Re a oo rae ANN RAS SSRN te A date dh ch FV at asl of oh at Ae A ROR A Oe Ye Saetolal a Oe) os AR AA DDR FH PN Re vr Mee €) / ’ 7 ’ y ; ’ fare very ‘ye ro , ana , Tar vr ’ a , vor , 7 , 7a ur ¥ ¢ Pogue a liad Bi ad we get: Ae RAS -SS ~ as LAAAKA KAA AKARAAHAAKAAHA Bess “eS Beers Ct ee ee ee Aa 4 = e* > a> Cotes eSeh perks Nm, c= Re eee bes SSS See > 2. 2 owt eS ~ Sie * ’ +o 0s Aes Pepto? ? ge , rp as ” zs » FF. ie 77 ye ? Se tak my ¥ 7 yer he vee i ah wey +? a vy ; Reacher M4 Caan) TNS. », yy! Lang if a Rts 36 + Ae AS AA ARES, athe yelp ° FP ean. a 4 ‘¢ 4 7 rr Ne s >" on * » a a 42 > Ba) is Se D 0 > , KY ty Ne + Nd hae at > Ses ? a : ie Re i Ph? ‘5 a > > 7, ; 5? ye ey. ?. ¥ 7: , oy > ” , 43 ry P; y) %, % ees +. ye (%4 ? Re y l¢ v iP ; , , , Aes Pete es PaV oe 4) a # 1G wy peat CH 3% Pa?) OC ( D S¢ i? y ie ae LA 2 % » > Ne « > ? “ eS4 4 > ‘S P, >: ? ¥. , 7. Sf > , , > é > ¥ 2 ? ia t < >? y, 43 4 9 6 ? :? , =) ee § 2 > 54) oes 2 » ? Se be ase > em aL >, Pars Phs Baeaae cade 3 eA i? > és es > yy? ny > 42948 > ee ie ate ey » > rade >, seSeS P75 6 oto we ; palorete? OLR Heats >, ts oe ee Se) 632 Mees SR) es re : 6 2 a>. Ae eee hesete NESE ENCORE: oho > > > \ rots ERes Se > > > PP Pate PF ar ote a4 Pars a Ae : eth ae ar a 4) >) <3 us ta y? . ses thehe SPA a nteps yy ~ ey 25 See a 9 sh? fe} Fp ee ee ey Se a BT 198 —D671>> 1391 aves Dorner, I. A. 1809-1884. fistory of the development of the doctrine of the : ~ » - ae a - rs ) ; j 7 < ~ ale ari : - ~ . - z ‘ oe — a i . aan ‘ey a are = Ss - ad “ = 7 3 - aoe ge’. ay ; Z “1. wee i ’ Me daca . 4 at a ) _ “i, , * as é p we Be +e iiuhal oe 7 -_ ( \ a y % =i es . 3 i ii = : ~~ a ta ‘ : ; : ; Aa ae ' ; ~~ y an ‘4 , ap an - a 4 os a rq 7 » ne a _ . ¢ aS , f R 7 , a > = - a sas J ¥ - q = 4 ¢ < S , » 2 ' : u x j : =m 7” 7 ; ‘ Ps ' ; a ee : ? ek . i s 3 - a s . =. F nd ““ LP) + Par. 5 _ ‘ j 7 ° : : rs ‘ U , : 1 i q~ oo } - =. 7 7 » “I . ~ a io, r < aot % < » s ‘ : al i> i : y : - mi ¥ = a gee - . “a 7 aT 7 “ -. , . ge a } % ' - J 0 os P d 2 + ae wes eo i . } qj ' a te — th > i. + Pin Abe eel FE ILEL RR SS CLARK’S FOREIGN THEOLOGICAL LIBRARY. THIRD SERIUS. VOL Ve Borner on the Person of Christ. HENS AO | Alem ANOGE IEE EDINBURGH: Tee eG WARK Ss GHEORGHE STREET TSUie PRINTED BY MORRISON AND GIBB LIMITED FOR T. & T, CLARK, EDINBURGH. LONDON: SIMPKIN, MARSHALL, HAMILTON, KENT, AND CO, LIMITED a NEW YORK: CHARLES SCRIBNER'S SONS. TORONTO: THE WILLARD TRACT DEPOSITORY. HISTORY OF THE DEVELOPMENT THE PERSON OF CHRIST. B ‘i y, f Yv DR. L A. DORNER, PROFESSOK OF THEOLOGY IN THE UNIVERSITY OF GOTTINGEN DIVISION FIRST, FIRST FOUR CENTURIES VOLUME II. TRANSLATED BY Rev. PRincipAL SIMON, D.D. EDINBURGH: Tec lSCLARK “3889 GEORGE STREET 1897. er Digitized by the Internet Archive in 2022 with a from https://archive.org/details/historyofdevelop00dorn_5 * ' i ay : =o af ~via wi - it oe a? amy . a aed eee aot i a . CONTENTS. FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. Page Cuap. II. The Two Forms of Monarchianism, : : 1 1. Ebionitical Monarchianism , ; : 3 6 Cuap. HI. 2. Patripassian Monarchianism, ‘ 15 SECTION II. THE DOCTRINE OF THE SON, AND THE REVIVAL OF MONARCHIANISM IN THE FORM OF SABELLIANISM AND SUBORDINATIANISM. Cuap. I. The Confutation of the New Form of Ebionism and Patripassianism by the Church :— 1. The Struggle with the New Form of Hbionism, 47 2. The Struggle with Patripassianism, . : 49 Transition to the Further Development. Origen, . 104 Cuap. II. Sabellianism, ; : : ‘ : ee WY Cuap. III. The School of Origen in the Third Century, and the Subordinatianism of Dionysius of Alexandria, . soenyaal SECTION III. THE CHURCH’S CONFESSION OF THE ETERNAL HYPOSTASIS OF THE SON, AND OF HIS ESSENTIAL EQUALITY WITH THE FATHER, AT THE COUNCIL OF NICHA. Cuap. I. The Controversy preliminarily carried on with Sabel- lianism and Subordinatianism, : ; aneoe Cuap. II. Arius and his Forerunners, : ; : wee 202 1. Lactantius, . . : : : . 205 2. Eusebius of Ceesarea, , é ; Sue 21 SaeATils,,- ; s : : a ADT Cuap. III. The Council of Niceea, and the Beginnings of Atha- nasius, : : ; 244 Vill CONTENTS. THIRD EPOCH. FROM THE COUNCIL OF NICHA TO THAT OF CONSTANTINOPLE, A.D. 381. SECTION I. TRINITARIAN MOVEMENTS. Page Cap. I. The Arian School, ‘ ; 261 Cuap. II. The Revival of Sabellianism, and the Ebionism which Y sprang from it, : : | aagah Cuap. III. The Confutation of Arianism and Sabellianism by the great Church Teachers of the Third Epoch, . 28h SECTION II. CHRISTOLOGICAL MOVEMENTS. Ay Car. I. The Christology of the Church Teachers prior to Apollinaris, 332 iY Cuap. II. The Christology of the Arians and of Marcellus, and its Redargution by the Teachers of the Church, . ee Cuap. III. Apollinarism and its Overthrow by the Church, J GBGe ad APPENDIX, . pr Mekeel FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. CHAPTER SECOND. MONARCHIANISM OF THE EBIONITICAL FORM, INTRODUCTION. The Two Forms of Monarchiansm. =jOWARDS the end of the second century, in harmony | with the New Testament, the doctrinal development, which had started with the historical, and had passed gradually from lower to higher ground, arrived preliminarily at its goal. Nothing short of attributing to Christ true divinity was able to satisfy minds conscious of having attained absolute reconciliation through Him. We find, too, that at a far earlier date, probably through the influence of the teachings of the Apostles, the conviction that Christ had introduced the abso- lutely perfect religion, and that everything, both in its rise and continuance, is essentially and originally conditioned by Christi- anity, had found an expression in the general doctrine of the pre-existence of Christ, and of His second coming to judgment. During the second half of the second century, the mind of the Church advanced unconcernedly onwards towards the goal which the necessity of the case had fixed, until it finally landed, and that with clearly defined consciousness, in the inner sphere of the supramundane divine itself, and traced back the roots of the Logos who appeared in Christ, to the ultimate ground of all BOte iat A 2 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. things, that is, to the very essence of God Himself. At this point, however, a great shock was experienced: the course taken by the development of the doctrine of the Person of Christ seemed to be adverse to the reigning doctrine of God. A reaction, therefore, took place on the part of the doctrine of the unity of God,—a doctrine which had always been taken for granted, and Christology was at first refused that resting-place in the eternal divine essence which it undoubtedly needed. Nor was this any longer a conflict with tendencies outside of the Church, but within its own bosom. For the unity of God, which the rational and religious mind universally regards as an unassail- able certainty (with which conviction Christians had hitherto unhesitatingly deemed themselves to be in harmony), appeared on reflection to be so irreconcilable with the distinctive prin- ciple of Christianity, that one or the other must needs give way. Had the new Christian principle given way, a relapse of humanity into its ante-Christian state would inevitably have followed; and it could have made but little difference whether the place of Christianity were taken by a pantheistic doctrine of the unity of the All, moulded after a Greek type, or by an abstract deistic monotheism, moulded after a Jewish type. On the other hand, did the Christian principle firmly maintain its position, as might be expected from the life and vigour it displayed, and were the monarchy of God sacrificed to it, a re- lapse into polytheism would be inevitable. In either case, the certain conviction of faith, that Christianity, as the revelation of the inmost essence of God, was the perfect religion, would have received a deadly blow. For a long time already, a storm had been brewing in the sphere of the unity of God, which threat- ened to spend its force against the course taken by the develop- ment of Christology; and no sooner had the doctrine of the Logos led to the distinct and conscious equalization of the Son with the Father, and to Christology directly touching the very apex of theology, than the storm began to burst. The reaction against the hitherto received Christology could only originate, it is true, with a defective, partially ante-Christian conception of God. For, although it cannot be denied that the conception of the attributes of God had already undergone many a change during the Gnostic movements, and that love had been recognised as a determination of God alongside of the physical THE TWO FORMS OF MONARCHIANISM. 3 determinations, and also alongside of righteousness and sanctity; still the doctrine of the inner nature of God had not been with certainty transformed by the Christian principle. And yet all depended on this latter. Christology gave thereto a mighty im- pulse; and this impulse governed, in the first instance, the fur- ther course taken by the matter, till, about the middle of the third and during the progress of the fourth century, the Church withdrew its attention from the development of Christology, and, taking its Christology for granted, applied itself mainly to the attainment of the true conception of God,—that is, to the task of conciliating the doctrine of the higher nature of Christ, and subsequently that of the Holy Spirit, with the idea of God, .—.and to the clear and conscious exposition of the Trinity as the properly Christian conception of God, in opposition to heathen- ism on the one hand, and Judaism on the other. From the end of the second century, then, we may say, Christology demanded that the previously prevailing conception of God should undergo a transformation in consonance with the divine revelation in Christ. We find, as a general rule, that whilst, on the one hand, the old is the fulcrum or stay for the development of the Christian principle, on the other hand, this development itself is unable to make way save as the truth em- bodied in previous systems is incorporated with Christianity ;— otherwise humanity relapses irrecoverably from Christianity inte its ante-Christian condition. And the same process of concilia- tion between nature and grace—that is, between the ante- Christian and the Christian — we find accomplished again in the remarkable stadium to which our attention is now to be devoted. There were not lacking men who, though opposed in other respects, were agreed in their dread of any approach to an undermining of the unity of God (compare Origen in John. At. ii. 2,— 70 Trodrovs hirod€ous eivat edyouévous Tapdacov, evAaBou- pévors Sv0 avayopedoae Oeods ; Tertullian adv. Prax. 3,—“ Sim- plices quique, ne dixerim imprudentes et idiote, que major semper credentium pars est, quoniam et ipsa regula fidei a plu- ribus Diis seculi ad unicum et verum Deum transfert, expa- vescunt ad ofxovouiav. Monarchiam, inquiunt, tenemus”); and because they paid sole regard to this one point, they were desig- nated Monarchians. ‘The Judaizing Christians, indeed, are ne longer deserving of much notice in this connection. The rigid 4 FIRST PERIOD SECOND EFOCH. conception of God entertained by unbelieving Jews had not entirely escaped the corrosive power of Gnosticism; the prin- ciples of Hellenism and Judaism had approximated to each other, in consequence of their return into their pantheistic ground; the old Ebionites, who denied Christ’s supernatural birth, whose number even at an earlier period seems never to have been large, and who appear to have been in part more closely connected with the synagogue than with the Christian Church, have now passed away, as far as their importance is concerned. At the very moment, however, when the Christo- logy of the Church had arrived at the above mentioned theolo- gical problem, but, though seeking, had not found the solution, old and new elements broke loose; consolidated themselves, as at the time when Ebionism and Docetism prevailed, into opposed heresies, —to wit, into Patripassianism, which was a higher form of Docetism, and into a new form of Ebionism, which had passed through, and therefore received a colouring from, Gnosticism. As has been remarked, Christology still constituted the moving principle; and the two heresies just mentioned were Christolo- gical, and not Trinitarian, like Sabellianism and Arianism proper. And as the two earlier Christological heresies found a new prop in the doctrine of the unity of God, which now. became a factor of the movement; so, in conjunction with the opposition raised against them by the Church, did they prepare the way for, and introduce, the century which in a doctrinal point of view may be properly termed, the Trinitarian century. But what we found occurring in the case of Cerinthus,—to wit, that when the Docetism and Ebionism, confusedly combined in his system, were separated, the principle of Ebionism logically led to Doce- tism, and vice versd,—occurs again at this higher stage. The Alogi (see Epiph. Her. 51; Ireneus 3, c. 11, 9; compare Hein- ichen de Alogis, 1829), opposed to Cerinthus on the one side, and to the Montanists on the other, appear, from the indefinite- ness which they sought to maintain in reference to the doctrine of the Holy Spirit and of the Logos, and from the latitudinarian and regressive movement which they initiated, to form the point of departure for the two possible forms of Monarchianism (Note lin the Appendix). The Ebionite Theodotus is expressly termed an d7rooTracpa éx Ths addyou aipécews. That the Alogi accepted the supernatural birth of Christ, we may with certainty conclude THE TWO FORMS OF MONARCHIANISM. i) from the position they assumed towards the Synoptics, which they made the basis of their operations against the Gospel of John. On this point, moreover, Epiphanius brings no charge against them. Nor is it at all probable that they denied the divi- nity of Christ, notwithstanding their rejection of the Gospel of John; nay, even although they may have taken up a position, not merely of indifference, but of actual antagonism, to the developed dogma of the Logos (see Epiphanius’ Her. 51, 28; Anaceph. ed. Pet. 2, 144). For such a denial would by no means have been excused by Epiphanius; he would then rather have justly classed them with the Ebionites: whereas he does the very con- trary. They had no intention, therefore, of denying divinity to Christ; but still it is not likely that they willingly traced it back to the Holy Spirit, as a being distinct from God; for to have assumed that, would have been incompatible with their re- lation both to the doctrine of the Holy Ghost and to Montanism. Even supposing they did the det Oeds Adyos TapeEéBarov, Tov amd ITatpos (Anaceph. 2, 144, 5), it is improbable that they admitted the existence of distinctions in God,—for the purpose of avoid- ing which, they contented themselves with simply saying that Christ was a man who had in Himself the deity of the Father, instead of adopting the doctrine of the Logos, by which His divinity was more distinctly defined. Naturally enough, when their aim was to preserve the true humanity of Christ, as it de- cidedly was (see Note 1, Appendix), the doctrine of the pre- existence of the higher nature of Christ became converted into the doctrine of the predestination (poyvwars, preedestinatio) of this peculiar union of God with a man.' Such a doctrine evidently left undetermined, whether the divine in Christ was personal, or a mere force. According, therefore, as the mind was more under the sway of religion, or of the practical understanding, this Monarchianism necessarily took a patripassian or an Ebionitic turn. Let us now consider these two tendencies. 1 The passage from Origen’s Comm. in Ep. Tit. T. iv., in Pamph. Apolog. p. 22,--‘‘qui dicunt . . . quod homo natus Patris solam in se habuerit deitatem,”—-probably relates to the Alogi. If so, the heresies which are there enumerated before and after, form a regular and orderly series. To the ‘‘ Deitas Patris,” zaraixn becrns, would then be opposed the rartpixos Osos Aogos, required by Epiphanius; see Heer. 51, 28. 6 FIRST PERIOD SECOND EPOCH. I. EBIONITICAL MONARCHIANISM; OR, THE REVIVAL OF EBIONISM IN A HIGHER FORM. The revivification of Ebionism, which we have now to con- sider, differed from the old in two respects :—in that, firstly, it allowed the supernatural birth of Christ ; and, secondly, perceived the impossibility of the belief in the unique and exceptional character of Christ standing its ground, or even of allowing the reality of His human development, unless the divine element which distinguished Him were confessed to have influenced it from the very beginning. This form of Ebionism is in advance also of that abstract, ethical point of view, which attaches worth to a moral development only so far as it springs from human power. There is no reason for doubting what Eusebius men- tions having found in an old writing (H. E. 5, 28), that Theo- dotus the Tanner, of Byzantium, arrived at his thesis— Christ was Widos avOpwros, although born of the Virgin (Tertull. de prescript. 53), after a denial of Christ, and that his heresy was meant to serve as a cloak to his apostasy. But this ground alone, even though, as is not improbable, he added higher predicates to Christ, should prevent us regarding him as a worthy representa- tive of the higher form of Ebionism which was now reviving into existence. It is quite certain that neither the Alogi, with whom he was connected (see above), nor the school which sprang from him, held Christ to be merely an ordinary man ; for then they would not have deserved even the name of heretics (Note 2). We will direct our attention a little longer to this school. It is probable that in the Theodotians a school was found for a speculative, or, more precisely expressed, for a pantheistic form. of. Ebionism connected with Gnosticism. The funda- mental features of this view, as laid down by Theodotus the Money-changer (Theodoret, Heer. fab. 2, 6), or by the Theo- dotus whom Clemens Alexandr. mentions (with Neander, I hold the two to be one and the same person), are the following :— During the second half of the second century, we find, in general, that the hypostases and mythical /on-world of Gnosti- cism, which were formerly kept apart, began to be confounded with each other; and the same thing is particularly observable 1 See the Inquiry into the true ‘dea of Heresy, contained in Note U, Appendix, Vol. I. Transi. EBIONITICAL MONARCHIANISM. 2 in the Theodotians, in so far as they assert even the Logos to be absolutely identical with the Father (Exc. Theod. 19). The image of this Logos, whom they take pleasure in designating High Priest (compare 27), or Melchizedek (Note 3; see Theo- doret’s Heer. Fab. 2, 6), was borne by Christ (ibid.), as, indeed, by all elect souls. No one individual, however, can be said to be identical with that. eternal.idea; not even Christ contained all its fulness, but was merely one word of the Word (Adyou doyos, 19); one ray of the divine was in His soul, and that He shares with all elect souls. ‘The presence of the Redeemer in the world was but a shadow of the glory He has with the Father. Both the elder and the younger Theodotus (Exc. 60) readily appealed to Luke i. 35. They considered the words, “The Holy Spirit will come upon thee, and the power of the Most High will overshadow thee,” to refer to the body of the Lord, and to the formative power of God, which moulded it in the womb of the Virgin. In this case, also, they meant to exclude the indwelling or incarnation of the wvedua or Aoyos. To the Logos who was in identity with the Father there attached, it is true, from eternity the mepuypady, but He had no personal exist- ence (ovaia). He was the Father’s countenance, or His circum- scription (Umschriebenheit) and form; and this is the meaning of the word Son, as applied to God apart from the incarnation (10, 19); Sonship is, as it were, a determination of the Father Himself, the element of finitude in Him. The Father Himself is the Aon so far as He turns His countenance towards us,—in which alone we are able to know Him (10, 23). But the Logos has by no means an exclusive relation to Christ. In becoming incarnate,—and we must not suppose there to have been only one incarnation, for the Son was incarnate also in the prophets (19),—this Son, that is, God, not. merely assumed flesh, but also personality (obcia), out BF the subject (man). ‘The person- ality, however, held the position of servant; for it was capable of suffering, and was subject to the active, supreme cause (19). It is scarcely possible not to perceive the after-influence of the system of the elder Theodotus in this form of Ebionism. In a variety of ways he affirmed, in opposition to the Church, that Christ was, after all, a true man; and whatever other divine ~ attributes he may have given to Him, rested solely on the basis of His full human personality. Such also was the position of 8 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. the younger Theodotus (Note 4). Now, although, like the Gnostic Ebionism which consolidated itself into definite forms towards the end of the second century, after the elder Ebionism had died out, Theodotus found little difficulty in attributing to Christ, or to His elect and predestined soul, a divine substance, the Ebionitic character of his views shows itself at once in his supposition, that the Redeemer merely awakened the soul out of sleep and kindled the divine spark, which lies at all events in the elect (3); and in his not leaving to Christ even the dignity of being an unique incarnation of the Word. The elect differ from each other only in the measure in which the one ap- proaches nearer to the Tédos mpoxoTs—that is, to the idea of the true man, created in the image of God—than the other. Accordingly, this form of Ebionism also was at last compelled to agree with the elder Theodotus when he says (Tertull. de prescr. 53),—“ Christ is raised above other men nulla alia nisi sola justitize auctoritate.”’ An exactly similar position was oc- cupied somewhat later than Theodotus the Elder, according to Eusebius (see 5, 28) and Theodoret (see Heer. fab. 2, 4), by Ar- temon; with the single difference that he had probably cast off the Gnostic element (compare Note 3, and take in conjune- tion therewith Heer. fab. 2, 5, at the commencement). Devoted to Hellenic philosophy (Euseb. 5, 28), and, as it appears, deal- ing arbitrarily with the Old and New Testament records, he and his school believed themselves warranted in describing it as an innovation to designate Christ, God ;—an assertion, the oppo- site of which we have clearly enough shown to be true, and the drift and nature of which is perfectly plain from his pretence of having the Apostles on his side. The further assertion, that his doctrine had prevailed in Rome till the time of Zephyrinus, does not accord very well with the reception given to Praxeas there; with the exclusion of the elder Theodotus by Victor, prior to Zephyrinus; with the intimate relation existing between Iren- zeus and the Romish Church; nor, lastly, with the remarks made above respecting the dogmatical views of the Romish Church subsequent to Clement’s day. In fact, he himself re- cedes from this position to the extent of granting, what he could not deny, that in ancient hymns deity had already been attri- buted to Christ; but he pretends that, in a doctrinal form, his ideas had held a place side by side therewith, or had even had EBIONITICAL MONARCHIANISM. 9 the predominance. ‘Taking it, however, to be a fact, as history unquestionably teaches, that there was little doctrinal develop- inent of the faith in Rome during the second century, this is in itself a refutation of his affirmation; for if we deny the exist- ence of doctrinal development in general, we must deny also the existence of a doctrinal Ebionism. It is, of course, plain that a faith as yet doctrinally undeveloped might tolerate many principles which a keener eye would have condemned; but it does not therefore follow, that the faith itself was identical with such principles; although it agreed with the interest of the Artemonites to maintain the fairness of such aconclusion. For the rest, Artemon does allow that Christ was supernaturally born of the Virgin, and that He was exalted above the prophets by His virtue (Theodoret’s Heer. fab. 2,4). In the matter of Monarchianism, therefore, he was at one with his predecessors ; but he was scientifically in advance of them, his views having acquired clearness and definiteness. Like them, he clung to the sinlessness and the supernatural birth; but, instead of mis- using the words, 0 Xoyos capE éyévero, as did the Theodotians, who, notwithstanding their adhesion to the formula of the Church, really attributed nothing distinctive to Christ, he en- tirely avoids such lofty expressions; at the same time, however, he acknowledges the more distinctly that, on account of His sinlessness, an unique dignity appertained to Christ. The divinity which he concedes to Christ is His virtue, which raised Him above the most distinguished of the human race; and that Artemon did not take a merely empirical view of this virtue by representing it as the sole work of Christ’s human freedom, is very evident, partly from the comparison with the prophets, who were prophets because they participated in the Divine Spirit, and partly from his assigning to Christ a rank above the prophets, both in consideration of His supernatural birth and of the superior measure of His virtue.! ‘Kel ’Apréwoy 0¢ tig 2 1... rb ety xara rev Gawy Osdy rapararncinc nuety eookaccy, aitov sipnxas sluat tov ravrds rointhy’ tov d¢ xvo1ov Iyoody Xororcy kvbpwroyv sine Wirov, ex wopbevov veysvynusvov, tay b¢ wooPytay aipern xpeirrove. Taira o¢ xeel rovs daoardrous tdsye xexnpuyeves, wopep- Lenvevay ray bsioy ypaQay THy Oievoleyv, rods O¢ pest exeivous beoroyHoas Tév Xplorov, ovx éyre Ozcv. Artemon’s party extended far into the second century, and even Paul of Samosata is classed with it by the teachers of the Church,—for example, by Theodoret, Heer. fab. 2. 8. 10 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. Paul of Samosata! gave the completest development to this higher form of Ebionism (about 270 after Christ). Many points of his system, indeed, are but a repetition of what had been taught before; and the early writers recularly described him as an adherent of Artemon. He did away with the songs of praise to Christ, under the pretence of their being of modern origin ;—a mode of procedure resembling that of Artemon in one respect, but in another respect in glaring contradiction to him ; for Artemon had maintained (see Schleiermacher’s 4. Theol. 2, 490), that a @eoroyeiv of Christ was discoverable solely in old hymns, and not in strictly doctrinal productions (to which the author of the Little Labyrinth already gave a fitting reply: Euseb. 5, 20). Like Artemon, with whom the ancients con- stantly class him, he starts with the unity of God, denies the existence of a codia, or Adyos, distinct from the Father (évuTro- oTatos), and represents the Logos in God as merely that which intelligence or reason is in the human heart. In this sense he took the passage, “ I am in the Father, and the Father in Me.” He advances, therefore, no further than that tautorns of the Logos with the Father, which the younger Theodotus so de- cidedly taught in opposition to the doctrine of the Church (dixe. Theod. 19). Up to this time, the Church had found no better way of describing the distinction between the divine in Christ and God, than the, as we have seen, unsatisfactory one of assigning the divine reason or cedia to the Son. Paul further resembles his predecessors in laying the main stress on the human personality of Christ; but he carries it out more fully. His Christ is from beneath (xdtwOev, Euseb. 7, 80; Theodoret, Her. fab. 2, 8): ébwpdOn tov Xpictov avOpwrov reyav, Geias ydpitos Siadepovtas jEvwopévov. Kuseb. 7, 27,—Tovrov oé (IIav- Nov) Tarrewa Kab yapal reTH TEpl TOD XpioTov Tapa THY EKKAN- ciactiKiy Sidacxariav dpovicavtos, ws KoLWOD TI) diow avOpw- mou yevouevou, etc. O. 30,—Tov pév yap viov Tod Oeod (So say the Bishops in their Synodal Epistle) od Bovderae oUVOMLONOYELY €€ ovpavod Katerndrubévar—reyet ’Incody Xpiotov Katwdev. They term Him é£opxnodpevoy To pvaotnptov (whereas even he 1 Compare Euseb. 7, 27-30 ; Hahn’s “ Bibliothek der Symbole u. s. W.,”” vp. 91-97, 129 f.; Epiph. Heer. 65; Theodoret, Heer. fab. 2, 8; Ehrlich’s ‘de erroribus Pauli Samos.” Lips. 1745; Schwab's ‘de Pauli Sam. vita atque doctrina,” Diss. inaug. 1839. EBIONITICAL MONARCHIANISM. 1] had previously had faith in Christ as Lord and God: Euseb. ed. Heinichen) cal éuropumevovta tH papa aipéces Tod “Aptewa (compare Kuseb. 5, 28, at the commencement). The Logos, that is, the activity of God which breathed through Him from above, did not dwell in Him as a person, but merely as_a quality or power (ovK ovatwdas GAG KaTa TroLOTHTa) ; and although he does not appear to have questioned the supernatural. birth of Christ (in opposition to the indefinite expression of Euseb. 7, 27, we may adduce the distinct declaration of Athanasius c. Apoll. 2, 3, that he taught, Ocov 逫 wapOévov), he laid no particular stress on it; and the utmost he could have meant by it was, that Christ continued permanently the subject of divine influence, and that His humanity was predestined to, and therefore also prepared for, this abiding union with the divine power. What is peculiar to him, however, is his endeavour to establish the Sonship or deity of Christ, on the ground of the divine power which dwelt in Him, after the analogy of the prophets, but in a fuller measure (according to the Contestatio Cleri Constantinop. quod Nestor. ejusd. sit sentent. cum Paulo Samos. Mansi Coll. 4, 1108, Paul’s doctrine was—iva unre 0 ék AaBid ypiceis adXOTpLos 7) THS codlas, unte » codia ev Adw obTws evolKT: compare Baur |. c. 1, 296), urging that it was the animating principle of His human development, which, having attained its goal, constituted Him, for its excellence, worthy of the name of Son of God. (Compare the above passage from Theodoret, Heer. fab. 2, 8; Athan. de Syn. c. 26,—Uatepov adrov peta tiv év- avOparnaw €x mpoKxoTrhs TeCcoTrona Oat, TH THY prow avOpwTroVr yeyovevat: c. 45,—€& avOparrwv yéyove Ocos. Fragm. Ep. Synod. in Leontius c. Nest. et Eutych., he taught cvvddesav pos tv codiay kata wadbnow Kat perovoiav; Epiph. Her. 65,—ép atta évéTrvevoev dvwbev 0 AOyos.) As of alike tendency, I am inclined to take the passage in Epiph. 65, 1,—éddwy 6 rAoyos evipynoe Lovos Kal avhirOe mpos Tov Tatépa; but I doubt whether it teaches a separation of the divine from this man, similar to that which Sabellians taught, as Baur affirms (1. c. p. 305). For the only idea justificatory thereof—to_wit, that after His perfection Christ was possessed of deity in Himself, in the way above men- tioned, and that He therefore needed no longer the influence of the Logos—can scarcely have been entertained by him, seeing that it would have still further weakened the, in other respects, 12 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. feeble proof of the deification of Christ. At what moment he considered the deity of Christ to have commenced, whether after His resurrection or after His baptism, we are not informed (Note 5). If God-manhood did not pertain to Him originally, it became His through the medium of His mpoxor, of His perfect human development, for the sake of which Paul repre- sents Him as deified. This deification is annexed as an external consequence ; but 1t cannot have been anything more than a quality, a thing of rank and of dignity, not of essence (‘Theo- doret 1. c.). The divine in the Son, or Christ, continues by itself impersonal (avaupel THY TOD viod [of the eternal Son] UTocTacw, hacker pi) evar avtov evuTrootator, GX év ad’Td Oe@, Epiph. Heer. 65,1). When, to his doctrine, “God is one person with the Logos, év rpécwmov (Epiph. |. c.), even as man is one with his reason,” the objection was raised,—“ The doctrine of the Church requires one God, but several T poo wa. of the same ;” he replied, that as he also held Christ to be a person (namely, as a man), his faith too (compare Epiph. |. c. 7) had several mpocwra; God and Christ stand over against each other as dpoovcrot, that is, probably, as alike personal (see Note 4) Ce vexatious dialectical procedure of this kind could, of course, Jeceive no one; but it had the effect of rendering the word 6jzoove1os, so employed and referred to personality in general, suspicious for a time (according to Athanasius de Syn. Ar. et Sel. c. 45, fears were entertained that, if Paul’s view were adopted, a human personality must be admitted into the Trinity), until the fourth century stamped it with the seal of Church authority (Note 6). If the word ovc/a be taken in the sense of substance or essence (Wesen), Paul teaches an érepoovaia of the Son and the Father; in their inmost centre, as to their person- ality, they continue apart; and the personality of the Son is conceived as merely finite, although év atv@ évérrvevoev avwbev 6 Nyos (compare Pauli Serm. ad Sabian.,—ai dudpopos pucess Kal Ta Sudhopa mpdcwra eva Kab povov Evacews ExovTL TPOTFOY, Thy Kata OérXnow ovpBacw). This Christology is remarkable for combining within itself such varied elements; and, indeed, as Epiphanius already (Her. 65, 9) seems to hint, Paul’s aim in its construction apparently was to attain a point of view from which principles, otherwise antagonistic, would be seen to form part of a higher unity : hence EBIONITICAL MONARCHIANISM. 13 also, until recent times, many were uncertain in what class Paul ought to be placed. We have no longer here to do with the old Ebionism, and its abstract dualistic conception of God; Paul taught, on the contrary, that the power of the divine Logos, in its highest energy, had appeared in this man ;—not, however, in a docetical manner, as the Gnostic Christology represented, but permanently. His conception of it, indeed, was such as te enable him to trace out a truly human, free development. for Christ, in a_more complete manner than the Church teachers of his day; yet at the same time he never supposed a time when the man Jesus, who rose by gradual progress from a lower position up to deification, had been without the Logos. He tried also to assert for Christ Sonship and deity; on the condition, it is true, that it should grow out of the humanity. In conse- quence, the deity thus claimed for Christ was neither selfless, nor involved a double personality. Further, the Logos who dwelt in Christ was not something subordinate, but a truly divine power, yea, God Himself in His activity. He formed as large a con- ception of this activity as appeared compatible with the require- ments of a free human development. In this respect, he occupied a far higher position than the Patripassians and Sabellians; for they were by no means able to give so perfect a representation of the humanity of Christ. On the other hand, he was essen- tially one with them in his unitarian conception of God; indeed, he harmonized so completely with them, that we can easily ex- plain how he should have been frequently classed with Sabel- hans. Epiphanius also charges him with the cvvadidn of the Logos and the Father; for he denies the pre-existence of the Logos and His possession of an independent hypostasis. On the other hand, he did not conceive God to be motionless and inert, or far removed from the world; but taught that the one God, who is in Himself Logos and Pneuma, and for whose unity he pleads, as did the Sabellians, in opposition to the Church, revealed Himself, became the dédyos mpopoptxos, and is present in His revelation. Indeed, he might himself have laid down a kind of ceconomic Trinity; and probably he meant to do something of the sort, when, in referring to the Son, he maintained that he also taught the existence of two hypostases, Father and Son. But even if Schleiermacher’s supposition were correct, that he regarded the soul in general as essentially divine, we should be 14 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. scarcely warranted in attributing to him the idea of a self- diremption of God, into the imner Logos and the Adyos mpodo- puxos ; In the sense, namely, that God placed Himself over against Himself in humanity (that is, God on earth), specially in the perfect man ; and that, out of the independent freedom with which He had, as it were, enfranchised Himself in man, He returns back to Himself through the ethical exercise of that freedom, in the first instance, in Christ. For Paul did not hold the world or humanity to be the Adyos évepyos. And even when he says,—* The Logos dwelt in Christ as in a temple ; He was in Him what-the inner man is in us,”—he merely bor- dered on, without actually proceeding to, the recognition of the hypostasis of the Logos; for he conceived the inner man rather as a simple attribute or quality. Because, however, he regarded the free human and the divine personalities as mutually exclu- sive magnitudes, we are justified in saying,—So far as Paul saw ‘1 Christ a manifestation of the Father (Epiph. 1. c. 5), and with the Sabellians appealed to John xiv. 9; and, further, so far as he held this person, in its ideal development, to be deter- mined by the évépyeva of God,—in so far was he on the point of passing over into Sabellianism, and under the necessity of sus- pending the évépyeua of the human aspect, of reducing it toa purely passive condition. So far, however, he was unable to go. For his fundamental Christological tendency plainly was to lay chief stress on the humanity; and therefore, notwithstanding some inconsistencies, his theory continued to be Ebionitical, an ‘nearnation of God to be an utter impossibility, and the divine to occupy a place merely on the surface of the kernel of the strictly human personality of Christ. In this sense, we may say that Paul considered the humanity to form the inmost centre and proper substance of the person of Christ; and that the divine, on the contrary, touched merely the actuality of the man Jesus, that is, His phenomenal aspect. Looking back from the point at which we now stand to the commencement of the series here terminated, we have a spec- tacle before us which will often be re-enacted,—the spectacle, namely, that a system whose basis was originally pantheistic, is necessitated, in consequence of the accession of the subjective, personal principle, either to become deistic, or to throw aside its error and accept the truth. For Judaistic and deistic it cer- PATRIPASSIAN MONARCHIANISM. 15 tainly is, to represent the essence of God and of man as neces- sarily foreign to each other, and as only coming into contact with each other through the medium of the divine power which dwells in Christ, as in a temple (Contest. cleri Const., Cts slicer ev XpiaT@ (iv 9 codia) ws év vad Ocod; and Paul frequently employs the expression,—in Christ copia évouxel; compare Neander 2, 1036). This, therefore, is again simply the inner relation of the heathenish and the Jewish principle, as we found it existing in the days of the older Ebionism and Docetism : they form two extremes, which unavoidably tend to a false union ; that is, they ceaselessly pass over the one into the other, when they fail to find a true union in Christianity. CHAPTER THIRD. II. MONARCHIANISM OF THE PATRIPASSIAN FORM. A FAR mightier tendency than the Ebionism just considered- mightier, because more amicably related to the interests of re- ligion—was Patripassianism, which, after undergoing a process of refinement and development, attained its most perfect. form and expression in Sabellianism. After making many uncon- nected beginnings during the course of the second centur : even prior to the time of Praxeas, this system attained sudden ripeness and wide diffusion even in the Church ;—first, under the imperfect form of Patripassianism, shortly before the end of the second century; and again, after some links of develop- ment had intervened, soon after the middle of the third century. Relatively to those beginnings, we may remark in the out- set, that Justin Martyr makes us acquainted, in his Dial. ec. Tryph. 128, with men who are very like the later Sabellians. One and the same divine S%vayus, say they, undivided and un- separated from the Father, as the light on earth from the light of the sun in heaven, has appeared under different names and forms, as Messenger, Shechinah, Man, and Word; and these appearances are the appearances of the Father. When He wilis, say they, He causes His power to go forth; and when He wills, H calls it back into Himself. Those who held such views 1G FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. must, of course, have regarded all revelation as something mo- mentary and abrupt: no such thing as a knowledge of perma- nent forms of divine revelation, and of their connection with each other is attainable ; everything remains theophany. We find, however, even here, the characteristic feature, that the divine Svvaus in itself is asserted to be absolutely identical with the Father, and that the element of limitation, of distinction from God the Father, is supposed to owe its existence to the entrance ‘nto the world of finitude, to be the effect of the ofkovoyia, or of revelation; whereas the divine substance in itself resists and excludes all distinctions. But if we ask, what is the funda- mental philosophical view which lies at the basis of such a theory of the revelation of God; and if, in this behoof, we apply the above propositions to creation in general, and not merely to the Old Testament account (an application which they themselves justify us in making, in that they trace back the origin of the angels also to that divine Svvapus, in which the Father as it were spreads Himself out),—we shall arrive most surely at our goal by taking our stand on their favourite image, and saying :—God is like the sun, which diffuses itself through, and as it were expands itself to the boundaries of, the sphere of light; and as the sun draws back every evening, at setting, the rays in which it appeared to us, so God draws Himself back into Himself. I would just hint with a word also, that the Pseudo-Clementines, with their Monas, which dilates itself to a Dyas, and again returns into itself, and perhaps also the enosticizing Gospel of the Egyptians, may be placed under the same category.| Whether the influence of the stoical cosmology or theology should also be taken into consideration as a further factor, is doubtful, notwithstanding that common or similar ex~ pressions, like svotod7 and Suactony, éxoracts, suggest such a course. More importance ought probably to be attached to the Neo-Platonic philosophy, which began to come into vogue, even before the end of the second century, specially through Celsus. For it does teach that God eternally mediates Himself with™ Himself through the world, that the divine life flows through 1 Baur, Ll. c. p. 274, refers the Gospel of the Egyptians to this connec- tion with a positiveness which I am unable to share ; for we know only of a sexual Dyas (Geschlechtsdyas) which becomes a Monas. Compare Grahe’s ** Spici'egium” 1, 35. PATRIPASSIAN MONARCHIANISM. 17? a circuit, and that God proceeds forth from Himself and be- comes a Son to Himself in the world. Related thereto, and unquestionably not without considerable influence on Neo- Platonism, was finally Gnosticism, between which, with its pan- theistic fundamental view and the principle of Sabellianism, the affinity was all the greater, the more it turned from its ethniciz- ing phantastic theosophy to the more sober doctrine of the unity of the Alleinheitslehre—a doctrine essentially involved in it from the beginning,—or the more fully it obeyed the injunc- tion of Irenzeus, to reduce its endless hypostases to momenta of the conception of God. The connection of Sabellianism with Gnosticism, apart from the pantheistic basis common to both, is specially noteworthy for two reasons. Firstly, the older patripassian form of Sabellianism, which did not shrink from attributing change and suffering to God, directs our attention to the transformation already experienced by the rigid Jewish conception of God at the hand of Gnosticism. Secondly, the older patripassian form of Sabellianism was guided, not so much by a philosophical or cosmological, as by a religious interest (not till a later period did it betaine religio-historical or religio- philosophical) ; and even in this aspect, the transition from Gnosticism to it was effected by one of the most noted Gnostics, Marcion.’ This religious interest manifested itself particularly in the opposition consciously raised by it to every form of Subordinatianism, and in its disposition to put Christ on a level with God; nor did it object merely to Ebionitical Monarchian- ism, but also to those doctrines of the Church which subordi- nate the Son to the Father (compare Origen in Matth. T. xvil. § 14, Neander 2, 994 f.). It is of far more consequence, however, to note the stadium at which the doctrine of the Church itself stood, when this tendency broke out. Here we refer not merely to the indeterminateness which prevailed, and which did not quite exclude Sabellian principles; for example, when the presbyter says, in Irenzeus, “ Mensura Patris filius ;” or when Clemens Alexandrinus says, with the younger Theo- dotus, “The Son is the countenance of the Father ;” or when Melito says, @eds témovOev bd Se€vas iopanditidos (compare Routh 1, 116). Still more positive countenance was given by So far as I know, Neander was the first to direct attention to this fact. (See above. ) VOL. II, B 18 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. two circumstances. Firstly: From the days of the Apostles down to Justin, the Church had, as we have seen, laid prime stress on the hypostatic pre-existence of the higher nature of Christ; and Justin, in connection therewith, had not even avoided subordina- tian elements. He himself, however, firmly believed the Logos te be of one substance with the Father ; and during the course of the history of the doctrine of the Logos, this constantly assumed a more definite shape, until, in the second half of the second cen- tury, the Church was concerned not so much to distinguish the Son from, as to establish His unity with, the Father. Inadequate momenta, which had been intended to aid in establishing the divine hypostasis of Christ, but which intertwined Him imme- diately with the world, were then cast aside, and the Son was introduced into the inmost adytum of the divine essence itself, as the reason and wisdom of God. Had the matter rested there (a thing to which the teachers of the Church were certainly opposed), Sabellianism would have found a home in the Church, and the impossibility of distinguishing the Son from the Father would have become a manifest fact. For if the divine Trias, which the faith of the Church had long held to be a settled thing, meant nothing more than that reason and spirit (Adyos Kal mvedua) are in God, Monarchianism would have had no reason for its opposition. Moreover, inasmuch as the Church most decidedly maintained that there was only one God, Sabel- lianism was the more justified in, as it were, asking the doctrine of the Church, whether a merely ceconomic Trinity would not meet the wants of the Christian mind; and in the then posi- tion of the doctrine of an immanent Trinity, it could with cer- tainty reckon on receiving, in many cases, an affirmative reply. Secondly: The revival of Ebionism must have caused the Church to cling more firmly to the doctrine of the essential equality of the Son; and fear both of it, and of the Arianism which now began to raise its head,' must have prevented it from insisting too strongly on the distinction between the divine in Christ and the Father. And, in fact, it is quite possible that the ever- 1 Compare Recognit. Pseudoclement. (see Vol. I. 216 and Note BBBB) On the other hand, after what has been advanced above (Vol. I. 192 ff.). it is not improbable that a class of Ebionites also (of course a higher class, to which one scarcely ought to apply the name) approximated te Patripassianism PATRIPASSIAN MONARCHIANISM. 19 strengthened tendency to affirm, even as regards the soul, the completeness of the humanity of Christ in opposition to Docetism (Note 7),—a tendency unquestionably little favourable to any form of Sabellianism,—w as, In many respects, restrained by the necessity of combating Ebionism ; for Ebionism postulated above all, for the integrity a the etait of Christ, a complete and free personality. The weakest side of the newer form of Ebionism, in the eyes of simple-minded Christians, was its inability to lay any stress on the death of Christ and His atoning work. (It was otherwise, perhaps, with those alone who are ea tinneths in the note on the last page.) Some, indeed, are said to have done so (Orig. Comm. in Joh. T. xxxii. 9), but it was mere inconsistency ; ; and the iepov Kal cwTnpLov yphwa, which, according to them, 6 cravpwbels Th Koopw@ émdedyjxev, can scarcely be aiineaeal otherwise than arbitrarily and magically, with an Ebionitic Chesniten In this respect especially, the patripassian view was far more satis- factory :—the more explicable, therefore, is the great impression made by Praxeas, its earliest representative, and a confessor, during his first stay in Rome. The heresy which Praxeas in- Bonuced Victorinus endeavoured to strengthen (corroborare curavit), says Tertullian in the passage from his “de prascr. her.” 53. This was, without doubt, the Roman Bishop Victor, who excommunicated Theodotus. The excitement which then prevailed precisely in Rome, on account of the revival of Ebion- ism, would appear therefore to have favoured the introduction of views of a directly opposite character, of which Praxeas, coming from Asia, was the advocate and representative. When we remember that a certain predominance had hitherto always been given to the Father over the Son, we shall confess the ad- mission of the idea, that in Christ the Father had appeared, had actually manifested Himself in His person, to have been an unheard of but a mighty step. The inmost nature of God is disclosed,— a completely new period is inaugurated. We thus enter into fellowship with the Most High God, who is God alone; and no middle being has been able to redeem us. It cannot have been the idea of the mere abstract unity of God that led Patripassians to the view they advocated; on the contrary, that Jewish momentum, in itself, would have absolutely excluded the possibility of change and suffering in God. But it was also 20 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. the consciousness of entering into immediate fellowship with the Most High God, who as such is the one God, in conse+ quence of His completely clothing Himself with our humanity, sharing the distress of finitude, and the sufferings which fall solely to the lot of our nature,—that constituted a second and equally important momentum of Patripassianism. On the one hand, Praxeas and Marcion are thus brought into closer proxi- mity, the former turning out to be the Church’s continuation of the latter; on the other hand, a new explanation is given of the warfare they waged in common with Montanism, and it is seen to have been the natural result of their essential principles. Montanism threatened the Church with a new form of legality, incompatible with the revelation of the inmost nature of God vouchsafed to men in Christianity. The doctrine of the Trinity by no means furnishes a sufficient explanation of the opposition raised by Praxeas to Montanism; for, in the first place, there are too few traces of an old Montanistic doctrine of the Trinity, and Tertullian had arrived at his doctrine of the Trinity prior to embracing Montanism ; and, in the second place, if, as some affirm, it were certain that the Montanistic doctrine of the Trinity was ceconomical, that is, in principle Sabellian, it would be difficult to explain Praxeas’ opposition thereto. Praxeas, says Tertullian (see Adv. Prax. 20), treats the words, “I and the Father are one; He that seeth Me, seeth the Father,” as though they formed the entire Bible (Note 8) ; and in the Old Testament, appeals most readily to the passages which testify to the unity of God (c. 18). This, says Tertullian, is right enough in opposing polytheism; but we are not thereby shut out from understanding, by the one God, the Father, the Son, and the Spirit. But what are the teachings of Praxeas concerning the Christian idea of God, which, even in the general baptismal formula, takes a Trinitarian form? One and the same, says he, is Father, Son, and Holy Ghost (c. 2). Now, as he absolutely refuses to admit of distinctionsinthe-simple: divine essence.(c. 12, the “unitas simplex,” the “unicus et singularis Deus”), what significance can he attach to that tri- plicity? The question of the Holy Spirit we must leave un- touched, for we do not know what Praxeas said regarding Him ; but we know that he denied the pre-existence of the Son, and. proposed to apply the designation to the Incarnate One alone. PATRIPASSIAN MONARCHIANISM. 21 It was not a mere power of the Most High that was active in the formation of Christ, but the power of the Most High is the Most High Himself (c. 26); He descended into Mary. Had Praxeas and his school brought the Trinitarian names into con- nection with the different revelations, the word Father also would have stood to him for a form of the revelation of the one God, and this one God he would then have distinguished, as the Monas, not only from the Son, but even from the Father. We do not find, however, that he did anything of the kind; on the contrary, it is probable that he identified the Father with the Monas.’ The distinction, therefore, that he draws between God in general and Christ, is the following,~“The Father is the Spirit, that is, God, that is, Christ: the Son is the Flesh, that is, the man, that is, Jesus. The higher element in the person of Jesus is God Himself, or the Father; in Jesus, however, He entered into finitude and became man. In the one person of Christ, Praxeas distinguished the part that was born, to wit, the flesh, and God, who is in Himself unalterable. The Father | proceeded forth from Himself, and returned back into Himself {c. 23). In this way, the incarnation is reduced to a mere theophany; not even the eternal continuance of this person is ensured, especially as Praxeas taught nothing concerning a soul of Christ. The man, the “caro,” must have been conceived as impersonal, as a mere garment, or as an organ whose office it is to present the Father visibly to the world.? Had Praxeas gone no further, his system would have differed little from the old Docetism,—for example, from that of Mar- cion. But he conceived the appearance of the Most High God to be at all events one of long continuance, a permanent one: like Noetus, he represents Jesus as having been actually born of Mary, as growing, hungering, thirsting, suffering, and dying. To the assumption of so permanent and peculiar an union of God with human nature, Praxeas was undoubtedly impelled by a re- gard to the religious nature of man, which feels that in Christ, God did enter into the most intimate fellowship with our nature Such a fellowship would not have been established, had not H« 16.16: ‘‘ Patrem in vulvam Marie deducunt.” C. 27: Out of the ‘‘ virtus Altissimi” which overshadowed Mary, ‘‘ Patrem faciunt.” Compare c. 23, 2. 2 C. 23: ‘ Tolerabilius erat, duos divisos, quam unum Deum versipellem pree licare.” 22 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. participated in all the acts and sufferings of the man Jesus, and had He assumed human nature merely externally as a garment. For this reason, Schleiermacher (I. c. p. 497) had no right to throw doubt on the statement frequently made by Tertullian and others, to the effect that Praxeas and his school represented God Himself, or the Father, as sympathetically suffering with us. Tertullian’s expression, “Patrem crucifixit,’ must, of course, perhaps be taken rhetorically ; for he distinguished _be- tween the “caro” and the Father, and therefore also, that which could befall the former alone, from that which might also touch the latter. But that he in some way or other held the Father to have participated in the sufferings of Christ, cannot be doubted! He and his school believed themselves the rather warranted in doing so, as even the recognised teachers of the Church were accustomed to say,—The Son, or even God, suf- fered; Christ, the Son of God, died? But they tried to make their meaning more intelligible by the formula, “ compassus est pater filio” (c. 29). For fear of directly blaspheming the Father, Tertullian supposes, they adopted this milder form of expression, and granted that the Father and Son are two. It is scarcely likely, however, that Praxeas and his school meant, in adopting the formula, to grant that there were two (duos) subjects; for this would have thoroughly clashed with their theory. Their meaning probably was,—The sufferings affected, it is true, in the first instance, merely the body, through which God is Son; for the human substance alone was mortal (c. 30). But the sufferings of the flesh could not remain in- different and foreign to the higher part of this person; on the contrary, the higher part, or the Father, sympathized in the sufferings (compassus est). We do not find Praxeas ever alluding to a human soul of Christ; and therefore it was im- possible for him to avoid representing the ipse-Deus, the avro- Oeos, as taking part in the sufferings of Christ. With this was 1 Inc. 2, where Tertullian professes to give an account of the doctrine of Praxeas, we read, ‘‘Itaque post tempus pater natus, Pater passus:” c. 16, —‘‘Tpsum credunt Patrem et visum et congressum et operatum et sitim et esuriem passum.” 2 Ergo inquis, et nos eadem ratione Patrem mortuum dicentes, qua vos Filium, non blasphemamus in Dominum Deum, non enim ex divina sed ex humana substantia mortuum dicimus:” c. 80; compare Melito in Routh Jn etee PATRIPASSIAN MONARCHIANISM. 23 connected his attributing a passible aspect to the nature of the Father, his assuming in the Father Himself that momentum of finitude, which others—as, for example, his opponent Tertullian -—assumed in the Son, even prior to His incarnation. Tertullian was quite right in drawing the conclusion,—Sympathy is, after all, taal ; suffering, that is, with another. lither the Father is tacapable of suffering, and then He is incapable of sympathy ; or, if He be capable of sympathy, He is also capable of suffering. And, in fact, a mere suffering of the body, espe- cially as nothing is said of he existence of a human soul, would be spiritless, and without significance relatively to redemption. If we ask further, how Pr axeas found it possible to transfer passibility to God, a reply i is offered to us by his doctrine, that the divine had Bicaitel itself in itself as finite, had set forth out of itself the momentum of finitude (the “caro”); or rather, inasmuch as this would lead to a docetical, heavenly humanity, the Father took up this finite momentum, that is, flesh, into His essence, out of Mary, fully appropriated it and identified Him- self with it, so that He really became man; and “caro,” with all its liability to suffering, is, not something foreign to Him, but a momentum of Himself. This incorporation of humanity with His substance evidently presupposes, however, that the Father was in one aspect susceptible to the finite, to the passible; and it is this aspect which is manifested in the incarnation. So we understand it, when Tertullian finds it necessary, in opposition to Praxeas, to assure his readers, “caro non deus est” (c. 27) ; and when he gives a long refutation and exposition of the above mentioned theory, which at this period was not an uncommon one, namely, that God had, as it were, transformed Himself into “caro;” in consequence whereof, Christ’s flesh participated in the divine essence, and it was possible to term His sufferings divine sufferings (Note 9). None the less, however, was God the Father present in this “caro,” even as to His unchange- ableness: the distinction between “caro” and “spiritus,” that is, “ Deus,” is a real one; for, without renouncing Himself, God, as it were, gave Himself another form of being (Andersseyn) in the “caro” of Christ; but inasmuch as it is God Himself who gave Himself this other form of existence, the two aspects meet in the person of Christ, and do not stand over against each other as foreign. Whether this were the theory of Praxtas or not, we 24 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. must allow that Tertullian was justified in charging him with great inconsequence. For either he was in earnest in asserting the Father, the adroGeos, to be an absolutely simple Being; and then he could not attribute to Him a capability and an incapa- bility of suffering at one and the same time, but must have reduced the incarnation to a process, which merely transitorily affected His unchangeable essence, and must have represented Christ as an organ through which the omnipresent, unchange- able Father appears differently from elsewhere, although the incarnation was not on His part, that is, objectively, a pecu liar deed. Or else, if he were in earnest in saying that God took finitude upon Himself in Christ, he must have allowed the existence of much more determinate distinctions in God, and have renounced on the one hand his doctrine of the abstract unity of God, and on the other hand his complaints against the doctrine of the Church.? This, too, was the point to which Tertullian endeavoured to drive him. With great insight he shows him how the incarnation must. either be reduced_to a mere semblance; how, consequently, it must be attributed to the subjective manner of consideration, when He, who in Him- self is unchangeable, appears in Christ and Christianity differ- ently from elsewhere; and how humanity would thus relapse in 1 C. 11. ‘*Veracem Deum credens scio, illum non aliter, quam disposuit, pronuntiasse, nec aliter disposuisse, quam pronuntiavit. Tu porro eum mendacem efficias et fallacem et deceptorem fidei hujus, si cum ipse esset sibi filius, alii dabat filii personam” (that is, if God in Christ seemed to be another, appeared as another, than the Father, and yet was in reality merely an appearance of the Father). Compare c. 23. ? What does it mean, says Tertullian, when the Son is said to pray to the Father, if there is no distinction between Father and Son? (c. 23). What is the resurrection of the Son, and His anointing (c. 28), or the curse which Christ was made for us? or the desertion of the Son, when He cried out, My God, My God, why hast Thou forsaken Me? (c. 30). It is a blasphemy to say that the Father became a curse for us.—In fact, the fellowship which God holds with man in Christ is reduced to a mere sem- blance, if full justice be not done to the distinction between the Father and the Son :—we see this most clearly in connection with the work of atone- ment. If God continue in simple identity with Himself, the process of reconciliation is a mere subjective play and appearance. At this point the affinity between Patripassianism and the entire Sabellian tendency on the one hand, and Docetism on the other, shows itself, as was hinted above, with peculiar distinctness. PRAXEAS. HERMOGENES. 25 its ante-Christian condition: or that he must go forwards (c. 4, 2, 6, 80; Apolog. 21), admit the existence of objective distinc- tions in God, reject the abstract simplicity of the divine nature ; and then it would be possible for him to regard the divine Son as really and truly participating in finitude. This he expresses in the following way (c. 13),—“ Through the appearance of Christ, the name of God has been more perfectly revealed. The difference between the worshippers of one God and of many gods (plurimz divinitatis) is fixed by Christianity; for if we really meant that there are three Gods and three Lords, when we teach that there are Father, Son, and Holy Ghost, we, the sons of light, should have extinguished the torches which hght us to the martyr’s death. But also between Christianity and Judaism (c. 31) there is no other difference than this, that the Jews believe monotheism to be incompatible with reckoning the Son, and after the Son the Spirit, to the one God. But what would be the work of Christianity, and the substance of the New Testament, which sets a limit to the law and the prophets with John, if Father, Son, and Spirit, believed in as three, do not constitute the one God?” By several teachers of the Church a connection is supposed to have existed between Praxeas and Hermogenes, the well- known defender of the eternity of matter (compare Philostr. de Heres. c. 54 f.; see Leopold’s “ Hermogenis de origine mundi sententia,” 1844, pp. 22 f. 28 ff.). As he does not appear to have called in question the deity of Christ (Tertull. adv. Her- mog. 1), although he probably doubted His pre-existence as a divine hypostasis and His participation in the creation of the world, he belongs without doubt to the class now under consi- deration. With this agrees the further circumstance, that, according to Theodoret, he did not hold the humanity of Christ to be eternal, but, like two Galatian heretics, Seleucus and Hermias, represented Him as laying aside His body in the sun ; | in proof of which theory, they appealed to Ps. xix. 4. His. opinion was perhaps the following :—that Christ laid aside the cross material element; whereas the soul, which (in his view) -appertained to matter, might have continued Christ’s (compare Theodoret’s Her. fab. 1,19). It is worthy of remark, that, with his view of matter, he was able to attribute a soul also to Christ,—without mvedua, it is true:—vedua, however, was 26 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. involved in the divine substance of Christ. That the doctrine of a matter, independent of God, might very well suit this class of Monarchians, we shall see below. In Asia, patripassian views appear to have already existed a considerable period ; at all events, the names of several repre- sentatives thereof have been handed down to us. So Epigonos and Cleomenes (see Theodoret’s Her. fab. 3, 3). But we have more precise information regarding Noetus, who, according to Hippolytus (c. Noetum, ed. Fabric. T. 1, 235 ff, of the Greek text, T. 2, 5 ff.) and Theodoret 1. ¢., as also according to John of Damascus, was a native of Smyrna; according to Epiph. (Heer. 57), of Ephesus. Noetus also aimed at conciliating the true and perfect deity of Christ with the unity of God,! by saying, “ Christ Himself is the Father.” For the Father is God (Fabr. T. 2, 7), but Christ, who Himself was Good, suffered ; inasmuch, then, as we know but one God and no other, to wit, the Father, I must necessarily at- tribute suffering to this God (rodrov b70 waos dépev). The Father is Himself the Son; the Son was born, suffered, and raised Himself from the dead. This explains, says he, why in the New Testament the resurrection of Christ is at one time treated as the work of the Father, at another time as the work of the Son. The meaning of this, again, is undoubtedly that the Father, God in Himself, is not the Son, apart from the incarnation ; and that the existence of a Son began with the incarnation ; whereas the Church terms the Logos doapxos, Son: so, for example, Justin, Tertullian, and others? The Father, therefore, consti- tuted Himself His own Son in Christ. Besides the passages in Praxeas, Noetus appealed to Baruch iii. 35, Isa. xlv. 14, in proof of the unity of God; on the other hand, to Rom. ix. 5, 1 Cor. viii. 6, which put Christ on a level with the Most High God, in proof of His identity with the Father. The fate of finitude, of suffering, and the like, Noetus probably transferred to God, much more decidedly than even Praxeas: moreover, he does 1. According to Hippolytus c. Noét., he said to his opponents, r/ ov» xaxdy Toa sozeCay rov Xpirdy; according to Epiphanius, rf yap HOKOY En wolnna; tye Osdy d024Ca, eve erlaramar nal odx &drov, vyevynbevta, a&70- devévre. To judge from the reply of the presbyters and from the nature of the case, Noetus considered the two to be indissolubly connected. 2 From this point of view Hippolytus ec. Noetum 15, must be estimated. PRAXEAS. NOETUS. 27 not appear even to have distinguished so clearly between the cap& and the God in Christ, as did Praxeas; but rather to have re- garded God Himself as one nature, which, in one aspect, is inca- pable of suffering, in another aspect, capable of suffering, mor- tal, and so forth ;—thus, like Praxeas, after blotting out the distinction between Father and Son, importing a distinction into the very essence of God. It deserves, however, acknowledg- ment and remark, that Noetus had already completed the sys- tem of Patripassianism, and had stripped it of that ethnic appearance of rendering God’s dvaus immediately finite, which it had in the hands of Praxeas. For, in the passage to be immediately quoted from Theodoret, the é@édew plays a great role relatively to the passible aspect A God’s being, sefaeanieea by Noetus. Everything finite, all change and kena bes God solely through the medium of His will; which, if it con- tinues the same and is in itself absolute (for example, as the will of love), is a sufficient guarantee of the unchangeableness of the divine being. To be invisible, ungenerated, immortal, and impassible, belongs, on the contrary, to the divine essence in itself; at the same time, however, in the view of Noetus, this His essence cannot be a check on His will, but remains subject thereto, and on that account can be made passible, mortal, and so forth. It would be interesting to ascertain Noetus’ precise doctrine of redemption, in order to see whether his conception of this will of God, on which he lays such great stress, as op- posed to the divine nature, or to the physical categories of the idea of God, is an ethical one; or whether he regarded it as mere unconditioned, perfect power, which, being destitute ot determinations in itself, is not raised above caprice. All that we certainly know, however, is that, in the view of Noetus, the eternal God put Himself, by His will, into the condition of pas- sibility and visibility ; such is his estimate of the significance of the appearance of Christ. I am not inclined, therefore, with Schleiermacher (Theol. Nachlass 2, 506 f.), to charge Theodoret with error in saying, éva faci eivar Oeov Kal marEpa, TOY Oh@V Snpusoupryov" apavij HEV, oTay eOeNy, Pasvopevov € pine av Bov- Aaya, Kab TOV aUTOV doparov Elva Kab op@p.evor, Kab ryevvy TOV Kab ayéevynTov" aryévUNToV ev e& apXS, ryevunTov Oe OTE eK TIS mrapbévou yevynOjvat iO noev' arab Kai abdvarov Kal Tadw ad maOnrov Kal Ovnrov: arabs yap av, dno, TO TOO aTaUpOD 28 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. wdOos eerjoas bréuevev. For Hippolytus, Epiphanias, and Theodoret agree too decidedly in representing Noetus as attri- buting suffering to God. Moreover, by introducing the element of will, he refined the representation; and in the very act of apparently undermining the unchangeableness of God (by mak- ing the divine nature, which is in itself impassible, unbegotten, immortal, dependent on the divine will), he gave it a new hold, in the potence of the same will. Besides the passages which those Fathers cite, and which, if not correct, they must have forged, the view just mentioned is specially favoured by the circumstance, that on the minds of Hippolytus and Epiphanius, who made use of independent sources of information, the theory of Noetus left the same impression,—the impression, to wit, that, to be consistent, he ought to have assumed an essential connec- tion between the humanity of Christ and the deity ; be it either by Christ’s bringing humanity with Him down from heaven,_or by God’s converting Himself into humanity: and this impression evidently arose from the circumstance that on his principles fini- tude was constituted a determination of the divine essence (Note 10). What further distinguishes Noetus from Praxeas is, not that he attributes a human soul to Christ,—for that is done rather by his opponent Hippolytus (c. Noét. 17),—but that he already brings under consideration the other revelations of God. He of course believed that it was one and the same divine nature which manifested itself in the repeated and multiform revelations; and to this one nature, which, like Praxeas, he designates Father, he must have attributed the capability of being finite, visible, pas- sible. ‘This general possibility became an actuality, in and through the various revelations of God. Here the horizon widens, and the task presented itself, of pointing out the distine- tion between the revelation in Christ and all other revelations. © Lo define this difference was the more necessary, as, from the absence of distinctions in the divine nature, we should naturally conclude that its revelations would be uniform and identical ; and that, consequently, notwithstanding the purpose to exalt Christ to the highest rank, there could have been nothing in Him, as a revelation, which had not been substantially con- tained in all other revelations. Noetus, however, did nothing of importance towards the settling of this question. On the con- trary, although he broke the ground for a comparison of the NOETUS. BERON. 29 Christian revelation with others, he did not advance beyond the affirmation, that, when God wills, He is invisible, and when He wills, He manifests Himself,—as though his sole task had been to show that the unchangeableness of God was not such as to ex- clude a revelation like that in Christ, seeing that related revela- tions had already been made. In this way, Christianity is plainly assigned a place again amongst mere theophanies ; nor, as a matter of fact, do we find retin expressing any opinion as to the duration of the Person of Christ. Quite as suspicious a feature of his system is, that it sets no limits whatever to the revelations of God. In each of them, it is true, He Himself is present; but ever new revelations might appear necessary, un- less it were proved that the full idea of a theophany had attained realization in Christ, and that God had manifested Himself once for all in the God-man. Thus viewed, the objection raised by the Noetians to the doctrine of the Church, that it afforded no protection against an endless polytheism, might have been justly retaliated; for the Church might have objected, that the Noetians came to no end with their endless theophanies. To the class of men who shared the tendency of Noetus, be- long further Beron and his associates (Note 11). “ Recently,” says Hippolytus (Fragm. 5, Fabr. 1, 228), “ Beron and some others made their appearance ; who asad the sect of Valentinus in order to involve themselves in deeper error. They say,—The flesh appropriated by the Logos worked like works with the deity (ravroupyos), in virtue of its assumption (mpdcAnWs), and the deity had the like capability of suffering with the flesh, in virtue of its xevwous ; thus teaching that the two aspects were changed, commingled, poured together, and converted into each other.” Hippolytus answers,—If both, to wit, the flesh and deity, suffered and worked in the like manner, then all distinction between deity and flesh must have vanished, and they cannot have retained their respective natures (Fragm.6). What conception can they form, then, of the one Christ, who is at one and the same time God and man by nature? What sort of existence can they attribute to Him, if, as they say, He became man by the conversion of deity into humanity; and if, on the other hand, He became God through the conversion of the flesh? For the mutation of the one into the other (uetamtwors) is the entire destruction of both. However confused this theory may at first sight appear, 30 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. light is thrown upon it when we commence our examination with the point which Hippolytus mentions second ; and when we assume, as the first and eighth Fragments J ustify us in doing, that two things, which, according to the representation of Hip- polytus, would seem to have been uttered, as it were, in one breath, were actually separated by an interval of time. Hippo- lytus was led to the view he took by Beron’s presupposition of the essential equality of the two natures. But if we take the xévoots, which Beron must have posited as the first, for our point of departure, we are led into the following course of thought :—God_has subjected Himself to the determination of finitude or of humanity ; He entered into the limitation and cir- cumscription of humanity; His self-emptying was real and_ob- jective (see Fragm. 1); and the result thereof was, that God posited Himself as an actual man. ‘The Tepiypagdn is thus taken up into God Himself; the limitation did not affect the humanity alone, but in positing Himself as a man, God sub- jected Himself to limitation. The man thus originated, as we may conclude from the second part of the frst Fragment, is related to God in Himself, that is, to the complete idea-of- the divine, as the lesser to the greater; and does not correspond to the latter. At this point, however, commences the opposed de- velopment. The humanity, which arose in such a manner, is not foreign to the highest, to the divine; but, conformably to its origin, carries the divine within itself, as its inner essence; consequently, the development of this humanity 1s its deification. We can now understand the proposition, on which Beron and his school laid such great stress, that Hippolytus derived their entire error from it (Fragm. 8, Fabr. 1, 229 f.). They maintain, says he, that the divine activity, which in reality did but mant- fest itself through the medium of the flesh in miracles, became the very activity of the flesh itself ((Siav yevéoOar tis capkoy tyv Oelav évépyevav, compare Bibl. Max. iii. 261, c. 7). At the same time, we see that the eternal duration of the humanity of | Christ is thereby secured,—a thing which always remained doubtful with the other men of this tendency. One might, indeed, here also imagine that God must restore Himself to the state in which He was prior to the transformation, after the revelation had been accomplished; but such a supposition would involve the disappearance of the humanity. Whereas the deve- BERON. 31 lopment of the humanity, which the divine potence constituted its own, is itself the return or restoration of God to Himself, for it is deification; consequently, to teach the laying aside of the humanity was forbidden on the same ground as that urged by the teachers of the Church. This theory is very far removed from Ebionism; but it is equally remarkable as indicating that Patripassianism, which had originally put the humanity of Christ surprisingly into the background, as compared with His divine nature, had arrived at a stadium when it found it needful to lay special. stress thereon. No allusion, it is true, is made to a human soul; but the doctrine that the divine had gained id/av ovcias mepuypadpny by the xévwous, and indeed the entire course taken by this Christology, secured for the humanity of Christ a dignity and importance such as the doctrine of the Church was as yet far from attributing to it. Hippolytus answered Beron as follows: — “God is un- changeable. The Logos, in the aspect in which He is identical with the Father, was not, in any respect whatever, rendered identical with the flesh through the cévwats; but what He was prior to assuming the flesh, that He continued,—to wit, indepen- dent of all circumscription (aepeypady). Through the whole- some act of incarnation, He introduced into the flesh the activity of His own deity; but this activity was neither circumscribed by the flesh, in consequence of the xévwous, nor did it grow puatxas out of the flesh, as it grew out of the deity (Fragm. 1, 11). What the divine was prior to the incarnation, that it was afterwards,-—to wit, unbounded as to its essence, incomprehensi- ble, impassible, incomparable, unchanged, unconverted, mighty in itself, abiding in its own natural existence, and working ac- cording to its own nature. So also, what the flesh was as to essence and operation, that it continued to be even after it had been most intimately united with the deity. ‘Thus the Incarnate One worked both after a divine and after a human manner. So far as He worked after a divine manner, the divine activity shone through the flesh. For the nature of the deity was by no means transmuted, as though it had become essentially flesh, that is, flesh of deity; but the flesh remained what it was, that is, weak flesh, in accordance with the word of the Lord, ‘The spirit is willing, the flesh is weak.’ In the flesh, He performed 32 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. and suffered that which pertained to the flesh. The abasement of the deity was solely a thing for us; that is, it had no objective reality. Moreover, the distinction between deity and humanity is not a merely quantitative, comparative one (KaTa cUYyKpLOW) ; otherwise, we should have to describe one and the same being as both greater and less than Himself. But beings of the like essence alone can be compared with each other; not those of unlike essence. Between God, the Creator of the universe, and the creature, between the unbounded and the bounded, between illimitedness and limitedness, no comparison can be instituted. God never falls out of Himself (wéves avéxrtwtos); never did He enter on an existence outside of Himself (€& yéyove) ; and yet the incarnation was a reality, and God truly revealed Him- self in it.” By way of illustration, he employs the relation of a thought to its representation in word, through the medium of the tongue, or in signs written by the hand (Fragm. 3). Thought is the self-moved energy of the soul, which flows forth, according to its nature, in a continual stream (as did the energy of Christ out of the deity). When I mould thoughts into words, or delineate them in signs, employing the tongue as an in- strument, or written signs, which in themselves are foreign to the thing represented, the thoughts themselves remain unchanged. Although they attain to actuality by means of something unlike themselves, they are not changed, but simply revealed and per- ceived. It is true, I employ my tongue and letters for the ma- nifestation of my thoughts; and yet the thoughts do not belong to the words or signs, but to me the speaker ; and I give expression to them as mine in both ways, just as they flow out of my rational soul, The tongue is merely the organ. Now, as the power, whose essence is rational, whilst continuing unaltered in itself, expresses itself by means of the bodily tongue; so, if two things utterly incomparable may be compared, by means of the supernatural cwpatwots, was the almighty, all-creating activity of the entire deity manifested without change through the holy flesh of Christ, in all that He worked after a divine manner; but the deity itself remained essentially exempt from srepeypadn, although it shone through a nature essentially limited. God is equal to Himself, and has nothing unequal to Himself." But for our redemption’s sake, and in order to constitute the universe a sharer in unchangeable- 1 Gott ist sich selbst gleich und hat nichts sich Ungleiches. BEKON. 33 ness, the Creator of the universe appropriated to Himself out of the Virgin, without conversion (rpo77), a rational soul and a sensitive body, became man, and worked nothing divine without the body (yuuvov ceparos), and nothing human without the participation of the deity (duoupov OeotyTos), in that He pre- served for Himself a new and fitting method of working after the manner of both, whilst leaving the nature of each unaltered. We have no original information to the effect that Beron taught that Christ had a human soul; but we need not be sur- prised at Hippolytus’ not making this a charge against him, for the human soul of Christ plays but an impersonal réle in Hip- polytus’ own system: indeed, his favourite name for the humanity of Christ is that.of a garment; and when he alludes to the soul of Christ, it is not so much on its own account, as because he meant to postulate the existence of two complete natures, and the human nature would not be complete without the soul. But, what is of still more importance, Beron is unquestionably in this aspect superior to Hippolytus, although he does not give any special prominence to the human soul. or the fundamental aim of his system was to show, that that which is otherwise attri- buted to the deity alone, working through human nature, must also be attributed to the human nature itself, and be regarded as its own activity.’ Beron’s aim was not an eternal or heavenly humanity, although he did not consider it incompatible with the eternal nature of God that He should be passible; but he be- lieved that God first became passible when He posited Himself as a man in Christ, by the act of Kév@ots.” But as he held that an individual man, Jesus of Nazareth, a limited personality (repiyparros), was thus brought into bene so also did he con- ceive the act of incarnation to introduce fee into God Him- self :—that is, by His own act, a limitation and circumscription was introduced into God, sain had not previously existed. In Christ, therefore, God was self-emptied, and had acquired an idéa 1 xewbevres idloey yeviobcs rns capnos ryy Osicv évépyecev. ‘This, like the doctrine of the werarolnots capxos in God, reminds us of Paul of Samosata. The point of departure, of course, in consequence of Beron’s doctrine of the xévoots, 18 quite different; and, for this reason, everything stands, from the very outset, in a different light. Beron, moreover, appears to have paid leas regard to the ethical and the intellectual than to the davueare. 2 Another view was soon afterwards taken by the Manicheans, with their ‘‘ Jesus patibilis.”’ VOL. 1G, C 34 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. rrepuypady. It is self-evident that, even though Beron spoke ef the Logos, as we may perhaps conclude from the fifth Fragment (Fabr. 1, 228; Bipwv tis, wel ETEpav twav Tv Barevtivou davraciav aévtes, XElpove KaK@ KaTETapnTaV, EYovTES TI [Lev mpoornpbcicay TO NOYH TapKa yeverOat TavToupyov TH OeoryTA, Sua thy mpoodmw Ti GeornTa Sé yevécOar TavtoTraly Th capKi Sud neva, TpoTV ood Kat pupow Kal ovyyvolw, Kal THY Els addjrous duhorépov wetaBorv Soypatifovres), he cannot have attributed to Him an hypostasis or 7epyypady of His own, apart from the incarnation. Apart from the incarnation, he could only speak of the Logos as perhaps Sabellius may have done (Ang. Mai. 1. c. T. 7, 170 #f.), and as Noetus (Hipp. c. Noét. 15) did (see Appendix, Note 16). The more Beron felt him- self compelled to attribute objective significance to the Kévwors, the more necessary was it undoubtedly for him to distinguish, from the time of the incarnation, between the divine which became man and subjected itself to circumscription and passi- bility, and God, so far as He did not enter into the weprypady ; for it could never be his intention to maintain that the absolute God existed solely and entirely in this xevwors, subsequently to the incarnation. But inasmuch as he represented the divine in Christ as acquiring a 7repuypady of its own through the incar- nation, it is the more certain that he did not attribute to Him a tepuypady previously.’ The divine element which thus sub- jected itself to the fate of finitude, might, indeed, appear as an aroxor of the original divine; nay, even, as though plunged and lost in Lethe, through the «évwovs which it voluntarily un- derwent; but, even after the transformation, it continued to 1 Gregor. Thaumat. speaks (see Ang. Mai 7, 170) of men who intro- duce an oxox into the essence of God, through the cou of Christ, and who, through the body, dvdoaxivas repiypaeQoves thy yévynot tov viod Ex Tov xerpos. Quite as objectionable is it, says he, to attribute progress and xeby to the deity, as to separate the progressing and suffering body (7.e., the humanity) from the deity (that is, from the non-emptied, unchange- able deity); as though the body were id:eCcvrws vQsorcs, that is, in the language of Beron, as though all évéoyvei, even the divine, were (dia ri onpxos OF ovamoas éxQvowévn Out of it (Fragm. 2). Because Beron did not believe in the existence of a Logos, prior to the incarnation, who possessed a xreptrype@y of His own, it was in his power to designate the deity which set itself forth as man, the zerpixy dedrns; and for this reason, we have a right to class him as above. BERON. BERYLL. oy) constitute 1 the inmost-essence-of the humanity, and manifested itself ever more and more fully in the development of the man Jesus, until he was at last transmuted into.God.* Here, there- fore, we find a course exactly similar to that taken by the theory of Paul of Samosata, though starting from a completely oppo- site theological point-of-view. The Ebionitical element, which sinks back to the category of power, and which would be in- volved in the dzroxo7, does not, however, like the azoxo77 itself, make its appearance in the Fragments of Beron ; indeed, it is scarcely likely that he, on the whole, shared this tendency to Ebionism. On the contrary, he may have been influenced by the double desire, neither to represent the humanity of Christ as impersonal, on the one hand, nor the natures outside of each other as a double personality, on the other. Similar, if indeed not more than similar, to Beron, both in name and in views, was Beryll of Bostra. We have nothing certain regarding him, save a passage in Eusebius, which has given rise to the most varied combinations.” The views enter- tained concerning him diverge as far as possible from each other. Furthest removed from each other are those of Schleiermacher and Baur. The former (1. c. 519-533) reckons him amongst the Patripassians, and maintains, not that he transferred suffer- ings into God, but that he believed the objective substance of God to have undergone an alteration, a limitation (id/a ovovas Tepiypad)), renee the incarnation; the latter (1. c. 284-292) classes him with ne Artemonites or Neo-Ebionites. A middle course between these two is taken by Neander (2, 1018-20) ; (similarly also Rossel, the writer of a review of Baur’s “Trin. und Menschwerdung” in the Berl. Jahrbiicher, 1844, Nos. 41-— 45.) The idea of areal indwelling of God Himself he does not venture on attributing to him, but considers that he occupied a middle position between Ebionism and Patripassianism, in that 1 LL. c., Fragm. 8; weraBorn dserntos yevepeevos dvbpwros, nal oapxos petraroimocs Occ. 2 EHuseb. H. E. 6, 383; Béve rived trys wiorews moepesoQepely 7 El0TO, TOY Larnpa xal Kupiov nuay rgyery TOALLOY LAN mpovQeor avers nar bolav voles mepiypaPny =po tHS eho dvbpamous em iOnpelors, pe noe poyy Osornta idloey eyeuy, GAN EeroAiTevomeuny aUTY LovnY chy weroimyy. The passage quoted from Socrates, in Note 7, indicates that the discussions relative to the soul of Christ plaved a great role at the Synod which was convened on his account. Compare Euseb. 6, 20. 36 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. he taught that the man Jesus was irradiated by a divine power. According to Rossel’s further exposition, the humanity of Jesus is the personal element; but alongside thereof are also patri- passian elements. This view, however, renders the theory self- contradictory, and introduces into it elements so heterogeneous, that they could not continue in combination. According to N eander, on the contrary, that irradiation which by the incar- nation became an hypostatization of divine power, was the per- sonific element. Even at an earlier period, the opinion was expressed by Mosheim (“de rebus Christianis ante Constan- tinum Commentarii,” p. 699 ff.), that Beryll did not conceive the entire essence of the Father to have passed over into Christ, on the one hand; nor, on the other hand, merely a divine power,. which would have been decidedly Ebionitic; but the purest, most glorious, wisest possible soul, taken out of, and therefore perfectly like, the nature of the Father. Such an idea would have been Arian. Against both Neander and Mosheim, how- ever, is the text of Eusebius, which says, not that a power or soul of the Father, or deity of the Father, but the (rv) deity of the Father, dwelt in Him. Ullmann (see his “Comm. de Beryllo Bostreno ejusque doctrina,” Hamb. 1835; and compare: “Theol. Studien und Kritiken,” 1836, pp. 1073 f.) is of opinion. that Beryll did not view the divine in Christ merely ebioniti- cally, as a simple power, but conceived it also to be possessed of consciousness or of personality ; thus approximating to Schleier- macher’s position. On the other hand, however, he represents. him not merely denying that the incarnation posited a distinction in God Himself, but also as maintaining that the circumscrip- tive, personific human element (das unschreibende personbil- dende Menschliche) constituted the personality of Christ ; which is scarcely reconcilable with the recognition of the personal existence of the divine in Christ, and involves the assumption of a double personality—an assumption, to which both Ebionites, Patripassians, and Sabellians were most thoroughly opposed. Baur also tries to show that Beryll assumed a twofold person- ality, after the manner of Nestorius. His words are (I. ¢. p. 289),—“'The expression €urodteveo@as, although it involves the idea of indwelling, implies, at the same time, that a free relation existed between the Redeemer and the Father, even as. a citizen stands connected with other citizens equal to himself BERYLL OF BOSTRA. 37 in the place where he lives.” I think, however, that the knot, which Ullmann leaves behind, can be untied. We must either start with the humanity as the primary, the personific element ; and then Beryll must be acknowledged to have been Ebionitical : or, we must take our start with the deity, as the personific, or, more historically expressed, as the active, the hegemonical ele- ment, the element which formed the cvoracvs (Hippol. c. Noét. 15). Those who took this latter view of the matter naturally denied that the Son of God had an hypostatical, or an in any way circumscribed pre-existence. He first became circumscribed when He became incarnate. There is, however, an ambiguity in this latter supposition, the clearing up and removal of which throws an important light upon the whole; namely, the circum- scription of the Son resulted either from the self-determination of God, or from the activity of the human nature. In the latter case, the divine aspect occupied a purely passive and receptive position ; it was subjected to circumscription, to limitation: if, however, it were inactive, nay more, passive, we cannot allow that God and man were united in the highest way, to wit, per- sonally and consciously; for such an union requires that the divine stand in an active, hegemonical relation to the humar aspect. If the divine aspect were passive, we must assume the existence in Christ of a higher principle, of a power, which, however, was by no means all-determining; in other words, we must go over to Ebionism. In this way, Ullmann appears to have glided over from the initiatory Patripassianism to the ulti- mate Kbionism of Beryll. But—and this leads us to the second case—it was not necessary that Patripassianism should pay this price for the personality of Christ, although we by no means intend to deny that many may have taken this course. ‘Those are chiefly chargeable therewith who conceived God, after an ethnic manner, to be immediately capable of suffering; or who resorted to the idea of an amoxom of God in Christ, in order not to be compelled to represent the entire Father as swallowed up and absorbed by Christ, at all events for the period of his development as a child: those are least chargeable therewith, who, like Noetus, set the é@éXew, the divine will, in opposition to the ethnic principle, and represented everything as depen- dent thereon. Indeed, Patripassians might also have said,—The conscious, personal God willed to exist in the form of an actual 38 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. finite being; He consequently either produced the limited hu- manity out of Himself,—which would be a Docetical idea, and incompatible with their recognition of the birth from the Virgin ; or, and this is the only possible alternative, God so perfectly appropriated the body, which sprung from Mary, and took it up into His own essence, that the unity of the person was complete, and the Father, or the fatherly deity, possessed the finitude and the passibleness of this man as its own. To this might be added (as we have found Beron doing) the xévwous, and, on the basis thereof, have been taught the doctrine of a conversion of God into a man born of Mary, which man, however, owed his rise out of the elements in Mary to the afore-mentioned divine conversion. Finally, Fock, in his Diss. de Christolog. Berylh Bostr. 18438, decides—and, as it appears to me, justly—both against Baur, with his imputation of Ebionism, and Neander and Mosheim, with their attempt to weaken the force of the words, Ti TaTpiKny Ocornta €utroNtTEvopevnv év avT@, Which leads toa kind of Arianism. For the reason assigned, he is also opposed to Ullmann ; he therefore substantially adopts Schleiermacher’s view, and classes Beryll with the Patripassians, putting him even on the same level with Praxeas. He is above all averse to grant- ing that Beryll attributed a human soul to Christ, as do Baur and Ullmann (Neander and Rossel ought consistently to do the same) ; justly urging, that unless Beryll had given occasion thereto, the Synod which was held on his account would not have proceeded so “ex abrupto,’ to the consideration and affir- mation of the human soul of Christ (see Notes 7 and 30). He fails, however, to answer the important objection, why Beryll was never reproached with the denial of the human soul of Christ. For we have shown above, that what he says regard- ing the absence of a soul of Christ in the systems even of Ireneus and other teachers of the Church, is historically inac- curate. Further, Ullmann’s objection, that the idea of the assumption of a mere body would be too coarse, Fock sets aside by an appeal to Apollinaris. Nay more, he hints that much may be urged in favour of the opinion, that they regarded the divine subject as the Ego and the intelligence, in brief, as the Spirit in Christ ; if, indeed, it be not quite maintainable. On the other hand, however, not content with characterizing (after Schleier- macher’s example) the strictly patripassian element, to wit, the BERYLL OF BOSTRA. 39 subjection of the Father to suffering, as an idea too coarse to be entertained by this entire series of thinkers, and in particular by Beryll,—a notion which, after what has been advanced above, is by itself untenable ; he will not even concede, with Schleierma- cher, that Beryll believed in the existence of a circumscription in the divine nature itself, subsequent to the incarnation. He is rather of Baur’s opinion, that we must then read, cat’ idiav ri}s ovcias Teprypadny, instead of Kar’ idiav ovcias mepuypagpyv. His judgment, accordingly, appears to be,—Beryll merely maintained that, subsequently to the incarnation, the Redeemer existed in the circumscribed form of an individual; whereas, previously, He had been neither hypostatical nor circumscribed, but abso- lutely identical with the Father. The circumscription was not therefore in Him, but He in the circumscription. Here again, however, we come upon the ambiguity cleared up above. If the Father had not posited circumscription as an objective determi- nation of His own being, He could only have existed in circum- scription so far as His entire being was embraced and bounded by finitude. But on this supposition, the finite would be the active element; and, as we have shown, Beryll must then be de- scribed asan Ebionite. As Fock, however, by no means intends to class Beryll amongst Ebionites, his only alternative is to re- turn to Schleiermacher’s view, and to accept the meprypady as an objective determination of the divine nature itself, with the following proviso—this determination and circumscription was not the effect of the action of the human nature on the divine (a notion which, besides being essentially Hbionitic, had been already given up as untenable by Noetus), but the work of the divine will. From what we know of the man as a whole, this must be assumed to have been his view, even should the sense of the words of Eusebius be, “The Redeemer exists since the incarnation in the circumscription of an individual being (ovcias).” It is more than questionable, however, whether this is the true sense of the words. In the first place, this use of ovcta is not the usual one, and is particularly unsuitable here, because the idea of individuality is already expressed in the words (dia mepuypady, as whose cbject we may very appropri- ately take the substance (ovoia) which is circumscribed. The article is not absolutely indispensable; for the connection itself, as we shall directly see, indicates clearly what sort of an ovota 40 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. is meant. Secondly, In the text of Eusebius, nothing is directly said of circumscription by means of the incarnation. We first arrive at that idea in the way of deduction. Eusebius rather says, the Redeemer did not exist car’ idiav odclas Tepuypadiy. How, then, can we translate as though Beryll maintained that Christ had not pre-existed in the circumscription of an individual being? for the Church itself did not assert such a pre-existence, and the denial thereof would therefore have been no ground of reproach. Eusebius blames him because he denied that the general substance (ovoia) of God had been distinguished into Father and Son; which is figuratively expressed by saying, he attributes to the Redeemer no circumscription of the divine substance peculiar to Himself. If we adopt the rendering, “not in the special circumscription of an hypostasis,” it is true, indeed, that ovcia, at an earlier period, and down to the fourth century, was used as equivalent to trocracis; but then a new difficulty arises, to wit, we shall be certainly compelled to com- plete the sense by supplying the thought,—“ but since the incarnation, the Lord and Redeemer exists in the particular circumscription of an hypostasis.” That, however, would be equivalent to saying, that Eusebius conceived the divine hypo- stasis to be of precisely the same nature, or identical, with that which was posited by the human circumscription ; which is hard to believe. For such a human circumscription brings merely limitation, finitude; whereas the idea of a divine hypostasis, be- sides the negative element, demands in particular a positive, spe- cial, independent divine existence. Eusebius, therefore, cannot have meant to say,—The hypostasis which Beryll denies to the Saviour, prior to the incarnation, he represents Him as acquiring subsequently ; for that is not true. Beryll was not of opinion that the incarnation introduced a special and distinct hypostasis into the divine substance; but that one and the same hypostasis or personality of the Father, continued to be the subject, the inner personality, of the circumscription effected by finitude. If, then, the translation, “‘ hypostasis,” is inadmissible, we must necessarily take the word ovc/a in its usual sense; and then the entire passage may be rendered,—The Redeemer did not pre- exist in a circumscribed form of being of His own (in virtue of a distinction in the fatherly deity); but after the incarnation a peculiar circumscription was introduced into this substance ;— PATRIPASSIAN MONARCHIANISM., 41 naturally, as Beryll was not an Ebionite, in consequence of the Father’s own act. Ovoias wepuypadi is, as it were, one con- ception—circumscription of essence; the absence of the article cannot, therefore, turn the scale. It appears to me, therefore, that the following ideas are con- tained in the words of Eusebius:—I. Beryll believed that the Tatpixy Oeorns was in Jesus, but not an idia Bedtns (Note 12). What the latter denotes, will be clear from the foregoing obser- vations. II. Our Lord and Redeemer did not exist, prior to His incarnation (émvdnuia), in the form of a circumscription of sub- stance of His own (xat’ idlav ovcias Tmepvypadiy) ; that is, He did not pre-exist as an independent being: consequently, it could only be the divine itself, the fatherly deity, that was_in Christ. III. But when Eusebius says, that, according to Beryll, the Lord did not exist prior to the incarnation in the form of an indepen- dent aepuypady, he gives us therewith to understand, that, sub- sequently to the émdnuta, the case was different. From that event onwards, the Redeemer, who had previously been identified with the watpixn Oeorns, and destitute of an hypostasis, became, at all events, a circumscribed being, possessed of an indepen- dent existence—in the sense, indeed, that the fatherly deity acquired a different determination in Him. Now, if the incar- nation introduced limitation and circumscription into the watpexy Georns, Beryll should unquestionably be classed amongst those who import finitude into God Himself. Not, however, by any means as though the humanity were a limit imposed from without, by which the sratpixy Ocorns was reduced to a passive condition. After what has been advanced above, on the contrary, it must be plain that, as Beryll did not adopt the opinion of the Ebionites, he, and other men of his age, must have traced the limit up to the appropriative act of God itself, and have conceived the divine as determining itself to finitude, as positing itself human. It would seem, therefore, that, as in the view of Beron—of whom, be it remarked, we are very distinctly reminded by some of the expressions here employed—so also, in the view of Beryll, the acquirement of an id/a ovelas treprypady by the Redeemer, and the rise of the humanity, was one and the same act ; nay more, the Father’s position of finitude and limitation in Himself was one and the same act with His self-abnegation. But although the aatpix) Georns thus circumscribed itself, that is, posited 4? FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH itself as finite and human, it did not absolutely cease to exist as divine. On the contrary, as its inmost soul and motive power, the divine was naturalized, yea, was at home in the human cir- cumscription and nature ; for the union between the two was not merely momentary, but essential and most intimate,—the latter, in fact, owing its very rise to the Tar pee) Georns, so far as it had given tect the determination of (d/a ovoias mepiypadgi). If this were Beryll’s idea, we can easily understand that Origen should have had greater influence on it than, for ex- ample, Hippolytus, and in that teacher’s doctrine of the soul should have been able to bring about that crisis m Beryll’s views, which, after the hints given above, we may probably assume to have taken place. Hitherto, namely, Beryll had treated the question of the humanity of Christ rather lightly than otherwise; the teachers of the Church, as, for example, Hippolytus, held a too impersonal view of the humanity, treating it as the mere organ or otony) of the divine. Patripassianism was.at first marked by the same feature; in its first forms, it conceded no place to the human soul of Christ. But the more decided the advances made towards conceiving passibility, and even finitude in general (wepeypady), as a determination of God, and the greater were the importance and worth attached to the finitude and the humanity, although merely as an aspect of the divine itself. For this, a welcome connecting link was found in the Church’s doctrine of the cévwats. This plainly involved an approximation to Ebionism, whatever abhorrence Beryll might inwardly feel for that system. In this state of mind, Beryll must have welcomed the theory laid before him by Origen, in which the free human soul of Christ held so important a place; and as coming from the Church, it must have appeared to him a new thing, nay more, as a development of that which he himself aimed at, in laying greater stress on the humanity. On the other Fand: however, the more decided the prominence given to the human factor, the more Beryll’s theory assumed uninten- tionally a predominantly Ebionitic character; and on this ground also we can understand why he would willingly accept from Origen the idea of the pre-existent divine hypostasis of Christ, offering as it did that counterpoise which his own theory lacked. To this course he might be led by several considerations. Firstly, Origen did not overthrow the povapyia of God, but BERYLL OF BOSTRA. 43 protected it by a species of subordinatianism, growing out of Sabellian principles. GSecondly; Beryll’s own Monarchianism,— and Monarchianism was, without doubt, originally one of his points of departure,—had gradually assumed such a form, that he himself could not have avoided attributing to God a certain objective circumscription; that is, he must himself have admitted a distinction into his idea of God (Note 13). It could, there- fore, be no great step for him to acknowledge this distinction, properly modified, to have eternally existed in the divine nature, especially as God Himself, and not the temporal world, was represented as the ground thereof (compare c. Celsum, 8, 12). From the view just given, it will be clear, on the one hand, why in the Synodal Epistle reference was made to the human soul of Christ; for it undoubtedly played a part in the conferences with Beryll; and, on the other hand, why he was not charged with denying the human soul of Christ. By raising the hu- manity to the rank of a determination of God Himself, Beryll secured it such a degree of relative independence and signif- cance, that, with his general tendency of mind, he must already have been on the way towards the assumption of the existence of a human soul of Christ. This becomes still clearer when we compare the related system of Beron, who, on the cround of that divine xévwous which constituted humanity a determination of God’s own essence, and of the immanence and hegemony of the divine principle, was able to represent all its activity and its deification as proceeding from the humanity itself. From our exposition, it is also plain why doubts could be entertained whe- ther Beryll held the circumscription to have been the work of the human or of the divine aspect. For the human aspect un- questionably was essentially connected therewith; it formed a circumscription. It was, however, merely the means employed by God for constituting circumscription a determination of Himself, and not in any sense the original cause. To have sup posed the latter, would have been Ebionitic. And now at last we are in a position to mediate between Baur and Schleiermacher. Neander was right in his surmise, that Beryll held a kind of middle position between the Artemonites and the Patripassians.; though I consider it should be argued on different grounds. We must, in the first instance, direct attention to the consideration, that the assumption of finitude into the fatherly deity, forming 44 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. as it did one act with the cévwous of God, reduced the divine tc the position of an active potence of the humanity itself; the latter consequently gained considerably in importance, and deity pertained as truly to its substance as it pertained to the sub- stance of deity. It was therefore possible for it to develop itself out of itself. So far the system bears a certain resem- blance to Ebionism. On the other hand, however, this person and its development owed their existence entirely to the fatherly deity, which became man; and therefore, when the person attained completion, its actual deity was not a mere title, nor a mere moral unity with God, but the realization of its own inner essence. Accordingly, the starting-point and the conclusion of this theory bear rather an anti-Ebionitical than an Ebionitical character. It may be said to occupy a middle position between Ebionism and the early Patripassianism: neither treating the human as a mere selfless accident, on the one hand, nor viewing the divine in Christ after the type of the indwelling of the Spirit in the prophets, on the other hand; but aiming to combine both in inward, essential, and abiding unity. At the same time, it did not teach that this unity was the result of an influx of personific, divine power into the humanity. But though Beron and Beryll aided decidedly in advancing Patri- volved new difficulties; and these difficulties, in turn, further explain Beryll’s adoption of Origen’s views. or the question still remained, Did the entire Father, the entire atpsxi OedTns, abase itself when God became man, and subjected Himself to a human development; or merely one part or one aspect of its substance? In the former case, we should come upon the monstrous idea, that the Father had no longer an existence save in the man Jesus; and that in him, in virtue of the Kkévwots which had taken place, He existed at first as the mere potence of true humanity : consequently, during the continuance of the Redeemer’s development, the world in general had no actual God. In the second case, we should arrive at Ebionism, that is, in its new Hellenic form. As Beryll declined being classed with the Ebionites, he would naturally welcome the loophole offered by the Church, and thenceforth regard the divine in the Redeemer, not as mere portion or segment, but as an aspect or particular mode of existence, of the entire divine substance. BERYLL OF BOSTRA. 45 In the line of Monarchians, Beryll forms the connecting link between the okler ones,—the Patripassians, who allowed of absolutely no mpoowzrov side by side with the tarpuxiy BedTns,— and Sabellius, who not merely recognised in Christ a distinct TpocwTor, a distinct mepuypady), bee by advancing onwards to the Holy Spirit, was able to construe a species of trinity. His system was the bridge between the two, firstly, because it de- scribed the being au God in Christ asa mepiypady. in God Himself ; Gcanaly, because it assumed a peculiar relation of ‘God to this man; and, lastly, seeing that the relation referred to could only be grounded in the divine essence, because Beryll necessarily regarded it as a determination of God Himself, con- formably to which He had both the will and the power to posit Himself as aman. Whether Beryll understood this in a patri- passian sense, as a self-subjection of the divine nature to passi- bility; or in Beron’s sense, as a conversion (tpo77) of God into the man Jesus; or in a more Sabellian sense, as the non-passive activity of God in the circumscription of the zpécwmov of Christ (which unquestionably interweaves God with finitude, if He not merely acted upon, but really dwelt in, Christ; see above, page 38) ; he is certainly akin to both, in so far as he attributes to the mepuypady, or limitation and finitude, a relation tg God’s own substance, whilst at the same time denying to it, as indeed to distinction in general, any, save perhaps an ideal, reality in God, apart from the incarnation. All these theories, although it cannot be doubted that their authors were stirred by religious motives, necessarily strike at the very root of religion in general, and of Christianity in par- ticular. If the Father Himself is immediately the revealer—if there is no distinction in Him, no Son through whom, as through His image, He reveals Himself, first in istmanrdl ml for Ea self, and then also in the w meinen the object of revelation is ieee and its idea is destroyed. For if the Father, as the final Pend Himself comes forth in revelation ; and if, in order that the revelation may be complete, nothing can be left behind in the ground; then did the Father, that is, God, pass over into, and really become, the world; and there is consequently nothing left but the world. This is ins ethnical, pantheistic feature of Patripassianism and Sabellianism. The Tek result is, to do away altogether with revelation; for, on the supposition referred to, 46 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. that which was to be made manifest by revelation no longer exists. Noetus escaped this danger; for, in the absolute will of God, which at one time decrees the assumption of visibility and passibility, and at another time the return to invisibility and impassibility, he had that potence, which, in that it has power over itself, is unalterable, and can neither succumb to the world, nor tolerate God’s passing over into it. But, not having laid firm hold of the eternal ethical principle in God, which is the only basis of an abiding incarnation, the incarnation recognised by him is but a momentary thing, originating and grounded in a particular act of will. Consistency, therefore, required him to treat Christ’s person and appearance as transitory (although it is scarcely likely that he actually taught it); unless he were pre- pared to suppose that the Father did not again return into that unalterableness which his Monarchianism compelled him to re- gard as the true essence of God. STRUGGLE WITH THE NEW FORM OF EBIONISM. 474 SOUR, VA THE DOCTRINE OF THE SON, AND THE REVIVAL OF MONARCH- [ANISM IN THE FORM OF SABELLIANISM AND SUBORDINA- TIANISM. (HA Rete. THE CONFUTATION OF THE NEW FORM OF EBIONISM AND PATRIPASSIANISM BY THE CHURCH. I. Zhe Struggle with the New Form of £bionism. When the Theodotians and Artemonites tried to surround their innovation with the nimbus of antiquity, and to represent it as the doctrine of the Apostles and the doctrine of the Church down to the days of Victor, an old work, attributed, after the example of Photius, to the Roman presbyter Caius (Cod. 48), answered them drily, but yet correctly,—“ One might perhaps believe them, if the Holy Scriptures, above all else, did not stand in the way.’ But there exist also works of brethren, reach- ing up to a time earlier than Victor, written against heresies, and addressed to heathens; as, for example, those of Justin, Miltiades, Tatian, Clement, and many others; in all of which Christ is designated God (év ois dracv Oeodoyettar 0 Xpicros). For who is not acquainted with the writings of Irenzeus and Melito, and the rest, who proclaim Christ as God and as man? How many psalms and hymns, moreover, have been composed by believing brethren, from the beginning to the present time, which glorify the Logos of God, the Christ, by landing Him as 1 Older writers, like Eusebius (H. E. 5, 28), Nicephorus (4, 21), and Theodoret (Her. fab. 2, 5), were not acquainted with the name of the author of the work. It bore, however, the title of ‘‘The Little Laby- rinth.” 4& FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. God?” And how many more witnesses the author might have cited against them, we have already shown. In fact, the asser- tion of the Artemonites, that theirs was the primitive Christian doctrine, was so baseless, that the only witnesses to whom they could at all appeal, namely, the older and proper Ebionites, would have been held in horror by them; partly because of their Jewish tastes, which sorely clashed with their own classical culture (Euseb. H. E. 5, 28); and partly because these newer Kbionites coincided with the Church in recognising the super- natural birth of Christ. Complaints were made of their arbitrary treatment of the Scriptures, of the erasures and alterations they made in their copies of the Biblical text: they were charged with swerving from and throwing it into confusion ; with paying more attention to Aristotle and Euclid, to syllogistic forms and geometry, than to the investigation of the contents of the Sacred Scriptures. The Church felt that theirs was a foreign, a worldly spirit: “They speak like men who are of the earth, and know not Him who is from above.” Their minds were open to worldly science, but not to religion : their system, therefore, did not grow out of an interest in reli- gion, in Christianity, but their views and their copies of the Scripture were cut and shaped in agreement with principles foreign to Christianity. We are not informed that they em- ployed dogmatical arguments in defending and establishing their own views, and in combating the prevailing doctrine: for this reason, it was only just that they should neither attain wide diffusion, nor be greatly regarded by the Church. Much as Ter- tullian wrote about the Trinity and Christology, he passes over this heresy, although contemporary, in perfect silence: he does not appear to have been at all acquainted with it;* on the con- trary, he speaks as though in his day the divinity of the Person of Christ were already accepted as beyond all doubt.” Not till 1 The only mention made of it is in the catalogue of heresies at the close of the work, ‘‘ de prescr. Her.” (c. 53), which is of doubtful genuineness. ? De carne Christi 1: Examinemus corporalem substantiam Domini, de spiritali enim certum est. ‘‘ Spiritalis substantia ” is,equivalent, with Ter- tullian, to ‘‘divina substantia.” Compare Apol. 21; de orat. 1; adv. Mare. 1, 19; 3, 6. 16; 4, 21; adv. Prax. 26.—‘‘ Spiritus” with him by no means denotes merely the Holy Spirit: but he applies the term also to the divine nature. Compare Tertullian, ed. Semler, 1825, T. vi. 572 ; and John iv. 24: Rom. i. 4; 2 Cor. ili. 17. See Note QQ, page 391, Vol. I. THE STRUGGLE WITH PATRIPASSIANISM. 49 the second half of the third century did this tendency find a vigorous representative in Paul of Samosata. In his hands it excited far more attention; for the state of the Church, when he appeared, was far more favourable to the introduction of his theory, than at the time when the monarchian heresies were rife. At the present time (as we have shown in the introductory remarks to this third chapter), the mind of the Church was powerfully occupied with the question of the equalization of the Logos with the Father, and of the expulsion of subordinatian elements from the conception of the Son. The patripassian form of Monarchianism must, therefore, have worn a greater appearance of affinity to the doctrine of the Church; and it was really a consequence of the continuous and necessary struggle carried on with this heresy, in the persons of the men who from time to time attempted its revival, that the Church took so strong a turn in the opposite direction, that is, towards the assertion of the distinction between Christ and God, and that a door was thus opened not merely to preludes of Arianism, but even to Ebionitical teachings. For this reason, the struggle with Paul shall be narrated at a later period. II. The Struggle with Patripassianism. During the period of the development of the doctrine of the Church, which extended from the énd of the second to the mid- dle of the third century, the part played by Ebionism is scarcely worthy of notice; but the case was somewhat different with Do- cetism. ‘There was a closer affinity between it and Patripassian- ism, and that, not merely at the commencement in the hands of Marcion, but even later also, in those of Beryll: indeed, one may in a certain sense say, that Patripassianism was the continuation of Docetism, under a more orthodox garb. At the same time, we must be careful to remember, that the principle of Docetism had already been negatived by the mind of the Church; and Ter- tullian did but, as it were, collect together the manifold and rank forms of Docetism, in order to pronounce on them the final judg- ment of the Church. The reasons assigned by Tertullian for his condemnatory judgment may be taken as the expression of the general view, to which the Church had been led in the course ef the struggle. But the after effects of the Docetical error VOU. MI, D AQ) FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. were far from being rooted out by that condemnation. All that it really did, was to lighten the labour of the Church; for the future, all that was needed was to bring to light the Docetical root of an opinion, and the Church at once, unhesitatingly gave the required decision. The Docetical aspect of Gnosticism is discussed by ‘Tertul- lian, particularly in the work, “ de carne (or humanity) Christi.” Marcion, says he, denies both the birth and the flesh of Christ, in order that the one may not testify to the other; for the one stands or falls with the other. “Thou hast cut away portions of the Gospel, cries Tertullian, in which, according to a letter of thine, and the confession of thy followers, thou thyself didst formerly believe. Thou showest thus, that the faith rejected by thee is the older; and that thy present faith is of yesterday.” Marcion did not intend to deny the sufferings of Christ; but how absurd to leave the sufferings and death standing, and to deny the birth and the human pote ! Thou leavest fifa cruci- fixion untouched; but how could God suffer without human flesh? Or was His suffering a mere show? If so, He might as easily have consented to the show of birth and childhood, and there is therefore no need for thee to deny them.” (Com- pare above, Epoch Second, Section First.) Apelles attributed to Christ a solid body, but supposed it to be compounded of sidereal elements. What, then, are we to understand by His mother and His brethren in the Gospel, if, though He had a human body, He was never born? Christ must then be classed with the appearances of angels, who also, according to Tertul- lian, gave themselves solid bodies, though they were never born. But the cause of the appearance in the two cases is a different one. No angelever appeared with a view to being crucified, to dying, and to being raised to life again. Christ, however, having been sent to die, must needs also be born, in order that He might be able to die (de carne Christi 6). This is the “ mu- tuum debitum” between “nativitas” and “ mortalitas,” that whatever dies must be born, and whatever is born must die. Why do we everywhere discover in His body the signs of its earthly origin? Nowhere did men regard it with astonish- ment ; nothing of heavenly brilliance clana to it, that it should be despised and derided. ‘Tertullian saw the dmalieed element which lay in this tendency; and acutely shows, not only that EEE, THE STRUGGLE WITH PATRIPASSIANISM. o1 Apelles must needs abide by a “caro peccatrix,” if the prince of matter (preses igneus) is the prince of the world, and if the world be a “delictum ;” for the world is one: but also, that he cannot represent our earthly world as made partaker of re- demption, if he hold that the exaltation of Christ involved the annihilation and dissolution of the humanity He had assumed. According to another theory, the soul of Christ gave rise to His body ; the soul became flesh; His flesh, therefore, was not like that of other men, for, as it was derived from the “anima,” it was soulical flesh (caro animalis). These latter teach that He did not need to assume our flesh, inasmuch as He only came to redeem oursoul. ‘“ Why, then, did His soul become that which He had no need to redeem, to wit, flesh; nay more, flesh of a different kind from ours, and which therefore cannot serve us? Nay more, if His soul were made flesh (carnea facta), it was not such a soul as ours; but was converted into a fleshly soul, such as neither required redemption, nor could aid in the work of redemption. They say, His soul became a body, in order that we might see it born, die, and rise again; and in order that the soul might look upon and recognise itself (that is, probably, its own history, or the momenta of the inner process through which it itself passes) in Christ, as the symbol of this inner history." But the body of Christ concealed His soul ; how, then, can the soul have been manifested in it? For that purpose, they must surely devise another body, capable of making the invisible visible.” This argument plainly cannot hold its ground. The following, however, may :—“ They have reduced the soul itself to flesh; what, then, remains to be revealed? Further- more, the main point is not, that the soul should know itself through Christ (as though it were already perfect in itself, and only lacked the consciousness of its perfection), but that it should know Christ in itself. ‘The soul is not in danger because it has not perfect self-knowledge, but because it has not the knowledge of Christ.” At the same time, therefore, he protests against a theory of redemption which requires merely a process of knowledge, and not a real and religious transformation through Christ ; which confounds religion with a theoretical process ; and which, consequently, has no need of the humanity of Christ, 1C. 11: Not the “ effigies anime” was given by or in Christ, says Ter- tullian, but its ‘‘salus.” ae FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. save as its history is the symbol of a spiritual truth. This pas- sage is in other respects remarkable, as showing that Tertullian ateienied to Christ a true human soul. (C. 10: “Ut animam salvam faceret in se ipso, suscepit animam Christus, quia salva non esset, nisi per ipsum, dum in ipso.”) Others endeavour to show that one of the pure, heavenly natures, which Christ (that is, the eternal Christ) is supposed to have assumed, might supply an organ qualifying Him for historical activity;—an organ which matter and weak human nature appeared to refuse. They say accordingly, —“ Angelum gestavit ut satellitem fortem, cum quo salutem hominis operaretur.’ In support of which, they ap- pealed to passages where Christ is designated an angel. _Ter- tullian, however, simply replied,—An an als is often a messenger : an ambassador. At the same time, Terai does not say that an angel or a messenger redeemed them, but the Lord Himself. It would, therefore, involve a shortening of the work of re- demption, to represent an angel as the Redeemer. It is true, they say,—Christ, in the angel. But that is superfluous, or too much. If He redeemed through the angel, what part did the angel take; and vice versd? But it is also too little. For the angels did not need to be redeemed: to men, not to them, was re- demption promised; and men would then come short. How could He further be made lower than the angels, if He were an angel and nota man? The Valentinians, lastly, invent a kind of spiritual body. They suppose that Christ stood amongst the angels invested with an earthly body, and was not born of the Spirit, nor of God, but of the will of the man.’ Consequently His body was of God, of the Spirit. “ Were it of the earth,” say they, “how could He be unperishable? Why was His body not dissolved into earth, if it was like ours? Orif we Christians are so entirely like Him, even in relation to the body, why do not we, like Him, rise again, and ascend into heaven, without undergoing corruption? If we attribute flesh at all to Christ, we must attribute to Him sinful flesh, and must suppose that He then annihilated it, and laid it aside.’ ‘To this Tertullian replies,—We say that neither did He lay aside His flesh, nor was His flesh sinful in essence. Unquestionably He assumed our flesh, in which dwell sin and guilt, and that not merely in ap- 1 Undoubtedly with reference to the ancient reading ¢s éyevy7dn, instead of of yevvndnoav, John i. 10. THE STRUGGLE WITH PATRIPASSIANISM. o3 pearance ; but had Christ therefore “ caro peccatrix?” No; He made our flesh His own by the act of assumption; and by making it His own, He made it sinless.” In proof that to the reality of the flesh, generation from the seed of a man was not necessary, he reminds them of Adam. As, in his case, earth was converted into flesh, even so was the Word of God able to pass over into the material of the same flesh, without the inter- vention of the seed of aman. “ Vacabat viri semen apud ha- bentem Dei semen.” Converting his defence into an attack, he goes on to say,— They believe that He died (c. 15), and yet they represent that which died as having been born of the unperishable. ‘They desire a man united with God (hominem Deo mixtum), and yet they deny the man: for a man who has not our body, a body taken from human nature, is a mere ap- pearance. ‘Caro ex hominis carne erat sumenda;” therefore He cannot have given Himself a body out of Himself. This the Valentinians themselves also, strictly speaking, grant; for they confess that He was born of the Virgin. And what can this mean, if He did not receive from the Virgin the body which He bore when He came forth out of her womb? It would then be much simpler to say,—He received a body of a spiritual kind, apart from Mary. “Sine causa eo se intulit, unde nihil extulit. Sed non sine cause descendit in vulvam, ergo ex illa accepit.” Though this line of argumentation goes back merely to the fact of Christ’s birth, which was recognised even by his opponents, Tertullian did not fail at the same time to recognise the idea which was connected therewith. Without doubt, says he, the seed of a man was not neces- sary to the Person of Christ: had He been entirely, and in every respect, like us—entirely and solely the Son of man—He would not have been the Son of God. But He lacked nothing that was necessary to constitute Him entirely one of us. ‘To ‘this the seed of a man was not necessary, as Adam proves. On the other hand, however, a mere creation (as in Adam’s case), or self-generation, or self-conception, was not enough; but He must needs stand in blood-relationship to the already existent race. To Mary must belong, not indeed that which she con- ceived, but what she bore; she must communicate to it her own blood. It was necessary that Christ should be the fruit, and not merely the guest, of her womb. Whoso denies that He was 54 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. a blossom and fruit of the royal stem of David, denies not merely the root to the branch, and to the blossom, and to the fruit; but also the fruit to its root; in order that the root may not be able to claim the glory of Him who was destined to be its blossom and fruit. In this case, it is necessary to go back through all the members (of the human race) to the beginning. All participate in this blossom and fruit, and its nature is no other than Adam’s; for, indeed, He is the second Adam. Ac- cordingly, we must either say, that men have the same spirit-like flesh as the second Adam, or else that the body of Christ, not having sprung from a spiritual stem, was not a spiritual body. Tertullian was not satisfied without declaring, in the strongest terms, his conviction of the reality of the connection between Christ and ourrace. “ Adhesit utero, avulsus est; ex utero est per illum nervum umbilicarem adnexus origini vulve.” He asserts a concarnatio, a convisceratio of Christ with our race. Ex humana matrice did He derive the substantia for His caro (c. 17). That is the new birth which He was appointed to bring : a man was born in God (in Deo); and in this man, God also was born; for He assumed the flesh of the old stem with- out the old seed, in order that, in the power of the new seed, that is, of the Spirit, He might recreate the old flesh, after hay- ing atoned it, by the exclusion of the old impurity. At the same time, that entire new birth (novitas) was formed out of the old material, as is the case with all, in such a manner, namely, that, by a wise arrangement, the Lord was born of a virgin. “In virginem adhue Evam irrepserat verbum edificatorium mortis. In virginem eque introducendum erat Dei verbum extructorium vitee.” Nor must we overlook the circumstance, that, when distin- guishing between conception and birth, Tertullian designates the former alone, not the latter, virginal. “ Virgo Marie et non virgo; peperit enim que ex sua carne; non peperit, que non ex virisemine. Virgo, quantum a viro, non virgo quan- tumapartu. Si virgo concepit (if she conceived as a virgin) in partu suo nupsit, ipsa patefacti corporis lege.” Hence the Apostle says, “ Nonex virgine sed ex muliere editum filium Dei” (Gal. iv.). THE STRUGGLE WITH PATRIPASSIANISM. 55 His opponents, however, appealed especially to two consider- ations, and these Tertullian then proceeds to examine more carefully (c. 3,4). These considerations were,—1. It is impos- sible for God to be born and become flesh; 2. It would be unworthy of Him. Marcion, in particular, raised both these objections; but they really lay at the basis of all Docetical and dualistic Christologies. Had He been born, and had He truly assumed a man, He would have ceased, thinks Marcion, to be God, losing what He was in that He became what He previ- ously was not. “ Converti enim in aliud finis est pristini.” Tertullian answers,—The fixed, immoveable being of God runs no 1 risk. It is true everything which stands far from God, and God from it, is subject to the law, that if its nature undergo an alteration, it can no longer remain the same as it was before. But God differs from man-precisely in this respect, that of Him the contrary holds good; that is, He is able to convert Himself into whatever He wills, and yet to remain what He is. In order to understand his meaning, we must take into consider- ation his doctrine of the Trinity, and particularly the mode in which he defines the distinction between the Son and the Father; and to this point we shall immediately direct attention. Ter- tullian demands, and that on religious grounds, that in recog- nising the unchangeableness of God, we shall not deny the possibility of His undergoing any process whatever, but merely such a process as purely finite creatures undergo, change in whose nature involves the loss of that which they had previously been. This latter thought is unquestionably, to some extent, akin to certain features of Patripassianism, though expressed in a tri- nitarian form. All depends on the will of God: was it His will to be born? For, if He willed it, nothing could prevent it, not even His nature. And that He willed it, is clear; for otherwise He would not have chosen to appear asa man. Who thinks of denying, when he sees a man, that he has been born? If the thing itself, the being man, has been displeasing to God, He would not have been disposed to assume the semblance of a man. If any one object,—He was satisfied with His self-consciousness; I answer,—It was better even for His own self-consciousness, that He should really be what He willed to seem to be. He enters into a still more detailed examination of the second objection (c. 4). The Valentinians ask,—“ Ergo Dei filius in 56 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. tantum humilitatis exhaustus?” Avpelles assures, “carnem habere ignominiam ;” Marcion (compare “ de carne Christi” 4; “ ad- versus Marc.” 3, 10), “aspernatus est Christus carnem illam, ut terrenam et stercoribus infersam.” Marcion. he meets with the apt reply,—He is ever preaching up the “ lenitas dei,” and the “ benignitas dei,” and will not hear of the stern-God, who is distant from the world. And yet, when this God really descends to the world, he complains that it is unworthy-of-God, that it is a “pusillitas.” But what you blame as unworthy of God, the Son of God has in Himself, in that He unites God and man; for He has God in Himself, in His power, and man in His weak- nesses (pusillitatibus). The entire disgrace of my God, as you term it, is the sanctuary of that grace which is the salvation of men. “ Deus pusillus inventus est, ut homo maximus fieret. Ex eequo agebat Deus cum homine ut homo ex zquo agere cum Deo posset.” If God despised man, why did He not also despise the appearance of a man? why did He assume the image (si- mulacrum) thereof? “ Nullius rei dedignande imago dignanda est.” If He played the part of a man, why did He not play it throughout, but omit, for example, its beginning, birth? Be- cause a true birth was unworthy of God! In that case, declaim against those holy, awe-inspiring works of nature; draw thy sword against everything that thou art; cast down the origin of the body and of the soul; call the womb of thy mother a cloaca; and become the foe and persecutor of the workshop, wherein that great being, man, is brought forth (adv. Marc. 3, 10; de carne Chr. 4)! How canst thou still continue to love any one ? Thou doest not love thyself; for thou hatest man, who is subject to birth. And yet see to it, whether thou art displeasing to thyself, or whether thou wast originated in any other way. Christ, at all events, loves the man, who is in impurity, and is doubled up in his mother’s womb, who is born in a manner which the modesty of woman counts holy, with whom his mother plays at her breast. For the sake of this man, He descended from on high; He humbled Himself even unto death, the death of the cross. So much did He, without doubt, love him, whom He has dearly bought. But if He loved him, surely He must also love his birth and his flesh. For nothing can be really loved, unless we love that through which it is what it is. Or take away birth, and still show me aman. Take away flesh, and THE STRUGGLE WITH PATRIPASSIANISM. 57 show me him whom God redeems. If this constitutes the man whom God bought, because He loved him, thou convertest that which God did into something of which He should be ashamed. But if Christ be the Creator of nature, He acts rightly in loving His possession. By the transformation of birth, by a heavenly new-birth, He restored the flesh from all its sufferings; He illuminated the blind, renewed the palsied, awakened the dead to life,—and yet He ought to be ashamed of having been born into the flesh! (“de carne Christi” 4). In the last instance, however, it is invariably the atonement which leads Tertullian to attach so much importance to. the reality of the humanity of Christ. A Docetical Christ would have been a vain pretence, a lie: he therefore exhorts his opponents to believe (“de carne Christi” 5) that God would rather become man than lie, appearing to be what He was not, not willing to be what He is. Jf His human person- ality were a mere appearance, so also were His human acts and works; and, therefore, the sufferings of Christ deserve no faith. The murderers of Christ are thus excused ; for in reality He suffered nothing at their hands, and the entire work of Christ is overthrown. “'Totum christiani nominis et pondus et fructus, mors Christi negatur, quam tam impresse apostolus de- mandat, utique veram, summum eam fundamentum Evangelii constituens (adv. Marc. 8, 8). Nonne vere crucifixus est Deus? vere mortuus et crucifixus?” ‘Did a mere phantom suffer, “ quod vacabat a sensu passionum Dei?” Then is our faith a lie, and our hope a phantom. Oh, spare the only hope of the entire world! Why dost thou destroy the necessary reproach of the faith? Whatever is unworthy of God, is for my benefit : willing am I to be shameless and blessed as a fool, and I require the material thereto. God’s Son was crucified; I am not ashamed (to avow it), for it is worthy of shame: and the Son of God died ; it deserves all faith, because it is foolish. He was laid in the grave, and rose again: it is quite certain, because it was impossible (“de carne Christi” 5).’ 1 Those whose nerves are too weak to bear the utterances of such a xanpoQopia of faith, will find a tonic in the preceding chapter, where he speaks of the divine folly, which confounds and puts to shame the wisdom of the world, and where the ethical nature of God, love, is made the stand- ard of the truly reasonable. 58 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. So rich had been the development of Tertullian’s intellect, relatively to the truth of the humanity of Christ. No preceding writer can compare with him in this respect ; no one plunges into the act of incarnation with such love and admiration, and at the same time with such penetration; no one took the same pleasure, as much speculative as religious, in conjoining the most glaring contradictions, the furthest extremes, in Christ, in order that he might behold in His complete concarnation and convisceration (concarnatio et convisceratio) with our race, on the one hand, the magnitude of the divine love, and, on the other hand, the exaltation of mankind. To the reality of the incarnation he considered it to belong, as did also Origen (Hom. in Lucam 14), that Mary, after the birth of Jesus, should no longer be a virgin, but a mother (Gal. iv.). But also as regards the divine aspect, he did not remain in- active. In narrating the course taken by the doctrine of the Logos, we have found, as might have been anticipated from the circumstance of the point of departure being the Person of the historical Christ, that in the doctrine of the pre-existence of the Son, which had been clearly laid down almost at the commence- ment of the process, there was strictly included the momentum, that the Son possessed a personality of His own, independent of the Father; gradually, however, the efforts made to exclude sub- ordinatian elements from the conception of the Son, and to ex- hibit Him as a participator in deity, led to His personality being no longer so strictly distinguished from that of the Father, as it was in the incarnation. Clemens Alexandrinus, in particular, furnished us an example of this ; but it appeared still more dis- tinctly in his predecessors. The definition of the Son, as a mere attribute, was a constant temptation to dissipate His hypostasis. For if the Son is the Wisdom of the Father (Ratio, Xédyos, copia), or His power (virtus, verbum), either the Father by Himself is without wisdom and power, or the Father and Son are identical, even as a man is identical with His reason and His will. That the Fathers desired to estabiish a deeper distinction between the Father and the Son, than that between a subject and its attri- butes, could not indeed be denied; for they gave these attributes again the form of a subject in the Son; and they supposed themselves to have hit upon that deeper distinction, which Christology required, when they had declared that a divine sub- _ THE STRUGGLE WITH PATRIPASSIANISM. 59 ject, and not a mere divine power, dwelt in Christ. But still they fell very far short of supplying that which was necessary actually to establish and secure the personality of the Son. Tertullian entered on this inheritance; and his opposition to the gnostic doctrine of the AZons, which wore to him a mytho- logical and pantheistic appearance, must have strengthened his antipathy to the introduction of distinct and separate forms into the inner sphere of the divine nature, and his tendency to give the unity the predominance over the distinctions. “ Valentine,” says he (adv. Prax. 8), “rends his eons, his probolas loose from the Father, and sets them at such a distance from Him, that they no longer know Him. But our Son knows the Father, and is in the bosom of Him, whom He reveals. For who knows what is in God, save the Spirit who isin Him? Ever was the Word with the Father and in God.” This, however, is but one aspect of the matter. If we are minded thoroughly to under- stand Tertullian’s peculiar doctrine of the Trinity, we must remember that his strong realism would naturally lead him to insist much more vehemently on the reality of the incarnation of the Son, than did Clement. As he gazed on the incarnate Logos, he felt certainly convinced of His personality. For it was not a meré impersonal power, but a divine subject, that had become man in Christ (Note 14). When, therefore, Patripas- sianism arose, which he justly deemed tainted with Docetism (adv. Prax. 11, 23), and brought to light the consequences of neglecting the distinction between the Father and Son, his real- istic principles naturally impelled him to assert more strongly, that the divine which had appeared in Christ was a distinct subject; whilst at the same time he avoided infringing on the ~essential equality of Father and Son, which he recognised along with his predecessors, and in which he saw the true element of Patripassianism. These, then, are the factors out of which we must endeavour to construct and understand Tertullian’s re- markable doctrine of God. The following is the mode in which he endeavoured to recon- cile the equality of the Father and Son, with the Son’s possession of a distinct personality. To two Gods he objects as strongly as the Monarchians (adv. Prax. 13); he desires but one God. Consequently, a double or triple hypostasis seems an impossibi- lity; in which case, the personality of the Father must be con- 00 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. cluded to be that of the Son also, and the distinction between the two to be a mere name. This he would be ready to con- cede, but for that “dispensatio, quam Ciconomiam yocamus.” But if the distinctions relate solely to God’s revelations, to His manifestations of Himself, we arrive merely at. different works of God, and not at distinctions in the divine being. The Trinity is thus reduced to a mere name or appearance, and denotes, strictly speaking, simply one and the same God engaged in different works; which works themselves, considered in relation to God and not merely in relation to man, must be pronounced to be momenta of one and the same work. Against such a view Tertullian protests (adv. Prax. 13). How, then, can he secure objective and real distinctions in God Himself? By regarding the deeds of God as modes of the divine being, by bringing the divine essence into greater nearness to. the world, by attri- buting finitude and growth to God Himself in one aspect of His being, and by representing to himself the fellowship of man with God as more intimate than it was commonly held to be. Human souls he deemed to be of divine substance ; humanity he held to have been from the beginning an object of the love of God, and destined to be exalted and transferred into the divine nature, through Christ. Again, he believed that it was involved in the eternal idea of humanity from the very begin- ning, that its history, and the history of the Son of God, should be interwoven with each other; and that, consequently, the Son of God was eternally related to and incorporated with humanity. When God created Adam out of the earth, He looked on the image of the future Incarnate One; and, creating Adam in His likeness, God created him in His own likeness, (De resurr. carn. 6 :—Quodcunque limus exprimebatur Christus cogita- batur homo futurus. Id utique, quod finxit, ad imaginem Dei finxit illum, scilicet Christi. Ita limus ille jam tune imaginem induens Christi futuri in carne, non tantum Dei opus erat, sed et pignus.) But let us enter into details. “ Seeing that the Patripassians,” says he (adv. Prax. 5), “regard the two as one, so that one and the same stands both for Father and Son, we must investigate the entire question concerning the Son, whether He is, who He is, and how He is. According to some, His genesis is referred to in the Hebrew text (Gen. i. 1), ‘In the beginning, God made ee 0 ‘ THE STRUGGLE WITH PATRIPASSIANISM. 61 for Himself a Son.’ Supposing, however, that this be not cer- tain, I am influenced by other considerations, derived from the inner nature (dispositione) of God, which He had before the creation of the world till the generation of the Son. For God was before all things; He was solitary; He was world, place, and everything to Himself. Solitary, because nothing besides Himself had outward reality; and yet, again, not solitary even then, for with Him was His Reason which He had in Himself. For God is a rational being: Reason existed in Him earlier (than the world); and so everything is from Him. This Reason is His intelligence (sensus), designated Logos amongst the Greeks, —a term which is usually not quite appropriately translated ‘Word’ (sermo). Jor, strictly speaking, we cannot say that the Word was in the beginning with God; for Reason in God is older than Word, inasmuch as Word subsists through Reason, Reason is its substance, and it is the revelation of Reason.” In these words, Tertullian would appear entirely to deny the existence of a distinction between Father and Son, in the inmost sphere of the divine being; for Reason, which he unquestionably conceived to be something substantial (corpus in his language, although spiritus), is the Father Himself : Word, on the contrary, which, as spoken being, contains, at all events, the first beginning of a distinction, he refuses to admit into the inmost divine sphere, treating it as the secondary, which the primary precedes, as the beginning (of that which is distinct from God in Himself), not as that which is prior to all beginnings. And plainly, those who translated Logos by “ Word,” and represented the Word as existing in the beginning, and not as first constituting the beginning by its own rise, were far more decidedly than Tertul- lian on the way to introduce the Word itself into the inner nature of God, and to give it a place alongside of the Father, however imperfect might be the result. And, as though with the feeling that he was just on the point of quitting the path trodden by the Church, he proceeds to say, as it were retracing his steps,—“ Yet that lack of precision (namely, to represent the Word as equally eternal with Reason, or to identify the two) is of little consequence; for, even if God had not yet sent forth the Word from Himself (miserat), He had it within Himself, with and in His reason, quietly meditating and ordering what He designed shortly to express in word. Consider thyself a 62 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. copy of God, a rational being, animated by divine substance. Dost thou not see that, when thou quietly, through thy reason, communest with thyself, the same thing takes place in thee? Thy reason takes up a position over against thee, by means of words, at every movement of thought, at every pulsation of thine intelligence. Whatever thou thinkest or perceivest, be- comes a word in thee, and in the word is thy reason itself. In thy soul thou must speak, thou canst not avoid it; and when thou speakest, the word in thee becomes another than thyself, as it were one who speaks with thee ; in the which, notwithstand- ing, there dwells the same reason, which enables thee to speak when thou speakest. ‘Thus there is, as it were, another than thyself, a second, the word in thee, through which thou speakest when thinking, and through which thou thinkest when speaking. After the same manner also, God, in virtue of His reason, quietly thinking and ordering, made the reason, word, which, in speaking, He set in motion. If thou art a copy of God, how much more perfect must this take place in the Arche- type! for He, even when He keeps silence, has Reason in Him- self, and in Reason the Word. So far, therefore, it is true, that, even before the creation of the universe, God was not alone, seeing that He had in Himself Reason, and in Reason the Word, which, by an inner act, He constituted a Second, another self.” Tertullian endeavours thus to give fixity to that eternal distinc- tion in God, which, so long as the Logos was deemed equiva- lent to Reason, continued a completely precarious and uncertain thing, by inweaving the word, to wit, the objectification of reason, with reason itself. This interesting passage sets further before us an effort to show how there may be a duality in God, from the necessity, immanent in all active, spiritual beings, to effect a self-diremption into word and thinking reason. Spirit, in order to be actually rational spirit, must not merely think, but must also have an object which is thought,—the object for the subject. That which is thought, again, must, on the one hand, be itself rational, or else it is not a thought of reason; on the other hand, as something thought, it must be different from the thinking reason. Only in that it is fixed as other than the reason, can it be termed thought, and can reason be said to have accomplished its thinking activity; but this other thing is fixed in and by means of a word,—be the word even THE STRUGGLE WITH PATRIPASSIANISM. 63 inner and quiet. It is clear, therefore, that Tertullian was al- ready on the traces of those who, at a later period, tried to show that the Trinity is the eternal process of the divine self-con- sciousness, confronting itself with itself. But from what has been advanced, it is equally clear, that Tertullian did not keep God’s thought of the world and His thought of Himself apart ; or, rather, he still puts the self-consciousness of God quite into the background. If the thought of God, which He sets over against Himself, and in which He sets Himself over against Himself, is not God Himself, but the world, then either no dis- tinction is effected in God’s being itself,—namely, when the world is clearly distinguished from God, and the pretended foundation laid for the Trinity turns out to be a mere distinc- tion between the God who thinks the world and the world thought by God; or—and to this alternative Tertullian neces- sarily inclined—that which is thought is God Himself, in alte- reity ; though, at the same time, owing to the circumstance of its being also immediately the world, or the principle of the world, there is the danger of confounding the mundane with the trini- tarian process ;—in which case, it is evident that an immanent Trinity can never be arrived at. Further, it cannot be regarded as an accident that Tertullian, in this entire section, never speaks of Father and Son, but solely of God, who is eternally “rationalis” and “tacite cogitando” Himself in Himself, con- stitutes Himself “ sermonalis.” Herein is decidedly involved, what he also expressly confesses, namely, that there is no place for a real, hypostatic Sonship in the inner, eternal essence.of God: all that he has tried to point out, is the existence in God of an eternally active potence of Sonship. God is the Thinking One; the Word in God is His thought absolutely, in fixed objec- tive form, though still confined to the inward sphere. As the thought of God, He is the sum of the thoughts of the world, or the idea of the world; and had Tertullian rested here, he would have had no alternative but to follow the example of heathen philosophers, and call the world the Son of God, so far as it is the external realization of the idea of the world: plainly, how- ever, an hypostasis of the Son would then be out of the ques- tion. For, on the one hand, the eternal idea of the world was not conceived in hypostatical separation from, but in unity with, God; and, on the other hand, the realization of this idea is so 64 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. characterized by discerption, that it no longer represents a real unity, to which the predicate personal could be applied. Here, however, we must take into consideration, that when Tertullian taught that the inner Word was the thought of God absolutely, under the impulse of His Christian consciousness, he treated, though not clearly and definitely, God Himself, and not merely the world, as the content of the divine thought. Not that he represented God as placing Himself, so to speak, over against Himself, even apart from the world and the idea of the world; for that would have involved an actual inner, and not merely a potential, Sonship: but he viewed God, considered as the object of His own thought, solely in and with the idea of the world. We are now in a position to understand the further course of his entire theory. In the first place, the heathen opinion, that the world is immediately the Son of God, is set aside; for, on the contrary, God, as the object of His own thought, is car’ é€oy7v the Son of God, so soon as He attains positive reality in the actual world. In the first instance, He has a mere ideal existence in the inner essence of God, like the world-idea itself ; but in this world-idea is involved that when it arrives at actuality, it will still have, in that actuality, the God who was incorporated with its idea, to wit, the Word, and in the manifestation of the Word, the arche- type become a reality, God amongst men, the Head of humanity, with a view to whose future realization God created Adam. And because the manifestation of God Himself is thus inter- woven with the idea of the world, and all the divine thoughts necessarily become realities, not only is the world a progressive actualization of the thought to which God gives objective exist- ence over against Himself; but this same historical process. through which the world passes, involves in itself, and requires. for its own completeness, that the Word (the thought) of God, so far as God Himself is its subject-matter, should have its his- tory and actuality in the world; and that, abandoning its hidden, tranquil, ideal existence, it should progressively manifest itself, until, standing in the midst of humanity as the Son of God, it give full objective reality over against God, to all that the divine thought embraced within itself, that is, therefore, to God Himself who is its subject-matter. Thus, in the actuality of the God-man, of the Son, an adjustment (Ausgleichung, a squaring TERTULLIAN. 65 up) takes place between God as thinking, on the one side, who now for the first time can in the full sense be termed Father, and, on the other side, the thought of God, whose inmost sub- stance is God Himself ;—primarily, it is true, in the form of a conception, a potence; but in due time as actual Son and God-man, possessed, like the Father, of objective existence and personality.’ The only difficulty yet remaining, is to account for Tertul- lian’s not representing the Word as haying first attained realiza- tion in the man Jesus, who formed the top-stone of that history, whose mission it was to subject the entire Word to Himself ; and why, on the contrary, he taught that the procession of the Word from God, or, as he terms it, the generation of the Son, took place prior to the creation of the world. The key to the mat- ter is contained in the account given above. God, objectively realized amongst men in Christ, is the climax of the idea of the world, is that goal, that final aim which gives unity to the world, and completion to the Word, that is, to the self-objectification of God. Now the absolute aim, even prior to its full realization at the end, must be more than a mere conception, it must be a real mundane potence. Hence Tertullian represents God as first_of all giving utterance to this potence, when the time came for the world assuming areal shape; and thus the pre-mun- dane Son of God entered on an actual, though still imperfect existence, and the one God became Father and Son. But that world-potence, although endowed with power, spirit, and wisdom (sermo fultus, structus virtute, spiritu, sapientia), was not as such sufficient to itself: it manifests, indeed, a certain reality, energy, for the Son creates the world; but He creates it with an eye to its idea, or to its future form as the God-man; and therefore this first appearance of the Son in the form of a person was not a renunciation of the goal, that is, of the incarnation, but the means and preparation thereto. And during the entire period from the creation onwards, Tertullian represents the Son as governed by the thought, that something was still lacking to ‘His full idea, until the incarnation had taken place ; and that it behoved Him to prepare the way for thisincarnation. He pre- pared, He trained Himself, for the incarnation. For this reason, He appeared so frequently to the patriarchs, to Moses and others: 1 See Note and Appendix II. for the German of this passage.---Tr. MODAII: B 66 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. as it were testing Himself, in sympathy with the sufferings and tears of men, and in loving intercourse with them (adv. Mare. 2,27; adv. Prax. 14,16). The Son of God, says he, revealed Himself from the beginning. “Ipse enim et ad humana semper colloquia descendit, ab Adam usque ad Patriarchas et Prophetas —ordinem suum preestruens ab initio semper, quem erat persecu- turus in finem. Ita semper ediscebat, et Deus in terris cum hominibus conversari non alius potuit (such seems to be the right reading) quam sermo qui erat caro futurus.” These His revelations from the beginning stand, therefore, in the closest relation to His incarnation; in the former, the Son of God had already an eye to the latter.. He then proceeds to say,—“ Edis- cebat (scil. que erat persecuturus), ut nobis fidem sterneret ut facilius crederemus, filium Dei descendisse in seculum, si et retro tale quid gestum cognosceremus. Sic etiam adfectus humanos sciebat jam tunc, suscepturus etiam ipsas substantias hominis, carnem et animam ; interrogans Adam quasi nesciens : ubi es Adam? pcenitens, quod hominem fecisset, quasi non preesciens, etc., cf. c. 30.” ‘The heretics who blame such things as unworthy of God, and misuse them for the degradation of the Creator, do not know that they pertained to the Son, who was destined one day to take upon Himself hunger, thirst, tears, birth, yea, even death itself. (Compare the “de carne Christi” 6.) But the Son reveals Himself more fully first in the flesh (adv. Prax. 14). “ With wisdom or reason,” says he (adv. Prax. 6), “ God first impregnated His works, to wit, ideally, in the depths of His Spirit” (“in sensu,” equivalent to Augustine’s “ memoria”) ; “afterwards, however, thou shalt know it, as it stands in its dis- tinctness alongside of Him, for it says, ‘When He created the heavens, I was by Him.’ Now, when God willed to bring into visible existence that which He had ordered within Himself, as it were in inward dialogue with reason, with wisdom, according to its various forms and substances, He first put forth the Word itself (ipsum primum protulit sermonem), which was the vehicle of reason and wisdom, in order that the universe might be created by the same by which it had been conceived, nay more, by which, regarded ideally in God (quantum in Det sensu), it had already been made. For one thing still failed the universe of things, to wit, an appearance coram in suis TERTULLIAN. 67 speciebus atque substantiis.” C.7: “Tune igitur etiam ipse Sermo speciem et ornatum suum sumit, sonum et vocem, cum dicit Deus; Fiat lux! Heec est nativitas perfecta Sermonis, dum ex Deo procedit, conditus ab eo primum ad cogitatum, in nomine Sophize dehine generatus ad effectum. Ex inde eum parem sibi efficiens, de quo procedendo filius factus est primo- genitus, ut ante omnia genitus, Unigenitus, ut solus ex Deo genitus, proprie de vulva cordis ipsius. Sermo in Sophiz et in rationis et in omnis divini animi et spiritus nomine filius factus est Dei, de quo prodeundo generatus est.” We must have the Sermo as substantivum, “in re, per substantize proprietatem ut res et persona queedam videro possit, et ita capiat, secundus a Deo constitutus duos efficere, Patrem et Filium, Deum et Sermonem.” Now this Word, which was found in the form of God, did not deem it robbery to be equal with God. It appeared at the end of the times, in order to reveal, or to accomplish fully, what was in the Father’s mind. The Father works ideally (sensu agit) ; the Son’s office was to give external, real existence to all that the Father inwardly thought (in sensu sentit, c. 14). In Him is set before us the principle of objectivity (c. 15, fin.). But of this the Son_is capable, not merely because in the Word also dwelt reason, wisdom, and power,—“ totus animus Dei,”—but also, and principally, because He has in Himself the momentum of finitude, is in one aspect connected with the world. For this reason, He was able to work in the world, to constitute it a reality, and finally, to appear as the First-born within its limits. The Father is only the Infinite One: division, limit, finitude, lie outside of Him; His relation thereto is solely that of the thinker. And even when finitude is the object of His thought, as it unquestionably is, in the idea of the world, He thinks it as a finitude united again with Himself (in Christ and the Holy Spirit eternally). For in the entire divine world- idea cogitated by the Father, is contained also the union of the world with, its eternal return into, God. But the Son super- intends the course of the world through time; He leads it, ho- vering over it, as the archetype and principle wherein it subsists, until He enter into it in complete actuality. From this it naturally follows, that Tertullian must have re- garded the Son as eternally destined to become incarnate, and as capable of appearing in the flesh. The Father is not only 68 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. not seen, but He cannot make Himself visible; He is “ inac- cessibilis,” He alone has immortality, unchangeableness : no man can see God and live. The nature of the Son was, from the beginning, otherwise constituted ; it was capable of appearing. He would not have become visible at the end of the days, had He not been visible from the beginning. To Him we must ascribe “mortalitas,” “ accessibilitas ;” and this is, in Tertullian’s view, so important a distinction, that he deduces from it the existence of a duality in God, of a “ Deus invisibilis et invisus,” and a “ Deus visibilis et visus” (adv. Prax. 14,15). “It is. true, the Son also is invisible,” says he, linking on again to Irenzeus, “so far as He is.the Word and Spirit of God; and, prior to the incarnation, He was visible merely in visions, enig- mas, and similitudes.* As Spirit, the Word cannot be seen, ‘nisi imaginaria forma.’ All religion, therefore, was symbolical and shadowy prior to the coming of Christ ; for in the flesh the Son became for the first time visible, from face to face. His body, it is true, veiled His glory, and it could not be beheld save by those who were exalted above their usual consciousness.” This, however, happened to the three selected Apostles on the mountain ; this happened afterwards to Paul; and at His second coming the Lord will be seen by all (adv. Prax. c. 14, 15). Nevertheless, the incarnate Word entered into visible existence through the incarnation; and now we have an actual person, whom we have seen, and heard, and handled.” We see, accordingly, that Tertullian recognises a threefold filiatio:—1. The eternal, inward one, which is shut up in God. 1 Moses alone appears to have been an exception; for to him the pro- mise was given,—With him will I speak face to face, visibly, with others. by dreams and in a glass darkly. But even this promise was not fulfilled till a later period, on the mount of transfiguration (Matt. xvii.). During his earthly life, like the prophets and patriarchs, he did not see Him face to face, but merely in a glass and in enigmas, so that he knew that God’s face was nich at hand. 2 At this point Tertullian’s view shows traces of montanistic influences : in the place of the process through which men are conducted from a mere: historical to a saving faith, which knows Christ in truth, he sets ecstasy ; he fails to carry out the beautiful beginnings of an objective, historical. accomplishment of the work of redemption, which he had made, in his teachings, relative to Christ’s connection with our race; and even partially retraced his steps, so far, namely, as he now represented the body merely as- a veiling, and not also as a revealing, of the Logos. TERTULLIAN. 69 This ne designates Sonship, not in itself, but solely with refer- ence to the second and third stages: strictly speaking, its name is Sermo or Sophia. This is the real potence of Sonship, which was eternally in God, though it had not yet assumed an inde- pendent form; impersonal, but already a personific principle, and, as it were, eternally on the point of breaking forth from its inner divine root into an existence alongside of God, which, though not yet including the world, included the real potence of the world, as also the potence of God-manhood. ( 2.) This coming forth to the creation of the world: Tertullian designates it, in particular, the “generatio of the Son,” of the “secunda per- sona” (adv. Prax. c. 6). It would be eternal if he had taught an eternal creation; but as it is, it 1s to be conceived as occur- ring in time.’ 3. Finally, the third stage is that in which the Son became man, and stood over against God in the form of a visible personality. This doctrine of the distinction between the God who can- not, and the God who can, become visible; the God who is generated, and the God who is ungenerated, he employs in the most various ways against the Patripassians. Both cannot be predicated of one and the same being, as though they were but two aspects ; consequently, we cannot rest in the abstract unity, the “singularitas Dei.’ In accordance herewith, those passages of the New Testament are explained, which speak of beholding God, and of divine appearances. This he confirms by means of passages from the New Testament, which refer to the distinction between the Father and the Son. He asks,—What meaning can Monarchians attach to the prayers of Christ to the Father, to His sending, to His cry, “ My God, My God, why hast Thou forsaken Me?” All the finitude, all the passibility, which the Patripassians attributed to God in general, or to the Father, he transfers to the Son; without, however, entirely denying the passibility of God, as might at first sight have been expected. That same religious interest, which found so inadequate an ex- 1 Adv. Hermog. 3. Here he denies that God had been always Dominus, and therefore that the world, or something in it, has existed eternally. ‘‘ Non ideo pater et judex semper, quia Deus semper. Nam nec pater potuit esse ante filium, nec judex ante delictum. Fuit autem tempus cum ei de- lictum et filius non fuit, quod judicem et qui patrem dominum (al. Deum) faceret.” Conf. Novatian de Trin. 31. 76 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. pression in Patripassianism, and which led to the work of atone- ment being regarded as God’s sympathy with, and participation in, the sufferings intended for us, moved Tertullian, when he spoke without bias, to make use of such terms as “ crucifixus, passus, mortuus est Deus.’’! We find him, however, at the same time giving expression to thoughts apparently of an opposite character, which must have strengthened the opposition raised against Patripassianism. He had, it is true, partially ensured the unchangeableness and impassibility of God by the view he took of the idea of the Father; but to have represented the Son as mere finitude, visibility, and passibility, would have been Ebionitical. Conse- quently, it was necessary to distinguish two aspects of the Son, —one eternal, invisible; the other visible, and subject to the process of finitude. The former he terms, car’ é€oynv, the divine aspect, or God in the Son; and, accordingly, he is able to say, towards the end of his work against Praxeas (c. 27 ff.), without inconsistency, though differently from before (see the “de carne Christ’ 3),—God is immutable ; consequently He undergoes no process, no conversion: and that which he had previously treated as an objection of Marcion’s against the ortho- dox doctrine—“ transfiguratio interemtio est pristini’—he now himself adopts in reference to the divine, that is, to the unalterable, in God Himself. This unalterableness was unquestionably en- dangered by Patripassianism; for, according to it, the Father, to wit, the final ground, Himself comes forth and subjects Him- self to change and finitude ;—unless it went on to distinguish more plainly between God as He is in Himself, and God as He is turned towards the finite ; in other words, unless it accepted the distinction laid down by Tertullian in his doctrine of the Son. In accordance therewith, Tertullian was able to say,— 1 For example, ‘‘de carne Christi” 5. Special prominence is given to that aspect of the Son on which He is turned towards finitude, in the pas- sage above adduced, adv. Prax. 16:—The Son not merely created the world, but is the One who, throughout its entire history, has accomplished the divine work in and for it; He has been the judge, the revealer. The passage concludes with the following words,—Such things ‘‘ heeretici repre- hendunt, quasi Deo indigna, ignorantes, hee in Filium competisse, qui etiam passiones humanas et sitim et esuriem et lachrymas et ipsam nativi- tatem ipsamque mortem erat subiturus, propter hoc minoratus a Patre mo- dicum citra angelos.” TERTULLIAN ek “The Word of God also abides eternally, perseverando in sua forma.” But defective is it, that he supposes himself able to bring this immoveable, unalterable One, the Son of God, immediately, and without any connecting link of thought, into union with the human in Christ. And the consequence thereof is, that he con- verts the incarnation into a being and dwelling in the flesh, or into a being clothed with flesh. (Adv. Prax. 27: Quem (sc. Sermonem) si non capit transfigurari, consequens est, ut sic caro factus intelligatur (Joh. i. 14) dum fit (al. sit) in carne et manifestetur.) To this point he allows himself to be driven by his fear of the theory of conversion; as though the incarnation of the Word were not itself a condition of its abiding in its nature, and as though he had not elsewhere usually taught that the Word was eternally destined to become incarnate, and that the full realization of Sonship was only possible through the incarnation.! “There would be no longer two substances,” he proceeds to say, “but one, a kind of mixture of spirit and flesh, as electrum is a mixture ‘ex auro et argento, if He had been converted into flesh. He would be neither God nor man; for He would have ceased, through the conversion, to be that which He was; and He would not be man, for He who was Sermo could not be truly man. He would, therefore, be neither the one nor the other, but a third something. On the contrary, “videmus duplicem statum, non confusum sed conjunctum, in una persona Deum et hominem Jesum. Et adeo salva est utriusque proprietas substantie, ut et spiritus res egerit in illo, ‘e., virtutes et opera et signa, et caro passiones suas functa sit.” Both substances remain “in statu suo (that is, immoveable) dis- tincte aventes. Neque caro spiritus fit, nec spiritus caro. In uno plane esse possunt: ex his Jesus constitit ex carne homo, ex spiritu Deus.” As he refused to allow the Patripassians to say, “compassus est Pater Filio,” because sympathy is a suffer- ing, whereas the Father is impassible ; so also does he affirm the latter of the Son, “ex ea conditione qua Deus est.” And yet, precisely at this point, the idea of sympathy, as something ethical, might have led him to the recognition of a suffering and a participation in finitude, which involved no curtailment of God’s infinitude; that is, to the idea of a participation, grounded in an act of love, that is, in a “virtus.” The finite, it is true, 1 Compare the passage cited from the “‘ de resurr. carnis,” page 60. 12 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. could not drag Him into suffering; nor could His nature, His vous, in itself be liable to suffering, as the heathenish and, in part also, the patripassian conception of God represents. At the same time, however, His dvs could not be a limit to His love and the manifestation thereof, but love, as the inmost essence of God, must have power over His dvaus ; and if the will of the former be seriously to sympathize with, and truly to participate in, finitude, the latter may not throw any hindrance in the way. To the above declaration, that the “Spiritus” worked in Him the “ virtutes” and the “ signa,” and the flesh suffered (a formula which we often meet with at a later period, and which we find also in Hippolytus, but which, if it be not supplemented, destroys the unity of the person in both aspects), he adds, for- getting the doctrine of the participation of the Son in finitude and suffering, which he had elsewhere laid down,—“ If the dis- tinction utriusque substantie ceased to exist, in a third being perhaps, then would have done et spiritus carnalia, et caro spiritalia ex translatione;” as though the work of redemption were anything apart from the participation of the divine in the human, and as though he himself had not also regarded it in all dther cases as a work accomplished in common by both “ sub- stantiz.” He had opposed to the Patripassians the capability of the Son to make Himself visible,—that is, surely, to become finite and passible,—with the design of proving it to be necessary that the Father, to whom absolutely no suffering and no process can be attributed, should be another than the Son: now, how- ever, he makes no allusion to this distinction, and retains only the difference, that the Son was born and begotten of the Father, and the Father unbegotten. Without doubt he meant, in any case, to recognise in the Son an aspect turned towards, and accessible to, finitude; but so far was he from having con- ciliated this with his conception of the divine nature, that he again denies it entirely to the divine nature, even of the Son. In that case, however, the sufferings of Christ were merely finite sufferings, and the incarnation was simply the origin of a man. For the Word either had or bore the man Jesus as His gar- ment; but the Son of God was not really the Son of man. Still, it would be unfair to judge him solely from this chapter, in which polemical zeal caused him to forget himself, and to strike into a path which his living conception of God would not permit TERTULLIAN. 73 him further to pursue. At other times (for example, in the chap- ter immediately following), he shows himself to be penetrated by the conviction, that the entire “novitas” of the “ nativitas” rested upon the circumstance, that the human was taken into the divine, and that the divine transported itself into the human, with its being and not merely with its activity, without being swallowed up therein. We shall find that the anxiety to ward off a pagan conception of God drove Hippolytus and others to cling very firmly to the pure eternity and immoveability of the divine essence, after the manner of the later Jews; instead of representing God as standing in that more positive relation to finitude, which was required by the idea of the incarnation. Lertullian saw with particular clearness the importance of insisting on a distinction of the Son from the Father; for, according to Patripassianism, there was either no divine self consciousness, apart from Christ, but the Father was solely and entirely in Christ, and the rest of the world destitute of a per- sonal God;’ or else the Father must be held to have been in Christ merely as a power, and not with His entire personality ;— in which latter case, Patripassianism would have been already on the point of passing over into Ebionism. The reason why Tertullian was so undecided and vacillating in his teachings regarding that which distinguishes and unites Father and Son, was, probably, apart from the undoubted difficulty of the ques- tion, that he had not advanced so far as clearly to deduce from ethical principles (which alone suffice in this connection), how far it was possible, or not, for the Word to participate in finitude and sufferings. At first he attributed finitude to the Word or Son immediately, physically, and not ethically,—that is, not as the result of a loving act of will (see pp. 68 f.); and the deeper ground of this course is to be found in his above noticed supposition, that the Son was directly connected and interwoven with the world, in so far as He became a person for the first time, at, and for the 1 Ady. Prax. 16:—‘‘ How could the almighty God, the invisible, the unapproachable One, who grasps the entire world in His hand like a nest, in quo omnis locus, non ipse in loco, qui universitatis extrema linea est, ille altissimus in paradiso deambulare, querens Adam, et arcam post introitum Noe claudere, etc.? Scilicet et heec nec de Filio Dei credenda, fortasse non credenda de patre, licet scripta, quem illi in vulvam Marie deducunt, et in Pilati tribune imponunt, et in monumentis Joseph recludunt.” 74 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. sake of, the creation of the world. And if we trace the matier to its final roots, we shall find that the fault lay in his doctrine of the Trinity. He recognised no act of self-objectification, by which God’s self-knowledge was mediated prior to any creation ; but what He knew, what He thought, though not merely the world, was still only God so far as He passes over into the world. If, then, we can concede him merely a partial victory over Patripassianism, to the extent, namely, to which he showed that the Son must be distinguished from the Father, in Himself and not merely in Christ,—the latter was allowed even by Patripas- sians (adv. Prax. 27: Fillum carnem esse, 7.e. hominem, 7.¢. Jesum, patrem autem Spiritum, z.e. Deum, z.e. Christum),—how do his views stand related to the monarchy of God? How does he reconcile the duality, and subsequently the triplicity, of the persons, to which he is led by the divine revelations, with that unity of God which he maintained inviolate? He preserves the unity, in the jirst place, by asserting the equality of the nature of the persons, nay, even the identity of their substance. The Son is designated “ Filius Dei” and “Deus ex unitate substantie. Nam et Deus Spiritus” (Apol. 21). An Arian Subordinatianism was, therefore, foreign to his mind; at that price he did not desire to purchase the unity of God. All, Father, Son, and Spirit, are one, because all are of one through the unity of their substance (adv. Prax. 2, 4). According to Tertullian, all have one essence,—that is, one power, one reason and wisdom. But that which gives rise to a plurality in God is the “ordo” (adv. Prax. 19), the “ cecono- mia,” which has not merely subjective, but also objective signi- ficance (c. 11). The words in which Tertullian here gave ex- pression to his meaning are remarkable ;—he says, Difference and number are not in God, so far as He is conceived in His eternal, immoveable being (in statu), but merely so far as He is regarded in motion (in gradu; as it were, whilst passing on from one form or stage of revelation to another). “ Giconomiz sa- cramentum unitatem in trinitatem disponit,—tres non statu, sed gradu. Unus Deus, ex quo et gradus isti et forme et species in nomine Patris, Filii et Spiritus sancti deputantur” (adv. Prax. 2). That is, we are to understand by the Trinity, not merely a threefold work, a threefold activity, but a movement of God Himself. When a ray proceeas forth from the sun, it TERTULLIAN. 1 is a part of the whole (portio ex summa) ; but the sun will be in the ray, for the ray is a ray of the sun, and does not break loose from the substance thereof, but merely dilates itself. So is Spirit of Spirit, God of God, like a light kindled at a light. Entire and unaffected remains the ground of a substance (ma- trix materi), even though thou shouldst make use of its kind for several branches; so is that which springs from God,—God and God’s Son are both one. Thus did Spirit constitute an- other of Spirit, God another of God, not in point of number, but of form (modulo alterum, non numero, gradu non statu, et a matrice non recessit, sed excessit). That ray of God, having entered into a virgin, and made itself flesh in her womb, was born as aman united with God (Apol. 21). “Ido not desire two suns,” he goes on to say (adv. Prax. 13), employing the same image, “but Christ I can call God, as does Paul in Rom. ix. 5. Even a ray of the sun, considered by itself, I call Sun: for example, when I say, ‘ There is sun ;’ but T do not, therefore, at once designate the sun, from which the ray proceeds, Ray. Two forms of existence, of one and the same substance (species, forme, effigies, moduli unius et indivisee substantize), I acknow- ledge, as of the sun, so of God, when I view Him in connection with the ceconomia.’ In the second place, he retains firm hold of the unity, through the intimate connection which he recognises as existing between the different persons. He does not regard them as three men, merely united by one generic idea, between whom there may otherwise be infinite differences ; but they are physi- cally and ethically so one, that they may be constantly termed one God. (Ady. Prax. 4: Filium non aliunde deduco, sed de sub- stantia Patris, nihil facientem sine Patris voluntate.) Every originator, says he, is in a sense a father ; everything originated is therefore a son. Nec frutex tamen a radice, nec fluvius a fonte, nec radius a sole discernitur, sicut nec a Deo Sermo. Radix et frutex dus res sunt, sed conjuncte, dus species in divisee, duze forme coherentes. Et tertius a radice fructus e frutice, et tertius a fonte rivus ex Flumine, et tertius a sole apex ex radio. Ita Trinitas per consertos et connexos gradus a Patre decurrens et Monarchie nihil obstrepit et Giconomix statum protegit (adv. Prax. 8). Alium patrem, alium filium dico, sed non diversum, separatum ;” “ distinctio,” he affirms, 76 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. and “ distributio,” but not “ diversitas” and “ divisio.” “ Mo- dulo,” that is, through a different mode of existence, each is different from the other two; but they are equal to each other, as in existence, so also in this, that as the Father constitutes the Son a Son, so the Son constitutes the Father a Father :—the Father does not constitute Himself His own Son, as the Patri- passians teach. (Ady. Prax. c. 10: vanissimi isti Monarchiani ipse se, inquiunt (Pater) Filium sibi fecit. Atquin Pater Filium facet, et Patrem Filius.” According to Tertullian, God was not Pater, but merely Deus, prior to the existence of the Son. “ Et qui ex alterutro fiunt, a semetipsis sibi fieri nullo modo possunt, ut Pater se sibi Filium faciat et Filius se sibi Patrem preestet ; quee instituit Deus, ipse etiam custodit. Habeat necesse est Pater Filium, ut Pater sit, et Filius Patrem, ut Filius sit. Aliud est autem habere, aliud esse.) And, indeed, the true element in the Valentinian Avons (probolz), is that the Word is produced from God and made His Son. “ Hee erit probola veritatis, unitatis custos” (c. 8). Connecting the two together, we arrive at an unity, which is not an abstract “singularitas,” but admits of distinctions, an “ unitas ex semetipsa derivans trini- tatem,” which is confirmed instead of being destroyed thereby (c. 3). The “ unitas irrationaliter collecta heresim facit,” the “trinitas rationaliter expensa veritatem constituit.” This trinitarian conception of God is opposed, on the one hand, to Heathenism, which clings to a multiplicity, without re- ducing it to unity (c. 13); and to Judaism, on the other hand (c. 31). The belief of the Jews in one God, is of such a nature as not to admit of the Son, and after Him, of the Spirit, being reckoned to God. For what difference would there be between us and them,—what would become of the work of the Gospel and of the substance of the New Covenant, which does not suffer the law and the prophets to extend farther than John the Baptist,— if from his day onwards the Three in whom we believe, Father, Son, and Spirit, do not constitute one God? The novelty of the Christian religion consists in the fact, that God willed to be believed in as One after a new fashion, to wit, through the Son and the Spirit; so that now He who was formerly merely pro- claimed by Son and Spirit, but was not known, is known in mundane actuality, in His persons. This view undoubtedly includes a speculative element, to TERTULLIAN. (7 which the later doctrine of the Church was long in attaining, viz., the conception of the Three Persons as inwardly connected (as consertos, cohzrentes). But the type of development to which he subjects the Trinity takes again a turn unfavourable to the doctrine of the Trinity , and thus he reaped the fruit of that immediate interweaving of the Son with the world, to which allu sion has been made above. He shows, it is true, that there was a necessity for the objectification of the reason in the Word, which was its vehicle ; but he does not explain why this objectification should be limited to a triplicity ;—for, so far as we can see, new branches might be continually produced. Because he did not posit the Trinity as an actuality even of the inner essence of God, but merely as a possibility, he found himself, like the Patripassians, unable to say,—God is a Trinity, and cannot be conceived of otherwise ;—all he could say was,—God wills to_be a Trinity, really indeed, but still only in the world. Hence also this Trinity is threatened with extinction, so soon as the world is perfected and returns into God, and the Son shall have given up all to the Father. Indeed, he goes so far (adv. Prax. 4) as to say,— The Monarchy continues so truly unshaken, although the Trinity is imported into it, that the kingdom will actually be given up again to the Father by the Son. The Trinity, however, appears thus to be reduced to a mere movement of God in his- tory, unless he meant perhaps to say, that the ever-abiding and essentially existent unity undergoes discerption in the world, and in the forms of the divine existence in the world; the sole end thereof, however, being that the divine persons, who are rendered distinct in the course of history, and also continue permanently distinguished, may afterwards be reduced to a more complete unity.” He says further, ~The Ciconomia, or the trinitarian ex- istence of God, is posited “in tot nominibus, in quot Deus voluit” (c. 4): a formula which is thoroughly patripassian ; but the cor- rective thereof was concealed, not only in Tertullian’s doctrine of the necessary objectivity of the “ Sermo,” but also partially in his doctrine, that not merely a single potence of God, of which there might be an infinite number, but “ totus animus Dei,” was in the “ Sermo ;” that in the revelation of Christ, therefore, the inmost essence of God was declared to the world,—the “ Filius” having been born, “ de vulva Patris,” out of the heart of the Father (c. 5). Lastly, owing to the somewhat physical 78 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH character of his view of God, he applies inappropriate physical categories to the Son,—such, for example, as that of the part and whole: which, however, should be set rather to the account of his mode of expression, than of his mode of thought. “ Portic totius cessura erat in Filiinomen.” The Son is “ substantiva res, ut portio aliqua totius (c. 26). Pater tota substantia est: Filius vero derivatio totius et portio” (c. 9); from which might logi- sally be deduced a still stronger Subordinatianism than that which is involved in the doctrine of the later generation of the Word to personal existence, to wit, an Ebionitical view of Christ. It may undoubtedly be replied,—* Portio,” in Tertullian’s usage, is also a designation of equality (cf. Index Latinit. Tert., ed. Semler, s. h. v.); that he considered the entire sun to be in the rays; that the Son knows the Father entirely, and also His generation ; and, even more, that Tertullian, describing the re- lation between the Father and Son in a quantitative manner, gives an opposite view, when he says,—The sun expands itself in the rays; or the Son is the river, the Father the fountain- head. Too much stress, however, must not be laid on this aspect of the images; but it must be acknowledged that he leaves the Son in a certain dependence on the Father, although he repre- sented Him as equal in essence, as most intimately conjoined with the Father ; and as, indeed, constituting the Father, Father. Tertullian refers Christ's words, “ The Father is greater than I,” neither to the humanity, nor to the state of self-abasement, but to the Son in Himself. It would be, indeed, totally opposed to Tertullian’s meaning, to regard the Son as a mere partial revelation of God: from Ebionism or Arianism he must be pronounced free; for his total view of the Son rather implies that he regarded Him and the Spirit as different modes of the existence of the one God, who dwelt in His entirety in each of them. The more evident is it, however, that the term “ portio” was badly chosen ; and that, by giving occasion to the use of phy- sical categories, it really disguised Tertullian’s proper meaning. Notwithstanding the important defects of his system, the fulness of Tertullian’s Christian consciousness, and the vigour of his mind, unquestionably lent him a very great influence on the development of doctrine in the Church, and enabled him to give a new turn to the tendency which had prevailed since the time of Justin Martyr. TERTULLIAN. 79 At that time, it is true, the hypostasis of the Logos was exalted to the rank of pure divinity; but the price paid was an increasing obscuration of the hypostatical distinction. Tertul- lian, now provoked by Praxeas, struck into the opposite path, and laid again energetic hold on the neglected momentum of the hypostatic pre-existence of the Logos; with the feeling that Patripassianism was threatening to substitute an ethnic for the Christian conception of God. The positive doctrine laid down by him may have its weak points; but it has also, as we have seen, both religiously and speculatively considered, its excellences; and as regards the latter, he pursued a course of his own, in- dependent of Irenzeus and others. As the point of most im- portance, and which gave a direction to the course of the sub- sequent development, may be mentioned in this connection his doctrine of the “Filiatio.’ Inasmuch as the Father also is reason, the word Logos no longer satisfied Tertullian as a desig- nation of the fy postaais of ane divine in Christ, although it accurately expressed the nature thereof, its true divinity ‘(and herein we see the man who clearly ae ned the true tendency and work of his age). The other meaning, also, which was attached to the Logos by the Church, to wit, “ Word,” ex- pressed, not His hypostasis, but at the utmost the objectification of reason; that is, it contained the hint of an hypostasis, but not the hypostasis itself. And Tertullian not merely clearly saw the inadequacy of existing terms, but endeavoured to find better ones. The new point which he brought to light, and which constituted an epoch in the future history of Christology, was his designation of the personal element in the higher nature of Christ by the name Son; and his endeavour to lay bare more fully the genesis of the Sonship, and its relation to the divine essence, with which, so long as he was merely termed Logos, He was too completely aeniinen This was undoubt- edly an important stroke; and, as we shall see, it met with the approbation of the Church. The age of Logology was now succeeded, in consequence of his labours, by the age of Son- ship. Not that Logology was by any means set aside; but it was reduced to its proper, that is, to a lower rank, because of its inability adequately to convey il to preserve the Christian thought: and, indeed, we find that John, though he began with the Logos, Fe with the term uovoyerys. The New Testa 80 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. ment expression, “Son of God,” had, it is true, naturally been often enough employed at an earlier period, but without a de- terminate, dogmatic idea being connected therewith ; very fre- quently it served merely to designate the entire Christ, or even His official dignity. Justin Martyr applied it also to the hypo- static Logos, but not constantly. Henceforth, however, whereas Logos marks in the first instance the impersonal nature, the word “Son” is employed, in a specifically dogmatic sense, to express the personality of the Logos and His possession of an objective existence of His own, distinct from that of the Father. On the history of the doctrine of the Trinity, this new turn had an important influence, although much that was transitory was connected with it. But even on Christology had the develop- ment of the idea of Sonship a favourable influence, owing to its suggesting and giving occasion to the attempt to view the reve- lation in Christ, not as something external and foreign to the divine in Christ, but as the full exhibition of the entire idea of Sonship, which lay originally in the Son. Closely related to, and dependent on, Tertullian, though giving a superficial version of his master’s system, was Nova- tian. He says (“ De Trinitate” 29, 30),—Because God alone is termed good by Christ, it does not follow that He also was not good. In Christ alone dwelt the Holy Spirit, entirely and per- fectly, “nec in aliqua mensura aut portione mutilatus, sed cum tota sua redundantia cumulate distributus et missus, ut ex illo delibationem quandam gratiarum ceteri consequi possint, totius sancti Spiritus fonte in Christo remanente, ut ex illo donorum atque operum vene ducerentur, spiritu sancto in Christo affluen- ter habitante.” Christ is God and Lord. The unity is not thereby affected. God the Father is the Orderer and Creator of the uni- verse, but unoriginated, invisible, infinite, immortal, eternal, the one God, to whose majesty, greatness, and power nothing can be compared, much less preferred. But out of Him has a Son been born, the Word; not like a sound which strikes the air, or a tone of the voice, but in the substance of a power produced by God. As to the time, Novatian employs the words,—The Father brought forth the Son quando voluit (c. 31). Nevertheless, he says,—He was always in the Father, and the Father was never without Son; but the “always” he does not use in the absolute sense. Because the procession of the Son took place before TERTULLIAN. NOVATIAN. 8] time and the world began, time cannot be applied thereto. And in so far we may, or rather must, speak of an “always.” Strictly speaking, however, He who has no origin must, In some way, precede Him of whom He is the source and origin. He had no intention of representing the Son as acreature; but still the Father is really to him the One God. The Son, it is true, knows the Father, and the secret of His own birth, which no apostle, nor prophet, nor any creature knows. He is God, but God born. “ We will not have two unbegotten ones,” says he; “ consequently, not two Gods.” Clearly, therefore, he regards the Father alone as “sensu eminenti” God, and the one God; whereas Tertullian had endeavoured to show that the unity con- stituted out of triplicity was the more perfect. The Father is alone “omnium rerum principium et caput.” The Son is the “Unigenitus et Primogenitus” of the Father; but, notwith- standing His birth from the Father and not from another,— notwithstanding that He also is God, He showed the unity of God by subjecting Himself to the Father “in morigera obedt- entia,’ and by being “ minister voluntatis paterne.” He was born in order to be God and Lord, for the Father has subjected all things to Him. But the time comes when the Son “ aucto- ritatem divinitatis rursus ad Patrem remittit.” So that it fol- lows from all, that the Father is the one true and eternal God, “a quo solo hee vis divinitatis emissa etiam in filium tradita et directa rursum per substantiz communionem ad Patrem revol- vitur. Gradatim, reciproco meatu illa majestas atque divini- tas ad Patrem, qui dederat eam, rursum ab ipso illo filio missa revertitur et retorquetur ;” and the Father is the principle of all things, even of the Son; the Son 1s God of all the rest, and ac- cordingly Mediator between God and man (c. 31). In what has been just adduced we can scarcely fail to discover a Subordina- tianism even still stronger than that of Tertullian. Both as- serted the unity of the substance of the Father and the Son; both viewed Christ during the period of His mediatorship as God; both take up a position of antagonism to the Monarchians ; but neither was able to confute them. The Monarchians were unable to establish the existence of distinctions in God; but Tertullian and Novatian, though they acknowledge and start with the distinctions, do not assert the divinity of Christ so clearly as the Monarchians. The reason whereof was, that the VOL. Il. F 82 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. former had not really transcended the point of view of the lat- ter. As the Patripassians rested satisfied with the work of revelation, so their two opponents felt the need of the ‘Trinity solely for the work of redemption. Relatively thereto, they believed it necessary that the Son should have an hypostasis, but not otherwise. And as the revelation was not eternal, there remained a point “a parte ante,” in respect of which the anta- gonists were essentially at one with each other. Prior to His generation for the creation of the world, the Son had not a per- sonal existence in God. In this respect, both parties were agreed; nay, they were even further agreed, with the exception of some opposed elements in Tertullian’s system, that the exist- ence of the Son or the time of His origin, depended on the will of the Father. And so, as soon as a mediator ceases to be neces- sary, the personality, or, at all events, the deity (auctoritas divina), of the Son will be endangered. The Trinity then threatens to sink down to a mere ceconomy, as in the systems of those whom they opposed. Irreconcilable, indeed, therewith was the Christian consciousness, which regarded Christ not as a transient revelation, not as a mere power; from which, however, all that follows is, that from the Christian consciousness must proceed the impulse to ever fresh efforts to secure for the doctrine of the Trinity a more satisfactory form, and to point out eternal and not mere arbitrary, both as to number and existence, distinctions in the nature of God Himself. This would require, it is true, that the two Per- sons, Father and Son, should renounce that exclusiveness towards each other attributed to them in the systems of these teachers of the Church. If the Son must again give up His deity or power, in order that the Father may possess it entirely; or if Christ be the ruler of the world in the stead of the Father, and no way be found of allowing both, together with the Holy Spirit, to participate in the entire work, each in His own way, then must the unity of God be purchased with the subordination or the merely momentary existence of the hypostases. We have already hinted that this relation of exclusiveness arose from the obscuration introduced by the application of physical categories ; for in the @vaxs, not only qualities, but even individuality of being is characterized by exclusiveness. This physical exclusiveness is only a feeble reflection of the fixed, ineffaceable mits and dis- tinctions which rule in the domain of spirit. But in the domain Ee CYPRIAN. HIPPOLYTUS. 83 of spirit, exclusiveness is not necessary to the maintenance of dis- tinctions, as in the finite, material world. There, on the con- trary, as Tertullian already vaguely felt, distinctions confirm unity; for an unity evolved out of distinctions 1s more compact and self-sufficient. This we may learn even from a comparison of organic with inorganic nature. In the domain of spirit, the unity is not an abstract identity or continuity, but one that posits and confirms distinctions. As belonging to the same African school, we might further mention Cyprian. His sphere was the practical, and he pro- duced nothing new in the domain of Christology; but as a prince of the Church, whose mind was bent above all things on the attainment of unity, and who left aside everything that was singular or still unfixed, we may fairly regard him as the truest representative of the doctrine regarding the Person of Christ, generally held about the middle of the third century. With his distinct and individual character, he may be taken as the embodiment of the Christological Symbolum of his age. For this reason, however, it will be more fitting first to listen to the voice of a man who took an active part in the dogmatical struggle of the period,—to wit, Hippolytus, of the Oriental Church, who combated Patripassianism in its very home. As has been already remarked by others, Hyppolytus has hitherto been unjustly neglected by writers on the history of dogmas,—a course, ‘ny excuse for which may be pleaded the possible doubts as to the genuineness of several of the works attributed to him, but which is not thereby justified. (Note 15.) What arguments he advanced against the Patripassianism of Noetus, we shall see below. Beron, however, who undoubt- edly spoke of the Logos as the manifested aspect of the Father (see page 29), he answered to the following effect :—So far are we from being able to assume a conversion of the Deity into a man, or a Kévoous, by which that which was identical (TavTov) with the Father became identical with humanity, that we can- not even predicate movement, much less change and conversion, of God. The divine will (Fragm. 1), by which God created and moves all things, remains ‘tself unmoved. For the infinite in no way admits of the idea of motion, seeing that there exists neither place to which, nor anything about which, it might move. ‘To that which is infinite and immoveable in its essence, 84 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. movement would be already conversion. The Son of God, therefore, in becoming incarnate, underwent no conversion of any kind, but merely assumed circumscription by the natural flesh, for our sake; He himself, however, remaining without flesh (Séya capxés) and apart from all circumscription. So im- possible is it that a conversion of deity into humanity, or of humanity into deity, should take place, that God and man can- not even be compared with each other. They are érepodueis. Between the Creator of the universe and the creature, between the infinite and the finite (7 aTreip@, TO Trepatov), between the unlimited and the limited, no sort of comparison can be insti- tuted ; for they are not merely relatively but essentially (puotxds) different. What the divine was before, that it remained after the incarnation, essentially infinite, unlimited, impassible, in- comparable, unchangeable, and immoveable (avadrolwtov, ar- pet Tov), possessed of all power in itself, and so forth. To the ethnic changeableness of God, which was connected with pan- theistic elements, is here therefore opposed His absolute immove- ableness. But where God’s a7retpov, dtpeTtov, is treated as it is by Hippolytus,—where even permission, in its distinction from act and operation, is excluded from God, on the ground of His unchangeableness, as we shall shortly see,—there the world is kept impersonal, and God alone is, strictly speaking, allowed to have reality. It appears, therefore, that Hippolytus, in the fundamental idea of his theology, is chargeable with approxi- mating in another way to pantheism, through raising a too hasty opposition to Patripassianism. It may be well indeed to say, that God cannot suffer through finitude (Fragm. 3: od TEhUKE Teprypaherbar yevnth dices to Kata ducw ayévntov), even though it grew into one whole together with Him, by means of the conception which seizes hold on all understanding (Tepuypagoveay crn). But it is not good to take the love of the Son, its power, and the unity of the Person of Christ so little into account, as to maintain that the divine, in its im- moveableness, infinitude, and so forth, and the human,_as being of a totally different substance, cannot be at all compared with each other. Not only is there a forgetfulness of the doctrine of the divine image; but with such premises the doctrine of Christ p A durch die allen Verstand gefangennehmende Empfingniss.” - Wenn sie auch mit ihm zu einem Ganzen zusammenwuchs: , HIPPOLYTUS. 85 can only assume an imperfect form. It will, nevertheless, be instructive to examine the Christological theory of Hippolytus more carefully. Let us examine, first, what he teaches regarding the divine aspect of the Person of Christ; secondly, his view of the incar- nation ; and, thirdly, his conception of the union of the divine and human in Christ. J. Patripassians of the school of Noetus, who appealed to the same passages as Praxeas,—to wit, Exod. i. 6, xx. 3; Baruch iii. 836; Isa. xlv. 5; Rom. ix. 5; John xiv. 9,—arrived at the conclusion that Christ was the Father Himself, that He was the Son, was born, suffered, and raised Himself from the dead. In reply, he urged that, in order to withstand Theo- dotus, who looked only at the humanity of Christ, we must not look solely at His deity, and attribute to Him the entire deity (c. Noet. 3, 11). Both are equally one-sided (povoxwdor). “Who will deny that God is one? But shall we, therefore, at ouce set aside the ceconomy,” which introduced distinctions into Him? If Christ be God, say they, and God is one, the suffer- ings which befell Christ must be attributed to the Father also. But the one God, in whom we are compelled to believe, is, on the contrary, unbegotten, arabs, a0dvaros, and doeth all things as and when He wills (c. 8). This self-identity of God is held so firmly by Hippolytus, that he is unwilling to admit even of the distinction of willing and not-willing in God (Habr. 1. 45). The Adyos tod Oeod also is azabijs, and solely through the flesh is He passible. It was not, therefore, as in the case of Tertul- lian, the desire to constitute God a participator in Hnitude that led Hippolytus to the distinction of the Son (vios, frequently mais Qeod), but partly the passages of Scripture, which distin- guish the Son from the Father, and partly the need of retaining firm hold of the personal indwelling of God in Christ as the unity of God. How, then, does he accomplish the task? He says (c. 10),—“ Whilst God was still alone, and had nothing with Himself that was contemporary, He willed to create the world. Thinking, willing, and uttering the idea of the world, He created the world; and soon that which was created was with Him, as He had willed it. It is enough for us to know that nothing was contemporary with God; nothing was besides Himself. But He, although existing alone, existed in plurality (arodvs av); for He 86 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. was neither without the Logos nor the Sophia (dAoyos, aaogos), without power or counsel: all was in Him, and He was Himself the All (ro wav). When it was His will, He showed His Logos as He willed, at the times afore appointed by Him, and through Him eral all things, creating all things through the Word, through Wisdom ordering all things § in Beaute As the Prince of that which then came into existence, as the counsellor and master-workman, He brought forth the Logos. The Logos, whom He bore in Himself, He made visible. This was His own intellect (vods), invisible at first to the growing world, and at an earlier period visible only to Himself. In that He uttered the first word, and produced light out of light, He sent forth for creation its Lord (apojKe 7h tices Tov Kvptov), to the end that the world, seeing Him through His manifestation, might be delivered. And so there stood another alongside of God” (c.11). “I have no intention of teaching,’ he goes on to say, “two Gods, but merely two wpdcw7a, the preservation of the ofxovouia (c. 11, 14), Light of light, water from the fountain, a ray from the sun. For He is one force out of the whole; but the Father is the whole” (c. 11). Christ in His divine aspect is wavtoxpdtwp (c. 6); everything is made by Him; He alone is of the Father (c. 11). Paul ventures to say, “ He is God over all;” and justly, for He Himself declared that all things were given up to Him (c. 6). As, according to John xvii. 22, we are not to be one with each other and with God in Christ as to our personality (kata tiv odciav, Persdnlichkeit), but as regards dvvayis and didPecus ths opodpovias (that is, without doubt, so far as there dwells in us the like dive power, and as we are animated by the same disposition); so did He confess that He was in the Father duvameu, duadécer, or the Son (6 Iais) is the one understanding of the Father. Coming forth into the world, God’s voids is set fates men as the Son of God (mats @cod; compare also “de Chr. et Antichr.” c. 3,—0 Tov Qcod traits, 6 Tadat AOyos). Do we, then, teach a plurality of Gods, which have come into existence in the course of time? By no means. All runs back again into one. The Logos is the Father’s vods, copia, Aoyos itself, one and the same dvvapus with that of the Father (uia dvvayus watpéa, c. 8, 6,11). As regards the dvvapus, it is one God. But as regards the ceco- nomy, its manifestation is threefold (éideEs, c. 8). The HIFPOLYTUS. 87 ceconomy, because it is an harmonious one (otkovowia cuppo- vias), leads back to one God, for God is one. He who com- mands is the Father; He who obeys is the Son; He who enlightens is the Holy Ghost. The Father is over all, the Son is through all, the Holy Ghost is in all (Eph. iv. 6); and it is impossible for us to assume one God, unless we really believe in Father, Son, and Spirit. The Jews boasted of the Father; but they never got as far as thankfulness (that is, they never had a childlike spirit, a real Father), for they did not recognise the Son. The disciples knew the Son; but not in the Holy Ghost, and therefore they denied Him (c. 14). Consequently, besides the equality of substance and the sameness of will and thought, it is their common origin from the Father, and the identity of the work with which the three Tpocwrra are occupied, each in its own way, that is to preserve the unity of the deity, notwithstanding the plurality of the mpocwra. The Father wills or speaks ; the Son accomplishes ; the Holy Spirit enables the mind to apprehend Christ’s work, and gives the necessary enlightenment (cuverifer, pavepody, c 14). Two different things are therefore connected, but not united. The greater the stress laid on the latter point, that is, on the identity of their work, the more is the basis withdrawn on which the three hypostases rest : the triplicity then relates, not to God’s inmost essence, but merely to His manifestations, to His work. Hippolytus has, on this ground, been charged with Sabellianism, but unjustly. For he claims divine worship for each of the three, and must therefore have conceived them to be hypostatical (c. 13; compare Theoph. 10). On the other hand, the more he insists on the triplicity of the mpocw7a, and, in particular, as regards the second srpocwrropr, assigns the precise moment, when the Understanding or Word of God was begot- ten as His Son, and was set into the world as an étepos over against God, the more distinctly do we perceive that he has Bat one means of guarding the unity of God, to wit, Subordina- tianism. The power of unity is in the Father, Gain whom everything, even the oixovoyia, proceeds, and to whom, as the qav, the Son is related as a mere ray to the sun, or as a part of the whole. He has, it is true, subjected all things to the Son, but not Himself; on the contrary, He commands, whereas the 1 For example, by Hanell. &8 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. Son obeys; nay more, He called the Son, His own vods, to an hypostatical existence alongside of Himself, because He willed, and just when He willed. A clear line of demarcation separates this doctrine of the Son from Arianism ; for, according to it, the Son is equal in substance to the Father, and is not a creature, but begotten by God prior to all creation. But though eternal as to His essence, He was not eternal as to His personality. His essence was the divine understanding, the divine wisdom, the divine power itself; the theoloeumena of the divine Word and the divine Wisdom were united in Him; but because the Father Himself cannot be without power and wisdom (aXoyos, acopos), Hippolytus, like Tertullian, ends with identi- fying, at all events, the eternal aspect, or the essence, of the Son with the Father; although, on the other hand, he broke the first ground for an eternal distinction of the Father from the Son, by teaching that the Father carried Him in Himself prior to His generation. This thought, however, if the potence of the Son in God was the voids, the codia, of which, be it re membered, the Father could not be conceived destitute, could not be further followed out, without encroachment on the Father; unless the divine vods were represented as in some way doubling itself, and, whilst abiding in the Father, to use Tertullian’s ex- pression, as objectifying itself in the Word. Wisdom and power, however, are not, in his view, hypostatical, but predicates of the Father Himself : they become hypostases outside of God, in the world. We may therefore briefly say,—With one foot, Hippo- lytus, like all the Church teachers of his time, still stood on the ground of his patripassian opponents ; and yet built.up a subor- dinatian system, as it were, on Sabellian foundations? Not distinctions which exist merely for the mind of the be- holder, but real and objective ones, were sought. Eternal dis- tinctions of essence, however, were not arrived at. The wisdom and word of Omnipotence, considered as an activity or as an attribute, must appertain also to the Father: hence the Son, who is the Wisdom of the Father, is constantly on the point of going back out of His hypostasis, which He owes solely to the will, not to the essence, of the Father, into His essence, which is undistinguishably one with the essence of the Father, whose hypostasis alone is fixed and established. Hippolytus gave more definite expression to this temporality HIPPOLYTUS. 89 of the Sonship than even Tertullian. The Only-begotten One, says he, was indeed neces Logos prior to the incarnation, but not yet perfect Son.’ Who was in heaven, save the Tatts without humanity, who was sent in order to show that He ae was on earth is also in heaven? The Logos took the name which was customary amongst the children fi men, the expres- sion of tender love (c. 15); and from the very beginning (for example, by Daniel), although He was not yet man, allowed Himself to be called Son of man, because He was destined to become man, and to be set forth asa perfect Son (c. 4). (Note 16.) His Sonship, therefore, was a growing one, and first attained completion at the incarnation. With the Sonship, however, was connected His personality, which, out of consideration for the redemption in Christ (c. 10) indeed, he represented the Logos as attaining, even prior to the incarnation; but which he must have been rae lited to derive from finitude, if the only place he had for it was one outside of the divine sphere. If God is abso- lutely arpemros (2, 45), immoveable (c. Ber. Fragm. 1), and if the divine Logos, notwithstanding, first became an hypostasis or Son in time, the hypostatical in Him cannot have pertained to God. The essence of the Logos, indeed, cannot by any means be described as a creature and finite; Bue His per sonality cer- tainly :—the latter, so far as it began in time, and gradually advanced from imperfection to perfection ; ; the former, in so far as not the essence of God is conceived to be trinitarian, but His understanding is held to have been constituted by Him into an independent hypostasis, as and when He willed (see above, and c. Noet.c.16). This birth of the Son, who out of the Logos of the Father, and in the Father, was constituted Son, is, like His birth in the flesh, a mystery ; the result and product of which is before our eyes in Christ, without our being able to understand the process. The eeennine thereof is re- served for the saints, who shall behold the face of God. And a still greater mystery than the incarnation is the birth of the Son out of God, which took place (Ps. ex. 3) before the morning star (c. 16). So much only he held to be certain, that the Logos continued one with the Father even after He had become a Person or a Son (axopiatos tod IIatpos; c. Noet. c. 1 C. 15:—Odtre yoo coopnos xat nab Eaurdv 6 Adyos rérsios Fy vide, KAITOL TEALIOS GY Adyos Kovoryerys, etc., Cc. 4. 90 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. 18; Theophan. c. 7), and fulfilled all things notwithstanding His hypostasis (Fabr. 2, 45). He is drreplyparrtos, akaTanT 708 (Theophan. 2). He terms Him povoyeri)s Oeod Aoyos (2, 29), Aéyos TOD maTpos po TavTwV yeyevynuevos (de Christo et Antichr. c. 11), or mpd aiwver wovoyerns (de Charism. T..d, 246). In his commentary on Genesis (Fabr. 2, 29), he appears to go even still further. The words of Christ,—-namely, John xvii. 5, “Father, glorify Me with the glory which I had with Thee before the world was,’—he explains in the following man- ner,—del yap vy €v TH SdEn Ocomrperret, TO iSio cuvuTapXov yevyTOpl TPO TaVTos alOvos Kal YpovoV Kal THS TOD KOo- wou KataBorys ; which reminds us of Ireneus. This passage cannot indeed prove that Hippolytus recognised the existence of the distinction of Father and Son in the eternal divine essence; for it would clash with all that we have hitherto advanced : but it does show that the apparently Arian elements in his system were there, so to speak, against his will. That there ever was a time when the Son as yet existed not, it would have been 1m- possible for him to affirm, if for no other reason, because he believed that time began with the world, and that the world was created by the Son, who was not a creature, but a Son. At the very same time, however, he unsuspectingly lays down the pro- position, that the Logos was not eternally a person (that is, Son), and represents His actual Sonship, His hypostatical existence, as following upon His substantial existence in the Father, as the Father’s power and wisdom ; or, what is to the same purpose in his eyes, he taught that the Father was at first alone, in com- pany solely with a plurality of attributes, and that when He willed He set the Son over against Himself (c. Noet. 10). The bringing forth of the Logos to light (Sevxvivat, ib.), who was eternally present in the divine essence, but visible only to the Father, was, in the view of Hippolytus, His bringing forth, or generation’ (yevvdv), as the hypostasis of the Son, so that He henceforth stood over against the Father as an érepos (c. 10, ike This hypostasis of the Son is not merely the Creator of the 1 I have tried here to render into English the play between the German words zeigen and zeugen ; to show, and to beget. They might be otherwise translated—‘ the producing” (7.e., to view) of the Logos, was His * produc- tion” (i.e., generation).—TR. HIPPOLYTUS. G1 world (xdvrwy Snusoupyos, Theoph. 2; c. Noet. 10), but also the Lord, King, and Judge of all heavenly and earthly things, and things under the earth (de Chr. et Antichr. 26). He keeps visible and invisible things together, and in a good condition (2, 29). The Logos or Son is the principle of all revelation; the Word spake (I. c. 31) and dwelt in the prophets ; in that He be- came His own messenger in them, He spake concerning Himself (€v TovTOLs TodLTEVOpEVoS), showing the Word which was des- tined to appear among men (c. Noet. 11). As Hippolytus did not deem the prophets in particular, to whom Moses belonged (1, 246), to have been themselves active at the moment of reve- lation (compare “de Chr. et Antichr.” 2,—édpydvev Sixenv ivo- pévov éxovtes év éavTots del TOV Aoyov, ws TAHKTpOV, Sv ob KwWov- pevoe aTrnyyeAXov Tadta amep HOcrev 0 Meds; c. 12, where he terms the prophets “ Christ’s eyes;” and c. 2, where he terms them “our eyes’), he was able to say that Christ sojourned already in them; and, as he appears to have done after the ex- ample of Theodoret (Fabr. 1, 267), to distinguish three forms of the wapovaia of Christ, if which the orcs) was undoubtedly His walking with the eee or His appearance to them (com- pare on Gan in. 8, Fabr. 2, 22); the second, His walking in the prophets, when they fecans as it were, forms under which He, for a time, manifested Himself ; the third, the incarnation, when He perfectly and permanently assumed humanity, and lived a thoroughly human life. This third he again distinguishes, in the usual'manner, into the advent of the Redeemer in humilia- tion, and His advent in glory (de Chr. et Antichr. 44). II. We confine our attention, in the first instance, to the in- carnation. The Father sent the immortal Son and Logos into the world; and He, entering into man and begetting us anew to immortality of the soul and of the body, breathed into us the breath of true life, and clothed us with an imperishable panoply (Theoph. 8). What the holy Virgin conceived was the Logos, the First-born of God, who descended upon her from heaven; and a man, who was formed in her womb as her first-born, in order that the first-born Logos of God might exhibit Himself in union with a first-born man (1, 267). Both substances, the divine and human, must He receive, as it were, as a pledge of His ability to appear in the character of Mediator, both of the two natures and of God and man (1, 266).—Fhe protoplast Adam, the 92 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. Logos sought out in the Virgin; the spiritual Adam sought out the earthly in the mother. He became a helper of vanquished man, by becoming like him (1, 269). The act of incarnation itself Hippolytus describes as follows:—'The only-begotten Logos of God, God of God, humbled Himself, voluntarily abas- ing Himself to that which He was not, and invested Himself with this dishonourable flesh of ours (2, 29, KexévwKev éavTov xabels eOcdovtns éavTov eis Orrep ovK Hv, Kal Thy adofov TavTHy cdpxa nyuméoxeto). At the same time, as the Logos of God, the glory of God belonged essentially and inalienably to Him, even after the act of incarnation. But His humanity partici- pated also, to a certain extent, in this glory. He gives the fol- lowing explanation of the passage Isa. xix. 1, “ Behold, the Lord cometh on a light cloud:”—The Lord is the Logos ; the light cloud is the purest of all tents, enthroned in which our Lord Jesus Christ entered into life (1, 271). And on Ps. xxvin. 1, he remarks,—“ The ark of imperishable wood was the Re- deemer. For His incorruptible tabernacle, which was unaffected by the rottenness of sin, was thus signified. The Lord was sin- less, was of the wood which knows no corruption, as to His humanity; that is, He was inwardly out of the Virgin and the Holy Spirit, and outwardly out of the Logos of God, covered as with the purest gold” (1, 268). We find in other writers also a reference of the ark of the covenant to the humanity of Christ (for example, Iren. Fragm. p. 342, Ed. Mass.). But whereas Irenzeus gives the image the application,—the ark was inwardly gilt, and outwardly covered with gold; and in like manner the body of Christ was inwardly adorned with the Logos, and out- wardly guarded by the Holy Ghost,—Hippolytus here takes Christ’s humanity as corresponding to the wood of the ark, that is, as the inner portion, surrounded by the uncircumscribed Logos, and as having been, as it were, fitted for union with the Logos, by the purifying and glorifying power of the Holy Ghost. On Gen. xlix. 11 (Fabr. 2, 24), “In wine washeth he his garments,’—he remarks, “ Through the Holy Ghost and the word of truth, He will purify His flesh.” Akin to this is another passage, which sets the incarnation in a still more determinate relation to the Logos. Prov. ix. 1 ff. he explains (1, 282) as follows :—“ Christ, the wisdom and power of God the Father, built for Himself a house, to wit, He took the odpxwous from HIPPOLYTUS. 93 the Virgin for a temple. ‘She set up seven pillars ;’—these, according to Isaiah, are the seven powers of the Holy Ghost, which descended on Christ. ‘She mixed wine in her cup; that is, the Redeemer united His deity, the pure wine, with the flesh, in the Virgin, and was born of her as God and man, with- out commixture. ‘She spread her table;’ that is, she commu- nicated the knowledge of the Holy Trias.” Doubts may be entertained as to the genuineness of the next sentence, which explains the table to signify the Holy Eucharist, in which the precious, sacred body of Christ is daily sacrificed on the mystical divine table, in commemoration. In another simile, borrowed from weaving, he depicts the various factors which worked to- gether in the Person of Christ as follows:—When as yet the Logos of God in Himself was destitute of flesh, He took upon Himself holy flesh out of the holy Virgin, and wove for Himself, as it were, a bridal garment in His sufferings on the cross (through His death of love, the glory which encompasses Him and His redeemed ones). The sufferings which He endured on the cross were the loom; the warp was the power of the Holy Ghost ; the woof was His holy flesh which was woven in with the Spirit; the weaving thread is the loving grace of Christ, which binds in one that which was dissevered; the Logos was the shuttle; the master weavers were the patriarchs and prophets, who wove for Christ His precious robe, His coat without seam; through them the Logos passed like a shuttle, weaving by them what the Father willed. These artificial allegories, which are very much to the taste of Hippolytus, show that he conceived the Logos to be the properly moving principle, as of all revelations, so also of the incarnation; and although he assigns to the Holy Spirit - His work in connection therewith, he really represents the Logos as building for Himself His own tabernacle. Indeed, he says, —‘* He raised His own body from the dead by the power of the Father” (€{eoydver rov vadv éavrod, 2, 27). Nevertheless, he insists, and repeatedly asserts, that the material, consecrated by the Holy Ghost, for the temple in which Christ was to be en- throned, was taken from the Virgin. He would not have been a Mediator had He not, in the man Jesus, assumed a man of our race. He lived through human conditions (c. Noet. 18; de Chr. et Antichr. 26, 46), the entire human stadium, and for this reason He is the arbitrator: He descended also into Hades, be- 94 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. cause it was His will to be counted among the dead (de Chr. et Antichr. 26 and 1, 269). “Let us believe, dear brothers,” says he (c. Noet. 17), “ that God the Word descended from heaven into the holy Virgin Mary; that He became flesh, assuming from her also a human, that is, a rational, soul (compare also the Fragment in Ang. Mai’s Coll. Nov. 7, 12; c. Beron. Fragm. 8, in Fabr. 1, 229 f.); that, in short, having become all that man is, with the exception of sin, He saves the fallen, and is able to confer immortality on those who believe in His name. Born of the Virgin and the Holy Ghost, He exhibited a new man, in that His heavenly nature was constituted of that which was of the Father as Logos; and, as far as concerns the earthly, He took a body from the old Adam, through the me- dium of the Virgin. He now, coming forth into the world, revealed Himself as God in a body; came forth as a perfect man.” III. But since Hippolytus, as we know, laid great stress on the unalterableness of God, and also represents the Son, who remains inseparable from the Father (the Father in the Son and the Son in the Father), as participating therein, even whilst He sojourned among men (c. Noet. 4), the question arises,— How did He reconcile the incarnation therewith? The idea.ofa humanity, possessed by the Logos already in heaven, must _ be rejected; there was a time when the Logos was not man (G. Noet. 4). Humanity exists in heaven, only since the paternal Logos presented a perfect man as a gift to God. Accordingly, He became what He was not before, without losing the divine essence and glory, which He had from the beginning (2, 29), consequently without conversion (c. Beron. Fragm. 1, in Fabr. 1, 225 f.; c. Noet.17). But from this he deduces, further, that. the incarnation did not affect His being, but solely His Having or Dwelling. It is frequently supposed that Hippolytus conceived the divine and the human to have stood in a very intimate rela- tion to each other: as, for example, when he says (c. Beron. 1, 230),—pndev Oeiov yupvov THpaTos evEpYNoAs, pndé avOperwov 6 autos dpotpov OeoTnTos ; OF when he reckons the incarnation necessary to the perfection of the divine Sonship. But he does not carry these ideas out. Consistently with the mode of thought to which he mainly adhered, Hippolytus cannot properly say,— The Logos became or was man ; but merely that He wore aman anaes HIPPOLYTUS. BERON. 45 as a garment, or dwelt in him as in atemple. 'ron), évdupya, vaos (de Chr. et Antichr. 11, 4; ; Theophan. 4,in Genes. xlix. 11; Fabr. 2, 24), are also sioaihiye expressions x his; and when he lays stress on Christ’s having a human soul, it is merely for the sake of the completeness of the human nature, and has not at all the effect of freeing the humanity of Christ from its total dependence on the Logos. As we have seen, Hippolytus did not conceive the freedom of man to involve his being an inde- pendent agent; for that would have led to the recognition of the distinction between divine volition and divine permission, of the possibility of change in God. He was far, therefore, from supposing himself to be curtailing the inten aspect of the Person of Christ, when Me denied it a free human Ego and - treated it as a meee organ. He gave the following account of the relation between the two natures during their conjunc- tion :—The dvvayis watpéa? which dwelt in Him worked all that was an expression of power, the miracles, the resurrection, and the like; whereas to His humanity appertained weakness and suffering. By His weakness He was to prove Himself man (2, 45; ¢. Noet. 15); by His glory He exhibited Himself as God (c. Noet. 18; compare Fabr. 2, 28; 1, 218; and Theoph. 7). Lhe work against Beron is simply a fuller development of these ideas. Through His health-bringing incarnation (cap- xwots), the Logos introduced into the flesh the activity of His own deity ;—not that His deity was bounded by the flesh ; and 1 To this connection belongs the well-known passage, c. Noet. 15. After the words adduced above (ore yao doupxos xal xa Exvrdv 6 Adyos, etc.), he proceeds to say :—So 008 4 cetpS xb’ eauray Oiye tov Adyou vxo- arava novvaro die To gy Adyw thy avotacy exeiv.—Svoracis, be it observed, is not yet equivalent to personality. The sense is,—it had its subsistence in the Logos; He was the connective and vehicular force. This is thoroughly unobjectionable: he does not thus necessarily pronounce the humanity of Christ impersonal; although, in view of what has preceded and what re- mains to be adduced, there can be no doubt that Hippolytus would have defended the impersonality, had the question been agitated at the period at which he lived. 2 C. Noet. 6. 8.10.16. Beryll says, dvvapss rarpixy. The above phrase employed by his contemporary, Hippolytus, shows how little right Baur has to bring it forward in proof of Beryll’s Ebionism. ‘To Beryll’s other expression also, dvvamss rarpiny gumorirevoutyy, x.7.A., parallels may be found in the writings of Hippolytus (see c. Noet. 4; de charism. 1, 246). For the incarnation, he employs also the term éxidnu/e. Fabr. 2, 29. 96 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCR. still less that it grew out of the essence of the humanity (Fragm. 1, 226). That which 1s revealed through the flesh, can by no means be described as belonging to the flesh. In proof of which, he brings forward the illustration above mentioned, of the thought which is expressed by the tongue, but which neither springs from nor belongs to it, nor to the hand that records it (Fragm. 8; Fabr. 1, 229 f.; compare Fabr. 2, 29). For our salvation, and in order to give the universe a share in unchange- ableness, the Creator of the universe incorporated with Himself a rational soul and a sensitive body (compare c. Noet. 17), drawn from the holy Mary, who was ever a virgin,” by an immaculate conception, without conversion. He thus became a man, who, being as to nature foreign to sin, was at once God and Word. For, as to His deity, He worked what was divine through His holy flesh, that is, such things as did not appertain to the nature of the flesh. As to His humanity, He suffered what was human, that is, such things as did not appertain to the nature of the deity, borne up by the deity (avoxyh Ths OedtnTos ; compare C. Noet. 15, in note 1, page 95); working nothing divine, without the body (yupvev coparos), and doing nothing human, without participation in deity (dpotpov OedrnTO0s; Fragm. 8; Fabr. 1, 229 £.). But if that which the divine nature worked pertained in no sense to the human, as its property; and if the latter was the mere passive organ of the former, wherein did the appearance of the Logos in Christ differ from His walking in the prophets? The distinction has already been mentioned : in Christ the union between the Logos and a man was not merely momentary, but permanent. By itself, the circumstance, that in the case of Christ the Logos first prepared for Himself a man, whereas, in the case of the prophets, the man was begotten by men, can- not constitute a difference; for Adam also was prepared by the hands of the Logos, and Hippolytus must consequently have put him on a level with Christ, had he regarded him as a pro- phet. If, then, the only difference were that between a momen- tary and a permanent indwelling of the Logos, the distinction 1 This predicate probably signifies merely, that Mary remained, even after the birth of Jesus, dice omirles civopes. With this supposition accord well the words of Theoph. (c. 3),—‘‘ The Baptist made the unfruitful fruis- ful; Jesus made the Virgin unfruitful.” . | j . | 4 HIPPOLYTUS. 97 between Christ and the prophets would manifestly be merely quantitative. Christ would in reality have been nothing more than a longer continuing theophany. We might thus account for the title of his discourse, e’s Ta dyta Oeopavera — émrupdveia 3 as also for his saying therein (c. 7),—He appeared, He did not be- come manifest (é€7repavn, ov« épavn). The last-mentioned words, however, refer to His self-abasement, in that at His baptism He took the appearance of subordination, He who had been always in the bosom of the Father; and assumed a human body for a garment, and therewith concealed His deity, in order to elude the snares of Satan. And the word @eoddvera had also, in the ° following century (see, for example, the “‘Theophania” of Euse- bius, recently edited by Cramer), a wider signification, which tnelaaed the incarnation of Christ. In the third century, too, the Feast of Epiphany bore also the name of Theophany. But as to the question, whether Hippolytus teaches a merely quanti- tative distinction between Christ’s working and appearance in Jesus and in the prophets,—it cannot be denied, that so long as the humanity of Christ is merely regarded as a garment or a temple, so long as the Logos merely has, or is the vehicle of humanity, without being man; and, vice versd, so long as the humanity of Christ cannot be termed divine,—so long is there no incarnation, but merely theophanies; so long is that imma- nent union of the divine and human not logically demonstrated, which faith feels to be the essentially new element in Christian- ity. (Note 17.) In reality, however, the very permanency of the indwelling of the Logos in this man, shows that we have to do with some- thing more than a theophany. If it be certain that the Logos remains eternally clothed with humanity (c. Noet. 4), that He no longer works apart from it, its relation cannot be merely the accidental one of a garment or of a covering, but it must be intimately and essentially united with the Logos Himself. Hippolytus also felt this (see, for example, c. Noce 15, com- pare note p. 89, and note 1, p. 95); and when he gives free and _unbiassed_ expression to his Christian intuitions, he goes far beyond the meagre category of a garment;* nay, even 1 Contra Beron, he says,—The union of the two natures is an d&éfyzros and 2éppyros ; the Logos had reserved for Himself a new and fitting method of so working what was divine and what was human, without that confu- VOL. It G 98 FIRST PERIOD SECOND EPOCH. beyond the merely organic comparison, according to whicn the humanity was related to the deity, as the tongue or the hand is to thought. For he aimed at showing that in Christ humanity had been renovated, and the first perfect man pre- sented to God. “AvOpwros év avOpwrots éyyernOn avatrao- cov d¢ éavtod tov ’Addu. Man, formed of the earth, and bound with the bonds of death, He drew forth out of the lowest Hades—He who descended from above and bore aloft into higher regions that which was below: the herald, who | brought the joyous message to the dead, became the Saviour of souls, the resurrection of the buried. ‘The Logos became a helper to vanquished humanity; in the Virgin He sought out the Adam of the first creation, who was formed of the dust of the ground; He, the eternally living One, sought out him who, through disobedience, had fallen a prey to death. He who was nobly born desired, by His own obedience, to put the bondsman on the footing of a free man; He transformed him who was dissolved into dust, and had become the food of the serpent, into a diamond; He set forth Him who hung on the cross as the Lord of the conqueror, and was found as a conqueror through the wood of the cross (1, 269). Through death He vanquished death. In Adv. Jud. 3, Fabr. 2, 2, we read,—* For that which I have not robbed, says the Logos in Ps, Ixxviii. (Hebr. Ixxix.), that is, for the sin of Adam, which I did not commit, I suffered death.” In i. 266, again, —“ On His arms, stretched out on the cross, He bore the sins of Gentiles and Jews, and nailed them, along with Himself, to the cross.” In the de Antichr. 61,— “ His holy hands, which were extended on the cross, are the wings of the eagle in the Apocalypse of John, which delivered the woman in the desert. He spreads out the right and the left, inviting all who will believe in Him, and He covers them as a hen covereth her chickens.” Again, in de Antichr. 11,— “ Out of His side spring two fountains, one of water, the other sion of the natures which he condemns in his opponent, that nothing divine took place without the body, and that the humanity in its activity partici- pated in the divine (Fragm. 1, 8). This connects itself with the principle laid down above, that not even divine activity ever became the property of the humanity, by the following link :—It participated in the divine at every moment solely in consequence ot communication of fellowship with the Logos. HIPPOLYTUS. 99 of blood, wherein the nations are washed and purified; and humanity forms, as it were, the bridal garment with which He is clothed.” The humanity which belongs to Him is the Church (c. 59), the parturient woman (c. 61). Out of her heart she will not cease to bring forth the Logos, who is persecuted in the world by unbelievers.” “She bears a Son,” we read further, “ who will feed all nations; to wit, ever bringing forth the man-child, the perfect Christ, the child of God (who is preached as God and man), the Church instructs all nations.” In this passage, Christ is described as the inmost essence, as it were, the heart of the humanity renewed by God, and the incarnation as a con- tinuous thing: and so we find him elsewhere not shrinking from the other view of Christ, as the sun with which the woman, the Church, is clothed, as with a garment. If the latter signifies that Christ, through his own person, wedded humanity with immortality, and that the Logos, descending into it from above, and encompassing it from without, transformed it, and set a perfect humanity before the Father in Himself (Theoph. 6, Fragm. on Ps. xxiv. 7, Fabr. 1, 2685 c. Beron'es)2 2000s). ue former, essentially connected as it is therewith, describes Him as the inmost vital principle and true substance of the humanity, as the principle of the birth of the divine-human life, which is ever continuing, and which diffuses itself through all nations. Theoph. c. 6,—“ Christ caused Himself to be baptized; and He renewed the old man, and entrusted to him again the sceptre of sonship. Immediately were the heavens opened above Him, for the visible and the invisible were reconciled ; the heavenly hosts were filled with joy; on earth all sicknesses were healed ; the mystery was revealed ; and enmity was turned to friend- ship.! Before His baptism, He stood like a bridegroom about to enter the heavenly bridal chamber, and the gates opened them- selves to Him and to the Holy Ghost, which hovered down- 1 Similarly c. Beron, Fragm. 2: The God of the universe became man, in order that, by suffering through suffering flesh, He might deliver our entire race from the death to which it was sold ; that, doing wonders by His impassible deity, He might lead men through the flesh to His immortal and blessed life, and might establish in immoveableness the holy ordinances of heavenly rational beings. The work of His capérwors was n TaY Cr@y es wirey cévansQarcelosic. (Similarly in de Chr. et. Antichr. 26.) The latter passage is like Origen :—The God of the universe became man iva re xan’ ? \ iA , ~ ~ y ~ , ‘ . , OUINVOUS YL THYLATH TOY YOSPUY OUTIMY OTOMGION TP0s atpebioy. 100 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. wards, and to the Father’s voice, ‘Thou art My beloved Son,’ which rang through the universe.” C. 2,—“ The Creator of the universe (the Son) descended like rain, and divided Himself like a stream, which is without limits, and rejoiced the city of God.” C. 7,—“ He who was called the Son of Joseph, was the Only- begotten One as to His divine essence , He hungered, who fed thousands; He was weary, who by His labours relieved the weary; He had not where to lay His head, and yet all things were in His hand; He suffered, and healed all by His suffer- ings; He suffered Himself to be beaten, and made the world free.” ©. 8,—‘ The immortal Logos came into the world in order to beget mortals again to immortality. When man be- comes immortal, he becomes also God. But if he becomes God by being born again of water and the Spirit, he will be also a fellow-heir with Christ after the resurrection.” These passages should suffice to show, that when he had to do with the prac- tical, and wished to set forth the glory of Christianity, Hippo- lytus was by no means chary in the use of terms which declare the existence of the most intimate vital union between the divine and the human in the Person of Christ, and through Him be- tween God and humanity in general,—expressions which stretch far beyond the strictly scientific results at which he arrived. The two are combined, in that he not seldom refers to the mys- tery which, after all inquiry, still encompasses the union of the divine essence with human nature. In his first two books against the Jews, Cyprian lays down the principal momenta of the idea of the Person of Christ, as far as they had become clear down to his day, with scriptural proofs, as follows:—The entire Scriptures refer to Christ, and He is the key to their understanding; not till we believe in Christ can we understand them. Then we see that the old covenant was destined to give place to a new one, circum- cision to baptism, the old temple to Christ, who is to be the house and temple of God, the old priesthood to the new eternal Priest (B.1). This Christ is the First-born and the Wisdom of God, through which all things were made (Prov. Vill. 1X7 j.; John xvii.); the Word of God (Sermo Dei, John i.); the arm and hand of God (Isa. |. lix.; Ps. xevii.). He is the Maleach Jehovah, the messenger of God, and God Kiumselt (Rom. ix. 5, where @eds, which Tertullian read, is not adducedy. CYPRIAN. | 101 But, besides being Son of God from the beginning, He must needs be born the second time in the flesh (cum a principio tfilius dei fuisset, generari denuo habebat secundum carnem); and the distinguishing feature of His birth (das Ausgezeichnete, signum) was to be His being born of a virgin, God and man, the Son of God and the Son of man at the same time (Num. xxiv.; Jer. xvil.; Isa. lxi.; Luke i. 35; 1 Cor. xv.), ex utroque genere concretus, ut mediator esse posset (2, 10). At His first advent, the Scriptures declared that He would be humbled and slain ; He is termed the Lamb of God, and was presignified in the paschal festival; Isaiah (lii.) and Jeremiah foretold His suffer- ings. But He became the precious stone laid in the foundations of Zion (Isa. lviii.), which shall grow to a mountain, to which all the heathen and the righteous shall come. He is the Bride- groom of the Church, which spiritually bears Him sons without number. For all power and might rest in His sufferings on the cross, and in the sign of the cross. This sign is redemption to all. After His death He was not to remain in the nether world, but to rise again on the third day (ab inferis). And then He received all power from the Father, and His might is ever- lasting (Dan. vii.; Apoc. i.; Matt. xxvill.). No one can come to the Father but by Him. He will come again as Judge, and be King eternally in His kingdom. All these titles, given to Christ, remind us of the ancient hymns, a specimen of which, from Clemens Alexandrinus, was given in the first volume (see page 182). At the same time, this collocation of Cyprian’s sets clearly before us the essential features of the Christological portion of the Apostles’ Creed. We will now subjoin a few passages, in which he not merely repeats passages of Scripture, but develops more carefully his own idea of Christ. We find, indeed, no precise scientific defini- tions; but still we gain a picture of that which Christ was to him. Special attention must be paid hereby to Cyprian’s doc- trine of the death of Christ and of the Eucharist. In his fifty- sixth letter (ed. Basil. 1558, Epp. L. 4, 6), he says,—* How can the servant be unwilling to suffer, when his Lord sutfered before him? how can he refuse to suffer for his sins, when He suffered for us, who knew no sin? The Son of God suffered in order to make us sons of God; and yet the children of men will not suffer in order to continue children of God.” In the 102 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. “De Idol. vanit.,” ed. c. Sep. 122 f., he says,—“ The Word and the Son of God, whom all the prophets proclaimed as the en- lightener and teacher of the human race, was sent as the steward of grace. He was the power of God—His reason, wisdom, glory ; He entered into the Virgin,—He, a holy spiritual being, clothed Himself in flesh.1. God constantly unites Himself with man (semper Deus cum homine miscetur). This our God, this Christ it was, who, as mediator between two, put on man, in order to lead him to the Father. What man is, Christ was resolved to be, in order that man might be what Christ is. The Jews also know of His advent :—but, it is true, only of His advent in glory. He must needs suffer, however, not that He might taste, but overcome death; and that, after the accomplish- ment of His sufferings, He might ascend up on high, to exhibit the power of the divine majesty, and to set the man whom He loved, whom He took upon Himself, whom He redeemed, as a victor on the throne, at the right hand of the Father. We follow Him as our guide, as the Prince of light and Saviour, who promises heaven and the Father to those who seek and believe. What Christ is, we Christians shall be, if we have followed Christ.” (Compare also Serm. 1, de Eleemos.) But especially does he regard Him as the revelation of pure love. In Sermo 3, “de bono patientiz,” we read,— We shall be- come perfect sons of the Father, if the long-suffering of God the Father abide in us, and if the divine image, lost in Adam, shines out of our actions. What a glory to belike God; what blessedness to have, in His virtue, something which is worthy of being compared with the divine! And this it is which Christ has not merely taught us by words, but fulfilled by deeds. As. He said regarding Himself, He descended to do the Father's will; and therefore, amongst the other marvels of virtue on which He stamped the seal of divine majesty, He proved the long- suffering of God by the patience which He manifested. De- scending from His heavenly glory to the earth, the Son of God did not count it a shame to take upon Himself the flesh of man, in order that, though Himself free from sin, He might bear the 1‘ Carne spiritus sanctus induitur.” See my remarks on the other read- ing—‘‘ (hic)—carnem spiritu sancto cooperante induitur,”—vol. i. page 391;—where also the necessary explanation is given of the expression ‘* Spiritus sanctus.” CYPRIAN. 103 sins of others. Laying aside for the time His immortality, He undertook even to be mortal, that He might die, the mnocent for the salvation of the guilty.’ Concerning the Eucharist, he says in the fifty-fourth Epistle (Ep. 2, 1. c.), that he who is ralled upon to shed his blood as a confessor, ought previously to partake of the cup of communion in the Church. In the sixty- third Letter (Ep. 3), after mentioning the prophecies iz the Old Testament relative to the Eucharist, and referring in particular Proverbs ix., where Wisdom is spoken of, which prepares her table and mingles her wine, to the Eucharist, as Hippolytus had done, he says, that “its blessing consists in the removal of all care, the awakening out of worldly sleep to the understanding of God, the forgetting of worldly conversation, the becoming drunk with divine wisdom, and the recovering from the intoxication of the world.’ Then he goes on to say (p. 89),—“ As Christ bore us all, nay, as He bore even our sins, so are we to regard the water which is mixed with the sacramental wine as the people, the wine as the blood of Christ. But as the water is mingled with the wine in the cup, even so is Christ adunated with His people (adunatur), and believers are married and united with Him, in whom they believe. This marriage and union of the water and the wine in the cup of the Lord is of such a nature, that it can no more be dissolved and broken up. For this reason, the Church, the people of the faithful and persevering, can no more be separated from Christ, but must ever remain firm in the em- brace of the divinelove. Wherefore, no wine without water, nor water without wine; even as Christ is not without us, nor we without Christ. When both commingle and interpenetrate as in marriage, the spiritual and heavenly sacrament is accom- plished. As, further, in the Eucharist many grains go to make the one bread, so is the people of Christians set before us as united: in Christ, the heavenly bread, we know ourselves to be one body, with which our race is connected and united. As an antagonist of the Monarchians, Origen was more tri- umphant than either Tertullian or Hippolytus, mainly from the importance of his own positive teachings, and not merely because of the arguments he adduced against them. As he not merely prought a section to a close, but was the starting-point of the 1 Compare the beautiful further treatment of the same subject, page LbosenGs 104 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. a new development and the new struggles, which took place «ll the Council of Nice, we shall, for this reason, accord him the special attention which he deserves. TRANSITION TO THE FURTHER DEVELOPMENT. ORIGEN. However different may have been the opinions entertained in all ages regarding the great Alexandrian Church teacher Origen, he cannot be denied the honour of having combined hearty love to the Church and its theology, with high scientific culture. He felt, asno one had felt before him, and as few have felt after him, the greatness and importance of the Trinitarian and Christological questions: with the candour of a noble and pure soul, he recognised the element of truth in preceding ten- dencies of the most different kind; and his richly endowed mind possessed resources and elasticity enough to overcome the difli- culties which he thus threw in his own way, to combine views apparently antagonistic, and to make them subserve the progress of the Church. He did justice to the truth in Ebionism, by asserting the completeness of the humanity of Christ, in a man- ner unlike that of any preceding teacher ; not contenting himself with the mere general recognition of the old canon in vogue even as early as the second century,—to wit, ‘it was necessary that Christ should assume the first-fruits of the whole of human nature, because He could only save that which He assumed,’— but assigning to each part of human nature an essential signifi- cance, relatively both to the purpose of redemption and to the possibility and reality of the incarnation. He allowed also the right of the other monarchian tendency, which denied to the higher nature of Christ any special hypostasis, in order to avoid the introduction of a schism into the divine nature, by endeavour- ing most carefully to preserve the unity of the Most High God. But he did this quite differently from Clemens Alexandrinus, who left the hypostasis of the Logos so far in the background, that he gave aid and countenance to Sabellianism. Origen, on the contrary, concurred with Tertullian and Novatian in the West, and with Hippolytus in the East, in asserting the particular hypostasis of the Son; his labours too in this direction bear a ORIGEN. 105 far more realistic stamp, and recognise more distinctly the basis of the faith of the Church. He made it his aim, so to connect the actual deity of the Son, conceived as a person, with the per- fect humanity of Christ, as neither to give a low representation of the Son of God, nor an unworthy (for example, ethnic or polytheistic) one of God, that neither the loftiness of the Son of God might curtail the full truth of the man Jesus, nor the completeness of the humanity infringe on the deity (de princip. L. 2, c. 6, cf. in Levit. hom. 13, 4). This endeavour to ex- hibit the truth held by the Church, as the force which holds together the scattered elements of truth contained in the various heresies, and to show that these different and partial momenta, each of which becomes an untruth as soon as it aims to be the whole, are organic, and, in their proper place, essential, parts of the fully developed system of Christian doctrine, reveals not merely the liberality and greatness, the comprehensive and syste- matic character, of his mind, but also the love which had enabled him, notwithstanding his varied culture, to strike his roots deeply into the doctrine of the Church, and to take it and its spirit as the regulative of his Christian gnosis, and the goal and soul of his efforts. All this is seen in his system on a grand scale; but. it ap- peared expressly also in the man. However many ideas of a questionable character, and needing continuous agitation and discussion, he may have thrown out; however many ideas he may have laid down, either tentatively or positively ; he never forgot—and herein consists his churchly character—the differ- ence between that which was certainly believed by the Church and his own theological speculations ; nor failed to demand un- conditional recognition for the latter, whilst content that the former should be simply examined and tested. It is such an equilibrium of the fixed and the alterable as this that renders progress possible in the Church. This he takes as his point of departure in the doctrinal work “de principiis” (§ 1), when ~ he remarks,—‘* All who believe in Christ are convinced that grace and truth were revealed through Him, and are to be found in the sacred books of the Old and New Testaments.” But he did not rest satisfied with this general recognition of the material and formal aspect of the Christian principle. For, though this very general norm was enough in itself to distin- 106 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. guish Christians from those who are not Christians, it was insufficient relatively to (heretical) divergencies within the Church itself; that is, it was insufficient relatively to such as, whilst professing to recognise, at the same time diverged so considerably on, essential points of doctrine as really to violate that fundamental principle, and to reduce their recognition thereof to a mere seeming. For this reason, he endeavoured to lay down a standard, and to draw a clear line separating the heretical from the orthodox. This plumb-line is, in his view, the “ecclesiastica preedicatio,” also designated by him “ eccle- siastica et apostolica traditio,” which had been uninterruptedly the common property of the Church, and had combined within itself the “elementa ac fundamenta” of Christian truth, its public and necessary principles. It may be regarded, indeed, as an imperfection, that he treats these “fundamenta,” that is, the Church’s rule of faith, rather as a distinct authority along- side of the first-mentioned principle, than as a necessary deve- lopment therefrom; but still he throws a clearer light on the common faith of the Church of his age, by setting specially before us the “ Regula Fidei” of the period, or the summary of the fundamental and essential doctrines of Christianity, as an objective authority. This “Summa Fidei,” agreeing substan- tially as it does with the “ Regula Fidei,” laid down by Nova- tian, Tertullian, and Irenzus,* teaches, in harmony with all the older formule, alongside of the unity of God, the deity of the Son; alongside of the pre-existence of the Son, His incarnation in the Virgin, and the essential features of His history—His sufferings, death, resurrection, ascension, and second coming to judgment. But whereas Irenzus, in his two “ Regule Fidei,” which are substantially identical with each other and with that laid down by Tertullian in his “de vel. virginum” 1, as also Novatian, rested satisfied with these most general elements, which had not yet been determinately distinguished from the baptismal formula and the Apostolic Creed (which had gra- dually grown out of the baptismal formula), and recognised 1 Compare Hahn’s ‘‘ Bibliothek der Symbole und Glaubensregeln der apostolisch-katholischen Kirche,” 1842, pp. 63-78; Iren. adv. Heres. 1, 10; 1, 3,4, 2; Tertull. de veland. virgin. 1; adv. Prax. 2; de preescr. her. 18; Novatian de Trin. c. 1, 9, 29; Cyprian’s ‘‘Ep. ad Magnum” and the ‘Libri adv. Jud.” ORIGEN. 107 as doctrinal—-we find, on the contrary, that the two other for- mul of Tertullian (see note), and that of Origen, were con- structed with a view not merely to give immediate expression to the faith of the Church, but also to set forth this faith in the form of dogma, as the summary of those fundamental doctrines which are the norm of all doctrine, and shut out that which is heretical. Even as it is, the arrangement was still mainly deter- mined by the baptismal formula of Matt. xxvii., and by the Apostolic Creed. The Regula Fidei also is trinitarian, and in its Christology specifies the chief momenta of the history of Christ. But that the doctrine of the Church was passing through a further development, we see plainly, when we find Tertullian placing alongside of the doctrine of the unity of God the “ceconomia,” by which that unity became a trinity ; or when he not merely mentions the “Filius Dei” in general, and more distinctly affirms the actuality of His incarnation, but also describes more particularly His relation to the Father : —WUnicum quidem Deum credimus, sub hac tamen dispen- satione, quam olxovouiay dicimus, ut unici Dei sit et Filius, sermo ipsius, qui ex ipso processerit, etc.” (adv. Prax. 2) 5— “Unum Deum esse, nec alium preter mundi conditorem, qui universa de nihilo produxerat per Verbum suum primo omnium emissum; id Verbum Filium ejus appellatum, in nomine Dei varie visum Patriarchis—postremo delatum ex Spiritu Patris Dei et virtute in virginem Mariam, carnem factum in utero ejus et ex ea natum egisse Jesum Christum etc.” (de prescr. her. 13).1 Origen lays down the “certa linea et manifesta regula,” which had formed the substance of the “ecclesiastica preedi- catio” in relation to the Son, from the days of the Apostles, and by which, therefore, he also aimed to be guided, in the following terms :—“ Species eorum, que per preedicationem apostolicam manifeste traduntur, istee sunt. Primo, quod unus Deus est.— Deinde, quia Jesus Christus, ipse qui venit, ante omnem crea- turam natus ex Patre est.2. Qui cum in omnium conditione 1 In adv. Prax. is subjoined :—‘ Hance regulam ab initio Evangelii de- cucurrisse, etiam ante priores quosque heereticos, nedum ante Praxeam hes- ternum, etc. ;” and in the ‘de preescr. heer.” (c. 12) the above is described as a rule to which the Church holds in order to guard its truth against the assaults of heretics. 2 That Origen had a good right to lay this down as the doctrine of the 108 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. Patri ministrasset (per ipsum enim omnia facta sunt), novissi- mis temporibus se ipsum exinaniens homo factus incarnatus est, cum Deus esset, et homo factus mansit quod erat, Deus. Corpus assumsit nostro corpori simile, eo solo differens, quod natum ex virgine et spiritu sancto est. Et quoniam hic Jesus Christus natus et passus est in veritate, et non per phantasiam communem hance mortem sustinint, vere mortuus, vere enim a mortuis resurrexit et assumtus est. Deinde honore ac digni- tate Patri ac Filio sociatum tradiderunt Spiritum sanctum.” That these words really express the collective, objective faith of the Church in his day, is clear,—if further evidence, besides his own testimony, which deserves perfect credit on the ground of his travels, his learning, and his honesty, be required,—from the abstinence, which induced him to leave his own doctrine of the generation of the Son and of the human soul of Christ en- tirely unnoticed, where his object was, not to set forth his own views, but the views held by the Church at large. But let us now pass on to the review of his own doctrine. Tertullian had distinguished between God in Himself, who is immoveable (in statu), and therefore without distinctions, and God in movement (in gradu); assigning the Trinity to the latter. But in this way the Son was not merely ethically, but also as to His essence and origin, interwoven with finitude, if not with time; in this way, further, he approximated too closely both to the Valentinian apoPodais (prolationibus) and to the very Theopaschitism which he himself combated under the form of Patripassianism. ‘The final result was the subordination of the Son to a degree which was incompatible with his own gene- ral view of the actual God, who had come near to us in Christ. Now, Origen denies every kind of physical emanation, of suffer- Ing, and of changeableness of God—not merely of the Father, Church from the days of the Apostles, and of the second century, even during that portion of it when the development of the doctrine of the Logos endangered the hypostasis and the pre-existence of the Son, is clear not only from what is advanced above, but also from the testimony of Celsus. To the period from the close of the first century until Athenagoras and lrenzeus, the words of Origen apply, after what we have demonstrated above, almost still more directly; for the hypostatic pre-existence of the Son was recognised as distinctly during the age of the Apostolic Fathers and Justin, as in the New Testament writings themselves. ORIGEN. 109 but also of the Son ;* though with no intention of thus laying hands on the ofcovouia. Herein we see the Alexandrian. His Trinity does not belong to the sphere of growth, not to that At the same time, it is to be remarked, that he does not regard the three hypostases as lifeless magni- tudes, existing alongside of each other, without motion or ac- tivity; but represents the Trinity as an eternal process in God. Clement’s doctrine of the Logos, who is co-eternal with God (in this respect, indeed, scarcely any longer hypostatical), on the one hand; and that of Tertullian and others, of the hypostatical Son, who is generated by a movement out of God Himself, on the other hand; he combines, by asserting in agreement with the latter, the procession of an hypostasis out of God Himself, and, in agreement with Clement, assigning that procession to eternity. And, indeed, consistency required this course to be adopted, if the Son, being divine as to His essence, were acknowledged to be identical with the eternal divine essence, and the divine were at the same time, with Hippolytus, defined to be unchangeable as to its essence. To this antagonism, therefore, to the patripassian conception of God; to the con- nection with Clement; and, finally, to the realistic doctrinal tradition of the Church, which had always tacitly assumed the divine aspect of the Son to be hypostatical, and which, since Tertullian, had been compelled to insist more strongly than 1 C. Cels. 4, 16. In Rom. vii. 13:—‘‘ Inseparabilis a patre est per naturam et immortalitatem.” C. Cels. 4, 5:—Key 6 Osos ray chav 7H EavTov duvamcs ouynatapalvn t® Inood sis tov tov advOpwmray Blov, nev o ey coxa mpos Tov Osov Advyos, Osdg nak autos dy, Eoxnt as Tpos nds, ox eSsdpoo yiverots, ovds xaTarsines THY SauToD Eopav. C. 14:—Mévav 77 ovale &tpertos cuynuta- Geives. The subject is @sés, with special reference to the Logos (compare c. 16).—6, 62 :—Ei 0’ dveyvaxes (Celsus, who charged Christians, because of their doctrine of the incarnation, with representing God as mutable) ra; Trav mpoPurav rAgEsis—ovd 0 autres ci (Ps. ci. 28; Heb. Vers. cil.)—éya sigs xal ovx rroiouwat (Mal. iii. 6), sopa dy, ors ovdsic nua Dror sivas “eT oBo- Any ev rH Oca, olr’ Epyw ovr’ éxivole. De Princip. 1, 2, 6:—‘ Observandum est, ne quis incurrat in illas absurdas fabulas eorum, qui prolationes quasdam sibi ipsis depingunt, ut divinam naturam in partes vocent, et Deum Patrem, quantum in se est dividant, eum hoc de incorporea natura vel leviter sus- picari non solum extreme impietatis sit, verum etiam ultimee insipientiz.” Compare § 10, 4, 28. 110 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. ever on this point,—we may be said to owe the rise, at the present juncture in the history of the Church, of that most important principle, the eternal generation of the Son. But, in conjunction with more external causes, we must not overlook the inner soul of the entire historical process, which, though, it is true, ever present, here more plainly manifested itself, as the leading impulse. This soul was the conviction which possessed the Christian world, that in Christ it had attained to unity, not with a middle being and secondary God, but with God Himself —an unity, the archetype of which is set before us in the incar- nation of Christ. This conviction,—call it mystical if we will; but whether mystical or not, it contained the kernel of Christi- anity,—never permitted the Church to regard the subordination of the Son as an end in itself, and as an independent dogma (as did Arianism). On the contrary, subordination was merely taught by the Church for a time; and during that time it was an auxiliary doctrine, whose object was to show that the truth in the general and ante-Christian conception of God, to wit, the divine unity, was not violated by the new conception of God set forth in Christianity. It must by no means, however, be regarded as indicative of a disposition to give up the elements which go to constitute the Christian trinitarian conception of God, and to reintroduce ante-Christian conceptions of God, as, for example, Arians, and on the whole Sabellians also, did (com- pare, for example, Tertull. adv. Prax. 13, 31). The work of transforming the ante-Christian conceptions of God, which the Church of the first centuries executed to the utmost of its ability, was greatly expedited by this proposition of Origen. The divine in Christ was removed into the eternal divine sphere, without therefore being represented asa mere power. Light cannot exist without giving light ; it is never without brightness: even so, the Father cannot be conceived without the Son. (Note 18.) There never was a time when the Son was not.' If it was a 1De princ. 1, 2, 2,4; Anaceph. § 28 (de princ. 4, 28); c. Celsum 8, 12; in Joann. T. i. 82; Fragm. ad Hebr. from the Apology of Pamphilus in dela Rue’s ed. iv. 697a, ad Rom. 1, 5. The expression gy dre ovx jy, which at a later period became a watchword, is frequently discussed by Origen in these passages, but most decidedly rejected by him. Compare Note 18; Hom. in Jerem. ix. 4; 6 owrnp quay coPia tort rod Ocod. “Ears 38 % c0Qia dravyacua Curds didiov. Ei ovy ¢ caryp adel yevvaras, etc. The ORIGEN. 111 good thing for God to have a Son, why should He not have had this good eternally,—why should He have robbed Himself of it? These thoughts, recurring as they do frequently in the works of Origen, show us that he was already on the point of stabilitating the position of the Son in the divine sphere, by representing Him as involved in the eternal idea of God Him- self (compare Anaceph. 4, 28). That Origen found it easier to give utterance to this eternity of the Son than others be- fore him had done, because of his doctrine that creation also should be conceived as eternal, and that God never was with- out dominion and omnipotence, ought not to be denied : but it 1s equally perverse to derive his doctrine of the eternity of the Son from it, or even to identify the two.' Against the co-ordination or identification of the Son and the world, speaks already, that though he represents the world as existing always, he at the same time, and for that very reason, leaves it within the limits of time and subject to change, whereas the Son exists eternally above it, as an hypostasis with the Father. The eternal wisdom, which eternally hypostatizes itself as the Son, contains within itself, it is true, the logical seeds of all things, the world in the form of a conception; but the generation of the Son was not eo ipso the position of the world as an actu- ality. Neither in His inner wisdom and reason, nor in the wisdom which eternally became hypostatical in the Son, had the Father an object of His omnipotence and dominion; but He first became almighty through the Son, who realized the idea of the world.’ It is thus put beyond all doubt, that Origen ex- fragment ad Hebr. runs as follows :—‘‘ Lux eterna quid aliud est senti- endum, quam Deus Pater, qui nunquam fuit, quando lux quidem esset, splendor vero ei non adesset ? Neque enim lux sine splendore suo unquam intelligi potest. Quod si verum est, nunquam est, quando Filius non Filius fuit—non erat quando non erat.” * As Baur does, in his altogether very free account of Origen’s system (pp. 208 ff.). Origen was certainly acquainted with the doctrine that the world is the son of God, which some seek to fasten on him asa speculative | ornament ; for his books against Celsus show this. But he gave it up as ethnic to Celsus, and despised such ornaments. ‘The truth he perceived it to contain, took the form in his mind, that the will, or the almighty love and the wisdom, of the Logos, are the constant medium through which the world is sustained. ? De prince. 1, 2, 10: ‘‘ Per Filium enim omnipotens est Pater.” EL? FIRST PERIOD SECOND EPOCH. alted the Son above the sphere of creatures (in Joh. T. xiii. 25) ; and that the eternity of the Son is one thing, and His so-called eternal creation of the successive worlds a Seally different thing. Hermogenes also taught that the world was eternal; but he did not, therefore, teach the eternal generation of the Son ;—on the contrary, by means of the former, he dispensed with the neces- sity of the latter.' Origen proceeds in a different manner, because he attached an independent significance to the eternity of the Son. It was not merely because of the world, that he needed and laid down the doctrine; in other words, his aim in teaching the eternal generation of the Son, was, not simply to be abled to conceive he creation of the world, which fell to the lot of the Son, as eternal. In general, the ground on which Origen claimed a Son, was not identical with that to which he traced back the existence of the world. A world exists because otherwise God would not be an almighty Ruler ; the Son exists because Light, to wit, the Father, cannot be without brightness. Yor this reason, he was easily able to show that his doctrine of the eternal creation of the world did not infringe on the dignity of the Son.? The correct view will therefore be the following : Not for the sake of the doctrine of the eternal creation of the world, did he posit the eternal generation of the Son; but his conception of God was such as to require that both world and Son, although the conception of each stood otherwise equally firm, should be eternally posited, though without. the violation of their logical relation; for, even on the supposition of the world’s being eternal, he still deemed it to remain a creature, whereas he did not intend to represent the Son as an object of omnipotence,—as a creature. God, namely, Origen supposes, must be recognised as mutable, as needing progress from a de- fective to a more perfect condition ; He would be deprived of His self-identity ; if on the one hand the Son were not His image, and on the other hand, if the world were not, through the creative Son, the object of His dominion. When, how- ever, we find Origen regarding it as an advantage for God to have not merely a world, but an eternal image of Himself, 1 As also Baur, p. 210, is unable to comprehend why Origen should posit an hypostatical Son alongside of an eternal world, it being in his view un- necessary. 4 De princip. 1, 2, 10 ORIGEN. 113 which the world cannot te (that image was rather destined to be the archetype of the world, and the world to be its copy), we must attribute it to the afore-mentioned Christian impulse, felt by the Church, to transform the conception of God, which had prevailed prior to the advent of Christ (Note 19). Had he been content with the ethnical idea of God, he would naturally have regarded the world as a satisfactory sub- stitute for that image, which he deemed a divine good. But he refuses to hear anything of a natural God-marhood of our race, in any other sense than that of a susceptibility to union with God. In reply to the observation of Celsus,—e? todro A€yels, OTL Tas avOpwros Kata Oetav Tpovotav yeyovws, vids eaTe Ocod, Ti dv od ddXov Siadépns (that is, thou agreest with us heathens),—he remarks (c. Celsum 1, 57),—“ Many indeed have pretended to be sons of God,—as, for example, Judas Gal., Theudas, Dositheus, Simon Magus; but their work perished, their school is extinguished. Christians, on the contrary, who are freed from fear, Paul calls indeed sons of God; but each of them 7roAA@ Kal paxpd Siahépes mavtds tod did Thy dperhv XpnwatiCovtos viod TOD Oeod, daTis @arepel THY Tis Kab dpyi) TOV ToLovTwY TUyydvel.” As he justly held physical participa- tion in the Logos to be something meagre, because immediate, and not truly spiritual or ethical, he was necessitated to assume for the world the existence of an ethical mediator, in order that it might really participate in divine life; and for God Himself, the existence of an eternal perfect image of His ethical perfection, such as the world could not be, and whose place it could not supply. For, even apart from sin, Origen held it to lie in the essence of a rational creature, that it should con- nect itself, by free efforts, with the ethical perfection of God; and as such a conjunction must be preceded by a process in time, it follows that, prior to the termination thereof, even if nothing else hindered, the world would not supply to God that absolute ethical image of Himself, which notwithstanding He ought eternally to possess. It must accordingly be con- ceded, that Origen’s doctrine of the eternal generation of the Son owed its origin, in the last instance, to the transformation of the conception of God brought about by the ethical appear- ance of Christ; although, as in all the great productions of the mind of man, other causes co-operated. These words of Origen VOL. II. H 114 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. gave expression to that which lay in the heart of the Church— to its inmost intent—to that pvotixi mapddocts of the Church, which existed, not as a formulated doctrine, but as an intuition of faith. That he had found the word which the Church had sought, and that he thus met its unconscious yearnings, is evi- dent from the results which followed on its utterance. The Church recognised it as its own; and whereas the other fruits of his labours were subjected to a criticism in many respects unjust, this determination immoveably held its ground. His doctrine of the eternity of creation, with much else, found no recognition ; it served merely the purpose of a ferment : his doctrine of the eternal generation of the Son, on the contrary, attained, through its own weight, the position of a corner stone in the doctrinal edifice of the Church,—it was applied even as a plummet to further doctrinal works, and became a standard for the judg- ment of other parts of Origen’s own system, which did not ap pear to harmonize with it. Origen, however, was not content simply to regard the generation of the Son as an eternal act, which, being accom- plished, was accomplished once for all. Tertullian, for example, still held it to be a single divine act, and naturally, therefore, treated it as a revelation, which had become an hypostasis, as a apoBory of God; and, consequently, either as an emanation or as dependent on the will of the Father (de prince. 4, 28). Such a view not merely involved the introduction of mutability into God, contrary to Origen’s conviction, but even the Son was not thereby brought into close connection with the divine essence. Ele would owe His existence to a single isolated, and not to an eternal, movement in God, essential to the very conception of the divine essence; for otherwise a single divine act would not have sufficed. Moreover, on the supposition that He originated in a single isolated act, the Son would be shut out too much from the essence and sphere of the Father; would be too inde- pendent, if it were meant to represent Him as God and not as creature; would be too far removed from the Father. Accord- ingly, we find Tertullian inclined to represent the Son as re- turning out of His independence into God at the close of the oixovojla; and then it is difficult to see how His distinction rom the Father can be preserved. Origen, on the contrary, in this connection also anxious to exclude both mutability and dead ” ORIGEN 115 torpor, teaches that in God there is an unchangeably active vitality ; in other words, that the generation of the Son is an eternally completed, and yet an eternally continued, act. On the ground of the same conception of God (which aimed at combining, in a higher form, the rigid Jewish and the mutable heathenish conceptions), he was able to describe the eternal creation of the world also as a continuous act: nor did he take a different view of the work of the Holy Spirit in believers.! The Son was not generated once for all, but is continuously generated by God in the eternal to-day.” He thus conceives the persons of the Trinity in most inti- mate union with each other. The Son is the stream, of which the Father is the source (in Joann. T. vi. 29). He employs both this old image and also that of light, which cannot but shine, not with the intention of favouring emanatistic ideas, but in order to set clearly forth the inseparable connection existing between Father and Son (dyépuotds éott Tod viod 6 matnp, in Matt. xiii. 19; contra Celsum 4, 14, 16; in Joann. TD. ii, 1, xix. 1: His @eorépa gious is Hvapuévyn 7h AYEVIATH Tov Tatpos ¢éce). Giving the former simile a different turn, he says (in Jerem. hom. 18, 9),—The three sources (of salva- tion) are Father, Son, and Spirit; whoso thirsts not for all three * Hom. in Jerem. ix. 4; de prince. 1, 2,2; Anaceph. § 28. In the first- mentioned passage he says:—Muxcpios 6 del yevvdmevos dad rod @sod. Ov yap amas t0u roy Oinatoy yeyevvijobas Urd Tov Osov, &AN cael yevver bar nob’ EXOTHY Tpaeiy ciryodiy, ev H yevue roy dinesoy 6 Osdc. This takes place also in the Redeemer, 67s ody! eyévynoey 6 rarip rév vidv, xl cardrvoey airey 6 Tarp dro rng yeveosws aitov, darn oel verve LUTOY—aTavyaoie THs 06en¢ ougs amas yeyevynros nol ovyl (1.€., ov 2s) yevvaeras &AN boov gor! ro Das TOMTILOY TO aTaVYydcomaArtos, ex! ToTOUTOY yevVaTal TO ar aUYy ao we THs O6eNs, tov ©cov. For this reason, also, it is said, xpd dé ravrav Bouvav yevvd us, nob yeyevunne mee, noel cel yevdiras 6 owrdp Ure rov waerpds. In Joann. T. i. 32: LaOas, 4 eiyivere weploreras tov viod, bre-ro vids mov el od, bya ohecooy YEYEVINKe Of, AévyeTas Tpos aUTdv UFO TOU Oeov, H al kort rd oreeepoy' odx evs yap tomipe Osov, sya Of nryodwas ors ovdd rpwla, AAN 6 cupewopextelyay TH cryevnty nol dlolo aired Can, iv obrac cixw, xpdvos qutow torly ceir@ onusoor, ty n ysyevuntos 6 ules’ dpxins yevivews airov obras oxy edpioxomsyns, ag ovds TIS NMEpas. * The German runs—-‘‘ Der Sohn ‘st nicht gezeugt, sondern wird gezeugt von Gott in dem ewigen Heute.” The distinction between “ist” and “wird” can scarcely here be rendered without paraphrase into English.— Tr. 116 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. cannot find God. The Jews thirst after the Father, but de- spise the Son, and therefore they have not the Father. Heretics desire the Son, but not the Father, who is the lawgiver ; or not the Spirit, who moved the prophets; and so they are without the Son and without the Father. On this ground he attributes all glory and all divine attributes, in common, to the Son and to the Father. That which is in God is in Christ Jesus (in Jerem. hom. viii. 2; mdvra yap, dca Tod Ocod, Tovadra ev avT@ éot ly’ o Xpiotos é€ote codla—bsivapis—sixatocvyn Tod Oeod, etc., in Joann. T. xx. 29, 30). When Celsus asked the Christian of the second century, Why do you honour a second God, in addition to the true one? Origen answered, He is one with God; and God, in generating Him, gave over all things into His hand (c. Cels. 8, 12, 18). Not alongside of, but in God, do_we worship the Son (ib. c. 12). In particular, the Son knows all that the Father knows, for the Son is the truth, and the truth is an indivisible whole ; if but one part failed, the entire know- ledge of the Son would be defective (in Joann. T. i. 27) ;—éav Sé tis Enh, ef wav oTimoTe eyvwopéevov itd To TaTpos—eTi- oTATAL 6 GWTIP HuaV, Kal pavtacia TOD Sokdfew Tov tatépa dropaivntal Twa ywooKopeva iro Tov maTpos ayvoeiabat to rod viod, émictatéov, aitov (because He is the arnOeva, and drnOeva is ONOKANpOS) OvSev aANDES ayvoet (Vv?) iva pn oKaty Nelrrovea % adijOeva ols od ywaoxet. Or let some one point me out an object of knowledge which is not included in, but lies out beyond, the domain of truth. ‘The case is the same relatively to the will. The Son is not merely the executor of the divine will, as though He worked outside of God, but the same will that is in the Father is an almighty and holy will in the Son. In short, the Father possesses in the Son an absolute image of Himself. “For no one, I believe, embraces the entire glory of the Father in Himself in copy, save the Son. He not only 1 In Joh. T. xiii. 36,—dare elvecs ro OeAnuce rod Ocod ev 7H Oernwors Tov vlov draparranroy TOV bcrnaros rov warpos cig TO enners elves OV0 DeAnMaTo, aan tv béanuwo. Hence Christ said, “‘I and the Father are one; ” there- fore, ‘‘He that hath seen the Son hath seen the Father also.” All the deeds of men are imperfect, but not those of the Son; He accomplishes the entire will of the Father, for ré d:Asiv rov Osod yevduevoy ev TH via rossi Tarra, amen Bovrcras TO beAnux Tov Osov’ wudvog 02 6 vidg wav 70 OeAnua moist xuphoces rod warpds’ Oirep ual slnay avrov. C. Cels. 8, 12; in Johann. T. xxxii. 18; compare Note 19. ORIGEN. 117 participates in wisdom, truth, reason, but is wisdom, truth, rea- son itself," and all the wise are wise through their participation in Him.” There can therefore be no doubt that Origen meant to attribute deity seriously, and not merely figuratively, to the Son. But as le maintained the eternity of the hypostasis of the Son so decidedly in opposition to the Monarchians,” he must needs consider how to reconcile the true element in the ante- Christian conception of God, to wit, the divine unity, with his Trinitarianism. We have seen already that he endeavoured to _ secure this unity by bringing the Son, through the doctrine of the eternal generation, into closer proximity to the essence of the Father; in other words, he effected an adjustment between the disparate elements of Tertullian’s system, with its temporal and almost mundane personality of the Son, on the one hand, and the eternity of His essence, on the other, by teaching that the generation or the personality of the Son was coeternal with the divine essence, and thus removing it out beyond the sphere of the world. In his view, both eternity and generation consti- tute the Father and the hypostasis (not merely the substance) of the Son, one essence. No less also the afore-mentioned common attributes of intelligence and volition, which can only appertain to an hypostasis. But precisely at the point at which enough seemed to have been done, a new danger arose. If Father and Son have absolutely everything in common, how are they distinguished the one from the other? Monarchianism 1 AdrocoDice, adroanrydesce, eiréroyos. C. Cels. 8,41; Exh. ad Martyr. A feoiny Ol... Lie * He speaks against them, for example, in Joh. T. ii. 2, 6, 18, x. 21; C. Cels. 4, 5, 8, 12; in Matt. xvii. 14 ;—Od vogsordov sivas deo airod rods Tae Pevdn Dpovovyras wepl eitov, Qavracie rov dokalew aitrov (Xpsordy)* dxoios ciotv of ovyxeovres marpos noel vied syvoscey, xl TH UmocTeaEs Eve O1OOUTES sivas TOY Tatepe nol Tov viev TH Exivole Ldn noel TOS dudmeceos OsceLpoDYTES TOY UTO- xelevov. On John ii. 2, see page 101. Still more explicitly in Joh. T. x. 21: they say wy dsecQépew re dpidud cov vidv rod warpds, &AW fy od pedvov ovgig hAAL nol Vroneievw tTuyxavovras duQotépovs nara tives trivoles Ola- Qoows ov xara varcorecw, rtysobn: rartpe xal vidv. The proof of their theory, drawn from the circumstance that the resurrection of Christ is now attributed to the Father and then to the Son, does not stand scrutiny ; for both were active, the Son through the Father. For the rest, it is necessary to oppose to them the passages which prove the distinction between the Father and the Son, amongst which he reckons those which speak in a lower way of the latter. 118 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. appears to him as objectionable as Polytheism; and therefore, not merely interest for the unity of God, but even for the Son’s own hypostasis, would seem to necessitate Origen to the adop- tion of determinations, fitted to secure both the one and the other. This is the origin of the peculiar form of Subordinatianism which we find in Origen’s system. He endeavoured to secure the unity of the essence of God, by means of the opposed prin- ciples of the equality and the subordination of the Son. The latter was intended to leave a place for an independent hypo- stasis of the Son; the former for His deity. Let us now submit this form of Subordinatianism to a more careful examination. Above all, we must here refer to his well- known distinction between Oeds and 6 Oeds (in Joann. il. 2, 3). The Son has, indeed, actual Oed7s; He is Beds, Erepos tv idt0- cta: but He is not originally 60s; the Father alone is the source of His deity... For this reason the Father alone-is adrd- Ocos; He alone is the péyiotos él aot Oeds (c. Cels. 8, 14) The conception which the Father has of Himself is greater than that which the Son has of Himself. But the knowledge of the Son is not thereby made imperfect. No one who, like Origen (in Joh. T. i. 27, see above), knows that truth constitutes an indivisible, organic whole, could style the Son adtocogia, avto- adjOeva, if he did not attribute to Him absolute knowledge of the Father ; and, indeed, otherwise He would not be the Father's per- fect image or mirror. His meaning rather was :—The Father has one self-consciousness, the Son another; the Father is the ulti- mate principle (a4py7), not the Son ; in His self-consciousness, therefore, the Son cannot, like the Father, appear to Himself as the Last, although, nay because, the Son really knows the Father as the final principle. The Father, therefore, is higher (xpeir- tov); He is both the first beginning and the final goal of all things. Although, therefore, the Son is the representative of the Father to those who are still to be saved, is their God, and, so to speak, their Father, as the goal at which they are preli- minarily to arrive, because He alone is the way to the Father ; and although it is accordingly natural enough for these to direct 1 In Joh.T. ii. 8,°6, 18, xili-'25; c. Cels. 85443; in Joh. T. 17S) aie Father alone is rn bedrnros : in so far, He alone is to be worshipped ; the Son and the Spirit are only to be worshipped in Him. ORIGEN, 119 their prayers to the Son, it should be otherwise with the re- deemed. Christ continues to be their Mediator; but they pray to the Father through the Son, not, however, to the Son Him- self.1 Still more: it is the duty of a mediator to bring men to the Father, who is the first and the last. Christ, therefore, does not keep Christians near Himself, because otherwise they would not attain to direct participation in the Highest; for the Father alone, and not the Son, is the Highest. Christians rise above the Son also to the Father, the pwovds or the évas (Note 20). Not that they become higher than the Son, or that the Son is lowered through the completion of His work; but His work itself would remain incomplete if He did not lead them out be- yond Himself to the final source and goal, even to the Father. Naturally, too; for if the Most High God is not also in Christ, if He be merely the leader to the goal, or a means, those who arrive at full age must go out beyond Him, and, what is more, through Him: the only question then is, whether He can, strictly speaking, be the Mediator, the personal mediation of God and man, if the absolute and final aim be not in Him also, as it is inthe Father. Origen himself often enough elsewhere treats Him as an end in Himself (for example, c. Cels. 6, 68) ; thus showing how far he was from considering the subordina- tion of the Son to be an end in itself, and that, on the con- trary, he intended thereby to show, on the one hand, that the Son had an hypostasis of His own, and, on the other hand, that the Most High God is in the last instance only One, to wit, the Father. But the passage in Joh. T. xii. 3 is specially fitted to unfold the real sense in which he used the above expressions. His intention was neither to give a Docetical account of Christ’s 1 Compare, respecting the knowledge of the Son, in Joh. T. i. 27; Anaceph. § 35. The apparent contradiction between these two passages Origen reconciled as follows :—The Son has true knowledge in its totality ; He knows the Father also truly. But His knowledge of the Most High God is never Being, as in the case of the Father. In so far as He knows that He Himself and His knowledge have their ground in the Father, His know- ledge is less perfect. For His knowledge of the Highest Being is never an immediate self-consciousness, but a mediate, reflective knowledge. Solely in this respect, however, is it less perfect. In every other respect higher knowledge is inconceivable (in Joh. T. xxxii. 17); His exaltation affected merely His humanity: 6 adyos, ¢v doxn wpds tov Osdy beds, ov ewidexeras Te vrepupobyvas (de prince. 1, 2, 10). 120 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. significance, as though all depended on the difference of the point of view; nor an Ebionitical, as though Christ could ever be surpassed : on the contrary, as the soul is dead, nay more, is nothing, without the Logos, even so the Church owes all that it has continually to Christ. It receives from Him, not merely the forgiveness of sin, but He is the any) Swtuxod ropatos ; so that the inner sense freely opens itself, and man attains to the highest of all, to the knowledge of the Father (7s dvavolas AD ropevns, Kal tayvota Svimtapévyns axohovws TH evKxwro ToUT@ voatTe HépovTos avTod, TOV GArecOar Kat TMHdGY ETL TO averepov (that is, probably, to the Father and the knowledge of Him) ést tv ai@vov Swnv). But if the divine unity is to be secured by the Father's being the Most High God, and not the Son; and if the former is, notwithstanding, one only, the hypostasis of the Son would seem to be entirely excluded from the sphere of the divine, and to be relegated to the sphere of the creature. How is it con- sistent therewith to represent the unity of God, notwithstanding the hypostasis of the Son, as secured by the fact of the Son having all that the Father hath?’ There appears here to be so glaring a contradiction in the system of Origen, that we can easily understand why, from of old, the most different opinions have been formed of it. In order to make him self-consistent, Maran has taken all pains, as far as possible, to deny the subor- dination; but his labour has been in vain. The orthodox oppo- nents of Origen, on the contrary, and his Arian friends, have left the other aspect of his system out of sight, and have inter- preted everything as much as possible in a subordinatian spirit. By recent writers the question has been put in the following form :—Does Origen derive the eternal generation of the Son from the essence, or from the will, of God? (Note 21.) It is true, that mode of securing for the Son at once equality of essence with, and at the same time hypostatical distinction from God, which consists in regarding Him as a “ portio” of the entire Deity, was not open to Origen. He justly persisted in maintaining that the category of part and whole is not ap- plicable to God; that God is an indivisible unity; that we can- not allow of a greater and aless in Him, because wherever He is 1 Compare the passages quoted page 115 f. ORIGEN. bat at all, He is entirely and indivisibly (de prince. 1, 1, 6:—“ Non ergo aut corpus aliquod aut in corpore esse putandus est Deus, sed intellectualis natura simplex, nihil omnino in se adjunctionis admittens; utine majus aliquid et inferius in se habere creda- tur, sed ut sit ex omni parte povds et ut ita dicam évds et mens ac fons, ex quo initium totius intellectualis naturze vel mentis est.” C. Cels. 1, 23 ;—@Ocds od5€ pépos, ov5é Oro», érret TO OAOV €x pepav éotw. Compare c. 21, 4; 14, 6, 62). Accordingly, one may fairly say, that Origen’s conception of God was such as to render it difficult for him to recognise the presence of the divine essence in the second hypostasis. In his eyes, as in Ter- tullian’s, the Father is originally the entire Deity ; nay more, not merely originally, but permanently: and He cannot constitute a part of Himself, His Son. There appears, therefore, to be no place for the Son save that of a creature. The case, how- ever, does not stand thus. Instead_of resorting to a quanti- tative division (through which the Father, who is originally the entire God, constitutes Himself one portion, another portion the Son, and a third the Spirit; on which supposition the Son, strictly speaking, would not have what the Father has, and either the nature of the Father would be changed, or, if He still continued to be the whole even after the generation of the Son, the hypostasis of the Son would be continually endan- gered), Origen adopts a different view of the mode of exist- ence of the divine as a whole. This is one of the most impor- tant and luminous features of Origen’s system. He saw that finite things are characterized by a certain exclusiveness: he who makes something external his property, by that act with- draws it from others; and so far as another is in possession, I am not in possession. But in the sphere of the spiritual and divine the case is otherwise. The art or science of any man is not lessened by its being in the possession of others ; and as it is with wisdom, so is it also with goodness, with ethical perfection. They are indivisible, it is true, in the sense that no one can truly possess any portion thereof without possessing the principle of the whole; but this does not imply that only one individual can pos- sess them. On the contrary, their nature is, to be principially* 1 T shall occasionally take the liberty of rendering the German word principiell (adj.) by the fresh-coined English adjective principial, instead of by the phrase ‘‘in principle,” ‘‘ as to principle.” —TR. | wy"4 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. indivisible and yet communicable; that is, they can be entirely possessed by more than one subject at the same time. Applied to the case before us, this means,—Though he held a division of God to be impossible, he did not consider a duplication— “dus positicnes” (Lev. hom. 13, 14)—or even a_multiplica- tion of the divine perfections, that is, their existence in. several hypostases, to be impossible. (De prine. 1, 1, 9 :—“ Intelligenda est ergo virtus Dei, qua viget, qua omnia visibilia et invisibilia vel continet vel gubernat, etc. Hujus ergo totius virtutis tantas et tam immensse vapor et ut ita dicam vigor ipse in propria sub stantia effectus, quamvis ex ipsa virtute velut voluntas e mente procedat, tamen et ipsa voluntas Dei nihilominus Dei virtus efficitur. Efficitur ergo virtus altera in sud proprietate altera in sud proprietate subsistens,—vapor quidam prime et ingenite virtutis Dei, hoc quidem, quod est, inde trahens, non est autem, quando non fuerit.”) He is thus able to attribute the entire fulness of the deity, and not merely one part thereof, to the Son, and consequently brings out more completely that inner or intensive equality of the Son with the Father, which Tertullian also aimed at when he asserted that the entire sun is in the ray. Tertullian, however, did not succeed like Origen; for in single passages, he described the distinction between the Father and the Son as a distinction between whole and part; in other, and these more standard, passages, however, it is true, he represents the entire divine essence as fixed under a determinate “ forma, species, modulus,” though the genesis and being of these forme are directly interwoven with the world and history. But this new idea of a duplication, or multiplication, of the fulness of the deity in several hypostases, brought also new difficulties. There appears to be a danger of putting the world on a level with the Son, inasmuch as the world also is susceptible of spiritual, ethi- cal perfections, which may be termed divine. And as Origen’s wish was to assign to the Son a distinctive position, which the world cannot share with Him, all depends on finding a_principle of-limitation. Such a limitation is set forth in his remarks “ in Joh. T. xxxii. 18.” It was not fitting that the Father should lack the good of having a perfect image of Himself; butit was only possible for one, not for many, fully to reflect the perfect glory of the Father in an image, and He who was_this full re- flection was the Son. The Son, moreover, is the medium through ORIGEN. Ie: which the divine essence 1s communicated to all who participate therein. The indivisible unity and unchangeableness of God do: not admit of the multiplicity and mutability of the world, being directly grounded in Him, that is, in the Father." Equally im- possible is it to conceive the world as existing independently, or as an atomistic multiplicity without unity. For this reason, the Son is the middle between God andthe world ;—in Him is, (1.) the idea of the world, or its eternal ideal unity; (2.) the principle of the actual hic —not, indeed, of an Pharite mul- tiplicity of objects, but still en ang tives multiplication of freedom in many subjects, completely resembling each other. Therewith is given the possibility of an infinitely manifold world; freedom hypostatized in countless Egos is its real po- tence. (3.) And lastly, when the individual beings, through their freedom, diverge infinitely from each other, the Word, or the Logos, continues to be their common, connecting principle. He is the substance which runs through the whole world, its heart or reason, present alike in every man and in the entire world. The Son is the truth, the life, the resurrection of the creatures , He is the One, who lies at the basis of their manifoldness, how- ever numerous may be His names, and various the modes in which He is regarded.? And however far freedom may go astray, however wide a field of action may be allowed it, as rational it is indissolubly connected with the Logos, who con- stantly manifests and maintains Himself, as the overarching (iibergreifend), omnipresent, and all-dominating power, in the development of the world. What we have adduced, shows that he considered the Logos to be the only perfect divine image, the archetype of the world, and the real ground of its being, of its continuance, and of its participation in the divine, in rationality, and in goodness. The Holy Spirit is, at the utmost, the only other being whom Origen would put on the same level as the Son: this latter doctrine, however, was but little developed by him. Relatively to the 1 Ritter 1. c. 294 :—‘‘ He could not hesitate to maintain that God must not be conceived as the ground of a multiplicity of mutable things; for the ground of a multiplicity is itself a multiplicity of grounds, and the ground of a change is grounded after a mutable manner.” 2 In Joann. i. 22; hom. in Jerem. 8, 2; de princ. 4, 28 (compare the painstaking work of Thomasius on Origen, p. 130). 124 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. world and revelation, Origen is unable to find expressions strong enough to glorify and exalt the Son, the First-born of creation, above all creatures, on the one hand; and profoundly to subor- dinate them to Him, on the other. And so certainly as he not merely recognised man’s need of being united with the Most High God, but believed also that Christ alone met that need; even so certainly must the Son be the vehicle and communicator of veritably divine nature (de prince. 1, 2, 4, 6 ;—the likeness borne by the Son contains “nature et substantiz Patris et Fili unitatem.” In Levit. hom. 13, 4; in Num. 12, 1). When Origen has in view the Most High God and His unity, he seems to lay down contradictory principles, and com- pletely to forget what he had previously taught; but it only needs a deeper consideration of his conception of God, to free him from a reproach so unworthy of a systematical theologian, and to show that, and why, it was no contradiction for him, on the one hand, to attribute an equal divine essence to the Son; and, on the other hand, to subordinate Him so decidedly to the Father, as even to allow himself the use of an expression such as—The Son, as to His ove/a, is other than the Father.’ He regards the Father, as the évas or ovds in absolute indi- visibility and wholeness, infinitely exalted above all that is mul- tifold and divided. Properly speaking, He is not truth and wisdom, spirit and reason, but infinitely higher than all these, out beyond being and_substance (ovc/a).? In short, He is the utterly unutterable, incomprehensible One, or the Absolute. All truth, goodness, power, is derived from Him; but He is not adequately described by all these names. He is the Father of wisdom and of all good; but will, reason, wisdom, cannot, strictly speaking, be attributed to Him without an admixture of _sensuous impurity. The Father alone can be this one, supra-substantial being. Tf, however, we wish catachrestically to apply to Him the ex- 1 De orat. c. 15. The Son is érepos rod werpos xar ovolav and xad txdoreow. Thismay signify (compare in Joh. T.i. 23, p. 26),—In abiding objective reality, not merely momentary being or subjective seeming. (The more precise definition of this objective being different from the Father, is his id/a odoies weorypey, here termed dxdoreos. But even so, the Son con- tinues subordinated.) 2 ©. Cels. 7, 38,—éxréxesve vou xal ovcias; de princ. 1, 1, 6; see above; in Joh. ii. 18, xiii. 21, 23. ORIGEN. 125: pression ovcia, then we must say that the essence of the Father is other than that of the Son. For the supra-essential as such cannot communicate itself, because it would thus renounce its abstract unity, simplicity. The Son is not supra-substantial, supra-essential (tiberseyend, tiberwesentlich), but is through and through évépyea: the Father is the primary principle, in Him self purely ideal, shut up in Himself. Though the Son is the Father’s perfect image, and has coeternally attracted to Himself all divine perfections.(c. Cels. 8, 14), that in which these per- fections inhere, which is their vehicle, can never become His: the Father alone remains the primal causality. When the Son makes Himself the object of reflection, He cannot regard Him- self as the original, as the primal apy7); otherwise He would be the Father, and not the Father’s image, to which the Father must hold the relation of archetype. The Son may, indeed, be the archetype of the world, and thus imitate, in the lower sphere, the relation subsisting between the Father and Himself ; but He can never Himself be the absolute archetype. Hence Origen was compelled to say, that the Son, in this respect, could not be compared with the Father; that the primal cause could only be one. This is the explanation of the comparison frequently made by him,—The Father is exalted above the Son, as the Son is above the world. Specially significant in this connection is the remark adduced above,—The self-consciousness of the Father is higher than that of the Son. For it implies, that the Father by no means beholds Himself in the Son, but that the self-consciousness of each is distinct. In the Son, the Father does not recognise Himself, but a derived being; and His knowledge of Himself is perfect independently of the Son. The duplication of which we spoke above is not a complete self- objectification of God ;—not only because the Son is merely the reflex, the image, in which, though the Father represents Him- self, His knowledge of Himself is not supposed to depend on, or to be mediated by, the Son; but 7 is merely the fulness of the deity, the divine do€a that is duplicated. Light cannot do otherwise than shine, the living God cannot do otherwise than reveal.._Himself_in_an_ objective, adequate image; but still the Father abides ever in the ground, and the ground does not come forth in His revelation. The Father does, however, completely embody His fulness and glory in the image of Himself. 126 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. This will enable us to understand why, and how far, Origen subordinated the Son. He had no intention whatever of deny- ing to Him the fulness of veritable divine powers, that is, divine essence ;! but he did not consider Him to be the primary ground. In the Son, therefore, is indeed the entire fulness of God—He proceeded forth from the divine essence : but He is God ina derived sense; the Father alone is the eternal ground of His being, and therefore also of the duplication of the divine power, goodness and wisdom, which exists in Him. From this we see clearly, that Origen approximated pretty nearly to principles laid down by the teachers of the Church many centuries after his time. For when they represented the Father,—as substan- tially they always did,—as the Monas, and not merely as a mem- ber of the Trinity, but as the whole, as the pita maons OeornTO0s, it is identical with Origen’s designation of the Father, as the sole any) waons Oeorntos, and the Son as the wnyn Ocornros for the world2 In fact, all that Origen meant in teaching the subor- dination of the Son, was to preserve strictly to God the original causal relation referred to above. So far from the Son’s co- essentiality with God being thus excluded, such an equality of essence is required, when the causal relation appears in its abso- lute perfection as in the case of the Word, the perfect image of God. And, on the other hand, this equality of essence, if we limit it, with Origen, to the possession by the image of the fulness of divine perfections, does not exclude the subordination involved in the image being, not the original, but that which is grounded. On the contrary, this image, as being the most per- fect possible effect, directs attention very surely to the most perfect possible cause, and in so far leads us out beyond itself. 1 De prince. 1, 2, 4:—He is Son, not by adoption, but by nature. Com- pare the fragment from Pamphilus in de la Rue’s Ed. vol. iv. 99. He can- not change to a less perfect condition, nor be exalted to a more perfect, ib. § 10, and in Joh. T. xxxii. 17; in Lev. hom. 13, 4: there is one will and one substance in the Father and the Son, but there are two “‘ positiones,” two distinct persons.—In the fragment of Pamphil. ad Hebr. (de la Rue, iv. 697b) it is said, after Sapientia vii. 25 :—‘* Vapor est (filius) virtutis Dei et aporrhcea glorie Omnipotentis purissima.” As the * vapor de substantia aliqua corporea procedit, sic etiam ipse ut quidam vapor exoritur de virtute ipsius Dei. Sic et Sapientia ex eo procedens ex ipsa Dei substantia gene- ratur.” 2 See note 1, page 117. ORIGEN. 127 But notwithstanding His subordination, the Son belongs as truly to the divine sphere, or the divine being, as brightness does to light. We may regard it, therefore, as proved, that in the system of Origen these two aspects do not contradict each other, that neither the one nor the other can be put aside, because both are equally:rooted in his conception of God, and both are necessary to its full expression. He knows God as the living God, re- vealed in Christ, and communicating His divine, above all, His spiritual nature, His wisdom and ethical perfection. But, on the other hand, he refuses to allow that the divine ground passes entirely over into that which is grounded; for such an admis- sion would have led him back to Patripassianism, which he had rejected, or to a kind of Pantheism. For this reason, he distin- cuishes between the communicable and the incommunicable in God, terming both, however, divine essence. The incommunica- ble in God, which he imagines to be the highest portion of the divine nature, is His primary, superessential, self-occluded being; the communicable is the fulness of His perfections, especially His spiritual essence. For it must be remembered, that, for example, moral unity with God is not, in his view, a mere ex- ternal relation of resemblance, but implies a_real participation in the ethical essence of God: so also as respects wisdom. Hence, when he attributes to the Son likeness, nay more, identity (ravrorns), of will with the Father, it means far more than is commonly supposed. The incommunicable the Father cannot communicate even to the Son; but, more closely examined, this reduces itself entirely to the momentum of grounding (Begriin- den), to the fact, that the Father is the primal apy7), the Abso- lute. Inthe communicable, the world participates solely through the Son, in whom all of the divine that can be communicated has assumed an hypostatic form. We can understand, there- fore, how he could say, at one time, that the Son, as the divine image, the unity of the nature or substance of the Father and of the Son, was set forth (de prince. 1, 2, 6); or (as in Joann. T. x. 21) could allow that Father and Son are one év ovaig, but not TO UroKxeévp or TH Urootdce (compare Selecta in Ps. 1 The Son is the expression of the entire will of the Father Himself, embodied in a person. Anac. § 28; in Joh. T. xiii. 36; c. Cels. 8, 12; de pring. 1, 2, 6: and the fragment from Pamphilus in de la Rue, iv. 99. 128 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. exxxv. and note p. 125); and yet, at another time, say, The Son is not one with the Father as to substance. ‘The former, when his attention was directed to the essence of the Son, which is derived from the Father, as a stream from its source, as a light from light; which is an outflow of the divine essence. ‘The latter, when his eye was fixed on the essence of the Father, and that which distinguishes Him from the Son. If, for example, he regarded the momentum of grounding, as that which distin- guishes the Father from the Son, or saw in the dpy7 the essence of the Father (as he perhaps does once, catachrestically; see de orat. 15, and note 2 p. 123), he could scarcely avoid maintaining, that, in this respect, the Son cannot in any sense be put on a level with the Father. In the same manner, also, he says regarding the world, that it is of a different essence from the Son, in so far as it is in no respect the ground of His existence." We can now also more definitely answer the question, whether Origen con- ceived the Son to have been posited by the will of the Father, as the world was posited by the will of the Son; or whether the relation between Father and Son was in this respect a more essential one. It was impossible for Origen, when he spoke with precision, to say, that the Son was posited by the simple will of the Father; for he did not allow that either the will, or any other aspect of the simple essence of God, could undertake anything in parti- cular by itself. It is true, the ground of the will, as of all the rest, is the supra-substantial Father; but the will itself be- longs to the évépyeva of the divine essence, to the fulness of its d0£a, which is hypostatized in the Son. For this reason, he could not properly say either of the wisdom or of the will, the power, the holiness of God,—The Son was posited by the Father’s will or wisdom; he must rather say,—The Son is out of the will of the Father, or He is the expressed will andwisdom 1 We need not resort even to this expedient relatively to the passage adduced by Baur, in Joh. T. xx. 16. For his protestation here against the generation from the essence of the Father does not refer to the eternal gene- ration of the Son, as a glance at the passage will show, but to the incarna- tion; and his opponents were suchas Beron. Baur might more easily have made use of in Joh. T. ii. 18, dséornxs rH odolge 6 raryp Tov viov, because, whereas the Father is light itself, the Son is the light in the darkness. But this passage also is cleared up by the remarks made above. Compare note 1, page 1384. ORIGEN. 129 of the Father. His doctrine of the eternity of the Son would thus be explained and established from a new point of view. And in point of fact this was his opinion. He styles the Son the Soul of God the Father,’ that is, the principle of actuality, the €vépyeva. Nay more, he frequently describes the Son in His relation to the Father, who is, it is true, the first principle, though by Himself He dwells in pure ideality, as the “ voluntas ex Patre (mente) procedens.” In Origen’s view, there existed in God no actual will prior to the Son; the Son Himself was first this will. If, then, the Son is not posited by the will of the Father, but is Himself the existence of that entire divine fulness Kat évépyevav, which is in the Father in the form of principle, a fresh proof is given that the mode in which Origen conceives Him connected with the will of the Father, instead of robbing Him of His divine essence, as many fancy, ensures it to Him afresh. Nor is the world, like the Son, the divine will; but is posited by the will of the Father, that is, by the Son. The world was the object of the divine omnipotence and predestina- tion, but not the Son (ad Rom. i. 5); for, on the contrary, as we have seen, the Father is first almighty through the Son. It is also further clear, that Origen could not at all shrink from the use of emanatistic expressions, although he endea- voured to rid them of their sensuous, temporal elements. The Son is not, like the world, a work and creature of the paternal will, but the ethical and intellectual emanation of God, the re- flection of the Father’s glory, which can no more be lacking than brightness to light. He is, therefore, eternally equal with the Father, and necessarily involved in His essence, though He, the hypostatical image, is not the originating principle of His own existence, but the Father who logically precedes all evépyeca (Note 22). From this, it is evident that Origen already ap- proximated to the doctrine of an immanent relation between Father and Son. The Son is the form and image of God, eter- nally assuming an independent existence (uopd1) Ocov; see note 1 p.127); the hypostatical realization of His fulness (8d£a) ; so far is He from being related to the Father, as something merely posited, that He eternally draws into Himself (in Joh. T. ii. 2- c. Cels. 8, 14), and exhibits, the deity of the Father. But the 1 De prine. 2, 8, 4, 5. VOD ILI. I 130 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. existence of the Son presupposes, of course, not merely His having been once for all generated and grounded by the Father, but also that He continues to be united with the Father, and to behold the depths of the divine being (without which He would not be God’s image). Separated from the Father, the Son could no longer be God (in Joh. T. ii. 2). Again, the Father is not merely the inner substance, the material or content which acquires shape in the Son, but remains something for and in Himself; for, though the generation of the image is a duplica- tion of God’s mode of existence, it is not a mere transformation of the archetype into the image. Such a transformation would be annihilation. The Father is, in his view, not simply divine iAn, but a self-contemplative subject, who passes over into the Son with the fulness of His essence, but not as the primary ground (8400s). Origen did not regard the Father as identical with the void Neo-Platonic *Ov, the mere arespov ;' but as the most positive of all beings, as the highest, unmixed unity, with- out any distinction, neither blind nor motionless, but knowing and contemplating Himself (in Joh. xxxii. 18), eternally gene- rating the Son, who is the causative principle of the many, and the connective principle of the manifold. Leaving aside for the time, the question, whether this con- ception of God, which involves the apparently contradictory determinations laid down by Origen, be a sufficient one or not, let us consider the relation of the Son to the world. He stands to the world in a more direct relation than the Father. As we have seen, He is the truth and the soul of the world ; in Him is all true reality, for only the rational can be said to have true reality.2, Through Him, therefore, the true spiritual substance of the universe, the world, this infinite Cov, is an organism ; He is the 7yewovexov, the reason in every soul. This substantial relation of the Son to the world, embraces not merely men, but also angels—nay, the whole universe, which can only have true reality so far as it also participates in spirituality, in 1 Whether in other respects he was quite free from the abstract "Ov, we shall see further on. 2 We must understand it in Origen’s sense, when he assigns to the Son the kingdom of the rational. As rational, the world belongs to Him ; to the Father, so far as it points to a first cause. Compare Huet, * Ori- peniana” |. c. 185. ORIGEN. Wo the Logos. At first sight, this wears the look of Pantheism. But he attributes to the world a relatively independent existence, as is clear from the one circumstance, of his representing free dom as the principle which posits the multiplicity of objects. The Son, therefore, does not continue alone possessed of being, but brings into existence an infinite number of subjects, of Egos, all alike free relatively to each other, and essentially connected, in common, with Him. No less again is the Son related in various ways to the different beings ;—which cannot be said regarding the Father. Nor is it a mere result of our mode of apprehen- sion, that one and the same Logos wears a different appear- ance to each different class, or each separate subject; but He in Himself is related to the many, He has objectively different modes of existence for different beings, without therefore ceas- ing to be the one Logos.’ With all rational creatures, whatever paths they may take in the exercise of their freedom, He is present: He is wedded indissolubly to men as to angels, to Christ as to Paul. This he deduces even from the omnipresence of the Logos ;” but He is different in different beings. ‘To this may perhaps be referred the thought, which repeatedly occurs :— What Paul says regarding himself, that he had become all things to all men, has held true in a much more divine manner of the Logos in all ages, for He became an angel to angels, and amantomen. Origen, however, by no means rests satisfied with this natural participation in the Logos. Even the last- mentioned thought implicitly attributes to the Logos a new form of existence, besides the immanent one in subjects. This is His objective appearance alongside of His creatures, particu- larly men. In His goodness and loving-kindness, He shows Himself to every one, according to his ability to apprehend Him. These differences of form also are not mere subjective seeming ; but He appears objectively in the forms which are necessary for 1 De prince. i. 1, 68; in Joh. T. i. 22; c. Cels. 4, 16 ;—Eilai yep de Qopos olovsl tov Adrvyou opQal, xabac éxaotw Tay sig ExsoTHeny adrvyomsvav Dalveras C Adyos, advacroyoy rH Eset TOD siceryomevov, em’ CAltyoy TpoxdwToVTOS 4 ETI xasiov. Christ is objectively all dya@aduol up to the Holiest of all; He unites in Himself all the stages, all the momenta of truth: and to each one He gives to see that of Himself, for which he has an eye. 2 Ana. § 29. Although He is omnipresent, He is not ‘‘ similiter in uni- versis. Plenius enim et clarius et ut ita dicam apertius in Archangelis est, quam in aliis sanctis viris, ete.” 132 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. His rational creatures; and though these forms are inadequate to, or even partially conceal, Him, and in so far may be de- scribed as a mere seeming, they nevertheless serve the purpose of bringing Him objectively near to men. This is the self- abet antl to which the Logos consented, concealing so much of His divine brightness as men were unable to bear, and ob- jectively revealing and setting before men so much as sufficed to enable them to rise by its means to the vision of His higher form, of his deity (zponyoupévn pices, wopdn). For our purpose, however, Origen’s doctrine of the conde- scension of the Logos to men, who occupy perhaps the lowest position in the ranks of the’classes of rational beings,’ is of the greatest importance. As is well known, Origen considered the human race to consist of souls, which, during their pre-existence, fell away from the Logos, through sin: the consequence of this apostasy was, that the lower powers of the yruy7 broke loose from their unity with the zrvedua (that is, the Logos), and made them- selves falsely independent of the Logos, in whom alone it was possible for thera to occupy their true position—the position, to wit, of integrant, but still subordinate, momenta of the true soeeatites ah are fired as it were by the mvedua. In_con- sequence of this their first fall, men walk in bodies, forgetful of their origin, forgetful of at Logos. But the rete could not forget them; and in order to remind them of Himself, the only true good, in order to enable them to approach Ean, He assumed the a of man, in the state to which sin had reduced it—He took upon Himself a mortal body—He lived a truly human life, though without sin—He delivered men from the curse of sin and death, partly by doctrine and example, but mainly by His death—and He perfectly re-established the union of souls with Himself, and, through Himself, with the Father (in Joh. T. 1. 23-29). At this point, however, we must halt and ask :—How far ‘ These classes he represents, however, not as different races, but as stages within one and the same race of rational beings. Here also bea is led by the thought, that reason is one, like truth. Hence he believed that the more perfect men become angels, even as, under the impulse of love, angels may become men. The essential feature of all is, not the body, but the spirit ; and the spirit is of the same nature, essentially alike in all, though they may occupy different stages. ORIGEN. 133 did the Logos participate in the incarnation? Did He really enter into fellowship with mutable, suffering men? Both the idea of the incarnation and His work, which len not merely in teaching, but in divine-human desde and sufferings, required that He should do so. His union with Christ must have been different from His union with men generally ; the history of the man Christ, must in a certain sense have been His own histor Vy. Otherwise, the incarnation would have been really nothing new ; naeeanth as the Logos was previously everywhere present. The new feature would bei mere subjective seeming, if the Logos had not entered into a relation to this man, which had objective significance for Himself. But if the history of this man were in any sense the history of the Logos, the danger to which Patri- passianism succumbed again reappears. In that case, it might appear advisable to adopt the expedient of saying,—The esos remained, even in Christ, unchangeably what He had been Petal and nitkgance lle Then, however, His appearance was a mere theophany, not an incarnation; the new element was at the utmost an act of manifestation, oi a being and living of the Logos, in new unity with artes Origen felt the difficulties attending both courses. In the Anaceph. (§ 30 f. p.191), he lays down the principle,—that two errors are to be avoided : firstly, that of keeping this divine ele- ment entirely or partially outside of Christ; secondly, the oppo- site error, of conceiving the deity so shut in by the humanity, as to be itself restricted and made finite through the limits of the body, deprived of its universality, rent asunder from the Father, and subjected to change and suffering.! In the solution of this problem, he was aided to some extent by the spiritual concep- tion he had formed of the divine. As the divine cannot be divided, nor enclosed in space, but remains everywhere entire and sitasttical with itself, no danger can be involved in saying even that the entire ‘bts of the Son was in Christ. nese 1 L. c.: Nonita sentiendum est, quod omnis divinitatis ejus majestas intra brevissimi corporis claustra conclusa est, ita ut omne Verbum Dei et saplentia ejus ac substantialis veritas ac vita vel a Patre divulsa sit, vel intra corporis ejus coercita et conscripta brevitatem, nec usquam preeterea putetur operata. The two dangers to be avoided are rather—ut neque aliquid divinitatis in Christo defuisse credatur, et nulla penitus a paterna substantia, quee ubique est, facta esse putetur divisio. 134 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. who suppose that a true incarnation would have been an un- worthy coarctation of the Son of God within the limits of the body, and who therefore maintain that merely a part of the deity of the Son dwelt in Christ, whilst the other part was elsewhere or everywhere, do not understand the nature of an incorporeal and invisible substance ; they fear that if it entered fully into the humanity of Christ, it would entirely lose its infinitude, and yet, by their division, they make it a corporeal and finite thing. But should it even be premised, that no danger to the deity of Christ is involved in the supposition of its dwelling undividedly in His humanity, nothing more is thereby done than to show the general possibility of a punctual (punktuell) presence of the Logos, the possibility of His dwelling entirely and fully in the humanity of Christ, without either an Ebionitical attenuation of the divine, or a Docetical dissipation of the human. That such a presence, however, was not an incarnation, was not in reality more than a theophany, Origen must have felt ; and all the more deeply, as he himself, when combating Patripassianism, could not often enough repeat,—The Son remained what He was, in that He became what He was not.! The incarnate Logos was like the sun, whose rays continue pure whatever may be the nature of the place on which they shine (c. Cels. 6, 73). The wisdom of God, which is His Only-begotten Son, is unchangeable in all things. In Him is the entire sum of essential good, which, as such, can undergo no change or alteration (de prine. 1, 2, 10). Even during His self-abasement, He lost no part of His evOaL- novia; He continued blessed, even whilst He was labouring and suffering for our salvation. Unchangeable in essence (ovcia), God descended to men in providence and activity (mpovota Kat otxovowia) on their behalf. It could not, therefore, escape him, that if the simple divine nature continued entirely by and in itself, and so also the human, no such a thing as an.incarnation took place. Hence, we find a number of passages, in which, starting with the idea of the Logos, whom on other grounds he represented as more closely related to the world, its multiplicity and finitude, he evinces an inclination to bring the Son into the intimate union with the finite, required by the Christian consciousness. Accordingly, he 1 For other passages bearing on the unchangeableness of the Logos even during the incarnation, see in Joh. T. xxxiii. 17, and note 1, page 108. ORIGEN. 135 says (in Joh. T. ii. 18), the Son is different from the Father; for the latter is the light which is unapproachable by, and exalted above all conflict with, darkness. ‘The Son, on the contrary, is the light which shines in the darkness, which battles with, suffers persecution from, but is not overcome by, the darkness.’ Else- where he says,— He left father and mother, that is, God the Father and the heavenly Jerusalem, His kingdom, and descended to us.”” From this it would seem that His incarnation involved a renunciation of His glory. So also, when Origen endeavours to exhibit the entire depth of His participation in our sufferings, he is frequently more concerned to assert that He notwithstanding retained His deity, that is, His love, unchanged, than that His blessedness and glory remained untouched. At such times, he does not shrink from the employment of those paradoxes and apparent contradictions, than which nothing is dearer to faith, because they alone seem to furnish an explanation of that actual contradiction which gnaws at the heart of a world created for God, and yet lying in destruction. “Christ,” says he, “is both Priest and Sacrifice. He committed no sin, but He became sin for us through the flesh, in order that He might carry our sins and nail them to the cross. He who is immortal, dies ; He who is incapable of suffering, suffers; He who is invisible, reveals 1 Also de prince. 1. 2, 8, may be referred to this connection: ‘‘ Ut autem plenius intelligatur, quomodo Salvator figura est substantize vel subsis- tentiz Dei, utamur etiam exemplo.” After remarking,—this comparison may be incomplete, but it is merely intended to show us how the Son of God, who was in the form of God, intended by means of His very self-abase- ment to reveal to us the fulness of deity,—he goes on to say,—Verbi causa, si facta esset aliqua statua talis, quee magnitudine sui universum orbem terre teneret, et pro sui immensitate considerari a nullo posset: fieret autem alia statua, membrorum habitu ac vultus lineamentis, specie ac materia per omnia similis absque magnitudinis immensitate, pro eo, ut qui illam immensam considerare atque intueri non possent, hanc videntes illam se vidisse confiterentur pro eo—quod omnia—prorsus indiscreta servaret: tali quadam similitudine exinaniens se filius Dei, de equalitate patris et viam nobis cognitionis ejus ostendens figura expressa substantiz ejus efficitur.— Filius Dei brevissimee insertus humani corporis forme ex operum virtutisque similitudine patris in se immensam ac invisibilem magnitudinem desig- nabat. 2 In Jerem. hom. 10, 7: "Ide pcos cov ev eopQn Ocod vrcpyovra, dvra sv TOlS ovpavols, Oe aUTOD TOY Oixoy UrEpoupaviov—ioE HUTOY OixoY dyTa TOY Osov. Karaasixes roy Tlarépa, nol rqy penrépa, thy ava Ispovonarnec, noel epyerate sis roy wepiyssov romov. Tlapédwxsy ceevrov ryy Puxny sic ras xsipas Tay ey dowy. 136 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. Himself. By coming to become sin for us, He intensified and awakened evil. For through His love He made Himself visible in the flesh and displeasing to men, so that they killed Him” (in Levy. Hom. 3,1). In Hom. Jerem. 8, 8 we read,—“ Let our discourse be bold, and let us say,—The divine which entered into the world, humbled (emptied) itself, in order that the world night be filled by its emptiness. But though it had emptied itself, its emptiness was still wisdom. For divine folly is wiser than men. Had I been the first to make use of this word, ‘divine folly,’ how would my accusers have assailed me! But Paul himself terms apostolic wisdom divine folly. For, as com- pared with the supra-celestial, supra-mundane wisdom, that which became man (70 évideujoav) was mere divine folly, but yet wiser than men,—wiser not merely than the foolish, but also than the wise. It did not need the wisdom of God to put to nought the foolishness of the world; the weakness and the folly of God were sufficient. And so my Redeemer and Lord took upon Himself all contradictions (€vavria), in order, by means of contradictions (for example, the humiliation of the Son of God, His xévwpa), to solve contradictions; in order that we might be made strong through the weakness of Jesus, wise through His divine folly, and, prepared in such a way, might rise to the wisdom and power of God Himself, that is, to Jesus Christ.” What he means here is not, that merely one part or one power of the Logos became man, but the entire person of the Son. Nor again does he mean that, strictly speaking, the entire fulness of the glory of the divine Son became man, and was merely not recognised by the folly of the world ;—that, consequently, His self-abase- ment was mere subjective seeming, which must then be recog- nised as such by faith. No; the incarnate One Himself was humbled, was emptied of His glory. One thing unquestionably was not given up, to wit, love, which retains its majesty even in the midst of humiliation, and that most certainly, when the humi- ation, though voluntary, is still not a mere show. ‘To this con- nection belongs also the remarkable passage from the Hom. in Jerem. 1. 8, where he says,—“ We cannot, indeed, say of Wisdom in itself, that it was ignorant, and acquired knowledge by learn- ing; but it is certainly true of Wisdom as it was in the flesh ; for Christ must needs learn to stammer and speak like a child with children (men).” Compare also de prince. 2, 6, 1. ORIGEN. 137 These passages show that Origen was not so completely absorbed in his antagonism to Patripassianism, as to mistake the essentially Christian elements, which it concealed under coarser forms. The more pressing, therefere, became the question, how both interests were to be reconciled :—On the one hand, there was the unchangeableness of the Son of God, which, taken by itself, reduces the incarnation to a mere theophany; on the other hand, there was the not merely apparent, but living and genuine, union of the divine with the human nature, which threatened to mix up foreign elements with the conception of God, especially when we take into consideration that the union must embrace also the flesh of Christ? This now is the point at which a view can be gained of Origen’s doctrine of the human soul of Christ in its full significance. ~~ With the body, the divine nature could not directly unite itself, without subjecting itself, in a manner unworthy of God, to mutability and suffering. In order, therefore, not to be compelled to transfer sufferings to God, and yet, at the same time, to be able to maintain the possibility of a true union with humanity, we must note that the Logos assumed the soul of Christ_directly; the body, however, indirectly, through the medium of the soul. But, having secured in the soul of Christ a means of carrying the incarnation through, even to the flesh, the importance he attached to that soul enabled him to assume the existence of a far more intimate relation between the Son and the humanity than Hippolytus, for example, had ventured to concede, and felt himself, consequently, able satisfactorily to meet the true aspect of the yearnings of Patripassianism. The perfect soul of Christ was as thoroughly able to participate in all the pains and woes of humanity, as to be completely united with the Son of God ;—thus also did it give Him a share in. the sufferings and works endured and performed by it, in His power. Never before Origen had the human soul of Christ been seen to have so profound and integrating a bearing on the intellection of the incarnation of God. But, though we may grant that his system—laying, as it did, so great stress on free- dom of choice, and concentrating therein, to a certain extent, the essence of human nature—was, in the highest degree, such as to necessitate the postulaticn, in particular, of the union of 1338 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. the Logos with a human soul, as unconditionally requisite to the full truth of the incarnation; whereas all the Fathers who preceded him evidently attached chief importance to the body, appearing frequently to see in it the real essence of humanity ; it cannot be denied, that the very ground which powerfully im- pelled him to the development of the doctrine of a true human soul, was, in another aspect, the source of great difficulties. For, if all souls must be deemed originally equal, on the ground that it would have been an act of partiality in God not to make the worth of each dependent on the use to which it put its freedom, it would appear that the incarnation must, in the first instance, have been a purely tentative thing, and that the union could not, from the beginning, have related to the inmost centre of the human soul,—to wit, its freedom. It was not permissible for the assumptive divine activity to penetrate at once so completely to the inmost centre of human nature as to leave it no longer free. In that case, however, an opening would have been left for sin and apostasy, and the tendency to incarnation which had been initiated would have been arrested. Nay more, if freedom of choice permanently belongs to the essence of human nature, it would appear impossible for the God-man ever to constitute an unity, and necessary that He should ever continue a double personality. And, even supposing this unity were finally to be in some way brought to pass, the incarnation must apparently be attributed rather to human merit than to divine grace; for the God-man was at the first a man like others, and the union with the deity was the reward of His virtue, as the Ebionites teach. These difficulties his clear eye discerned quite well. . Let us now see how he endeavoured to overcome them. In order to set them aside, he goes back to his doctrine of the pre-existence of souls. Christ’s soul also must be of like nature with ours:! however exalted Christ may have been above other men, however distinguished and unique was His appearance (so that even His body must have participated in the glory of the soul, although usually concealed), He could not have enjoyed this exceptional position from the very begin- ning, but must_have attained it as the reward of His virtue. 1 De prince. 2, 8, 4. In general, as in Tertullian, so also in Origen, we find the expression: Christ had two natures, He was a cuvbstoyv Tpmey Loe (c. Cels. 2, 9, 24, 31). He first employed the term, @:cvdpoaros. ORIGEN. 133) Now, had He earned this distinction on earth, the birth of Christ would have been in no respect peculiar, it would not have been an incarnation: His soud would have entered into the present world as one still accessible to sin; nay more, if it were David’s seed, it must have been stained with sin. Like all souls, however, it pre-existed from the beginning of the world. By its decision for the good, and by its virtue, it was fitted for anflinchinely carrying out all the will and all the saving revela- cons of the Word and Wisdom. The Logos dwelt in an unique nanner in this soul. At the commencement of creation, it is true, He was united with all souls; but this one alone clung to Him so closely, faithfully, and unchangeably, that it became ne spirit with Him. (De princ. 2, 6, 3: Cum pro liberi arbitrii facultate varietas unumquemque ac diversitas habuisset animorum, ut alius ardentiore, alius tenuiore, et exiliore erga autorem suum amore teneretur, illa anima—(Jesu) ab initio creatures et deinceps inseparabiliter ei et indissociabiliter in- heerens, utpote sapientize et verbo Dei et veritati et luci vers, et tota totum recipiens, atque in ejus lucem splendoremque ipsa cedens, facta est cum ipso principaliter unus spiritus.) Hence the Son of God did not dwell in this soul merely as He dwelt in the souls of Peter and Paul; for neither of them was free from sin. But the soul which was in Jesus had. chosen the good ere it knew the evil. Connected with the Word of God by an unspotted alliance, it alone was incapable of sin, and precisely because of its capability of entirely and perfectly receiving the Son of God. (De prince. 2, 6, 5: “Verum quo- niam boni malique eligendi facultas omnibus presto est, hac anima, que Christi est, ita elegit diligere justitiam, ut pro im- mensitate dilectionis inconvertibiliter ei atque inseparabiliter inhereret, ita ut propositi firmitas et affectus immensitas et dilectionis inextinguibilis calor omnem sensum conversionis atque immutationis abscinderet et quod in arbitrio erat positum longi usus affectu jam versum sit in naturam.”) Wisdom, truth, and life, it had made completely part of itself; it was the box of the precious ointment, the Apostles have the smell; in it was the entire fire of the Logos, and by His glow and heat it was pervaded in love as iron heated in the furnace; the Apostles ? Ad. Rom. 1, 5. Even so, if sin had been the substance of our nature, Christ also would have been sinful, de prince. 4, 37. 140 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. had the warmth which streamed forth from it.’ Hence also, both the reason and mode of its entrance into this world were, of necessity, completely different from other men. ‘The reason was not punishment or chastisement for sins, committed during its pre-temporal existence; nor the practice of, and establish- ment in, good; but love to men. Having continued unchange- ably in the Logos, even after men had fallen, and being united with Him by the tenderest love, this soul willingly became the organ by means of which He appeared on earth, and wrought out human redemption. The self-abasement of which the Apostle speaks (Phil. ii.) is not seldom referred by Origen, as it would seem, to this soul of Christ, which gave up its glory, although not its connection with the Logos,’ and entered into the fates and sufferings of the finite, into the condition which 1s the consequence of sin, but without being touched by the least breath of sin; for, even prior to its entrance into the world, it had become incapable of sin, through its perfect love to the Logos (Note 23). In dignity, it is true, it is inferior to the Only-begotten One, for it was created; but it, the most blessed and most exalted of all souls, was so distinguished, that it stood in the midst between God and the rest of mankind. Hence, also, the mission of accomplishing the work of redemption mainly devolved on it (ad. Rom. T. iii. 8). But, precisely for this reason, its mode of entrance into this world could not be 1 De prince. 2, 6, 6. The image of glowing iron, so frequently repeated at a later period, is here carried out by Origen in the following way :— ‘Ferri metallum capax est frigoris et caloris. Si ergo massa aliqua ferri semper in igne sit posita, omnibus suis poris omnibusque venis ignem reci- piens—si neque ignis ab ea cesset aliquando, neque ipsa ab igne separetur, num quidnam dicemus hance, que natura quidem ferri massa est, in igne positam et indesinenter ardentem posse frigus aliquando recipere? Quin- imo magis—eam totam ignem effectam dicimus, quoniam nec aliud in ea nisi ignis cernitur: sed et si qui(s) contingere atque attrectare tentaverit, non ferri sed ignis vim sentiet. Hoc ergo modo etiam illa anima, que, quasi ferrum in igne, sic semper in verbo,—sapientia,—Deo posita est, omne quod agit, quod sentit, quod intelligit, Deus est, et ideo nec conver- tibilis aut mutabilis dici potest, quee inconvertibilitatem ex Verbi Dei unitate indesinenter ignita possedit. Ad omnes denique sanctos calor aliquis Verbi Dei putandus est pervenisse; in hac autem anima ipse ignis divinus substantialiter requievisse credendus est, ex quo ad caeteros calor aliquis venerit.” 2 Anaceph. §. 32. cli. 3i. ORIGEN. 14] the usual one. It was in God and in the Pleroma; thence it went forth at the bidding of the Father, and took from Mar Vy the Virgin a true human Theres ; and because, in the strict sense, those spirits alone can be designated men who have a mortal body (for those who have no eth ought rather to be termed angels), we may fairly say, that Greed then first became man, although it be true that His soul, with which the Logos Hee been ever united, had the same nature as all other souls —-con- sequently, the same nature as the souls of men. According to Origen, therefore, the incarnation was not ac- complished in one act, but had a history, progressed from one stage to another, and fell into three main acts ;—-and this is a point of deep significance. The first two acts were played out ere time commenced; the third commenced with the earthly life of Christ. The first was the original and essential union into which the Logos entered with this soul, and which sub- sisted from the very commencement of its existence. But as this first union with the soul of Jesus was simply that which subsisted between the Logos and all souls, at the moment of their creation (otherwise, Origen’s view of he divine righteous- ness would be violated, de princ. 2, 6, 3), it was not by itself any mark of ghana Sizictly speaking, it constituted merely the presupposition of the incarnation, and declared that hnman nature was susceptible thereto. To the actual realization of the incarnation, it was necessary that the union established, in the first instance, by the Logos, should be affirmed by the soul of Christ. It actually did decide for the Logos, and that with such sincerity and love, that it was completely taken up into the Logos, or even, as many } passages teach, into His essence; in other words, the incarnation was perfectly accomplished as far as affects the soul. For, whereas previously the bond was dissoluble, by this second act an in- destructible union was founded between the soul and the entire Logos. Origen did not intend thereby to shut out freedom ; but to represent the freedom as one which can no longer choose the evil, as one that is bound and perfected by love (compare ad. Rom. L. v. 10). Equally far also is this perfect love, which includes freedom of choice as a momentum of itself, and no longer leaves it to occupy an isolated position (Note 24), from shutting out the incarnation from further progress: on the 142 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. contrary, this perfect love in the soul of Christ is itself the living principle and motive of the assumption of a human body. The idea of incarnation, so far as it is the work of condescending love, arrived with this third act at its extreme limit; for, in order_to be able to suffer and die on men’s behalf, the Logos became flesh, by means of the soul of Jesus: even then, how- ever, further development was not rendered impossible, but the movement now began to take a reverse direction. At first, the Logos learned to stammer in the man Jesus; the child Jesus had a truly human development, and participated thoroughly in human weakness, so far as it was not marked by sin. But this self-abasement of the Logos in the soul which had descended to earth, was intended to promote the glorification of humanity, primarily in this same man. Even on earth, the glory of His higher nature was communicated to the body (c. Cels. 3, 41), as the transfiguration proves: usually, however, it was not per- mitted to appear, but remained concealed, or was revealed as men needed it (c. Cels. 6, 77; 4,16; Tract. in Matth. xxxv. 100; hom. in Gen. viii. 8; in Joh. T. i. 34; ad Rom. L. 1. 4). In His miracles was displayed the divine power of His entire person ; His death is not to be conceived as mere passive suffer- ing, but also as the work of His free will: His resurrection also was effected, not by the Father alone, but also by Himself Gn Joh. T. x. 21). Finally, the entire Person of Christ, even His body, ascended up to heaven and was glorified. In reward for its condescension and love, His soul was then exalted, and ad- mitted to a participation in the divine omniscience ; which was not the case on earth (Tract. in Matth. xxx. 55). Its glory communicated itself also to the body of Christ. When He ascended into heaven, He took with Him His earthly body; and the heavenly powers were filled with amazement when they beheld humanity coming in Him into their midst. Elias and Enoch did not, strictly speaking, ascend to heaven; Christ, however, as He was the first-born from the dead, was also the first to raise flesh into heaven (Fragm. in Ps. xv.,. And now there is no longer any difference between His humanity and His deity, the former having passed over into, and been entirely blended with, the latter.’ 1 ¢, Cels. 3,41 :—To bvyréy aired chun, nai chy dvdpwmivny ev aire Luxny ri woos éxsivoy od wedvov xowavie, BAAR xal Evooet nal advanpaoel Ta miryloTa ORIGEN. 143 These expressions are so strong, that at an early period Origen was suspected of holding the humanity to be a transient phenomena of the Logos." It is inaccurate, indeed, to charge him with teaching that Christ laid aside His humanity: so far from that, he rather conceived it to have been constituted, as it were, a momentum of the Logos Himself, and regarded its passage into deity as its perfection. All human weakness was removed ; divine power and glory took its place. At the same time, we here come upon a defect which, on closer examination, we find running through Origen’s entire system, and which leaves unsettled difficulties at all the chief points. It is true he believed human nature to be destined for the divine, and incapable of attaining its truth, save in union there- with. But this divine is, strictly speaking, something which | transcends human nature; and human nature must be exalted above itself, that is, must change its nature, in order to fulfil its destiny. Its ideal lies immediately in God, not in God’s idea of man, of which unity with Him is an essential consti- tuent. In order, therefore, to reach its goal, humanity must cease to be humanity, must pass into another substance, to wit, the divine, and be swallowed up by it. Accordingly, his theory exposed him to the danger of representing the perfection of humanity as the termination of its existence. The reverse aspect thereof is, that when he attributes independence to the man, he is compelled to exclude the action of God; as we find from his not regarding the decision for the Logos formed by the soul of Christ as the decision of the Logos Himself. At. this point, therefore, the view he takes of Christ is really Ebionitical, not- withstanding its relating to His pre-temporal existence. It_is an important defect of Origen’s Christology, that when it aims to assert the full truth of the humanity of Christ, it does not entirely avoid Ebionism; and, on the other hand, when it sets forth the deity of Christ in its victorious, all-conquering might, Doceev TporesAnPevact, nal rns Exsivov Oeoryntos xexoivovynnora eis Osov merase. Anniver. “Eely 08 rig apooxdrry xal wepl rod cdmatos aiTov ravd guar Aeyovrwy, eriotycaTH TOls UO TAY EAAHVaY Asyomevols Tepl THs TO lOlw Aoye aTrolov YAns, ToLerntas &uUPionouéyns Orolas 6 Onloupyos Bovarstas HLTH TeEple Tibevert, wal TOoAAaKIS TAS Lesy TpoTepas aworiOsmeEvns, xpeitroves O€ xal d1eDd- povs cvanrauBavovens. Tract. in Matth. xxxiv. 70. " Compare Huet’s ‘‘ Origeniana,” in de La Rue’s Ed. iv. 152. 144 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. it approximates too closely to Docetism, by representing the hu- manity as absorbed in the deity. An exactly similar fault cha- racterizes also his doctrine of the Trinity. The common root of both defects is his peculiar conception of God. We have found / that Origen’s doctrine of the Son follows necessarily and clearly from his conception of God, according to which, the Son, who, at one and the same time, is eternally generated, and is being eternally generated (der ewig gezeugte und gezeugtwerdende), possesses all that is communicable of the divine essence (that is, volition and knowledge) ; and further, that he denies to the Son solely that which appears to him absolutely incommunicable, indivisible, and inconceivable in different hypostases, save on the condition of denying the unity of the ultimate, ungenerated, and generating ground. The consequence thereof was, that, contrary to his soteriological principles, the Son was shut out from the inmost sphere of the divine, and reduced to the rank of something secondary, almost to the rank of a creature. That which the Son did not possess, is represented as the inmost, the highest part of God; this the highest part of God, therefore, is -incommunicable, exclusive. lftows we come again upon the false “jdea of God, which teaches that something shy sical, the physical category of the Absolute, and not love nae Kosanees not His spiritual attributes, are the highest, the inmost, the proper being of God. Origen had not yet succeeded in Eviinae ireaiane loose from the’ ‘Ov of Hellenic philosophy ; and the direct ae thereof was the impossibility of the Son’s being one with the Most High God. His primary and predominant tendency to set the essence of the Son, as far as possible, on an equality with that of the Father, fails because of this rigid “Ov, this dark remnant of the old heathenish view of the world, which trans- fers the inmost constituent of the conception of God to the sphere of the natural, where all things are characterized by ex- clusiveness. Heine would Helse, assumed an entirely dif- ferent position, had he regarded love and the spiritual attributes as constituting the inmost essence of God; for therein the Son might participate. Aseity, on the contrary, instead of being described as the inmost essence of God, in which it was impos- sible for the Son to participate, would then have denoted simply that which was distinctive of the Father, whilst the entire divine nature would have been recognised as belonging in common to — * ORIGEN. 145 the F'ather and to the Son. Origen, however, puts the matter as follows :—The Son could only participate in the inmost and highest part of the divine nature, so far as He entirely lost Himself in the One, Indivisible God, and ceased to be any longer Son; but so far as there is a difference between Him and the Father, the latter sets forth the entire and inmost divine essence, whereas the former remains excluded from this sphere. We remark, therefore, in Origen a phenomenon which fre- quently reappeared at a later period, especially in the Mystics,— namely, because the divine, in its dissociation from all multipli- city, singularity, or determination, was conceived to be the Highest, whereas man in general, and the Christian in parti- cular, demands that the very divine itself, and not merely a derivative divine, be accessible to him; he was compelled te speak of a going out beyond the image of God, to wit, the Son, into the depths of the divine nature, into the essence of the Father,—the effect of which naturally was, to threaten both the mediatorship of the Logos, and the historical significance of Christ. It is false, indeed, to regard it in Origen’s sense as a mere subjective seeming ;! he had, at all events, no intention of modalistically dissolving the hypostasis of the Logos and His his- tory in the divine Monas; but still he by no means completely extricated himself from this error, for, according to his teaching, the inmost essence of the Most High God scarcely penetrates to the essence of the Son. In the Son, we know the Father solely according to His doa, and to the divine substance thereunto appertaining, not according to His inmost essence. The world represents to him, as in another form to Pseudo-Dionysius Areo- pagita, a divine hierarchy, all the members of which are rational in themselves, but in different degrees; and the higher stage, by stretching out its hand in aid of the lower, leads it out be- yond itself to a higher. Those who cannot lay hold on Christ’s external appearance are retained in connection with the Logos, by means of rational beings in whom He dwells more perfectly. The second class lays hold on the outward appearance of Christ, but does not understand the highest and alone true element in Him, into which His own humanity passed, after enjoying for a moment an individual existence. The third class is led on through the humanity of Christ to His pure deity, and then * As notwithstanding Baur does, 1. c. p. 219. VOL. II. K 146 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. knows Him no longer after the flesh. But even to be united with the Logos is not the highest attainment; for, inasmuch as He Himself is not in Himself the Highest, He directs us beyond Himself to the Most High God, the Father, to whom we are to enter into a relation of contemplation (@éa), as intimate as that of the Logos. Origen forgets not, indeed, to remark that per- fect Christians owe their attainment of this highest stage to the Logos, that is, not merely to the eternal, but to the incarnate, Logos; and that there is no way to this height, save the way through the God-man and the Logos. In particular did he regard the death of Christ as the eternally operative means of reconciliation, which continues to be a necessary preliminary to the attainment of the highest stage,—a circumstance which leads us to form a favourable estimate of the depth of his Chris- tian consciousness. His endeavours to exalt the sacrifice of Christ to an absolutely universal significance, to strip it of the limits of time and space, and to represent it as having been pre- sented in heaven, were not dictated by a wish to dissipate His historical death, but rather, on the contrary, by a desire to set *t forth as the central event of history and of the universe,.as the point in which heaven and earth meet, and God andthe world are reconciled. For this reason, though the sacrifice of Christ was presented on earth, he places it in heaven, and teaches that even the pious who lived prior to His advent, were counted among the reconciled, for its sake ;—indeed, he repre- sents the entire world as participating in its blessing. But if in Christ by Himself and in the Logos, we do not merely not possess the entire God (for even the Church does not suppose that), but not even the Most High God, then is merely a porch of heaven, and not heaven itself, come down to us, and thus we see clearly that the revelation of the highest in Christ can only be viewed as a modalistic shining into Him. At this same point, we are not less instructively reminded also of the essential connection between Modalism and Subordinatianism. For when Modalism endeavours to conceive the revelation in Christ as a permanent, fixed thing, and not as a mere theophany, it falls into Subordinatianism ; and so, on the other hand, all Subordinatian- ism unavoidably represents the truly divine as merely shining ‘nto the Son. Neither of them, consequently, possesses in Christ the absolute religion, and both are impelled to aspire beyond this RETROSPECT. 147 revelation to a fanciedly higher and deeper mystery. This mys- tery is, it is true, empty enough; but its influence is pernicious, because it weakens the conviction that in Christ we possess the highest ; it reduces His revelation from the rank of an absolute to that of a relative one; and it may turn away the eye from the mysterious treasures which are contained in Christ Himself, and which demand to be revealed to our consciousness (Note 25.) The statement just given may show us that the attempt made by Origen, with a clear insight into the nature of his task, to free the momenta of truth, scattered through the sys- tems of his predecessors, from the one-sidedness of heresy, and to unite them in one great whole, necessarily failed because o the imperfection of his conception of God. Origen thereforc forms a knot in the history of doctrine. Many threads meet in him ; his far-reaching mind saw that they must be united in one web; and, standing as it were at the cradle of the develop- ment of Christian doctrine, he, the first Christian dogmatician, lays down the problems which should busy the mind of the Church for a long period, but was himself unable to find the solution. The threads of thought, which, like so many lines, had converged towards a centre in his great mind, separate again still more widely from each other in quitting him; the various aspects which he aimed at uniting, did not find a form capable of embracing them all; and the more closely he brought them together, the more clearly was their permanent disharmony revealed. His attempt at effecting an union became, on the contrary, a watchword for the unchaining of antagonisms and the initiation of new struggles. This point now demands our attention. Let us first cast a glance at the development of doctrine during this remarkable period, and at the three principal figures who acted the part of representatives of the Church. From the end of the second century and onwards, the teachers of the Church arrived at the common conviction, that, in order to secure doctrinally the hypostasis of the Logos, they must.advance beyond the literal signification of the term, inasmuch as God in general is also Reason (Adyos). Following Tertullian’s example, the term “Son” was therefore adopted for a watchword. Hippo- lytus now says, the Son is out of the Logos; the Logos is the ‘spiritual substance of God or of the Father Himself: so far is 148 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. He from being Himself the Son, that logically the Logos. pre- cedes the Son,—a thought which is further carried out by Ori- gen. A great part of Tom. i. in Joh., where he represents the apy of John (in which was the Xdyos, that is, the povoyevijs or Son) as the divine co¢éa, that is, as the vods or Adyos of God Himself, out of which the Son then proceeds, 1s occupied with the development of this same thought. By means of the word Son, a clearer distinction was now drawn between the essence and the personality of the second hypostasis ; but, at the same time, Sonship was understood at first to denote, not the essence, but merely the personality (for example, by Tertullian and Hippolytus); whereot the natural consequence was, that whereas, or because, the essence of the second hypostasis is eternal, its personality was conceived to be non-eternal. The temporal diremption, namely, was intended to aid in setting plainly forth and establishing the distinction between the eternal substance still undistinguished from the Father, and the personality. The less mature and ready mind of Tertullian (for example) was unable to discover any other means of mastering the distinction, than by fixing it in time. Without doubt, too, the watchword now chosen, “Son,” brought with it the temptation to conceive the Sonship as having begun in time. At all events, one can easily understand that men like Clemens Alexandrinus and Jrenzus (the latter of whom had already begun to treat the doctrine of the Logos critically), who in the main rested satisfied with the word Logos, must have found it easier, yea, even more neces~ sary, to affirm the eternity of the divine wisdom and reason (that is, the eternity of the Son, in their sense), than those who started with the word Son. The consequent commixture of the Son with finitude, which on the one hand brought Tertullian nearer to Patripassianism, and on the other hand involved him ‘n contradiction with himself, seeing that he, notwithstanding, deemed the Son to be derived from the eternal essence of God, Hippolytus endeavoured to set aside by drawing a clear distinc- tion between God, as the alone infinite, supra-infinite One, and the world. His determinism, however, reduced the world, nay, even the humanity of Christ, to selflessness ; and he also sub- jects the hypostatic existence of the Son to the almighty will of God. His gaze was already directed away from the later mani- fested personality of the Son, back to His eternal essence: and RETROSPECT. 149 he tried to establish a connection between the two, by means of the idea of the predestination of the personality of the Son. But the Son is plainly thus reduced to still greater dependence on the divine will; and that eternal essence is represented as belonging to the Father alone, and as communicated to the hypostatic Son, according to His will and counsel. Origen first rose decidedly above this point of view. He saw the con- tradiction between the supposition of an hypostasis, whose exist- ence commences at a later time, on the one hand, and the attribution to it of an eternal divine essence, and the denial that it is a creature, on the other hand. He therefore combined the eternity of the divine essence with the fact of the genesis of the personality, by means of the doctrine of the eternal, that: is, the eternally processive generation of the Son by the Father. Earlier writers had spoken much of the will of the Father in a way that equalized the Son and creatures, contrary to their in- tention; and Origen, in whose system the will plays so impor- tant a part, did not entirely escape this fault : at the same time, he described the Son as the hypostatized will of the Father, which proceeded forth from His wisdom, spirit, vods =Adyos. In har- mony with the doctrine of the eternal generation, Origen thus brought the tendencies of Tertullian and Hippolytus to a certain sort of conclusion; but at the same time set himself into strong realistic antagonism to the men of the second century, who had viewed the Son more idealistically as the divine reason and wis- dom, or, at the utmost, as the divine thought which is at the same time world-creative. It is evident, however, that the definition of the Son as Will, can, in itself, no more secure the distinction of His hypostasis from the Father, than the definition of Him as the Logos. For as the Father is, and must continue to be, Logos, Reason, so also is He Will,—a circumstance which might escape the attention of Origen, with his peculiar concep- tion of God, but could not be concealed from the Church, holding, as it did, the Christian idea of God. The only means of averting that danger, was the idea of a diremption of the divine essence. We have seen, also, that Origen repeatedly approximated to this idea, but was unable fully to carry it out, because his conception of God was essentially opposed to such a diremption, and was interwoven with the Hellenic Absolute or "Ov. On the other hand, it deserves to be noted with approval, 150 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. that he tried to assign to the will also a place in the humanity of Christ, although his efforts ended somewhat ebionitically.. Still more does it deserve mention, that, primarily for the sake of securing the truth of the ethical development of the humanity of Christ, he represented the incarnation, not, after the universal custom in his day, as a fact once for all accomplished and con- cluded, but as a continuous, nay more, progressive one. CHAPTER SECOND. SABELLIANISM. SABELLIANISM—taking the word in its doctrinal, not in its historical signification—is capable of assuming many forms, the attainment of an acquaintance with which is our present object. The essential feature, it is true, of all the forms of Sabellianism, is the Movapyia, the unity of Gods. but the assertion thereof was compatible with a recognition of the distinction between God as He is in Himself, and God as revealed. ‘The relation between the two, however, may be very differently Viewed. Sabellianism, in its earliest form, did not deem the unchange- ableness of God, His freedom from processes of growth and from suffering, necessary to His absolute unity: on the con- trary, the early Patripassians taught that God entered into: change and suffering... That God Himself was present in His: revelation, was maintained by them with such intensity, that they directly identified the two. They took for granted, it is true, that God still continued God; but how His subjection to suffering and processes of growth was compatible therewith, they did not further inquire: in other words, they did not define the inner essence of God to be that which continues ever the same, and permanently distinguish it from the sphere of that which He became. Noetus does this more distinctly than Praxeas. He distinguished God’s permanent being in Himself and the revelations, in which He manifests Himself as He pleases. It is clear, however, that even so, the unchangeable- ness of God is not fully secured. For, in the act of manifesting Himself, He enters, according to Noetus, into externality and SABELLIANISM. 151 passibility. At the same time, he thus affirmed the objective truth of the revelations in harmony with the claims of the reli- gious mind. But the speculative knowledge of God seems all the more strongly contradictory thereto, as, on the one hand, no motive is assigned why God should begin to reveal Himself, nor the revelation reconciled with His unchangeableness; and, on the other hand, the mode and number of God’s revelations are not shown to be conditioned by His eternal essence. Beron and Beryll also neglected to give more attentive consideration to the divine unchangeableness, though, in a Christological point of view, they occupy higher ground. Another more refined form of Monarchianism was that which, whilst aiming to exclude all suffering whatever from God, never- theless held that God Himself was really present. in His reve- lations under the form of deeds; and sought to reduce their in- defined plurality within fixed limits. God would then be in all His revelations unalterably one and the same; the possibility of a difference of revelations being based on the distinction drawn between God’s unchangeable inseity (Insichseyn) and His his- torical life in the world, and the attribution of the change of revelations solely to this latter. A still more sublimated form of this tendency was, thirdly, that which not merely excluded suffering and change from God’s essence, but, instead of His historical life, admitted solely the existence of a movement, which, as the movement.of His will, was held to have Hone to do with His.being. So far as revelation is regarded merely as a work, and not as a mode of the existence “ae God, all that is present therein, is undoubtedly His thought or will; He Himself, however, is not revealed, but remains withdrawn from the world. But as the Christian mind could never be content with the meagre description of Christ as a mere work of God, the expedient might be adopted of saying, that though the entire God was not present in the revelation, or in the actuality, yet a ray of the divine essence was. A merely quantitative distinction from Patripassianism,—a distinc- tion, too, which, in addition, pays an earnest-money to Ebion- ism,—is thus effected, but nothing more. The final logical result of this tendency to give prominence to the abstract simplicity and immutability of God, would natu- rally be to transfer this abstract simplicity to the so-called reve- 152 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. lation also. For, as the divine omnipresence itself forbids the separation of the will and work of God from His being, seeing that He continues present in both, the movement or change which was meant to be confined to them, falls back into His being Consequently, if God be regarded as the abstractly simple One, we can no longer represent Him as active in the work of revela- tion; for if He were, especially on the supposition of different revelations, He must be brought under the limits of time. That, therefore, which is termed revelation, is a simple subjective matter: the objective God remains in His being and doing ever and eternally the same: He merely appears as a different being, be it that the objective medium through which He presents Himself to the consciousness, breaks the rays of His essence differently ; or be it that the individual subject, at different stages, knows the divine, which is one and the same, and which presents itself always alike, more or less perfectly. In the for- mer case, we should have a feeble remainder of an objective self- revelation of God, in the sense, namely, of the world, and not God, being the cause of different aspects of the divine nature being revealed at different times; in the latter case, no objective revelation at all takes place, but the entire process of religion and revelation is dissipated, after a Pelagian (or deistic) fashion, into a simple matter of subjective human development :—so, in- deed, that not even in the creation of the world is a place left for a revelation of God; for the creation of the world must be as incompatible with the abstract simplicity and unchangeableness of God as the act of the second creation. The entire mode of thought of early thinkers indisposed them for carrying this prin- ciple out to its logical results; but representatives of the second and third forms of Monarchianism made their appearance even as late as the third and fourth centuries. We see thus, within this tendency, a gradual_progress from a pantheisti¢ principle, that is, a principle which.commingles God and the world, to a deistic principle: these two extremes, however, are connected by the predominance given to the con- ception of God as substance, relatively to which the ethical aspect of God is thrown into the background, and which, from its unsatisfactory character, sways about between the extremes of a God who is immediately passible, and one who is separated from the world. SABELLIUS. 153 After these preliminary observations, let us return to the history. The result of the development of the Church, which since the days of Hippolytus and Origen had brought the doc- trine of the immutability of the inner, divine essence decidedly to the foreground, had been to repress Patripassianism. About the middle of the third century, it withdrew from the scene : and only a few forlorn, anonymous voices were raised on its behalf: unless we take into consideration the pantheistic, dual- istic movement which went forward almost outside of the limits of Christianity, and whose occurrence at this precise period cannot be regarded as accidental (Note 26). But we have seen also, that even the system of Origen had not advanced beyond the idea of the abstract simplicity of God. If, as he maintains, the supra-essential God suffers within Him- self no inner distinctions ; and if, notwithstanding, on the other hand, the main matter is, that the Most High God should come forth and enter into fellowship with humanity ; it appears more correct, with Sabellianism, to posit the latter, and, whilst re- taining hold on the simplicity of God in Himself, to distinguish between the revealed and the hidden God, than, with Origen, to represent the Most High God as constantly hidden. And almost still more strongly than the interest in religion is the interest in science opposed to the reduction of the Son, after the example of Origen, to an uncertain middle being between God and the world. Sabellius the Libyan, Presbyter of Plotemais in the Penta- polis, endeavoured to purify the patripassian system, and to bring it to far more complete development.1. What had never at all before, or only very indefinitely, been done by earlier re- presentatives of this tendency, he drew the Holy Spirit into the circle of his theory, and so laid down a doctrine of the Trinity of his own. He thus reduced the indefinite plurality of the re- 1 Sources :—Athanas. c. Arian. Orat. iv. c 2, 9, 13, 14, 25, cll. 12, 22; de Synod. c. 16 ; Expos. Fid. c. 2; Epiphan. heer. 62; and the Anaceph. ; Eusebius, H. E. 7, 6; Theodoret, heer. fab. 2, 9. Compare also Basilius, Kp. 210, 214; Ambrosius, de Fide 1, 1, 2; 4, 4, 6. Augustine con- stantly confounds him with the Patripassians, but communicates some in- teresting particulars in the Tract. in Joh. 36 ff., 53 l.c., iv. 725 ff. 731, 853. Hilarius, de Trin. 7, 39. Compare also Schleiermacher’s Simmtliche Werke ; Erste Abtheilung, Bd. i. pp. 485-574. 154 FIRST PERIOD, SECOND EPOCH. velations of the one God to the number three, in agreement with the Church. His fundamental idea is the following :—That which in God is an unity, undivided and indistin ouishable, sepa- rates into a plurality in the world, and init alone. Only in virtue of the mundane aspect (Weltseite) can we speak of dis- tinctions or of a plurality in God. These distinctions, it 1s true, are not mere names, or mere subjective seeming ; but the divine Monas is really and objectively in them, so that a real objective something corresponds to the different revelations. For, though they are by no means distinguished from the divine unity, in which they are contained as momenta, and which is in them, the one form of revelation is not identical with the other; for example, law and incarnation are not the same: therefore, also, Father and Son, which according to Theodoret correspond to the above-mentioned two, are not the same. The Sabellians illus- trated the relation between the divine unity and plurality by a reference to the relationship between the Holy Spirit and His charisms.! The Holy Spirit is one in the many gifts which He bestows, although the gifts themselves really differ from each other. But as the gifts can only be apprehended and appear, in their difference, through the addition of the world, even so the plur ality inGod. The question then arises,—Did Sabsltrte conceive this plurality to be the work of God, or (just as the differences in the charisms arise from the differences in the natural bases on which they are engrafted) the effect of the al- ready existing nature of the world, which reflects the one divine ray in different ways, although it, for its share, strictly speak- ing, works undividedly always and everywhere, and is merely dividedly appropriated and reflected by the objective world ? The former supposition would lead to a divine history, be it of the nature or of the deeds of God: the latter would characterize the differences in the revelations, as the mere effect of the world. Applied to the incarnation, the latter would lead to Ebionism ; applied to the Holy Ghost, to Pelagianism: for it depended, for example, entirely on the man Jesus, how much of the divine unity appeared in Him. There can scarcely be any doubt that Sabellius referred the 1 Athan. c. Ar., Orat. iv. 25,—Qnal yep (SaBerrsos) dorep Iscespeosss yapto- wcray elal, TO 08 aUTO TrEvmd, vita nal oO Tarip 6 aiTOs meV EoTI, FAUTUVET tS d¢ sig vidv wel ryed me. SABELLIUS. 155 differences in the revelations back to God Himself, and insisted on their being regarded not merely as different deeds and works, but as different modes of the existence of God, although un- donbtedly in the world.’ For the divine Monas is not, in his view, motionless, but living. If it keep silence, it is without operation ; if it speak, it is active. So far as it speaks, it may be termed Logos, and that mpodopixds ; so far as it keeps silence, it answers to the Logos évévaGeros. Logos, therefore, in the language of Sabellius, means something different from Son, who is but one of the forms of the speaking God.?__ Epiphanius and Augustine also (in Joann. Tract. 53) designate the speak ing of the Monas, deed or will. The Son is also called the arm which God stretches out for action: probably, too, the Spirit is represented in the same manner agreeably to older Church ana- logies ; so that the image refers again to the entire God. The outstretched arm is God engaged in action; the arm drawn back is God in rest, in His insetty® (Insichseyn). The arm denotes, therefore, that the revelation contains no new divine hypostasis , but simply that the Monas, besides its motionless inseity, is also ‘to be viewed as active and living. What and how many move- ments and outstretchings of the arm, or revelations, pertain to God, is no more clearly indicated by this image than by the 1 To the question of Athanasius, c. Ar. 4, 14,—Whether the Monas expands itself for others or for itself? the answer may be given,—Tor others, but also for itself; it is itself that whereto it expands itself. This is not inconsistent with the charge brought against Sabellius, that, like Arius, he made men of greater consequence than the Logos, representing the Logos as proceeding forth from God for our sake. Athanasius himself (c. Ar. 4, 11) affirms both of him. If, as they say, the silent God is power- less (cévevgoynros), and first powerful when He comes forth on our behalf, we are the means of His completion, our origin contributes to His perfec- tion. We therefore are higher than He, because our creation gives Him that which He did not yet possess: He needs us for His own existence. 2 The Logos is referred to the incarnation according to Athan. 1. c. 22, cll. 20: He did not, however, first come into existence in Christ, but merely became a Son. The Monas as Logos creates the world, 1. c. 11 :—Awray de urlCew AoZero. They say :—Tov rdyov tv choy ety elvces Aoyov anras, ore OE évnvdpamnae, Tore Gvoeceabes vicv' po yep Tis ExiDavelees fon civert viov dhAB Adyou pedvov' nal womrEp 6 Adryos aap eryévero ovx Ay wpoTEpoy GAPS, OVTHE O Adryos vids yéryovev ove dv wpérepov vids. The Logos, therefore, advanced to Son- ship by degrees, as Tertullian taught. 8 After the analogy of “ aseity.”—TR. 156 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. analogy of the charisms. All that we learn is, that in the silent and motionless God, there is a potence of speech and action; and this potence Sabellius undoubtedly conceived to be eternal. But now, as regards the relation between God’s being and essence, on the one part, and His doing, on the other, there arises the question,—Whether the Monas continues outside of its doing and work, or whether its being is in the work, whether it is itself each of the movements? ‘The latter is decidedly to be assumed, and the different revelations are different modes of existence, which the Monas assumes by means of its movements. In proof of this, we cannot indeed appeal to the oynpariter Gat of Sabellius; for this word, by itself, might characterize the different oynuaticpovs as the result of the conjunction of the Monas with different parts of the world, through which the One appears as though it were diverse. But it is strikingly evident from the proposition, that the Monas expands itself to a trias (wratbveTat, éxtelverat), even as the one Spirit exposes and dif- fuses its fulness in the multiplicity of charisms. This expan- sion, extension, also termed evolution, wAaTuapos, ExTacts, ava- Tracpos Tpocwmev (Athan. c. Ar. 4, 13, 14), is the positive ground of the rise of the Sabellian plurality or trinity; its anti- thesis is the cvorod7, the withdrawal or constriction, which is a mere negative presupposition of a new IIAatucpos. In order, namely, to accomplish a new act of revelation, or to assume a new form of existence, the Monas must undoubtedly recede from its full surrender to the previous mode, and must again collect itself, so as to be able to come forth in its entirety under a new shape. These two momenta, which appertain to a divine revelation, Sabellius appears to have termed the divine dudde&s, dialectic (see Basil. Ep. 210, compare Note 29). Revelation may, therefore, progress intensively, and yet, extensively considered, the circles of the self-evolution of God may become ever narrower, as he unquestionably appears to declare, when he draws the parallel between body, soul, and spirit, and Father, Son, and Holy Ghost. The general spirit of the system, however, requires stress to be laid on the fact, that all the forms of existence assumed by the Monas in the course of the process through which it passes, are of equal value, in so far as no one of them can fail, and in SABELLIUS. Hoey all of them the entire Monas is present after some manner or other.* But if it be taken as certain that the revelations are move- ments of the divine life itself, and that Sabellius does not dis- tinguish the doing and work of God from His living being, his system must plainly be pronounced completely pantheistic, unless its Trinity presupposes a creation, and with the creation, the distinction of the world from God. For then the world is no- thing more than a mode of existence which God assumes ; whereas, on the contrary, if an already created world be taken as their scene and medium, the revelations may be regarded as different modes of the divine existence, without any danger of Pantheism: nay more, they must be so regarded, if God is not to be kept strange to, and at a distance from, the world, and the purpose of revelation to be frustrated. If Sabellius regarded creation also as a self-expansion of God out of straitness (azo atevoTntos), he must have designated this mode of existence either Father or Monas or Logos, not Son; for one of the charges most frequently brought against him, was that of denying the pre-existence of the Son and the Spirit. He can no more have termed that mode of existence Monas, than all the other modes of existence ; for Sabellius regarded Monas, not as the individual mode of the divine existence, but as the unity which continues the same in all. If the relation between the Monas and the revelations is similar to that between the Holy Ghost and His charisms, it follows, that as the Holy Ghost cannot have a real existence in the world and reveal Himself, save by means of His charisms, so also the Monas can only come forth through the medium of one or the other of its modes of existence and actions, though it itself cannot be at all identified with a single action. 1 According to the work ‘ c¢. Sabellii Gregales,” in Athan. Opp. 2, 37 ff. (in Basil. Opp. as the 27th Homily), the image of body, soul, and spirit is employed by the Sabellians as follows :—As man consists of different parts, and is notwithstanding one, even so the Trinity: it may be compounded— that they were willing to allow (c. 13)—but the parts together form the one divine hypostasis. Athanasius says :—Ov0? dvdpurov éx rpiay varovows civdcrov, rvevwatos, WuxIs, cbpearos, ota xal Occv nadawep xansivos (0. €., the Sabellians) rorawdor.—Ta yap rod ovydérov peton, nal r& xivovmsvou xLYN- pare Tpds rhy cdovvdsrov nol kvaerroiarov Prat ovdepeloev exes xorvaviory. "Exel nal Tas drOoTEANEL TO Epos 4 TO xivnua aITOV 6 FaTIp, eTOTTEAAwY roy viov $ WTO Tvsipece TO Krylov I UlOs EXMEL TOM KEG TOY KOTLLOY ; 158 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. On one supposition alone could Sabellius refer the Monas to the creation,—the supposition, namely, that he regarded creation or the world, not as a single revelation, but as a living presence or existence of God in actuality. In that case, however, the dis- tinction between the silent and the speaking God would be done away with as regards creation, and a coarse Pantheism be substi- tuted in its place. Every form of the actualization of the being and life of God should rather, on the contrary, be conceived, if not as one of the Sabellian wpocw7a, yet as something different from the Monas in itself. Only in consequence of a confusion of the Father with the Monas, therefore, could a single revela- tion, like the creation of the world, be reduced back to the Monas. It is quite possible that Sabellius may have made such a confusion (Note 27); it was a common fault of the Church teachers of this and even of a later period. The entire God, the Monas, is undoubtedly designated Father in His relation to the world (Athan. c. Ar. 4, 22, xowvos mavrov matnp), and does not bear this title solely in the Trinity. The Sabellians, there- fore, may also have frequently used the word Father, without fault, for Monas. Be that as it may, so far as we know, the Sabellians never traced back the creation of the world to the Father, or to the Monas in itself. Legislation alone is attri- buted to the Father (Note 28). It cannot be at all historically shown that Sabellius referred one of his trinitarian Scarpécets, or the trinitarian 7Aatucpovs, to the creation also. It 1s not even certain whether he believed creation in general to have been brought about by a self-extension of God. All that Athanasius says (c. Ar. 4, 18) is,—The Sabellians perhaps derived their doctrine from the Stoics, who represented God as contracting nd expanding Himself with the creation of the world Though it cannot be at all shown that Sabellius held the Monas or the Father to be the Creator of the world :—it seems certain rather, on the one hand, that his trinitarian distinctions first arise within the world which had come into existence in some other way, but do not refer to the creation; and equally certain, on the other hand, that the creation was ascribed to the Logos, whom Sabellius regarded as the Monas in life and motion. But how could he posit a particular deed of the Logos alongside of, and in addition to, the trinitarian revelation of God in the world? If the silent God is powerless, and the SABELLIUS. 159 speaking God strong; if He could do nothing whilst silent, and began to create when He spake, that is, as the Logos (Athan. c. Ar. 4,11); we have a hint which distinguishes the act of creation essentially from all the rest. Apart from the world, God cannot be, cannot be conceived; it would be to conceive Him powerless, whereas He is not fully conceived, unless con- ceived as icyvovra, as speaking, or asin motion. Very similar was the judgment both of Origen and of Hermogenes, whom several older writers classed with the Sabellians. The distinc- tion in God, on which is based the rise of the world, Sabellius deemed essential to Him; for God cannot lack power; God cannot, as to His essence, be merely the silent God; whereas the case is a totally different one with the other revelations of God in the world. They are not grounded in the nature of God, but are occasioned by the world, by its necessities. ‘The condition of the world rendered them necessary or desirable. One of the most frequent accusations brought by the teachers of the Church against Sabellius, was that of representing God as appearing in the world, solely mpos tas éxaotote ypetas, either as Father, as Son, or as Holy Ghost (Note 29). Therein was involved also the transitoriness of the single Sabellian po- oora. When the ypeta was once met, the mpocw7ov was no longer required. ‘The need arises from sin, that is, from some- thing which is not meant to be eternal; but if the ground of the existence of the rpocwrra is ephemeral, they themselves also must _be ephemeral. Such is the representation given by Gregory of Nyssa, in a passage hitherto unnoticed (A. Mai, Coll. Nov. T. 8, Appendix, p. 4). The Sabellians, says he, through reading such words as,—‘ I and the Father are one;” “ Whoso seeth Me, seeth the Father also ;” “ When He shall have given up the kingdom to the Father and God,’—with too little acuteness of judgment, have fallen into godless error, olojevot Sid peev AEvTrO- Taklav avOpwreivny TpoednrvUévas TOV UioY EK TOD Tra1 POS TpoT- Kalpws: avOus O€ weTa THY SiopOwcw THY avOpwTivey mrnupEedn- patov avareducota évddvar Te Kal avapeniyGar TO Tatpi. The same follows also from Sabellius’ notion, that God proceeds from one revelation or self-extension to another by resumption, which he appears to have figuratively described as a drawing in again of His outstretched arm (Aug. in Joann. 53, Opp. 4, 853). 160 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. A more fully developed system than that of Sabellius seems to have been, would have been compelled to make greater efforts to bring the creation, that general work of the speaking God, which continues the same through all revelations, into connec- tion with its doctrine of the Trinity, and, as the first and funda- mental revelation, to co-ordinate it with the succeeding ones ; in other words, to ascribe it to a wpdcw7rov after the manner of those which followed. But, on the one hand, even the Church itself did not do this, so far as it ascribed the creation indiffe- rently both to Father and Son; and, on the other hand, crea- tion itself and its character furnished Sabellius with an occasion and starting-point for the assumption of certain distinctions in, and manifold revelations of, the undivided divine unity : conse- quently, the Trinity, in his view of it, presupposed creation as an already accomplished thing; and apart altogether from a Trinity, he necessarily attributed it to the speaking Monas, which he terms Logos. If the work of creation pertained to one member alone of the Sabellian Trinity, and not to the speaking Monas in general, then the Monas must be divided, independently of, and prior to, the creation, into a simple prin- ciple of the creation of the world, a principle of incarnation, and so forth ;—that is, God would be distinguished in Himself. Sabellius, therefore, abode by the position,—The divine unity does not divide itself ; wherever it is, it is in its entirety; as far as concerns the eternal essence of God, the sole distinction is that into a silent and a speaking God; but the world which exists through His word, gives occasion, by the differences in its constitution, not merely to three different acts of revelation, but, as was indicated above, to three different modes of existence of Himself, in the law, in the incarnation, in the Holy Ghost. (Note 30.) From all this it would appear that the relation of the Monas to the Father, the Son, and the Spirit, is the following :—The Monas is the €v trroxeiwevov, the one hypostasis, which mani- fested. itself, during the course of the history of religion, in those three in ARs sits ways. Out of its fulness and unity, which continue ever the same, it sets forth different things for the different needs of the world. But it is not led to this manifesta- tion by inner distinctions of essence, but by the world. It is true, the world alone does not make the distinctions. Not that SABELLIUS. 161 it and revelation in general are mere subjective representation , or that, as Ebionites might suppose, the one, indivisible, divine, which in itself stands related alike to all, is unequally appre- hended by the world,—perfectly, for example, by the most vir- tuous man, Jesus. On the contrary, Sabellius recognised really different divine deeds and movements ; but because these dis- tinctions owe their existence solely to peculiarities of the world, which have not their ground in God, they are transitory, so far as the said peculiarities are transitory (Note 31); they do not contribute to the perfection of the divine essence; whereas that the silent God should speak, was necessary to the completion of the conception of God. The teachers of the Church, taking the opposite course, looked upon creation as in itself an accidental feature of the conception of God, and in no respect necessary to its complete intellection. By the Trinity, on the contrary, they deemed it to be perfected; and they would sooner have allowed, in opposition to Sabellius, that the ceconomic Trinity set forth essential momenta of the divine life itself (which, be it noted, is also of an ethical nature), than, in agreement with him, teach that the genesis of the world was the completion of God. Ath.c. Ar. 4, 11:—Odroe éXatrov TO Oeod, 7) Hyuty Sdoac. “Hyeis yap ToraKws Kal crwmdvres pcr, evOupovpevor 5é évep- youmev, WaoTe Ta éx THs evOuuncews Kab eiSwrorroLEtc ba ; these, however, rov Ocov cwwrdvra pev dvevépyntov, Nadrobvra 8é io- xveww adtov Bovrovrau eltye cuwTrav pev ovK NOUVATO TOLELV, NAN@V de xriceiy hpEato. ’Epécbat yap avtovs Sixatoy, ef 6 Néyos ev TO Oecd ov, Térev0s Hv, Sate Kal rovelv Sivacba ; Ei [eV OV ATES WV, ev Oce wv, yevynbels S8 TérEL08 ryévyoven, niLels ai'tiot THs TENELO- THTOS avTOD, eltye SL ds yeyévyntau Sv nas yap Kal TO Svva- cOat Tovey Tpoceihnder’ et 8 TEdXE105 Fv ev Oc@, Wore Kal Tovey dwvac bat, mepittiy 1) yévynots avtov, édbvato yap, Kat év matpl OV, OnLoupyev’ Hate 7) ob yeyévyntat, 4} yeyévyntat ov Ov 1uas, GAN OTe det x TOD TaTpds éoTtw. ‘H yap yévynaots avtod ov THY Nov Ktlow Seikvucw, GNA Td éx TOD Ocod eivas. This passage shows that the Sabellians spoke not merely of a Aoyos, but also of a yevvnows Tob NOyou; probably they identified this latter with the AaXetv of the Father, Like Tertullian and the Arians, they represent this yévynots as taking place before the creation of the world, nay more, as taking place for the sake of the creation. In common with the former, they assume a process of growth, VOL. I. L 162 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. a progressive hypostatization. But they differ from both in con- ceiving the yévynots, not as the origin of the hypostasis, but as the manifestation of the world-creative power. This passage, therefore, is an evidence, partly, that Monarchianism, about the year 260, had already assumed a form in many respects like the Trinity of their opponent Tertullian; and partly, also, that the Sabellians decidedly ascribed creation to the Logos. Having investigated the relation of the divine Trias to the Monas, let us now take a glance at the relation of the members of the Trias to each other. It is clear, from what has been advanced above, that, as was frequently objected by the teachers of the Church, these three were never simultaneously, and, therefore, never properly speaking, members of the Trinity. During the period when God revealed Himself as Father, the Son did not yet exist ; and during the period of the Holy Ghost, the Son and the Father no longer exist (cf. Montfaucon, Nov. Coll. T. ii. 2, Epiph. her. 62, 1; and in Athan. c. Ar. Or. 4, 12). According to Epiphanius and Theodoret (heer. fab. 2, 9; compare Germanus Constantinop. de heres. et Synodis in A. Mai, Spicileg. Roman. T. 7, 11, 12), to the Father was attri- buted legislation, to the Son the incarnation, to the Holy Ghost the inspiration of the Apostles, as also the quickening and ani- mating of believers. ‘The objective difference of these revela- tions is thus expressed and characterized with sufficient clear- ness (Note 32). But they employed two images in order to describe this relation with greater precision. Father, Son, Spirit, are analogous to body, soul, and spirit ;—the three mo- menta or modes of existence of the one man. There isa similar trinity also in the sun. Firstly, there is its form in itself, its outward appearance (cidos, ox a TaONS THS imtoo tacews, Which is to be distinguished from the imoctacts itself). This corre- sponds to the revelation of the law, which was a strange and purely objective thing; or, when the word Father is taken strictly, to the Father. Secondly, the pure disk of the sun makes its appearance for men, and enters into their sphere, in that it expands itself, as it were, to a circle of light and illumin- ates the earth. This corresponds to the revelation of the Son. Lastly, the sun penetrates into things themselves, bringing warmth and light. This corresponds to the visits of the Holy Spirit. Both images connect the individual members of the SABELLIUS. 163 ‘Trias with each other, and both imply progress ;—not, however, in the sense that those who have the Holy Spirit are more than those who have Christ; but merely in the sense, that the divine revelation or Monas penetrates ever more deeply into the exist- ing world. The progress, therefore, is on the side of men, to whom one and the same God approaches constantly nearer through His different cynuaticpods. To God Himself the Trinitarian process (dudAeEts) brings no progress. The sun does not first acquire enlightening and warming power, but has it from the beginning. Through the employment of special means (law, incarnation), the entire divinity comes ever more fully into activity. But although the entire divine essence is present in each of these oynuatiopol, each of them sets forth a different aspect of the objective divine essence, according to the requirements of men; and thus prepares the way for an in- creasing appropriation of God. This, of course, implies that the incarnation of God, for which Sabellius employs also the expression évavOpwrrnots Tob Aoyou, could merely have the significance of a means to an end in his system; and that, as such, it might cease as soon as it had accomplished that for which it was brought into existence. He did not regard the Person of Christ as an end in itself ; Christ is not the essential good, or, as Head and King, an essential part of the highest good, whose glorification we also have to subserve. But the Logos was born for our sake, and returns that He may be again as He was.!_ The reason thereof is, that the incarnation was occasioned solely by the world, and had not a necessary ground in God Himself, that is, in an inner distinc- tion of the divine essence. Such a distinction did not exist in God, prior to His appearance on earth: “Before the appearance of Christ, there was no Son, but merely the Logos; and when the Logos became flesh, not having previously been flesh, the Logos became Son, not having previously been Son” (c. Ar. 4, 1 Athan. c. Ar. 4, 12 (see following note), 4, 25:—Avayxn 0¢ xel mavbyoecbas ro bvopene Tov viod xal tov wvevmurtos, THs xpeias wAnpwOElons nol eorot Dorwov ayer Wesdices, TR yyivopeva, Ors oy AnOcie, AR Gyopears emedeixn. He goes on then to say that this is the destruction of the Church and the world. ILevomévov d¢ rod cvopartos rod viov nur avrovs, mavorrar xl rov Bantiomaros 4 xapis—xal ti axorovdyce 4 aPavic“os THS wtiaewz. The latter would be true if the world owed its existence to the Son, and not to the Logos (Note 32). 164 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. 22). The Son is an energetic, but still a transitory theophany. Sabellius must, therefore, have treated the human_aspect. of Christ as.a-mere accident; and so far from following up the efforts made by Origen, to ensure the full reality of the human- ity of Christ, by giving prominence to His soul, we do not even know whether he acknowledged Christ to have had a human soul. It is, in fact, improbable that he did; for otherwise he could not so easily have persisted in maintaining that this reve- lation would cease—and cease not merely at the end of the days, but when Christ returned to the Father, and the Holy Spirit was revealed.’ 1 Compare the passage from Epiph. in Note 29 ; Athan. c. Ar. 4, 12:=— Ey cb yeyevigades adrov txriobnusy, nol TH yEevvyoes avTod ovyeaTnney n xTiols, covert pinges 08 tux Thy OE TpoTEpoy fv.—llarrvdpomodytos Tov Advyov ovx, Umapess 4 xrlots. (For aéyov Sabellius probably said viov) ; compare c. 22, 25; Ambros. de fide 4, 6,—‘‘ ut in Patrem filius refundatur.” Montfaucon, Coll. Nov. T. ii. p. 2, in ‘‘ Eugenii Legatio ad Athan.” 2 Athan. 1. c. 20:— H oapé, nv 2Qopsaev 6 Aovyos, avrn gotly 6 vids. ib. :— Tov dvdpwrov ov ePopeoey 0 névos airov elves Agyoucs TOV viov rov Oxrov ror Lovoryzva. —_——_ SABELLIUS. 165 God or Logos,—whom this system presupposes indeed to be in Himself an intelligent subject, and nothing more than the living Monas, but without being able to enter more deeply into the question of its inner personality, in consequence of being based on the category of substance,—appeared in Christ as limited, in aman, and in this sense as a person, or as a vids; whereas as hoyos, He was not vids. If we ask then,—Does not Sabellius represent humanity as constituting the revelation in Christ per- sonal ?—we may answer both in the negative and in the posi- tive ; for, strictly speaking, both the divine and the human aspect constitute the personality, though each in a different way, or in a different sense. So far as the personality is taken to be some- thing positive, which as positive must appertain also to God, the divine is the principle of the personality of the Son; though in no other sense than that in which the personal Monas is so in itself, and in each of its revelations. So far, however, as a limit and bound is to be conceived as attaching to this positive some- thing,—and it must be allowed to attach to the human person- ality, consequently also to Christ,—so far is the humanity. of Christ that which is limited, and which, by bounding or cir- cumscribing the divine extension, constitutes it Son. The real meaning of Sabellius must therefore have been the following :— The Son resulted neither from the correspondent expansion of the Monas, nor arose solely through the man who was born of Mary; but from the conjunction of the positive and the nega- tive—a conjunction to which God gave the prime impulse. For only on the supposition that the two were in some way united, can the divine have had an historical, not merely a Docetical, existence; and the human life of Christ have been, not merely human, but of a higher significance. But if the conjunction of the two (1) dudotv cbvoSos) cou- stituted the Son, the question at once arises,—Did the divine ' This is also the actual report which Athanasius gives of the Sabellians, Lc. c. 21:—@ael wen cov dvOparrov xed’ éevrov, cv EQepscev 6 xUpios, AAC TO nuvePorepov, Tov Te Aoryou nol tov evOpwaoy, sivecs viov, cuynumeva yap &uQe- Tepe, vies, ws avrol Agyovuaty, cvomeleras. * ilar. de Trin. 1, 16 :—The Sabellian incarnation is ‘‘ protensio potius 166 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. existent world exercised an influence on God, and inasmuch as God Himself is present in His extensions, made God passible, or limited Him. This would involve attributing a false inde- pendence to the world, relatively to God, such as might har- monize with a deistic or an ethnic mode of thought, but not with Sabellianism. He must, therefore, have regarded this limitation, in which the Person of Christ originated, as itself again a deed of the Logos. It was by His own act that the Logos subjected Himself to limits and bounds, though He employed the world as a means; and the world could not have possessed the power to be a limit to God, save through God Himself. If, however, God posits limitation in Himself, and yet, on the other hand, the entire divine Monas is not absorbed in this oynwatapos,— because, although in itself indeed it is entirely therein, actually it is only therein in one aspect,—then a distinction is introduced. into the inner essence of God, and the Monas must have posited in itself the determination through which it became Son. This limit now might be constituted by the principle of the Ay in Christ, which would be transferred to God with a touch of dualism. Christ’s humanity must then be judged to have been protruded from God’s own essence, as the material circumscrip- tion of His spiritual éxraous; but this would be incompatible with the human birth of Christ, which Sabellius leaves un- touched, and would lead back to the doctrine that God converted Himself into the man Jesus. Such a view Sabellius can have had no wish to adopt, inasmuch as he rejected what the earlier teachers of his tendency allowed, to wit, that God underwent suffering.! Consequently, unless he meant to sink back to a deistic or to a patripassian conception of God, it was necessary for him to suppose the distinction, by which God constituted in hominem, quam descensio.” In order that the unity of God may remain: unaffected by the “series ex solido in carnem deducta, dum usque ad vir- ginem Pater protensus ipsi sibi natus sit in Filium,”’ that is, in order that God extending Himself as in an unbroken line might stretch Himself even unto Mary. Ib. 1, 26:—Sabellius—‘‘ Deum verum operatum in corpore esse non ambigit.” 1 Augustine, indeed, brings this charge also against him. But as Epi- phanius (heer. 62) expressly pronounces him innocent thereof, which he would not have done had he not been necessitated thereto, we must take for granted that Sabellius did not belong to the Patripassians, but forms a new knotty point in their series. SABELLIUS. 167 Himself Son, to have been effected independently of all orn, whether in or out of God; that is, he must have supposed it to take place in the spiritual essence of God, in harmony with the doctrine of the Church. The only other alternative was, to lower the significance of Christ, and no longer to maintain that the positive something above referred to, and the basis of the personality of the Son, were the Monas itself (Note 33). But if the distinctions fall into the essence of God, they cannot have been successive, nor are they ephemeral, but must be simul- taneous, as the Church teaches. Even at this point, therefore, we see that Sabellius cannot maintain his position. This will become still clearer, when we consider the opposite conclusions which may be drawn from his system. In point of fact, there is by no means a lack of elements of an Ebionitical cast in the system of Sabellius. The one point alone, that he reduces the revelation of Christ to the rank of a mere means, and does not also regard Him as an end in Him- self, is a degradation of Him, which approximates to Ebionism. If we remark further, that he designates the divine in the Son a ray (deriva), which proceeds forth from, and returns to, the Monas,—for which reason, besides the common charge of con- founding everything together, founded on his merging the hypostatic distinctions into the one hypostasis of the Father or the Monas, we find also the opposite charge of falsely sepa~ rating (aroxo7) and dividing the divine essence, which neces- sarily leads to Subordinatianism or to the Hellenic form of Ebionism (Note 34) ;—if, finally, we consider how difficult for him, who refused to admit of any distinctions in God, must have been the question, whether the entire God was so present in the Son, that during His existence He was not active outside of Him ;—we can well understand how he should again seek for expressions to lessen the importance of the revelation of the Son, and thus allow Ebionitical principles to gain a foothold. An intensive interest in religion might, indeed, have preserved him from such a false course; but, however coarse Patripassianism may have been in this respect, it was superior to Sabelliamism. The latter was not a deepening of the interest in religion: on the contrary, its greater refinement seems to have been accom- panied by religious superficiality ; for if we ask what Sabellius supposed Christ to have accomplished, no passage can be 168 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. pointed out in which the Passion of Christ is made the sub- ject of consideration. In agreement with Patripassians, on the contrary, he appears in general to have formed a slight estimate of the significance of the sufferings of the God-man, even when he did not set them aside, and to have limited Christ’s work principally to enlightenment and sanctification. This, at all events, seems to be implied by his employment of the image of the sun, and by his remarks on the activity of the warming and enlivening Holy Spirit. Yet all this pertains to Sabellianism, as it were, contrary to its will, and in simple obedience to the law which binds extremes together—in the present case, the extremes of Ebionism and Docetism. It is interesting to take note of these Ebionitical features of the system, in order to see the comparatively short step from Sabellius to Paul of Samosata. Both agree in deny- ing the pre-existence of the Son, and indeed the existence of hypostatical distinctions in generalin God. ‘They further agree also in their recognition of the distinction of the manifest and revealed God, alongside of His unity. The silent Monas of Sabellius answers to the Adyos évdudGeros of Paul; the speaking, or the Logos of the former, to the Aéyos mpofoptxos of the latter. And although Paul took the world for his point of view, and Sabellius the divine, they approximate to each other, in so far as Paul, on the one hand, conceives a divine power, even though impersonal, to have been at work in the man Jesus; and on the other hand, Sabellius, although he had no ‘intention of denying the humanity of Jesus, did not really advance beyond a determinate and momentary exhibition of the power of God in Him (a stretching out of the hand of God), It is true he believed the entire God Himself to have been pre- ‘sent in the exhibition of power, after a determinate manner ; but neither this presence nor its particular character was grounded in inner distinctions of the divine essence; the occa- sion thereto was given entirely by the world; and as far as concerns God, it was solely His will, receiving its impulse from the world, and not His own essence, that called into existence the triple revelation, which is unquestionably to be termed a manifestation, a coming forth, of His essence. That which He wills in revealing, He also, it is true, becomes: His deed 1s also being, self-unfolding, but merely momentary being, and DEFECTS OF SABELLIANISM. 169 has solely the purpose of communicating to humanity that which it lacked." The needs of the humanity having been met, it lives in unity with the indivisible Monas, and the Monas in unity with it: Christ henceforth has no significance whatever, nor even a bare existence. To represent Christ.as transitory, as a mere passing means to another end, contradicted the Christian consciousness in its very depths. For the Person of Christ does not stand in a temporary relation to the religion He founded, as do the founders of other religions, but is an eternally constitutive and integrant element thereof ; and even the view taken by Paul of ‘Samosata was more satisfactory in this respect, for he assigned to the man Jesus a permanent position, nay more, in reward .for his virtue, a divine position after His exaltation. Whilst ‘Sabellius taught that humanity would one day become the body of God, through the Holy Spirit, apart from the Person of Christ (see Note 31), Paul, on the contrary, left a place for Christ as the eternal Head of humanity. Herewith, however, is most closely connected something of still greater importance. Sabellianism could not look upon humanity and. deity as_re- conciled and united at the very centre; and as to this matter, Paul and Sabellius occupy exactly the same position, though they arrive at it from opposite-directions. Paul represents the humanity of Christ as the final cause of the deity which he at- tributes to Him; the divine, therefore, was an accident of the man Jesus. Savalling reduces the humanity to an accident; it is curtailed and made transitory. But an union with an hu- 1 The charge repeatedly brought by Athanasius against Sabellius, of recognising merely distinctions xer éx/vomy, that is, distinctions which are purely subjective, must consequently be explained in the light of what has been advanced above. Sabellius aimed to represent God as objectively dif- ferent in His different revelations. He believed the divine communications to have as true an objective existence as the human needs. But it is un- mistakeable, that if Sabellius had rigidly insisted on the indivisible unity of the Monas relatively to the sphere of revelation, he could not have be- lieved that the different revelations were objectively different. In itself, and considered in relation to God, legislation and incarnation were one and the same, that is, the absolutely identical Monas was in both. This conse- quence, however, as we have seen, Sabellius does not draw. And he con- sidered to be subjective representation, rpoawxoroi«, not the difference in the revelations themselves, but merely the hypostatic difference of the principle in each case. 170 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. manity which is an illusion, is itself an illusion. Consequently, according to the Sabellian view, that which is of the highest importance, that for which there is the greatest need, has not been effected. From the stand-point of Sabellianism, so long as humanity and deity in Christ are represented as standing in so exclusive a relation to each other, it is impossible to designate Christianity the absolute religion, especially when we remember that it leaves the rest of men but one choice, the choice, namely, between an impersonal existence and an imperfect union with God. Instead of regarding the appearance of Christ as a mere momentary exhibition of divine power, the Christian Church sees in Him the eternal centre of regenerated humanity, in and through whom God is personally and actually united with men. It was compelled, therefore, to ground the divine in Christ in the eternal essence of God; and the category of the will of God showed itself to be inadequate. But if there is an eternal element in God Himself corresponding to the divine in Christ, and if the divine in Christ is not to be placed under the category of power, but under that of hypostasis, then the distinction between the divine in Christ, or the Son, and the Father, must be posited as simultaneous and eternal, and the polemic of the Church will, in this aspect, lay special stress upon the doctrine, that the divine which was in Christ was the pre-existent Son and a permanent hypostasis. As regards the other, the task of the Church would be to assert the full truth of the human aspect. During an entire century, however, this aspect was thrown into the background relatively to the former. In fact, the question of the Trinity, which engaged the attention of the entire succeeding period, was absolutely necessary as a basis for the accomplishment of the other task. For full justice can never be done to the humanity in Christology, until the self-limitation, the self-exinanition of God be recognised; but how could such an idea be seriously entertained, where the absolute unity of the divine Monas is maintained, and where, consequently, the entire Monas must thus abase itself? The chief opponent of Sabellius, Dionysius of Alexandria, of the two chief defects of Sabellianism,—to wit, that it did not recognise the truth of the humanity, and therefore arrived at no real incarnation, and that it could not characterize the divine PIERIUS. PHOTIUS 171 in Christ as an eternal determination of the essence of God,— appears to have taken notice almost solely of the latter. In- deed, the designation of the humanity of Christ as a mere gar- ment, was long employed by the teachers of the Church without giving offence. And when Origen attempted to attain to a higher point by giving prominence to the free human soul of Christ, he did not succeed in lis aim without making a step in the direction of Ebionism. Paul, however, to whom, be it re- membered, this inheritance descended, and by whom it was increased, only served the purpose of causing the teachers of the Church to shrink from giving prominence to the free human soul of Christ. This aspect of the dogma, therefore, was left entirely untouched for the time; for, in fact, its day could not arrive until the necessary trinitarian presuppositions had been settled, the uncertainty of which laid open to question the very primary, that is, the objective, divine, foundations of Christology. CHAPTER THIRD. THE SCHOOL OF ORIGEN IN THE THIRD CENTURY, AND THE SUBORDINATIANISM OF DIONYSIUS OF ALEXANDRIA. BrrorE passing to the consideration of Dionysius of Alex- andria, the most important follower of Origen, a few particulars must be mentioned, relative to the school of Origen in general. A great number of the first men of the East, during the second half of the third century, was educated by Origen, or by his writings. Apart from the exegetical schools of Egypt and Antioch, whose rise appears to have been due to his influence, and which were formed by Hesychius on the one hand, and Lucian and Dorotheus on the other (compare Neander’s “Church History” ii. 1247), except Methodius, who at a later period became an opponent of Origen, we may enumerate, in this connection, Gregorius Thaumaturgus, and his brother Athenodorus; Pierius, with his brother Isidorus (Phot. Cod. 119), and Theognostus (cod. 106). Hierakas, also, was deci- sively influenced by Origen. At the beginning of the fourth century, we may mention Pamphilus and Eusebius of Ceesarea. v7 yp. FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. It is not just, with Baur (1. c. p. 308 f.), to describe the en- tire school of Origen as subordinatian, in relation to the Son; still less is it just to charge them with letting go the predicate of Kternity. Respecting Pierius, who was styled a second Origen, Photius relates, that he taught evce8ads concerning the Father and the Son; and that, although in one passage he termed them two ovcias or ices, instead of two hypostases, he did not use the terms in the Arian sense, as is clear from that which precedes and that which follows (7@ tis ovcias Kal dicews ovopatt, ws Ofjrov &k Te TOY éromevav Kal Tponyoupévov Tod Xoplov, avtt THs UTocTdcews ypwpevos). The honour and dis- honour of the image (e/xwv), he considered to be also the honour and dishonour of the prototype. The Holy Ghost, however, he subordinated to the glory of the Father and the Son. Had Pierius denied the eternal generation of the Son, Photius would not have failed to charge him with it. There must have been a ground for the praise which he bestows on his doctrine of the Son. Least of all is it likely that he classed him amongst those who repeated the subordinatian element in Origen’s system in a heightened form. The subordination of the Holy Spirit, at that time, does not warrant us in concluding that the Son also was sabordinated :—indeed, Photius expressly contradicts it. For when he blames him as dvaceBds Soypari- Covra, on account of the subordination of the Holy Ghost, and praises his doctrine of the Son as edce8H, the praise must be grounded on the circumstance, that he did not subordinate the Son. And as he elsewhere reproaches Origen with subordinat- ing the Son, it would seem probable that Pierius further de- veloped rather that part of the system of Origen, which taught the equality of the Father and the Son, than that which bore a subordinatian character. According to Basilius (Ep. 210), the same line was adopted by another important disciple of Origen, Gregorius Thaumaturgus, who was even reproached with confounding Father and Son, after the manner of Sabel- lius.". In his panegyric of Origen (c. 4.), he designates the Logos the Source of all good, who alone can heal our defects, who is the Guide and Deliverer of our souls, the Creator and Ruler of the universe. In relation to the Father, he terms Him the rpwroyerns Adyos Tod matpos: He Himself is the truth, the * Basil. Ep. 210, 5,—seeréooe nal viv rivole dv elves d00, Uxoardocs 08 Ev. THEOGNOSTUS. Lid copia, and the dyvayus of the Father of the universe. Besides this, He is in Him, and completely united with Him, not atreEevrysevos avtTov, not too weak to attain to the Father; for which reason, it is wrong to suppose that He either cannot or will not lead everything to the praise of the Father; whereas, in fact, He alone can give to the Father the most perfect honour, on His own behalf, and on behalf of all things. For the Father has made Him one with Himself; so that we may almost say that the Father, through Him, goes out of Himself, in order to embrace and encompass Himself (8? avdtod povov ovyt avTos avtov (leg. abtov) éxmrepi@y), and to a certain extent holds Him in like honour with Himself, and is held in like honour. Himself, therefore, being perfect and living, and ani- mated by the highest reason (tod mp@tov vod dOyos Euauyos av), He fits us completely for presenting worthy sacrifices of thanksgiving to God. That this is far enough removed from Arianism is self-evident, notwithstanding the decided colouring of Subordinatianism. He does not reckon Him as part of the Universe, but represents the Father, after having gone out of Himself, as it were, through the living Logos, as embracing Himself in the Logos. He terms Him further, indeed, accord- ing to Basilius, woipa and xticua; but this must not be so interpreted as to invalidate his previous statements. That he cannot have taught that the Son was of a different substance from the Father, is evident also from his being regarded as a patron of the Sabellians. He probably used these words in agreement with Proverbs vili., without intending thereby to call in question Origen’s doctrine of the procession of the Son from God, by generation. It is probable, therefore, that, like his-master, he combined emanatistic and subordinatian elements in his system (Note 35). Theognostus endeavoured, in his “ Hypotyposes” (vzotvu- mooes, adumbrationes), to show that the Father.must-have a Son, as also that we must conceive a Holy Spirit." In the second discourse, he designates the Son a «ticua; for which Photius blames him severely; but as the work appears to have been written in the form of a dialogue, and as, according to 1 Athan. de decret. syn. Niczen. c. 25; Phot. Cod. 106.—Athan. Ep. 4 ad Serap. c. 9, 11, he speaks against the supra-ordination of the Holy Spirit above the Son. | 174 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. Photius, in the last conversation, especially towards the close, he speaks more worthily of the Son, we may probably regard the idea, which suggested itself also to Photius, as well grounded, namely, that Theognostus wrote the passages which put the Son on a lower level, not in his own name, but in the person of another. But even if this were not the case, Proy. viii. would prevent us allowing the words any weight, in opposition to the passage which Athanasius has preserved, and which is also found in the second book of his d7otut@ces. “The essence of the Son,” says he, “was not superadded from without (ov« &€wbev ths dot éehevpebetca % Tod viod ovola), nor was it intro- duced out of nothing, that is, into the Trinity (o0d€ é« un dvtmpy éretony On), but was produced out of the essence of the Father (ex Ths Tod TaTpos odcias épu, @s TO pwTOos TO aTAVYAT LA, WS iSatos atuts), as brightness arises from light, and as vapour arises from water. The brightness is not the sun, nor the vapour the water; nor, again, is it anything foreign, but an amoppova, an outflow from the Father’s essence; which notwithstanding no more undergoes division than the sun, which remains the same, and is not lessened by pouring forth rays. Even so, the essence of the Father undergoes no alteration through having the Son for His image.” Here, therefore, we find those eman- atistic comparisons which Origen also employed, and which in his case were compatible with a certain degree of Subordina- tianism. But we find no trace whatever of Arianism, of a sur- render of the doctrine of the eternal generation of the Son. From Arianism Theognostus is far removed, not merely by his doctrine of the essential equality of the Son, but also by his re- jection of the idea that the Son was in any sense a mundane being: on the contrary, he polemicizes against those who repre- sented the Son as having been produced out of nothing,—a doctrine which became a watchword of the Arians at a later period! Besides Athanasius, Titus of Bostra also (Phot. Cod. 232), together with the two Gregories, held Theognostus in high 1 According to Photius, he did not assume the existence of an eternal ian, and cannot therefore have taught that the world was formed out of a San in God, that is, out of the substance of God. Consequently, in this respect also, it must have been impossible for him to put the Son on an equality with the world. Agreeably to the prevailing views of the time, he believed the world to have been created out of nothing. METHODIUS 175 honour. It would be interesting to know how he proved that the Father must have a Son. ‘The very idea of such a proof, however, shows that he did not regard the existence of the Son as in any respect a matter of caprice or accident. What he then says concerning the essence of the Son, warrants us in pre- suming, that he aimed at discovering some sort of a necessity for a Son in the divine essence itself. If this be the case, he clearly cannot have given up the doctrine of the eternal gene- ration of the Son. Christology must have been treated by him in detail, for th fifth and sixth sections of his “ Hypotyposes” are devoted to the question of the incarnation of the Son. Photius found therein many Origenistic elements, which he deemed it proper to blame; but, as the worst point of all, he mentions his doc- trine respecting the real omnipresence of Christ.’ He is said to have taken special pains to demonstrate the possibility of an incarnation. Methodius of Patara (compare his Opp. ed. Combefis. Paris, 1644, pp. 284-474), in his genuine writings, so far as we can ete from the fragments still extant, did not indeed apply the term ouoovctos to the pre-existent ce as did the Roman Synod (I consider the work entitled “ De Sym. et Anna” to be spurious) ; but still, probably accepted the doctrine of His eter- nal pre-existence, though not in the Origenistic form of eternal generation. He did not adopt Origen’s explanation of the words, “ This day have I begotten Thee,’ denoting the eternal to-day; but substituted for it another, to wit,—God willed to generate Him who was before the Alons, for the world also; that is, to reveal Him (1. c. 388,—rTov mpodvta dn mpd TeV aievey €v Tots ovpavois éBovAnOny Kal TO KOcUm@ yervncaL 0 OH éoTt, Tpoabev: ayvootjpuevov yvwpicat). His teachings appear to have much greater affinity with those of Tertullian and Hippo- lytus. ‘There still remains between them, however, this impor- tant difference, that whereas the latter represented the hypo- stasis of the Son as originating contemporaneously with the creation of the world, and accordingly attached the highest significance to the matter of generation, relatively to the Son Himself, Methodius, on the contrary, made the entire signifi- 1 "Aroronpey Agvet ort tov vidv Davralcpeeber hAnoTE Ey KAAS TYTOLS TEBE ypaDopeevoy, poovn Of TH Evepyeig po TepiryouPdpevoy. 176 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. cance of the yévynois for the Son, to consist in its revealing Him to the world (probably in Christ) ; whilst He remained in Himself unchangeably what He was before the AZons. Christ did not first become Son at His baptism by adoption; nor will a time ever come when He will cease to be Son, but He is Son out of the limits of time, timelessly (dopictws, aypoves, p. 387). Of the words, “In the beginning (év apyn) God created the heavens and the earth,” his explanation is, that apy7 is the divine wisdom. In harmony herewith, as with Prov. viii. 22, 1s John i. 1. For the ’Apy, out of which the Aoyos grew, is the Father (ryv pev yap apynv.ad? ts aveBAdorncev 0 opGoratos Aéyos, Tov ILatépa Kal Troumtiy TdV bdoV Payer €v @ Hv). On the contrary, the words,—“ The same was in the beginning (ép apy) with God,”—signify that the Son shared the dominion with God (7d é£ovcractixov Tod Adyou, 0 cixe mapa Te Iarpt Kal po Tod Tov KOcpoV eis yeveow TapehOelv, EorKe onpaweL, tiv éLovolav apyiy eirwv). After the beginningless beginning, the Father, He therefore becomes the beginning of the rest, through which all things were made (Ov«odv APXNs META TID idiav avapyov apXnV, TOV IIatépa avtos Tov dArd@v yiverat, Ov fis Grravra Snucoupyetras, |. c. 345). If the Son be said to be produced from the Father, the equality of His vous, His co- essentiality, is affirmed in the strongest manner, Still, the pas- sage adduced does not altogether exclude the possibility of Sub- ordinatianism. 'The Son is not, indeed, said to have owed His origin to the will of the Father; but, at the same time, He is not said to have been coeternal with God. The highest predicate assigned to the Son, according to p. 388, is that of aypovos; the predicate dvapyos is reserved for the Father. We must not, however, conclude therefrom, that he meant to teach regarding the Son, jv te ovx Fv, for apyiy does not necessarily denote origin in time (otherwise the word would be used in the context alternately in three different senses), but denotes the real ground:—the Father alone is the pifa of the Son. Another passage also admits of being interpreted subordinatianally ; though that is not necessarily its meaning :—De Creat. p. 344 ; “There are two creating powers: one which produces whatever it wills out of nothing, by its mere will,—this is the Father; the second, on the contrary, which, in imitation of what already ex- ists, and gives to the world its beauty, order, and variety, 1s the DIONYSIUS OF ALEXANDRIA. 177 Son, the Father’s almighty and strong hand, by which He estab- lishes beauty and order, after having called matter into exist- ence, out of nothing.” (Avo é Suvdpeus Edapev eivat, TountiKas, TH && ovK dvTwD, YEVO TH Bovdyjpari, yopls pepicod dua Td (leg. TO) Ochjcas adbroupyotcay, 5 Bobreras Tro.ely" Tuyyaver Oé 0 matip’ Odrepov S& Kataxocpodcay Kad croiktdroveup KaTa hipnow Ths mpotépas ta iSy yeyovota. gore dé 6 vids 4 Tavto- dvvapos Kal Kpatad XElp TOD Tarpds, &v H peta TH Tovhoar THV vAnv €& ov dvtwv xataxoopet.) When, therefore, Photius speaks of Arian adulterations by Methodius, what has been ad- vanced above shows that they are, at all events, not discoverable in the fragments now extant. As to Christology, he refers the bride (“ Song of Songs” iv. 7), amongst other things, to the humanity of Christ, for the sake of which He left the Father and came to the world, to bestow Himself upon her (the vdudy is the capE dpudduwtos Tod Kuplov, Fs Xapw Kataretbas Tov Tatépa kath rGev évradba Ka) TpoTeKOAAHON adTH évavOpwmycas, pp- 386 f.). Further, the queen who is placed at the right hand (Ps. xlv.), whilst God actually places Himself at the left, is the humanity of Christ adorned with virtue, as with a gar- ment worked with gold, the unspotted blessed flesh, which the Logos carried with Him into heaven, and set at the right hand of the Father. The genuine fragments in our possession do not contain more precise ideas on the subject of Christology: one thing only deserves mention, that in the Sympos. Virg. p. 392, Christ is styled the Archetype of virginity. In the work en- titled “De Sym. et Anna,” the high estimate here put on vir- ginity has already been developed into the doctrine of the eternal virginity of Mary. With Dionysius of Alexandria (about a.D. 200) the case is otherwise than with the last-mentioned writers. That he was far from entertaining Ebionitical views, indeed, is clear from his relation to the First Antiocheian Council held against Paul of Samosata.! But it can scarcely be denied, that, for a time, the zeal with which he opposed the Sabellians, and endeavoured to lay down fixed distinctions between the Father and the Son, carried him to greater lengths in the matter of Subordinatianism, than those to which Origen went. In a letter to Ammonius * Euseb. H. E. 7, 27, 80. init, but specially from 7, 6. VUL. 11. M 172 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. and Euphranor against Sabellianism, which had spread se widely in Libya, that several bishops became its adherents, and the Son of God was scarcely preached any longer in the Church,’ he said,—‘ The Son is a work and a creature of God, not ap- pertaining to Him by nature, but in his essence as foreign to God as the vinedresser is to the vine, the shipbuilder to the ship ; for, inasmuch as he was a creature, he did not exist prior to his creation.” (Athan. 1. c. 4:—IToiqpa kat ryeVNTOV €lval TOV ULOV rod Ocod, ponte && dvoe iSav, ddrda Eevov KaT ovolay avTov elvan Tod TaTpos BoTep EoTW O yewpyos Tpos THY GLTENOV, KAL O vauTrnyos Tpos TO cKapos. Kai yap ws Tolnua, @v ovK Hv TpwW yévntat.) He therewith attacks, consequently, both the doc- trine of the eternal generation of the Son taught by Origen and his school, and also that of the equality of the essence of the Father andthe Son. Athanasius would fain, indeed, refer these words to the God-man, instead of to the Logos. In fact, on a sub- sequent occasion, Dionysius himself took partial advantage of this expedient :” for in the same passage of his later work, he deemed it necessary to justify his employment of those words, relatively to the Logos. But when he pleads that the Greeks were in the habit of styling the authors of books and the originators of ideas, their creators, although, strictly speaking, the writer or the thinker is their father, he is far from being excused; for the latter image is also subordinatian in tendency. Least of all does he thus justify the words—“ He was not, ere He was brought into existence ;” and there is scarcely a hair’s-breadth between them and the Shibboleth of Arianism. Still less can the excuse pleaded by Athanasius be accepted, namely,.that he did not intend to lay down a positive confession regarding Christ in that letter, but merely to.controvert Sabellianism.; that, for this reason, he simply laid. down the opposite view with all possible emphasis, and by means of the passages of Scripture, which teach that Christ thirsted, hungered, suffered, prayed to the Father, and so forth, endeavoured to force from his_op- 1 Athan. de sententia Dionysil, c. 5. 21. ¢, 20,22. He might avail himself of the expedient, with some show of justice, relatively also to the image of the vintner and the vine, which is evidently borrowed from the Scriptures, where it bears upon the relation of the Father to the God-man. His words, however, clearly referred the images to the pre-existent Son (see the quotation given in the text). DIONYSIUS OF ALEXANDRIA. | 179 ponents, the recognition of the personality of the Son, in dis- tinction from that of the Father. It is true, indeed, that the Church was led to acknowledge the necessity of a distinction of God from God, by the person of the historical Christ. Buta man who, in his polemic against others, himself assailed the true deity of the Son (as he did in that concluding proposition), cannot have reserved for himself the right of positively confess- ing that deity, as Athanasius appears to take for granted. What he had to do, was simply to retract; and an open con- fession, that his polemical zeal had carried him away into false statements, would only have done him honour. But however decidedly this is to be acknowledged, some excuse must still be discoverable for the omission of this con- fession, by aman of a so decidedly honourable a character. His mind was directed more to the practical than to the speculative ; and, whilst possessed of a healthy feeling for the actual, he was endowed with but asmall measure of scientific acuteness : hence, he did not fully grasp the consequences of the principles he laid down. Further, when we compare him with Arius, there can be no doubt that, in the main, his tendency and intention were very different from that of Arius. “Si duo faciunt idem, non est idem.” The principle referred to, which formed the central and main feature of the Arian system, did not hold that position in the system of Dionysius; but was a wrong and premature deduction from the distinction which must be allowed to exist between the Father and the Son. He had no interest in deny- ing the reality of the deity of the Son ; and the actual infringe- ment upon it, with which he is chargeable, was an unconscious one. In the very same letter in which he drew that Arian conclusion, he laid down completely contradictory principles. Instead of the words, £évov tis ovcias Tod matpos, we find again the old image of the fountain and the stream, of the root and the stem (de sent. Dion. c. 18), and the new one of parent and child (de decr. Nic. Syn. 25); which decidedly imply the essential equality of the Son and the Father. It was possible for him, therefore, with some show of justice, to complain that his opponents had given a distorted version of his views. For, said he, they quote the first-mentioned words as expressive of my full and real views; whereas, those comparisons, as being imperfect. I merely threw out in passing; and the more apt 180 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. ones, such as those just mentioned, I treated in detail. In that therefore he did not feel the contradictions of his letter, it was the more necessary distinctly to charge him with his lack of doc- trinal clearness, rendering him as it did, first incautious, and afterwards too ready to give way, and preventing him from seeing plainly that, as to the doctrinal principles actually laid down, if not as to his inmost meaning and tendencies, he had gone over to another point of view ;—to confess which, would have been his duty, had he been capable of thinking with greater precision and acuteness. By the letter to Ammonius and Euphranor he was unable to. convince his opponents, as in the Nepotian controversy : on the contrary, Sabellians must have been confirmed in their own view, when they found that the view taken by their antagonist led to such results. His letter, in fact, did awaken opposition in the minds of some non-Sabellians; and some of them travelled to Rome for the purpose of laying the matter before the Dionysius there. Besides what has been just mentioned, they complained that he declined to term the Son equal in essence with the Father (ouoovcwos). In his reply to this charge, the Alexandrian Dionysius (a7roroyla Kal édeyyos) says,—It is not correct to charge him with rejecting this word (c. 20). He states, that though he could not find the word in the Scriptures, he did find the sense; and with this sense his own opinion harmonized. With the greatest distinctness, he then declares that he viewed the Father as the eternal light, and the Son as the equally eternal brightness ; because there cannot be light without brightness. He calls the Logos an adméppora of God, as truly of like sub- stance with Him as a human son is of like substance with his father (c. 22). When he says, the Father created al] things, he does not mean to reduce the Son to the rank of a creature, but the Son is posited and meant along with and in the Father ; that is, the word Father he considered to be of significance, not merely in relation to mundane beings, but also in relation to the divine nature itself (c. 15-21). In the main, therefore, he returns to the doctrine of Origen, as regards the eternity and essential equality of the Son. Nay more; Origen, as we have seen, was never able to lay down this essential equality with distinctness, because the incommunicable *Ov always ap- peared to him to be the properly divine; whereas Dionysius, in DIONYSIUS OF ALEXANDRIA. 181 entire agreement with his more practical point of view, seems to have been no longer confused by the distinction between the*Ov and the do€a of God (Note 36). On the contrary, he believed the Father to be the root of all deity ; that is, actually commu- nicable as respects His @eorns. If Origen said,—The Son is the Will, proceeding forth from the divine vods ; so Dionysius designates the Father the Xoyos éyxeipevos, the necessarily and self-existent Reason, the Son, Adyos rpomndav, the self-objec- tifying Reason, the self-manifesting Word, in which Reason is inmanent,—the former, indeed, being the appearance of the latter (c. 23, Note 37). But as the Father and the Son are inseparable and indivisible from each other (dyépeotor dd.at- petot), even so is in their hands the Spirit ; which can neither be emptied of Him who sends it, nor of Him who is its vehicle and bearer (c. 19). 182 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. SECTION III. THE CHURCH’S CONFESSION OF THE ETERNAL HYPOSTASIS OF THE SON, AND OF HIS ESSENTIAL EQUALITY WITB THE FATHER, AT THE COUNCIL OF NICA. CHAPTER FIRST. THE CONTROVERSY PRELIMINARILY CARRIED ON WITH SABELLIANISM AND SUBORDINATIANISM. Tur Roman Bishop Dionysius (see Athanas. de decret. Nic. Synod. c. 26) had informed the Alexandrian Bishop of the charges brought against him by several African bishops. He convened also a Synod in Rome, with the general tenor of whose conclusions we are acquainted: Athan. de Synodis, c. 49, Ard twov aitiacapévov Tapa TO érioxoTr@ Peps Tov THs ’AnreLavSpelas éricKoTrov, @S Ayovta Tolnwa Kal put) OmoovaLOY rov viov TO TaTpl, 1) MEV KATA ‘Padpny avvodos nyavaKTncey, O Sé rhs ‘Pdyns érickotros THY TaVT@V yveuny ypaper mpos TOV duovopov éavtod. Besides this, he appears to have written a work under the title "Avatpomi etc., of which Athanasius has preserved a tolerably large fragment (de decr. Nic. Syn. 26). In this work, he first attacks the Sabellians, and tlien those who distinguish and cut up the povapyia into three powers and divided hypostases, or beings (Wesen), and divinities (SvarpouvTas Kay KATATEMVOVTAS Kab GVALPOUVTAS Thy wovapylay eis Tpels SUVa- els TWWas Kad pemeplopévas UTOGTATELS Kat Oedrntas Tpels: ib., Eévas ddd jAaLS Kal TaYTATATL Keyopiopévas). can scarcely go with Neander, when he asserts the inaccuracy of the statement of the Roman Dionysius, that such doctrines were taught by some in Africa (“ Church History” 2, 1045). tis not at all improbable in itself, that, during this trinitarian century, the feeling of the DIONYSIUS OF ROME. 183 necessity of a Trinity, which then possessed the Church so strongly, and which sought satisfaction in all possible directions, may have led some to the verge of Tritheism: and this passage gives us a hint, where those who gave way to such a tendency are tobe sought. It isa modified form of Marcionitism, adapted to the striving after a doctrine of the Trinity which characterized this century, that here presents itself to us. To Marcion’s God of legislation, and to the God of incarnation, there was added, at this time, the Holy Spirit. If we note further, as did the Roman Dionysius, that the Sabellians were intent above all things on the assertion of the divine unity, whereas these Tri- theists had landed in a triplicity of principles, we shall agree with him in judging them to be diametrically opposed to each other. At the same time, this does not prevent us seeing that there is a connection between the two. We found above (see Note 34, and the passage to which it relates, page 167), that when the Sabellians tried to maintain the newness of the objec- tive revelation in Christ—a point to which Marcion attached prime importance—or, as we are now in a position to say, when they yielded to the trinitarian impulse of their age, they actually might be easily led to the topats, duaipéceow, arroppoiats, with which Theodoret reproaches them. The Arians, too, almost constantly charge the Sabellians with dividing the divine unity (Note 38); and Athanasius and Hilary partially follow their example; so that it is not improbable, that in Africa Marcion- itism and Sabellianism were so commingled, that the entire divine essence was, strictly speaking, held to be compounded of these principles. After pronouncing an adverse judgment on the Sabellian doctrine, the Roman Dionysius passes on to the consideration of the doctrine of the Alexandrian Bishop (without, however, men- tioning his name), the natural tendency of which was to reduce the Son to the rank of a mundane being. If the Son were born (yevnros), if we may say that He was formed and created, then there must have been a time when as yet He was not. He was, however, always in the Father (who can never have been with- out power and wisdom), as His power and wisdom (Note 39). Of this absurd consequence, that the Father was once without Son, those, he goes on to say, appear to have taken no notice, who term the Son a creature («ticua). They do not under- 184 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. stand Proverbs viii. 22—“The Lord created me as (geschagfen als) the beginning of His ways’—aright; for the passage refers to the dominion transferred over created things; and other passages which speak of the generation of the Son ought to be compared. His view of the true doctrine of the Church, which preserves equally the divine Trinity and the holy procla- mation of the divine povapyia, he expresses in the following words :—“ With the God of the universe, the divine Logos must necessarily be united; but in God, the Holy Spirit also must be and dwell. But now the divine Trias must needs again be combined and summed up in one, as in a head, that is, I mean, in the Almighty God of the universe.” (De decr. Nic. 26: —Hvicbat yap avayxn TO Oc@ TAv OdNev Tov Ociov Noyou" Ewht- Aoxwpely 5E7O Oc@ Kat evdiaTao Oar Set TO Gyrov veda’ HON Kat Tv Oelav Tpidda eis Eva Barre els KopupHy Tiva (TOV Ocov THY Ov TOV TravToKpaTopa Néyw) cUyKEparaovabal Te Kail cuvdyerOaL maca avayKn. Mapkiwvos yap tod watatoppovos Sidaypa, eis Tpets apyas Ths povapylas Tounv Kat Siaipecw (sc. elapepovTos), K.T-A.) Dionysius of Alexandria trod so closely in the footsteps of this significant statement, in his Defence, that the formula itself is legible out of the main position which he lays down. “So we unfold,” says he, “ the indivisible Monas into a Trias, and sum the Trias up again, undiminished, in the Monas (es 77v wovdda ovyxeparatovucba, de Sent. Dionys.17).’ The utmost differ- ence between the two is, that the Alexandrian Dionysius gives more decided expression to the distinction than is given to it by the formula of the Roman Bishop; and that, further, the former allows the hypostasis of the Father more distinctly to predominate, if, as is probable, he assigned to the Monas the place of the Father. It is possible, however, that the Roman understood by xopudy) the Father, and that the entire divine sphere presented itself to his mind under the image of a triangle, whose uppermost angle is the Father.’ 1 The other view would be,—The three constitute the one Almighty God, concentring in Him, as different lines converge in one point or in one centre. On this view, as well as on the other, the distinctions are taken for granted, that is, the existence of a Trinity is presupposed; and then steps are taken to combine them. In the latter case, however, the three are and remain completely co-ordinated, which was not as yet the case even in the system of Athanasius. LATIN CHURCH. 185 One might almost wish, with Neander, that Dionysius of Alexandria had not so soon given way, but that the struggle which so nearly awaited the Church, and of which a feeble pre- lude occurred even in the third century, had been fought out peacefully and thoroughly between men of like spirit such as these. Not merely single individuals, however, but the Church as a whole, was destined to take part in the great work, in order that the knowledge which should finally result from bringing the discerpted elements into the fullest antagonism to each other, might the more clearly and surely become common property. But even these discussions must have exerted a most important influence on the more extended ones that followed, and, as it were, have chalked out the course they should pursue. And as this struggle preluded the great Arian controversy, so also did the decision arrived at prelude the decision in the case of Arianism. As the Alexandrian Dionysius, by withdrawing the Arian proposition which he had advanced, did justice to that general Christian consciousness which had always retained its power over him, and which could never be satisfied with a redemption effected by a mere creature, however exalted; so are we fully warranted in anticipating that the Church, how- ever great its previous vacillation, will prove capable of taking the right course, relatively to the points which constitute its foundation. But even at the time of Dionysius, the circum- stance brought out during the struggle, that no one of the controversialists was disposed to treat the Son as a mere crea- ture, or even consciously and decidedly to subordinate Him to the Father, must have greatly tended to strengthen this common consciousness. The principle of the equality of the essence of the Son with that of the Father, laid down by the early Church, was merely revived by these controversies ; but, in consequence of the temporary effort to conceive the Son as posited in time, had developed into a clear conviction that Origen’s doctrine of the eternal generation of the Son was an inevitable consequence of the coessentiality or true deity of the Son, and must be adopted by the Church, unless it were prepared to pass over into Sabellianism or Arianism. From the time of Tertullian onwards, the Eastern Church alone was the arena of doctrinal movements; the Western Church disappeared from the scene. Dionysius of Rome was 186 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. the first to lead the Western Church again to take part in the movement: but he was so far in advance, as compared with Tertullian, and so very different from him, that, in order to account for the sudden leap, we naturally look for connecting links between the two; and such connecting links there must unquestionably have been. Whilst the Greek. Church had made such affinity with Hellenic philosophy, that it was unable entirely to break away from the conception of God, as the ‘Ov (even the ayévntov, which was employed to denote deity “ sensu strictissimo,” and was deemed predicable of the Father alone, was merely a new form of the “Ov),—the natural con- sequence whereof was, that the Son could not be represented as participating in the inmost divine essence, and must, there- fore, even though in part contrary to intention, be subordinated to the Most High God ;—the Western Church continued, as it would appear, a stranger to the Hellenic. philosophy, and. its idea of God. Taking the facts of Christianity for its starting- point, it ventured to undertake the transformation of the old conception of God, in a trinitarian sense; and never ceased to attribute to the Son true divine substance,—as, indeed, fol- lowed naturally enough from the circumstance, that it did not, like Origen, assume a divine *Ov back of the divine d0£a, but reckoned this divine 8d£a, in which the Son was acknowledged to participate, as part of the inner divine essence, or reckoned the inner divine essence to the d0£a. We have seen that Tertul- lian and his school were unable to establish the hypostasis of the Son, on which they insisted so strongly, and which, it is true, they held to have proceeded forth from the inmost es- sence of God, save at the price of a decided subordination under the Father. In the hands of Dionysius, on the con- trary, half a century later, we find that things wear altogether a different appearance,—that subordination, namely, has been strongly repressed, and that the unity of the essence of the Father and of the Son is not merely asserted, but carried out in such a way, that the hypostatic distinction of the Son lost the clearness given it by Tertullian, and approximated in some measure to Sabellianism; though with the difference, that the distinctions in the divine essence were represented, not as originating in consequence of the creation of the world, but as immanent, eternal, and simultaneous. In order ZENO OF VERONA. 187 to fill up the gap between Tertullian and Dionysius, a man deserves mention, who has been overlooked by recent writers on the History of Dogmas,—I mean Zeno, Bishop of Verona. The opinion, that the works attributed to him, and which were first published at Venice a.p. 1508 (Bibl. MaxeePRectaa, 356 ff.), were either written by entirely different authors, or by a Zeno who flourished somewhat before Ambrosius (about A.D. 360), and was Bishop in Verona, 1s based on a letter ad- dressed by Ambrosius to Bishop Syagrius in Verona, where he says (see Ambr. Opp. 5, 297) :—* Puellam (Indiciam) Zenonis sanctee memorie judicio probatam ejusque sanctifica- tam benedictione—in periculo reatus deducendam arbitrare.” But this passage neither says that the nun was from Verona, nor that the Zeno who confirmed her was Bishop in Verona. On external grounds, little objection can be made to accepting the statement as true, that these works were written by a Bishop Zeno in Verona, who lived about the time of Origen and Cyprian, and under Gallienus; unless internal grounds are opposed thereto (compare Bibl. Max. 1. ¢. 357 ff.). But the portions which we shall here bring under consideration, con- tain a doctrine of the Trinity, such as could not have been sanctioned by the Church subsequently to the Council of Nicwa; and which indicates that their author most probably flourished between Tertullian or Hippolytus, and Dionysius of Rome. At the same time, the very decided originality and individuality of the writings, alone render them worthy of a more detailed consideration. In the first Homily on Genesis (1. c. 359a), the author speaks against the eternity of matter, and a duality of opposed principles, in terms similar to those employed by Dionysius of Alexandria (see above). God_is rather the principle; out of Himself He gave to Himself the principle of being. This is our God, who has discriminated Himself into God: this the Father, who, in His abiding state (statu, which reminds one of Tertullian), in His entirety, duph- cated Himself in the Son, in order not to rob Himself of any- thing. “Hic est Deus noster, qui se digessit in Deum, hic Pater, qui suo manente integro statu, totum se reciprocavit in Filium, ne quid sibimet derogaret. Denique alter in altero exultat, cum spiritus s. plenitudine una originali cozeternitate renitens. Quemadmodum, si dicere dignum est, duo maria que 188 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. in semet recumbunt, freto estus alternos in unum conferente connexa ; que licet sui proprietate, locis, vocabulisque discreta sint, tamen trini profundi vaporis (a7oppoias) una virtus, una substantia, una est fluendi natura, nec potest incomprehensibilis communisque unde dividi magnitudo, et tamen utrunque (utrin- que?) commeando largiflua, utrisque propria, nulli privata. Ete- nim damnum patientur ubertatis et gratize si adimatur (sc. id), quod uno eodemque estu alterum ex altero decoratur.” This obscure passage compares Father and Son to two seas, each of which exists for itself, but whose waters meet and combine in a strait. Hach of the seas is something by itself; is distinguished from the other by its peculiar character, by place and by name; but neither is lessened by the existence of the other. Through the narrow channel, by which they are connected, both gain in fulness, being otherwise of the same substance ; whereas both would be losers if the interchange were to cease, and they were deprived of the adornment they mutually owe to the meeting and blending of their waters. The Holy Ghost appears here to be described as the connecting link; but main stress is still laid on Father and Son. He speaks in a similar way in the third Homily :—“ The Son is equal to the Father. He says, —The Father is in Me, and I am in the Father; one embraces the other (invicem se capit), with the Holy Spirit.’ The relation between the Father and the Son is treated with still greater speciality in the Homilies “de eterna Dei generatione ” (l. c. p. 386). If, on the one hand, what has been adduced is sufficient to show, that for the successive Trinity of Tertullian he had substituted a simultaneous one, and that, inasmuch as he transfers Tertullian’s gradus, as simultaneous, into the status of the divine essence, which he conceived to consist of several centres, enjoying, notwithstanding their connection, an exist- ence of their own, he had not witnessed the Sabellian con- troversies without profit; the latter passage betrays, on the other hand, a remarkable affinity with Tertullian. It is true, the Son is termed “ Totus de toto,’ not merely “ portio;” the Father brought forth in the Son another Self (pater in ipsum alium se genuit ex se) out of Himself, out of His ungenerated substance (ex innascibili (7.e., ayevvytw) sua substantia) ; out of God, God is born—out of the unborn One, the only-begotten One. But he says also,—Before all the ons, in the secret ZENO OF VERONA. 189 depths of His holy intelligence, in the counsel of His own mind, unsearchable and known only to Himself, the Father embraced the Son, not without love to Him, but without as yet revealing Him. Hom. 2 :—“ Out of the mouth of the eternal Father, who alone was acquainted with the secret of His own mind, proceeded the only-begotten Son, the noble guest of His heart (cordis ejus nobilis inquilinus), in order that the universe, which as yet did not exist, might be created. Thence onwards, He hecame visible, because He was destined to visit the human race; though, in all other respects, He was equal to the Father.” The third Homily says still more distinctly, that, prior to the creation of the world, the Father kept the Son hidden in His own consciousness (nescio qua sua conscientia velatum), and embraced, not indeed without love, but without as yet fully distinguishing Him from Himself (non sine affectu, sed sine discrimine). In order, however, to the realization of the order of things which had been devised, that unutterable power and incomprehensible wisdom thrust forth the Word out of His heart. Then Omnipotence propagated itself: out of God was born God, who possesses in Himself all that the Father is, and has,—not, however, withdrawing anything from the Father, for that which is the Son’s is the Father’s, and that which belongs to the Father belongs. to both (excogitatarum ut ordi- nem instrueret rerum, ineffabilis illa Virtus, incomprehensibilis- que Sapientia e regione cordis eructat verbum. Omnipotentia se propagat. De Deo nascitur Deus, totum Patres habens, nihil derogans Patri—quia, quod est Filii, Patris est, quod Patris, amborum). The Father rejoices in the other Self, which He has produced out of Himself (letatur Pater in alio se, quem genuit ex se). The mode of generation is inexplicable ; but to suppose that He cannot be termed generated, who pro- ceeded forth, is madness. For the Son. limits Himself (tem- perat se), on behalf.of nature; “ne eternze majestatis dominum non possit mundi istius mediocritas sustinere.” In these latter words, he seeks to guard against the appearance of bringing the eternal divine essence of the Son. into too close proximity to the world; as would seem to be the case, if He first pro- ceeded forth from God as His Word, at the creation of the world. It is unmistakeable, however, that he represents the Son as proceeding out of the heart of the Father, and His 190 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. determinate “discrimen,” as first taking place at the creaticn of the world; and the sole perceptible difference between Zeno and Tertullian is, that the former takes greater pains tc make sure the full eternal deity of the Son in the Father (in corde Patris), the co-ordination of the Son with the Father after His procession to hypostatical existence, and, in general, the permanence and simultaneity of the Trinity. The position __that the Father has in the Son His other Self (alterum se), or Himself as an object—was further carried out, at a later period (in the fifth century), in the treatise appended to the works of Cyprian, entitled “De Sina et Zion adv. Jud.,” after the following manner: “ Salvator speculum Patris immacula- tum, eo quod sanctus spiritus, Dei Filius geminatum se videat Pater in Filio et Filius in Patre, utrigue se in se vident; ideo speculum immaculatum.” We shall find similar language used, however, even by Athanasius and Hilary. The principal momenta of the Christology of Zeno (if the sections which treat thereof be genuine; and in favour of their genuineness many things plead, although I should not like to assert it so confidently as in the case of the previous portions) are as follows. We must distinguish a double birth of the Son (as Tertullian and Hippolytus taught),—the first was without mother, the second without Father. In the womb of the Virgin He prepared for Himself a body (nothing is said re- garding the soul). Out of love to His image, constricted into a child, God weeps (amore imaginis sug coactus in infantem vagit Deus). The Virgin comprised in herself Him whom the world and its greatness cannot comprise. Meanwhile, He threw aside His glory, but not His power. He whose eternity admits of no age, went through the different ages of man. He who confers eternity on the times, borrowed human life from time. Contrary to His consciousness, he suffered as a weak man, in order that immortality might become the portion of man, who was snatched away by the law of death. This pas- sage reminds one of early Christian hymns. Somewhat Doce- tical in character is “de nat. Chr. hom. 2,” where he tries to show, that if Mary were a virgin in conceiving, she must also have been a virgin in bringing forth (sine dolore, etc.). As God, He must have been able to be what He willed; accordingly, He became what He was not, but did not cease to be what he had ARNOBIUS. 191 previously been (Hom. 1, de nat. Chr. :—“ Vultis scire in com- pendio veritatem? actus est quod non erat: nec tamen desiit esse ante quod fuerat”). But we need not be surprised at these Docetical features; we know both from Hippolytus and Methodius, that they were not foreign to the time. Jor a long period after Origen, it was an universal custom to slight the soul of Christ; and where it is done, it is a sign of high anti- quity. Nor, again, need we be surprised at the repudiation (hom. de nat. Chr. 1) of Ebionism, which teaches “Jesum Christum ab utero Mariz sumsisse principium, Deumque exinde ob justitiam factum esse, non natum;” of Subordinatianism, which does indeed term the Son of God, God, “sed non ex Patre nobilitatis perpetuitate progenitum, fuisseque tempus quando non fuit ;” and of the “Judea secta,” which refuses to distinguish between Father and Son. For, as far as con- cerns the second in particular, we have certainly found the doc- trine, that there was a time when the Son did not exist, both taught under various forms during the third century, and also expressly condemned by many teachers of the Church, for example, by Origen. This is probably the most suitable place for devoting a word to some other men of the Latin Church ;—for example, first to Arnobius and Minucius Felix, of whom the former at all events was an African, and both of whom flourished in the third century; then to Lactantius, who was a scholar of the former. | Arnobius endeavoured to demonstrate from the miracles of Christ, that He was not one from amongst us (adv. Gent. 1, 45 f.); but, on the contrary, because of the great gifts which He has brought us, deserves to be called God (1, 42). “Deus ille sublimis fuit, Deus radice ab intima, Deus ab incognitis regnis et ab omnium principe Deus sospitator est missus.” “Ye say, it is true,” he cries to the heathen, “ Your God is dead.” “ But death is no disgrace ; Socrates and others lost nothing by death ; as little did their cause lose thereby. Moreover, the simple divine essence did not suffer when Christ died. If the Sybil, whom you believe to be filled with Apollo, were to be murdered by wicked robbers, would you say, ‘Apollo was killed in her?’ Death befell the man assumed by Him, not Him Himself; that which was borne, not the vehicle and bearer (mors gestaminis 192 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. fuit, non gestantis). And even this He would not have had to endure, had there not been so great, so mysterious a work to be accomplished” (1, 62). The illustration of the Sybil might be taken to indicate that he regarded Christ as a mere prophet. But he also designates Him, “ Deus radice ab intima,’ and in 1, 60, “vis invisibilis, habens nullam substantiam corporalem. * So exalted, indeed, was He, that it was necessary for Him to throw around Himself a covering of dark matter, on which the eye might rest, and on which the gaze of dull contemplation might be fixed. Had he presented Himself on earth, in His “ primogenita natura,’ who would have been able to behold Him? Wherefore He assumed the human form, and con- cealed His might under a cloak of resemblance to our race, in order that He might be seen, and might be able to execute all that for which He came into the world, in pursuance of the behest and commission of the Most High King. His Christ is so far from being a man, that he rather verges strongly towards Docetism ; and he does not appear to have objected even to the expression—Christ was “homo simulatus” (1, 61). The real kernel of the “velamen”’ or “ tegmen,” that is, of His humanity, is His “ primogenia natura.” For this reason, he ascribes to the death of Christ, as the taking away of that “tegmen,” the peculiar effect that He was now seen in His real essence, espe- cially by the spirits, who were seized with terror when they dis- covered that He was God, whom they had esteemed to be one of us. (Exutus corpore, quod in exigua sui circumferebat parte, postquam videri se passus est, cujus esset aut magnitudinis scirl: novitate rerum exterrita universa mundi sunt elementa turbata, tellus mota contremuit, etc. Quid enim restabat, ut fieret, postquam Deus est cognitus is, qui esse jam dudum unus judicabatur e nobis? 1, 53.) He treats the work of Christ as consisting mainly in His doctrine of the true God, who che- rishes the same feelings towards all alike, who neither punishes nor requires sacrifices ; and in the exhibition, in His own person, of the divine longsuffering and tenderness. He was the Mediator of the revelation of God. The idea of the God-man had no constitutive significance for him ; indeed, with his undeveloped system, he had scarcely arrived at the idea. Still, we may sup- pose without improbability, that he did not wish to appear oefore the heathen with all the mysteries of Christianity, and MINUCIUS FELIX. 193 that he passed over the doctrine of the Trinity in particular, because the unity of God appeared to him to supply a peculiarly forcible argument in favour of Christianity against the heathen, —which argument he perhaps feared to shake by bringing for- ward the doctrine of the Trinity, especially as he may have felt incapable of fully grappling with the difficulties it presented. This, however, is a new proof that he had not penetrated very deeply into the soul of the doctrines of Christianity.—Still more meagre are the results arrived at from an examination of Minucius Felix. He says (Octavius, e. 20),—All philosophers of repute teach one God, even though under different names. So that everybody must believe, either that Christians are now philosophers, or that philosophers were already Christians. In his view, as in that of Arnobius, the principal and characteristic doctrines of Christianity are, the unity of God, His invisibility and omniscience, His providence, the end of the world, and the resurrection of the dead. Of Christ, he only says in passing (c. 29),—“ To our religion you ascribe a guilty man, and reckon to him his cross. But you wander far from the truth, when you fancy that a guilty man could deserve, or an earthly being bring about, His own recognition as God (—“erratis, qui putatis Deum credi aut meruisse noxium aut potuisse ter- renum”). Still, these words imply, not merely that Christ was holy, but also that He was not of the earth, and for this cause He is believed in as God. “ Woe to him,” he goes on to say, “whose entire hope rests on a mortal man; all his help is lost, as soon as this man disappears.” Neither Arnobius nor Minu- clus Felix allude to the Holy Spirit and the Trinity. : The peculiar, and as yet little considered, Christology of Lactantius, laid down in his “ Institutiones,” belongs properly to another place; but the traditional elements thereof, which are to a certain extent inconsistent with his own views, both in tone, form, and substance, bear a remarkable resemblance to that portion of Zeno’s system which we have touched upon. I refer to what he says regarding the pre-existent higher essence of Christ. This is the more remarkable, as the doctrine of Christ’s higher nature, contained in his Tnstitutiones, though evidently emasculated, is out of harmony with his general views of things, could not be deduced from his premisses, and must therefore be regarded as fragments of an entirely different HOES AU N 194 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. system of the world. Lactantius becomes, on this very ground, a striking witness to the correctness of the view we have taken of the history of this dogma, prior to Arius. The Son of God, says he, proceeded forth from God for the creation of the world, as a word proceeds out of the mouth,—hypostatically, however, and not as “tacitus spiritus.” This Son is also termed the Word of God, which the Greeks express still better by Logos, for Logos denotes both word and reason (1. c. 8, 9). He is very different from the other angels. “ Quoniam spiritus et sermo diversis partibus proferuntur, spiritus naribus, ore sermo pro- cedit, magna inter hunc Dei Filium ceterosque angelos differ- entia est. Illi enim ex Deo taciti spiritus exierunt, qui non ad doctrinam Dei tradendam sed ad ministerium creabantur. Ile vero, quum sit et ipse spiritus, tamen cum voce ac sono ex Dei ore processit, sicut verbum, ea scilicet ratione, quia voce ejus ad populum fuerat usurus, 2.¢., quod ille magister futurus esset doctrinze dei et ccelestis arcani ad homines perferendi.” He is therefore God’s spokesman, produced by God, in order that He might speak, “quod ipsum primo locutus est, ut per eum ipse ad nos loqueretur, et ille vocem Dei ac voluntatem nobis reve- laret. Merito igitur Sermo et Verbum Dei dicitur : quia Deus procedentem de ore suo vocalem spiritum, quem non utero sed mente conceperat, inexcogitabili quadam majestatis suz virtute ac potentia in effigiem, que proprio sensu ac sapientia vigeat, comprehendit.” This “sensus” and “potentia” He derived from the Father (de Patre tanquam rivus de fonte traduxit). If his derivation of the “Sermo Dei” from God, for the pur- pose of the creation of the world and of revelation, fully war- rants us in classing Lactantius amongst the teachers of the Western Church, particularly subsequent to Tertullian, he bears a special resemblance to Zeno, through the idea, which he repeatedly advances, of the “ duplex nativitas” of Christ, the one for the creation of the world, the other for the incarnation ; then a still closer resemblance, through his description of the first birth, which he says was “sine matre.” In this connection he protests against the doctrine of Orpheus and Hermes, who represented the Son as the fruit of a sexual dualism in God, who is both adromdrwp and avtoujtwp. Apuleius quotes, as a verse of Orpheus, the words, Zevs apanv yéveto, Zevs aPporos erac.o voudn. At His first birth, on the contrary, we should LACTANTIUS. 195 rather say that the Son was aujtwp, and in the second aTaTW). Finally, Lactantius follows the example of the older writers, but specially of Zeno, in applying to the first birth of the Son the words, “eructavit cor meum verbum bonum;” and shows, in the above passage, how in his view the Son was at first con- cealed in the “mens Dei,” and then was manifested through the speaking of God. All this sufficiently proves that he too be- lieved in the equality of the essence of the pre-existent hypo- stasis of the Son with that of the Father. But Lactantius undoubtedly betrays also a strong retrogressive tendency. Wher- ever the Son is represented as proceeding forth from God for the creation of the world, and for the revelation of God in We it is possible in itself that such a doctrinal system may end either in Sabellianism on the one hand, or in Arianism on the other, and such a vacillation we find to have been characteristic of the Fathers between Tertullian and Origen. Nor was it possible for it to cease, so long as the various elements had not been separated, and the heterogeneous principles to which they alter- nately surrendered themselves had not been logically developed into opposed systems. The decisive appearance of Sabellianism in the third century led to a partial separation of the elements ; and, as we see, even Lactantius very decidedly, though, it must be allowed, inconsistently, ranged himself under the banner of one party. In doing so, he repudiated very distinctly the Sabel- lian view, with its denial of an hypostasis, but at the same time inclined all the more decidedly to Subordinatianism. Zeno, on the contrary, endeavoured to nullify the subordination involved in the doctrine, that the Son first proceeded forth from God for the creation of the world, by teaching that He was previously an object of love in the heart of the Father, coeternal with God; but he fails to answer clearly the question, as to the rela- tion between the eternal existence of the Son in the Father, and His production for the purpose of the creation of the world and of the incarnation. Dionysius of Rome, on the other hand, appears to have left the idea of the generation of the Son en- tirely aside, and to have contented himself solely with the eternal unity of the Son with the Father in distinction from Him, with- out more carefully inquiring into the mode of this being, or asking whether an eternal generation or production of the Son took place in God. Dionysius of Alexandria, like Zeno, finally 196 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. arrives at a kind of duplication of the vods in the Father and the Son (Note 40). Whatever other differences there may have been between them, and whatever indefiniteness may have characterized their expositions, it is evident that this entire series of men, from the Eastern and Western Church, had certain fixed and invariable doctrinal views. They all clung to the essential equality of the Son and the Father, and to the distinction of the Son's pre- existent hypostasis from that of the Father. But we find also various indications that the Church was gradually arriving at a more and more fixed doctrinal type, of this same general charac- ter. After the controversy between the two Dionysiuses, Sabel- lianism disappeared ever more completely from the scene; and in the following century was treated, both by Arians_and orthodox, as a view already repudiated by the Church,—a circumstance which points back to the afore-mentioned Romish Synod. In opposition to Arianism, also, the later Church teachers appealed to this Synod. But the reaction which now set in against the system of Origen, especially against its sub- ordinatian aspect, is particularly deserving of notice. This re- action was characterized, indeed, by many displeasing features, but strikingly demonstrates the correctness of what has just been said. The first and milder form of the polemic may be found, perhaps, at the close of the Confession of Faith adopted by the Synod of Antioch (Note 41). But a still more strong polemic was waged about the year 300. It is instructive to read, in the Apology of Pamphilus, the points of accusation against Origen, as they are the same which were brought for- ward even prior to the Arian controversy, and indicate very plainly what was at that time deemed necessary to orthodoxy in general. Inasmuch as Pamphilus does not say that the oppo- nents of Origen were in error on these points, and required what was false, but endeavours rather to show that Origen had taught what they required; nay more, in that he grants that it would have been heresy in Origen to have taught the doctrines which his opponents attributed to him ; this monument is the more in- teresting. Whether he was able to clear Origen of the charges, or whether Eusebius took part in the composition of the first book of the Apology or not, does not concern us in this connec- tion. ‘Che work was certainly written between a.p. 307 and 309. PAMPHILUS. SYNODS OF ANTIOCH. 197 The first charge is, that Origen did not believe the Son to have been born, or begotten,—which does not mean that he recognised no distinction between the unbegotten Father and the Son, but, as the answer shows, that he did not hold the Son to be Son of God by nature; whereas he ought to have taught, that He was of the substance of the Father, and of a different nature from the creature." The second charge was that of re- presenting the Son as having arrived at subsistence by mpo[3ony, after the manner of Valentinus. The third charge was, that he refused to designate Christ God, and made Him a mere man. The fourth charge was, treating the history of Christ docetically. The fifth, teaching two Christs. In connection with this latter point, special remark is deserved by the hint that the giving great prominence to the human soul of Christ seemed to many to be equivalent to teaching two Christs, and was, therefore, a cause of offence. “Si quis sane offenditur, quod dixit, Salvatorem etiam animam suscepisse, nihil de hoc amplius respondendum puto, nisi quod hujus sententiz non Origenes auctor est, sed ipsa sancta scriptura, etc.;—from which we see clearly how very far the completeness of the human aspect of the Person of Christ was lost to the view of the Church, in consequence of the prominence given to the doctrine of His higher nature. We shall have occasion to make the same remark respecting Athanasius, at the beginning of his career. Another very important source of information concerning the character of the general views of the Church during the second half of the third century, are the two Synods of Antioch, convened in the years 265 and 270, for the purpose of judging Paul. of-Samosata (Note 42). Their decrees, although they undoubtedly, lacked a strictly doctrinal form, and had rather 1 Pamphilus adduces, in reply, a number of passages, in which the Son is described as Light of Light; as Love from God, who is Love; as an out- flow from God; nay more, as ¢“oovoros with the Father. The latter pro- bably originated with Rufinus, though we have found that, on a subse- quent occasion, Dionysius of Alexandria, when he was required to use this term, showed himself ready to do so. But that, in the main, the translation of Rufinus gives a correct impression of the work of Pamphilus and Eusebius, 1s evident from Jerome’s charge against it, of containing the poison of Arianism. Compare the Introduction to this treatise in de la Rue’s ed. Wer Rig: 198 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. an exegetical character, were recognised as orthodox by later Synods. We find in them a strong predominance given to the Father over the Son, for example, at the very outset; and other words and turns of expression are employed, which would probably have been avoided subsequently to the Council of Nice. The Confession runs as follows :—“ We believe that God, to wit, the Father, is unbegotten, One, without beginning, in- visible,” etc. “Through the revelation of His beloved Son, we receive a knowledge of Him, though it is imperfect, owing to our weakness.” “The Son is yevvntos,” it goes on to say, “the only-begotten Son, the image of the invisible Father, the first- born of creation, the Wisdom and Logos and Power of God, who existed before the Alfons, not merely in the divine fore- knowledge (srpoyveces), but we confess and proclaim Him, as we have learnt from the Old and New Testaments, as God, both in His essence and in His hypostasis (otela cat trrocracer).' Whoso denies that the Son of God existed before the founda- tion of the world, and maintains that this is to teach two Gods, him we regard as estranged from the canon of the Church; and all the communities of the Church General are of the like opinion (TodTovy aANOTpLOY TOD eKKANTLATTLKOD KaVOVOS 1YyoU- ela, Kal macar ai Kaborxal éexkrnolar cvpdwvodow Hiv). Concerning Him who was always with the Father (adv Té Tatpt ael dvta), we believe, that He accomplished the Father’s will in the creation of the universe. Through Him the Father created all things, not as through an instrument, nor as through an impersonal wisdom (ody ws 6” dpydvou ov0 ws Ov ériaTHuns avuTrooratov) ; for, when the Father begat the Son, He begat a living, personal energy (@s f@cap évépyevay Kat évuTooTarov). He appeared to Abraham, conversed with the patriarchs, now as an angel, now as the Lord, now as God. But we say also, that the law was given to Moses by the intervention of the Son 1 Judging from the context, ovo/g, as the antithesis to rpoyvaees, will refer to the reality of the pre-existence. At a later period, the Arians frequently adopted the above Confession as their own, possibly for the very reason that it corresponded to the requirements of the Fathers of Antioch. ? The Oriental bishops sent the Epistola Synodica to which this Con- fession was annexed to the Western Church, to Dionysius of Rome, to the Alexandrian Church, and, indeed, to all bishops, presbyters, and deacons, nara thy olxovuévyy (Euseb. 1. c. 7, 30 init.). —_ se CONFESSION OF ANTIOCH. 199 (Scaxovodvros Tob viod).”* And now the Confession passes on from the pre-existent Son to His incarnation :-—“ We believe and confess, further, that the Son, who was God with the Father and Lord of all creation, was sent by the Father from heaven, and became flesh, assuming humanity; for which cause, tie body out of the Virgin, containing as it did all the fulness of the Godhead bodily, is unchangeably united and deified with His deity. Hence was one and the same Jesus Christ pro- claimed as God and man in the law and the prophets, and in the entire Church which is under heaven is believed in as One.” (Tov 88 vidv rapa tO Tarpt dvta, Ocov pev Kal KUpLOV TOV YEVYNTOV aTAVTOD, imo S€ Tod TarTpos amootanevta é& otpavav Kab capxobévta évnvOpwrnxevat (Ojoroyoupey, K.T.r.)° Suotrep Kal TO éx Ths mapOévov cpa, xwphoav wav TO TAN- papa THS OeoTNTOS TOMATLKOS, TH Oeotnte aTpeTTMS HvwTat Kal teOcomointar. (This last expression of Paul’s was allowed to pass.) O8 ydpw 6 adtos Ocds kal dvOpwros ’Incots Xpioros mpoednreveto év voum Kal mpopytats, Kab ev TH EKKANTIA TH ind tov oblpavov rdcon TeriotevTat, Oeds pev KevOTas EavTOD amd Tod elvat ica Och, dvOpwTos dé Kab x orréppatos Aavid T4 Kata cdpKa, TA pev onucia Kal Ta Tépata, Ta ev Tots EvaryryEdtoLs avayeypappeva 6 eds Hv éritedécas, TO O€ GapKos Kal aipaTtos precynkevas TOV avTov TeTELpapevoyv KATA TavTA Kal opowoTnTa yopls awaptias. Otro Kab 6 Xpwctds mpo THs capkwoews €v tals Oelats ypaais, ds eis, @vomacTat.”) The Confession opens with the following words :—* It seemed good to us to set forth as follows, in writing, the faith 1 As everything which relates to the hypostatical pre-existence of the Son was directed primarily, indeed, against Paul,—naturally, however, against Monarchianism in general, and, therefore, against Sabellius also,—so should I be inclined to see in this very emphatic mention of the share taken by the Son in the law, an allusion to the Sabellians, with whom the Ori- eutals must certainly have become acquainted after, if not before, the controversy between the two Dionysiuses. For the Sabellians ascribed legislation to the Father, whereas they excluded the Son entirely from the Old Testament. 2 Then follow the passages, Lamentations iv. 20; 2 Cor. iil. 17; 1 Cor. eos Hob. x1..208) betcha Oat. to 1 Cor. i. 24. Ei b& Xptoros Ocov Divers nal Osov coQicec, xpd wiavey éotly, ovr nol xaebo Xpisrds ev nal ro xitd dy TH ovolae, ei xal TH MaALoTR morals xivolats emivocires. Nota word is spoken concerning the soul, which, after the time of Apollinaris, would be quite unintelligible. 200 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. as we have received and held it from the beginning, which has been handed down to us, and is preserved in the Holy Catholic Church to the present day, which has come to us in an un- broken line from the holy Apostles, who were eye-witnesses and servants of the Word.” By this act of the Church, Ebionism, in its higher Hellenic form also was shut out (a circumstance which, as we shall see, was not without an important bearing on the Arian contro- versies); and if to this end it was necessary to confess. the pre-existence of the hypostasis of the Son, Sabellianism also was excluded; and if, finally, the real motive for the rejection of Paul of Samosata was the conviction, that the full concep- tion of Christianity requires us to acknowledge that the Deity appeared in the Son in a personal form, and was not a mere power; if, accordingly, the doctrine of the Son’s pre-mundane generation out of the Father were taught, and these two points —that is, the pre-existence of the hypostasis and the generation out of the Father—were developed into, and summed up in, the determinate doctrine of the eternal existence of the hypo- stasis of the Son with the Father,—we may see very clearly what direction the stream of Church thought... was..taking, towards the end of the third century. It is the direction which resulted, by an internal necessity, from the course pursued by the preceding history, from its ever fuller and clearer development of doctrine, no less than from the inner, ever-present principle which gave the impulse. The position of the Arians was that of men who are born out of due time; or, to adopt another image, they resembled stagnant, or even receding waters; for, just as the Church, in consequence of the favourable political position in which it was placed, quitted its earlier career—a career rich in conflict, and therefore rich in vitality—and en- tered on the easy and open, but also flat plain; and further, when, in consequence thereof, the vital power by which the Church should work up, purge, and appropriate the ante-Chris- tian elements, ceased, at all events, for the moment to bear any proportion to the masses of the heathen world which now pressed into it, the Arians stood still. At this point, however, our atten- tion must be directed to a new aspect of the matter. As early as the second half of the third century, we find within the Church itself, independently of the heathens who CONFESSION OF ANTIOCH. 201 pressed rapidly into it, a dangerous mixture with the world, and a suspicious attention to externals, to power and mere numbers, even at the cost of inner truth; and, finally, an in- timacy with heathen philosophy, without the vigour necessary to its transformation, which necessarily reacted corruptingly on the Christian mind, and sapped the energy of the conscience of Christian science in relation to its subject-matter, that is, faith.’ These external considerations alone, prove that the storm which burst at the commencement of the fourth century was not sudden and unprepared. On the historian, however, de- volves the further task of showing that the possibility of even the great Arian movement was promided in the doctrinal con- dition of a previous.age, and that, agreeably to a higher order, it was both necessary to, and exerted a wholesome influence on, the development of doctrine in the Church. To this subject the introduction to the next section will be devoted, where we shall find the doctrinal materials of the great conflict; that is, both the weaknesses and defects of the dogma, in the form to which we have seen it grow; and the frequent inclinations to subordinatian and Arian representations, on the part of the world of cultivated laymen,—inclinations which necessarily assumed greater power in the Church the more it endeavoured to stand forth in a worldly shape and form. 1 Let us call to mind Paul of Samosata (Euseb. H. E. 7, 30), whose part even Lucian the martyr is said to have taken; the claims of the Romish bishops, which rose with every new success ; the commencing pomp and externality of the Cultus; the opposition already necessary to be raised against the worship of martyrs (for example, under Commodian) ; the impurity of the view taken of marriage and celibacy ; the beginnings of monasticism—a fleeing from the world which only a feeble Christian con- sciousness could regard as identical with the denial of the world required by Christianity, whilst it really served, along with that other, to make the Church hierarchical, that is, to give it a worldly form, whilst preserving the appearance of Christianity ; and, finally, let us call to mind how fre- quently men highly esteemed in the Church were styled Rhetors and Sophists—titles by no means so unobjectionable as that of Philosopher, used in the second century. 202 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOOR. CHAPTER SECOND. ARIUS AND HIS FORERUNNERS. Wuart led so many even of the cultivated into the Church, from the end of the third century onwards, and from the time of Constantine the Great, was not so much an universally dif- fused and deeper conviction of the need of redemption and the necessity for a redeemer other than man, as the total decompo- sition of Heathenism, brought about by philosophy or illumina- tism and by Christianity. As compared with Polytheism and its superstition, Christianity was the religion of Monotheism, and it was distinguished from Judaism by its universalism. It was recognised, therefore, as the true religion, and as fitted to give life and reality to the final conclusion at which heathen philosophy had arrived, to wit, the unity of God, and to secure for it a place amongst the convictions of mankind as a whole. In which connection, it was not forgotten that the merely nega- tive universalism at which the heathen world had arrived, after the annihilation of its national gods, was converted by Chris- tianity into a positive universalism. For the one God taught by Christianity, and the knowledge of whom it deems to be the true philosophy, is not a mere idea of the reason, but a living, watchful Providence, who reveals Himself for the whole of humanity, and thus satisfies not merely the intellect, but the re- ligious impulse; which latter especially can be content with nothing short of the communication of God Himself. We can thus understand why Christianity took such immense strides, and why also it made extensive, in part, at the cost of intensive, progress. The danger of taking a superficial view of Christianity, and the temptation to regard the development of doctrine hitherto considered, as a secondary matter, and the living Monotheism of Christianity, on the contrary, as the main matter, could only have been easily evaded in one way,—to wit, by connecting the doctrine of the Person of Christ with a more fully developed doctrine of His work and office, and thus giving the former a greater hold on the mind. This, however, presupposed a deeper ARIUS AND HIS FORERUNNERS 203: estimate of the doctrines of anthropology, and of the state of sin and grace, for which the time had not yet come. Those who were truly animated by the.spirit of the Church devoted their best powers to the subject of the Trinity, and had there- with enough to do. Did not the foundation-stone need first to be laid?—what Christianity is in itself objectively, first to be ascertained? So long as the reason why Christ ought to be regarded as the Son of God, in an hypostatical form, and why, because of the appearance of Christ, the old Morcthician should be so boldly cast aside, was as imperfectly understood as it was at first; many Christians, specially of the just-mentioned mo- notheistic sort, were necessarily driven to regard it as an useless expenditure of pains on the part of God, to appear, as the creeds of the Church maintained, in the hypostasis of the Son in Christ; and to such a feeling neither the Scriptures nor the tradition of the Church could furnish a sufficient counterpoise, where the religious impulse, whose cry is for a marriage of the perfect God with humanity, lacked vitality, and there had been no experience of the need of redemption. Precisely in this con- nection the circumstance must-be-considered, that the Eastern Church had taken a predominantly theoretical, the. Western a predominantly practical turn; and that both had diverged in many respects from the true religious centre. — In the _East,.from the time of Origen onwards, theological science flourished ever more and more, but passed frequently over into a supernatural intellectualism, which laid chief stress on doctrine in general; and, as the character of this Church would lead us to expect, on the doctrine of God in particular. 0 regard ( Christ, however, merely as the teacher, the revealer of God, is, at the very outset, to make Him a mere organ and means, and not a constitutive element, of that which is to be revealed.” His person, and therefore the Trinity also, could not then be regarded as forming part of the contents of His doc- trine, as He would rather be the mere “ principium cognos- cendi,’ or the formal principle. To this conclusion, too, many actually arrived, both_Arians—and Sabellians. Furthermore, the theology of the Eastern Church had not yet freed itself from the abstract conception of God, taught by Hellenic philo- sophy, as we see most plainly from the circumstance that aseity was attributed, not to the entire trinitarian God, but to one 204 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. hypostasis; the consequence of which was, that this hypostasis was inevitably put into the position either of the Most High God, or of the entire God, and a constant vacillation between Subordinatianism and Sabellianism. It is particularly deserv- ing of remark in this connection, that the Church teachers of the fourth century very frequently appeal to Philo, to Por- phyry, to Plotinus, to Amelius, to Numenius, and other Neo- Platonists; and believed that they could find the Christian conception of God in an almost pure state in the writings of these men, who, in consequence of the Christian influences under which they had lived, had constructed a kind of doctrine of the Trinity. The Father is the "Ov, the airiov, etc. This Ov, which is the Father, was probably the ultimate foundation of the Subordinatianism from which the Eastern Church found such difficulty in freeing itself, notwithstanding the evident in- compatibility thereof with its religious convictions. We need scarcely remark, that such an intellectualism as this could not pos- sibly ensure to Christ an eternal significance, nor indeed assign to His humanity in general a sure place, but always necessarily inclined to seek a one-sided support in the Logos; nor, lastly, that there invariably slumbered behind it a superficial view of sin, a notion that it could be overcome by higher enlightenment. Indeed, there is no doubt that this intellectualism, with its dis- regard of anthropology, of the doctrine of sin, and of the work of Christ, was already Pelagianistic at the bottom. The Western Church, on the contrary, was stirred by a spirit of a more practical or ethical kind. It very quickly saw the change in the position occupied by Christianity in the world, and understood how to make use thereof; accordingly, instead of taking up a negative position, or theoretically isolating itself, the Church set itself the task of morally transforming the world by means of Christianity. This powerful moral impulse was embodied in the Western representative of Montanism, Tertul- lian, but propagated itself from him in Novatian, Cyprian, in ‘Aaroniie! Minucius Felix, and Lactantius, the last mentioned of whom incorporated a kind of ethics with his Institutions. At a later period, Ambrose and Augustine intensified this tendency in the direction of religion ; ‘Pelagius made it more superficial. LACTANTIUS 205: I. Lactantius. At the period now under review, when, although the Western Church was stirred by the practical impulse just described, at the same time the consciousness of the need of redemption and of the power of sin was still undeveloped, the significance of the Person of Christ was limited principally to a aiiseantes to the will. He appeared in order to bring about right action. Now, it is self-evident that, if Christ came merely to be a teacher and example of virtue, the Church was at very useless pains in bringing forward its doctrine of the Trinity. At this point, however, the idea of the ethical incarnation of God, which re- quired to be included as a momentum of Christology, was brought forward for the first time in a more developed shape. Nor need we be much surprised to find that Lactantius, who represented this aspect in a vigorous and original manner, did not succeed very well in combining it with the Trinity. We shall have occasion, however, to recognise that the tendency in the Church to assert the identity of the essence of the Son with that of the Father, must have been very strong, when it forced from Lactantius, with his one-sided ethical fundamental views, such a Christology, however defective its form. In the view of Lactantius, the ethical constitutes the central feature of Christianity. The vigour of his moral consciousness expresses itself in a remarkable manner, and in glaring contrast with most of the Oriental Fathers, in his work “ De via Dei;” especially also in his Christology. “He bade His only-begotten Son,” says he (Instit. 4, 11), “the Creator of the world (opificem), His counsellor, descend from heaven, in order that He might carry the holy religion of God to the nations of the heathen, and might teach ee the righteousness which a faithless people had cast away.” Here, deeds he places religion and ethics Agus of each other; but, as is well known, he derives “religio” from “religare” (4, 28), and, accordingly, gives to the ethical element even in religion the decided predominance. Christ he terms, therefore, “Magister, doctor virtutis (4, 11), doctor, preceptor justitie” (4, 10, 13, 23, 24, 25). He does not understand this, however, merely of His words :—the Son was sent to be the “viva prasensque lex,” so different from the Old Testament law, that Moses, the lawgiver, was himself 206 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. obliged to prophesy His coming (4, 17, 25). He is the bringer in of anew law. No one, since the foundation of the world, was like Christ, who taught wisdom by His word, and con aed His doctrine by the presence of His virtue (c. 23), But why was it necessary for such a teacher to come from heaven? In order that henceforth there might be no longer a difference be- tween earthly and heavenly. Here he (ae for support on his supernaturalism. “ In homine interna et propria doctrina nullo pacto esse potest.” The spirit which is shut up in the body, and its perishable nature, cannot by itself understand and lay hold of the truth, if it do not learn it elsewhere. The pure knowledge of virtue must therefore come from above. But why would not an earthly teacher (terrenus doctor), to whom the good had been revealed, have sufficed? Because it did not depend merely on the teaching, but also on the representation, of virtue, and be- cause the former, without the latter, is an imperfect and inope- rative thing. An earthly teacher could not be perfect; for, even if we were to conceive him in possession of a pure knowledge of the good, he could neither grasp the highest virtue, nor resist all sins, the incitement to which lies in the body. On the contrary, the heavenly teacher, whom His deity made partaker of wisdom, and His immortality of virtue, must needs be perfect, both in His doctrine and in all things. Accordingly, it is not merely necessary for the right teacher of virtue to come down from God; but he alone is the true teacher, who personally embodies the good, or who is the living and present law. He is thus led by the ethical to the recognition of the necessity of the incar- nation, to the idea of the incarnation of the law. God must become man _in order to realize righteousness on-earth. On this thought he dwells with peculiar fondness, and by its means was able to give an explanation even of the exinanition and the death of Christ. “It has often been denied,” says he (c. 22), “that anything can be taken away from an immortal nature, and that incarnation, the burden of the flesh and its sufferings, could be either worthy of or necessary for God. For surely it must be easy enough for Him to show Himself to men, and to teach them righteousness, without assuming the weakness of the body; nay, indeed, with the better result if He showed Himself as God. For if the power and might of the commanding God had approached to men, all would have ren- LACTANTIUS. 207 dered obedience. Why, then, did He come, not as God, but poor and lowly, so that He was despised and punished by men? Why did He not warn the men who sought to lay hands on Him away, by His power, or escape from them by His deity? Why did He not reveal His majesty, at all events, in the article of death?” All these objections, says he, I will carefully examine and refute, that every one will not merely cease to wonder that God should be crucified, but will see clearly that Christ could not have been believed in as God had not that happened which some blame. He who gives a command must himself observe it; other- wise, it has no force, For if that which is commanded is good in itself, the lawgiver must not separate himself from the num- ber and fellowship of the rest of men; on the contrary, he must himself live as he teaches other men to live. Only on condition that he who commands, puts himself on a level with him who is commanded, is the freedom of the latter ensured to him. Then the latter is free in obeying; if, however, he who commands, does not submit to the law which he imposes on others, and lives otherwise than as he commands, those who are commanded are not free in their obedience, and cannot be bound to render obedience. For this reason, it behoved God to subject Himself to His own law; and this He could only do, by becoming a man and living as we live. Now, for the first time, is our obligation complete. For now no one can any longer say,—* IT am unable to do what Thou requirest ; my nature is too weak. ‘Thou for- biddest me anger, concupiscence, passion, the fear of pain and death, and yet it is against nature : or, if Thou supposest we can resist nature, show me how, that | may know. What presump- tion to impose laws on a free man, which one does not obey oneself! Hence comes it, that no man obeys the laws of philo- sophers. Rather will I have examples than words; for to talk is easy, but to do, hard. Such excuses, which lead to our de- spising the teachers when they are men, and, when God is the teacher, lean for support on human weakness, are put to silence as soon as God subjects Himself to the law,—the condition whereof is His incarnation. ~ From this statement, we might, strictly speaking, draw the conclusion, that the incarnation was necessary to the ethical per- fection of God Himself, to the full actuality of His ethical 208 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. existence. This aspect of the matter he passes over lightly, and gives the greater prominence to the ceconomical (c. 24). “ Without assuming a mortal body, God could not be a perfect teacher of righteousness. For if He came to men as God, He could not, even apart from the consideration that mortal eyes would be unable to bear the brightness of His majesty, as God teach virtue ; for without body, He could not do what He had to teach, and therefore His doctrine would be imperfect. It is true, Thou sinnest not, one might have said to Him; but it is because Thou art free from this body of ours. Thou hast no desires, because, as an immortal, Thou hast no needs. I, on the contrary, need many things, for the support of this life of mine. Thou fearest not death, because it has no power over Thee. Thou despisest pain, because it can do Thee no harm. But Tyra mortal, fear both; for both cause me pain. Such excuses the teacher of virtue must needs cut short; but he could only do so if he were able to say,—‘ What thou callest impossible, I do myself ; therefore thy sin is not necessary, but is thy guilt. The flesh, concerning which thou sayest, To sin is essential to it, I also bear; and yet sin does not reign in me. Pain and death for righteousness’ sake, which appear to thee unbearable because of the weakness of the flesh, has also its power in me; and that which thou fearest I conquer, in order to make thee also a victor over pain and death. I go before thee, through that which thou callest unbearable ; canst thou not follow one who merely com- mands ? so follow him who goes before thee as a leader,’ Thou seest, therefore, how much more perfect a mortal teacher is than an immortal one; for the former can teach mortals, whereas the latter, not being himself subjected to suffering, cannot instruct in patience. I do not, however, say this in order to place man higher than God; but in order to show that a man cannot be a perfect teacher, if he is not at the same time God, and there- fore able to impress upon others the necessity of obedience by heavenly authority : nor, on the other hand, can God be a per- fect teacher, if he do not clothe Himself in a human body, in order, by carrying out His words into action, to shut up all others under the necessity of obedience. The leader to life, the teacher of righteousness, must have a body ; otherwise it is im- possible that His doctrine should be full and perfect, should have root and ground, should abide in and cling to men. He LACTANTIUS. 209 Himself must needs subject Himself to the weakness of the flesh and the body, and take up into Himself the virtue of which He is the teacher, in order that He might teach it both by word and deed” (c. 24). In order, then, that virtue and the law might abide in us, be perfectly implanted in us, Lactantius supposes that it was neces- sary for it to assume a living shape, to become man; the good must suffer, virtue must become incarnate. But this living law, this living virtue, is. Christ, God and man, as Mediator between the two. (uit ergo et Deus et homo, inter Deum atque hominem medius constitutus. Unde illum Greci Meoirnp vocant: c. 25.) . One might still suppose that Christ, though conceived as the living law, as the personal embodiment of virtue, stood outside of us, even as did the law of Moses. He reminds us, however, that example has a very different effect from commands. It is a hand which draws us after itself (He is “ preevius et manum porrigit secuturo,” c. 24); it is an attraction and an incitement (incitamentum) ; first when the Lawgiver becomes man, does His law acquire perfectly obligatory force, and therefore its per- fect power (c. 25). Through Him who is eternal, and as man also God, God has confirmed the eternal law (c. 17), and the law has gained an authority and force, which it would not have had if the Lawgiver had been a mere man. Men could not be compelled to righteousness by a merely human lawgiver, unless a higher power and authority were superadded (c. 25). But inasmuch as He is both God and man, necessity is laid on men to obey (that is, the law has acquired power to influence) ; not by any sort of violence, but by shame, and in such a way that freedom, rewards, and punishments remain;—the former, because it was still possible for them to disobey if they chose. in that He appeared, not in might and glory, but in lowliness_ the latter, because they were able to obey if they would. Veilea in the flesh, He has shown that flesh also is able to lay hold on virtue (carnem posse capere virtutem). The Master of virtue became perfectly like men, in order, by His own victory over sin, fo teach men that sin may be conquered by them (c. 24). A spirit without body could not conduct to immortality, for it is the flesh which prevents us men from following God; being earthly and mortal, it drags down the spirit which is united with Welle O 210 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. it to the earth, and from immortality to death. For this reason the Mediator came, God in the flesh, in order that the flesh might follow Him, and that He might rescue man from death, to whose dominion the flesh is subject. In order that we might be able to resist the lusts of the flesh, God has opened up and shown us a way to overcome the flesh. The perfect and ideal virtue (omnibus numeris absoluta) confers on the victors the wreath and the reward of immortality (c. 25). This ethical view of the Person of Christ, Lactantius then carries out in relation to His work. He by no means denies the outward miracles of Christ; on the contrary, he regards them as proofs of His higher nature ; but still he takes particular delight in searching out their ethical significance. They are the types of much higher spiritual miracles: and so also have His sufferings a deep figurative meaning (c. 26). The heavenly power opened the eyes of the blind, and proclaimed by this deed, that, turned towards the nations which knew not God, it would illuminate the heart of the foolish with the light of wisdom, and open the eyes of their understanding to the con- templation of the truth. He unstopped the ears of the deaf ; and thereby proclaimed, that those who knew not the truth would soon be able to hear and understand the words of God. He caused tongues to speak; for not until the tongue pro- claims the power and majesty of God, does it come to its natural use, whereas previously it is dumb. In like manner He goes through the miracles of healing and the raisings of the dead. Not merely what He did, but also what He suffered, had a sig- nificance for the future, and announced that wisdom would be an object of hatred, The vinegar mixed with gall, which was given Him to drink, foreboded to His disciples bitter and hard experiences ; for truth seems harsh and hateful to all who, not knowing virtue, spend their life in deadly lusts. And the crown of thorns which surrounded His head denoted that He would gather to Himself a divine people from amongst sinners. We, who were unrighteous, and were gathered together from amongst thorns, surround the sacred head of God; called by Him who is the Master and Lord of all living creatures, we surround Him like a wreath. He bore tortures, blows, and at last death, in order that, under Him as a leader, man might lead death, vanquished and bound with chains, as a captive in LACTANTIUS. 211 triumph. But this most shameful mode of death, to which the lowest alone are condemned, was inflicted on Him in order that He might bring help to the low and weak; in order that there might be none unable to imitate Him; and, further, in order that His body, which was destined to rise again the third day, might remain unmutilated. But, above all, because He was appointed to be lifted up, in order that His sufferings might be evident to all. And so, in His passion, He stretched wide His hands and embraced the world, in order even then to show that, from the rising of the sun to the going down of the same, a great people should be gathered together, out of all tongues and tribes, under His wings, to receive that highest and exalted sign on their foreheads (c. 26). It cannot be denied that Lactantius thus struck a new and very remarkable chord; nor ought it to be objected, that the ethical method adopted by him leads only to a perfect man, but not to the incarnation of God. For he maintains that man eannot even know, much less set forth, the perfect good apart from God. And if, as he hints, the ethical perfection both of the law and of God requires that God also should realize virtue as aman, living amongst men; and if, further, the revelation of the good remains incomplete, so long as the heavenly and the earthly are not fully adjusted, until the former manifests itself completely in the latter; Lactantius had ground enough for teaching an incarnation in the strictest sense, especially as he must have been concerned to represent the love which mani- fested itself in the “ viva preesensque lex,’ or “virtus,” as the inmost essence of God. This, however, he does not carry out: on the contrary, out of regard to his Monotheism, he glaringly contradicts the doc- trine of the Church; at the same time, also, falling into in- consistency with himself. God he-considers-to -be-absolutely simple and indivisible (Inst. lib. i.). It is true, uncultivated people, such as misunderstand the Scriptures, are incautious, and weak in the faith, look upon Christ as a second God (4, 29). But He never called Himself God, in order that He might not be untrue to His mission of overthrowing Heathenism, as He would have been had He introduced in its place a new kind of Polytheism; and in order not to seek His own, and thus be guilty of falling away from God, who sent Him (4, 14). Lac- ai? FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. tantius could not indeed have held a mere man to be the living law, the personal virtue; for the flesh drags all to the earth, to sin, and to death, with the sole exception of Christ. In order that it might have no power over Him, He must be an_un- changeable and perfect. spirit, who merely assumed flesh for the purpose of vanquishing it, and who, to the end that He might be able to withstand its assaults, had been previously established in good. He thus arrives at the idea of a higher nature in Christ, which he even conceives as a pre-existent hypostasis ; but his Monotheism prevents him admitting this hypostasis into the inner circle of the divine. We see from this connection that Lactantius ought properly to have represented Christ as assuming an humanity tainted with the sin of the race, in order that He might endure and overcome the temptations which we experience, and which, in his view, proceed from the body. And, in point of fact, he did not deem the significance of the supernatural birth of Christ to be its protecting Him from the sin of the race; but He must be born differently from other men, to the end it might be certain and plain that a heavenly spirit had become man, in the man Jesus. With the flesh which He bore, He took upon Himself sins,—not of course His own sins, for He had none, but the sins of the flesh; and the effect of His bap- tism was to wash out these sins, as in a spiritual bath (4, 15). This higher, blessed spirit (beatus, 4, 8), although he is a spirit amongst others (ceteri angeli, 4, 8, 16), although he is a creature and belongs to the world (factus), is also very different srom the rest. He was created before all, that He might be the Creator of the universe and the counsellor of God. When God was about to put His hand to this glorious work of crea- tion, He brought forth an holy, incorruptible, and irreprehen- sible spirit (sanctum et incorruptibilem et irreprehensibilem spiritum genuit), whom He designated Son. And although He afterwards created innumerable other spirits through Him, whom we term angels, He deigned to confer the divine name on this. first-born One alone, the Head of the angels (4, 14), because in Him was the fulness of the Father’s power and glory. His proper name no one knows, save He Himself; but it will be made manifest at the end of the days. Amongst men He is termed Christ, that is, King; not because of this earthly king- dom, for the taking possession of which the time is not yet LACTANTIUS. peal hs come, but because of the heavenly and eternal kingdom. But as His origin from God was a peculiar one (see pp. 193 f.), out of the heart of God—for which reason, also, the words “ gionl, generar,” are applied to Him (c. 6, 8),—so also was His nature exalted. The personal Word of God, which He is, abides to all eternity; for power and wisdom flowed over from the Father into Him, as a stream from its source (c. 8). God having determined to send to men the perfect law and the teacher of virtue, He commanded the Son to subject Himself to a second birth. He entered, accordingly, into the pure womb of the Virgin, and clothed Himself with a human body. But because Christ came on earth, adorned with virtue and righteousness, nay more, because He was Himself virtue and righteousness, it was right (He deserved it from all peoples, for His virtue’s sake) that He should be believed as God (4,16). For the sake of the virtue and faithfulness He displayed towards God on earth, the kingdom and the honour and the dominion were con- ferred upon Him, and all peoples and tribes and tongues shall serve Him, and His power is eternal, and His kingdom shall see no end. Even now He has power with those who honour His name, who confess His majesty, who follow His teachings, who imitate His virtue; but when He shall come again to judge all souls, and to restore the righteous to life, then will He truly be- come the Governor of the whole earth ; and the golden age will begin (c. 12). In the eternal temple which He founds, He will be the eternal Priest (c. 14). Notwithstanding -all.the subordination, therefore, he places Him so high, as not merely to assign Him a thoroughly unique position in the universe; but even to see occasion for justifying Christians in asserting that they worship but one God, whilst at the same time they speak of two, to wit, of God the Father and God the Son (ec. 29). When we speak thus, says he, we do not mean an entirely different one, nor do we separate the two (non diversum dici- mus, nec utrumque secernimus) ; for neither the Father can be separated from the Son, nor the Son from the Father ; indeed, God could not be termed Father without Son, nor could the Son have been generated (generari) without Father. Inasmuch, then, as the Father makes the Son (faciat), and the Son is made, both possess one common mind, one spirit, one substance {una utrique mens, unus spiritus, una substantia est). The 214 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. former, however, is, as it were, the overflowing fountain (fons exuberans); the latter is the stream which flows out of it. “ Ile tanquam Sol,” says he with Tertullian, “hic quasi radius a Sole porrectus.” Because the Son is as dear as He is faithfur to the most high Father, He is no more separated from Him than the stream is separate from its source, or the ray from the sun; for the water of the fountain is in the stream, and the light of the sun is in the ray. Even so, we cannot conceive the word without the mouth which gives utterance to it, nor the hand and power separated from the body. But all these names are given to the Son. And,though a father concede to his only and beloved son the title and authority of the master of the house, still the house continues one and the lord one. Father and Son, therefore, are one God. One is alone, free, the Most High God, without beginning (carens origine), in that He Himself is the beginning of things, and in Him all things, even the Son, are included. And because the mind and will of the one is in that of the other, or, better, because one mind and will is in both (vel potius una mens et voluntas in utroque), both persons are justly termed the one God; for all that is in the Father flows over into the Son, and whatever the Son has He derives from the Father. Wherefore, also, the Most High and singular God (singularis Deus) can only be worshipped through the Son. Whoso honoureth not the Son, honoureth not the Father. Lactantius thus approximates more closely to the doctrine of the Church, at the close of his treatise on Christ; for, in agreement with it, he recognises the equality of the essence of the Son with that of the Father, His hypostatical pre-existence, and His divine dignity. When, however, he denies that He is coeternal with the Father, who alone is without beginning, he contradicts his own assertion of the equality of the essence of © the pre-existent hypostasis of the Son with that of the Father. He also, according to what was advanced in the preceding sec- tion, fell foul of the clearly indicated tendency of the Church subsequently to Origen; but, at the same time, he must be allowed to have been justified in entertaining the view he did, so long as teachers of the Church, like Zeno of Verona, main- tained that the generation of the Son occurred simultaneously with the commencement of the world. For thus the generation LACTANTIUS. 215 of the Son and the creation of the world were brought into too close proximity. When, then, he modified this view of the Son, as originated prior to, and for the purpose of, the creation of the world, which was traditional in occidental Africa, by placing the Son in the series of mundane beings, and thus representing Him asa creature, even though the highest, he separated, indeed, elements which, though incompatible with each other, Tertul- lian had combined in his system ; but fell, in consequence, into inconsistencies, and failed to meet the claims of his own ethical construction of Christology (see p. 210). Nor did he ward off the danger of Polytheism; for he gave to a creature the name of God, designated Father and Son the one God, and attributed to the Son equality of essence with the Father, in such a way as to give the idea of creation an ethnic and emanatistic colour- ing. Even at this point, it is clear enough that Monotheism, out of regard for which he adopted subordinatian views, is more completely secured when the Son is put on an equality with the Father, than when He is subordinated in any sense, at all satis- factory to the Christian mind. Indeed, Lactantius himself was at last compelled (c. 29), for the purpose of securing the unity of God, to recognise the equality of the Father and the Son (una mens, unus spiritus, una substantia). By this doctrine of the pre-existent and created Son was his Christology also destined to be pressed; for it is incom- patible both with a true humanity and a true self-abasement. The highest of the angels can naturally only assume a human husk, the body; otherwise, two complete, finite beings would be, as it were, incased in each other. Further, that higher spirit comes to the earth with virtue already perfect ; and yet He is to be an example to men, and is to grow in virtue and be rewarded for it; whilst, at the same time, as an eternal spirit, He is unshakeable, and therefore in no danger whatever from the assaults of the flesh. That a being with such a nature bore merely an apparent resemblance to us, who possess a soul, and are through it exposed to temptations, could only have escaped the notice of Lactantius in consequence of a further fault of his, that, namely, of regarding the spirit of man as perfectly good and pure in itself, and of attributing evil entirely to the body. Herewith also are connected Pelagian principles, such as, the presupposition that, if we have the perfect image of 216 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH virtue before us, our spirit is capable of the same virtue, and of vanquishing the flesh; which involves him in plain contradic- tion with the argument he had previously employed, that an earthly teacher could not be without sin, and that a higher power, a heavenly teacher, is therefore necessary to the exhibi- tion of perfect virtue in the flesh. For, indeed, our moral power would be greater if He needed the indwelling of the Word, in order to set forth perfect virtue; whilst we, through simply be- holding this representation, without the communication of His power, and even without having previously attained the forgive- ness of sin by Him, are able to rise up to heaven. It is at this point we see that Lactantius must either attribute a higher sig- nificance to Christ, or the pains he is at to posit such a person as he does, are useless and without sufficient ground. The fault thereof, however, must by no means be sought in the stress he lays on the ethical, but in his inadequate conception of the ethical. His virtue is confined to secondary spheres ; even the moral relation to God is not more carefully considered. Had he distinctly recognised the ethical to be the highest, as, in agreement with his entire tendency, he should have done, he would not have been able to call a secondary being the “ lex viva,” but the Most High God alone. Then the question arises,—Can a subordinate being bind us to unconditional obe- dience to the law in his own name? Or, can the arbitrariness which is not bound to the law find a place in God, when it can find no place in Him who is the living law? In that case, the ethical has in the last instance no hold, is based on caprice, and has its ground, not in the sphere of the absolute, but in that of the secondary. Had he conceived God Himself to be the living law, the appearance of the living law would have been, as the Church teaches, the appearance of God Himself, and the latter might have been shown to be an ethical necessity. Lactantius’ strange doctrine of the “manus sinistra Dei,’ the Holy Spirit who takes part in the evil, the “interpretamentum boni,” is a clear enough proof that he deemed it necessary to think God in false and fancied exaltation above the ethical. But to represent arbitrariness, caprice, as the highest in God, is simply the prac- tical Occidental expression for the absolutely indeterminate “Ov of the East,—it was falling back into the physical. A similar re- gression was his making the body the seat of sin ; in consequence, EUSEBIUS OF CESAREA. a however, of failing to show completely that the ground of the ethical is in God Himself, and therefore of not recognising its absoluteness, he failed also to see that the ethical must root in fellowship with God, and in His real communication of Himself. Had he weighed this properly, he would have arrived, with his deeper view of the divine righteousness (de via Dei), at a clearer conviction of the necessity of the atonement, which is quite left out of sight, even in the beautiful remarks which he makes con- cerning the death of Christ. In this way, also, the significance of Christ the Mediator would have been heightened; and both for the sake of the atonement and of vital fellowship with God (necessary to be established even on account of the ethical alone), he would have been driven to see in Christ, not the presence of an exalted finite spirit, but of the Most High God Himself. With all this, however, we must mention, to his praise, that he did not regard Christ as a mere organ of God, as a means in God’s hand, as Sabellianism was compelled, and as Arianism was inclined, to do. In his view, Christ is an end in Himself, and that in a sense which does not hold of men or spirits in general; He is, namely, the object of divine worship together with the Father. He recognised it also as necessary to the per- fection of the Son, that He should have fellowship with the Father, nay more, that He should be of one substance with the Father. Il. Husebius of Caesarea. In casting a glance at the Eastern Church prior to the appearance of ne on the scene, the system of Eusebius of Czesarea gives us the truest picture of the points which the then prevailing doctrine of the Trinity and of the Person of Christ had left unsettled, and which rendered it possible for many to continue vacillating between Subordinatianism and Sabellian- ism. He stands both near enough to, and far enough from, Arius and Athanasius, to show us plainly that he decision arrived at by the Council of Niczea, in the case of Arius, could not but be adverse; and that, notwithstanding, the controversies which succeeded that ddeieiea were still a possibility. We learn from him, further, that the Church had arrived at a point at 218 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. which it could not.stand still, but must choose one_or other of two courses,—either to take a step in advance, and define the indefinite, or to go backwards either into Heathenism_or into Judaism. It has been matter of controversy for a long period, whether Eusebius should be reckoned orthodox after the Nicene standard, or be classed with the adherents of Arius.’ In recent times, the Catholic Church has shown a decided inclination to the latter supposition; the former supposition has become almost tradi- tional with investigators belonging to the Anglican Church.’ German science, on the contrary, is pretty unanimous in the opinion, that neither of the two is the case.* In fact, his doc- trinal system is a chameleon-hued thing, a mirror of the un- solved problems of the Church of that age. According to Eusebius, God is in His inmost essence one : only with an eye to the world, and God’s relation to it, can we speak of a Trinity. ‘To hold that the unity of God, or the Monas, expresses that which is inmost in God, and not that the unity is to be conceived as containing plurality within itself, appeared to him necessary, whether regard be had principally to the general, or to the distinctively Christian, idea of God. Inas- much, namely, as God is the highest, and as this highest can only be one and not several; inasmuch, further, as there cannot be more than one uncreated being; contemplation, in its loftiest flights, arrives at the One. This One is exalted above all plu- rality, for plurality has place only in subordinate spheres; it is absolutely perfect in itself, self-sufficient, and is as far from needing, as it is from suffering itself, to be complemented by another. It lies out beyond all that has been-created, because it + Amongst the ancients, Socrates, Theodoret, Gelasius Cyzic. pronounce him orthodox ; Athanasius regarded him with a degree of suspicion; Epi- phanius and Jerome treat him more harshly. * For Arian, he is held by Petavius, Baronius, Montfaucon (Coll. Noy. T. I. xv.-xxix.), Clericus, and Mohler; for orthodox, by Montacutius, G. Bull, Cave (Hist. liter. Appendix, Diss. 3, pp. 193-206), and with a refer- ence to the work of Eusebius on the Theophany, first edited by himself, Samuel Lee, in a longer treatise (pp. xxiv.—xcii.). Valesius, also, takes the favourable view of the case. 3 Martini, Eusebii Cesar. de divin. Christi sententia, 1795; Baur, Tri- nitiit. 473 ff.; and specially Henell, de Euseb. Cees. religionis christ. de- fensore,” Gott. 1843, pp. 42 ff. EUSEBIUS OF CAESAREA. 219 is absolutely self-caused: for this reason, it cannot be compared with the world; and to attempt a comparison is godless. ‘There- fore, also, is it the Unutterable, the Inexplicable, Being abso- lutely (70 *Ov), or the primal substance (77 mpatn Ovoia) ; it is aseity conceived as a person. In setting forth this (as he deemed it) exalted conception of God, Eusebius was quite aware of his accordance with the Neo-Platonists; but it did not seem at all objectionable, that the extra-Christian and the Christian idea of God should be identical. In its relation to all things lying outside of this unity, he designates the “Ov, apxn avapyos, the mpatov aitvov. But as respects the Chris- tian idea of God, it is universally allowed that even the Son is not self-caused, but is caused by the Father ; and if the Son is generated, then the Father alone can be described as ungene- rated. But as the Ungenerated is one and the same with the ‘Ov, the Christian expression “Father” is to be referred to the ‘Ov; and as that aseity, and the supreme unity involved there, constitutes the proper essence of the Deity, deity can be predi- cated alone, “sensu eminenti,” of the Father. He is the repre- sentative of the wovapyia. If another, for example, the Son, were coeternal with the Father, we should have two eternals, or Polytheism (adv. Marcell. 2, 12). By this line of argument, however, Eusebius meant rather to establish than to do away with the Trinity. As Polytheism is abhorrent to faith, the Christian mind could never acknow- ledge a Trinity if Father and Son were placed on exactly the same level. And if they be supposed to constitute together the one Eternal, we should arrive at Sabellianism. For, either both would be completely the same, and then every trace of a Trinity would be blotted out;* or if they constituted one, in the sense of one being the complement of the other, neither the Father nor the Son would be complete, neither would be en- tirely the one, by Himself, apart from the other. H, however, they need another element to constitute their being, neither of 1 Compare Prep. Evang. 11, 9, 16-19. Theoph. 2, 24. 27. 29. 2 Ady. Mare. 2, 12:—¢ 09 Mapxeanos, oindels el olov sivas avtoyv Tov O¢ov Aéyov, rovréoriv dyevuyrov, ToAranxis aplowro, ov avvopay, ors ek “ey Erepoy TOU OQz0v rev Advyov Deonst, O00 Zoras ki'dia, 6 Adyos nai 0 Oxos nol oux &r cares cox) pela. Ei 08 y rgyorro af Osov, tov aires Gpiopeevos sivas roy Ozoy Tq ACY, yupevoy TOY—LaBEAALOV Gmoroynasl, viowarTopa Toy Eve slocryuy. 220 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. the two would be a perfect, self-sufficient hypostasis ;' but the one must be reduced to the rank of divine mowoTntes, that is, become a predicate, and the other be recognised as the subject : in which case, the distinction can have no reality. Or the one will be accident, the other substance; or the one divine essence will be divided into several parts, which taken together consti- tute the Deity. In either of these cases, the hypostasis of the Son, which is universally recognised as necessary, would become an unreality; for the Christian mind is not satisfied that God should be in Christ as a mere power, or transitorily, but demands that He have a personal existence in Him. Precisely, therefore, in order that a lofty and permanent significance may be attached to Christ, and that a Trinity may be possible, the Son must be regarded as something different from the Unbegotten One, who is the highest deity itself. He must be the debrepos Oeds, in rank (74) inferior to the Father; He is the devTEpa ovala or brdéotacis: the Father is to be conceived as existing prior to Him (mpovTapyeav), not indeed in time—for before the creation of the world there was uo time—but causatively: for the Father is the highest and ultimate aizvov.? Both His being and the mode of His bein the Son derives from the Father, and that through the medium of His will and purpose (qvén, Tpoaipecis, Bovrn).° The idea of God, therefore, is complete, prior to and apart from the Trinity; the unity alone constitutes the full concep- tion of God, and not the plurality with the unity; the Hovapyia is God, “sensu eminenti;” and the Hovapyia pertains to the Father alone. God’s being a Trinity depends on His will, At the same time, this does not signify that God might be other * Demonstr. ev. 4, 3, ed. Paris, 1628, p. 148:—o ev x06 sevurdy Tersioc xeel Tparos we Tarinp xal tis row viov ovoracems aitios, ovdey éic TUL TAnpwow rhs éevrov bedrnroc Tepe Tov vied AeuBavav. “Dem. ev. 4,8 7" 0 03) de && eirlov (xarpos) yeyovas vide, devrepoc ov catty vids nedéornxen, Tape Tov weerpos nol rd elvees xeel rordade elves SiAnQuc. ° L. ¢. "H pév adyy (this had been the favourite image of Origen; but it seemed insufficient to Eusebius, because of its physical, or even emanatis- tic character) ob xara Tpotipsow Tov Qwros exhaperes, xara 08 rt THe odoles guKB ‘ € , sy \ \ ~ DA dC > ~ / [77 U 4 ‘ AUTOS O Aayos toTh TpEMTOS, TH OE dim HUTESOVTIM, £a¢ CovAsTal, Lever xaAOZ, 7 Ld ’ ery \ \ 7 \ c ~ ~ a” ore wsytos OAs, Ovvaras tpercobar nal avros OO%ED Hab HUSIS, THETTYS ws , \ x \ 5 , G ‘ ” ‘ ae GA Quoeas. Arie rovro yao Dyot, xb Toovyivaocuwy o Osos, eosabas xaxAcv cevres ARIUS. 241 birth, and consequently by nature, is taken away; and saints also, with the aid of the like tpovwv émipéreva kal aoxnors, may become what He is (compare Theodoret, H. E. 1, 3). An en- tirely different principle now begins to be adopted, and a merely ethical Sonship to be substituted for that of essence and nature. We have already found the idea of an ethical Sonship in a very developed state in the system of Lactantius (after hints by Paul of Samosata) , Lactantius, however, never ceased to pre- suppose the essential and natural Sonship. The only novelty, therefore, is, that Arius reduces the natural divine Sonship of Christ to a completely inoperative thing, or, more exactly ex- pressed, reduces it to nonentity. This harmonizes very well with one part of his system. He was concerned not merely to establish the loftiness of God, which, in the last instance, he was compelled to define as the absolute freedom of an arbitrary causality ; but also to separate God and man in such a way as to secure to each complete (deistic) independence. If man is completely set loose from God, he is by that very means endowed with a likeness to God, in that, namely, God and the divine bear the same non-essential relation to him as the world bears to God. This separation, therefore, restores to man his equality to God ;—neither the will of God nor the will of man is deter- mined by anything essentially contained in it. Man also enjoys, in his measure, that. formal freedom, which in God is absolute, and which constitutes the divine loftiness. Although, therefore, the divine causality was unable to transfuse any part of the divine essence into man and into the nature of Christ, because otherwise the distinction affirmed by Arius, between God and the world, would be effaced; yet the freedom of Christ, indeed the freedom of men in general, is the principle which enables that which was created out of nothing, and is yet void of con- tent, to secure a divine substance for its form; which, in a word, renders it capable of producing the divine out_of_itself,.and of thus becoming deified. And, if we are not very nice in our use of words, this self-deification might be described as a divine apts, or Géous or Oeorroinats,* so far as God does not prevent it, wporeBayv arte ravryy tiv dofey dédwxev, qv kvOpuros nal ex rig coerijs axe Let e TavTe, WoTe ef Epyav avTOV, ay rpotyyw 6 Osds, ToLovrov avToy vUY vErYo- vives ~eroinzgy. Compare Theodor. H. E. 1,3, and the next note. 1 Athan. c. Ar. or. 1, 5. 6:—Ei 6¢ xeel Agyeras Osos, AA ove &Anbivds VOL. Vt, Q 242 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. but allows it to come to pass, and so far as He accepts the per fect man, the man who has become God, as His Son, and con fers upon Him titles and dignities. But although this formally ethical principle fits very well into one portion of the system of Arius, it is equally far from suiting the remainder. If divine Sonship, not merely in the new and higher form, but in general, must first be earned through the medium of formal freedom; if, further, the pre- existent hypostasis, and the good which may be inherent therein, — ought to be, nay more, must necessarily be, inactive, inasmuch as resemblance to God cannot proceed from God Himself, but must be the fruit of the exercise of freedom, not only in the case of men, but also in that of Christ ;—to what purpose, then, this pre-existent hypostasis, which is reduced to inactivity? It is without significance relatively to Christology; it is nothing but a burdensome, confusing, cosmological appendage, which ought rather to have been cast aside with the occupation of this totally new point of view. Athanasius and Alexander were justified in saying to Arius, that his home was rather with Paul of Samosata than in the Church. Or is the pre-existent hypo- stasis of the Son supposed to render any service at all, even though merely in connection with creation? But he has so lessened it, and reduced it to the level of other rational creatures ; he has made its entire dignity so completely dependent on its moral behaviour, that it is powerless to effect the creation of the world." Or was this necessary, that Christ might be able to bring His revelation? What Arius thought of this matter we have seen already; and, at all events, his disciples very gOTIV, AAAL METoXH Ku piTos, aamep xoel ol AAAOL WavTEs, OUTH xual KITOS Aéyercee cvouars wovoyv Oecev. Desent. Dion. c. 238 :—Odx gars pev xard Qdow xel aAnOivoy Tov Qeov vies, xara Beary O€ Agyeras xael oTOS vids, ws uticue. Or. 1,9 :—Meroxyy nai adres ebeoroindn. Ep. Alex. ad Alex.in Theodor. H. E. 1, 3:—‘ No one is Son of God by nature,” say they ; ‘‘ therefore also the Son has not Qvcss eZc/perdv ts above others: but God selected Him from all others (éZesney das atrov xo xevrwy) because He foreknew that He would not go astray.” ‘ It is true, even in the Thalia, he does not venture to give utterance te this thought, but, at the same time, it sets forth the Son, so far as, in virtue of His office of Creator, He must occupy a higher position than we, as a mere instrument and means, of which we are the end; and, so far as He does not exist solely on our account, He is put on a level with us. Compare Athan. c. Ar. or. 1, 5. 6; Socr. H. E. 1. c. 170: ARIUS. 243 properly went on to maintain, that the Son also needed first to learn what He knew, and to deny to Him both essential know- ledge and essential goodness (see note, p. 236). Nay more, Kustathius of Antioch (Gallandi Bibl. IV. 580) informs us that some Arians did not even shrink from classing Christ amongst sinners. Inasmuch, further, as, in his view, all men are alike free, being rational creatures, what need can there be of Christ? Even in his Thalia, Arius found nothing whatever to say regarding sin. Nay more, according to his idea of virtue and freedom, every man must be able to redeem himself, or rather to raise himself up to God. Still, Arius must always have attached great significance to this pre-existent. hypostasis ; for he regarded it as, strictly speaking, the personal element in the human life of Christ, and on its account was compelled to mutilate the humanity of Christ, by denying to it a human soul; because, otherwise, two finite spirits must have been represented as constituting one person. But even on this supposition, the only office discharged by the hypostasis, is that of an hindrance ; and precisely at this point does it become very evident that his principles, carried to their logical results, necessitated the rejection of the notion of a pre-existent hypo- stasis. Had he taken this step, he would have completely identified himself with Paul of Samosata. As it is, however, he is neither one thing nor another; and, being occupied solely with finite and single objects, never rises to a free survey of the connections of the whole as such. He reduces God Himself, in His pre-eminence, to singularity, to an abstract individual, shut up in His own egoism: of love, that is, of the absolutely ethical, he has no notion whatever. Even the ethical which he recog- nises is a relative thing, grounded in the antithesis between God and man. We might also show, in connection with all the main points, that his dialectic, being that of the understand- ing, never fails, agreeably to its innate character, unconsciously to nullify earlier by later principles; although, at the same time, it consoles itself with the ineradicable conviction of the clearness and certainty of its own knowledge. Let it suffice, however, to draw attention to one or two. Arius affirms that there is but one God; and, because he refuses to allow any- thing to be abstracted from Him, he represents Him as mcom- municable. And yet his deistic point of view drives him ta 244 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. attribute such an absoluteness to the world, as constitutes it in reality a plurality of deities. In presence of the freedom of man, God actually recedes completely into the background. Further, let it be remarked how Arius at first represents the Son as a «rica, in order to preserve the simplicity and unity of God; and at the same time constitutes Him a creative, in- ferior God, in order that the gulf arising from the loftiness of God may not be too great. On a subsequent occasion, for the sake of this same divine loftiness, he puts the Son on a far lower level ; but did not reflect that he was thus depriving the world of its basis, as which, his conception of God required him to regard the Son, and the Son alone. Finally, if this basis can no longer consistently be held to lie in the Son, but must be contained immediately in the Father alone, the principle of the entire course of thought, that on which he had mainly leant for support when reducing the Son to the rank of a xricpa, is undermined; to wit, that of the abstract simplicity, incommuni- cableness of God, and His absolute separation from the world. It is clear, that a system of thought so destitute of hold, and so unweariedly occupied in refuting itself, could never ER iliie: a permanent type of doctrine ; the renee however, with which it jumped from one momentum to Lire and ever turned the one against the other, was fitted to set them all in motion and ferment, and thus to prepare the way for their interpenetration and intermixture. CHAPTER THIRD. THE COUNCIL OF NICZA, AND THE BEGINNINGS OF ATHANASIUS. Ine doctrine of Arius met with the warmest opposition, in the first instance, in Alexandria. Alexander refuted it from the Holy Scriptures, specially by means of the prologue to the Gospel of John. How can He be the First-born, if He is to be put on the same level with us all? Or how can He be the creator of Him whose equal He is? If the Logos and Wisdom were not as eternal as God, God must at one period have been ALEXANDER AGAINST ARIUS 245 without wisdom and reason. Further, were the Son mutable, how could He be so intimately united with the Father? If He is in the Father, and the Father in Him, He must thus be pre- served from mutability; and not even the incarnation can have produced an alteration in Him. Further, how is it possible that He, who is reason itself, should not know the Father, whose reason He is (Adyos)? Or how can He have been brought into existence solely on our behalf, for whose sake, and by whom, all things were created? (Socr. H. E. 1, 6.) So far from having been Himself created out of nothing, He rather Himself created all things out of nothing, and must, therefore, be far removed from that which is created. On the contrary, it is impossible even in thought to represent an interval (éca- oTnua) between Father and Son. Not as though the Son had not been generated; one only is unbegotten, to wit, the Father ; but the generation of the Son was something so exalted, that it surpassed the understanding of the Evangelists, and surpasses, perhaps, that of the angels also. He then, in particular, lays bare the subreption contained in the Arian proposition—jp drte ovx nv. ‘This, again, involves the existence of a time; but all time is created by Him, and comes into existence along with the world ; consequently, the time in which He is said not to have existed, must have existed through Him, for otherwise the cause would be posterior to its effect. If a time had been created anterior to Him, He could no longer be described as the First-born of all creation. The Father, therefore, must always have been Father, because the Son, through whom He is Father, sways existed. Precisely for this reason is He ever the perfect Father, who never lacks anything good (rédevos avedduTijs év T® Kadk®). Whoso denies the brightness, denies also the arche- typal light (wpwrdtumov das), of which it is the reflection. If He, who is the express image (yapax7yp) and copy of the divine essence, is not eternal, neither is the substance of the image and the object of the copy eternal. On this ground, the Sonship of the Redeemer has nothing in common with that of others; for His was a natural Sonship (cata dvow tijs maxpuxfs Oeorntos) : the latter is one of adoption (@écer). We are mutable in both aspects, and therefore need help from the Unchangeable One. How, then, can the wisdom of God be supposed to progress, or the power of God to increase? Or how can wisdom be sup- 246 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. posed to be turned into folly, and strength into weakness? To the creature alone, on the contrary, is it given as a blessing, to be able to increase in virtue; and through Him, who is by nature Son, to be freed from the spirit of fear, and to receive sonship by grace, by adoption. The latter may possibly be lost ; the former cannot be lost. But it is a calumny of the Arians to charge him (Alexander) with teaching that there are two ungenerated Beings, or to maintain that he ought to teach it, if he do not. The Father alone is unbegotten; He alone nee no oon of His being out of Himself (ovdéva rod civas avT® Tov aitvov dvta). ‘The*Son is in every other respect equal to the Father, and falls short in nothing, save that He is not unbegotten (ons TO ayEevynT@ AELTrOM“EVoY avTOD) ; and to this difference refer the words, “'The Father is greater than I.” But He was not, therefore, created out of nothing, but is of the Father. In connection herewith, not only Arius, but also Sabellius and Valentine, are repudiated, who ascribe to God something resembling the body, corporeal divisions and emis- sions, instead of resting satisfied with the unutterable mystery, whose unsearchableness is declared even by the Scriptures (Isa. li. 8), “ Who shall declare His generation?” (Theodor. H. E. 1, 3.) We see from this, that Alexander’s aim was to establish the closest possible connection between the hypostasis of the Son and His eternal divine essence. In carrying out his design, he decidedly posits a duality in God, and, if we may judge from the images employed by him, conceives the Logos of the Father to be objectified in the Son; though he does not express any opinion as to the relation between the reason and power of the Father (apart from which, no conception can be formed of Him), and the reason and power of the Son. His images, in themselves, would warrant us in concluding, that he conceived the Father to have reason and power, not in Himself, but in the Son ; that he simply identified the reason of the Father and of the Son; that, consequently, the Son was the Father Himself, under a determinate form, and, as a determination or attribute, constituted part of the full conception of the Father. This, however, would contradict the duality which he had pre- viously laid down. A very numerously attended Synod, held at Alexandria (Soer. 1. ¢.), concurred with Alexander, and deposed Arius and COUNCILS OF ALEXANDRIA AND NICHA. 247 his followers. But as Arius had a supporter in Eusebius of Nicomedia, and other Oriental bishops also took his part, an (Ecumenical Council was convened at Niczea, in the year 325, for the settlement of the points in dispute. The judgment of the Alexandrian Synod was confirmed, and the Nicene Creed was framed, which acknowledges the generation of the Son from the Father, and gives the following more precise defini- tion of it:—That the Son is of the essence of the Father; that He is very God of very God; that He was begotten, not created. Mainly, however, in consequence of the efforts of Athanasius—that vigorous champion of Christian interests— there was added the recapitulatory term, ofoovcvoy, the main purpose of which was, to express the identity of essence, though it also further implied or presupposed the equal coexistence of two: this latter was involved also in the term yervav. The only expression in the Symbolum, bearing on the nature of the distinction between the two, is the following: “The Son is of the Father, who begat Him.” It is primarily directed against Arianism, not against Sabellianism. The latter, however, was also excluded, in so far as it was unable to attach any meaning to the idea of generation, specially not to that of the generation of a pre-existent hypostasis, which, as the Symbolum affirms, created the world. But the Creed contains also the idea of the eternal generation, as is clear when we combine the simultaneity of Father and Son with the yeyvav. To the double affirmation contained in opoovctov, there is a correspondent double nega- tion :—1. The Son did not arise out of nothing, nor indeed out of any other substance, or any other essence, than the Father (consequently, not merely duosos to the Father) ; He was, there- fore, neither created nor mutable. 2. It is unlawful to say, There was a time when He was not, or, He was not ere He was generated; for these are propositions which apply the idea of time to the generation of the Son, and imply that the genera- tion had a commencement. (Note 48.) The duty devolving on the Fathers at the Council of Nicza, was to set forth and confess the substance of the Christian faith, not to give doctrinal speculations. Hitherto, only.a few had entered on dogmatical investigations ; not till twenty years later did the Church in general devote attention thereto. If we take into consideration that the first effect of devoting attention te 246 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. the dialectic conciliation of doctrines must necessarily be to rob many of that immediate assurance of the truth of Christianity by which they were possessed, and that the place of the really grand unity of spirit evinced in Nica must be usurped by a manifold variety of views, which, ere they could be brought, as to their principal features, not to say into uniformity, but into an harmonious unity, must be discussed, reflected upon, and thoroughly cleared up,—we shall esteem it a special favour of Providence, that the conscience of the Church was appealed to for its testimony and confession, so long as it still retained its direct certitude and simplicity; and that thus, at the very com- mencement of its voyage, a beacon was enkindled to mark the Church’s pathway across the stormy seas which lay before it. But a firm and steady pilot’s hand was also provided for the voyage, in the person of a man who was endowed with a superior, farseeing, and no less speculative than Christian mind, and who, through his power of endurance and strength of character, always remained master of the position. Athana- sius the Great made it the task of his long and very eventful life to defend the creed adopted by the Nicene Council, with all the weapons of science and spiritual chivalry, against the vacillating and shortsighted on the one hand, and the apostate on the other hand, and to constitute it, not merely a vital and common treasure of all believers, but also a subject of real knowledge. And to him was given what, is given to but very few—the happiness of seeing the idea to which, as youth and man, he had devoted his life, attain to ever wider influence and recognition, and of sinking into the grave, not merely crowned with honour, but laden with the fruits of his labours. Specially noteworthy, as indicative of the character of the tendency of the Church at the beginning of the fourth century, are (besides the above) the two works written by Athanasius prior to the Nicene Council, and without reference to Arius, entitled Adyos Kata ‘ENjvev (oratio contra Gentes), and sept ‘THs evavOpwricews tod Adyou (de incarnatione Verbi Dei). These works set before us, at the same time, the beginnings of Athanasius. He evinces an acquaintance with Greek philo- sophy, and his presentation of Christian doctrine has many points of affinity therewith; at the same time, however, the vital centre of Christianity is grasped by him with such intense ATHANASIUS. 249 fervour, and is treated in such a scientific spirit, that it gives us the groundwork of a grand system of speculative Christian theology. What engaged his attention above all things else, was the Logos. His existence he presupposed, firstly, as the faith of the Church, secondly, as conceded by the philosophy of the day; lastly, on historical grounds. He does not, it is true, enter into a closer investigation of the relation of the Logos to the Father, and to the unity of God; he does, how- ever, examine His relation to the world in all the three aspects, of creation, preservation, and incarnation. The purpose of his work was to communicate that which he had learnt from the many blessed teachers who had explained the holy. Scriptures, and to show that the Christian faith—by which he understood the belief in the incarnation of the Logos —was no slight (edredés) nor irrational (dAoyov) thing. Let us, in the first place, consider his doctrine of God and man, in order thus to see what was the basis of his doctrine of the God-man. Oe oe He arrives at his idea of God, in the first place, by overcom- ing the error of Heathenism. God is neither the world, says he, nor a part of the world. In the world, every part is dependent on the other,—the rivers on the mountains, the mountains on the earth, the earth on the sun. God, however, cannot be dependent on another; if He were, He would not be God (ce. Gent. c. 27). God must be self-sufficient, and requires for His existence nothing beside Himself. Nor can the whole world, its members joined together, as it were, into one body, be called God. It is true, there is nothing outside of the entire universe ; and therefore it appears independent, self-sufficient. But if the individual members combine to form a whole, and this whole is therefore constituted by them, the whole consists of the indi- vidual parts, which together are the parts of the whole. This, however, is totally different from the idea of God. God is a whole; but He is not the parts; He does not consist of differ- ent parts, but is the cause of the world and of its composition. If He consisted of parts, He would be unequal to Himself, inasmuch as that which is unequal would be the complement of His being. Sun is not moon; moon is not earth; earth is not sea. The ear is not the eye; nor the hand the foot. This difference of the parts pertains to the idea of the body; the } | a 250 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. same difference, therefore, would appertain to God also, if He were identical with the universe, conceived as one body. Further, not being compounded, God is incorporeal, invisible, not tangible by hands, but apprehensible solely by the spirit ° for this reason, therefore, He cannot be the world. On the contrary, He is in Himself, in His essence, self-sufficient, full of Himself (contra Gentes 28); and the cause of the existence _-of the universe. But he does not believe that this self-sufficient God abides in His transcendence, On the contrary, like the old propounders of the doctrine of the Logos, particularly of the Alexandrian school, Athanasius says,—He is in the world as the immanent principle of its harmony. He desires no abstract loftiness of God, as did unbelieving Judaism; he neither apprehends any danger to God, nor regards it as unworthy of Him, that He should come into contact with the world. Although it is created out of nothing, and therefore, considered in itself, can neither bear nor maintain itself; still its idea involves an essential con- nection between God or the Logos and itself. This presupposes an entirely different conception of God from the heathenish one of the “Ov, and from the Jewish, to both of which abstract simplicity is essential,—in the former case, the simplicity of substantial Pantheism, in the latter case, that of Deism. Rather, says Athanasius, giving the idea of God an ethical turn,—God is good and not envious; therefore did He create the world ; but especially in men has He taken an interest, through the Logos. Seeing that they cannot live always, He created them in His image, and endowed them with the power of the Logos, so that they became, as it were, shadows of the Logos (cxvat Aoyov) and Aoyxot. In that He further saw that the will of men was in itself still empty, and might incline to either side, He protected it preveniently by the command and by paradise. By nature, man was mortal; for he was created out of things that were not (é& ov« dvtwv). But he possessed the capacity of immortality, through his union with the Logos. Had he by obedience continued in that union, the physical necessity of death would have been overcome by the divine principle of immortality, the Logos: men would then have been as gods. But man disobeyed, and death penetrated into the world, even as the divine threatening had announced. It ATHANASIUS. pols Ai entered by an inner necessity ; for sin deprived man of the Logos, the only principle able to overcome his natural mortality. As sin grew, death grew; the image of God was destroyed; the work of God was overthrown (de ince. c. 38-6). The knot was tied still more firmly by the threatened punishment. ‘The divine threat, the pledged word of the God of truth, could not suffer: on the other hand, must the work and image of God perish? It was not worthy of God to allow His own noble work of art to perish, for the sake of a deceit of the devil. Better had it been for God not to have created, than for the evil to have the better. To have allowed that which love had created to perish, would have been weakness, and inconsistent with omnipotence. Still more inconsistent with love. God did not look with indifference on His perishing work; it appealed to His love (€exanréoaro, c. 4, 6). Should God then require repentance, and through repentance restore man to immortality? In itself, this would not have been unworthy of Him; but He could not lay Himself open to the charge of untruth, even though for our benefit. Repentance was not sufficient: had sin been the sole point in question, and not also punishment, repentance would have sufficed. But as matters actually stood, and seeing that God (the righteous) 1s true, who could help out of the difficulty, save the Logos? He, who created man out of nothing, was able to suffer for all, to stand in the stead of all (c. 7). Therefore the Logos came ; He, who was incorporeal, imperishable, omnipresent, appeared in order to reveal Himself. He saw both our misery and the threats of the law; He saw how unseemly (drozov) it would be to annul the law, save by fulfilling and satisfying it; and at the same time, how unseemly it would be that the Creator should allow His rational world to perish. And as He saw the ever-swelling tide of sin, and that all were in bondage unto death, He took compassion on them and assumed.a body, not by any necessity of nature (ficews axodoviig), for His essence is incorporeal (c. 1), but for the purpose of confirming and maintaining. the. first..creation. by..means of the second. It is characteristic of the speculative mind of Athanasius, that he everywhere treats the first and second creations as closely connected with each other; that, in accounting for the miracle of incarnation, he goes back to that of creation ; and shows that, 202 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH for the sake both of the unity of the idea of the world and of God, it was necessary that He, and He alone, through whom the Father created the world, should renew it. But He assumed no other body than ours. Had His object merely been to appear in some sort of body or other, He would not have needed ours; and if a simple theophany had been all that was required, He might have taken to Himself a much worthier organ. Rather did He assume our body, and out of the unspotted Virgin He built to Himself a body for a temple. This He constituted His organ (idcoTroteioae Bamep dpyavor), that He might dwell in it and be known through it. In con- Sequence of this appropriation of our nature, He was able to give His body to the death for all. And now, inasmuch as all have died in Him, the law is annulled by being fulfilled, that is, its curse is removed through the satisfaction. But in appro- priating the body, He bestowed upon it immortality, and through it has restored immortality to our nature. That which the act of appropriation implanted in our nature, as a mere potence, at the incarnation, became an actuality through His resurrection. He must needs let death have power over His body; in order that, by the death of death (the negation of the negation), in His resurrection there might be revealed the full and settled reality of life triumphing over, and reaching beyond, its antagonist, death (c. 8, 9). The entire appearance of Christ, but, above all, His death, had an universal significance ; because the Logos, who is above all, who is the Creator and Archetype, thereby made human nature His own. The appropriation had an effect not merely on the particular man Jesus, but also on human nature in general; for this reason, the death of all found its fulfilment in the body of the Lord (€7AnpovTo, c. 20). Guilt was heaped upon Him, collected itself in Him, the representative of the race; and His death was a payment for all. It was necessary that death should be broken, not merely in some one particular form, but as a general principle; and therefore did it behove Him to admit and take it up into Himself, so that He might overcome it completely. Now, inasmuch as the Logos, being the immortal Son of the Father, could not die, He took upon Himself a mortal body, to the intent that, by participating in the Logos, who is over all, it might be capable of dying for all, ATHANASIUS. 253: that is, of taking the euilt of all upon itself, of admitting the universal principle of death into itself, and of thus paying the universal debt and obtaining an universal victory over death. ‘Note 49.) Athanasius had the deepest insight into the con- nection between that which the incarnate Logos did and men, into its validity for us. To no other did it pertain to convert mortality into immortality, than to Him who in the beginning created the universe out of nothing, and who was Himself the Life (avtofw7); to no other than the archetype, the image of the Father, did it appertain to create man anew, “in the image of God” (c. 20, 13). If an image has been defaced, in order to its renewal the original must be compared (c. 14). Now that this Logos has taken to Himself our nature, our nature possesses Him; He belongs to us, who constitute the body of which He is the Head. Henceforth corruption has no more power over men, even in death; for in virtue of the unity of the body (which believers constitute for Christ), the Logos dwells in them. When a mighty king enters into a great city, even/ though he should but occupy one house therein, the whole city (just because it constitutes a whole) receives the highest honour. And so, when the Logos entered into our region and became the tenant of (even though only) one body, which was like ours, the power of death, which had reigned over all men from of old, disappeared (c. 9). We die still, it is true; but merely in order that we likewise may participate in the resur- rection to a better state. The first and principal ground of His incarnation, therefore, was, that the condemning law might be done away with, which burdens us with guilt and with the punishment of death. With this, also, was most closely connected, that death itself should be overcome by His payment of our debt, that is, by His own death. Another ground why the Logos must needs become man, was that_men were otherwise too weak to know God (c. 11-13). Without the knowledge of God, men would have lived in vain; for, from the very beginning, they were created thereto. They had received a share in the Logos, the image of God; they were created to be His and the Father’s image, in order that they might be able in the Spirit to lay hold on the Logos, and, in the Word, on the Father. This grace of the commencement (% Kat’ eixova ydpis) sufficed in itself, apart 254 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. from the world or anything else, for attaining a knowledge of (rod (c. 12, c. Gentes 2, 30); it of itself reflected God. But as God knew the weakness and negligence of man, He gave him the world as a revelation, that great and beautiful edifice, which, in its harmony and unity, reflects the unity and wisdom of God. He further sought to help them through the law and the prophets, as through a sacred school, appointed to give the knowledge of God to the whole of humanity, in order that it might learn to rule its passions, and to live virtuously. Men, however, degraded themselves ever more to the level of irra- tional and brute creatures. How then were they to be helped? By the revelation in creation, which they no longer regarded as a revelation, but as a deity? They had turned their gaze downwards; and therefore the Logos also descended, assumed a body from beneath, made Himself like men, in order that they who refused to know Him out.of creation might learn to know Him from the works which He wrought through the body (de incarn. c. 12-14). In this latter exposition, the in- carnation is represented, not as the substance, but merely as the means or organ of doctrine. It might appear, therefore, as though, in the view of Athanasius, the main point was simply the knowledge of the Acoyos deapxos and of the Father, prior and subsequently to Christ. But, after the above account of the points to which Athanasius attached chief importance, this would plainly be a false view. His object was rather, after having treated of the main purpose of the appearance of Christ, which he deemed to consist in deeds, to show that even the intellect of man required a revelation, such as was given by the incarnation: as was natural, however, he did not succeed so well in showing the unconditional necessity of the incarnation in relation to the prophetical office as he had succeeded in rela- tion to the high-priestly office; as to the latter point, indeed, he approximated very nearly to Anselm. But in opposition to this incarnation objections are raised. Tfow can we reconcile, he goes on to say, the dwelling of the Logos in a human body with His all-embracing infinitude? (c. 16,17.) He replies—Though He dwelt in the body, He was not shut up in it; nor was He shut out from other places; but, as the Logos, He was in the body, moving it even as He moves the universe, which He created. It is true, He is not merely ATHANASIUS. 255 in the universe, but also outside thereof, as to His essence (xar’ ovciav); He is also in the entire creation, seeing that He is in all its powers (€v Tacw éotlv tats éavtod dvvapece), ordering all things, extending His providence to all in all, giving life to each individual thing, and to the universe as a whole, embracing the universe without being embraced by it, existing everywhere in His entirety (60s kata mavra) in His Father alone. Our soul images forth in a weak way, how He, though in this body, was yet able to animate the universe. For, whilst sitting in the house, it is able to embrace distant objects, and to think of the heavens,—only, that its thoughts are not deeds, and do not move the heavens, as did the Logos in Christ; it merely knows their motion. What he here above all insists upon is, that the Logos, and not the limited humanity, is the true point of de- parture for the consideration of the Person of Christ. The Logos was not bound by the body, but held and bore it, even as He holds and bears up the universe; at one and the same time He was in the body and in the universe; nay more, as He was in, so also was He outside of, the All, resting in the Father. For this reason, it was impossible for the Logos to suffer either through birth, or through sin, or through death; on the con- trary, in holding, He sanctified the body. Out of the Virgin He formed for Himself a body, in order to show that He was the Oreator of the universe; and, without being seen as the Logos in the body, or being shut in by it, He made Himself known as Creator by His miraculous works. ‘That Athanasius appro- priates the sufferings of Christ to the divine nature also, even though not immediately, is evident from his doctrine of the iSvomroinots, referred to above. Because the Logos appropriates the sufferings of the human nature along with the nature itself, they acquire a significance in and for the Logos Him- self; and, on the other hand, because they are His, they ac- quire, as does His victory, an universal significance. He takes special pains, however, to point out that His miracles were revelations, self-representations, of His person, of Himself, as the Creator. He did not regard them as the mere credentials of His doctrine, but as veritable victories over nature, and over the heathenish view of the world. In the miracles, Creator and creature were most clearly discriminated from each other ; for by the obedience which nature then rendered to His com- 256 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. manding word, He was revealed to it as its Ruler and Creator, Still, he deems the constantly occurring spiritual marvels the greatest of all (c. 27 ff.). No one doubts, when darkness disap-- pears in the morning, that the sun is the cause thereof. And so, no one can doubt who Christ is, when he once beholds His works. Fear of death, and impotence to resist it, reigned ere He came. Now His followers tread death under their feet. They despise it as already dead; and the devil, who had the power of death, is treated by believers as dead. Previously, death was a terror; now, youths and maidens despise him and hasten to the martyr’s fate. That Christ rose again and now lives, is evident from what He does: He daily erects trophies to Himself out of His disciples. That He is not a dead man, is clear from His omnipotent workings in the hearts of Greeks and Barbarians (c. 46 ff.). Since the incarnation of the Logos, Heathenism has fallen, the wisdom of this world has become folly, and the oracles are dumb. In the place of innumerable particularistic religions, one has been substituted which em- braces all nations. In heaven, in hades, in humanity, and on earth—everywhere does man see the deity of the Logos un- folded before him, and himself encompassed by it. IT[dvrwp yap TOV THs KTicews pepav inNvato 6 Kupuos (c. 45, cll. 16 faye Our heathen opponents, it is true, advance, as their principal objection, “It was not worthy of the Logos to appearin a body”’ (c. 41 f.). With the penetration of a speculative mind, he answers,—If the Logos is in all things, in the entire world, which is justly termed one great body,—nay, even in each in- dividual thing,—why could He not also dwell in a man, whom He moved, through whom He manifested Himself, even as He manifests Himself through the world? That which is true of the whole, must be true also of the parts; if the former is not unworthy of the Logos, neither is the latter; and if it be un- worthy of Him to dwell in this body, it must also be unworthy of Him to dwell in the world. If He is in the whole, He is also in the parts. If He is in one part, He can use it as His organ for and on the whole. He is in Himself indivisible, 6Aos év ExdoT@ Kal mace; as He is in the sun and moon, so is He in humanity, which is a part of the universe. But—and he here- with provides for assigning a specific position to Christ—the spirit of man, also, although it pervades the whole man, reveals ATHANASIUS. 25 itself at one point of the body, to wit, the tongue. They ask, further,—“ Why then did He not, at all events, assume a shin- ing body?” Because His coming had not an epideictical, but a curative purpose. The main point was not simply to appear and to strike the eyes of beholders. He came to teach and to heal: therefore did He become a servant; therefore did He become that which men needed, in order that they might not be merely stunned by the loftiness and divinity of His appear- ance. It was not the brilliantly shining bodies, the sun, the moon, the ether, that had gone astray; they had remained in their proper order, the order appointed for them by their King, the Logos: it was men who had gone astray. He therefore constituted their body His organ, in order that, although they were unable to know Him in the universe as a whole, He might perhaps not remain concealed from them in the part; and in order that, though they were unable to behold His invisible power, they might possibly be able to understand and know Him through His resemblance to themselves. For the contrast between His divine works and the body like their own must needs suggest a comparison, and thus lead them to the know- ledge of His deity. If this is inconceivable, it is inconceivable also that He should be known by means of the world. Although in the world, nothing of the world pertains essentially to Him; but the world does participate in Him. Even so, though He employed the body as His organ, there was nothing in common between them; on the contrary, He sanctified the body. Plato says,— W hen the Generator of the worlds sees the world storm- tossed and in danger of coming to the place of inequality, He ascends His throne at the helm of the soul, gives it aid, and sets all things to rights. What marvel, then, if we say,— Humanity had gone astray, and therefore the Logos ascended His throne on it, and appeared as a man (ce. 42, 43)? Another objection is,—“ God might have helped men by a mere nod.” Athanasius answered,—The world, it is true, was created by a nod; but now it was a question not merely of the creation of man, but the man already created must be consi- dered: and he could only be helped by one like himself; in other words, man could not be magically helped by an entirely new creation, but the redemptive work must make use of, and begin with, his already existing powers and character. The VOLAEI 1: R 258 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND EPOCH. Creator must come nigh to the fallen through the medium of a human organ, and this organ He must take from that which already existed; for it was the existent, and not the non-exis- tent, that stood in need of salvation. Further, the death which needed to be overcome was not something external to the body, but adhered inwardly to it; as a permanent principle, and not merely as a single assault or act, did it threaten man. He might have overcome death from without; but it would still have remained in man. Hence it was necessary. that the pro- cess should be an inward one. Our body, subjected as it was _to death, was assumed, and was married with life; it was clothed with immortality, and death was vanquished. ‘The body now has life for its garment,—as it were, a robe of asbestus. This is far more than if a stop had been put to death’s work, by a mere external and authoritative command, and it itself hae remained unvanquished. It was therefore perfectly worthy of the Logos to come in the body in order to overcome death, and to reveal Himself everywhere,—as through creation, so also through His body and His deeds, and to fill all things with His knowledge (c. 44). Therefore, let every man regard the Logos in the works which He accomplished as God-man, which were _not human works, but works of the Logos, and let him judge for himself whether that be human or divine. If it be human, let him mock. If it be not human, but divine, let him stand and admire this revelation. Through this trifling thing (apadyya evTedes) was the divine exhibited to us; through this death did immortality penetrate to all; through the incarnation of the Logos was providence made ariteee for the universe. But ee things which He accomplished by His incarnation are so numerous, that to attempt to count them up would be like attempting to drain the sea. Wave presses on wave, and for the eye to embrace the whole is impossible. ‘O Xédyos évnv- Oparrnoev, tva iets OcotromOayuev (c. 54). Although the immediate subject of these writings is not the relation of the Logos to the Father, so much is clear, that, ac- cording to this view of the matter, drawn as it is out of the very centre of Christianity, to wit, the idea of the atonement, to the Son pertains true and perfect deity, even as to the Father. He is discriminated in the clearest manner from all creatures; and as the Logos over all, rather rests in the Father (aird- ATHANASIUS. 259 Aoyos Kat eos, de incarn. 54); is the Father’s image and like the Father, the archetype of men (c. 13). He is also most decidedly distinguished from all angels, for they are not the image of the Father (ibid.). In these treatises, therefore, - Athanasius stands nearer to Sabellianism than to Subordina- tianism ; so far, namely, as he is more concerned about the true and full deity of the Son than about His distinction from the Father. But he differs from Sabellius in regarding the Logos as the image of the Father, pre-existent, yea, ever resting in God, ata Marcellus, for example, could not allow. As re- spects his Christology, by the depth of his view of the funda- mental idea of Christianity, he reminds us of the best Fathers of the second century, particularly of Ireneeus. He surpasses them, however, in clearness and scientific precision. ‘The soul of hig system, is the Logos over all, who, as such, in that He became man, is the eeu and representative of humanity in two respects,—to wit, in that He took upon Himself its guilt and punishment ; sl that the healing of human. nature in and through Him becomes the portion a humanity, and is diffused fon ern to all. At the same time, it is worthy of note, that he did not conceive the Logos in Christ as a mere influence, but as a being of God in Him. In fact, he looked upon the Logos as the motive, hegemonic, personal principle in the God- man; but he makes no particular allusion to the human soul. The arguments he advances, undoubtedly presuppose a complete humanity (compare, for example, de incarn. c. 42 f.); but he makes express mention of the body alone (c@pua, cap&); and the enemy to be vanquished is principally death. The impo- tence of the soul to know itself immortal, is undoubtedly repre- sented as one ground of the incarnation; but his theory, in the form in which it is here set forth, does not require for the removal of this impotence, that Christ should substitutionarily appropriate or feel it Himself, but merely that He should admit into Himself the objective principle of death, that He should take upon Himself the debt (dhevAopevov, not culpa) of men ; and this supplied no occasion for more carefully considering the question of the human soul of Christ. Such a view leaves no place in the humanity for free choice, free determination, for change, or even for true development (although he aimed at preserving the reality of the humanity); but the man Jesus was 260 FIRST PERIOD. SECOND FPOCH. simply and solely the Logos, walking among men in the human nature which He bore. Athanasius thus verged towards the old representation of the body of Christ as a garment or temple, which excludes the full idea of the incarnation. It is remark- able, however, that precisely here, Athanasius made a decided effort to rise beyond that meagre notion, in that he started from a different point, to wit, nts the idea of Christ as the repre- sentative both of guilt- ans and of God-pleasing and immortal humanity. For he frequently repeats the remark,—What we needed was not a mere theophany, but that He shouid really - become one of us; in order to be our representative, He must not merely have, or bear, or dwell in a man, but must Himself be this man. Athanasius thus rose most decidedly above every form of Sabellian Christology; and therefore, taking our stand. on this thought, which was the centre of his system, we may beforehand anticipate the nature and degree of the progress which we shall afterwards find him making. THE ARIAN SCHOOL. 261 KPOCH THIRD. FROM THE COUNCIL OF NICHA TO THAT OF CONSTANTINOPLE, A.D. 381. eee AS OTE EE SECTION FIRST. TRINITARIAN MOVEMENTS. CHAPTER FIRST. THE ARIAN SCHOOL. Tue creed adopted by the Council of Nicaea did nothing more for Christian science, in the first instance, than define the goal at which it should aim; it neither did, nor pretended to, attain to the goal. But the determination of the goal is the commence- ment of its attainment. After the long course through which the dogma had run, now unduly inclining to the one side and then to the other, it became very necessary that the immediate conviction entertained by the Church, relatively to Christ, should assume a more concentrated form, and that testimony should be laid concerning the totality of His person. To this, Arianism gave occasion; for it called everything in question. Not merely did it tend back to Ebionism; not merely was it unable, with its Docetism and its doctrine of a created higher spirit, to allow even the possibility of an incarnation ; but, by putting a fantastical under-God between God and man, it sepa- rated the two quite as much as it appeared to unite them. Finally, the secret of Arianism was simply, in the first place, that a real, above all, a complete, revelation of God Himself was 262 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. an impossibility ; ; and in the second place, that such a revela- tion, if it were possible, was unnecessary. But the creed ad adopted by the Fathers of the Council of Ni iczea, to the point which had been established during the preceding century,—to wit, the in- dwelling of God in Christ under the very highest, that is, under a personal form, in other words, to the hypostasis of the Son (a point which was now confirmed, in substance, if not in a strictly doctrinal form, as in accordance with the faith),—added that of His true deity, which also had been recognised at a previous period, though for a time allowed to recede to the background. Each of these points, as we have learnt from the course hitherto taken by them, stands or falls with the other, notwithstanding that they appear to be mutually opposed. They are opposed in the sense, namely, in which two poles are opposed. In reality, they constitute the momenta of the higher nature of Christ, which relate to, are inwardly conditioned by, and therefore depend on and are involved in, each other. Hach preserves the truth, which was of essential importance relatively to its own aspect of the Person of Christ. They being taken for granted, the necessary conditions of Christian piety are completely fulfilled, as far as this matter is concerned. Without one of the two, a scientific Christology is impossible. An hypostasis without deity (such as Arianism teaches, which is but a refined form of Ebionism, differing therefrom merely in degree, not in kind), would be as paneeicee to Christian piety and science asthe divinity, without a particular hypostasis, of the higher aspect of Christ (such as is taught by that refined form of Docetism, Sabellian- ism). Whilst the former, strictly speaking, denies the Christian revelation altogether, the latter changes its inner character, and, not recognising Christ as an abiding revelation, it cannot roe God and man as truly and completely baoaiteitar Both, there- fore, necessarily arrive at the same conclusion—at the conclu- sion, namely, that the highest revelation has not yet been made, nay, more, that such a revelation is an impossibility. Both are characterized by the abstractness of their conception of God ;— the latter clinging to the abstract unity of God, which may easily change into the notion of the All-unity (Alleinheit) ; the former clinging to the quite as abstract, incommunicable simpli- city of God, to the POdvos THs Oelas picews, as Gregory Nazi- anzen aptly terms it (Or. 1). According to both, therefore, we THE ARIAN SCHOOL. 263 are still bound by the ante-Christian view of the world in gene- yal, and have not yet arrived at the Christian. But though the Nicene Creed very clearly recognised these two constitutive momenta of the higher nature of Christ, it avoided with right tact a more determinate doctrinal formula- rization thereof. This creed, it is true, claims unconditionally for the Son, deity and full “eqetiltie of essence with the Father ; but it passes over without further investigation, the questions of the precise nature of the hypostasis, the mode of its generation, and the basis of the Trinity in the Christian idea of God. In- deed, the greatest variety of opinion prevailed amongst the principal Church teachers of this and the following centuries regarding this matter; and all were recognised as christolo- gically admissible, in so far as they did justice to the funda- mental demand of faith, to wit, to the doctrine, that the divine which was in Christ was personal, and corresponded to a dis- tinction in God, or of God from God, really existent, though not more precisely defined ; and was therefore not a momentary, but a permanent and eternal, being of Ged in Christ. 4 The stormy discussions of the half century succeeding the Nicene Council, for which the scientific position occupied by the Church afforded, as is clear from what has been advanced, op- portunity enough, were in the first instance excited by Arianism. We have already remarked, that through Arianism the momenta hitherto recognised were set into a condition of ferment relatively 1 In accordance herewith, the history of the doctrine of the Trinity henceforth pursues a separate course from that of Christology, so far as it is mainly occupied with its own distinct and peculiar questions ; though it continues to hold by the two momenta above mentioned, which are the indis- pensable conditions of Christology. These its theological presuppositions once recognised (similarly also, the necessary anthropological presuppositions), it was possible for Ciritloes to enter on its distinctive work ;—and this we find it doing in the fourth century. All that we shall therefore need to do, in order to accomplish the purpose we have in view, is to consider, on the one hand, how, during the conflicts in which the Church engaged till the Second CHeunenical Synod, the trinitarian conception of God, laid down in the Nicene Creed, was established and confirmed, and consequently the momenta of the higher aspect of Christ's person, which had been completely gained, were ensured; and, on the other hand, how the elements of the Mioase aspect were poatpleesta and conclusively recognised ; and on the basis of these presuppositions, to proceed to our further Christological work. 264 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. to each other. Hence we find that all the principal heresies of an earlier period were revived; be it that they proceeded forth from, or were set loose by it. Inakind of rapid recapitulation, they reappeared for a moment on the stage of the Church, serving the purpose of ripening its judgment in all directions ; but themselves sinking quickly again into oblivion, and losing all their former seductive power, as soon as they had fulfilled their mission. Lhese struggles took place principally between three factors : jirstly, the Arian school ; secondly, the newly revived Sabellian school, with the new form of Ebionism; thirdly, the Church and its tendency. One section of the first-mentioned school, the Semi-Arians, an unsteady and bustling party, were in a special degree the life of the movement; and after they had stoutly overcome Sabellianism and Ebionism, embodied in themselves on a large scale, the tendency towards the doctrine of the Nicene Council. In their own system, with its undecided character, and inability to offer serious resistance, religion and science were in conflict; but the more advanced Arians pressed them to a decision ; and having once allowed their interest in Christianity to predominate over other considerations, this inner approxima- tion to the great Church teachers of the time, gave their system also by degrees a firmer hold. As far as concerns the Arians proper, their number always was relatively small; for, without truly satisfying the intellect, or advancing beyond the dualism between God and the world, they inflicted a death-blow on christianly religious interests. Hence they gained admission and acquired importance, solely either where they were favoured by external combinations, or where they resorted to reserve and accommodation, or even made concessions. Small as this party or school was, as the nature of the case would lead us to expect, its influence on the further development of the dogma of the Trinity was by no means insignificant, nor did it lack important representatives.! Above all, mention must be made of Aétius and Eunomius,, both of whom lived in Antioch; the former a physician and theo- logical writer, the latter deacon? ’ The strict Arians were designated "EZovxévrios, Avoeesos, or, after their chiefs, Aétians and Eunomians, also Eudoxians. * Compare Lange’s ‘‘ Der Arianismus in seiner weitern Entwickelung,” AETIUS. EUNOMIUS. 265 Neither of them followed out further that ethical principle which, as held by Arians, would lead back to Ebionism; on the contrary, so far as we are informed, Aétius was principally occupied in confuting the equality of essence and the coeter- nality of the Son with the Father, whereas Eunomius directed his efforts to the development of Arianism as a doctrinal system. In their polemical works, both start with the conception of God as the abstractly simple Being, of whom neither self-communica- tion nor generation can be predicated. God Himself is, in their view, nothing but this absolute simplicity,—Being, in the abso- lute sense. They regarded it as the most sublime and lofty, but also as the indispensable, predicate of God; and therefore they identified this primal simplicity, which is neither derived from another being, nor can generate another being out of itself, with the essence of God in general. Accordingly, adopting the style of the Church, they taught,—The Father is, as all allow, ayév- yntos; nay more, the Father is the ayévynrov in God. But this dyévyntov is absolute Being, or the strict and proper essence of God; consequently, the Father, who alone is unbegotten, is also, in the strict sense, alone God. And as He cannot have been derived along with the Son from another source, for then He would no longer be unbegotten ; so also can He not generate the Son, for then He would not be the unbegotten, simple one, but God would be divided into a begotten and unbegotten one. The dyévynrov excludes parts and division, difference and com- position ; but it is neither a mere subjective notion, nor the bare negation of generation, but something positive and objective. This positive something is the absolute sel/-relatedness (Bezo- genheit auf sich), absolute selfsameness or simplicity, which needs only to be made the object of thought to exclude all generation; because generation necessarily involves the diremp- in Illgen’s Zeitschrift 5,1, and Klose’s‘‘ Geschichte und Lehre des Euno- mius,” Kiel 1833. With special love, but also with his usual disfavour to- wards the Church, is this portion of the History of Dogmas treated by Baur, ]. c. pp. 361-394 ; with skill and happy insight by Meyer, in his “ Trini- titslehre,” pp. 175 ff. Of Eunomius himself, there belong to this connec- tion his Apology (Fabr. Bibl. gr. vol. 8), and the” Exéeoss xiorews in Socr. 5,10. Against him Basilius wrote the’ Avrifpnrixds xara bvaceBovs Evvomiov; and Gregory of Nyssa replied to the response of Eunomius in 12 books, entitled ’Avripénrixol pcs Edvoytoy advo: 12. For notices of Aétius, see Epiph. Her. 76, and the first Book of Gregory, c. 6. 266 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. tion, the division, of the absolutely simple. The causal relation, which the Arian school so stoutly defended in opposition te Sabellianism (see above), is therefore not applied directly to God in Himself, as though His absolute Being were regarded as an eternal volition or grounding of His own existence; but the fundamental presupposition is, that God can only be said to Be, and that He is absolutely identical with Himself.' If God abides unceasingly in His unbegotten essence, and that which is begotten continues ever begotten, the notion of equality of sub- stance or of similarity is plainly untenable. For as long as the two beings continue what they are, so long is it impossible to in- stitute a comparison between their essence. And as their being, so also is their knowledge of themselves, totally different. Each of the two knows Himself, when He knows Himself at all, as He is, and not as the other:—the one knows Himself as un- generated, the other as generated. Were Father and Son equal, as the Church teaches, the Son also must be unbegotten ; and what would then become of the doctrine of His generation, or of His distinction? Eunomius therefore requires of the doctrine of the Church, etther, that it exclude every species of subordi- nation, even that which is involved in the one being unbegotten and the other begotten; in which case, it would soon be seen whether, in returning to the one God, all distinctions between Father and Son must not be allowed to fall to the ground; or, that it take the subordination seriously, as do the Arians, and represent the one unbegotten One as unbegotten, absolutely simple, and therefore incapable of generating anything out. of His essence, and place the Son in the class of creatures. What, asks he, could the unbegotten One take out of His essence, ex- cept that which is unbegotten? But according to the doctrine of the Church, inasmuch as the Son is conceived to be on the one hand begotten, and yet on the other hand, to spring from the essence of God, there must be both a begotten and an un- begotten element in God. The Church has undoubtedly its meaning, said they, when it teaches that God is to be conceived * Thus Aétius says, in No. 5 of the ’Exiyepjpuara (see Epiph. heer. 76), —‘If God has not given Himself being, not because of any weakness of nature, but because He is exalted above all causality (above being caused), how can a being that is generated reach up to His essential unchangeable- ness ?”” Compare No. 2. AETIUS. EUNOMIUS. 267 as the cause of Himself ; but that lies beyond our horizon; fer we regard abstract simplicity as the ultimate and highest in God. Better, says Aétius naively, is the unbegotten than the begotten ; for the former has in itself the advantages which the latter has outside of itself. That which is unbegotten, Kunomius goes on to say, cannot possibly resemble the essence of that which is be- gotten ; the unbegotten is unbegotten, and that is its essence : if then the begotten resembles the unbegotten in its essence, it also must be unbegotten.* Without doubt, Eunomius was quite right in maintaining, that if God in Himself is merely the one simple Being, which, being absolutely without distinctions, stands related solely to itself, there is no place for distinctions in God, and therefore none for a Son. But that is a mere tautological proposition, dogmatical system of their opponents. When, in opposition to the Son who is generated, the Father is said to be ungenerated, the Father must be deemed identical with the Georns, with the divine essence in general, if aseity were thus meant to be pre- dicated of the Father alone, and, after the example of older writers, they did not go on to say that the Father is as truly constituted Father by the Son, as the Son is constituted Son by the Father. So long as it was deemed necessary to the pre- servation of the unity of the Trinity to represent the one Father as the source, not merely of the hypostasis, but also of the deity, of the others; and so long as the Son was not most distinctly conceded a participation in the aseity of the divine substance ; so long was He not freed from subordination, notwithstanding its being called for by the ideas of His equality of essence and eternal generation. If, however, the Son be allowed to partici- pate in aseity, the passivity, which the Arians were never weary 1 Besides, Eunomius persists in asserting that Sonship and generation imply a beginning ; that they are consequently incompatible with the pre- dicate of eternity ; and that the predicate of eternity would involve the Son’s being unbegotten. 268 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPCCH of asserting to be necessarily characteristic of generation, must be decidedly excluded from the generated, and the Son be rather constituted a living momentum of the self-causative God, and thus the Trinity be introduced into that inmost-root_of the deity, the aseity. The bases thereof were laid even in the fourth century ; but they had not yet been plainly and completely car- ried out. So much the more instructive is it, therefore, to see how the defenders of the view, that God is abstract simplicity, fall into contradiction with themselves, and thus give negative testimony in favour of the very tendency which they were en- gaged in combating. The incomparable (davyxpitos), self-sufficient, simple, un- approachable (ampoceros) God, who is exalted above every cause, whether in or out of Himself, must not be represented as en- tirely alone, nor the world as without its cause. But to repre- sent God as the cause of the world, and yet to maintain that the world is characterized solely by unlikeness to its Author, is scarcely reconcilable with the idea of the first cause; and the only resource of Arianism is, to take refuge in the mystery of the creation out of nothing, which nothing it is compelled to de- scribe in an absolutely supernatural or Docetical manner as the essence of the world (7 efvav). The following point, however, is still more important. How can the absolutely simple, self- identical God, ever come to create? Eunomius denies both movement and self-communication to the divine essence, but goes back to the divine will (évépyewa), which—as to be dis- tinguished, be it noted, from the divine essence—called into existence out of nothing that which is, and first of all, the Son as the Creator of the world.!. But to appeal to the will in dis- tinction from the substance—that the Church had a right to do, and availed itself of its privilege when it taught that the world was grounded in the will of God; but Eunomius was not at liberty to make this distinction between will and essence, unless he ceased to represent God merely as abstract, absolute simplicity, and turned to a more living conception. And then the strength of his opposition to the generation of the Son would have been broken, in so far as he could no longer say that aseity or sim- plicity constituted the essence of God, was that in Him which is inviolable. The method adopted by Eunomius necessitated his * Compare Gregor. Nyss. adv. Eunom. or. 1. AETIUS. EUNOMIUS. 269 dissociating the divine will from the divine essence, contrary to his own presupposition, if he meant to arrive at a world. He might, indeed, have described the will in God, as something non- essential, accidental, superadded from without. But being un- willing to do so, he fell into new difficulties. He was compelled to trace not only the active will (évépyeva) of God, but also the idea of the world, back to the divine essence, as its aE seat. The real and ee potence of the creation of the world, must surely have been contained eternally in God, as he himself ac- knowledges ; but how could it break loose from the simple essence of God? We see, therefore, that when he abides by the rigid simplicity and self-identity of God, he either arrives at no world at all, or is compelled to assign the actual world a place eternally, tit even immediately, in he essence of God: in other words, he unavoidably falls into the very heathenish| error which he himself repudiates—that error which is unable to distinguish between the substance and the will of God, and is, therefore pantheistic.” The Son was held to owe His existence, not to the essence, but to the eve pryela of God; and the essence not to be in any sense contained in the évépyea. The divine essence, therefore, cannot properly be termed Father; for the essence continues immoveable in its simplicity outside of the évépyea: the évép- ryeca alone can be termed Father, so far as it brings forth the Son. And the Son is not unlike this energy, but is its image and likeness, seeing that He also has the power to create. In this direction, it was possible for him to approximate to the Nicene Creed, and to return to the milder form of the doctrine of Arius; and, in fact, he says, in his Confession of Faith,— “The Son is a creature, but not like other creatures, etc.; and the higher dignity possessed by Him was not solely the reward of His virtue, but, on the contrary, He became God because He was the Son, and as a Son was generated.” Still there is a wide gap between him and Lactantius, who laid down essential deity 1 Apol. Eunom. ec. 24. 2 Kunomius does neither the one nor the other, but continues helplessly clinging to the dualism between the finite and the infinite, which, under his hands, forces its way into God Himself :—the dualism, namely, between the essence of God, which is ézsipov and simple, and the will of God, which relates to finite objects. Gregory, therefore, charges him with Manicheism. 270 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. as the starting-point for the ethical. Eunomius, on the con- trary, lets the ethical go; indeed, he lacked real interest as well in the ethical as the religious. (Note 50.) These Arians, to whom substantially belonged Arcacius also, who tried to make himself out more orthodox than he really was, exercised a special influence on the Semi-Arians (‘Hysdpevoc), who bore, besides, the names Eusebians or Homoiusiasts. Over- powered by the force of the arguments brought against their halting and uncertain position, both by the Arians and the Church, and feeling themselves repelled by the former, these Homoiusiasts advanced ever more completely from the doctrine of the similarity to that of the identity of essence. Athanasius aptly met them with the consideration, that similarity can only be spoken of in relation to qualities, not to the essence.by itself ; for the essence must either be the same or not the same. And so also, the Arians urged, if God or the Father is the ungene- rated One, everything outside of Him must belong to the class of generated things; if to be ungenerated is the essence of the Father, to be generated must be the essence of everything out- side of Him; consequently, the essence of the latter is the anti- thesis of the former, and completely dissimilar, not similar, to it. In fact, the Semi-Arians displayed little power of resistance and little productiveness: they belong rather to the general history of the Church than to the history of Dogmas; and, in consideration of this circumstance, or, in other words, in con- sideration of their interest in religion, might with greater justice be termed Semi-Nicenes than Semi-Arians. For a long period they did not advance beyond the doctrinal position held by Eusebius of Ceesarea (see above); and the various formulze adopted by them bore essentially the same stamp, until the Synod of Ancyra, in the year 358, distinctly asserted the Son not to be a created being, and taught that He was begotten of the substance of the Father. Athanasius now recognised them as brethren; and the doctrine of Cyrill of Jerusalem, who also acknowledged the Son to be coeternal with the Father, is scarcely distinguishable from the Nicene Creed. (Note 51.) Apart from external circumstances, they had a hold only so long as the authors of the Nicene Creed could be supposed to have inclined towards Sabellianism. This supposition was strength- ened during the first twenty or thirty years after the Council REVIVAL OF SABELLIANISM. 271 of Nicea, by the conduct of Marcellus, who was one of its adherents; and against him, rather than against the Council itself, were their weapons directed, especially those of Husebius of Cxsarea. After having convinced themselves that those who taught the duoovcvov were not Sabellian, they gained an ever clearer insight into the untenableness of their own position, and consequently passed more completely over to the party of the Nicene Council. CHAPTER SECOND. THE REVIVAL OF SABELLIANISM, AND THE EBIONISM WHICH SPRANG FROM IT. i Marcewuus of Ancyra had stood in the foremost ranks of the antagonists of Arianism,—a circumstance which spoke in his favour at Rome longer than it ought to have done. (Note 52.) A short time after the Nicene Council, however, when he be- came aware of the strength of the party which, whilst conceding to the Son divine essence and eternal generation, yet, in perfect agreement with Eusebius of Caesarea, assigned to the Father the first, to the Son the second place, and in many other respects subordinated the latter; and further, when he found that Arianism derived great support from this vacillation, he opened a campaign in a great work, especially against this middle tend- ency. At the same time, he attacked also older writers, such as Origen; but he particularly assailed the strong Oriental party, which consisted of the two Eusebiuses, Paulinus, and others, whom he also expressly mentions, although he pretended that Asterius was the proper occasion of the work (compare ady. Marcell. 1, 4, p. 27). They cannot, said he, maintain the divine unity, if they regard the Son as actually God; for by making Him a distinct personality, outside of God, they rend the divine essence; but if they assert the divine unity, they deprive the Son of deity by subordinating Him. — So far, therefore, Mar- cellus was at one with the Arians; the Semi-Arians could not continue in their vacillating position. But he goes beyond the Nicene Council when, with a view to destroying in its very 272 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. roots the Arian separation between Father and Son, he believed it necessary to subject to examination, and to cast aside, all points on which those were accustomed to lay stress, who main- tained a distinction between Father and Son. These are the ideas of generation, Sonship (in the place of which he wished to substitute “ procession of the Logos,” Kecl. Theol. 2, 8), zmage, visibility, which were applied by the Fathers of Nicza to the Logos. The Semi-Arian party in particular took pleasure in calling the Son the image of the Father; so also Asterius. But they drew the conclusion, that so certainly as the image is different from, and inferior to, that which it represents, even so certainly must the Son occupy a lower position than the Father. Further, the Father is absolutely exalted above the world, invi- sible; the Son, on the contrary, in virtue of His relationship with the world, is characterized by visibility, and therefore ap- peared under the Old Testament ; finally, Sonship and genera- tion subordinate the Son as an effect to its cause. In order to evade these objections, Marcellus endeavoured to limit all these expressions, which even the Fathers of Nica had referred to the higher aspect of Christ’s Person, to the human aspect, or to the person in its unity and totality ; thus hoping the more certainly to exclude every element which could prove of advantage to the Arians. Hence he says,—Not the Logos is termed the image of God, but the God-man; for otherwise the Arians would un- questionably be justified in subordinating the Logos to God, and denying to Him true divinity. The Logos, who is invi- sible like God, first became the visible image of God when He assumed the man Jesus, and in Him humanity, which is the image and likeness of God. Thus also the Logos first became Son through the humanity which He assumed. Christ usually styles Himself Son of man, and this is to be carefully noted (Eccl. Theol. 1, 16): He first became Son of God by becoming Son of man, or man; for the Logos caused the man whom He assumed and completed to be exalted to the rank of Son of God.’ The passages in the Old Testament, otherwise referred to the pre-existence of the Son, he described as prophetical an- ticipations of that which should come with the incarnation; hence also he treated Prov. viii. as a prophecy, and counted i Compare ady. Marc. 1, 4, pp. 20, 24 (Ed. Paris, 1628), 2, 3, pp. 43, 46. MARCELLUS. 273 Soiomon amongst the prophets.!. When Wisdom says, “TI was set up from the beginning of the world,” he referred it to that divine purpose of incarnation through which the Logos first received a sort of existence outside of God as the Son of God. The idea of generation also would remove the Logos outside of, and subordinate Him to, God. He therefore justifies the Arians in asserting that the Nicene Fathers cannot maintain their point of view, unless they call the Son ungenerated, and therefore eternal like God; but accepts without hesitation the consequence threatened by the Arians, and avows his belief in a Logos, who is unbegotten, eternally united with the Father, coeternal with, consequently in no sense subordinate to, but also not discrimi- nated from Him (adv. Mare. 2, 1, p. 32). The Logos, in his view (ady. Mare. 2, 2, pp. 35 f.), is equivalent to Pneuma, as he endeavours to prove by a comparison of the prologue to the Gospel of John with the Synoptics; but Pneuma is equivalent to God, for God is a Spirit: the Logos, therefore, is simply God Himself—conceived, namely, in activity. We have directed attention above to the great significance attached to the words, Son, generation, etc., since Tertullian’s time ; and to the circumstance, that in the third century the doc- trine of the Logos taught during the second century was cast into the shade, by the hypostatical element denoted by the word Son. We have seen also, that the Sonship continued to be marked by subordination, so long as it had not found a place in the eternal essence of God Himself. Now Marcellus, who took the doctrine of the Church as his point of departure, stands before us as the embodiment of the-despair of solving the pro- blem, how the eternal Logos can be at the same time designated the eternal Son. If we suppose the Son to have a place in the inner sphere of the divine nature, He must be unbegotten, like the Father, and then He is no longer Son. There is therefore no alternative but to renounce the idea of a Son, both as far as affects the inner essence of God (in which there is room for identity of essence, but not for a distinct hypostasis), and also for the period preceding the creation of the world. The renun- 1 Adv. Mare. 2, 3, pp. 44 f.; Eccl. Theol. 3, 2, p. 154; adv. Marc. 2, 1, p. 82:—-Mare sive, ware wpovPeoraves, ents brug romwore vidv drdpla: ro Oy, wpo row rex Oqvar Oi THs moepévov dosaelayv avrdv 08 mdvoy Elvees Aovyos Dacnoy. aa & s 274 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. ciation of the idea in this latter respect leads of itself to the subordination of the Son, as is abundantly clear from the his- tory of the third century. But by thus letting go the fruit of the struggles of the third century, namely, the idea of “ Sonship,’ and going back on the mere Logos, the entire system was at once altered. Out of regard, however, for the full deity of the Son, in the sense in which he still conceded Him an existence, namely, to the deity of the God-man, he totally denied His hypostatical pre-exist- ence; for only in this way did it seem possible to him to ascribe full deity to the Son, to preserve His equality with the Father. As he constantly repeated,—Before the incarnation there was no Son, but merely the Logos; so also did he go on to say,—Prior to the creation God alone existed.1 God abode in Himself, keeping silence; besides Him was merely the Nothing. But out of nothing, God purposed to create the world. He carried the idea thereof in Himself, but the idea lacked actuality. ‘Tvhe world was conceived, and also named (or more correctly, “ pre- pared,” érowudfwv, according to Kecl. Theol. 2, 8, p. 113, to be read for dvowafov, adv. Marc. 2, 2, p. 41), by God through the Logos, who was in Him. For He was ever reason, and always spake within Himself. But in order that the world might be- come an actuality, He gave utterance to the creative word; and tltis was the procession of the creative omnipotence of God, in whith wisdom also is inherent, or the procession of the Logos, as the évépyeva Spactixy mpa£ews of God.’ With men also the ordering, commanding word is that by which they accomplish most of their works. This word is, on the one hand, distin- guished from God at rest and silent; on the other hand, how- ever, united with Him; both together constitute the complete conception of God. Marcellus was quite aware how closely he thus approximated to Sabellianism; but he expressly blamed Sabellius both for his lack of insight into the significance 1 For example, adv. Marc. 2,1, p. 32. The consequence of applying the word Son to the Logos, Marcellus supposed, were sensuous representa- tions of God. Adv. Mare. 1, 4; Eccl. Theol. 2, 8. Ady. Marc. 2, 2, p. 89. Prior to the world, ovdev erepov qv xarny Ocov uovov. The Logos alone first dvyeémer in the Father, and absolutely one with Him (ib. p. 37), ofos dv etn 6 év dv dpaxw rdyos. 2 Also Adyos évepyés. Compare Hecl. Theol. 2,9.15. p. 125; adv. Mare. 2,2. p. 41; Eccl. Theol. 3, 3. p. 166. MARCELLUS. 275 cf the term, and for not having the right conception of (sod. It must be allowed that there is an important difference between Marcellus and Sabellius. Marcellus decidedly main- tains a creation out of nothing,’ and imports into God Himself a Kdo/L0$ vonTos, reason and the potence of the Logos; whereas Sabellius gives a more substantial and physical representation of the process. Marcellus had also appropriated the category of absolute causality, of which Arius made such vigorous use, and had engrafted it on the principle of Sabellianism as far as con. cerned the relation of God to the world. Still, Eusebius was probably right in characterizing his doc- trine of the Trinity as Sabellian.? We see this especially from the mode in which Marcellus explains the words, “Let us make man.” Instead of regarding them as addressed to the Son, as did the Fathers of -Niczea, he explains them as follows :—Even an human artist, when all lies ready, and he is just about to commence his work, may say, Let us make the picture. In such a sense did God speak these words to Himself. One might, indeed, suppose for a moment that the idea of a distinction in God was not hereby completely cast aside; but had merely passed over into that of the divine self-diremption, which fre- quently recurs at a later period, and which was supposed to constitute the divine self-consciousness. In favour of which might also be pleaded, that he, notwithstanding, assigned to reason an eternal place in God. ‘This, however, cannot be carried out; for, firstly, nothing whatever is said regarding the Holy Ghost in the silent God; secondly, Marcellus would then * Ady. Mare. 2, 2. p. 39; de eccl. theol. 2, 15. p. 125. But still we find him also employing the expression, ‘‘ The Monas expanded itself into a Trias.” De eccl. theol. 3,4: dzofégrw radyw 4 povas Dalverces Bharvvoweyn wey sig rptoda, Oscerpeioboer 02 wndapeas drousvovoc. In conjunction with which, however, must be taken c. Mare. 2, 2, according to which the ex- pansion of the Monas related not to it itself, but merely to the évépysia of the deérys, whereas the Monas continues indissolubly one (évepysig 4 deérns oun Trcutuvecbecs Ooxsl). * Keel. theol. 1, 1.15. pp. 76 f., c. 17 p. 79; adv. Mare. 2, 2. pp. 39, 40: The Logos is not an angel or other being outside of God ; not even in the revelation, o¥02 yap rov rod evdparov Adyov duveues noel Srocrcéast apiaces Tivk Ouverdy® Ev yap éort noel rebrdv Ta ckvbohaw 6 Advyos xxl adder! xoprlouevos (fee, >\ , ~ ~ , > f STEPD, 4 Keon TN THS Tpakcoc Eveoyeloe. 276 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. have a double Trinity, an immanent and an ceconomic one :—of which no evidence can be adduced. He evidently conceived the évépyera Spactixy, so far as it accomplished its highest work in the incarnation, as the second momentum of the Trinity; and, so far as the Holy Ghost proceeds from the God-man, he aimed at representing the third momentum as a branch of the second (Eccl. theol. 3, 4. p. 168). Finally, the distinction he draws is by no means between a speaking and a spoken, but between a speaking and a silent God. _The speaking God is his évépyeva Spacrixy, which constantly dwells in, and remains inseparable from, God, and bears within itself the divine power and wisdom. The alent or resting (jovydtov) God, on the contrary, is God in His inner fale and glory, sree acral to the Father ; even as the évépyera Spactixn has the Son for its goal, carries within itself the principle of the incarnation, and, as it were, attains to and satisfies itself in the effect produced, when it brings forth Him in accordance with whose idea all things were created from the beginning. For this reason, Baur’s conjecture, that Marcellus tried to draw between the Father and the Son some such distinction as that between being and thought, is untenable ; for there can be no doubt that he regarded the silent God as identical with the Father, and believed the latter to have in Him- self all fulness, with reason and thought. Marcellus was necessi- tated, it is true, to regard speaking and thought as still one in the inner essence of God; but for this very reason, speaking, in the strict sense of the term, had as yet no existence. The God who merely thinks is primarily silent, and silent alone; contrasted with whom is the Speaking One, the Aoyos. This silent one is the Father; the Logos, so far as He does not yet speak, must, according to the fundamental view of Marcellus, be simply identified with the Father, who is also designated the One who is (der Seyende), though not in the sense of His not being able to think. Undoubtedly, the principle of the speak- ing Ged the Logos, must also be contained in God; and in he aspect, one might say that the speaking God is the Xéyos mpoopixos, and that this Noyos is in God évdidberos (Klose, p. 29). This distinction, however, we do not find that Mar- cellus drew; still less did he distinguish in the inner divine essence between being and self-consciousness ; but the "Ov itself Marcellus conceives to contain the divine fulness, to which be- MARCELLUS. 277 long also reason and thought. He does not teach a preforma- tion of the évépyeta Spacrvxy in the inner divine essence, but is accustomed to look upon the silent God monadically, or as the ov; and not till he comes to the speaking God (the évépyeca Spacrixn) does he refer to the Church doctrine touching the Son. Still less, as is clear from what has been arene are we warranted in representing him as teaching that Father, anne and Spirit are three persons of the Monas, completely co-ordi- nated with one another (as Klose does; see pp. 27 f.), and so co-ordinated, that the Son (and the Spirit also?) is not derived from, but united with (sjvwpévos, cvvnpévos), the Father as an equally independent apy (or, if we include the Holy Spirit, apxat). In opposition to this view stands Marcellus’ conception of God as the ov, of the Monas which admits of no d.aipeas, and the series of passages (Klose, pp. 27 f.) in which he lays stress on the unity of God, after the manner of the Monarchians. Nowhere does he attempt to reduce back the Trias, taught by him, to the Monas; and he could scarcely have avoided doing this had he held the Trias to consist of eternal hypostases in God. The incarnation he considered to have been undertaken on account of the sin and necessities of men, and on no other ground ; ‘but he can only assion even to Christ the transitory position of a means to another end. “Who was worthy,” says he, “amongst righteous men and angels to take away the punish- ment suspended by God over men? No other being but the Logos, who was with the Father, and who created along with Him, and to whom God said, Let us make men in our image and likeness’ (adv. Mare. 2, 2. pp. 40, 41). “Not to seek or to find anything for Himself, but purely on our account, did He become man," in order to set forth him who had been van- quished by the devil, as the devil’s conqueror. For this reason He took man upon Himself, in order to bestow on him the first fruits of His power. Now, this man who is united with the Word is the beloved one. His purpose was to battle with the devil in human flesh; and to render man not only imperishable and immortal, but also to set him on a throne in heaven with 1 Ady. Mare. 2, 3, 4, pp. 48 ff: Ody iy 6 Adyos dDerndn, rdv guerépay civelAnQe oorpuo, &AA ive 4 cape Ose Thy wpos Tov Adyou xomvwvieey dbavacios TUXN. 278 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. God. In His immeasurable goodness, He purposed not only te free man from bondage, soi and parichableness but also to confer upon him a glory Piel transcends man (THs virép av- Opwrov So€ys). Fallen man, who had lost the kingdom, was meant by God’s will to cit Lord and God; and, therefore, the method of salvation was devised. When the Logos came in human flesh, and became King, man, who was previously abased, Aeened all the power and might of the devil.” “What greater glory,” he exclaims, “can be conferred on man than this glory! Fallen man He has counted worthy to be united with His Logos, through the Virgin” (cuvapOjvar, |. c. p. 48, c. 8). “Let not Asterius be surprised that something which is younger than the body (that is, the divine Sonship of Christ, which was the result of the incarnation) should attain to the dignity of being regarded as the eldest. For in that the Logos thought fit to take upon Himself, out of the pure Virgin, humanity, although younger, and therewith to conjoin His own nature (évwaas), He not only constituted the man created in Him the first-born of all creation, but wills also that he be the principle of everything which is in heaven and upon earth.” What he means to say is, that Christ, although later in point of time, was, as the idea and operative principle, the earlier; even as the final aim, though later in point of appearance, is the first in point of idea. In Him humanity attained its completion. At this point one would expect Marcellus to introduce the doc- trine of the eternal duration of the person and kingdom of Christ ; why he did not do so, we shall soon see. On account of His humanity, therefore, Christ is termed the First-born of all creation, and not as though He had been begotten prior thereto. For how could He who had always existed be the first- born of another? On the contrary, the first-born is the new man, in whom God purposed to sum ap all things. (IIpwro- ToKos obv Taons KTloEws Sia THY KATA cdpKa yéverw wvou“acOn, ov Sid THY TpPOTHV, WS adTol olovTaL KTiTW. . . . . TOV MPOTOV xawov avOpwrrov eis Ov Ta TaVTA avaxehadai@cacbar éBovrAnOn 6 Ocds, TodTov ai Octar ypahal tpwrotoKoy Taans dvouafovot cticews: l.c. p. 43.) But what is Marcellus’ conception of the incarnation, when he endeavours to describe it more precisely? ‘The body was a. 1 Adv. Marc. 2, 3, p. 44. MARCELLUS. 279 truly human body, and consequently, like all things else, in the :ast instance, created out of nothing. In so far, therefore, the évépyera Spacrixy of God, or His Word, held precisely the same relation to this man as to other things in the world. But with this man (cap&), the évépyera Spactixy was connected in a peculiar manner. For, whereas generally it remains outside of the objects which are brought into existence by its command, it dwells in His cap&; the action of God was, as it were, fixed, so long as the purpose in view required it. The divine évép- yea, says he, expanded itself as far as, and into, this man, lay- ing hold on, assuming, and uniting itself with him. Henceforth this divine évépyeva was the motive, the active principle of the body.* Marcellus was thus able to assign to the God-man a distinctive position ; for, whereas the divine activity does not fill, and is merely present with, so far as it outwardly works upon, other things, it filled Christ with its presence, and had an existence in Him. But, even on this view of the matter, the divine in Christ cannot be described as a peculiar hypostasis different from the Father. The operative Word, when it extends itself into the humanity of Christ, is not personal in itself; personal alone is the Father in His entirety, and He, as Father, keeps silence ; and if He also, like the Word, is immanent, we cannot suppose that Marcellus conceived the entire divine évépyesa, which was fixed in the man Jesus, to have been included in Him. For humanity appeared to him absolutely incapable of being the suitable organ of God.” Here, therefore, we find occurring again what we have noticed at an earlier period, namely, that TL. c. 2, 4, p. 54: Apecorinn volo evepyste wivy tH capxl ovydy rod HAYELY LUT YY “oll WaT TEL, COUTEp Ey EdaryryeAlois Deperees, ovoig TH OcQ avvirro, ole Adryos Uarcepyow ovTOU axoptotos nel dd:eotaros. For this reason, also, he magnifies in forcible terms the greatness and novelty of the mystery re- vealed in Christ. De eccl. theol. 8, 3, p. 157: Tés yap xpo rig trav rpary- earav amodsiSews eriorsvocy dv, ort Adyos Oov, Osk wapbévov tex dele rHy Neeetepay civaenn perce copro, rol THy Taoav Oscrnte gy avTn cwomatinos ETI- dsiZercs. The flesh assumed by Him had not previously existed: the Lord our God created it, the Creator of the «4 cv. Adv. Mare. 2, 3, p. 453 2, 2, p. 40: Ti yep erepov qv drroxexpympevoy mvorypioy, 4 neta Tov Advyoy ; ovTaH O¢ Hy droxexpuyeeevoy ey TH Oeg rovTi rporepoy TO evaTyplov, Wore Londevee TOU Tporeoov Anov caus Ta xaTad Advoy eidéveet, AAA Nuads TOV TAoUVTOV Tis DoSns noel Tov ckroxsxpuumtvov mvornploy a&mroravery vuvi. 2 Ady. Marc. 2, 4, p. 52: If any one suppose, riy dvdowmivyy saoxe 280 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. the God-man is represented as owing His personality to the limit, the circumscription, the negation, added by the humanity to the divine évépyesa, which continues the. positive element, though not hypostatical in itself. Marcellus, it is true, did not by any means consider the hypostasis of the God-man to have been grounded in an human Ego, and a positive finite principle ; but looked upon the circumstance, that so long as the Logos dwelt in, and was encompassed by, the humanity of Christ, He had a certain existence of His own outside of God, and was so far a kind of hypostasis, not as an advantage possessed by, but as a defect of, the person: of the God-man, as part of His humiliation? Not merely the earthly form of His humanity, therefore, but His being a man at all, he necessarily counts part of. His humiliation, which, as such, could not be permanent. With some degree of acuteness, he argues as follows (adv. Mare. 2, 4): If the Logos had become man for His own sake, to seek some- thing for Himself, or if He Himself could have profited any- thing by His humanity, it would be conceivable that His humanity should abide for ever. But as it was pure love which moved Him to condescend to appear in the form of a servant— that form in which we are not completely united with God, and as, on the other hand, His work for us willterminate at the judgment; it would be erroneous to suppose that. His humanity will abide eternally. By His incarnation, the Logos subjected Himself to a limit and form inadequate to His true essence. He was extruded from God, it is true, merely évep- yela, but still this is not a small matter; and the distinction between God and Him became to a certain extent an actuality, through the humanity which He assumed. The God-man spake: “J do not Mine own will, but the will of My Father.” And in Gethsemane, the harmony (cupdavia) between the will of Christ and that of God was dissolved for a moment, though aSiav elves rov Adyov, at all events, the cdp which rose again, let him know, ors ob way, orep &bavarov, rovro &Zi0v Ocod" tellav yelp xual airings tis abavacias 6 Osdc. 1 Thid. p. 51: Keyapiodes (leg. xeyapicbas) rod reerpds Dalveras wpoQceoss sapxos. Kecl. theol. 3, 18, p. 181: evepyele wcvn xupiler airov dona». Adv. Mare. 2, 4: [lag tors rijv rod dovrcv popQyy gu ctvelAn@ev 6 rovyos, HopQyv ovocy dovarcv avusivas tO Adyw duyardv; God, or at all events His fvéprycie, IS passive under the limitation : a remnant of Patripassianism. MARCELLUS. 281 without sin." Must the Logos, then, be supposed to be eternally saddled with this humanity, which is inadequate to Him, and to the assumption of which love alone moved Him to humble Himself? By no means. Were such the case, not even He Himself could ever be said to be perfect; on the contrary, He would for ever fall short of His idea. He must needs, there- fore, become again that which He previously was. One might suppose, indeed, that the humanity of Christ could be so glori- fied as to be worthy of, and adequate to, the eternal indwell- ing of the deity, of the Logos. But even though the humanity should be made immortal and imperishable, the deity would continue infinitely exalted above it. And, further, what end would the eternity of the humanity of Christ serve, even rela- tively to us? Christ Himself said, “It is the spirit that quickeneth, the flesh profiteth nothing.” Accordingly, the hu- manity of the Logos and its regiment will continue so long as the work of redemption lasts, and the victory begun therein is not fully completed. The goal, however, once gained, the con- summation of things will demand that the Logos return into God, and become that which He previously was (adv. Mare. 2 4, p. 53: wa ottas 4 ev Oc@ 6 Royos WoTrep Kal TpOTEpoV HY) 3 tap the body must be emptied of the Logos, or laid aside lem écec0at TO cHua ToD Adyou, |. c. c. 2—4).? Looking at the high position Marcellus had assigned to the God-man, to wit, the position of the crown of humanity, we should deem Him fitted for something better than a mere transitory means. And yet he was compelled at last to regard Him in the latter light. On the one hand, Marcellus con- sidered the destiny of man in general to be perfect union with God (c. Mare. 2, 2, pp. 40 ff.); and the incarnation was in his eyes so great a thing, because the God-man and His fate were the solution of the problem, the beginning of the perfection of humanity. But, on the other hand, humanity contradicts full union with God ; it has something in..it..essentially.imadequate to God, which, so long as it exists at all, cannot be abolished. For this reason, the “perfect man, the Goan must needs Seve Marc..1, 4) po coteue2 ep. oiqog- * Compare adv. Marc. 2, 8 and 4; Eccl. Theol. 3, 12-14, pp. 180 f He denies, therefore, the eternal pre-existence and post-existence of the Son, and limits His existence to the miadle period. 282 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. return out of the other form of existence which He had as- sumed, into identity with God, and cease to be man, in order that He may be made perfect. This was necessary, further, in order that He may go before us in the process through which we too are destined to pass. We also can only attain to per- fection by being raised above ourselves (l. c. p. 42), in order that God may be all in all. The conclusion, therefore, is un- avoidable, that our humanity, too, must cease to be, in order that God alone may be. At this point, Origen’s opponent be- comes almost more Origenistic than Origen himself. He re- marks,—If at the time of the universal doxardotacts, accord- ing to Paul, even creation itself is to be converted into freedom, will not the servant’s form which the Logos assumed, be by its very idea unsuitable to Him? (Euseb. Eccl. Theol. 3, 1} From this passage, as also from the view given by Marcellus of the relation between the human and the divine, we may con- clude with certainty, that finitude in general was, in his eyes, equivalent to bondage and the form of a servant; that, conse- quently, if the world is destined to attain to freedom, which is its goal (as he often asserts),’ it also, as well as Christ, its Captain, must cast aside the servant’s form ; or, in other words, humanity must be abolished, and be transferred or transformed into the divine essence.’ We see, therefore, that Marcellus separates the divine and human in the same abstract way as the Arians; and the con- clusion to be drawn also is substantially the same, to wit, that the one member of the antithesis excludes the other. Those Arians whose tendency was predominantly empirical, and who lacked, so to speak, both practical and theoretical piety, really represented man as the Highest, as the concrete and living Divine, whilst they reduced the personal God to a bare abstract unity. Marcellus, on the contrary, in consequence of his more religious and speculative tendencies, arrived at the conclusion, that, in the last instance, God alone will exist. The God of the Arians is purely envious; but man, notwithstanding, took care of himself, by setting himself substantially in the place of God. The God of Marcellus is good and communicative ; but, because He is represented as only communicative (His com- munication is effected through the medium of the plan of sal- ' Adv. Mare. 2, 4, p. 52. ? Adv. Mare. 2, 3, pp. 44, 47. MARCELLUS. 883 vation),—in auch a sense, too, that nothing permanent, nothing good, can be allowed to pertain to the first creation,—the con- tinuity of the communications of the divine life leaves no room for any distinction whatever; in order that man may be per- fected, God sets Himself in his place; the aoxatdotacts does away with the very grounds of the creation; the perfection of the world is its termination; and finally, therefore, the God whose sole work was self-communication, stands as isolated, as worldless, as He was in the beginning. From which it is clear, that, even according to this system, God continues Gezov pOovepor, until He allows the world to be distinguished from Himself as a Good, and concedes to it an unity with Himself, which admits of and maintains the distinction. If the divine love has not the dpos in itself, it becomes in its very effusion again exclusive, and therefore physical. And, in point of fact, this exclusiveness shows itself clearly enough in the circumstance, that he continues to view the inmost divine essence as an abstract, simple point, as a silent Monas. Love is not the inmost and highest element in God ; nor is that inmost substance ever revealed. He tries to keep God far from all division and separation, by assigning every- thing outside of Him, not to Himself, but solely to His activity.’ This activity neither touches nor moves the divine essence in its simplicity; the divine simplicity admits of no distinctions whatever. But, as this simplicity is represented as the highest element, as the very essence, of God, it follows, that the évép- yeta Spactexn, or the will of God in its actuality, can only play on the surface of the divine being. (God is not through and through will or living; but in Himself is inactive and rigidly silent; at times, however, He breaks this silence, though we can scarcely attribute it to any necessity of nature. Once again, therefore, as in the case of Eunomius, we find the doctrine of a will, which, on the one hand, has nothing in common with that which constitutes the essence of God (that is, with its simple infinitude, its solitariness), and yet, on the other hand, relates to the finite, which is supposed to be excluded from the divine nature. In this way, the world’s existence is at one and the same time posited and made impossible ; and both by God, for 1 Compare Hilarius de Trin. 7, 3-7, pp. 916-919, ed. Maur. The Sabel- lius to whom he refers in these passages, is in my opinion Marcellus. 284 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. the évépyera Spacrixy is in both cases His. The world alter nates between existence and non-existence. But the same con tradiction of position and exclusion affects God also, who Him- self has an alternating idea: at one time He speaks and works ; at another, He returns to silence, absorbs the world into Him- self under the pretence of perfecting it, and shuts it out from independent existence. What was necessary, was that that rigid distinction, which afterwards passes over into uniformity, should be given up, and that, instead of the alternation, an inward mediation should be effected between unity and distine- tion, and that the one should be shown to involve and be con- tained in the other. This work, however, could never be ac- complished so long as attention was devoted solely to the relation of God to the world, and no successful efforts were made, above all, to reconcile the divine unity itself with distinc- tions. In the respects just touched upon, the system of Marcellus contains a still unvanquished remnant of Dualism. But it has besides still more objectionable features. If the highest in God is that unity which abides in itself; and if the essence of God takes no part whatever in His productive activity (évépyeca dpactixn); then, in Christ there dwelt, not the essence, but merely an action of God, fixed in the man Jesus through a longer series of momenta. Marcellus thus diverged, it is true, from the earlier Sabellianism, which conceived God to have converted Himself into the man, even more distinctly than Sabellius him- self, who regarded God’s self-unfoldment in the Son as an unfolding of the divine essence itself. By this means also, he removed, more completely than Sabellius was able to do, the appearance of a change having been produced in the divine essence by the incarnation. For time and change, the manifold movements, etc., undertaken by the Logos in Christ, affected merely the divine activity, not the divine essence On this supposition, however, the presence of God in Christ is reduced to a purely dynamical one; not, indeed, as though there had been in Christ merely a divine effect, whilst the power produc- ing the effect remained outside of Him, for both the divine ? Only in so far as he allows the evépryeice Opaotixy to be connected with the essence of God, does he fail to exempt it from the movements and changes which the former undergoes, MARCELLUS 285 action and the acting power were in Him. Notwithstanding, the inner essence of God took no part in the incarnation. Nay more, where a more living conception of the omnipresence of God is entertained, where the “ omnipresentia operativa ” is conceived to involve the “omnipresentia essentialis,” there the distinguishing features which Marcellus supposed he was pre- serving for Christ, fall away of themselves. Nor shall we be able to charge Eusebius with injustice, when we find him ob- jecting,—“ A divine power lived and moved in many men, even before the days of Christ: the new element introduced by Christianity, is the personal indwelling of God.”! Such a per- sonal indwelling, however, Marcellus was unable to concede, because he denied the existence of distinctions in God. A personal God-man, objective to God, appeared to him an essen- tially imperfect thing; humanity, being inadequate to the divine, must be cast aside ere a perfect union with God can become possible. We arrive, accordingly, at the principle,— It is impossible for the incarnation of God to be a complete one, nor can the union of God and man be thereby brought to pass ; both are essentially, physically (#¥ow) separated, and can only be united on one condition, that the humanity cease to exist. But so long as the so-called divine Sonship lasted, it was sustained solely by the divine power, by divine action, not by the divine essence. Eunomius also was quite willing to allow the Logos to be as close a resemblance to God as possible, provided only the resemblance were not referred to the essence, but merely to the will of God. The Ebionism into which this new and refined form of Sabellianism (compare above, p. 150) debouched, occupies in one respect a lower position than Arianism, or even than the Ebionism of the common kind :—to wit, the means which Mar- cellus represents God as employing for the production of Christ, merely sufficed to exclude the human personality of Christ, and 1 Adv. Marc. 2, 4. Eusebius raises, also, frequently the very apt objection, that although Marcellus affirms that the Logos is invisible, and that no man can know God, save through Him in His visible state, or in the God-man, he still arrives at no revelation, because he is unable to allow that God had a real existence in the Son; all that he attains to is a hint or a symbol of revelation, a ongayzixzy Svvemis; for example, Ecc!. Theol. 1, 175°20,p. 90. 286 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. to constitute His entire appearance a living theophanic symbol, which continues in existence till the judgment; without, how- ever, on the other hand, advancing beyond the category of the dynamical. In this respect, the system of Marcellus’ disciple, Photinus of Sirmium, shows traces of progress.’ Photinus developed more clearly the Ebionitical conse- quences of Sabellianism; but he also, after taking his stand on the true and full humanity of Christ, which he only allowed to have been the subject of a divine influence, sought a com- pensation for the lack of a physical unity between Christ and God, in their moral unity; for which he required no further condition, than the supernatural birth of Christ. From which it follows of itself, that there can no longer be any reason why the man Jesus, crowned and deified for His virtue’s sake, should not be eternally King and Lord in His kingdom. (Note 53.) CHAPTER THIRD. THE CONFUTATION OF ARIANISM AND SABELLIANISM BY THE GREAT CHURCH TEACHERS OF THE THIRD EPOCH. WHEN treating of the struggles with Gnosticism, through which the Church had to pass, we found that it had at command an array of able men, who had been raised up to fight its battles and gain its victories; and so now, especially towards the close of the conflict with Arianism, a series of great men was called into existence, distinguished alike for the depth of their Christian life, and their ability for speculative inquiries, who served the Church by their labours, and adorned it by their intellectual and moral eminence. ‘The greatest Fathers of the Church flourished at this period: during the second half of the fourth century, the Patristic literature of the early Church reached its culminating point. To the objections raised by Sabellians and Arians, apt replies flowed forth out of the fulness of the Christian intellect; and the wounds inflicted by opponents, 1 Compare Athan. de syn. 26; Epiph. Heer. 71; Socr. H. E. 2, 18; Hil. de Trin. 7, 8-7; Fragm. 2, 5, 12; de Synod. c. 38, 39; Marius Mercator Nestorii, serm. 4; Theodoret. heer. fab. 2, 11. STRUGGLE WITH ARIANISM, ETC. 287 served but to unseal afresh the sources of Christian knowledge, and to cause them to overflow more richly. Arianism, it is true, was soulless, a product of the bare understanding; and, incapable of viewing the matter from the centre, and the parts in their connection with the whole, it clung to the individual and empirical. The positive element which it lays down, or, at all events, leaves standing, is also characterized by abnormity. Not only to minds of the present age, but also to sound reason in general, does an inferior God, a finite, created being which is represented as a creator, appear monstrous, and even super- stitious. Furthermore, seeing that, as a system, Arianism has little or nothing to recommend it in itself, and that the human mind would never by itself have arrived at such a monstrous mixture of rational and supernatural elements, it testifies in- voluntarily to the prior existence of an entirely different faith, which, on the one hand, it has essentially altered, though, on the other hand, it bears clear traces of its influence and impress ; in other words, it testifies to the true power of the Christian idea. It stands like a soulless, fantastic ruin, which points to a higher past, and owes its existence to a blundering attempt to coerce the fulness of the primitive Christian idea within the forms of the abstract understanding. In so far, it has a certain resemblance, not only to Socinianism, but also to the older Rationalism of the present day. ‘This latter had no intention of breaking with Christianity ; but was willing to allow all that the Scriptures teach regarding Christ to be true in an inferior sense; without perceiving, in its self-deception, that there re- mained merely a fantastic shell, a soulless, idealess history, which is at once too much and too little. But however untenable Arianism may be as a system, in a scientific point of view; and so certainly as only those whose sole culture is a superficial one of the bare understanding, can regard it as the golden mean be- tween two extremes; in another respect, as we have previously shown, it was a highly important phenomenon; and it was justified in disputing the right of the Church to the principle which is its life, until the Church had refuted the objections brought against it, and reconciled the contradictions, to which its attention was called, by setting forth the empirical and individual in the light of that view of the whole with which it started; and, above all, until it had renounced all connection 288 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCII. with the basis on which both Arianism and Sabellianism rest, That basis is the ante-Christian idea of God, as the unknown, infinite being, which, remaining shut up in the rigid simplicity of its own nature, cannot enter into true fellowship with man, —an idea, whose natural and logical end is either Deism_or Pantheism. We have seen previously (compare the Second Epoch), that during the conflict with the various heathenish and Jewish forms of Gnosticism, the Christian Church acquired its know- ledge of the essential attributes or momenta of the idea of God in general. Subsequently to that period, Pantheism and Deism made their appearance in great, though still bungling and in- consequent, forms. Both were far superior to the two older tendencies of Gnosticism and Ebionism, with which they have otherwise so many points of affinity, in so far as they were pene- trated by many Christian elements, which, on the one hand, were the source of strength, though, on the other hand, the source of inconsistency and weakness. Both Arianism and Sabellianism appeared to recognise, or at all events to leave untouched, the results at which the Church had previously arrived relatively to the attributes of the idea of God. And yet, in accordance with the experience, that when new and deeper questions are asked, doubt is always thrown for a time on the whole of the principles already recognised, these heresies were destined to make clear, that the Church must either be prepared to lose all that it had gained, or, besides refuting objections, advance on to new results. In point of fact, both Sabellianism and Arianism introduced changes into the doctrine of the divine attributes. In the case of the former, this is quite evident from its older and predo- minantly physical forms; for it drags down God completely into the physical ; it establishes no distinction between God and the world, that can hold its ground; and the very continuity which it posits between the world and God, prevents it taking an ethical view of the latter, prevents it from gaining an insight into that divine love, which, having power over itself, wills the existence of free creatures, and even in the incarnation honours. the freedom of humanity. In its later forms, Sabellianism en- deayoured, as far as possible, to avoid emanatistic elements ; but to the extent to which it succeeded, to that extent did it repre- sent Ged as abiding in Himself, without communicating His STRUGGLE WITH ARIANISM, ETC, 289 essence; and His revelation as merely “ showing” Him, as mere doctrine ;—and the doctrine of a God who does not communicate Himself is meagre, nay more, is manifestly self-contradictory in substance, and therefore fitted to lead the way to the opposed deistical point of view. Deism distinguishes more clearly be- tween God and the world, by substituting, as we have pointed out, the category of causality for that of substantiality :—though, be it observed, this substitution affected merely the relation of God to the world, and by no means His relation to Himself, as the cause of Himself. In the relation of the divine causality to the world, Arianism recognised the following point,—that the effect, if it have areal, and not merely an apparent existence, is neither a momentum of, nor primarily annexed to the cause ; but exists outside, and relatively independent thereof ; and that a cause is not really a cause, has not really worked, until it gives its effect a being of its own. This relative independence of the effect is then heightened by the introduction of the ethical prin- ciple. Arianism, however, in consequence of its deistic character, was not able fully to carry out the category of causality, even in relation to the world, but advanced no further than the first step. It posits, indeed, an activity of the first cause ; not, how ever, on its own account, but merely in so far as is necessary to demonstrate the possibility of a world independent of God; it goes back to a first cause for the commencement, but not for the continuance, of the world. It believed the world, once brought into existence, to possess in itself, in particular, power for the exercise of virtue and the attainment of knowledge. Nay more, from the Arian point of view, a deed of God, an act of divine self-communication, must necessarily have been esteemed a dangerous commingling of God and the world, a threatening of the existence of the latter, and a resumption as it were of the act of creation; for the world owed its independent existence to the fact, that the divine causality posited something outside of God. But herein is involved also, that for Arianism, God must stand in an alien and cold relation to man, that He cannot be Love; nor, on the other hand, can the virtue of man be viewed as love, seeing that love eries out for real fellowship The only ethical element, therefore, that can here be recognised, on the supposition that God and man stand over against each other as personalities, justified in maintaining a kind of exclu- WOOL aL, T 290 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. sive independence of each other, is justice or righteousness, but not love :—the view taken of the ethical, is simply a juridical, a legal one. The very discrimination, therefore, aimed at by Arianism, like the continuity aimed at by Sabellianism, rendered it impossible to retain a hold on the full ethical character of the idea of God. Both alike lost sight of the attribute of divine love, in a rigid conception of God. Rut if love fail, all other attributes receive at once another significance and position. On this matter, however, it is not necessary further to dwell. In con- nection with the idea of creation, we may remark further, that when Arianism represents the causality of God merely as one single act, that is, the one act of the production of the Son, who was destined to be the Creator of the world, it has at once toc little and too much. The world is deemed too bad for God to have been concerned either in its creation or sustentation; and yet, after it has once been created, it confronts God almost on_a foot- ing of equality, in accordance with the category of bare justice. God being supposed to be absolutely immutable, cannot take part in the world any further than is necessary for its attaining an independent existence outside of Him. And yet, to assert Him to have been only once the cause of the world, and to deny that He continues at every moment its cause, is to represent Him as inutable. Nay more, the divine causality also is interrupted, if God is not also the ground of the continuous existence of the world. And if it be incompatible with the divine sublimity or unchangeableness, that God should live in constant activity, a single act, the quitting of His rest even for once, 1s equally in- compatible therewith ; and Arianism, therefore, must either deny the existence of the world, or conceive God to be constantly active. This would indeed lead back to Pantheism, if, in cha- racterizing the causality as perennial, the idea of causality itself were given up, instead of acquiring completeness. But so cer- tainly as the idea of a perennial causality destroys the possibility of Deism, even so certain is it that, instead of involving, as some think, the abolition of causality, it is its confirmation and full carrying out. As such, it also confirms and establishes the dis- tinction between God and the world. This it only does, of course, when such a view is taken of the ethical causality of God, or of self-communicating love, as does not involve its passing beyond the category of right and law, without at the same time STRUGGLE WITH ARIANISM, ETC. 291 constituting that category part of the full ethical idea; in other words, without assigning to subjective freedom its place as a momentum in the collective process. The only way to protect the treasures once gained, against the new heresies, and to overcome Pantheism and Deism, was determinately to_advance, on the foundations laid, to.the deve- lopment of the doctrine of. the Lrinity.' If God is merely self-communicative, without at the same time, and above all things, possessing and maintaining Himself (sich selbst zu haben und zu halten), He is selfless and undistinguishable from the world, He is a being which can neither be termed God nor world, because it is physical and absolute at one and the same time. If God, on the contrary, 1s conceived as personal, as master of Himself, the world is shut out, it is true, from form- ing part of His idea, it is no longer a momentum of His being. The idea of God, however, is first to be viewed in its auTdapKe.a, purely by itself. But if we rest there, as Arianism did, we cannot posit the existence of any world at all; or, if one exist, it has a merely accidental existence. God shuts Himself up in abstract self-sufficiency and simplicity. But as such an abstract simplicity contradicts the ethical nature of God, it must be renounced; and accordingly, the very preservation of the result already arrived at, that is, of the ethical idea of God, rendered it necessary that the Church should further define God as He is in Himself to be, not an abstract Monas, but rather, even apart from the world and His activity therein, a living spirit, originating movements in His own being. Therewith was laid the foundation-stone of a speculative doctrine of the Trinity. This was the knowledge at which the great Church teachers of the age then arrived. The idea of a living God, as_con- trasted with the pantheistic or heathenish, and with the deistic idea, found fixed expression in the doctrine of a Trinity of the divine essence. It is undoubtedly true that Christendom owed its conviction that God is a Trinity to revelation, and did not deduce it directly from the conception of God. But at the same time, the doctrine of the Trinity rescued for, if it did not directly confer upon, the Church, the idea of God as the essen- * Nitzsch has shown, with peculiar clearness, that the doctrine of the Trinity is the victory alike over Pantheism and Deism, over the error of Heathenism and that of Judaism. 292 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. tially living God. That God can only be conceived by us as possessed of spiritual vitality through the medium of the Trinity, was not yet clearly perceived; and few attempts were made to construe the Trinity out of the idea of God. At all events, however, the conviction was arrived at, that there is the widest difference between the Christian idea of God and both that of Hellenic philosophy and that of Deism, inasmuch as God is to be conceived as a living spirit. The Church felt that it had secured this living idea of God in the Trinity, the existence of which was vouched by faith, although it was not yet scientifically understood, that is, the perception had not yet been arrived at, that a triplicity of momenta was necessary to the constitution of the conception of God as the living Spirit. Let us now examine more carefully the conflict of the Church with Arianism and Sabellianism. This conflict in- volved three things :— I. The critical examination of the systems. Il. The confutation of their objections. Ill. The further development of the doctrine of the Church. I. Athanasius was fully justified in asserting the Arian doc- trine to be an innovation (c. Ar. or. 1, 8). Never had the Church defined the Son to be a being created out of nothing ; never had it separated Him from God, or attributed to Him a different nature from that of the Father. As little had any teacher of the Church ever dreamed of dwelling with satisfac- tion, as Arius did, on expressions which lower the Son, still less of basing his system upon them. To curtail the dignity of Christ, was not the end they had in view; they taught subordination only so far as they were unable to reconcile the highest utter- ances of Christ (to which, be it remarked, they felt themselves, properly speaking, chiefly drawn) with the unity of God. Their view of redemption was totally different from that of Arius, and they saw in Christ the realization of fellowship, not merely be- tween a higher and a lower creature, but between God and man. The Fathers at Niczea were fully justified, therefore, in appealing both to the whole of Christian antiquity and to the Scriptures ; and alongside of many men of the third century, Athanasius adduces Ignatius as a witness against Arius (de Synod. c. 47) The individual elements of the Arian conception of God are ATHANASIUS—ARIANISM. 293 then, in particular, condemned. Athanasius aptly directs atten- tion to the lack of a religious principle in the system of Arius, when he says (de decr. Nic. Synod. 1),—The entire position taken up by Arianism is a false one; for, instead of asking, How could Christ, although God, become man? it asks, How can Christ be God although man? In other words, its Christ- ological starting-point is untheologically the humanity, and therefore it failed to arrive at the deity. The deity can be shown to be the principle of itself and of humanity; but the humanity can neither be the principle of itself nor of the deity. Further, God is to them as light without brightness, as a dried up fountain (c. Ar. or. 1, 14, 19). Through sheer sublimity, the God of Arius is unable to create (c. Ar. or. 2, 25). But if the world is so unworthy of God, and cannot bear Him, what help is it to posit a Son whose work is to create, but who is Himself a creature? If the world cannot bear God, no more can the Son, seeing that He also is a mere creature; and He would require another mediator, that mediator a third, and so on in infinitum (2, 26). Again, if the principle which created the world is not itself God, but is superadded from without (€EwOev émencayomevov, érixtntov, compare or. I, 17), God stands in no connection with the world, but both He and the world remain by themselves, isolated and abstract. The Son is said to have come to bring us into connection with God. If He is to effect this object, He must Himself also be an object of faith ; but how can a creature be the object of faith? The true and pro- per object of faith is the divine ; if, then, faith were directed to a creature alongside of the true God, it would be divided in itself, and we should have 8vo aléoreus,! and the dismemberment of the divine and the disunity of the religious consciousness, which were characteristic of the heathens, would characterize us also (or. 8,16). A creature made an object of worship is an idol, and to no being created out of nothing can it pertain to create out of nothing (2, 20-22, 29; 1, 26). A creature has not the power or capacity to unite us with God (2, 69); and miserable is the self-deception which con- 1 Avarynn rye adrove duo bcode, Eve beev xriorthy Toy Of ErEpov xTLaTOv, xoel Ovo xupiows Acerpevery Evl eesv dyevyytw, TH dE ETépy yevunto, nal xtiowers GVO Te lores exe, eloev prev cic Tov &rnbivov, Srépoev O¢ eis Tv woindévre al Trao- ivr, wap cebrav xual rAsybévre Oedv. 294 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. tents itself with the mere semblance of a gift, which supposes itself to be able to receive from a creature that which God alene can bestow. Freedom is inconceivable, if he who is to free us is himself a bondsman, and not rather God (2, 16). The Son alone can make us children; adoptive sonship presupposes a real sonship. Only in union with God are the wants of men satisfied ; but how can we be deified or made free from the curse by a nature that is foreign to us, or indeed by any other than God Himself? God-must.reconcile and unite us to Him- self through Himself (1, 37-39, 49-51; 2, 69, 70). We first received the Holy Spirit asa lasting possession (GeBalws), after Christ had animated humanity with the Holy Ghost in Himself, in His own person. Jivery created thing is mutable ; in order, therefore, to our standing fast, it was necessary that we should participate in the immutable. Man was to be deified; and that God alone could effect : he was to be made like Him: ; and that was possible alone through the archetype, whose image we were meant to bear from the beginning (2, 70, cll. 1, 49). How could a creature, which itself must be subject to judgment, de- liver us from judgment? (2, 6.) How can he, whose know- ledge of himself and God is imperfect, reveal God to us even in the way of doctrine? How can he who, like the Logos of Arius, needs first to learn, and who therefore may be subjected to error, forgetfulness, and change, be Wisdom ? (1, 23 ff.) In short, both the idea of religion and that of creation are incom- patible with Arianism. The world is a whole, a living being. If, then, the Son is Himself a creature, and yet at the same time the creator of the world, we arrive at a world that both creates and is created,—a notion which rends the unity of the world, in the same manner as we have previously seen the unity of faith to be rent (2, 28). Such a mediator for the creation of the world would derange and disturb, instead of mediating." Yet ae strictly speaking, gave up the ae of union an RFRA union to be the task imposed on the Logos and the God-man. It therefore assigned to Christ merely the position of .a teacher and example. Athanasius also acknowledged Him to be such ! Athanasius points out the dualistic features of this point of view when he speaks of the Manichzism of its advocates, ad Episc. Algypt. et Lib. C102 C. Atl eo: ATHANASIUS—ARIANISM. 295 (c. Ar. 1, 51; adv. Apoll. 1,4, 5; Ps. xvii.); but he at the same time shows that if this be all, Arianism ought consistently to pass over into Ebionism. The Arians maintain, that Christ merely proclaimed the forgiveness of sins (c. Ar. 2, 68); but a remission of sins by mere edict must necessarily remain exter- nal to man; the guilt and bondage of sin would still remain. What was required, was.a.real redemption by means of a real _union with God (2, 14, 69). When God works, His work must be permanent, and cannot require to be constantly repeated : on the Arian view, therefore, man can never arrive at perma- nent perfection, Nay more, Arianism depotentiates man alto- gether; for it denies that union with God is his destiny; whilst, on the other hand, it degrades God, and reduces Him to a Oetov p0ovepov, by the false sublimity which it feigns for Him. The error of Arianism, therefore, is, that, on the one hand, it commingles God-and the world, by setting up a creature as mediator between God and man, and making thereof an article of faith ; and yet, on the other hand, separates the two so essen- tially and completely, that not even love is able to reduce the distinction to unity. As then the pretended exaltation of God turns into an abasement of Him, nay more, to a confusion of Him with the world, in the Son, so is it with the Son also. Ap- parently He receives a lofty position, for He is the Creator, the causality ; but because He is not the final cause, He is in reality lower than the world, for the world is the final cause. Hence Athanasius rightly says,—If the Son exists only for our sake, if He came into existence merely that we might be brought into existence, He is a mere means, and we, as the end in view, were the object of the divine thought before Him. His exist- ence, therefore, is a transitory one,—that is, only necessary so long as the means, the organ, is necessary, by which we are to be called into existence. His origin He owes to us. The case is the same, if His exaltation affected His higher nature also, and if it were exalted on account of the virtue, which He had the opportunity of displaying towards us (c. Ar. or. 1, 40). All this Athanasius sums up in the one proposition,—If He was not God, there was no need of Him (2, 41). But we need God; for we are created to know, and be united with, Him ; and He alone can give us this knowledge, and bring about this union.—In so many respects does he show that Arianism, with 296 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. its inner invalidity, is incapable of affording the mind the satis- faction which it promises. II. No less acuteness characterizes his rejoinders to the main objections brought against the doctrine of the Church by the Arians and Sabellians. To notice in detail their explan- ations of Scripture passages and the Church’s exposure thereof, would lead us too far away from our main purpose (compare, however, on Prov. viii. 22, Heb. i. 4, Rom. viii. 29, Col. i. 15, -Heb:,iv.'2, Athan. e.-Ary or.>2,,.and! 3,7 it.; BasileMi ae. Eunom. L. iv.; Greg. Naz. or. 30). Let us now consider the refutation of their dogmatical objections. The Arians _said,— The Son must be a creature; for if He were of the substance of God, coeternal with Him, God would be divided, and physi- cal ideas be applied to Him. They asked therefore also,—Did God beget His Son voluntarily or not? If involuntarily, God was subject to compulsion; if yoluntarily, the Son having been begotten by the will of the Father, does not belong to His sub- stance, but is a creature. Further,—Did He exist ere He was begotten, or not? If He existed, He must have been eternal ; and then we should have the contradiction, that He existed ere He was generated. Consequently, He was not before He was generated ; and there was therefore once a time when He did not exist. Finally, they asked,—If the Father is unbegotten, and the unbegotten alone can be designated God, how can deity, in the strict sense, be said to belong to the Son? If the Son is begotten, but yet eternal like the Father, He ought to be described as the unbegotten-begotten one (ayevyntoyévyntos) ; He must be the Father’s brother, and, in order to be perfectly like Him, must Himself also have a Son; not to mention that we should thus fall into Ditheism. That the latter objections, in a slightly altered form, proceeded also from the Sabellians, we have seen in the case of Marcellus. Athanasius replied as follows,—Heathenish it is not, to give the Son divine honour, if He is really God; certainly, however, if He be a creature, as the Arians affirm. Perfect resemblance to the Father does not require that the Son be the Father, i.¢., it does not require identity. The Son is perfectly like the Father, in virtue of His immutability, because He remains what He is, even as the Father remains what He is, Amongst men we see only imper- ATHANASIUS. 297 fect copies of fatherhood and sonship; for the same person stands successively in both relations: he who is now a father was once a son, and he who is now the son will one day himself be a father. Instead of the mutability and mobility which characterize men, in the deity the Father represents Fatherhood absolutely and eternally, and the Son Sonship. Indeed, this absolute Father- hood and Sonship in heaven are the archetype of all fatherhood and sonship on earth.’ The Arians, as we know, were parti- cularly proud of the syllogisms which they derived from the position, that ayéyyntov was equivalent to Gedrns. Athanasius maintains, that it is an abstract formula to describe God as the Unbegotten One. In prayer, when we seek out the fullest and worthiest conception, no one dreams of addressing God by the name, “Unbegotten One.” The proper name of the Unbegotten One is Father. If we look at the world, which was created or begotten, in this sense the Son was not at all begotten, but is unbegotten like the Father. So also, if we look to the relation between the Son and the divine essence, and designate this essence unbegotten, it belongs to the Son equally with the Father, and therefore the latter is eternal; but the Father ought not to be identified with the divine essence.2 On the contrary, considered in relation to the Son, the Father is unbegotten, and the Son begotten by the Father. Human mothers, it is true, first become mothers, and are not such eter- nally; even as they themselves come into existence out of non- existence. But this is a sign of finitude. The F ather, on the contrary, because He is perfect, does not first begin to be a Father, as though He had not been a Father previously ; it belongs to His essence to be a Father, even as brightness belongs to light; and this His essence He does not acquire gradually, but it is His eternally. Therefore, because the Father exists either not at all, or is eternally Father, the Son also is eternally 7 C. Ar. or. 1, 21. Of dv Oparor nerd diadoyiy &rrhrov yevvavror nok J yevvawevos éx yervapiven worpds yevundels cixéras nal cebrdc erépov yiverocs TarHp'—O10 ovoe éorsy ev Tov, ToLovToIS nuplas rarnp nal xuplac vids ovde ornxev ér avToY TO warno xol TO vids, 6 yep avrds vies yiverat nal rarnp. “Obey él ris Oeornros movns 6 Tariyp xuplag warnp tort, xal 6 uldc xuplas vioc £oTly. * Compare c. Ar. or. 1, 80-34; de deer. Nic. Syn. 28. ’Avyévyroc is the Father designated, not in relation to the Son, but sclely in relation to the SEV NT 298 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. Son.’ Gregory Nazianzen developed this idea further, as follows,—Not even in earth is the causal relation limited to cases in which the cause precedes and the effect follows; in other words, succession in time, is not an essential attribute of the causal relation: the causal relation may have a place, he urges, in connection with things whose existence is contem- poraneous ; and adduces as an illustration, light and the effects it produces.” This contemporaneity of cause and effect is .evi- dently a form of the causal relation which is more akin to the higher category of interaction, according to which, without con- fusion of the distinction, both members of the relation are fully co-ordinated. It is plain also, that causality is in one aspect more perfect, when it is contemporaneous with the existence of that which is the cause. For then it is not merely an acci- dental cause, which might just as well not be a cause at all; but it is essentially a cause, and it is involved in its very idea that it should be a cause. At the same time, however, it is quite as evident, that on this view of the causal relation, the effect ceases to be something external to the cause, and to occupy an independent position relatively thereto. for, inasmuch as henceforth we are not to conceive the cause without the effect, the effect must belong to the essence of that which is the cause. Not that the Son is therefore the Father, or the brightness the sun; on the contrary, the distinction still continues; but it must be transferred to the sphere of eternal being and its reciprocally related distinctions. Taking this view of the connection between causality or generation and the eternal essence of the Father, two..conclusions must be drawn :.firsily, that it is no longer contingent or dependent on. the pleasure of that which is the cause, whether it be a causality or not; for if the generation of the Son had its ground primarily in a particular act of will, He could no longer be maintained to be coeternal with the Father, in the full sense of the term; it would be possible 1 ©. Ar. or. 1, 12-14, 20, 22, 23, 27.—C. 27. “Qerep gparnoav res yuvaines Tepl ray xpovov, ovtTa mruvdavecbacay xal rov HAlov wepl Tov drav- YHOULTOS KUTOD nal THS BnyHS Tepl Tov z= adriIg, Lye wadwoww, Ori—radre gorsv—aisl* avy exeivois. CO. 12:—Tis otras early cdvdnrtos, as d&u@iBarrsiv wept tov cel sivas tov viev; Ilors yap tis elds Qas Kapls TIS TOV dTavyAouaTOS Axum poryros ; “ Greg. Naz. P 29, 3 :—Ajjroy 02 70 aitiov, as ov wavras mwpeaBuTepor TOVT@Y, WY EoTLY aITLOY, OVOE yap TOU DuTds HALOS. ATHANASIUS—GREGORY NAZIANZEN. 29 to form a complete conception of the essence of God apart from the Son; and the Son must be looked upon as some- thing superadded to the divine essence from without. For this reason, secondly, that which is effected can no longer wear the character of fortuity or mutability; but as a necessary effect, without which a proper conception cannot be formed of ie divine, both the fact and the mode of its being are determined by the essence of that which is its cause. No wonder, then, that the struggle was concentrated specially on this point. Arianism did its utmost to prevent the application to the rela- tion between Father and Son of this form of causality, which supposes an eternal connection to exist between the effect and the essence of that which is its cause: this is the explanation of the dilemma adduced above (page 295). Athanasius, however, replied,—If the Arians talk of constraint, because the genera- tion of the Son did not take place after precedent consultation, or in accordance with an act of volition, they ought to apply the same rule to other matters pertaining to the essence of God ; for example, to His attributes. Does God, then, first consider ere He resolves to be good? Does freedom consist alone in the possibility of choice, in the capability of acting otherwise? No; a nature that is good and perfect is higher than choice (3, 62 f.)." Similar also is the reply given by Gregory Nazianzen.” But the Son is not on that account of the nature of a mere attribute, as the Sabellians affirm; nor is He an efflux of God, which would involve the division of the essence of God, but the entire (oNdKAnpov) divine essence, which, wherever it is present, is present in its entirety or not at all, and in this aspect is simple, indivisible, uncompounded, is in the Father and in the Son, though in each after a peculiar manner: to wit, in the Father Salida otal , as the living archetype, the primal source ; in the Son antitypically, as the absolute image, which reflects the Father. 1Q, Ar. 3, 62:—Kel cis 6 ryy dvayuny triBardy aire, Tovnporarol, xol Tovrea Thos THy ipso sevray ernovres; To dy yop dvtineiusvoy TH Bovarnoss (compulsion) tapaxcor, ro 08 wsiCov xal varepnsiwevoy on edeopnonv—r0 naTe Quow.—Eirarocay nuivy adrol ro dyodoy sivas xal olxtipove tov Osov, ex Bovarnosag wpoccotiv avt@® 4 ov Bovaryoss; In the first case, it is possible that He be not good, for the sake of the choice (ford eis txarepe, of the rads of the rAcyix} Qvais). But to say this of God is absurd. * Greg. Naz..or. 29, 6. ¥ 300 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. If. This leads us to the third point, which was the further development of the doctrine of the Church. Each of the two, both Father and Son, directs attention through Himself to the other," because each of the two is involved in the distinctive essence of the other (édvdrys is the word used by Gregory Nazianzen). When then, asks Athanasius, are we to suppose God to have existed without Him who is His own (that is, who is so far from being contingent, who is so imperdible, so indis- pensable to the integrity of His own idea, that this other self constituted as it were a part of the very divine being)? Or who can regard that which is His own (iévov) as something foreign, as something pertaining to another substance? No created thing, indeed, whatever bears any resemblance to its Creator, as far as the essence is concerned, but is external to Him; and, owing its existence to His good pleasure and His will, exerted through the Logos, it is possible for it to cease to exist, should such be the Creator’s will. This is the nature of the creature. But that which belongs peculiarly to the essence of the Father, namely, the Son, how can it, without audacity and impiety, be described as a something created out of nothing, as something which had no existence prior to its generation, or as something contingently superadded, which may, some time or other, cease again to have being? If any man find such ideas arising in his mind, let him consider well, that nothing may be deducted from the perfection and fulness of the essence of the Father ;* and in order that he may perceive more clearly the absurdity of the error, let him remember that the Son is the image and brightness of the Father, the configuration (ya- pax7ip) of His essence and the truth. If the light exist, the brightness is its image ; if the essence exist, He is the complete expression of the essence (yapaxtnp orOKAnpos).’ Let those, therefore, who subject the image and form of the divine to the t Ath. c. Ar. 1, 33: To rerip dnrwrixdy tors rod viod. Compare c. 34, 16 :—Adroy O¢ rev vidv BAswovtes Cpauey tov waréon. “H yep rov viov tyvore nal narannlis yvaots totl wepl Tov rarpos, did 6 éx THs ovalas adroD Pos0y elvas yévunud. *C. Ar. 1, 28, in a manner similar to this the eternity of the Son is argued, from the consideration, that it was x«adyv that the Father should always have been Father. See above on Origen. * Ist das Licht, so ist der Abglanz sein Bild, ist das Wesen, so ist er des Wesens vollkommner Ausdruck. HILARY OF PICTAVIUM. 301 conditions of time, look well to the abyss of godlessness into which they are falling. If there ever was a time when the Son did not exist, then the truth cannot have dwelt eternally in (zod ; for the Son says, “I am the truth.’ Given the essence (vTocTacus), the image and expression must also be given; for the image of God is not a thing painted from without, but God Himself i as the begetter thereof, 2; hehotding fT, ereserp therein, He rejouces (ares 0 Oeds yevyntns ects tabrns év i éavtov Opav mpooxaipes tavty). When can the Father be said not to have looked on Himself in His image? or when was it not His delight? (Prov. viii. 30.) How could the Creator and Origi- nator of the world behold Himself in that which was merely created? For the image must.needs be, as is the Father of the image.” We have found writers in the West giving utterance to similar thoughts even at an earlier period (see above, pages 186 ff.). In the fourth century also, the same view was pro- pounded by Hilary cf Pictavium. The idea that Father and Son know and behold themselves in each other, was familiar to him. One is, as it were, the mirror of the other; not in the sense that the divine lucific essence projected the merely ima- gined image of a being foreign to itself, but the mirror or the image is a living nature, and the one is essentially identical with the other. But if they (along with the Holy Ghost, who is still less made the subject of consideration) constitute the Deity, then it necessarily follows from the premises, that the self-con- sciousness of the Deity consists in this reciprocal knowledge of the Father and the Son (cognitio mutua), which is not merely a knowledge which the one has of, but which each has in, the other. And this relation seemed to Hilary so clear and cer- tain, that he applied it also to the ceconomic Trinity. To the sphere of the Father’s thoughts belong the things which He predestines to realization in the future. The Son, looking into the will of the Father, has the knowledge of the idea of His 1C. Ar. 1, 20: Tas troordoewg trrcepyovons, wavras ebbds elvas det rey xepantinoae xa ryy eixove ravtns’ ov yap eeubév tors ypaPouevy 4 Tov Osov sinay’ &AA adres 6 Oeds yevunrys tors ravens ev n Eavrdy cpay wpoovelpes Tavry. Ilore you ody, eupee Eevroy 6 rarip ty ry Eevrod eludvis y Tore Ov Tpoaexcelps s— aus Of noch eevrov dy Voor 6 roinris nol urioris ev xriotn nol yevnrn ovola; Toscevrny yoo sivecs Ost Hy sixdvec, olde eoTiy 6 THUTYS TAT. 302 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. own work; in other words, by gazing on the thoughts of the Father, He attains to the self-knowledge of that which is essen- tially the will of His own nature. But this introspection is brought about through the medium of their mutual love and nature." This remarkable theory contains already a kind of specula- tive construction of the doctrine of the Trinity, out of the idea of the divine self-consciousness. The Father must see, must gaze upon, Himself. In the world, that is, in the created world, He cannot do this; for it is not His perfect image, unchange- able, eternal, divine. If it were, it would no longer be world, but would rather belong to the essence of God; it could neither be said to have become, nor to be now becoming. And, on the other hand, to suppose that genesis (das Werden) belongs to the character of God, is to substitute the heathenish in the place of the Christian conception of God. But if the world is not the other self, in which He can contemplate and know Himself, He must have a perfect image in and with Himself, and this image is designated Son. It belongs necessarily to the essence of God, and is as eternal as God, inasmuch as He can neither begin, nor ever cease, to know Himself. We see now, therefore, ae significance of the thought which so frequently occurs in the writings of AG Ree iatiee Saar from the Son, the Father would be without reason, without wisdom (knowledge), without the truth (without the knowledge of Himself, the truth). It has not the same import as it perhaps had in some of the older writers, that the Father, taken by Himself, has not in Himself the principle of all this, but the Son alone; for that would lead to the notion, so frequently repudiated by him, that God is a composite being; whereas he asserts the entire deity to be in the Father and in the Son. Nor can he mean 1 De Trin. 2, 3: ‘‘ Pater autem quomodo erit (sc. Pater), si non quod sn se substantie atque nature est, agnoscat in Filio? 9, 69: Tanquam speculum unus unius est, speculum autem ita, ut non imaginatam speciem naturge exterioris splendor emittat, sed dum vivens natura nature viventi indifferens est. Comment. in Matt. c. 11, v. 27: Eandem utriusque (Patris et Filii) in mutua cognitione esse substantiam docet (Christus). Tract. in Psalm. xci. 6: Voluntatem Patris Filius tanquam exemplum operationis introspicit, quia intra paternarum cogitationum providentiam quadam futurarum rerum predestinatione formantur (sc. res future). In- trospicit autem per mutuam caritatem atque naturam.” HILARY—ATHANASIUS. 303 to teach that the Son was a mere quality of the Father, that is, of God (compare, for example, c. Ar. 4, 4, 2); for then there would have been no need to battle with Arianism and Sabelli- anism, inasmuch as both would, without hesitation, have con- ceded the existence of such a Logos in the Father. His mean- ing must rather have been the following (especially as it was a common custom to attribute wisdom, reason, etc., to the Father also) :—that divine self-knowledge, in other words, the divine knowledge ‘ sensu eminenti,” is inconceivable, save on the assumption, that a perfect image, a Son, stands over against Him, in whom He beholds Himself, or with whom He has self-consciousness.. That a very decided step was thus taken in advance of the ante-Christian conception of God, needs no further elucidation; it deserves notice, however, that a death- blow was thus finally dealt at the view of the divine essence, as abstract, motionless, simplicity. The positing of a perfect image, in which the Father contemplates Himself, would be impossible, had not God previously discriminated Himself in Himself; in other words, were it not as just to apply the idea of distinction as that of unity to the divine nature. This point, opposed as it was alike to Sabellianism and to Arianism, was so far from being regarded as dangerous by Athanasius and the other Church teachers of that day, that they used it as a new argu- ment for the refutation of their opponents, and as a funda- mental principle for the development of the doctrine of God into a doctrine of the Trinity. That idea of God which ex- cluded a Trinity, to wit, the idea of Him as shut up in His own sublimity, as indiscriminated in Himself, as the Monas, they considered to be false. They believed, on the contrary, that in God is eternal life, eternal movement. Who is able, says Athanasius (de decret. Nic. Syn. 12), to separate bright- ness from the sun, or to conceive of a fountain without life (c. 15)? God is not to be compared to a sea, which receives its water from without, but to a fountain. The divine foun- 1 After the above account, it will be impossible to give Baur the credit vf having gone to the sources for the view of Athanasius contained in such words as—‘‘ At one time he regards the Son as a free subject, at another as selfless and dependent, without doing anything to combine the two ;” and, ‘*‘no trace of an attempv to reconcile the unity with the distinctions is discoverable in his writings” (I. ¢. 489). 304 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. tain is never dry; light never lacks brightness. God is not unfruitful (@yovos). Were He dyovos, He would also be dvevép- yntos, and could not create; for He creates through the Son. This was a correct view to take of the matter, whether they had regard to the Scriptures which teach that the creation was the work of the Son, or to the circumstance (see above, pages 287 ff.) that, through the Trinity, the idea of God acquires that completeness in the self-consciousness by which pantheistic elements are excluded, and the idea of creation rendered pos- sible; or, finally, to the consideration, that, through the Trinity, the idea of God as a self-occluded, motionless being, with which the existence of a world is incompatible, is overcome, and that, with the assumption of a Son, who, inasmuch as He is deity under a fixed form, stands in a closer relation to finitude, a path of transition is opened to an external world.” But that we must not merely say,—the Father and Son eternally coexist, but,—The Son is begotten by the Father, he demonstrates as follows: If we only say the former, we arrive at a double God (Supuh Geov, c. Ar. 4, 3), at a duality of original beings, which do not derive their existence from some one being. The divine unity, therefore, is preserved by representing the Logos as de- rived from the Monas, not by introducing a dyas of beings, neither of which is the Father of the other. In like manner, Sabellianism also is to be condemned, because it shuts out a duality conciliated through the medium of unity. Athanasius reproaches it with fusing the distinct ideas of cause and effect (aitvov Kat aitvatov), of generator and generated, into one. On the contrary, Gregory Nazianzen remarks (or. 29, 2 ff.), carry- ing the matter out further in this aspect,—There were three cases possible: the divine might be represented either as an 1C. Ar. 4,4: El dyovoc, xcel ctvevépynros 6 Occ, yévvnuce yap “vTov oO vids, O¢ ov éoyeleras. Adv. Sab. Greg. Init.: The Jews have a God éyovoy viov, xa axaprov Cavros Adyou xat aoQies éArnbivys. Athan. c. Ar. or. 1, 14, 19. 2 C. Ar. or. 1, 16: It is precisely the same thing to say,—God gives a share in Himself, as to say, He begets. No one teaches that the self-com- munication of God introduces division and separation into God; for, were it so, we could have no part in Him. But if we can have part in God, it follows, that the Son also can have part in Him, and that indeed ‘sensu eminenti ;” for we can only have part in God, so far as He communicates Himself to us. ATHANASIUS—GREGORY NAZIANZEN, 305 anarchy, or as a polyarchy, or as a monarchy.. The first is disorder; the second brings tumult, and leads also to the dis- order of a dissolution. We must regard_ monarchy, therefore, as the preferable alternative. Not, however, a monarchy cir- cumscribed by one mpécwrov; for the one also revolts against itself (€ore Kal 7d &v oractatov Tpos éavrov), in that it strives to pass into plurality; but a monarchy constituted by the like dignity of the essence (opotuuia), by harmony of sentiment (yvoOuns cvumvoa), by identity of motion (Tavrorns KivicEws), and by inclination (suvvevors) to one of them (the Father). In finitude, a plurality without division is an impossibility ; but it is possible in God. For this reason, the Monas moved forward from the beginning into the Dyad, and finally came to a stand in the Triad (8a rodtTo povas an’ apyiis eis Sudda Kw Oeioa, uéxpt tpiddos gore); and this we hold to be the Father, the Son, and the Holy Ghost,—the one the generator and producer (arpoBorevs), Impassive, above time, incorporeal ;_ the second, begotten; the third, produced (7poBAnwa). For we cannot venture, with some of the wise men of Greece, who, when dis- coursing of the first and second cause, compared God to an overflowing bowl], to designate these, overflowings of goodness (Urépyvow). To do so, would be to run the risk of introducing an involuntary generation, a physical overflow, which God was unable to repress (epirrevja puaotxov, Svoxdbextov), and which would be totally unworthy of Him. Epistle 243, mpos Ev- aypiov povayov (which, however, it is true, is probably spurious), employs, besides, the simile of a circle and its radii, which, although distinct, can yet only be thought in conjunction with each other; the simile of a word, which, without being separated from the speaking intellect, acquires, at the same time, an ob- jective existence in the souls of the hearers, and, instead of separating, unites the souls; that is, a word continues identi- cally the same as to essence, and yet exists in different forms. “ As the rays of light have their peculiar constitution (tiv wpos adrnra cyéow), without division of substance, and are neither separated from the light nor cut off from each other, but carry the pleasant light to us; so also our Redeemer and the Holy Spirit, these twin rays, bring to us the light of the Father. They diffuse their blessings even to us, and yet they remain united with the Father.” Accordingly, there are different WO ledge U 306 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. modes of existence (e/5n) of one and the same substance (ovcta) in the Trinity. There is one river (ula por), flowing forth from the one eye of the source (that is, from the Father) from the beginning; but there are two branches, inasmuch as the streams assume distinct forms (d/ppuTos, TOY ToTapaVv oxnuatia Devt wv trois eiSeov). Although, therefore, the distinctions in God are termed three tpeor@res in point of number, as Athanasius saw in each hypostasis not merely a part of God, but.the entire God (édov ddov TUTrov Kar TavTOV padXrov 7) apopwoimpa, Com- pare Greg. Naz. or. 30, 20),—yet there is one deity, one puts in all, and Father, Son, Spirit, are tpets iSudtntes voepal, TéE- Deval, KAP EavTas KperTaoas (compare mpos Apetay sub fin.), that is, three different modes of existence of one and the same whole,’ With their derivation of the Trinity from the eternal vitality and movement of God in Himself, we must undoubtedly con- nect the circumstance, that Athanasius and Gregory Nazianzen were inclined to suppose that the generation..was.not moerely..an eternal, but an eternally continuous act. Otherwise, the act of generation would be represented as a single act of God; and God, therefore, must be concluded to have been imperfect prior to the act, if to generate and the thing generated pertain to His inmost essence.* It will repay our labour to ascertain more exactly the views entertained by Basilius.and Gregory of Nyssa on the subject of the Trinity. The main position of the former, in opposition to Eunomius, is,—the word “unbegotten” 1s_a name, not of the essence of God, but of one of His modes of existence (c. Eun. 4, p. 763, C., umdapyews TpoTros TO ayevyNnTOV Kal ovK ovaias dvouwa) ; the divine essence has other predicates. If every pecu- liar mode of existence brings with it a distinction in the essence, and if the Son cannot be of like substance with the Father, be- cause He has one mode of existence peculiar to Himself and the Father another, men could not be of like substance with each other, because each of them has his own distinctive mode 1 Compare Greg. Naz. rep! viod roy. w. (or. 29, 13). The Arians ob- ject,—el atv od wixavras Tov yevvay o @edc, areas 4 yévunois, xal wore wotosre:. He endeavours to show that it never ceases, although it can never be said to be areags. Athan. c. Arian. 4, 12; Basil. c. Hunom. 4, 760, ed. Paris, 1638, T. 1. BASIL—-GREGORY OF NYSSA. 307 of existence. We regard Father, Son, and Spirit, therefore, not as different ovcias, but as names denoting the vrrapEs of each of them (p. 765, B.). As they are all God, the Father cannot be more God than the Son; even as one man is not more man than another. Quantitative differences do not bear application to essences; there, it is either to be or not to be. But this does not_make.it.impossible.for the Son to be other than the Father (érépws éyew, p. 762); for example, the former is other in virtue of His generation. The dignity of both must be alike, for the essence of the generator and the generated must be one; and the effect is not always less than the cause (paiols B.). Were the dyévyntov a title of honour, it must be given to the Son also; and it does belong to Him, in so far as we under- stand by it, the uncreated, the unbegotten, the one who is with- out beginning (pp. 715, 719; ¢c. Eun. L. 1). Whence, then, the necessity for a subjection in point of rd£is, or a precedence in point of time, finding place amongst those whose essence is one? Why could not the God of the universe coexist eternally with an image of Himself eternally reflected? In this case, there- fore, we can only speak of an order involved in the inner reia- tion of the matter itself, to wit, the relation of cause and effect. As the cause, the Father takes precedence of the Son (p. 720, C.); but although the Father in this respect may be termed greater (TO Tijs dpyns Kal Ths airlas Oyo), it does not interfere with the ouoripuov ris dElas. But notwithstanding that their essence and their dignity are equal, the one is not the other. The Unbegotten is God, it is true; but it is not a definition of God, for not everything which God is, is unbegotten. The conception of God is not covered by the term a@yévynrov; but to the common essence must be superadded characteristic marks, which distinguish the Father and the Son. In the first place, the Father begets-the Son. If God, as our opponents maintain, is not to be supposed to beget, for fear we should have to hold the doctrine of an efflux; let us also say that He does not create, in order that He may not become weary. But if God can create without. being passible, much more can He beget. without being passible (c. Eun. 4, 760). And in the second Book against Kunomius (p. 730), he sharply blames those who talk in a tone of compassion about the multitude, confuting opinions which they pretend only brute 308 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. like men can entertain respecting God; but who, whilst they themselves reject the figurative word generation, and, in re- jecting the word, reject also the idea of the hypostatic essential equality of the Son and the Father, and leave unreproved those who lower the Son to the rank of a creature. Secondly, the Son,—such is the import of generation,—has His apyn from _the Father, in-equality.of.essence (c, Kun. 9,737). He 1s not a part of God, but ddos ddov yervntov ; they are not two parts, made out of one whole, but are téXeva Sv0 (c. Eun. 4, 765). Nor is the element common to the two, a substance which existed prior to the persons, and which was divided, one part being given to the one, and another to the-other; but the entire essence is in each, though each has it in a different mode. This mode con- stitutes the distinction or peculiar character (duaopa, wvoTns yapaxtnpifovca, c. Hun. 1, p. 719; compare 2, 728). Now, whereas, in the case of men, the differences between those who are of like substance are constituted also thereby, that one has an advantage which the other has not; in other words, whereas human individuals are discriminated from each other also by limitation or privation (distinctions which in their very nature may be transitory, if the one acquires the advantage of which he was formerly destitute) ; such differences cannot exist in the Trinity. For each of the rpocw7a must possess all divine qua- lities and excellences. The distinctions, therefore, are not con- stituted by orépnous, that is, by one possessing an advantage which the other lacks: the distinctive characteristic must rather be something positive, something which does not involve the su- periority either of the one or the other (c. Eun. 4, 765). Nor, on the other hand, is this positive something a superior quality pertaining to the divine essence. It is another mode of being of that essence; and the names, Father, Son,. Spirit, are-not-ab- solute, but relative, designations ; for, were they absolute desig- nations, the three would be different. essences. They refer to a relation of the mpécw7ra, not_primarily.to the world,-but.rcather toeach other; just as the idea of Friend, of one who is begotten, says nothing regarding the essence, but is a relative idea which we can imagine to be connected with another essence. For this reason, Basilius, like Gregory of Nyssa and Athanasius, says,— The idea of the Father is given with that of the Son, and vice rersd. This other mode of being or these idvrtyrTes, which he BASILIUS 309 also terms yapaxtijpas, popdas (c. Eun. 2, 744), distinguish the common substance, it is true, by characteristic marks (Tots io.dfover yapaxthpat), but do not discind it. For example, deity is common to all; Fatherhood and Sonship are distinctive peculiarities ; and the union of the two, of the common and the peculiar (€« Ts éxatépov cuptAoK}s TOD Te KoLWOD Kal TOD idiov), gives us the true conception of both. How, then, do they describe the relation of these peculiar modes of existence of the one Deity to each other? In the first place, although totally distinct from, they are not contradic- tory to, each other; seeing that they share the same essence. Secondly, they do not merely exclude, but rather mutually pre- suppose, each other,—the one suggests to the mind the idea of the other. They stand in such an inner relation to each other, that the thought of the one necessarily involves the thought of the other; in other words, they are relative conceptions; even as one cannot think an angle, or a side of a triangle, separately, without thinking both. By way of explanation, Basilius uses the following illustrations :—The Son is like a seal, which ex- presses the entire nature of the Father, or like the knowledge which passes entirely out of the teacher (that is, out of a sub- jective mode of being) into the pupil, and acquires in this latter another (objective) mode of being. Or He may be compared to thoughts, which as products are different from the producing intellect, or from the movements of the intellect, but yet are, and remain, connected therewith, in a manner unaffected by the conditions of time. Neither Father nor Son is a designation of passivity; but both are relative ideas, which declare that the two are intimately united with each other, that they are in- wardly related to, whilst distinguished from, each other (compare ce. Eunom. 2, 740, A., 737, B.). In consequence of this intimate relation between the mpdcwma, which makes it impossible to form a conception of the one apart from the other, the unity, the simplicity of God, is not endangered by the different TpOTrot Ths UTapEews (p. 745). With equal justice we might say, that to affirm any plurality whatever of God, disturbs His simplicity. As the persons are internally connected_with each other by the identity of their-nature, and of their eternal point of departure ; so also are they connected in their works, and yet remain dis- tinct. Every work is accomplished by the entire Deity, by each 310 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. person in a different way; so that we arrive at the formula,—- the divine will, starting with or deriving its impulse from the first cause as from a source, passes through its own image, the God-Logos, in order to manifest itself in actuality (c. Kun. 2, 745, E.). It is true, the simplicity of God is in this case not so disturbed by the Trias, that a different conception is formed of it than that recognised by the Arians. The Arians reckoned thereto, the divine incommunicableness ; the self-communication of God, which the Church represents as absolute in the relation between the Father and the Son, His image, they considered to be a passivity on the part of God. ‘This, all the teachers of the Church deny. Negatively contrasting it with divisibility and composition, they view the simplicity of God positively in the following manner :—the occluded, eternal unity of the divine essence subsists in a trias of hypostases, which can neither be increased nor diminished, but are indissolubly conjoined with each other. This latter idea, Gregory of Nyssa especially has carried out. But Basilius also did something of the same sort, in his own way. If we ask, namely, whether, when he speaks of hypostasis, he means a person in the sense in which we use the term of men, we must answer, No. There is a resemblance be- tween person and hypostasis, it is true, in so far as both are con- stituted by the superaddition of distinctive momenta to the common essence (by mpocOjxn of the idvopata, or of the iédud- fovca evvora, or of the yvdpicpa, c. Kun, 2, 745). They re- semble each other, further, in.that.each ofthe hypostases_has something which the other has not (é€aipera idu@yata, de vera Fide, T. 2, 390). A difference between them, however, lies in what we have advanced above, namely, that each of the divine hypostases possesses all the qualities which can be regarded as superiorities ;—a thing which cannot be said of human persons. With this is connected the further consideration, that whereas men can be numbered, number is inapplicable to God. Com- putability presupposes a separateness of existence which can have no place in God. We do not designate God one, at all, as to number, but as to essence; that is, we define Him as simple ; whereas amongst creatures, even that which is one is not simple. It does not follow, because a thing is one in point of number, it is therefore simple ; and that which is one as to essence, that is, simple, is not therefore one as to number: to the divine simpli- BASILIUS. 311 city, the idea of number cannot be applied, for number relates to corporeal objects (Ep. ad Ces. 141, T. 3, 164). His idea seems to be, that whatever is subjected to the laws of number, is for that very reason not absolute. or the One involves the possibility of a duality (see above, page 303 f.), of a plurality of beings of the same genus; it implies therefore a limitation, which has no place with God. Sooner could we suppose Father, Son, and Spirit, if not the essence of God, to be subjected to number. But even this, Basilius refuses to allow (de spir. S. c. 18, T. 2, 334). “We donot maintain three Gods, but one essence. The king and his picture are one. But each of the hypostases is like itself alone, and therefore cannot be taken together with the others by computation. We cannot say of Father, Son, Spirit, one, two, three; but one Father, one Son, one Spirit.’—In the last point, he goes undoubtedly too far, unless he means wholly to exclude number from the Trinity: for what objection can there be to comprising the three under the common idea of the tpozros trdp£ews, and to saying, there are three hypostases? His intention, however, was simply to avoid viewing them as three Gods; the unity of essence, de- nominated deity, must remain unaffected by the triplicity; re- garding the matter in the light of the deity alone, there is but a simple, indivisible unity. asilius appears further to have been guided by the just feeling, that deity, divine essence, ought not to be taken as the higher, the generic conception, under which the three are subsumed; ‘for if deity be the generic idea, it will scarcely be possible to avoid Tritheism, and then the distinctions in the divine substance would be di- visions. Whereas everything wears a different aspect if hypo- stasis be taken as the common conception, under which are in- cluded Father, Son, and Spirit; for hypostasis can undoubtedly be a subject of computation, seeing that, as a relative idea, it suggests at once another like itself, which cannot be affirmed of the divine essence. In this respect, the position taken up by Gregory of Nyssa is peculiarly interesting ; for he enters into a more careful con- sideration of the question of the relation of the divine essence to the hypostases, and of the unity in the plurality. Our opponents, says he (de s. trin. T. 3, 6 ff.), charge us at one time with Tritheism, at another time with Sabellianism, 312 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. or the error of the Jews. We abhor both. In opposition to the heathen, we maintain the unity of the divine essence; in opposition to the Jews, the distinction of hypostases (Orat. catechet. Magna, T. 3, 43 ff.). We do not reject every sort of plurality, but merely that kind which penetrates so deeply as to discerpt the essence of God; for that is heathenish. ‘The truth holds its onward course between the two, Heathenism and Judaism; overthrows the heresies on both sides, and adopts what is good from all. By the unity of essence, we cut away the phantastic plurality of Heathenism, and so heal the heathen ; by number, on the other hand, in the form in which we hold it (the plurality of hypostases), we cure the Jews (Cat. c. 3). But now it is possible for the same thing to fall under number, and yet not to fall under number, to be distinguished as to hypostasis without being divided as to the substratum (vzroxeiwevov); a vague notion may be formed, but it cannot be clearly expressed. That there is a plurality of Deerviers in God, he deduces, in the first place (Cat. M. 1, on from the consideration, that no one maintains that God is devoid of utterance or word. If God be not without word, it follows that He must have a Logos (Noyov Eye Tov wn aroyov). It is true, that men also have word, without therefore having the Logos. But the word must be conceived to be appropriate to the nature of which it is an utterance ; and will have a loftier import in the case of God; in our case, a lower import, agreeably to the finitude of our nature. Indeed, the same thing holds good of power, wisdom, life; all which pertain to us also, though in limited measure. In ac- cordance with our nature, our word has no fixed form (azray7s). But when we speak of the word of God, we must not suppose ‘that it has merely a momentary existence in the movement of the speaker, and that it immediately disappears again. On the contrary, just as the word of our perishable nature is perishable, even so the word of the eternal and unchangeable essence of God is eternal and substantial. But from the idea of the eter- nity of the divine word, we must advance to that of its vitality ; for it cannot be regarded as lifeless, after the manner of stones ; on the contrary, its subsistence is so completely incorporeal and spiritual, that it would have no subsistence at all, if it had no life. As spiritual, it is further to be deemed simple and not composite ; from which it follows, that it does not merely parti- GREGORY OF NYSSA. 313 cipate in life, whilst it has its subsistence in some other being , for on the latter supposition, it would be composite. Seeing, however, that it is not composite, but simple, it must be life in itself (abtofwnv elvat tov Noyov). If the divine word is a living Word, it must be able to determine, to form resolutions; and this capacity (mpoarperext Svvauis) cannot be impotent, but must be conjoined also with power. Now the almighty will of this Word is always inclined to the good and never to the evil, and is able also to carry out whatever good it may resolve. Ac- cordingly, everything is created through the Logos; He is able to do what He will, and He wills only the good, the perfect, the wise (compare Rupp’s “ Gregory of Nyssa,” pp. 168 ff.). But as far as concerns the relation of the Logos to the Father, he goes on to say,—The Word is different from Him whose word it is; it is, in a certain sense, one of the relative ideas (TOV pds TL Aeyouevav éotiv), for a word suggests a speaker. Accord- ingly, Judaism is kept at a distance. Even a human word is something different from the mind, and yet it is not separated from it, nor is it identical therewith ; for the word renders the mind (vods) visible (dyes ets To éudavés) or reveals it. Hence Gregory of Nyssa regards the relation between Father and Son as an inner self-revelation of God. By its independent subsist- ence, the Word is distinguished from Him through whom it exists; but having the same attributes as God (for example, goodness, power, wisdom, etc.), it is by nature one with God (Cat. M.c. 2). Should some one reply,—If you count three hypostases, why do you not count (in other words, hypostatize) the other attributes, but say, One power, one goodness ?—we answer,—Because we believe in one deity, and because the attributes together constitute this deity, or the divine essence. Inasmuch now as we know the divine essence solely from its works and revelations, one may also say,—By deity, as it exists for us, we understand the divine activity (€vépyeua). But this, too (like all the divine attributes), pertains to all three hypostases, though to each after its own manner (de s. Trin. T. 3, 6 ff.). Relatively to the Trinity, Gregory lays special stress on the distinction between the ideas otcla and trédctacis, — ideas which at an earlier period were frequently confounded, because UToatacts was held to be etymologically identical with substance (Heb. i.3); whereas ovc/a, as opposed to a mere notion, or to # 314 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. merely phenomenal existence, might be employed to denote the real substantial distinction in God; for as actual realities they can be termed ovcias. But the distinctive feature (édcxor, idtoTns) was not designated thereby. Gregory now sets apart the word broctacis to express the distinctive peculiarity, and employs it no longer in the sense of ovc/a, of substance, as the Nicene Fathers, and with them Athanasius, had frequently done, but as equivalent to 7pocw7ov, interchanging the terms iroctacis and mpdcwrov. On account of the misuse of the latter word by the Sabellians, he limited himself to the former when he aimed at logical precision, for in his view it expressed the real objective substance of the idcxov.' Gregory devoted three works to the discussion of this ques- tion, and contributed materially to fix the uncertain usage of the Church :—the work “De differentia essentize et hypostasis” (T. 3, 32 ff.); the “Quod non tres Dii sint” (T. 3, 15 ff.); and the Ilepi xowav évvordv (T. 2, 82 ff.). In the first-men- tioned work, he describes it as an error common to both Arian- ism and Sabellianism, to confound the two ideas of essence-and hypostasis. Because the hypostases are different, therefore, say the Arians, the essence also is different; because the essence is one and the same, say the Sabellians, therefore there can only be one hypostasis. But they ought to be discriminated as fol- lows :—ovc/a is the common element; the hypostases are to be defined as the centres of unity of the distinctive peculiarities (cuvdpoyn TeV Tepl ExacTov idiwpatwr, |. c. p. 85; compare Basil. c. Eun. 2, 728); and these hypostases are incommuni- cable in relation to each other, and cannot meet in one common hypostasis (Ta iSiipata or yroplopata yapaxtnpivovta Tas UTocTAcEls, aKoWwarvynta, actuPata, |. c. p. 382). So far ought we to be from interchanging essence and hypostasis, that the latter is related to the former as an accident (cuuSe8nxora) is related to its substance (rept x. évvol@y, p. 88). Now, as hypo- 1 The divine essence, ovo/a or vroxeiwevov, he does not term hypostasis, though there can be no doubt that he ought to have ascribed to it that which we call personality, because personality is the highest form of spiritu- ality, and spirituality in its full compass belongs, according to Gregory, to the very essence of God. His view of the matter therefore was,—he had not at all fully developed it,—that the one divine Ego exists in the three hypostases; in each, however, after a different manner ;—each hypostasis is a particular form of the Ego. GREGORY OF NYSSA. 315 stasis is that which discriminates those who have the like essence (Father, Son, Spirit), and as each of them has this distinctive characteristic, Gregory is perfectly right in not hesitating to apply number to them ae 2, 82): he treats the fynoetasie however, and not the essence, as the One, which repeatedly occurs in the Trinity (“ Quod non tres Dil,” p. 17: “O pev trav imroctdcewy AOyos Sia Tas evOewpoupéevas idioTHTAas exadoT@ TOV Svapepiopov émidéyetat, Kal Kata obvOecw év aplOu@ Oewpetrat, the hypostases can be counted by addition, 7) dé dais pia éoriv). But if the three hypostases can be counted, and are incommix- tible (no wikis nor avaxvKrnats of the hypostases can take place, because the distinction between cause and effect, the dsadopa KATA TO aiTLoy Kal aitLaTov, always remains) ; if they are ovcias peptxal, or, more precisely, if each is (Ouxa, dtopov Strep éoti Tpo- owrov (I. 2, 83), the question arises, Does not this lead to ‘Tri- theism? This question is handled in detail in his other two works. Ablabius had asked,—Peter, James, and John are called three men, although they have one nature; and it is not absurd, there- fore, to use the plural of the term nature, in reference to several beings of the like substance. And yet we are suddenly told that the sacred Trinity is an exception to the rule; that Father, Son, Spirit, are three, and of like nature, and yet are not to be counted as three Gods. Gregory’s answer seems at first sight strange ; but it is rooted, and that deeply, in the realistic cha- racter of his entire view of the world. It is an abuse of lan- guage, says he (8, 17), to describe those who have the same essence as several, by cyanate to them the plural of the word nature. The cord “man” denotes the nature which is com- mon to all, and this nature can only be one; there are not many human natures. The nature is in itself incapable either of increase or.of alteration. And yet we use the word which describes the nature in the plural, and speak of many men; which is just as if there were many human natures, or many humanities. Gregory, therefore, does not protest against all counting whatsoever, but against the use of a word to denote plurality, which has been coined to denote the nature, which cannot be multiple. Those who think of three Gods fall into precisely the same error. The idea of God, or of the deity, is one, indivisible ; there exists but one simple hile essence; the plurality does not affect this essence itself, but merely the hy- 316 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. postases, each of which contains the entire essence. It is wrong, therefore, to speak as though the divine essence itself were a plurality. If we wish to speak accurately, scientifically, we ought not to attribute that to the essence, which falls solely into the sphere of the hypostases. Consequently, the idea of God must not be treated as the generic idea under which Father, Son, and Spirit are subsumed, but the idea of hypostasis. This he expresses in various ways. ‘The essence is not divided in the three Persons, therefore also not the word “God;” for it de- notes the essence. That unscientific mode of expression is attended with no danger when we speak of men, because scarcely any one will fall on the notion of several humanities. But when we speak of God, we must use greater accuracy ; for if we say that there are several Gods or divinities, we lose the idea of God altogether : we no longer have any God at all, seeing that God is simple and unchangeable (8, 25 f.). In the case of hu- manity, it is, to a certain extent, allowable to treat the word man, although it denotes the essence, not as the self-same, iden- tical, simple essence, but as capable of change, and of being used in the plural form. For that which falls within the compass of the idea man is, in fact, mutable; of those who bear the name man, there are at one time more, at another time less; at one time these, at another those. He means to say, therefore, that in the case of the human race, humanity itself is, to a certain extent, drawn into the change of the individuals, so that it is partly justifiable to use the term in the plural. But in the Holy Triad there remain eternally the same mpdcwra; these mpocwra continue eternally the same; they admit of no increase to a Tetrad, no diminution to a Dyad, of no growth and no ter- mination (2, 84). Herein lies not only the thought, that the idea of God, which excludes change and multiplicity of Gods by its simplicity, does not allow of being subjected to the law of number, but also the beginnings of an answer to the further near-lying question,— Whether the persons of the Trinity are not distinguished from each other, as, for example, human _per- sons are distinguished? Individual men are peculiar modes of existence of the entire genus. The question is negatived. There is undoubtedly a certain similarity ; namely, neither in the case of God nor of man is it allowable to identify essence and hypostasis ; nor is it just to regard the latter as the former GREGORY OF NYSSA. SL when we wish to speak precisely,—for example, to speak of the Son as a God. But there is also a difference; and the percep- tion of this difference prevents us in another direction from using language which implies that there are three Gods. We are able to conceive of a man by himself; he is so subjected to the laws of space, especially through his body ; he is so exter- nally separated from others, that counting has its full import as applied to him. And when several carry on the same work, each usually ackomplishes it by himself, and separated from the rest (T. 3, 22, 25). Indeed, the loose connection between, the isolation of, the persons of the human race, mark their mutabi- lity. Itis otherwise in God; for no conception whatever can be formed of the one hypostasis apart from, but solely in and with, the two others, and there is not room for a more or a less. They are relative conceptions, which stand or fall with each other; and are therefore conjoined in the most intimate manner to a solid- aric unity.’ This idea is then developed, both in relation to their being and to their operation. In regard to the former, Gregory refers to the fact, that not all human zpocw7a are derived from one tpocw7ov, but each from a different one. In the Holy Triad, on the contrary, everything proceeds forth from one centre of unity, the Father, who on that account is termed xupiws God,” because in His hypostasis, as it were, divinity has its principial seat (apx7).” But as to the operation of the hypo- stases, all divine activity proceeds forth from the Father as the primary impulse, advances onwards through the Son, and cul- 1 De diff. ess. et hyp. p. 36 :—The author of the Epistle to the Hebrews (c. i. 8) speaks as xeracxsvalay To ddieoraros exivosiobcs TH moaTpl Tov vier. —So also is the Son involved in the conception of the Father :—dore tov to KLPAXTHOL TOD pLovoryevors ie Tov THs LUKAS buMaTOY avaTEvicMYTA, Kal TIS TOU Tarpos UTosracews ey Tepivola yeviabas, ovx ETaHAAMOTOMEYNS OLDE GUYHYE- usyvumeyns THs Oewpovmedyns avrois idsetnTOS, Hore Yeh waTpl THY yevoNTLY y TE via Thy aysvunolayv erimopDalesw, etc. Ovdd yep eorl duvarov, vidv dvopaoarta Ly nal warpos ey wepivole yevicbat, ox%ETIn aS THS Tpocnyoples TavTNS Hal TOD marépe cvvevadavovons. 2 That is, because He is the principle of the hypostatical element in the two others, but not of their divine nature. At all events, he says (2, 82 ff.), —Not as God, is the Father this distinct hypostasis (that is, Father); other- wise the Son would not be God. 3 T.2, 85:—Ep yep xal rd aire rpdawmoy tov weerepos && ov 6 vids yev- vero nol ro music TO chy. sxmopsverac’ O40 wal nvplag TOV Eve aiTiOY GYTH THY > ~ > Sect ec , avTOV aitiaray, sve Osov Daey. 318 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. minates in the Holy Spirit. Every work, therefore, passes through the three points or prosopa, wy, évépyela, TehElwats ; in their respective activity, which setting forth, as it does, one movement and one governing (kivynots Kat dvaxoopnaols), of the good divine will, they are not separated by time." Accordingly, the Son is immediately out of the first (poceyas €x TOU TpwToOV), and the Spirit is immediately through that which is out of the first (Quod non tres, etc. fin.). Not, therefore, by time, not by place, not by will, not by work, are the persons separated.” Not even number bears a full application to them, because they are essentially connected, and in no respect separated, momenta of the entire divine essence (T..3, 25). Those things alone can be arithmetically added which have an (8/a repuypady ; such an iota mepuypady is possessed alone by objects corporeally bounded ; consequently, the divine cannot be counted. Gregory, there- fore, employs also an expression which connects the hypostases (cupPS_eBnxora) more closely with the essence, without, however, confounding them therewith ; to wit, the divine nature is simple, but it is discriminated in itself (Ssapopay dé mpos éavTny Exel), as becomes its majesty (c. Eun. 1, 842). What his meaning was, will probably be clear from another passage (de differ. ess. et hyp. pp. 38, 84). The Trinity, says he, presents us with an enigma—a conjoined distinction (dudxpiows ouvnevn) and a dis- criminated conjunction (d:axexpiynévn cuvadera). He employs a beautiful image to show that the distinction need not destroy the unity, nor the unity exclude the distinctive (r@v yvwpioua- tov To tduatov). The rainbow is a reflection of light which, whilst it proceeds forth from, is also refracted back to, the sun. To the light corresponds the divine essence. The light in the rainbow and in the sun is one; but in the rainbow the light, which in itself is one, arrives, as it were, at its maturity. The one light does not therefore distribute itself into many lights, but the colours of the rainbow remain conjoined in unity, and 1 T, 3, 22 :—Tldow évéoysie 1 bcodev ext ryy xtiow Oinnovon, nal nora Teas morvrpomous gyvores dvomaloutyn, é% wartpos dQopudra: xal dic tov viov Tpistol, nel ev TH yl TeAiovTa:. Asad rovto eis AROS THY EvepyouYTmY TO Ovopece Tis eveprysias ov OsocoxiCeras. 2 T. 2, 85 :—Odre yap xpcvw Oioipsiras: dranray ta rpoowre THs bsornros, ours TUTW, OV BovAY obx EmitndedMaTI, oVx EvEepysio, ov Tabet ode! ToOLoUTMY, olemep Ocapeiras tml cov &vOpamruv' 4 ovov, OTs 6 waTHp Tarrp soTl, nal Wx vids, etc. GREGORY OF NYSSA. 319 although clearly distinct each from the other, shade away im- perceptibly into each other. After the same manner may the hypostases be represented as the full-blown flower of the one divine essence; its distinctive characteristics beam forth from each of the three whom we believe to constitute the sacred Triad, as from the rainbow. No difference, however, can be perceived between the essence of the one and that of the other; but along with the unity of essence, there shine forth from each the pecu- harities by which it is known (@omep toivuy év TO brrodelypare (sc. Ths iptdos) Kat Tas TOY YpopaTwv Siahopas pavepas Suaryt- voorKouer, Kab Sudatacw étépou Tpos Erepov od &aTt TH aicOnoet AaPelv, obTw pot hoyicat Suvaroy civat Kab Tep Tov Oelwy Soy- Latwv avadoyicacba, Tas wev TOV UTooTdcEwV LdL6THTAS, WOTEP TL avOos TaV KaTa THY ipw Tmpohawopmévwy éracTpaTTew eKdoT@ TOV EV TH ayia TpLdd. TeTLoTEULEVOV THS 6€ KaTa THY d¥ow tOuorntos pundepiav érépov mpos To erepov érrwvociabat duaopar, ANN €v TH KOWOTHTL THs ovolas Tas YyvwploTiKas iSioTNTAS emI- AdpuTrEwW €KaoTH).” A more careful examination, therefore, shows that there is uo ground for reproaching him with Tritheism. It is incorrect co say, that Gregory conceives the hypostatic distinctions in the Trinity to be related to each other as are two individual men; for, on the contrary, he rather reduces the entire distinction be- tween Father and Son to this—that the former is the airuop, the latter the aitiaroy (7. x. é. p. 85), whereas the distinctions between actual men are much deeper.” In connection herewith 1 T. 3, 36 :—Read further, Kai yop xaxei ty ro drodelyport 4 druvyc- Covoe ryyv rorAvxpameoy exsivay ceiyny pele ovola gy, y did Tis Arsenic a&urivos avaenrasyn, 70 OE kvbos Tov Deesvomévov woruetoes, TasdevouTos Olteas TOD Adryou Lal THS uTloEwS Huds, Lyn noeoredsiv toils wept Tov Odyparos Adyols, orav sis 70 Ovodcapuroy ereadures (1. terrépupeev) rods Thy ouynaradeow Tay Asrvyoedvun. * Baur’s view of Gregory (1. c. p. 453) is inaccurate, because he has not taken into consideration the chief works which bear upon this point. The imperfection of his acquaintance with Gregory is particularly clear, from the judgment contained in the words,—‘‘ What he says respecting the unity of ‘man’ is plainly invented in the interest of the Christian doc- trine of the Trinity.” Nor would he otherwise need to say (p. 451), that he cannot quite make out what Gregory means to teach. The judgment just quoted proves also that Baur has taken no notice of Gregory’s work, wepl xareoxevis avOparov; for its fundamental idea (c. 16, 17, ed. Bas. 1567) is, that humanity before God is to be considered as one man. Gom- pare Rupp’s ‘‘ Gregor v. Nyssa,” pp. 175 ff. 320 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. it must be carefully borne in mind, that neither Gregory nor his age generally, regarded the Ego as the central feature of the person. He considered human zpdcwza to be formed by the arepuypady or circumscription of human nature, and by the idvxov, the principle of individuation or the distinctive charac- teristic. Men are constituted droua by both together. These aroja are not described as Egos, but merely as the centres of unity of the characteristics, which distinguish the one from the other (cuvdpoun Tov iditoudtov, 3, 35). Kqually far is he from speaking of an Ego in connection with the divine hypostases ; and it is the more unjust to charge Gregory with teaching three divine Egos, as he takes pains to forefend the application to the sphere of the divine, of the series of determinations by which one finite individual is distinguished from the other. If he defines the divine hypostases also to be cuvdpopat tov ivwpd- Tov, itis in a different sense from that in which he uses the expression relatively, for example, to men; as is very evident from the simile of the rainbow. Had Gregory more carefully examined the matter, he would undoubtedly have arrived at the conviction, that to be an Ego, or to have self-consciousness, is the highest form under which spirit in general can appear; he must therefore have reckoned it to pertain to the ovc/a of God (see note, page 313), and have regarded the Ego as the com mon vzroxeiuevov of all three. Gregory does not plainly teach, as did Athanasius, that the eternal self-consciousness of God is brought about or mediated by the trinitarian distinctions ; though there are faint traces of such an idea in his writings :— for example, when he appears to represent the Logos as an inner revelation in God Himself (C. M. c. 2); or anon he says,— “ As aman who has looked upon the expression of his form in a clear mirror, so he who knows the Son has taken up into his heart the distinctive characteristic of the hypostasis of the Father through his knowledge of the Son” (de differentia, etc., Dahale When we glance backwards at the.period through which we have passed, with a view to determining the doctrinal. pro- gress made, relatively to the higher aspect of the Person of Christ, we find it to be in the main the following. The two factors, the true divinity and the hi ypostaliia ice of the higher element in Christ, of which the former had had the pre- GREGORY OF NYSSA. SEMI-ARIANS. a | dominance in the Church during the second, the latter during the third century, were destined to unite and coalesce by inter- penetration during the fourth century, if things took their orderly course. As it were, in order that this process of inter- penetration might be properly accomplished, it happened that each of the two factors found its own representative, the one in the new_Sabellians, the other in the new Arians; and that the two confronted each other at one and the same time. The former asserted the true deity, eternal, non-subordinate, and itself the apy, but conceded no distinct hypostasis to Christ ; hence the possibility of a relapse into Docetism or Ebionism. The latter affirmed the hypostasis; but it is one that bears merely the name of divinity, and, as a creature, remains constantly outside of God. Each of these parties, in their mutual anta- gonism, repudiated the factor affirmed by the other; whereas the Church teachers of the second and third centuries, whilst giving predominance, now to the deity and then to the hypostasis, had always tacitly recognised the non-predominant factor. The consequences of retaining the one factor to the exclusion of the other being thus set livingly and clearly before the mind of the Church, it saw the necessity of combining both together, anc prepared to accomplish its task. But it was precisely to this combination that the two heresies above mentioned were equally strongly opposed; for its realization would be their extinction. Earnest attention was devoted to the problem from the com- mencement of the fourth century onwards, in Alexandria, as we see from the labours of such men as Peter of Alexandria, Mierakas, Alexander, and others. Alongside, however, of this line of thinkers, who alone were occupied with the further de- velopment of dogmas, there arose another party which adhered more rigidly to the system of Origen. Partly because it co- alesced with elements of the older school of Antioch (that of Lucian) ; and partly, because, for the one it bridged the way over to Arianism, and for the other to a higher view of Christ, this party speedily attained great influence and dimen- sions. Husebius of Caesarea was its chief representative. For a long time, it looked upon itself as the true golden mean between the two extremes; inasmuch as it actually did bring about an apparent union of the factors, by commingling the Sabellian and Arian principles. Had the great teachers of VOUT. x 322 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. the Church, however, contented themselves with this seeming solution of the problem, that sharp separation of principles which was destined to bring about the crisis and to prepare the way for a higher union, would have been a lesson given in vain. Instead of making progress, the Church would then, in the best case, have been forced to fall back on the vague and indeterminate doctrinal condition of the third century. The peace thus established, would have been merely apparent ; for the Christ of the Semi-Arians was not in a position to accomplish that work of atonement and deliverance which the Church believed their Christ to have accomplished. The Church was compelled to adhere to its conviction, that the inmost, the veritable divine had been revealed to and conferred on humanity, in Christ ; whereas the delusive nature of the solution furnished by Semi-Arianism was demonstrated by the circumstance, that its conception of God was essentially identi- cal with that of Sabellianism and Arianism, and that it was as incapable as they of expressing the fulness of the Christian revelation. This is specially apparent from the position taken up by Eusebius relatively to Marcellus. Marcellus, with a view to establishing the true deity of the higher element in Christ, taught that the Logos was coeternal with God; and, in order to exclude all subordination, affirmed Him to be an aryév- yntov like God. At the same time, in agreement with the Arians, he required of the teachers of the Church, that if they meant to assert the true divinity of the higher element in Christ, they should represent the Logos also, and not the Father alone, as dyévyntov. By this Marcellus did not merely mean, that the Logos must have true deity (that aseity must pertain also to Him); but in excluding yévunots, he deemed himself also under the necessity of excluding the Sonship and the particular hypo- stasis of the Logos. To Eusebius, not merely the latter, but also the former, seemed very objectionable. For, even though Mar- cellus were free from the fault of denying the hypostasis, in his view, to introduce the Logos, after this manner, into the inmost divine sphere, would involve the assumption of a plurality of divine dpyat, that is, Polytheisin or Dualism (de eccl. theol. 1, 5, 2, 12); from which it is evident, that the hypostasis of the Son, according to Eusebius, is unsuitable to the inner divine essence, and must destroy the unity of God and of the divine SEMI-ARIANS. ARIANS. Ooo self-consciousness. He cannot, therefore, have regarded Christ as the absolute revelation of the Most High God Himself, but must have believed that God remains shut up in Himself. That Sabellianism also participated, against its own will, in the in- communicableness of God which characterizes Arianism and Semi-Arianism, so far as it did not fall back into Patripassian- ism, we have seen above. What position did the teachers of the Church take up in relation to this matter ? I, With the Arians, they advanced decidedly beyond the Sabellian idea of substantiality (the traces of which are still discernible in the 7Xatvapos of the Monas, taught by Marcel- lus) to that of causality; in the first instance, with regard to the relation between God and the world. They thus excluded everything of the nature of Pantheism. All that is called world, was absolutely caused by the first aizvov, which itself has no cause higher than itself. Accordingly, everything truly divine stands over against the yevntots (that is, the world), as ayevyntov, or, more precisely, ayévntov. So far they were agreed with the Arians. So also, in conceiving that the higher element in Christ existed in the highest, that is, in the hypo- statical form, and neither as mere activity, influence, nor as an indwelling of the entire God in general, which would have in- volved Patripassianism or Docetism. For this reason, the dis- tinction between aitsov and aitvarov, generator and generated, must_not be allowed to sink down into identity. IL. But instead of supposing, as did the Arians, that the highest had been predicated of God when they had predicated mp@tov altsov and ayevvnoia, they say,—To describe God as the cause of the world, is not to describe His essence (otherwise He would be merely the substance or the force of the world) ; nor, when we deny that He is caused like the world, or attribute to Him ayevynota, have we described His true essence, for this is a merely negative determination. All that the ayevynaia does, is to bring the chain of causality to a stand still; it does not bring the cause itself to perfection. And though the teachers of the Church do not view the ayevyncia positively, as the eternal self-grounding of God, of which no conception can be formed apart from a Trinity, and in which the Son also participates, the distinction just referred to, between generator and generated. 324 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. between aitiov and aitiatov, leads to the same result; for it implies that causality has a place also. in. the.divine essence, that God stands to Himself in the relation of cause.and.in the relation of effect. The emptiness and abstract simplicity of the deistic conception of God they despise, and refuse altogether to allow that the highest in God or His essence is described when we say,—He is the cause of the world, or He has not Himself been caused ; their conception of God includes, besides the idea of causality, also the spiritual ideas of love and wisdom. How- ever highly they. may estimate the significance of the idea of causality relatively to the world, they assign it. but..a.secondary or subordinate position when. they treat of the conception .of the divine.essence. So is it to be understood when the Fathers say,—Lhe Son is partly not to be subsumed at all under the category of causality, for He does not form part of the world, but is ayévntos; and yet the category bears a partial application to Him (for He is yeryntds, a yévynwa of the Father, and this ensures the unity along with the distinctions), though in a sub- ordinate, secondary sense (cuuSeBnxdtas). For that He is caused, is not His essence, otherwise He might be a “con- tingens” like the world, which, the ground of its existence lying out of itself, has the yu) dv cleaving to it. The essence of the Son is the divine itself, the ayévnrov (as Marcellus teaches) ; and, compared with this His absolute essence, His relation to the Father, His being begotten (such is the form in which he presents the category of causality), is a secondary feature. The yopiotiKat iuoTnTes are cupPeSnxviat in comparison with the essence or with the conception of God, of which the Son forms as nécessary a part as God Himself. III. If, now, that which constitutes the Son (and the Spirit) a particular hypostasis is a cvp~PeSnxos in comparison with His divine essence, a secondary relatively to the common primary, it might appear as though the view propounded by Marcellus, who regarded all distinctions in God as merely momentary, posited for our sake, but not as required by the divine essence itself, were justified. The intention of the Church teachers, however, was not_to.reduce.the Triad in God to something accidental, to some- thing dependent on the will of the Monas. We have seen even Origen striving to advance beyond such a representation: the teachers of the fourth century had decidedly advanced beyond SEMI-ARIANS. ARIANS. eb it (see above, pp. 301 ff.); for they regarded it as necessary ta the full conception of the living God, that He should exist in the form of a Triad. Wehave also already come upon very remarkable attempts to show that the triplicity is a necessary one. But attempts of this nature could never succeed, unless the three hypostases were presupposed to be perfectly equal in dignity ; and this presupposition was adopted in the following form :—They are equal in essence, in the fulness of attributes, divinity pertains alike to all; they are included in that unity of the divine essence which must be taken as the point of departure ; the eternal diremption of that unity, therefore, with the iSéuuara of the individual hypostases to which it gives rise, can no longer be deemed incompatible with their equal dignity and deity; this stands firm once for all, the iScouata NapaxTynptotiKa are for it something indifferent (cupSeByxos). But they are by no means, in every respect, something accidental; on the contrary, they are required both by the Christian faith and by the Christian conception of God, which has left behind it the lifeless, self- absorbed “Op of the ages preceding the advent of the Redeemer, The Christian God,—this is implied by the constructive efforts referred to,—opens Himself, in the first instan ce, in and for Him- self (placing Himself over against, knowing and loving, Himself), and then for the world. This height was ascended neither by the Arians, with their idea of causality, nor by the Sabellians, with their substantiality, nor by the Semi-Arians :—indeed, such a conception of God was derivable neither from the Platonic philo- sophy, nor from any other region of the ante-Christian world. But undoubtedly. the Church teachers, in order to be able to place the Son.as the objectified- divine. over against.the objecti- fying-Father,-must.needs partially renounce.the conception. of hypostasis, which had been frequently laid down in the third century, and by the Semi-Arians, and which was essential to Arianism. To Arians, the main matter was the hypostasis, which they viewed as essentially finite, with whatever lofty pre- dicates theymight adorn it. The personality of the Son, so under- stood, has in it an exclusive, a repelling element, and cannot at all be represented as endowed with the veritable divine nature, vithout an approximation to Paganism, that is, to Tritheism. “It-is therefore deserving of all recognition, that from the moment the Church clearly saw that the problem awaiting solution was 326 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. the full union of essential deity with the hypostasis, new dog- matical terms were coed, in order to define the word Hypo- stasis more precisely, and in such a manner as to show its recon- cilability with the unity of the deity. Such terms were diaopat, Suaxpicess, TO ETEPWS EXEL, ro iduxdv, idiafov, cvvdpopat or cup- TroKal Tov iLoLdTwV, OL TOV yvOpLoTLK@V yapaKTnpllovg wv iStoTTeVv, THs Lvalovans évvoias, THY éEarpérov (Oimpatav, TOV iStalovT@y yapaKTnpor, oyNpaTic Los TOV Ela, that is, points of unity, foci, or central-points for the marks by which the dis- tinctions are constituted; and starting with this, it was possible to speak of three principles in God, for example, under the image of three connected, suns. Further, tpovou vmap&ews, pophal, 7) pos adAnAG oYeTls TOV TPITwWT OD, elon, LOLoTNTES. As the content of the divine essence, its fulness, is common to all three, the distinction can only relate to form, or to the different. modes of existence which are eternally contained in, or appertain to, the one deity, and which are. the presupposition of God’s revelations and-their--diversity. With all this, these Fathers by no means succeeded in answering the further ques- tions which here suggested themselves ; though, as far as lay in their power, they prepared the way fora further development of Christian knowledge. This they would not have done, but, on the contrary, would have stifled all further activity of the Christian mind, under the pretext of the Trinity being an abso- lute and unapproachable mystery, if, as many seem still to sup- pose, they had appropriated the Arian, or even the Semi-Arian conception of God, and therewith the problem, that three are no more than one. But, in fact, they-objected_quite- as-strongly to subjecting the hypostases.to number in respect.to their_essence, that is, to-their-divinity,-as-the entire deity itself, notwithstand- ing that it has the distinctions eternally in itself. They were as zealous in opposing those abstract and exclusive representations of the Monas, which reduced it to something finite, as against circumscribing the hypostases in a finite manner (aepiypad2). The consequence whereof plainly was, that the hypostases were approximated more nearly to the divine essence than was possible for Arianism, whilst at the same time, unlike Sabellianism, they did not represent the distinctions as affecting God merely in His relation to the world, or reduce them to mere activities, or, in the best case, to different modes of the divine existence, in the world. DEFECTS OF NICENE TRINITY. 327 It must of course be allowed, that the doctrine of the Trinity, as laid down even by the Nicene Fathers, leaves much. to be desired. In one point above all, to wit, that the Father is represented, not merely as the fonieal commencement of the trinitarian process, but not seldom flee, as the root and source of all deity and identified with the Monas. He thus acquires a predominance which necessarily involves the subordination of the Son-and Spirit. But it would be a gross misapprehension of the spirit of the Church during the fourth century, to sup- pose that the subordination of Aan Son and Spirit therein in- volved, was distinctly intended; above all, to maintain that it 132° ine one essential determination, in comparison with which all other determinations must withdraw to the background ” (Baur 1. c. p. 468). Inasmuch as these teachers of the Church, on the contrary, uniformly resisted everything of an Arian character, and plainly gave decided prominence to the idea that Son and Spirit are of like substance, like honour, like glory, and coeternal with the Father, and deny that they lack any excellence possessed by the Father; inasmuch, further, as they even go so far as to lay down the principle, that the causal relation between Father and Son does not involve the subordination of the Son under the Father, that the Son is as far exalted above originated things as the Father; and make the proviso, that if the causal relation imply that the cause lies outside of the effect, the idea of causality is altogether inappli- cable to the Son (compare Basil. c. Eun. 1, 715, D.) ; and, lastly, when we find that the teachers of the Church in general maintain, that that which distinguishes one hypostasis from the rest (that, therefore, which is peculiar to it, but not to the others), cannot be subsumed under the category of having (é&is, Haben), and of deprivation (arépyats), that it implies no superiority, but merely signifies the peculiar being, which in all three is of like dignity, ad also equally divine; the afore-mentioned~predomi- nance given. to the Father as the Monas, cannot be regarded.as penconal: but simply as an unyanquished remnant of the ideas =a prevailed during the third.century. The historian, therefore, if he is minded not to mistake the living pulse of the entire dogmatical movement, must at this point take pains to recognise the true nature of the task reserved for the next period: and which demanded the complete separation of the 328 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. old, heterogeneous elements. That the complete equalization of the hypostases was, and continued to be, the goal of the collective efforts of the Church, is evident, not merely from the course pursued by the doctrine of the Trinity, during which, by means of the idea of the wepyywpyous of the persons in each other, on the one hand, and in the Latin Church, by the doctrine of the procession of the Spirit, not only out of the ¥ather, but also out of the Son, on the other hand, the object aimed at was ever more completely attained ; but, especially during the fourth century, from the circumstance, that the subordinatian consequence undoubtedly involved in that prin- ciple was in no instance drawn, whilst, at the same time, the whole of the view otherwise entertained and clearly indicated, expressly stood in the way of the drawing of such a conse- quence. That position, therefore, was a remnant of the old subordinatian inheritance handed down from the third century, the influence of which was already broken by the development given to the true, permanent idea of the equality of essence which had been received as an inheritance from the primitive Church. We can also clearly see, what it is that prolonged the existence and vitality of that principle,—to wit, its apolo- getic significance. It was intended, namely, to show that, not- withstanding the triplicity of persons, the unity 1s preserved, inasmuch as the Son and the Spirit both proceed from, and return to, the one Father. But the moment this proof is found insufficient, and a more satisfactory one is discovered (as, for example, the idea of the immanence of the persons in each other), we shall find the teachers of the Church readily reject- ing the one and embracing the other; and the more so, as they were not in the habit of considering the Father to comprise the entire deity within Himself, and therefore did not designate Him the source of all divinity, in the sense of the other hypo- stases being merely parts of Him, the whole (compare Eusebius) ; ——and this must certainly have been their meaning, had they aimed at saving the unity of God, by representing Him as the source of all deity. Two things, however, must not be_over- looked in connection herewith :—(1) ‘The more recent of the teachers referred to already arrived at the principle,—The_ Father is not the source and root of the entire deity; the.Son. and Spirit derive merely their hypostases, not their deity, from DEFECTS OF NICENE TRINITY. 329 the Father; for the essence is one and the same in all. Deity is the element coeternally possessed in common by the three persons. (2) The Church teachers ofthe period now under consideration say, indeed, that no one of the persons can be cogitated apart. from ee other, that each suggests the other, ae that the idea of God. cannot..be perfectly grasped, save under the form-of-a-Trinity. But even supposing, as this im- plies, that the three stand in precisely the same relation to the divine essence, the question still arises, How_are they related to each other,.so far as they are distinguished from each other, or are hypostatical? And here they were justified in taking the Father as their point of departure, to prevent the three bee regarded as three effulgurations, completely independent of any other, and only Sonnred a the common divine essence from which they proceed. For, on the latter supposition, we should have three atoms, or individuals, without inner connec- tion; and the unity would either be reduced to a nominalistic generic idea, or the divine essence, lying at the basis, must be allowed the independence which it has in Tetradism. In this respect, therefore, the teachers of the Church were quite right in describing the Father as the motive principle and starting- point of the process, out of which the hypostases arose. For, logically viewed, the Father must continue the first hypostasis. The only thing, therefore, for which they deserve blame, is that in oui eeaes to the propositions which say,—Not the Father by. Himself, but the Trinity, is the entire God; they occasion- ally constitute the Father the Monas. This latter fault, how- ever, is partially to be excused, on the ground that they never say,—The Father by Himself is the Monas; their meaning rather is,—The Father is the Monas, so far as He is conceived in His actuality and not as an abstract idea, or, so far as He must be conceived as the principle and starting-point of the hypostatical process; in other words, so far as He does not exclude the two other hypostases from the deity, but so com- prises them in Himself that He would not Himself be the Father if He had not eternally possessed the Son and been the principle of the Spirit. Thecsecond defect is, that these teachers determine rather negatively than positively what hypostasis is. What their posi- tive determination would be, may be best ascertained by con- 330 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. sidering the claim they make relatively to Christology. Their fundamental presupposition undoubtedly was, that God in Christ was not merely a motive power, nor a mere activity, but a con- scious, permanent mode of existence of the deity, distinct.from that of the Father.. They felt, therefore, that in the incarnation the Most High God Himself was present among men, and that He had not withheld the highest, but had communicated Him- self without reserve to hurianite’ in Christ. But Patripassianism having been found worthy of repudiation, the question naturally suggested itself,How shall we determine the nature of the distinction between the God who became man and the God who did not become man, without destroying the unity of God, on the one hand, or interfermg with Christology, on. the other ? Neither the Gonne of Mace nor the (Cras Fathers of the century now under review, Prat rl answered this question. Instead, then, of complaining, as some do,‘ that a clear and distinct answer to the question,—What is the true conception of hypostasis ? and just to pay the tribute of acknowledgment due to the efforts of these “reat”? men, as they are allowed to be; in doing which, we should perhaps, nay, after what has been ad- vanced above, must discover, that they did their full share towards the accomplishment of the task which they actually did and were necessitated to set for themselves. (Note 54.) Through their labours the pantheistic and deistic conception cf God, or the heathenish and Jewish error, was excluded ; and fh point established, relatively to the divine aspect of the Per- son of Christ, which it was necessary to take for granted, if the divine and human were to be conceived as having attained to absolute union in Christ :—this aim, moreover, they consistently and consciously kept in view, in opposition alike to Heathenism and Judaism (compare Gregory of Nyssa, Cat. M. T. 2, 43 ff. ; Gregory Nazianzen, Or. 33, and the Homily in Athanasius adv. Sabell. Gregales, which may be read also in Basilius, Opp. T. 1, 518 ff.). However decidedly they testify, as with one voice, that in the nature of God there are unsearchable depths, they are equally decided in asserting the possibility of, and in endeavouring to attain to, a knowledge of God through the medium of His revelation; and the charge brought against 1 See Baur 1. c. 441-470. DEFECTS OF NICENE TRINITY. 33) them, of taking their refuge in a Platonic, or, more precisely, a Neo-Platonic ignorance of God, is utterly baseless. That God is triune is not merely to be believed, but to be known (com- pare Gregory Nazianzen’s IIpos Evaypuov epi Georntos, ed. Basil. p. 193). But this knowledge must flow forth, in the first instance, from religious experience, through the medium of the Holy Scriptures, They expressly declare it to be both pos- sible and necessary, that in relation to the cogitation of God as a Trinity, faith should become gnosis. Only the “ How ?”’ of the procession of the Son and the Spirit is unsearchable ; although, even in relation to this point, they maintained that a knowledge becomes every day more possible, in that we are able to say what the process is not; and such a negative explanation implies a certain positive insight. On the other hand, too, they deserve all praise for the sobriety and moderation which they display, and which give the lie to the opposite reproach, fre- quently brought against them, of being too much given to formularizing and dogmatizing. The spirit of modesty just alluded to prevented them from treating as settled that which was still unsettled, impelled them to continue their investiga- tions into the true idea of hypostasis, and to give free play to all attempts to further a solution, provided only, on the one hand, the interest of Christology were kept in sight, and, on the other hand, that neither mixture nor separation, neither Sabellianism nor Arianism (or Tritheism), were favoured and aided. In fact, we have found also among the Nicene Fathers, considerable differences in this respect, which both indicate that the field still left open was very wide, and show that these first post-Nicene teachers at once earnestly set about the work left them to perform,—the work, to wit, of determining the precise nature of hypostasis and its relation to unity. on the one hand, and to other hypostases, on the other. 332 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. SECTION If. CHRISTOLOGICAL MOVEMENTS CHAPTER FIRST. THE CHRISTOLOGY OF THE CHURCH TEACHERS PRIOR TO APOLLINARIS. WE have already had frequent occasion to remark, how the activity of the Church in connection with Christology abated during the century to which may be given the title of the Irmitarian Century. Indeed, the Christian conception of God was to furnish the groundwork for the construction of a doc- trie of the Person of Christ. How this foundation was laid, we have described in the preceding section. We should be very greatly mistaken, however, if we were to suppose that Christological labours had meanwhile been totally suspended : on the contrary, in the case of the thinkers of the Church, Christology was the perennial motive of their trinitarian efforts. These inquiries, however, took precisely the form which they alone could take, and which corresponded to the position held by Christology as the mainspring of the trinitarian movement; they related, to wit, not to the individual momenta of the Per- son of Christ in their relation to, and movement towards, each other; nor to the question, What are the fundamental elements of this person? but the Person of Christ, in its entirety, was the object of the attention of the Church. What we have in the first instance to recount is not, points which became matter of clear consciousness, in consequence of the solicitations of heretics ; not the settlement and defence of a single point, in opposition to single attacks; not the analysis of the momenta of CHRISTOLOGY PRIOR TO APOLLINARIS. 333 Christology as a whole; but the utterances which proceeded from the Church concerning the Person of Christ, when it gave free and unreserved expression to the impression once and con- stantly made upon it by this person in its entirety. The grand total image of the living Person of the God-man, who includes heaven and earth in Himself,’ hovered before the eyes of the greatest teachers of the Church, especially in flourishing periods, as, for example, in the time of Irenzus and Tertullian, or at the epoch now under consideration, when the Christian mind gathered up its powers for a full or new exercise on the work set before it. They were not able, it is true, to set forth the entire fulness of that image in a scientific form; but still we have numerous scattered utterances of theirs, which indicate its nature, and show that the fixed logical forms which they adopted did but faintly reveal the substance that occupied their hearts and minds—a substance which science could only slowly, and perhaps by long roundabout methods, reproduce. As the im- mediate and original outflow of the Christian mind, this total image of the living Person of Christ deserves special considera- tion in the present connection ; especially as it throws the true light on the attempts made during the following period, to con- struct the unity of the person on the basis of two distinct natures. For, on the one hand, it will show us clearly that the existence of this mystical intuition of the Person of Christ, in which the conjunction of the divine and human aspects to per- sonal unity is immediately posited and intentionally anticipated by faith, does not render unnecessary, but rather requires, that full justice be done to the distinctions between the two aspects, in order that an unity may be arrived at based on the recogni- tion and conciliation of the distinctions. It further, also, shows us, that even when the work of discrimination was carried too far, or scientific thought remained entangled in the distinctions drawn, the total Christological possession of, at all events, the better teachers of the Church was not absorbed by such imper- fect attempts; on the contrary, that unity of the person or con- junction of the widely separated distinctions, which they had not been able scientifically to establish, was certified to them in the sphere of faith by the immediate intuition of the image of Christ 1 yeQ@upoi, compare the Homil. on the Theophan. in the Opp. Greg. Thaum. ; dvaxcParciodvras, after Paul. 334 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. in its totality. That immediate intuition accompanied their mind in its dialectic activity; and as it could not be replaced, so neither was it supplanted, by the scientific process. This primitive Christian intuition of the Person of Christ, of which we discover frequent traces even in the New Testament, and which is of the highest significance relatively to His redemp- tive work, to baptism, to the Eucharist, and to the right view of the idea of the Christian Church, we have found repeatedly ex- pressed, in the most fully developed form, however, by Ignatius and the Ep. ad Diognet., by Ireneeus and Tertullian. ‘he same remark holds good of the Fathers of the third century also, as we have seen, for example, in the case of Hippolytus, Cyprian, and others. Origen especially lived in it, though it took in his mind a distinct and peculiar character. The First-born of all creation, says he, the noblest nature, is designated King and Son of the King; the man whom He assumed, was formed by Him in righteousness, and so they are one. For the Redeemer made of two one, in that He united the first fruits of both in Himself.? If God has made Him, who knew no sin, sin for us, we can no longer say that. there was no darkness in Him (as there is none in the Father). But He took our weakness upon Himself, our sin did He bear; and the sickness of the soul, the pains of the hidden man of the heart, lay upon Him. On their account, in order to carry them away, He confessed that His soul was troubled and shaken, and, accord- ing to Zechariah, put on unclean garments. Because He took upon Himself the sins of the people which believeth in Hin, therefore saith He so frequently, as though speaking in our name,— The account of my sins is far from salvation; Thou knowest my folly, and my sins are not hidden before Thee.” No one can suppose that we thus blaspheme against the Anointed 1 See Vol. i; 103 ff., 259 f., 818, 816 fl. ; 11. 65 fi. 96 ff." 101aE 2 Ad Rom.i. 5. Origen designates the Logos ‘‘ promiscue” Only-be- gotten and First-born. During the Arian controversy (compare Ath. c. Ar. or. 2, 663), these ideas were more precisely defined as follows: ‘‘ Only- begotten” refers to the eternity and singularity of His Sonship; whereas ‘‘ First-born” has reference also to the many brethren, whom He does not lack notwithstanding His own pre-eminence, nay more, whom He gains through it. The designations, therefore, are taken as mutually comple- mentary. The former is the absolute expression for Christ; the latter, the relative, which refers back to the former. eet” ew oe) ee ORIGEN’S TOTAL IMAGE OF CHRIST. 335 of God. For as the Father alone has immortality, whereas the Lord took our death upon Himself, out of pure love to men, we can only say of the Father, “ In Him is no darkness.” If God has made Him, who knew no sin, sin for us, we cannot say of Him, “In Him is no darkness.” For Christ, in His love for men, took our darknesses upon Himself, in order that by His power He might kill our death, and dissipate the darkness of our soul, as Isaiah saith, “ The people which sat in darkness, hath seen a creat light (rod Kupiov hua Sia prrabpwriav Gavarov TOV UTEP HOV aveiknpotos,—ep avTOV TAS 1)LOV TKOTIAS avadedeyLevor, etc. In Joh. T. ii. 21). His flesh also is termed “sin;” for He came in the form of sinful flesh. It is called sin, because it is a sacrifice for sin; through this sacrifice, which is termed sin, He has put sin to flight and destroyed it (ad Rom. iv. 12 ; T. iv. 589). Life is stronger than death ; righteousness is stronger than sin; the grace is greater than the mischief. For the grace of Christ is more richly and widely poured out than the death of Adam ; seeing that it has not merely driven away death, but brought life to dominion ; nay more, it has even brought us to dominion through Christ (ad Rom. v. 2). He is the tree of life, into whom we must be implanted. His death becomes the tree of life to us. In this way we can imitate Him in holiness. And the Church is His body (in Joh. T. x. 23, 27) ; so that the resurrection of Christ embraces the mystery of the resurrection of the entire body of Christ (in Joh. T. i. 34, x. 20). ‘This is the deeper reason why, in all the principal momenta of the history of Christ, Origen sees our history, the history of in- dividuals or of the Church. In this aspect, his allegorical in- terpretation is not a play with coincidences ; Christ he viewed, not as a naked symbol, but as the principle of the process through which the Church must pass in imitation of its Head. For this reason, the thought recurs in the greatest variety of ex- pressions,—His history is our history, and_our history is His. The anointing of the Son, the union of the Spirit and of man in Him, denotes the marriage, the commingling, of the believing soul with the Holy Ghost (in Joh. T.i. 30). He gives a similar turn to our crucifixion with Christ (in Joh. T. i. 34), and to the sufferings of believers (ibid., and in Jerem. Hom 14, @:t8312): In every martyr, Christ is condemned. For if a Christian is condemned, not because of a sin, but because he 1s a Christian, 336 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. Christ is condemned in him. Throughout the whole earth, Christ is constantly suffering from unbelievers and sceptics, who divide Him in sunder. It is foolish to suppose that Christ has been only once scourged, by Pilate. As often as unbelievers persecute Christians, Christ presents His back to the smiters. When Paul, in 1 Cor. xv. 28, speaks of the subjection of the Son under the Father, he shows us that all that he means thereby is, the subjection of believers, whom He comprises in Himself.! Because Christ is the life in each, the life multiplies itself ; for Christ is found in every saint, and for the sake of the one Christ there are born many christs, His imitators, formed after H im, ' who is the image of God (Ava yap tov év éxdot@ Xpuorov dvta Sony mrnOvvovras ai Soai—otovel yap kal’ &caorov dytov Xptartos eupioKetat, Kal yivovtat du Tov eva Xpictov woAXol Xpttrol, ot exeivot pyuntal Kal Kat adbrov, ecxdva dvTa Ocod ELoppwpevor 3 in Joh. T. vi. 3). Between this birth of Christians from God, which he conceived to be mediated by Christ, and the birth of the Son from the Father, he finds also a resemblance (in Jerem. Hom. ix. 4). As the Father did not generate the Son once for all, and then send Him forth from Himself, ceasing therewith any longer to generate, but begets Him eternally ; so also, if thou hast the spirit of sonship, God begets thee continually in Him, in every work and every thought ; and thus begotten, thou becomest a continually begotten son of God in Christ Jesus. That which gives the humanity of Christ this universal sig- nificance, is simply and solely the Logos, who united Himself with it in vital unity. The Logos illuminates everything, even the ideal world, and the logical souls in the real world Gn Joh. T. i. 24). As wisdom, He is the beginning and the end; in Him is included the idea of the entire world, so far as He is wisdom in God (i. 22, 34). He is the light for all men and all rational beings, the source of all pure life (1. 28, 29). Christ, the only-begotten One, is all in all, beginning and end. As the 1 II. dex. L. iii, 5, 6: Quid non solum regnandi, verum etiam obedi- endi venerat reparare disciplinam, in semet ipso prius complens, quod ab aliis volebat impleri, iccirco non solum ad mortem crucis Patri obediens factus est, verum etiam in consummatione seculi in semet ipso complectens omnes, quos subjicit Patri, et qui per eum veniunt ad salutem, cum ipsis et in ipsis quoque subjectus dicitur Patri: dum omnia in ipso constant, et ipse est caput omnium, et in ipso est salus et salutem consequentium plenitudo. Compare above, pp. 134-138 a ae oe ee . “tee et, Meet e — ORIGEN’S TOTAL IMAGE OF CHRIST aay d beginning, He is in the man whom He assuined ; as the end, iz the last of the saints. Or otherwise put,—Even in those who are in the middle (between the beginning and the end of the world) is He: as the beginning in Adam; as the end in the Son of man, the second and last Adam (i.. 34). Christ is Alpha and Omega. No one knows the Father save through Him, no one can stand connected with the Father save through Him. And perhaps, as in the temple the steps were many which led to the sanctuary, so is the First-born of God all steps to us; as reckoning downwards, He is the first and the second, so also the last. His humanity is the first and lowest step. Beginning with it, we pass on through the entire series of steps, so that we ascend through Him, who is also angel and the rest of the powers. Above all, however, He must be to us the Lamb, which takes away our sins (in Joh. xix. 1). In a much diviner way than Paul He became all things to all, passing through all stages, from the angels down to the beings in the néther world, in order to win all. To the angels He became an angel, to men aman. If there exist letters of God, after the reading of which, the saints say that they have read in the tables of heaven, elements through which heavenly things can be read, these are the ideas, which are, as it were, broken into small fragments, to wit, into the Alpha and the following letters to Omega, which is the Son of God. Again, regarded from another point of view, the same Son is as Logos, simultaneously, both beginning and end (in Joh. T. i. 34). In passages like that just adduced, and in similar ones, the distinction between the first and second creation is not always thoroughly maintained. Sometimes the Logos is represented as the soul of the world, which is broken up into a plurality of beings (Novos). This by itself would not sufficiently explain why che Logos should become man, angel, and so forth; for in a certain sense He became man and angel by the creation of these beings: why, then, was a further special act of union with them necessary ? From our previous exposition of Origen’s system, however, we know that he considered the participation in the Logos involved in the creation to. have been but imper- fect, so far as free beings were brought into existence, to whom an abid ng and indissoluble connection with the Jogos was primarily a task to be accomplished. This is the point at which COLOR ERE x 338 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. his theory, that the Logos must take His place in history, and undergo a regular process of development on behalf of all yational creatures, finds application. He must become all rational beings, in order that, as one of them, He may be near to all, may be laid hold of by them as the atoning principle in its totality, and may lead them to the Father. He zs able to assume all, because all are created by Him; and in them all is but one generic substance of different grades, for there is but one Logos. For this reason, He pervades all the genera of beings as different stages of the Noyxov. But believing as he did, that all rational beings are, as such, inwardly connected with the Logos, and that He, as their common principle of unity, assumed them all, and exhibited all in Himself in their perfection, the way was paved to his doctrine of the aoxara- otaots of all things (c. Cels. 8,12). He set forth all in their verfection by becoming all; but He returned out of them to Himself, by deifying them in Himself. As He passed through all stages, even so must we, strengthened by His power, and, jn imitation of His example, advance from stage to stage, till ve become one spirit with Him. In this aspect also, therefore, Origen’s Christology may be said to have a somewhat Docetical character. Not because of the universality lent to his view of redemption, by his doctrine of the assumption of all classes of beings; for, as we have re- marked, he looked upon angels, not as a different genus of beings, but merely as a different grade of one and the same logical genus. Nor because the historical life of the Logos was blended with and dissipated into His life in eternity, by the doctrine of His assumption of all beings; for He was actually of opinion, that the Logos showed Himself to angels as an angel, and as a man to men, and that men, at a higher stage, will become angels, in consequence of the Logos having first become man for them. Finally, the Docetical element does not he in his notion, that whilst the Logos was.man, He was aiso the light and vital principle of the entire world; for Origen appears to have connected the two things as follows,—the soul of Christ heing indissolubly united with, and fired throughout by, the Logos, was one spirit with Him, and the centre whence He, unhindered by body and space, was universally active. We have seen above, that he regarded the sacrifice of Christ on the ORIGEN AND ATHANASIUS. 339 cross as the sacrifice offered in the centre of the werld on be- nalf of the entire world; and to those who expressed surprise that the Pneuma (that is, the Logos) should be sent into a corner, instead of filling all bodies in the entire world, he re- plied,—“ We have enough with one sun; it is for all. This Anointed One made many anointed; Christ is the head; He and the Church are one body. If thou desirest to see many bodies full of the Divine Spirit, look at the Church (c. Cels. 5, 78, 79).” The Docetical element rather consists in his denying to hte humanity of Christ constitutive and permanent. signifi- cance in itself. (for example, ad Rom. i. 6, compare TS pp. 218, 214), even as he denied it to the feiss forms which he Sate ; attributing to them, on the contrary, a merely peda- gogical or anagogical significance, as guides to the pure and needs deity. Our perfection, too, will be the termination of our personal existence; and thus the system which made so strictly ethical a beginning, ends by being physical. The utmost that remains is, that a new world may arise through a new apostasy; which, however, must be represented as running through the same course, unless the ideas, respectively, of God and the mera) are stripped of their mutually exclusive character.’ How important was the position held by that image of Christ in His totality, in the system of Athanasius, prior to the Arian controversy, we have seen above (pp. 249 ff.). Arianism necessarily felt inwardly estranged from it; all that it sought in Christ was a teacher and pattern of virtue. Only men like Kusebius of Czesarea endeavoured to retain their hold on it; in the sense, however, that the Logos in and by Himself, and not first the Logos incarnate, or the God-man, was the First-born of creation, the Head of humanity and of the world (see above, pp. 221 ff.). When the office of mediator or substitute for humanity is conferred on a creature, such as the one proposca ' The ideas of Irengeus and Tertullian, which belong to this connecticr, have been treated above. The important thought, that Christ was the archetype even for the creation of Adam, appears to have been contained also in Methodius’ Suuxcoiwy rapdevixcv, where he remarked,—i-o/noev o Oso¢ tov dvdpwmrov nar eindve duoicy tis eixdvos ebtov, Tour tots xad sindve Xpiorod, The word Xpsres might refer, it is true, merely to the Son of God in Himself, for Methodius goes on to say,—Adrés yap gor 70 drat- YAO ~alO KdpuxTHp THS UTooTACEHC a’rov. Compare Gregory of Nyssa wepl natacx. &vboooror, c. 16. 340 ¥IRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. bv Arianism, it becomes ethnic and unethical; for only on the ground of an act of deification, and of the curtailment both of our personality and of the task assigned to us, can a mere crea- ture be represented as taking our place, and as holding the position of our representative before God. In the aioe di- rected against Arianism, Athanasius constantly recurs to this idea, wieneect his object is to confront the entire fulness and weight of true Christianity with the scanty view of it taken by Arianism. It was that intuitional image of the Redeemer in His totality that marked out for cies during all his controversies, the direction which he ought to pursue; like a never-erring compass, it enabled him to steer safely between heresies wearing the appearance of the full truth, like those of Marcellus and Apollinaris. He employed it against Arianism, not merely when his purpose was to establish the Christian idea of atonement, in opposition to the false deification of man, on the one hand, and his false humiliation and separation from God, on the other; but both he and his friends used the idea frmotpally3 in order to turn aside Arian objections, which de- duced the lowness of Christ’s higher nature from the lowness of the declarations concerning Him contained in the New Tes- tament. To a whole series of passages of this nature in the New Testament they applied the canon,—When Christ was troubled unto death, and cried out, “ My God, my God, why nast Thou forsaken me?” He spalien in our name, bechu seule naa put himself into our place, and had taken upon Himself our guilt and abasement.t Against Sabellianism they aroued, on the basis of this intuition of theirs, that Christianity was not a mere transitory theophany, or an évépyeca of God; but that its aim was the perfection of humanity. Now the perfec- 1 Athan. c. Ar. i. 48; Greg. Naz. or. 29, 18: ‘‘ Count up, unthankful ynan, the words, ‘My God and your God,’ ‘greater,’ ‘ created,’ ‘made,’ ‘sanctified ’ ‘servant,’ ‘obedience,’ ‘He learned,’ ‘ He was commissioned, ‘he was sent,’ ‘Of myself I can do, speak, judge, give, will nothing.’ Add tnereto His ignorance, His subjection, His prayer, His questions, His pro- gress, His being perfected. Add, further, His sleeping, being hungry and weary, His weeping, His trembling and shuddering. Perhaps thou wilt reproach Him also (O Arian) with His death and His cross.” Let the answer serve: ‘Ev! xsQaralia rad wc orbnrdrepe wacoays tH Jeoryti xml ri, xpertrore Quasi waday nol cojmaros, ra 0 Tamewarepe TO CUVbETY. nel TH Osa ba xebwosres re ncel capxadévri, xal avOpwmicbsyes. Compare 30, 1, 21. ATHANASIUS’ TOTAL IMAGE OF CHRIST 341 tion of humanity requires that it be constituted the Church, the body of the Lord, of which He is the Head.’ How, in the last place, Apollinarism was combated by the aid of this image, we shall shortly see. Let us now specify a few of the more important passages. In becoming a man Himself, says Athanasius repeatedly, the eternal Son constituted mankind sons and gods; for He set forth in Himself, in the first instance, a man who was God, and now He draws us into fellowship with Him (viozroince, Kat éGeo- moinoe TOs avOpwTrous yevomevos adTos dvOpwrros, c. Ar. or. 1, 38).? Neither the Logos was exalted by becoming man and displaying virtue, as the Arians suppose, nor was He humbled (jrAaTToON) by the assumption of a body; but deification be- came the portion of the body which He assumed (c. Ar. 1, 40, LON As humanity is worshipped in Him, the heavenly powers can no longer wonder when they see us, who wear His nature, entering into heaven (c. 42). His humiliation is a fact; but it produced no change in Him. For not physical defect, but the riches of His love, was the cause of His humiliation, and there- fore He remained the same, though we were savingly altered (c. Ar. or. 1, 48). He first sanctified Himself in order that He might sanctify us all. ‘I, the Logos of the Father, give even the spirit to Myself, the Incarnate One, and thus sanctify Myself, the Incarnate One, in order that all may be at once sanctified in Me, who am the truth.” Accordingly, He gives as God; He receives as man; but in His person we have made a beginning of receiving. From Him streams forth the Spirit as a precious ointment over tne whole of humanity (or. c. Ar. 1, 46-48). C. Ar. 4, 33 :—“ He wrapped Himself in our first fruits, and mar- ried Himself therewith. Taking this perishing man into Him self, He renews him: by a stable renewal unto eternal duration.” (Hvora. dirravbporas jpiv, Thy arapynv nov Tepiepevos, Kal tavtn avakpabels.—Ei towvy (tov avOpwrov) cabpwobévta 1 Compare c. Ar. 4,12, 25. The question with which we have to do, is not something epideictical, a rasd:2, but the éaqder«, which is contained in Christ for the individual and the Church. 2 Compare 39,1, 48. Of dvdpwmos eioiy ctpyiy Exovres TOV AnmBavery ty wire xal 00 cebrod* aire yap viv Asyoutvov civdpwmivus xplecbas, necis Eo (ED of tv aire xpicpeevos’ exesdy xal BarriComévov abrov gusis topev of ev aut BumrsCoucvor. 28, 34 342 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. els EauTov AaBomevos Tar avakawiter Sua THS BeBaias avtot avaveHcews Tpos Stamovnv atereUTHTOV Kal dia TODP EevovTas Ets Oevotépav avtov avdywov MEw—Tas olov Te—Tols atroaTONoLS— cuvaplOwely Tov TOV aToaTOAwY KUptov;) “The Word became flesh, in order that, as the Logos is Son, God might be termed our Father for the sake of the Son dwelling in us. Whoso, therefore, has not the Son in his heart, of him God cannot be termed the Father” (Ata rodto yap 6 Adyos yéyove oapé, ty’, ETELON O AGYOS €oTlY Vids, Sia TOV évolKodYTA ev Hiv ViOV NeyNTat Kal Hua Tatip.—OvdvxKodv oO év tuly vios Tov idioy TaTépa emI- KANOULEVOS KAL HuUdV AVTaV ToLee TaTépa KaretcOar. *Apénet @V OvK EoTLY Eis TAS Kapdias 0 Vids, TOUTwY OvdE TraTIpP 0 Oeds dv rex Gein, 4, 22). “ When the Spirit descended on Him in the Jordan, He descended upon us, whose body Christ bore. When He was washed in the Jordan, we were washed in and by Him (Evdnrov, dts Kal 7 eis adtov év TO Iopdavyn tod TVEVILATOS yevouevn KaO0d0s eis Huds Hv ywvomevn, ia TO hopety avToV TO HpweTepov THua.—T'od yap kupiov ws avOpwrrov Novopevoyv—nwets Huey of &€v ALTO Kal Tap avTod Aovopmevor, etc., 1,47). “ God calls men, who are created, sons, as though they had been be- gotten. As they are created natures, they can only become sons by receiving the Spirit of Him who is by nature and truly Son. He who was our Creator becomes our Father, from which it is clear that we are not by nature sons, but the Son who is in us. Nor is God by nature our Father, but the Father of the Word, which is in us. But the Father designates those sons in whom He sees His Son” (2, 59). “ Man united with a mere creature could not have been deified, nor could he have ven- tured to present himself to the Father, had not Christ been the _ essential Word of God. As man, He is become the beginning of the new creation (adpyn xawns Kticews); for He is the man created for us. For this reason, this union of the divine and human (cuvvady)) took place in Him, in order that, with that which is by nature divine, He might unite that which is by na- ture human, and the salvation and deification of the human (Georroinots) might be firmly established” (2, 70). “ As a wise builder does not merely think how to build a house, but also arranges it so that it can be restored if it should receive damage, so the basis of our renewal was laid in Christ ere we ewisted, in order that we might be created again in Him” (2, 77). ‘This ATHANASIUS’ TOTAL IMAGE OF CHRIST. 343 passage appears to represent the connection of our nature with Christ as so essential, that it must.have subsisted even if sin had not entered the world.! “ We must not be surprised, therefore, to find Christ speaking of His image (tv7r0s), which is in us, as of Himself; for when Saul persecuted the Church, in which was His image and likeness, He said, as though He Himself were the object of the persecution,—Saul, Saul, why perse cutest thou Me?” Similar also is the import of the passage, Prov. viii. 22:—He speaks of the creation as of Himself. After explaining in c. Ar. or. 3, 32 f. that the grand thing is, that whatever sufferings are undergone, or works are performed, by a man in Christ, do not concern this man alone, but the Logos also, who makes all things His own (olxevo?, idvorovet ), he goes on to say,—Inasmuch as the flesh was born of the Vir- gin (Mapla OcorcKos), He Himself was said to have been born, who is the principle of the birth of others, namely, that He might transfer our birth to Himself, and thus obtain the mas- tery over the principle of death in us.” He regarded the work of redemption, therefore, as already begun with the act of incar- nation ; the entire finitude to which He subjected Himself, and ‘of which that act formed the beginning, finds its explanation, “hot in His nature, but in His substitutionary love. (Note 55.) “This leads us to notice a particular class of passages whicn relate to the sufferings of Christ. (Note 56.) ©. Ar. 1, 41: “ As man He endured death for us, that so He might present Himself to the Father for us. As He died for us, so also has He been exalted on our behalf, in order that, like as we all died in the death of Christ, even so we might all be unutterably exalted in Him.” “He takes our sufferings upon Himself and 1 His meaning can, however, also be,—The posstbilety of the incarnation was grounded in the creation itself, because the Logos or the Wisdom of God was informed in the world (compare c. 79); but still merely typicaity, in comparison with the archetype, wisdom itself. 2 "Tye civ quay sis &avrdy meradn vyéveosy, nal wnneTh OS YR LoUN Ovres 26 viv arinbamcy, AAW OS TH EE ovporvod Advyou suvaQbévres cis odpavovs vada uey rap avtov. Ovxovy svt wal Te brrw wadn Tov ooparos ovn areinoTas sig joeuroy werednusy’ lvoe “ennets Os avOpaTrol, &AA dic 10108 TOU Acyou THs ehavioY Cons wsracyoper. THs yevissns nav nol maons THS capuixns dobeveias Ueto reBévru els tov rdvov (cf. 2, 69) eyespoedae dad ys, Avoslans THs O00 humerioy narepes, ete. Obdxérs as ynivis, BhA& Rosmoy noyobslons THs coeonos Aum Tex rod Ocov ndyor, 65 O8 Huss eyévero cae 344 FIRST PERIOD THIRD EPOCH. presents them to the Father, interceding for us, that they may be destroyed in Him” (4, 6). “Although not weak, He took upon Himself our weakness ; although not hungering, He hun- gered; He sacrifices that which is ours, in order to extinguish it; but instead of weaknesses (which were laid on Him, and through His bearing of them were extinguished), He receives gifts from God, of which those will become partakers who are united with Him” (c.7). “The death, which is termed His, the death of the Logos, was a ransom for the sins of men, and a death of death” (1, 45). “aden with guilt, the world lay under the condemnation of the law; but the Logos took the judgment (xpiua) up into Himself, and suffering in the flesh for all, He bestowed salvation on all” (compare Ar. or. 1, 51. 60 5! 25569): Similar expressions occur repeatedly in the works of the two Gregories and of Basilius. Gregory Nazianzen, after saying, in Hom. 30,—the rameworepas and avOpwrixorepar dovat which are recorded respecting Christ, are to be referred to the véos 8” nas avOpwros; he proceeds (c. 3),—7@ dvru éSovAevTE capKl Kab yeveoet Kai Tabect Tois tywerépors Sid tiv Apetépav €dev- Gepiav, kal maow ols céowxev b16 THs dwaptias KaTEyoLEVOLs. Ti d€ petlov avOpdrrov tarreworntt, ) Oc@ TAaKHvat Kal yeverOau Ocov €x tis piEews ; The Oela eixav is commingled with the covtixn poppy. On 1 Cor. xv. 28 (c. 5), he remarks,—Is He not now subject? Did He need, as God, to be subjected to God, like a rebel? "AN odtw cKdTeL, bt. Horep KaTdpa jnKovoe Ou ene, 0 THY wiv Nav Katapay, Kal dwaptia 6 aipov THY Gpaptiay ToD Koopov, Kab’ Addy dvti Tod TadaLod yiverat véos' oUTW Kal TO éuov dvuTrOTaKTOV EaUTOD TroLEtTAL Kepary TOU TavTos cwmatos. “Ews pev ody avurrdraxtos éy® Kal ota- ciwdys, avuTrOTAKTOS TO Kat’ e“e Kal 6 Xpiotos AeyeTa' Grav Se UTOTAYH avT@ Ta TavTa (iToTaynceTas Sé Kal TH éeriyvooer Kal TH MEeTATIOWNTEL), TOTE KAL ALTOS THY UTOTAYY TETANPOKE, ™ poo- ayov ee Tov cecwopévov. The Father subjects all things to the Son, the Son to the Father; the former by His decree, the latter by His deed. Thus, He who subjected it sets forth before God that which belongs to us, as subjected, by appropriating to Flimself that which belongs to us (&avrod rovotpevos TO *yere- oov). In like manner, he then further explains the desertion of Christ. He was not left in Himself. either by the Father or by ATHANASIUS. GREGORY NAZ R44 His own deity, but representea in Himself that which we ex- perience (€v éavt@ TuTot TO Huétepov). “Hyeis yap wer ot eyKATANEAELMLEVOL Kal Trapewpapévol TpOTEpoV, Elita VoV Tpoc- Ei\nupévoe Kal ceawopévor Tots TOD aTrabobs Tabeow. “QNaorep cal TV ahpoctynY HuaV Kal TO TANUMENES OiKELOUpEVOS TA EES &ia Tod Yradwod (Ps. xxii.) dyow. C.6:—So also must we understand the words, —“ He learnt obedience,” “He was heard.” As Logos, He was neither obedient nor disobedient, for He was the Lord; as 6€ dovdov pop pn ouycaraBatver TOUS opodovrots Kal Sovhaus, Kal tasted eh TO GANOTPLOP, OXOV Ev EAUTO epe Pepow ueTa TOV éuav, va év EavT@ SaTravicn TO xXElpov ws KNpoV Tp, ) @s aTpida yhs TALos, Kayo peTarxdBw Tov Eéxelvou Sia THD avyxpacw. The perfection will consist in our ceasing to be many, to be as we are now—for now we carry little or nothing of God in our movements and feelings; aAX drot Peoesdets, Orov cod yopntixol Kai povov, seeing that Christ is all in all (Gal. iii. 28). C.14:—He lives eternally, in order to intercede for us, as a man for my salvation. For He will continue united with the flesh which He has assumed, until He shall have deified me by the power of the incarnation (7H duvdpes THs avOpwrn- cews éue Oeov troinon). (Note 57.) 30, 21:—He is called (and is) Man, ody wa yopnOh povov Sia capatos capaci, adros ov av xwpnbels dia TO THS HUoEws AAnTTOV, GN iva Kat dylan 60 éavtod Tov avOpwrror, daTEp Gbun yevomevos TO TavTi pupa- watt, Kal Tpos EavTov Evocas TO KaTaKpiHev brov NUCH TOD KaTa- Kpluatos, TaVTAa UTép TaVT@V YyEvo“EVoS boa HpEis, TAHY TIS dpaptias, cua, Wyn, vods. Similar passages are contained in the Ep. ad Cledon. 1, 10, 14. A more complete conception of the mediation, of the repre- sentation of the entire race by the God-man, could not be framed than the one given here. Gregory, like Athanasius, did not derive it from the Logos as He is in Himself, but from the Logos incarnate; or from the fact that, as to His humanity, He became the vine-stock, the Head, cahichi as it is the first, so. also is it the principle of Ne holes whole in_ its eel powerful, all- mastering, and all-appropriating unity.’ 1 Athanasius did not hold Origen’s doctrine, that Christ became an angel tor angels; but still he believed that the incarnation had some sort of a reference to them also. Previously they had not seen the Logos; but since He has become man, they behold Him, c. @ av@pwros) of the subject to the ruler. The inner man becomes the kernel of the essence; the outward man, on the contrary, is something almost accidental, merely determined by the inner man. In Christ, the Logos assumed the place of the inner man.’ Whereas in Adam there was at the very utmost a vods, which was the servant of the cap&, and was compelled to make the flesh its content, but never passed out of its potential and impotent existence to actuality and dominion ; in Christ, on the contrary, because the Logos was His voids, there came an all-prevailing holy principle. No evil thought could arise in the inner being of Christ; however seductive the flesh might be, it found a ruler instead of a response, in the vods of Christ. But if Christ never had even an evil thought, and if His spirit never carried an evil thought into execution by means of the body, sin found no place in Him, however strongly the flesh, with its yuvy7, may have been opposed to the voos. or only that can be called evil in which the vods takes part (Athan. c. Ap. 1, 2).” From what has been advanced, we may see that Apollinaris might without hesitation have designated Christ a composite person (cvvGerov), after the example of the Church ;* save that he most decidedly protested against representing the factors as anything else but elements of the one, indivisible person: a com- position of the person out of two persons, to which the opinion of many of the teachers of the Church seemed to lead, he felt compelled entirely to repudiate. ‘T’o his mind also, the duality of the dicets,—if the dvcevs are to be conceived as complete,— was equivalent to a duality of wpdcwma. For if Christ’s hu- man nature hada vods and an avre£ovccov like other men from Adam, according to Apollinaris, it was an independent spo- 1 Ath. c. Apoll. 1, 2: “Avt? rod goadev gy quiv avOnamov vous éroupeeyios Ey Xpiot@" as yao opycvinw nevpnToroxynuati TO TeolsxovTse’ ov yelp oldvrs ys TéAciov cevOoumrov airov yévecbasr. Avo rércice Ev yévecdocs ov Ovvaret. 2 Compare Gregor. ]. c. p. 273, c. 55; Athan. c. Ap. 1, 2. 3 But still he only believed in ule Qvais ovyvberos. Compare A. Mai 7 301 f. 366 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. cwrov. For this reason, he deemed it necessary to refuse con- ceding even a duality of guceis. We see, therefore, that the favourite phrase of the later Synousiasts, pia dtvows Ocod royor cecapxwpévn, belonged to him also as to its sense. On the other hand, the preceding exposition shows that it could occasion him no difficulty to represent the humanity of Christ (cdua and ux) without vods) as something appropriated from Mary, to designate it érixtntov.! ‘To teacha conversion of the deity into humanity and its tpemrov, could by no means be his intention ; for the very obvious reason, that in order to avoid the tpemov, and to secure unalterable virtue and wisdom (dvowxn) for this man, he repre- sented the Logos as his vods. By doing so, he would unneces- sarily have posited the very thing which he had made every effort to avoid. Without giving up His being and undergoing conversion, God cannot become man, says he, save in the sense of His taking the place of the vods in the man (J esus).” The features hitherto mentioned, give us, however, but a superficial view of the theory of Apollinaris. Were that all, the charge of teaching a Christ who does not at all belong to our genus or class of beings, repeatedly brought against him by Gregory of Nyssa, would be, without any restriction, well founded. For in the case of men, the new divine principle con- nects itself with a vods which is human, although it may be merely an impotent or subject potence until the wvedua comes, which proceeds from Christ : in the case of Christ, on the con- trary, no trace whatever of vods would appear to have been de- rived from the humanity. On this supposition, the charge of positing as one, things which are two and cannot be one, brought by Apollinaris against the doctrine of the Church, would recoil upon himself; for the humanity which he attributes to Christ is something external to the personal centre therein, like a gar- ment, or like the house in which any one dwells. In point of fact, although he saw that to represent the human as the mere 1 Compare Gregor. 1. c. p. 230; p. 222, c. 29; p. 207, c. 34; p. 240, c. 44. 2 Tas, Onot, Oscs dvdparos yiveras, poy mera Banbels dao TOV civas Osos, sl Len vous gv dvoparw xertorn, |. c. c. 56, p. 277. Both Theodoret (see above, page 355, note) and Epiphanius discharge him of intending to teach such a conversion, as also of the doctrine of a heavenly c@oZ. Athanasius also (c. Apol. 1, 2) speaks of the different theories which had been worked out relatively to this point. APOLLINARIS. 367 doyxetov of the Logos did not exhaust the idea of the incarna- tion ; notwithstanding, further, that he frequently condemns the avOpwrros évGeos as a meagre representation, the propositions adduced above do not give us anything more than the notion of a God present in a human shell, unquestionably impersonal ; which is very far from an incarnation, and is rather a mere theophany. We must, however, at the same time, not forget to mention that the (clint teachers..of his day had not really ad- vanced a: any fur ther. ' They were even undecided whether the man Jesus, so far as a human soul is to be attributed to Him, ought not to be conceived as personal by Himself ; in which case, seeing that the Logos could only influence Jesus from without, either Christ must have been a double person (whose unity falls more into the subject and its presuppositions than into the object),” or God was not present in Him in any specific sense ; and consis- tently they ought to have gone back from the idea of a theophany as far as Ebionism (compare A. Mai, Coll. Nov. 7, 20 a). But what makes the theory of Apollinaris specially interest- ing, is the mode in which he overcomes this difficulty, in which he represents the composite person as an indivisible unity, and in which he aims at assigning to the Logos, as the substitute for the human voids, not an external and foreign position, but one which constitutes Him the truth of the humanity, and gives His incarnation its reality. “The humanity of Christ,” says he, “is that which is moved, the deity is the mover; the former, which was not a perfect living being by itself, in order that it might be a complete being, was compounded to an unity, was conjoined with its hegemoni- eal principle. It was united with, and made part of, the hege- monical principle from heaven, as to its passivity ; and it in turn received the divine, which was constituted its own, as to its 1 The less can we be surprised to find Apollinaris sometimes using also the simile—Humanity was the temple of the Logos. A. Mai, Coll. Nov. 7, 203. John does not say that the Logos became cap and Wuyy, édvveroy recip Sv0 vospa, noel bernrind ty TH dua norolnsiv, ive Loy TO ETEpov nate TOD Erépov ctvrioTpareunr es dice THs olxslas bernocws nal evepysias. The Logos, therefore, assumed, not a human soul, but merely Abraham’s seed, roy yap roy coaros Inoov vacv mpoditypabev 6 arpuxyos, nal dvous, xal a&beang tov Sorowavros vadc. 2 Deren Einheit schon mehr in das Subject und seine Voraussetzungen, als in das Object fallt. 368 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. activity. And so one living being was formed of the moved and the mover, and not two beings ; nor one being out of two complete, self-moved beings.”* In the Holy Scriptures, we find no separation whatever made between the Logos and His hu- manity ; but it is one being, one hypostasis, and one activity (Ovdeuia Svaipecis Tod Adyov Kai THs capKos adTod ev tals Geiaus ypadais: ad’ éore pla pious, ula bTrooTacts, wia évépyeta } A. Mai I. c. p. 73). A disciple of Apollinaris, Julian, writes to another, Polemon, as follows: °—“ Alone, and for the first time, did our father Apollinaris give utterance to, and clear up, the mystery hidden from all; to wit, that Christ became one. being and a composite nature, constituted out of the moveable and the immoveable ; which nature alone, moved by the one will, by one activity accomplished the miracles and the sufferings.” Apollinaris himself also was very well aware that the Church teachers of his time made too light of Christology, and he set for himself a higher and truer goal, in that he aimed at attain-. ing a living intuition of the unity of this person, and at an understanding of how the same subject can be designated both God and man; whereas (as he objects) the teachers of the Church contented themselves with merely saying what belonged to a complete humanity, and what to a complete deity, but troubled themselves little with the question of how the two can become one person. And yet this question was just the prin- cipal thing ; for unless it be answered, the incarnation cannot be shown to have really happened, and all previous labour has been in vain. They who, under the cloak of faith, take up a * A. Mai, Coll. Nov. 7, 301 :— Hadpé érepoxiunros oven ravras bd Tov xivovrros wal cryouTos, O%oIds Tore ay Eln TOUTO’ xal odw gyTSASs ODTH Caov &@ eauriis, &Ar eis ro yévecdars Coon evrenrss ovuredereeeyy TpOs EVOTNTA TH Nryepooving ovynrdev, xk cuvstedn mpos TO ovpayioy rysovinoy, eLorxeiwmbcion AUTO xara TO waenrixoy savrns, sal AcBovoe ro bciov oixsiwbev aUTN noted TO Evepyntinoy" ovra yelp sv Caov éx xivoumsvov xael xivytixod ov¥lotero, ucel ov U0, } gx O00 Té- Asian nal avroxivynrar’ didmep dvbomros nev Erepov ts Caov wpdg Osdv, xcel ov @sds, aAAG DOvAS Ocov, dev ovpaviay Tis Ovvaels, aoavTUS eyes caps 02, Ocod aap yevowevn, Cacy tors sta ravta cuvredcion cig wlav Quow. 7 A. Mail. c. p. 70: Ex xuvarinod nol céxivyrod, tvepyntinod ce nel 3ee- Ontixod, tov Xpiorcy shvecs, winy ovolev noel Qvow avvderov, vl re nal wovoy xivovpeevyy Osrnuwarh nal wie evepysla re re Oavmora reroinnsva nol ra rebn udvos xl rpuros 6 rarhp quay Aworwepies EC0syZero, +6 HEXOULLEVOY TAAL “xaetTaQor ioe: MvoTApioy APOLLINARIS. 369 position, with which the incarnation is as good as incompatible, are chargeable with entertaining ante-Christian views, either of an heathenish or of a Jewish kind. But such a position is taken up by those who teach two self-moving (adtoxivyta) beings, a twofold vods, a twofold will; for these can never be made one. (Note 68.) The human aspect of Christ must rather be so conceived, that it shall of itself point to the divine as its comple- ment, and not be represented as a perfect thing, standing side by side with another perfect thing. Consequently, the only satisfactory course is to represent the divine as the active ele- ment, the human as that which is moved by the hegemonic divine principle, not as moving itself. In this way, he consi- dered, we can understand that the two together first constituted the one person. For that which is moved presupposes, and of itself suggests, that which moves; and, on the other hand, the divine that moves would continue shut up in itself, a lifeless principle, if it did not display its motive power on something that is moved; indeed, without an object moved, the Logos would have no organ by which to manifest Himself.t Mover and moved are correlative ideas : a mover is inconceivable with- out a moved ; and vice vers4, a moved is inconceivable without a mover; and so, deity and humanity, as belonging in this re- spect inwardly to each other, combined to constitute one actual, indivisible divine-human life. Apollinaris, however, endeavoured to gain a still more com- plete conception of this personal unity. It is true, he_repre- sented the humanity of Christ, considered by itself and apart from the Unio, as an imperfect being ; but the deity which took the place of the soul and of the human vods, was not something alien to the human essence ; but the human essence, which tends, as it were, towards the perfection of itself in the form of a per- son, acquired it for its own: and, in like manner, the Logos made the human His own, constituted it a determination of Himself. As it is an imperfect description to say,—I have, or am the vehicle and bearer of a body or a soul, seeing that the connec- tion of the two with my essence is not accurately expressed till * He designates humanity an organ, A. Mai 1. c. 302, and p- 20 b. :— ” \ \ ae, ] me , re > ~ \ 2) ae ew ONS Opyavoy nal ro xosvory (1. xvod) pricey méQunev drorensiv ray bvéprescey bd cepxoc. (From his work against Diodorus.) VOL. It. 24 370 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. having is supplanted by being; Apollinaris felt that merely to speak of God bearing a man in Himself, or of God having | a man as His organ or Annee was not to do justice to. the idea of the incarnation. NaonEE his aim was to show that each of the two, humanity and deity, stood in the position of a deter- mination of the being of the other, both belonging together. In these genuinely speculative efforts, he was guided by the most important practical and religious interests. “ If there was in Christ one being and another being, unity and sameness of worship must be condemned; for the Creator and the creature, God and man, may not be worshipped after the like fashion. But the worship paid to Christ is one, and therefore God and man are included under one ‘and the same name. Consequently, we must not say that in Christ there were two essences, God and man; but one undivided being, constituted by God’s con- junction of Himself with an human body.t And as it would involve the division and destruction of the object of Christianity, the Person of Christ, to maintain that He ought to be worshipped as to one aspect of His being, and not as to the other (which we certainly must maintain, if the humanity were not in some way or other a momentum of the deity); so also would it involve the breaking up of the unity of His own consciousness (A. Mai 7, 301). ‘Adwvaror, TOV avTov Kal T poo KUUTOV éavTov eidévat Kal un. “Adtvarov dpa Tov adtov etvat Oedv Te Kal dvOpwmov é€ odo- KANpPOV, ANN €V {LovoTntl cuyKpatou praews Oeixis TETAPKWLEVNS. Further, the idea of the incarnation is weakened, and we fall back into long-repudiated. heresies, if we teach merely an activity (évepyeta) of the Logos in a complete man, instead of teach- ing that an human Slevin formed. part.of the Logos Himself. 1 A. Mar. 1. c. 16:—"Aaans xal darng ovolas play elvas nal roy aoriy mpooxvynow abéuiroy, TouTéotiy ToinToD xeel roimworos, Osod xal cevOparov. Mic 02 4 pooxtyqots Tov Xpiorod xal xara rodro ev rH Evl cvomars vosiras Osos nol dvbpwmros. Ovx dow &rrn xol arrn ovale Osds nal evOpumos? arred olor nar cvvbcow Ocod xpos coma evbporivov. Compare ibid. the fragment from the letter to Jovian. 2 A. Mail. c. p. 20:—Ted caQas eAnrer/ eve zoel Lah sada EnneeY- puypéve viv mary aveveovobal rives ET IMEKELPIKOO, wel cov && ovpavov dev- repov avOpumroy moxpordedopuevoy UrO THY aTOCTOAMY &x YS dv Bpucroy elvoes ofoy roy ~pdrspov BrcoOnuovar, ro avOpamrivoy Tov Aavyou eis Evepyssay THY EV civ Opormes wsrapaarnovtes. (From the work of Apollinaris entitled, xepi ris Oelas oap- XOTEOE, Cc. 12.) APOLLINARIS. ayilé F inally—and this he deemed of chief importance—a perfect union of the divine and human appeared to him indispensably necessar y to the accomplishment of the redemptive work of Christ.1 Against the doctrine of the Church he brought the char ge of having merely human sufferings in the sufferings of Chia eras, that the death of a man could not be the death of death (Greg. Antirrhet. c. 51, pp. 263 ff.). Gregory saw Clearly enough the importance of the objection, and sought to show that the Logos was truly humbled and truly took part in sufferings ; but all he really succeeded in doing, was to repre- sent Christ as reckoning to Himself the sufferings which, strictly speaking, belonged solely to His humanity, on the ground of the ment belonging to His person. Apollinaris, on the contrary, maintained at he unity..of..the.Person..of..Christ..was.not secured, unless we can say,—Our God was.crucified, and man is Peed to the right hand.of God: the Son of Man was.from heaven, and the Son of God was born of a woman (Greg. Nyss. Antirrh. c.6; A. Mai 7, p. 73 :—Tovéaiou 76 cha cravpob&rtes (leg. oravpdcavtes) Ocdv éotavpwoav). And the work of unit- ing God and man is first accomplished when God puts Himself completely in the place of humanity, and man is exalted to God. But how does he bring the two together? We have already remarked, that whilst representing the humanity of Christ as neste apart from the incarnation, he refuses to allow that, on this ee the ee Sor in the Person of Civ expresses ¢ as Stern. TVvEd La In iret was freee TVEVLA, although divine (c. 27). Nay more, he says also, the divine mvedua or the Logos, which in Christ was human mvedua, was eternal, and _existed.before the incarnation. The Logos must eRorere have existed as man also, prior to the incarnation, and His deity was in itself man from “ke very beginning. Gregory took the words to mean, that Apollinaris held the flesh of Christ * Greg. Nyss. Antirrhet. p. 131 ff., c. 5. His entire aim in the Aoyo- ypePie on the incarnation is to show,—ré dyyrdy rod Movorysvovs viod ray eornra, xl ory! Ta dvOpwrivw ro wabos OsEacbat, AAR THY drodH nal dvar- Aolwroy Quow wpos wabous pustrovolayv &arroiwdyves.—C. 27: The doctrine of the Church allows Him who was crucified nothing divine in His own nature, not even the best, that is, tyvsiue. C. 26, p. 185; ¢. 54, p. 271. Si2 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. to be eternal; and inasmuch as he, notwithstanding, represented Mary as the mother of Christ, therefore, concludes Gregory, he must have conceived Mary also to be eternal. He posits coarse composite matter as eternal. But Apollinaris never taught this; nowhere did he assume an heavenly humanity in this sense. But he viewed the wvedua or the Logos in Christ as the eternal humanity ;' probably on the ground of His being the archetype of universal humanity. To him the Logos was ina God and archetypal man; and that in the sense of His having been eternally destined to become man, in an his torical form. The Logos thus revealed that iy had been latent in His nature from the very beginning.” It is possible that, in his mind, he connected therewith the Platonic doctrine of a Kdapos vonros, in which the archetypes (e/67) of all things are ideally or potentially contained, though as yet by no means possessed of phenomenal, external actuality ; hence also the in- carnation of the Logos. Of this tendency are undoubtedly the words attributed to him by Gregory, ovpdvidv tt capkos eidos advaTatTeL Tept TO Oeiov (c. 42, p. 234, compare c. 6); which, however, cannot by any means have been already the principle of the material element of the humanity of Christ, but merely the form or plastic power. At all events, regarding the Logos as he did, not as something foreign to, but as the truth of, the hu- manity itself, he was able to say,—The primal grounds of the incarnation lay, not in the Virgin,* but in the eternal Logos 1P. 149, c. 18:—Tlpourapyes, Qnaly, 6 &vbowros Xpisrs, ovx%, as Erépov Gyros weep avToy TOU TvEV[LaTOS, TOUT ZoTs TOV Ocod, HAA ws Tov Kuplov ev rn Tov becevOparov Quoes delov avevaros dvros. He existed as a man zpo ris Davepiozas, to wit, abray rod viod deornrae && cipxns avdpuxay elves, that is, in Himself, in essence, but not in appearance. 2C.14:—"Oxep qu ri Quoet, toro EPavepadn vu». C. 15, p. 154: Ta Aavbcvoy Osiov xara Quow dv, rovtTo TH THs EvavPpwaryoews EPavepady xeelpy. Compare below, page 372, and notes. 3°H dele ceprwots ov ry dpyny dro Ths Tapbevov toxev, Cc. 15, p. 153. But he cannot have added,—the humanity of Christ, which existed from the beginning, before Abraham and the creation toe’rn ravrws qv, ole ois wabnrais taparo orefpa. However strongly Apollinaris may have expressed the identity of the eternal ’ € ~ , OUTOS FO HUTOY TOV TYEYMLATOS—AAA wo TOD xvpiov . . . belo TVEVLETOS Ovros. APOLLINARIS. 377 humanity, though He assumed our form of humanity in order to exalt it and to transform us." This He was able to do, be- cause, as mvedua or avOpwros érrovpavios, He was in Himself also Divine Logos. Hence, too, the condescension of His eternal humanity to our form was a divine deed (@cia odp- coos). A further evidence of the correctness of the view we have presented, is in particular the circumstance, that whereas the theories of a heavenly humanity of Christ were strongly marked by Manichzan or Docetical features, and aimed, on the one hand, at raising Christ.as muchas possible above earthly lowness, and, on the other hand, at reducing His earthly humanity to a era transitory thing, an the design, as they fancied, of thus giving a worthier representation of Him; the erdeney of Apollinaris was precisely the contrary one,—to use the expression employed by Gregory, the ultimate purpose of all his writings was to represent the divine nature as mortal, that is, to vindicate for it as complete a participation in suffering as possible. This leads us to the other aspect of the matter. In the foregoing, we have seen how he endeavoured to conjoin deity and humanity to a perfect unity, by maintain- ing at all events the cupswtatov of man, his wvedua, to be an eternal determination of the Logos Himself; nay more, by positing the incarnation as a latent potence of the Logos. In addition to this, it must also be mentioned, that he tried to bring the deity as near as possible to huagndt ee and that not merely to the eternal humanity which he asserts the Logos “Himself.to.be (for therein would merely be involved the im- mediate or essential unity of the two), nor merely by means of the Platonic eidos of the cap£, but also to humanity in its tem- poral form, To take note hereof was the more necessary, as at 1 So is it also clear that Apollinaris says,—obx cv@pum0s,— aan as cy- Ooumos, O1ors ovx, Cmoovatos TH ckvOparw xaTa TO xupiaratoy. C. 35, p. 212 :— "AAA ovn advbpwmroyv evry Elves, Ono, AAA xcebawep cvOowroy (that is, only like, not identical with, a man of the same nature as ourselves ;—as to His inner essence, setting forth the true idea of man, the gow &vdpwxos, which is to become our true personality also; as to His appearance in time, on the contrary, like, but not equal to, our present humanity, as it exists apart from Him) dvovy, évowpxov dvre. His favourite expression was,— Christ is vos Evowpxos, not Acyos evoepxos. For vovs seemed to him to ex- press the eternal point of unity of the divine and human ; and this vod< became LYTU PHO. 375 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. this point a gap, or, if we will, a break, was discoverable in the system of Apollinaris. The Logos, or the eternal srvedua, which he also designates the eternal man Christ, is supposed to con- tain the potence of an incarnation in time. This thought appears to require that the historical humanity of Christ be regarded as the exposition of the eternal potence contained in the Logos. But how can His assumption of a cdma, and of the Wuyn Sortxy from Mary, be reconciled therewith? Accord- ing to the former idea, consistency would appear to necessitate him to derive the earthly humanity of Christ also from the essence of the Logos or the wvedua; according to the latter, the earthly humanity was derived to Him from Adam through Mary. In the former case, the Logos is conceived as pro- ductive; but what becomes, then, of the birth from Mary? In the latter case, He is conceived as receiving, assuming (dvada- Sev); but what becomes, then, of the unity, the identity of the Logos with Himself in the earthly humanity of Christ, which is not derived from His own essence? In point of fact, Apollinaris betrays here a certain degree of uncertainty. He frequently condemns the notion of a mere “assumption” of humanity; for he desired to advance beyond the category of “having” to that of “being,” and to regard. the..Person_ of Christ as a veritable unity, of which humanity -as-well-as deity was an integral, constitutive. element, and not-a~mere external addition. But, on the other hand, unless he were prepared to give up the doctrine of the birth of Christ from Mary, he must allow the presence in His person of something received, appropriated from without (an ésletntov, émuyevdpe- vov).. For he is far from adopting the principle referred to above, and which may he termed pantheistic, to wit, that human nature generally, cdua and aruy7), pertained to and was * As he also does; see note 1, p. 365; cf. note 3, p. 872. According to a fragment preserved by Theodoret, Dialog. 1, p. 70, he said;—Ei ¢ TpoorceeBaver Tis, ov tpémeras sis TovTo, mpoctraee Of oapuae 6 Xpiatos, dpo ove exparn cic ocepxo.—Kal votp tevrcy uiv cic ouryyéverny eyeplouro die TOD comoros, ive chon. Meaxpoy 08 ncbdArsoy Tod culouévov TO aalov’ maxpa epee moeArLoy nuay nol tv TH caparoocs’ ox dy Do qv xcArrsOy sic CapKe TpeTEic (-€v). P. 71:—Tpooxvvoduev 32 Osdy ccepnoe tx rig dylas ruobévov xpoo- AaBovrae, xal oie rodto kvOpwrov pecy dura xard Thy oepnee, Ocdy 08 nara TO vsveece.— Onoroyoduey tov vidv Too Weod vid avbpamov yeyevijcbat, ov Ovomats aan Andel roocrabduTx tx Meplas rio mwopbivov caoxn. APOLLINARIS. 379 the external realization of the @vats of the Logos. How then does he combine the two? In one way alone ;—not indeed by asserting the Logos to be eternally c@a and yvyx7, in the same sense as he asserted Him to be essentially and eternally wvedua ; but by regarding it as an essential and eternal determination of His being, to yearn for the assumption of both, to be susceptible of that which meets and is offered to it by the already existing humanity. If, then, there was in Him an essential and eternal inclination to this humanity, we are warranted in saying, that in receiving and assuming the human element from Mary, He was receiving that which belongs to His own complete idea, or, in other words, the potence of incarnation contained in Him is capable of becoming an actual, visible reality. What He thus received was something lower, something suffering, not some- thing higher: the receptivity which thus appropriated the lower was therefore in reality an act, an act of love; or, regarded from another point of view, He gave far more than He received, when human nature was given to Him; for, through being assumed by the Logos, the human nature became participant in divine nature. Still, this deed is not a deed of productive or creative power or majesty; but being an act of condescend- ing loye, it implies that the Logos by love had constituted Him- self susceptible of the lower element from Adam’s stem, and to His humiliation or condescension belonged His actual assump- tion of that humanity from Mary. Inasmuch, therefore, as He lovingly assumed our lower humanity, instead of creating a humanity afresh, or setting it forth and producing it out of Himself, the real earthly incarnation is converted from a physi- eal into an ethical process undergone by God the Logos. or this reason, it was possible for two things which, prior to the act of incarnation, were separate, to wit, the Logos and the Adamitic nature, to coalesce to a personal unity, provided only, that on the part of the Logos, there was a susceptibility to that in respect to which the humanity was, as it were, a giver and actor; and that, therefore, the presentation to the Logos of the human elements of Jesus, by the Adamitic nature, was simply as it were the fulfilment of His eternal yearning to become man. Humanity and deity.are perfectly capable of combining to form a personal unity, because the idea. of each points to the other from the.very. beginning. We have seen above, that, according 380 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. to Apollinaris, when the Adamitic humanity received the divine vous, it received its true ruler, the ruler which. its very vous compelled it to demand, in order that it might pass from an imperfect to a perfect form (which vods, however, it could not beget out of itself ); and that the two in combination set forth the unity of the moving principle and the object moved, or, in other words, the movement of life in its normal state. Even SO, (lo we find on the part of the Logos a susceptibility to that which the humanity has to communicate to Him,—a susceptibility rest- ing, however, on an ethical basis ;—accordingly, in this aspect also, it is clear both that the conjunction of humanity and deity to a complete personal unity was a possibility, and that that which the Logos in the first instance received from without, might become verily His own and a momentum of His being. It is therefore possible that Apollinaris himself may have taught, what his school certainly taught, that through its union with the uncreated, the flesh also became uncreated; that is, the idea of creation passed in this instance into that of being (com- pare Ath. c. Apoll. 1, 4). For it not merely became the pro- perty of the Logos by the Unio, but was brought to sameness of nature (c. 5), and was made coeternal with the nature of God ;—naturally, not in the sense of eternal pre-existence, but of post-existence. These observations will throw light on that which Apollinaris says regarding the participation of the Logos in human, par- ticularly in suffering, conditions. He maintains that we ought not to teach merely that Jesus was born as to His humanity ; and characterizes it as an Hellenic and Jewish error to form so incorrect a conception of that unity of the divine-human per- son, which first gave the incarnation its truth, as not to admit of God being represented as born of a woman As far as concerns the suffering in particular, according to Gregory, his intention was to teach, not merely that the deity of the Only- begotten took suffering upon itself in its humanity, but also that the divine nature converted itself to participation in suffer- 1 G25, p., 188 Ra anves yep, not, xoel Lovdaios xpoQavac dartorodes un xaraderd Osov a&xov yy é } b¢ C. 36 215 :— xomevos Osoy ainovery tov &x yuvainos rexbevra. C. 36, p. : Ei “y vovc, Qnow, tvoupuds tori 6 xUploc, oPia dy ein, QuriLovee vod cky- doazov, etc. (see Note 66); but then odx ny Exsonuin Ocov 4 Xpiotod rxpove ire akrA advOoarov yévurosc. APOLLINARIS. 381 ing." Gregory's account would lead us to believe that he made the Logos Himself die. But that this cannot have heen his meaning is plain, even from the observation directed against him by Gregory,—“ One cannot say that He died as to one part of Himself, and therefore not as to the other, for He was without parts, and uncompounded; what He is termed He was entirely, not this to one part and that to another.” Apol- linaris himself grants that the Son is the Father’s wisdom, power, and so forth (p. 133); but if He is such, and yet, on the other hand, ceases (in death) to be what He was, every- thing dies with Him. Being indivisible, He must either die entirely or live entirely: if He die, everything dies, for every- thing depends on His deity, which is supposed to have died. From this it is clear, as Gregory himself also acknowledges afterwards, that Avpollinaris had no intention of absolutely re- presenting the Logos as dying; but he distinguished in the one Logos two aspects (Gregory says “parts”), as to one of which He was susceptible of receiving what humanity was able to communicate, whilst as to the other He was and con- tinued immortal.? It must be possible to refer sufferings to the divine nature of the Logos; otherwise Christ. did not really put Himself in our place, and could not have conquered sin, for then it would have been a mere man that suffered (c. 51, 54). “If Christ were united with the Father even prior to the resurrection, why can He not have been united with the God in Him? ‘The Redeemer suffered hunger, thirst, weariness, conflicts, and sadness. But how could He be at the same time God? He is not two persons, as though God were one, man another. Accordingly, God suffered ;_and that suffered, which, properly speaking, admits no suffering into itself, not by a necessity of its nature altogether—inde- 1 C. 5:—Ovnrgy rod pmovoysvods vlod rhy Oscrnre, nai ovyt TH évOpurives To Tabos OfEacbe, drArAR TAY away nal éverAOlatov Quo pos Tebous LuETOv- clay &Aroiwdjves. 2 Gregory (ibid.) brings against him the charge,—dveraAartte: Arn» duvewiv (along with the aspect which was susceptible of receiving the communication of the human, of the passible) avaxaarovuéuny ravtny &x Tov dxverov, that is, in the aspect which was and continued immortal, was con- tained, according to Apollinaris, the power to overcome death, and to re- unite with itself, the aspect of His essence, which had as it were been given up to death along with the body 382 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. pendent of the will, but in agreement with the arrangement of its own substance ; that 1s, the deity did not suffer immediately or by physical necessity, but in consequence of a free impulse given it by the Logos, who panto to sympathize with, or par- ticipate in, the sufferings of men.’ From the words of Christ concerning the corn of wheat that dies (John xii. 24), Apol- linaris concluded,—Christ’ s dying could not have brought so much fruit if it had been the death of a mere man, instead of the suffering of the deity. But the Church, in its doctrine, does not leave to Him who was crucified anything divine in His own nature; not even in His noblest part, in the mvedua, was the human at the same time also divine.” If, in the view of Apollinaris, the Logos did not, properly speaking, take the place of the usual human vods, as something foreign to humanity; and if, on the contrary, He who became flesh (€voapxos) set forth true humanity, and was the mvedua in Christ, he had no alternative but to represent this human mvedua, Which was at the same time Logos, as actually man, and as participating in all human qualities. We discover at once, however, that this 7vedua presents two aspects : one, as to which it is Logos or God, and absolutely immutable ; the other, as to he it is finite, and is able really to humble itself and sympathize with our sufferings and conflicts. This duality of aspects in the one Logos necessarily leads to a distinction being drawn between the Logos and the Father (see Note 1, page 378); and, in fact, he consistently persisted in referring the words éuov Oénua, which occur in Luke xxi. 42 (“not My will, but Thine be done”), not merely to the human will of Christ, but also to the Logos,—that is, so far as the Logos was united with the man.2 The will of the Logos in the man, says 1 C. 58, p. 283:—Ei xpos rov Tlarépa yywras o Xpioros Tpo dvacracews, wis mpeg Tov ey adt@ Osoy ody, quwras; 6 Suryp werovbe weivey, Oipav noel noworoy nol eyaviev, nel Avanyv. Tis dv 6 Swrip; 6 Osos, Drow, (5) od Ovo wpdowme, wo etépov meeyv dyTOS, ErEpov de tov dvbpaxov. Ovxody o Osos rimovber, nal maoyer TO amapadextov Tabous, ox civaryxn Quaews &BovaArroy, nabamep dvOowmos, AAA cexoravbie Ducews. 2 C. 27. Compare c. 51, 52 :—Alridras roy exxarnoreotiney Aovoy, Ort wep) cavbpuroy Ocapotucy ro webos* avOparov Of bavaros ov xarapyel Tov Pava- TOY, OVOE ceviaTaral 6 oy} aTrobavar. 3 C. 81:—Od pynuovedoval, Qnaorv, ort 70 bérAnux rodte Tdsey elpyroes oom avipnmov ToD tx Vis, xabas avrol voui(Covow, aAAe TOV Osad Tov xaTaBavTog APOLLINARIS. 383 he, did not therefore come into conflict with that of the Father; for, even when He was not heard, not to be heard was His will, and consequently, in any case, His will was done. Accordingly, the Logos and His will were rendered by His humanity dif- ferent from, but not antagonistic to, the Father: the truth of the humanity of Christ manifested itself in this difference (ro iwOpomwov Xpiorod eelxvuto Oédnpa). One can easily under- stand how, with such principles, he came to be charged with Arianism; for Arius also taught that there was a TpeTTov in Christ different from the will of the Father. But apart from the consideration that the tpewrov posited by Arius involved the possibility of sin, whereas Apollinaris represented it as an out- flow of the unchangeable Jove and essential sinlessness of Christ, those who brought this charge forgot that Arius at- tributed immutability to ane Father alone, and mutability alone to the Son. Apollinaris was far from intending to do this: he represented the Son also as unchangeable as to His deity, but believed, notwithstanding, that by His incarnation the Logos made iiemagal unequal to Himself, though He restores Himself again to His original equality with Himself,'—an equality Bich always continued to be potentially His. He is much rather chargeable, therefore, with entertaining patri- passian principles 1 in relation to the deity of the Son, than with Arianism. But even this would not be correct, for he totally repudiates ae idea of a conversion, nay more, of a passibility of the Logos ;” on the contrary, he regards His suffering, as in the last ae an act of love, as évépyesa. Not merely the ad- justment of the dsatpecss, but even the submission thereto, the xévwols, was an act of the eternal and ever self-identical love of the Logos. It is true, the first product of this love was suf- ~ ci ~ ¥ > 22 otpavod, 70 els Eywosy eavrov wposstanicuévov. A. Mai 7, 203:—Ei 0¢ ioo- \ \ ‘ ~ ~ 3 ° \ abeving nok noLvavos THs marpinys ovolas oeml To Teebos noel Tov oTaAUpOY EpyoLeEvOS Ss Jul > / / ~ iy, was ev cyavie yevopsvos wpoonvyero wapenbeiy cevtoy To morypioy, xal Ley ’ ~ ~ = ~ nw vyevioboes cirov To béAnuec, dARL MAAAOY TO TOD TaTpos; Ti Os nal Tpoomryoper- ) oa \ ~ > , t 9 Soe teh s ~ ig , ely éxpiy TO TOU svxopcevou HéAnicce, AAA y doveQuvoy Oov xoek eveevTiov; 1 ©. 29:—Arcipav peo (Xpiorcs) tiv evépystav nord ocpxa, eeioov OE ~ Tangs \ / nur Tuevpeo, Owep Eyer Thy ev Ovvaemer THA locryTa, mal THY KaATe OupKO ~ ? ‘ , < Pp oo > , 2 / ) / ‘ ris évepysioes Oseelpeosy’ xa qv, Quo, ov wevras sCworolnoey, AAAS Tivos, obs nbennosy. ow / 2 Compare c. 56, p. 277 :—Tlac, Quoi, Oeds kvboumwos vyiveraly ey peres- ’ ’ | iA 9 . ~ ~ . % , Banbels deo rov sivas Osds, ci on vos ev avdpurw XOTEITY | 384 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. fering, was a feeling of pain, resulting from the conjunction of the Logos with the suffering Jesus; but if the Logos could not lovingly have sympathized with humanity, even whilst in the humanity of Christ, His divine nature would not have been in harmony with, but would have stood in the way of, His love; and therefore the physical categories in the conception of the Logos, instead of heing subject to, would set a limit and restraint to the ethical, or, in other words, to His love. “Gregory Nazianzen directs special attention to this inequality of the Logos, who is at the same time the archetypal man, with Himself." He says,—The words, He was begotten, tempted, He hungered, thirsted, slept, was weary, they (that is, the Apollinarists) refer to the human aspect; but that He was glorified by the angels, that He conquered the tempter, and wrought miracles, they attribute to the deity. The question, “Where have you laid Lazarus?” belonged to our weak nature; but when He cried, “ Lazarus, come forth,” and raised him from the dead, that belonged to the nature which is higher than ours.” When He struggled with distress, was nailed to the cross, and buried, it affected the outward husk; that He rose again and ascended to heaven, was due to the inner treasure.” But when Gregory Nazianzen asserts, that thus the very fault is committed which was charged upon the doctrine of the Church, and that it involves the assumption of two mutually conflicting natures, he overlooks, in thé first place, that at that time the Church had not seen as clearly as did Apollinaris, that Christ must be regarded as one indivisible person, and that we must not take such a view of His humanity as would constitute it a second person; and, in the second place, that, as we have shown, Apollinaris believed the human and divine aspects, which he never describes as natures, to be contained in each other. The inequality of Christ to Himself, referred to above, did not affect merely one of the two aspects, but both, each by and in itself. In the; first\place, humanity was present in Christ in its complete form; the archetype, the eternal wvedpa 1 Ep. ad. Cledon. 2, 7, or Or. 52. * Compare Athan. Tom. ad Antioch. 7. But see also Note 65. * Compare Athan. c. Apoll. 1,3, where the same is designated by %ewées dvdoamoc. He speaks also, in c. Ap. 1, 12, of men who say,—’Or: dadog tatly 6 reba vicg and daros 6 uy radon. APOLLINARIS. 383d was there; but it passed into inequality with itself, by assuming the form of our humanity. That eternal wvedua in Him was, further, and at the same time, the deity of the Logos; conse- quently, the deity also passed into inequality with itself, in the suffering God-man. (Note 70.) In that Apollinaris thus represented the divinity of the Logos as having, in itself, an aspect turned towards, yea, even apper- taining to, the humanity (even as humanity has an aspect turned towards the divine), we can understand how it was possible for Gregory Nazianzen further to charge him with introducing a “scala” into the divine (Ad Cledon. 1, 16). He constructs the Trinity, says Gregory, by representing it as compounded of a great, a greater, and a greatest." This can only refer to the circumstance of his attributing to the Logos, besides His perfect deity, an aspect turned towards finitude; and of his using similar words respecting the Holy Spirit, so far as He dwells in believers, groans in them, as Paul teaches, is grieved, and so forth. But this ceconomic Subordinatianism is as widely removed as possible from Arianism; for it might very easily have the doctrine of the Council of Nicaa, the onto- logical Trinity, for its presupposition (Mansi 3, 461). Further- more, on the basis thereof, by the application of ethical prin- ciples, it was possible for him to teach an humiliation, that is, a self-emptying of the Son and the Spirit, in the sense, namely, both of their making themselves unequal to the Father, and, as we have shown above, of their making themselves each unequal to Himself. This, however, must be evident from what has preceded. We have also express testimony to the effect that he adhered firmly to the Nicene doctrine of the Trinity. (Greg. Nyss. l.c. c. 52, p. 264, says, —“ He established piav ths Tpsiddos Geornta, in opposition to the Arians ;” Theo- doret himself (1. c.) was compelled to testify,—“In some of his writings we find also the Church doctrine of the Trinity, év évéous ouyypaupaciw—opolas npuiv Kal thy piav ths OedtnTos ovciav Kal TAS TpEls UTOaTaceLs Exnpvéev.) Apollinaris believed, further, that the power to adjust that Scaipeots was always inherent in 1 Compare also Theodoret, Her. Fab. 4,8: Adrod yep toriy eipnuc ro Héyee, siCov, evyiotoy, Or the Babuol &Ziwmarav’ as weycrov uesy bvtos ToD IIvevecros, tov 02 vlot gesiCovoc, weyiorov d¢ rov Ilerpds. Then we shoul have the reproach of Sabellianism. VOL. II. 2B 386 . FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. Christ; and that the perfect adjustment would take place in the thousand years’ kingdom, when the glorified person cf the Redeemer, having attained to complete unity, will dwell and walk among men on earth, in a form which shall be at once adequate to the deity, and perfectly human. (Note 71.) The remarks just made throw light on an expression of Apollinaris which has occasioned much surprise. The man Jesus Christ, says he, is one, as God the Father is one; this_ belongs to the idea of an essence. ‘This same unity is, in like manner, predicable of the compound being which stands in the middle between God and man (@oTe Kal TodTO dicews cur- Gétov petakv ovons Oeot Kai avOpwrwv). In his Syllogisms, Apollinaris had said,—If different qualities concentre in one, there arises a kind of middle thing; for example, spring is a middle thing between winter and summer. No middle thing, however, includes within itself the points of both extremes in completeness, but merely partially. Wherefore, the middle between God and men, in the Person of Christ, is neither completely man nor completely God, but a commixture of God and man.’ At first sight, this passage does not at all seem to fit into Apollinaris’ system; this wecorns appears to merit being charged with the same fault as he himself had brought against the doctrine of the Church (see Note 1, p. 360). Indeed, Gregory of Nyssa already makes the same observation (c. 49, p- 257). The doctrine of the Church does not desire a half, but réXevov Ocdv and térevov dvOpwrov in Christ; Apollinaris, on the contrary, presents us with a mutilated man. But that he omits the one axporns, the human zpoaipecis, the human vovs from his conception of Christ, is certain; and equally certain, that he allows the Aeyos during Christ’s life on earth to become unequal to Himself, and does not allow Him to exhibit His proper axporns. The pecdrns resulting herefrom fits per- fectly into his system, provided it remains eternally; the more so, as with this “temperamentum,” which the God-man sets 1A, Mai 7, 310: Mecorures yivovres idsornray die Dépay eic Ey cuverboucay, aos Ev Hecsovm Diudens 6 dvov xal immoy, noel Ey VALUED Kpapecert idsorng Agvxov xeel feerocvos, nol év cteps xeseavos noel bepats idiorns gap epryaloutun' ovdeule dé Hecdtns exaetépas exer tas aupdrntas && CAonANpov, GAAR pecpinas arimEenly- usvas. Meodrns df Osod xeel avbparwy év Xpiord, on kpe aire kvbowmxos bros. cits Occ, dara Ocov xal ctvdparov pelts. APOLLINARIS. 387 forth on earth, well consists an idea to which Apollinaris at- tached great importance,—the idea, namely, that the Logos, or the eternal wrvevywa, was a determination of humanity, and that, on the other hand, the cap was a determination of the deity thus approximated to it. Christ therefore is wéa duvors, one essence ; by which he un- derstood both the unity of the person and the essential unity of the two aspects, the divine and the human. To the unity of the person corresponds unity of volition and of thought! The hegemony in this unity is constantly in the hands of the Logos who became vos évcapxos. For this reason, Christ was raised above all necessity of practice (@oxnows) ; and only on the con- dition that He was raised above practice, both as to knowledge and virtue, could He be the Redeemer. Without learning, He must needs be wise and holy from His very birth.” He worked His miracles, not like a prophet by the power of God, but by His own power (Cat. Cord. p. 255; Greg. Antirrh. c. 29, p. 196.—Cat. Cord. pp. 884, 329). He spake not by revelation, but was Himself the lawgiver. Consequently, the inmost core of His personality remained untouched by that inequality or diremption (dvaipeous) ; this core was not merely a principle, but the complete inner man, the perfect mavedua or the Logos. It is, further, particularly interesting to bring under consi- deration the relation of believers to Christ. The principal term employed by Apollinaris to designate it is wyunows. Mohler has coarsely interpreted the word to denote a mechanical copying or mimicking. With a Protestant colouring, this is repeated also by Baur (pp. 635 ff.), who finds in the word a species of Pela- 1 Compare A. Mai 7, 70. The passages from Apollinaris, Polemon, and others, p. 20: pla évipyeia, ule Qvots. P.16:—wla Qvois otvberos, ovy- xparTos, copxiny xo being. °O. xeivy loric, exclaimed Apollinaris, xx! wigss bcomeolae, Ocds nal oobpS wlav dweréacae Quay. * Greg. Nyss. c. 38. Ei ts wagov erepog Erépov xomilercet, rovro Of aoxyory ylveros’ ovdeuele 02 hoxnots ty Xplore ove kpa vovs toriv aevdparivos. C. 28, p. 192 :—Tés Qnotv, 6 &ysos éx yeveris 3 (Therefore, in order that it might be sinless, it was necessary for Christ’s humanity to be deity: thus was it equal to the enemy.) Tis edldcexrog coe; Compare especially c. 51. A man subject to the common corruption of men, even to the tpexzev, could not help. Only a perfectly sinless being could take away the curse of sin. Compare Cat. Cord. in Joh. 8, 88, where he designates this essential know- ledge of Christ yvaors Quciny. 388 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. gian idea of imitation, which would involve the laying of a false stress on the moral example of Christ. Against such a suppo- sition, his antagonism to the Antiocheians, especially to Diodorus of Tarsus, ought alone to have protected him.’ Still more, the importance he attached to the death of Christ (compare, for example, the Cat. Cord. on Joh. xix. 17). Apollinaris’ fault was rather that of allowing the ethical to fall into the back- ground, as compared with the religious. ‘The passage quoted by Athanasius (c. Apoll. 1, 2), indeed, of which the men above- mentioned seem alone to have taken notice, does not show us clearly what Apollinaris’ real opinion was. All it reports is,— capKos mev KawwoTnTa Xpiotos eTrwdéberxTar Kal” opolwow (that is, Christ exhibited the new humanity in likeness to us) tod 6é bpovovvtos év iv THY KawoTHTA, Sid pinTEwS Kal OpotwcEews Kal aToyns THS apbaptias Exactos év éavT@ emoeixvutas (that is, the novelty of him who thinks in us, each one shows by imitation, resemblance and abstinence from sin). More light is thrown on the matter by Ep. ad Cledon. 2, 3, where the complaint is made against the school of Apollinaris (Gregory alludes particularly in the letters to Vitalis, for whom, in other respects like Epiphanius, he entertained a very high regard, Ep. ad Cled. 2, 5), that it gives a different explanation of the words, “ We have the spirit of Christ” (1 Cor. xi. 16), from the Church, understanding by the spirit of Christ, His deity. This,. however, first becomes quite clear from several passages pre- served in a Catena to the Gospel of John.’ How far removed he was from Pelagianism, we may judge from his remarks on John iil. 5:—The Lord leads Nicodemus to true knowledge by attributing regeneration to grace, which is accomplished by the service, indeed, of water, which cleanses the body, but by the energy of the Spirit sanctifying the soul and fill- ing it with deity. If He dwell in usas a pledge and first fruit, the perfect kingdom of God will come, and the fulness of the deity fillus.” On vi. 27, he remarks,~ ~ , > ~ / ~ iy dvOodrots cbperns posipryuomtuns a&rereds mevovong avev Xosotov, waonc Oe APOLLINARIS. 391 self, and made like Christ, and thus perfected." A new and wonderful birth was introduced by Christ: it is attended by inexpressible pains ; but the suffering is followed by the resur- rection, and brings a joy which will no more change, and which cannot be taken away ; for through the resurrection of the new man ye stand as new men, and obtain free access to God. Ye will rejoice when ye shall witness the birth of the child which was unknown to the world, and which is exalted above death and corruption; and that is He in you. ‘These propositions are plainly fitted to establish the owooveia of Christ, if not with the human race in general, at all events with perfected men, with Christians. It cannot be denied that Apollinaris’ doctrine of faith is a logical development of his Christology; and that, on the whole, his system is governed by one principle. Faith corresponds to the fact of the incarnation: by the incarnation Christ became like us; by faith we become like Christ. As the divine voids was the hegemonic principle in Christ, so is the Spirit of Christ inus. And as that divine vods was not something foreign to humanity, but rather the true, the eternal man, the éow avOpw- Tos; even so are we perfected by our reception of the vods of Christ, although we are thereby at the same time exalted above ourselves. Prior to the coming of Christ also, it is true, human nature appeared as a relatively independent being: it had a relative centre of unity, a vovs, in which the powers were con- joined to unity. But this was not yet the true vovs; for, inas- U0 Qcov wepl advdoarove yevomevns wpovoles ey TH wape Xptorod awrnole ro Téreoy crore Scvovons. 1 On John xvii. 13 :—‘‘ These things speak I in the world.” Saag gv Tout O1eipe? TO xara Qvow xal xad cuolworv. He, namely, is not of the world ; His disciples also are not of the world: the former is clear, for He did not descend from heaven. O/ 02 daréoronro: xara thy ouolwoty tiv Xpiorov wereBeRnxsoav ad tov xdojov. They became strangers to me, ds& ray vxrep avbpamov éperqy. Through their ofxesérng with Him also, they were estranged from the world. 2 On John xvi. 21:—otrms adcroBycera: viv gal rod xervov nol Oevpo- ciov rovrov Toxerov. Nov yep ag dandas dvdpuros sis Tov xdapeov vyevuciros én rapeoczav aolvav, noel Avany wsy duly ai wepl To ~edos Adives wpocoicovar, xyopoy 06 n eerae TO TeLbos cevdaTaaIs’—oTE Dice THs dvaaTaTEMS TOU YEOv ctv bpa- Tov vot wareoravres sig thy pds Ocov ners wafpyalav. Xeapyosade yap orev yonre (10.) Zévov ro noon rasbloy drorex bev &Pbaprov re nal avcnrebpay, sevToy 32 Onrovers Oyaiv. 392 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. much as it lacked a divine content, its content was sensuous, and thus all was disfigured. The vods in Christ ruled, and was no longer merely mutable, elective, or psychical (1 Cor. i. 14) ; it was the hegemonical spirit; and through faith the same thing takes place by grace in us. We also need the drpemrov for our perfection, the veda as a new principle, which must be our essential righteousness; we, however, attain to it by grace. This, like many other ideas of Apollinaris, reminds us strongly of the system of Andreas Osiander, of his “ justitia essentialis.” Apollinaris has, notwithstanding, left a discrepancy in his system. Men, even apart from Christ, have vods in themselves ; but it is, as it were, merely the form or the possibility thereof, it is Sexrexds for good and evil, tpemros, and so forth; in reality, however, the servant of sin. Christ, on the contrary, has no vovs at all which is derived from the Adamitic nature; and, therefore, His equality of essence with men suffers. Had Apol- linaris been minded to carry out the parallel between Christ and men strictly, he must have maintained, ether that believers have no vods, no mvedua, before they believe; and that it is first created in them by Christ. But although Apollinaris sometimes inclined thereto, he could not be prepared to carry the notion out strictly; because men prior to Christ would thus be degraded almost to the rank of beasts, and redemption and completion would be a new creation, instead of a renovation; especially as the new element superadded by creation, the mvedpua, con- stituted, in the view of Apollinaris, the inmost centre, the very kernel ‘fi the human personality itself. Or, on the other hand, as it was impossible to carry this out, he must have attributed. a voos, a human soul, to Christ as to ie human nature, the nature assumed from Mary at all events, in the sense that this vovs, so far as it owed its existence to the first creation, was a vovs dex- rwxos, neither filled with the sensuous nor with the divine, but still endowed with the possibility of both. In the incarnation itself, however, he must have conceived it filled and appropriated by the divine vods or Logos, as was required by the idea of a true incarnation and a true development. At the same time, justice would thus be done to the deep, speculative insight of Apollinaris into the fact, that the Logos who fills this ainanet soul, and con- joins it with Himself, is not a something foreign to - essence, but that which it had, as it were, yearned for and expected, be- APOLLINARIS. 3935 cause it could not attain to its true shape and form until it had been filled with its true content ;—in other words, it was com- patible with the view in question, to hold the Logos to be the truth of human nature. We have found previously that Irenzeus, pursuing a course of thought similar to that of Apollinaris, en- deavoured to avoid the fault just mentioned, by distinguishing in the human soul between possibility or susceptibility, and realization or fulfilment: attributing the former to the human aspect_of Christ derived from the Adamitic nature, which the Holy Ghost had prepared and consecrated for the scene of the incarnation ; the latter to the Logos;—and believing, on the one hand, that the human nature, because pure, tended towards union with the Logos; on the other hand, that the Logos, out of love, strove towards an incarnation. Apollinaris, however, did not do this, because he reckoned to the Adamitic nature, no#* merely opposed possibilities in the form of a double susceptibi lity, but also an independent power to take opposite resolutions, the adre£ovcwv. If he necessarily regarded an human vods, possessed of independence, as an hindrance to the incarnation, it was still more the case, because he appears to have attributed to the soul derived from Adam’s race, as others had done to the body, a natural bias to evil, and because he deemed it impossible that a human being with freedom of choice should remain with- out sin. His only resource, therefore, was to shut out this human pods; which he then futilely endeavoured to make good by designating the vots émoupavios or Noyos, also avOpwires came to heal and perfect ; supposing that the only way to secure the unity of the divine-human person was to let fall the truly human soul, instead of so defining it that it should be able to be conjoined in unity with the Logos, without being tainted with sin, and without having a separate personality of its own. A God in a human body with animal life (puy7 Soren), they say to him therefore, is a mask, but_not_a God-man. Apolli- naris, it is true, constantly exclaims afresh,—Christ cannot have 394 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. so entirely become that which we are as to have lost the ability to make out of us that which He is. He says, in particular, influenced by his antagonism to Arianism, a human voids of the first creation must necessarily possess freedom of choice, and thus an uncertainty and an impotence against sin would have attached to Christ, that must have rendered it impossible for Him to fulfil His vocation of Redeemer. But they replied,— That which was not assumed by Him remained unhealed (To ampoohnrrov Kal abeparevtov). They asked,—Is not the soul precisely the highest in man? and would not, therefore, an incarnation without soul be Docetical in the main point?* Or, did the body alone stand under sin and condemnation? and did the soul need no redemption ? To this he might indeed have answered,—The work of re- demption consisted precisely in the perfection brought by Christ, or in the completion of the creation of our nature; and it be- comes unnecessary to lay special emphasis on the redemption. Yor if through faith the vods of Christ enters into us and becomes our hegemonical principle, we become thereby new persons, pleasing to God, sinless. Plainly, however, the second creation thus comes into conflict with the first, inasmuch as the second neither recognises nor seeks a living link of connection in the first. And even if he recognised the existence of such a point of union in believers, and thus escaped a magical creation of a new constituent of human nature, he did not acknowledge its existence in Christ ; otherwise, as we have just shown, he must have attributed to Him a human wy, which was susceptible to the active divine vods. This also floated before the minds of the teachers of the Church when they remarked,—His theory renders the incarnation more difficult, instead of explaining it. For, through denying the human soul, he lost that middle link, . by means of which it was possible for the deity to appropriate the body and its sufferings.’ It is true, Apollinaris professes ' Greg. Nyss. 1. c. c. 33, p. 204, charges him with teaching a rootless man, cévoparoy appsCov, ral chovvaPy wpds viv qerépav Ovow. 212 :—ExQvarov Tis Nustépas Ducews. He teaches strictly two species of men :—an earthly, consisting of body, soul, reason; and an heavenly, consisting of body, soul, God. Christ, therefore, stands over against us as érepoovetos, and is not Cuoovatos xara +d xvpiararoy, in relation to the highest element of the Adamitic humanity. alee 25Gec. 46 7—He proceeds we olxsiotépas rapa Tov vovy TH, ocep- APOLLINARIS. 395 that it was necessary for Christ, in order to exhibit virtue, to walk among men as a man. But if His humanity was a body without rational soul, His virtue was not human virtue. Nay more, says Gregory of Nyssa, if He had no freedom (adrefov- ovov), His virtue was no virtue.’ This curtailment of the human nature in itself has a Doceti- cal character; but that Apollinaris was tainted with Docetism, shows itself still more clearly in the circumstance, that (as, indeed, might consistently be expected) he was unable to attri- bute growth in wisdom and grace, learning, exercise, tempta- tion, to the human soul of Christ. But if He was not the subject of actual growth, and merely revealed to others in ever increasing measure the inner treasures of His being, which re- majned in themselves ever the same, and, being complete and closed, were susceptible neither of enlargement nor diminution, He did not pass through a truly human course of life. The cause of this fault, was his assuming the human mvevpa of Christ to be immediately of like nature with the eternal Logos. Instead of positing merely the possibility of the incarnation in the eternal Logos, distinguishing therefrom every actualization of this possibility, and representing the possibility as becoming an actuality, by an ethical process (that is, through the love of the Logos, wnich impelled Him to the act of xévwous, and by the ethical process which Christ underwent), he posits the humanity as eternally complete, KaTa TO Kupt@Tatov ; he repre- sents it as the Logos Himself. Prior to the incarnation, it is latent merely in relation to men; in itself, it is eternally com- plete. On this view, however, the childhood of Christ was necessarily mere appearance. He cannot be a moral example, but the physical or metaphysical process of the incarnation of God, begun in Him, is simply continued in believers, who re- ceive, in the place of their earthly vous, His veda, or the victorious principle of that union of the divine with the ‘flesh xos obons pds THY Ths bedrntos Evaow. CO. 41, p. 239: The assumption of the cip2 by the Logos becomes more intelligible, if the vod; formed the transition to the God Adyos. 1 Tbidem:—How can the cap have virtue without the exovosoy? And the éxoveroy is impossible without a vods. OC. 41 :—- wpoulpeats ovdey erepoy ¥ vode ris forty. How, then, could Apollinaris say,—Man, in whom is no vous, weranauBaver THs xedupes dosrig? To darpouiperoy can neither be é@iasror nor praiseworthy, although it may be without sin. 396 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. which was archetypally realized in Christ. Apollinaris seems to have had not the slightest notion, that even if the Redeemer did assume a human soul, and with it subject Himself to a pro- cess of development through freedom of choice, His victory and work of redemption were notwithstanding sure; and, besides, that only on this supposition could His virtue be human virtue and be tested. Freedom he believed to involve sin, at all events for a soul of Adam’s race. Such notions may not be directly branded Manichzan ; but, at all events, the notion that freedom of choice is not fit for appropriation by the Logos, whilst at the same time it is an essential constituent of the nature of men and angels, involves a complaint against the first creation. This complaint is. the more unjustifiable, as, in the further course of his system, a representation is given of the essential nature of man, according to which freedom of choice by no means forms part of its eternal idea, but merely appertains to man at a lower stage; for he maintains that Christ was the perfect man, and the process of the “ Unio” of the Tvevpa With the cap&, undergone by Him, is continued also in those whe believe on Him. To Christ, however, he ascribes no freedom of choice; and so likewise believers, in his view, are first raised. by the Christian principle above mutability. In accordance herewith, therefore, instead of saying, the first creation was not suitable in its completeness for appropriation by the Logos, he ought rather to have expressed himself as follows :—The first creation itself was still imperfect ; it was marked by un- fixity and mutability: the true idea of creation was first realized in the man, who was raised above all freedom of choice. It would thus have appeared as a mere defect or transition-stage, as the not yet existent divine fixity. But this he did not wish to teach; he regarded freedom of choice as something positive, which, though derived from God, was incompatible with the full goodness of the world, seeing that it was not even capable of aiding in the realization of this goodness. Accordingly, Apollinaris is undoubtedly chargeable to a certain extent with Manicheism. On such a theor 7, redemption must of course consist, above all, in deliverance from that freedom of will which naturally tends to evil, and in the informing of the fleshly man with a higher principle, with the third factor of the true human essence. This leads us to the other aspect of APOLLINARIS. 397 the matter. Apollinaris had no conception of an historical mediation, of an historical process, but believed that the whole result was brought into existence at one stroke. His strength lay alone in describing magnitudes already complete, in their mutual connection and simultaneous existence. Accordingly, the idea of perfection predominates over that of reconciliation and redemption; and, strictly speaking, he can only attribute activity to the divine aspect ;—-for the human aspect he has no essential place, no mediatory significance. The human aspect, selfless in itself, has the office of showing, of revealing, the divine—nothing more; it is simply the organ moved by the divine. The preliminary decision arrived at by the Synod of Alex- andria, in relation to the question of the human soul of Christ, in the year 362 (see above, pp. 985 ff.), was adhered to by the Church teachers, Athanasius, the Gregories, Basilius the Great, Amphilochius Damasus (Mansi l. c. 488 f.), and others. That they also justly regarded the incarnation, in and by itself, as the principial completion of the reconciliation between heaven and earth, we have shown above (Chapter I.). But precisely on that account, Apollinaris was unable to satisfy them. For, although he appeared to be able to charge the Church with arriving rather at an dvOpw7os évOeos, or a double person, that is, at a monstrosity, than at an incarnation, if a complete man and complete deity are to be supposed to have met in Christ ; they in return might justly reply, that precisely he, with his repudiation of a human voids, could never show the possibility of an incarnation. For vy and cdpé do not constitute, they are merely momenta of, a man: they could only form the doyetov or temple in which the Logos dwelt. On the other hand, vods forms part of man; but He is not supposed to have become an human vods; consequently, He did not become man. It is true, he maintains that the Logos was eternally man in Him- self, kata Td Kupibtatov, TO TYE} wa; but inasmuch as cap§ and yuy7 belong as essentially to the idea of man as the mvedpa, both which he is supposed to derive from Mary, Christ, as mere mvedua, was not yet a complete man. One might sup- pose, indeed, that He found His complement, and became a complete man, through the appropriation of yy and oapé ; but the wvedua or vots differed too widely from these two to be 398 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. able to constitute with them one living unity. The vovs was complete, eternally perfect, identical with the Logos, so that a divine person appeared and dwelt in an human living body; but to represent this as the accomplishment of an incarnation is inadmissible, for the simple reason, that a complete and per- fect vos can only stand in a purely external relation to a body that must grow ere attaining to completion. And if, for the purpose of avoiding this fault, Apollinaris had posited the vous, which connected itself with the cap£, as imperfect, inasmuch as the vots was at the same time the Logos becoming incarnate, he would have fallen out of Docetism into Arianism or Ebionism. If, further, the work of redemption could not be accomplished unless Christ passed through all the stadia of human develop- ment, sanctifying and honouring them all, it must necessarily be mutilated by a theory which does not allow of such a de- velopment of the human soul in the case of Christ, and repre- sents Him as commencing His career with a complete spirit (vods), which was also the Logos.’ The Church teachers must be allowed to have rightly per- ceived that the first and most important thing to be done, was to lay the foundations completely, prior to thinking of further tasks. What profit would be the appearance of bringing out the unity of the Person of Christ more completely with Apolli- naris, if it were purchased at the price of the completeness of the incarnation? First of all, it was necessary to recognise the elements constitutive of incarnation in their completeness, and then it might be permissible to ask how they could be united in the Person of Christ. The Fathers, therefore, acted rightly in decidedly affirming that Christ had a human soul; and that in defiance of the great difficulties pointed out by Apollinaris—difficulties which they thus took upon themselves, and which he had pronounced insoluble. The problem of re- ducing two complete magnitudes, the Logos and man, to unity, 1 Compare Theodoret, H. E. 5, 3:—Tyy royinny Woxny eorepncbas ring yeyevnuéuns Enos cwtnpias. Odx eianQads yep ravrny xara tov éxeivov Adyoy 6 @eds Adyos ore larpslas HEiaoev, ore timis merédaneyv. “AAAA TO peey Goipee TO yyivoy (Man) ore THY cdopatay wpooxuueites Ovyamsewy (that is, in Christ) ; 4 02 Luxq (ours) 4 ner eixdve belay yeyevnutyn xaTo memvnne Thy THs aucotias arimiay wepixeievy. Ib.1018: Flavian’s expression,—res voUY TOY HuérEpoy THs owrnplas aroorEpEls. APOLLINARIS. HILARIUS. 399 may be much more difficult than that of uniting two magnitudes which are incomplete and tempered; but faith demands that the humanity be complete, because, otherwise, the work which it feels to be complete, must be confessed to be incomplete ; and because Christ could not work upon us at all, if He were not of like substance with us. Accordingly, the alternative lay before them, either to let fall the incarnation itself, or to take up the more difficult problem, which faith assured them must be soluble. In connection herewith, it is deserving of special remark, that they did not allow themselves to be driven to the opposite ex- treme by their opposition to Apollinaris. Because they assumea that Jesus had a human soul along with His body, they were by no means disposed to reduce the incarnation to a besouling or bespiriting (Beseelung, Begeistung) of this man: they re- pudiated the notion that Christ was merely an dvOpwzros evdeos ; they refuse to hear anything of such a predominance of the hu- man aspect as would reduce the divine aspect to an accident of the human hypostasis. Their wish rather was, that the Logos in hypostatical form should be there, as a perfect man. With equal firmness also, they rejected an error nearly allied to the truth just set forth, to wit, the doctrine of a double personality, of the ulds Oerds side by side with the vids Ocod dice. The two complete aspects of the nature of Christ must constitute, they taught, a living personal unity. In this respect, they ap- proved of and directed their own efforts to the same goal as Apollinaris ; and they were far from falling into the mistake of later Christian thinkers, who laid great stress on the distinction between the two natures, but did not bestow equal care on showing how they could be united in one person. When we review more carefully the attempts made plainly to set forth the union of the two complete natures, our attention is above all attracted to Hilarius of Pictavium, who flourished about A.D. 350 :—we feel the more drawn to him, because he does not appear hitherto to have met with the consideration he deserves. Hilarius is one of the most difficult Church teachers to un- derstand, but also one of the most original and profound. His view of Christology is one of the most interesting in the whole of Christian antiquity. But in order to form a proper estimate of this theory, we must bring to mind the tendencies to which 400 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. it was opposed. In the first place, Sabellianism had been re- vived in a new form; and the older patripassian doctrine of conversion had also been resuscitated, with the difference that now—at all events by some—it was referred to the trinitarian Son. The former (compare Hilar. Comm. in Matt. xi. ¢. 9, De Trin. 10, 50 ff. 18 ff.) regarded the incarnation of the Logos as a mere operation of the divine power and wisdom, not as a personal existence thereof in a man, and thus naturally fell into Ebionism ; for the obvious reason, that the incarnation was un- avoidably reduced to the level of a mere extension or continua- tion of the divine power of the Logos into the man Jesus: the latter also arrived at an Ebionitic result; for if the Logos so far fell away from, as to lose Himself, and if, in particular, by emptying itself and submitting to weakness, the Word became a human soul, then there remained nothing but the man in Christ." We have seen above, that even Arianism, which as to its inmost essence was Kbionitical, by availing itself of the Platonic doctrine of the pre-existence of spirits, and of the for- getfulness which resulted from their earthly birth, was able to _ arrive at the same result, as this latter view. In opposition to these errors, it was necessary to demonstrate the existence of a truly divine and a truly human aspect, or, if one will, the duality of the natures in the Person of Christ; in other words, it was necessary to draw as clear a distinction as possible be- tween the divine and the human. 1 De Trin. 10, 50, 52:—Plures eludere dictum apostolicum, quo ait Christum Dei Sapientiam et Dei virtutem, his modis solent: quod in eo ex virgine creando efficax Dei sapientia et Virtus exstiterit, et in nativitate ejus diving prudentiz et potestatis opus intelligatur, sitque in eo efficientia potius, quam natura Sapientiew. De Trin. 10, 50:—Per quod etiam illud vitii adjungitur, ut Deus Verbum tanquam pars aliqua virtutum Dei quo- dam se tractu continuationis extendens hominem illum, qui a Maria esse coepit, habitaverit et virtutibus diving operationis instruxerit, animee tamen suz motu naturaque viventem. C. 51 :—The power of the Word who thus extended Himself from without unto Jesus, strengthened him to perform deeds of power after the manner of the prophets: thus also may be ex- plained the words, ‘‘My God, My God, why hast Thou forsaken Me?” Jesus, namely, was again also a Dei Verbo contracta rursum protensione desertus. De Trin. 10, 50:—defecisse omnino Deum Verbum in animam corporis volunt, ut—de se defecerit Deus Verbum, dum corpus officio anime viviticat.—51: ut Deus Verbum anima corporis per demutationem nature se infirmitatis exstiterit, et Verbum Deus esse defecerit. HILARIUS. 401 In the second place, there were not wantizg men who, it is true, took their start from this duality, and thus left room for an act of grace, nay, even for a personal appearance of the Son of God in the sphere of Adamitic humanity ; but, through rest- ing in the duality, did not attain to a living unity.of the person. To this class belonged that part of the Arians which did not ac- cept the idea of a conversion of the Logos into the soul of Christ, nor of a substitution of the Logos in the place of the human soul; but taught that there was an human soul, nay more, an human Ego alongside of that of the Logos.t. Further, all those who, in the predominance they gave to the bare understanding, were the forerunners of the school of Antioch, and believed it necessary to be more on their guard against commixture than against separation, and objected less strongly to a double Christ than to theories like that of Apollinaris and his predecessors. In opposition to these separators, it was necessary, on the con- trary, to make every effort to point out the solid unity of the person. For, independently of these, the doctrine of the Church itself, as we have seen in the case of Apollinaris, was threatened with the danger of the God-man being reduced to an av@pwzrogs évOeos. But if this task presented great difficulties for Apolli- naris, whose doctrine of the divine vovds, which took the place of the soul of Christ, appeared to lessen it ; still more difficult must it appear, when a human soul also was reckoned to the humanity of Christ. It deserves remark, that even prior to_the public appearance of Apollinaris, Hilarius had most decidedly upheld the true human soul of Christ ; and that he had continued both the doctrine of Tertullian (with whom he had otherwise many points of affinity) and that of Irenzeus in Gaul. A denial of the human soul of Christ would have appeared to him a Docetic confusion of the human and the divine. So much the more desirous, therefore, must we be to learn what he had further to say. The more widely he separated the two aspects, above all, the more distinctly he affirmed, and the more sharply he defined, the completeness of the human nature, whilst at the same time quite as jealously asserting for the divine aspect, everything that pertains to its full idea; the more interesting is it to observe, that he displayed quite as intense an anxiety to demonstrate the 1 Valens and Ursacius (compare Hilar. de syn. 79 f.) assumed a com- passio Filii Dei, which involves the duality. VOL. TI. 2¢ 402 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. unity of the clearly discriminated aspects. By the combination of these two tendencies, Hilarius evinced himself to be, in the true sense, a teacher of the Church. As to the former :—Hilarius, who was one of the most resolute defenders of the cause of Athanasius, developed the doctrine of the eternal divine Son, who exists alongside of the human aspect, by, above all things, bringing more decidedly into play than others the creative activity which per tains to the Son of God, in connection also with the act of incarnation, though, as we shall soon see, only in order afterwards to convert the category of creation more completely into that of incarna- tion. It was not the human race or Mary that gave body and soul to the Person of Christ’; but if we distinguish accurately, the creation of the human soul of Christ was a deed of the Logos... In the view of Hilarius (Tract. on Ps. exvin., Lit. x. pp- “298 ff.), it is an error to suppose that the souls of men spring from Adam in the way of propagation. They have a higher nobility, a worthier origin ; they are of a heavenly, God- role nature, and their nature in itself is not stained with earthly material. In the case of Adam, indeed, we know that his soul was created before the body, which is of the dust. The dust, when reduced to form, was not yet man, but matter; the giving a form to the rough matter was not a creation, but a moulding of the already existent dust. It was fitting that a creative hand should show itself in connection with this highest work, and that it should not be a mere forming of what already existed. Hence the origin of man is divided into several acts. ‘The first is indicated by the words, “ Let Us make an image, which shall be like Ourselves.” This refers to the creation of the soul, which was called into existence to be an image of the First-born. The second was the formation of the earthly image out of the dust. Whereupon followed, as the third act, the conjunction of that soul with this material, by the Spirit af God, in consequence of which the soul soit a body, the matter was animated, and the unity, the living man, became an actuality. However strange this theory may appear at first sight, Hilarius seems to have regarded it as typically teaching what takes place at a higher stage in connection with the incarnation. In the case of Adam, he fixes the material and spiritual aspects each by itself, and sepa- rates them as widely as possible from each other, in order then HILARIUS. 403 to conjoin them the more firmly to an unity in man; and such also is his course of procedure with the total humanity of Christ, on the one hand, and the deity, on the other. The theory de- scribed has also a further significance for him: by its means, the share taken by Mary in the work of incarnation is reduced to its proper limits. She did not give Jesus His soul, otherwise His soul would have been sinful, like that of Adam; and yet His soul was of like substance with the souls of men, for they also are created immediately by the Logos. Nor, further, did she give Jesus His body, if we speak strictly ; for a body is first formed out of the material by the accession of the enlivening, animating soul, which she did not give. Not by themselves, but through the soul, have the members of our body their sensations. As soon as the soul ceases to have anything further to do with the body, as soon as it ceases to feel the body with its sensations, it has already become alien from it, and, properly speaking, no longer belongs to it. As a consequence, the body soon corrupts, and must be cast aside. If, then, the soul first constitutes the material a body, and if the material without soul is an unformed mass, we can only partially say,—Christ derived His body from Mary; for, strictly speaking, Christ’s body first became a body through the soul, and His soul He did not derive from Mary. For this reason the Son of God, or the “Spiritus Dei,” is termed the “conditor” of the body." The God-man derived ; His origin from Himself, and not from Mary, even as to the corporeal aspect of His being. Hence also was His body con- secrated and pure from the beginning, through His God-de- scended soul. And as His soul was most intimately united with the heavenly Son, Hilarius did not hesitate to use even the ex- pression,—-The body of Christ was of heavenly origin.” * De Trin. 2, 5: —Humani generis caussa Dei Filius natus ex virgine est et spiritu sancto, ipso sibi in hac operatione famulante, et sua, Dei videlicet inumbrante virtute, corporis sibi initia consevit et exordia carnis instituit. 10, 16:—Non enim corpori Maria originem dedit,—inasmuch as without the Spiritum Sanctum and the Verbum Dei no man would have been brought into existence. By the potestas Verbi is the caro initiata et con- dita. C.18:—Ipse corporis sui origo est. C. 22 :—Si conceptum carnis, nisi ex Deo, virgo non habuit, longe magis necesse est, anima corporis, nisi ex Deo aliunde non fuerit. C.25:—Ipse quidem per virginem ex se natus homo. ‘To exactly the same purpose, Gregor. Nyss. Antirrhet. c. 54, pp. 271 fff. 2 De Trin. 10, 73 :—Caro illa de ceelis est. C 15-—Corpus celeste. 4()4. FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. This has been understood as though he denied Mary to have been the actual mother of Christ xara cdpxa; as though he left her merely the function of the bringing forth, or of the nour- ishment and reception in her womb, of an human germ, im- planted into her from without,—a germ which was derived, as to soul and body, from the essence, or, at all events, from the creative power, of the Logos; and to which Mary, therefore, stood, as it were, in the relation of foster-mother.’ This view, however, notwithstanding many passages appear to justify it, 1s incorrect. Rather did the Son of God, by becoming incarnate, appropriate something which was foreign to Him (quod alienum a se erat), even as Adam’s body also was not created, but was formed out of a substance that already existed. From God the soul, from the Virgin the earthly material of the body. What- ever a child derives from its mother from the beginning, that Christ’s humanity derived from Mary. (Note 74.) If Hilarius derived the body of Christ from the essence of the Logos, or even, as to material, from the creative power of the Logos, how could he have conceived the God-man to be so completely united and interwoven with collective humanity as he evidently did? His entire doctrine of the “evacuatio,” for the sake of assuming the “forma servilis,” would then be useless, unintelligible. For if the Logos had produced the “ forma servilis” out of His own substance, or had lowered Himself thereto, the “ evacuatio” would be identical with the “forma servilis ;” whereas he draws a clear distinction between the two. And if He did not derive His body from Mary, He was a stranger in the human_race, and was neither born into humanity nor rebare humanity in Him- self. The Son of God, considered in Himself, had no “ caro,” although He possessed the power to acquire “caro.” He did acquire it, in that He “se ex alto defixit in limo profundi” (in Ps. Ixviii. 4). Rather by His human birth, therefore, was “nova natura in Deum illata” (de Trin. 9, 54), which previously was not in God. The Son really received something from_humanity, which He previously had not, to wit, the “forma servilis,” and 1 Baur l. c. p. 686, says :—‘‘ The Divine Logos became man by creating out of Himself the human nature which consists of body and soul.” Even the writer of the very thorough treatise prefixed to the Benedictine edition of the works of Hilarius, and which Dr Baur does not take the trouble te favour with a refutation, took a more correct view of the matter. HILARIUS. 405 what pertained thereto. Nevertheless, His birth and rise were not like those of other men: without the divine act of the Son, who united Himself with the soul, which He created, and who by, this soul animated the material which became the body of Christ, that material would not have become a body, much less would a man have been produced. ‘The grounds or causal prin- ciples of this origin lay not in humanity; the stamina or ele- menta of this person lay in God alone; for without the divine act, Mary would not have given birth to anything at all." If we ask after that which was originally active in connection with the generation of Christ, we must go back, not to Mary, but to the Son and to the Holy Ghost.” The material contained in Mary was but the means employed by the Logos for the realization of His will of incarnation. What Mary gave, was simply the mass susceptible to the divine act of appropriation through the Logos. Substantially she gave the same for the generation of the second Adam, as the earth gave for the first Adam, with the sole dif- ference, that the second was born into our race.” The “ caro” thus acquired by Christ was able to experience pain and change; the divine aspect, on the contrary, is “indemutabilis;” it can neither lose its dominion, its omniscience, and so forth, nor fall away from, nor lose itself. The parts taken by the human and the divine in the work of incarnation having been thus set as far apart from each other as possible, the second problem presented itself for solu- tion; and to this Hilarius devoted himself with equal earnest- ness. The Person of Christ is of the earth, of the “limus” of Adam ; but it is also from heaven. How are the two things compatible? How can heaven enter into such close union with 1 De Trin. 10, 35 :—Maria licet sexus sui officio genuerit, tamen non terrenze conceptionis suscepit elementis. Genuit enim ex se corpus, sed quod conceptum esset ex Spiritu. 2 De Trin. 2, 27 :—Initia nascendi Spiritus sanctus superveniens (cf. 2, 26) et inumbrans Virtus Altissimi moliuntur. 10, 35 :—Corpus illud spiri- talis conceptionis sumsit exordium. * Compare Hil. on Ps. lxviii. c. 4 :—Ineuntium passionum non aliunde, quam ex assumtione carnis et virtus est, et potestas. Non enim incidere in Deum hic infirmitatum nostrarum terror valebat, aut exserere se nisi in carne corporis nostri tanquam in subjacente materia, potuerant passiones.— Primus homo de terree limo: et secundus Adam in hujus limi profundum de coelis descendens se ipsum tanquam ex alto veniens defixit. 406 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. earth, and earth with heaven? Hilarius found means to com- bine the two, on the one hand, by venturing to attribute to humanity a great capability of being exalted ; and, on the other hand, by forming a full enough conception of the loving con- descension of the Son. The second point claims our attention first, as the motive power of the entire process lies on the side of the divine. At the same time, we may precursorily remark, that Hilarius shows peculiar skill in setting forth the factors in the act of undergoing their process, and declines accepting any unity until justice has been done to the distinctions, and the distinctions have been conciliated by the process Hilarius frequently makes the remark, that if in Christ the Son had still retained His divine form, He could not at the same time have had a truly human form, for the humanity which He had to assume was in the form of a servant. The divine form and the servant’s form cannot subsist together in one and the same person, at one and the same time.’ In addi- tion to this, it must be remembered that the Logos was neces- sitated to take the servant’s form into Himself; only thus could a personal unity of the divine and human be brought.to_pass, and the weakness of humanity be converted into divine power. To his mind, the incarnation had accomplished nothing, unless the entire person was as truly God the Word as the man Jesus; that is, unless God was also man, and man was God.’ If, then, he were compelled to demand such an intimate “ intus- susceptio” of the human into the divine, and of the divine into the human, that each belongs to the other, and is necessary to its completeness; we see also that it devolved on him to show that the introduction of the servant’s form was compatible with 1 On Ps. lxviii. c. 25:—In forma hominis existere, manens in Dei forma qui poterat. De Trin. 9, 14 :—The ‘ concursus utriusque forme ”— that is, ‘‘et Dei et servi””—became Him not; not merely because it would have been a logical contradiction, but because the reality of the state of humiliation would thus have been done away with, the divine condescen- sion would have been reduced to a mere show, or else the Person of Christ would have been split up into a duality. 2 In De Trin. 10, 52 ff., he speaks against the division of the one Christ. GO. 52 :—Totum ei (ecclesia) Deus Verbum est, totum ei homo Christus est retinens hoc in sacramento confessionis suze unum, nec Christum aliud eredere, quam Jesum, nec Jesum aliud preedicare, quam Christum. C. 22: —Ut totus hominis filius sit. C. 54, 55. HILARIUS. 407 the idea of th divine nature, and that the latter does not by its inherent glory and majesty exclude the former. At this point Hilarius brings forward his doctrine of the “ evacuatio forme Dei.” The Son of God emptied Himself of the divine form, in order that He might exist in the servant’s form of men.' Now, wherein consisted this self-renunciation or self-evacua- tion of the divine nature? He resigned the “forma Dei;” but the “forma Dei” is identical with countenance. By the “forma Dei,” in the case of the Son, therefore, we may understand the full actuality or personality, as stamped in the countenance, and by which the Spirit appears for others.? Consequently, the subject of the “ exinanitio” or “evacuatio” was the form of the Son which shone in eternal glory. He renounced His own countenance, His “ substantia” (hypostasis ?), in order that, during the period of His earthly humiliation, the “forma servilis” might be His countenance, until, by glorifying humanity and its “forma servilis,” the Logos should have restored the glory of His countenance in the perfected God-man. ‘This implies, therefore, regarded from another point of view, that the incar- nation was not complete from the very begining; that the Logos did not all at once enter into humanity with His entire essence, but kept back His majesty in Himself, and perfectly exhibited His countenance or His personality in the man Jesus, for the first time, at His exaltation. In his view, then, the human countenance, the servant’s form, occupied the foreground during the earthly life of Christ; this, however, must not be confounded with the human Ego, for to the Ego he never alludes. On the contrary, the deity of the Son, which, having renounced its glory, had been able to unite itself perfectly with + On Ps. lxviii. c. 25:—In forma servi veniens evacuavit se 2 Dei forma. Nam in forma hominis existere manens in Dei forma qui paterat ? De Trin. 10, 50 :—Erat enim (sc. Christo) nature proprietas, sed Dei forma jam non erat, quia per ejus exinanitionem servi erat forma suscepta. On Ps. liii. c. 8, 14:—Cumque accipere formam servi nisi per evacuationem suam non potuerit, etc. 2 On Ps. lxvili. c. 25 :—Forma et vultus et facies et imago non dif- ferunt. ©. 4:—The divine nature semet ipsam exinaniens transit, ut ex Dei forma in formam servi decideret. This is also described as follows :— Substantia ei non fuit, infixo in limo profundi. The substantia existed quee assumta habebatur ; that existed no longer nec jam videbatur restare, que in aliud se evacuando concesserat. 408 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. the servant’s form, continued to be the ruling power in Christ and His soul. At the same time, he constantly repeats, that the Son Himself remained the same even in the “ exinanitio;” that He was constantly, by His own deed, by His own will, in “ exinanitio;” which, of course, implies, that the same will which maintains the “exinanitio” so long as it 1s necessary, possesses in itself the latent power to return to full and entire actuality.! This he often expresses as follows :—The divine natura, although not the “substantia” (that is, probably, v1 0- cracts), not the “ forma (or “ facies”) Dei,” remained unalter- ably His. The limit of the “exinanitio” was, that it could never advance to a renunciation of the “divina natura,’ or to the point when the “ forma servi” alone would remain in Christ without the “divina natura.” That would be Ebionism ; nay more, on that supposition, inasmuch as the Son would have lost Himself and disappeared in the servant’s form, the very purpose of His self-abasement would have been frustrated. Moreover, to the attainment of the end in view, it was neces- sary that the divine should be introduced right into the ser- vant’s form, or into the humanity, in order then to accomplish its work of exaltation as from within.? Besides, the ‘“ exina- nitio” could not then be regarded as a continuous deed, as an expression of might or power, but solely as a suffering. Had 1 De Trin. 11, 18 :—In forma enim Dei manens formam servi assumsit, non demutatus, sed se ipswm exinaniens et intra se latens (sc. in Dei forma) et intra suam ipse vacuefactus potestatem, dum se usque ad formam tem- perat habitus humani, ne potentem immensamque naturam assumte humili- tatis non ferret infirmitas, sed in tantum se virtus incircumscripta mode- raretur, in quantum oporteret eam usque ad patientiam connexi sibi corporis obedire. Tract. in Ps. Ixviu. 4. 2 On Ps. Ixviii. 25:—Aboleri autem Dei forma, ut tantum servi esset forma, non potuit. Ipse enim est et se ex forma Dei inaniens et formam hominis assumens. Evacuatio non est divinee nature interitus. Fragm. ex opere hist. ¢. 82 :—Iccireo immutabilis et inconvertibilis filius Dei, ut in assumtione hominis corruptioni potius gloriam intulerit, quam labem eeter- nitati. De Trin. 9, 14 :—Obedientia mortis non est in Dei forma, sicut nec Dei forma inest in forma servi. Per sacramentum autem evangelice dispensationis non alius est in forma servi, quam qui in forma Dei est although the evacuatio takes place. It does not abolish the identity of the subject: non alius atque diversus est, qui se exinanivit et qui formam servi accepit. Accepisse enim non potest ejus esse qui non sit.—Ergo evacuatio forme non est abolitio nature, quia, qui se evacuat, non caret sese, eb qui accipit, manet. HILARIUS. 409 He lost Himself, He would not have been able to assume humanity. For the assumption of humanity must also be con- sidered as a deed following upon the “ evacuatio.” We now come to the second momentum, the “assumtio forme servilis.’ In the view of Hilarius, the “evacuatio,” so far from being identical with, was merely the condition of, the incarnation, on the part of God, to which corresponds a further condition on the part of man... The Son of God laid aside His divine form so far as He did, in order that in Him there might be no obstacle in the way of His making the servant’s form to such a degree His own, that it might be counted as forming part of His own existence. For the same reason the humanity was not swallowed up through its union with the Logos, or its essence done away with (de Trin. 11, 48; see Note 1, page 407). But as the divine nature, on the one hand, rendered itself, as it were, susceptible of the “intus-susceptio” of the humanity, which, though originally a foreign element, it was the divine will should be appropriated ; even so was it necessary that humanity should possess a capability of being exalted to unity with the Son of God. How Hilarius conceives this to have been brought about we shall shortly see. As far as relates to the divine aspect, he makes the “assumtio forme servilis” follow upon the “evacuatio,” as the second momentum in the act of incarnation. The “evacuatio” proceeded so far that the way was prepared for the “assumtio forme servilis,’ but by no means so far as in itself to constitute the servile form. ‘That would have been a falling away of the Logos from Himself, a conversion ; suffering would thus have been introduced into the Logos. We can only avoid this passivity, this self-losing, of the Logos in the servant’s form, by supposing the assumption thereof to be a new, distinct act of the Son, who thus showed that even in the “evacuatio,’ He had maintained and had re- tained power over Himself. (Note 75.) That which belonged to the divine Natura could not be lost by the Son: the “ potestas generis sui” He retained (9, 51; 11, 48). The divine essence is not something void and indeter- minate; but contains a fulness of attributes: these attributes, therefore, pertained to the Son whilst He was in the “ forma servilis,” because the “natura Dei” remained His. Nor did they lie inactive; but were operative and benefited humanity, 410 FIRST PERIOL, THIRD EPOCH. which was to be raised to God. (Note 76.) This leads us to notice Hilarius’ doctrine of the susceptibility of human nature for God. We have, in the first place, to remark in general, the high estimate he formed of the nobility of the human-soul. It is not of foreign substance, like the body, which is taken from the earth; but springs from God, and is a likeness of the image of God (imaginis Dei exemplum), of the First-born of creation. By its thoughts and their infinite speed, the spirit imitates the omnipresence of God. It is true, the souls of men have laden themselves with guilt; but when they proceed forth from God, they are pure, and so also continued the soul of Christ. It was therefore spiritual, and of héavenly, yea, of divine origin, shin- ing with its natural brightness. The body, on the contrary, is not directly from God, but “ex aliena substantia.” The souls of men are all defiled by their entrance into the body. So also must it have happened to the soul of Christ, if His body had not been conceived of the Holy Ghost. He sanctified the inner being of the Virgin, and, breathing therein, united Himself with the nature of the human flesh. And in order that no discrepance might remain by reason of the weakness of the human body, through which the “Unio” would have been rendered impossible, the power of the Highest over- shadowed the Virgin and strengthened her weakness. In this manner, her corporeal substance was prepared for the implant- ing activity of that Spirit, which was to enter into her (of the Son).” His body thus became, indeed, different from ours,— that is, as to its attributes, not as to its substance. So far is the integrity and excellence of the body of Christ from being opposed to the idea of the human body, that we rather are to participate in its glory: and first, when we are conformed to 1 Although Hilarius speaks of different kinds of souls, he has laid down © nothing particular relative to the ‘‘species” of the soul of Christ. On Ps. cxli. (c. 4), he says,—‘* Anima Christi signis et factis Deum se pro- baverat.” * De Trin. 2, 26. For the commencement of this passage, see Note 74. It proceeds as follows :—Atque ut ne quid per imbecillitatem humani cor- poris dissideret, Virtus altissimi virginem obumbravit, infirmitatem ejus veluti per umbram circumfusa confirmans, ut ad sementivam ineuntis Spiritus efficaciam substantiam corporalem divine virtutis inumbratio tem- peraret. HILARIUS 411 the glory of the body of God (that is, of Christ), will that image of God be completely formed in us, to which regard was had from the beginning. (Note 77.) The advantages which accrued to the humanity of Christ from the consecrating and sanctifying power of the Divine Spirit, who prepared it for assumption by the Logos, are still further enhanced by the assumption itself, or by the activity of the incarnate Son of God. According to Hilarius, to Christ pertained corporeally also, natural immortality, freedom from pain, from want, etc. This must not indeed be understood to sionify that He was incapable of dying, of suffering, of hunger- ing, etc. His history shows the possibility thereof, by the actuality ; and He also grew, passing through the different ages (de Trin. 2, 24; see Note 78). On the other hand, we should not quite hit the view entertained by Hilarius, were we to suppose that the divine Sonship of Christ, and the union of humanity therewith, merely gave Him the power at every moment to rise even physically above all suffering and need, | if such were but His will. For that would be to represent the humanity of Christ as in itself needy, mortal, and so forth, even subsequently to its assumption by the Son of God; out of which passive condition it could only be raised by a particular act of will in each particular instance. Indeed, on the contrary, by the incarnation, the humanity of Christ was, strictly speaking, so completely raised above everything of the kind just mentioned, that no assaults of hostile powers could harm it or involve it in actual suffering, save when, by a special act of will, He laid Himself open to their operation, and voluntarily submitted Him- self to suffering. Hilarius’ great aim was totally to avoid repre- senting the weakness or the perfection of Christ as a physical determination and necessity; and, on the contrary, to view all His sufferings as deeds, that is, as ethical. As he refused to allow that the Son of God, by His act of self-abasement, as it were, lost Himself and reduced Himself to a fixed condition of humiliation, the necessary and physical consequence of that act (for, on the contrary, His self-abasement was the effect of con- tinuous loving acts of will, and He remained at every moment in possession of power over Himself); so neither, on the other hand, did the humanity assumed by Him, ever in any instance impose on Him the necessity of suffering or dying. Far from 412 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. that, conceived. as it was by the Holy Ghost, and personally united with the Son of God, it was in itself raised above every necessity of the kind. Indeed, in the view of Hilarius, such a necessity never did pertain to the true idea of humanity in itself, but merely to the form of humanity embodied in us. But, on the other hand, the same free will of love, which was the cause of the “evacuatio” of the Son of God, and which went through the entire period of Christ’s earthly existence, must then have become the will of the entire God-man ; consequently it must have gone on to the more concrete determination, that the God- man should freely will that which, because of the perfection of His humanity, was not a matter of necessity, to wit, the keeping back of the deification and the laying Himself open to suffering and need. That this was Hilarius’ meaning, is most apparent where the sufferings of Christ attained their climax. For Christ not to have been able to suffer at all, would have been an imper- fection, would have been a limit imposed on His love; His ethical would have been restrained by His physical nature. On the other hand, the necessity for His death must not be sought in His own spiritual or physical nature; the ground thereof Jay outside His perfect nature, in us, to whom it was His will, and it was necessary, He should become like, if He were purposed to redeem us,—like, not merely in general, as a man, but also as a man in the servile form, in the present form of our humanity. For this reason He gave Himself up, by a free act of will, to suffering and death: His very death was an act.! He who in Himself was exalted above all subjection to hostile powers from without, allowed them to force their way to Him, conceded them power, in order to conquer them, in order that they might, as it vwere, exhaust themselves on His person. In this way He demon- strated, even in suffering, His power and dominion ;—primarily, His power over His own nature, which He constituted passible, that is, accessible by suffering (for thereto also was His éfoucla necessary, John x. 18); and then in the triumph which He gained over the hostile powers by His patient endurance of suffering. But if every part of the suffering of the God-man was, in the full sense, an ethical deed, He must at every moment have had power over Himself and over His sufferings, and never have been passively lost therein. Hilarius was therefore able to * De Trin. 10, 57. 61 62; specially ¢. 11. HILARIUS, 413 say,—in the mystery of the Son of man, who is also the Son of God, we have this, that He ruled even whilst dying; and, although ruling,-died (De Trin. 10, 62, 48). It is self-evident that, as Hilarius held the suffering of Christ in its inner essence to be a deed, he was able to concede to the divine nature also a participation therein; and even in regard to this matter, to up- hold the unity of the divine and human aspects. His suffering was not merely voluntary; it was His joy: it pertained to His blessedness, for the head loves the members.’ This delight in suffering love passes over also to His members: through love, the pain which is undergone for the honour of God or for the brethren, is scarcely felt, but is forgotten ;—the less felt and the more forgotten, the more completely love in all its fulness enters into the very depths of suffering for others (De Trin. 10, 44). We find also in the writings of other teachers of the Church —for example, Epiphanius, Athanasius, etc.—substantially the same notion of the glorification or deification of human nature in Christ, >esulting from the “assumtio,” which was a reality from the very beginning. And even if they did not all agree in teaching that the humanity in union with the Logos ex- perienced no needs, but went, in this respect, some farther than others, they were all one in the conviction that the humanity of Christ by itself was subject to the necessity of death, even as is ours. Death does not belong to the idea, but merely to the present form, of humanity. Had death been a physical neces- sity for Christ, He would not have been the perfect man, and His death could not have had redeeming efficacy. They there- fore assert merely the ethical necessity, as of the birth, so also of the suffering and death of Christ ; and persist in maintaining, that, even after the act of incarnation had taken place, it lay at every moment in the power of Christ, in virtue of the indwelling of the Logos, the advantage of which felt to the humanity also, to rise above sickness and death, suffering and sorrow; in other words, His servile form was at every moment the work of His free will. MHiularius carried out this thought further, not 1 Tract. in Ps. cxxxvili. c. 26 :—Domino itaque passio ista delicize sunt, dum portas areas confringit, dum vectes ferreos conterit, dam omnem potes- tatem despoliat, dum de his in se triumphat dum eum, quem ad imaginem suam fecerat. redimit, dum deliciis paradisi restituit. In his igitur pas- sionis oblectamentis atque deliciis nox ei illuminatio est. 414 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. merely in an anti-Arian interest, but also in order that the unity of the Logos with the humanity thus assimilated to Him might be at every moment a present fact. Whatever judgment may be pronounced on his manner of carrying it out, the rigidness with which he adhered to the ethical point of view deserves so much recognition, that we ought not to be too ready with the charge of Docetism, especially as the ethical basis on which he stood enabled him to acknowledge that Christ truly suffered and really died ;—the only difference between Him and us being, that in His case they were free acts, whereas in our case they are the result of a necessity of nature. As is evident from his doctrine of the “evacuatio,” and from his frequent use of ex- pressions like “God was born; God died,” he was so far from shrinking, after the manner of Docetists, at the idea of the incarnation of the Logos and of the closest unity of the two natures, that he might rather be charged with adopting the idea of God-manhood too quickly, and without the necessary inter- mediate steps. Jor one might undoubtedly ask,—Why is the glorificatory influence of the Logos on the humanity with which He was united conceived to have been from the very beginning so great, that it could in no instance undergo suffering without a special act of self-abasement, if this same glorification had to be immediately resumed again for the sake of the work of redemption? ‘To posit a thing which must immediately after- wards be done away with, seems to be an useless labour; and the view laid down by Hilarius comes into conflict, not merely with the passages in which Christ declares Himself to be igno- rant,’ but quite as much with all true development on the part of His humanity; which he persists indeed in attributing to it, though he fails to find a fit place either for it or freedom.? The more does it deserve mention, that Hilarius himself also recognised this defect, and endeavoured to solve the problem. He sought, namely, to show not merely that there were moments 1 ** Non sibi nescivit (horam), sed nobis” (9, 51, 71); such is the turn which he found himself compelled to adopt. 2 De Trin. 2, 24:—Dei imago invisibilis pudorem humani exordii non recusavit, et per conceptionem, partum, vagitum, cunas, omnes nature nos- tre contumelias transcucurrit ; in de Trin. 9, 50, he speaks of the ‘‘ libera voluntas” of Christ, but understands thereby merely will and power, like vther Church teachers of this period—for example. Gregory Nazianzen HILARIUS. 415 of “exinanitio,’ by which the “exaltatio” of humanity, which began with the “assumtio,” was interrupted, but also that there was a “status exinanitionis,’ a “servilis habitus;” at the same time avoiding all curtailment of the idea of the God-manhood. In attaining this end, all depended on the incarnation being conceived, not as absolutely completed in one act, but as under- going a process. ‘This process, again, required to be so viewed that space was left for a stadium during which the idea of God- manhood came into inequality with itself, only, however, to restore itself from the inequality to the true equipollence of the ideal and factual. It is at this point that Hilarius displayed in a particular manner the speculative character of his mind. He by no means wished to represent the idea of the God- manhood as adequately realized all at once, but demanded for that purpose a longer process. Nor does he refer the process to the human aspect alone, but also to the divine, which submitted itself to the “evacuatio” and fell into inequality with itself, in order afterwards to restore itself to itself, in unity with human- ity. Humanity in itself, in its idea, is not inadequate to the divine: had it been possible for a perfect humanity to have been at once assumed, the “evacuatio” of the divine nature would have been unnecessary. Inasmuch, therefore, as he asserts that the “evacuatio,” which ceased at the end, was necessary at the beginning, he must have regarded the status of the humanity assumed by Him as really imperfect at first, and therefore have intended to restrict the afore-noticed glorifying influence of the Logos within certain limits. The real purpose of the idea of the “evacuatio Verbi” was to enable him to conceive the Logos as SO intimately united with the man Jesus, even whilst He was in the “forma servilis,” that the progress of the man might appear as an ever increasing return of the Logos into equality with Himself, even as the humiliation attendant on the servant’s form was a ne behind His true reality and glory on the part of the Logos. We see that on this view everything was common to the entire person at every moment, though to each aspect in its own distinctive manner. The entire person entered into inequality with itself: the actuality of each aspect, during the state of humiliation, fell short of its idea-—of the idea of the Son, of the idea of the perfect man, of the idea of the God-man. Tt was not merely the human aspect that was at first inadequate 416 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. to the divine; for, through the medium of the voluntary “ eva- cuatio,” it dragged down the divine nature also, so far as it per- mitted it, into its own inequality. ‘Non conveniebat forme utriusque (Dei et servi) concursus” (de Trin. 9, 14). As room was to be left for the “forma servilis,” the “forma Dei” must needs become latent. “Decedere ex Deo in hominem nisi ex forma Dei Deus evacuans non potuit” (de Trin. 12, 6). Seeing, then, that by means of the “evacuatio” the Son of God appro- priated to Himself the “forma servilis,” a diremption, a disturb- ance of the unity (amissio, offensio unitatis) with the divine nature, found its way into this person. (Note 79.) Not, indeed, in the sense that the unity of the Son with the Father was en- tirely done away with, or even interrupted; for otherwise the Word could not have attained the end for which He emptied Himself. He entered into humanity in its low estate, in order that God might be born into humanity :* consequently He must have retained within Himself the potence of that which He was to bring and to bestow. Only, however, by becoming like us, and unlike or unequal to Himself, that is, by entering into a state inadequate to Himself, into the “forma servilis,” was 1t possible for the Word to do away with the inequality of human- ity with itself and its idea, to make it like Himself, in the glory to which the Son should restore Himself. To this glory, how- ever, He returned not merely as the Logos, but as the God-man ; that is, created humanity was in Him and through Him trans- lated into the sphere of the divine essence. Christ, therefore, in the state of humiliation, was “dividuus a se;” He had taken up into Himself the inadequate element humanity, in order that it might be reborn in Him; but, notwithstanding all these “ sacramentorum diversitates,” He never so far fell away from Himself as no longer to be the Son and Christ, possessed of power over Himself.’ For this reason, also, it was possible for 1 De Trin. 10, 7:—Namque cum in hominem Deus natus sit, non idcirco natus est, ne non Deus maneret, sed ut manente Deo homo natus in Deum sit. Nam et Emanuel nomen ejus est, quod est,—nobiscum Dominus ; ut non defectio Dei ad hominem sit, sed hominis profectus ad Deum sit. Vel cum glorificari se rogat, non utique nature Dei, sed assumtioni humilitatis hoe proficit. (But to this belonged also the evacuatio forme Dei.) Nam hane gloriam postulat, quam ante constitutionem mundi apud Deum habuit. 2 De Trin. 10, 22:—Cum Jesus Christus et natus, et passus, et mortuus et sepultus sit: et resurrexit (that is, by His resurrection He manifested : Tt HILARIUS. 417 Him finally to restore Himself to equality with Himself (zequa- litas) ; into which equality human nature, too, is taken up. The distinction between the last and the preceding stadium becomes especially clear, when we consider that Hilarius desig- nates the third again a_birth.? The jirst birth of the Son was the eternal one out of the Father, on the ground of which He was equal to Him in all things, even in glory. The second is His birth into humanity, and into the humble form of a servant, through which, by a free act of love, He acquired a different mode of existence; He sunk Himself into humanity, in order to raise it up out of its depths into Himself. And yet, even during this relative separation from the divine unity, to which He subjected Himself by His union with humanity, He re- tained sure hold upon Himself. The overreaching power of the divine essence perfected the humanity, created a “forma Dei” out of the “forma servilis;” and so, with the perfection of the humanity, the Son was again restored to Himself. (Note 80.) And that was the third birth. The day of resurrection was the birth-day of His humanity to glory; and thenceforth Te was, as a whole (as the God-man), that which He had been before time as Logos. Although He was born to that which He had been before time, still, He was born in time to be that which He previously was not: henceforth, however, the Son of man is to be seen at the right hand of power; for humanity having been made partaker of glory after the resur- rection, advanced onwards to the brightness which the Logos had previously enjoyed; and the Son of man, enthroned at the Father's side, the mortality of the flesh having been swallowed up in immortality, celebrated His birth as the living, never: dying Son of God. Taking a survey of the whole, we find that Hilarius consi- dered the eternal Son, who created the souls of men as images of Himself, to be naturally the archetype of these souls, and, the divine Natura which had ever remained His). Non potest in his sacra- mentorum diversitatibus ita ab se dividuus esse, ne Christus sit. 1 De Trin. 9, 54:—Si nativitas hominis naturam novam intulit, et humilitas formam demutavit sub assumtione servili; nunc donatio nominis (Phil. ii. 10) forme reddit equalitatem. * De Trin. 9, 6, and Ps. cxxxviii. 19, he distinguishes a threefold state of Christ: ante hominem, in homine, post hominem. TwOtaIT: 2D 418 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. therefore, to stand in an original relationship to them; hence the possibility of the incarnation. Because of the entrance of sin, the Son, the archetype, manifested His love by being born ‘nto the servile form of the image: our archetype made itself like us. This is his predominant mode of looking at the matter. But, as Hilarius was as far as possible from regarding the assumption of humanity as a mere transitory theophany, or as a mere means of redemption, but believed humanity to have attained to eternal and permanent perfection in the glorified God-man ; he arrives, at the close of the process, to the convic- tion, that in the God-manhood the full idea of humanity was first realized, and in Christ, the creation of our race fully ac- complished. The necessity for the God-man, previously de- monstrated from the existence and nature of sin, was now traced back absolutely, and for all stadia, to the idea of our nature. Henceforth, not the Logos alone by Himself is our archetype, but the entire God-man, with body and. soul,—He who took upon Himself the likeness of our servile form, in order that we might bear the likeness of His divine form. Into that divine form were swallowed up primarily, in His person, the mortality and weakness of humanity, to the end that we also might be converted into the image of the Creator, agree- ably to the idea which God had even at the creation of the first man Believers also participate in this divine-human life. By faith they become, not merely morally like or one with Him, but essentially.” All believers have put on the one 1 Compare de Trin. 11, 49 (see Note 77) ; specially the words,—‘‘ Con- summatur itaque homo imago Dei. Namque conformis effectus gloriz corporis Dei, in imaginem Creatoris excedit secundum dispositam primi hominis figurationem.” According to this, even the first man was created under the idea of the God-man; and the idea of the ™ imago Dei” is first completely realized when man becomes conformed to the God-man. Com- ment. in Matt. c. 3, $ 2:—‘‘ Exspectatum Deo Patri manus hominem, quem assumserat, reportavit.” 2 De Trin. 8, 7, 9, 12; 11,19. Compare, in connection with what fol- lows, the Preefatio (pp. 24 ff.) to the Opp. Hilar. ed. Maur.; de Trin. 8, 13 :—‘ Eos qui inter Patrem et Filium voluntatis ingerunt unitatem, inter- rogo, utrumne per nature veritatem hodie Christus in nobis sit, aut per concordiam voluntatis? Si enim vere Verbum caro factum est, et vere nos Verbum carnem cibo dominico sumimus, quomodo non naturaliter manere in nobis existimandus est qui et naturam carnis nostre, jam insepa- rabilem sibi, homo natus agsumsit, et naturam carnis sue ad naturam eter- HILARIUS. 412 Christ, and have become the same. We put Him on in baptism ; but the holy Eucharist is of special significance to Hilarius, in this respect. Christ is in the Father through His divine nature; we, on the contrary, are in Him through His corporeal birth, and He is in us through the sacraments. In this way, a gradually as cending, perfect unity is brought about. We remain in Him, He in the Father; but, remaining in the Father, He remains also in us, so that we also advance onwards to unity with the Father; for in Him, who by His nature, on the ground of birth, is in the Father, we also dwell by our nature, even as He dwells in us by His nature. Hilarius employs the strongest and boldest expressions to designate the universal sionificance of the incarnation of Christ, in relation to our entire race, maintaining that therewith something was potentially done, not merely for, but to us all; because human nature, in its entirety, was reborn and united with God in Him. Tract. in Ps. i. ce. 16: “Ut et Filius hominis esset Filius Dei, naturam in se universe carnis assumsit, per quam effectus vera vitis genus in se universe propagationis tenet.” (Note 81.) His humanity is the city on the hill; in Him, as in a city, the human race is gathered together; accordingly, He who thus gathers us to- gether in Himself is the unity of many, the “civitas;” we, bound together in Him, participating in His body, are the inhabitants of the city, we are one in Him. For our sake the Son of God Himself laid the foundation of His humanity, in order that, having become man, He might take to Himself, out of the Virgin, the nature of the flesh, and that, by means of this marriage and union, the body of the entire human race might be sanctified in Him. As His will in assuming a body was to see all rooted in Himself, so was it His will to give Him- self back to Himself in all, by means of His invisible nature. Not that He, through whom man was created, needed to become man; but we needed that God should become flesh and dwell in us, that is, that He should take up His abode in the inmost essence of hu- manity in general, by the assumption of one man (carnis unius). nitatis sub sacramento nobis communicande carnis admiscuit? Ita enim omnes unum sumus, quia et in Christo Pater est, et Christus in nobis est. Quisquis ergo naturaliter Patrem in Christo negabit, neget prius naturaliter vel se in Christo, vel Christum sibi inesse.” (C. 15. 420 FIRST PERIOD. THIRD EPOCH. As might be anticipated, we find Hilarius taking a corre- sponding view of the work of redemption. Having assumed our sinful body, Christ bore our sin (de Trin. 10, 47). All the weakness which He took upon Himself, He bore voluntarily, translating Himself into our nature and its weaknesses. ‘T’his weakness, therefore, can only be understood when its substitu- tionary significance is recognised. We have previously referred to this point. But He did not merely wish to stand in our stead ; no, we died in Him; in Him humanity as a whole sits at the right hand of the Father ; in Him all peoples behold their own resurrection and perfection ; every momentum of His history becomes, as it were, an active potence to reproduce the same history in men. (Note 82.) It is evident, therefore, that Hilarius, equally with Apol- linaris, aimed at showing the union of the two aspects of Christ to be so intimate, that one should be warranted in saying,— “totus hominis filius totus est Dei filius,’ and vice versa; that is, this person is entirely man, or the perfect man, and it be- longs to His perfection to be also God; and vice versa,—this person is entirely God; in other words, His humanity was not a mere possession or dwelling-place of the Logos, but a momen- tum of Himself, apart from which no complete and exhaustive conception could be formed of Him. At this point we see very clearly that his aim almost coincided with that of Apollinaris, only that he goes to work more carefully, and does justice to the distinction, ere attempting the union of the two aspects, as, in fact, an union is nothing, if it be not the union of elements that are distinct. Quite as clear is it also, that there is a very wide difference between the Christology of Hilarius and that of a later period, when, on the one hand, the distinction between the two aspects was exaggerated, and, on the other hand, their union was effected solely by the subjection of the human aspect; that is, by curtailing it relatively to the divine. In short, Hilarius had not yet, like a later age, repudiated the truth lying at the basis of Monophysitism. Having the same object in view as Apollinaris, to wit, the unity of the person, he showed his superiority to him particularly by attaining it in more complete measure, and without the sacrifice of the human soul. On the | contrary, he employed the soul for the purpose of denoting the personal unity of Christ. Furthermore, he did not, for the HILARIUS—ATHANASIUS. 421 sake of the unity, resort to the representation of the humanity of Christ, that is, the mvedua, as eternal, complete, and im- mediately identical with the Logos. He maintained that the human created nature was susceptible of being so appropriated by the Logos, that creation might pass over into the incarnation of the Logos. The Logos, however, brought this to pass, in that He stripped Himself of His actual glory by an act of His loving will; having done which, He became capable of incar- nation—a work which was demanded indeed by love, but was not physically, immediately, eternally accomplished. Undoubtedly, however, the unity of the Person of Christ, as delineated by him, although settled as to its main outlines, bore no reference to the question raised in connection with Apol- linaris—Can the human soul of Christ be conceived without freedom of will? ) ai / ; 4 ; 1 A cA ay F q oe : ‘ : . “y i 4 oye! Me « ‘ q x : A ey ‘ be Fee “a oe we > a q a 7 ‘ ¥ ¥ ar 7 v a n° a4 5 ’ ae te . be f i LM Ai, : ¢ ie ‘ 2 vy " 1 a, A ly isn . . A > phys if Gj “ Si “i ran ( afl hi ApS, ru * ; es ! ty tn i bad , bie ff eet pha “Bis nis hy Hes nhs yu - j a Tn ie ee Dieta pa | ‘ Avs ey sre a DP ae re em «| ee aa wee a Be eis. “api Te ester ti aps GEE ye ot Eh. i ; i | tee Uae! @ Sct Nae ee ifs se pore: “ep ve eae ts dia a Ca et, HE! Mima raat Ms iit Ce ‘Sturt *)»¢in = ’ ‘ © id sf APPENDIAZ Atak ia ec a NOTES. Note 1, page 4. Eprpu. |. c. 1:—xal ofror ta oteped TOD KNpiYWaToS [ELeo} caow. O. 32:—tl wderet Huds 4 Tod “Iwavvov ’Atroxaduyis ; Whether they rejected the doctrine of the Logos altogether, or not, is not quite clear from what Epiphanius reports. It is true he designates them (c. 3), Tavtatracw GddotTpiovs TOD KNpUYyLa- Tos THS adnOelas ; but, from the connection, we should judge him to refer to their rejection of the Gospel of John. Besides, the name Alogi was given to them, not because of their rejec- tion of the doctrine of the Logos, but because they rejected the strongest witness for it in the canon,—a course the more irra- tional, as, apart from this critical point (c. 4), Ta toa piv muotevew Soxodot, and as they protested against being at all charged with the Ebionism and Docetism of Cerinthus. They represent Cerinthus as the author of the Gospel which they repudiate. Epiphanius was quite justified in entertaining a low opinion of such criticism. The isolated voices which in recent times have attached importance to this criticism, have given in their adherence, not to its positive, but solely to its negative aspect, that John was not the author of the Gospel which bears his name. But the two things cannot be separated. On the contrary, an attentive reading of Her. 51 shows that, in their view, the beginning of the Gospel—which passes so rapidly from the 6 Adyos cdpe éyévero to the calling and witness of the Bap- tist; contains no reference to a history of the childhood of Christ ; at once brings the Incarnate One into connection with 432 APPENDIX. the Baptist; in chapter i. 6 (compare 1. 11) appears to repre- sent the Baptist as having made his appearance prior to the incarnation, and first mentions the act of baptism supplement- arily,—was fitted to favour the heresy of Cerinthus. This is the abrupt feature, the feature favourable to Docetism, which they supposed themselves to find in the Gospel of John; and the contradictions which they discover between the fourth and the other three Gospels may be all reduced to this one point. Herein lies the reason of their doctrinal criticism; and it is useless for Heinichen to attempt to show, on a priort grounds, to wit, from the malice of Epiphanius, and so forth (pp. 42 ff.), that the Alogi attributed the Apocalypse alone to Cerinthus. If they followed the example of others in regard to this latter point, it is easy to see that they might the more strongly incline to use similar language relative to the Gospel ; nay more, I should be almost surprised if modern critics did not adopt this view of the prologue, and, with the Alogi, find Cerinthianism in it. What they otherwise say,—namely, that according to the first three Gospels, one Passover alone took place during the official life of Christ; according to John, two,—does not give a very favourable idea of their ability for historical criticism. For the first they derived not from the Synoptics, but from a false explanation of the passage relating to the gracious year of the Lord, rather usual at that time; and the second is false, for, according to John, more than two Easter festivals occurred during the interval between the bap- tism and the death of Christ. Finally, also, their doctrinal acuteness must have been very limited, or else they could never have so completely failed to see the relation of the Gospel and Kpistles of John to Docetism and Ebionism. The Alogi ap- pear to have laid chief stress on the practical intelligence, not without a certain degree of superficial illuminism. Compare Neander’s “Church History” 2, 908 (Germ. ed.). They can- not be shown to have had Marcionitic tendencies. We may remark by the way, that the Alogi did not venture to describe the Gospel of John as a new work; but completely harmonized with the tradition of the Church in relation to the date of its composition. Indeed, Cerinthus was a contemporary of the Gospel of John. ‘This testimony, given as it was about the year 170 after Christ, deserves notice. Had they had before NOTES. 433 them a single trace of the recent origin of the Gospel of John, they must certainly have made it the chief basis of their attack. Norte 2, page 6. It may be justly questioned whether this Theodotus did deny the supernatural birth of Christ. At all events, the words of Tertullian, in “de preescr. heeret.” 53, imply the contrary,— he maintained that Christ was a mere man, and denied that He was God, though he believed Him to be born of the Holy Ghost from the Virgin Mary, “sed hominem solitarium atque nudum, nulla alia pre coeteris nisi sola justitiz auctoritate.” Theodoret also says (Her. fab. 2, 5),—“ He taught the like doc- trine with Artemon.” The testimony of Epiphanius, who attri- butes to him the words (Her. 54),—“ Christ was born of the seed of a man,”’—cannot prove the contrary. For, in the first place, Epiphanius makes the same remark concerning his school, which, so far as we are acquainted with Theodotus the Argen- -tarius, is not correct. In the second place, it does not follow, from the denial of the birth from a virgin, even if it should be attributed to the elder Theodotus, that he therefore denied the supernatural birth of Christ. For Theodotus might still have assumed a divine act in connection with the origin of Jesus; nay more, he did assume this, according to the testimony of Epiphanius himself. He says that Theodotus appealed to the circumstance of its being written, not “the Spirit of the Lord will be in thee” (yevjcetas év coi); but, “the Spirit of the Lord will come upon thee” (Luke i. 35): by which he intended, on the one hand, to acknowledge the action of God in connec- tion with the birth of Christ; and, on the other hand, to exclude the incarnation of the Holy Spirit (compare Epiph. 54, 3), or of the Logos, if with Justin Martyr we understand mvetywa and duvamus to signify the Xeyos. He deemed Christ to be the prophet who mediates between God and men; retaining hold, however, solely on the humanity of Christ, and appealing merely to Deut. xviii Lays Ser xvid selsaelin on Actsiine22 s\ LiDim.i. 5. His mediatorship he undoubtedly regarded as grounded in His higher divine gifts, and, above all, in His righteousness. Nay, further, when we consider that, according to Epiphanius, he was a learned man, who stood in connection with many heretics, and when we remember, besides, that his disciple Theodotus the VOL. IT. 2 E 434 APPENDIX. Money-changer evinced an affinity with the Valentinians, and was the founder of the Melchizedekians, we may very fairly raise the question, whether Epiphanius did not misunderstand the position, “Jesus was born of human seed,” if he really did lay it down. For, in the Excerptis Theodoti in Clemens Alex- andrinus (whose doctrinal principles Neander, for example, in his “Genetische Entwickelung, etc.,” p. 189, attributes to the Money-changer, and which certainly belongs to this school), much is said of the orépya appnvixov (see 2, 21, 39, 40), from which the elect souls are derived, and Christ in particular (17). In this case, however, the o7épwa appnvixoy is said to denote Christ’s origin from the codua. Norte 3, page 7. Theodoret, Her. Fab. 2, 6:—Tods 6& Meryicedexcavors Tuhpa pep evar TovTwy (the Theodotians) ¢act, cal’ év O€ ovo Sabwveiv, To TOV Medyucedex Svvapiy Twa Kar Oelav Kal peyio- cnv brodapPdvew Kat eixdva dé abtod Tov Xpiorov yeyevjoGat. "Hp£e Sé tijs aipécews TavTys addos OcdSoros apyvpopouBos THY réyynv. Tertuil. de preescript. heret. 55 :—Alter post hune (after the Byzantine Theodotus) Theodotus hereticus erupit, qui et ipse introduxit alteram sectam, et ipsum hominem Chris- tum tantummodo dicit ex spiritu sancto ex Virgine Maria con- ceptum pariter et natum, sed hune inferiorem esse, quam Mel- chisedech.—Nam illum Melchisedech preecipuze gratize coelestem esse virtutem, eo quod agat Christus pro hominibus, deprecator et advocatus ipsorum factus: Melchisedech facere pro coeles- tibus angelis atque virtutibus. Nam esse illum usque adeo Christo meliorem, ut dmrdrap sit, durjrap sit, ayeveadoyntos sit, cujus neque initium, neque finis comprehensus sit aut compre- hendere possit. Christ is, therefore, merely compared with Mel- chisedek in the Epistle to the Hebrews. Note 4, page 8. As further disciples of the elder, we find mentioned Ascle- piades, Hermophilus, Apollonides, Natalius (Euseb. 1. c.). So completely do these later Ebionites betray their connection with Gnosticism, which had notwithstanding despised the human aspect of the Person of Christ, that the Theodotus mentioned by Clemens Alexandrinus (xe. 2) gave even to baptism a similar NOTES. 435 meaning to that given it by older Gnostics, in order to be quite certain of describing the human aspect of Christ as that which presented the ovcéa. Instructive in relation to the conception of ovcia at this period, is the fragment of Clemens Alexandrinus in Fabric. Opp. Hippolyti, T. 2, 74. The fundamental idea is To Ka?’ éavtod vpeotos, whether it be inorganic or gurév, or éurpvyov aicOntixov, CHov, or, in addition to the latter, Noyexdv also, like man. Ovcia, therefore, is always the essential element of a thing, its substance. Hence we can see how, in certain circumstances, ovaia might be used to denote that which we understand by Ego or personality ; only that ovc/a then stands for the completely undefined notion of personality. In the Tri- nitarian Controversy, during the fourth century, odcia and tmo- oTaclis were separated. Compare also Ang. Mai Collectio nova, L 7, 52 ff.; Suicer..Thesaur. s. v. Norte 5, page 12. Baur |. c. pp. 297 ff. attributes greater importance to the inoral perfection of Christ in connection with His glorification, than the authorities warrant him in doing. Nay more, in op- position to his own account (according to which, on the one hand, divine Wisdom exerted a permanent influence on, and heightened the spiritual and moral power of Christ, and on the other hand, there dwelt in the man Jesus a divine prin- ciple, developing itself in Him, p. 298), he remarks in con- clusion (p. 305),—“ The divine Logos works, it is true, upon the man, but the Logos is properly and essentially merely the inner man himself” (nowhere does Paul go so far, but merely compares the Logos in Christ, in so far as He is a mere quality and not hypostatical, with another common personification, the inner man, which also simply signifies a zrowdrns) ; “and man therefore can, by himself, through the progressive development and perfection of his moral power, arrive at divine dignity.” Such an universalization of the divine Sonship cannot be his- torically established; nor can the idea of the man Jesus raising Himself to perfection by moral power. On the other hand, Neander, in avoiding these faults, has wrongly overlooked the moral element in Christ's poxomn and pabnou. 436 APPENDIX. Note 6, page 12. In other respects also, Paul evinced little honesty. Eusebius styles him xpuiivous, admatydos (7, 29). In the matter of the doctrine of the Trinity, he endeavoured to accommodate him- self to the Church expressions, Holy Ghost and Word. Thus he teaches also a N6yos wrpodopixds. Anacephal. 2, 146 :—royov mpodopixov avtov (Tov Xpiatov) axnwatlcas (comp. Theodoret. Her. Fab. 2, 8). Naturally, this Adyos is impersonal; He is merely God conceived in a particular ézwolg or activity. Huse- bius tells us (7, 29), that at the Synod of Antioch, held in the year 269 on Paul’s account, a learned presbyter, by name Malchion, compelled him to give utterance to his real opinions, after he had for a long time taken refuge behind ambiguities. At this Synod there were present, besides a great number of other teachers, Firmilian from Cappadocia, the brothers Gre- gory Thaumaturgus and Athenodorus, and so forth (see Euse- bius 7, 28, 30). They all agreed in describing Paul’s doctrine as an innovation, a revival of the already condemned heresy of Artemon ;—indeed, their confession contained already a more fully developed, far higher doctrine of the Son of God and of Christ. Paul, on the contrary, held an isolated position in the discussions of the Synod. In this respect, there was a marked difference between his age and that of Arius. Arte- monites there undoubtedly continued to exist, but they did not hold a position within the Church (Kuseb. 5, 283; and 7, 30, ed. Heinichen 1. c. p. 404). Still, Paul does not seem to have entirely lacked disciples, although they too were excluded after the Synod of Antioch (compare Athan. de Synod. c. 26). It is simply one of that scholar’s daring, but historically unjustifi- able propositions, when Baur (1. c. p. 305) maintains that Paul's view, and that too in the form in which he gives it (see Note 5), is to be regarded as a general type of a determinate doctrinal system. It is true, he was Bishop of Antioch, where we shall find kindred views subsequently upheld by Lucian, but still Lucian himself was very different from Paul. Note 7, page 19. Compare, besides the above, Melito in Routh 1, 115;—he taught Oedv dpod Te Kal avOpwrop Tédevov, Sv0 ovcias : further— NOTES. 437 TO adnbes Kai abavractov Ths uxijs adtod Kat Tob cépyaros THs Kal nas avOpwrivns procws. ¥ urther, may be compared Socrates, H. E. 3, 7:—ottw yap waves of aN aor Epo) mept ToUTOU Noyov Seay GaauT es éyypahov nuty Katédutrov' Kat yap Eipnvatos Te Kal Krjpns, "Arronwadpwos Te o Leparronirns Kal Sepatriav euapvyov tov évavOpwrncavta év Trois trovnbeiow avTots NOYoLS WS OmoroyoUpEVvoY adTois ddcKovoLW* ov p\v Gra cal y da Bypudrrov tov Piraderdgias rhs év’ ApaBia émlaKxorrov yevouévn ctvocos ypadovca ByptAXw Ta abta rapadédoxev. ‘Dpuyévns dé Tavtayod év Tots pepopévors abrod BiPrLous, uabv- xov Tov évavOpwrijcavta oidev. Kusebius and Pamphilos testify that Origen, he goes on to say, was not the first to lay down the principle ; addAda tHv THs éxKAnolas MUOTLEND Eppnvedoas Tapa- doow. These words, like the commencement of the chapter, in which he believed it necessary as it were to justify Athanasius and the bishops of the Synod of Alexandria who taught that Christ had an human soul against the charge of innovation, suf- ficiently prove that that doctrine had not, up to this time, been completely adopted by the Church ;—neither as to all the mo- menta thereof, nor with sufficient insight into the full conse- quences of its denial. NorTE 8, page 20. Adv. Prax. 20, 26. When Baur (I. c. p. 254) maintains that the polemic of these Monarchians (as also of the Alogi) against the Church’s doctrine of the hypostatical Logos is in- compatible with the supposed fact of the Gospel of John hay- ing already long been in existence and operation in Asia, I can only say, that I am surprised, and that it betrays a misappre- hension of the course of development run by the doctrine of the Logos.—W hat was it not possible for heretics to do, who, to use the words of Irenzeus, like bad wrestlers, were accustomed to iay convulsive hold on one member of the truth? Finally, like Theodotus of Byzantium, Praxeas also recognised the Gospel of John, though he at the same time clung to his theory; not to mention other more recent and more pertinent cases (compare adv. Prax. 23-25). As to the Romish Church, that is, the pretendedly Ebionitical Church,-—if it had been really Ebioni- tical, it must plainly have taken the greatest offence at Praxeas. Whereas, on the contrary, we know from Tertullian that at first 438 APPENDIX. he found in Rome much sympathy, even with the Bishop him self. How is it possible, then, to regard the favourable recep- tion accorded to Praxeas as a proof of the Ebionism of the Church at Rome in the second century? Supposing the Church did incline to Patripassianism prior to the coming of Praxeas, they must have believed that the Most High God Himself appeared in Christ, though not a particular hypostasis ;—for re- gard to the divine unity prevented them believing the latter If we take into consideration, that the teachers who at that time taught most definitely that the Son was a distinct hypostasis, did not free themselves from a certain measure of Subordina- tianism, which was favourable to Arianism or Kbionism, we are compelled to say,—Patripassianism was really further from Ebionism than these teachers of the Church; and that, what was intended to prove the Ebionism of the Romish Church, is a proof to the contrary. A fresh warning not to treat the ideas, “ Judaizing Christianity” and “ Ebionism,” as interchangeable. Judaizing the Patripassians may be termed, because they clung so rigidly to the unity of God in the Old Testament sense; but they were not therefore Ebionites. Tor the one God in whom they believe, does not abide shut up in Himself, but manifests His essence in the form of actuality ; appears in, nay more, be- comes, a man. Note 9, page 23. The passage runs as follows (¢. 27) :—“ Et de hoc queeren- dum, quomodo sermo sit caro factus. Utrumne quasi transfigu- ratus in carne, an indutus camem? Immo indutus. Ceterum Deum immutabilem et informabilem credi necesse est, ut eeter- num. ‘Transfiguratio autem interemtio est pristini. Omne enim, quodcunque transfiguratur in aliud, desinit esse, quod fuerat, et incipit esse, quod non erat. Deus autem neque desinit esse, neque aliud potest esse.—Si ex transfiguratione et demuta- tione substantize caro factus est, una jam erit substantia Jesus ex duabus, ex carne et spiritu mixtura quedam, ut electrum ex auro et argento, et incipit nec aurum esse, 1. e. spiritus, neque argentum, i. e. caro, dum alterum altero mutatur et tertium quid efficitur. Neque ergo Deus erit Jesus, sermo enim desiit esse, qui caro factus est; neque caro, 1. e. homo, caro enim non proprie est, qui sermo fuit. Ita ex utroque neutrum est, NOTES. 439 aliud longe tertium est, quam utrumque.” Hippolytus informs us that this was the view held by Beron. My opinion is not that Praxeas actually taught the view in question; but that it appeared to Tertullian a possible and nearly-lying deduction from his theory—nay more, to constitute a proper termination thereto. We may here beforehand direct attention to the cir- cumstance, that Beron in Hippolytus, and at a later date Apol- linaris, arrived at similar conclusions from similar premises. Servetus and Schwenkfeld are examples of the same thing in recent times. Norte 10, page 28. Epiphan. her. 57, 8. Tl ody épe? Nontos év tH attod dvo- nola; pn €v TO Olpave® capE Fv; and so forth :—which words are partially borrowed by Hippolytus (c. Noet.),—TV otv Syret 3 pate pel, OTL ev ovpav@ capE Hv; C.17:—od yap Kata pavraciay 1} TpoTny, AN adnOas yevowevos avOpwros hv. It would seem, therefore, that the theory of Noetus contained, though in vague outlines, the doctrine of the wia pious cecap- Kowevn advanced at a later period; naturally, with the differ- ence, that he repudiates the Trinity, and consequently refers the incarnation, with the 7a@yTov, etc., not to the Logos, but to the Father Himself. At this point, therefore, it becomes for the first time clear, that even now it was necessary to oppose the atpertov dvaddolwtov, acvyyutov of the two natures, al- though not in these precise terms, to those who aimed at con- stituting the Father and humanity an unity without distinction in Christ. At a higher stage, the very question which now occupied the Church in relation to the Father, was raised again in relation to the Logos. Had this position of the matter been properly understood, the chief objection against the genuine- ness of Hippolytus’ work against Beron must have fallen to the cround of itself. Norte 11, page 29. Compare “ Hippolytus contra Beronem et Helicen” (cara Bypwvos cai" HA Xuxos), in Fabric. 1, 225, who conjectures that we ought to read, cal 7AtKwTa@v aipetixov. I consider the work from which these fragments were taken, and which bore the title mept Ocoroyias Kai capKwcews, to be genuine. The eight frag- 440) APPENDIX. ments relating to Beron appear to me to be taken from the larger work of which the treatise against Noetus formed a part: —indeed, the Biblioth. Max. iii. 261 introduces the treatise against Noetus with the similar title, “De Deo trino et uno et de mysterio incarnationis.” Its commencement also shows that it formed part of a greater whole. The work appears, too, to have been designated “Memoria Heeresium” and “adversus omnes heereses.” The arguments against its genuineness, so far as they deserve consideration, are the following (compare Christ. Aug. Salig’s “ De Eutychianismo ante Eutychen.” 1723, pp. 26 ff.; Hiinell’s “De Hippolyto Episcopo,” 1828, p. 41) :— 1. His style of representation is heavy and obscure; his proofs are philosophical, not exegetical :—both which things are opposed to the manner of Hippolytus. But the work, although requiring thought, is not more difficult to understand than, for example, many passages of the treatise against Noetus. In the latter, in particular, the entire discussion of the doctrine of the Trinity is quite as difficult, and its tone quite as philosophical. Besides, it must be borne in mind, that we only pessess fragments of the work against Beron, selected for a particular purpose, and relating to a subject which is comparatively little fitted for an exegetical treatment.—2. The work presupposes a definite heresy, which reminds us of Apollinaris and Kutyches (Hinell, p. 42); nay more, the word évépyeva, which plays so great a part here, reminds us of the Monotheletic controversies. And we cannot suppose the author to have refuted an heresy which had not yet been devised.—We have already subjected this reason to a preliminary examination in Note 10. Only those can attach importance to it, who fail to perceive how necessary it was in the development of Christology that, prior to the deter- mination of the doctrine of the Trinity, the same synusiastic theories should make their appearance, as were set forth at a higher stage, and in a more fully developed form, subsequently to the Council of Nicea. After the Nicene Council, it was regarded as a settled point, that the divine in the Person of Christ was the Logos, who is decidedly distinct from the Father ; but there were not a few (as the Monophysitic controversies from the time of Apollinaris onwards show) who knew of but one method of securing the divine-human unity of the Person, to wit, by clinging to the unity of nature; for though, in itself, NOTES. 441 it consisted of two momenta, they represented these momenta as passing over into each other. Was it not necessary, then, that prior to the Nicene Council,—at a time when, though the conception of the divine in Christ in its relation to the Father was still a very indeterminate one, the unity of the Person of Christ, the union in Him of the divine and human, was unques- tionably recognised,—there should be preludes of the attempt to view the divine and human aspects of the Person of Christ in each other? Is not the history of Christology even during the pre-Nicene period full of such attempts? But a simple reference to what has preceded is enough to show, that Beron by no means stood alone in the first half of the third century. Tertullian, as we have previously shown (p. 23 f.), makes fre- quent allusions to heretics, who endeavoured to establish the unity of the Person of Christ by representing the one nature as passing into the other (transfiguratio; in Hipp. c. Noet. 17, tpom). The objection which is derived from the word évepyeva scarcely deserves a refutation. If the expression Geavdprxy évépyeva, or some such other one, had been used, it might be suspicious; but no such expression can be found in the frag- ments. Indeed, I cannot understand how it is possible to find anything particular in the word, when we know from the writ- ings, for example, of Origen and Paul of Samosata, that 1t was in common use at that period.—3. The argument drawn from Theodoret’s not adducing any testimonies from this work in his refutation of the Apollinarists, is allowed to be feeble even by Hinell himself; but it completely loses its force when we take into consideration the fragments preserved by others from the work “de Theologia et Verbi incarnatione” (Fabr. 1, 235; 2,45; A. Mai Coll. Nov. T. 7, 14, 68), and which harmonize completely with the otherwise well accredited doctrine of Hip- polytus.—4. What does Hiinell mean by denying the first of these fragments (Fabr. 2, 45) to be the work of Hippolytus, because the words, 7d Oérew eyes 6 Oeds, ob TO px Oérewv, do not seem to him to betray the lover of philosophy? Does not the fragment in Fabr. 1, 280, from the “Cantic. trium puer- orum,” harmonize most fully with this theory of the freedom of the will? Does not the decided protest raised against all cperrov in God, in the first fragment c. Beron, agree perfectly with the procedure of Hippolytus, in attributing merely volition 442 APPENDIX. and refusing to attribute non-volition or permission to God, for fear of introducing a tpewtov into His essence?—5. That, further, Hippolytus most decidedly opposed the duality of the natures to every species of cvyxvaus thereof, and that the terms ovyxXvels, dxpavtos, TpoTn, évépyera (c. Beron, Fragm. 5, 8, 1), were certainly familiar to him, is plain, for example, from c. Noet. 17, and Pfaff’s fragment in Fabr. 1, 282. No less is the early character of the work evident from the circumstance, that where later writers say ojoovotos, it uses the terms ouoduns and oudduros; whereas opoovotos never occurs at all. See Note 4. , Nore 12, page 41. Baur’s view (1. c. 284 ff.) does not square with the words of Eusebius. For how could Beryll have taught that the matpixn Oedtys (not merely dvvayus) was in Christ, if his con- ception of Christ were Ebionitical, essentially the same as Arte- mon’s? We should then have expected a totally different description of Beryll’s views, and a totally different polemic against them: moreover, it 1s scarcely likely that an Ebionite would have so readily yielded ground to Christian truth as Beryll is said to have done. Baur translates as though, according to Eusebius, Beryll denied the @eorns of Christ; but he merely denied the i8/a @edrns prior to the incarnation, that is, the hypostatical Logos with pre-existence, scarcely, however, His post-existence. For, as Fock justly remarks, the passage in Kusebius constantly uses the present of the Redeemer, and alludes to Him as one still present. Besides, he was not charged with error on this point; and from our statement of his views it will be evident, that he could have had no ground for representing the Person of Christ as transitory, but that, in his case (as already in that of Beron), Patripassianism had taken the forward step of ensuring the eternity of the humanity of Christ. If it could be affirmed, in the manner in which Baur affirms it, that Beryll believed the humanity to be the personific element in Christ, and conceived the divine to be a mere power, he must have laid the greatest stress on the soul of Christ, because, without it, a human personality would be inconceivable. Instead of that, we find that the Synod, which addressed an epistle to Beryll, gave special prominence to the NOTES. 443 soul of Christ (Socr. H. E. 8, 7). Grammatically, also, this interpretation is inadmissible. 1. The most natural explanation is, that the words, Oeornta idiav éxyew, have the same subject as the preceding words—rov xuptov py Tpovpertavat. Now, in the latter, «Upuos evidently stands for the higher nature of Christ; for Beryll would not have merited blame for denying pre-existence to the human nature or to the divine-human unity. Consequently, the higher nature of Christ must also be the subject of the words, OedrnTa idlav ovd« Exew ; and the meaning cannot be that which Baur brings out, to wit, “the humanity of Christ had no iSia Oedrns”” (where idia, moreover, would be com- pletely superfluous) ; but, “the higher nature of Christ had no isla OedTys, as had the Logos or Son;” the divine in general, the Oedrns marprx alone was in Him. Only when we thus take the iSia Oedrns, in agreement with what precedes, as equivalent to idla, that is, Tod viod OedTyTa, does the antithesis TAT pLKn Oedrns become clear.—2. Baur takes the word é€utronuTever Gat in the sense—“to be a citizen alongside of a citizen ;” that is, the expression implies that the matpikn Oeorns merely dwelt, as it were, side by side with another citizen, to wit, the personal humanity of Jesus; from which he deduces the further conclu- sion, that Beryll conceived the indwelling of God in Christ, under the category of influence and moral union. But, even supposing the explanation were lexicographically justifiable, the conclusion referred to would be too hasty. For, inasmuch as, on the explanation adopted, two persons must be supposed to have co-existed in Christ; why should this be reduced to a mere influence of the divine power? Baur ought rather to have attributed to Beryll the assumption of a double person- ality in Christ. Besides, the works of Hippolytus (which Baur, it is true, has left unnoticed) show us, that the word é€u7roX- revecOas was used in an entirely different sense. As eTrLonpLla was employed even at this time to denote the incarnation, so the Church, which repudiated the notion of a duality of per- sons, and of the separate personality of the human nature, in Christ, adopted the term éumontteveoOat, which, with its dative, was used as about an equivalent to évavOpwrety (com- pare, for example, adv. Noet. 12 with 4). So that this word can by no means be regarded as having an Ebionitic stamp.— 3. Finally, as regards the word Teovypady), a more careful con- 444 APPENDIX. sideration of the writers of this period shows us, that we must be very cautious in transferring our idea of personality, in the sense of the Ego, to them. Our idea of personality, notwith- standing its apparent simplicity, presupposes very complicated processes of reflection; and we shall altogether fail to see that the Church’s doctrine of the Person of Christ and of the Trinity made real progress, if (as I did myself in the first edi- tion of this work, and as Baur repeatedly does) we start with the presupposition, that our idea of personality was familiar to every period, instead of regarding it as a result of the conflicts of many centuries. Only by keeping these remarks in view can the changes in the use of such terms as ovola, irdataats, mpocwmov, be understood and followed. For example, “ own proper personality,” is not a correct rendering of the words, idia ovalas meprypady) (although such is Neander’s opinion; see his Church History 1. c. 1020, Note 1, German Edition) ; they signify rather simply, “circumscription,” “determination,” and contain directly no trace of the “Ego.” In the formation of this expression, on the contrary, we find an unmistakeable re- flection of the point from which ancient thinkers started in seeking the idea of human personality, to wit, limitation through the body, or individuality. See Note 4; and compare Niigels- bach’s “ Homerische Theologie,” Section Seventh. Of course there is an analogous specific distinction between those who regarded the divine, and those who regarded the human, as the proper substance of the Person of Christ, on the one hand, and, on the other hand, between those who represent the divine nature alone, and those who represent the human nature alone, as the personific element; only that, until a determinate idea of personality has been arrived at, he who says merely, “ Christ was filled with divine power or OedrTns,” might mean the same as he who says, “God dwelt personally in Christ,”—namely, if the former does not apply the word personality also to the humanity. For the rest, the word Tepvypady was applied already at an early period to God, or the pre-existent Logos. Compare above in connection with Theodot. Excerp. 10, 19; Orig. in Joh. 1, 42, Vol. iv. 47. There it is equivalent to iToatacis. On the other hand, in Hippol. c. Ber. Fragm. 1, we read,—'O dXoyos—vorxiis capKds Trepuypadijs aVATYOMLEVOS —mTdons &Ew Tepiypadhs pewevnxer. Fragm. 4: ‘H Oedrntos NOTES. 445, évépyea Tdaons éxTos Kata piow Treprypadis Suapévovoa b.é- Aapape Sia capKos puces TeTEpacpEryjs ov yap TépuKe TeEpt- ypaherOar yernth pice TO Kata piow ayévntov. There, repi- ypady) is not equivalent to b7dcracts, but signifies “limit.” Nore 13, page 43. The same ambiguity characterizes his doctrine also, accord- ing to the account given of it by Kusebius. It contains the con- tradiction that, on the one hand, in the interest of Monarchian- ism, the pre-existence of the Logos and His ida Oeorns are denied, and no step is taken in advance of the simple divine or Tatpixn Oeorns: on the other hand, the entire mode of ex- pression would lead us to suppose that, precisely like the Beron of Hippolytus, he represented the divine itself as made subject to limitation, through the incarnation. For if, with Baur, we were to take the words ida otclas mepuypady with tatpixy Qeorns, as though Beryll meant to say,—“Christ was a man who was the subject of special divine influence,” the expres- sion for this very obvious thought would be too forced and prolix. For that a man is an (dla ovolas Trepuypady, and that as a mere man he has no (d¢a Oedrys, is self-evident. Neander, therefore, appears to me to have approached in the main nearer the truth, and still more Schleiermacher ; though Baur is pro- bably right when, in opposition to them, he urges that Beryll attached greater significance to the humanity of Christ than is commonly supposed. But it seems to me impossible to form a clear conception of this significance, if, as it has almost become customary to do, we make it our aim to strip this line of thought as much as possible of all trace of Patripassianism ; for it must have been stirred by both religious and speculative considera- tions, when it represented God as a suffering God, and asserted His intimate participation in finitude. ‘The defect was simply that Patripassianism unavoidably tended, even against its own will, towards an ethnic mutability of God, because it did not take its stand definitely enough on the ethical idea of unbounded participative love. In one aspect, indeed, the line of thought which we have considered is the proper continuation of that principle of love which Marcion had more energetically brought to light and advocated. But the view taken of these unques- tionably difficult questions is still bungling. In consequence 446 APPENDIX. of the lack of the intermediate links, the love which they set forth threatens constantly to become a merely physical thing, and the entire tendency acquires a pantheistic character, shared also by Monophysitism, which was the revival thereof at a higher stage. Nay more, the Manichzeism which made its ap- pearance some few decennia after Beryll or Beron, was a degenerate pagan form of this same tendency. For the rest, this age was so stirred by such questions, that theories of this nature were probably developed in much greater variety than has been commonly supposed. Indeed, traces enough of their actual existence are discoverable, though we must not make it our aim, as some do with a confidence that I cannot share, to reduce back all doctrines which bear any resemblance to each other, and are anonymously handed down, to one common source. For example, when Origen (see his Comm. in Joh. T. ii. 2) speaks of those who, out of anxiety for the unity of God, denied to the Son an independent subsistence of His own (i610- rnta ToD viod érépay Tapa THY TOD matpos), and distinguished Father and Son merely in name, he is said to refer to the same party with the Patripassians (as in the above-mentioned pas- sage from the Apology of Pamphilus, T. iv. 22; or as in his Comm. in Joh. x. 21, Vol. iv. 199, and c. Cels. 8, 12, Volar 750). But when in the first quoted passage (in Joh. ii. 2) he mentions, as the second class, dpvoupevous Thy OeoTnTa TOU viot, ribevtas d8 adtod Thy iSubtnTa Kab THY ovatay Kata Teprypapny Tuyyavovoay éTépay TOU matpos; and in the further passage, cited by Pamphilus,—“Sed et eos qui hominem dicunt Do- minum Jesum precognitum et predestinatum, qui ante adven- tum carnalem substantialiter et proprie non extiterit, sed quod homo natus Patris solam in se habuerit Deitatem, ne illos quidem sine periculo esse, ecclesize numero sociari;” or when Greg. Thaum. (A. Mai l. c. 7, 171) alludes to men who, though they conceived Christ to be filled with deity, really allowed no distinction between Him and the saints and pro- phets, but approximated to heathenism or Judaism by offering worship to a man endued with divine power; for it is hea- thenish aAnpwbevta deotntos céBewv, Jewish, to regard Christ as a xtlowa:—there is undoubtedly a relationship between them, but we van scarcely be warranted in identifying them al), either with each other or with Beryll, or with any other NOTES. 447 teacher. ‘The passage cited from Origen by Pamphilus re- minds us of what Eusebius says respecting Beryll, and may very well relate to him ; for it does not attribute Ebionism, but rather the contrary, when it speaks of the “deitas Patris:” which is further evident also from the mild and rather warning character of the judgment pronounced by him. Still its iden- tity with Beryll is by no means certain; for we miss an essential feature noticed in the account given by Eusebius, namely, that when it became incarnate, the watpsxi Oeorns took up into, or posited in, itself a limitation, a mepvypady. Through the omission of this feature, the description becomes vague and in- definite enough to suit many others, for example, the Alogi. At the same time, this feature may lie in the first passage (in Joh. ii. 2); for the party there mentioned, posited the idcorns Tov viob, and said,—His ovela is cata mepvypadiy étépa Tapa tiv Tod Twatpos. But they again denied the @edTys, and not merely the idfa Oeorns, of the Son; they would therefore ap- pear to have been Ebionites, and cannot have been identical with the previous ones. Schleiermacher also (I. c. 532), and with him Fock and Rossel, seems to hint at the same view of the matter. The words of the latter passage can only be re- ferred to Beryll, or better to those who resembled him, if we understand them to deny the @edrns of the Son not absolutely, but “ad tempus,” or on the ground of the xévwous, by which God posited Himself as a man. In favour of which meaning might be adduced the consideration, that otherwise in this con- nection also the following words, from tufevres dé to matpoy (see above), would have far too wide a scope, if they were merely intended to state that Christ was a man, and indeed a man whose ovcoia cata trepiypadiyy étépa mapa tT. T. 7.3 for the latter point would only have been regarded as too self- evident by Ebionites. Whereas, on the contrary, these wide- reaching words acquire their full and sufficient import if we suppose them to set forth an opinion which, according to the account given in the text, resembled either that of Beron or that of Beryll. They would then refer, namely, to a form of their doctrine, in which fuller development had been given to the very nearly related element, to wit, that by the xévwous a dis- tinction, a section (dmroxo7m) of the divine essence in general, or a second mpécw7ev in addition to that of the Father, was 448 APPENDIX. brought to pass (compare Orig. in Joh. T. xx. 16: de princip. 4, 31); a form with which Gregory Thaum. also was acquainted, and which constituted a point of transition to Subordinatianisni (see Note 1, page 34). But I should be unwilling to lay any particular stress on this explanation. It must always be a perilous thing, supplementarily to give definite names and shapes to the authors of systems which have been anonymously and vaguely handed down. Nor would Baur have been able so confidently to refer the passage in Joh. T. ii. 2 to Beryll, if he had considered that Origen began his commentary on John as early as A.D. 219, and that, according to in Joh. vi. 1, and Kuseb. 6, 24, the first five tomes thereof were ready before a.p. 231; whereas the discussion with Beryll took place far later, to wit, in the year 244; although I, for my part, should by no means decidedly conclude from this circumstance, that Beryll could not be meant. Jor Origen had been even at an earlier period in Arabia; and in that land, where mystical and theosophic movements were the order of the day (see Ullmann, p. 8), might easily long before have become acquainted with the opinions entertained by Beryll or those related to him, especi- ally as Beryll must have attained to an advanced age about the year 244, and was then designated Bishop. For this reason, also, it is not improbable that Hippolytus, Bishop of Portus Romanus, in Arabia, named Abulides in the East, may have had fruitless discussions with Beryll prior to 244, although we have no information to that effect, unless where Beron is men- tioned we ought to understand Beryll. Eusebius also (see his H. E. 6, 20) sets Beryll and Hippolytus together. Completely indefinite is the description given by Gregory of those who worshipped a man filled with deity. It looks like what we know of Paul of Samosata and his followers; but, as we shall soon see, might also have belonged to the school of Sabellius. Note 14, page 59. He had this realistic tendency, and therefore also substan- tially the same doctrine of the Trinity, even prior to his adop- tion of Montanism. Indeed, he gives utterance to it already in his Apologeticus, c. 21. In the Adv. Prax. he gives the “ Re- cula Fidei,” which contains the belief in a real Trinity, and says, —“Hane regulam ab initio Evangelii decucurrisse probabit NOTES. 449 novellitas Praxez hesterna.” “ As always, so now more than ever, instructed by the Paraclete, who leads into all truth, we believe, indeed, in one God, but agreeably to the divine order which we call ceconomia;” c. 2, 13, 30. Tertullian himself, therefore, in a work intended to justify Montanism, and to con- fute its opponents, confesses that, prior to coming under the influence of Montanism, he held, with the Church, substantially the same doctrine of the Trinity as he now expounds. Indeed, altogether apart from what has been previously advanced, it must in itself be much more likely that the later Montanism was modified and rid of its character of abruptness by the influence of the doctrine of the Trinity settled by the Church, was puri- fied by the principle of gradualness and order defended by Church teachers like the author of the Epistle to Diognetus or Irenzeus, and was brought to the recognition of the divine ceco- nomia and its orderly course, than that the Church was led to the doctrine of the Trinity through the influence of Montanism. Nore 15, page 83. Baur also, in his large work on the Trinity, has left him entirely unnoticed ; and Hiinell gives an inaccurate and incom- plete picture of him (1.c.). Reuter has justly directed attention (see the “ Berliner Jahrbiicher,” 1843) to the importance of the man, who was not only ranked among the first by his own age, but stood high in the esteem of Eusebius, was much used by Epiphanius (for example, Her. 31), and on the ground alone of his work, mpos amdcas tas aipéces (Kuseb. H. E. 6, 22; Photius Cod. 121), occupies a high position as an Heresiologer. We know from Photius that the work commenced with Dosi- theus, ended with Noetus and the Noetians (Phot. |. c.), and discussed the Nicolaitanes, Montanists, Cainites, Marcicn, and Valentine. The Valentinian sect (of which the Beron referred to in the text was an offshoot) appears to have made an effort at the beginning of the third century to enter into closer connec- tion with the doctrine of the Church. We have previously remarked the same course of procedure adopted by the school of Marcion. This is proved, after his fashion, by Apelles, who inclined towards Valentinianism; by Alexander (Tertull. “de Carne Christi” 15, 16), who taught that Christ truly suffered ; and by the afore-mentioned Beron. For the rest, in considering VOL. IL 2 F 450 APPENDIX. the question of the genuineness of the writings of Hippolytus, we must take our start from the fragment of his work against the heresies, entitled “Against the Heresy of Noetus.” That the heeresiological work with which Eusebius was acquainted, and which Epiphanius used, was identical with that read by Photius, no one will doubt. But as the work seen by Photius concluded with Noetus, and the fragment extant on Noetus, which was invariably attributed to Hippolytus, not only con- cludes in a manner suitable to the termination of an entire work, but begins also in such a manner as to show that it is a fragment, and not a homily, as the title of the Vatican manu- script represents it; nay more, the fragment of a work in which other heresies had been spoken of, consequently of an heeresio- logical work,—we have every reason for assuming it to be the last part of the work with which Eusebius and Epiphanius were acquainted. To this must be added, that Gelasius, Bishop of Rome (Fabric. 1, 225) adduces a passage which is identical with c. 18 of our fragment, the commencement being taken from c. 11 and 12 or 17. Still more striking are the mner grounds. For the views of the author are so peculiar, that they could no longer have been put into the mouth of au orthodox teacher of the Church even in the fourth century. They set before us the orthodox doctrine of the Trinity at a stage at which it had not yet been warned by Arianism of the conse- quences of teaching that the Son first attained an hypostatical existence outside of the divine sphere, at the creation of the world. The author still adhered to that more harmless form of Subordinatianism, the very inner inconsistency of which impelled it to further progress and to the exclusion of all inadequate ele- ments; and there could be no doubt whatever that, when the time arrived for deciding between Athanasius and Arius, he could not possibly feel drawn towards the latter. He had not yet reached the stage at which Origen stood; on the other hand, we find that, as compared with Tertullian, he took up a more decidedly antagonistic position relatively to the continuous patripassian movements. The work, therefore, of which this fragment formed a part, must be concluded, on inner grounds, to have been written between Tertullian and Origen ; and this would exactly suit Hippolytus, who is said, by Gelasius, Bishoy: in Arabia, to have addressed a letter to the wife of Philippus NOTES. 451 Arabus. This fragment shall furnish us, to use one of his own figures, with the warp into which we shall weave our image of Hippolytus. J further believe myself justified in describing as genuine, among the works bearing upon Christology, that which treats of Antichrist. As he occupied himself greatly with chronological studies, and wrote a commentary on Daniel (com- pare abr. 1, 272); and as the Catenz on the first three Gos- pels (compare on Matt. xxiv.; Luke xxi.) show that he had bestowed much thought on the subject of Antichrist; and, finally, as the style and thoughts are both archaic (Photius makes the same remark),—there seems to me to be no ground for doubting the genuineness of the work. Further, in it Hades plays a great role (c. 11, 45); hence also the work, Adyos pds “EXaAnvas, of which the treatise entitled cata IIddtova (Fabr. 1, 220 ff.) formed a part, and the fragment in A. Mai’s Coll. Nova (7, 12), may very fairly be assigned to him. With the Christological principles of the treatise against Noetus, and of the work on Antichrist, harmonizes also the Xoyos els Ta ayta Jeopavera : compare c. 6 with c. Noet. 18. Chapter Third of these homilies appears indeed to contain the doctrine that Mary remained a virgin even subsequently to the birth of Christ, against which Tertullian strongly protests. But, in the first place, even the discourse at the Feast of Epiphany, attributed to Gregory Thaumatureus, contains this doctrine ; in the second place, perhaps Tertullian’s serious defence of the true view may be a sign that an antagonistic view was beginning to be taught ; and, in the third place, another explanation of the passage seems to me to be more probable than the one referred to (see Note 3, page 95). This doctrine may have been first taught by Docetists, who were willing to recognise the birth of Christ,—for example, by the Valentinians,—and have then commended itself to the Church of this age on other grounds. Indeed, the history of Montanism shows a similar course of things. The teachers of the second century, and in particular Tertullian, were con- cerned to assert the complete truth of the incarnation of Christ on quite different principles from Hippolytus, as we shall soon see. As far as concerns the remaining fragments, that of Mai 7, 134, is preserved in Latin by Leontius (Fabr. 1, 266), in greater compass; that of Mai, p. 68, we possessed previously in Greek (c. Beron. Fabr. 1, 227). The fragment (Fabr. 1, 266) 452 APPENDIX. from his commentary on Genesis is attested by Jerome; and the fragments, Fabr. 1, 267-269, by Theodoret. The remain- ing Christological fragments from the commentary on Genesis (Fabr. 2, 22-31), and the “ Demonst. c. Jud.” (abr. 2, 2-5), are as far from causing difficulty as the trinitarian and Christo- logical fragments, 1, 267 to 281. Doubt may be thrown on the fragment 1, 282, because of the superscription taken in conjunc- tion with its doctrine of the Eucharist. On the other hand, the work srepl yapicpdtov is above suspicion, with the exception of the uncertain title ; though there is nothing in it of importance for our purpose, if we except the confession of faith (246), which is brief, simple, and archaic in its character. Spurious, on the contrary, is that communicated by Joannes Antioch. (Fabr. 2, 32), which is completely Monophysitic in tone, and contradictory of all the accredited Christological views of Hip- polytus. Nore 16, page 89. Herewith Hippolytus aimed at showing that he was justi- fied in giving to the Logos also the name Son. It is very remarkable that the Monarchians, to whom he was opposed, raised no objection to the use of the word Logos, nor even against the position that the Logos became flesh. But they protest, as against an innovation, a £évov, against identifying the Logos with the vids, in that they explain the word Adyos so that it retains no hypostatical significance, and assert. that this was the sense in which it was used by John. “Iwdvyns pév yap Eyes AOyov, GAN adAXwS aAXnyopel. Two things herein are remarkable. Firstly, we see again the groundlessness of Baur’s argumentation, that Patripassianism furnishes an indirect but powerful testimony against the authority or genuineness of the Gospel of John, seeing that the doctrine of the Logos plays a great role with John, and that it was rejected by the Patri- passians. For, inasmuch as both understood how to get over the difficulty, by adopting a peculiar interpretation, John could by no means have brought about a collision. On the contrary, the adherents of this tendency believed the Gospel of John to furnish the strongest scriptural proofs in their favour. In the second place, the assertion of the opponents, that it was some- thing new to identify the Logos with the Son, and thus to NOTES. 453 ensure to the Son a premundane hypostatical existence, if it deserve credit, introduces us very plainly to an age in which all alike were thoroughly convinced that the higher nature of Christ was of one substance with God; but in which also the inclination to assert for that higher nature an hypostasis of its own, which we found so strong and lively at the commence- ment of the second century and subsequently, had almost died out in the neighbourhood of Noetus. The reason whereot being, that the Christian mind had laid firm hold on that which it considered preliminarily to be the main point; to wit, that the person of the eternal God Himself had drawn near to men in Christ, which seemed possible, without ascribing to the Son an independent hypostasis of His own. Even the Patripassians could say, The wisdom, the understanding, the omnipotence of God, became man in Christ; and, in point of fact, they recog- nised the eternity of the hypostasis which appeared in Him even more fully than the Church teachers whom we have noticed, for they conceived the one hypostasis acknowledged by them—that is, God Himself, the Father—to have personally appeared in Christ. Therein lies also a further evidence of the high antiquity of this work, nay, even of its composition during the first half of the third century. For, as the indifference to the hypostasis of the Logos and of the premundane Son, which was so markedly a characteristic of Tertullian, presupposed the entire course of the doctrine of the Logos depicted above, so, on the other hand, no later writer could have made the con- cession made by Hippolytus (c. 15 init.), that the identification of the Logos with the Son, who had always been conceived to be hypostatical, was a new thing, although justified by Paul and Apocalypse xix. 11. When we ask historically, what was new and what was old, we must undoubtedly reply,—It was new to employ the word Son, in this distinctly doctrinal sense, to de- note the momentum of personality; for at an earlier period the term, Son of God, had been applied, not merely to the pre-ex- istent second hypostasis, but also to the entire earthly person- ality of Christ—a thing which now, when writers aimed at creater precision, was no longer suffered, or suffered solely out of regard for the higher nature of Christ. ‘This clearly de- fined use of the word owed its rise to the necessity (a necessity whose grounds we have previously pointed out) of establishing 454 APPENDIX. the hypostasis of the Son by other means than by the doctrine of the Word and the Sophia, the union of which in the Logos, after the manner indicated, sufficed solely to establish the divine essence of the Son. ‘The perception of this necessity impelled the Church to endeavour to seek another basis of the hypostasis of the Son; but it was tempted to aim at securing this object, in the first instance, by connecting the genesis of the hypostasis of the Son with the genesis of the world: thus, of course, glid- ing into thoughts of an Arian tendency,—not, indeed, in relation to the essence, certainly, however, in relation to the personality of the Son. That from the days of Tertullian onwards, stirred especially by the influence of Patripassianism, the Church aimed with renewed energy at asserting for the Son a distinct hypostasis,—this was old; for that the higher nature of Christ was a pre-existent divine hypostasis, had long been allowed to be a fact, although, as we have remarked, less attention had been bestowed on it from the end of the second century on- wards. But the mode of establishing that He was or became a person was new ; for earlier writers had not gone so far as, out of regard to the divine unity, to remove the hypostatical ele- ment in the Son outside of the inner divine sphere. This new feature soon became antiquated, it is true, and passed away ; indeed, those who insisted on it could not avoid falling into the Arianism which they did not desire to adopt. To the praise, however, of the Church teachers whom we here have in view, it must be said, that they did their best to oppose that Arian tendency, which threatened to reduce the hypostasis, and not merely the hypostatical element, of the Son to a mere creature. And that not only by always requiring truly divine essence to be attributed to the Son, but also by endeavouring to bring the Son, although outside and alongside of God, yet into the most intimate relation to the inner Logos of the Father. Tertullian, as we have seen, aimed at pointing out the existence of the potence of Sonship and incarnation in the inner, eternal essence of God, the inner Word; Hippolytus appropriated to the Adyos acapxos in God, also the name of Son, in particular on ac- count of His destiny to incarnation,—a course which he him- self, as we have said, allows to be to a certain extent an inno- vation, but which was at the same time in agreement with Scripture. Its adoption may be taken as an indication that he NOTES. 455 was unwilling, and very justifiably, to be content with an hypostasis of the higher nature of Christ, whose origin and subsistence lay outside of the inner essence of God; and that he felt compelled to give it a seat in the inmost sphere of the divine. This effort, as, on the one hand, it was evidently closely allied to the tendency which prevailed in the earlier days of the Church’s existence (a thing to which Patripassianism also, in its peculiar way, testifies), so, on the other hand, it was the fore runner of that doctrine of the Trinity which was laid down by the Fathers of the Council of Nicsea, and which made its ap- pearance in the course of the third century, so soon as the Arian elements contained in the systems of the Church teachers, above referred to, began to be consolidated to an independent and self-consistent whole. The remark just made remains true, although we should have to grant that the attempt to unite the hypostasis of the Son with the inner Logos could not realize its object, so long as no other basis of the doctrine of the Trinity was discovered in God Himself than the illusory one of the multiplicity of the divine attributes (for example, wisdom). That this was insufficient, is clear alone from the consideration, that a Trinity does not result at all, if the divine attributes are to be taken as so many potences of hypostases. In that case, to reply to Hippolytus with Hippolytus himself, God is rows, not a Trinity. Furthermore, until the conception formed of God had been transformed, and thus a different foundation laid for the distinctions of the Trinity, that connection of the wisdom and omnipotence of God with the mundane Son in- volved a partial retrocession to the very ground which had just been quitted, with the design of establishing the hypostasis of the Son on a surer footing than the doctrine of the Logos was able to afford. But although we perceive here a remainder of the obscuration of the insight which we have praised above, this defect is fully counterbalanced by the consideration, that the reduction of the mundane Son back to the inner divine essence, thus commenced, was also the commencement of the rejection of creatural and Arian features from His hypostasis. So that the very same thing which we found accomplished during the second century in relation to the essence of the Son, we now find accomplished in relation to His hypostasis. For, in the second century, the Logos was brought far nearer to the 456 APPENDIX. essence of the created world than was the case in the third ;— He was conceived to be immediately (that is, without the mediation of ethical categories) the world itself, in its ideal aspect, the xocpos vontos ; on which view, justice could not be done to the idea of creation. That was cast aside towards the end of the century through the acquisition of the “stamina” of the Christian idea of God, during the conflict with the many forms of Gnosticism; and although we can trace the influence of the earlier theory in Tertullian, who regarded the inner divine Logos as also the idea of the world; and although the entire distinction between the inner Logos and the mundane Son bore a certain analogy to the doctrine of the Aoyos évdua- Oeros and mpodopixds rejected by Irenzeus, we must not forget to notice the step taken in advance, in that the Aoyos évdud- eros and mpodopixos, in its new, higher potence, was no longer represented as containing the idea of the world, both as resting in God and as actually realized, but was rather taken to denote the inner divine reason on the one hand, and, on the other hand, the reason after it had become hypostatical, or a Son. In other words, the distinction now drawn between Logos and Son, instead of relating as heretofore to the product, in the idea of the world, related to the idea of God Himself; although, in the first instance, a precipitate resort was made to the world, in order to secure the hypostasis—not the divine essence—of the Son. Norte 17, page 97. Patripassians of the earlier kind failed also to advance be. yond the idea of a theophany. So that the result described above in connection with the Trinity, reappears also in connec- tion with Christology:—the teachers of the Church at this period still stand on the same basis as their opponents. Cling- ing as they still did to their premises, they were unable to attain the mastery over them. It is instructive to observe how the doctrine of the absolute unchangeableness of God led the teachers of the Church to the like theophanical result, as the doctrine of the immediate passibility of God, held by their opponents of the so-called Patripassian school. Both were necessitated to regard the humanity as impersonal, as a mere husk of God. We have already indicated that the idea of God. NOTES. 457 which on both sides was still dominated by physical categories, only needed to be taken in an ethical sense, in order to the doing of full justice to the immutability of God on the one hand, which the Patripassians misapprehended, and on the other hand, to open up the prospect of a much more intimate participation of God in the finite, without endangering His divine essence, than Hippolytus judged admissible. Norte 18, page 110. De princip. 1, 2, 2:—“ Quomodo extra hujus sapientize generationem fuisse aliquando Deum Patrem vel ad punctum momenti alicujus quis potest sentire vel credere—? Aut enim non potuisse Deum dicet generare sapientiam antequam gene- raret, ut eam, que ante non erat, postea genuerit, ut esset ; aut, potuisse quidem et, quod dici de Deo nefas est, noluisse generare, quod utrumque et absurdum et impium esse omnibus patet, id est, ut aut ex eo, quod non potuit, Deus proficeret ut posset, aut cum posset, dissimularet ac differret generare sapi- entiam. Propter quod nos semper Deum Patrem novimus unigeniti Filii sui, ex ipso quidem nati et quod est ab ipso tra- hentis, sine ullo tamen initio, non solum eo, quod aliquibus temporum spatiis distingui potest, sed ne illo quidem, quod sola apud semetipsam mens intueri solet, et nudo ut ita dixerim in- tellectu atque animo conspicari. § 4: Est namque ita eterna - ac sempiterna generatio sicut splendor generatus ex luce. Non enim per adoptionem spiritus Filius fit extrinsecus, sed natura Filius est. § 7: Deus lux est; Splendor hujus lucis est unigenitus Filius ex ipso inseparabiliter velut splendor ex luce procedens. §10: Pater non potest esse quis si filius non sit. Lhe Father is not omnipotent prior to the birth of wisdom; per filium omnipotens est pater. Ever created thing accidentem habet justitiam vel sapientiam, et quod hoc quod accedit, etiam decidere potest, gloria ejus sincera et limpidissima esse non potest. Sapientia vero Dei, que est unigenitus Filius ejus, quoniam in omnibus inconvertibilis est et incommutabilis et sub- stantiz in eo omne bonum est, quod utique mutari atque con- verti nunquam potest, idcirco pura ejus ac sincera gloria pre- dicatur. 4,2,8: Sicut lux nunquam sine splendore esse potuit, ita nec Filius quidem sine Patre (Pater sine Filio?) intelligi potest, qui et figura expressa substantiz ejus et Verbum ef 458 APPENDIX. Sapientia dicitur. Quomodo ergo potest dici, quia fuit ali- quando, quando non fuit Filius?” Compare in Joh. xin, 25. Norte 19, page 113. Compare the de princ. 1, 2, 7 :—“ Splendor est gloria Dei et figura expressa substantize ejus, capable of leading us to the light of the Father.’ Ib. §9-13. I Joh. T. xxxu. 18 :-—"OXns pev odv oluat THS SoEns ToD Ocod adtod aravyacpua eivat Tov viov,—bOdvew pévtos ye ard Tod arravydcpatos ToUTOU TIS OAs So€ns pwepiKa aTravydopata emt Thy NOLTTY oYLKNY KTITW OvK oiuas yap Tiva TO Tay Sivaclar ywphoat THs ONS d0Ens Tod Ocod dmatvyacpa, i) Tov viov avtov. Ibid. on Joh. xiv. 9 (“ Whoso seeth Me, seeth the Father also”): Oewpettar yap é&v TO hoy dvt. Oc Kal cixdve Tod Ocod aopdtov o yevvijcas avtov Tarnp, Tod évidévT05 TH eiKoVe TOL adpadtov Ocod evOéws évopav Suvapevov Kal TO TpwTOT’T® THS EiKoVvos, T® Tatpi. Everything besides Himself is created by Him, or comes into existence through Him, even the Holy Spirit, to whom he ascribes hypostasis and wisdom (see in Joh. T. ii. 6), and who notwithstanding does not belong to the world (ibid.). C. 29,—“ John says, He is in the midst of you.” This Origen refers to the Logos, and takes occasion therefrom to set forth the uniqueness of His relation to the world :—'Emloxewat, ef dua TO év péom Tod mavTos eivat cdpatos thy Kapdlav, év é 7H Kapdia TO HYyEemoviKoV Kal TOV ev éxdat@ Noyou, Suvatat voeicHar TO pécos tudv EoTyKev, Ov pets ovx oldate. Compare de prince. 4, 28 :—Supra omne tempus et supra omnia secula, et supra omnem zternitatem intelligenda sunt ea que de Patre et Filio et Spiritu sancto dicuntur. Hee enim sola Trinitas est, que omnem sensum intelligentiz non solum temporalis verum etiam eternze excedit. Czetera vero, que sunt extra Trinitatem, in seculis et in temporibus metienda sunt. Compare Note 1, page 116. Nore 20, page 119. Compare Huet’s “ Origeniana” in de la Rue’s Ed. iv. 150. In Ad Rom. L. 1. 5, he speaks of the eternal Evangel which will be manifested when the shadow passes away, when death is swallowed up, and the truth has made its appearance. In Joh. T. i. 29:—Kait éet év 76 watpi odx Eats yevéoOae 7) wapa TO Tatpl, mi POacavtTa, TpaTov KaTwOev avaBalvovTa, NOTES. 450 éri THY Tod viod Oeornta, dv Hs Tis YepayoynOjvas Sivatas Kah éml THY TaTpLKnY paKkaploTnTa, Oipa o YwtHip avayéypartat. Specially characteristic is the classification of men given in “in Joh.” T.ii. 3. The highest class Qeov éyoucr Tov THY OX@V Ocov: of & Tapa TovTOUS SEevTEpOL ioTapeEvoL ert TOV viov Tot cob, Tdv Xpictov avtod- Kat tpitor ot Tov iALov, Kal THY cEARVHY Kal Tavta Tov Kocpov, etc., which is indeed an error, but far better than idolatry. In Joh. T. xix. 1 (towards the close) we read,— “The knowledge of the Son is not the same as that of the Father, for an avaPaivew takes place aio Ths yvOoews Tod viob éml THY yv@ow Tov Twatpos: but the Father cannot be seen otherwise than in the Son (yu) GAdws opdcbar tov matépa [StvacOat| 7) TO opacOas Tov vidv).—Kat 0 Gewpav tiv codiar, iy exticev 0 Ocds Tpd Tov aldvar, avaBaiver ato Tod éyvaxévas Tv copiay éml Tov TatTépa avTns. Previously, however, must Wisdom or the truth be recognised, iv’ obtws €XOn emt TO éviety TH ovola, ) TH Umrepéxewa THS ovolas Suvaper Kai dioew Tod Ocod. Kal rayarye, dotrep kata Tov vaoy avaBa0puol tives tjoav, dv wv eiones Tis els TA Ayta TOV aAyiwv, OUTWS Ob TAVTES 71)WOV avaBabpuol o povoyerns éote Tot Ocod, cai daTrep Tev avaPabpov 0 govoyerns eats TpOTOS éml TA KAT, 0 O€ TOVTOY avwTépw Kal otTws épeEhs pméypt TOU avwTdTw, oVTWS ol Mév TaYTES ELoW avaSabuol 6 cwtip* 0 5é oiov TpATOs KaTwTépw TO avOpwTwop avtod, © ériBaivovtes odevomev, Kai ta é&fs adbtobd évta Ti macay, év Tols avaBabmols odov, ate avaBhAvas dv advTod bvToOS Kal ayyéXov, Kab TOV AoLTraV Svvayewv. In “in Joh.” T. xx. 7, he expresses his belief that the end will come (1 Cor. xv. 28) when glorified spirits shall see the Father Himself as He is seen by the Son, and no longer know Him merely in the Son (dyrovrae TA Tapa TO TaTpr ovKéte Sia pecitov Kal vmrnpétou BA€trovtes avTa.— Ore ws 0 vids Opa TOY TaTépa Kal Ta Tapa TO TaTpi— olovel opolms TO viP avtomTns eotar TOO TaTpOsS—ovKETL ard THS ELKOVOS EVVOOV TA TEpt TOUTOV, ov 4 Eik@v é€oTL). Yet he adds in the previous passage,—The first thing is, that He be- came to us also the Lamb, which bears our sins and sanctifies us; then, having been cleansed, we eat His flesh, which is the true food. Compare contra Celsum 6, 68 &60 APPENDIX. Nore 21, page 120. Baur (1. c. 204 ff.) gives it as his opinion, tliat Origen vacil- lates between a generation out of God’s will, and a generation out of God’s essence; and refers to “in Joann.” T. xx. 16, as containing the former view. The point, however, is to discover the cause of this vacillation. Had Baur taken this course, he would perhaps have been able to confine the vacillation within very narrow limits. Neander starts with the view—one with which I am unable to agree—that the doctrine of the identity of the essence of the Son with that of the Father was gradually arrived at, and first clearly taught in the West, during the third century; that, on the contrary, Subordinatianism had its home in the East, from the days of Origen onwards; and that, in order to exclude Emanatism, Origen assumed that the Son originated from the will of God. The first-mentioned point is contradicted both by Patripassianism and by a whole series of Church teachers of the second century ; and the Subordinatian- ism of Tertullian and Novatian, so far from being weaker than that of Origen, is, taking all things into consideration, stronger. As far as concerns Kmanatism, Origen, it is true, was opposed to it in its coarsely sensuous forms; he could neither allow of a division in God (azroxovn), nor of a “fatum” above God, ne- cessitating the Father to the generation of the Son. But he was not therefore obliged to represent the generation of the Son solely as a matter of the “liberum arbitrium” of God. He did not even trace the origin of the world to that “liberum arbi- trium.” On the contrary, he held that the divine will was the unity of freedom and necessity. If, however, it should be replied,—The existence of the Son is undoubtedly not accidental, in the sense, namely, in which the world’s existence is not acci- dental; but still the Son, no less than the world, owes His existence to that divine will in which freedom and necessity are combined ; out of the divine essence, on the contrary, neither the world nor the Son is derived ;—we shall shortly give it closer consideration. Ritter (see his “ Geschichte der christlichen Philosophie” i. 498, 501) represents the Son as brought forth by the will of the Father, though out of His essence. He justly recognises that the essential tendency of Origen’s teachings was to show that the entire fulness of the Deity dwelt in the Son; NOTES. 461 aud that the Son is not to be regarded as a creature, but as the creative spirit, the true Mediator, of equal perfection with the Father. The subordination of the Son and the appearance of a commixture with creatures did not attach to the doctrine which he really meant to teach, but merely to the imperfect development thereof: they were a remnant of the sensuous ideas, which prevented him from seeing the difference between the dependence of the Son as generated, and the dependence of creatures. ‘The assumption of the imperfection of the creation must also have reacted on the conception he formed of the creative power of God (that is, of the Son, or Word). Possibly, however, a certain degree of subordination may be shown to be grounded in Origen’s conception of God; but no less also His equality with the Father. Note 22, page 129. The chief passages relating to this personification (Person- werdung) of the divine will in the Son, who proceeded inde- pendently eternally forth from the divine “Mens” (Augustine uses the word “ memoria”), through the self-duplication of God, are collected in Note 1, page 125. In the “de prince.” 1, 2, 6, he teaches, that to describe Him as the image of God, is to affirm “nature ac substantise patris et filil unitatem. Si enim omnia, que facit pater, hec et filius facit similiter, in eo,— Imago patris in filio deformatur, qui utique natus ex eo est velut quzedam voluntas ejus ex mente procedens. Et ideo ego arbitror, quod sufficere debeat voluntas patris ad subsistendum hoc, quod vult pater. Volens enim non alia via utitur, nisi que consilio voluntatis profertur.” It might appear as though, in the last words, he returned completely to the stage at which Tertullian and Hippolytus stood, apportioning all to the will instead of to the essence of God. We must not, however, overlook the “ideo,” which refers to what has gone before. God’s will being of such a nature that it can personally objectify itself in the dupli- cation of God, therefore, says he, it appears to me unnecessary to resort to anything else than the will; in other words, if the divine will were merely creative, we should have to leave it out of consideration in the present case. If Origen had intended, as Baur maintains (1. c. p. 207), by the mention of the will, to represent the origin of the Son as the work of a kind of divine 462 APPENDIX. caprice, he must have contradicted his own position, that for the Father to have a Son, a perfect image, was a good; and that to bring forth the Son belonged as truly to the essence of the Father as brightness belongs to light. Moreover, Origen does not allow the existence of such a thing as caprice in God. But he does not even content himself with a creation of the Son by the will of the Father, grounded in rational necessity or rational freedom. For, apart from the consideration that the idea of an immediately creative will of the Father was something foreign to his conception of God, he says (see Note 1, page 116, and Note 19, Appendix), He was the divine Will proceeding forth from the divine “ Mens;” He was the will as proceeding ; how can He have been created by this will? The words “consilio voluntatis profertur” exclude all caprice; though, at the same time, they are an outflow of the defect already mentioned, of conceiving the Father to be self-conscious in and by Himself, and not in and with the Son. But the idea of purpose, of decree, cannot lie in the word “consilio;” for that would involve His being a creature, and contradict Rom. i. 5, according to which the Son cannot be the object of a divine decree. In the original Greek probably stood yeu, which was intended to set forth the divine will, which emanates and becomes a person, as con- scious; that is, it was intended to set aside the passivity and unconsciousness which attach to the common Emanatism. With this explanation harmonizes the immediately following polemic against such emanatistic doctrines. “Magis ergo,” he concludes, “ sicut voluntas procedit e mente (this favourite expression of Origen’s shows that he deemed the so-called generation of the Son to be quite as truly His own act as the act of the Father) et neque partem aliquam mentis secat neque ab ea separatur aut dividitur, tali quadam specie putandus est Filium genuisse, ima- ginem scilicet suam, ut sicut ipse invisibilis est per naturam, ita imaginem quoque invisibilem genuerit—Imago ergo est invisi- bilis Dei patris Servator noster; quantum ad ysum quidem patrem, veritas, quantum autem ad nos, quibus revelat. patrem, imago est, per quam cognoscimus patrem.” Norte 23, page 140. We can scarcely do otherwise than characterize it as play, when some make the play on words in which Origen indulges NOTES. 463 the corner-stone of his doctrine, deducing from his derivation of uy from vye, and his supposition that yrvy7 denotes cooled down 7rvedua, the conclusion that he conceived Christ’s soul also to be not entirely free from impurity. When Baur—not very confidently, it is true—gives utterance to this conjecture, he overlooks the numberless passages in which the perfect sinless- ness of the soul of Christ is maintained in the strongest terms (compare ad Rom. 3, 8; 6, 12; in Joann. I. xx. 17; de prince. 2, 6, 3, 4, 5; 4, 81), and has not properly considered Origen’s course of thought; otherwise he would have seen that the acces- sibility of the soul to suffering, and its subjection to finitude, as taught by him, was based, not on the guilt, but on the love of Christ, which condescended to us and became a curse for us. In Paul also was a reflection of this love, which neither vanishes nor cools down, in that it is ready to become a curse for others, but during its humiliation remains what it was as love, though, instead of enjoying the blessedness naturally belonging to it, sympathizingly makes the unhappiness of the brethren its own (compare the passages quoted, page 134 f.). In general, more- over, Origen did not understand yvy7 to mean merely some- thing cooled down, but frequently something substantially good ; nor did he regard the human soul as a mere cooled down vedpa. Thus he calls the Logos the soul of God, speaks very frequently of holy souls, and therefore uses yvy7 in its usual sense of an individual spiritual being, which also, as such, may proceed forth from the hand of God: compare ad Rom. i. 8. The soul of Christ was foreordained to be a sacrifice; de Martyr. AT; Noysexn vrvyy. In Joann. T. xiii. 25, yuyy dueaia; xiii. 3, Oevorépar puyai; T. x. 16, dvvatas Kai puvoe lepov eivar 1) evpuns ev Aoyw Wuy7) Sia TOV cUpTrEduKOTA Adyov: 13, 43; 20, 7. he a&ortpa also are éuypuya, and the Logos éuuyos. In Joann. T. ii. 25, xi. 25. Nore 24, page 141. Compare de prince. 2, 1, 2; 8, 3; and the passage quoted ADOVe#2. GO) 3,8) pe Of Oso gnc. Wels, 8,072 sead_ Romuilsi 5,910: Origen’s conception of freedom was by no means so formal as appears commonly to be supposed. His doctrine of a final atoxataoracts, after all possible delays, relapses, purifications, shows clearly that he looked upon grace as a power which over- 464 APPENDIX. arches even freedom, without, however, exercising physicai con- straint. He regards not merely choice or caprice as freedom, but whatever stress he lays on the middle momentum or stadium of the idea of freedom, represents it as preceded by the essential connection of the spiritual nature with the Logos, or by essen- tial freedom; and, on the other hand, in that perfect love which is the goal, he sees neither the possibility of evil nor unfreedom, but rather the union of freedom and ethical necessity. At all the lower stages, says he, ad Rom. L. v. 10, a relapse 1S pos- sible; but where there is the love of the whole heart, it pre- serves from the possibility of a fall. If, as the Apostle says, nothing can separate us from the love of God, the faculty of choice cannot separate us. It remains, it is true; but the power of love is so great, that it draws all powers and all virtues to itself, especially since the love of God manifested itself as pre- venient. The free grace which apparently renounces the jaw, establishes the rule of love in opposition to caprice and to free- dom of choice. Note 25, page 147. The correctness of the above exposition, which starts with the conviction that Origen is by no means chargeable with vacillation in his teachings regarding God, but, on the contrary, remained in the main self-consistent throughout,—that, in agreement with this his conception of God, he always, and very distinctly, assigned essentially the same position respectively to the Logos, to Christ, and to the world,—and that he by no means at one time conceived the entire divine essence to be present, for example, in Christ, and at another time regarded the Logos as a mere creature,—finds confirmation in the circumstance, that it appears to furnish an explanation of his strange doctrine of several worlds successively following upon each other. As God is the goal of the world, and His inmost essence abstrac- tion from all multiplicity and finitude, the world is threatened, the nearer it approaches perfection, the more with complete absorption into God: nay more, in order to attain perfection, it must be raised above its own nature; in other words, it must really cease to exist. Feeling this, Origen was driven to seek for a counterpoise, especially as he held the existence of the world to be a great good for God Himself. For this reason, NOTES. 465 he keeps the world as long as possible undergoing processes of purification,—processes which he represents as continuing even after the resurrection. On the same ground, also, he leaves the matter open, and conceives it as a possibility, which may become an actuality, that freedom should, by renewed apostasy, prolong that relative independence of God, which he was able to deem perfect solely outside of God, not in Him. And thus the unre- conciled antagonism between finite and infinite in his system assumed the form of a doctrine of objective alternating worlds ; and the same thing assumed subjectively the form of an alterna- tion between mystery and revelation (see Martensen’s “ Meister Eckart”). With this is further intimately connected another point. Corporeality he represents at one time as the product of sin, or at all events as the seal of imperfection, the existence of which is therefore threatened when it approaches perfection : at another time, he deems it to be that through which the ideal world first becomes a reality; and accordingly posited its ex- istence as eternal. That perfection would bring at once the most intimate union with God, and the most complete confir- mation of individuality, Origen was as yet unable to see; because he neither viewed individuality as a work of God, nor reckoned it as a part of the divine creation. He regarded it as grounded, not in God’s idea of the world, but solely in the freedom of man. Thus viewed, however, it had a very doubt- ful existence. The eternal and true element in the idea of the world does not extend to the concrete and individual, but is merely the potential creation, the xdcpos vontds. The actual world, on the contrary, in his representation, hovers constantly, so to speak, between existence and non-existence ; and accord- ingly very much that he posits at one time, becomes at another time doubtful. This alternation between position and negation, however, which characterizes his system at so many points, was erounded, not in caprice and unsteadiness, but in his concep-~ tion of God, which still suffers from the contradiction of cor- stituting the lowest and most abstract determination the most essence and highest element of God, though Origen himself elsewhere saw clearly enough that the spiritual determinations are the highest. It was reserved, however, for the teachers of a later period to perceive the erroneousness of Origen’s notion, that the divine essence contained within itself a fulness of VOL. II. 2G 466 APPENDIX qualities, of which those embodied in the divine volition and knowledge are but a feeble copy; and to acknowledge that spiritual love is itself the inmost essence of God, His uncreated being; and that consequently the Son, if He be actually in relation to will and intelligence of a truly divine nature, may also be of one substance with the Father. The task then be- comes to establish the distinction between the Father and the Son in another way; for this distinction could not be estab- lished without subordinatian and modalistic vacillations, so long as the Father was identified with the ungenerated divine essence, instead of ime same essence being attributed to the Son equally with the Father. If we take for granted at the very outset that the true distinction cannot be established unless we sup- pose that the Father, for the sake of knowing Himself, objecti- fied His knowledge and will eternally in the Son, we find Origen far removed therefrom; for he believed the Father to know Himself in Himself, and not in the Son, His image. Still we may say,—Origen also represents the Father as be- coming objective, and, as issuing forth out of the inner depths of His being, in the Son, who is His évépyeva; but He did not contemplate Himself in the Son as in the mirror of Himself, but merely an imperfect image, not equal to the one only archetype, Himself. Norte 26, page 153. Baur has rightly directed attention to the fact, that Mar- cionitism (which even during the fifth century, to judge from Theodoret’s letters, had many adherents in the East, and, ac- cording to the above exposition, was intimately allied with Patripassianism) subsequently passed over into Manicheism. The occasion thereof was the rigid antagonism posited between Law and Gospel. But Sabellianism also offered a point of con- nection for this antagonism, in that it represented the earlier revelations as disappearing when a new one was given; for example, the law disappeared when Christ came. Athanasius also (c. Ar. 4, 23) charges it with dividing the Testaments (Siatpety tas SiabijKas, Kal yu) rHv éxépay Tis Erépas &yvecOar— Maviyaiov—ro éritiSevpa). Manicheism proper, which arose about the year 260, like Patripassianism, subjected the divine in the world to physical suffering, to wit, through matter; and NOTES. 467 its doctrine of the “Jesus patibilis omni suspensus ex ligno” (see August. c. Faust. 20, 2; compare Baur’s “Das mani- cheische Religionssystem,” pp. 71 ff.) may be regarded as a cosmological extension, though also a dissipation, of Patri- passianism with its more soteriological character. Only in one aspect, it is true; for though both alike attribute suf- fering in the physical sense to God, Patripassianism repre- sents Him as subjecting Himself thereto by assuming an ex- ternal, visible shape; whereas Manicheism teaches that the sufferings of the pure lucific principle arise from an antagon- istic primal dark principle. We shall find afterwards that Sabellianism was finally driven to Dualism, and that, with its rigid conception of God, it was unable to allow even of a creation, and was compelled to fall back on an eternal iAn; but the presages of this course of things are discernible even in the earlier forms of this tendency. For, so far as the one God converts Himself into corporeality, as they in part teach, not- withstanding that they retain their Monism, and only their conception of the one God comprises contradictory elements, the reality of the incarnation and of the birth from Mary was threatened. Now, when the adherents of this system, with a view to escaping the danger of Docetism, represented God as assuming from without that which constituted Him passible, to wit, His body, we have an entrance of God into passible matter, similar to that which Manicheism sets forth in its “ Jesus patibilis,” or its duvayuss taOntixy). The more, then, all obscura- tion and darkness are removed outside of the pure divine essence, that is, the more the pure divine essence is fixed in its immutability, the more, as we shall see, does the Sabellian system become affected by Dualism, until at last it is unable to allow the one Divine Being to be even the cause of the world, and is therefore necessitated to represent the world as having its principle in itself, and as a second primal principle standing over against the first. Clearly, however, Sabellianism contained this Dualism merely in the form of a consequence, of which its adherents were partially unconscious, whereas it was the constitutive principle of Manicheism. Sabellianism differs essentially, not only from Manichzeism, but also from the milder Platonic form of Dualism, in that it scarcely occupied itself at all with the question of the creation of the world, and limited 468 APPENDIX. its inquiries entirely to the already existing world; the other two systems were decidedly cosmogonical. The same remark may be made also of the Sabellianism of Schleiermacher. This is not the place to give a more detailed account of the Manicheean Christology.. Compare Baur, who says (I. ¢. p. 407),—“ The Christ of Manichzism has nothing but the name in common with the Christ of Christianity.” It is an expression cata- chrestically, traditionally adopted. The Manichzan Christ is the universal lucific Spirit, enthroned in the sun and moon, the pure efflux of God, represented perhaps as the pure archetypal man, between whom, however, and their “ Jesus patibilis,” or the seed of light enchained and suffering in every plant, etc., there is a clear difference. The latter is bound and com- mingled with matter (Sdvapus maOntixy). For whereas the second divine Stvapus, the Snusoupyixn, the world-forming dvva- pus, is only able to set limits to the dominion of matter by bringing the world into order, but was unable to rescue the light-germs confined in it; a third power, Christ, the form which is enthroned on the sun, draws all related elements out of matter upwards to the light of the sun. Baur. |. c. pp. 205, 991. This Christ, therefore, cannot be born; for birth would bring with it the loss of the purity which gives Him redeeming power. In general, that physical and cosmical process of re- demption is by no means connected with the person of the historical Christ, although the Manichzans frequently use Him as an allegory of the Christ on the sun, to wit, so far as the inmost essence of Jesus, which came to light at His transfigura- tion on the mount, like the essence of every “ Electus,” may undoubtedly be designated pure and divine. But quite as truly, and even more fully, is the historical Christ a mere allegory of the “ Jesus patibilis,’ who himself needs redemption in his sufferings. On the Christology of the Priscillianists, who diffused Manicheeism in the East from the fourth century onwards, compare Liibkert’s “ de Heresi Priscillianistarum,” 1840, pp. 25-29. Similar phenomena manifest themselves in connection with the Bogomils (compare Gieseler’s “de Bogo- milis Comment.”) and the Cathari. According to Augustine (ad Oros. c. Priscill. et Orig. C. 4, T. x. 735, ed. Maur. 2 a.), the Priscillianists were Sabellian in their doctrine of the Trinity. It is also allowed that the Sabellians made use of the Gospel of NOTES. 469 the Egyptians, which contains dualistic elements. Augustine says (1. c.),—* Priscillianus Sabellianum antiquum dogma resti- tuit, ubi ipse pater, qui Filius, qui et Spiritus S. perhibetur.” Similarly Orosius, Leo the Great, and others. Leo’s terming them, besides, Patripassians, is plainly explicable from the character of their Christology. But when he entitles them also Arians, he is certainly chargeable with inaccuracy, especi- ally in view of the position—“ Christum innascibilem esse,” which probably related to His divine nature, which it was thus intended to put on a level with the Father (Conc. Tolet. Reg. fid. Anath. 6); though, as Liibkert justly observes (p. 25), it may undoubtedly be explained from the Emanatism which, ac- cording to the same Council, the Priscillianists combined with their Monarchianism, as did also the Arians. ‘ Credimus,’ says the Council (Anath. 14), “Trinitatem indivisibilem indif- ferentem ; preeter hanc nullam credimus divinam esse naturam.” The Priscillianists are charged with entertaining the opinion, “esse aliquid, quod se extra divinam ‘Trinitatem possit ex- tendere.” It is not likely, however, that they represented these emanations as concrescing into definite hypostases. A canon of the Synod. Bracarensis says,—“ Si quis extra sanctam ‘Trini- tatem alia nescio qua divinitatis nomina introducit dicens quo? in ipsa divinitate sit Trinitas Trinitatis, sicut Gnostici et Pris- cilliani dixerunt, anathema sit.” How it was possible for Sabel- lians to arrive at propositions concerning a double or triple Trinity of this nature, which had been already laid down by Neo-Platonists, for an explanation see Note 31. As the Pris- cillianists looked upon the body as the seat and work of the devil, they could not attribute an earthly body to Christ; hence the charge of Docetism brought against them by Leo. Ac- cording to the Conc. Tol. Anath. 6, they denied also the hu- man soul of Christ. Had they remained simply content with denying to Christ both human body and human soul, they would not have deserved even the title of heretics, for they would have cast aside the fundamental idea and fundamental fact of Christianity. (See Note U, vol. i., on the true con- ception of Heresy.) With this, however, it does not harmonize to say that they maintained “Deitatis et carnis unam esse in Christo naturam” (1. c. Anath. 13). These words, namely, im- ply, that they assumed the existence of something analogous to 470 APPENDIX. matter in the divine nature itself, of which they took a physical view. In harmony therewith is also the further charge of teaching “ Deitatem Christi convertibilem esse et passibilem ” (1. c. Anath. 7), which, with their Monarchianism, caused them to be blamed for Patripassianism. This admission of finitude into the nature of God, indicates undoubtedly that the original Dualism had begun to be conciliated and weakened down ; but even the old Manicheism had done the same with its “ Jesus patibilis.” For this reason I consider unsatisfactory the view to which Liibkert inclines (Il. c. pp. 27, 28), plainly through not paying sufficient attention to the many appearances which speak of a tpo7m7 of God, or of an origin of the body of Christ from the essence of God,—to wit, that this conversion was not ob- jective, but merely subjective, symbolical or Docetical; the effect of which would be, contrary to his own intention (p. 28), to reduce the entire historical appearance of Christ to a mere illusion. There is the more reason for accepting this supposi- tion, as, according to Leo, they taught the birth of Christ from the Virgin; not, indeed, as Neander rightly remarks, in the sense of the doctrine of the Church, but still in the sense that He passed through Mary with the glorious body which He brought with Him from above, and which He derived from God. They may indeed have supposed that this heavenly or divine body appeared to be sensuous to the sensuous, to the spiritual, spiritual, according to their different power of appre- hension; but still a real and objective union of God with the “caro” took place. How far they admitted suffering also into this divine “caro,” is difficult to say; at all events, it contains the element of finitude. As they denied the resurrection of Christ, they must have denied either the susceptibility of His body to injury, or the continuance of His corporeality. Against the latter alternative is the objection, that they can scarcely have been willing to give up a body derived from the divine nature to the kingdom of earthly matter. But in that case, Christ’s body, which is supposed not to have needed resurrec- tion, cannot have experienced injury and death; in the place of the resurrection must be substituted the ascension; and, ac- cordingly, His sufferings must undoubtedly be deemed Doce- tical. - NOTES. 471 Note 27, page 158. Decidedly favourable thereto is Athan. c. Ar. 4, 25 (see Note 1, page 153). Contrary thereto appears to be the pas- sage 4, 13, where we read,—Ei tolvuyy 1) wovas wratuvOcica yéyove TpLas, y Sé wovas eoTLv oO TaTHpP, Tplas Sé TaTip, vids, dywov mvetua: mpatov pev, TAaTUVOEica 4 movas Tabs wrré- pewve, Kal yéyovey Orrep oOvK Hv,—to Wit, cHua—errAaTUVON yap ovK ovca TAaTeia. “HEretta, e+ avty 1 povas ératuvOn eis Tptdda,—o avTos apa TaTnp yéyove Kal vos Kal TVEDMa KaTA SaBerriov: exrds ef pur) 1) Neyowévyn trap av’T@ pwovds ado Ti éote Tapa Tov matépa. Ovx ére ody TAaTUVETVaL (sc. avTOV) det Aéyerw (al. Adyov) GAN % povas Tpidyv TromTiKH, HoTE Eivas povdea, eita Kal Tatépa Kal viov Kal mvedua. But even it does not prove, either that Sabellius consistently carried out the dis- tinction between the Monas and the Father, or that he gave distinct utterance to it (for otherwise Athanasius could not have spoken so doubtfully regarding it); the utmost it proves is, that Sabellius sometimes verged towards the distinction (compare Neander’s “Church History,” ed. 2, vol. 11. pp. 1024 f., German Ed.). Baur, on the other hand, following the example of Schleiermacher, is of opinion, that Sabellius dis- tinguished the Monas very clearly from the Father. Sabellius’s designating the one God viordtwp, Son-Father (Greg. Nyss. Or. c. Ar. et Sabell. in A. Mai Coll. Nov. T. 8, Appendix p. 1), does not decide the matter; for we do not know whether to translate,-—“ The Monas became viordtwp, that is, both Father and Son ;” or, “The Father as unity becomes also Son.” The prefixing of vids seems to be opposed to the former translation ; whereas it is very intelligible if we adopt the latter. This also was the view taken of the matter by Gregory of Nyssa. Nore 28, page 158. The words of Hilarius in his “de Trin.” 7, 39,—“ut in assumto homine se filium Dei nuncupet, in natura vero patrem,” etc. might be taken to imply, that as Sabellius designated God in the incarnation Son, so he designated God in nature Father. But “in natura” may also signify “by nature ;” for this notice is too isolated, and is too little accredited by Greek Fathers, te permit us to build any argument upon it. Even Athanasius 472 APPENDIX. did not know in what relation the 7Aatucpol stood to the crea- tion. C. Ar. 4, 14. If, says he, the self-expansion of God did not exist from the very beginning, He must have had a reason for passing over into expansion. What was this reason? After inquiring whether this reason could be that the Father might acquire a Son, or that the incarnation might take place, he says,—ei 5é dua 76 xtlcas éraTUvOn, atoTrov. For the Monas cannot have become powerful in consequence of the expansion, but must have been powerful already in itself. Moreover, on that supposition the world would cease to exist when the 7Aa- rucjos was withdrawn. Athanasius quotes elsewhere expres- sions of Sabellius verbatim (for example, 4, 25). And yet even he was unable to say whether or no Sabellius conceived creation to be one of the purposes of the expansions of God. Against this supposition may be pleaded, too, that he represented God as arriving at a new revelation only after withdrawing from the earlier: this may be carried out to a certain extent in the relation between legislation and Christ, and between Christ and the Holy Ghost; that is, if the significance of Christ is con- ditioned solely by sin. But how can Sabellius have supposed that the creation would cease, if the revelation begins with the incarnation? (Compare pp. 160 f.) Nore 29, page 159. Athan. c. Ar. 4, 25:—To the Sabellians the Father must be both Logos and Spirit, in that, mpos tv ypelav éxdorou dppofomevos, to the one He is Father, to the other Logos (that is, Son), and so forth. ’Avayxn 5é cal mavOncecbar TO dvopa Tov viov Kal Tov mvevpmaTos, THS xpEelas TANPwOEicns. Basil. Ep. 210,—Tov airov Ocov &va TO UTroKenpév bvTA TpOs TAS EKa- OTOTE TapaTITTOVGAS YpElas WEeTAMOpPOU[EVOY VUV eV WS TATEpA, vov S€ ws vIOV, VOY WS TO ayLov mrvedua SiadéyerOas (a passage without doubt quoted verbatim). Ep. 214,—"Eva pév eiva, rH iToctace. Tov Oeov, mpocwromoseicOar Sé WTO THS ypadhs Sia- popws, Kata TO ilwpa THs UTroKEwévns ExdotoTE yYpelas, Kal viv EY TAS TaTpiKas éavT@ TrepiTOévar dwvas, bray TovTOU KaLpos 9 TOU Tpocw7Tov, voy Sé€ Tas vim TMpeTOovVaas viv Sé TO TOU TvEevpatos viTodverOat mpocwreiov. Ep. 235,—Thv adrny iToctacw Tpos THY ExdoTOTE TapeuTinTovcay ypelay peTa- oynuativecOar. August. Tract. in Joann. 53,—“ Pro diversi- NOTES. 473 tate causarum ipsum dici Filium, ipsura dici Spiritum Sanctum.” Of the Son, in particular, Epiph. Heer. 62, 1;—ITeudh0évta tov rN lal (4 > a \ VLOY KALP@ TOTE, WOTTED AKTIWA, Kal Epyacduevoy Ta TavTa ev A A a > f a > aA an TO KOTMW TA THS OLKOVOMLAS THS EevayyEhKs Kal cwTNplas TOV > , ) / de 50 > 5) A ¢ eee NY TR avOparrav, avarnplerta dé avis eis ovpavov, ws td Alou TeupGeioav axtiva, Kal TAL Eis TOV HALOV avadpamovcar. Nore 30, page 160. Whether the speaking of God, through which the world was brought into existence and still exists, is conceived as an actual creation, and the trinitarian self-evolution of Ged as there- fore taking place on the basis of a world distinct from God; or whether God Himself is the plurality which attaches to His works (for Athanasius repeatedly asserts that God Himself ¢s, that to which He expands Himself); or whether the creation also was represented as a self-evolution of the Monas (a view which Athanasius frequently attempts to fasten upon him; see ce. Ar. 4, c. 11-14), is not quite clear. As he certainly held the trinitarian revelation to be a self-continuation of the speaking Monas or Logos—which is very clearly evident in connection, at all events, with the incarnation; and as the standing desig- nation of the incarnation is self-evolution; we might refer the same expression to the creation also. The views of Sabellius would thus acquire a certain unity, in that all the relations of God to the world would be classed under the one type of self- expansion. It is possible, however, that Sabellius may have shrunk from the pantheistic consequences contained in the term “self-expansion,” have limited it to the sphere of spirit, and have conceived it as a gradually intensitied informing, by God, of a world which already existed in distinction from Him- self. And, indeed, this charge of Pantheism was not brought against him; a circumstance which ought to be noted. The charge of Dualism lay much nearer. For he represents the impulse to the divine movements within the world, as arising solely from that which for God already had existence; and conceived that God needed a given material, an eternal An, for His work of creation. His view may have resembled that of Hermogenes. (Compare Leopold’s “ Hermogenis de origine mundi sententia,” 1844, pp. 8-22; especially note 9.) Dionysius of Alexandria also demonstrated the impossibility of 474 APPENDIX. an eternal #Am, in opposition to Sabellius (Kuseb. Preep. Evang. 7,19). Further, if Sabellius had held that God Himself be- came the world, he could not have retained the unity of God, which it was his purpose to retain; the distinctions would then have existed in the divine life itself, and not have first owed their rise to the world. Creation, redemption, and sanctifica- tion would then be three momenta or stadia of the development of His life: and Sabellius would thus have given up the efforts he had been making to combine the objectivity of revelation with the unity of God and the indivisibility of His essence. Instead of saying,—For the sake of the ‘dua, of the peculiarity of the need of the world, He purposed to assume the mode of existence of the Son,-although it stood in no essential and necessary relation to His own inner being; he was now com- pelled to say,—The vital evolution of God took the course of evolving itself into a world, and so forth. And if, in the view of Sabellius, it was essential to the idea of God, that He should be not merely a silent, but also a creative or a world-forming God, even so essential must also have been the other revela- tions. The correct view to take of the matter is, probably, that Sabellius accepted and presupposed the doctrine of the Logos traditionally ; though neither in the strictly hypostatical form given it by Origen, nor in the sense that the world is clearly and purely distinguished from the Logos. But just as some of the older writers,—for example, several of the Apologists, Clemens Alex. and Tertullian,—held that the world was imme- diately contained in God, and conceived the distinction between the Logos and God as He is in Himself to have been first fully accomplished at the creation of the world, without therefore intending to be pantheistic ; so may it have been with Sabellius, with the difference, that inasmuch as he assumed an eternal drm, he identified merely the idea or the forms of the real world - with the Logos, and more distinctly than Clemens let fall the hypostasis of the Logos :—indeed, strictly viewed, to represent the world as immediately contained in the Logos, is to exclude His hypostasis. It is also deserving of remark, that in com- bating (c. Ar. 4, 11) the Sabellian dcetrine of the Logos, Athanasius really combated all those older teachers of the Church who conceded to the Logos, prior to the creation of the world, at the utmost a latent and inactive existence in God NOTES. 475. (compare Note 1, page 154), and au actual existence merely subsequently to the creation. Norte 31, page 161. The Fathers of the Church adduce no evidence to show that he believed that the world would one day perish. It is in itself improbable that he held such an opinion, and is very likely a mere conclusion drawn from the transitoriness of the members of the Sabellian Trinity. It would undoubtedly be correct if the Father, as the first member of the Trinity, were the Creator. In that case, however, creation must have disap- peared with the appearance of the Son in the incarnation, even as the law also was then done away with; which may again be an indication, that Sabellius did not attribute creation to the first member of the Trinity. As concerns the Spirit, Sabellius neither demonstrated nor proclaimed a new revelation after Him; nay more, he did not even teach that He would some time cease to confer His gifts: indeed, this would have been far from harmonizing with the continuance of the world, which he undoubtedly assumed. Nor did he maintain that the mpo- cw7ov of the Spirit would cease to exist, unless we accept the words of Gregory, quoted in Note 32, as true. He might, accordingly, have held that history terminates with the age of the Spirit. If he held that God began to create as the speaking God, we might suppose that creation would attain its perfection in the age of the Spirit (Athan. c. Ar. 4, 1l,—ow7av pev [Qeds] ove HddvaTo Tovey, Maddy dé KTiew HpEaTo). The intervening sin would then be set aside by the revelation in the law and the incarnation (Aerota&ia; see the passage from Gregory of Nyssa, quoted on page 712); humanity would be led back to the beginning, to the rd&s in the Holy Ghost, in a higher way; thus the Holy Spirit would have brought in a new and permanent element. It is more probable, however, that he believed the Holy Ghost to lead men back merely to a perfection which they had at the beginning. At all events, Epiphanius says,—The Holy Ghost is sent into the world te every one who is counted worthy of receiving again life and warmth (avafmyoveiv 5é tov TotodTov Kal avatéew) ; with which agrees also the passage above quoted from Gregory of Nyssa. Accordingly, he was able to represent the mpdcwzrov of the A76 APPENDIX. Holy Spirit, so far as it was directed against sin, as ceasing to exist, whereas the positive element in His gifts remains, a \ Suh > ff Ninoy, > / \ adnOwod rarpos, dopatos aoparou, Kat apGaptos ad@aptou, Kat > tr b v4 \ > Sf. 9eQ/ NU a ee > dOdvatos aOavatou Kal aidsos aidiov. Kai ev mvevpa ayvov, eK Ocod tv UrapEw exov, Kat dv avtod mednvos Sndadi Tots avOpo- mots, ekaVv TOD viol TEAr«lov TErcla, Fon Covrov aitia, ayloTns ayiac pod Yopnyos, €v @ pavepodTar Ocds 6 TaTHp O él TavT@V Na a? aA \ x SN € \ is AN / I \ Ka ev Tao, Kat eds vids 0 Ova TaVTMV, TpLaS TEhEla do&n Kat aidwornts Kal Bacirela pr) peptCopév 5é amandXoTpLouper dry uotrela pa) mepibopcvn poe oTpLoupiern. > 3 3 an 3 > > Oiire obv Kxtictov te 1) SodNov ev TpLad., OTE eTELTAKTOV, WS / \ > ¢e / ef NG? / A 9 TpoTEpov pev ovX UTapXoV, VaTEPOV dé émrecceAOov. Ovrte ovv evérumé mote vios Tatpl, ote vid TrEeDUA, GAN aTpeTTTOS Kat avadrXrolwros % adtl tpids ae’. In favour of the genuineness speaks the Origenistic form of the sentences before the con- clusion, the vagueness with which the question of the essence of the Son is treated ;—it was a characteristic feature of the age of the Arian conflict, to return from the subject of the personality to that of the essence. Suspicion may be enter- tained relatively to the last words, concerning the Holy Spirit ; because they already teach His eternity. But compare Note 1, page 173. Norte 36, page 181. In his first work against Sabellius, Dionysius of Alexandria said (Euseb. Prep. Evangel. 7, 19),—Ei pev yap avts ayévyn- rév éotw 6 Ocds, Kal ovola éativ abtod, ws dv elirot Tis H ayer NOTES 483 vnola, ovk av ayévynrov ein 4 DAN; in other words, not to be generated is represented as the essence of God, after the man- ner of the Arians. But if that be the essence of God, then must the Son, whom he probably described as generated in this work also, stand outside of the divine essence. To this, how- ever, we may reply,—In the passage referred to, the unbegotten- ness of God,—not of the Father,—is opposed to the #An as be- gotten, not to the Son. Besides, we never afterwards find any trace of such a view in the Alexandrian Bishop. He only re- tained subordination in the sense in which the teachers of the Church long continued to hold it,—in the sense, to wit, that the Father is the source of deity, which would imply that He is at one and the same time the whole and a member of the Trinity (compare de Sent. Dionys. c. 18, 22, 23). To this connection be- longs also, perhaps, the fragment of the work of Dionysius, vrepi édeyxou Kal aoroyias, in A. Mai’s “ Coll. Nov.” T. 7, 96:— "Avapyla uadrov Kal otdots, #) e& icorywlas avriTrapeEayouern ; from which it is evident that he was an opponent of Tritheism. Nore 37, page 181. \ io e e ld / A A [Tpocipnrat pev odv, says Dionysius, bre myn tov dyabev / e NS \ >) A / id \ aTavtwv éotly 6 Ocds, TOTAMLOS O€ UT aUTOD TPOYEOMLEVOS O VLOS / , A / \ avayeyparral amdoppota yap vod NéOyos (the Word). Kail os / fal \ i / - ém avOp@rav eimeiv ad Kapoias Sta oTOmaTtos eEoyverTeveTas, ¢ / Cali} / / ¢ \ / ral ETEPOS YEVOMEVOS TOU ev Kapdia AOYoU O dia YAWooNS vos Tpo- a & \ / / Ne, @ 9 \ TNooV" Oo mev yap Eéueuve TpoTreuwpas, Kal EaTLv otos Hv: Oo bé / A \ \ e€emtn mpoTrendpbels Kal pépetar Tavtayod: Kat ottws eat V4 p 3 fe ld (6 exaTepos év éexatépo, Etepos av Garépou' Kat &v eiaw, dvtes Svo° e \ VS si \ ¢ e\ v4 \ > b) / (4 OUTM Yap Kal 0 TATHP Kai oO ULOS EV Kal ev ANXjdOLS hey Ojoav 2 ° ° ¢ / eat. Another passage runs as follows (ibid.) :—'Ds 0 jérepos a / b) A \ / 4 \ vovs epevyetas ev ad’ éavtod Tov AOyov—Kal gore pev EKATEPOS ? Ye An / > XN €tepos Oatépov, idvov Kal tod Rourod KEYWPLOLEVOV ELMNYXOS / € \ 3 a / e Nee EEN fal / \ a / TOTOV, O pev ev TH Kapdia, oO Oé ert THS yAwTTNS Kal TOU oTd- PE a / \ > \ / HATOS OLKGY TE KAL KIVOUpEVOS’ ov piv SieaTHKacLW, OUSE KAdTraE b) / / Ea) ” e an bY oo v7 aNdWY TTEPOVTAL, OVSE EoTLY OUTE O VOdS dAOYOS OTE VOUS ¢ / 5) > a a \ if > b) A / Ae as 0 Noyos, AAX O ye vows Totes TOV AOyoU év aUT@ Paves? Kal O / ( / al aA Aoyos eyKelpwevos, 0 € NOYos vods mpoTNdSav' Kal peOlaTaTaL ev id A \ / ¢ f \ A \ \ 0 vovs els TOV AOYoV, 0 SE Adyos TOV vod eis TOS akpoaTas an a id An / an an / EYKUKNEL, KAL OUTHS O VoDS Sia TOD Aéyou Tals TOV adKovdvT@V , / A y ¢ \ a Wuxats evidpverar cvvectov TO Oyo" Kal otw 6 pev olov 484 APPENDIX. maTnp 0 vovs TOD Noyou, ay eh’ EavTod, 6 Sé Kabdrep vids 6 NOyos TOO vod" mpd éxelvou pev advvaTor, arn ovdé &Ewbév Trobev civ éxelv yevopevos, Bractycas Sé am avTod oTws O TaTHP 6 péytotos Kal KaOdXou vods TpeTov TOV viov Noyov épynvéa Kat dryyedov éavtod éye. This exposition reminds us of Origen and Hippolytus; but it bears a still closer resemblance to the Logology of the Apologists. Still the step taken in advance since Tertullian’s time, which consisted in discriminating the Son from the Xdyos = vods, is not given up. It is true, the Son is spoken of as vods here also; not, however, as such, but as the vods which had assumed another mode of being (we@iotatae 6 vods eis tov NOyov). Thus through this werdoracis of the xaddXou vods into the hypostatized Word he arrives at an ob- jectified vods, or a duplication of God; for in speaking of a uetdotacs, he by no means intends to teach a conversion in which God the Father should cease to be what He was. Norte 38, page 183. De Synodis 16;—3aBerruos tiv povada VIOTTATEPA €LTTED. Compare Hilar. de Trin. 4, 12; 6, 5, 11. Hilarius adds in the latter passage,—“ Divisee a Sabellio unionis (that is, of the Monas) crimen exprobrant, cujus unionis divisio non nativita- tem intulit, sed eundem divisit in virgine.’ Schleiermacher finds these words obscure; but the meaning probably 1s,— There would be no objection to be made against a distinction, still less against the division of the Monas, if it preceded and were the principle of the birth of Christ; but they rather divide God in the Virgin ; that is, the birth and humanity of Christ are the principle of a division in God, and since the incarnation the person of the Son stands over against that of the Father. We find exactly the same thought also in the work adv. Sab. Gregal. c. 8. When the objection was brought against the Sabellians, that the Scriptures so frequently dis- tinguish Christ and the Father as two persons, they replied,— We also recognise two hypostases ; the one is God the Father, the other is the Son, who is a man (kal odtw dvo0 troctacets dalvecOar, Eva Tov Tatepa Ocov, Erepov SE Tov viov avO@pwrrov) ; to which it was again answered,—In that sense Paul of Samo- sata also recognised two hypostases. Here is, at the same time, the weak point of the Sabellian system, at which Patri- NOTES. 485 passianism might again be resuscitated; even as, through the incarnation, an dzroxo77 might be introduced into God. The same thing is clear also from ec. 6 and 12, where Sabellians, in order apparently to meet the demand for a Trinity, are said to have resorted to the evasion,—when they conceded distinc- tions, they wished at all events that God (so far as He reveals Himself in the world) should be compounded of three things (atvOeros éx TPLaV TrPAYWaTwV). Nore 39, page 183. Some difference remains here between the two Dionysiuses. The Roman Dionysius develops nothing that resembles a dupli- cation, a self-objectification of the vots, and must therefore either have conceived the Father in Himself, apart from the Son, as without power and wisdom, or have regarded the Son in the light of an attribute: and it is not probable that he intended to do either. Whereas the Alexandrian Dionysius reckoned, even at a later period, power and wisdom to the essence of the Father; for he held the Father Himself to be the Aoyos as éyxetuevos (see page 180). This was more cor- rect in itself, and was also accepted by later teachers of the Church, in order that the Son might not be reduced to a mere attribute of the Father, and that there might not be attributes of which the Father was destitute. The Alexandrian Diony- sius probably intended thus to characterize the Father as per- fect in Himself, even apart from the Son; whereas the Roman Dionysius, with his doctrinal form, intended to say, that apart from the Son only an imperfect conception could be formed of the Father. His aim, therefore, was to connect the Son more distinctly with the divine essence itself. Still this formula always threatens the hypostasis of the Son, in the manner of Sabellianism. And, in point of fact, the Roman Dionysius does not appear to have expressed himself so strongly against Sabellianism as against the Tritheites and Subordinatianists of the above kind. Norte 40, page 196. For the sake of completeness, we will here devote a word to Victorinus, who, as a Greek by birth and yet a Latin Bishop, occupies a middle position between the East and the 486 APPENDIX. West. We have a tolerably long fragment of his, entitled “de Fabrica Mundi” and “Scholia in Apocalypsin” (compare “ Victorini Petavionensis in Pannonia superiore episcopi opera ” in Gallandii Bibliotheca Vett. PP. T. 4, pp. 49-64). The genuineness of the fragment is unquestionable; but it is in part scarcely intelligible, owing to its bad Latin and the writer’s awkwardness in the use of language, with which even Jerome also seems to have been struck. These faults are somewhat less glaring in the other work, which may possibly be due to the copyist. In the fragment we not merely read,—“ Verbo domini cceli firmati sunt, et spiritu oris ejus omnis virtus eorum; —sic dicit Pater ejus; eructavit cor meum verbum bonum: and John,—in principio erat Verbum, et Verbum erat apud Deum, et Deus erat Verbum—omnia per ipsum facta sunt, et sine eo factum est nihil,’—but he also assigns to the incarnation so high a place, in virtue of mystical numbers (in use also by earlier writers), that he regards it and the history of Christ as the idea that dominates the universe. The Son with the Father, he holds to be the unity of the seven spirits of Isaiah ; in the six days of creation these spirits successively revealed themselves. He completes the number seven by representing the Son as revealing Himself to the human race in two prin- cipal forms:—firstly, as the principle of the fear of God; secondly, as the principle of blessing and sanctification. Fur- ther on, however, the six days’ work is typically employed for the parallel with the history of Christ, and particularly with the week of the Passion (c. 2, 6). For example :—As Christ came (in carnem conversus) that Adam might be created anew, He assumed human nature on the same day of the week on which Adam was created, He suffered on the same day on which he fell, and so forth. At the basis hereof lies the idea of a full “ recapitulatio,’—an idea which we have already found set forth by Irenzeus. With this fragment, whose conclusion also treats of the Apocalypse, the other work has the most un- mistakeable affinity, both in style and thought. Jor example, the “septem spiritus” are very frequently employed for the explanation of apocalyptic passages; the mystic numbers of the fragment occur also in the Scholia, especially the construc- tion of the history of the world according to the number seven, —a procedure which has drawn upon its author the unjust NOTES. 487 charge of Chiliasm (for example, from Cave), whereas the con- clusion of the Scholia expressly protests against the supposition that the completed kingdom of Christ will endure only 1000 years, and not for ever. Both monuments undoubtedly lay very great stress on eschatology, on the judgment through Christ, and on the perfection at the last day. These scholia supply far fuller Christological data; but as the work has pro- bably suffered from interpolations, doubt is thrown on the elements just referred to. So, for example, the number 666, Apocalypse xiii. 18, alongside of earlier and more absurd ex- planations (recrav, Diclux), is referred also to a “ verbum gothi- cum Tevorpixos.” The words, “ He who is, and who was, and who is to come” (Apocalypse i. 4), he explains as follows,— “ Est, quia permanet, erat, quia cum Patre omnia fecit, et nunc ex virgine initium sumsit, ventwrus est, utique ad judicandum.” He redeemed humanity by His sufferings (1,5; 5,45; 12, 1-4). Death is the “debitum” of every descendant of Adam ; not, however, of Christ (qui de semine natus non erat, nihil morti debebat, propter quod eum devorare non potuit, id est in morte detinere). He became “agnus;” but “tanquam leo confregit mortem” (5, 5), Thus was he made heir (“ heres Domini,’ not “Diaboli”), “ut possideret substantiam morientis, 1. e., membra humana (5, 4, 5). Ut sicut per unum corpus omnes homines debito mortis suze ceciderant, per unum etiam corpus universi credentes renati in vitam resurgerent.” The higher nature of Christ is here also described as the unity of the seven spirits (Apol. 1, 4; 5, 6); but on c. x. 1 he remarks,— “Patrem esse dicimus et hujus Filium Christum ante originem seculi apud Patrem genitum, hominem factum in anima vera (?) et carne,—morte devicta et in coelos cum corpore a Patre re- ceptum effudisse Spiritum Sanctum.—Hunc per prophetas preedicatum, hunc per legem conscriptum, hunc esse manum Dei et Verbum Patris ex Deo, per omnia Dominum et con- ditorem Orbis.” The author is specially zealous in his attacks on Dualism, because it aims at rending asunder the Old and New Testaments. The Word was the founder of both Testa- ments. Eyerything in the Old Testament is treated by him as atype of Christ. But the type still resembles an unbroken seal, a shut temple; nay more, one seal has been added to the other in the Old Covenant. The opening of the seals (Apocalypse 488 APPENDIX. v.), which no one could accomplish save the Lion of tlie tribe of Judah, the Root of the stem of Jesse, is the opening of the Old Testament (v. 8, 9); by Christ all the seven seals are broken at once. He is the opened temple of God (compare Apoc. v.). The new song which is sung after the breaking of the seals by His death, is the confession of the new element in Christianity. New is it, that the Son of God should become man (whose Head is God, Apocalypse i. 14); that He should ascend up to heaven in the body (which He united with the spirit of His glory, Apocalypse i. 12); new, that He forgives our sins, and so forth (Apoc. v. 8, 9). In accordance herewith, he explains the woman, which is adorned with the sun and travails in birth, to be the old Church of the fathers and prophets, of the saints and apostles (prior to its union with Christ). This old Church “ genitus et tormenta desiderii sui habuit, usquequo fructum ex plebe sua secundum carnem olim promissum sibi videret Christum ex ipsa gente carnem sumsisse.” He deemed the incarnation, therefore, to be the uncovering of the divine mystery, on which the noblest minds of the old period had toiled with earnest longings. He then naturally conceives this humanity to be permanently united with the Word. Because of His incarnation, says the Scholium to Ap. i. 16, is He ap- pointed judge of the world. The Father intended to show, “quoniam verbo preedicationis judicabuntur homines” (com- pare on Apocalypse vi. 1, 2, 5), that only the highest revelation of God can judge men. Note 41, page 196. The unity of Christ, ef xal ta padwota ToAXals érrwotats émwoeitat, is expressly defended. Pamphilus, however, found it necessary to answer the charge of teaching two Christs, which was the fifth brought against Origen (Apol. c. 5). Now, as Paul of Samosata did not teach two Christs, but a Logos and a man, representing the latter, however, as becom- ing Christ, through His union with the former, the words of the Confession of Faith (Hahn’s “ Bibliothek,” ete. p. 96) will not refer to him; unless we suppose that here also Paul had spoken dishonestly of the generation of the Logos, in order to make it appear as though he attributed an hypostasis to the Logos (even as to the man Jesus), either prior to the creation NOTES. 489 of the world, as the spurious letter of Dionysius of Alexandria maintains; or at the incarnation, as Ehrlich thinks, when the évépyeva, which had hitherto been impersonal, became a person. This view bears some analogy to that of Tertullian and others, according to whom the Logos became a person at the creation, but it was not Paul’s; compare Schwab’s “de Pauli Samos. vita atque doctrina dissert. inaug.,” 1839, § 12, pp. 64 f. Norte 42, page 197. Eusebius, who gives us long fragments of the discussions of this Synod (H. E. 7, 27-30), says also, that a doctrinal por- tion was recorded in writing; but he has not preserved it. The Confession of Faith directed against Nestorius, discovered amongst the Acts of the Synod of Ephesus, is spurious (see Hahn |. c. p. 129); for it contains the word ojoovctos, whereas we know that the Synod of Antioch avoided it, because of the abuse made of it by Paul. On the other hand, with Hahn and Walch, I consider that recorded in Mansi 1, 1035, Hahn, pp. 91 ff., to be genuine. It neither contains the term opooveros, nor any other determination which does not completely suit the period to which it is attributed. The vagueness which charac- terizes it in important points, and of which the Arians took advantage, would be inexplicable if it had been framed subse- quently to the Council of Nicea. But precisely because of this remnant of vagueness, that other Confession of Faith appears to be a spurious changeling. Nore 43, page 226. More particular mention is here deserved by a man who ex- erted a great influence on many Orientals of the Nicene gene- ration, to wit, Lucian of Antioch, the martyr. That he was like-minded with Paul of Samosata, is an unfounded suspicion cast upon him by the heresy-hunters, with which it is inconsist- ent that the Arians appealed to him as a witness in favour of their views (Epiph. Her. 48). But quite as far am I also from believing that Lucian’s affinity to the Arians is the result of a falsification of his writings by that party, as Athanasius sur- mises. On the contrary, there is no reason for throwing doubt on the declaration of the Semi-Arian Synod of Antioch, held in the year 341, that the Confession of Faith which they 490 APPENDIX. adopted as their own (the so-called Second Anticcheian For- mula) was that of Lucian the Martyr (see Sozomen. H. E. 3, 5, cll. 6, 12). It runs as follows (according to Athanas. de Syn. Arim. et Seleuc. § 23, T.i. p. 2, 735),—“ We believe in one God, the Almighty Father, the Former and Creator of the universe, and the Provider; and in one Lord, Jesus Christ, His only-begotten Son, the God through whom are all things (dc ob), who was begotten of the Father before all ‘Mons, God of God, a whole of the whole (€£ 6dov), an only one of the only one (ovov), a perfect one of the Perfect, a King of the King, a Lord of the Lord, who is living Word (Adyos), living Wisdom, true Light, the Way, the Truth, the Resurrection, the Shep- herd, the Door, immutable and unalterable (dtpemrov te xat avanrdolwtov); the unchangeable image (a7rapadnaxtov eixova) of the deity, of the essence (ovcias), of the will, of the power and glory of the Father, the First-born of all creation, who was in the beginning with God, as God the Word, according to the Gospel;—who in these latter days came down from above, and was born of a virgin, according to the Scriptures, and became man, Mediator between God and men, the Apostle of our Faith, the Captain of our salvation, as He saith, ‘I came not to do Mine own will, but the will of Him that sent Me;’-— who suffered for us and rose again the third day, ascended up to heaven, and sitteth at the right hand of the Father, from whence He will come again, with power and glory, to judge the quick and the dead ;—and in the Holy Ghost, who is given for the comfort, sanctification, and perfection of believers; as the Lord commanded to baptize into the name of the Father, of the Son, and of the Holy Ghost (Matthew xxviii.). Since the Father is truly Father, the Son truly Son, and so also the Spirit truly Spirit, and the names are not empty and idle, but for each of the afore-mentioned exactly denote the hypostasis, the order and the glory (ra&w «al Sd£av), so that there are three as to hypostasis, but one in harmony (77 cvpdovia dé &). In this faith, which we hold from the beginning and to the end, we condemn all heretical false faith; and if any teach in opposition to the sound true faith of the Scripture, saying, There was an interval, a time, or an Alon, before the Son was generated, let him be anathema. And if any call the Son a creature, like one of the other creatures, or a production or work, like one of the NOTES 49} other productions or works, and refuses to teach each one of the afore-mentioned points, one after the other, as the Holy Scriptures have handed them down, and teaches other than as we have received, let him be anathema,” etc. ‘This Confession of Faith, with the exception perhaps of the close, which does not really belong to it, accords exactly with the Pre-Nicene period, and is marked by the following noteworthy features: 1. The Father is identical with the one God (eis Oeds); He represents the povapyia. The Son, therefore, is termed, not coeternal with the Father, but the image of His essence and of His attributes ; He is not equal to the Father, but stands in ra€es and 60a under Him. We can, accordingly, understand why Athanasius was not quite satisfied with the Confession, and why Arian falsifications were surmised. 2. On the other hand, how- ever, the Son is designated God of God; His perfection, singu- larity, immutability, and exaltedness above time, are asserted with a decision which proves how offensive Arianism must have been to those whose doctrinal convictions were firmly established, and tolerably developed. Lucian therefore (he died a.p. 311) vecupies substantially the same point of view as Kusebius. Measured by a strictly scientific standard alone, both of them are more closely related to Arius than to Athanasius. For, without question, if the Father is the one God by Himself alone, nothing remains for the Son but to be a creature, and there is no place for a Trinity. To posit a middle thing be- tween God and a creature, is unquestionably a contradictory procedure, and an expedient of the resort to which Eusebius and his adherents had already anticipatorily deprived them- selves, by representing God as too exalted to enter into any immediate connection whatever with the world, and therefore with that which resembled the world. But to a this, would be to measure them by a scientific standard foreign to them. For such a middle being, which is for us an incogitable thing, seemed to them not only cogitable, but even the solution of the difficulty. They are consequently not to be measured by the more perfect scientific standard ; for, according to it, they ought, without doubt, consistently to have gone on to Arianism. But precisely because their theory was in itself so far from meeting the requirements of science, it is necessary to refer back to their Christian consciousness, as the second factor, 492 APPENDIX. which alone furnishes an explanation of their procedure. In- deed, with men like Eusebius, this second factor was so de- cidedly the earlier and more powerful of the two, that if they had become aware of the results to which their theory, scienti- fically considered, must lead, or if they had been compelled to choose between the doctrine of Arius and that of Athanasius, they would not merely have declared themselves against Arius, as in fact, at a subsequent period, they constantly did, but would have given up their own views, and endeavoured to reconcile themselves to the formula of Athanasius. This also was the exact position taken up by Eusebius relatively to the Nicene Council. That Arianism ought to be repudiated, he felt sure; but he was by no means so sure that his theory must scientifi- cally end in Arianism. Now, so far as he feared that Sabelli- anism would be favoured by the term ojoovccov, and supposed either the hypostasis of the Son or the unity of God not to be sufficiently ensured, he shrunk from adopting it; but he con- sented thereto as soon as he had convinced himself, that the Synod had no intention of rejecting Arianism in a sense that would involve giving in its adhesion to Sabellianism or Poly- theism, and that his own view might possibly coexist along with the formulas of the Synod. It is true, the points of difference between him and Athanasius, and to which he also subsequently clung, did not attain recognition at the Council of Nica; but he had a presentiment that a path was thus struck into, which must lead away therefrom, namely, the path towards a lessen- ing of the hypostatical distinctions. Hence the zeal with which he subsequently battled for them in opposition to Marcellus. The momentum about which he was chiefly concerned he saw defended by the Arians, though, it is true, under an exagge- rated form. Herein appeared to him to lie the justification of Arianism; and therefore he was never able to take so decided a part against Arius as others, although he by no means in- tended to rank himself amongst his followers, least of all in a religious point of view. So much the more gratifying is it to find, that Athanasius (de syn. Ar. et Sel. c. 41 f.) did not con- found men of Eusebius’ mode of thought with Arius, as did later Inquisitors, but regarded them as brethren, because they accepted the entire substance of the Nicene Creed, and did not stumble even at the term ouoovccor, in the sense of wishing to NOTES. 493 represent the Son as a creature. On the contrary, they derived Him from the substance of the Father and no other, and be- lieved Him to be the true Son of the nature of the Father, who, as Logos and Wisdom, was eternally with the Father. That Eusebius, with Origen and Pamphilus, could well accept the latter determination, we have shown above. Athanasius, with the equitable judgment he pronounced on the matter, was right in taking into consideration the religious convictions which alone could have produced formulas attributing such lofty attributes to Christ. But he must be pronounced to have been in the wrong, if we regard their doctrine merely in a scientific point of view, and not in the light of the opinion and tendency they really entertained in their inmost heart. Fixing our eye solely on the former, we must allow that they were con- stantly liable to fall into Arianism , it was, therefore, both necessary and highly advantageous for the doctrinal progress of the Church, that Arius should make his appearance: for in him, those who had hitherto held an indeterminate position saw, embodied in a distinct and repellent form, principles which they had no intention of avowing as their own, but the possi- bility of which they had not consciously and thoroughly enough excluded, and were thus led to a decision. Nore 44, page 231. Ta te onpeia Tava, doa érroincer, Kat ai dvvapers Seixvucw avtov Ocdv évavOpwmncavta’ Ta cuvaudhdtepa Toivuy deiKkvUTat OTe Ocds Hv dices, Kab éyévero dvOpwios ducer. In Galland. Bibl. Vet. PP. T. iv. 112, another passage is communicated from the Chron. Pasch., which runs as follows:—O traons dopatov Kal dopatis Ktlicews Snpwoupyos Kal Seamdtns 0 povo- yevns vios Kab Noyos, 6 TO ILarpi nal TO ayiw Tvet pate cuvai- 610s, Kal Omoovatos Kata THY OeoTHTA, oO KUPLOS HuoV Kal Oeos, ‘Incods Xpiotés, éml tH cuvtedela TOV aiovev KaTa capKa TeyOeis ex THs aylas évddEou Seorolvns uav OeotoKov Kai aevrapbévov, Kal Kata adjGeav OeotoKov Mapias, Kai éri Tijs yiis odbels, Kal Tols opoovators Kata THY avOpwrotnTa av- Opetrots @s avOpwros adnOHs cvvavactpadeis, etc. This pas- sage, however, with its formulas, betrays too clearly a post- Nestorian, Eutychian period, to permit of its being taken into consideration in this connection (compare the Prolegg. 494 APPENDIX. ad Bibliuth. Vet. PP. T. i. cxxi.). On the other hand, we may regard as genuine the passage (Gall. 1. c. p. 108), which is preserved in the Acts of the Council of Ephesus,— Grace and truth came by Jesus Christ; by grace are we saved ; it is the gift of God, etc. Oedjpyats Ocod o Aoyos capE eyé- veto Kal oxnpate evpebels ws avOpwros’ ov KatedeipOn Tis OcétynTos* ode yap iva Ths Suvdwews adtod » d0&)s—amooTh, TTMXEVTAS TAOVTLOS WV, TODTO éyéveTo, ANA Wa Kal Tov Bdva- rov iTrép hudv Tov dpaptorav avadéEnrat, Sikatos U7ep adiKov Straws Hyas Tpocayayn TO Oc@, OavarwOels wev capKl, Cworrown- Gels 88 rvebpart.” In another passage, he says,—“ ‘The incar- nation took place when the angel spake to the Virgin, saying, ‘O cds dAéyos apd (notwithstanding) tiv dvdpos arovclay Kata BovAnow Tod TdvTa Suvapévov Katepydcacbat Oecod, yéyovev év pntpa Ths Tapbévov capé, pyte SenOels Tis avopos evepyelas, i) mapoualas: évepyéotepov yap TOD avépos eveTroincev 7) TOD Oeod Sivamis, émicKidcaca Th Tapléve ody TO émEdAAVOOTL ayi avevpatt.’—Mention may further here be made of Eustathius of Antioch (about 325). See Galland. Biblioth. Vet. PP. T. iv. 573 (from Theodor. Dial. 1). Christ’s true descent, says he, is not from Mary. Ei 6€ Adyos Kal Oeds tw avéxabev Tapa TO TaTpl, Kat Ta cbpmavtTa SV avTo yeyevjolat paper, ove dpa yéeyovev eK yuvalKos 0 OV, Kal Tols yerynTots aTrac tw altios BV, GAN éatte Tip dicow Ocds avtapKns, aretpos, aTrept- vontos’ ék yuvaikds S€ yéyovey avOpwros o év TH TapOeviKh patpa mvetpaTe mayels dyio. One of his favourite designa- tions of the Logos is, 6 ¢vceu Tod Ocod vids. Page 574 :—Paul does not say that we shall be formed like the Son of God, but like the image of the Son of God (Rom. viii. 29). ‘O pev yap vids Ta Ocla Tis TaTpwas apeThs yvapicpata Pépwv eik@v éoTe Tod jwatpos, meld Kat Suovor €E opoiwy yevvapevot, eiKoves ot TiKTomevot aivovtat TOV yevvnTopwv adnOeis. The image of the Son is the man whom He bore. His humanity was re- lated to the Logos as the wax to the colours, which, although very unlike it, are painted on it. His sufferings and humilia- tion did not pertain to the essence of the Logos, but are expli- cable solely from His love. By no means, therefore, 6 Xoyos imréxetto TO Voww KAOdTrep of cuKopavTat Sof§dfovor (that is, the Arians, who derived the subjection of Christ under the law of the Old Testament from His subordinate essence), avros dy a NOTES. 495 vowos.— AXN et Kal ex THS TapVévov 70 avOparwov spyavov avaraBav épopece, Kal U7TO Vomou éyévEeTO, KATA Tas TOV TPwTO- roxov alas Kabapiobels (Luc. ii. 21 f.), ode adtos Sedpevos THs TovTav yopnylas Uréueve Tas Oeparrelas, GAN Wa THs TOD vopov Sovrelas eEayopdon Tovs TeTpapévous TH Sixn THs apds. When it is said, “They crucified the Lord of glory (Acts ii. 36), but the same hath God exalted to be Lord and Christ,” both the sufferings and the exaltation refer, not to the Logos, but to the man Jesus, who might well be termed Lord of glory (compare the fragment in Theodor. Dial. 3, Galland. |. c. 575, 576), anabés Xpictod To mvedua ov dSejoe waos TO Oeiw Tpoc- dmrew ; nor did the exaltation concern the Logos (tov ra@ovra "Inoobdv Kvpiov éroincev, Kat od THY Zodpiav ovbé tov Adyov Tov avéxabev Exovta THs Seorrotelas to Kpatos). If there was any defect, any weakness (acOévera) in Him, 76 av@pwr@ tadra Tpocaptav axoovOov civas pain Tis av, odte ye 8) TO TANPO- pate Ths OedTnTOS, ) TO aEtoOpatL THs avwTadTw Zodpias, } TO én mavtwv Kata Ilatrov ypadopévm Oc@. The sun, a visible body, does not suffer, although it is compelled to witness so much that passes on earth; nor does it go out of its path. Shall we then believe, tiv adowpatov Sopiav ypaiveoOa, kai peTadratrew THY diaow, Eb O VALS aUTHs cTAaVPe TpocyrodvTAL, ) AWow Uropéver—} StabOopay rrodéyeTat; ANA TaTKEL MEV 6 veds, 7 S€ AKNALOSwWTOS OVola TavTaTacWW dypavTos THY aktiav Kabéotnkev. Hierakas also, who was the most influential and learned ascetic of Egypt about the year 300, belongs to this connection. Much as Epiphanius finds to blame in him (Heer. 67), he praises him for not coinciding with Origen in the doctrine of the Father, the Son, and the Spirit ; and for really believing that the Son was begotten of the Father. Arius was the first—and not with- out a certain sort of astuteness—to charge him with heresy in the matter of the doctrine of the Trinity. To him we owe a more precise account of the mode in which he conceived the Son to be related to the Father (Epiph. her. 69, 7). He was as a lamp kindled at another; or, God is as a torch which is divided into two (@s Avyvov amd AUxVOV, 1) Os NapTrdda eis SvO; compare Athanas. de syn. c. 16). We have here the same diremption of God into Father and Son as in the case of Zeno; the same fault which Arius finds in Sabellius (see above) 496 APPENDIX. Hierakas held the Spirit to be as nearly like as possible to the Son, but at the same time subordinated the former to the latter. Note 45, page 232. This is implied also by the oldest document we have of Arius, to wit, his letter to Eusebius of Nicomedia, written prior to his stay with him, during which he appears to have written his Thalia. Alexander has driven us away, says he, because we do not agree with him in the doctrine which he publicly teaches :—“ Always was God, always the Son; at the same time is the Father, at the same time the Son; the Son exists at one and the same time with the unbegotten God, for He is ever begotten, unbegotten begotten, ayévyntoyeryntos (this is natu- rally one of the specious conclusions drawn by Arius); in no respect is God before the Son, for the Son is derived from God Himself.” And then, after appealing to Eusebius of Cesarea, Theodosius, Paulinus, Athanasius in Nazarbe, Gregorius and Aetius, and in general to the teachers of the Oriental Church, who all, with the exception of Philogonius, Hellanicus, and Macarius (in Jerusalem), say, that God avdpyws precedes the Son; whilst the three exceptions term the Son an épevy?), mpo- Bor» ayévvntos, he proceeds to give his own doctrine. Nore 46, page 233. Compare Arius’ “ Ep. ad Alex.” in Epiph. and Athan. 1. ec. In this latter he gives the following further remarkable testi- mony to Alexander :—That he had frequently, in the Church and in assemblies, refuted those who taught such doctrines. Preceding are the words,—“ To be rejected is tov dvta mpotepor, votepov yevvnbevta 1 érixticOévta eis viov;” that testimony, therefore, refers perhaps merely to the fact that Alexander had frequently controverted those who supposed that the Son had being prior to His generation or to His suppletory creation. What else can this refer to, than to the circumstance that Alex- ander rejected also the view entertained by many older writers, who conceived indeed that the Son had a certain potential and eternal being in the Father, but still represented Him as first proceeding forth from God for the creation of the world ? Without doubt, therefore, Alexander was unwilling to separate the genesis of the hypostasis of the Son from His deity, which NOTES. 497 existed eternally in the Father; and, on the contrary, endea- voured so to conjoin the eternal divine essence of the Son with His hypostasis, that the latter should be coeternal with the for- mer. But when Arius denied that theory of Tertullian’s, he did it with a different purpose from Alexander. The latter aimed at doing away with the interweaving of the Son with the world, and the subordination essentially therein involved; he therefore removed the yévvnows of the Son into eternity, substi- tuting, in the place of “ potentia” and “actus,” either the eternal “actus,” or, at all events, the idea that the one is eternally con- tained in the other. Arius, on the contrary, in denying the eternal “potentia” of the Son in God, aimed at doing away with the last trace of His eternity. He was to have no essential root in God. Note 47, page 239. Or. 1, 6 :—"EOnxev &v th Oadrela, os dpa Kat TO Vid 6 TaTIp dopatos UTrdpyel, Kal OUTE Opay OTE yiVdcKEW TENELWS Kal aKpLBaS duvatat 0 Adyos Tov éavTOD Tatépa: GAA Kal 6 ywwodoKer Kal d / b) / PX NG, ig a3 \ , v4 \ PreTret, avadoyws Tots idiots wétpots ode Kal BréErrEL, WoTrEp Kal nels ywwaoKouev Kata THY idlav divauw. Kat yap Kai o vids, dyow, ov povoy Tov Tatépa axpiBas od ywooxes' AelTrEL yap avTO > % al b) \ \ SVEN ¢ e\ \ ¢ a > if b Lg ELS TO KATAAAP ELV ANAG Kal AUTOS O VLOS TI EAUTOD OVTlaV OVK OLE" Kal OTL pmemeplopévat TH pvoet, Kat amreEevwpévat, Kab aecxot- / \ > / \ b) / / > b) A € b) / VITMEVAL, KAL AAOTPLOL Kal ALETOXOL ElolY GAN@V AL OVTlaL TOU TATPOS Kal TOV viOD, Kal TOD ayiov TVEvpaToOs, Kal WS a’TOS b) / int. / b) J an x > HA \ / epbeyEato, avomowor Tamav GAAnAwY Tals TE OVoIaLs Kal ddEaLS siee\ Si dee EY ° ° elo em arretpov. ‘Lhe axiom thereby is always,—that every- thing which is not God, is essentially foreign and unlike to God (kat ovoiay &évov). If the entire world is so essentially foreign to God, the Son also must be so (kata mavta avdopmotos THs TOD TaTpos ovolas Kat idvoTnTos) ; and must be classed with things that have been brought into existence, with creatures (/dcos eivat), of which he is one. De Syn. 15:—“ That which has a beginning, is plainly unable either to embrace or to know Him, who is without beginning (€urrepwvoncar 1) Ewrrepidpagacas).” Nore 48, page 247. The Nicene Creed runs in the revised form, given by Hahn (1. c. 105-107), as follows :—ITiorevopev eis va Ocov trarépa VOL. II. 2 J 498 APPENDIX. , e lal 4 t \ > TAVTOKPATOPA, TAVTWY CpaTaV TE Kal adopaTov TonTHY. Kai «is &va Kbpiov Incodv Xpiarov, tov viov Tod Oeod, yervnOévta €K Tov TAaTpOS MovoyEvhj, TOUTETTW EK THs oVTIas TOU Tatpos, Oeov x Ocol, dds é« hwris, Ocdv adynOwov ex Ocod adrnOwvod, yevvn- bévra ob Trombévra, doovctov TO TaTpl, Sv ob TA TaVTA eyEVETO, Ta Te &v TO OUpAVe Kal TA em) THs As Tov Ov was Tous avOpe- mous Kab Sut Thy jwetépav cwrnpiay KateNOovta Kai capx@bevta kat evavOpwnijcavra, Tabovta Kal dvactavta TH TpITN LEAs cai averbdrvra eis Tods ovpavods, Kal épyopevon Kpivat CovTas Kal vexpots. Kat eis 7d aysov mvebua. Tovs oé AéyovTas, OTL Hv more OTe ovK Hv, Kal Tply yevvnOVvaL OdK Tv, Kal OTL EE OVK OVTOY éyéveto, ) e& érépas tUmoctdcews 1%) odclas pacKovtas eivat, 7) KTLTTOV, TPETTOV, 4) GAXOLwTOV TOV viov TOD Ocod, avalepariter kaboruxn éxkanola. The two main positions of Arius—of which the drift of the one was the temporal origin of the Son; of the other, His creation out of nothing—-were excluded by the double affirmative significance of the term ojoovctov, whose two meanings, however, probably found their unity in the fact that both Father and Son are equally truly the essential being ; for which reason, they must both be coexistent or coeternal, and of like substance. Compare, on the double force of opoovoros, Athan. de Syn. 41, 48, 52. Nore 49, page 253. \ X e / xX / qn C. 9:—Suvidov yap o Noyos, 6Tt GAAS OVK av AVOEin TV > , ¢e N: > \ \ an "6 b] an > / avOporrav 1 pOopa, et pn Sua ToD TavTws amolaveiv, aBavatov nr \ i if, 4 \ / > lal dvTAa, Kal TOV TATPOS VIOV, TOUTOU EVEKEV TO Suvdpevov atroVavetv la we an n \ / / éavT® AapBaver cHpa, iva todTo Tov emi TaVTwV oyoU METAra- % e \ / / \ \ \ , Rov avtt wdvrwv txavoyv yévntat TO Oavato, Kat Oud TOV EVOLKN- / ” / \ \ ’ % / € \ cavTa Noyov aplapTtov dtapeivyn, Kal NOLTFOY ATO TAVT@V 1) plopa / An VA e nm \ 4 TAVONTAL TH THS avacTacEews YapUTl. "“Oev ws lepeiov Kat Ovpra \ iA / A > \ ¢ a dF. lal / TAVTOS édevOepov OTLAOV, 0 AUTOS EAVTH érxae TWA TPOTAY@V ’ / >] x / ’ \ n id / >) f x / els CavaTov, amo TAVTMV evOds TaV opolwv Hpavite TOV Oavatov An A ral f ¢ \ / x xX e / TY Tpoapopa TOV KATAAANAOU. L7rep TAaVTAS Yap WV O Aoyos n n / \ lal \ sN \ / Tod Oeodv, eiKoTwS TOV EaUTOD VaoV Kal TO TWLATLKOY Opyavov / > v4 id \ / > / A: 3 / , Tpocayov avThpuxoy UTEP TAVTWY, ETANPOU TO OevAojevov eV A ¢ \ \ Aut / n € / 7 Oavdto Kal odTws cuv@V Sid TOD ofolov Tols TAT O ad@ap- lal n e\ b>) / \ if bed b] / b] lal Tos TOD Meod vids, ELKOTWS TOUS TAVTAS évéducev apPapatav €v TH an \ ’ mept ths dvactdcews érrayyedia. OC. 22:—Tov Oavaroy eis / \ al ” dvalpecw Trepiéuewe, Kal Tov Sidopevoy Cdvatov UTrEp THs TAVTOY NOTES. 499 cwrTNplas EoTevoe TEAELM@TAL. Od TOY EavTOD Gavarov, GANA TOV TOV avOparreoy mrGe TENELMOAL O TOTTI" oOev ov« idio Oavato ovK elye yap, Sar) wv: amreTiOeTo TO opty GNA TOV Tapa TeV avOpwrreav édéxeTo, va Kat TodTOV év TO EavTOD GepaTs TpocEr- Govra té\eov efapavion. Compare 21, 387. Similarly also ce. 20 :—The main cause of His appearance was the common guilt of humanity, which demanded payment. Wherefore tarép zrav- Tov THY Ouvolav avédepey avTt TavTwV TOV EavTOd vadv eis Odva- Tov Tapacioovs, iva Tors ev TaVTAS avuTevOUVoUS Kal édevOEpouS THS apxyaias TapaBacews Tromon SelEn Sé éavtov Kal Oavdrov KpelTTOVa, aTrapyny Ths Tov blov avactdcews TO idiov cHpma apOaprov émiderxviuevos. And afterwards, ibid. :—Through the union with the Logos (77 émuBdoet Tod Adyou els adTO) two wonderful things met in the same being ; OTL TE O TaVTwWY Oava- TOS EV TO KUpLaK® Topatt eTANpovTO, Kal o Odvatos Kal 4} dOopa Sia Tov cuvovTa Noyou &Enhavitero. Nore 50, page 270. It is interesting to see how, under the hands of these Arians, who fought in so abstract a manner for the infinitude, the absoluteness of God, God was reduced to an individual shut up in Himself, that is, substantially to a single finite being. In this is rooted the, not “bold,” but cool (nicht kiihne, aber kiihle) and irreligious assertion of Eunomius, that he knew God even as God knew Himself. If the divine essence is nothing more than the abstractly simple independence of the primitive, fixed, ungenerated Monad; and if, by applying this meagre category to the idea of God, all higher categories are anticipatorily excluded, it is a small or even a trivial thing thoroughly to know such a God. And the teachers of the Church had a thorough right to maintain, in opposition to him, the incomprehensibleness of God. In addition to this, Baur ought, for the sake of historical completeness, to have added, that they defended the cognizableness of God in the Son, in opposition to Arius :—it is clear, therefore, that they aimed at taking a middle course between the timidity of the one and the defiance of the other class of heretics; both which lead to the same result, to wit, to the denial to man of any actual knowledge of God. — Still more mistaken is it to reduce the teachers of the Church hack to Platonism, the Arians to the philosophy of 500 APPENDIX. Aristotle; for, amongst the teachers of the Church also, were some who had received an Aristotelian training. The questions considered were, on the contrary, new; and neither Eunomius’ doctrine of the creation, nor that of the Son, nor that of God, can be said to be Aristotelian. And these are the doctrines in question. These unspeculative men, who employed the simple dialectic of the understanding, were entirely destitute of the Aristotelian mpaétov cwodv, which moves itself. Their concep- tion of God was that of the abstractly simple “Ov, which we find in Neo-Platonism; the Church, on the contrary, which demands that room be left for motion and distinctions, opposed that conception, and ever more completely freed itself from its influence. But at this*Ov an empty abstract idea of God arrives in every age; and in the “étre supreme” of the last century no one will fail to discern the same fundamental thought. Although, therefore, I grant that the Arians were trained in the Aristotelian dialectic, and, on the ground of the empirical feature common to both, recognise a relationship be- tween them; I consider it rather adapted to promote confusion than an understanding of the matter, more to resemble play than sober inquiry, to seek, as Baur does, to class the Arians and their opponents in the Church as Aristotelians and Platonists. Nore 51, page 270. Catech. 11,12. His designating the Logos eternal High Priest, the Father the dpyi of the entire deity, which is the head also of the Logos, and his esteeming the unity of God. to be preserved by the Father, from whom alone divinity proceeds, are slight further traces of his Semi-Arianism. On the other hand, he confesses that the Son was Son of God, not by adop- tion, but by nature,—the only-begotten One, because He has no brother, no one equal to Himself. For, on the contrary, all others become sons through Him, by means of adoption. “He did not rise from the condition of a servant to sonship; but was brought forth by an unsearchable act of generation; He was not first another, who then became other than He had been.” On the question of the mode of this generation he lays down merely negative determinations: that it took place and is to be believed, he will endeavour to show, not how. It is interesting to observe, in his case, how Semi-Arianism was led NOTES. 501 on to the recognition of the coeternality of the Son with the Father, by following out the idea—In the production of the Son, who was not out of nothing, but out of His essence, God is not to be supposed subjected to the limits of time. If time is absolutely to be denied of the Father, and the Son be of the essence of the Father, no interval can be conceived to have existed between the being of the Father and that of the Son, but the latter must proceed eternally forth from the essence of God. From which it follows, strictly speaking, that this gene- ration cannot have been the work of one moment, which never happened again, but must be eternally going on, even as light constantly proceeds from light. Athanasius gives distinct ex- pression thereto; Cyrill also approximates to this idea of Origen, when he asserts that the words, “ This day have I begotten thee,” must be understood of the eternal to-day. At the same time, we find also expressions of an opposite tendency; for example, when he says, “ Far more rapidly than we produce words and thoughts, did He generate the Son.” In this case, the genera- tion is again represented as a single act. He describes the act of generation more precisely as follows:—“The Father did not generate the Son, as a master begets his pupil by his teachings, or as we Christians are made His children by enlightenment. Nor, again, as the spirit of man begets words; for, whereas sounds are scattered, Christ is a consistent and living word; not spoken by the lips and then again dissolved, but continually born of the Father in an unutterable manner and with an in- dependent being. Whilst generating, the Father is neither unconscious, nor does He proceed by choice and reflection; for to say that He does not know and love Him whom He begets, would be godless; and no less godless, to represent Him as first considering a long time and then generating, seeing that He never was without Son. We have not two unbegotten beings, nor again two only-begotten ones; but one is the unbegotten Father, who has no Father; the other is the eternal Son, born of the Father. The Begetter neither robs Himself, nor con- verts Himself into the Begotten; and the Begotten lacks nothing. Not the Father became man, nor did He suffer for us; but the Son, whom the Father sent to suffer for us. Let us then neither estrange Father and Son from each other, nor combine the two to a Sonfatherhood (Sohnvaterschaft) ; let us rather walk in the 502 APPENDIX. royal road, turning neither to the right hand nor to the left. We will not call the Son Father, in order thus to honour Him the more; nor, with the notion of doing honour to the Father, will we regard the Son as a creature ; but let the one Father be worshipped through the one Son, and the worship not be divided.” This, therefore, is all that he demands,—that the unity be not reduced to uniformity, and the distinction be not converted into separation; for the rest, he refrains from more precise determinations, and declares, if not a progressive know- ledge of, yet a full and satisfactory insight into, the nature of this generation, to be impossible. (Catech. 11.) This eternal Word now, begotten before all Afons without mother, took upon Himself in these last days a body from the Virgin, without father. To worship a mere man would be idolatry ; but quite as perverse would it be to designate Christ simply God. If Christ, who is God, did not assume humanity, we are far from redemption. The causes of the incarnation were the following:—Man was the noblest creature, having been made, not by the mere command, but by the hands of God. In six days was the world created—the world for the sake of man, who is in the image and likeness of God. But, moved by envy, the devil cast this noblest of all creatures out: of paradise; the human race became constantly more wicxed. Deep were the wounds of humanity; from the crown of the head to the sole of the foot, there was no soundness in it; its wounds were not attended to; they were not anointed nor dressed. Then God, hearkening unto the prayer of the pro- phets, sent His Son, the Lord and Physician, from heaven. To every one of My warriors, saith He, | will give the royal seal which I won by My wrestlings on the cross, that he may bear it on his forehead. Where sin abounded, there did grace much more abound. Our Lord must needs suffer, but without the devil recognising Him; for had he recognised Him, he would not have approached Him. His body thus became a bait of death; so that when the dragon expected to swallow up it, he was rather compelled to give up those whom he had swallowed. Again, men had heathenishly worshipped God in human forms ; God now became truly a man, in order that the imagination (the self-made service of God) might cease. It was further necessary for Him to be with us, to become like us, in order NOTES. 503 that we might be able to lay hold on, to enjoy, to trust Him. Daniel could not be quickened till a human hand touched him: so did it behove the Physician to be present, the Lord to eat with us as He ate with Abraham; for we could not have borne His naked deity (Cat. 12). Norte 52, page 271. Compare Klose’s “ Geschichte und Lehre des Marcellus und Photinus,”’ Hamburg 1837. The fragments of Marcellus are collected in the Marcelliana, etc. of Rettberg, Gottingen 1794. Compare Epiphan. her. 72; Theodor. her. fab. 2, 103; Basilii M. Ep. 52 (Ed. Paris 1638, T. ili. 80); Hilarius, fragm. 1-3. Above all, Eusebius’ “Libri duo adv. Marc.,” of which the “Libri tres de ecclesiast. theol.” are a continuation, belong to this connection. The Eastern Church held him for heterodox, especially since the appearance of Photius; even Athanasius denied him fellowship. See Klose |. c. pp. 17 ff. Hilarius and Epiphanius hesitate, but still incline to condemn him. The charge of Samosatenism brought by Arians and semi-Arians was unjust, as fairer thinkers have allowed. After his resignation at Constantinople, in the year 336, he betook himself with a Con- fession of Faith to Julius in Rome: it was so framed that Mar- cellus could continue to hold his own view, and yet deceive others. He does not say that he believes in the eternal Son, but refers the being always with God to the Logos. At the close, he speaks of the eternal duration of the kingdom, but in such a manner that the words may be referred to the Father or the Son; indeed, the Father is mentioned immediately before these words. The Confession of Faith is given by Epiphanius. Norte 53, page 286. His doctrine of the Trinity does not appear to have differed from that of Marcellus; indeed, there was no reason why it should. The Dyad, with which Marcellus really contented himself, between the silent and speaking God, he did not need to let drop. For the Holy Spirit he might have found a similar place to that assigned Him by Marcellus, who designates Him a secondary expansion (Theodor. Heer. fab. 2, 10, wapéx- Tacis THs éxtdcews, a branch) of that expansion which was contained in the Son. Only the latter, Photinus was compelled 504 | APPENDIX. to describe rather as an influence on, than a dwelling in, Christ. As to the mode in which Photinus passes over to the humanity of Christ, from a passage in Epiph. heer. 71, we might surmise that he represented it as being brought to pass by means of a conversion of God into man (compare Hilarius, de syn. 38, xi.). This information, which is indirectly sustained by the circum- stance, that he is so frequently styled a Sabellian, might in itself, according to what has been set forth above, be correct, and would only presuppose that Photinus, with the view, on the one hand, of instating the humanity of Christ in its rights (which he declares to have been his intention), and, on the other hand (in agreement with the influence still exerted on him by Marcellus), of drawing in the divine dvvapls, repre- sented this dSdvvauis as converting itself, that is, as reducing itself to the potence which became the man Jesus. By his virtue, this man raised himself up to deity; and thus the deity, or divine power, which had lowered itself to a potence in the complete humanity of Christ, attained again to its original actuality. But although Photinus was by no means alone in entertaining such a theory, it is scarcely reconcilable there- with, that others should speak of him as rejecting all conversion and change on the part of God. Compare especially Vigil Taps. Dial. adv. Arianos, Sabell. et Photin. 1, 4;—“Ceterum Deus inviolabilis et immensus non ex se alium genuit, nec ipse unquam genitus fuit ut merito de se filium habere aut ipse sibi filius esse credatur. (He rather designated the one God Doyo- mdtwp in imitation of the Sabellian viordrwp, avoiding, how- ever, the hypostasis which might lie in the word Son.) Sed est unicus et singularis nec generando passioni obnoxius, nec se ipsum protendendo cumulatus, nec suam in virgine portionem derivando divisioni subjectus.” Independently of this passage in Vigilius, his opposition to Sabellius, against whom he ad- vances it as a reproach, that he represents the essence of God as expanding itself, is scarcely reconcilable with a conversion or division of God. With Marcellus, he restricts this expan- sion to the divine activity. Opposed thereto is also the assump- tion of a true birth from Mary, and of the eternal duration of the humanity. For this reason I coincide with Klose, who characterizes the above statement of Epiphanius as erroneous (p. 79). Epiphanius was, perhaps, led astray by Anathemat. NOTES. 50 xi. of the Synod of Sirmium (of the year 351, in Hilar. de syn. 1. c.), which he may have referred to Photinus, as others did whereas, according to Klose’s probable view, it may have been a justification, as far as Photinus was concerned.—This Synod anathematized also both the application of the idea of the Xeyos mpodopixos and évdtaberds to the Son, and the doctrine of a “ dilatatio” and “contractio” of God. Nore 54, page 330. Baur indeed assigns them an entirely different task from that to which they actually did, and were compelled, to devote themselves. In his opinion, they ought to have described the world as the Son of God; and finding that, instead of doing so, they repudiated the notion as heathenish, he has no alternative, but to look upon the second and third centuries as further ad- vanced than the fourth. For the former had not yet attained a clear perception of the distinction between God and the world; in the Son, many regarded the world as still immediately or physically one with God. And the heathen philosopher Celsus had formed a still more complete conception of this unity of God and the world already, in the second century. Now, as the aim of the Church, during the history of its doctrine of the Trinity, was to overcome both the Jewish and heathenish conception of God, and above all, to render it complete in itself, and then to derive the world (because it is not to be reckoned to the essence of God in Himself) from the will of the essentially purfect God; the entire doctrine, in its further phases, is for Dr Kaur one mass of confusion. The Nicene Council having ex- cluded the Hellenic conception of God, the Church from this time onwards is, in his view, on a false track. A few heretics silone can be said to have seen the truth from afar, and some of the teachers of the Church to have given utterance, at all events in the form of suggestive questions, to sentiments more desirable to hear. That a historian thus at the very outset takes up a polemical position towards the central-point of the efforts of the teachers of the Church, scarcely needs mentioning ; we can well understand also, that such a position must bring with it a perennial feeling of discontent with the entire work of ene teachers of the Church (that is, in reality with the entire course of the history of the doctrine), which is not likely to 306 APPENDIX. further the true understanding of the matter. Our great aim ought to be, to penetrate to the very centre of the efforts of the Church Fathers, and thus historically to comprehend why the heathenish conception of God neither did nor could satisfy them; further, to consider the endless contradictions which marked the conception of God laid down by heathenish philo- sophers ; and therefore, not to cease criticism here, but to do honour to that criticism which was pronounced in so grand a manner by history. If, on the contrary, we treat that heathenish idea of God, without further inquiry, without even giving it an essentially new turn, as the self-evidently true one, we take up a point of view which, though clearly too self-contradictory to allow of our feeling contented with it, leads to our examining the history of the doctrine of the Trinity in the light of princi- ples foreign to itself. The natural consequence whereof is, that our criticism of the individual phenomena of the History of Dogmas, instead of coinciding, as it should, with the criticism pronounced by the history itself, and with the positive advances made by the dogma, is in conflict with the judgment of history at all the points at which the Church gives judgment, and there- fore remains alien from the heart of the matter itself. Regard- ing the subject from the centre of the movement, the sole strength of that method of precedure appears to consist in looking at things separately which are really connected with each other, and in then taking advantage of the isolation to strike each down im succession. A notable illustration thereof is furnished by Dr Baur, |. c. pp. 443-470, where, by bringing to view now solely this, and then solely that aspect, he makes Basilius, Gregory Nazianzen, and Gregory of Nyssa, first Tritheites, then Monarchians or Sabellians, and finally appears to rest in the conclusion that they were Subordinatianists. We have already referred to the charge of Subordinatianism (p. 326). As to the two other charges, one would suppose that, at all events, if the first were brought against these men, they would escape the second and opposite one, especially, when we find Dr Baur himself, in several passages ; expressing his respect for the great- ness of their mind. In the case of heretics, he frequently suc- ceeds in happily pointing out a connection between things ap- parently contradictory : we are therefore justified 12 asking,— firstly, whether the position taken up beforehand towards the NOTES. DOT doctrinal development of the Church, or the nature of that de- velopment itself, furnishes an explanation of the constant charge of inconsistency? and secondly, why, in the case of the teachers of the Church, no attempt whatever is made to reconcile ap- parently contradictory elements, to distinguish the fixed goai and the immoveable kernel of their doctrine, from its moveable and, in part, still fluctuating elements, and thus to view their efforts in their very centre and motive principle? In the main, then, it is not at all the fault of these men, if they appear to be Tritheites and Sabellians at one and the same time; especially as it is only through making an inadmissible use of passages which speak of the difference of the hypostases, and of the divine unity, that Dr Baur has succeeded in setting them forth in the light in which they appear. If we allow ourselves to translate the important term (sons (distinctive characteristic), as applied to the hypostases, by “quality” or attribute,” whereas these men call the divine attributes zroorntes, and unweariedly re- peat that all the zrovornres belong to each of the hypostases— not, however, the (Svorntns; it cannot be difficult to show them to be Sabellians. And so, if from the simile of the rainbow employed by Basilius (see Baur 1. c. p. 469), we draw the con- clusion, that as the one light appears in the rainbow in different colours, even so God “ appears” differently in the three persons ; whilst at the same time there is nothing to prevent us supposing that Basilius regarded the different colours of the rainbow as objectively different modes of existence of the one light; for- getting, at the same time, that Gregory of Nyssa also uses the simile, and further, how strongly, for example, Basilius (Ep. 52) requires not merely that the sword be drawn against Arians. but also that Sabellians be formally rejected. Precisely the same course must be adopted by Dr Baur in order to make them out Tritheites; both in regard to the image of the three suns, and the comparison with the plurality in the one humanity. For in this case also, all that is needed is to stretch the simile far enough, and to take little notice enough of the annexed limitation of the resemblance,—indeed, in general, of that of which the simile is meant to be asimile ; by such means, Trithe- ism may withoat difficulty be deduced therefrom,—only that it does not harmonize with that which all these teachers of the Church intended, not figuratively, but logically, to convey when 508 APPENDIX. they employed the term édudrns. Of Gregory of Nyssa’s use of the last-mentioned comparison, we have already spoken (pp. 313 ff.). If we take the various utterances of Gregory Nazi- anzen together, not even in his case can we finally deduce Trithe- ism from his employment of the image of the three suns. For the meaning of his words is not, that the three hypostases are three suns, existing in independence of, and isolation from, each other: on the contrary, the very discourse in which he employs this simile contains a protest against Tritheism (or. 31,14; rept Tvevpatos ayiov, ed. Bas. p. 222). The stress is not to be laid on the isolation ; for immediately before, he says,—“ What have we to do with Tritheism or Ditheism? We have one God, for we have one divinity ; and that which proceeds therefrom has its relation to the unity (mpos & ra é£ abrod tiv avadopdy éyer, Kav Tpla meotedntat). For the one is not less God, and the other not more ; neither is prior to, or later than, the other; they are not split up in relation to the will, not divided in power ; nor do we find here any of the characteristics which pertain to divided things (ovdért Tév dca Tots pepictois uTapyet Kav Tad0a AaBelv eorwv) ; but, in one word, the deity is undivided, in those which are distinct from each other (duépiotos év Tots [eMEpio-- pevors 9 Oedrs) :”—after which follow the words, ofov év nrlots Tplaty éxouévous GAMjrwD pla TOD dwTos otyKpacts. This image, therefore, as he himself says, was not intended to denote a division of the one deity: but his meaning was,—One light is in the three suns (the Oedrns); and besides, the three are most intimately united with each other, for they adhere to, or rather, according to what has preceded, depend on each other, and dart their rays into each other. The import of the image then is as follows,—The three are different points of unity, different centres for all that which pertains to the divine essence in general, that is, for the divine attributes ; the divine essence, however, although present in each of the hypostases in a different manner, is en- tirely and undividedly present in each: so that, considered in their connection, the words denote precisely the same thing as the usual comparison,—the Son is the Father's perfect image, or stands over against Him as a living mirror. That this is the right view to take of the matter, is put beyond all doubt by the following chapter (c. 15). He represents some one as objecting, Have not the heathen also, at all events the more intelligent, NOTES. 903 one deity and yet many gods, even as there is one humanity and yet many men ?—in other words, the unity and sameness of the essence, of the Gedrns, does not preserve you Christians from Polytheism. He answers,— Exe? pev 4 xowdrns rd ev exer povov érivola Dewpyntdv’ ra dé xa’ Exactov Tretotov dAN- Awv Kal TO Xpov@ Kal ToIs TAaDEoL Kal TH SuVdper pEeweptoéva. ‘Hyeis re yap od abvOerou pdvov, dArd Kad avriOetou Kab adr}- Aows Kal juiv avdrois, ode éml pds Hépas Kabapas pévovres oi aUTOL,—aAXA Kal copact Kal ~uyais del péovtds Te Kal peTa- mimrovtes. And the like remark may be made concerning the heathenish gods: they are in conflict with each other and with the first causes. But not so we. Each of the hypostases has unity (To év éyev), no less when we look to that which is together with it (To ovyxeipevov, namely, the other hypostases), than when we have regard to itself: and that, indeed, through the identity of essence and power (c. 16). We must further consider what he says regarding the use of comparisons in general (for example, c.11). When, on the contrary, Athanasius (or. c. Ar. 3, 15) says,—We have not used the image of three suns, but that of the sun, its brightness and so forth; he rejects, not that which Gregory meant to teach in using the image, but merely one explanation thereof, namely, that which represents it as de- noting the isolation of the three,—an explanation which Gre- gory would have repudiated, seeing that he intended in the passage to speak of unity (compare c. Ar. 3, 4); precisely as the same Gregory repudiates the similes of the sun, of the ray and the light, of the primal source, of the bubbling fountain, of the flowing stream, not absolutely, but merely so far as they could be used to obliterate the hypostatical distinction. On this ground, he elsewhere unhesitatingly avails himself of these images ; finding them sufficient, indeed, to mark the unity of essence, but not sufficient to define the i&iéTnres of the different hypostases. Gass also has justly directed attention to the fact, that the two Gregories (Naz. or. 35; Nyss.c. Eun. 2, 6; com- pare T’. i. p. 22; like Athanasius T. i. 530, ii. 5), understand by “ God,” not merely the essence common to the hypostases, but also the “ collective divine image” (the dv0os of the essence), which embraces essence and hypostasis, in a word, the Trini- tarian God. They best succeeded in doing this in relation to the divine activity; which they persistently regard as a one, 510 APPENDIX. undivided, collective activity of God. God, therefore, is 1n their view an acting personality ; though, leaving Athanasius out of sight (see above, pp. 301 f.), they do not enter on the questions, whether this one personality is constituted by the hypostases ; and whether the divine Ego has its seat in the essence, apart from the hypostases, or in the essence, so far as it unfolds itself into hypostases. ‘To such questions as,—lIs the common essence, the basis of the hypostases, self-conscious spirit or Ego? or, does each of the hypostases form a distinct Ego? or finally, whether the absolute self-consciousness of the deity results eternally from its hypostases, being as it were the col- lective consciousness of the distinctions ?—these Fathers would supply us with no answers. Indeed, we have frequently had occasion to remark that the idea of the “ Ego” belongs rather to modern times, and that tadctacts, or even mpoowtTrov is by no means to be identified with our conception of personality. The utmost that can be done, is to divine from the principles laid down by these Fathers what side they would have taken had such questions come within their range of vision. We un- hesitatingly aver our conviction, that Athanasius and Hilarius would have decided for the last-mentioned view ; for they were furthest of all from regarding the hypostases as oupBeBnkoTa ; indeed, on the contrary, they incorporated them, as mediatory causes of the divine self-consciousness, that is, as essential, with the idea of God. Basilius the Great, however, and Gregory of Nyssa, would probably have maintained that the one, common, divine essence knows itself in a different manner in the three hypostases, and would therefore have taken the first-mentioned view of the matter, though without intending to adopt Sabellian- ism. Whilst, finally, Gregory Nazianzen, without any thought of being a Tritheite, would probably, with greater determinate- ness than the rest, have ascribed a distinct and independent ex- istence to the hypostases. Compare Or. 31, 31-33. Note 55, page 343. Baur (pp. 573 f.) misunderstands the doctrine of Athanasius, —‘“that the Logos, in the very act of being born as a man, éOcorrovet the humanity, in the first instance naturally His own,” —-so far as he affirms that the Logos did not really become man, but that man was at once “deified and raised above his natural NOTES. 411 attributes.” Of such an elevation of man there is not a trace in the works of Athanasius, but the contrary (for example, c. Arian. 8, 37 f. 42-48). The deification may, however, be a growing one; and, indeed, was so in the view of Athanasius; for he believed that the human nature of Christ attained per- fection with the resurrection and ascension. Nowhere does he say that the body of Christ did not in itself, and by its nature, suffer hunger, but merely that the Logos did not; in that He subjected Himself to the body and the laws of finitude merely out of substitutionary love. Baur has neglected to take into consideration that passages of this nature were directed against Arianism, which attributed to the Logos immediately and physically, what Athanasius attributed to Him merely ethi- cally and through the medium of the humanity, which love had moved Him to constitute His own. Compare, for example, ad Serap. 4, 14. Norte 56, page 343. Psalm xy. p. 1024:—To xowdy domep tpocwrov rijs évOpw- TOTHTOS avaraBav Tovs mpos Oeov Kal matépa Trovetrat Adyous ; > € \ lal € n Cy MK 4 aA \ Nae \ e An ©. e@ > OUK UTrEp Ye MANAOV EavTOD, Ov Ids OE Kal UTEp Hudv ws els &F e la \ \ > / XN \ \ > / e€ \ x Nav Sia THY oiKoVvoLiav—i Sid Ty éKKdnoiav,—1 oap— yap avtod 7 éxxhynoia. Many other passages of this kind may be found in other works of Athanasius; for example, in the Epistle to Epictetus, in the two books against Apollinaris. ‘Compare the “de Incarn. c. Ar.” c. 20. On the words, “ When we shall be subjected” (1 Cor. xv. 28), he remarks,—“ When we are found as His members, and have become sons of God to Him. ‘Yueis yap, dnow, eis ote év Xpictd ’Inood. Tore n A \ 6€ abTos Umotayjcetar avO iyav TO TaTpl, ws Kepady irép cal a A lal A / / TOV Wioy pedov. Tov yap merav avtod pndéra trotayévtav TAVT@V, AUTOS, 1) Kepady) avTOY, oUTw UTOTéTAKTAL TO TaTpl, avapévov Ta iva médn. (Here, therefore, he represents Him as identifying Himself with those who do not yet believe, but are . ¢ An first to become believers; compare c. Ar. 2, 80.) ‘Hyeis éopev Ol €V AUVT@ UToTaTaOpEVoL TO TaTpl, Kal Huets eopev ot ev aire 5) an a ig \ x Bacirevovtes, ws av TeGow oi éxOpol uaY Ud Tods Todas ¢ an \ \ \ \ aA > fa) nea@v. Compare c. Ar. 1, 43-—Aia tiv mpds TO cHpa adTod ovyyéveray vaos Ocod yeyovamev Kat 7pels, Kal viol Oeod rosrrov wetrounucla, @ate Kal év Hiv nOn TMpocKuvetaVaL Tov KvOLD. Gai APPENDIX. 3, 88; on baptism, which he views in accordance with this idea, see c. Ar. Or. 1, 48; compare 3, 22:—Epwtd, iva Kal adtol yévervtat &v Kata TO év €uol cua Kal KATA THY AVTOD TEdElwow, iva Kal avtol yévwvtTat TédeLot, ExovTes TpOs TODTO THY évoTNTA, Kal eis avTo Ev yevopevor iva @s av TavTes hopebévtes Trap’ éuod TAVTES WoW EV CHUA Kal Ev TVEDWA, Kal Eis dvOpa TédELOY KaTAY- THTWOLW. Nore 57, page 345. The passage concerning His ignorance of the day of judg- ment he refers, with Athanasius (ec. Ar. 3, 37 f. 42-48), to the human nature of Christ; it, therefore, he held to be actually ignorant in some respects (Or. 30, 15). It is not said, “The Son of God knew it not,” but “the Son,” which in this case is equivalent to the Son of man. Athanasius says,—dvOpeécrov idtov TO ayvoeiv, as TO Trewvav. Nor does he afterwards recede from this position, as Baur’s account makes it to appear (pp. 576 f.), but abides by the principle,—“ As man He was able to say, I know it not; for as man He did not know it, although the Word knew it.” It is a misrepresentation of the opinion of Athanasius, when Baur argues as follows,—According to Athanasius, Christ had merely a body, not a human soul; for him, therefore, there was no other subject to which knowledge or ignorance could be attributed save the Logos; but if the Logos was the speaker, the subject, His attribution of ignorance to Himself must necessarily appear to Athanasius as a false accommodation.—Baur has overlooked, that though Athanasius, prior to the appearance of Apollinaris, never gave special pro- minence to the human soul of Christ, he never denied it. On the contrary, the entire view he took of the incarnation and redemption as something affecting the totality of man, rests on the presupposition that Christ had a human soul. This pre- supposition shows itself still more clearly in passages like the present, which without it would be destitute of meaning. For, that ignorance cannot be ascribed to the body, Athanasius was surely well aware; and in this passage he uses the term dv@pe- mos as a substitute for cap& For the rest, we find similar things elsewhere also during the period before Apollinaris; for example, he frequently says, the Logos assumed a man (c. Ar. 4, 34), the anointed element in Christ was the man out of Mary; NOTEs. 513 He is visible and invisible at the same time, the former 8: thy "pos TOV opemevov avOpwrrov &wcuy, opapevos S& dnt, od ™ aopat@ Oeorntl, Gra TH Ths OedTyTOs evepryela, Sid Tod avépw- TiVOU T@maTOS Kal dAouv avOpwrou, dv dvexaluice TH OLKELO- get TH Tpos éavTov (c. 36). But Athanasius speaks also in the same manner of mpoxom in Christ, and defines it, c. Ar. 3, o1-53, as ) Tapa Tijs copias wetadiSouévn Ocotroinats Ka) XApLS. —To avOparwov &v tH codla mpoéxorren, uTepBaivov Kar’ orLyov THY avOpwrivnv diow, Kal Ocorrovodpevov—Ka) Opryavov —Tpos Thv évépyevav Ths Oedrntos Kat Tv éxraprbw avris yivouevov Kal davdpevov tact. When he further, c. Ar. 3, 34, speaks of the AoywOfvas of the odpé in Christ, it is evident he cannot have meant, that the body of Christ was endowed with wisdom and divine reason, but the humanity. On the words of John xii. 27, “ Now is My soul troubled,” he remarks, not, with the Arians, that they relate to the Logos, but they were spoken, ore 0 Aoyos oaipE éyévero Kal ryéyovev avOpwrros (compare c. Ar. Or. 3, 54, 55, 57). Another thing is the question, whether Athanasius succeeds in combining a non- knowing humanity and an all-knowing deity into a personal unity; to this point Baur might with much greater justice have directed his attack. Yet more on this subject below. Nore 58, page 346. Compare Or. Catech. M. c. 16, 32, 33 ff., 37; T. Opn 92, 95 ff., 102; c. Eunom. L. 2, T. 2, 464. His treatise on 1 Cor. xv. 28, T. 2, 12-16,—é« mdons 88 rhs avOpwrivns picews, 9 KaTewiyOn TO Oetov, ofov aTapyn Tis TOD KoWod hupdwatos 6 Kata Xpiotov avOpwros tréorn, that is, from humanity as a common mass, the “primitie” are united in Christ with the divine; hence through Him all that was human grew into con- nection with the divine (8? ob mpocedin th OcéryTe wav TO dv- @pwmwvov). All good things are now gained, @ote ia rdvT@v Tv Ociav Cony dieEeNOodcav, éLadavicar xaborov é« tov dvtev tov Oavarov. (The divine life proceeding from Him, and per- vading all, drives death totally out of the world.) That which took place in the first fruits, must take place also in the whole mass of humanity. Tore ddov 7d hipaa ths pucews TH aT anyn cuppenGer, Kal &v KaTA TO cUvExYes THA Yyevouevorv, TOD avabod wovov Tv ayewoviay éd’ éavtod Sd£erar. And when the entire VOL. II. . 2 6. Fila APPENDIX. substance of humanity shall thus have been penetrated by the divine nature, that. daoray? will take place which is designated a subjection of the Son, because it is His body in which He brings it to pass. The image of the ¢vpapa is physical ; but that the “tertium comparationis” was not a physical process, is clear, in part, even from the circumstance that He is repre- sented as the soul of the humanity, His body (c. 16). To ova TOD THpaTos HudV ywwomevov KaTa cvvjOeLav TWA TH WUXH oyto- ucba.— Sepa & adrod raca } avOpwrivn vats, 4} KaTewixOn, and, as far as men are concerned, Gregory lays special stress on human freedom (Or. Cat. c. 7, 31). Indeed, Rupp justly re- marks (1. c. p. 262), that in contrast to the physical point of view of Eunomius, a strictly ethical estimate of Christianity was characteristic of Gregory of Nyssa. But Gregory's notion of the ethical was certainly not of so meagre a nature, that he deemed it feebler and less sure of attaining a result than physi- cal power; nor did he regard the unity founded by it as less intimate and firm than a physical unity. For this reason, he might very well apply the above images, in order to mark the final certainty of redemption, and the uniting power of love :—this all the more, as he did not rend the ethical from religion, and recognised no freedom which needs to cast a jealous eye on grace.—Or. Cat. 16,—“ As that which had been dissolved by death was again united, to wit, in the resur- rection; even so, the union of that which is dissolved passes over, as from one principle, to the whole of humanity ” (otov amd Twos apxis eis Tacav THY avOpwrrirny plow Ti Svvapet KaTa TO tcov 4 Tov SuaxpLOévTos Evwors SiaBaiver). In C. 32 he expressly describes the same idea as something 6 els tds é« Tapadocews Hxet (p. 93). The entire Gospel contains a pigss of the divine and human; everywhere are both conjoined; and so also on the cross. Its very figure sets forth four lines, which radiate in all directions from one centre. That is the symbol of the God-man. He who was nailed to the cross was To map Tpos EavTO cuvdéwv Te Kal cvvappLoCwv, Tas Suapopous TOV OVTWY dices pos wiav cvpmvovay Te Kal appoviav S¢ EavTod cvvaywv. As, when one of our sensuous organs is active, everything united with the part is drawn into sympathy and participation, so, inasmuch as the God-bearing flesh (cap& Oeodoxyos) was taken from our mass, the resurrection of one part passes over NOTES, | 515 to the whole, as though the entire nature (humanity) were one living being (caOdzrep twos dvtos wou rdons Tis dpvcews). For, agreeably to the continuity and unity of nature, it communi- cates itself from one part to the whole. ©. 37. As a little leaven leavens the whole lump, so does His slain body, having passed into ours (in the holy Eucharist), convert it entirely into itself. Our body also thus becomes cpa Geodoyov, and by this perovola in adOapaia we also become immortal.—As the soul is united with the Logos by faith, so also through the Eucharist is the body, or its dvcts, united with the body of Christ, which has life in itself. Concerning baptism, he says, —lts true idea is the full and entire extinction of death and sin, and the complete resurrection to a new immortal life, in the imitation of Christ. Because, however, of the weakness of our nature, that which really forms one connected whole was separated into its parts, and the entire force of the baptism unto Christ is not concentrated in the one ritual act. But believers are not therefore less sure and certain of becoming, in the future, complete copies of Him into whose death and life they are baptized.Compare Basilius, de Bapts Ti. je. 15.2); T. 1. 551, 553, 561, 565, 568, 574; Lib. 2, Q. 1, pp. 582. f. Specially worthy of comparison, also, is the homil. rye AN Vi a oF 04 if. of Basilius. God is amongst us in the flesh: not as in the prophets, working from afar, d\Ad ouput EAUT@ THV av- Opwrornta Kab Hvopévny KATAKTNTAMEVOS, Kal Sia THS TuyryEVOdS nuiv capKos abtod mpos éavtov éravdyav THv avOpwrornta. ITés ody 80 évds, dyow, eis mdvtas HOE 7d AaTTHpLOV ; Tiva Tpotrov ev capri % Oedtns ; bs TO Tp EV oLOnp@ Ov MeTAaBaTLKaS (that is, so that the Logos would have changed His place), but petadotixas. He lost nothing ; He underwent no conversion. Aia todtro Ocds &v capri, wa évatroxretvyn Tov éudwrevovta Gavatov. ‘Qs yap tov dapudKkav ta aneEntnpia KaTaKpatel Tov dbaptixav oikewOévTa TH cHpmaTtl,-—obTos 6 évduvvacTEevor 7H avOpworivyn (pice) Odvatos Th Tapovola ths Oeorntos nda- vicOn. (The genuineness of this homily is established; not so that of the Libri de Baptismo.) Ephram (Phot. cod. 229) designates Christ rov odvxov, not Tov twa dvOpwrrop, that is, an “homo universalis,” and not merely “singularis.” “I will,” says Christ, “that they all become one body in Me,”—in Him who carries all in Himself, through the one temple assumed bv 516 APPENDIX. Hin (é €uol—a@s travtas hopobvrs dia Tod évds avadnpOévTos vaod). Legat. ad Athanas. f. Marcell. in Monttauc. Coll. Nov. 2, p. 3. The Exposit. Fid., professedly by Gregor. Thaumat., in A. Mai, 1. c. 7, 175:—@avat@ wapadovs tiv capka tod Oavatouv édvce Oia THS avactacews els THY TAVTOV nuav advactacw: aviprOe Sé eis ovpavorv, wrydv Kal dogalov avOpwrrous év €avt@. Similarly Chrysostom (Opp. Paris 1840). Christ’s sufferings are to be regarded as a deed (9, 6, E.; 70 malos mpaéis). ‘Through them, namely, He has worked more good in the world than sin has worked evil (4, 786, E.); @ava- tov Oavatos 0 Gavatos abtod yéyovev (9, 585, A.; 11, 426, A.; 734 D.). He paid the debt for Adam and us all (i7ép Tob Katexouévou KatédaPe Tov-Oavatov); and even more than that (3, 910, A.; 9,574 D.). He humbled Himself, in order to exalt thee; He died, in order to make thee immortal; He be- came a curse, in order to fill thee with blessing. In Him 7vAo- ynOn 4 avOpwrivn pdous (Expos. in Ps. xlv. T. 5, 198).—We are born of Christ, as Eve was born of Adam, by baptism, and in the holy Eucharist He nourishes with Himself (8, 258, on Ephesians v. 25 ff.; de prodit. Jud. hom. h. 1, 6; T. 2, 453; 3, 389 f.). He calls us brethren, friends, bride; yea also His members and His body; and, as though all other things failed to satisfy Him, and still appeared too alien, He styles Himself our Head (2, 278; 8, 193; 9, 763): now, as body and head are one man, so is Christ and the Church one (hom. 30, 1, in 1yGorsu Sl 2 wl OaS lb ys Cyrill of Alexandria says (Thesaur. 20),—Grace has deified our nature, first in Christ, a ov abtod tpéyn AovTrov eis TavTas ) Xapls, WS On Ooleioa TH hicet, Kal owTrdov OAM TwloMEVN TO yévet. (See other passages from his writings in Petav. de in- earn. 2,9; 17, 9; Hilarii Opp. ed. Maur. Pref. pp. xxi. ff.) Similarly Theodoret (Her. fab. 4, 13; Opp. ed. Schulz, T. iv. pp. 373, 374):—In His nature, our nature rose again; but inasmuch as this happened to our nature, it is counted to our persons. Similarly Ep. ad Eneraph. viii. p. 1066; Ep. 15, p. 1291.—Page 275,—2) amapyn tiv mpos TO ddov ExeL ouyyé- vecav. Christ, however, is not amapy7 as God, rola yap cvy- yevera Oeotntos Kal avOpwrroty 1:5; on account of His capé, we are termed His members, and He the head (p. 279, 16, cf. 278, 15). In Dial. 1, 40-44, this idea is already subjected to a cri- NOTES. abr tical treatment, with reference to Eph. ii. 6. One might sup- pose that when He is said to have become man, or even a curse, for us, we ought to understand it subjectively,—namely, that so it appears to us, without objective reality. This is the one extreme. ‘The other extreme is that of Apollinaris, who taught that Christ, in becoming man, converted, transubstantiated us into Himself. This is refuted by 2 Cor. v. 21; for we cannot say that Christ substantially became sin. The substitution, how- ever, he is determined to retain. In pp. 424-426, he shows, from Rom. v. 12 ff., 1 Cor. xv. 21 ff., that the unity of all in Christ was the purpose of the incarnation. As the Apolli- narists exaggerated, so the Arians fell short, of the idea. They acknowledge that Christ had a body, in order that it might be possible for us to see Him, in order to reveal the brightness of His divine essence in such a manner that it might be endurable; in other words, they limit the significance of Christ to His pro- phetic office. But for this purpose, an incarnation was not needed: did not the Son appear to Abraham without becoming aman? What was necessary was, that the same nature which had been conquered should gain the victory; in this the Arian theory fails. On its basis, namely, we do not know ourselves as victors in Christ, through the victory gained by our nature in Him. Even Theodore of Mopsuestia (A. Mai, Spicileg. Rom. T. 4), in his commentary on the Epistle to the Romans (c. vi. 6, p. 508), says,—76 X pict, dnow (Paul) éoravpopéve dorep amraca nuav 1) bro Thy Ountornta Keipévn dvors cuvertaupoOn ETELON KAL TACA avuT@ cvvavéotn, TaVTOV avOporrav avTe cup- Ketacyely éeXmiovtwv Ths avactdcews’ ds évredbev ovvavaha- via Ohvat ev THY Trepl TO apaptavew huav edtxoriav, Sid THs émh trv aBavaciay Tob cdbsaros petactacews. Compare my Christ- mas Programme for 1844, “'Theodori Mopsy. de imagine Dei doctrina,” pp. 23, 24. In Christ the likeness to God borne by man is brought to perfection; He is the fixed, the indissoluble bond of unity for the entire world, which Adam was not com- pletely: Adam, on the contrary, rent the bond. Of later writers, we may further mention John of Damascus, “de orthod. fide” 3, 12, 4,4; Theodorus Abukara, Opusc. ed. Gretser, 6, p. 453. This latter tries to make clear by images how it was possible for sin and salvation to pass through the whole of humanity ; and how the first and the second Adam might have the signifi- 518 APPENDIX. >ance of an universal principle. Coll. Nov. ed. A. Mai, T. 9, 104, of Photius: efSes rpecBevtod iravOpwriay, ob yap Tpos &va Kat Sedrepov HrOev, GAA Tpos THY Kowny poow. For fur ther passages, see Petav. 1. c.; Hilar. Opp. ed. Maur. |. c. ; Calov’s “Examen doctrine public eccl. refer. de persona Christi,” Viteb. 1663, pp. 95, 130 ff., 170 f., 192, 290, 331, 394 f., 419, 450; Mansi Coll. Conc. 4, 1186 ff. Nore 59, page 348. Compare the fragment of Eustathius in Theodoret’s Dialog. 8, T. 4, ed. Schulz, p. 233 :—Aua ti O€ wept ToNXOV TroLovYTaL ) ) I ir / \ lal / Seuxvivat, Tov Xpiorov dapvyov avethnpévat copa, yewders TAT- rovtes amrdtas ; Wa et Suvneiev trrodOcipat twas, TavO ovTwS yew opifecbat, Thvixadta Tas Tov Taber adrotocers TO Gein Tepiarparres Trevpatl, padiws avaTretowow AUTOUS WS OUK EOTL \ a es: ams / / / > TO TPETTOV EK THS ATPETTTOV pucews yevynbev. ‘That this was the doctrine of Arius (and specially also that of Eunomius ; compare Marcelliana, ed. Rettberg, p. 157), is repeatedly af- firmed by Athanasius; for example, c. Apollinaristas 1, 15 :— parnv obv Apeavol copiforvras capKka movny vToTWemevor avet- Andévat Tov cwrthpa, trv é Tod wdOous vonow emt THv aTraby Ocdrnta avadépovtes doeBas. 2, 3:—'Apevos capKa BOVNV TpoOs A ¢ a A 5 lal amoxpupny THs OedtnTos Oporoyel, avTt dé TOU écwbev ev nut avOpwrrov, TouTésTL THS Wuyijs, TOV hoyou év TH capKl. eve ye- yovévat, THY TOD wdOous vonow, Kal Tv €E dou avacTacw TH Oeotnte mpocdyew Torpev. Greg. Naz. Ep. ad Cledon. 1, 7; Gregor. Nyss. c. Eunom. 2, 484:—spopépovoa tiv Tod evary- / \ e e / \ xs ¢ \ n \ yediou hoviy: 6Tt 0 Aoyos aapE éyEveTo, ws Ola TOV PN TULpVYN- povevOnvat Kai tv Wuynv KatacKevdferOa TO apuxov avel- MibOas Tv cdpKa, wabérwoar, br aivnbés eote TH ayia ypahh, an / A . TO pepes cuptrepirapBavew To brov. Kpiphan. her. 69, 19 :— ’ an \ > peas e / > / > Sal den la} Apvobvrat Wuyi avtov avOpamuwny ethynpévat, avVTO TOUTO Tpo- / "4 N: e a 9 \ ) \ / KatacKevacovTes: cadpka yap Oouoroyovow adnOinv aro Mapias 24=\ > i \ / ¢/ b) \ b) > t \ A avrov éaynkoTa, Kal Tata boa éoTiv ev avOpeTre, xapis WuXI)s- This they do, he proceeds, in order that they may be able to say,—Such things (as éuBp/ynows, etc.) the flesh did not work by itself, without soul; but Christ had no soul; consequently they must be ascribed to His higher nature. NOTES. 519 Note 60, page 349. The fragments of Eustathius in A. Mai, T. 7, of the Coll. Noy., contain scarcely anything bearing on this subject. Only the words contained on page 85, which are taken from the work to which the above passage belonged, might possibly, inasmuch as they are directed against the idea broached by certain philo- sophers, that the soul in its wanderings drinks the cup of for- getfulness prior to each new birth, have a reference to the Arians, who may have made use of the philosopheme for the purpose of demonstrating the reality of the human development. The work of Eustathius was entitled arep) wuyijs cata bidocd- gov; and the peculiar circumstances of Antioch (see the text) probably gave occasion to these investigations, which initiated a new series of works on the soul (compare Gregory of Nyssa, “de Anima;” Augustine, “de Anima;’ Nemesius, “de natura hominis”). More to the purpose is offered by the fragments in Theodoret, Dial. 1, 3; Galland. 1. c. pp. 578 ff. The passage cited above, in Note 59, page 518, proves that Eustathius not merely understood and remarked the Arian artifice of teaching that Christ had a cama apuyov, in order to be able to transfer the emotions and so forth to the Logos; but also saw that the Church must of necessity either accept the Arian, subordina- tian consequence, or teach a human soul. LEustathius, however, was led to the same result by other considerations,—to wit, by the consideration of His descent into Hades. In death, the soul of Christ was separated from His body; but ris capkos éxtods yevouérn Ff kai bpéoryKe, Nay more, yéyove Kat €v TS Yopio TOV avOpotivov yuyav. It thus had experience of both the things which befall us (éxatépwv creipav oye); Noyexi dpa Kab tais wuxais TOv avOpeTrwv capKt Tuyydvel, ex THs Mapias tpoed- Qotca. He therefore attached great importance to the truth of the human development of Christ. In his view, it was by no means deified or in possession of divine prerogatives from the very commencement (Gall. pp. 577 f.). The exaltation (Sofa émixtytos) did not concern the Father, who is TéNevos, azretpos, aTEpwvontos, ampocdens Kaos; nor the Son, to whom Eusta- thius gives the same predicates; dAN 6 dvOpwros tod Xpictod ex vexpav éyetpomevos trrovtat Kat So€dkerar. P. 578 :—adros tip’ oUTOS éaTLV O peTa TAS UBpes, devdrs, duophos opabels, eira 520 APPENDIX. Tddw €« weTaBorHs evTrpéTrerav evduTapmEvOS’ OVSE YAP 0 KATOLKAV év avT@® Oeds apuvod dixnv eis Oavatov iyyeTo, etc. Pp. 580, 581 (from Facundus Herm. 11, 1):—‘“ Dicamus, inquit (Kusta- thius) cujus rei gratia filius hominis diem proprii adventus ignoret (Matt. xxiv. 36). For our good, He was ignorant of the day of judgment. Sicut enim hominem—Verbo coaptavit et Deo (salutis hominum causa); sic et insignem judicii diem caussa divini beneficii homini competenter abscondit, ne forte ineffa- bilia mysteria similis generis hominibus indicans et diem secundi adventus ostenderet.” But unquestionably for the sake of His voluntary sufferings on our behalf, He is crowned with honour and glory. He sits also as to His humanity on the holy throne, avvOpovos amrodédekTat TO OevoTadtw Tvevpatt, Sia TOV oiKODYTA Ocov &v avT@ dunvexas (Theod. Dial. 2, Gall. 577). Page 581: —The words of Ps. ix. 8, “ Dominus in ceelo preeparavit sedem suam,” refer neither to the Father nor to the Word, who both already have the kingdom, but to Christ. “Nam omnium simul creaturarum dominator (sc. Christus est) propter Verbi divini commixtionem.” Similarly the fragment in Gelasius’ “de duabus naturis in Christo” (Gall. 581):—Homo Deum ferens, qui mortis passionem sponte censuit sustinere,—honorem et potestatem percepit. Ht ubi (ibi) recipitur gloria, guam ne- quaquam prius habuerat.” HKustathius, therefore, conceived the communication of the divine attributes, not as complete from the very beginning, but as first fully accomplished at the ascen- sion. Indeed, he was in general concerned to allow the humanity of Christ free and full play; thus showing himself to be a true Antiocheian. According to a passage in Gelasius (Gall. 581), he taught that Christ had an human soul, expressly because he could not otherwise deem the incarnation complete. Sadness, emotions, hunger, and the like, could not affect the fulness of the deity. “ Homini vero heec adplicanda sunt proprie, qui ex anima constat et corpore; congruit enim, ex ipsis humanis et innoxiis motibus demonstrare quia non phantastice et putative, sed ipsa veritate totum hominem indutus est Deus perfecte adsu- mens.” At the same time, we must not omit to notice that, after the manner of the later Antiocheians, the deity and the hu- manity remain separate and distinct, and do not constitute a living unity. He describes the incarnation most frequently under the image of the indwelling of the Logos in the temple of NOTES. 521 humanity ; the unity of the Logos with the humanity he reduces to the anointing of the humanity with the Holy Ghost by the Logos, who, at the same time, remained by Himself. Accord- ing to A. Mai, 1]. c. p. 203, in his homilies on the Gospel of John, he remarked on the passage, “Ido not Mine own will,’—In Christ there was no will which stood in need of negation (“ Ne- gation,” caradvcews), neither the divine (@eixov), nor that which sprang from the incarnation (To 7Hs avOpwmjcews) :—which latter will, according to another fragment, superadded aperas émuxtytous. From this it would seem that Eustathius assumed the existence of two wills in Christ, which, however, will the same thing. ‘The same conclusion may be drawn from a frag- ment in Theodor. Dial. 3, Gall. 576 :—Birth did not lessen His é£ovoia; the cross did not wound His mwvetwa. To pev yap THUA peTapatov éoTavpodTo, TO dé Ociov THs Zopias mvetwa Kat TOU c@uatos elow SinTatTO, Kal Tots oUpaviols eTEBaTevE, Kal Tacayv Trepletye THY HV, Kal TOY aBvocwV expadTel, Kal Tas ExdoTov Wuyas aviyvetav Siéxpive, Kal TAaVTA O600 cvV}OIws ola Ocos erpattev. Ov yap elow TOV cMpaTiKoY OyKaV 7 aVwTATw Aopia kaberpypévn TeprexeTat, Kabdrrep ai TOV typav Kat Enpav Var TOV Lev ayyelwv elow KaTAKELOVTAL, TrepLeyovTaL 5é Laddov i) Tepleyovot Tas Onxas. *ANAa Gcla Tis odca Kai avéxppacTtos Sivas TAT evdotatwo Kat éEwtdtw Tot vew TepthawPavovca Kparatot KavTedOev éréxewwa SujKovaea TaVTAS Omov TOS OyKOUS Kparet mepiéyouca. Page 582 :—God (and the Logos is God) fills the universe; for Him, therefore, there can be no such thing as movement from one place to another (ovdauas é& Eré- pov eis éTépovs peOlotatat ToToUs, Ta TavTa TAnpav) ; for if He were outside of a place, the place which He failed to fill, would bound Him (e¢ yap é@ NéyouTo TOTOU TLVOS, avayKN TreE- propiver Oat adtov tm éxeivov, obTep otepicxetat). ‘This now must be applied to the incarnation also :—and, at a later period, we find Theodore of Mopsuestia taking it as his point of depar- ture. But if no advance were made beyond the position thus described, the Logos must be judged to have had His own inde- pendent consciousness and sway (at all events, during the earthly life of Christ), and the man Jesus also his; and it is not clear how Eustathius could avoid assuming a double personality, at all events during the time referred to. It will therefore not be accidental, that, besides Theodoret, Facundus of Hermione, an 522 APPENDIX. adherent of the doctrine of Theodore of Mopsuestia, so fre quently cites him. He pays quite too little regard to the unity of the person, although he still unsuspectingly supposes himself to be in possession thereof. The utmost he arrives at i an ac- tion of the Logos in and on this man; an incarnation, an hu- manification of the Logos lay beyond his reach. Nore 61, page 350. C. Ar. 3, 30:—O Aodyos oapE éyévero—avOpwrros Sé yéyove, Kal ovK €is avOpwrrov AVE Kal TodTO yap avayxatov cidévat, lest being led astray by the ungodly, we should suppose, érz do7rep a , a ° év tois éumpoobev ypovols eis Exactov TOV aylwv éyiveTo, olTH kai vov eis avOpwrov érednunoev 0 Oxyos ayiatwv Kai TodTOV \ he WA \be. a ” S) \ ee 9S Kab davepovpevos wamrep Kal év Tois adAOLS. Hi yap ovTws Hv \ / > 5) , \ 9 IQ\ 3 / Kat povov év avOpworrm dhavels hv, ovdév Hv tapddoEov. Then, those who saw Him, would not have asked, What manner of man is this? and, Why doest thou, being a man, make thy- self God? Nop 6é, éretd2) 0 Tod Ocod Aoyos Sv od yéyove Ta TUVTa, UTéeweWE Kal viov avOp@Tov yevécOat, Kal érarretvwceV éauTov, AaB@v Sovrov popdyv, dia TodTo Tovdalows péev oKdv- darov €otw 0 Tod Xpiotod ataupos, piv dé Xpratos Ocod Sivas cal Ocod copia. “O dAoyos yap capE éyéveto, THs ypadhs eos éyvovons, eye cdpKa Tov avOpwtov. C. Arian 4, 35, he shows that Christ Himself counted His body part of His person and actuality. In Luke xxiv. 39, Christ says not—“Touch this man, or My man (that is, the man, whom I have); but, touch Me” (ovx etme tov oe i) Tov avOpwrdv jov, dv aveiAnda GAN ewe). Thus in the presence of Thomas (see John xx. 27), God, the Logos, terms the hands and the side His own. He in His entirety is God and man at the same time (6dov adrov dvOpw- Tov Te Kat Ocdv owod). Ep. ad Maximum Philos. c. 2:—Od yap avOpérou Tivos Hv TO BrETOMEVOY Hua, GArXd Ocod. For this reason, we cannot say,—6re els dvOpwrrov Twa e&ytov éyévero 6 ToD Ocod Aoyos" TobTO yap ev Exdotw éyévero TOV TpodnTav Kal TOV adrAaVv aylov' va pH Kal’ Exactov yevveOpevos Kal / b] , / ’ ” \ ec \ / Taw atrobvnckwv paivntar. Ovx gate dé ottws, pu) ryévolTo, b) oe, Pea af a / a I. > ts, a ¢e arr amaké etl TH cvvTedcia TOV aidver eis atéOnow THs apap- if > \ ¢ / \ > if: \ > fe A / Tlas avTOS 0 AOYos GapE eyéeveto Kal éx Mapias THs TapOévov A BA ») e , e , eee mponOev avOpwros Kal duoiwow ierépav, John viii. 40. Ovx« avOpeérov te Twos METEYOVTES TWMATOS, GANA avTot Tod NOTES. 523 Aoyuu cowa AawBdvovres (in the Holy Eucharist) Geor ocov- peGa. Norte 62, page 352. The question appears to me to have taken in the mind of Athanasius the form which I have indicated in the text; not, however, that a human soul alongside of the Logos would threaten the unity of the person, as Baur supposes (p. 579). The soul by itself would scarcely have occasioned him difficulty ; for he did not conceive it as a particular substance, or as a sub- ject, which, as such, would exclude another subject from itself (in the present case, therefore, the hypostasis of the Son), or would at all events come into conflict therewith; but rather as a multiplicity of powers, or as a movement of thoughts and volitions, which have an individual limitation in and through the body. On such a view of the soul, the union of the hypostasis of the Logos with a human individuality might be accomplished without much difficulty, because two subjects would not then be supposed to meet in the one Christ. The divine hypostasis alone (as it were the universal element) in Christ receives hu- man individuality. At this time, not a single word can as yet be spoken regarding an human Ego. Athanasius felt that, in order for Christ’s soul to be of like nature with us, it must be free; and on other grounds, this seemed to him a doubtful opinion. We see, as often as he approaches this question, that he feared it would be necessary to exchange the theological point of view of the Church with the anthropological one of Ebionism, if a free human soul were posited. For he constantly warns against forming such a conception of the full humanity of Christ as leads to Samosatenism, and against seeing in Christ merely an independent man apart from the Logos. Compare the passages c. Ar. 4, 35; 3, 30; Ep. ad Max. Philos. 2, 3. Norte 63, page 393. The main sources are the very numerous fragments in Gregor. Nyss. Antirrheticus adv. Apollinarem, ed. Zacagni, p. 123-287; A. Mai, Coll. Nov. T. 7; Gregor. Naz. Ep. i. ii. ad Cledon. and ad Nectar.; Athanasius c. Apollinaristas, L. 1, 2 (compare below, Note 65); Epiphanius, Her. 62; Theodoret 524 APPENDIX, her. fab, 4, and Dialog. 3. Many fragments of Apollinaris are contained in the Catene ; compare especially the Catena to the Gospel of John, ed. Corderius, 1630. He forms the strongest antagonism to the school of Antioch, which even in his lifetime had already acquired, under Diodorus of Tarsus and Carterius, the features which were distinctively characteristic of it; and from it, for a considerable period, proceeded many attacks on Apollinaris and his school (so, for example, from Diodorus in his work against the Synusiasts, from Theodorus of Mopsuestia xv. LL. ady. Apollinarist. et Eunom., and from Theodoret). That even as early as the year 360, it was usual for some in Antioch to draw a distinction between the divine and human aspects of Christ (see Note 60), which, in the apprehension of many, threatened the introduction of a double personality, is evident from Athanasius, c. Apoll., and from the Alexandrian Synodal Epistle, entitled Tomus ad Antiochenos a. 562. Apollinaris himself perhaps wrote to Diodorus (Marl! o.\7, 17) aqme events, he wrote about and against him. If we consider, on the one hand, that Apollinaris deduced the description of the per- son, the dissolution of the incarnation, relapse into the heathenish error of denying the incarnation of Christ, and into the Jewish error of viewing it ebionitically, from the doctrine of a par- ticular human soul, to which his opponents gave such promi- nence; and on the other hand, that which we know of Eusta- thius of Antioch; this doctrine would undoubtedly appear to have found a seat in Antioch from the year 330 onwards, and to have been vigorously represented by Diodorus and his school, though at the same time to have been strongly opposed both by Apollinaris and others. Nore 64, page 354. Many polemical arguments of the Church Fathers have been prematurely referred to Apollinaris, which did not relate to him at all. For example, what has Athanasius’ Ep. ad Epictetum Corinth. Episc. (Opp. 1, 901 ff.) to do with Apollinaris? The ““tessera” of Apollinaris is not mentioned amongst the views there controverted, namely, the denial of the human soul of Christ. The only allusion is to a heavenly humanity and a conversion of God; just as in the Ep. Basilii M. to the Sozo- politans (1. c. Ep. 65, T. 3, 103). Still less can the words of NOTEs. 525 Hilarius (de Trin. 10, 15 ff.) be referred to Apollinaris. For that work was composed before the doctrine of Apollinaris had attracted the attention it subsequently did. Besides, the views there controverted are totally different: they combine three momenta in themselves :—-1. The Logos emptied Himself, fell away from Himself in the incarnation (defecit a se Deo), and was present in the man Jesus merely as a passible potence or power. 2. In this form He animated the man Jesus, even as the Spirit of prophecy stirred in the prophets. 3. Hence Jesus was so perfectly a man, that He had not merely a body, but also a soul from Adam. They reproached the teachers of the Church with not bringing out the full equality of the essence of Christ with us, in relation to body and soul ; which is necessary, seeing that the body and soul of Adam lay in sin. We have here, therefore, another illustration of the truth of the assertion, that the doctrine of a conversion of the Logos may pass into Ebionism. How widely diffused such views were, we see from the circumstance, that Athanasius controverts them in his Ep. ad Hpictetum 2, 11,12. They did not deny the birth from a virgin ; nor the Trinity ; but from Apollinaris they were so far removed, that in point of result, they might be more justly classed with the Antiocheians of the fifth century. Nor is it allowable to distribute the above views between different parties ; they stood all together, for example, in one work, Athan. ad Epictetum, cap. 3. Further, even in Can. 11, 12 of the Synod of Sirmium of the year 351, we read,—“Si quis Verbum caro factum est, audiens Verbum in carnem translatum putet, vel demutationem sustinentem accepisse carnem dicit, anathema sit.—Si quis uni- cum Dei filium crucifixum audiens dealitatem (Ocoryra) ejus corruptionem vel passibilitatem aut demutationem, aut deminu- tionem vel interfectionem sustinuisse dicat, anathema sit.” Norte 65, page 359. These views are partially controverted also in the three books of Athanasius, which usually bear the title, “Adv. Apollina- ristas ;” in which, however, neither Apollinaris nor any other name is distinctly mentioned. Still, the form of the refutation is such as to betray that its author had gone through the Apol- linaristic phase of doctrine. It is a mistake to suppose that these books contain, strictly speaking, an account of the theory 526 APPENDIX. of Apollinaris himself; but it would be equally erroneous to suppose that Athanasius did not think he was really combating the view propounded by Apollinaris. The true state of the case is rather the following:—These books, according to Proclus, written after the death of Apollinaris, are taken up with his school in general, which, in consequence of coalescing with theories such as those above described, had separated into dif- ferent parties, pursuing different tendencies. Many of the opinions controverted by Athanasius in these books, must there- fore not be laid to the account of Apollinaris; although they may be fairly counted part of Apollinarism, as a phenomenon of the Church. The three positions—the conversion of the Logos (dAXolwois Tod AO¥Yov) ; that the passion of Christ was mere seeming; that the flesh of Christ was heavenly and un- created (cap Xpiotod dxtiotos, émoupavos)—in particular, were laid down as we have seen by writers prior to Apollinaris :— whether by himself also, we shali soon see. The existence of these parties prior to Apollinaris throws also a clearer light on the Synodal Epistle of the Alexandrian Synod, which was written about 362 (Athan. Opp. 1, 770 ff.; entitled Tomus ad Antioch.). This Synod, namely, lays down the principle,— ‘Dporoyour yap Kab TodTO, 6tt ov cHua dapvyov ovd’ avaiaOnTor, ov’ avontov elyev 6 wtp ; whereby the opinion of Apollinaris is substantially excluded. Moreover, it is scarcely to be doubted that Paulinus, who shortly after handed over to Epiphanius a copy of this Synodal Epistle, which he had subscribed (Hpiph. l, c.), referred these words of the Council, either to Apollinaris or to his faithful pupil Vitalis. At the same time, we have no right to conclude that the Council attributed to Apollinaris or to Vitalis all the opinions which it condemns, and that it con- sequently had had to do with Apollinaris alone. Neither the opinion, that the Word did not become flesh, but that it “ hap- pened to Christ,” or that it came upon Him, as upon the prophets; nor that of a duplicity of Christ, in the sense, that the Son of God before Abraham was one, the Son of God after Abraham another (repos): He who raised Lazarus from the dead one, another He who inquired after him, fits Apollinaris. But by these are meant such as Hilarius describes (de Trin. 10, 21), who represented the man Jesus as influenced after the manner of the prophets, and brought against the teachers of the Church the NOTES. 527 charge, “quod Christum dicamus esse natum non nostri corporis atque anime hominem.” Indeed, from the latter one might ven- ture to surmise, that when the Synod of Alexandria maintained that all the orthodox with them, agreed 67 0b capa dapuyov ov avaic@ntov ovS avontov eiyev 0 cwTNp, it merely meant in the first Instance to say,—In rejecting that Ebionitical view, the Church teachers have no intention either of leaving the charge brought by Ebionites unnoticed, or of detracting from the com- pleteness of the humanity of Christ; on the contrary, if there are any who posit, for example, no human soul, this also is to be blamed. Looking at the matter in this light, Apollinaris and his followers can by no means be said to have been arraigned before the bar of the Synod, although they were eventually con- demned. What was in the first instance arraigned, was a Chris- tology which substantially led back to Ebionism, which no longer took up an unitarian position relatively to the doctrine of the Trinity, but merely, out of regard to the unity of the Person of Jesus, represented the Logos as a mere power in the human personality, either on the basis of a conversion of the Logos into a mere potence (see Note 64),—a view which was certainly taken by some; or without such aconversion. In the latter case, even on the supposition of a partial conversion, we should arrive at a double Christ, and at an Ebionism engrafted on the doctrine of the Trinity,—a phenomenon which we shall shortly find in the school of Antioch. Deputies from Apollinaris attended the Synod and subscribed its decrees; so that it is doubtful whether the Fathers always had Apollinaris in view, or whether his position was not at that date a more favourable one :—namely, whether he and his adherents were not at that time the strongest defenders of the view of the Church, in op- position to those who arrived at a double Christ, and approxi- mated to Ebionism as regards the human aspect of the Re- deemer. But, however it may stand with the persons and with the judgment of the Synod as to the views entertained by the persons, it is substantially clear that the Fathers rejected, not only a double Christ, but also such an unity of His person as involved the mutilation of His human nature, or as was in any way effected by a conversion of the divine into the human. Compare also, Mansi Concil. T. 3, 355. 528 APPENDIX. Nore 66, page 361. Gregor. Nyss. |. c. c. 48, p. 237; ¢. 36, p. 215 :—Ei un vods dnow evoapKos éotw 0 Kbptos, Sopia av ein dwrifovca vodv avOparrov (but He would not be God-man). / a / / / > \ e 4 avOporwv tod Oavatov Bactrclav KaTanvet, eb wn os aVOpwTrOs ws NOTES. 529 amébave nal avéctn. OC. 45, pp. 244 f.:—Ei avopworov, dbnow, vieTat Tis evodcbat Oe (in the Person of Christ) rapa wdvtas avipwmous Kat ayyéhous . . . Trouser pr adte£ovalous Tovs > t \ \ > 4 e EERO ai ¢ \ 5) / ayyedous Kat Tovs avOpwrous, ws ovdE ) capE adte£ovctos" Popa dé tod avteEovolov Sdov TO wn iva adte£ovaov ot Pbeiperas 5é 1) Hvats UO TOU TromcayToS avTyV. He appears also to have said,—Where there is a complete man, there also is sin. Athan. c. Apoll. 1, 2:—’Oou yap /. ” > a Nese ts > ee 3 nm ¢ TeheLos avOpwrros, éKet Kai duapTtia’ érrel EaraL Kal év XploT@ 1) cv Nu Layn THS dpaptias, Kal értat ad’T@ ypela Tob Kal” Huds Kabaptopod, et To ppovoty Kai TO aryov év julv Tv cdpKa, Xpic- TOs év EavT@ érridcbeuxtar yevouevos avOpwros. “AAA edra/Pé, bot, TO avontor, iv’ ats 7 vods év abTa, Kal dyevotos rdvTH THS amaptias, Kata ye TO Oeixov Kal TO dvontov Ths capKos. Ovre yap dpudpro dv 7 cap, Tod dyovtos THY cdpKa, TovTécTL Tod hpovovytos, yun TpoevOupnOévtos tiv Tpakw THS apaptias Kat éevepynoavtos dia Tod cdpatos eis éxTAIpwow THs apap las. Gregory of Nyssa’s Antirrhet. c. 48, p. 254:—Ex tpidv 6 avOpwrros, to wit (p. 248), wvedpuaros Kab apoyns Kal oop.1TOS (c. 8, p. 141 :—oapxos te kat uyhs Kat vod). P. 255:—AdAd Kai 0 Kupios avopwrros éx tpiav Kaxelvos, tvebvpartos Kal puyns \ / 3 \ VO 9 / BA pee / Kat cwpatos. “Ada Kat éroupdvios avOpwios. Ei é« rdvrev TOV Lowy Hiv éaTe Tols xoiKois 6 érroupdvios avOpwrros, ovK > / ; % 9 / * = . A eTOUPaVios GAN éTroupaviou doxeiov. That is, if man is complete apart from the heavenly, it can only stand in the relation of an unnecessary accident to the humanity of Christ. Present or absent, the man remains complete. Theodoret, Heer. Fab. 4, 8. Sapx@Ohvai tov Ody ence AOyov, cha Kab apuyny avetAndora, b] \\ \ >’ \ \ yA xX a\ + / ov THY hoyiKnY aAdAG THY adoyov HY huTiKHY Hryouv CwoTiKHY TIVES ’ / \ x a BA \ \ \ 5 / b ovopacovar Tov dé voov aAXO TL Tapa Thv ruxnv evar NEyov ovK edyncev averknplat, aN apkécar tHv Olav pvow eis TO TAN- pOcat Tov vod THY YpElav. Nore 68, page 369. A. Mail. c. p. 70:—Aaxtiro yridovet rérpav of S00 véas emi Xpictod Soyparifovres, Oeiov, dnt, Kab avepwrwov. Hi yap Tas vods avtoKpatwp éorlv (dike Oehnpuare Kata dvow Kivov- peevos, advvatov éotw &i Kal TH adT@ brroKxeywev Sv0 TOds tavavtia Oédovtas addjdows cuvuTrapyetn, exatépov TO Oernbev EavT® Kal’ oppiy abtoxivntov évepyotvtos. My antagonists, he WOU. LI. | ou ot 530 APPENDIX. goes on to say, do not consider, what must be clear to every one, Bre 6 pev Oeios vods abroxivyTos ott Kat TAVTOKWWNTOS, AT PETTOS yap, 6 8é avOpaerrwos avToKivnTos MEV, Ov TAVTOKIVNTOS Oe" TPETTOS yap' Kal Ore TEep ATpéeTT@ VO TpEeTTOS Ov ptyvuTae vods els évOS imoxetpévov cvoracww, craciacbijcetat yap Tots €& ov Gat, OveAKO- wevos evavtiow Oernpact, 80 i aitlay jets Eva Tov X PloTOV OfL0Q0- yoomev Kal play as Evds abTod THY Te HUoW Kal tiv OérAnow Kal THY évépyevav TpocKuvoduev, Oavpacw 6pod Kal TaOnpace c@fovoar. Norte 69, page 374. C. 57, p. 280:—Ei pera thy avactacw, says Apollinaris, Beds yéyove, kal ovKéte Eotw avOpwTros, THs vios avOpwrrou aTooTENE. TODS ayyédous avTOd, etc., TAS dé Kal Tp ev@bFjvar cal arrobewbhvar Neyer eyo Kai 6 matnp &v éopev ; For this Gre- gory rebukes him sternly, asking, whether he denies altogether the glorification and conversion of the humanity of Christ, or whether hair, nails, form, and compass, are all to remain ? On the contrary, nothing corporeal must be conceived to cleave to the perfected Redeemer; we must not any longer rest in av6po- mivows iSwopact. He will appear in the glory of the Father, and the Father has no body; compare c. 25, p. 185. In chap- ter 53, Gregory says,—pera TH els ovpavor dvodov is the cap& ovKére ev TOIS iSlows iSubpaor. God did not remain cap. Even Paul says, “I know Christ no longer after the flesh.” The human nature is changed into something better, from corrup- tible to incorruptible, from corporeal into acwpatov and aoxyn- uatictov. But compare also Mansi Coll. Cone. 3, 480; 8, 489. Nore 70, page 380. Greg. Nyss. lL. c. c. 50, p. 259 :—Ei éx dv0, PNTL, TEAELWY, ore ev & Ocds Eat, év TOOTH GVOPWTOS EaTIV, OUTE EV @ avOpw- mos, év ToUT® Oeds. He aims, then, at taking up the point of view, from which the humanity appears as an essential determi- nation of the Logos, and vice versd, the Logos of the humanity. This he carries out both in the aspect in which the xéveovs is an humiliation of the wvedya of the heavenly man (see Note 1, page 376); and especially in that other, in which the Getov became aaOnrov in Christ (see the text). How important and familiar to him was this dialectical method of combining opposed ele- ments, by showing the one to be contained and involved in the NOTES. 531 other, we may see from the circumstance that he applied it to the Trinity also, in order to set forth the relation between the unity and the distinctions. As he endeavoured to point out the man in the Logos, and the Logos in the man, in the sense, namely, of each being a determination of the other; even so did he conceive the Father and Son to be related to each other. The Son has the Father as a determination of Himself; He is accordingly qartnp though vixds, etc. He lays it down as a canon,—Ilaytayyn cvvelevypévws, wadrov S€é Hwopevos TH ére- poTnte voey avayKaiov THY TpwTnY TavTOTnTa, etc. Basil. M. Ep. 129, 1. This has been interpreted as Sabellianism (Theo- doret, Her. Fab. 4, 8); but may also be interpreted in agree- ment with the Nicene Creed, and serve to introduce the doctrine of the repry@pnots of the hypostases. Note 71, page 386. Such I believe to be the true sense of the difficult passage, Ep. ad Cledon. 1,15. It is true, if Apollinaris, like Origen, had held that the inequality of Christ with Himself, as also the inequality of the regenerated with themselves, would con- stantly recur; and that thus there would be an eternal alterna- tion between the draipeous (Greg. Nyss. Antirrh. c. 29) and the €€ccodv; he must also have assumed that the same history would be constantly repeated, that the incarnation would be again and again accomplished, metempsychosis, etc. We have, however, no sufficient ground for such a supposition. The necessary basis of such an alternation in the endless progress, would be a dualistic view of the two connected aspects, God and man; for then they would constantly be as strongly repelled from as they are drawn towards each other. Apollinaris un- doubtedly appears sometimes to regard human nature, the free will, as sinful in itself (see ad Cledon. 1, 10; Note 68 and Note 2, page 387). This, however, he scarcely deemed a prin- cipal point, but employed it rather as a proof. In order to show that the divine zrvedua must be the vous in the perfect man, he assigns to the human vods as low a position as possible. For the rest, he everywhere aims, not at dualism, but at unity, and tries to grasp the Logos as the truth of the human vots, as the vods of the completed, second creation, which notwithstand- ing he conceived to be eternal. 4532 APPENDIX. NoTE 72, page 389. On John xi. 35:—Ovd yap dvaivetas tiv Tpds avOpe@rous Cuolwow, ovd évdeikvuTar TavTayod TO UTép avOpwroV, cupTa- Oevay dé THY Tpds Tovs TeVvOobVTas diravOpwrras bToTLOncL,— Kal ua TovTO els Chua KaTAANMEV oO AOYos, i avOpwTroLs ériba- Kpvon Keymévois Kal THY ao@patov BeoTnTa Tpos Cworroinow avOporav érayayntat. "Eyouev yap apyvepéa Suvapevov cuptTra- Ojcat tats acbevetars yuov. On John xiv. 7:—Eavtov ama TOPEVOMEVOY ElpnKE Kal OOOV VTA TopEVOMEVOV [LEV KATA THY éTTl ys ToduTElay, ev ) TaCaY eTANPwWOEV apETHY, Kal THY CwonY émn)- yayev @oTrEp Eis GTéhavoy THS TodtTElas’ OdoV Sé dVTA, KaOOTE autos av Swas apeTn, WoTE OV KaTA THY do@paTov OedTynTaA TropEia TLS AUTOU Kal TPAELS ETL POS TaTépa GUVaTTTOVGA, AAA dUcts avtTn Kat ovata. TI poceitnde 5€ bia capKocews Kal Tas él yis évepyeias kal mpakéers ayabas, 8¢ av Twacw érl Ocdv KaOnyeiras mpos THv tdtav PeornTra. At the same time, He was constantly perfect in Himself, like the Father, and was in fact the Father’s processive will. His growth was subjective; in other words, that which was already present in Him was more and more clearly revealed to us. Compare on xi. 42, xii. 28, pp. 292, 314. On John xiv. 14, “ Whatsoever ye shall ask, that will I do, that the Father may be glorified,” for the Father appears through the power of the Son (éxdaiveras). Ov yap éotw étépa Tpos Tatépa Tpdcobos, 7) St viod, ovTE mdadat, OTE VoD, oute éoavdis, dX oiKeLoTeEpoy 1) St’ Viod Tpocebus ~ayNKE VOD, OTL TANGLAITEpov Hiv KaTécTn capKwbeis. On verse 17:— aopatov dowpatov Tapovela; hence also, when the spiritual is present, it is not perceived by the sensuous. But those who are susceptible thereof, know from fellowship with Him who is present, the inner essence, which is better than the sensuous per- ception, comprehending themselves out of the other (é é erepaoy EavTovs KaTadauPavorTes). NoTE 73, page 390. 2 3 / On John xiv. 12, p. 360 f.:—"Apte pév tv huotny évornta ¢ bps \ \ / r , Asia's A ures \ eavTov mpos Tov ITarépa SdieEnes, péper 5é ees Kal thy Kata Xapw EavTov Trpos TOds aTroaTOAOUS Evol" TODTO Yap Opolwpa exelvou, Kal minnows Tod KaTa hvaw TO KaTa Yap Kat yap oud trictews tobra ywerat, éxeivo 5é ody) dua TiaTews NOTES. add dANG Kata Svivapw dvotxny. Od yap lore. TH eis IT atépa Ta Gaupacva Xprotos épydberar, wiates dé TH ets vlov émiTeNodow GTOCTONGL TA viod TA Sta TOUTwV Tpattopeva. Arad Kat oéBas HEV TO VIG Tpocayerat, céBas Sé ovdamobev atroaréXots opet- AeTat, ovde av peilova Tod Kuplov troujcwow. On John xiv. 13:—Ta pev ddetretar TO Kupio map’ jue wept av Kai Tapay- t N \ Cy eS / \ @ b] A yedret Ta 6€ avTos TAPENEL, TEPL WY ETTayyEAAETAL. ( Compare Augustine’s words,—“ Da quod jubes et jube quod vis.) Our obedience is a sign of our love to the Lord (amrodetEts ayarns), Tap avtot dé hiv 4 TAS Oelas gucews yopnyla Kowvwvetrat. On xiii. 16 :—Not men lay hold of the good, but the good con- fers on men communion (o’Ketwors) with itself. Od yap apé- gavres eEehéyOnuev, GAN iva dpécaper. Awd xal dyow éxnre- Eauevos abtovs él KapTopopia Téeker, iva ef kab wi) Sid Ta J, / nA / 3 \ \ \ las i TpoTepa Titov Med xabeatynKerpev, AAA Sia TA TEXEUTALA yevo- fi NaS na ’ / \ v 3S \ >] Hea. Tis 86 0 tov’ AroctéXov KapTros aplaptos obTos, Kal eis aiava pévev ; 7) Exxvnola. Nore 74, page 404. The soul of Adam and the soul of Christ was created, not formed out of already existing material. This opus non habet in se assumte aliunde alterius nature originem. The forma- tion of the body, on the contrary, was a “sumere, accipere materlam,” in order to give it a form; it was not a creation; it was, therefore, a recelving of an external, foreign material. That Hilarius entertained a similar conception of the incarna- tion also, is clear from de Trin. 2, 26, where we read,—“ Spiritus sanctus desuper veniens virginis interiora sanctificavit, et in his splrans nature se humane carnis immiscuit, et id, guod alienum @ sé erat, vi sud et potestate prasumsit. 10, 15:—Quod si assumta sibi per se ex virgine carne, ipse sibi et ex se animam concepti per se corporis coaptavit, secundum anime corporisque naturam, necesse est et passionum fuisse naturam.” When Hilarius aims at precision, he says, as here,—animam ew Sey corpus per se, habuit; ex virgine corpus conceptum ;” but “non per humane conceptionis coaluit naturam, anima ex Deo.” (, 15, 22. So, for example, c, 22:—ut per se sibi assumsit ex virgine corpus, ita ex se sibi animam assumsit quee utique nun- quam ab homine gignentium originibus prebetur. C. 10, 16, 17 :—Mary contributed ad incrementa partumque corporis omne, 534 APPENDIX. quod sexus sui est naturale. ‘The nativitas ex virgine officio usa materno, sexus sui naturam in conceptu et partu exsecuta est.—Conceptus est ex Spiritu Sancto et ex Maria. Norte 75, page 409. That the “forma servilis” was not the immediate, as it were physical, consequence of the “evacuatio,” but that between the two intervened an ethical act, performed by the “ evacuatus” Son, that is, by the Son who willed to become man, Hilarius maintained with just emphasis; thus excluding, in the most distinct manner, the opinion attributed to him by Baur. Com- pare on Psalm Ixvii. c. 25 :—“Tpse enim est, et se ex forma Dei inaniens et formam hominis assumens; quia neque eva- cuatio illa ex Dei forma nature ccelestis interitus est, neque forme servilis assumtio tamquam genuine originis condition- isque natura est; cum id, quod assumtum est, non proprietas interior sit, sed exterior accessio, quod ipsum consequentibus docet (v. 30). Pauper est, qui cum esset omnium dives, se ipsum, ut nos ditesceremus, paupertavit : dolens est, qui secun- dum prophetam pro nobis dolet—Hune pauperem in salutem vultus Dei (i.e., filius) qui forma Dei est, in zeternitatis sue vita —collocavit.” De Trin. 9, 14 (compare Note 2, page 408) : —‘Ttaque evacuatio eo proficit, ut proficiat forma servi non ut Christus, qui in forma Dei erat, Christus esse non maneat, cum formam servi nonnisi Christus acceperit. Qui cum se evacua- verit, ut manens Spiritus Christus idem Christus homo esset, in corpore demutatio habittis et assumtio natures naturam manen- tis divinitatis non peremit, quia unus atque idem Christus sit, et demutans habitum et assumens. ©. 51 :—Manens sibi Dei natura in se humilitatem terrenze nativitatis susceperat, generis sui potestatem in habitu assumte humilitatis exercens.” Norte 76, page 410. 11, 48:—Quod autem se ipsum intra se vacuefaciens con- tinuit, detrimentum non attulit potestati cum intra hance exi- nanientis se humilitatem virtute tamen omnis exinanite imtra se usus sit potestatis (compare the fragment cited in Note 2, page 408). According to 9, 51, cll. 68, c. 25, one might sup- pose Hilarius to have conceived the “ evacuatio” of the Son, whom the Father eternally generates, to have consisted in His NOTES. 535 returning out of the existence which He had independently of the Father, into the “natura Dei,” to the potential existence of the “facies,” or of the “vultus,” or of the “imago Dei;” and that, during the state of humiliation, His actual personality (facies, vultus) was limited entirely to the “forma servilis.” The passage 9, 51, runs as follows :—“ Nos enim unigenitum Deum in natura Dei mansisse profitemur, neque unitatem forme servilis (that is, the personality in the form of a servant, which alone remained after the accomplishment of the ‘ exinanitio’) in naturam divine unitatis statim refundimus, neque rursum corporali insinuatione Patrem in Filio praedicamus, sed ex eo ejusdem generis genitam naturam naturaliter in se gignentem se habuisse naturam; que in forma nature se gignentis manens formam nature atque infirmitatis corporalis acceperit.” Nore 77, page 411. Tract. in Psalm Ixviii., Lit. x. c. 6-9. De Trin. 11, 49 :— Nostra hee itaque lucra sunt et nostri profectus, nos scilicet conformes efficiendi gloriz corporis Dei. Ceterum unigenitus Deus, licet et homo natus sit, non tamen aliud quam Deus omnia in omnibus est. Subjectio enim illa corporis, per quam, quod carnale ei est, in naturam Spiritfis devoratur, esse Deum omnia in omnibus eum, qui preter Deum et homo est, con- stituet : noster autem ille homo in id proficit. Ceterum nos in hominis nostri conformem gloriam proficiemus, et in agnitionem Dei renovati ad Creatoris imaginem reformabimur (Col. iu. 9, 10). Consummatur itaque homo imago Dei. Namque con- formis effectus gloriz corporis Dei in imaginem Creatoris excedit, secundum dispositam primi hominis fiqurationem. Et post peccatum veteremque hominem, in agnitionem Dei novus homo factus, constitutionis suze obtinet perfectionem, agnoscens Deum suum, et per id imago ejus; et per religionem proficiens ad eternitatem, et per seternitatem Creatoris sul imago man- surus.” Nore 78, page 411. On Psalm liii. 12 :—Unigenitum Dei filium frequenter imo semper predicamus non ex nature necessitate potius, quam ex sacramento humane salutis passioni fuisse subditum, et voluisse se magis passioni subjici, quam coactum. Et quanquam passio 536 APPENDIX. illa non fuerit conditionis et generis (that is, physically ne- cessary), quia indemutabilem dei naturam nulla vis injuriose perturbationis offenderet, tamen suscepta voluntarie est, officio quidem ipsa satisfactura poenali, non tamen poenz sensu lesura patientem ; non quod illa ledendi non habuerit pro ipsa passi- onis qualitate naturam, sed quod dolorem divinitatis natura non sentit. Passus ergo est Deus, quia se subjecit voluntarius pas- sioni; sed suscipiens naturales ingruentium in se passionum (quibus dolorem patientibus necesse est inferri) virtutes, ipse tamen a nature su virtute non excidit, ut doleret. 10, 47 :— Passus igitur unigenitus Deus est omnes incurrentes in se pas- sionum nostrarum infirmitates, sed passus virtute nature su, ut et virtute nature suze natus est: neque enim, cum natus sit, non tenuit omnipotentize suze in nativitate naturam. 10, 23:— Caro illa, i.e., panis ille de ccelis est, et homo ille de Deo est. Habens ad patiendum quidem corpus, et passus est; sed naturam (that is, neither physical necessity nor susceptibility in itself, apart from a particular act of will) non habens ad dolendum. Naturee enim propriz et sue corpus illud est, quod in ceelestem gloriam conformatur in monte, quod attactu suo fugat febres, quod de sputo suo format oculos. C. 24:—Cum potum et cibum accepit, non se necessitati corporis sed consuetudini tribuit. C. 387:—Non sibi tristis est: neque sibi orat, sed illis quos monet, orare pervigiles. C. 55 ff.:—There was no “ne- cessitas flendi” in Him; non sibi flevit, sed nobis. And yet His weeping was not a mere seeming; for the needs of men are not mere seeming, nor anything of that to which He sub- jected Himself, moved not by necessity, but by self-emptying love. ‘Specially important, however, are the passages, 10, 23, 48; de Synod. c. 49; in Psalm Ixviii. c. 4, 10, 23 :—“ Hominem verum secundum similitudinem nostri hominis, non deficiens a se Deo sumsit: in quo, quamvis aut ictus incideret, aut vulnus descenderet, aut nodi concurrerent, aut suspensio elevaret, affer- rent quidem hac impetum passionis, non tamen dolorem passi- onis inferrent: ut telum aliquod aut aquam perforans, aut ignem compungens, aut aéra vulnerans omnes quidem has pas- siones nature sue infert, ut foret, ut compungat, ut vulneret ; sed naturam suam in hec passio illata non retinet, dum in natura non est, vel aquam forari, vel pungi ignem, vel aérem vulnerari, quamvis nature teli sit, et vulnerare et compungere NOTES. 537 et forare. Passus quidem est dominus Jesus Christus, dum ceditur, dum suspenditur, dum crucifigitur, dum moritur, sed in corpus Domini irruens passio nec non fuit passio, nec tamen naturam (that is, physical necessity) passionis exseruit: dum et peenali ministerio deszevit, et Virtus corporis sine sensu poene vim pcene in se deseevientis excepit. Habuerit sane illud Domini corpus doloris nostri naturam, si corpus nostrum id nature habet, ut calcet undas et super fluctus eat—penetret etiam solida. At vero si dominici corporis sola ista natura sit, ut sua virtute, sua anima feratur in humidis, insistat in liquidis, et exstructa transcurrat, quid per naturam humani corporis con- ceptam ex Spiritu carnem judicamus? To the right under- standing of this passage, the following further citations are necessary (10, 48) :—“Succumbere ergo tibi videtur Virtus ista vulneris clavo et ad zctum compungentis exterrita, demutasse se in naturam dolendi?—Si in passione sua necessitas est et non salutis tuee donum est, si in cruce dolor compungendi est, et non decreti, quod in te mors est scripta confixio est; si in morte vis mortis est, et non per potestatem Dei carnis exuvie sunt; si denique mors ipsa aliud est, quam potentum de- honestatio, quam fiducia quam triumphus: adscribe infirmi- tatem, si ibi necessitas est et natura, si ibi vis est, et diffidentia et dedecus.” This, therefore, is, in his view, the “punctum saliens,” that in Christ there was no “infirmitas nature,” no “necessitas.” For this reason he says (10, 23),—if the “na- tura” of the God-man and the hostile powers are confronted with each other in and by themselves, the latter cannot cause the former pain, any more than the air can be harmed by a dart. The pain felt by Christ, therefore, was due to an act of love, which emptied itself on our account, and which not merely coerced the hostile forces by its “potestas,” but also discharged the “ ministerium pcene” (compare Psalm Ixviii. c. 8) ;—and Christ bore punishment, not as an evil or a pain, but “sine sensu peene;” for it was rooted, not in guilt of His own, but in a love which forgot itself, and forgot all suffering. We see, accordingly, that he can say of Christ, “dolet et non dolet.” The latter, so far as He took delight in suffering; and as the pain which He endured never, as in our case, got the master of His body, nor was able to change or destroy Him by its power (compare de Synod. c. 49), although His “ passio” was a reality. 538 APPENDIX. Thus we read in 10, 47:—Fallitur ergo humane estimationis opinion, putans hunc (al. hinc) dolere, quod patitur. Pro nobis dolet, non et doloris nostri dolet sensu, quia et habitu ut homo repertus habens in se doloris corpus (that is, a body which is capable of suffering), sed non habens naturam dolendi, dum et ut hominis habitus est, et origo non hominis est, nato eo de conceptione Spiritus S. Tract. in Psalm cxxxix. c. 11 :—Per- missum enim corpus passioni est, sed permissa sibi dominata mors non fuit. De Trin. 10, 27 :—Quam infirmitatem domi- natam hujus corpori credis, cujus tantam habuit natura virtu- tem? C. 32 :—Extra carnalem naturam dolendi vulneris re- peritur. 9, 7:—Tametsi in partu et passione et morte nature nostre res peregerit: res tamen ipsas omnes virtute naturz suze gessit, dum sibi ipse origo nascendi est, dum pati vult, quod eum pati non licet, dum moritur, qui vivit. By thus setting forth the sufferings of Christ in the light of deeds, he deprives Arians of their proofs of the lowness and physical passibility of the Logos, in a more striking manner than if he had appor- tioned them to His humanity. But when he represents Christ’s suffering as a deed, as a display of power, it is of course im- plied that he did not consider Him incapable of suffering, that he did not deny Him the power of making Himself passible. Undoubtedly he frequently repeats, the “ Verbum Dei’ as such cannot suffer; but the body taken up into union with Him, is the “materia” in which sufferings might be undergone. Tract. in Psalm Ixviii. ¢. 4:—“ Non enim incidere in Deum hic infir- mnitatem nostrarum terror valebat, aut exserere se nisi in carne corporis nostri, tanquam in subjacente materia, potuerant pas- siones. . . . Cum se contra nature ccelestis terrenzeque diversi- tatem, in hunc limum potestatis sue virtute definit: quia ea, que natura dissident, ad quandam connexionis sus soliditatem non generis ipsius propinquitate conveniunt, sed potiore vi tan- quam confixa sociantur, tunc et pati coepit et mori posse.” In accordance herewith, therefore, is also “impassibilitas” to be judged, on the ground of which Hilarius has been partially charged with Docetism, in that it is supposed to signify that He neither could nor did suffer. A passage, however, has been overlooked, which clearly explains the bearing of the term, de Synod. 49 :—* Pati potuit, et passibile esse non potuit (Ver- bum caro factum), quia passibilitas nature infirmis significatio NOTES. 539 est, passio autem est eorum, que sunt illata, perpessio: que quia indemutabilis Deus est, cum tamen Verbum caro factum sit, habuerunt in eo passionis materiam sine passibilitatis infir- mitate (that is, without the weakness which is unable to do otherwise). Manet itaque indemutabilis etiam in passione natura, quia auctori suo indifferens ex impassibilis essentiz nata substantia est.” Psalm Ixvii. 18; x. 15. Norte 79, page 416. De Trin. 9, 38 :—Dispensatione assumtz carnis et per exin- anientis se ex Dei forma obedientiam, nature sibi novitatem Christus homo natus intulerat, non virtutis natureeque damno, sed habitus demutatione. Exinaniens se igitur ex Dei forma, servi formam natus acceperat, sed hanc carnis assumtionem ea, cum qua sibi naturalis unitas erat, Patris natura non senserat ; et novitas temporalis (that is, the new condition of the entire person) licet maneret in virtute nature, amiserat tamen, cum forma Dei, nature Dei secundum assumtum hominem unitatem. Sed summa dispensationis heec erat, ut totus nune filius, homo scilicet et Deus, per indulgentiam paterne voluntatis unitati paterne nature inesset, et qui manebat in virtute nature, maneret quoque in genere naturee. It enim homini acquireba- tur, ut Deus esset. Sed manere in Dei unitate assumtus homo nullo modo poterat, nisi per unitatem Dei in unitatem Dei na- turalis evaderet, ut per hoc quod in natura Dei erat Deus ver bum, Verbum quoque caro factum rursum in natura Dei inesset, atque ita homo Jesus Christus maneret in gloria Dei Patris, Sl in Verbi gloriam caro esset unita; rediretque tunc in nature paternee etiam secundum hominem unitatem Verbum caro fac- tum, cum gloriam Verbi caro assumta tenuisset. Leddenda igitur apud se ipsum Patri erat unitas sua (i.e., a Patre filio), ut nature suze nativitas in se rursum glorificanda resideret: quia disnensationis novitas offensionem unitatis intulerat, et unitas, wt perfecta antea fuerat, nulla esse nunc poterat, nisi glorificata apud se fuisset carnis assumtio. Nore 80, page 417. De Trin. 9, 54:—Major Pater Filio est, et plane major, cui tantum donat esse, quantus ipse est; cui innascibilitatis (ayye- ynolas) esse imaginem sacramento nativitas impertit, quem ex 540 APPENDIX. se in formam suam generat (to wit, in the eternal generation), quem rursum de forma servi in formam Dei renovat, etc. Tract. in Ps, i. c. 27-80; c. 27:—Christ begged that id, quod tum filius hominis est, ad perfectum Dei filium, i.e., ad resumendam indulgendamque corpori eternitatis sux gloriam, per resurrec- tionis potentiam gigneretur; quam gloriam a Patre corporeus reposcebat.—Non nova querit, non aliena desiderat; esse talis qualis fuerat, postulat, sed precatur: id se, quod antea erat, esse, gigni scilicet ad id quod suum fuit. Non erat autem idip- sum tunc totus, quod fierl precabatur: fieri autem totus non aliud, quam quod fuerat, postulabat. Sed cum fit (1.e., gloriosus) quod fuit, et quod non erat, est futurus (on account of the humanity, which is to participate in the glory), ad id quod fuerat, id quod totum non erat, quodam novi ortus nascebatur exordio. Ergo hic resurrectionis sue ad assumendam gloriam dies est, per quam ad id nascitur, quod ante tempora erat. C. 30:—The words, “To-day have I begotten Thee,” refer, not to the birth from the Virgin, not to the baptism of Christ, but, according to the Apostle, to the first-born from the dead (Acts xi. 82). According to Baur (pp. 690 ff.), with this elorifica- tion at the end, the Docetism, which does away with the human, shows itself quite plainly. He adduces in evidence, de Trin. 9, 38 38 (see Note 79), and c. 41; these passages, however, are not at all pertinent to the matter (see Note 79). He might have adduced other passages with a far greater show of reason ; especially de Trin, 11, 40:—“ Quibus subjectis subjicitur subjicienti sibi omnia, Dominus scilicet, ut sit Deus omnia in omnibus (1 Cor. xv. 28) natura assumti corporis nostri nature paternee divini- tatis invecté. Per id enim erit omnia in omnibus Deus, quia Mediator, habens in se ex dispensatione, quod carnis est, adep- turus (est) in omnibus ex subjectione, quod Dei est, ne ex parte Deus sit, sed Deus totus. Non alia itaque subjectionis causa est, quam ut omnia in omnibus Deus sit, nulla ex parte terrent m eo corporis residente natura, ut, ante in se duos continens, nunc Deus tantum sit.” Compare ec. 41, 42, 49. But, on the other hand, Hilarius says, that we are to become like the glori- fied body of Christ (11, 19; Ps. ii. 41, lv. 12). Ixviti"35'; ‘conm pare Note 82). Further: Christ presented the expected gift, the man He had assumed, to the Father (Comm. in Matt. c. 3, PA F134 oD brought into heaven materiem assumti corporis conso- NOTES. 541 ciatam Spiritus et substantiw suze eternitati” (ib. c. 4, 14). Indeed, his fundamental view of the work of redemption re- quired that there should be no necessity for the humanity to be annihilated, in order that the man Jesus might attain to perfec- tion; but that the humanity should really be exalted to God in Christ. Not merely for Thomas had the Risen One a body, but eternally; and at the day of judgment, they will know Him whom they have pierced (de Trin. 3, 16, 20). We shall therefore have to consent to take note of passages of this second kind, in order that we may not form a false representation of Hilarius, and the many Fathers who use similar language to him on this point. But how are the two things to be united? | In fact, the contradiction would be unreconcilable if the words, “nulla ex parte terreni in eo corporis residente natura,” taught the complete annihilation or swallowing up of the body by the deity. This, however, cannot be the opinion of Hilarius. For he adds, immediately after (11, 40),—the perfection is accom- plished non abjecto corpore, sed ex subjectione translato, neque per defectionem abolito sed ex clarificatione mutato, acquirens sibi Deo potius hominem, quam Deum per hominem amittens. Subjectus vero ob id, non ut non sit, sed ut omnia in omnibus Deus sit, habens in sacramento subjectionis esse ac manere quod non est, non habens in defectione ita se carere, ne non sit. That which is swallowed up by the divine “Gloria,” is not the “materies” of the humanity, but the “corruptio,” the “ infir- mitas,” which is an “accidens” of it, but not its essence (com- pare Ps. lv. 12). This is also clearly declared, Ps. exliii. 7. Who was it that was thus exalted? (Phil. ii. 7, 9). “Non ei utique, qui in forma Dei erat, donatur, ut Dei forma sit.” For although “cohibens in se formam Dei,’ the Son of God re- mains in Himself “ Dei virtus,” and can restore Himself to the “forma Dei” when He will. It is given to Him, as the One who took upon Himself the form of a servant, “ipsi habitui ser- vili id donatur, ut quod erat, esset in forma scilicet Dei esset.— Et heec quidem evangelici sacramenti et humane spei veritas est, humanam naturam corruptibilemque carnem per hujus gloriz demutationem in eternam transformatam esse substan- tiam.” What, then, is the perfection of the God-man, save that by it humanity is brought to its true state, to God; is stripped of all false independence; 1s deprived of that existence outside 542 APPENDIX. of God which characterizes the “servilis forma,” with its “io- firmitas” and “corruptio:” and, on the other hand, that the creature is taken into the divine sphere and glory, in which it is a never-disappearing, eternal momentum of the divine life itself. Norte 81, page 419. Verbum caro factum est et habitavit in nobis, naturam scilicet in se totius humani generis assumens. Ps. liv., c. 9: —“ Uni- versitatis nostree caro est factus.” In Matt. iv., c. 12 :—“The city on the hill is the humanity assumed by Christ, quia, ut civitas ex varietate ac multitudine consistit habitantium ita in eo, per naturam suscepti corporis, quedam universi generis humani congregatio continetur. Atque ita et ille ex nostra in se congre- gatione fit civitas et nos per consortium carnis sua sumus civi- tatis habitatio.” Ps. exxiv.,c. 4, 143,c.18. De Trin. 2, 24:— (ut) homo factus ex virgine naturam in se carnis acciperit, perque hujus admixtionis societatem sanctificatum in eo universi generis humani corpus exsisteret, ut quemadmodum omnes in se per id, quo corporeum se esse voluit, conderentur, ita rursum in omnes ipse per id, quod ejus est invisibile, referretur. ©. 25:—Non ille eguit homo effici, per quem homo factus est, sed nos eguimus, ut Deus caro fieret, et habitaret in nobis, i.e., assumtione carnis unius interna universe carnis incoleret. In Matt. 2, c. 5 :—Lrat in Jesu Christo homo totus. Ps. xii. 4. NOTE 82, page 420. Tract. in Ps. xiii. 4, 56, c. 7, 8:—“‘ Compatiendi et com- moriendi fides nos glorificat in Christo.” Hence David calls the sufferings and glory of Christ His own, quia se per assum- tionem carnis in ccelestibus collocandum Propheta non nescit, quippe cum concorporales et comparticipes effecti simus in Christo Jesu. Ps. exxiv., c. 8:—Christus est mons superim- minens et excelsus, in quo ipsi nosmet ipsos per assumtionem carnis nostra corporisque speculamur. ©. 4:—In eo enim sumus resurrectionem nostram in resurrectione nostri in eo cor- poris contemplantes. It is true, Hilarius says also concerning others besides Christ, that all are in them; and from this the Benedictine draws the conclusion, |. c. p. xxv. § 81:—“Kos omnes qui humanz nature consortes sunt, Hilarii aliorumque Patrum sententia naturali unitate esse conjunctos. Et uniuntur quidem NOTES. 543 in illa massa, ex qua omnes originem habent et ex qua Christus ipse carnis sue substantiam sumere non recusavit;” in support whereof might further have been adduced, that, according to Hilarius (compare Ps. li. c. 21), all men are “ generalis anime et corporis.” But even this does not furnish an explanation of the phraseology in question. If all are one in virtue of their common origin, it may justly be said,—AIl individuals subsist, have their roots therein, as in the universal, but not in each other, or all in one, unless indeed this one can in some aspect or other be regarded as the vehicle and representative of the whole and the universal. In point of fact, Hilarius does not use the terms in question relatively to every man ; but only relatively to Adam, on the ground of his being the universal father as to the body, with which also is connected the spread of sin over the entire race. Hence he frequently says,—“ We all fell in him” (in Matt. c. 8,5; Ps. exliv. c. 4, 1386; ¢. 5,7). In his remarks on Matthew xviii. c. 6, he uses Abraham with Sarah as a symbol of the whole of humanity; but merely allegorically. Hence the application to the first Adam along with the Second proves all the more clearly that, like the other Fathers, Hilarius regarded Christ also as the representative of the race. As all men were potentially in the first Adam, so in a spiritual sense are all men potentially in the Second Adam; so, namely, that as the Logos, the Second Adam is the final cause of the origin of the first Adam and all his descendants. On the other hand, the Mau- rinist is right when he denies that Hilarius held Christ to have assumed merely the general nature of the human race, and not an individual human nature. This is evident from the passage de Trin. 2, 25, quoted above. See Note 81. Note 83, page 429. Even at an earlier period, the opinion entertained in the Church respecting Apollinaris was pretty unanimous, as is clear from what has been advanced above (see page 424). For, independently of the Synod of Alexandria, held in the year 362 (see Note 65), through the influence of Vitalis, Apol- linarism was condemned by several Roman Councils under Damasus. Compare Dozom. 6, 25; Theodoret. H. E. 5, 10 Mansi Cone. Coll. T. ili. 461, 447-482, 486, and the epistle of Damasus to Paulinus in Antioch. In this letter we find the 544 APPENDIX. following words (I. c. p. 426) :—“Confitendus ipsa sapientia sermo, filius Dei humanum suscepisse corpus, animam, sensum, 1.e., integrum Adam, et ut expressius dicam, totum veterem nostrum sine peccato hominem. Sicuti enim confitentes eum humanum corpus suscepisse, non statim ei et humanas vitiorum adjungimus passiones: ita et dicentes eum suscepisse et hominis animam et sensum non statim dicimus et cogitationum cum humanarum subjacuisse peccato.” According to Theodoret, the Romish Council (Mansi 488) said,—’ Avabewarifowev xaxelvous ov TWvES aVTL KoytKHS Abuyts Sicyupifovrat OTL 6 TOD Ocod Aoyos eotpagdn év Th avlpwrivy capKt’ avTos yap ovToOs 0 ToD Oeod Aoyos ovyl avTl THs NoyiKs Kal voepas wuyns ev TO éavTod TMOLATL yéyover, GAA THY HyeTépav, TOOT eoTL AoyiKIY Kal poepav avev THS dpaptias ~ruyny avéraBe Kal érwoev. Another Roman Council under Damasus says (p. 461) :—Adserunt (the Apollinarists) dicere, dominum ac salvatorem nostrum ex Maria virgine imperfectum, i.e., sine sensu (vods) hominem suscepisse. Heu quanta erit Arianorum in tali sensu vicinitas! Jl imper- jectam divinitatem in Dei filio dicunt, isti imperfectam humanita- tem in hominis filio mentiuntur. Quod si utique imperfectus homo susceptus est, imperfectum Dei munus est, imperfecta nostra salus, quia non est totus homo salvatus.—Nos autem, qui integros ac perfectos salvatos nos scimus, secundum catholica ecclesiz professionem, perfectum Deum perfectum suscepisse hominem profitemur. This was constituted an cecumenical decree in the year 381, when the Council of Constance in Can. 1. said,—avaGeuaticOjvas (sc. Set) Tacav aiperw, Kal (diKdS.. . Thy Tov AmoddvaptoTov (1. c. p. 560). With this cecumenical decree were soon associated imperial edicts, forbidding Apol- linarism. We cannot, therefore, understand how Baur can assert it to be inaccurate (1. c. 647), to say that the doctrine of the complete humanity of Christ received the official sanction of the Church at the Synod held in the year 381. END OF VOL. LI. T. & T. CLARK’S PUBLICATIONS, WORKS BY PROFESSOR A. B. BRUCE, D.D. tered cs Apologetics; or, Christianity Defensively Stated, By ALEXANDER Batmain Bruce, D.D., Professor of Apologetics and New Testament Exegesis, Free Church College, Glasgow. In post 8vo, Third Edition, price 10s. 6d. ‘Dr. Bruce has won for himself the foremost place among living apologists. . . . There does not exist in our language so satisfactory or original a treatment of the historicity of the Gospels, the claims of Jesus, and the Significance of His appearance; nor have we so just and informing a criticism of the theories of primitive Christianity. ... The Church at large will inevitably recognise Dr. Bruce’s ‘“‘ Apologetics” as a volume of great and permanent value.’— Expositor. Being the Third Volume of ‘Tur INTERNATIONAL THEOLOGICAL LIBRARY.’ St. Paul’s Conception of Christianity. In post 8vo, price 7s. 6d. ‘ A living book, candid, clear, and supremely able; a book worthy alike of the author and the great subject with which it deals.— Review of the Churches. ‘There need be no hesitation in pronouncing it the best treatment of Paulinism we have . . . A book of first-rate importance.’—Hpositor. The Kingdom of God; or, Christ’s Teaching according to the Synoptical Gospels. In post 8vo, Sixth Edition, price 7s. 6d. ‘To Dr. Bruce belongs the honour of giving to English-speaking Christians the first really scientific treatment of this transcendent theme . . . his book is the best mono- graph on the subject in existence.’—Rev. JAMES STALKER, D.D., in The British Weekly. ‘ The astonishing vigour and the unfailing insight which characterise the book mark a new era in biblical theology.’—Professor Marcus Dons, D.D The Training of the Twelve; or, Exposition of Passages in the Gospels exhibiting the Twelve Disciples of Jesus under Discipline for the Apostleship. In demy 8vo, Fifth Edition, price 10s. 6d. ‘A volume which can never lose its charm either for the preacher or for the ordinary Christian reader. —London Quarterly Review. ‘An elaborate study of the teaching of Jesus, which after twenty-five years is still unsurpassed.’—British Weekly. ‘A great book, full of suggestion and savour. It should be the companion of the minister.’—Mr. SPURGEON in Sword and Trowel. ‘That minister who has not read ‘‘ The Training of the Twelve” betrays an indiffer- ence to modern thought which is unpardonable.’—President Harrer in The Biblical World, The Humiliation of Christ, in its Physical, Ethical, and Official Aspects. In demy 8vo, Fourth Edition, price 10s. 6d. ‘ These lectures are able and deep-reaching toa degree not often found in the religious literature of the day; withal, they are fresh and suggestive. ... The learning and the deep and sweet spirituality of this discussion will commend it to many faithful students of the truth as it is in Jesus.’—Congregationalist. ‘We have not for a long time met with a work so fresh and suggestive as this of Professor Bruce. . . . We do not know where to look at our English Universities for a treatise so calm, logical, and scholarly. —English Independent. *K T& AS CuARK'S “PUBLICATIONS. The Life of James McCosh. A Record chiefly Autobiographical. Edited by Professor Winn1am Mrniican Stoang. Ilustrated with Portraits. In demy 8vo, price 9s. This volume has been in the main compiled from papers left. by Dr. McCosh, Large portions are his personal reminiscences, in his own words ; while the chapters which, for the sake of completeness, have been added by the editor, follow closely the ample material afforded by letters, printed speeches, and published articles. ‘Reveals the man, a man of whom his countrymen have every reason to be proud, and who was an almost perfect embodiment of all that is best in the Scottish character.’ —Glasgow Herald. Books which Influenced our Lord and His Apostles: Being a Critical Review of Apocalyptic Jewish Literature. By Joun E. H. Tuomson, B.D., Stirling. In demy 8vo, price 10s. 6d. ‘This is a clever, imaginative, scholarly, interesting volume. Mr, Thomson has the gift of making the old world times and personages live again ; and his book, being written with unflagging spirit, is likely to prove of value by investing the apocalyptic writings with an attractiveness they have not always seemed to possess... . A book which is a credit to Scottish scholarship. . . . It is a volume worthy of the attention both of scholars and of the public.’—Professor Marcus Dons, D.D., in The Expositor. Pseudepigrapha: An Account of certain Apocryphal Sacred Writings of the Jews and early Christians. By Rev. Witniam J. Deane, M.A., Rector of Ashen, Essex. In post 8vo, price 7s. 6d. ‘It is the most complete book on the subject in the English language, and contains the most ample information on these writings. It is indispensable to every scholar who wishes to be acquainted with this class of literature, and should occupy a place in the library of every theologian.’—Paton J, Guoae, D.D. Central Truths and Side Issues. By Rosrrr G. Barour, D.D., Free New North Church, Edinburgh. In cr. 8vo, price 3s. 6d. Conrents:—I. The Incarnation and Humiliation of the Son of God. II. The Eyan- gelical View of the Atonement Explained and Vindicated. III. Alternative Theories of the Atonement Discussed. IV. The Doctrine of Baptisms and Laying on of Hands. V. The Sinai Covenant: its Place and Purpose in the History of Redemption. VI. The Resurrection of the Body. Index. ‘The book is well worth buying and keeping. The chapter on the Incarnation and Humiliation of the Son of God is admirable in every way—reasonable, liberal, and full of acute and forcible argument.’— Review of the Churches. Inspiration, and other Lectures. By the late President T. Gzrorcr Rooks, B.A., Rawdon College. Edited by Two or His Stupents. In One Volume, 8vo, price 7s. 6d. ‘Intrinsically good. . . . The chapters on pastoral work glow with a whole-hearted devotion. The counsels given are excellent.’—London Quarterly Review. The World of Faith and the Everyday World. As Displayed in the Footsteps of Abraham. By Pastor Orro Funckg, Bremen. From the Sixth German Edition. Post 8vo, price 7s. 6d. ‘A remarkable volume, . .. The plainness and freedom of his speech, the homeliness and force of his illustrations, the general directness and vigour of his method, are such as one does not often meet with. . . . To describe the author in short, we should say that he was a German Spurgeon.’—Spectator. T. & T. CLARK’S PUBLICATIONS. WORKS BY PROFESSOR F. GODET, D.D. (Copyright, by arrangement with the Author.) ‘For devotional warmth and practical application, Godet is perhaps unsurpassed by any modern commentator amongst foreign Protestants.’—GUARDIAN. Introduction to the New Testament. The Epistles of St. Paul. By Professor F. Goprr, D.D., Neuchatel. Just published, demy Svo (pp. 630), price 12s. 6d. net. The original Edition is to form Three large Volumes—Vol. I. Containing ‘St. Paul’s Epistles ’ (Translation now ready, as above); Vol. Il. ‘The Gospels, and Acts of the Apostles’; and Vol. III. “Hebsews, Catholic Epistles, and the Apocalypse.’ ‘ Anything that comes from Dr. Godet is sure to receive a cordial welcome in Great Britain, and our familiarity with his eloquent and luminous commentaries prepares us to appreciate very highly a work in which the venerable Swiss thus gathers up the harvest of a lifetime.’—Professor ADENEY in The Critical Review. ‘In every particular it is fully abreast of the times. For the purposes of the hard- working preacher there is no book on St. Paul’s Epistles quite equal to this. For the student, it must always lie in a place that his hand can reach. It is delightful reading.’ —Methodist Times. A Commentary on the Gospel of St. Luke. In Two Volumes, 8vo, price 21s. ‘Marked by clearness and good sense, it will be found to possess value and interest as one of the most recent and copious works specially designed to illustrate this Gospel.—Guardian. A Commentary on the Gospel of St. John. In Three Volumes, 8vo, price 31s. 6d. ‘This Gospel forms one of the battlefields of modern inquiry, and is itself so rich in spiritual truth that it is impossible to examine it too closely; and we welcome this treatise from the pen of Dr. Godet. We have no more competent exegete, and this new volume shows all the learning and vivacity for which the author is distinguished.’— Freeman, A Commentary on St. Paul’s Epistle to the Romans. In Two Volumes, 8vo, price 21s. ‘We prefer this commentary to any other we have seen on the subject.’—British and Foreign Evangelical Review, A Commentary on St. Paul’s First Epistle to the Corinthians. In Two Volumes, demy 8vo, price 21s. ‘We do not know any better commentary to put into the hands of theological students.’—Guardian. ‘A perfect masterpiece of theological toil.and thought. . . . Scholarly, evangelical, exhaustive, and able.—Hvangelical Review. Defence of the Christian Faith. Translated by the Hon. and Rev. Canon Lyrrenron, M.A. In crown 8vo, New and Cheaper Edition, price 4s. ‘There is trenchant argument and resistless logic in these lectures; but withal, there is cultured imagination and felicitous eloquence, which carry home the appeals to the heart as well as the head.’—Sword and Trowel. T. &,. T. CLARK’S PUBLICATIONS. BISHOP MARTENSEN’S WORKS. ‘The greatest Scandinavian, perhaps the greatest Lutheran, divine of our century.’—EXPosiTor. Christian Ethics. In Three Volumes, 8vo, price 10s. 6d. each. Volume I, GENERAL ETHICS.—II, INDIVIDUAL ETHICS.—III. SOCIAL ETHICS. ‘ As man is a member of two societies, a temporal and a spiritual, it is clear that his ethical development only can go on when these two are treated side by side. ‘This Bishop Martensen has done with rare skill. We do not know where the conflicting claims of Church and State are more equitably adjusted. ... We can read these volumes through with unflagging interest.’—Literary World. ‘Dr. Martensen’s work on Christian Dogmatics reveals the strength of thought as well as the fine literary grace of its author. . . . His chief ethical writings comprise a system of Christian Ethics, general and special, in three volumes. Each of these volumes has great and singular excellence, and it might be generally felt that in them the author has surpassed his own work on ‘‘ Christian Dogmatics.”’—Rev. Principal Carrns. Christian Dogmatics. In One Volume, 8vo, price 10s. 6d. ‘The famous ‘‘ Dogmatics,” the eloquent and varied pages of which contain intel- lectual food for the laity no less than for the clergy. . . . His ‘‘ Christian Dogmatics ” has exercised as wide an influence on Protestant thought as any volume of our century.’ —LHxpositor. ‘We feel much indebted to Messrs. Clark for their introduction of this important compendium of orthodox theology from the pen of the learned Danish Bishop... . Every reader must rise from its perusal stronger, calmer, and more hopeful, not only for the fortunes of Christianity, but of dogmatic theology.’—Quarterly Review. ‘Such a bock is a library in itself, and a monument of pious labour in the cause of true religion.’—IJrish Ecclesiastical Gazette. BY DR. C. VON ORELLI, BASEL. TRANSLATED BY Proressor J. S. BANKS, HeapincLEy CoLLece, LEEDs. The Twelve Minor Prophets. In demy 8vo, price 10s. 6d. ‘It is rarely that a commentary is given us so scholarly and yet so compact.’— Glasgow Herald. ‘ A very valuable and trustworthy compendium of the latest results of critical research, written in a sober and devout spirit..—Christian World. The Prophecies of Isaiah. In demy 8vo, price 10s. 6d. ‘The characteristics of this admirable commentary are brevity, separation of the more grammatical from the more expository notes, and general orthodoxy combined with first-rate scholarship.’—The Record. ‘Characterised by consummate ability throughout, this work will undoubtedly take high rank among the expositions of the ‘‘ Evangelical Prophet.”’—The Christian. The Prophecies of Jeremiah. In demy 8vo, price 10s. 6d. ‘Will be found a most trustworthy aid to the study of a book that presents many difficult problems.’—John Bull. The Old Testament Prophecy of the Consummation of God’s Kingdom. Traced in its Historical Development. In demy 8vo, price 10s. 6d. ‘Cannot fail to be regarded as a standard work upon the subject of Old Testament prophecy. ’—Sword and Trowel. ‘An unusually interesting work for the critical student . . . it possesses that intrinsic quality which commands attention and inquiry such as scholars delight in.—Clergyman’s Magazine, 1. & T. CLARK’S PUBLICATIONS. WORKS BY PATON J. GLOAG, D.D. Introduction to the Synoptic Gospels. By Rev. Paton J. Guoac, D.D., Edinburgh. Just published, in demy 8vo, price 7s. 6d. ‘Dr. Gloag has kept his mind open to the light, and has produced a volume which the student of theology will find most helpful to him in his professional work.’— Scotsman, ‘A volume of sterling value; learned, clear, candid, cautious, thoroughly well considered; it should be a welcome addition to the library of the biblical student.’— London Quarterly Review. Introduction to the Catholic Epistles. In demy 8vo price 10s. 6d. | ‘Dr. Gloag, whilst courteous to men of erudition who differ from him, is firm and fearless in his criticism, and meets the erudition of others with an equal erudition of his own. He has displayed all the attributes of a singularly accomplished divine in this volume, which ought to be eagerly welcomed as a solid contribution to theological literature; it is a work of masterly strength and uncommon wmerit.’—Hvangelical Magazine. ‘We have here a great mass of facts and arguments relevant in the strictest sense to the subject, presented with skill and sound judgment, and calculated to be of very great service to the student.’—Literary Churchman. Exegetical Studies. In crown 8vo, price 5s. ‘Careful and valuable pieces of work.’—WSpectator. ‘A very interesting volume.’—Literary Churchman. ‘Dr. Gloag handles his subjects very ably, displaying everywhere accurate and extensive scholarship, and a fine appreciation of the lines of thought in those passages with which he deals.’—Baptist. The Messianic Prophecies (one of the Baird Lectures). In crown 8vo, price 7s. 6d. ‘It has seldom fallen to our lot to read a book which we think is entitled to such unqualified praise as the one now before us. Dr. Gloag has displayed consummate ability. —London Quarterly Review. ‘We regard Dr. Gloag’s work as a valuable contribution to theological literature. We have not space to give the extended notice which its intrinsic excellence demands, and must content ourselves with cordially recommending it to our readers.’— Spectator. Introduction to the Pauline Epistles. In demy 8vo, price 12s. ‘A work of uncommon merit. He must be a singularly accomplished divine to whose library this book is not a welcome and valuable addition.’— Watchman. A Critical and Exegetical Commentary on the Acts of the Apostles. In Two Volumes, 8vo, price 21s. [At present out of print. The Primeval World: A Treatise on the Relations of Geology to Theology. Crown 8vo, 3s. LASS CLARK SABUBLIGA TIONS: How to Read the Prophets: Being the Prophecies arranged Chronologically in their Historical Setting, with Explanations, Maps, and Glossary. By Rev. Bucnanan Brake, B.D. Now complete, in Five Volumes, crown 8vo. Part I, THE PRE-EXILIAN MINOR PROPHETS (with JOEL). Second Edition. Price 4s.—Part IT. ISAIAH (Chapters i.-xxxix.). Second Edition. Price 2s, 6d.— Part II]. JEREMIAH, Price 4s.—Parr IV. EZEKIEL. Price 4s.—Parr V. ISAIAH (Chapters xl.-lxvi.) and THE POST-EXILIAN PROPHETS, Price 4s. The Series being now complete, Messrs. Clark offer the Set of Five Volumes for FirreEN SHILLINGS. ‘It has often been found a difficulty to profit fully from the reading, especially of the smaller prophecies of the Old Testament. To make these prophecies intelligible to the plainest reader, it seems desirable that a chronological arrangement of the prophetic books should be attempted Alongside of the several prophecies should be placed those portions of the Old Testament historica: books which deal with the same period. The aim of these manuals is consequently in this direction: to bring within the reach of the many a clear and succinct presentation of these prophets in their historical environment.’—From the AUTHOR’s INTRODUCTION. ‘ Mr. Blake seems to have hit upon the right thing, and he has proved himself com- petent to do it rightly. While these books are the very best introductions to the study of the prophets, even the accomplished scholar will find them indispensable.—The Hapository Times. BY THE REV. JAMES STALKER, D.D. The Life of Jesus Christ. A New Edition, in larger type, and handsomely bound, crown 8vo, price 3s. 6d. ‘No work since ‘‘ Ecce Homo” has at all approached this in succinct, clear-cut, and incisive criticism on Christ as He appeared to those who believed on Him.’—Literary World. ‘ Even with all our modern works on the exhaustless theme, from Neander to Farrar and Geikie, there is none which occupies the ground of Mr. Stalker’s. . . . We question whether any one popular work so impressively and adequately represents Jesus to the mind... . It may be despised because it is small, but its light must shine.’-—Christian. The Life of St. Paul. Uniform with the ‘Life of Christ’ in size and price. ‘ Even to those who know by heart the details of the great apostle’s life, this glowing sketch will be a revelation. Written with a fine sympathy for the more tender and personal aspects of his theme, Mr, Stalker has portrayed the outer and the inner life of Paul with a mingled power and beauty which is as rare as it is needed in evangelical writing.’—Christian. ‘A gem of sacred biography. . . . Well does it deserve the new and handsome dress in which it now appears.’—Christian Leader. The Kingdom of God, Biblically and Historically considered. By Prof. J. S. Cannuisu, D.D., Glasgow. In demy 8vo, price 10s. 6d. ‘Dr. J. S. Candlish, of Glasgow, perhaps the most learned of living dogmatic theologians.’—British Weekly. ‘As to the ability of this volume there can be no question: it is of profound interest, touches on time-present subjects, is free from all rhetorical display, is in no sense superficial, but scholarly and able, and is worthy of the reputation and position of its author.’—Kvangelical Magazine. ‘Dr, Candlish treats his subject with an admirable combination of scholarly com- prehensiveness, historical candour, and regard to the practical demands of mankind,’— Christian World. a ‘Peso df 2 CuARK’S ‘LUBLICATIONS, Nature and the Bible: Lectures on the Mosaic History of Creation in its Relation to Natural Science. By Dr. Fr. H. Reuscu. Revised and Corrected by the Author. Translated by KatuHireren Lytretton. In Two Volumes, 8vo, price 21s. ‘Other champions much more competent and learned than myself might have been placed in the field; I will only name one of the most recent, Dr. Reusch, author of “ Nature and the Bible.”’—The Right Hon, W. E. GLADSTONE. ‘The work, we need hardly say, is of profound and perennial interest, and it can scarcely be too highly commended as, in many respects, a very successful attempt to settle one of the most perplexing questions of the day. It is impossible to read it without obtaining larger views of theology, and more accurate opinions respecting its relations to science, and no one will rise from its perusal without feeling a deep sense of gratitude to its author.’—Scoltish Review. ‘We owe to Dr. Reusch, a Catholic theologian, one of the most valuable treatises on the relation of Religion and Natural Science that has appeared for many years.’— Literary World. Pre-Organic Evolution and the Biblical Idea of God: An Exposition and a Criticism. By Principal C. Capmany, M.A., LL.D., Plymouth. In crown 8vo, price 6s. ‘A volume which will take an important position among Theistic, not to say Christian apologetics, and which, in the present growth of scepticism, we may well be thankful for.—Literary Churchman. Darwinianism: Workmen and Work. By J. Hurcuison Stiruine, F.R.C.S., and LL.D, Edinburgh. In post 8vo, price 10s. 6d. ‘Undoubtedly the most trenchant criticism of Darwinianism that has yet appeared. The book is a work of art.’—Professor M‘KEnprick in The Critical Review. “To say that these chapters abound in acute reasoning, telling examples, sharp criticisms, and brilliant flashes of wit, is only to give a very modest impression of their argumentative power, ... Dr. Stirling has produced an amazingly clever book.’— Scotsman. ‘ He has set forth all this in such a graphic and humorous way that we read on and on, and cannot stop till we have read it through. There is no dulness here. He is alert, and we are kept on the strain. . . . Dr. Stirling has most effectively done a piece of work which willremain. It is done once, and once for all.’— Professor IvErAcH, D.D., in The British Weekly. Philosophy and Theology, the First Edinburgh University Gifford Lectures. By J. Hutcnison Srirune, F.R.C.8., and LL.D. Edinburgh. In post 8vo, price 9s. ‘This volume will make for itself many friends. There is a bracing, stimulating masterfulness about the lectures, which, on a careful perusal of them, will be found to lead to many rich veins of thought.’—Professor SrEwartT in The Critical Review. Apologetics; or, The Scientific Vindication of Christianity. By Professor J. H. A. Eprarp, Ph.D., D.D., Erlangen. In Three Volumes, demy 8vo, price 31s. 6d. ‘The author of this work has a reputation which renders it unnecessary to speak in words of general commendation of his ‘‘ Apologetics.” Dr. Ebrard takes nothing for granted. He begins at the beginning, laying his foundations deep and strong, and building upon them patiently and laboriously, leaving no saps, no loose work, but adjusting each stone to its place and use.’—Church Bells. THE LATE PROFESSOR FRANZ DELITZSCH, D.D., LEIPZIG. ‘Probably no commentator of the age brought so many gifts to the interpretation of the Bible as did Franz Delitzsch. . . . Walking hand in hand with such a guide through the garden of the Lord, one can not only gather its ripened fruit, but also breathe the fragrance of its flowers and gaze upon their loveliness.’—Professor J. F. M‘Curpy, Toronto. A New Commentary on Genesis. By Professor Franz Deuirzscu, D.D., Leipzig. In Two Volumes, 8vo, price 21s, Nore.—While preparing the translation, the translator was favoured by Professor Delitzsch with numerous improvements and additions. It may therefore be regarded as made from a revised version of the New Commentary on Genesis. ‘We congratulate Professor Delitzsch on this new edition. Byit, not less than by his other commentaries, he has earned the gratitude of every lover of biblical science, and we shall be surprised if, in the future, many do not acknowledge that they have found in it a welcome help and guide.’ —Professor 8S. R. Driver in The Academy. ‘The work of a reverent mind and a sincere believer, and not seldom there are touches of great beauty and of spiritual insight in it.’.—Guardian. The Prophecies of Isaiah. By Professor Franz Deuirzsocs D.D., Leipzig. Translated from the Fourth and last Edition. The only Authorised Translation. With an Introduction by Professor S. R. Driver, D.D., Oxford. In Two Volumes, 8vo, price 21s. ‘Delitzsch’s last gift to the Christian Church. .. . In our opinion, those who would enter into the meaning of that Spirit as He spake long ago by Isaiah, words of comfort and hope which have not lost their significance to-day, cannot find a better guide; one more marked by learning, reverence, and insight, than Franz Delitzsch.’—Professor W. T. Davison in The Expository Times. A System of Biblical Psychology. §8vo, 12s. ‘Still the best book on the whole of the subject.’-—-Principal Cave, D.D. re Pa er es ee ae Franz Delitzsch: A Memorial Tribute. By Professor §. I. Curtiss, D.D. In crown 8vo, with a Portrait, price 3s. This work is based on an intimate acquaintance with Professor Delitzsch, which began in 1873 ; on a careful examination of original documents not previously brought to light ; and on personal interviews with those who were acquainted with him. ‘A highly interesting little monograph on the personality of the great theologian, and on his work.’—Svpectator. BY Jd. Jd. VAN OOSTERZEE, D.D. The Year of Salvation: Words of Life for Every Day. A Book of Household Devotion. Two Vols. large crown 8vo, price 6s. each. ‘This charming and practical book of household devotion will be welcomed on account of its rare intrinsic value, as one of the most practical devotional books ever published. ’—Standard. Moses: A Biblical Study. In crown 8vo, price 6s. ‘Our author has seized, as with the instinct of a master, the great salient points in the life and work of Moses, and portrayed the various elements of his character with vividness and skill.’—Baptist Magazine. i logical Seminary-Speer Libr. My 1127 oe cele “at etht vale ble eperegheatt : Re eal eT = Se nap opab-~ eres TFs SPF FLEE POOL POLO EI PANTS SOTHO ROTH SHY © OM MM ee ed tee ee de ede i a Tee: : ew i ee ewe ey c eS 848 oP Pe i A ee ee PD OD OO hemo wwe as ee oe ye ee te ceed re! Fb Nn *, i! we CVS 48 Ss CN e+ ~~ we : Pe EO ee Ow Ara! . - , 2 , . eRe, a wets 7 Stes 6 4 Hoe schrieb 4 4cé “4 ores Potts 4 Oe) 4 ¥ s a8, nate . LS vee + yt Setet 4) H6 “4 4 ‘it Ry 4 7 ove 444 FLO TS VS ¥. LAA PILD ASSIS HS 4 € fy « aeSdy “4 ales ee ‘te »; ‘a8, ofa) * 78, 0 C0 7 ee : . I Perry ae ee PLD * 3 M at, 4 My? < 448 4 <8 ae as * >: ads Pa) esate “4 #34 % 9 $e > > 72 Ook; ad ‘ “fe ds 4) ae Phy 2) ‘ 2) Pas « « 5 eed Py: 4 > ees < se 4 J Xe {) s My 7. « os: fe am 40 aie aes é ¢ m2 ses Ph f 0) .% * A ‘“ 4 4 ede ad sae Ps) 8, .%, %, € “ 4 ss ~ ~ - ye c ee “ ELAS A See SAEs vy y os Ais EA : SERA ess LPG AL LASS SEE IIA IIASA ADAP ISA LAGS AIL APHIS, a hee ELIE EAE EE ILLIA SLE A ARMADA REA AAA RADE AR ORR RD AERO Ray he Sa sin tint aioe ans PO Pew PPE EPO =e a Mots