= ee Peep ee ee —— 2 oo rao Sete i i Cos Sere a ae me Oe ince aes es SM stehcksipapepneteepe tee seas Hrum the Likrary of Professor Benjamin Breckinridge Warfield Beyueathed by him to the Library of Princeton Theological Seminary 20 1887 Percy, 1846-1937. conduct ; “es __ Digitized by the Internet Archive . ms in’ 2022 with funding from Princeton Theological Seminary Lib ‘gt “https://archive.org/details/faithconductessa0 | FAITH AND CONDUCT % FAITH AND CONDUCT AN ESSAY ON VERIFIABLE RELIGION Lonvon MACMILLAN AND CO. AND NEW YORK 1887 All rights reserved “‘ God or Eternal is here really, at bottom, nothing but a deeply- moved way of saying, ‘The power that makes for conduct or righteousness. ‘Trust in God’ is, in a deeply-moved way of expression, the trust in the law of conduct; ‘delight in the Eternal’ is, in a deeply-moved way of. expression, the happiness we all feel to spring from conduct. Attending to conduct, to judgment, makes the attender feel that it is joy to doit. Attend- ing to it more still, makes him feel that it is the commandment of the Eternal, and that the joy got from it is joy from fulfilling the commandment of the Eternal.” MatTTHEW ARNOLD, Literature and Dogma. “The thought of God, as Theists entertain it, is not gained by an instinctive association of His presence with any sensible phenomena ; but the office which the senses directly fulfil as regards the external world, that office devolves indirectly on certain of our mental phenomena as regards its Maker. These phenomena are found in the sense of moral obligation. From the perceptive power which identifies the intimations of conscience with the reverberations or echoes (so to say) of an external admonition, we proceed on to the notion of a Supreme Ruler and Judge.” Carp. J. H. Newman, The Grammar of Assent. PREFACE Those readers will entirely misjudge the present work who suppose that it professes to be a com- plete account of religion. It is no complete account, but a sketch from one point of view. It is very unlikely that any person would believe just so much as is set forth in these pages, and believe no more. The author, a lay member of the English Church, certainly does not thus limit his beliefs. He divides the field of religion into three parts, of which in the pre- sent work he concerns himself only with one. There is an old-established division of religion into natural and revealed. It would, however, be better to contrast with the revealed religion, which is accepted on the authority of the Church or the Bible, religion which can be verified, which can be judged of by the reason and scientifically examined. It is evident that a vi Preface religion which is based on authority is by that very fact removed from the application of reason and science. Verifiable religion, on the other hand, claims investigation, and it is of this alone that we intend to treat. The difficulty of course arises that many of the doctrines which we regard as verifiable are due, historic- ally speaking, to the teaching of the founders of the Christian doctrine and Church. But this difficulty need not be fatal, nor even serious, if we do not accept these doctrines on authority, but investigate them as we might doctrines due to any great teacher. It is conceivable that the result of our investigation might be to establish the truth of the whole body of doctrine which is commonly spoken of in this country as Chris- tianity. But for those who, without investi- gation, accept that body of doctrine, we of course do not write. Treating thus of verifiable religion only, we have carefully excluded from each chapter, even from that which deals with the future life, all appeals to authority. But we do not profess to treat of the whole even of verifiable religion. Religion is both a social and an individual thing. It is rather social than individual; and he who treats of it Preface vii only in relation to persons and not in relation to societies will take but a very one-sided view of it. This is, however, the aspect in which religion is regarded in this volume. Thus we leave on one side, for the present, any consideration of religion as a_ historical erowth ; and we postpone all dealing with the religious side of human relations, the relations of the family, the society, the state, and man- kind. It is possible that the reader may be occasionally surprised to see how little is here said of the love which binds society together, and the higher love or charity which is at the root of all satisfactory relations between man and man. We say nothing of the Church as a constituted organism, of its doctrines, its ministers and ceremontes. It may be that, if he finds it possible, the writer of these pages will hereafter attempt to supplement his investigation of Faith and Con- duct with some account of the social and _his- torical aspects of religion, an investigation of Foth and Charity, and of Faith and Progress. At present he has made but scattered notes on those high subjects, and it is his hope that they are destined for worthier pens than his own. viii Preface We are compelled also to postpone the treat- ment of the relations of religion to science and art. For the history of science and of art must be considered as part of that general growth of mankind of which we are determined to avoid speaking ; while, on the other hand, the relations of science and of art to us in the present day, and their connections with the beliefs which make life possible to us, can only be spoken of when it is human society at large, and not the individual, which is in question. The case is otherwise with conduct. Conduct is by the very necessities of the case a purely personal matter. It can be approached from the side of the individual consciousness, and treated of apart from theories of the Church or of human development. And since conduct makes up, in the view of the most clear-sighted writers among us, the chief part of the hfe of man, and right- doing is his great concern, the present writer cannot help feeling that if he can help but a few to understand better the meaning and the neces- sities of conduct, he will have indeed been fortunate. The general argument of the book may be followed, even if some of the chapters which it Preface ix contains be passed over. ‘Thus those who do not care to follow the writer’s brief summary of the aroument from evolution may omit Chapters V. and VI.; those who have no interest in meta- physical discussions will probably prefer to pass Chapters [X., X., and XI. On the other hand, to the specialists in biology and in metaphysics these two groups of chapters respectively will probably seem slight and defective, perhaps quite inadequate. It was, however, impossible, in tra- versing so wide a ground, to do more than indi- cate a position and determine a point of view. On the other hand, Chapters L-IV., VII.-VIIL, XIV.-XXVI., constitute a chain of which no link can fairly be judged apart from those which pre- cede and follow it. The reflections and experiences of succeeding years have continually strengthened the convic- tion held by the writer of these pages, that the views they contain are consistent one with the other, as well as with the constitution of the world. But this confidence does not extend to approval of the form in which the views are put forth. Chapters written at intervals over a long period, in the rare leisure hours allowed by a laborious profession, are not likely to be perfect i Preface in development. If the author could hope for a long period of leisure, he would reserve them in the intention of entirely recasting them. But he sees no prospect of long rest for many years to come. And it may fairly be claimed that these pages, in the absence of all external grace of style, at least possess the merit of having been written without any settled intention of publication, and in the simple and direct intention of finding and setting forth so much of the truth as the faculties of the writer can with severe diligence discover. In renouncing all attempt at a graceful style, he has been saved from the temptation to put down anything of doubtful truth because 1t seemed at the moment attractive. It is one of the pleasantest of duties in writing a preface to say to whom the author is most in- debted for aid in his task. To the present writer this is not an easy thing to do. Personal aid he has received from one friend only, who necessarily remains anonymous. Probably he is by no means the best judge to decide to whom he owes most in his views and his mental habits. He feels a debt of gratitude especially to Mr. Matthew Arnold’s Interature and Dogma; and among lesser writers to Mr. Murphy and Mr. A. J. Preface xi Balfour. But it is likely that he may really be indebted equally to Butler, or Kant, or Mansel, or Mill, or Comte, or even to some of those writers with whom he agrees the least. In every case in which a view of this book is consciously taken from the writings of others the fact is stated. As, however, the author has had for many years little time for reading books on ethics and philosophy, it is likely that much of the furni- ture of the mind, which he supposes that he has made, was really imported in college days, and has so often been made use of that its origin is forgotten. Lonpon, September 1887. CONTENTS . CONDUCT REGARDED FROM WITHOUT . . WHAT IS RIGHT ConpDuUcT ? . How CAN WE KNOW WHAT IS RIGHT ?. . How SHALL WE DO WHAT IS RIGHT? . . HIGHER PURPOSE IN EVOLUTION . HIGHER PURPOSE IN HIsToRY . . DIvInE AID AS EXPERIENCE . THE DENIAL OF SELF . THe History OF SCEPTICISM . THe PRACTICAL GROUNDS OF BELIEF . ReLicious IDEALISM . SUMMARY AND ANSWER TO OBJECTIONS . A Priori THEOLOGY : EXPERIENCE IN RELIGION . THE POWERS OF GOOD AND EVIL XVI. XVII. XVIII. HuMAN RESPONSIBILITY . KNOWLEDGE AND FAITH . LAWS OF THE HIGHER LIFE 108 115 128 152 173 185 193 203 212 224 231 241 xiv Contents CHAP. XIX. XX. XXI. XXIL XXIII. XXIV. XXV. XXVI. XXVII. XXVIII. XXIX. Tuer TEsts oF FAITH GRACE : : PRAYER AND TRUST PROVIDENCE NATURAL PIETY OpriMIsM AND Evin Tue Furure LIFE aa Tae Furore or MANKIND TESTIMONY IN RELIGION AUTHORITY IN RELIGION CONCLUSION : : GHA PTER CONDUCT REGARDED FROM WITHOUT THERE are two proverbs, whereof one says that man is a creature of circumstance, another that he is a bundle of habits. Neither of these phrases pretends to any scientific exactness; they are aphorisms, and like other aphorisms express half-truths with vigour and clearness, but will not altogether bear a close examination. Man is a creature of circumstance. No doubt we all know what we should do under certain circumstances, or if we do not, friends who look from outside, and know us better than we know ourselves, will easily tell us what we should do under these circumstances or those. We feel, indeed, in any con- junction of circumstances, as if our path of action were open, and we were free to do what we choose; but a little reflection shows us that we are not really free to do an absurd thing without a motive for doing it. We have the power, when walking to catch an important train, to sit down on a doorstep and wait until it has gone, but we can scarcely be really said to be free to do so, for it is a moral impossibility to do a foolish thing which we do not want to do. Again, we all feel how from the first entry into life B 2 Faith and Conduct CHAP. the force of circumstances has gradually pent us in and driven us along until we have come to occupy the position which we now hold. We think we can swim as we will, but, after all, the net of circumstance hems us in, and cuts off one by one all our chances of choosing our own path in life. And as circumstances form an outward bar or limit to our action, so habit forms an inward bias. Alike in mind and body we inherit a set of tendencies the grasp of which only becomes stronger as we grow up. And to the inherited bias we add and add every year some new tendency. The seed determines the species of the plant; soil and weather limit and direct its growth, and every fresh bud and leaf which it puts forth hem its possible growth within closer limits. It is the same with men; they too inherit possibilities and are limited by the conditions of their life; and in addition every day adds to their habits and the tendencies which as they grow older they can less and less resist. As the body of a new-born infant is already endued with tendencies which, as time passes by, will cause it to develop in some special direction, to become slight or stout, tall or short, so the mind of the infant is destined to become vigorous or weak, fond of theory or fond of fact, Platonic or Aristotelian. And as the infant thus inherits traits, bodily or mental, which are sure to grow with its growth, so it also inherits a certain moral frame or constitution. There are certain views which must needs powerfully attract it. If the parent never controlled bodily passion, the child will grow up in- continent; if the parent loved slander, the child will as much inherit a tendency to slander as a tendency to fair or dark hair. Of course we do not say that I Conduct regarded from without 3 the child must graw up like the parent, but there will be in all the fibres of his nature a tendency to do so. It is obviously merely for the sake of simplicity that we speak of children as inheriting only from their parents. It would be more exact to say that the nature with which each starts in life is the result of the doings and feelings of his ancestors through count- less ages. But as the influence of parents on their children is the most direct of inherited influences, it is convenient to make it stand for all. And again, it is clear that we have here no space to distinguish between mere superficial characteristics and those which reach down to the roots of the nature. If the child of a thief, for instance, be early removed into a state of society in which stealing is out of fashion, we need not expect him to retain a custom as unusual in his new state of life as it was usual in the previous state. Thieves constitute in large cities a class; and there are among them many degrees and kinds of virtue and vice as in other classes. Again, the drunkard may be driven into drunkenness by the stress of intolerable anxiety; but his children, if free from anxiety, may not feel the need of the stimulus. Leaving out of view all such distinctions, which are here as superfluous as they would be necessary in a formal work on psychology, we may venture on the broad assertion that the child’s nature is determined by his descent. Thus all of us start in life, like bowls on a lawn, not smoothly and roundly, but with a certain inherited bias. That bias we can never wholly set aside. But education and circumstance, though they cannot wholly remove bias, may greatly modify it. The 4 Faith and Conduct CHAP. wolf, if taken from its mother very young, and brought up among dogs, will never wholly lose its savage instincts, yet in externals at least will assume much of the habits of a dog. So the son of a drunkard may be brought up to dislike the sight of wine. Or the son of a slanderer may, by being shown the ugliness of the habit of slander, acquire a fixed dislike to it. A man’s nature being thus fixed by inheritance and modified by circumstance and education, the course of his action will follow, in general, the bent of his nature. Ifthe beast nature be strong in him, he will act like a beast. The French proverb says, Chassez le naturel et il revient aw galop ; and never was there a truer proverb. People do not, as a rule, find themselves able on any occasion to throw aside the sum of their past feelings and pleasures and_ start afresh. Usually, quite usually enough to give rise to generalisations and to give validity to calculations of the action of masses, men act at each crisis of their lives in accordance with the impulse of their inherited nature, as modified by circumstance and education. Out of the abundance of the heart a man’s deeds will come. The covetous man will act covetously, the envious man will be carried away by his envy. The self-indulgent man will sacrifice his real interest to his momentary pleasure; the strongly sympathetic man will help those whom he loves at the cost of his own advantage, or even at some sacrifice of principle. The man of high principle will do what he feels to be right though it may seem to disadvantage himself and others. Each will, as a general rule, move on the path he has made for himself. Rivers do not flow back towards I Conduct regarded from without 5 their sources, nor trees grow again towards the ground ; nor is it often that a man changes in the midst of life the tendency of his conduct. He does so, indeed, sometimes; but this is a phenomenon with which we shall hereafter deal as with an exception. Some Necessarians think, or seem to think, that the course of life is wholly determined by the inter-action of habit within and circumstance without. They think that if they knew precisely what nature any person inherited, and could precisely trace the course which his life would have to pursue, they could then foretell, or at least that some wiser being than man could foretell, what habits that person would form, and how he would act at any given turn or crisis of his life. In this case our feeling of freewill would be altogether delusive. We should be as much under the control of natural law as the bullet when shot from the gun, or as the tides of the sea. It is scarcely necessary to say that if we agreed with this view, the present book would not have been written. From the first page to the last it maintains that man is within certain limits free—free to choose between courses of action which lie open to him, free to rise to a higher or sink to a lower level. The limits of that freedom may not be very wide, but they are sufficiently wide to make man a moral and respon- sible being, and to introduce into the world and into conduct infinite possibilities of good and bad. In the next few chapters we shall try to show how these views are established by an examination of the nature of conduct. In the meantime we wish to point out that looking at life merely from the outside, observing it as we observe the phenomena of the 6 Faith and Conduct CHAP. eer aaa oY ieee material world, we shall find that human action is not entirely determined by forces that are without. The same man, placed in the midst of the same circum- stances, will sometimes act in one way and sometimes in another. It is found by experience that even when human action is treated of in the general, and by means of statistics merely, there are yet variations which seem to.show an element of disturbance in all calculation. Let us take an illustration to make this clear. Two boys are born in two neighbouring villages ; they inherit an equally promising and healthy physique, and crow up equally capable of exertion and fatigue. Their circumstances of life are the same, and an observer might think that the courses of their lives will flow in parallel streams to the end. But one applies himself with energy and persistency to all athletic sports, and learns in their practice to excel all about him; he becomes a noted athlete, and perhaps founds a race of men who carry on from generation to generation the skill of body for which he was famous. The other lad gives way more and more to habits of physical indolence, prefers resting to exertion, perhaps mental to physical development; his muscles grow flaccid and his chest contracts, until he seems but as the shadow of his sturdy contemporary. ; We see the same kind of differentiation going on around us in moral matters. Men start as it were side by side with equal ingenuousness and natural goodness, and their path in life seems to lead them in the same direction, yet one seems steadily to grow better as the years pass by, to rise higher and_ higher in the esteem of those whose esteem is worth having, I Conduct regarded from without 7 while the other seems to fall to a lower and lower level, and ends by making shipwreck of the better purposes of his nature, and perishing on the barren rocks of life. And we are all, in all our lives, rising to better or falling to worse things—usually rising and falling alternately. The course of our conduct is like that of the lines in a chart of temperatures or of prices, full of constant fluctuations, yet on the whole tending, over long periods, gradually to rise or gradually to sink. And as the fluctuations of the thermometer are deter- mined by the contest of hot air and cold, so the course of a man’s life as regards conduct is the result of a conflict between good and evil impulses and tendencies. Looking on the world from without we see that the current of history is the sum of the lives of individuals; and the life of each individual is a line of conduct. The line of conduct again may be resolved into a series of individual actions, in each of which a better or a worse course may be pursued. Thus the ultimate factors into which history may be resolved are indefinite, vague, and not to be reckoned on. But in saying this we do not intend to deny the possibility of a science of history. Science is simply orderly knowledge. To become matter of science a subject must be known, and must be known in orderly fashion. Now a great part of history can be known, if not with absolute certainty, at least with a certainty practically sufficient. And many of the main ideas or laws according to which the course of history takes place have been discovered, and more will be hereafter discovered. It is even possible that these laws may some day be so well understood that able observers may foretell with something approaching to certainty 8 Faith and Conduct CHAP. part of what will happen in the immediate future. In fact, in some branches of historical science attempts to foretell the future are made, and are considered reason- able. Sir Stafford Northcote when Chancellor of the Exchequer constructed his budget on his belief in a certain expansion of the revenue. And in all western countries far-sighted people have made large fortunes by rightly forecasting the spread of population into certain districts. As knowledge increases and becomes more systematic, such forecasts will become more common and more exact, and will perhaps spread from the field of economics into that of social and constitu- tional fact. But that is all. History can never become an exact science. There are limits set in nature alike to our knowledge of the past and to our forecasting of the future. The idea that there are no such limits arises merely from confusion of thought, and from a hasty transference into the historical field of ideas acquired in the study of material phenomena. The physical sciences, in consequence of their greater simplicity, have reached maturity far earlier than those which have man for their subject-matter. And as a consequence they often claim the monopoly of scientific method. Such branches of historical science as the nistory of political forces or archeology are quietly relegated to the domain of literature. We English are in this matter sinners beyond all nations. Academies of sciences on the Continent consist of two sections—of an academy of natural and an academy of historical sciences. But our English Royal Society, after a few spasmodic efforts to be more comprehensive, is fast settling down to exclusive concern with physical and I Conduct regarded from without 9 biological studies. The University of Cambridge has of late years established two degrees—the degree of Doctor of Science for mathematicians and physicists, and the degree of Doctor of Letters for philologists, psychologists, and the like. When in London assemblies men of science are spoken of, it does not occur to those present that the phrase means any but those concerned with the aspects of nature, and may with equal propriety be applied to those who study man, the historian, the philologist, and the archeologist. So deeply rooted is this way of looking at things that those who cultivate the historical sciences are very slow to recognise the necessity of placing them on an entirely new footing in accordance with the advance of knowledge in the world. Many walk in the old paths, and a dilettante spirit reigns in their works. When some more energetic young man talks much of their duties to science, they set him down as a quack and a sciolist. And it is to be feared that very often they are right, and he really is a sciolist. And the natural result is that those who seriously set themselves to bring scientific method into any branch of moral and historical science often import their methods direct and unaltered from physical science. There is no tendency of our day more alluring, nor any more dangerous. It is easy to find in this country (for abroad the tendency is less clearly marked) original and energetic books dealing with such subjects as philology or archeology which are led into occasional absurdities on this account. The writers assume that human affairs proceed in certain fixed ways, as if man were a machine, and had no power of choosing between one way and IO Fatth and Conduct CHAP. another. Tendencies in human affairs may of course be observed and described, but a tendency is not a fact, and human will and choice can at every moment step in to counteract the tendency. The moral and historical sciences will never be placed on a sound basis until it is recognised that they have two sets of phenomena to take into account ; first, the natural course of evolution, as it would pro- ceed if man were a mere passive machine; and secondly, the innumerable deviations from that course produced by the free actions of men, more especially of great men. A few instances must be cited. In the early cen- turies of the Christian era the great movements of nations were mainly determined by competition and survival of the fittest. But some of those movements were the results of the personal policy of rulers. Trajan, in pursuance of a fixed idea of policy, de- stroyed the Dacian nation, and put in its place the nation of the Roumans. It is simply beyond all cal- culation what changes in the history of past times, and even of future times, would have resulted had Trajan made peace with Decebalus instead of making war on him, and so had not driven a strong wedge of alien population between north and south Slavs. Perhaps it will be said that if Trajan had not destroyed the Dacians the Roumans would have done the same work under another leader. This is, however, by no means likely, since the policy of Trajan’s immediate successor, Hadrian, was to reduce, not to increase, the size of the Roman Empire. The historian who believes in Providence may hold that in this case Trajan ful- filled a purpose of a higher power; the historian who I Conduct regarded from without II does not believe in Providence will have to ascribe an enormous share in the history of Europe to the results of the reflections of Trajan. But the historian who sees in the matter nothing but the working of natural law in human development is simply ignorant of his subject. If there be one part of history wherein the action of natural law can be clearly traced, it is the history of art; and in no branch of art can the succession of phenomena be more clearly traced to law than in sculpture. We can see clearly that the development of the sculptural types in Greece, from the very begin- nings of plastic art down to the times of Alexander the Great, is an orderly and gradual process subject to definite laws. But in his day we find that the physical peculiarities of his body had a marked effect on the development of sculpture, an effect which art never entirely shook off. Can it be maintained that any conqueror of Asia must necessarily have had precisely that physique? If not, we can scarcely deny the interference of personal peculiarities on the whole history of art at this time. At a later time, in the reign of Hadrian, a strongly-marked influence of a similar kind originated in the strong affection of the Emperor for the youth Antinoiis; a fact of personal caprice, yet a fact which dominated for a time the history of sculpture, nay, even in all probability, by altering the ideal of human beauty, greatly influenced the course of the physical history of mankind on which that ideal is always working. It would be as easy to produce a thousand examples as these two, but these are sufficient. The course of history is not determined, as Carlyle thought, by the 12 Fatth and Conduct ~ CHAP. decisions of great men; and it is not, as many far eruder minds fancy, independent of all influences of personal character. It is in accordance with natural law, but modified by the will and character of indi- viduals; and the only point of view in which natural tendencies and individual volitions can be referred to a common origin is the point of view of those who believe that the same Power which rules the universe works for good purposes in the hearts of men. An extreme instance of the danger of purely physi- cal methods in historical sciences is to be found in Mr, Cotter Morrison’s work on Zhe Service of Man. Much of that book is in accordance with reason, and it is written in an earnest and manly spirit; but the main views are entirely vitiated by his denial of freewill and his hypotheses that man is an automaton, and that no Deity works in the world. Given these pre- misses, there is no escaping from Mr. Morrison’s con- clusion, painful as a nightmare, that the only chance for the future of the human race lies in the cultivation of the race of man as the races of animals are cultivated. What ideal of mankind is to dominate this process of cultivation is not clearly stated. One lays down the book with the momentary impression that there are many vicious tendencies in the world, and many classes of men who should be ruthlessly exterminated, but that the nature of good is hidden for ever from human understanding. But this nightmare, like nightmares of a more vulgar kind, comes merely from neglecting the teaching and despising the ordinances of nature. Man has, it is true, departed far from nature and found out many inventions. We have allowed a state of society to I Conduct regarded from without 3 arise among us to which, in many aspects, no lighter word than accwrsed seems applicable. While hasting to be rich the nations of the west have, like many men who are in haste to be rich, forgotten to look to their mental and moral health, and terrible symptoms in all countries show how far disease has made inroads on our social condition. But we have not yet reached the state spoken of by Tacitus in which remedy is no less intolerable than disease. Return to a better state is yet possible. But it is possible only in one way— by admitting into our lives more of the good impulses and tendencies which flow down on mankind in a never-ceasing stream. So long as the doors are shut, the stables of Augeas are full of filth, but if they be opened to admit the stream it will sweep in with purifying force. However, we must not allow ourselves to be led, by a strong feeling as to Mr. Morrison’s book, into such discussions of social questions as are excluded by the plan of this work. We cannot here consider possible remedies for social ills. We will only, before beginning our investigation of conduct, point out what is Involved in the mere fact that the history of morality is an evolution. It is not difficult to see whence come the evil impulses of which all of us must be but too conscious. For the gradual evolution of the human race through long ages has been undoubtedly, on the whole, a pro- gress towards a higher level. One by one the vices which make the lives of savages hideous have died out or become rare. One by one the virtues which make civilised life possible have become established among us. We are still far enough from perfection, 14 Faith and Conduct CHAP. and have allowed many vices to grow among us to a height which they do not reach in less highly-de- veloped communities. But the root-vices of human nature, improvidence, lust, and cruelty, are the pre-emi- nent characteristics of barbarians. And it is well known that there is a strong tendency in all species of animals sometimes to revert to ancestral forms. The race never forgets, but always bears about with it traces of every stage of development through which it has passed, As the whale has rudimentary feet as a relic of the actual feet possessed by his ancestors, so each man bears about in his heart relics of all the foul vices which deformed his ancestors, and still retains the possibility of being possessed and controlled by them. They are like sleeping dogs which may at any time be awaked; lke genii imprisoned in a vase which may be shattered by any of the shocks of active life, so as to let them loose on society. Thus men’s temptations to evil naturally arise from the known facts of atavism. That there is no other source of evil inspiration we do not for a moment assert; on this point we have more to say in our fifteenth chapter. But the obvious facts of inheritance will in themselves account for much of the power of evil wish and passion. But it is important to note that the impulses which bear us towards what is better cannot be thus accounted for. Every person acquainted with history knows how small a part even of historic time is occupied by such deeds on the part of our ancestors as we should wish to copy. Nor could a mere repeti- tion of such virtuous deeds as they have done advance us to a higher level of virtue than that which they I Conduct regarded from without 15 occupied. How then is moral progress possible? It is evident that there must be a strong force drawing us upwards if, in spite of all these backward tendencies, mankind have continued, on the whole, to improve, at least in countries controlled by Europeans. What is this force ? It is either a fortuitous force acting through natural selection, or it is a divine power overruling natural force for higher purpose. To Mr. Cotter Morrison it is the first; in the present work it is maintained to be the last of these. And these are really the two alternatives between which every man must in these days make his choice; it is of no more avail now than it was in the time of Elijah to halt between two opinions. GHA PTERBLE WHAT IS RIGHT CONDUCT ? Ir is from the practical side rather than from the theoretical that we shall approach morals. We shall not greatly concern ourselves with those deep meta- physical problems connected with ethics, which have in all ages exercised the highest faculties of man. These great questions we shall avoid, as not directly lying in our path. We are like travellers in haste, who search out the best and most accessible roads for passing through a country, and have no leisure to stay and ascend the various snow-crowned mountains which lie to the right and left. Our journey is long enough, and the ground we have to traverse rough enough, to excuse us from such digressions, however they might tempt a mind which loves philosophy. We single out, then, in the field of ethics three questions wherewith to concern ourselves—three in- tensely practical questions of great concern to every human being. They are these :—(1.) What is right conduct? (2.) How can we know what is right ? (3.) How shall we compass what is right ? Taking up these questions in succession we shall consider what solutions of them are offered by the CHAP. 11 What ts right conduct ? 17 most widely-followed ethical schools of our days, such as the School of Utility and the School of Natural Selection. To consider all the solutions which have been proposed, even by modern writers, would of course take us beyond all moderate limits ; we therefore select those which especially represent the course of thought in this age. Afterwards we shall propound our own solution; no one, therefore, can accuse us of pulling down but not building up, rather we only pull down to obtain the space necessary for our own foundations. The School of Utility has had many representatives in recent days who have widely differed among them- selves. This very fact makes their position harder to attack. Like Douglas, who at the battle of Shrews- bury slew in succession several leaders wearing the arms and semblance of the king, and yet could not meet the true king, so those who attack the camp of the Utilitarians must always expect that a victory over one champion of the cause will only reveal the fact that the rest repudiate his claim to be their re- presentative. But it seems that two propositions at least must be maintained by all followers of the doctrine of Utility. The first is, that attainment of the greatest happiness by the greatest number is the sum of good, and all conduct which tends to that result virtuous. And the second is, that happiness is a definite thing, as to the nature of which people have made up their minds. This second proposition may not seem quite so essential to the position of the School of Utility as the first; but really it is indispensable if Utilitarian ethics are to be of any use in the world. For if happiness be a thing by nature as vague and indefinite C 18 faith and Conduct CHAP, as virtue, we gain nothing by putting it in the place of virtue; we do but try to explain an obscure idea by one equally obscure. If these two propositions could be established, no doubt much would be done towards the production of a really scientific scheme of ethics. But can they be established ? We will begin by examining the second. And we shall find after very little examination that not only is happiness a thing not definite and measure- able, but that even the Utilitarians themselves differ greatly in the conception of it. If one is content with easy dogmatism, like that with which Bentham draws up a list of the kinds and degrees of happiness, then happiness may seem a simple thing. But to a more care- ful and candid inquiry it appears anything but simple. The tone taken by Utilitarians in fact depends very much on the interpretation given to the am- biguous word happiness. When moralists talk of pro- moting the happiness of the most, we must carefully inquire exactly what is intended by the phrase. For happiness may, in the first place, be regarded merely as the sum of pleasures, the gratification of the desires of common life. Utilitarians who take this view, and form what may be termed the School of Pleasure, will naturally maintain our duty in matters lying outside the range of personal affection to consist in furthering the satisfaction of the wishes of others and making their ends our own. But it will easily be seen where maxims like these will land us. The most prominent and general desire among men is the attainment of money. In this view, then, it will appear that he is the most commendable, nay, the ethically best man, who does most to increase the wealth of the com- 1 What ts right conduct ? 19 munity, say, the daring engineer or the energetic merchant. Most people’s most earnest desire is to be clothed and fed; those therefore who do most to diffuse food and raiment will be admirable beyond all others. Jompared with these pressing desires of the many, the love of political freedom or of religious life is but slightly diffused and dim. Therefore, although it may doubtless be moral to supply these more vague and unusual needs, after the really urgent ones are satisfied, yet he who ministers to them must be content to stand on a far lower platform of desert than the multipliers of physical resources. Our ideal heroes must be not Francis of Assisi, Milton, and Washington, but Ark- wright, Hudson, and Soyer. We shall fill our heaven not with those who have taught of heaven, but with those who have succeeded in making life go on easy wheels and filled it with material comforts. Now there is, no doubt, a good deal of feeling of this kind abroad in an age of great material develop- ment. Nevertheless the view of those who make plea- sure all in all, and value pleasures according to their distinctness and directness, is not true. No outward prosperity can make mental and spiritual emptiness anything but a hideous state of misery. It were a mere waste of words to dwell on a truth so obvious, a truth enforced by every moralist, and forming the basis of almost every keen satire since the world began. Why quote Hesiod, Plato, Horace, and the rest down to Lord Byron and Robert Browning? Surely, with- out producing authorities, we may safely assert that those who aim only at improving directly the physical wellbeing of mankind will assuredly utterly fail even of their purpose, the very accomplishment of which 20 Fatth and Conduct CHAP. might not hinder men from falling into the utmost abyss of misery. It is this truth which lies at the bottom of the general feeling against Utilitarianism. In their desire to get at definite results, and establish morality on a basis of palpable fact, some Utilitarians have made too much of results which can be measured and weighed, have thought too highly of pleasures of which every one must know the value. This has led them natu- rally into the habit of looking very much at the surface, and neglecting all the finer springs of action, building on nothing which can possibly be denied. Spiritual delights, moral pleasures, mental enjoyments, the love of truth and of liberty, are things which cannot be weighed or measured by any invented scale, and a shallow cynicism might throw doubt even on their sohd reahty. Thus they are first thrust into the back- ground, and finally put almost out of sight by the moralists of a hedonic turn. And all Utilitarianism which professes to reach definite results and give con- crete advice must needs somehow set them aside. The ill consequences of such pernicious preference of the definite to the immense, and the obvious to’ the real, can scarcely be exaggerated. If it became universal, all lofty aspiration and heroic action would cease, and life would fall to a dead level of meanness, on which it is painful to dwell even in thought. It is true that the removal of extreme physical misery from the life of a man is a necessary prelim- inary before he can be expected to appreciate any noble pleasure or indulge any high aspiration. There are in our great cities whole classes of people who live below that line, and to whom therefore no benefit can be It What ts right conduct ? 21 so great as the raising of their standard of material comfort, as the securing of some outward decency in their dwellings, and the removal of the constant pangs of hunger. It may be said that great heroes and saints have borne more bitter privations, and under- gone harder daily miseries, than the poorest of our days, and yet have all the time lived and breathed in a high and pure air of enthusiasm. But the remark is not to the point: a saintly and heroic life is possible amid physical pains and privations in a desert, but it could scarcely exist amid the squalor and all-surround- ing sordidness and vulgarity of a modern court in a ereat city. At all events, it must be in such surround- ings of phenomenal rarity. It is the crowding, the dirt, the indecency which prevail in the crowded parts of great towns which form a crust almost impervious to moral ideas. Poverty in the country, or in small towns where a man is after all a man, is by no means so unfavourable a soil for the seeds of noble living. And if we grant that to very poor labouring families in ereat cities some degree of improvement in physical surroundings is necessarily the first step in the ladder of good, yet this does not apply to those who are less poverty-stricken. If ever a man’s life consists in the abundance of the things which he possesses, it is only at a very low level. In case of most dwellers in cities, and nearly all dwellers in the country, the goodness, the real happiness of life, depends far less on material satisfaction than on a thousand things which cannot be measured or weighed—on disposition and habit,on domestic affection and the attachment of friends, on feelings and beliefs. These are the things which with the bulk of mankind make life noble and successful or base and miserable. 22 Faith and Conduct CHAP, But there are other Utilitarians beside the School of Pleasure. These might be termed the School of Well- being. While making the happiness of the most the true end of action, these are careful not to make happi- ness consist of those enjoyments which are merely outward. They make it synonymous with a certain balance of the faculties and satisfaction of all the parts of man’s nature. They think with Plato that some parts of man are by nature higher and better than others; and that he cannot be really happy unless the due subordination of part to part be maintained. Thus they set a truer and higher value on intellectual pleasures, on the satisfaction of a good conscience, and on spiritual delights. We feel at once that writers of this school have a noble aim and a fitting sense of man’s place in creation, and if we differ from them do so with circumspection and regard. Yet this scheme of ethics will not bear examination. It is evident, at first sight, that it must lose all definite- ness and clearness by taking a higher flight and sur- veying a more comprehensive field. The pleasures which it most highly esteems cannot be taken into account in any calculation of consequences. They cannot be weighed in the balance or dissected by the knife. But there is yet a far more radical objection. It is obliged to assume a normal or healthy condition of man, towards which every one should strive to approach, and in attaining which every one will realise his best happiness. It is obliged to assume that from a mere inspection of human nature it can be deter- mined which parts of man are of a higher and which of a lower grade. Yet if man has a higher and a lower nature, it can be at once determined what he ought to e) 11 What ts right conduct ? 23 do without any of the calculations of Utilitarianism ; clearly he must follow what is best within him; the voice of conscience and of his higher nature is sure to cuide him aright. There are thinkers, Mill at the head of them, who have tried to amalgamate the two kinds of Utilitarian- ism above described. This attempt, which can scarcely be called happy, has taken the following form :— Though it can never be our duty to promote anything but the pleasures of others, yet pleasures are of very different kinds, and some of a very superior character to others. Of course these better pleasures have a ereater claim on us, and what they are may be judged from the testimony of mankind; by the verdict, that is, of all who have experienced both them and the worse. It is assumed that under this test mental and moral pleasures will turn out more desirable than mere physical comforts, and therefore have a better claim than they on our activities. Unfortunately, at the touch of fact, this house of cards comes clattering down. It is not true that most people would, apart from a feeling of duty, prefer higher to lower pleasures. Some would, but only a few; certainly not the half of those who can appreciate both. Virtue and wisdom must compete at disadvantage with material pleasures in the highways of life; here and there a man will follow them, but the masses will crowd after their rivals. And why should the verdict of the few be truer than that of the many? Why, unless men have a higher and a lower nature? which phrases Mill re- jects. Is it because the few only can appreciate both kinds of pleasure—the spiritual and the material ? Surely not. The number of those who, while yet 24 Faith and Conduct CHAP. capable of material enjoyments, abandon them for higher pleasures, is exceedingly small, while the number of those who, quite aware of the nature of these better delights, abandon them for the worse, is very large. Take a youth with mind and body well developed, offer him on the one side wealth, ease, luxury, a con- stant stream of enjoyments, and on the other poverty, celibacy, wisdom, and an uncorrupt life, and then bid him choose between these, not in the light of duty, but of pleasure; which will he prefer? The fact is, that, without some appeal to an ideal standard, it is impossible to find a reason why we should prefer the pleasures which we know to be nobler to those which we feel to be baser, but which attract us all the same. And further, can anything be more unscientific than the appeal to opinion for a fact? What should we think of a physician who should try to settle the question whether a patient was or was not in a con- sumption, not by use of the stethoscope, but by asking the opinions of all that patient’s relations and friends, and deciding with the majority? What should we think of the moralist who, when asked to do an act of dubious character, should appeal, not to principles and tendencies, but (say) to the first fifty people he happens to meet, and do or abstain as twenty-six of them ad- vise? After all, certain modes of action must be best fitted for the reasoning and conscientious creature man : his business is to discover what these are by a study of his nature and his circumstances, and the opinion of all the world will never make what does not fit man right, or in the end pleasing, any more than it can make black white. It is the nature of a magnetic needle to point to the north, and all the surmising and It What ts right conduct ? 25 fancying in the world will not make it turn to the east, or keep time like a watch. Just so the fact of certain courses of action tending to wellbeing is fixed in human nature. Opinion changes; now happiness is supposed mainly to lie in this, and now in that, but the changes of fashion, unless human nature radically change, have no more effect on the nature of well- doing and wellbeing than the clouds of the world have on the body of the sun, which warms us all the same if we go blind, or if we fancy that it has been swallowed by a dragon. This paper bridge breaking down, it would seem that Utilitarians have to choose between the School of Pleasure, which infinitely degrades human nature by putting the better parts of it on a level with the worse, and the School of Wellbeing, which, by allow- ing the distinction between higher and lower pleasure, does away with the essential characteristics of Utili- tarlanism, and deprives it of any advantage it might possess as a scheme of working ethics. If, however, we were to grant for the moment that happiness is a thing of obvious and easily discernible nature, we should soon come to another difficulty. For the first proposition of the School of Utility, that happiness should be the end of action, will no more support a serious examination than does the second proposition. That happiness has a right to be the guiding principle of our lives may be assumed by any one who chooses to assume it, but it cannot be proved to an objector. And clearly, unless it can be so proved, the basis of the Utilitarian ethics is very unsound. Mull, indeed, has tried to prove it by an argument which has gained considerable notoriety. 26 Faith and Conduct CHAP. “The only proof capable of being given that an object is visible is that people actually see it. The only proof that a sound is audible is that people hear it: and so of the other sources of our experience. In like manner, I apprehend, the sole evidence it is pos- sible to produce, that anything is desirable, is that people do actually desire it. . . . No reason can be given why the general happiness is desirable, except that each person, so far as he believes it to be attain- able, desires his own happiness. This, however, being a fact, we have not only all the proof which the case admits of, but all which it is possible to require, that happiness is a good; that each person’s happiness is a good to that person, and the general happiness, there- fore, a good to the aggregate of persons.” On this Mr. Sidewick * justly observes: “It must be borne in mind that it is as a ‘standard of right and wrong,’ of ‘ direc- tive rule of conduct, that the Utilitarian principle is put forward by Mill. Hence in giving as a statement of this principle that ‘the general happiness is desir- able, he must be understood to mean (and his whole treatise shows that he does mean) that it is what each individual ought to desire, or at least to aim at realis- ing in action. The proof he offers of this is that each one actually does desire his own happiness. But it may surely be objected that the natural immediate conclusion from this, on Mill’s own method, is that Own Happiness, not Universal Happiness, is what each one ought to desire: the argument leads primarily to the principle of Egoistic instead of Universalistic Hedonism.” This is incontrovertible, and a heavy blow at the foundations of Mill’s whole ethical teach- 1 Methods of Ethics, p. 365. 11 What ts right conduct ? 27 ing. The fact is, that there is an ambiguity in Mill’s words, such a fallacy as he, above all men, delighted in detecting in others. The termination -able or -ible in English has more than one meaning. Sometimes it implies the possibility of the action implied in the verb to which it is appended ; sometimes the excellence or goodness of that action. Audible is apphed to things which can be heard, visible to things which can be seen; but these words do not in the least imply that things ought to be heard or seen. But the term desirable usually does not mean that the thing of which it is asserted can be desired, but that it should be desired, that it is men’s business to desire it. Muill’s argument is clearly only a play upon words. Of course any one would allow to him that people can desire happiness, and that they do desire it; but to assume that therefore they ought to desire it is to make the fatal leap from the fact to the ideal. It requires the major premiss whatever is, 7s right to make it at all conclusive, and Mill would have been the last to pass that thesis. Nothing, then, can be clearer than that there is no path whatever for argument from the psychological statement that men desire their own happiness, to the Utilitarian precept that we ought to seek the happiness of the greatest number. It is the more important to disentangle this knot of fallacies, because there can be no sort of doubt that Utilitarianism owes very much of its success among modern thinkers to the belief that it possesses some sort of proof derived from experience; that it does not, like other ethical systems, boldly assume a certain end of life as the most desirable, but rather finds its end from a study of human nature and the constitution 28 Fatth and Conduct CHAP. of society. People who are tired of ideals of all kinds seek refuge in it to escape the pain of the contempla- tion of what ought to be, and to rest wholly in what is and has been. Vain hope! So long as man acts at all he must act for an object, and it is impossible that he should find that object anywhere save in the realm of the imagination, among the things which are not, but ought to be. Thus both the propositions on which the system of ethics advocated by Utilitarians is based, turn out to be worthless, and entirely unfit to bear a super- structure of theory. Happiness is not a definite and unmistakable thing, nor is there any obvious reason why happiness and that alone should be the one thing to be sought. Let us here leave the theories of Utility, which, after all, belong to the times before the unfolding of those luminous ideas of evolution and development which have of late served to remodel the sciences which deal with the physical world, and may here- after remodel most of the historical sciences. From the writings of the great teachers of the School of Evolution we may expect light on the fundamental problems of ethics with more confidence than from the narrow and provincial school of the Utilitarian philo- sophers. And light we shall scarcely fail to obtain, though it may not be sufficient to illuminate for us all the abysses of our subject. To modern men of science two views are suggested as to the nature of virtue. One of these we might style the historical view, and connect specially with the writings of Auguste Comte and others who main- tain the continuity of all history. The other we may — —_ eee oe I What ts right conduct ? 29 eall the biological view, and connect with the writings of Darwin and Spencer. From both views we may learn much, but neither is entirely satisfactory, with- out addition and enlargement. Examination of conduct from the purely historical point of view would seem to suggest that a careful consideration of the course of moral development in the past may show us what the nature of virtue is, and by what landmarks we should guide our lives in the future. Notoriously this view underlies the whole teaching of Auguste Comte, and it has a great attrac- tion for other writers, who, however they may differ from him in principles and in results, agree with him in looking on the history of man as the course of development of an organism. From this point of view it might seem that the mere fact, when fully estab- lished, that the progress of human society is a regular evolution following certain ascertainable laws, would at once suggest a new theory in ethics. What have we to do, a believer in evolution might say, but to continue on into the future, in thought, the line which we trace in the past? If we have observed the direction in which a plant is growing we may readily judge the direction of its future growth. If we have traced the history of some variety of animal since it branched off from the parent stem, we have the best possible grounds for judging of its course of development in the future. In the same way a knowledge of the past history of a people must needs help us to foretell the history of that people in the future. And our observation of the course of ethical development in the past will enable us to form an opinion as to what will be its course hereafter. 30 Faith and Conduct CHAP, Thus it might seem that we have only to follow on into the future one by one the converging lines of the past history of ethics, in order to discover the constituent parts of a perfect morality. For example, it may be said, our age has witnessed in many fields the abolition of exclusive privilege; it therefore seems that democratic equality les before as an inevitable goal, and therefore as something desirable. Belief in unseen spiritual powers in the world is not so common in modern days as it was in the Middle Ages; its final extinction, therefore, may be expected in the line of development. Reasoned activity is usurping much of the province formerly occu- pied by habit and instinctive action ; it is clearly, then, in the line of human perfection that instinct should make way for reason. Feelings of universal philan- thropy are gaining on mere patriotism, and patriotism is gaining on local interests and sympathies; therefore the good man will expect broader sympathies to oust narrower ones, and will do what he can to secure that result. In short, let the observed line of human pro- gress in the past, say the line A B, be continued in a straight line to the point C, at C will be found the ideal morality required. The idea of development is very fruitful, but does not make sufficient account of the fact that change and improvement are not the same thing. A human body develops, but occasionally the line of its changes lies through disease and danger. A physician who is called to attend a patient afflicted with consumption has not to encourage, but to hinder, the ordinary course of development. So the moralist may find himself in a state of society in which habits are deteriorating, 11 What ts right conduct ? 31 and in which the best thing he can do is to practise a violent and unreasoning conservatism. Nor does it do much good to bring in the distinction between healthy and unhealthy, normal and abnormal, development. Suppose a moralist, believing in the steady develop- ment of human morality, to have lived in the times so terribly painted by Tacitus, when the Roman world could neither endure its vices nor their remedies, by what tests would he distinguish the true and healthy development of morality from its fevers and abscesses ? From the modern point of view we should say that at that time the world was growing better chiefly in two respects ; the feeling of one universal humanity was being fostered by the Stoics, and deeper notions of virtue were being introduced by the Christians. But there was no observer of the time who thought so. The cosmopolitan equality of peoples at Rome, and the influx of strange religions from the East, were just two of the symptoms on which Juvenal dilates as proving the utter corruption of Roman society. If Epictetus, or some other of the great moralists of the time, had produced in thought the lne leading from Fabius Cunctator to Vespasian, where would it have brought him? Assuredly not into the Middle Ages, which we yet clearly see to have been times of real greatness and improvement. And indeed, we need not go back to Roman times, when our own may be just as well instanced. Is it safe for us to assume that we English are in all the points in which we differ from the English of Hampden’s time better than they ? Have we more steadfast courage, or must we say that courage is a vice, which disappears in a erowing society? Are we more courteous than the 32 Faith and Conduct CHAP. Black Prince, more enterprising than Raleigh? Is it not absurd to suppose that every change in the morals of society, or even every deep and lasting change, is for the better? He who thinks so must be but a superficial student of history. It is not necessary, before admitting this reasoning, to abandon all belief in the future of the race. If we compare times distant enough one from the other, and if we eliminate what is clearly unhealthy, we may see enough to strengthen into belief our hope of the final triumph of good in the world. When by long practice a certain virtue has become innate in every child, it will not easily again be lost; while vice, on the con- trary, being never at one with itself, has a constant tendency to break down. Great inventions like that of printing raise to a far greater height the posszble excellence of the masses, and by lhmiting the kingdom of ignorance increase that of light. All here main- tained is that our eyes cannot take a wide enough view of the entire course of human growth and development to distinguish its essence from its acci- dents. As the tide comes in, to use a hackneyed but excellent metaphor, the water gradually gains on the land, but has seasons of apparent retrogression. And compared with the length of time during which man has existed on the earth, the portion of time spoken of by history seems but a few moments. How sanguine, then, to expect, as many do, to find a visible law of progress operating in the last century or so. We are of course at liberty to believe that we are on the crest of an advancing, not in the wake of a receding wave ; but if we do so believe, we must justify ourselves, not by any attempt to deduce from mere inspection a law II What ws right conduct ? 33 of progress, but by an appeal to the ideals of man and his aspirations. It thus appears that although we should be very foolish if we made light of the knowledge in regard to conduct which is furnished by history, yet history is not by itself capable of marking us out a course for the future. Duty has a higher law than past history can furnish. Nor shall we find an all-sufficient guide in those general laws which modern sociology has dis- covered, and which, wisely considered, are full of instruction for all; such as, that progress is from the indefinite to the definite, from the simple to the complex, from homogeneity to heterogeneity, and the like. These are facts which the moral philosopher must ever bear in mind, but they are not concrete and exact enough to help us much in determining the future of morality, and of scarcely any use to us when, as individuals, we desire to discover what is the path of virtue for ourselves. At such a time intellect and science lead us but a little way. We must next turn to the English School of Evolution, to see if, amid its teachings, we can find any new light as to the nature of the supreme good. The Darwinian discoveries make known not only the fact of progress, but also the method in which it takes place, namely, natural selection, with competition and survival of the fittest. It would be easy to form from such data an ethical law—TZhat conduct 1s the best wn reality which tends to make the doer survive vm the struggle for existence, and produce descendants fit for the world in which we live. Or, if perhaps this defini- tion may seem too narrow and egoistic, it may be easily expanded into—TZhat conduct is the best which D 34 Faith and Conduct CHAP. tends most to make the family or the community of the doer likely to survive and multiply. Just as that mud- fish is best which is most closely of the colour of mud, so as to escape its enemies, and just as that wolf is best which runs fastest and overtakes its prey most easily, so that man is best who possesses most faculties for doing the work of man and escaping man’s enemies whether living or inanimate. ‘This may perhaps be as well put in Mr. Spencer’s form as any: Zhe man 18 the best man whose internal organisation best accords with his environment. | Thus we get several formule for the definition of perfect virtue. Some of them are very valuable, but none, as hitherto interpreted, is fully satisfactory. Let us consider the formula that right action is action fitted to man’s environment—that the sum of his duties is to make that which is within him cor- respond to that which is without. By that which is without is in this phrase meant the visible surrounding world. If this be the case, it will seem that the true and sufficient guide in matters of conduct will be observation and experience. Now the visible environment of man is twofold— physical and social. He has to do with the world of matter and the world of other selves. We shall have to consider two questions in regard to each of these spheres: first, as to the amount of influence which each exercises over man; and second, as to man’s faculties for learning how to adapt himself to each. | To begin with the power exercised over man by the physical world, it is at once obvious that there is the greatest and most essential difference between man’s 1 What ws right conduct ? 35 relation to the scheme of nature and the relation borne to it by the lower animals. To these latter it may be the highest virtue to adapt themselves to physical surroundings, at all events when they are in a wild state. But to man this is evidently but a small part of virtue, and the lowest kind of it, if indeed it can properly be called virtue at all. If a man intends to live on the earth at all he is compelled to make allow- ance for, and bow to, the laws which regulate matter and his own physical frame, which is made up of matter. If he lives in filth and foul air, no wisdom and no goodness will save him from disease and death. If he eats and drinks unwholesome things, no good intention will make them agree with him. But the physical environment of man is not fixed, as it is for animals, who cannot change it, but must merely wait on nature. Man modifies his surroundings to a great extent at his will; he acts upon nature just as nature upon him. He can change the productions, the aspect, the very climate of the country where he dwells. By wearing clothes and building houses he makes a climate for himself; by the invention of fire he makes all sorts of food palatable and nutritious. As he advances nature recedes before him. Every advance in civil- isation involves a fresh victory over physical nature. She starts as the mistress of man, but she becomes his slave, a slave ever more obedient and humble as years go by, and the power which she jealously guards of retaliating on man for neglect of her directions grows every day more restricted. To man alone of living creatures there is opened an endless vista of victories over the physical world. Man’s power over the social world, the world of his 36 Faith and Conduct OHAP. fellow-creatures, is more limited. It might seem easier to move men than physical forces, but it 1s not so; human nature is a stubborn thing, and develops according to laws which admit of but little change. Very few are the men who in the course of history have been able radically to alter the social medium into which they were born. But, on the other hand, though we cannot greatly alter the tendencies and tone of society, yet we can to a great extent withdraw ourselves from them. ‘The influence of others does not follow us like the power of nature into solitude and into the closet; there we can shut out intruders. And the men who are strong can dare, even when among their fellow-creatures, to act in defiance of their pres- sure, to take a path and cleave to it in spite of the opinion of men. The selfish man does it in pursuit of his own interests, and the religious or moral reformer does it in pursuit of what he considers a good end. Still more have small coteries, when they agree among themselves, the power of living outside of the general stream of life and feeling, as an eddy maintains itself in a river under the shelter of a shelving bank in spite of the pressure of the river. Thus it appears to be by no means a full account of human virtue that it consists in self-adaptation to our material and social surroundings. Such a view of human excellence leaves out of account man’s power to modify his surroundings, which is exactly the thing wherein man differs most from animals, and wherein resides the power of development and progress. But having reached this point, we must point out that if the view of man’s surroundings be extended to its real limit, then the view that it is his highest duty II What ts right conduct ? 37 to accommodate himself to them becomes defensible and true. For man belongs not only to the physical frame of things, and to a surrounding world of other selves, but also to an encompassing spiritual universe— a universe quite different from that which is visible, and above all different in this, that in the spiritual universe the facts are ideas and possibilities. In it that which might be is the reality, and that which at present exists 1s the mirage; the possibility is the spirit, and the actuality only the body in which it dwells. This is the greatest and deepest of all the facts of our lives. Few indeed are those who do not recognise it as a fact. But its very greatness makes it hard to grasp. And a thousand writers, since men began to speculate on themselves and their surroundings, have expressed it in a thousand forms. It is like the air around us, of which we in our ordinary moods are scarcely conscious, yet without which we could not live for a minute. It is like the force of gravity, seldom the object of direct contemplation, yet conditioning every movement and every thought. “In him,” said St. Paul, “we lve and move and have our being.” And the modern poet replies: “Closer is he than breathing, and nearer than hands and feet.” In vari- ous ages the spiritual power which rules the world has been variously regarded and spoken of. And in modern days there are some who suppose that we need speak of it no longer. Vain dream! Let a man try to live without food, to walk where there is no ground, to live in contact with human beings without liking or disliking them, but never let him try to act in independ- ence of the spiritual power which sets the bounds of 38 Faith and Conduct CHAP. good and evil, and is the source of the ideas which slowly, in the infinite ages, form the world and human society after themselves. This spiritual force is not only the most important but the most real of all our surroundings. All else may be illusion, this is an eternal fact. And while we may change our physical and social surroundings, this force remains unchanged. We may to some extent turn our back upon it, and we may try to act independ- ently, but it remains all the same eternal and un- changed. Moral laws cannot be removed or altered. That no one can do what he knows to be wrong without remorse and misery, that no one can act unselfishly without feeling better and more healthy—these are facts as independent of man’s will as the facts of astronomy or of electricity, and of infinitely greater practical im- portance, since the facts of astronomy and of electricity demand our attention but rarely, but the sanctions of conduct may apply to every deed of our conscious hours. And while man may make of electricity a mere servant to do his will in the world, he is on the other hand entirely subject to the moral laws of the world, and cannot change them in the least degree. As then we live in a threefold sphere, and two of the elements of which it is composed are of a modifiable kind, while the third is altogether unmodifiable, it is clear that this last element must form the ultimate norm or standard by which human progress must be guided and regulated. It appears then to result that if man’s highest good be to live in accordance with the laws of the universe in which he lives, it is above all the laws of the spiritual world to which he will have to give heed. It will seem likely that the more completely our lives are II What ts right conduct 2 39 in accord with those laws, the more they will prosper and be in health; the more they are at variance with the highest laws, the more frail and unstable is their condition, the more sure are they to be suddenly cast down or to slowly decay. A life so at variance with the power which ultimately rules it is in a chronic state of insurrection, and will be certainly put down, is in a perpetual disease and cannot be far from death. But revolt and disease are conditions incompatible with any sort of happiness; if then, as all moralists are agreed, it 1s man’s business to be happy in the world, his only safe course will be to seek wellbeing through submis- sion to higher law. It is well, however, in speaking of the spiritual powers of the world as man’s environment to enter a caveat against misconceptions. The phrase, if used baldly, may seem inadequate, even presumptuous. For in biology we have to consider the medium which surrounds living things as a thing to be made use of and appropriated. The living individual seizes on parts of its environment and absorbs them for its own purposes ; it grows by appropriating what is without, and advancing its personality at the expense of the medium. It need scarcely be pointed out that there is in spiritual matters no such process of appropriation. There the task is the opposite, to subordinate one’s self to surrounding moral law; so that it shall live in us and absorb us, instead of our absorbing any part of it. This is a distinction so fundamental that we must always use the utmost caution in transferring the language of biology to this more exalted sphere. The social medium is between the other two; it is neither recklessly to be used for any mere personal 40 Faith and Conduct CHAP. Ope ae ig eg development or advantage, as 1s the physical medium, nor on the other hand are we right in entirely subordi- nating to it our personalities. We have to live for others, and yet to live according to the highest law we can discover, so as not to be mere idle flatterers of the desires and wishes of those about us, but rather a power to raise the tone of the society in which we dwell, and make it more fully show forth the will of the moral ruler of the world. With such explanations and limitations we are willing to accept the phrase of evolution, making the internal organisation correspond to the external environ- ment, as an expression of the swmmum bonum or supreme end of conduct. But it is clear that these explanations and limitations are important, and go to the root of the matter. They are quite fatal to any hasty and materialistic attempt to place the virtue of man on the same level as that of animals, or lightly to deduce the true law of ethics from the mere con- sideration of man’s surroundings at any point in his long and complicated history. Let it be called man’s virtue to adapt himself to the highest law of his being: but then, What is that highest law ? Our assertion is that in all the higher branches of conduct there is an ideal element, that our conduct has to be conformable to certain ideas which exist outside us. For every man, every society, every nation, there is a possible best; and the more nearly that possible best is attained the better it will be for the man, the society, and the nation. History and biography reveal to us in the past an approach to the embodiment of . these highest ideas in the lives of nations and men. Religion, poetry, and art impress us from time to time IT What ts right conduct ? Al with a sudden feeling of their reality, and their reality for us; and we are raised and strengthened until the vulgar motives of daily life regain sway over us. The more we think of these ideas, the more do they seem to us the only real things; and in comparison with them the material world seems but a bubble, and the lives of men like passing clouds. They live for ages, we for a day. ‘They may become embodied in us in some degree, but if we refuse to embody them they none the less exist without us, and overshadow our lives if they do not fill them. We shall consider in the next chapter what faculties we possess for the apprehension of these disembodied ideas, how we are to supply the deficiencies of the mere understanding, which can by no arrangement of facts, and no observation of tendencies, find out the path of virtue. CHAPTER HI HOW CAN WE KNOW WHAT IS RIGHT? To believers in the theory of utility the problem of discerning what is right will seem to admit of an easy solution. If the greatest happiness of the greatest number be the sum of good, and if happiness be a thing quite definite and understood by all, then it is quite clear that the reasoning faculties of any and all of us are sufficient to tell us what it is right to do in all affairs of life. The matter becomes one of calcula- tion, rather elaborate calculation it is true, but still a matter requiring only such faculties as are used in mathematics. And this is certainly the view of Bentham and Austin, and all the more uncompromis- ing advocates of the principle of Utility. To some of those, also, who maintain an evolutional view in ethics, intellect will still seem an all-sufficient. guide in matters of conduct, but that intellect will turn its attention less to arithmetical calculations and tables of statistics than to history. It will trace the course of conduct in the past, and thence try to con- tinue it into the future. That such proceedings may at. times be useful and help us, more especially in those parts of morality which are simple and definite cuar. in S7ow can we know what 7s right? 43 in character, is not to be denied. But we have shown cause for thinking that they offer no test which is final and complete. Far more valuable for the discernment of right and wrong than any mere train of reasoning is experience. We are indeed most ready to admit that experience does give us guidance in conduct, and guidance without which we should be helplessly mazed in the conduct of life. But experience alone is not all-sufficient ; we need other guidance besides. As regards living in accordance with the laws of the physical world, experience is certainly an excellent guide. The science of health and disease, however its development falls short of what we might hope, is yet firmly founded and fast advancing. Its general principles, indeed, have been fixed since the days of Hippocrates. If any man claimed to know by any intuition or any analogical reasonings what food would be good for the health, or what habits would preserve it, rather than by citing the results of experience, we should surely not listen to him. We can see and feel health, and can judge by the ordinary faculties of every day what causes produce it. We can see sick- ness, and by questioning the sick man ascertain what brought him into such misery. Science which is essentially nothing more than well- arranged experience, is in our days perfectly well aware of its right to dictate to us in all matters relating to our health and our relations to the forces of nature. Indeed men of science are very apt not merely to preach in the pulpit which really belongs to them, but to dictate to us our duties in life generally. The needs of the body are fixed and definite, and continually 44 Fatth and Conduct CHAP, obtrude themselves upon us, so that the philosophy which understands them and shows how they may be met, has a natural advantage, an advantage of the greatest value in these days of moral chaos. Thus sanitary authorities claim moral authority: and there are hundreds amongst us who regard all laws and all customs which appear to have a salutary tendency on the physical health of the community as necessarily moral and right. They regard a healthy mind as a sort of corollary of a healthy body, and consider crime as a kind of disease of the structure of the brain. It 1s naturally among physicians that we find this material- istic way of regarding human life most prevalent: but after all it is a pedantry which must necessarily be confined to the few. The course of life is too strong and vigorous to be for long confined in so narrow a channel. A few hypochondriacs may accept such views, but the rough sense of mankind makes light of them. Rather than holding that a healthy body makes a healthy mind, we shall reverse the proposition, and make a healthy body the corollary and result of healthy mind and right conduct. Small indeed is the fear that a people who live uprightly and honourably will physic- ally degenerate ; but it would be possible, on the other hand, to bring forward many cases in which a decay of manners and morals has ruined the physique of a whole race. Therefore a wise man will set bounds, and not very wide bounds, to the interference of medical science in his conduct in life: he will allow it to forbid him many things but prescribe to him few. When, however, we quit the physical surroundings of man for his moral and social surroundings, then we at once reach the realm of ideals, and science has to ree Flow can we know what rs right ? A5 content herself with a very subordinate task. Her voice drops at once from the categorical imperative to the conditional. She can no longer order us to do this or that as a condition of flourishing or even of exist- ence, but merely advise us that if we desire this or that end we had best hear her advice as to the means by which the end may be reached. Medicine tells us what conduct in regard to the outer world must be good if we would keep our health. But, as we have already seen, history does not tell us thus clearly and distinctly what conduct we must pursue in regard to our less obvious surroundings. Parties and sects differ in these matters as widely as possible. A man may of course accept the teaching of the particular sect among whom he is brought up. But if he quit that teaching, reso- lutely determined to find out what it is right for him to do, he will find it necessary to take a long voyage, and is indeed fortunate if he at last reach a haven where it is well with him. Conduct is a personal matter: our will is ours to act or not to act. It is our own selves and not another who must discover what is the right course to pursue. If then mere reasoning cannot guide us aright in this matter, if the opinions of men differ widely one from the other, and if there be here no science to prescribe what is right for man as man, we must turn to the consideration of our practical faculties and try there to discover the law of conduct, to discern what is right, and why we do the right. The simplest of all accounts which can be given as to our faculties of discovering right and wrong is that which states right and wrong to be qualities of actions, just as softness and hardness are qualities of material 46 Faith and Conduct CHAP. objects, and which asserts that each of us has a moral sense whereby we can discern these moral qualities, just as by sight we discern colour and shape, or by touch warmth or cold. This is a view which has in its day had able defenders; yet to state it is to show its absurdity. It is misleading to speak of the faculty of moral discernment as a sense. It is indeed like a sense in its immediate and instinctive judgment ; but it differs absolutely from a sense in the most important respects. We are all agreed as to the facts of sense, European and Asiatic, savage and civilised, rich and poor alike; they are true for man as man. But as to the morality of actions we diverge very widely; no two of us indeed altogether agreeing. Each nation and sect and family has its own scale of virtue. Take a Scotchman and a Frenchman of ordinary cultivation and average virtue, and question each of them as to the rightness of strictly observing Sundays, or as to the comparative importance of truth-telling and charity, and the result will be to show the widest differences of view in elementary matters of morality. And if it be so, they cannot both have a moral sense. If we called the faculty a moral sentiment we should use a phrase far more defensible. When we listen to a strain of music, sense tells us what are the sounds of which it consists, but it is not sense but sentiment which tells us whether the strain is pleasing or unpleasing. On the first point we do not dispute; the latter is matter of infinite differences of opinion. Our judgment of right and wrong in actions far more nearly resembles the second of these judgments than the first, for it also is a matter on which men differ widely, and which involves the ideal. The natural method in which to trace out the nature a m1 Flow can we know what ts right ? A7 of the moral sentiments is introspection and an exam- ination of our active faculties. If there be in usa faculty of direction which leads us to good rather than evil, which shows us what it is right for us to do, and arouses us to follow that which is right, then it might naturally seem that such a power would be visible to a mind turned in on itself, that psychology could explain its working and analyse its nature. And yet such a hope is destined to a very partial fulfilment. In all mental analysis we labour under serious dis- advantages; we can only observe thought and will as they are presented to consciousness,—that, is as if we had to decide by means of anatomical study the facts of physiology. The mind is ever active, and when we bring it into the field of observation its action is thwarted and distorted and turned from its original character. Nothing is more destructive than self- consciousness, not merely of vigorous and _ healthy action, but even, as we see in everyday life, of graceful or natural pose. Hence when we look in on our own minds we are exposing ourselves to the risk of a mis- take at every turn. And the more so when the very subject of our investigation 1s active movement. It is almost as if one should dissect a man’s leg in order to discover his motive in going to this or that place. We may indeed lay it down as a general rule that the more healthy and vigorous conduct is, the less it enters into consciousness. Consciousness implies a lapse of time between impulse and action, and every moment spent between the two tends more and more to make the action feeble and constrained. The beauty of conduct, like the beauty of active physical exercise, consists in rapidity and grace of movement, and absence 48 Faith and Conduct CHAP, of hesitation and doubt. The man of strong will is not he who long deliberates and finally determines in one direction or another, but the man who directly he has heard the circumstances of a case knows what he means to do in it. The virtuous man is not he who decides after long conflicts to do what he thinks to be right, but the man to whom virtue has so much become a second nature that he cannot hesitate to do rightly. As in the arts so in conduct, the greater the personality the more rapid and the more unerring the execution. If any man pause long, and carefully consider the right and the wrong of any contemplated deed until the impetus which urged him to activity is entirely exhausted, he will find the question from the specula- tive point of view insoluble. Before long, unless the matter be one of quite elementary morality, he will learn to doubt what is right and what is wrong; and -the longer he reflects the more he will doubt and hesitate. In so simple a matter, for instance, as voting for one candidate for Parliament or another, it is quite easy, by considering every side of the question, to make it impossible to vote at all. But to think of life as a series of deeds planned with a view to particular purposes is to take quite a false view of it. Life is not an elaborate piece of machinery, but a living and growing organism. Its development is like that of a tree. And so if instead of dissecting branches to discover the principles of hfe, we observe which way the sap flows in winter and which way in summer, how the flowers come forth and how the fruit succeeds them, we may be able to discern a law of growth and development. Most men have at times in their life experienced a ee — —— TI flow can we know what ts right ? AQ voice which has suddenly made itself heard within them forbidding them to perform some action on which they were bent, and that with such clearness and force that either they have turned back on the very thresh- old of action, or else, persevering in their purpose, they have felt a bitter sense of guilt and shame. Socrates, sceptic as he was in some things, yet was fully convinced that there dwelt in him a warning voice ordering him back from whatever was wrong for him. This voice, which the ancients called by the general name Demon, which they applied to any person or manifestation which seemed to them of more than mortal dignity, is familiar to all of us under the name of conscience. No one, unless he drown thought in excess, or paralyse it by incessant activity, can do a thing which he knows to be wrong without a distinct protest from this inward monitor ; no one can obey its voice without feeling the better and the happier, or can disregard its warnings without feeling that he has sunk in the scale of humanity and taken a step towards the abyss of sin and misery. And those who know the history of human lives, whether by experience of men or from the discipline of books, know how great a part in human affairs is played by the feelings of content arising from the sense of time well spent, and of remorse for past misdeeds,—feelings so strong that they not only tinge the life, but mould the character, and finally indelibly express themselves in the character of the face. But though conscience be most clear and strong in its negative utterances, yet its voice is by no means always negative. It not only tells us what to avoid, but it incites us to do better things than we have done E 50 Faith and Conduct CHAP. hitherto. And no one can work well and thoroughly in any department of activity without often feeling this strong call to what is best in that department. Few pleasures are greater than that enjoyed by the worker who feels the character of his work rising in obedience to this impulse, nor can misery be more complete than that felt by the worker who steadily opposes the better impulse and keeps down his work at the old level, or even sinks below it. When the good impulse leads to very brilliant results it is in ordinary language termed an inspiration, but when the results are less marked the character which it shows is the same. The kind of work wherein we may trace the prompting to better efforts most clearly is the work in the world which we call conduct—our dealings with each other and the world. The man who sees that his conduct is false, cowardly, and selfish, and feels no desire to alter it for the better, is a monster, and rare as monsters are. A thousand times he may feel prompted to raise the tone of his conduct, and a thou- sand times he may fail from the force of habit, indo- lence, and temptation, but the wish to do better is nevertheless still present and survives many failures. And however completely a man may stifle the better impulses, yet he will now and again hear them in spite of all. Butler remarks with perfect justice that a mere consideration of the scheme of man’s nature will show that conscience should be obeyed. It is a faculty which claims the direction of our conduct, and if it is not allowed to direct conduct, it becomes a useless incumbrance, an organ without a function. It is as Se It flow can we know what ts right ? 51 evidently made for the guidance of our lives as a rudder is for the guidance of a ship, or reins for the guidance of horses. And, in fact, we need not occupy ourselves with proving that men ought to follow the dictates of conscience, for any one who systematically disobeyed them would soon be destroyed by the course of the world, and cease to exist. But though men ought to follow their conscience it does not follow that conscience is always right. The writer of these pages does not contend, evidently no one could contend, that every man at all times has within him a monitor infallibly directing him to virtue. This would be equivalent to maintaining that actions done conscientiously can never be wrong—an obvious absurdity, when we know that many of the worst ' deeds recorded in history were done in pursuance of conscientious feelings. This is a notorious fact, and it is a notorious fact that people about us continually do what is wrong, and what they afterwards allow to have been wrong, without any qualms of conscience. It will be necessary to explain that facts like these are really no argument against our view of morals. Virtue is a progressive revelation to man, and deeds which to our apprehension seem wrong may not have been so at the time they were done. It is as unjust to judge the deeds of past ages by the moral standard of to-day as it would be to condemn the paintings of an Esquimaux or a Red Indian because they did not conform to our notions of colouring and perspective. Even highly-developed arts, such as that of Japan, are in some respects childish; and in the same way nations at a high stage of civilisation may have a morality on some sides undeveloped. The first 52 — Fatth and Conduct CHAP. requisite for considering the history of morals is a share of the historic or comparative spirit which insists on judging the deeds of each age by the standard of that age, and praising them when they rise above it, even if in any way they seem to fall short of ideal perfection. Still, after making such allowances, we must admit that many deeds recorded in history were wrongly done, though done with the approval of conscience. And to find such deeds we need not turn to history, but just look at the deeds of our fellow-men, or recall incidents in our own lives. What does this prove ? It proves simply this, that we have not only to obey our conscience, but we have also to keep our conscience true to something outside us. A mariner cannot do better than steer by his compass, yet the compass may be out of order, and then he steers to de- struction. A man must regulate his employments by his watch, but his watch may be wrong, and then he will reculate them badly. Just so must a man abide by his conscience ; but if the conscience cease to corre- spond to the highest facts of his environment, then he will act to evil end. | The only way in which our conduct can be brought to conform to what is most fixed and highest in our surroundings is not only by following conscience, but also by producing a concord between our conscience and the eternal purposes according to which man was made and is sustained. These purposes may be to some extent discovered by reasoning and experience, as we showed at the beginning of this chapter. But that which is highest in them can only be reached by some kindof inspiration. The divine ideas must be III Flow can we know what ts rroht ? ote revealed to the conscience before it can understand the nature and the ends of virtue. It is too early in this work to say much as to the inspiration of conduct. We return to the subject in a future chapter. And it is not a matter in which investigation is very successful. Nature seems studi- ously to hide from us all her most important and wonderful processes. No one knows how or when the infant becomes a separate personality from its mother, or at what point of its life it first attains consciousness. The most skilled observer will fail to trace the begin- nings of a disease that soon grows strong enough to destroy a strong man. Who can tell at what moment he first felt the stirrings of the passion of love, or when he became aware of the weight of moral respon- sibility ? When some philosopher is able to tell us how it was that George Eliot, living an uneventful life amid a small circle of friends, was able to recall and make real the feelings and emotions which stir the hearts of people in utterly different conditions from any she ever experienced, nay, how it was that she even lived again the life of Florentines of the days of Savonarola, then we may fairly look to that philo- sopher for some account of the way in which the divine ideas are revealed in the conscience of man. Mean- time we must confess that the process is almost, though not quite, as difficult to explain as is that other process by which we become aware of the objects in the material world, or of the existence of human beings about us,—almost, though not quite, as mysterious as the vital process by which the child develops into the full-grown man. Generally, then, we may say that when conscience 54 Faith and Conduct CHAP. i ee ee Ee is in a good and healthy state its action in matters outside reasoning and experience lies in the reception of the divine impulses which urge man to be better than he is,and in looking at the field of activity in the light of those impulses. Its eyes should ever be turned upwards. Only we must remember that we have, as St. Paul says, “this treasure in earthen vessels.” Though the light which shines in upon our lives be pure and wholesome, it is reflected from cankered or tarnished surfaces. If from the cradle one of our race gave himself up wholly to better influences, and never mingled a selfish or unworthy feeling with his motives for action, then the impulses at least of such a man would be purely virtuous, though even he might often fail of the best course for want of fully understanding all the circumstances of particular calls to action. But none of us has a mind thus pure; from the very first we neglect the better course and follow the worse; we allow selfishness, idleness, and passion to fill us with clamour until we cannot distinguish the gentle voice which calls to right and to duty, and constantly mis- take for it some promptings of our worse natures. We are like water into which the light falls; the fouler and muddier water utterly quenches it and prevents its passage, the pure water at all events refracts it and turns it aside. It will occur to many readers that though some- times, especially in momentous matters, they feel a power within them distinctly pointing them to certain courses of action rather than others, yet this is the exception and not the rule. To experience so direct an inspiration seems to belong rather to great and exalted characters, or to characters of more ordinary c= UT flow can we know what ts right ? 55 kind only at times of mental and moral exaltation. In the ordinary choice between good and evil, which occupies so much of our waking time, we act rather from habit than conviction. And even in the case of actions where we hesitate and only on deliberation decide to pursue the better course, our choice may seem to be guided by considerations of a more mun- dane sort—desire to preserve a consistent character, pride, the desire to secure the good opinion of other men, or admiration for some noble deed of friends or those of whom we have read. All this may be true, and yet it may not form an insuperable objection to the acceptance of the view above set forth. This may be made clear by means of a comparison. We know well that the source of natural light and warmth is the sun. If it did not daily shine in the heaven we should very soon perish and fade away. And yet in our goings and doings in the world we seldom, at least in this country, act in the direct rays of the sun. In our houses we hardly ever feel his direct influence. Often his rays only reach us through thick cloud and mist; but when the sky is cloudless, the light whereby we live does not come straight, but is reflected from a thousand objects about us, thrown from one surface to another, and finally reflected to our eyes. It is diffused light which makes life and action possible, and not solar beams. Yet no one on such grounds denies the sun to be the final source of light. It is the same in the realm of conduct. It is mainly through the inspiriting deeds and the _per- suasive words of others that the power of righteous- ness makes itself felt by us. The great moral heroes 56 — Fatth and Conduct CHAP. of the world have absorbed much of the direct influ- ence of that power, and they reflect it far and wide, standing up like beacons for all time. Their lives and sayings must always be the strongest incentives to goodness in the lives of most people. But besides these well-known and lofty beacons, there are lesser lights which serve to guide and inspirit us—lghts whose proximity to our own lives makes up for their want of illuminating power; a kind and patient friend, an acquaintance who shows an unselfish disposition or displays resignation and gentleness under the attacks of some painful disease, a parent who sets the ex- ample of a blameless life. These are the lights of our homes; but it will usually be found that the brighter and more steadfast their splendour shines, the more fully are they aware that it is but a borrowed reflection. Thus it is not only in our isolated state as con- scious and moral creatures that we hear the inner voice which speaks for righteousness. Indeed to many men who are of an objective nature, and not given to the probing of their own hearts, it is not at all in this way that better impulses come to bear on their lives. The conscience is not conversant only with the quality of our own deeds as good and evil, but it is not less energetic in approving or disapproving the deeds of others. We are unable to observe deeds of cruelty and injustice without feeling in our hearts the glow of a rush of passion, of burning indignation against the doer of such deeds. Even if we suspect that under such circumstances we might ourselves behave as ill, yet we feel that the deed is wrong, is an offence against the light of heaven and the constitution of the world; and if we would fain stifle the feeling we can- = =o ee a a II How can we know what ts right ? oF not do so. On the other hand, it is impossible for us to contemplate any deed nobly done, any act of mercy, of self-sacrifice and self-control, without a warm feeling of approbation, a feeling independent of will, spon- taneously filling the heart, and urging it to follow such precedent. To the bulk of mankind this vision of themselves, so to speak, in the mirror of the lives of others, is the strongest incentive to virtue. The force of imita- tion is very strong in all of us; and it is impossible that we should see in any one a deed we admire, without receiving a strong impulse to act in like fashion when circumstances permit. The effect on emotion, and through emotion on will, is direct and powerful, and not weakened by having to pass through the tortuous chambers of the mind. And so the force of example is in all the world the most powerful lever of conduct. But we are at present speaking of this moral approbation and disapprobation not as a source of action but as a source of feeling and of perception. From feeling what we ought to do ourselves, and from admiring the good deeds of others, we pass to the per- ception that alike our own hearts and the lives of others are but mirrors which reflect a light which shines above and beyond them, and which is itself one though it glances upon us from a thousand facets. The knowledge, then, of right and wrong, so far as it cannot be reached by reasoning or by experience, may be attained in some degree, in such degree as the knowledge of good and evil is attainable by man, by means of a twofold process. First we have to con- sult our conscience, and secondly we have to keep our 58 Faith and Conduct CHAP. conscience true to the realities of the world. But conduct is an entirely practical thing, and it is in practice that the rules of right and wrong conduct are discovered. If a man set himself, in an otiose and speculative mood, to discover whether his con- science did accord with the highest law, he would very probably fail, and lose himself in words and fancies. But in looking back on his conduct as it lies in the past, he will find it comparatively easy to see whether he acted conscientiously, and if so, whether rightly. And amid the actual stress of living, many doubts and difficulties, which in the study might seem serious, erow cloudy and vanish. If a snail tried to think out the form of his shell he would certainly fail; but when, by the exercise of his noblest functions, he has formed a shell, we can all of us see how well it conforms to his surroundings. It is the same with much of the highest human work. George Eliot. has recorded that she sat down to write some of her noblest scenes with- out any notion of the course they would take. In the same way it is not for man to plan but to act, and in acting to learn to act rightly, by keeping a certain attitude of mind towards that to which his conscience must learn to conform. Before leaving the subject of this chapter we must, in few words, meet an objection sometimes brought from the practical point of view against a strongly ideal view of ethics. Writers hike Mr. Henry Sidegwick, who see clearly the speculative weakness of the reason- ing schools of morality, turn on the opponents of those schools with a sort of argumentum ad hominem. Any of us, they say, who has practically to decide an im- portant point of conduct, does so by considering the ‘ ile i te a, HI Flow can we know what rs right ? 59 advantages and disadvantages of various possible courses, balancing the one against the other; and thus, whatever be thought of the doctrine of Utility specu- latively, the practical appeal to it is universal. We cannot, however, allow that this 1s an accurate statement of fact. Observation seems rather to show that people in general do not balance consequences, but follow the feeling at the time strongest. People of a cool and reflective turn of mind may amuse them- selves with reckoning up consequences; but even these usually end, like Brennus, by throwing a sword into the scale. Of course there are cases in which calcula- tion is of use, but in those kinds of action which especially come under the term conduct, it leads com- monly only to endless hesitation and weak and vacil- lating action. What then is to be done, practically, when the conscience gives no clear mandate? We should say that two or three things may be done. First, a man may look back over his life, and may try to discern there the true thread of action which leads into the future. He who doubts what he ought to do in the future does not usually doubt whether he has done rightly in the past, and may thus deduce the unknown from the known. And secondly, a man may consider carefully, and with some exertion of imagination, how one or the other course of conduct will harmonise with what is best in his surroundings. Or thirdly, he may try to look on the alternative courses of action with the dispassionate eyes of a mere spectator; for there are many whose feeling of moral right and wrong 1s far more easily excited by the deeds of others than their own. 60 Fatth and Conduct CHAP, III None of these courses is infallible, but certainly any of them is better than the helpless attempt to reckon up consequences. And none of them will be necessary, except in rare cases, to those in whom conscience is healthy and active. They must be con- sidered not as food for the healthy, but as dieting for the diseased, since the beauty of conduct les most in its freedom from self-consciousness. CHAPTER IV HOW SHALL WE DO WHAT IS RIGHT ? WE turn next to the third great question in regard to conduct, How can I compass what is right? And we shall find that the reasoning schools of ethics are in respect to this question even more hopelessly defective than they were shown to be in regard to the discovery and knowledge of right and wrong. Supposing these ethical systems to have established the rule of conduct, to have shown men how they ought to behave, it is obvious that this is in itself not enough: it is clear that they have to account for something further—why men do what they think to be right. If men be able of themselves, by mere reason- ing and experience, to discover what they ought to do and to do it, then religion must be confessed to be either altogether unnecessary in the world, or at all events to have nothing to do with conduct. But if, on the other hand, men cannot discover what is right, nor accomplish it without aid from above, religion stands justified. And if such aid is necessary for one thing of the two, either for knowing or doing, still religion remains necessary. In the last chapter we tried to show that a man must put himself into a certain rela- 62 Fatth and Conduct CHAP, tion towards his highest spiritual surroundings in order to discern right and wrong. In the present chapter we shall try to prove that he cannot choose the right and avoid the wrong unless he be aided from above. Is the teaching of Utility effective in the last-men- tioned matter? Supposing, for the sake of argument, that it has been proved that reason and observation are able to show us what course of conduct we ought to pursue in life, does reason help us practically to follow it? The advocates of the Utilitarian theory certainly try hard to show that there is a close relation between thinking it right to forward the happiness of the most and actually forwarding it. But their efforts can scarcely be called successful. Those who are in the habit of trying to bring strong motives to bear on everyday people tell us that the essential qualities, without which motives have usually small weight, are distinctness and near- ness. A promise of five pounds to-morrow will urge © to exertion many a man who could never be roused by an indefinite hope of getting his prospects improved. It is notorious that a person who orders goods on credit looks far less closely into their prices than if he paid for them in hard cash. Even death, though a certainty for every one, is yet by its obscurity and remoteness hidden so far out of the ken of ordinary people that they do not think of it unless they are ul or disappointed. It is another phase of this same law of human nature, that every one cares very much more about the pains and pleasures that come under his notice than about others of which he knows but which he does not witness. JI may know that there is a family dying of starvation at the other end of the IV Flow shall we do what ts right ? 63 town, but unless the case happen to strike my imagina- tion, it gives me far less pain and is far less likely to make me take some action than if I heard that my dog had lost his dinner. The impulses to action arise directly out of feelings, and feelings are not produced by mere thought and reflection, but arise from experi- ence, quite apart from the action of will. Thus it is that feeling and fancy guide our conduct. We cannot, with the greatest wish for justice in the world, give a greater pleasure to A whom we hate instead of a lesser one to B whom we love. Affection is like a central sun warming and gladdening far more readily and fully those bodies which are near than those which are far off. We all range all that we love about us in circles, circles growing larger and larger as they recede farther from ourselves, and it is really unreasonable to expect that our feelings for any that lie beyond our immediate neighbourhood shall prompt us to vigorous action. Nay, further, he whose affections are centred in some half-dozen people will make their good his end in life; he who has many friends, none of them supremely beloved, will mostly act either from selfish or from conscientious motives. To expect any creature to count the happiness of every person just as the happiness of one, and equally to rejoice over it whether he witnesses it or not, whether he wins gratitude through it or not, whether he sympathises with it or not, is plainly the most impracticable folly. This, then, is an impediment to the theory that our one end should be the promotion of the happiness of the most. If this be the recognised end of all action, it must be right and proper to count people by the head, and consider less whom we please 64 Faith and Conduct CHAP, than how many and how much. ‘Thus the ground is cut away from action by the destruction of healthy and natural motive, and mere sentiment is substituted for active goodwill. Moreover, before passing on, we must observe that if any teaching be immoral—that is to say, productive of evil conduct, it is the teaching which allows a man to weigh his own happiness against that of his neighbour, and deliberately to choose a greater happiness for himself instead of a | lesser happiness for the other. The very basis and root of all virtue is the denial of self, and if self- denial for the sake of another be declared unnecessary, nay even immoral, unless the happiness procured for the other be greater than the happiness sacrificed by oneself, there is an end to ideal virtue. It is not on such principles that heroes and martyrs are bred; and unless there were heroes and enthusiasts in virtue, the virtue of the most would sink to a deplorable level. Perhaps to the arguments of the last paragraph the Utilitarian might reply that the road to the production of general happiness is not a direct road, but an in- direct. It may be asserted that the only safe and right plan is not in each action to aim at an indis- criminate production of pleasure, but to look to the wellbeing of those nearest to us, convinced that such a course must in the long-run best tend to the general good. Now at first sight this reply may seem satis- factory enough, but it is also true that explanations and modifications of this sort completely destroy the value of the Utilitarian theory in a scientific aspect. But even if Utilitarianism could make to natural feeling the concession that the nearer persons stand to us the better is their claim on our service, it would IV How shall we do what ts right ? 65 reap small advantage from the admission. It would simply amount to saying this, “You must not work our principle to death, but temper it by means of your common sense.” But still there is no line drawn where common sense is to stop and Utilitarianism come in. Of course to do good to our friends and neighbours, however pleasant a part of morality, can scarcely be reckoned the whole of it. “Do not even the publicans the same ?” Everybody who is not drowned in selfish- ness is in the habit of acting and abstaining in order to please a few. But it scarcely occurs to anybody that it is a case of moral desert. It is quite clear that this habit of action may, just like the judging of indi- vidual deeds by their utility to the world in general, be carried a good deal too far. We have already spoken of another kind of Utili- tarianism which should take a higher view of happiness than regarding it merely as the filling of material needs, which should speak of higher and lower satis- factions, and should consider human nature as an organised frame with higher and nobler as well as baser parts. Perhaps it may be contended that the theory of Utility in this more enlightened form may have greater power over the will, or supply a stronger stimulus to virtue. We believe this notion to be entirely unfounded. On the contrary, while the pro- motion on purely Utilitarian grounds of the merely physical and social wellbeing of men has been some- times an inspiration quite strong enough to stimulate to an energetic and self-sacrificing career, it will be very hard to produce from the storehouse of history a single satisfactory instance of a man’s having so sacrificed himself for the sake, not of the comfort, but F 66 Faith and Conduct CHAP, of the moral and spiritual wellbeing of his fellows, merely on grounds of utility. The reformers and saviours of society have always a very vivid sense of their relations to the higher powers; what they have wanted is not the development but the salvation of men, and their motive, so far as it is self-respecting, is the love of duty, and, so far as it is unselfish, a burn- ing desire for the glory of God. Than desire of cul- ture, when cut off from religion, nothing is more egotistical, or more incapable of furnishing any ground for healthy and vigorous action in the world. But if Utilitarianism tries to rise to grasp such notions as salvation and the divine glory, it will find itself quite out of breath and paralysed. It is a solid bird of heavy flight, and cannot mount towards the sun like an eagle. But Utilitarianism belongs properly to the period before theories of evolution made their way in the world and entirely altered the foundations of the various sciences, not less of those concerned with man and society than those which are concerned with vegetable and animal organisms. It is probable that few who have entirely understood and assimilated the new views of society would accept the Utilitarian theory of ethics in the form in which it is put by Mill. In- deed, Mill himself, in spite of his high talents and splendid honesty, must be regarded as one who missed the drift of his time, and mistook a backwater for the stream of human thought. No one can read his works without feeling better and stronger, so manly and truth- loving is the spirit which pervades them; but there are few indeed among those who think who would choose to be called his disciples. IV How shall we do what ts right ? 67 The ethics of evolution, if evolution neglect the spiritual elements of life, remains as helpless in this field as Utilitarian ethics. We have already seen that this theory is not able to furnish us with a perfect ideal of moral development. It is not, on the other hand, able in itself to furnish to the will a sufficiently strong impulse to make it strive with energy towards the attainment of that ideal in oneself and in others. A man does not take so keen an interest in his remote descendants, who may probably never come into exist- ence at all, as to be willing to guide his conduct in life by the thought of what may be expedient for them. — And however devoted he be to evolution as a theory, he will scarcely be willing to sacrifice himself in order to make the course of evolution in the human race more speculatively perfect and uniform. Darwin, however, has made a deliberate attempt to prove that man’s intellect, combined with his social instincts, is quite sufficient to impel him to virtue ;? and it is due to the memory of so great a writer that we should with care and respect examine his argument. He points out, firstly, that man is a social animal, and feels instinctive sympathy with those with whom he comes in contact; and, secondly, that this social instinct acts on the. mind continually and without any intermission, whereas the lower and selfish instincts of man act only from time to time, and their force is not easily recalled to memory. As man, he remarks, is a being of great mental activity, reflections on his past conduct will be constantly passing through his mind ; and if he perceives that he has on any occasion sacri- ficed the gratification of the abiding social instinct to 1 Descent of Man, i. 70. 68 Faith and Conduct OHAP. the indulgence of some other instinct, such as hunger, which passes away, leaving small memory of itself behind, it is certain that such perception will cause him considerable pain. Then, at a later stage of the growth of moral sense among men, when they freely express their feelings, such expression must more or less constitute a law for whole communities; and respect for public opinion will compel people to do what is considered right. The power of approbation and disapprobation by our fellow-men on the course of conduct has long been acknowledged by moralists; and it plays a still more prominent part in the scheme of Bentham than in that of Darwin. Sut the fact that the force of the social instinct mainly consists in its abiding character has at least never been so clearly stated before. And no one can venture to deny that there is force in the argument set forth by Darwin. But this is not tantamount to saying that this one reason will account for men’s right-doing and for the growth of morality. His social and sympathetic nature may help a man towards knowing what he ought to do, and even towards wishing that he had done it; but every moralist knows what an enormous gap there is between even the last of these feelings and doing right. And as a matter of historical fact a very great part of the impulse towards moral action has come from feelings of a religious character. Indeed so great has been their practical power in matters of morality that we may well doubt, considering how slow the improvement in human con- duct has been from age to age, whether there would have been any such progress at all without religion. The fortress of virtue has, on the whole, held out against IV flow shall we do what ts right ? 69 the enemy; but would it have held out if half, and that the most determined and energetic half, of the garrison had been withdrawn? The ship of virtue has made slow way against the opposing tide, but would it have progressed at all if the mainsail had been cut down ? The processes mentioned by Darwin do really take place, but it does not follow that no other process is involved. The great philosopher confesses in his later works that in his earlier he attributed too much power to certain tendencies of his own discovery. And were he still alive he might perhaps be willing, with his noble candour, to admit that in this case also he was misled by a natural partiality for the discoveries of his own genius, In fact there are many sorts of virtue, and those the highest, which are not encouraged by the social feelings. These feelings will tend to make a man courteous, gentle, and friendly, but they will not nerve him to perform an unpopular duty or inspirit him in those cases in which he has to follow his conscience in despite of the opinions of those about him. Exclusive attention to the social feelings will produce a character charming and attractive in daily life, but weak, un- truthful, even radically unjust. It will make a pleasant comrade, but one unfit either to command or to obey, and quite unequal to heavy responsibility. Moreover, to recur to an argument already used, the existence of social feelings, even if it could account for the rise of the morality of individuals to the level of what is expected of them, would certainly not account for the rise of the moral tone of individuals far above the level usual around them. Yet this higher level in individuals is the first necessity for moral progress in 70 Faith and Conduct CHAP. the race. The gradual refinement of intellect does indeed gradually refine morality, but it does not raise its tone above selfishness and falsehood. Thus, incompetent as are observation and reasoning to point out the path of virtue to men, they are still less competent to lead men along that path when it is found. On the practical side the ethics of Utility and of Darwinism are even more defective than they were on the intellectual side. To those who with us believe in divine aid bestowed upon men in the course of conduct, the question, How can I compass what is right? is quite as simple as that other, How can I know what is right? For if there be a power making for righteousness within us, then the secret of success in reaching what is good will neces- sarily be to get this power on our side, however that be possible. Whatever progress in virtue we may make by the exercise of our own will, we can certainly make greater progress by the help of a power which is not ourselves, which urges in the same direction. However swiftly a vessel can go by the aid of oars or wheels, yet if she spread her sails to a favouring breeze she must needs go more swiftly still. However fast a man may swim, if the tide is with him he will swim faster. But the testimony of those who have risen to great heights of virtue has usually been that their own will has been able to make but very little progress, and that all that they have accomplished is the work of a higher power, coming to their aid when they were beaten and baffled by the power of circumstance. There does not seem any reason why we should refuse to believe this evidence, or set it aside. In each art we allow those to speak who are the greatest masters of that art. We Iv Flow shall we do what ts right ? 71 listen with respect to the testimony of a painter as to what makes the essence of good painting. We read eagerly what a good cricketer has to say about cricket or a good oarsman about boating. Surely, then, those who most excel in the art of conduct will best be able to explain how they themselves reached that excellence, and to show how others may reach it. It may seem to some readers that the question, How shall I do what is right? must needs be preceded by another, Why should I do what 1s right? Why should I not do what my inclinations prompt rather than that which my conscience urges? We mention here this question, lest we should seem entirely to have over- looked it. But it will lead us into no lengthy discussion, since we write for loyal souls anxious to play a good and worthy part in the world, not for triflers who wish by refinements of sophistry to escape the burden of right-doing laid upon them at birth. The question, Why should I do what is right? is really even more otiose than the question, Why should I try to be cwred of disease ? John Stuart Mill observes in his Utilitarianism that it is a question to which the answer must needs be only partially satisfactory, whatever be our standard of conduct. But this is true only with a qualification. The answer, we would rather say, must needs be un- satisfactory when it comes from the adherents of any of the reasoning schools of morality. And the cause is evident. The adherents of these schools trust to their intellect only to discover what is the course of right amid the complications of life. And as the intellect of none of us is a perfectly pure and white lhght, but swayed by emotions and by desires, there is room and 12 Faith and Conduct CHAP. opportunity at every moment for those emotions and desires to suggest all sorts of doubts and hesitations, and among others the doubt whether one’s own enjoy- ment or immediate expediency may not be as good a motive to act from as any other at the moment visible. And when a man’s will is in this unsound and feeble condition, the most ingenious and plausible theories as to the sanctions of ethics will not greatly help him, or strengthen the sinews of conduct. But if a man believe, with us, in a voice within which forbids or commands, the nature of which is to reflect the purposes of the spiritual Ruler of the world, the matter becomes simple. When it speaks in clear tones, there is little room for hesitation or doubt as to the comparative value and importance of various motives. The voice within does not advise, but commands. We are able to disobey it if we please, but we cannot hesi- tate as to whether it ought or ought not to be obeyed. And we may add, what is a matter of everyday experience, that it not only commands, but commands with a threat, so that we feel in our hearts that if we obey it, it will be well with us; and if we disobey it, it will be ill with us. The question where and when punishment for disobedience will fall upon us—whether sooner or later, whether in the present life or in some future state of existence—is a matter of doubt and of comparative unimportance. The essential thing is, that we have gone wrong, have passed into a state of dis- organisation and discord with our surroundings. Thus the reason why we should do what is right is abun- dantly clear. This is, of course, the hard doctrine of mere moral obligation. We shall hereafter come to considerations Iv How shall we do what ts right? vis which modify and soften it. Men who reach virtue in the world are commonly not driven to it by threat and command, but led gently by the bonds of love, whether it be the love of God, or the love of men, in whom more or less imperfectly dwells the image of God. On this aspect of the matter we shall have more to say at another time. But we are now regarding conduct in the severe light of strict ethical doctrine ; and we say that conduct thus regarded bears in its essential nature good reasons why “because right is right, to follow right were wisdom, in the scorn of consequence.” We may now venture on a second and completer analysis of conduct. If conduct be examined, the forces which bear upon it will be found to be three. First, we have the force of motive; in which word we would sum up all the tendencies existing in the mind at a given moment— the moment preceding volition. We might again analyse motive, as indeed we have already analysed it in a past chapter, into various elements, such as in- herited tendency, acquired tendency, and circumstance. These elements constitute, as it were, the strands of which the line of ordinary life is made up. Conduct which follows motive may indeed fall short of the tenor of the actor’s previous life; for there is in human nature an inertness which acts upon conduct that goes on regularly and mechanically, in much the same way in which gravity acts on a bullet discharged from a gun, bringing it nearer and nearer to the earth. And as the bullet cannot rise higher than the line along which it is fired, unless it be drawn upward out of its course by some extraneous force, so it is with conduct. 7A Fath and Conduct CHAP, Conduct cannot rise above the dead level of motive, unless it is drawn up by a power outside that motive. Secondly, we have the power of the divine ideas, which tends ever to raise the tone of conduct, and to guide it in the better course. These ideas not only act in the mind, clearing the sight, and enabling us to discern between good and evil, but also in will and _ heart, helping us to do what is right and to avoid what is wrong. They are an ever-present force making for righteousness, and tending to mould the human world after that which exists eternal in the world above—to make the will of God done upon earth as it is done in heaven. In some men at some times this power works with a force which is irresistible-—as when the Hebrew prophet declares that the word of the Lord was as a fire within him, and gave him no rest until he spoke. This feeling of dissatisfaction and of unrest, if felt ina less keen degree, is still felt by those who make them- selves deaf to the inner voice, and resist its impulses. Such men are fighting against the law of their being; are refusing to accommodate themselves to the environ- ment which hems them in on every side. Their con- stitution is in an unhealthy state, their nature at war with itself, and they are following that lower will and that immediate self-interest which are sure to plunge them deep in the waters of guilt and misery. We will not here discuss the question whether there be not traceable amid the springs of action also the. working of a power not ourselves, which makes for wickedness. Many of the greatest and best of men have recorded their experience of temptations to evil attacking them from without, and sometimes even iv How shall we do what ts right ? 75 assuming the semblance of the powers of light. Are we tempted to evil by our own hearts, or by inherited tendencies, or by spiritual powers of wickedness? This question we will merely mention and pass it by. It is one on which the wisest and best of men have held varying opinions. In our fifteenth chapter we shall recur to it. The third element in conduct consists in our will itself. But it does not appear that our will is an actual force, like the other forces mentioned, the force of motive and of the ideal. Rather, its power is regu- lative merely. It can add to or subtract from the force which impels us to this side or to that. By steadfastly inclining to one or another of the energies which bear upon our personality, it can make 1t more powerful. Will may be compared to the sliding-bar of a stream, which lets the water through fast or slowly ; or to the hand of a flute-player, which directs the breath as to which of the holes it shall pass out by. An evil-will will give full course to evil motive; a good-will will listen to the voice which calls to righteous- ness. He who steadily inclines to the inner voice which urges him to do what is best, will rise constantly to a higher moral level. On the other hand, he who follows the voice of passion and selfishness, may find his path turning more and more in the direction of evil, until the better tendencies with which he started are lost, and he sinks lower and lower in the waves of out. The power of the will must not be exaggerated. It must not be supposed that it rests with a man at any stage of his life to put aside the power of habit and to take quite a new departure. In each individual 76 Fatth and Conduct CHAP. action the power of willis very limited! We may put the matter, if we please, in a mathematical form. Let us say that will possesses the faculty of diminishing or increasing the force of the motives which impel to action by one-hundredth only. Then let us suppose a case, such a case as occurs to many daily, in which the impulses which drive a man towards some evil deed, impulses derived from the whole course of his lite and character, may be represented by 150, while the preventive impulses, which also derive from his character, are but as 149. If nothing interferes, the man will surely do the ill deed; it is in the natural line of his development. But if his will yield to the power that supports morality, and admit it into the heart to the extent of but one-hundredth of the evil tendency, then the line of action will be entirely reversed; for the forces tending to good will now be represented by 149 plus 14, or 1504. And we must further consider that no action ever takes place without tending to make a custom. In conduct as in war the result of a skirmish may decide the result of a campaign. Every action tends to smooth a road for future action in the same direction. A man’s whole nature is modified for good by such an interference as has been described. On the next occasion the impulses towards good in the breast of the man whose actions we are following will be stronger, and his impulses towards evil weaker. He will find him- self more disposed to do what is right, and at the same time his will will have acquired a precedent for inter- ference in the course of action. His whole character 1 What follows is suggested by Mr. Solly’s remarks on the will in his excellent work, The Will, Human and Divine. IV flow shall we do what ts right ? veh will have taken a turn for the better, a turn slight indeed, and yet of vast importance; for with a suffi- cient number of slight turns the whole character may be changed. The wish to do rightly may act upon the course of life as a rudder acts on a ship, bringing it round by slow degrees into a new course. And as in a steamship the very smallest turn of the rudder will, if persisted in, soon turn round the whole ship, so may a very feeble desire of virtue, if persistent, lead every one from bad ways to good. And on the other hand, if will sink in sloth and lethargy, the character will move vaguely and inconsistently, like a ship which has lost its rudder—sometimes moving in wide and meaningless circles, and sometimes drifting back towards its point of starting. We scarcely seem to be stating more than the ordinary facts of human life, which no one in his senses would question. And indeed in practical matters no one ever does question them. No one doubts that a persistent and vigorous determination to do better will lead to improvement in conduct, or that an unstable will is destructive of high virtue. As, therefore, we are at present entirely concerned with practice and not with metaphysics, this admission will satisfy us. CHAPTER V HIGHER PURPOSE IN EVOLUTION Tue fundamental thesis of this work is that there is a Power which works in the world in the interests of righteousness. The phrase, “ A Power not ourselves which makes for righteousness,” will be at once recog- nised by readers as belonging to the greatest critic of our time, Mr. Matthew Arnold. To his eloquent words in regard to that Power the present writer owes and gladly expresses a deep debt of gratitude. Yet a sense of indebtedness to other writers who have not indeed used this phrase, but have expressed the same idea in other forms, will not allow him to claim to be altogether Mr. Arnold’s disciple. This fundamental thesis we must now endeavour to justify, so far as by argument it can be justified. In the present chapter we consider it in the light of physical science, in the next chapter in the light of history, and in the succeeding chapter in the light of the experience of mankind. Firstly, then, Does that methodical observation of the external world which is called science give us any reason for supposing that in the course of the evolution of the universe, a higher Power is working his will and onar.v Ligher Purpose in Evolution 79 eradually realising plans which we may see to be good ? This work is not mainly concerned either with physical or biological science, or with history. Its main object is to deduce from an analysis of the facts of consciousness, and from the nature of conduct, proof of the truth and the necessity of religion. And the writer, while he can claim some knowledge of mental science and metaphysics, has but a slight acquaintance with the methods of physical research. Nevertheless he deems it necessary, before proceeding to the essen- tial part of the task before him, to discuss as briefly as possible the question whether modern scientific discovery has shut out religion from the field of know- ledge, or proved that the universe can be fully explained without introducing the hypothesis of a Deity. Our only attempt will be to show that physi- cal science does not present a final barrier to our attempts to build the foundations of faith. So much seems to be necessary: unless the problem be attacked from both sides, the half of mankind will be ready to declare that it has not been attacked at all; for every one has a strong tendency towards either the historical or the metaphysical way of looking at the problems of life and mind, and men in general will allow but little weight to a line of argument unlike those to which they are accustomed. We must therefore endeavour to show in what ways the working of the Deity may manifest itself in the course of the development of the world as well as of mankind. And this is the more necessary because the defences of religion on the side of physics and history are somewhat outworn, There has been a 80 Fatth and Conduct CHAP, great attack upon the battlements, and the defenders have not yet formed in new order to resist the foe; indeed they are still undecided as to who is friend and who is foe. They do not clearly see which of the new views set forth by eminent men of science are inconsistent with religious belief, and which may be safely admitted, or may even serve to strengthen the defences. We speak, of course, of religious writers in general, for some recent books have shown clear and true insight in the matter. We propose to speak of the world and its develop- ment under three heads: first, we shall take inanimate matter; secondly, living things; and, thirdly, human beings. In primeval times men supposed the several forces of nature to be under the direct control of spiritual agencies, who wielded them at their pleasure. Not only were the seemingly capricious movements of rain and wind and thunder regarded as mere instruments wielded by higher powers than man; but even the more constant features of the land, springs and rocks, as well as things endowed with vegetative life, such as trees, were supposed to be instinct with will and energy. The savage at the stage of animism regarded them as inhabited by the spirits of deceased ancestors. Ata far higher stage of civilisation the pagan had outgrown this kind of belief. He found it indeed quite unten- able, in view of the regularity with which the forces of nature acted, proving that the power which swayed them was not one of caprice, but a regularly-moving stream of influence. But he still supposed that many of the great provinces of nature were swayed by certain divine persons to whom they were allotted. A Spartan v Fligher Purpose tn Evolution 81 army did not cross a river until sacrifice had been offered to its indwelling divinity, and until the favour- able appearance presented by the victim proved that the god of the stream was willing to allow the cross- ing. Though the Greeks knew very well that it was the wind which roused the waves of the sea, yet in a tempest they would call upon Poseidon or the Great Twin Brethren to still the force of the waves. And the phenomena of thunderstorms in particular were regarded by the masses in pagan countries as manifest- ing in a marked degree the feelings of the deities. That it was Zeus who thundered and Zeus who rained they always believed, and it seemed to them impiety to doubt it. As monotheism gradually superseded the pagan polytheism in Europe, beliefs again changed, in so tar at least as polytheism really died out, and was not merely changed into a closely-similar worship of saints. As the various forces of the material world were in constant antagonism one against the other, it was not possible to regard them all as manifesting forth the direct volitions of the Supreme Being, who must in that case be divided against himself. The phenomena of the heavens, indeed, the most sublime and the most unaccountable of all, were transferred from the chief god of the pagan mythology to the supreme Deity of the new religion; and people still saw the immediate effects of the wrath or the pleasure of God in storms and in fair weather, and considered Him the direct sender of comets, meteors, and volcanic eruptions, But most material things were removed from the supposi- tion of immediate spiritual interference ; it was allowed that they were not swayed immediately by inscrutable G 82 Faith and Conduct CHAP. volitions of an unseen power, but followed certain regular paths of action, so that their action could be with certainty foretold. So in place of the animistic and pagan theories, the world accepted the Jewish hypothesis of an original creation of the world by the Deity ; though many supposed that after that creation the Deity stood apart from the world of matter and governed it from above, not interfering with it save in rare and important cases. From the time of Democritus of Abdera, and prob- ably from earlier times still, certain thinkers set up against one or other of these religious theories of the divine origin of the material world the hypothesis that matter had existed from all eternity, and possessed in its very essence certain qualities which enabled it to cohere into an orderly universe. Entirely denying the intrusion into the world of supernatural powers, they maintained the strict efficacy of physical law, and tried to show that if matter were but possessed of a few inalienable qualities, that fact would fully account for all the phenomena of the universe. In short, they supposed themselves to have proved that the hypothesis of a god or gods was unnecessary; either the gods did not exist, or they did not concern themselves with human affairs. Many a time, and in many forms, has the doctrine of Democritus been revived between his day and ours. If we were compelled to choose one of these two kinds of view, and either to assert that the universe moved by sheer inherent necessity, or else that it was regulated by the capricious will of spiritual beings external to it, we could not long hesitate to make our choice. For the uniform laws of the material world a ee v Fligher Purpose in Evolution 83 would obtrude themselves ever upon us in our daily lives; and all the difficulties of the materialist theory would seem small when compared with the fact that it did not contravene the facts of lfe, whereas the theo- logical theory did. But scientific and religious thought have long been erowing towards a compromise. All that is good in both the theological and the materialist theories may be combined into a new view of the world. Religious thought has long ago reconciled itself to the view that there is nothing capricious or unexpected in the move- ments of the physical forces of the earth. We all now believe that even the most apparently wayward of natural phenomena, wind and rain, observe fixed laws, and do not come and go at the bidding of irregular volitions. It is true that the great majority of religious people make exceptions to this rule. They still hold that at certain stages of the world’s history miracles were wrought in the world—that is to say, that the ordinary laws of matter were temporarily and locally violated. But this fact does not affect their way of regarding the universe. They do not believe that miracles are wrought now; and most of them are care- ful to explain that even in the case of miracles the laws of nature were not suspended, but that a new and spiritual force came in, and by the agency of natural laws wrought an effect contrary to what might have been anticipated from a review of the visible causes— which is quite a different thing. And at the same time men of science have come to see that the materialist theory also contained not a little of superstition and unreason. In the old con- ception of matter there was much absurdity. Setting 84 Faith and Conduct CHAP, aside for the present the metaphysical view of matter, which must hereafter occupy our attention, mere physical science has taught us this. “Matter,” says Mr. Wallace,’ “is essentially force, and nothing but force; matter, as popularly understood, does not exist, and is, in fact, philosophically inconceivable.” To modern physicists matter consists of an _ infinite number of centres of energy. But what is that energy, and whence comes it? Of course it is possible to maintain that these centres have always existed, and that it is part of their nature to exert force. But this is no explanation; it is merely a dogmatic asser- tion of a fact, not only beyond scientific proof, but even, as Kant has shown, in itself unthinkable. To sum up: the theory that matter is worked upon by the capricious will of supernatural beings must be given up; so must the theory that matter is the per- manent objective thing that we imagine it. We must hold that matter is a mere form of force, and that the force which it embodies acts in certain fixed and orderly methods. Beyond that, we cannot be said to know anything, at least from observation and experi- ment in the material world. And yet one view as to the ultimate source of force and of law in inanimate things must be regarded as more reasonable than others. For the only kind of force with which we are acquainted, which is not originated but originates, is the force of will revealed to us in consciousness—will, whether our own or that of the Power which makes for righteousness. This last is a real cause, we ourselves are real causes; but we know of no other real causes in the wide universe. 1 Contributions to the Theory of Natural Selection, p. 365. v Fligher Purpose in Evolution 85 Therefore, if we must form a theory as to the ultimate source of force in the world, we are compelled to choose between three alternatives.. Either the ego is that source, or the Power that works for righteousness is the source, or some other will entirely unknown to us is the source. That the ego is not the source is too obvious to need any demonstration. Between the other two theories it is possible for even a religious man to hesitate. And as a matter of history, great religions have chosen sometimes the one view and sometimes the other. The religion of the Jews regarded the material world as manifesting the power and glory of its Maker at every moment, as absolutely under his control and swayed by him. But the religion of the ancient Persians adopted quite a different view, that matter was under the control of a malignant being—the enemy of light and of righteous- ness—against whom the Power of righteousness and the spirit of man waged eternal war. In the early Christian Church both views found advocates; but that which taught the divine origin of material force prevailed. And those who are accustomed to the teachings of modern science will probably regard the alternative theory as blasphemous. But to the argument of this work it is not neces- sary to decide between the two views. Gravitation, electricity, and other such phenomena are modes of action which we find by experience to be inherent in matter. Those who believe the world to be under divine control will naturally regard these properties of matter as imparted to it by the divine Ruler. But even of materialism there is a kind which is by no means inconsistent with religion. Let a man regard 86 Faith and Conduct CHAP. inanimate matter as existing from all time, and en- dowed by its very essence with the qualities which we discern in it. He may even in that case be- heve in a deity who is the cause and ruler of life, and who brings out of dead matter things which grow and creatures which move and feel. To him matter will be a sort of incarnation of evil, as it was to the Manicheans of old—a dead weight which is being con- stantly rolled away and upwards by the pushing of divine energy. We are not justifying this doctrine, but we merely wish to point out that materialism and religion are not necessarily opposed unless the materialism is pushed up into the regions of life, and unless matter is regarded as possessed of properties of life and progress. Now, whereas the atheistic theory of the origin of material force only involves a difficulty in philosophy, the atheistic theory of the origin of life in the universe is a matter in which experiment is possible. And the experiments, so far as they have hitherto gone, are entirely on the side of the Theists. They seem to prove that life could originate only by a direct fiat of spiritual power. Referring to the experiments of Tyndall and Dal- linger, Mr. Drummond’ points out that they have conclusively shown spontaneous generation to be a process which does not take place. “The attempt to get the living out of the dead has failed. Spontaneous generation has had to be given up; and it is now recognised on every hand that Life can only come from the touch of Life. Huxley categorically an- nounces that the doctrine of Biogenesis, or life only 1 Natural Law in the Spiritual World, p. 68. v Fligher Purpose m Evolution 87 from life, is ‘victorious along the whole line at the present day.” And even whilst confessing that he wishes the evidence were the other way, Tyndall is compelled to say, ‘I affirm that no shred of trust- worthy experimental testimony exists to prove that life in our day has ever appeared independently of antecedent life’” Thus, on the very threshold of biology stands a proof, to all present appearance con- clusive, of divine purpose and action in the material world. Until this proof breaks down, it is legitimate to appeal to it; though at the same time we must say that should it hereafter break down, our arguments would scarcely be perceptibly weakened. That the history of the world is an evolution, is a view advocated by all important schools of modern thought. Towards this view we have been. growing for centuries; and in our days, after long underlying the scientific and philosophic thought of Europe, it has appeared on the surface, and been on all sides fully recognised as an essential part of any rational theory of the universe. We can no more suppose that the view will be ever again abandoned than that the Chaldean system of astronomy will be re-intro- duced, or that men will return to the belief that eclipses result from the attempts of a dragon to swallow sun or moon. We cannot doubt the truth of the doctrine of Evolution ; and its truth is assumed in every page of this book. It is, however, an error, widely spread if vulgar, to suppose that acceptance of evolution implies the acceptance of the special biologic doctrines of Spencer and Darwin. Of course scientific men do not fall into this confusion, but so many of the ordinary 88 Faith and Conduct CHAP, run of mankind do, that it is necessary to draw attention to it. Asin England Spencer and Darwin have been the most notable advocates of evolution, while their opponents have in many cases been men who rejected the doctrine entirely, it is not wonderful that ordinary minds should confuse the essence and the accident, the essential doctrine of evolution and the accidental accompaniment of the peculiar opinions of these two great men of science. Yet some of these peculiar opinions are very dis- putable, and even a layman in science may venture to call them in question. The theory of Darwin is, that in organic beings of all kinds there exists a tendency to fortuitous varia- tion, and that those of the variations which are bene- ficial confer such an advantage on the creature endowed with them that he is successful in the struggle for existence, and leaves descendants who inherit his ad- vantages and perpetuate them far and wide. And there can be no question that with great ability, and by means of a vast array of facts, Darwin has proved that this process plays a very great part in the history of the animal world, and accounts for a vast number of changes and developments which were before unin- telligible. The special theory which Darwin attacked was that which held that the Deity had directly created from time to time new species of living creatures, and carefully adapted them in each case for the surroundings amid which they had to live. It was contrivance and design which the theological writers of the last century were never tired of dis- covering and admiring; and they regarded living things as mere pieces of mechanism made by a con- v Fligher Purpose mn Evolution 89 triver of like nature with ourselves, to fulfil some purpose of his own. Against this view the Darwinian polemic must be regarded as successful. It is now proved that a vast number of changes which had been attributed to the direct interference of Providence arose from mere competition among various dissimilar individuals of a species for existence, the more highly endowed naturally surviving. And after tracing this process in many cases, we cannot help believing that it takes place in many other instances where we can- not clearly trace it. We must therefore give up the idea of repeated creations of species by a sudden mandate of heaven. But for all that, it does not follow that there is no limit to the application of Darwin’s theory. It has been denied, and strongly denied, that natural selec- tion is the only working factor in evolution. The denial has not come merely from the partisans of established theological opinions, but from eminent scientific men whose prejudices would be rather on the side of Darwinism than against it—-G. H. Lewes for instance, and Wallace. Mr. Murphy, in his able work on Habit and Intelligence, appears to have clearly shown the deficiency on some sides of the Darwinian theory. “According to the biological philosophy, whereof Darwin and Spencer are the exponents, there are but two possible kinds of cause for any vital function or any morphological character. These may be described with extreme brevity, as, firstly, self-adaptation, effected according to the laws of habit; and secondly, spon- taneous variations, produced according to unknown laws, but probably by the agency of external circum- 90 | Faith and Conduct CHAP. stances, and preserved, so as to become the characters of species and of classes, chiefly, though not ex- clusively, by natural selection ensuring the survival of the fittest. Both of these agencies accumulate by inheritance, through successive generations, to an in- definite extent. “There is no doubt that these are real agencies, and that their agency is co-extensive with life. The purpose of the present work, however” (Habit and Intelligence), “is to show that these, though universally acting, do not act alone, and that Intelligence is as much an ultimate fact as Habit. These two agencies which we call self-adaptation and natural selection, though acting on living things and through the vital forces, yet act mechanically; and, moreover, they are unintelligent and therefore incapable of foresight. . . . Habit, which is the acting power in the process of self-adaptation, cannot fit an organism for a hfe on which it has not yet entered, and natural selection can only select what is «immediately useful. If it can be certainly shown in a single instance that the form- ative energies have acted with reference, not to the then existing, but to an anticipated state of things, this will amount to conclusive proof that there must be a formative agency at work which cannot be resolved into self-adaptation and natural selection, and which must be intelligent.”} We may select a few among the instances which have been cited by Mr. Murphy and other writers as proving that other forces govern the development of animals besides natural selection. The arrangement . of feathers in the wings of birds is a notable instance. . 1 Murphy, Habit and Intelligence, second edition, p. 339. OE v Fligher Purpose in Evolution QI Fully-developed feathers in a wing no doubt enable birds to fly; but partly-developed feathers would be of no use to them at all, and would in no way aid the preservation or multiplication of the creatures which had them, as compared with the creatures that had them not. Are we to suppose that feathers were developed in birds by a long process through ages, erowing from a rudimentary to a complete form ? This could only be the case if the prevision of use- fulness in the future acted as a force among the generations of birds. The structure would grow in anticipation of function; and this, as Darwin himself allows, could not be done by natural selection. But perhaps the feathers came full grown to some definite bird. If so, that was no mere variation, but an actual miracle; and to gratuitously assume a miracle is contrary to modern methods of reasoning. Again, consider the eye of men or animals. It is an extremely complex structure, and no improvement in its structure could possibly take place without a number of simultaneous changes in its different parts. If variations be merely fortuitous it becomes almost inconceivable that such a marvellous conjuncture of changes should take place again and again, as the eye developed into a better and better instrument. Mr. Murphy! justly observes that by the laws of mere chance the hope of procuring a distinct working improvement in the eye which could be transmitted by descent, is not “greater than the chance of ob- taining a poem or a mathematical demonstration by throwing letters at random on a table.’ We cannot avoid the conclusion that in the development of the 1 Murphy, Habit and Intelligence, second edition, p. 383. 92 Faith and Conduct CHAP. eye of animals variation was “guided along beneficial lines” by some sort of prevision and intention; or at least by some power quite different from mere chance. In this case it becomes legitimate to suppose that certain variations, the co-operation of which was needed for one result, were brought about by a governing power. And even if we could allow that in the course of infinite time, amid variations of all possible kinds, sufficient chances of the right kind may have turned up to produce our very complicated organ of sight, yet we must remember that we have not infinite time at our disposal, but only geologic time, which is a comparatively brief period—a time utterly inadequate for the purpose. In the opinion of Mr. Wallace, the human brain is one of the clearest instances of an organ which could not be produced by natural selection. “We are driven,”! he writes, “to the conclusion that in his large and well-developed brain” (the savage) “ pos- sesses an organ quite disproportionate to his actual requirements—an organ that seems prepared in advance, only to be fully utilised as he progresses in civilisation. . . . We must therefore admit that the large brain he actually possesses could never have been solely developed by any of those laws of evolu- tion whose essence is that they lead to a degree of organisation exactly proportionate to the wants of each species—never beyond those wants. ... The brain of prehistoric and of savage man seems to me to prove the existence of some power distinct from that natural selection ””—-which in Mr. Wallace’s view has guided the development of the lower animals. 1 Contributions to the Theory of Natural Selection, p. 343. v Higher Purpose in Evolution 93 eee ees In fact Mr. Wallace, who, as one of the first and ablest promulgators of the theory of natural selection, has every right to be heard in such a matter, distinctly denies that that theory will account for man, or for man’s progress. He maintains even in regard to man’s physical frame that it could not have grown to what it is by the mere action of natural selection. Not only is the human brain far too large and too complicated for the needs of the savage, but also the human hand is a far more exact and delicate instru- ment than he requires for his rough purposes. In the same way in the structure of man's larynx, which is complete quite beyond the needs of savages, Mr. Wallace discerns an organ which could never have been produced by natural selection. And the soft- ness and sensitiveness of the human skin, and the absence of a hairy covering, must have been to primitive races a real disadvantage. But that this peculiarity immensely tended to civilise and soften them, by making them dependent upon shelter from the weather and other contrivances which encouraged dawning civilisation, is evident. That peculiarities which were of no service to primitive man, but which were destined to be of use to man in a higher state of civilisation, grew and became prevalent in the infancy of the race, can prove, according to Mr. Wallace, but one thing, that “a superior intelligence has guided the development of man in a definite direction and for a special purpose, just as man guides the development of many animal and vegetable forms.” As a layman in biology and physiology the present writer is quite content to accept Mr. Wallace’s dicta upon these points. If he is right, the argument which 94 Faith and Conduct CHAP, we shall bring forward as to man’s moral nature will have an independent support. But if he is wrong, that argument will still have sufficient foundation in itself to be fairly independent of the support of biology. It thus seems that we should have adequate support from competent scientific men in contending that natural selection is not the only path of development in the living world. It is important to our purposes that this thesis should be maintained; for it is undeni- able that if all living structures could be shown to be built up by a force which acts by pure chance, then the share of chance in the regulation of the universe would be very considerable. We do not say that the Darwinian theory necessitates atheism, for there are many ways in which a man might avoid inferring the latter from the former, but it has a certain kinship with atheism. Of course the argument which we used in regard to the material world still applies. Because the laws of hfe act with great regularity it does not follow that they are self-created or entirely incompatible with a divine control. The laws of nature, as J. S. Mill has observed, do not account for their own origin; and they do not bear on the face of them their own sanction. The world might be strictly under divine rule and yet the Deity might choose to work his purposes in it by means of natural selection as explained by Darwin. But at the same time a theory which resolutely shuts out from the field of hfe all action of intelligence and foresight is perhaps as favourable to atheism as any biological theory can be. The case is very different if we can discern in v Fligher Purpose in Evolution 95 biological development the working of thought and purpose. If we can show, firstly, that natural selection does not proceed altogether at random, but is guided in certain beneficial directions, and secondly, that foresight may be observed in the living world in the preparation of structure for functions which are as yet unnecessary, then we certainly gain a clearer and more satisfactory view of divine government in the world. We shall readily feel that the power which guides and arranges and foresees in the origin and development of species is of divine origin. In that case we shall naturally believe that variations of a beneficial kind are prompted by purpose, and the inworking of a beneficial power. Variations of a pernicious character we shall compare to diseases in the frames of men and animals; and shall consider them temporary revolts of the body against the impulse of a higher law. What is meant by the last phrase will more clearly appear when we come to speak of the nature of evil. CHAPTER VI HIGHER PURPOSE IN HISTORY In the inanimate world about us we see only the working of certain invariable laws. We see effect following cause with undeviating regularity, and all this moving in an even succession which seems not merely to exclude an external will, but even to exclude the action of chance. What the secret of the force which inheres in the material world may be we are utterly ignorant of; science gives us no hint in the matter; we discern from the outside its methods of working and its effects, but we cannot see it from within or dissect it into simple elements. When in ascending the scale of being we come to vegetable life, we find, in addition to the action of the forces of the material world, a power of growth and of assimilation ; by which power plants gather nutriment from air and soil and make it part of their own being, having in them an energy for reducing outward things into dependence upon themselves and absorbing them into a system. We also find in the history of plants the process of evolution, whereby they change con- stantly in certain directions in subordination to the influences which surround them. The nature of this cuar. vi = LZzgher Purpose in FTrstory Q7 process is fully set forth by modern writers on biological science. Among animals we find less subordination than amone plants to surrounding influences, and a greater central power rendering them more capable of mastering what is without them, and making them able to conquer and feed upon vegetables and other animals. ‘Their doings are guided by a certain light of intelligence, and they know within limits what will be good and what evil for them. In the history of animals we more plainly trace the course of evolution, through which from simple beginnings they have risen to their pre- sent highly-developed state. And in this evolution we may fairly trace, according to competent observers, the control of an extraneous force, which appears to euide variation in the better directions and to lead it away from the worse, and to prepare organs for func- tions which are still undeveloped. Let us pass upwards from the phenomena of de- velopment in the world of life to the highest class of phenomena which lies open to our observation, the facts of the conscious and voluntary life of man. Can we there too discern the working of a power which shapes the ends of the lives of individuals and of nations ? Can we trace there the presence of a wise and fore- seeing power which guides action in the direction most suitable 2 Is there a providence manifested in the human world as well as in that of nature ? In these questions is involved the possibility of religion. If a divine force acting in and on our lives and the lives of our ancestors can be discerned, then we are wise in making account of that force, and seek- ing its aid to carry us to good ends. If such force i 98 Faith and Conduct CHAP. cannot be discerned, then no power of fixed tradition, or gorgeous ritual, or established interests, can maintain religion in the world. It is impossible that modern minds should accept any theory, however pleasing or however useful, unless it will bear investigation, All our beliefs must be founded on the solid rock of fact, or the tempest of sceptical tendency which year by year waxes stronger must necessarily before long sweep them all away; and the love they inspire in mankind will not be able to hinder their destruction. Our inquiry should naturally fall into two branches. In the first we might interrogate history to see whether the records of human progress show us proofs of divine control of the course of events. In the second we might question men not in society but as individuals, and seek for traces of divine influence in their lives. It would be an interesting and important task to try and discover whether there is to be discerned in the history of mankind something similar to that guidance of variation in the better directions, and that prepara- tion of organ for function which many able men of science find in the animal world. We might hope dimly to discern amid the events of history the working and interference of a higher Power leading men in advance of their own thoughts and discoveries in the path leading to higher developments of civilisation. Something of the kind has already been attempted in such works as Bunsen’s God in History, and Bishop Temple’s well-known essay on the Education of the World, in Essays and Reviews: in fact many historians have pointed out in the course of their narratives what seemed to them to be indications of the interference of divine power in the course of human affairs. _-_ VI fligher Purpose in F{rstory 99 Though these observations are legitimate enough, yet we can hardly believe that any man can obtain so perfect a mastery of historical facts as to be able to make them with much confidence, from the purely scientific point of view. If he bring to his historical studies a full belief in the overruling power of divine providence in the world, a belief gained from his own life, then he may easily trace that power amid the turmoil of human affairs. But if, on the other hand, he starts with a profound disbelief in the divine government of the world, he may almost as easily account for the course of events without being forced to recur to that hypothesis. The fact is that our knowledge of history, especially if we go back a few centuries, is so extremely limited and partial that it does not furnish material for the solution of problems of such difficulty. In each generation there are but a very few historians who so thoroughly realise and live in some period of the past by the action of that rare quality, imaginative insight, that they can be said thoroughly to understand it. And even these gifted and fortunate men can so assimilate but a small period in one or two countries. Even to them it is quite impossible to form a complete estimate of all the moral and intellectual and physical forces at work in any age or country ; they can at best see the stream of life, at that stage of its flow, from a long distance and by means of a series of distorting mirrors. Those who have longest loved history know best how difficult it is to be sure even as to simple matters of fact in the distant past, and how impossible to form a final judgment as to less definite things,—the character of a man, the value of an institution, or the full bearings of an event of importance. 100 Fatth and Conduct CHAP. Thus while there is absolute certainty that no future study of history can ever prove that there are no such divine influences at work as those of which we have spoken, there is yet much doubt whether their existence will ever be proved in such a manner as to convince those who do not wish to be convinced. ‘This line of argument in favour of theism cannot be, therefore, of much value. And this may be the less regretted when we consider that after all it is utterly absurd to sup- pose that people must wait to make up their minds whether religion is reasonable until historians have succeeded in fathoming all the abysses of the history of the past. Such a supposition would be paralleled if one could not determine what food and drink agreed with him until he had ascertained the exact habits of food and drink maintained by his ancestors since the Saxon Conquest, with the effect on the constitution of each. We are born for action and not, in the main, for interminable controversies reaching to the limits of history and the roots of the world. History as written in books being too complicated a congeries of phenomena to yield us the results of which we are in search, we must change our line of investigation. Instead of looking at the tapestry of history we must try to select in that tapestry a few threads, and trace them through all turns and amid all patterns. We must try and discover the nature of haman action and its laws, to see if thence we may gain light on the course of human development, and discern what forces guide and regulate it. And the progress which most interests us is the moral progress, whereby man rises from a lower to a higher stage of morality. vi fiigher Purpose in [Listory IOI Is this moral progress to be accounted for as a mere result of competition with spontaneous variation and survival of the fittest, or does it bespeak the control of an overruling spiritual power? Does the practice of virtue give a man such advantages in the battle of life that he survives and leaves more descendants than the man who contravenes the laws of virtue? If so, there is a prumd facie case in favour of the evolution of virtue by the processes of natural selection. But if, on the other hand, it appears that virtue is not an advantage in the immediate battle of life, then it would seem that the evolution of virtue must be the work of a controlling spiritual power. Our contention is that while certain virtues, and those by no means the loftiest, are a help to mankind in the battle with the world, other virtues, which are among the highest, are by no means a help, but rather a hindrance. In considering the matter we will divide virtues into three kinds: dealing well with one’s self, dealing well with others, and dealing well with the divine ideas, which are with us the soul of human society. Reasonable self-love seems to be formed of a mixture of that desire of self-preservation and of happi- ness which is the most primitive and enduring of all our instincts, with coolness of intellect to judge of the future, and power of imagination to realise that future as if it were present. A man who thinks before he acts, and sees things in their true perspective, will seldom be wanting in this quality. No trait more strongly marks one from the other, the barbarian and the civilised man—the barbarian heedlessly pursuing the pleasure of the moment at the risk of severe suffer- 102 Fatth and Conduct CHAP. ing at a future time; the civilised man content to labour and to undergo present privations with a view to procuring himself solid satisfactions at a future time. As regards the progress of society in all out- ward comforts, no quality in man is so propitious as this ; none is so helpful in the conquest of nature and the foundation of physical prosperity. And as no quality in man is more useful to society than a reason- ing self-love, so none tends more directly and more surely to the preservation of the person who possesses the quality. Like a well-ballasted ship, such aman will outride the gales of life and make his way steadily in any direction he chooses. Yet this quality, so useful to individuals and societies, is looked on by moralists and the world at large scarcely as a virtue at all. It is coolly commended, but awakens no emotions of enthusiasm, kindles no aspirations, and attracts no affec- tions. Sometimes it is even confused with selfishness. Altruism is a result of warmth of sympathy with others, an imagination which enters into their feelings and desires, and finds happiness in supplying their needs and seeing their enjoyments. In the opinion of many people this is the essence of goodness. It is a warmth to all who come near it, the sunshine of life. And yet it is easy to see that this feeling, delightful as it is, may yet, if the sympathies be confined in too narrow a field, become a source of injustice, may divide class from class, since class barriers commonly form impediments to sympathy, and unfit men for many of the most important duties of life. That altruism when not carried to excess should be spread through the world by the action of natural selection is readily to be understood. For not only does the VI Fligher Purpose in FIistory 103 man who makes many friends stand more strongly in the world and secure a better chance of survival, but also societies among which the feeling is prominent will have natural advantages over other societies among which the sympathetic feelings are weak, and will tend to supplant them in the battle of life. Whether the theory of natural selection will fully account for the gradual intensifying of the feelings of care for one’s own future and love for one’s neighbour—that is, will explain the rate of their growth—it is impossible to say; but that the process of natural selection must necessarily favour their growth is a matter of obvious certainty. When we reach higher kinds of virtue, ideal mor- ality, the case is by no means so clear. It is not easy to see how this can be spread by natural selection. Rather would it seem that the tendency of natural selection would be towards its extinction. As regards a man’s own career, scruples of conscience and a high ideal of conduct are a heavy weight to carry, more especially in those barbarous and semi-civilised states of society which virtue has to traverse in the course of its evolution, In troublous times of struggle between beliefs, it is those who are of most inflexible principle who perish. In the great religious persecu- tions, for instance, those who absolutely refused to abjure their faith were commonly put to death, while the more pliable were allowed to escape. It has been pointed out by more than one writer that the want of intellectual enterprise now characterising the Spanish nation may be partly accounted for by the fact that for centuries there flowed in Spain, under the hands of the Inquisition, a constant stream of the blood of 104 Faith and Conduct CHAP. those who dared to think for themselves, while the dull of mind and the bigoted were left to carry on the race. But as amatter of fact this same process has been going on in all countries, though with less inten- sity. We do not mean only the process of putting to death those considered as heretics, though this has been done in all countries, but their persecution in milder forms, which has been still more usual, and must have told against them terribly in the struggle for existence. In how many cases have men of unbend- ing principles been deprived on their account of an inheritance, a situation, or a bride? And in such cases the advantages they lost have been secured for the most part by others of more pliable nature. In this way natural selection has constantly acted against the spread of strong principle ;—yet with how little success 1s implied in the old Christian proverb that “The blood of martyrs is the seed of the Church.” But it may perhaps be thought that conscientious- ness and high principle, though they are not of service to individuals in the battle for existence, are yet of advantage to the societies in which they prevail, and enable those societies to outlive their competitors. But this could scarcely be proved. Among barbarous tribes we find in single districts the widest extremes of falseness and love of truth, so that a man of one tribe may be implicitly trustworthy, and a man of another utterly unworthy of trust. In such cases, the truth-loving tribe is usually the more unwarlike and less enterprising, and by no means likely to spread and prevail. Among civilised races the peoples that stand by their word and have a high sense of honour win no doubt the respect of their neighbours, but it ; vI Higher Purpose in Ffrstory 105 may be doubted whether they secure more solid advantages. That good men on the whole are well- to-do, and their children after them, was not a new discovery even in the Psalmist’s time. But it not unfrequently happens, though circumstances may be much to blame, that for considerable periods of time the worse type of man has more chances of succeeding in life than the better. Those races of serpents best survive which are most poisonous, and those kinds of antelopes which are most cowardly. The Greeks at Rome seem to have prospered in proportion to their skilfulness at flattery, and the Jews in the Middle Ages were preserved even more by their cringing suppleness than their business talent. The Chinaman in California seems likely to hold his own against better races, partly because he is so much of a machine, and so wanting in loftiness of mind. In fact, 1t must be considered a delusion to suppose that competition must necessarily preserve the better and eliminate the worse. The savage tribes who are always fighting are very bad fighters. No one supposes that the soldiers of Aétius were better than the soldiers of Augustus or of Alexander. The Chinese officials who are examined and re-examined with immense competition are not prodigies of wisdom. It is indeed probable that as moderate and regulated exercise strengthens the frame, while immoderate exertion ruins it, so limited competition produces a healthy and vigorous set of men, but excessive competition does not. Thus when Darwin asserts that natural selection has had much influence in the development of the altruistic impulses, we must allow much weight to his 106 faith and Conduct CHAP, view. But when Mr. Clifford, in an able paper in the Fortnightly Review for 1875, writes as follows: Conscience “has been evolved and preserved because it is useful to the tribe or community in the struggle for existence against other tribes, and against the environment as a whole,” we must pause before con- ceding a thesis which is apparently contrary to the weight of evidence and reason; unless, indeed, by the phrase “environment as a whole” we mean something much wider than Mr. Clifford meant. We must, however, insist on a distinction. If natural selection will not account for the evolution of conscience, then conscience must have been developed by some higher power. But if, on the other hand, Clifford is right in holding that races with more highly- developed conscience will survive in the struggle for existence, this does not in the least degree prove that conscience is delusive, or a mere human invention. If conscience come from divine influence, the source of conscience may have so arranged the world as to give an advantage in it to those who listen to its voice. Our examination of the evolution of morality on the whole leads us to a negative conclusion. The conclusion is this: that it is impossible to affirm confidently that the law of natural selection and the survival of the fittest will account for the growth of morality in the world such as the growth of morality has been. Indeed there seem to be many virtues, and those some of the highest, which we might easily suppose would be rooted out or at least discouraged by the process of natural selection. This conclusion seems to render it probable, though vI Fligher Purpose in Flistory 107 it does not prove, that the growth of human morality is furthered by spiritual power working from without on human life. It may seem that the result of our arguments 1s slight and unsatisfactory. It is slight; but this results from the very nature of the case. For to examine morality from outside is a difficult task, and one which can bring little satisfaction and no conviction. Our ideas as to conduct are based on the testimony of our own individual consciousness ; and we must interrogate that if we would arrive at any solid or satisfying con- clusion as to its nature. It must be unsatisfactory to analyse from without what we can never see from without, for it is the results and not the facts’ of conduct that we see. CHAPTER VII DIVINE AID AS EXPERIENCE If is in inner experience, one might almost say by experiment, that the existence of the Power which makes for righteousness is known to men. It is a point on which Mr. Arnold, with unequalled eloquence, has insisted, that the matter is one in which verification is possible. And he speaks the truth, as thousands by daily experience can testify. “Taste and see,” says the Hebrew Psalmist, “that the Lord is good.” And every one can taste and see. Ifa man sets up a wheel in a stream, and arranges matters so that the wheel turns grinding-stones one upon the other, then the power of the stream will grind that man’s corn for him. If a sailor so arranges his sails that the wind fills them and urges him the way he would go, he sails on and on by no force of his own through the sea. In the same way,—if things so sacred may without impiety be likened to common things of earth,—in the very same way, 1f a man earnestly and modestly tries to set aside his own will, and to do that which his conscience assures him to be right, he will find a power greater than his own lifting him up and bearing him along towards the accomplishment of his desires. The desire of those cpap. vir = Davine Aid as Experience 109 who hunger for righteousness shall be filled, and that which fills the desire shall be handed from without. This, we say, is the experience of thousands in every age. But of course we must not be understood to put spiritual experience on quite the same level as that of natural things and of every day. To the miller who sets up his wheel in the stream, to the sailor who spreads his sails on the sea, it makes no difference whether his character or his motive be evil or good ; the force lies there, and he has but to seize it and make it his slave to do his bidding. The wind wafts the pirate as well as the merchantman, and the mill will grind food or poison with equal readiness. Of course it is quite otherwise in regard to the power which leads to righteousness. That can by no man be used for private purposes; it only uses us for a higher purpose than ours. None but the will set on good is lifted up and carried forward by its inspiring force. But it may be asked why, if the reality of the power of righteousness be thus easily verified, and be daily confirmed by the experience of thousands, so many people are sceptical as to its existence—more people practically than theoretically sceptical, but many both. The main reason is the pressure of the daily life of care and of struggle in which we are immersed, and whence we seldom emerge.