; for the Epicureans the relation is reversed. The goal of all effort is happiness, and virtue is only a means to this end.” 1 Ethical theories are not evidential as to the moral state cf a CHRISTIAN ETHICS 33 both natural and supernatural means. To Him is due the dispensation of paganism, which represents His work through the natural reason alone, in prep- aration for supernatural revelation. In the earlier dispensations moral truth is developed in fragmentary forms and a definite philosophy cannot be developed without caricature. The Mosaic and Christian dis- pensations represent a gradual development of authen- tic relations with God;! and this development makes possible a true knowledge of righteousness and a dis- pensation of saving grace. The outcome is a moral philosophy which is both sound and capable of appli- cation. Judaism, or the system which resulted from the Mosaic dispensation, supplied what paganism lacked, that is, authentic relations with God; but righteous- ness was conceived externally as the fulfilment of God’s will by God’s people, that is, as obedience to the law, for moral obligations were identified with divine people, for their embodiment in actual practice is very limited. P. V. N. Myers, op. cit., p. 4, “The facts for a history of morals must be sought chiefly outside the literature of ethical theory and specu- lation. They must be looked for in the customs, laws, institutions, mythologies, literatures, maxims, and religions of the different races, peoples, and ages of history.” Cf. H. Rashdall, Conscience and Christ, lec. vi; and, for the moral conditions when these systems were fully developed, Sir S. Dill, Roman Society from Nero to Marcus Aurelius, passim. 1J. R. [llingworth, Christian Character, starts with theses which correctly describe the guiding principle of revealed ethic: that life is the goal of truly guided human effort, and that sin, being destructive of life, is man’s chief enemy. 34 INTRODUCTION AND HISTORY commands. Thus was developed; (a) a sense of sin and of need of salvation from above; (b) the mes- sianic hope, that the law would some day be written on men’s hearts, and become effective among all peoples in a kingdom of righteousness.! In relation to Judaism Chrisitanity? translated divine and moral perfection into human terms in the life and conversation of God-incarnate. Thus was unfolded the deeper implications of the older dispen- sation: (a) the philosophy of love, which at once 1Qn Old Test. ethics, see A. B. Bruce, Ethics of the Old Test.; T. B. Strong, Christ. Ethics, pp. 12-20, 35-46; C. E. Luthardt, Hist. of Christ. Ethics, pp. 33 ff; Dewey and Tufts, op. cit., ch. vi; A. Alex- ander, op. cit., pp. 44-52; P. V. N. Myers, op. cit., ch. ix; Hastings, Dic. of Bible, s. v. “Ethics.” On Jewish ethics in our Lord’s time, C. E. Luthardt, op. cit., pp. 57 ff.; Hastings, Dic. of Bible, as cited; H. Rashdall, Conscience and Christ, pp. 77-94. Special attention is called to S. A. B. Mercer on O. T. Morals, in Angl. Theol. Rev., May and Dec, 1918, Oct., 1919. With refreshing honesty he shows that the Old Test. morals are less elevated than usually represented. 2On Christ’s ethical teaching, and the distinctive elements of Christian ethic, see Chas. Harris, Pro Fide, pp. 335-356; Chas. Gore, The Sermon on the Mount; T. B. Strong, op. cit., Lec. ii; W. L. Davidson, Christ. Ethics, pp. 4-10; Hastings, Dic. of Christ, and Dic. of Ap. Church, s. vv. ‘Ethics.”” The crude interitmsethic theory, set forth by A. Schweitzer, Quest of the Hist’l Jesus, that Christ believed the end of the world to be immediately impending and therefore disregarded men’s responsibilities for this world, is met by E. D. La Touche, Person of Christ, pp. 163-167; C. W. Emmet, in Expositor, Nov. 1912; A. Alexander, op. ctt., ch. vili. The para- doxical commands of Christ are to be taken as heightened illustra- tions of principles; e.g. Have love enough to turn the other cheek also, if that is expedient. And the virtues exemplified by his exam- ple are of abiding value for this world. They have the note of universality. . CHRISTIAN ETHICS 35 explains the law and emancipates from it. Duty is no longer constraint, for its principle is love; (0) the new external rule of the imitation of Christ; (c) the working power which pagan systems lacked; (d) a clear revelation of man’s chief end and destiny, which is to become the friend of God in life eternal. In relation to paganism! Christianity achieved three results: (a) it absorbed whatever was true in pagan systems; (0b) it supplied the principles which enabled men to bring the fragmentary truths of pagan- ism into harmonious relation and to apprehend their ultimate meaning: (z) that we were made for God and for His fellowship; (z) the whole conception of Christian immortality; (cz) the true meaning of sin and evil; (iv) the gospel of redemption and grace; (v) a complete manifestation in human terms of what man is intended to become in the example of Christ; (c) It transformed what it assimilated from paganism, e.g., the pagan cardinal virtues took on a transfigured meaning when brought into relation with the heavenly virtues of faith, hope, and charity. Some of the more obvious innovations? which emerged were: (a) Monotheism and the consequent 1W. Wundt, op. cit., vol. II, p. 33, says the chief points of differ- ence between pagan and Christian ethics are: (a) the latter substi- tutes love for fear; (6) the Fatherhood of God and the brotherhood of man for the limits of nationality and rank; (c) gives an adequate view of the origin and future destiny of man. Christianity also effected certain changes in terminology: “virtue” was replaced by “righteousness,” “‘happiness”’ by “blessedness,”’ ‘‘evil” by “‘sin.” 2,'W. L. Davidson, of. cit., ch. ii. 36 INTRODUCTION AND HISTORY unification of practical ideals by relating them to one God; (b) Catholicity of appeal to all men in behalf of a common brotherhood; (c) Certain new virtues,! such as humility and self-judgment, purity and self- discipline, as distinguished from destructive forms of asceticism; (d) The putting of a new valuation on individual lives. Christ did not teach a moral phil- osophy or science, but: (a) taught and exemplified certain fundamental principles which made the devel- opment of a satisfactory ethical system possible; and (0) established a concrete society or Church wherein the conditions of ethical development are afforded. Considered in its scientific aspects, how- ever, every ethical system is the work of human think- ers, fallible and progressive. The Christian Church was intended by Christ to become a leavening force ina larger world. In it are supplied: (a) what the New Testament calls the “Way” of Life, and that in concrete and social form; (6) effectual relations with God as man’s chief end; (c) means of supernatural grace which are the imme- diate sources of the power that pagan society lacks; (d) an effective propaganda. In this manner was established a twofold process: (a) of applying the principles gained through apostolic experience of Christ to an ever-widening and varying experience of the world; (6) of growth of articulate ethical concep- tions and of a systematic Christian ethic. But this growth was necessarily conditioned and hindered 1'W. L. Davidson, op. cit., ch. x CO tS oOo ese CHRISTIAN ETHICS 37, by certain accidents of the Christian propaganda. In order to leaven the wider world-society, imper- fectly converted men of the world had to be received within the Church, and they brought with them many pagan notions. The progress of moral development which is involved in this may be summarily described as having three stages: (a) the revelation of Christian principles to the Church in terms of apostolic experi- ence of Christ; (6) progressive application of these principles to wider and more varied experience under the handicap of the invasion of pagan ideas; (c) a slow development of ethical definitions and, finally, of a scientific ethic. The definitive stage culminated in the scholastic period, but began in the patristic. Systematic schemes, developed in the scholastic period, have been given a more truly inductive and scientific form in modern days. § 7. The patristic period was one of tentative exposition and definition of particular ethical ideas, called forth, and also hampered, by the Church’s contact with classical paganism! and with the northern barbarism. This contact involved many centuries of struggle with pagan ideas, which entered the Church in two general forms: (a) an exaggerated asceticism, which makes invidious distinctions be- tween religious and secular and between the flesh and the spirit, as if the secular and the flesh were 1See T. R. Glover, The Conflict of Religions in the Early Roman Empire; Chas. Bigg, The Church’s Task under the Roman Empire; T. B. Strong, op. cit., Lec. IV; C. E, Luthardt, of. cit., pp. 77 ff. 38 INTRODUCTION AND HISTORY intrinsically evil; (0) naturalism, or treatment of Christianity as designed simply to improve natural morality. The patristic age under these circum- stances saw the accumulation of material for moral science and the determination of certain preliminary issues with paganism. The battle with false asceti- cism emerged in the rise and condemnation of Monta- nism and Novatianism, which represented recoil from pagan social life, and were coloured by belief in the inherent evil of flesh and its pleasures. This belief was embodied openly in the Gnostic and Manichean systems. Incidental manifestations within the Church were due to the exaggerated emphasis placed upon monastic life and celibacy. The Church came to the position that these are vocational, and that true spir- itual development is possible in the world and in married life. The conflict between Christian ideals and the purely natural conception of morality came to the surface in the Pelagian controversy of the fifth century, which drew pointed attention to the subject of the will’s capacity and responsibility, and to the doctrines of grace and predestination. It was St. Augustine’s task in this connection to vindicate the dependence of human wills upon super- natural grace for power to choose and to follow the 1 This error still explains much indifference to supernatural religion and to its embodiment in the Church. Religion’s claim has reference to the cultivation of those relations with God wherein eternal life consists. Natural morality, indispensable for this Christian purpose though it be, cannot of itself bring men to God and to the enjoyment of their chief end hereafter. Ee CHRISTIAN ETHICS 30 good. Pro forma, he made the will the basis of responsibility, but his definition of divine predestina- tion threatened to overthrow the doctrine of human freedom. However, he was a prolific writer and is not to be regarded as merely the founder of what is called Augustinianism. By his improved classifica- tion of the virtues, as well as by his treatment of free will and grace, he marks a period in the history of Christian ethics. He connected the cardinal virtues with the theological;! and laid the foundation for the Calvinistic view that the virtues of the heathen are “‘splendid vices,’ being apart from the love of God in which all true virtue is grounded. Among his contributions to moral science are the following: (a) The summum bonum is the vision and love of God, and the means of attainment is growth in virtue by which all man’s faculties reach their highest per- fection and the complete satisfaction of all his desires. (b) Love is the sum of virtue and is threefold in its object, namely, of God, of self, of neighbour. Its manward branches are the so-called cardinal virtues. 1C, E. Luthardt, of. cit., p. 225, ‘The four cardinal virtues become virtues in so far as they are manifestations of love to God (de Mor. Eccl. Cath., 1, xxv, 15): temperantia, in opposition to love of the world; fortitudo, as the overcoming of suffering and pain by love; justitia, as service to God; and prudentia, as the right distinction between what is to be avoided and what is to be chosen (de Mor., I, xxxv-xlv).” St. Augustine defines virtue: “Definitio brevis et vera virtutis: ordo est amoris,” de Civ. Det, XV. 22. On his ethical teaching in general, see T. B. Strong, op. cit., pp. 188-199, 245-251, 258-250. 40 INTRODUCTION AND HISTORY (c) The essence of moral evil is the privation of good by choice of inferior good. The patristic age saw the beginning of what is called ‘‘Canon Law,” which is based upon the prin- ciple that Christians owe obedience in practice to the Church because of the charge of Christ, “Make disciples of all nations.’”’ The Canon Law, in its larger sense, includes: (a) divine law, as interpreted by the Church; (0) the Faith, as supplying the light by which we ought to live; (¢) liturgical require- ments, including the so-called jus liturgicum of bishops; (d) canons, strictly so-called, or the laws enacted by councils and the decrees of competent ecclesiastics, especially of the Papal See; (e) ecclesiastical customs and traditions, which are reckoned to outweigh indi- vidualistic private judgment; (f) decisions of com- petent ecclesiastical courts, which constitute much of the so-called common law; (g) Church laws enacted by the state, in so far as they have been accepted by the Church; (hk) digests, collections, penitentiaries, which have gained recognition by ecclesiastical authority. The penitentials ! were originally lists of sins with their appropriate penances, compiled from patristic literature for the guidance of the clergy in dealing with penitents. They began to appear in the sixth century and developed into collections of miscella- neous rules calculated to assist in the administration 1C. E. Luthardt, op. cit., pp. 288-297; Cath. Encyc., s.v. “‘Peni- tential Canons.” CHRISTIAN ETHICS 4r of public penances. With the decline of public penances these manuals dropped out of use, but their materials were incorporated into later moral treatises. § 8. During the middle ages! and subsequently the line of opposition between rival systems of ethics was determined by the emphasis, on the one hand, and rejection on the other, of those elements in Chris- tian ethics which are distinctively Christian and supernatural. Abelard (1079-1142 A.D.) treated Christian ethics as simply a reformation of natural ethics, and made intention, or intellectual motive, the subject matter of moral distinctions, rather than the actions which follow. The mystics of the twelfth century represented a reaction from the ethics of Abelard, and over-empha- sized the supernatural side. The chief original promoters of this development were St. Bernard (r0gI-1153 A.D.), and Hugo of St. Victor (1097- II4I A.D.). They made union with God the proper business of human life, and said that this was to be gained through withdrawal from the sensuous, illu- mination, and ecstatic contemplation, resulting in union with God based upon love. They anticipated the later division of the spiritual life into the purga- tive, illuminative, and unitive ways or stages. Their 1Qn medieval Ethics, see C. E. Luthardt, op. cit., §§ 50 ff.; H. Sidgwick, op. cit., pp. 134-151; Extracts in Benj. Rand, The Class- ical Moralists, ch. xi-xii. 42 INTRODUCTION AND HISTORY one-sidedness appears in their ascetic disparagement of the normal conditions in the world, to which Christians in general are bound to adjust themselves, and of the practical virtues of everyday life. The main lines of ethical development were car- ried on by Peter Lombard and by St. Thomas Aquinas. The former laid the foundation for scholastic devel- opment by collecting in systematic order the opinions of the ancients in four books of Sentences. This work became a universally employed text-book for several centuries, and every scholastic writer of emi- nence wrote commentaries upon it. The scholastics were too profound and too restless to be satisfied with mere reproductions of patristic opinions, and the commentaries on Peter Lombard’s Sentences contained much original thought and prepared the way for the great Summae. The flower and most representative product was the Summa Theologica of St. Thomas Aquinas (1226-1274 A.D.). The second part of this work not only finished the codrdination and systematic presentation of moral science up to his time, but crystallized the science on lines that have been followed ever since in the Roman Church. It also contains many of the elements of modern Protest- ant systems. St. Thomas combined the Christian standpoint with a free use of Aristotelic and Platonic elements and forms of thought. God is the chief end. Good and being are the same in fact or reality, and evil is defect or falling short. Considered in the abstract the good is the desirable, whether morally ————— ae CHRISTIAN ETHICS 43 desirable, useful, or simply pleasurable. The moral good constitutes the determinative end of Christian conduct. It pertains to voluntary actions, and these are formally good according to their end or intention, materially according to their own nature. This dis- tinction appears in speaking of sin. We are formally guilty when we sin knowingly and wilfully, but our guilt is only material when we sin ignorantly or invol- untarily. Every human act has good for its end, positively speaking. The sinfulness of a sinful act lies in the substitution of a lower good for one that is higher and ought to be pursued. ‘The intellect, when acting in the moral sphere, consists of: (a) synderesis, or the theoretical faculty; (0) conscience, which applies moral principles to conduct. All virtues fall under seven heads, the four cardinal virtues and the three theological. The former are natural and lead to natural happiness, while the latter are fruits of supernatural grace and lead to supernatural beati- tude; but the fall makes God’s help necessary for the acquisition even of the natural. So God becomes the source of all virtues. The divine law is grounded in the reason of things as seated in the divine nature, and the divine will is what it is because of the divine nature, not vice versa. After St. Thomas a decay of scholasticism set in and moral ideas degenerated. Two factors hastened this decay; namely, the theory of works of super- erogation, with its mechanical and commercial scheme of merits and indulgences, and, in the seventeenth 44 INTRODUCTION AND HISTORY century, that form of probabilism which is called laxism. §9. Modern Roman Moral Theology is largely based upon St. Thomas, but is influenced negatively by the indulgence system, and is elaborated with reference to the conditions of modern life. In most moral treatises the principal heads adopted are: (a) ‘Virtues; (6) the Decalogue; (c) Precepts of the Church; (d) Sacramental Obligations; (e) Contracts and Civil Obligations of all kinds. Certain special departments of moral science have also been developed: (a) Casuistry, the chief pro- moters of which have been the Jesuits; (0) Ascetic Theology; (c) Mystical Theology. During the reformation period the chief influences at work were a partial reform of the system of indul- gences by the Council of Trent, and the development of Probabilism.! The pioneer in this last-mentioned 1QOn Probabilism, see C. J. Shebbeare, in Ch. Qly. Rev., July, 1912; K. E. Kirk, op. cit., pp. 194-197; Koch-Preuss, Moral Theology, vol. I, pp. 218-235; J. P. Gury, S.J., Compend. Theol. Moralis, §§ 51-80; Cath. Encyc. and Schaff-Herzog Encyc., q.vv. There are six theories: (i) Rigorism, that the safest course should always be followed, even when the less safe is more probable. This would often result in a negation of action, and it was condemned by Alex- ander VIII, Prop. dam. 3, Dec. 7, 1690. (di) Tutiorism, that the safe side must be taken unless the preponderance of probabilities for liberty is very great. (ci7) Probabiliorism, which does not require more than a perceptible preponderance of evidence for liberty. (zz) Equi-probabilism, that we are at liberty when the balance of argu- ments is equal; the view of St. Alphonsus Liguori, whose writings have had great influence. (v) Probabilism, which concedes liberty if there are solid reasons for it, even though the reasons against CHRISTIAN ETHICS AS development was Bartholomew a Medina (d. 1581). Starting with the thought that a doubtful law cannot impose indisputable obligations, the question arises between the safer and the more rigid course and the apparently less safe but probably permissible one. — The various systems of probabilism are distinguished by their attitude towards this issue. The rigorist school makes the safer course obligatory. At the other extreme was laxism, which maintained the per- missibility of any course that had any probability in its favour. The ultimate form which probabilism took in Roman moral science makes a freer or less safe course permissible, if it is based on “‘solid”’ probabil- ities and upon due enquiry. The less safe course may never be resorted to by a conscience which is sub- jectively certain that the safer course ought to be pursued, nor is a doubting conscience free to choose the less safe course until enquiry has been made as to whether “solid” probabilities make it permissible. In this form the system is crystallized in the more mature writings of St. Alphonsus Liguori. Current moral science of the Roman type differs from medizval literature in its adjustment to changed ecclesiastical and civil conditions. The independence which the state has gained in modern days, although not fully recognized by the Roman See, is to some it are stronger. This and the preceding are the theories generally followed. (vz) Laxism, which justifies liberty when any arguments can be advanced for it. It was condemned by Innocent XI, Prop. dam. 3, March 2, 1679. Laxism was ridiculed with terrible power by Pascal, Provincial Letters. 46 INTRODUCTION AND HISTORY extent recognized in moral science. Modern socio- logical questions are also reckoned with, although under the handicap of a terminology which is not wholly intelligible to the modern mind. One rather important illustration of development is the treat- ment of usury, or receiving interest on money loans. Down to quite recent times surplus money was regarded in the light of a means for moral service, and it was considered wrong to charge for such service. The progress of the science of political economy has made it clear that money is also a commodity, and that to charge for its use is in line with rentals of real estate. Therefore usury is now sanctioned, or, rather, the word usury is applied only to excessive interest. Among the standard manuals of Roman moral theology are those by Gury, Lehmkuhl, Liguori, Thomas Slater, and Koch-Preuss, the two latter being written in English. § io. The Protestant movement of the sixteenth century, ethically considered,’ was a revolt against: (a) excessive ecclesiastical control; (6) the whole scheme of wage-merit and works of supererogation; (c) mechanically conceived purgatorial penalties, and indulgences therefrom. ‘The emphasis was laid upon: (a) private judgment; (6) justification by faith independently of good works; (c) human deprav- ity and arbitrary predestination. The consequences 1See P. V. N. Myers, op. cit., ch. xvii; T. C. Hall, op. cit., ch. viii; Thos. B. Strong, Christian Ethics, Lec. vii. MODERN ETHICS 47 of this revolt, or rather of its excessive thoroughness, were: (a) a loss of vital elements of the Christian covenant and a serious reduction of the divinely appointed machinery of grace; (6) ethics was grad- ually divorced from religion and reverted to a natural- istic form, somewhat akin to pagan ethics; and this © paved the way for modern utilitarianism. Among the particular developments should be mentioned: (a) the monastic life was barred out entirely; (6) legalism revived in what was at a later date called Puritanism, with its man-made precepts and repro- duction of Judaic requirements under Christian con- ditions. It represents partly a reaction from six- teenth century antinomianism and partly a protest against wickedness in high Anglican life; (c) Casuistry was at first retained on the basis of Scripture and pri- vate judgment in interpretation; but it soon gave way to the naturalistic point of view, which makes the unaided reason or common sense a sufficient guide in morality. III. Modern Ethics } § x1. From Hobbes dates a revival of interest in ethical studies, stimulated in part by the reaction to his theories, which Deism strongly tended to keep alive. He was the founder of the modern non- 1On modern Ethics, see H. Sidgwick, op. cit., ch. iv; Jas. Mar- tineau, Types of Ethical Theory; Schaff-Herzog Encyc., s.v. “ Ethics,” yan, 48 INTRODUCTION AND HISTORY theological ethics and approximated the position of Epicurus.! Thomas Hobbes,? 1588-1679 A.D., maintained that man is by nature selfish and egoistic. The result is, that, to prevent moral clash, the state must regulate personal life, and the authority of the state must be absolute in the determination of right and wrong? This is a reversion to pagan political ethic. He was assailed on two lines: (a) in behalf of the absolute- ness of the principles of right and wrong, as intui- tively discerned, as against all wills, governments, etc., by the Cambridge Platonists, e.g., Ralph Cudworth # 1Thos. Whittaker, The Theory of Abstract Ethics, pp. 40-54, regards him as the founder of abstract ethics. 2R. A. P. Rogers, op. cit., pp. 126-143; T. C. Hall, of. cit., pp. 445-447. 3R. A. P. Rogers, of. cit., p. 136, ‘Thus the primitive egoism, with which Hobbes starts, ends in the opposite extreme of Political Absolutism;” that is, he shows the impossibility of maintaining the thesis with which he begins. W. Wundt, op. cit., vol. II, p. 56, _ “For Hobbes the natural moral law consists in a correct weighing of the beneficial or harmful consequences of an act. A breach of the law is therefore an error of the understanding merely; it can proceed only from false deduction, since nobody intentionally acts contrary to his own advantage. It is impossible that divine law, which is contained in the moral teachings of Holy Scripture, should have any other contents than that of natural law.” Hobbes says, On Human Nature, ch. vii, § 3, Even the goodness which we appre- hend in God Almighty is His goodness to us.” With the Leviathan, his chief ethical work (pub. 1651), we may compare Mandeville’s Fable of the Bees, and Rochefoucauld’s Maxims. R. B. Perry, Approach to Philosophy, p. 261, says his “‘unblushing materialism and egoism stimulated by opposition the whole development of English ethics.” 4 Treatise concerning Eternal and Immutable Morality, published posthumously, 1731. MODERN ETHICS 49 (1617-1688), Henry Moore, and Samuel Clarke (1675-1729); (0) in behalf of common good, regarded as secured by divine sanctions and laws, prior to human law, e.g., by Richard Cumberland (1632- 1719). Hobbes was the precursor of modern utili- tarianism,! and emphasized the greatest benefit to all as the summum bonum. In the meantime René Descartes (1596-1650) had propounded, on the continent, the doctrine of innate ideas, or self-evident truths.2 This raised the ques- tion as to moral truth being of this nature. Male- branche and Leibnitz viewed moral truths as absolute. Spinoza? (1632-1677), the pantheist, reduced moral- ity to an inevitable play of love and hate, expressive of a universal law of substance. Rationally perceived law is sovereign and explains moral conduct. The will is an illusion. John Locke (1632-1704), rejected innate ideas, especially moral,* and founded modern empiricism. 1 The title was first used by Jeremy Bentham. 2See W. Wundt, op. cit., vol. II, pp. 87-92. Descartes made doubt a means for testing truth; laying aside all that could be doubted he fell back upon innate ideas. 3R. A. P. Rogers, op. cit., pp. 143-146; W. Wundt, op. cit., vol. IT, pp. 92-97. ¢ Essay concerning Human Understanding, ch. iii, § 6, ‘ Virtue is generally approved, not because innate, but because profitable.” Self-love is the ultimate motive for all moral acts. W. Wundt, op. cit., vol. II, p. 62, says his labours “‘ were less distinguished by the novelty of his ideas than by the circumspection of his judgment, and. his careful avoidance of such extreme views as might seem para-- doxical to healthy human reason. . . . He is especially anxious to steer clear of Hobbes’ radicalism,” Jbid., p. 65, ‘‘All judgments om 50 INTRODUCTION AND HISTORY All knowledge is obtained through sensation and reflection, and it is thus that we arrive at the knowl- edge of moral law. This law is independent of pleasure, although supported by the Christian belief in happiness or misery hereafter. Joseph Butler 1 (1692-1752), the greatest writer of this age, vindicated the authority of conscience in judging what is right and what is wrong. He speaks of conscience as a “faculty,” but really makes it equivalent to the true self. David Hume? (1711-1776) formulated the skep- ticism that was involved in the philosophies of Des- cartes, Locke, and Berkeley, and reduced the mind to a mere stream of impressions possessing no real unity. All our knowledge is derived from experi- ence, we have no knowledge of law, whether moral or other, and the will is an illusion. For practical pur- poses he was, however, a utilitarian? § 12. After Hume four issues came to the front: moral values are the results of rational insight and intellectual deliberation.” But this intellectualism is distinguished from that of earlier schools by the increased weight he gives to empiricism. See also T. C. Hall, op. cit., pp. 447-450. 1R. A. P. Rogers, op. cit., pp. 163-176. See his Sermons on Human Nature. 2R. A. P. Rogers, of. cit., pp. 177-190; W. Wundt, of. cit., vol. II, pp. 74-79; T. C. Hall, op. cit., pp. 460-465. His chief ethical work, the Treatise on Human Nature, was published in 17309. 3H. Rashdall, Conscience and Christ, p. 28, “Utility, according to Hume, is the true criterion of morality just so far as utility actually pleases. But real utility does not always please. The public does not always know its own interests; and what is useful to one circle #8 pernicious to others.” MODERN ETHICS SI (a) between the intuitional and the empirical view of the knowledge of moral distinctions; (6) between belief in the absoluteness of moral distinctions and the utilitarian interpretation of morality; (c) between the acceptance of freedom as a fact and its denial by necessitarianism; (d) between intellectualism and sensationalism or estheticism. Thomas Reid (1710-1796) fought for the superiority of innate knowledge over empirical, and the self- evident and intuitive nature of fundamental and moral ideas. He was followed in the same line by Dugald Stewart and Victor Cousin. A long series of later writers have also taken the intuitionalist point of view, including Henry Calderwood.! Immanuel Kant, 1724-1804 A.D., reduced knowl- edge to impressionism, in which forms and categories and transcendental ideas are postulated, but not themselves known. Modern empiricism owes much to him. As a counter-poise to his skepticism con- cerning knowledge, he set forth the “categorical imperative,” or rule of duty, and the necessity of living in accordance with its requirements. He sum- marized all duty in the proposition, ‘‘ Act on a maxim which thou canst will to be a universal law.’”? His 1His Handbook of Moral Philosophy. Pt. I. His contention that conscience can not be educated is characteristic of his position. Cf. H. Sidgwick, of. cit., pp. 224 ff. 2R. A. P. Rogers, op. cit., pp. 191-210; W. Wundt, of. ci#t., vol. I, pp. 106-119; T. Whittaker, op. cit., pp. 56-65; F. Ueberweg, Hzst. of Phtlos., §123. For a criticism of his theory of the ‘Good Will,” see Dewey and Tufts, op. cit., pp. 240-246. *The moral quality of an action is wholly dependent upon its 52 INTRODUCTION AND HISTORY moral position agrees with Butler’s assertion of the authority of conscience; but he may be criticized as undermining the intellectual validity of moral judgments, as making morality too much a matter of law, and as leaving too little place for the emo- tions. Meanwhile, the intuitionalists contended for the absoluteness of moral truth, while the empiricists became avowedly utilitarian, making moral distinc- tions either equivalent to, or at least wholly deter- mined by, happiness. Happiness was further de- fined as permanent and of the greatest number. William Paley (1743-1805) made benevolence the characteristic principle of morality and the mark of divine government, which provides everlasting hap- piness as the reward and motive for righteousness. Jeremy Bentham (1748-1832)1 said that the greatest happiness of the greatest number deter- mined the moral quality of actions. being done in fulfilment of what is conceived as duty, the ideal man morally is one whose acts are entirely independent of inclination or desire. For a criticism of this view, see quotation from H. Rash- dall, p. 19, note, above. 1R, A. P. Rogers, op. cit., pp. 235-237; W. Wundt, op. cit., vol. II, pp. 142-146. The securing of pleasure and avoiding of pain “point out what we ought to do, as well as determine what we shall do.” The personal value of pleasure depends upon: (a) its intensity; (6) its duration; (c) its certainty; (d) its propinquity; (e) its fecund- ity, ie., its ability to beget other pleasures; (f) its purity, ie., its freedom from accompanying pain; and (g) its value for the com- munity depends upon its extent, i.e., upon the number of persons who may share it. It may be described as an algebraic system, pleasure standing for positive quantities, pain for negative. MODERN ETHICS 53 John Stuart Mill (1806-1873)! was utilitarian, while maintaining that the love for virtues as such, without reference to utility, is to be cultivated. This is because utility is thus promoted. Universal benev- olence, with discrimination between higher and lower forms of happiness, should determine conduct. The publication of the Origin of Species by Charles Darwin (1809-1882) in 1859 originated a line of thought which has had profound effect upon recent ethical theories. ‘The moral sense came to be regarded as a product as well as a factor in the evolution of the species; its foundations were treated as biological and social, and utilitarianism was modified by the thought that the happiness of the species is to be sought because it makes for the preservation and development of the species. Theologians criticize Darwin for interpreting nature as cruel, and for giving to brute power to survive the higher place; but it must be acknowledged that Darwin did not regard the process of survival by the extinction of the weak as a moral process. Evolutionary thought also raised the question as to whether moral judgments have any larger validity than that of passing phases of evolution. In the hands of naturalistic thinkers evolutionary 1R. A. P. Rogers, op. cit., pp. 237-240; W. Wundt, op. cit., vol. II, pp. 151-153. 2Herbert Spencer (1820-1903) especially. His fundamental ethical principles are found in the Data of Ethics and in Justice. See R. A. P. Rogers, op. cit., pp. 261-279. Evolutionary ethics sees bad only as good in the making, and reacts against personal respon- 54 INTRODUCTION AND HISTORY ethics have become “‘scientific,” by which is meant that all our ethical undertakings should be guided by the law of evolution. The propagation of the species, e.g., should be regulated by eugenics so as to produce offspring fit to survive. There is a ten- dency also to deprecate hospitals and all forms of philanthropy calculated to preserve the unfit. The Christian reply is that moral distinctions are what they are, and possess absolute validity, independently sibility and moral effort. As Aubrey L. Moore says, Lux Mundi, p. 47, ‘‘Moral evil is ‘sin’ only to those who believe in God.” Bp. D’Arcy, A Short Study of Ethics, Pt. ILI, ch. iv, has a good criticism. Ibid., p. xxvi, ‘Consciousness and will erect an eternal barrier against the attempt to explain the spiritual activities of man by the processes of nature.” See also Dewey and Tufts, op. cit., pp. 371-375; W. Wundt, op. cit., vol. IL. pp. 153-159; R.A. P. Rogers, op. cit., Pt. IL. ch, viii. Ernst Haeckel, Riddle of the Universe, ch. xix, sets forth the theory in terms of crassest materialism; also H. A. Taine, who says, in History of English Literature, Introd., ‘Whether facts be moral or physical, it makes no matter. They always have their causes. There are causes for ambition, courage, veracity, just as there are for digestion, muscular movement, animal heat. Vice and virtue are products like vitriol and sugar.” We acknowledge that there is no uncaused action, but we still allow for freedom of choice. The method of evolutionary ethics is to explain the present condi- tion by tracing the past history and stages of development. This is shown especially in E. Westermarck, of. cit.; and in W. R. Sorley, Ethics of Naturalism. One result is to evolve conscience out of existence, and to lead us on to Nietzsche’s “superman,” who becomes “‘super,” in part, because he has no conscience and is swayed only by the ‘will to power.” See the very able refutation of Nietzschean ethics and philosophy by J. N. Figgis, The Will to Freedom. Fora full historical account and defence of evolutionary Ethics, see C. M. Williams, Review of the Systems of Ethics Founded on the Theory I Evolution. MODERN ETHICS 55 of the manner in which the human capacity to per- ceive them originated. If this capacity is of evolu- tionary origin it is not less trustworthy on that ac- count, nor are the judgments of conscience reduced in authority by the nature of the origin of the con- science. What is called ‘‘Transcendental Ethics”’ was first evolved by G. W. F. Hegel (1770-1831),! to whom thought was the fundamental reality. This actu- alizes itself in society, regarded as the sphere of per- sonal self-realization. Thomas Hill Green (1836-1882) ? translated this into terms of English thought. He said man’s chief end is to be a person, i.e., to realize himself in a society of persons. The Christian idea is to grow like God, who is the only complete person. Green touched on important matter but he did not complete it. The chief end of man is to glorify God and enjoy Him. § 13. Little attention has been paid in these out- lines to separate definitions of the ethical systems that have been developed. It will be convenient to classify them as objective and subjective? The 1R. A. P. Rogers, op. cit., pp. 215-230; Wm. Wundt, op. cit., vol. II. pp. 124-127. It is impossible to give his ethical ideas apart from a study of his whole system of philosophy, which would require too much space. It may be criticized as too abstract to admit of general practical application. It also abounds in contradictions. 2R. A. P. Rogers, op. cit., Pt. II. ch. ix. Green’s system is set forth in his Prolegomena to Ethics, which is of an extremely meta- physical character. 3 J. H. Hyslop, Elements of Ethics, ch. viii, is followed in this sec- tion. W. E. H. Lecky, Hist. of European Morals, ch. i., divides 56 INTRODUCTION AND HISTORY objective theories are further classified as ontological and nomological. The ontological ground morality in the nature of God, or of the universe, or of both. The nomological ground it in will, either: the divine will, as found in the law of God, or human law and convention. The subjective theories are either teleo- logical or gnosiological; the éeleological relate morality to the end sought, whether utilitarian, hedonistic, or properly moral. The gunosiological theories are non- teleological and regard moral qualities as unrelated to all else, whether they are perceived intuitively or learned by experience. : The true theory is ontological, in that it grounds morality in the divine nature; and teleological, in that it treats actions as moral with reference to their bearing on the attainment of divine fellowship. The will, both of God and of society, may furnish rules and standards of moral action, but may not be regarded as the ultimate source of moral quality and obligation. Right is right, of course, whether we discern its per- tinency to our chief end or not; but the reason for its being right is that it does so pertain. It is well at this point to define in terse terms the chief specific ethical theories. LEgoism makes the good of the agent the end of action; while Altruism substitutes the good of others. Iniuitionalism claims ethical theories into intuitive and utilitarian, the former treating the sense of duty and the fundamental moral ideas as independent of utilitarian considerations and intuitively certain, the latter deriving moral ideas inductively from experience and making the pursuit of happiness the determinative ideal. MODERN ETHICS 57 that we can see clearly and immediately the contents of duty and their absolute nature. Hedonism makes pleasure the aim of conduct. Utilitarianism is hedonism universalized by making the aim the hap- piness or welfare of the greatest number or of society at large—the happiness referred to is earthly. Mod- ern practical idealism is utilitarian, as is also socialistic ethics. Evolutionary ethics in its several forms pre- supposes that moral distinctions and the moral sense are products of biological development, having their roots in pre-human stages of evolution! From the 1In general Bishop D’Arcy says, op. cit., p. 229. ‘Though the various ethical theories may be described as rivals, the opposition is not so great as it appears. Each theory has contributed some valu- able element to the whole of ethical thought.” Dewey and Tufts, op. cit., p. 224, “A classification of types of theory is rendered diffi- cult, a thoroughly satisfactory classification almost impossible, by the fact that the problems arrange themselves about separate prin- ciples leading to cross divisions.” ‘This last work classifies them as (a) Teleological and Jural; (6) Individual and Institutional; (c) Empirical and Intuitional. Egoism and Altruism may be identified by holding that “the Zrue Good for every man is a Common Good and an Absolute Good,” Bishop D’Arcy, op. cit., p. 102. For “this cosmos will not be good for self if determined with reference to self only; for persons, though each as a person, that is, for himself, is separate and unique, must yet be members of a higher order, com- bined by the operation of some transcendent principle of unity. They are all one in God. What is good for one is good for all,” ibid., p. 104. Bishop D’Arcy develops this at length in Pt. I. ch. iili-v. See also Dewey and Tufts, op. cit., pp. 375-391. A good description of modern extreme Egoism is found in Geo. Meredith’s novel, The Egoist. Intuitionalism is excellently described by Bishop D’Arcy, of. cit., Pt. III. ch. i. He says, p. 230, “This theory claims conscience as a special faculty, whose office is to give judgment upon conduct. Conscience, it is said, is ultimate. It is 58 INTRODUCTION AND HISTORY Christian standpoint the battle to-day lies between opposite notions of man’s chief end. Christianity makes eternal life with God the goal and organizing intuitive in its judgments. It is an essential part of human nature. It is therefore supreme. ‘There is no appeal to any higher court.” This is the position taken in Jas. Martineau, Types of Ethical Theory, and criticized by H. Sidgwick, Methods of Ethics, Bk. III, ch. xii. Hedonism is described by Bishop D’Arcy, op. cit., Pt. III. ch. ii. He says, p. 236, “The basis of Hedonism is the assump- tion that the object of desire is always pleasurable.” On p. 237, “In general, the mistake of Hedonism seems to be a confusion of self- satisfaction with pleasure. Self-satisfaction is the true end of all volition. Pleasure, as a rule, accompanies self-satisfaction; but it is not even an index to the value of any particular satisfaction. For some of the objects of desire which, when obtained, yield most pleasure are among the least satisfying.” “Utilitarianism, Bishop D’Arcy says, p. 243, “ is Hedonism grown democratic.” See the same work, Pt. III, ch. iii; R. A. P. Rogers, op. cit., Pt. I, ch. vii. H. Spencer’s criticism, that the ‘method of universalistic hedonism, or utilitarianism, is far more unsatisfactory than egoistic hedonism,” Data of Ethics, p. 133, seems to be war- ranted. Germany, e.g., would be justified in all that it did in the late war if it acted on the premise that its dominion was for the great- est good of the greatest number. That is, the end would justify the means. As W. E. H. Lecky says, op. cit., vol. I, p. 40, “Even if every virtuous act were incontestably useful, it by no means follows that its virtue is derived from its utility.” T. C. Hall, op. cit., p. 596, “English utilitarianism has had a long and honorable history, but it has been mainly outside of or even in avowed indifference or antagonism to organized Christianity.” We may sum up the teach- ing of this important school by giving its fundamental doctrine “the greatest happiness of the greatest number,” the attainment of which supplies the ultimate ethical standard by which conduct is to be judged. Henry Sidgwick (1838-1900), attempted to form a com- bination of the Intuitional and Utilitarian positions. Idealism is best set forth in T. H. Green’s Prolegomena, and finds many adherents in the modern ethical world. MODERN ETHICS 59 principle of conduct; while current secular idealism makes the earthly welfare of society determinative. The former stresses the other world, while the latter emphasizes the improvement of this world. To the Christian supernatural religion is of central impor- tance, but to the modernist religion is an adjunct only of idealistic aims in this present world-society.! 1See F. J. Hall, “This Miserable and Naughty World,” in Anglican Theol. Rev., Oct., 1920. CHAPTER III MORAL PHILOSOPHY OR SYSTEMATIC ETHICS § 1. Moral Philosophy deals with the theory or rationale of duty and virtue.! It is here treated under the heads of the Agent, the End, and the Act. We must state at the outset certain specific assump- tions upon which our treatment rests, assumptions which do not belong to Moral Science as such, but do affect its treatment. (a) “The chief end of man is to glorify God and enjoy Him forever.’ (6) To fulfil this end requires the light and prac- tice of true religion.? Religion, concretely speaking, is the working system by which men are brought into 1 Dewey and Tufts, op. cit., ch. xvi. A very brief summary of Moral Philosophy is given by F. J. Hall, Creation and Man, pp. 226-248. Among the best manuals are, Jos. Rickaby, Moral Phi- losophy; H. Calderwood, Handbook of Moral Philosophy; J. S. Mackenzie, Manual of Ethics; N. K. Davis, Elements of Ethics; N. Porter, Elements of Moral Science. For larger lists, see J. M. Baldwin, Dic. of Philosophy, vol. III, pp. 812-912; Schaff-Herzog Encyc., s.v. Ethics.” 2 Westminster Catechism. See F. J. Hall, op. cit., pp. 243-245. 3F, J. Hall, op. cit., pp. 229-232; M. MacColl, Christianity in Rel. to Science and Morals, pp. 292-303. 60 ASSUMPTIONS 6r relation with God, and true religion is nowhere fully exhibited except in the Catholic Church.! (c) Holy Scripture, viewed as recording a pro- gressive revelation, and interpreted by the Catholic Faith, affords true and determinative knowledge of the will of God and of human duty.? (d) Men are born in a state of moral insufficiency and corruptibility, with more or less blinded con- sciences, perverted affections, and weakened wills; so that, apart from supernatural revelation and grace, they are naturally prone to sin and vice. (e) The death of Christ is the basis of remedy for this evil; and the means of recovery and per- fection are committed by God to the stewardship of the Catholic Church. The entire removal of the taint of evil is not achieved, however, until aiter death.* (f) This life is probationary. Men are respon- sible agents. An everlasting future is to come after death, determined as to its nature by the judgment of God upon the moral value and tendency of our lives in this world? 1 F, J. Hall, op. cit., pp. 213-226. Cf. H. P. Liddon, Some Elem. of Religion, Lec. i. 2N. Porter, op. cit., §§ 140-144; J. B. Mozley, Ruling Ideas in Early Ages, passim; F. J. Hall, Theol. Outl., vol. I, Q. xvii, §§ 3-4. 3 F. J. Hall, Creation and Man, ch. ix, esp. pp. 285-289; H. Calder- wood, op. cit., Pt. V; J. J. Elmendorf, Moral Theology, I, vi.1o. 4F, J. Hall, op. cit., ch. x, §§ 1, 6-7; and Passion and Exalt. of Christ, pp. 103-109. SF, J. Hall, Eschatology, ch. ii, §§ 4-6, 8. 62 MORAL PHILOSOPHY, SYSTEMATIC ETHICS (¢) Men will hereafter be judged not only accord- ing to the knowledge which they have actually acquired, but also according to their disposition to obtain knowledge of the divine will. It isa part of human righteousness to learn, so far as opportunities permit, wherein righteousness of life and heavenly virtues consist. I. The Agent § 2. Men are called moral agents because they pos- sess rational freedom and can distinguish and choose between right and wrong action, having a sense of responsibility for their choice.2 As moral agents they possess what are called moral faculties, and these correspond to the psychical faculties of intellect, feel- ing, and will. The moral faculties are neither inde- pendent nor separable; but are specific functions and operations of the above-named psychical faculties. Moreover, we may not divide the psychical faculties from each other, for each faculty is conditioned in its exercise by the action of the others; neither pure intel- lect, nor pure emotion, nor pure will have ever been experienced.2 The moral faculties of the intellect are the ordinary intellectual faculties, which are called moral in so far as they are given moral direc- tion and are subject to moral conditions; any good 1F, J. Hall, Eschatology, ch. vi, §§ 6-8. 2H. Calderwood, op. c##., Pt. I, div. I, ch. i, §§ 8-9. 3F, J. Hall, Creation and Man, pp. 190-194. THE AGENT 63 treatise of psychology is, therefore, a serviceable introduction to their study. For the purpose of moral science these faculties may be conveniently divided into the theoretical and the practical. The theoretical faculty, called syn- deresis by scholastic writers,| has to do with the speculative and scientific appropriation and consid- eration of moral truths and principles. It calls into play external perception, intuition, memory, imagina- tion, generalization, and discursive thought gen- erally. Its exercise furnishes the mind with axioms,” facts, and generalizations which make possible and guide moral judgment. ‘The moral judgment, as its name indicates, is the practical faculty by which we apply moral principles to determine the moral quality of immediate lines of action and of habits. The conscience is this faculty of moral judgment as exercised with reference to one’s own actions and habits. By it the individual determines whether his actions are right or wrong.? ‘The rational faculties do _ 1 The scholastic writers define it ‘‘as a habit:by which the soul per- ceives the general principles of right conduct,” Koch-Preuss, of. cit., vol. I, p. 188. See Jos. Rickaby, op. cit., pp. 137-138; J. J. Elmen- dorf, op. cit., p. 499. J. M. Baldwin, op. cit., s.v. “Conscience,” gives the full history of the meaning of the two terms and the change of the meaning of conscience. 2H. Calderwood, of. cit., I. I. iii, shows that the fundamental intuitions of morality cannot rationally be contradicted, nor can they be proved. They do not result from induction. Cf. ch. iv, as criticized below. 3 Of the immense literature on the subject we mention only cer- tain works which are representative of different points of view. 64 MORAL PHILOSOPHY, SYSTEMATIC ETHICS not become either more or less trustworthy merely by being exercised in a moral direction. It may there- - See in general H. Calderwood, op. cit., I, I, ii, §§ 9-12; I, I, iv; J. J. Elmendorf, op. cit., p. 499; J. P. Gury, op. cit., Pt. I, § 36; Bishop Butler, Sermons on Human Nature, serm. ii; J. Locke, Essays on the Understanding, Bk. I, ch. iii, § 8; R. H. Lotze, Practical Philosophy, § 3; Jeremy Taylor, Ductor Dubitantium, Bk. I, ch. i; Robert San- derson, Lectures on Conscience and on Human Law; H. Rashdall, Is Conscience an Emotion?; G. L. Richardson, Conscience, Its Origin and Authority. We refer to these authors below by name only. It may be helpful, first, to see some typical definitions. St. John Damasc., de Fide Orthod., IV, 22, says conscience is the law of the mind, which defines it objectively. St. Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theol., I, lxxix, 13, says conscience is an act; Bp. Sanderson, p. 14, says it is neither an act, nor a form, nor a power; but a habit, partly innate and partly acquired. He defines conscience as “‘a Faculty or Habit of the Practical Understanding, which enables the Mind of Man, by the use of Reason and Argument, to apply the light which it has to particular Moral Actions.”’ According to the Aristotelean division of the mental faculties,—(a) Cognitive Intellect, speculative and practical; (6) Appetitive, or Will—conscience belongs to the practical cognitive. So Kant, Intro. to the Metaphysical Elements of Ethics, § XII (B), says, “Conscience is man’s practical reason, which holds before him his law of duty in every case so as either to acquit or condemn him.” Bp. Butler, Sermon i, it is “the principle in man, by which he approves or disapproves his heart, temper, and actions.” J. Martineau, op. cit., it is “the critical perception we have of the relative authority of our several principles of action.”” N. K. Davis, op. cit., p. 77, “Conscience is pure reason discerning morallaw. This faculty has the moral law for its exclusive object, and its exercise is the primary, original antecedent condition of any moral activity whatever, without which liberty has no moral restraint, and volition no moral character.” H. Calderwood, I, I. iv. § i, “Conscience is that power of mind by which moral law is discovered to each individ- ual for the guidance of his conduct.”’ All these trace ultimately to Aristotle, and are well summarized by Origen, In Ep. ad Rom., lib. II, ch. ii, who says it is affectum corrector, aique anima pedagogus. THE AGENT 65 fore be said that the synderesis and moral judgment or conscience ought to be educated and rightly informed As distinguished from other knowledge, Hugo of St. Victor well says, Inst. Monast., III, xi, Conscientia est cordis scientia; also, Cor noscit se et alia. Quando autem se noscit appellatur conscientia, quando preter se alia noscit appellatur scientia, Jeremy Taylor relates it to God and gives it a wider basis in human nature; he says, ‘God rules in us by His substitute our conscience.”’ As all are related to God none can be wholly without a conscience, through it God wit- nesses to Himself, it is a perpetual pulse; passively conceived it is a witness, actively it is a guide in all moral acts, words, thoughts. As to the mental faculties involved, he says, “‘although conscience be primarily founded in the understanding, as it is the law-giver and dictator, . . . yet it is also memory, when it accuses or excuses, when it makes joyful and sorrowful; and there is in it some mixture of will; . . . so that conscience is a result of all, of understanding, will, and memory.” To the same effect Koch-Preuss, op. cit., vol. I, p. 192, ‘‘We may roughly define conscience as a habit or capacity of the three faculties of the soul—intellect, will, and feeling,—by which man is bound to the moral order of the universe, i.e., the will of God; or, in other words, the capacity of applying objective laws to sub- jective conduct or of regulating man’s actions in accordance with the law.” Most modern definitions may be criticized as being too one-sided; thus Bp. D’Arcy, op. cit., “‘ Conscience is simply the consciousness of obligation,” which places it too much upon a basis of feeling. On the other hand, H. Sidgwick, “Conscience is essentially Intellect or Reason applied to Practice,”’ errs in identifying it too thoroughly with the rational faculty. G.L. Richardson attempts to include both sides, “Conscience is the whole personality acting ethically,” p. 69; and from a different, practically Christian rather than philosophical, standpoint, “Conscience is not sentiment, but a healthy abhorrence of sin,” p. 200. H. Rashdall argues against Edw. Westermarck and Wm. McDougall (in An Iniro. to Social Psychology) that conscience is not an emotion but a rational faculty, for if it is merely an emotion ft can have no more objective value than a liking or disliking for mustard. Emotions fluctuate. It is by no means certain that I 66 MORAL PHILOSOPHY, SYSTEMATIC ETHICS for their best exercise. The necessary and universal intuitions and axioms of the spiritual reason, indeed, will react emotionally to-morrow as I do to-day. Westermarck’s thesis, op. cit., vol. IT, p. 738, is that “‘the moral concepts which form the predicate of moral judgment are ultimately based on moral emotions,—they are essentially generalizations of tendencies in cer- tain phenomena to call forth either indignation or approval.” The hollow unreality of his whole scheme is shown by his treatment of the Parable of the Good Samaritan, vol. I, p. 111; and his thesis seems to be defeated by such statements as the following, “ Moral ideas are expressed in moral judgments,” vol. I, p. 158, for one does not ordinarily think of judgments as being founded upon the emotions, certainly not in a well-regulated mind. As to the origin of conscience there are two opposed schools, one regarding it as due to intuition (Calderwood), the other to evolution (Spencer). Christianity is committed to neither position, but may be said to furnish a synthesis of the two. ‘The fault of the first posi- tion is that it denies the ability of conscience to be educated. ‘‘That conscience intuitively recognizes moral law, that it is supreme in its authority, and that it cannot be educated, are three propositions which hang or fall together,’”’ H. Calderwood, p. 71. The argu- ments which he uses do not hold good, for both the eye and the ear may be, and are, educated. His view is considerably modified in the chapter on Moral Sentiments. In opposition we may set the statement of Jeremy Taylor ‘Conscience is only a good guide when we are truly informed,” in which we should mark the adjective “good,” for, as we have seen, conscience must in any case be our guide. The error of the evolutionary school is more serious, for it tends to leave God out of consideration and to regard conscience merely as a natural product. Finally, as to the authority of conscience, this is supreme. ‘Had it strength as it has right, had it power as it has manifest authority, it would absolutely govern the world,” Bp. Butler. In moral decis- ions the fundamental standards of judgment are invariable, e.g., truthfulness and honesty. They are not like the standards of zsthet- ics, or even of measurements, which may vary. H. Calderwood, Pp. 53, ‘Truths which are ultimate, . . . are universal not particular; THE AGENT 67 cannot be rationally rejected, for they constitute the basis of all moral conclusions and, for that reason, are beyond either proof or disproof. But moral science can be more soundly developed and the judg- ments of the conscience can be changed by education, fuller knowledge, and more deliberate reflection. Yet no appeal may be taken from the conscience, for its judgment signifies our existing knowledge or convic- tion as to right and wrong. To disregard this is culpable. The practical authority of the conscience necessary not adventitious; self-evidencing not demonstrable; un- questionable (indubitable and indisputable), incapable of contra- diction, whether in thought or practice.” G. L. Richardson, p. 96, “As we are bound to trust reason in the intellectual sphere, so we are bound to trust conscience in the moral sphere. To deny the authority of the one or the other is to distrust the Power in whom physical and moral law have their source. The authority of con- science is thus paramount for the individual; it will be better for me to do what is objectively wrong, but what I conscientiously believe to be right, than to do what is in fact right, but what my conscience disapproves. And the reason is that to distrust and to disobey conscience is an act of disloyalty to my personality; it is a kind of moral suicide. Conscience will work itself clear of error in propor- tion as it is used and trusted, just as intellectual truth is attained by the exhaustion of error.” P. 97, ‘‘The essential thing is not the verdict, but the motive which underlies it; and the motive must be that we shall allow the Divine Purpose to move freely through the human personality.” As to the relation to other authority, T. Slater, $.J., A Manual of Moral Theology, vol. I, p. 57, says: “The voice of the conscience is the authoritative guide of man’s moral conduct. Not that the individual conscience is independent of all authority; if the individual conscience is right, it proclaims the duty of submitting to all properly constituted authority, and especially to the supreme and absolute authority of God.” 68 MORAL PHILOSOPHY, SYSTEMATIC ETHICS is self-evident and impregnable. Sin has, indeed, clouded the human mind, and made its moral judg- ments less accurate and trustworthy. But, even in error, one is morally bound to do what he thinks right and to avoid what he thinks wrong, although previous neglect of light may make the error itself blameworthy. § 3. Some of the more important emotions of the moral nature are: (a) pleasure and pain; (bd) desire and aversion; (c) love and hate; (d) hope and fear. Pleasure and pain are impelling and deterring feel- ings which attend, or result from, action or experi- ence, whether internal or external, mental, emotional, volitional, or physical. Desire and aversion have some thing or event for their object, the former seek- ing, the latter avoiding, it. Love and hate have persons for their object. Love impels to union with, and, therefore, also to self-sacrificing service in behalf of, persons. Love towards God is the basis and regulative principle of righteous love towards man. Hate is the opposite of love.' Hope and fear are con- cerned with future and contingent events or results supposed to be possible. Hope is based on desire that the possibility may be realized. Fear is anxiety growing out of belief that what is hoped for is uncer- tain, or that what is undesired is probable. Despair is the entire absence of hope, due to the belief that what is desired has become impossible, or that what is not desired is inevitable. Sin has caused the 1F. J. Hall, Eschatology, pp. 250-253; H. Calderwood, op. cit., p. 155. THE AGENT 69 wounds of concupiscence and malice. By reason of concupiscence the feelings of pleasure, desire, love, and hope are directed upon or controlled by inferior objects and ends, while malice causes a misdirection of pain, aversion, fear, and hate. The activities of the intellectual and emotional faculties afford the motives by which the will is influ- enced, but with a difference. Intellectual motives are either directive or prohibitive, while emotional motives either impel or restrain. But the intellect and the feelings are inseparable. The emotions help or hinder the mind in arriving at truth, and to a real extent determine the judgments of conscience. The mind, on the other hand, affords the objects which call forth the emotions. § 4. The will! is the power of choice, and must be distinguished from the power of executing choice. The acts which are caused or determined by the will are called voluntary. Many human acts are either 1A, Alexander, op. cii., ch. v; Wm. James, Psychology, Briefer Course, ch. xxvi; R. Hooker, Eccles. Polity, ‘‘Appetite is the will’s solicitor, and the will is appetite’s controller; what we covet accord- ing to the one, by the other we often reject.”” A. L. Moore, Essays Scientif. and Philos., p. 134, “‘ Will is a power of control over the other faculties and capacities of our nature, by means of which we are enabled to determine personal activity.’ Bishop D’Arcy, op. cit., p. 177, ‘ What is of the utmost ethical importance is the cultivation of a virtuous will, that is, a will habituated to subordinate desire of every kind to the true good whatever it may be.” See further sbid., Pt. I, ch. iii; H. Calderwood, of. cii., Pt. III; J. J. Elmendorf, op. cit., I, ii; N. Porter, op. cit., ch. iv; J. P. Gury, op. cit., Pt. I, §§ 4 ff. %o MORAL PHILOSOPHY, SYSTEMATIC ETHICS involuntary or non-voluntary. These may often, however, be controlled, modified, or ended by the will! If actions were never really determined by the will, there could be no moral responsibility for them. ‘The will is the pivot of all moral conduct.? The will, as will, is necessarily free.? Voluntias, will, and voluntary have the same root. ‘The willis a true cause. So far, indeed, as the origination of its activity is concerned—the choosing of something— it is subject to causation; that is, as a rational being man must have a motive which moves him to act or to refrain from action. But so far as the direction of its choice is concerned—its choosing between alternatives—it is itself a cause, and free, within certain limits imposed on human freedom. In other relations than that of choice between courses of action the effects of choice are, of course, subject to 1H. Calderwood, op. cit., III, ii; N. Porter, op. cit., p. 110. 2.N. Porter, op. cit., §§ 70-72. 8J. P. Gury, op. cit., §§ 11 ff. Cf. Ecclus. xxxi.10. Kant, Intro. to the Metaphysical Elements of Ethics, init., “Nothing can possibly be conceived in the world, or even out of it, which can be called good without qualification except a good will. ... A good will is good not because of what it performs or accomplishes, not by its aptness for the attainment of some proposed end, but simply in virtue of its volition, that is, it is good in itself. . . . Even if it should happen that, owing to special disfavour of fortune or the niggardly provision of a step-motherly nature, this will should wholly lack power to accomplish its purpose, . . . it would still shine like a jewel by its own light, as something which has its whole value in itself.” On the conflict between free will and determinism, see C. Harris, op. cit., ch. xiii. 4N. K. Davis, op. cit., pp. 13-14. THE AGENT nt laws of causation which lie beyond the sphere of the human will! The freedom of the human will, and of every creaturely will, is circumscribed, because it is finite and part of a higher will-scheme. Its limita- tions include: (a) occasions and motives, for we can- not simply choose to choose apart from motive or interest;? (6) power of execution, for what is known or thought to be impossible or unpreventable is not a matter of choice;? (c) external environment and per- sonal influence, whether of men or of unseen spirits;* (d) heredity; (e) divine determination, and grace, although grace is not irresistible;> (f) character and habits,® which within their sphere tend to become more and more difficult to alter;’ (g) bodily condi- tions, e.g., need of food and sleep, sexual cravings, 1W. G. Ward, Essays on the Philos. of Theism, distinguishes be- tween spontaneous impulse and the effort often made to resist such impulse. The fact that we can thus resist, and choose action which is contrary to spontaneous impulse, affords clear proof that the will is free and not merely the register of antecedent causes and motives. 2N. Porter, op. cit., parag. 28, §§ 2, 4; H. Calderwood, of. cit., Ill, ii, 3; J. Caird, Fundamental Ideas of Christianity, vol. II, pp. 53-56. 3J. J. Elmendorf, op. cit., I, ii, 36; R. Hooker, op. cit., I, vii, 5. Compulsion may leave the will unaffected, but relieves of responsibil- ity for the act, when not consented to. 4N. Porter, op. cit., ch. xiv. On angels and their influence, see F. J. Hall, Creation and Man, ch. v. 5 F, J. Hall, op. cit., ch. i; H. Calderwood, op. cit., Metaphysic of Ethics, ch. v, div., II; J. J. Elmendorf, of. cit., pp. 18, 20; St. Thomas, I. xxiii. 3 ad tert. 6 Habits are either infused by grace or acquired; and may be good or evil. See Koch-Preuss, op. cit., vol. I, pp. 275-284. TN. Porter, op. cit., parag. 34, and ch. vi. gz MORAL PHILOSOPHY, SYSTEMATIC ETHICS disease. These limitations circumscribe or influence the will more or less, but do not determine it abso- lutely or nullify it.! One is responsible only when free and within the divinely ordered sphere of freedom. But avoidable limitations, such as those imposed by habit and char- acter, or vincible ignorance, wittingly and freely incurred, do not exempt from accountability; which also somewhat depends in degree upon the amount of mental deliberation in choice. The will never acts apart from the mind and the feelings. Yet these should be carefully distinguished. The mind and the emotions are the sources of motives. Thus desire affords a motive of choice, but the will chooses,? sometimes against strong desires and impulses. The mind affords reasons for choice and the judgments of conscience have authority, but the will is free to choose contrary thereto. Yet there is no such thing as non-intelligent choice; and what is so described is really an instinctive act? Choice is an act of will in a given case. Purpose or intention is a state of will with reference either to future action or to an end designed to be subserved by such action.4 1 Koch-Preuss, op. cit., vol. I, pp. 86-90, gives three chief individ- ual determinants of free will: age, temperament, talent; and, pp. 91-97, three social determinants: sex, education, society. Lom- broso exaggerated the strength of this last factor and made it mechan- ically and absolutely determinative. 2H. Calderwood, op. cit., ITI, i, 2. 3 Ibid., III, ii, 6. *N. Porter, op. cit., §§ 33-34. THE AGENT rR The will is momentary or habitual. A habitual will is one which has become more or less disposed to similar choices between similar alternatives, so that it acts with slight deliberation, almost spontaneously.! Personal character is constituted by the habitual will. Liberty means personal success in the sphere of choice, or the power of self-control and of realizing one’s purpose in action. License means choice with- out reference to moral principles and ends. It is fatal to liberty because opposed to the will of God, which cannot really be thwarted. Experience shows also that license gradually subjects the will to the passions, thus narrowing its freedom.” Pot enos, Lo LL, iexvil) 75. 7.) Slater, op. /ct., Vol. Ly p20, 218 the power of deliberation is wholly wanting, the act which follows cannot be sinful, however wrong objectively; if the act is semi- deliberate, however grievously wrong in itself, it will be imputed to the agent only as a more or less serious venial sin. These principles are of great importance for forming an estimate of the moral guilt of children, of habitual drunkards, of persons long habituated to sins of the flesh, and persons with weak intellect.” Jbid., vol. I, p. 36, Acts of this sort become sinful only ‘when consent is yielded to them after advertence to their malice.” They lack the consent of the will which is essential to make an act sinful. Such acts are said by theologians to proceed from antecedent concupiscence or mono- * mania, ib7d., vol. I, p.35. The agent, however, is bound to use every precaution, and the means of grace, to prevent their recurrence and especially to avoid occasions. Moreover the responsibility for falling into inveterate evil habits must be reckoned with and empha- sized. 2See H. Calderwood, op. cit., III, iv, 1; H. P. Liddon, Unio. Sermons, 1st Series, iv, pp. 78-81; N. K. Davis, op. cit., p. 55. The thought is pre-Christian, Seneca said Parere Deo libertas est; but the dynamic is found only in the Christian dispensation. Koch- 74 MORAL PHILOSOPHY, SYSTEMATIC ETHICS Sin has weakened and enslaved the human will. Divine grace operates to emancipate it, by impelling towards righteous ends and actions. But the bene- ficial efficacy of grace depends upon the will’s response, and the cure of sin is gradual; for grace does not take the place of practice in self-control or self-discipline, but assists us in such practice. The will’s response to, or use of, grace consists in this practice—practice in obeying higher motives, and in thwarting lower impulses and motives, even when these motives do not directly pertain to sinful ends or actions. The essence of self-discipline lies in this thwarting of impulses that are not in the given instances sinful? Preuss, op. cit., vol. I, p. 8, “true liberty, i.e., ‘the liberty of the chil- dren of God’ (sanctity, 2 Cor. iii. 17-18) is not the beginning but the end and object of morality and religion.” It is “victory over sin and passion, the result of a constant and patient codperation with grace.” As St. Anselm points out, if liberty meant the ability to sin or not to sin, neither God nor the angels would possess it. Koch- Preuss, op. cit., vol. I, p. 149, “Christian liberty means order in con- formity with the law of God, not license.” 1See Koch-Preuss, op. cit., vol. I, pp. 102-112, the friends or foes of the will are the instincts, affections, passions. Affections belong to the rational appetite, passions to the sensual. ‘The will is respon- sible only as it consents and codperates wittingly. It is not respon- sible for their origin. ‘They are ours not to annihilate, as the Stoics ~ taught, but to control by the aid of grace and by the training of the understanding. The passions and affections are listed somewhat differently from the list here given: (a) love and hate; (6) joy and sorrow; (c) desire and repugnance; (d) hope and despair; (e) fear and daring. 2H. Calderwood, op. cit., Pt. V, 9, points out that the laws of moral victory are those of (a) attention, selecting dispositions and motives with which to concern one’s self; (b) habit, directed to establishing THE AGENT 75 § 5. Man has a composite nature, and his moral faculties are conditioned and influenced in their operation by the bodily organism. The mind is determined in its operation by the condition of the brain and nervous system, which means practically by the condition of the whole body. An unhealthy physical condition tends to induce dulness of mind, and even to pervert the moral judgment. Unneces- sary carnal emotions and passions tend to debase the mind and will, and are frequently either caused or increased by bodily disorders. Even the healthy appetites and normal propensities of the body require discipline and self-control, if they are to be kept in line with moral interests. The will itself is often weakened and made inert by physical weakness, excessive weariness, and disease.} Bodily conditions are most apt to influence the moral faculties when they themselves have been caused by moral antecedents, because they then express, crystallize, and perpetuate such antecedents. Thus the physical results of intemperance and lust render these vices more difficult to remedy, and their evil effects may even be perpetuated in offspring. Physical heredity and other native physical condi- tions have effect upon the moral faculties, and tend to develop corresponding moral habits. For example, this concern. He adds that philosophy alone cannot solve the prob- lem of enabling the will to persevere along such lines. He refers to an essay on Moral Dynamic in Shairp’s Studies in Poetry and Phi- losophy, p. 348. 1Cf. F. J. Hall, Creation and Man, pp. 190-194. 76 MORAL PHILOSOPHY, SYSTEMATIC ETHICS men have what we call passionate natures, and are impelled to unregulated passions accordingly. Physi- cal environment also has moral influence by calling forth bodily responses which are either favourable or unfavourable to moral interests. Fortunately the mind has some power to combat and even to improve bodily conditions and their effects upon moral inter- ests, and this power is susceptible of enhancement by self-discipline.t No bodily conditions can change the material quality of the moral actions resulting from them; although they may reduce the formal guilt to the extent of the individual’s lack of respon- sibility for their presence. § 6. Man’s moral history is marked by a series of dispensations or covenants established with him by God: (a) a primitive dispensation of innocence and grace, nullified by sin; (6) the patriarchal and Mosaic dispensations, in which, by reason of sin, men had to assume a propitiatory attitude towards God—one which in itself was symbolic, and ineffective for the remedy of sin,—and in which they were placed under revealed laws that could not secure obedience and thus made their sinful inclinations more manifest; (c) the Christian dispensation, grounded in the pro- pitiatory death of Christ,? and affording means of sanctifying grace, with the assistance of which grad- 1 This is illustrated by the phenomena of mind healing, Christian Science, etc. The grace of Unction of the Sick assists the mind in exercising this power. See F. J. Hall, The Sacraments, pp. 320-324. 22 Cor. v. 14 (R.V.). THE END 77 ually the body can be brought under control, the conscience illuminated, the affections purified, and the will strengthened, for the fulfilment of man’s chief end through the attainment of everlasting life with God. This cannot be achieved, however, except through life-long discipline and a progress which continues after death.! II. The End § 7. The end of every act, so far as it is rational and free, is some good, whether higher or lower, real or apparent.2_ By the good is meant the desirable. It is of three kinds: (a) the useful; (6) the pleasur- able; (c) the morally desirable. The last men- tioned constitutes the true end of moral conduct. The useful and the pleasurable often minister to the moral good, and then take on moral value;? but they are not moral goods either in themselves or under all circumstances. Utilitarianism,* which identifies moral good with 1F, J. Hall, Creation and Man, pp. 220-223 and ch. x. 2 J. J. Elmendorf, of. cit., I, ii, 3; St. Thomas, I, I, x, x. 3N. Porter, op. cit., § 130. 4 Treated historically and critically by H. Calderwood, op. cit., div. II, ii, ff. He does not clearly distinguish Hedonism, which is concerned indiscriminately with pleasure, whereas Utilitarianism stresses higher and social well-being and lasting happiness, distin- guishing values of pleasures. J. 5S. Blackie, Four Phases of Morals, searchingly criticizes Utilitarianism; also W. E. H. Lecky, op. cit., vol, I, ch. i. Cf. H. Sidgwick, op. cit., pp. 236 ff. The practical idealism of our day is essentially a species of Utilitarianism in its tremendous emphasis upon efficiency for immediate results and upon the perfecting of human welfare in this world 78 MORAL PHILOSOPHY, SYSTEMATIC ETHICS well-being or happiness, and Hedonism, which iden- tifies it with pleasures of the moment, are absolutely to be rejected. They both substitute inferior for higher good, and this is the distinctive mark of evil aims. It is man’s duty to seek the morally good, and, when alternative goods are involved, the high- est one. Progress in attaining moral ends is, indeed, attended and to some degree conditioned by present pleasure, and results necessarily in ultimate happi- ness. If it were not so, we would have reason to suspect our whole philosophy and the justice of the universe. Pleasure and happiness are none the less incidental to moral good, and at times have to be sacrificed in its interest. Moreover, beatitude is not happiness in the abstract, but that form of it which we obtain through making our chief objective end to be life with God.! The moral ends of conduct are immediate and remote. The immediate ends are duties? and vir- tues—present obligations to be discharged, and habits to be cultivated and maintained. The chief end, or summum bonum, is “to glorify God and enjoy Him forever,” that is, perfected divine communion and fellowship? As essential to the realization of this, 1 See F. J. Hall, ‘This Miserable and Naughty World,” in Anglican Theol. Rev., Oct., 1920. 2 Duties in the comprehensive sense of what we ought to do under existing conditions—including the promotion of others’ present wel- fare, when legitimate opportunities occur. 3 J. J. Elmendorf, op. cit., I, i; Westminster Catechism, 1st answer; R. Hooker, op. cit., I, xi, 1-2; St. Thomas, I, I, i-v. THE END 79 personal perfection in virtue and character is also a necessary remote end of moral life. This means per- sonal assimilation of character to that of God, the only possible basis of either divine pleasure in us or our enjoyment of God. Such personal perfection is also needed for unqualified and lasting enjoyment of mutual human fellowship. The communion of saints obtains its fruition in common life with God, and is the only communion between human beings which is unattended by disappointment. Thus true brotherly love looks to the future, and seeks mutual sanctifi- cation, as the necessary condition of its realization. Personal sanctification is also the road to self-realiza- tion, or to what Aristotle described as ‘‘ perfect activity in a perfect life,” attended by perfect happiness. To seek such self-realization is not selfish, for it does not require or permit us to make the attendant happiness of self our aim. Thus Christian love when satis- fied is pleasing, but is by nature unselfish. To be pleased with what is righteous makes the pleasure righteous. And the self thus realized is what God created after His own likeness.! Christian Ethics is both individual and social. ‘Men are placed under social conditions by God, and are by nature social beings.2, A man must realize himself because he is a moral individual, and his per- 1Gen.i. 26. Cf. J. Caird, op. cit., vol. I, pp. 56 f. 2 God places us in the world society as the sphere of our probation; and He gathers those who respond to His call in the Church, which is the inception of that blessed society which in its perfection will enter into the full joy of God in the world to come. 80 MORAL PHILOSOPHY, SYSTEMATIC ETHICS fection is essential to the common good, as well as to a fulfilment of his personal obligation to please God. But his achievement of this is conditioned by the love of others, and by seeking the welfare of others. One is to love his neighbour as himself Altruism and egoism, as usually conceived, are alike inadequate. Both of the ends which these systems severally emphasize exclusively are vital, and neither may be sacrificed to the other. §8. The final causes or ends of moral choice become moving causes, when subjectively considered, and are embraced within the motives of action. The term motive ? describes whatever immediately moves and consciously influences the will from within. Motives spring either from intellectual or emotional sources. The intellectual motives are reasons for action or non-action. They are either directive or prohibitive, taking the form of practical judgments upon the ends and results of actions, whether in the sphere of utility, of pleasure, or of morality. They have as sources: (a) experience;? (6) reflection on experience; (c) intuition and a priori considerations. Emotional motives impel or restrain. They may arise from (a) immediate excitement; (0) subsequent’ imagination; (c) temperament. They take the 1 God alone may be loved with all one’s heart and soul and mind. 2See H. Calderwood, op. cil., Pt. If; J. J. Elmendorf, op. cit., I, ii, 4-5. 3 Conceived of as including the reception of divine revelation and moral education at large. THE END 8x form of pleasure or pain, desire or aversion, love or hate, and of hope or fear.! The motives are always mixed, being both intel- lectual and emotional; and are often conflicting ?— making both for and against the pursuit of the highest good. The question sometimes asked, whether the will is inevitably determined by the strongest motives, is ambiguous. If ‘‘strongest’”? means the motives which in fact prevail, the question is idle and has an affirmative answer, of course. If it means the most rational or the most excitingly felt, these do not in fact invariably determine choice. The will really determines, and is no mere register of the inherent strength of the motives involved. 1Cf. § 3, init., above. On the last, see T. Slater, op. cit., vol. I, PP. 37-39. 2 Per contra, Bishop D’Arcy, op. cit., p. 33, “A conflict of motives is impossible. What is called a conflict of motives is properly a conflict of desires.”” The motive is “that which moves to action,” tbid., p. 80 (cf. pp. 80-83). The motive is the desire which prevails; it is helpful to remember that motive and motion come from the same root. Dewey and Tufts, op. cit., p. 237, ““A ‘mere’ motive which does not do anything, which makes nothing different, is not a genuine motive at all, and hence it is not a voluntary act.”” There is a con- fusion here in terminology between motive and act; but the thought is that the motive can hardly be conceived as a determinative which does not strongly tend to realize itself in act. Hence it is possible to speak disparagingly of the “‘good’’ man, that is, the man whose motives are good, but who rarely expresses them in act. Ibid., p. 238, ‘The man with a truly benevolent disposition is not the one who indulges in indiscriminate charity, but the one who considers the effect of his gift upon its recipient and upon society.” Kant, we may note, in his theory of the “good will” over-emphasizes the motive. 82 MORAL PHILOSOPHY, SYSTEMATIC ETHICS Motives and choices are inseparable although dis- tinct phenomena of personal activity,! and the person is simplex. Motives do not determine the will from without, as separate factors, but from within as personal considerations and feelings? The will exhibits personal attitude, while motives exhibit personal conditions of that attitude. The will expresses self-determination, and nothing else is really meant when we say loosely that motives deter- mine the will. We should not confuse determina- tion as thus used with compelling conditions, nor forget that the will can so direct attention and reason as to modify the motives? The will itself is the personal faculty by which the choice of action is made. ‘The will ought to be influenced by the high- est motives—i.e., by those which make for holiness of life and character, and for the attainment of the summum bonum. The highest of all motives is the love of God or desire of union with Him—a motive which grows out of true and adequate faith and knowledge, and which is sustained by the hope of realization. This love in its perfection is the result of much moral and spir- itual development. Owing to our sins, the sense of guilt, and the expectation of penal consequences, the earliest motive which makes for better things is nor- 1H. Calderwood, op. cit., III, iii, 5-14, treats of the relation of motives to the will. Cf. R. Hooker, of. cit., I, vii. 2 J. Caird, op. cit., vol. II, pp. 44-45; R. Hooker, op. cit., I, vii, 3. 3H. Calderwood, of. c#t., ITI, iii, 14-19. THE ACT 83 mally the fear of punishment—‘ servile fear.” This fear, in those who seek an escape, leads to aversion to sin and to desire of its opposite; which in turn induces love of Him in whom the opposite is clearly to be found. All this, including the desire to escape, is contingent upon the illumination and prompting of grace. Thus it appears that, while servile fear is not an adequate motive or worthy of heaven, it is a necessary “‘beginning of wisdom,” and the motive of heavenward repentance. Repentance signalizes the birth of “holy fear” or loving anxiety lest we dis- please God.! The conscience judges with authority, and there- fore the motives afforded by its judgments ought to govern the will in every instance. It is true that the divine will is the supreme standard to which the human will should be conformed. But the con- science is the faculty by which we judge whether given acts are in accord with the divine will.? Ill. The Act §9. The moral quality of actions is ultimately determined by their relation to our attainment of the summum bonum, and for Christians this makes supernatural religion with knowledge, love and ser- vice of God, central.2 No act is moral which does 1F, J. Hall, Eschatology, pp. 220-222; F. H. Hallock, in Amer- scan Church Monthly, June, 1921, pp. 346-355. 2F, J. Hall, zdem, p. 185. 8F, J. Hall, Creation and Man, pp. 229-232; J. J. Elmendorf, 84 MORAL PHILOSOPHY, SYSTEMATIC ETHICS not either immediately or remotely pertain to this. The possibility of moral acts depends upon the pos- session by their agent of a moral nature. Such acts have to be rational and free. Moral actions include the operations of psychical faculties, and the use of language, as well as physical movement—that is, “thought, word, and deed.” 2 The causes which may make materially moral actions to be formally non-moral are: (a) invincible ignorance;? (6) necessity or compulsion.* If, how- ever, these conditions are due to previous fault of the agent,® they do not have this effect; and in any case actions which under normal conditions have moral quality are likely to be followed by moral conse- quences. Man is a responsible agent. He will be held to account by the supreme Judge for any witting op. cit., I, iii; J. P. Gury, op. cit., Pt. I, §§ 22 ff; Koch-Preuss, op, cit., vol. I, pp. 264-274; T. Slater, op. cit., vol. I, pp. 41-55. Koch- Preuss, vol. I, p. 264, ‘“By the morality of an act is understood its intrinsic relation to the moral order and to reason. Every human act, in concrete, is either good or bad. It is good if it conforms to the moral law; it is bad if it violates that law. The sources of morality, i.e., the factors or principles which determine the relation of an act to the moral law, are: (¢) the object or matter of the act; (iz) its form, intention, or end; and (iii) the attending circumstances. Generally speaking, an act is good if all three of these factors codp- erate in making it conformable to the right order; it is evil if any one of them is wrong or sinful.” 1H. Calderwood, op. cit., Pt. I, div. I, i, 3. 2F, J. Hall, Eschatalogy, pp. 175-178. 3 J. J. Elmendorf, of. cit., I, vi,6; T. Slater, of. cit., vol. I, pp. 30-34. ‘T, Slater, op. cit., vol. I, p. 40. 6 E.g., the failure of the priest to obtain the knowledge which he needs for his work, a matter of obvious obligation. THE ACT 8s and avoidable failure to use his faculties to their best advantage for attaining the swmmum bonum, that is, within the limits of his providential opportu- nity and available knowledge.! Duty, in the concrete, is an action or series of actions which ought to be done. In the abstract it is the quality or relation which is common to such actions, and which distinguishes them from all else— their oughtness.2 The sense of duty is universal and necessary. It teaches every man that he ought to do right, and also to seek his highest end. It implies in every normal mind the distinction between right and wrong, or between what he ought and what he ought not to do. The reality and nature of duty are grounded in the nature of God and of man; and its contents are measured by the standard of the divine will. But we cannot explain why men ought to seek any end. Yet all men know that they ought, however grotesque and mistaken their notion of the particulars of duty may be.? The ultimate source of morality is the divine nature; but it is also grounded in human nature, and is made known to us by the will and law of God.* Subor- 1OQn the imputability of human acts see Koch-Preuss, of. cit., vol. I, pp. 256~263. 2.N. Porter, op. cit., §§ 2-3. 3H. Calderwood, of. cit., I, i, 5. In ch. vi he shows that duty implies a natural and inherent right to act according to duty in spite of all hindrances. Cf. N. Porter, op. cit., § 5. 4H. Calderwood, op. cit., div. I, ch. v; J. J. Elmendorf, op. cit., pp. 35-36; N. Porter, op. cit., §§ 128-129; N. K. Davis, op. cit., 86 MORAL PHILOSOPHY, SYSTEMATIC ETHICS dinately and in particulars, the will of God is deducible from the laws of nature, and from humanly created law and social convention. These last two factors we shall consider later. The relation of the sover- eignty of God’s will to the permission of evil con- stitutes the most baffling of all problems. We can only maintain that God’s will is righteous, and the standard of righteousness; and that somehow, unknown to us, the existence of evil can be reconciled with this.! Many actions are seen to be right without conscious consideration of their ends, but it is always to be assumed that they do in fact pertain to man’s chief end. This assumption may arise either from the natural constitution of the mind, or from previous moral culture; and can be brought to light by sub- sequent reflection. Some actions are normally right or wrong because their effect upon the attainment of the swmmum bonum is normally in the same direction? The moral quality of actions, however, is also depend- ent upon circumstances; and grave problems may arise, calling for the judgment of learned and trained casuists.? § 10. Acts are either moral or non-moral, and PP. 202-204. By the will of God is meant the “will of signs,” or what He makes known that we should do and should not do. St. Thomas, I, xix, 11-12; F. J. Hall, Creation and Man, pp. 246 f. 1F, J. Hall, Being and Atirib. of God, pp. 187-193; and Creation and Man, ch. iv. * They afford the sphere of moral law. *N. Porter, op. ctt., §148 and ch. xvii. THE ACT 87 moral acts are either virtuous or vicious as they con- form or fail to conform to the requirements of moral- ity. Non-moral, spontaneous, or reflex acts may be produced by the will without due knowledge or at- tention; and to this class belong also those acts in which the will has no part, as in sleep, in disease, or under compulsion; also, and more generally, acts which are morally indifferent.! A moral act is a free and rational one, to which moral judgment is applicable, whether in relation to the divine law or to the summum bonum. It must pro- ceed from the will with knowledge and deliberation, in which case it is truly voluntary; but, if the knowl- edge and deliberation are not complete, it is imper- fectly voluntary, although still moral. The consent of the will may be implicit or explicit. Virtuous acts agree with the divine will and conduce to our attain- ment of the summum bonum, while vicious acts disa- gree therewith. Virtues and vices are the habits which issue respectively in virtuous and vicious acts. A vicious act is called sinful in relation to the divine law. Sin? strictly defined, actual sin, signifies con- scious disobedience of the divine law, but applies practically to any conscious violation of God’s will. Original sin, a symbolic use of terms, is the sin breed- ing state of nature when deprived of grace, caused by 1 Koch-Preuss, of. cit., vol. I, pp. 113-118. 2On sin, J. J. Elmendorf, of. cit., I, vi; H. V. S. Eck, Sin, Pts. J-II; J. P. Gury, op. cit., Pt. I, §§ 143 ff; W. W. Webb, The Cure of Souls, pp. 71-90; F. J. Hall, Creation and Man, pp. 247, 290-297: Hastings, Dic. of Bib., s.v. “Sin.” Cf. ch. ix, below. 88 MORAL PHILOSOPHY, SYSTEMATIC ETHICS the first man’s disobedience and universally inherited by natural birth. It is called sin because its existence is due to sin and its results are sinful.! Actual sin is distinguished as material and formal. It is material in so far as the act, as such, is wrong; and formal in so far as the agent acts freely and with knowledge of the sinfulness of his action. By formal sin the agent incurs formal guilt and penal respon- sibility for the act. Sins of ignorance are material only, but become formal when either persisted in or not repented of after their sinfulness is perceived.” Actual sins are distinguished also as venial and mortal or deadly. They are called venzal when they have not become so grave as of themselves to be fatal to the spiritual life, being without wilful deliberation and concerned with relatively light matter. They are called mortal when of themselves they are fatal to the spiritual life, unless remedied by repentance and pardoning grace; either because due to deliberate wilfulness or because concerned with grave matter? The distinction between venial and mortal sins is 1F, J. Hall, Creation and Man, ch. ix. 2 Jas. Skinner, A Synopsis of Moral and Ascetical Theology, p. 11, gives the causes of sin as: (a) ignorance; (6) weakness; (c) wilful- ness; (d) habit; (e) contempt. 3J. J. Elmendorf, op. cit., I, vi, 11; W. W. Webb, of. cit., p. 75, “The gravity of sin is the measure of its maliciousness, whether it be more or less offensive to God, and is more or less worthy of punishment.” P. 76, “Three things are necessary to make a sin mortal: (a) grave matter either in itself or on account of the cir- cumstances; (0) Full intention to commit a malicious act; (c) A perfect consent of the will. THE ACT 89 relative, and no exact boundary line can be drawn between them in practice. No sin, known to be such, can be treated as outside the scope of need of repentance; and to console one’s self with the thought that one’s sins are venial is most dangerous. By being cherished venial sins become mortal! The divine covenant provides remedies for every form of sin on the basis of Christ’s death, and under the con- dition of sincere repentance; and every sin causes the need of repentance and remedy. But sin may crystallize in habit, and in that form may reach sucha climax of obstinacy in conscious rebellion as to become irremediable and unpardonable—the sin against the Holy Ghost. § 11. Analysis of righteous conduct in the light of nature and revelation brings to the surface certain fundamental principles of action which lie behind all moral laws. Taken together these constitute an eternal law or order which is grounded in the divine nature. ‘They constitute fundamental premises of a right conscience. So far as they have become dis- positions favourable to righteous conduct they are called virtues, as are also the habits of action conform- ing to them. To define, virtues are the regulative principles or habits of conduct which when fully observed produce perfect righteousness of life and character.” 1Qn the comparative guilt of sins, see J. J. Elmendorf, of. cit., I, vi, 3; Jeremy Taylor, Doctrine of Repentance, III, ii, 5. 2J. J. Elmendorf, op. cit., I, v; Bishop D’Arcy, op. cit., Pt. IT; 90 MORAL PHILOSOPHY, SYSTEMATIC ETHICS Virtues are generalized under the two heads of cardinal and theological virtues. The cardinal or earthly virtues pertain to the natural order and to earthly relations, and fall under four heads: wisdom or prudence, temperance, fortitude and justice. Wisdom is seated in the intellect, temperance and fortitude in the emotions, justice in the will! The theological or heavenly virtues pertain to the super- natural order and are directly and expressly related to the attainment of the summum bonum. ‘They are faith, hope and charity.2 They supplement and Koch-Preuss, op. cté., vol. I, p. 277; A. Alexander, op. cit., ch. xi; Dewey and Tufts, op. cit., ch. xix. N. K. Davis, op. cit., p. 140, “Virtue is the conformity of the will to the law discerned by practical reason or conscience.”” W. W. Webb, op. cit., p. 91, “‘ Virtue is the habit of doing right.” He distinguishes virtues as natural or super- natural; infused or acquired; theological or moral. Virtue is some- times derived from vis, strength; but usually from vr, man. Soc- rates held that it wasa kind of knowledge, and that no one does wrong knowingly; but this removes the responsibility for sin and the possibility for blame, and is inadequate as resting upon only one side of man’s nature. 1J. J. Elmendorf, op. cit., I, v, 4, and Pt. III; T. B. Strong, Christ. Ethics, Lec. iv. 2j. J. Elmendorf, op. cit., I, v, 5-7; J. B. Strong, op. cit., Lec. iii; J. P. Gury, op. ci#., Pt. I, §§ 185 ff; W. W. Webb, of. cit., pp. 92-115. Bishop Webb distinguishes faith as (z) habitual or actual; (i) explicit or implicit. Explicit faith must extend to the Creed, the doctrine of the Sacraments as taught in the Catechism, the Deca- logue, and the Lord’s Prayer. Implicit faith may suffice for other truths of revelation; (i) Exterior or interior; exterior involving an open profession of our faith, and duty to God, to our neighbour, and to ourselves. Solemn profession is prescribed when certain sacra- ments are received; (iv) Living (bearing fruit in charity and good works) or dead (not joined to sanctifying grace). Koch-Preuss, THE’ ‘ACT. or transfigure the cardinal virtues, giving them a per- tinent relation to the attainment of the swmmum bonum which is otherwise lacking; that is, the car- dinal virtues are made to serve supernatural pur- poses. Faith elevates wisdom, hope elevates justice, and charity elevates temperance and fortitude; but in a complex interaction and mutual dependence. Vices are principles and habits which produce un- _ righteousness of life and character. They have been summed up under seven heads, called capital sins; pride, covetousness, lust, anger, gluttony, envy and sloth. Every sin can betraced to one or more of them.} op. cii., vol. I, p. 279, “Faith furnishes certain supernatural prin- ciples, which the intellect perceives by a divine light. Hope directs man to his supernatural end. Charity unites the will with God.” On faith in general see Heb. xi. T. Slater, of. cit., vol. I, pp. 165-176. P. 165, “It is an act of the intellect assenting to the truth of a propo- sition, not because it is evident to reason, but because its truth is vouched for by some one who knows and whom we can trust.” By it, p. 166, “we believe all that God has revealed and the Church proposes to our belief on the authority of God Himself.” This faith must extend to all that God has revealed. The detailed treatment of it belongs to dogmatic theology, but it has also a place in moral theology, for it is a necessary means to the attainment of our super- natural end, and without it the divine precepts of the Decalogue could not be accepted, except upon such authority as natural reason supplied. The chief sins against faith are infidelity, heresy and apostasy. Material heresy is not necessarily a sin, for one often falls into it through ignorance; but either formal heresy (the knowing and wilful rejection of revealed truth, proposed for our acceptance by the Church) or wilful doubt of such truth is sin. Apostasy is the aban- donment of the faith in its entirety. On hope and charity, see T. Slater, of. cit., vol. I, pp. 177-206. 1W. W. Webb, op. cit., pp. 79-90. For a more detailed treatment, see ch. ix, § 6, below. 92 MORAL PHILOSOPHY, SYSTEMATIC ETHICS § 12. It has been assumed in these outlines that, in order to fulfil his chief end, man must practice true religion, and that this can be done normally only in the Catholic Church. True religion brings us into authentic relations with God.2 Thus it secures a knowledge of the nature of, and means of attaining, the summum bonum, without which we may indeed seek after God, but can hardly expect to find Him. The summum bonum cannot be won by unassisted human wisdom and power, but is the gift of God. And it is promised only to those who seek it in His appointed way, with the use of His ordained means of grace. The Catholic Church is the sphere within which this way and these means are provided; and the death of Christ is the necessary basis and war- rant for the bestowal of these benefits upon sinful man. Justification signifies a state of acceptance by God which makes available the opportunity and means of salvation from sin and of attainment of the summum bonum. It signifies that a man is reckoned righteous because he has been put in the way of becoming so with divine help. ‘That is, the child of God is valued at the outset for the fullgrown man of God into which he is to grow—the condition being presupposed, how- ever, that he will achieve this growth with the help of grace. In order thus to be justified we must have a 1Cf. F. J. Hall, Creation and Man, ch. vii, esp. § 6. 2On religion see H. P. Liddon, Some Elements of Religion, Lec. i; F. J. Hall, op. cit., ch. vii, §§ 1-4. THE ACT 93 living faith in Christ and be born anew of water and of the Holy Spirit.t For the growth in the righteousness which justifica- tion initiates, certain means of sanctifying grace, called sacraments, are provided in the Church, the use of which, in their several applications, is necessary. The result of sanctification is personal merit, or moral fitness to enter upon divine fellowship. With- out such merit or fitness of personal character we can neither be pleasing to God nor find pleasure in the personal fellowship with Him, wherein the crowning joy of heaven consists and upon which our future hap- piness depends. This merit should not be confused with wage-merit. No works of ours can earn the summum bonum. ‘The value of such works lies in their making us worthy, and in showing that we are worthy, to receive it as a gift. The earning of it was achieved by Christ.? The practice of religion has for its central purpose to bring us into touch with God and to develop our relations with Him. Therefore its central action is worship, and this requires habitual performance. The fundamental element of worship is sacrifice or self-oblation; and this has to be expressed and per- formed objectively, for what is not thus expressed soon ceases to have vitality within ourselves. The 1F, J. Hall, of. cit., pp. 343-345; and The Church and the Sacra- mental System, pp. 259-263. 2F, J. Hall, The Church and the Sacramental System, pp. 271-278; Creation and Man, pp. 348-352. 904 MORAL PHILOSOPHY, SYSTEMATIC ETHICS appointed method of this expression is the formal offering to God of a representative gift of sufficient value to be acceptable to Him. This has been made possible by the death, resurrection, ascension, and perpetual heavenly oblation of Christ; and it is performed by us in the Holy Eucharist. In this service men both express and perpetuate the rela- tions necessary for keeping in touch with God and for making progress towards their chief end.1 The chief defect of modern systems of Ethics is their neglect of the central place which religion and its sacraments occupy in true righteousness. 1F, J. Hall, The Incarnation, pp. 283-293; and The Sacraments, ch. v, esp. §§ 11-12. CHAPTER IV MORAL THEOLOGY PROPER: LAW I. The Law of God §1. Moral Theology Proper is the practical branch of our subject, and treats of specific obligations and duties. Inasmuch as the standard of righteousness is the will of God, it treats of the application of the will of God to human conduct, whether considered at large or in relation to particular estates and con- ditions.1 The will of God here meant is technically 1QOn the history and literature of Moral Theol. (cf. p. 20, note 1, above), see Schaff-Herzog Encyc., s.v. ‘Theology, Moral;” ‘Thos. Slater, Short Hist. of Moral Theol.; Koch-Preuss, op. cit., vol. I, pp. 41-73; Cath. Encyc. s.v. “Theology,” pp. 604-611. Anglican works (more frequently contributory than systematic), W. W. Webb, Cure of Souls; J. J. Elmendorf, Elem. of Moral Theol. (follows St. Thomas); Bp. Sanderson, Lec’s on Conscience and Human Law (trans. by Wordsworth); Jeremy Taylor, Ductor Dubitantium; and Holy Living; James Skinner, Synop. of Moral and Ascetical Theol. (rare, needs reprinting); V. Staley, The Practical Religion (popular); R. L. Ottley, The Rule of Life and Love; T. B. Strong, Christian Ethics (Bamp. Lecs.); Chas. Gore, Christ. Moral Prin’s; A. J. Hum- phreys, Christ. Morals; K. E. Kirk, Some Prin’s of Moral Theol. 95 96 MORAL THEOLOGY PROPER: LAW called the ‘‘ Will of Signs,” or the revealed will of God with regard to our conduct. Its revelation may be either natural or supernatural, but supernatural reve- lation is primary, in so far as it is more definitive of the manner in which we must fulfil our chief end. In applying the will of God to our individual actions we judge in terms of conscience, therefore conscience has authority from which there is no earthly appeal. In brief, our primary guides are: (a) the will of God as objective standard; (6) the conscience as subjective interpreter. tn their Applic’n; W. W. Williams, Moral Theol. of the Sac. of Pen- ance; F. G. Belton, A Man. for Confessors; and Present Day Problems tn Christ. Morals; Cyril Bickersteth, The Min. of Absolution; A. H. Baverstock, The Priest as Confessor. Roman works (more complete and systematic, necessary for con- sultation but requiring cautious adaptation to Anglican conditions), Thos. Slater, Manual of Moral Theol., 2 vols.; A. Koch (ed. by A. Preuss), Handbook of Moral Theol., 5 vols.; J. P. Gury, Compend. Theol. Moralis; Aug. Lehmkuhl, Theol. Moralis, 2 vols.; St. Thomas, Summa Theol., Pt. II; A. Tanquerey, Brev. Synop. Moralis et Past. St. Alphonsus’ Theol. Moralis, 4 vols. is historically important, but needs cautious reading. A. Alexander, of. cit., p. 22 says, ‘‘ Christian Ethics presupposes the Christian view of life as revealed in Christ, and its definition must be in harmony with the Christian ideal. The prime question of Christian Ethics is, How ought Christians to order their lives? It is therefore the science of morals as conditioned by Christian faith; and the problems it discusses are, the nature, meaning and laws of the moral life as dominated by the supreme good which has been revealed to the world in the Person and teaching of Christ.” The Roman distinction between General and Special Moral Theology corresponds roughly to what is here designated as Moral Philosophy and Moral Theology Proper: Koch-Preuss, vol. I, p. 74. THE LAW OF GOD 97 § 2. The “Will of Signs,” as we have seen, includes commands, prohibitions, permissions, counsels and example. These five branches may be conveni- ently reduced to three: (a) Law, including commands and prohibitions; (6) Expediency, including permis- sions and counsels; (c) Example, embodying the Christian ideal in concrete form. Commands and prohibitions are included in what is called law, and they are treated as the primary and immediate basis of Moral Theology Proper; but the funda- mental principles of love and expediency have also to be reckoned with, and the example of Christ throws needed light upon many problems of duty. Law signifies that which is fixed or set, but has many forms and applications outside the moral sphere. In Moral Theology it means formal requirement or authoritative definition of what ought to be done and what ought not to be done. All law is ulti- mately grounded in the eternal law of Divine Nature.! The various branches of law by which this eternal law gains expression and fulfilment are exhibited in the following table: 1Rich. Hooker, op. cit., I, xvi, 8; Koch-Preuss, op. cit., vol. I, p. 120, “Law is but another name for the divine will recognized as the standard for human conduct.” Jbid., p. 141, “The moral law of the New Testament is the purest and most perfect expression of the divine will.” Its superiority to the moral law of the Old Testa- ment appears from its character as: (c) a new law; (0) a law of the spirit; (c) a law of grace and liberty; (d) a law of love. 98 MORAL THEOLOGY PROPER: LAW Of ( Internal ee Divine Processions, Rela- Divine | and tions, and Character. Opera- | Essential tions : External { Of Causation—natural law. and Vol- \ Of Progress—supernatural. Eternal Healy, Law of the divine nature, gov- erning all Of Innate—of Reason. Human Actions | Super- Revealed—Will of Signs, etc. _imposed Human Ecclesiastical. Dispensa- Civil. tions Conventional.! Moral Theology Proper treats of the laws of human actions. ‘These laws may be either (a) universal and 1 Koch-Preuss, op. cit., vol. I, p. 156, “ Human law is in every respect subordinate to the natural and to positive divine law, and its pre- cepts have binding force only if they agree with both. . . . Christ ex- pressly bestowed legislative power upon HisChurch (St. Matt. xvi. 19; xviii. 17; St. Luke x. 16), and furthermore Himself acknowledged the laws of the State and exhorted His disciples to obey them (St. Luke xx. 25; Acts xv. 28; xx. 28). St. Paul says that all power is from God and that the ordinances of legitimate authority bind in con- science (Rom. xiii. 1 ff.; cf. St. John xix. 11).’”’ Human law is an inter- pretation and application of the general principles of the natural and revealed divine law. Jbid., p. 157, ‘Every human law is mediately and by derivation a divine law.”’ J. Skinner, op. cit., p. 7, gives the heads of law: in genere, (2) Cause; (b) Object; (c) Subject; (d) Promulgation; (e) Acceptation; (f) Obligation; (g) Interpretation; (4) Dispensation; (7) Cessation; in specie, (a) Natural and divine; (b) Positive and divine; (c) Ecclesiastical; (d) Civil; (e) Penal; (f) Ineffective; (g) Custom; (4) Privilege. THE LAW OF GOD 99 naturally revealed;! (6) covenantal and_ positive, made necessary by the fall, and for the attainment of man’s supernatural end. Covenantal law may be either immutable or mutable, this distinction being ordinarily indicated by the terms moral and ceremonial. The ceremonial law is also subject to many excep- tions, according to necessity and enlightened discre- tion.2, Even moral law has exceptions, although they are rare and of a nature to prove the rule; for it is impossible to define moral obligations in human terms that will accurately describe duty under all possible circumstances. § 3. We shall treat of our subject in the following order: (a) innate moral obligations, or the law of reason; (b) superimposed law,? this being sub- divided under the heads of the Decalogue, inter- preted in the light of our Lord’s summary of love, and so treated as to include ecclesiastical, civil and conventional requirements; (c) virtues and vices. It will be necessary to supplement these comprehen- sive divisions by special treatment of (d) social and individual aspects of duty, (e) economic obligations, 1 Koch-Preuss, op. cit., vol. I, p. 122, “By the moral law of nature is understood the sum-total of those ethical precepts which God has implanted in the rational nature of man.” It is fundamental, and no other law can abrogate it. 2Cf. St. Matt. xii. 1-8; St. Mark ii. 27. 3T. Slater, op. cit., vol. I, p. 83, “Divine law is either natural or positive. The natural law is promulgated in the rational nature of man, and is a participation in human reason of the eternal law of God, which bids us observe right order, and forbids its disturbance. Positive divine law is made known by revelation.” too MORAL THEOLOGY PROPER: LAW (f) voluntarily incurred obligations, (g) expediency, (hk) example. II. The Law of Reason §4. The law of natural reason teaches certain obligations which are capable of being ascertained and recognized by all who seek to do right, whether they are Christians or not. They may be divided into individual and social obligations. Of individual obligations the general law is that we should live according to nature as it comes from the hand of God. Todo this means to maintain a perfect activity of our faculties and to preserve them in the fulness of their capacity. The aim of all education, properly conducted, is to lead out, educere, all our faculties in just proportion and relation, in order that we may be emancipated from every unnecessary hindrance to do and be what we ought to do and be. (a) It is a natural duty to obtain good and nourish- ing food, and to partake of it in the quantity and manner which available knowledge shows to be con- ducive to the preservation and development of physi- cal, mental, and moral capacity. (0) Sufficient sleep should be taken at regular times and without excessive indulgence, the amount being controlled by the laws of health and efficiency. (c) Habitual work is essen- tial to good morals, but also needs to be regulated. We ought to exercise our powers as fully as possible, but without overstraining any of them. This requires THE LAW OF REASON IOr that labor should be systematic, and that hurry as well as worry should be banished as much as possible. Work of high quality is more valuable, morally as well as otherwise, than a large quantity of work poorly done. (d) Recreation is a closely related obligation, the form and quantity of which ought to be deter- mined by its value in improving the efficiency of our work, and in facilitating our personal development. The word “‘recreation”’ itself signifies the true end of all righteous forms of pleasure—to re-create our facul- ties. This does not mean that we should take our pleasures solemnly, for that would be to defeat their moral function. The point is that we should deter- mine the manner and duration of play with reference to the general purpose of increasing the value of our lives and characters. (e) All other rules of health, such as outdoor exercise, fresh air, reasonable clean- liness, etc., pertain to natural moral obligations. § 5. Man is by nature a social animal, and it is part of natural law that he should adjust himself to his social environment. The law of natural evo- lution teaches that utility depends upon adjustment, and that natural selection works against those who disregard this requirement. This adjustment may be described in moral terms as the duty of recognizing and protecting the rights of others: (a) The right to enjoy life and happiness, which includes oppor- tunity to earn one’s living, under suitable conditions, and with proportionate results; (0) The rights of kinship as between parents and children, brothers 102 MORAL THEOLOGY PROPER: LAW and sisters, husband and wife, and others. Nature teaches that the obligations between husband and wife normally include propagation of the species; (c) The rights of strangers, including those whom we meet in public, and especially those who are com- pelled to depend upon our hospitality; (d) The rights of enemies to be treated as human beings; (e) The general duty of advancing the greatest good of the greatest number. The fallacy of utilitarian ethics is that it makes this the sum and substance of morality, and in effect repudiates the probationary relation of this life to eternal life. All natural obligations can be reduced to the heads of prudence or wisdom, tem- perance, fortitude and justice, the so-called cardinal virtues.! III. Superimposed Moral Law §6. The revealed law of God is described in Deuteronomy as consisting of statutes and judgments. Statutes define forms of conduct, which are either commanded or forbidden; and judgments determine particular cases and constitute authoritative prece- dents. In Christian application many of these prece- dents cease to be valid because of the new dispensa- tion and the change of conditions.2 Divine statutes 1 Cf, ch. ili, § 11, above. 2R. L. Ottley, Aspects of the Old Testament, p. 171, “It would be misleading to speak of Mosaism as if it embraced a formal system of ethics. It did, however, prepare the way for a system by a gradual, but in the long run effectual, elucidation of two great ideas which a SUPERIMPOSED MORAL LAW 103 contain two elements: (a) moral and permanent; (b) ceremonial, pertaining only to the dispensation in connection with which they are given. Some statutes are exclusively moral and some are exclusively cere- monial, but others, such as the fourth commandment of the Decalogue, contain both elements and have to be interpreted accordingly! The ceremonial ele- ment may cease to apply either because of counteract- ing necessity or by reason of a new divine dispensa- tion. But some ceremonial laws, in particular that of tithing, reveal degrees of moral responsibility of abiding validity; and these retain a certain moral value even when the law as law has ceased to bind. The revealed moral law is found primarily in two documents, the Old Testament Decalogue and our Lord’s twofold summary in the Gospels. The former consists of specific rules, the latter defines the deter- minative principle of righteousness which should control their interpretation and the practical appli- cation of all rules of conduct. The law of the Old Testament was binding in its letter only upon the Chosen People; whereas the Christian summary, given by Christ, is for all men, and is permanently binding upon all who have learned of it.2 The older must be Christianized by the newer. The provisions religious system of morals seems to presuppose: first, the idea of holi- ness; secondly, the idea of the worth and dignity of personality.” 1Tbid., p. 215, The Decalogue ‘“‘defines in broad outlines the con- ditions of a right relation to God and to all that He has made.” Cf, St. Iren., adv. Haer., IV, 15, i; IV, 16, iii; St. Thos. of. ctz., I, I, c. 3. 2St. Matt. xxii. 36-40; xxviii. 19-20. 104 MORAL THEOLOGY PROPER: LAW of the older are rightly criticized as largely negative and external, regulating outward conduct; but Christianized they_ stand for positive principles regulating thought as well as word and act.! The Decalogue is not exhaustive, although it gives leading and representative examples of how we ought to conform to the divine will. Its requirements pre- suppose the binding force of the laws of human dis- pensations, whether ecclesiastical, civil or conven- tional, and afford guidance in their fulfilment. They will here be treated in this light and as including (a) ecclesiastical application (growing out of the sacra- ments, canon law and ecclesiastical precepts); (0) civil law; (c) social customs and institutions. The several commandments constitute so many methods by which the principle of love ought to be applied Godward and manward. ‘This is also true of all special statutes and judgments of God.2 The Decalogue is divided into two tables, concerned respectively with duties to God and duties to man. The division between these is usually drawn between the first four and the last six; but it is more scientific to include the fifth in the first table, because it has to do with obedience to authority, and every legiti- 1 Chas. Gore, Christian Moral Prin’s, Serm. ii-iii, and pp. 110 ff. ‘ 2Qn the Commandments in general, see W. W. Webb, op. cit., ch. v; R. L. Ottley, The Rule of Life and Love; T. Slater, op. cit., vol. I, pp. 207-473; Hastings, Dic. of Bib., s.v. “Decalogue”; J. P. Gury, op. cit., §§ 257-472. Gury says, “Sicut Symbolum epitome est credendorum, sic decalogus agendorum.” SUPERIMPOSED MORAL LAW 105 mate authority represents, in ultimate analysis, the authority of God.t § 7. The general principle embodied in the First Commandment is that of entire and exclusive allegiance to the one and only true God.? In practice this allegiance ought to be shown in four directions: (a) The profession of a true faith, not only in God Him- self, but in all that He has revealed concerning our relations to Him, His purpose for us, and what He has done and is doing in and for us. The truths which we ought to believe consist of those which are known to have been revealed, and we may not make exceptions because some of the truths do not appear to us to be vitally important. Our allegiance to God is violated by rejecting even the slightest authen- tic revelation from Him. Moreover, the acceptance 1In Roman use, the first two are counted together as the first; and the tenth is broken into two, the ninth being, ‘Thou shalt not covet thy neighbour’s wife.” 2 The first commandment may be summed up as defining the duty of worship and prayer, faith being presupposed. The opposed vices are: (a) superstition, magic and divination; (the last including telling of fortunes by palmistry, cards, etc., reliance upon dreams, the use of the Ouija board, consulting of mediums). ‘These need not be thought of as sins when the motive is light, but become such when they are taken seriously; (0) Irreligion; (c) Tempting God by our failure to use ordinary means to secure an end, as neglect of remedies in sick- ness (Christian Science); seeking a miracle for the support of one’s faith; the ordeals of the Middle Ages, which the Church condemned as superstitious; (d) Sacrilege, the irreverent treatment of sacred persons, places, and things dedicated to the service of God. Under this head is included receiving or administering sacraments in a state of mortal sin. A more common offence is that of joking or light | speaking in religion. 106 MORAL THEOLOGY PROPER: LAW of revelation carries with it the duty of professing our faith, so far as our circumstances afford suitable occasions for such profession, and whenever the Church of God requires. (b) The practice of religion is necessary to this allegiance, for in its practical aspects religion is all one with a conformity of our lives to the relations in which we stand to God. The duty of taking part in public, especially Eucharistic, worship rests upon the individual as a member of the group from which cor- porate worship is due. The form which this wor- ship takes is determined by the authority of the Church; and public or common prayer may be con- ducted only according to the forms provided by eccle- siastical authority, whether by canon law or by bishops in the exercise of such jus liturgicum as is consistent therewith. Private prayer and the other ‘notable duties” of religion.are considered below.! (c) This allegiance also involves the fulfilment of all the conditions of the covenant which God has given us. The duties involved may be summed up by saying that we ought to be faithful members of the Church and obedient to all ecclesiastical precepts.? (d) Observance of the covenant carries with it certain specific obligations pertaining to the sacraments.® § 8. The Second Commandment has reference to wor- ship in the sense of /atreia, and requires that it should 1In ch. vi, §§ 1-3. 2 Treated of in § 11, below. 3 Treated of in ch. v, below. SUPERIMPOSED MORAL LAW 107 be paid exclusively to God and in the manner ap- pointed by Him. The use of images, as external aids, must be determined and controlled not by our device but by divine revelation. And this last principle applies not only to sensible images but to mental ones. Two leading classes of sin are, therefore, forbidden, external idolatry and false doctrine, so far as em- bodied in worship. Incidentally all superstitious ob- servances, such as we have already referred to under the first commandment, are forbidden here also, as is participation in schismatic worship. The latter is for- bidden because it violates Christian unity and substi- tutes for divinely appointed worship a modified and human substitute. The divinely appointed worship is the Holy Eucharist, and around this should be gath- ered and subordinated all our approaches to God. The lawfulness of any form of worship, therefore, can be tested by its agreement with, and capacity of min- istering to, the Holy Eucharist. Material art may be used to make worship more effectual, but not in such wise as to alter its object or divinely appointed method. This commandment also implies and reg- ulates the duty of prayer in all its branches. Fasting and almsgiving are usually grouped with prayer, because these three constitute what are called the “notable duties” of religion. These will be consid- ered below.! §9. The Third Commandment inculcates reverential piety, or that loving loyalty to God which moves one 1Tn ch. vi, §§ 1-3. 108 MORAL THEOLOGY PROPER: LAW to avoid treating anything divine or sacred in a thoughtless or careless manner. Among the obvious branches of its violation are: (a) irreverent use of the divine Name as an expletive, oath, or common exclamation, and of sacred things; (6) Tempting God by challenging His particular providence; (¢) Sacrilege, or the handling of sacred things for secular purposes; (d) Blasphemy, or the use of God’s name for purposes of sin. (e) Simony, or buying spiritual advantages;! (f/f) The facetious use of Holy Scripture and other sacred language; (g) Trifling in sacred places; (%) Careless ceremony in participating in religious services. One of the problems which arise under this com- mandment is, what constitutes a lawful oath or vow’? 1 Acts. viii. 18. 2 On oaths and vows, see W. W. Webb, pp. 131-137; J. J. Elmen- dorf, pp. 343-353. An oath is “the calling on God to witness to the truth of what we say,” T. Slater, op. cit., vol. I, p. 240. It may be either solemn, when attended by the ceremonies prescribed by law, as holding up the right hand, kissing the Bible, or simple, when these ceremonies are omitted. Such oaths are not only permissible, but are public professions of our belief in God, His omniscience, truth, etc. They are not forbidden by St. Matt. v. 34; cf. Jerem. iv. 2. A promissory oath is not binding when a change of circumstances makes it unlawful, useless, or an obstacle to a greater obligation. The obligation to fulfilment may be annulled, dispensed, commuted or relaxed, in the same way as a vow; but private judgment alone is not competent except in obvious necessity. A vow “is a contract with God, a deliberate taking on one’s self of a new obligation which binds the conscience,” T. Slater, op. cit., vol. I, p. 246. It differs from a mere promise of amendment. .To constitute a vow there must be full knowledge, complete use of reason, freedom from force, and physical and moral possibility of fulfilment. It may be either absolute or conditional. SUPERIMPOSED MORAL LAW 109 The answer in brief is, that we ought to have a suf- ficiently grave reason, and should have in view the interests of truth and righteousness. A reverent manner and careful fulfilment are also necessary. The legal name for false oaths is perjury; and this is a double sin because including both the sinful use of God’s name and lying. A vow which cannot be ful- filled without sin is sinful and does not bind. In every Christian vow there is a qualifying assumption that competent authority may, for sufficient and law- ful reasons, either dispense from vows or overrule them. The spirit of this commandment cannot be ful- filled except by those who cultivate the moral and spiritual tone which lies behind reverence for holy things. High tone is of Christian obligation, and flippant vulgarity is a hindrance to the fulfilment of this commandment. § 10. The Fourth Commandment requires the con- secration or appointing of regularly recurring times, sanctioned by religious authority, for the public worship of God and for the fulfilment of other relig- lous responsibilities.1 In form it is ceremonial, be- cause the selection of the seventh day and abstaining from all labour do not constitute morally necessary and permanent conditions of the fulfilment of its spirit. The Lord’s day has displaced the Sabbath, 1See Vernon Staley, op. cit., Pt. II, ch. xi; F. G. Belton, Present Day Problems, ch. vi; J. A. Hessey, Sunday (Bamp. Lec.); H. R. Gamble, Sunday and the Sabbath; W. B. Trevelyan, Sunday. 110 MORAL THEOLOGY PROPER: LAW Christian festivals have displaced the Jewish Calendar, and the question of labour on Sunday is not deter- mined by definite divine precept. Various problems arise under this commandment. They are determined by a very simple principle, that Sunday has its own proper business to be fulfilled. If under normal conditions that business is ade- quately and sincerely attended to, freedom remains as to what else is done or is indulged in, similar to that which we enjoy on other days of the week. In application, however, questions of expediency arise, as distinguished from law; and it is our duty to show reasonable regard for other people’s consciences and for our own moral and spiritual reputation. Public association of ideas causes a natural sense of incon- gruity between the appointed Sunday business and certain forms of self-indulgence. This limitation, however, is wholly extrinsic; and we may not raise to the level of legal requirement matters which per- tain to variable expediency.! The business of Sunday, or its positive obligations, include: (a) public worship, especially the Holy Eucharist; (0) the practice of religion in any and all of those elements for which other days of the week do not afford sufficient opportunity, reading of the Bible, spiritual books, etc.,—in short, making religion the day’s specialty; (c) works of mercy, both corporal and spiritual; (d) the religious instruction of the young. The sum of the matter is that to observe 1See H. R. Gamble, Sunday and the Sabbath, passim. SUPERIMPOSED MORAL LAW IIt Sunday is to fulfil its positive business, in so far as it pertains to each individual; and in other respects to control Sunday occupations in such wise as not to reduce either the external fulfilment or the spiritual value of what pertains to Sunday duties, regard being had also to the effect of our example upon others. As we have said, questions of expediency come sharply to the front. We have, therefore, to con- sider in this connection what is permitted, on the one hand, and what is to be advised, on the other. Taking permissions first, it is intrinsically lawful to do and to enjoy any and everything that it is lawful to do and to enjoy on other days of the week, provided nothing is done that interferes with a reasonably adequate and habitual fulfilment of Sunday’s proper business. On the other hand, from the point of view of counsel, it is often inexpedient and may, in effect, become sin- ful under some conditions to take part in: (a) bois- terous and strenuous occupations of secular nature; (6) occupations which our neighbours consider sinful on that day; (c) amusements that offend weak consciences at all times. Like all positive precepts, this commandment may cease for the moment to bind when real necessity interferes with its fulfilment, e.g., (a) in sickness; (0) when one’s subsistence depends upon continuing work on Sunday; (¢c) when a Sunday’s outing is the only possible way of obtain- ing sufficient recreation. It is to be observed, how- ever, that we are responsible for planning our life 112 MORAL THEOLOGY PROPER: LAW work, as far as possible, in ways that permit an adequate discharge of religious obligations. As regards absorbing occupation, ordinary servile work is forbidden except under unusual circumstances; but agricultural labor is allowable under necessity, as in harvest time, when grave loss might be occasioned if it were neglected; and the same liberty applies to foundry labour customarily, to transportation of all sorts, especially at sea, to preparing food and, in gen- eral, to any form of occupation which could not be interrupted for a day without grave loss or incon- venience. Admitting this liberty, there is in various directions much room for doubt as to whether what is customarily termed necessary is really so. It is plainly sinful for employers to require labour on Sun- day without real necessity.1 The broad principle is involved that every duty should have provided its appropriate time for attention, and that a life which is without plan or system is one that makes many sins inevitable. §11. The Fifth Commandment requires obedience 3 This applies to such unnecessary recreations as involve the labour ‘ofothers. Encyclical Letter of the Lambeth Conference, 1888, ‘‘The due observance of Sunday as a day of rest, of worship, and of religious teaching, has a direct bearing on the moral well-being of the Christian community. We have observed of late a growing laxity which threat- ens to impair its sacred character. We strongly deprecate this ten- dency. We call upon the leisurely classes not selfishly to withdraw from others the opportunities of rest and of religion. We call upon master and employer jealously to guard the privileges of the servant and the workman. In ‘The Lord’s Day’ we have a priceless heri- tage. Whoever misuses it incurs a terrible responsibility.” SUPERIMPOSED MORAL LAW 113 to all divinely sanctioned authority, whether involved in providential circumstances at large or based upon specific divine appointments. Speaking broadly, its sphere is threefold: the family, the Church and the State. In each sphere the duties are twofold: of inferiors to superiors, and of superiors to inferiors. To-day the second class of duties is apt to receive a false emphasis because of reaction, inasmuch as the rights of inferiors were formerly insufficiently acknowl- edged. But emphasis upon rights gradually becomes forgetfulness of duties; and a crying need is a general revival of unselfish emphasis upon duties to others. (a) In the family } children owe obedience, love, and reverence to parents in all things lawful;? and the younger owe deference to their elders. On the other hand, parents and elders owe to the young teaching, both secular and religious, example, guidance, and discipline, along with physical support. The ful- filment of these obligations ought to be governed 1A, Alexander, op. cit., pp. 220-229; N. K. Davis, op. cié., Pt. II, ch. ii; Dewey and Tufts, op. cit., ch. xxvi; F. G. Peabody, The Chris- tian Life in the Modern World, ch. i; W. F. Lofthouse, Ethics and the Family; Hastings, Encyc. of Relig., s.v. “Family (Biblical and Christian).” 2St. Bernard, Ep. cxi, ‘‘There is only one circumstance in which it would be wrong to obey parents, and that is when God forbids it.” Cf. St. Matt. x. 37. Obedience only ceases to be obligatory when children attain their majority; and then arises the duty of supporting parents if needful. Parental authority during minority is supreme if rightly exercised. When abused the State may interfere; but the Church may not do s0, e.g., if parents refuse to permit their children to receive one of the sacraments. Parental responsibilities towards. illegitimate children are the same as towards legitimate offspring. 114 MORAL THEOLOGY PROPER: LAW by a love which is neither backboneless amiability nor careless disregard of the rights of the young. Related to family obligations are those between teacher and pupil at school, and these relations are determined by parental consent and by the necessi- ties of real education. Within their recognized limits they involve parallel duties of authority and of obe- dience. (b) In the Church* the relationship which deter- mines duty is that between mother and mistress of souls and individual children of God. It isa relation, however, which is limited, on the one hand, by the authority of parents over minors, and on the other hand, by the authority of the State over temporals. In brief, it is a spiritual relation based upon the per- suasion of free agents and to be enforced only by spiritual penalties. Its branches are usually formu- lated in what are called the precepts of the Church. These precepts are either ecumenical or provincial. The word ‘‘precept”’ is here applied to every form of obligation known to be imposed by the Church, whether by canon, by liturgical, rubrical, or sacra- mental prescription, or by recognized custom. These precepts may not be dispensed by mere private caprice, and judicial decisions and decrees have authority in their interpretation. An individual Christian is bound both by ecumenical precepts and by those of his own portion of the Church. 1T. B. Strong, op. cit., Lec. viii; V. Staley, op. cit., Pt. I, chh. x-xi; A. Alexander, op. cit., pp. 236-244; N. K. Davis, of. cit., Pt. II, ch. v. SUPERIMPOSED MORAL LAW 115 The ecumenical precepts are reduced by moral writers to five or six heads, of which the following is a general summary:! (1) To observe the canon law and ecclesiastical judgments wherever applicable; (2) To take habitual part in the public services of the Church in the manner ecclesiastically and provin- cially prescribed, and to avoid schismatical worship; (3) To observe the holy days appointed, whether fes- tivals or fasts, in the manner directed;? (4) To give habitually and in proportion to our means for the support of the Church and her interests, whether parochial, diocesan, institutional, or missionary.? (5) To receive the sacraments in their appointed order and manner, and to promote their reception by others. (6) To repent habitually of sin, using the sacrament of Penance when ecclesiastical rules require, and at least as often as needed for rightly quieting the conscience. Underlying all these is the obligation of faith, of belief in the doctrines of the Trinity and the Incarnation, and in all the other chief articles of the Christian Faith as set forth by the Church. 1Bp. Cosin, Works, vol. II, p. 121; vol. V, p. 523; Bp. Webb, op. cit., pp. 194-202; J. P. Gury, op. cit., §§ 473-516; T. Slater, op. cit., vol. I, pp. 564-581. 2 Fasting, we may note, has the psychological value of aiding dis- cipline, keeping under the body and bringing it into subjection, and the moral value of aiding penitence. 31 Cor. ix. 13-14. 4St. John vi. 53-58 establishes the general obligation of commun- ion, the details of its application being left to the regulation of the Church. 116 MORAL THEOLOGY PROPER: LAW (c) The authority of the State! pertains to the reg- ulation of those temporal concerns which require public control. Within that sphere and under the limitations of human constitution and law, the officers of the state are entitled to obedience; being themselves under obligation to avoid either tyranny, laxity or partiality. Men also owe loyalty to the State as an institution, and the virtue of patriotism is a Christian virtue.” Somewhat related to this sphere of authority is that of employer or master, over employee and ser- vant.? Like civil constitutions, these relations are subject to alteration and reformation; but existing laws and customs determine for the time being the 1A, Alexander, op. cit., pp. 229-236; N. K. Davis, op. cit., Pt. II, ch. ili-iv; Wm. McDougall, An Introd. to Social Psychology, passim. 2Rom. xili. 1-7. We treat of civil obligations in ch. vi, §§ 4-5, below. LEncyc. Letter of Pope Leo XIII, Jan. 10, 1890, “Law is of its very essence a mandate of right reason, proclaimed by a prop- erly constituted authority, for the common good. But true and legitimate authority is void of sanction, unless it proceeds from God, the supreme Ruler and Lord of all.” Some recent writers, e.g., Durkheim, Royce and Ames, have found the basis of all religion in social obligation. 8 Of employees is required a faithful discharge of their appointed duties and a proper care for the interests of their employers. Morally they are bound to make restitution if they waste time or cause damage by their neglect. Of employers a fair wage, considerate treatment and good working conditions are required. Obviously the moral standard is higher than the legal. In the present confusion of social conditions Moral Theology must deal with broad and unquestionable principles, rather than enter into details concerning which practical sociology is still uncertain or perplexed. Reason is to be used and an undue intrusion of partisan emotion is to be guarded against. SUPERIMPOSED MORAL LAW 117 nature of the obligations involved. The reason is, that to disregard existing institutions which have the sanction, whether formal or informal, of the com- munity, is to introduce disorder and to cause greater wrongs than the particular disobedient course can remedy. The right of revolution lies, not with private individuals, but with society as a whole. § 12. The second table has reference to the manner in which love should control conduct towards our neighbours. Interpreted from the Christian stand- point, the love with which this table is concerned is determined primarily in form and reference by the prospective congenialities of a heavenly communion of saints, these congenialities being perceived to be already potential in our neighbours because of redemption and grace. ‘The fruition of love requires personal friendship and contact, but to snatch at this, here and now, is often to violate love and to sin most grievously. ‘The sum of the matter is that the second table requires such lines of conduct as will promote and ultimately secure the future fellowship which constitutes the joy of eternal life. Therefore no works of charity are really Christian unless they are religious in standpoint and quality; for although Christian love presupposes and exercises natural affection, the standpoint or aim is supernatural, and is determined in its reference and intended effect by consciousness of a supernatural destiny—one in which the highest welfare of all men alike is involved. The Sixth Commandment requires display of love 118 MORAL THEOLOGY PROPER: LAW with reference to our neighbour’s person, in the popu- lar and physical sense of that term. Murder is the most conspicuous.form of its violation, and murder is to be defined as malicous or unlawful killing. But the principle involved obviously applies to all forms of physical injury, and to the malice which affords motives for such conduct. Suicide is self-murder.! Among the special forms of sin which come under this commandment are duelling, unlawful warfare, abortion,? bullying, hazing and every form of inhuman- ity, as well as anything which causes danger to the persons of others, e.g., reckless automobile driving, which the English law treats as manslaughter. Capital punishment is not forbidden by this com- 1 See E. Westermarck, op. cit., ch.xxxv. For pagan views, W. E. H. Lecky, op. cit., vol. I, pp. 212-222; Virgil, Aeneid, vi, 434, mildly censures suicide. For the related modern problem of Euthanasia, see F. G. Belton, Present Day Problems, ch. xi. An interesting prob- lem in casuistry is afforded in W. R. Thayer’s Theodore Roosevelt, p. 393. In the Brazilian forest Mr. Roosevelt, sick and injured so that his condition retards the progress of the rest of the party towards safety, determines to shoot himself if his condition does not speedily improve. Sir Thomas Browne in his Religio Medici has an expression worth noting. ‘When life is more terrible than death it is the truer courage to dare to live.” One is not, however, bound to use extreme and difficult measures for the preservation of one’s life, as resort to a surgical operation when the outcome is uncertain, or to remove to a distant climate; but he is bound to use available and ordinary precautions for the preservation of life and health. A physician, or any one in care of the sick, may not omit anything that would prolong life, in order that the period of suffering may be shortened. 2 See E. Westermarck, of. cit., ch. xxi; Cath. Encyc., s.v. “Duel.” 3T. Slater, op. cit., vol. I, pp. 312-315; Cath. Encyc., g.v.3 C. Coppens, Moral Principles and Medical Practice. SUPERIMPOSED MORAL LAW 119 mandment; Holy Scripture allows it,! and the Church has never legislated against it. It belongs to the State by natural reason, for the State must have liberty to act so as to secure and preserve its well-being and safety.2 The right of inflicting such punishment belongs to the properly constituted authority and cannot be exercised by any private individual or unofficial group of individuals. Therefore lynching is a violation of this commandment. “ Justifiable” homicide, likewise, is not forbidden. It may be defined as the killing of an assailant in order to protect one’s own life, limb, chastity, or property, including that of another; but it is not justifiable when less extreme measures will secure the end, nor is it war- ranted for insult or contumely. Lawful warfare is not forbidden, the legality of any particular war being dependent upon its being undertaken by the state to which obedience is due? §13. The Seventh Commandment requires us to have regard for the holiness of our neighbour’s body,in 1 Rom. xiii. 4, 2E. Westermarck, of. cit., vol. I, pp. 490-496. 3G. L. Richardson, Conscience, Its Origin and Authority, ch. xix; and the various works on the Thirty-nine Articles under Art. xxxvl. E£.g., E. J. Bicknell, Theol. Introd. to the Thirty-nine Articles, pp. 548-540, “As civilization advances the use of force is abated. Con- duct becomes moralized. Higher motives for obedience tend to supplant the lower. But at the bottom there must always be the appeal to force to put down disorder. . . . War is simply the result of human sin and self-seeking. It is a symptom of the depravity of the human heart. Christianity sets itself not to abolish the symptom only but to root out the cause of the evil.” 120 MORAL THEOLOGY PROPER: LAW the older sense of its consecration to God. It implies the obligation of preserving the same holiness of our own bodies.! The text of the commandment names a most obvi- ous external violation of its principle, but there are at least five principal lines of external sin involved: (a) with the married, adultery; (6) with the unmar- ried, fornication;? of these two the most aggravated form being incest in which relationship either of blood or of marriage is involved; (c) Intemperate d unnatural use of marital privileges; (d) Unnat- aral sexual actions between members of the same sex,* or between human beings and the lower animals; (e) Sins against one’s own body.5 The principle of the commandment covers purity of thought and speech, as well as of physical action, and every sphere of conduct which is connected with the preservation of purity. The following lines of conduct are therefore sinful, although in varying degrees: (a) immodest dress, including any form of dress which because of its violation of convention obtrudes immoral suggestion; (0) any departure in 1W. W. Webb, o?. cit., pp. 169-176. A full treatment of the whole subject will be found in St. Thomas, IJ, II, cliii ff.; A. Vermeersch, De Castitate. See also Koch-Preuss, of. cit., vol. II, pp. 73-77; T. Slater, op. cit., vol. I, pp. 324-339. 2 Ephes. v. 5. 3St. Aug., de Bono Mair. 8, expresses in strongest terms the evil of incest, ‘Adultery will be good because incest is worse.” ‘See Koch-Preuss, of. ci#., vol. II, p. 88; E. Westermarck, of. cit., ch. xliii. 5 z Cor. vi. 9-10, 15-20; cf. Gal. v. ro. SUPERIMPOSED MORAL LAW 12 conduct from social conventions that involves such suggestion; (c) undue intimacies, whether between the sexes or between those of the same sex; (d) loose conversation, especially scandalous gossip, suggestive witticisms and dubious stories; (e) giving rein to the imagination in relation to sexual indul- gence;! listening to foul conversation and looking at pictures which are either obscene or suggestive; (g) reading trashy stories, or attending plays which exploit sexual problems and affect realism in the alleged interest of more perfect information concern- ing human life; (%) high living, that is, a life of habit- ual self-indulgence in the comforts and luxuries which wealth and modern invention place at our disposal; (i) taking part in, or sanctioning in any way, dances which are suggestive or tend to give rise to impure thoughts and desires; (7) slothful physical habits; (k) unnecessary meddling with one’s own body; (/) marriage contrary to the law of God.” There are four lines, among others, along which antecedent protection against the sins of which we have spoken is to be sought: (a) preoccupation, both of body and of mind; (6) cultivation of a wholesome atmosphere, both in relation to compan- ionship and to reading and thought;? (c) the main- 1 This includes the custody of the eyes; St. Matt. v. 28. “For it is all one with what part of the body we commit adultery, and if a man lets his eye loose and enjoys the lust of that, he is an adul- terer;” Jeremy Taylor, Holy Living. 2 Cf. ch. v. § 7, below. 3 Philip. iv. 8. 122 MORAL THEOLOGY PROPER: LAW tenance of good health and the avoidance of nervous exhaustion; (d) in some instances marriage! The one immediate way of resisting temptation when it comes is flight.2 This may be either interior, by change of attention, or exterior, by physical removal. The effectiveness of this flight will depend upon imme- diate resort to prayer. If one undertakes to reason with this kind of temptation he is almost certain to yield to it, because the temptation does not per- tain to reason but appeals to the imagination, and to argue is to keep the imagination fixed upon the subject. Diversion*of mind is what is needed. §14. The Eighth Commandmeni inculcates love in reference to care of our neighbour’s possessions.2 It forbids three principal things: (@) unjust appropria- tion of another’s goods, e.g., by secret theft, open robbery, fraud, or embezzling; * (0) failure to give to each his dues, e.g., defaulting in matters of debt, legal injustice, personal extravagance to the injury of dependents and the poor, delaying the payment of debts, mutual injustice between capital and labour, 1 As indicated by St. Paul in 1 Cor. vii. 9. 2St. Aug. Serm. 350, “If you want to win a victory against the temptation of lust, flee.” 3°W. W. Webb, op. cit., pp. 177-187; J. P. Gury, op. cit., § 436, ‘‘prohibet omnem injustitiam externam in bonis fortuna proximi. ... Decimum vero peccata etiam interna seu concupiscentiae, i.e., desiderii bonorum proximi et actiones injuste vetat.”’ 4J. P. Gury, op. cit., §§ 605-625, treats of the species of theft: (a) furtum; (6) rapina (with violence); (c) fraus et dolus; (d) sac- rilegium; (e) peculatus. For the causes excusing from theft, see §§ 615-625; and on restitution, §§ 626 ff. SUPERIMPOSED MORAL LAW 123 and violation of contracts; (c) all private practices and habits which create a personal disposition unfav- ourable to keeping this commandment.! This last- mentioned head includes: (a) undue wealth, which stimulates avarice and disregards the interests of employees and smaller capitalists; (6) substitution of the maintenance of rights for the Christian ideal of doing justice to others; (c) extravagant habits, which preclude just administration of wealth, whether this wealth is one’s own or is administered in behalf of another; (d) living beyond one’s means, which induces temptation to secure greater means by illegitimate methods; (e) waste and needless destruction of what might be useful to others; (/) overcharging for services, commodities, etc., that is, profiteering; (g) all forms of failure of employees adequately to render the services for which they are paid. In offences of this sort the mark of genuine repent- ance is effort, whenever possible, to make sufficient reparation. So far as is possible restitution must be made for whatever damage has been caused. The same applies to one who either assists in or sinfully 1T, Slater, op. cit., vol. I, p. 339, ‘‘Directly and explicitly it for- bids theft, but implicitly it commands us to observe justice in our dealings with others;” 7.¢., to give to every one his due or right. Moral theologians in speaking of one’s right to do as he will with his own, e.g., to throw away his money, disregard the important principle of stewardship, which is a corrective of the plea, “‘Shall I not do what I will with mine own?” 2T. Slater, op. cil., vol. I, pp. 398-453, gives a fuller treatment. See St. Thomas, I, II, xii. 124 MORAL THEOLOGY PROPER: LAW benefits by an act of injustice. The offender is released either if the offended does not wish restitu- tion, or if there is either physical or other legitimate incapacity to make it; but this release ceases when the incapacity ceases, even though there be no legal obligation, as, e.g., in bankruptcy cases.! Questions of title to property, etc., are legal rather than moral. Presumably the pertinent civil laws are in harmony with sound morality; and, inas- much as these laws are complex and differ in various states, it is not to be supposed that any one except a legal specialist can make expert determinations con- cerning them. §15. The Ninth Commandment requires love in relation to our neighbour’s name and mind. The common forms of its violation are evil speaking, lying, and slandering. In the sphere of thought we may include rash judgments, which arise from malice and violate Christian charity.2 Reporting evil of another, except when required by duty, is always sinful. Its most frequent form is ill-natured gossip. A lie? 17T, Slater, op. cit., vol. I, pp. 438-451, gives authorities pro and con and concludes to the contrary. 2St. Matt. vii. 1-3; Rom.ii.1. On this commandment, see W. W. Webb, oP. cit., pp. 187-192; T. Slater, op. cit., vol. I, pp. 456-473. $ Col. ili. 9; Eph. iv. 25. Durant Drake, Problems of Conduct, ch. xix, Truthfulness and its Problems. St. Augustine says it is never under any circumstances permitted to falsify. This is not universally accepted; but Roman casuists and Jeremy Taylor allow too many exceptions to the general principle, e.g., in the form of men- tal reservations. gsA lie may be told by either gestures, other signs, _ tone of voice, or silence, as well as by word of mouth. St. Augustine, SUPERIMPOSED MORAL LAW 125 means an unjust falsehood, but falsehood is so rarely just that in normal practice the qualification should be left out. Yet there are cases in which duty requires falsehood, e.g., to the insane in dangerous emergencies. The burden of proof always lies on him who would falsify, and it is almost always the case that the ele- -ment of doubt is practically absent. The reason why truth-telling must be observed, even when its neces- sity is not apparent, is that the general welfare of mankind, as well as the virtue of the individual speak- ers, depends upon the ability of one man to trust another. . cit., chh. iv-vi. 222 THE SACRAMENT OF PENANCE to forgive you?” “‘Do you forgive all those who have in any way injured you?” The priest will proceed to give instruction concerning absolution, not neces- sarily using the word, however, but speaking of it as God’s assurance, ministering consolation to our doubts. He will then give absolution, conditional or absolute, if there is reason to hope that the man feels any penitence. With the unconscious this may be taken for granted. All can be done in a surprisingly short time, a time not exceeding that to which a priest should be expected to confine himself in visiting the sick; and it will be found in many cases most efh- cacious in opening the eyes of the soul to the presence of sin and in leading to sincere repentance. CHAPTER IX SIN § x. The Old and New Testaments use a number of terms to describe sin in its various phases.! It was necessarily dealt with from the beginning in the pa- tristic age, and its nature was brought out with increasing clarity as the Church gained practical experience in dealing with its manifold forms. Much of the theoretical treatment of the subject belongs properly to Dogmatic Theology,? and we need not concern ourselves at length with general definitions or distinctions. Perhaps as good a definition as any is that of St. Augustine: ‘‘Anything done or said or desired contrary to the eternal law.’’? It is there- 1Space is lacking here for detailed treatment; but the Hebrew and Greek terms and their proper meanings can be ascertained in the lexicons, especially Brown-Driver-Briggs, Hebrew-English Lexicon of the Old Testament, and J. H. Thayer, Greek-English Lexicon of the New Testament. See also A. B. Davidson, Theol. of the O. T., ch. vii; E. R. Bernard in Hastings, Dic. of the Bib., g.v.; 5S. A. B. Mercer, in Anglican Theol. Review, vol. II, No. 3, pp. 234-236. 2¥F. J. Hall, Creation and Man, pp. 270 ff.; H. P. Liddon, Some Elem. of Religion, Lec. iv; H. V. S. Eck, Sin; T. B. Strong, Christ. Ethics, Lec. v; Wilhelm and Scannell, Manual of Cath. Theol., Bk. IV, ch. 1. 3In c. Faust, xxii, 27. “The will of admitting or retaining that 228 224 SIN fore unnatural; that is, when nature is considered from the standpoint of its Creator! It is a dis- turbance of right order, and order has been described as heaven’s first law. § 2. Sin has certain characteristics, the considera- tion of which will help us to deal with it from the moral side that properly concerns us here: (a) It does not inhere in the nature of things, nor proceed from the divine essence or from some other independent principle; but owes its existence entirely to free will. “By the will a man sins or lives a good life.” 2 This is the distinctively Christian teaching in contrast to that of Aristotle, who placed sin in a defect of the understanding. It is not, in scholastic terms, a sub- stance, but an accident. It is a privation or corrup- tion of good. (6) God is not the Author of sin# which righteousness forbids, and from which one is free to abstain,” tbid., c. Jul., i, 47. St. Ambrose, de Parad., cap. viii, 39, ‘What is sin but the transgressing of the divine law and disobedience to the heavenly precepts?” St. Thomas, I, lxxi, 6. T. Slater, op. cit., vol. I, p. 133, ‘A sin is nothing but a bad human act, and it may be defined as a free transgression of the law of God,” “act” here in- cludes thought and word, of course. Koch-Preuss, op. cit., vol. II, pp. 3-11; J. P. Gury, op. cit., §§ 143-184. The Westminster Shorter Catechism, ‘Sin is any want of conformity unto, or transgression of, the law of God.” 1St. Aug., c. Ep. Manich. Fund., xxxv, 39, ‘Sin is not nature, but against nature.” 2 Tbid., Retract, I, ix, 4. St. Thomas, I, II, Ixxvii, 6, “‘Sin consists essentially in an act of free choice, which is a function of the will and of reason.” Jbid., II, II, lxxx, 1, “‘A man’s will alone is directly the cause of his sin.” 8 Tbid., I, xix, 9, “God in no wise wills the evil of sin, which is the CHARACTERISTICS AND ORIGIN 225 The doctrine of the “divine concursus’’ does not make God the Author of evil, but the accomplice, if we may so speak, of the will’s freedom, for without Him nothing can be done; but the will, by virtue of its freedom, has the power of doing good or ill, and is the determining cause.! (c) Because sin proceeds from opposition of the human will to the will of God, who is the supreme Lawgiver and the benevolent Father of all, it is an act of disobedience and ingratitude. It diverts man also from his own true end. It derives its motives from an inordinate self-love. As to its origin, according to Scripture, (a) the first sin, that of Lucifer and his angels, was purely spiritual. Man’s sin differs in that it is not purely spiritual but partly carnal, and therefore, not the result of malice alone but of malice and infirmity combined. Also in human sin the effect of original sin is to be allowed for, because even after its removal the wound of privation of right order towards the divine good. The evil of natural defect, or of punishment, He does will, by willing the good to which such evils are attached.” Jdid., I, xlix, 2, ‘‘God is the Author of the evil which is penalty, but not of the evil which is fault.” 1 Jbid, I, II, xxix, 2, “God is the cause of the act of sin, yet He is not the cause of sin (as such), because He does not cause the act to havea defect.” Koch-Preuss, op. cit., vol. II, p. 8, ‘‘God’s contribu- tion toa sinful act isin itself good. He merely enables man to employ the faculties which He has given him for a good purpose. It is man who renders the act evil by having a wrong intention.” Jbid., p. 9, ‘Besides, God often employs sin as a means of punishing the sinner and thus indirectly causes good to spring from evil.” In brief, although God operates in man’s sinning, His end is holy and this ultimately triumphs, overruling the evil. Cf. F. J. Hall, Creation and Man, p. 74; B. Boedder, Natural Theol., pp. 355-370. 226 SIN concupiscence remains. Man, as distinguished from the angels, can consequently be redeemed from sin. (6) To understand the origin of sin aright, and to avoid the modern tendency to make little of it, we must remember that whether we take the Eden narrative historically or symbolically, the Holy Spirit teaches us thereby that sin grew out of ingratitude and con- tempt towards special privileges and gifts. All light views of sin are impossible when we recollect that Christ became Man and died because of it. Its heinousness to-day is aggravated by the fact that it is committed by those whose minds are enlightened by revelation, whose wills are strengthened by grace, and whose emotions are stirred by the love of the Atonement. § 3. The distinction between mortal and venial sin is very important both for priests and for peni- tents, not less so because requiring judgment in appli- cation. It helps priests in dealing with penitents to avoid the opposite errors of rigorism, which treats every sin as fatal, and of laxism, which underesti- mates the gravity of certain sins and treats venial sin as practically negligible. It also helps penitents to avoid these errors in estimating the results of self- examination and in making confessions which are at once sufficiently full and discriminating Mortal sins are those which because of their gravity in matter and formal guilt are fatal to the life of grace. Venial sins are less grave, proceeding largely from weakness rather than from deliberate wilfulness, and not imme- MORTAL AND VENIAL 227 diately fatal in their results. The unequal gravity and effect of various sins is everywhere taken for granted in Scripture; 1 and St. John tells us expressly that ‘‘there is a sin unto death . . . All unrighteous- ness is sin: and there is a sin not unto death.” ? The ancient exomologesis presupposed this distinc- tion, and emphasized the peculiar gravity of certain sins;* and as the Church’s experience widened, the difference between mortal and venial sin was clarified and technicalized.+ The practical rules for applying this distinction are easy to be understood, whatever may be the uncer- tainties that in cases attend their use. The compara- tive gravity of sins depends upon their matter and upon the degree of deliberate wilfulness with which they are committed. If the matter is grave, that is, if the act itself is highly subversive of the divine will, the sin is presumably mortal; and it certainly is so when committed with consciousness of its gravity and with deliberate wilfulness. On the other hand, if the matter is comparatively light, like a momentary loss of patience, the sin is presumably venial; as is also the case when there is no deliberate wilfulness in 1Cf. especially St. Matt. v. 22; xil. 31-32; xxiii. 23-24. 21 St. John v. 16-17. 3See O. D. Watkins, op. cit., passim; F. H. Hallock in Anglican Theol. Review, Oct., 1921. 4QOn the distinction, see pp. 11-13, above; F. J. Hall, The Sacra- ments, pp. 239-240; K. E. Kirk, op. cit., ch. xi; T. B. Strong, op. cit., pp. 228-231; W. W. Williams, of. cit., pp. 178-183; J. G. H. Barry, Holy Eucharist, pp. 48-58; St. Thomas, I, II, lxii, 5, Ixxxvili-Ixxxix. 228 SIN its commission. Clear as these rules appear to be, in practice both the gravity of matter and the delib- erate wilfulness are matters of judgment, in many instances of uncertain judgment. To forget this is to make the distinction between mortal and venial sin a source of danger instead of help to priest and pen- itent. In doubt, the penitent will most safely sus- pect himself of mortal rather than of venial sin; but, in dealing with penitents, the priest errs most safely for them on the side of merciful judgment, that is, of course, when the sinner appears in practical effect to repent truly of all his sins. In judging whether a sin is mortal or venial, the following considerations are helpful: (a) Even when the matter is light, if the sinner thinks it to be grave and under such impression commits it with formal wilfulness, he sins mortally. In fact, any sinful act, regardless of the sinner’s estimate of its material gravity, is mortal when committed with gravely sinful intention and deliberation. (6) When a particular species of venial sin becomes habitual and is wilfully cherished, it becomes mortal, especially when per- ceived to nullify one’s purpose of conforming to the will of God. (¢) A sin which is ordinarily mortal because of the gravity of its matter may be judged to be venial when the sinner is either blamelessly ignorant of its gravity, or does not act deliberately and intentionally in committing it. Marriages per- mitted by civil law but forbidden by the law of God,! 1 Marriages contrary to the law of God introduce a continuing TEMPTATIONS AND OCCASIONS 229 and killings either in self-defence or by accident, supply examples. Absence of certainty in determining whether given sins are mortal or venial will not bring disaster, if priest and penitent observe: (a) that all sins, even venial ones, are really sinful and need to be repented of; (6) that, if all sins known or thought to be mortal and all besetting faults, so far as they can be recalled, are contritely confessed, along with sincere expression of contrition for sins not remembered, God will not refuse mercy, and His priest may not in final issue refuse sacramental absolution. § 4. As we have seen, the will is the cause of sin; for its functioning is the determinative factor in converting moral motives into action. The fact that evil impulses are thus actualized by the will consti- tutes actual sin, and sin is wilfulness. But the motives—feelings and considerations—by which the will is influenced in sinning, while partly due to inward habitual dispositions and native concupiscence, are also called forth by external factors. Of these are temptations and occasions. Temptation to sin means putting the will to moral proof, testing it, by affording opportunities and in- ducements to sin.! In this its proper sense to be state which is materially sinful in grave degree. The question of their treatment by a priest is elsewhere considered. The possibility of converting a sin of ignorance into formal rejection of God’s law, and the interest of the children, have to be taken into account. The priest may be justified in certain cases in not taking official cogni- zance, if no public scandal is involved. 1Qn temptation, F. J. Hall, Incarnation, pp. 250-259; Hastings, 230 SIN tempted involves no sin whatever until we yield and will the evil act°or non-action which is suggested. The appeal is to natural cravings and propensities which are lawful in themselves, but which cannot be gratified or obeyed in the specific manner suggested without sin. The fierceness and pain-producing power of temptation are felt in degrees proportioned to the will’s resistance. That is, one who remains sinless alone experiences to the full the brunt and agony of temptation; and Christ alone has fully entered into the personal cost of overcoming tempta- tion.! (a) We are placed in this world on probation, and inasmuch as without temptation no real probation and establishment of interior virtue is possible, the natural conditions of our lives afford opportunities and inducements to sin, and divine providence brings them to bear on us in manners wisely adapted to our testing and to a fair chance to advance by rightly meeting the test. In this sense alone we are tempted of God? (b) Because of that native lack of the supernatural grace originally given to our first parents and conse- quent insufficiency of our moral powers which we call original sin, temptations come from within as well as from without, and we are apt to yield to them. Dic. of Christ, Blunt’s Dic. of Theol., and Cath Encyc., q.vv.; Hastings, Dic. of Bible, s.v. “Tempt, Temptation”; J. B. Mayor, Ep. of Si. James, on i. I-15. 1F, J. Hall, as cited, and refs. there given. 3 Cf. St. James i. 12-18. TEMPTATIONS AND OCCASIONS 231 We cannot invariably avoid actual sin, although in no single instance are we literally obliged to sin, unless previous habits of sin have deprived us of all power to resist. This native tendency is called concupiscence; and is symbolically described as sin, not as really so, but as springing from primitive sin and predisposing us to acts of sin of our own! By divine mercy we have been redeemed; and the grace of baptismal regeneration, while it does not at once eradicate concupiscence and put sinlessness within our power of immediate attainment, imparts the potential principle of progress through life-long disci- pline towards final and complete victory.” (c) Men are social by nature and their develop- ment is conditioned by social relations, and by the influence of other persons than themselves. We are also surrounded by personal spirits or angels, and are subject to their influence, under limitations of divine appointment; and among these are evil spirits 3— the devil and his angels. So it is that we are often tempted from without by evil men and angels, who wilfully offer us suggestions and inducements to sin. These sources of temptation are summarized in the phrase “the world and the devil.” To social beings in a world not wholly made up of perfect persons the liability to external personal influence for evil is inevitable—a necessary incident in the probation of a 1¥F, J. Hall, Creation and Man, pp. 277-279 and ch. ix. 2 Idem, The Sacraments, pp. 15 ff. 3 Idem, Creation and Man, ch. v. 232 SIN race. But even so, we are not in any given instance tempted beyond power of resistance, unless our own previous fault has made us helpless. We may be com- pelled to perform actions materially sinful, but no one can compel us to will sinfully, that is, to become per- sonally guilty of sin.! Moreover, the power to resist all forms of temptation, to outgrow concu- piscence, is assured to us by sacramental grace when codperated with in a life of progressive self-discipline and imitation of Christ. An occasion is an external circumstance which is apt to afford temptation.2 It does not always bring temptation, for there are many such occasions the tempting factors of which do not secure our atten- tion; but when attended to they tempt by suggest- ing evil thoughts and inciting concupiscence. Like temptations, occasions are indispensable tests of vir- tue. For example, our honesty incurs no actual test, when there is no occasion to steal2 Foreseen occa- sions of sin are to be avoided whenever this is possible without evasion of duty. Various distinctions in regard to occasions have been made: (a) a proximate occasion is one which leads a person to sin more often than not; (6) a remote occasion leads to the commission of sin only occa- sionally. A proximate occasion is either absolute, in that it constitutes a danger for all in all circum- 1_ Cor. x. 13. 2T. Slater, op. c#t., vol. II, pp. 220 ff. + Eccles, xxxi..r0; 5. (Cor. v.20; TEMPTATIONS AND OCCASIONS 233 stances; or relative, when the danger involved de- pends upon individual character or disposition. An occasion of this sort which offers temptation to one may offer none at all to another. Occasions are also distinguished as either (a) voluntary, if wilfully sought after when the danger has been discovered; or (6) necessary, if they can be avoided only with great difficulty or not at all. In the latter case, they are called physically necessary. An occasion morally necessary Is one which cannot be avoided without great injury or inconvenience, because there is in- volved a conflict of duties, perhaps an evasion of responsibilities in one’s providential vocation. Occasions are never to be sought, for such seeking is foolhardy.! To avoid all remote occasions, how- ever, Is impossible;? but we are morally bound to avoid all proximate and voluntary occasions? To expose oneself wittingly and without necessity to an occasion which is apt to lead to mortal sin is itself a grave sin, being in effect an acquiescence of the will in mortal sin. And so long as one wilfully remains thus exposed, although able to escape, he ought not to. receive priestly absolution. In a morally necessary proximate occasion one is bound to do all in his power by fervent prayer, frequent and devout reception of the sacraments, renewal of intention, avoiding perilous 1 Ecclus. iii. 27. 21 Cor. v. 9-10; St. John xvii. 15. 3 Prov. vi. 27-28; xviii. 6-10; St. Matt. v. 29-30; St. Mark ix. 41-46. 234 SIN company and other methods to convert the proxi- mate into a remote occasion. The dangers of a physically necessary occasion ought to be met by the use of extreme caution and all other available means. : § 5. Sins are classified in numerous ways, and knowledge of the distinctions involved is helpful in dealing with penitents. Several of them have been indicated, but a SpE survey seems desirable at this point.! The first series of distinctions have to do with estimating the several degrees of guilt: (a) Material sin means any objective violation of God’s will, any action or non-action which as such is sinful; but is very commonly restricted to sins which are committed ignorantly or without sinful intention. Formal sin is one committed knowingly and wilfully, and there- fore culpably. (6) Venial sin is concerned with a comparatively light matter, and represents momen- tary weakness or impulsiveness. Mortal sin is con- cerned with a grave matter, and is committed wit- tingly and with deliberation. It benumbs the soul and, unless remedied by adequate repentance, is fatal to the life of grace.2 (c) Sins of ignorance, that is, vincible and culpable ignorance; sins of infirmity, due to passion and unconquered evil habits; 1 Qn these distinctions at large, W. W. Williams, op. cit., ch. vi; W. W. Webb, of. cit., ch. iii; St. Thomas, I, II, lxxii-lxxiii; A. Lehm- kuhl, Theol. Moralis, vol. I, §§ 220 ff. 2 Considered in § 3, above, where refs. are given. CLASSIFICATION 235 and sins of malice committed with deliberate fore- thought; constitute a rising series in the degrees of guilt. (d) Sins that cry aloud for vengeance; and the sin against the Holy Ghost, which is obstinately impenitent defiance of light, are singled out in Scrip- ture as especially grave—the latter not subject to forgiveness.? (e) Actual sins, are distinguished from habitual, the latter consisting of such as are cherished and persisted in without repentance, therefore espe- cially grave. A second series has to do with species of sin con- sidered in the manner of their committal, or their subjective factor. (a) Of commission, in violation of prohibitive law; and of omission, failing to fulfil some positive requirement. The former are usually more grave, but the latter are apt to become dangerous through neglect of repentance. (6) Sins are spiritual or carnal according as they proceed from, or are com- mitted in, the higher or lower part of our nature. The latter are most scandalous, but the former, especially pride, are the deepest and most difficult to remedy, and therefore are often the most serious.® 1 J. J. Elmendorf, op. cit., pp. 92-106; K. E. Kirk, of. cit., p. 224; T. Slater, of. cit., vol. I, pp. 30-34. 2St. Matt. xii. 31 and parallels. Cf. Heb. x. 26-31; 1 St. John v. 16-17 (perhaps not pertinent). See §§ 7-8 below. 3 St. Thomas, I, II, lxxiii, 5, ‘Spiritual sins are of greater guilt than carnal sins: yet this does not mean that each spiritual sin is of greater guilt than each carnal sin; but that, considering the sole difference between spiritual and carnal, spiritual sins are more griev- ous than carnal sins, other things being equal.” 236 SIN (c) Sins of thought, of word and of deed are distin- guishable without the aid of definition. All sins begin in thought, of course, but their classification depends upon whether they are manifested in words or deeds. Thought becomes sin when it amounts to evil consent of the will, as in impure imagination wilfully pursued, and in pride and hatred. A third series of distinctions is determined by external standards of right and wrong and by the parties other than ourselves who are offended. (a) In the category of law, sins may be against the Jaw of natural reason or against the commands and prohibi- tions of positive law. (6) They may be against the revealed law of God or against human law, whether ecclesiastical or civil. (c) Sins against God’s law are chiefly against the Decalogue, and are then classified according to its several commandments.! (d) With reference to the parties involved, sins are aimed either against God, against our neighbours, or against self. In ultimate analysis, however, all sins are against God. § 6. The capital sins are so called as constituting heads or categories under which all forms of sin can be classified. They are comprehensive categories because they are determined by the instincts in us which make up the possible roots of sinful action; and the list, which is ancient, is found to be substan- tially in accord with modern psychological investi- tigation. They are sometimes called “deadly sins”; 1 Treated in ch. iv, Pt. III, above. THE SEVEN CAPITAL SINS 237 but this is quite misleading, for each of them may be either venial or mortal according to its comparative degree of malice and gravity of matter. They are seven in number: pride, covetousness, lust, envy, gluttony, anger and sloth.’ Of these, lust and glut- tony are carnal; pride, covetousness, envy and anger are spiritual; and sloth may be either spiritual or carnal, Pride is inordinate self-esteem, with desire to induce others to accept one’s exalted opinion of self. Under this head are to be included: (a) vanity, which may be shown either in undue care for one’s personal appearance, attainments, talents and repute or in the contemptuous neglect of the same; (6) ambition, that is, inordinate as distinguished from that which is fitting; (c) arrogance, including bragging and boast- fulness; (d) hypocrisy or the feigning of virtues or qualities which one does not possess. ‘The danger of pride lies in its turning one’s thoughts from God, as the source of all we have and are, and in making one feel self-sufficient and independent, thus making repentance unlikely. It is the sin of the Pharisee. 1 Thus enumerated in St. Gregory I, Moralia, xxxi, 45. On capital sins, see St. Thomas, I, IT, lxxxiv, 3-4; T. B. Strong, op. cit., pp. 2597 266; K. E. Kirk, op. cit., pp. 264-270; W. W. Webb, od. cit., ch. ili, C.; H. V. S. Eck, Sin, Pt. II, ch. vi; T. Slater, op. cit., vol. I, pp. 154-164. For treatments of them severally, see in each case Cath. Encyc., Hastings’ Encyc. of Relig., and Dic. of Bible, q.vv., where further refs. are given. 2St. Matt. vi. 1-6; vii. 1-5; St. Luke xviii. 9-14; 1 Cor. x. 123 Phil. ii. 3-8. St. Thomas, I, I, clxii. 238 SIN It begets contempt of others and kills charity. The opposed virtue is humility, a fundamental Christian virtue! It is the mean between pride and the opposed evil of pusillanimity or mean-spiritedness, which keeps a man from occupying the place for which God created him. Humility keeps him in his place both with reference to God and to his fellowmen. Covetousness or avarice is an inordinate longing for earthly goods, with an immoderate desire to possess, keep and increase them. It leads to the service of Mammon instead of that of God;? and begets a numerous offspring of sins, such as lying, deceit, perjury, theft, treason, lack of charity in the narrow sense of the term, and every form of injustice. There- fore St. Paul terms it “the root of all evils.”? It leads to insatiability, discontent and fear of poverty, and is often responsible for great unhappiness tend- ing to become fixed.4 Lust is that form of inordinate desire which breeds the sins of unchastity. It may be either internal, confined to thoughts and desires, or external, of words or acts. Unless promptly overcome in time of temp- 1St. Matt. xi. 20, cf. v. 3; xviii, 3; St. Luke xiv. 1; St. John v. 14; St. Jas. iv. 6. J.B. Scaramelli, Direct. Asceticum, vol. III, art. XI. 2St. Matt. vi. 21, 24; St. Paul calls it idolatry, Eph. v. 5; Col. iii. 5. $1 St. Tim. vi. ro. Cf. St. Thomas, I, II, Ixxxiv, 1. Generally, see St. Matt. vi. 31-33; St. John xii. 4-6; Heb. xiii. 5; 1 St. John ii. 15. 4 T. Slater, of. cit., vol. I, pp. 157 ff. Ibid., p. 158, ‘It is opposed to liberality by defect, while prodigality is opposed to liberality by excess.” THE SEVEN CAPITAL SINS 239 tation it is apt quickly to result in mortal sin. The subject has been dealt with elsewhere.! Envy is grief because of another’s good. Accord- ing to one theory, it caused the fall of Satan.2 Envy seeks another’s hurt or loss rather than his good, and is therefore opposed to charity. From it spring hatred, revenge, calumny and slander. A deeply seated vice, it has far-reaching effects and destroys interior peace. Gluttony is inordinate desire for food and drink on account of the pleasure they give. Of those addicted to it St. Paul says that “their god is their belly.” 4 It is opposed to the cardinal virtue of tem- perance. Excessive eating and drinking are its chief manifestations; but drunkenness is its most common form. Sins committed during drunkenness are mor- ally imputable, unless the state is due either to an accident or to ignorance. Excessive drinking, even when not resulting in intoxication, is sinful, and may become very grave and mortal by reason of foreseen liability to cause injury to health, scandal and neglect of duty, and because practically every man knows that excessive drinking is for him a proximate cause 1 Tn ch. iv, §13, above. Cf. ch. v, § 7. 2St. Aug., Serm. 254, alias 151, de Temp.; St. Thomas, II, II, xxxvi, 1-4. Cf. Wisd. ii, 24. But see Isa. xiv. 12-15; 1 Tim. iii. 6. 3 On envy, 1 Cor. iii. 3; xiii. 4; 2 Cor. xii. 20; St. James iii. 14, 16; v. 9. It is described as cause of the first murder, Gen. iv. 3-8; and of the demand for our Lord’s crucifixion, St. Matt. xxvii. 17-18. 4 Phil. iii. 19; cf. St. Luke xxi. 34; Rom. xiii. 13-14; 1 St. Pet. iv. 3. 240 SIN of further sin It is a most common cause of crime, disease, and human misery generally. Anger is craving for revenge. Abstractly consid- ered it is not always a sin, for there is a ‘‘righteous anger’’ 2 which is praiseworthy and the lack of which may be a sin, as when one is unmoved by evil acts. But even this becomes a sin when it leads a man to lose control of himself and harbour feelings of hatred and enmity. And this is especially true when anger lacks a just cause. It becomes a sin in a way analo- gous to lust, by failure to control oneself ad rem.? Sloth is sluggishness of soul which makes one shirk physical and mental labour in the fulfilment of duty and the practice of virtue. It may take the form either of lukewarm indifference to these things, or of disinclination for them, developing into positive aver- sion. Its result is spiritual and moral paralysis.* § 7. Sins that cry to heaven for vengeance, men- tioned above, include in usual reckoning wilful mur- der, sodomy, oppression of the poor, and defrauding labourers of their hire5 They are not only moral transgressions positively considered, but they violate 1 Prov. XX. 13 XXiii, 29-35; St. Luke xxi. 34; 1 Cor. vi. 10; Eph. v. 18. 2St. Matt. iii. 7; St. Mark iii, 5; St. Matt. xxi. 12; Rom. xii. 17; Acts v. 3 fi. 8 Psa. xxxvil. 8; Prov. xiv. 17, 29; xvii, 14; St. Matt. v. 22; Ephes, iv. 31; St. James i. 19-20. 4 Prov. vi. 6-11; St. Matt. xxv. 26-27; Rom. xii. 11; 2 Thess. iii, 10-12; Revel. iii, 15 ff. 5 Gen. iv. 10; xviil. 20 ff.; Ex. ill. 7; xxii. 22 ff.; Deut. xxiv. 14 ff.; St. James v. 4. THE SIN AGAINST THE HOLY GHOST 241 with peculiar directness the laws of nature, out- raging certain generally recognized natural instincts, including those of self-preservation, the sexual and the social. By their nature they are always mortal. Of the first two mentioned we have already treated.} Oppression of the poor, especially of widows and orphans, is committed in a variety of ways, ¢.g., by unjustly administering an estate, by the unjust appropriation of goods, by defrauding one who is unable to defend his right, by oppressive combina- tions and monopolies of food, fuel, and other neces- sities of life, by adulteration of such necessities, and by usury. Labourers are defrauded of their hire when compelled by necessity to accept a lower wage than that to which they are justly entitled, as in “sweat shops.” The latter forms of these sins require special study at the present time in the light of modern sociology and political economy. §8. In final analysis every wrongdoing is sin against the Holy Ghost, for all sins are in ultimate reference against God. In particular, all sin is op- posed to sanctity, of which the Holy Ghost is the Author. But, technically speaking, the description applies to a certain kind of sin? It is the most malignant sin of all and the only unforgivable one, for it does not proceed from ignorance or infirmity, 1In ch. iv, §§ 12, 13, above. 2 See T. Slater, Questions of Moral Theology, pp. 78 ff.; 176 ff. 3St. Matt. xii. 24, 31-32; St. Mark iii. 28-30; St. Luke xii. 10; Heb. x. 26-31. 242 SIN but is a deliberate and unalterably fixed opposition to the will of God as revealed by the Holy Ghost. St. Augustine and Peter Lombard enumerate six distinct sins of this kind,! but all may be reduced to one, deliberate revolt from God with final impenitence. Such sin is necessarily unpardonable, not because in objective form any human sin is beyond the reach of divine mercy, but because the sinner himself delib- erately and finally rejects such mercy. He who thus sins against the Holy Ghost cannot obtain forgive- ness for the simple reason that with, incurable obsti- nacy he refuses to be forgiven. It isthe fixedness of his attitude of rebellion which explains the situation, and all forms of sin are susceptible of final develop- ment to this climax of incurable malignity. Pre- viously to such development all are forgivable on repentance. 1 Presumption against God’s mercy, despair, resisting known Christian truth, envy at another’s spiritual good and obstinacy in sin, are all steps leading to the last which is alone unpardonable. See H. B. Swete, on St. Mark, inloc.; A. Plummer, St. Matt., in loc. BIBLIOGRAPHICAL INDEX ALEXANDER, A. Christianity and Ethics. N. Y., tor. AtpHonsus Licuort, St. Theol. Moralis. Many edd. AMBROSE, St. JN. and P.N., vol. 10; M.P.L., vols. 15-17. American Church Monthly. N. Y., 1917 ff Anglican Theol. Review. N. Y., 1918 ff. Anglo—Cath. Theol., Lib’y of. Ed. by E. B. Pusey and others, 88 vols. Oxf., 1841 ff. Referred to as A-C Lib. Ante-Nicene Fathers, The. Ed. by Coxe, 10 vols. N. Y., 1905 ff. Referred to here as A-N. ARISTOTLE. See Welldon. AucusTINE, St. NV. and P.N., 1st ser., vols. 1-8; M.P.L., vols. 32-47. ee H. A. Marriage Legisl. in the New Code of Canon Law. INCU 3 LOLS, Batpwin, J. M. Dic. of Philos. and Psychol. 3 vols., N. Y., Lond., 1902-5. Barry, J. G. H. The Holy Eucharist. N. Y., 1920. BAversTOcCK, A. H. The Priest as Confessor. Lond., Mil., 1915. Betton, F. G. A Manual for Confessors. Mil., 1916; Present Day Problems in Christ. Morals. Oxf., Mil., 1920. BICKERSTETH, CyrtLt. The Ministry of Absolution. Lond., 1912. BICKNELL, E. J. A Theol. Introd. to the Thirty-nine Arts. Lond., IQIQ BIGG, GANA The Church’s Task under the Rom. Empire. Oxf., 1905. BLACKIE, J.S. Four Phases of Morals. N. Y., 1871. deat. SIR Wm. Commentaries on the Laws of Engl. Many e Brunt, HucH F. Great Penitents. N. Y., 1922. BLUNT, J.H. Dic. of Doctr’l and Hist’l T eae Lond., 1870. BoEDDER, B. Natural Theol. Lond., 1801. BrRown-DrivEr-Briccs. Heb, and Engl. Ps of the Old Test. Bost., 1906. Bruce, A. B. The Moral Order of the World in Ancient and Modern Thought. Lond., 1899. Bruce, W.S. Ethics of the Old Test. Edinb., 1895. Butcaris, Nicw. The Holy Catechism of. Lond., 1893. Butt, P. B. The Threefold Way. Lond., 1916. 243 PAA BIBLIOGRAPHICAL INDEX an Jos. Serm’s on Human Nature. Ed. by W. E. Gladstone. xf., 1896. CatrD, J. Fund’l Ideas of Christy. 2 vols., Glasg., 1899. CALDERWOOD, H. Handb’k of Moral Philos. 12th ed., Lond., 1885. Carey, W. J. The Life in Grace. Lond., 1914; Prayer and Some of its Difficulties. Lond., 1915. Catholic Encyc., The. Ed. by Herbermann, 16 vols., N. Y., 1907. Church Quart. Review, The. Lond., Spottiswoode. Cuurton, E.T. The Use of Penitence. 2ded. Lond., 1913. Coprens, C. Moral Prin’s and Medic. Practice. New and enl. ed. N.Y; 102, Costin, JoHN. Works. In A-C. Lib. 5 vols. Oxf., 1843-55. CupwortH, Rate. Treatise concerning Eternal and Immutable Morality. Lond., 1731. D’Arcy, C.F. A Short Study of Ethics. Lond., 190r. Darwin, Cuas. The Origin of Species by Nat’l Selection. New ed. Lond., 1900. Davips, T. W. Rays. In Sacred Books of the East, vol. 2. Oxf. Davipson, A. B. Theol. of the Old Test. N.Y., 1906. Davinson, W.L. Christian Ethics. N. Y.,n. d. Davis, N. K. Elements of Ethics. WN. Y., 1900. DEARMER, PERcy. Body and Soul. N. Y., 1909. De LEHEN, FRr., S.J. The Way of Interior Peace. N. Y., 1888. Denzincer, H. Enchirid. Symb. et Definitionum. 12thed. Freib., 1913. DEWEY, JOHN, and Turts, J.H. Ethics. N. Y., 1900. Didache, The, or Teaching of the Twelve Apos. In A-N, vol. 7. Didascalia Aposiolorum in English. Transl. by Eadem. Cambr., 1903. Dit, Sir SAMUEL. Roman Society from Nero to Marcus Aurelius. Lond., Igrt. DRAKE, DurANT. Problems of Conduct. Bost., tor4. Eck, HAV. 8) San. Lond. 1007; ELMENDOoRE, J. J. Elements of Moral Theol. basedon .. . St. Thos. Aq. N. Y., 1892, 1895. ELwin, W. Confession and Absol. in the Bible. Lond., 1883. Ey, R. T. Monopolies and Trusts. N. Y., 1900; Socialism: Its Nature, Strength, and Weakness. Lond., 18094. FENELON, ABP. Spiritual Letters. Transl. 2 vols. N. Y., 1878. Ficcis, J. N. The Will to Freedom. N. Y., 1917. FLiInT, Rosert. Socialism. Lond., 1904. FOERSTER, F. W. Marriage and the Sex Problem. Lond., 1912. Forses,A.P. An Explan. of theXXXIX Aris. athed. Oxf., 1881. GAMBLE, H. R. Sunday and the Sabbath. Lond., N. Y., 1901. Gaume. See Pusey. Gippincs, F. H. Prin’s of Sociology. N. Y., 1898. Giover, T. R. Conflict of Religions in the Early Rom. Empire. Lond., 1908. BIBLIOGRAPHICAL INDEX 245 Gore, CHas. In Lux Mundi. Lond., 1904; Christian Moral Prin’s. Oxf., 1921; Dominant Ideas and Corrective Prin’s. Oxf., Mil., 1918; The Sermon on the Mount. Lond., 1896. Gott, Joun. The Parish Priest of the Town. Lond., 1888. GoupbcE, H. L. The First Ep. to the Corinth. 3ded. Lond., 1911. GREEN, T. H. Prolegom. to Ethics. Oxf., 1890. Grecory I., St. In M.P.L., vols. 75-79. Trans. in Lib. of Frs. Oxf., 1844. Gury, J. P., S. J. Compend. Theol. Moralis. 2 vols. Ratisb., 1874. HAECKEL, Ernst. Riddle of the Universe. N. Y., 1900. Hatt,A.C.A. Christ. Doctr. of Prayer. N.Y. , 1904; Confirmation. Lond., N. Y., 1900. Hatt, F.J. Theol. Outlines. 3 vols., Mil., 1905 ff.; The Being and Altirib. of God. N.Y., Lond., 1909; Creation and Man, ibid., 19123 The Incarnation, ibid., 1915; The Passion and Exalt. of Christ, ibid., 1918; The Church and the Sac’l System, ibid., 1920; The Sacraments, ibid., 1921; Eschatology, ibid., 1922. Hay, T.C. Hist. of Hihics within Organized Chrisi’y. N.Y., 1910. Harris, Caas. Pro Fide. New ed. Lond., rorq. Hastincs, James. (ed.) Dic. of the Bible. 4 vols. with extra vol. Edinb., N. Y., 1898-1904; Dic. of Christ and the Gospels. 2 vols. tbid., 1906; Dic. of the Apos. Church. 2 vols., 1916-18; Encyc. of Religion and Ethics. 12 vols., 1908-21. HERMANN, WILHELM. Faith and Morals. N. Y., 1904. HessEy, J. A. Sunday. 4thed. N. Y., 1880. HrpeBen, J.G. The Problems of Philos. N, Y., 1898 Hosses, THos. On Human Nature. Lond., toy. “The Leviathan. Oxf., 1881. Hosson, J. A. Evolution of Modern Capitalism. Lond., 1894. Hooker, Ricu. Works. Ed. by J. Keble. 3 vols. Oxf., 1865. Hueco or St. Victor. In M.P.L. Vols. 175-177. Hume, Davip. Treatise on Human Nature. Ed. Selby-Bigge. Oxf., 1896. Humpureys, A. J. Christian Morals. Lond., 1920. HunTeER, R. Poverty. N. Y., 1904. Hutcaines, W.H. The Life of Prayer. Lond., 1897. Hux tery, THos. Collected Essays. 9g vols. N. Y., 1908. Hype, W. DEW. Five Great Philos. of Life. 2ded. N. Y., 1913. Hystop, J. H. Elements of Ethics. N. Y., 1895. ILLINGWORTH, J. R. Christian Character. Lond., 1905. IRENAEUS, ST. Against Heresies. In A-N., vol. 1. JAMES, Wm. Psychology. Briefer Course. N. Y., 1920. Joun or Damascus, St. Expos. of the Orthod. Faith. In N. and P-N., 2d ser., vol. Q. Journal of the Soc. of Oriental Research. Chi., 1917 ff. Kant, Immanuet. Introd. to Metaph. Elements of Ethics. Trans, by Semple. 3d ed. Edinb., 1871. 246 BIBLIOGRAPHICAL INDEX Kirk, K. E. Some Prin’s of Moral Theol. and their Application. 2dimpr. Lond., N. Y., 1921. Krrxup, THos. A Hist. of Socialism. Lond., 1909. Kwox-LitrLe, W. J. Holy Matrimony. Lond., N. Y., 1900. Kocu, A. Ed. by Preuss, A. A Handb’k of Moral Theol. 5 vols. St. Louis, 1918 ff. Lambeth Conferences, The Five. Ed. R.T. Davidson. Lond., N. Y., 1920. Deca W.E.H. Hist. of European Morals. 2 vols. N. Y., 1874. Lecc, J. W. Papal Faculties Allowing Food before Communion. Lond., 1906. LEGGE, J. Religions of China. Lond., 1880. LEHMKUHL, AuG., S. J. Theol. Moralis. 2 vols. Freib., 1886. LeusaA, J. H. A Psychol. Study of Religion. N. Y., 1912. Lippon, H. P. Univ. Sermons. 1st ser. Lond., 1869; Some Elem. of Religion. Lond., 1904; Clerical Life and Work. Lond., 1894. Licutroot, J. B. Epis. to the Philippians. Lond., 1900; Epp. to the Colossians and to Philemon. Lond., tgo0o. LINDNER, D. Die gesetzliche Verwandtschaft als Ehehinderniss im abendlindischen Kirchenrecht des Mittelalters. Paderb., 1920. Linton, E. C. Notes on the Absol. of the Sick and Dying. Lond., IQI5. Locke, JoHN. Essay Concerning Human Understanding. Oxf., 1894. LorrHousE, W.F. Ethics and the Family. N. Y., 1912. LorzE, Herman. Prac’l Philos. In Outl. of Philos. Ed. by G. T. Ladd, vol. 3. Bost., 1885-92. Lutwarpt, C. E. Hist. of Christ. Ethics before the Reformation. Trans. by W. Hastie, Edinb., 1889. MacCotzr, Matcotm. Christianity in rel. to Science and Morals. Lond., 1903. MAcKENZIE, J.S. Manual of Ethics. 4thed. N. Y., 1901. Mackenzigz, W. D. Ethics of Gambling. Lond., 1889, 1897. MANDEVILLE, BERNARD. The Fable of the Bees. Lond., 1714. MartTInEAvU, Jas. Types of Ethical Theory. 2 vols. Oxf., 1901. Mayor, J.B. The Epis. of St. James. Lond., 1892. McDovucatt, Wu. Introd. to Social Psychol. Lond., 1912. Mercer, S. A. B. Growth of Relig. and Moral Ideas in Egypt; and Religious and Moral Ideas in Babylonia and Syria. Both Mil., IQIQ. Micne, L’Appk. (ed.) Patrologiae Cursus Completus. (Latin 222 vols. Greek 166 vols.). Paris, 1884 ff. Referred to as M.P.L. and M.P.G. Moore, AuBREY L. Essays Scientific and Philos’l. Lond., 1890. Mortimer, A. G. Cath. Faith and Practice. 2 vols. N. Y., Lond., 1907, 1909; Helps to Meditation. 2vols. N. Y., 1881. Moztey, J. B. Ruling Ideas in Early Ages. N. Y., 1879. Myers, P.V.N. Hist. as Past Ethics. N. Y., 1913. BIBLIOGRAPHICAL INDEX 247 Newso.t, W.C. E. The Cardinal Virtues. Lond. n. d.; Speculum Sacerdotum. Lond., 1894. Nicene and Post-Nicene Fathers, The. 1st series ed. by P. Schaff. 14 vols. Buffalo, 1886 ff. 2d ser. ed. by Schaff and Wace. 14 vols. N.Y., 1890 ff. Referred to as N. and P-N. OricEN. In A-N., vol. 4; M.P.G., vols. 11-17. Orttey, R. L. Aspects of the Old Test. Lond., 1904; The Rule of Life and Love. Lond., 1913. Parmer, G. H. The Field of Ethics. Bost., root. PASCAL, BLAIsE. Provincial Letters. Many edd. Preazsopy, F. G. Christian Life in the Modern World. N. Y., 1915. Perry, R.B. Approach to Philos. N. Y., 1905. PLummMer, A. An Exeg. Com. on the Gospel according to St. Matt, Lond., N. Y., 1909. Pour, Jos. (Ed. andtrans. by A. Preuss). Penance. In The Sac- yaments, Vol. III. St. Louis, 1917. Pottock, F. First Book of Jurisprudence. Lond., 1896. Porter, Noan. Elements of Moral Science. N. Y., 1887. Poutain, A. The Graces of Interior Prayer. Lond., 1912. Putter, F. W. The Fast before Communion. Lond., 1891; The Anointing of the Sick. 2d ed. rev. Lond., roro. Pusey, E. B. Advice for those who Exercise the Ministry of Recon- ciliation: being Abbé Gaume’s Manual for Confessors, abridged . . . adapted, etc. Lond., 1893; Is Healthful Reunion Posst- ble? Lond., 1870. Rann, BENJ. The Classical Moralists. Bost., 1900. RASHDALL, Hastincs. Conscience and Christ. N. Y., 1916; Is Conscience an Emotion? Bost., 1914; The Theory of Good and Evil. 2vols. Oxf., 1907. REvTER, J.,S. J. Neo-Confessarius. Paris, 1895. Ricwarpson, G. L. Conscience, Its Origin and Authority. Lond., 1915S. RICKABY, Jos.,S. J. Moral Philos. WLond., 1912. Rocers, R.A. P. SCSAR STE LCDI ALTE REED SADETURTY AG LTS OL EAE S Une ma ATR ETERS RW RQOCRTES ears * SADE ETE WAEE DENT ET RN SERS TTT NPTE ND at a ~ Spe eed eeapnnesmeesapgete pens rans mos os SE EES BC SREB NT er ERAN es CFT See Te T Aro = - — — = - —_— > — LC A =] a —— oo: = = ° 2 renee SSI EL RITE AEDST TAL TET IS WENERS TES TE Se TENE TS : = = — “3 ICES ASSES INSET EE SDAEUSSEEOTSET EDS Retr eeneunenyaeerae sesepoe: =