eres eenes rs r attest
steretopreeres:
i,
‘
i
i
ree
poeta btare ts
eleienet ria re
=
MNT
ne
a
Seow
Bateson
tas =r _ ae
See feceres sain
‘3
tity
i
nay)
He
a
aes
SS
REPENS
paths
BT 1102 .L44 1857
Leitch, Alexander.
Christian errors infidel
argument ~
Digitized by the Internet Archive
in 2022 with funding from
Princeton Theological Seminary Library
httos://archive.org/details/christianerrorsi0Oleit
AiR
Pt taba |p
ay, ay} ati
} Hee
; By: Ay
Shear
(to Oe ee
mi SAT ol an
Pe ak Ov
eo! 3) CMR
or A i J: iM ld
a) 5 Pe We 1
LAY Or iN
pee EAS oh ea ,
* JAN 20 1911 4
Ht
ox, Be eee
ttf Ud Gs
SEVEN DIALOGUES,
by vi
A | e@xander os eit rat
SUGGESTED By
THE BURNETT TREATISES, THE EVANGELICAL ALLIANCE
PRIZE ESSAY, AND OTHER APOLOGETICS,
EDINBURGH: ANDREW ELLIOT, 15 PRINCES STREET.
LONDON: HAMILTON, ADAMS, & Co.
M.DCCC.LVII.
EDINBURGH :
PRINTED BY JOHN HUGHES,
3 THISTLE STREET.
CONTENTS.
PAGE
INTRODUCTION, cccsssssesessercseseeeneneseeeenensscsssnsessesesseserescanentaetes 9
SUMMARY OF THE ARGUMENT DEVELOPED IN THE
DIALOGUES, -...0c:sersccsecsssoescnsectnscccsdanorsensatsesesoseseanneneneseseseni 24
DIALOGUE I.
TRUTH AND ERROR, .....ccsccsccssssresseeceeseseeneseseesaeseesseasenenenenencnens 53
DIALOGUE It.
KNOWLEDGE AND BELIEF, .....::scscssssssssessesseeseeserssetenessssnsseneas 98
DIALOGUE II.
BELIEF AND RESPONSIBILITY, .......ccscsscscessescsssssenssensessosonnes 143
DIALOGUE IV.
MYSTERY AND CONTRADICTION, .......cscscscsecssesesssssssssesseeeees 193
DIALOGUE V.
PRACTICAL AND SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGES,......cecsees 231
DIALOGUE VI.
CERTAINTY AND PROBABILITY, .......ccccccsesececeeeceseessteneeeneness 280
DIALOGUE VII.
THE STANDARD OF MORALITY, .0...cccecsescsesesecsseeeseseseeeenes 298
CONCLUSION.
REASON AND FAITH: THEIR CLAIMS WITHOUT CON-
BTL OT icon cesscastaas asta eno seeks es persone Saeed 331
oy
oF
PS tas | Sit a
INTRODUCTION.
Ir would appear as if Christianized men were too
supine and careless to purge themselves from error,
through the sole stimulus of ardent love for pure truth.
Hence in the Providence of the Almighty an external
irritant is produced, which shall so act upon the lethargy
of the Christian body as to enable it to throw off its
diseases and corruptions. In the whole history of the
Christian community no power has ever risen up in con-
flict with her, so well calculated to sift her principles and
separate the precious from the vile, as infidelity in its
various forms. The attack of Unbelief on Christianity
will be continued ; and it will from time to time change
its form and augment its intensity, till Christians shall
by means of this process be cleansed from their impuri-
ties, and become one in Christ Jesus. Nor does it seem
as if there were any other means so suitable or efficacious
for accomplishing this desirable end.
Heathen idolatry has assailed Christianity with brute
force, but never contended with her in argument. Per-
secution with its fires has given the due temper of intense
A
10 INTRODUCTION.
hardness to the Christian cause ; another process is re-
quired to produce fineness and sharpness of edge. The
claims of Jupiter, or Brahma, or Baal, to be the object
of human worship and obedience, cannot stand a moment’s
examination before those of Jehovah. The contest be-
tween these parties was never much of an intellectual
east. The avowed reason, far less the real reason, for
worshipping the gods of heathen mythology and for
oppressing even to imprisonment and death the followers _
of Christ, has never been an expression of intelligent
preference for the deities of the classics or the shastres
over the God of the Bible. All the evil that Paganism
can do to pure Christianity is to attempt to crush it by
violence; and all the good that can come out of this
attempt is the development of the virtues of patience
and endurance.
The same remarks apply to Mohammedanism. The
weapon of the false prophet, his Khaliphs, and the
Imams, is not argument or discussion, but war and the
sword. When Mohammedanism and Christianity, there-
fore, come into collision, the question at issue 1s one
simply and directly of life and death—of fealty or of
faithlessness to the King of kings and Lord of lords.
There is no call or necessity to examine the first prin-
ciples of truth, or to trace them in their varied ramifica-
tions.
Popery, so far as it is a persecuting power, stands in
the same relation to Christianity—the Christianity of
the Bible, as Mohammedanism or Pagan idolatry. Her
INTRODUCTION. 11
persecutions, being the severest and most protracted,
have evoked the grandest displays of the martyr spirit,
and shewn that the soul of man, when he loves and
possesses the truth, can endure any amount of anguish
as well as part with life itself, rather than relax his
grasp of the gospel of Christ. It is no doubt also a fact,
that the discussions between protestantism and popery
have done very much to elucidate and define the truth
on those topics which are controverted between the two
parties. And every corruption from which the cause of
Christianity has been relieved by the Reformation of
the sixteenth century, is undoubtedly a weapon wrested
from the hand of unbelief. But in relation to infidelity
there is a good deal of ground occupied in common both
by the adherents and opponents of papal Rome. Both
parties accept Christ Jesus as the Saviour of men, and
the Holy Scriptures as the word of God. The disputes
between them turn very much upon the import of what
both adopt as fundamental principles. They are, there-
fore, apparently but not really, agreed in these funda-
mental principles; and yet the controversy is seldom
fought at the point where it must be ultimately lost or
won. Asa purely intellectual contest between truth and
error, the battle between popery and protestantism has
too frequently been one of outworks and skirmishes,
rather than one in which a decided victory is gained. If
this conflict were differently managed—if either party
were more thoroughly intellectual and consistent than
they actually are, the strongholds of both would become
12 INTRODUCTION.
more prominent and better marked, the engagement
would speedily be found gathering itself around these
strongholds, and, the onset being severer, the’ struggle
would be shorter and more decisive. Neither party,
however, seems to feel itself called upon to adopt this
more searching and resolute mode of action. Conse-
quently, the controversy between romanists and protest-
ants, as actually conducted, fails to develope the finer
lineaments and more delicate features of Truth, — to
bring out the full proportions and spotless purity and
divine majesty of New Testament Christianity. This
work must be done; and other means must be used for
its accomplishment.
Will not the schisms and divisions that prevail among
protestant and evangelical Christians assist in the pro-
motion of this end? Undoubtedly they do assist, and
would assist much more effectually, if they were carried
on in a more reasonable and Christian-like manner. But
what has been said of the popish controversy generally
is to a great extent true of protestant disputes. Pro-
testants are not agreed in the grounds or reasons of
their protest against the Church of Rome, and their
internal schisms are the proof of this disagreement. If
they would set themselves to the business of mutual
reconciliation—if in a spirit of devout, humble, charitable
diligence, Christians would strive to be “ of one mind
and of one accord”—if when they oppose each other in
sentiment on a matter of importance, they felt that one
party must be wrong, and that by prayer and effort
INTRODUCTION. 13
they could and ought to “see eye to eye,’—if they
would sedulously probe the matter to the bottom, con-
scientiously suspend their judgment when evidence was
imperfect, form their opinion only in the clear sunshine
of truth, and hold it in all humbleness and forbearance,
then, indeed, would Christianity soon “ shake herself
from the dust,” and “ put on her beautiful garments.”
But since Christians have not done so, and do not seem
as yet to be much disposed to do so, there are other
means in reserve and at hand, that the work may not be
left undone. The attacks of infidelity will force Chris-
tians to examine their own principles and purge away
their errors—a labour which apparently they would
never spontaneously undertake.
Infidelity has nothing valuable to maintain, no truth
to propagate. Hence when she is thrown on the defen-
sive, or begins to propound some theory, she is sure to
be worsted. We now regard Unbelief simply as a power
of resistance—a resolute and active determination to
repudiate and expose every belief, that cannot be sub-
stantiated by sufficient and valid and consistent proof.
Christianity comes into direct collision with this power ;
for the religion of the Bible is essentially aggressive, as
it demands the belief and attachment of every man under
the heaviest penalties. If Christians might consistently
remain satisfied with holding the ground they already
occupy, they might often avoid the conflict. But pro-
fessing as they do a system of positive truth, which, they
maintain, is divine in its origin, and in its nature adapted
14 INTRODUCTION.
to mankind, and in its results ineffably blessed, they are
under the necessity of constantly acting upon the aggres-
sive as well as the defensive. When Christians have ex-
posed and refuted the various positive theories of infi-
delity, their work with that same infidelity is less than
half-done. You have overthrown our system, an un-
believer may be supposed to say, now your system must
be made good by evidence and argument. But in de-
fending and expounding their own system, Christian con-
tradicts Christian in most momentous and vital points.
Infidelity has thus a temporary triumph.
When. the Christianity of this age comes before the
world displaying her banners, proclaiming her message,
and demanding the allegiance of men, her forces are
evidently in disorder, and her arguments fragmentary
and disjointed. Paganism is too stupid and sensual and
besotted to take notice of this disorganization or turn it
to her own advantage. If a stray Christian were to
come in her path, and provoke her malice in any way,
she would, if she could, trample him in the dust, and
leave his cause just as it was. In the same manner,
Mohammedanism acts towards the religion of the Bible.
She is too deeply steeped in fatalism and stained with
profligacy to take much interest either in the creeds or
conflicts of Christendom ; although, like her elder sister
just noticed, her scimitar could draw without reluctance
giaour blood. Popery has a system of her own to pro-
mulgate and defend, and she is too busy or too proud to
interfere deeply with the disputes that arise among her
INTRODUCTION. 15
opponents. Christians themselves seem too lethargic to
undertake the task of self-reformation.
In this state of matters, infidelity confronts Christianity
in her onward progress, challenges every statement
which is made, sifts every evidence adduced, confronts
Christian with Christian and argument with argument,
and being equally regardless of character and consequen-
ces, carries on a desultory and remorseless warfare. In
the course of these attacks, Christians are brought to
feel, through sad experience and discomfiture, every
weakness that may be in their defences, every flaw that
may be in their weapons, every derangement in their or-
ganization, every deficiency in their supplies and every
quarrel in their camp. Under the stern teaching of
painful trial, they will be constrained to do what they
would gladly neglect ; they must begin to set their affairs
in better order. The shafts of infidelity will not cease
to fly, nor will they be innocuous—so long as the
panoply of the church is incomplete, or a fissure may be
seen in any portion of her armour. The scorn and con-
tempt of infidelity cannot be avoided or triumphantly re-
torted, so long as there is a rent in the garment of the
Church, or a stain upon her raiment.
Infidelity is thus, in the hands of God, the most
effectual, if not the only means, by which the Church of
Christ is to be purged of her more latent errors, as well
as reproved for her more obvious faults. It is but one
work, to expose and correct the mistakes and transgres-
sions of the Christian community, and to repel completely
16 INTRODUCTION.
and satisfactorily the assaults of the most inveterate
Unbelief.
The “ Christian errors” which the author has had in
view in writing the following pages, are not those more
gross and open offences against-Christian principles,
which are palpable to the least reflective, and which are
made good use of by infidel orators, although constantly
acknowledged and lamented by our apologetic writers.
Lhe obvious and very painful fact that to a large extent
the truths of the Bible are not reduced to practice by
many who profess to believe them, belongs properly to
the pulpit, and affords abundance of work to the faithful
pastor. This evil, however, is found among the office-
bearers as well as members of our churches; and the re-
Jaxation of Christian discipline which is the consequence,
gives to the unbeliever some considerable advantages in
his opposition to the gospel. This matter, though trite,
is one of the most vital importance, but it does not fall
within the the scope of our present design.
The author has felt a lively sympathy with those who
have experienced a degree of dissatisfaction after the peru-
sal of even the ablest treatises in defence of Christianity.
He who goes to these treatises for the confirmation of
his belief in the gospel is more or less disappointed. He
does find much to strengthen his Christian convictions;
but neither can he avoid the impression that a thick mist
envelops some of the most important points in the argu-
ment, and he toils through volume after volume, vainly
seeking for that clearness which he is unwilling to regard
INTRODUCTION. Lz
as an unwarranted expectation. When this confusion or
difficulty is freely confessed by the most skilful advocates
of Christianity, and is, at the same time, asserted to be
unavoidable and inexplicable, whatever others may have
felt, the writer is free to say, that this assertion has
appeared to him only to make “ confusion worse con-
founded.” His mind would indeed have been shaken,
and his Christian faith hopelessly overthrown, if he had
not been able to fall back upon the persuasion, that Chris-
tianity, as embodying the Truth, must be herself unen-
cumbered with that confusion and those contradictions,
and that they belong only to the present views and argu-
ments of her friends and defenders.
Since the writer has been led in the course of his stu-
dies to flatter himself that he sees a way through some
of this confusion, and a resolution of some contradictions,
which weaken the Christian defence, by putting weapons
into the hands of the enemy, he feels it to be a duty to
lay his thoughts before the public. The most prejudiced
cannot but admit it to be at least a possible thing, that
the Christian argument, as at present managed, may be
perplexed and enfeebled by the admission of one or more
erroneous principles, which, finding their development,
and bearing their fruits among the Christian people,
damage the cause of truth, and give to infidel objections
an importance far greater than they intrinsically possess.
It is obvious that to whatever extent this possibility may
be realised in our actual circumstances, to the same
extent the full and unanswerable overthrow of infidelity,
18 INTRODUCTION.
by the clear and impregnable vindication of the prin-
ciples of the Christian religion, will depend upon a
reformation in some of the sentiments of the Christian
community.
We have been led to the persuasion that “the Resto-
ration of Belief” depends very much upon its Rectifica-
tion, and that the “ conflicts of Faith and Reason” being
most unnatural,—being in fact both unreasonable and
irreligious, will only cease when “the claims of Faith
and Reason” are clearly apprehended. It seems to us
as if some needful work were yet to be done at “the
Bases of Belief.” When the excavations are more nearly
completed, and the foundations more carefully laid, the
living temple may rise more rapidly and more securely
to its full proportions; for let no one suppose that the
work which we have taken in hand is one of mere hair-
splitting refinement or wire-drawn distinctions. If we
cannot make good our positions, both by the precise and
perspicuous statement of principles, and also by making
manifest their weighty practical consequences, let our
attempt meet with its merited reward in contempt and for-
getfulness. |
We claim the reader’s indulgence in stating the exact
design which we would endeavour to accomplish. It is
not our purpose to write a defence of Christianity in
which we believe, nor an exposure of Infidelity with
which we have no sympathy. But there are some salient
points in the argument, not less important than difficult,
on which the controversy frequently hinges, while the
See se en ee eee
INTRODUCTION. 19
lax views of some Christian writers, and the mutual con-
tradictions of all on these very points, give to the skilful
opponent no trivial advantage. To these points we solicit
a little candid attention. However much we may have
grieved over the inconsistencies and confusion which we
have noticed in the best defences and expositions of
Christian truth, we should never have undertaken the
heartless task of uttering that grief, and unfolding its
cause, unless we had been led to see something like an
outlet from the perplexity, and what appeared to our-
selves at least a hopeful mode of terminating the contilict.
At the same time, the views which we venture to pro-
pound will not be regarded, we trust, by any reader as
dogmatic assertions on our part, but simply as suggestions
for the consideration of the thoughtful.
Being placed in these circumstances, more than one
method of procedure lay ready for selection.
In the first place, an appeal might be made directly to
the Word of God. What saith the Scripture, it may
be asked, upon those points in the infidel controversy on
- which Christians are individually confused and mutually
at variance? Has the Bible not been often defended
with weapons which it neither supplies nor sanctions‘
Are the advocates of Christianity never untrue to the
principles of Christianity herself? As a Christian, we
admit fully the validity of this reference. We shrink not —
from testing the positions which we may have to take up,
by their conformity or non-conformity with the testimony
of God; we rather court an exegetical appeal to the
20 INTRODUCTION.
statements of Holy Scripture. But this is not our pre-
Sent purpose.
In the second place, the questions at issue might be
taken up in a strictly philosophical style. The nature
and limits of our knowledge might be speculatively ex-
amined and discussed. A treatise on moral science might
be composed, and an attempt made to solve some of its
hard problems. The views which we have to propose
might be vindicated after this fashion; nor do we shun
their exposure to this ordeal. If any one will lift them
up for discussion to the speculative or metaphysical plat-
form, we are not unwilling to follow. But our present
design is to leave abstruse and metaphysical or philoso-
phical speculation in its own lofty sphere, far from the
usual haunts of busy men.
The Scriptural argument is waived, because it is irre-
levant as used against the infidel. It is vain to refer a
man to the affirmations of a book whose very authority
he is disputing. And we are unwilling to abandon our
two-fold design of inflicting a severer wound on Infidelity
by the same process that will promote the union and ~
spiritual prosperity of the Church. Both ends will be
to some extent gained, if we succeed in relieving the
Christian argument of any of its inconsistencies and con-
tradictions. The strictly speculative mode of treating
the subject is also adjourned for the present, though for
another reason.
78 DIALOGUE I.
more certain, not only in mathematics, but also in morals
and religion, than the existence of God and the divine
origin of Christianity.
Theologus.— When men express a judgment in matters
of opinion or of probability, a real contradiction is never
evolved. In matters of probability or of opinion, the
proposition is not known or affirmed to be either true or
erroneous. Hence men can agree to differ, while their
judgments are moving to and fro on this sliding scale of
mere opinion. ‘Their differences can be measured by
degrees of more and less probability. One man asserts
such and such an event is very likely ; another says it
is not likely at all; and there the business must rest till
the fact be developed. It is a totally diverse case, when
one affirms, and another denies, the reality of a fact, or
the truth of a principle. A man who holds his principles
as mere matter of opinion, is generally regarded as an
individual of no principle whatever. ‘The denial of one
principle implies the affirmation of a counter, or reverse,
principle. An undoubted contradiction is also manifested
in the affirmation and non-affirmation (that is, the refusal
to affirm), a fact which is of much importance to both
parties, and within the sphere of their knowledge.
Seneet. ye Origen. —The conclusions in natural
theology are not invalidated by the diverse
forms in which the argument is put.
Celsus. — The argument is not only diverse, but the
arguments of different advocates are contradictory.
Origen.—That is too sweeping an assertion.
TRUTH AND ERROR. 79
Celsus. — Let us look at the facts. One of your
friends says: ‘The argument for the Being of a God
is neither exclusively @ posteriori, nor exclusively & prior’,
but partakes of both. It is vain to assert an exclusive
claim for either argument, since they involve and aid each
other.”’! An exclusive claim has been often made for both
these arguments, and made by men whom you highly
honour; and now each claim is reprobated, and a good
argument is asserted to be found in the combination of the
two. Iam ata loss to understand how two invalid argu-
ments can form, or be regarded as forming, a sound one;
—unless it be somehow in this way, that a man must be
content, because he has two coats, although neither of
them fit his person.
Origen.—Surely you do not assert that Clarke would
deny the validity of Paley’s argument, or Paley deny
the validity of Clarke’s ?
Celsus.—This is not my opinion only. ‘“ We consider
that these writers (Brown, Brougham, and Chalmers),
while rightly repudiating the conclusiveness of a@ priori
reasoning in reference to our subject, have failed to set
forth, and even to apprehend with clearness and com-
prehensiveness, the subjective conditions, or, in our pre-
vious language, principles, which their a posteriori argu-
ment at once pre-supposes as its essential basis, and de-
mands in order to its complete and effective validity.” ”
A contradiction is surely affirmed here. And it becomes
all the more emphatic when taken in connection with the
' Infidelity, pp. 35, 27. 2 Theism,,p. 7.
80 DIALOGUE I.
following remarks, in which the essential unity of the
argument is asserted. ‘We deem it unnecessary to
enter into any question as to the separate force and
value of this department of evidence (moral intuitive evi-
dence.) All such questions are, according to our view,
quite irrelevant. For the genuine apprehension of the
theistic evidence is not that of a series of separate and
independent proofs, but that of a great scheme of argu-
ment presenting itself under a variety of aspects.” !
Origen.—When such eminent and godly men thus dif-.
fer so seriously, one is almost tempted to conclude that on
such topics truth is not to be found by weak erring man.
Celsus.—Ha! that is exactly our conclusion; and it is
strongly confirmed by another of your distinguished
authors, who says :—‘ There is no more concurrence
among Christians respecting the foundations of natural
religion, than among the various systems of unbelief.” 2
He immediately adds :—“ Nothing is more certain to
retard the progress of truth, than to recommend it by
doubtful evidences, and inconsequent proofs.” In such
circumstances instead of talking of retarding the progress
of truth, would it not have been more to his purpose to
show its beginning ?
Origen.—But after all, the conclusions of natural theo-
logy are not invalidated by these contradictory arguments.
Celsus——At all events, on the shewing of your own
advocates truth is damaged. And it is always a suspicious
circumstance to find men agreeing to hold a conclusion,
' Theism, p. 251. * Christian Theism, v. 1, Beds
TRUTH AND ERROR. 81
while they cannot agree why they hold it ;—like travel-
lers, who during their journey are full of contention and
strife, at its termination suddenly and unexpectedly and
without apparent cause embracing each other as long-
tried faithful friends.
Religion not an 4 Origen.—We are on the wrong track,
affair oflogic- when we suppose that religion is an affair
of severe logic and hard argument.
Celsus.—Do you then abandon your favourite funda-
mental position, that your faith is reasonable ?
Origen.—No, not at all. ‘‘ Religious life is mainly of
an emotional character. That, in human nature, which
we have termed religiousness—that which capacitates man
for pleasurable communion with the Eternal Spirit—that
which craves, in order to its proportional development, a
communication of appropriate religious ideas—consists far
more largely of sensibility than of power. It is more
emphatically responsive to love than to light. Knowing
is less its characteristic exercise than feeling. Perfect
subjective religion is perfect oneness of will between man
and God—and the will, as everybody must admit, is less
influenced by the conclusions of the understanding than
by the affections of the heart. Not that religiousness has
no need of the intellectual faculties—for how but by their
aid can we become cognizant of God or of his will? But
such cognizance, although absolutely necessary to religious
life, is not the life itself.’
Celsus.—While it is admitted, as you have just done,
' Bases of Belief. By E. Miall, M.P. London, 1857. pp. 97, 98.
82 DIALOGUE I.
that cognizance, or knowledge of God and of his will lies
at the basis of religious life, and so long as the question
concerns the nature and validity of that knowledge, it is
vain to talk of the mere quantity or amount of sensibility
and feeling that may legitimately enter into religiousness.
Besides, if knowledge be “ absolutely necessary to reli-
gious life,” then it is plain that knowledge must be re-
garded as much, and not less, a characteristic exercise of
religiousness as feeling. To assert that religiousness is
independent of knowledge, is sheer mysticism. To admit
this dependence, or, in other words, the reasonableness
of faith, is to open up the questions which we have been
discussing. |
Theologus.—It is necessary to observe, on the state-
ment that “ the will is less influenced by the conclusions
of the understanding than by the affections of the heart,”
that the fact may be admitted as it is here stated, with-
out any advantage to the scheme that would sever reli-
gion from truth. In morals, what is never can prove
what should be. Will any one deny that the will ought
to be influenced as much at least by the conclusions of
the understanding as by the affections of the heart?
Hence any religion that is worthy of the name, and that
would command the assent of intelligent beings, must
clearly state the truth on which it is founded, and suc-
cessfully vindicate its validity. Tuill this is done, emotion
and feeling must be suspended; only, however, like
waters under restraint, to burst forth more freely in due
season,
TRUTH AND ERROR. 83
Origen. —But “ religious insight is not to be confounded
with intellectual processes.’
Celsus.—Will you have the goodness to explain what
you mean?
Origen.—< Men may be thoroughly competent to de-
clare to their fellow men what there is of God’s character,
of God’s intention, of God’s will, in any special embodi-
ment of them, without being necessarily beyond the reach
of correction or criticism in any of the modes of commu-
nication they may deem it expedient to adopt. The
stammering tongue does not destroy the worth of a kind
message. The heart’s love may be truly declared even
in broken metaphors. The spirit of a law may be lucidly
and impressively set forth, although, in doing it, a man
may illustrate his point by a mistaken allusion, or an
exploded fact. And the mind of the highest may be
unerringly interpreted for us by those whose figures of
speech are occasionally confused, and whose chains of
argument are not always logically conclusive.” ?
Celsus.—All this only amounts to the simple statement,
that a man may be right in one point, and wrong in an-
other. And how he can be right on any point, where
truth is concerned, without an intellectual process of
some sort or another, I am at a loss to perceive. In
religious insight or instinct there is an exercise of the
understanding, or there is none. If there is none, reli-
gion is undiluted enthusiasm. If there be an exercise of
the understanding, then there is an intellectual process,
1 Bases, p. 376, &c. eb A ps 379s
84 DIALOGUE I.
and the above distinction, for all practical purposes, falls
to the ground.
Origen.— The still, small voice of the Creator may be
heard within the soul, though formal proofs may be
unknown. Deeper than logic, and prior to it, is the
truth that God exists.””}
Celsus.—The truth which is deeper than logic, and prior
to it, is of course independent of it. Why, then, so much
bustle and labour to prove the existence of God?
Theologus.—That there is an unformal evidence, or, in
other words, practical proof, and that it is both valid and
sufficient, has not received the prominence which it
deserves.” The relegation or dismissal of religion from
the sphere of logic or of truth,—a shift which has been
so often resorted to by both parties,—can be regarded as
nothing better than a dexterous move to evade a diffi-
culty, or to escape the shame of confessing a failure.
Celsus._We have no objections whatever to the doc-
trine, per se, that religiousness is mainly a matter of sen-
sibility. As there is no reasoning about affairs of taste
and feeling, every man should be left quietly to indulge
the dispositions and propensities of his own peculiar con-
stitution. If Christians would only act consistently on
this principle, as we should do, if fanatics would let us
alone, the acrimony and anger and bitterness of religious
controversy would soon be buried in the grave of forget-
fulness.
Theologus.—There would be room in the same tomb
* Christian Theism, vol. i. pp. 14, 15. * See Dialogue 5.
TRUTH AND ERROR. 85
for Truth deceased. At the obsequies of Truth, the uni-
verse would go into everlasting mourning.
Origen.—It seems almost too much to
expect that the present conflict of senti-
ment on vital doctrines and important duties that prevails
in the Christian community should terminate.
Celsus.—It is more likely that Christianity will perish
under these very contradictions, when the human race
shall rise from the minority of superstition to the man-
hood of reason.
Christian Union.
Theologus.—There is no chance of mankind adopting
infidelity, at all events, till the race is in its dotage. But
it cannot be doubted that the union of the Christian
Church, as described in the New Testament, is an union
of sentiment and judgment, as well as of love and affec-
tion. This union may allow “ endless varieties of admi-
nistration, and local laws and customs widely differing
from each other,” only so long as no religious principle
or weighty obligation is therein implicated. Whatever
“ intractable diversities” there may be, they surely can-
not be supposed to involve, when Christian union is
realised, a contradiction on any prominent moral or reli-
gious topic.
Origen.—W hat are the means by which you expect to
witness the accomplishment of such a marvellous consum-
mation ?
Theologus.—Y ou do not doubt, that if an unbeliever in
the gospel, Pagan, Mohammedan, Jew, Infidel, or Papist,
were to seck the truth, that God would leave him help-
86 DIALOGUE I.
lessly entangled in damning error; so I believe, that if
Christians were to seek the truth, they would escape
from their scandalous contradictions and damaging errors.
If the world is ultimately to come to believe that Chris-
tianity is true, by giving it a devout and diligent atten-
tion, and the triumph can be effected in no other way, is
it extravagant to expect that by the use of the very same
means Christians shall come to know what Christianity
in its purity and integrity really is, and thus avoid every-
thing like collision in expounding its doctrines, and in
enforcing and obeying its precepts? And if a vigorous
and impartial examination, an honest search for truth,
may be reasonably expected and authoritatively de-
manded from the unbeliever, how much more from the
believer ?
Origen.—After all, the question still re-
turns, what is Truth?
Celsus.—Ay, that is the knot that has to be untied.
Theologus.—tf we treat Christianity and religion prac-
tically, as we treat any other subject practically, there
is no call to answer that question. An illiterate Christian
can give a reason for the hope that he entertains, without
the aid of metaphysics or science. If that reason is
Truth.
judged of, as reasons for acting in other matters are
judged of, it wili stand the test.
Origen.—Do you then decline to answer the ques-
tion?
Theologus.—No. But I take my main position on
practical ground, which shall hereafter be explained and
et ee ee ae
TRUTH AND ERROR. 87
vindicated at length. So far as the science or speculation
of the matter is concerned, I have only a hypothesis to
propose for consideration.
Celsus.—How, then, do you propose to define Truth ?
Theologus.—We have thought that the foundation of
a speculative argument might perhaps be laid thus: know-
ledge implies an object known, and an intelligent subject
knowing. Knowledge is thus the act of the intelligent
being, when knowing the object, and may always be
expressed in a proposition. Hence we would agree with
those who have represented Truth to be the harmony or
agreement of a proposition (or knowledge) with the object
known. Hrror, consequently, is the disagreement of
knowledge, or a proposition with its object. Thus we
obtain immediately the two kinds of knowledge formerly
noticed. Normal or true knowledge is the first of these,
in which the agent knows the object, and knows that he
knows it. The second, abnormal or erroneous knowledge,
is developed, when the agent does not know the object,
and thinks he does.
Origen.—One or two points have come up in the course
of this discussion, on which I should like to hear your
views somewhat more at length.
Theologus.—I myself have felt the desirableness of a
fuller exposition of my sentiments, but was unwilling to
interrupt the course of argument in which you were
engaged with our friend here.
Origen.—I cannot see how you get over the distinction
between mathematical and moral truth.
88 DIALOGUE I.
Alltruth specia- Zheologus.—Since truth is the agreement
PaPriGpe. of a proposition with the object to which
it refers, all truth is specifically one. No truth, therefore,
can with propriety be called contingent ; although this
mode of describing some truths is very old and very com-
mon. We may suppose a contingent eaistence to be an-
nihilated, but we cannot suppose any true proposition
respecting that existence to become untrue. The state-
ment that Napoleon died at St Helena is true, universally
and for ever; that it should ever cease to be true is in-
conceivable ; it is as unchangeably and everlastingly true
as any axiom in mathematics. |
Sir W. Hamilton not only takes substantially the same
view, but explains the philosophy of the case. “I may
here also observe,” he says, ‘ that though the primary
iruths of fact, and the primary truths of intelligence (the
contingent and necessary truths of Reid) form two very
distinct classes of the original beliefs or intuitions of con-
sciousness ; there appears no sufficient ground to regard
their sources as different, and therefore to be distinguished
by different names.” The reason which he assigns for
this representation is, that the distinction between these
two classes of truth is nothing more than “the distinction
between the data or deliverances of consciousness simply,
in themselves, as apprehended facts or actual manifesta-
tions ; and these deliverances considered as testimonies to
the truth of facts beyond their own phenomenal reality.” }
The matter may be represented to the mass of man-
* Sir W. Hamilton’s Edition of Reid’s Works, p.p. 748, 744.
TRUTH AND ERROR. 89
kind thus. Evidence on any point whatever, if valid and
sufficient in itself, is irresistible to the intelligent being
who gives it due attention. When due attention is with-
held, however sufficient and valid the evidence may be,
or to whatever subject it may relate, knowledge of the
truth is not attained. When a proposition is professedly
supported by evidence, the evidence is valid, or it is not.
If it be invalid, it is improper to call it evidence at all.
When a proposition is supported by valid evidence, this
evidence is sufficient, or it is not. When valid evidence
is sufficient, the proposition is declared to be true; when
insufficient, the proposition is declared to be probable.
This principle applies equally well to every kind of pro-
positions, however diverse the objects of the propositions
may be. In thus abandoning the distinction between
necessary and contingent truth, we also abandon the dis-
tinction between moral and demonstrative evidence,
especially as this distinction is used in the infidel contro-
versy.
The reason why there is more discrepancy of opinion
in morals than in mathematics, seems to be twofold.
1. Moral subjects have far more to do, especially at pre-
sent, with the region of probability than the exact
sciences; and hence there is more occasion and room for
diversity of sentiment in the former than in the latter.
2. But, chiefly, there are contradictions in morals when
there are none in mathematics, because there is a greater
number of rash and prejudiced judgments in the one
than in the other, which may be traced partly to the
F
90 DIALOGUE TI.-
fact, that there are stronger temptations in the one than
in the other, to pronounce a judgment without due atten- —
tion. The same amount of honest mental labour, which
is found to be necessary to master many a scientific prob-
Jem, would put an end to many a moral controversy.
It is not difficult to show that abnormal or erroneous
knowledge on any point whatever is not involuntary. If
asum in arithmetic be cast incorrectly, it must be be-
cause the mind of the calculator denied, in one part or
other of the process, that one and one are equal to two.
Since he has the means of attaining perfect certainty and
perfect accuracy together, if he shall affirm that the sum
is correctly reckoned, when it is not, is there not some-
thing wilful in this, and, if wilful, blameable? The same
remark applies to every department of science. Is a
man not deserving of some censure for saying or think-
ing of any proposition that it is true, before he has
given it proper attention, or before its evidence has been
seen by him to be valid and sufficient? If, therefore,
any one in olden times affirmed it to be an actual truth
that nature abhors a vacuum, did he do so altogether in-
voluntarily and inculpably ? Even those who affirmed
it to be true, had they duly reflected, must haye seen
and felt that it was somewhat misty in itself,—or, at all
events, that it was not supported by sufficient evidence.
Many may have held it as a hypothesis to be examined,
not as a conclusion to be trusted.
Hence, we infer, that on every question evidence
which is valid and sufficient is irresistible to him who
TRUTH AND ERROR. 91
gives it due consideration, and to him only, and that on
no matter whatever can a man innocently or sincerely
take truth for error, or error for truth. It thus appears
that all true knowledge is equally clear and certain.
Mathematical proof is frequently cumulative or compli-
cated, just as moral proof is. An indocile mind can
ward off both. If man’s welfare were made to depend
on the study of Euclid’s Elements, individuals would be
found to profess that they could not understand them,
though they could not, just because they would not.
Others would be found misrepresenting the application of
the principles contained in that book to cases in actual
life. And many, doubtless, while well acquainted with
the principles would set them at practical defiance. To
deny the validity of some of Euclid’s demonstrations
might be described as polite and reasonable when com-
pared with some of the gross and violent perversions that
have been practised upon the word of God.
Origen.—There is another topic that needs elucidation,
namely, what you have called the validity of the human
understanding.
The validity of Theologus.—To set this in a forcible and
oon. practical light, allow me to quote the
words of M. Cousin. His remarks, which we are about
to transcribe, will be regarded by many Christians as
offensive ; they seem to us to be substantially correct.
After hearing them it will be necessary for me to show,
how this philosopher’s principle may be turned against
infidelity and in favour of Christianity.
92 DIALOGUE TI.
“The Theological School, in order to defend religion
to better advantage, undertakes to destroy philosophy,
all philosophy, the good as well as the bad, and perhaps
the good still more than the bad. . . . . Here is
the well known argumentation of this school. Reason is
a faculty altogether personal. When therefore we
affirm anything in the name of reason, it is in the name
of our own reason that we affirm it; certainty in that
case has no other basis, no other criterion than our indi-
vidual sentiment; but this is absurd. Reason then
cannot give us genuine certainty. Now, reason once
proved to be impotent we must look for another autho-
rity. This authority is that of common sense opposed to
individual sentiment, common sense preserved by tradi-
tion, made visible by the church, and promulgated by the
Holy See. . . . . That no inconsistency may be
wanting, the Protestants have found it so admirable that
they have not hesitated to borrow it of Catholicism.
Open any of the Methodist publications; except in
ability, you would think that you were reading the Abbé
de la Mennais. The same principles, the same mode of
reasoning, the same hatred of reason and philosophy ; the
only difference is, that the word of God is substituted for
common sense, and the Holy Scriptures for the Church.
In every philosophy, they say, it is always a man who
speaks ; it is a single man who addresses himself to our
reason with his own; but we wish for no man between us
and truth ; we wish to surrender our minds to God him-
self and to his word. Assuredly our adversaries are
= ray) ‘
ae ee ee a ee ee ee
ee ee ee
va: Vos
ee ee ee Se A
a
OO ie eset Sete
a ee, ee ee. eh eS
TRUTH AND ERROR. 93
not difficult; but, I ask, who is to teach them that
word? Who will warrant them that it is the word of
God? What ground have they for believing it? Who
shall tell them that God has spoken? And by what sign
shall they know it? The former propose to us as proof
the researches of erudition and historical criticism; the
latter appeal to a sort of immediate illumination in the
reading of the Holy Scriptures. But it is not a little
strange to refer us to criticism through fear of philoso-
phy; to send us back to history in order to avoid the
intervention of men between truth and ourselves. As to
immediate illumination, the intervention of reason in that
is less evident, but quite as real.” }
Need I assure you that I have no sympathy with the
sneers or the sarcasm contained in this passage. The
subject scarcely admits of such treatment. But I have
felt it proper to introduce the passage for the purpose of
putting the matter vividly before the mind. I am con-
strained to acknowledge that not a few divines have been
found neutralising the distinction between truth and
error, or, which is virtually the same thing, abandoning
the veracity of reason, It is of the utmost importance
to notice how this argument of the philosopher may be
retorted against infidelity and ungodliness in some of
their subtlest forms.
Origen.—How is this to be done?
Lheologus.—-Philosophers, as a class of men, shrink
most sensitively from anything like an attempt to dis-
* Cabinet Library, vol. ix. pp. 34, 37.
94 DIALOGUE I.
criminate between religious truth and religious error.
They thus, inconsistently with their own principles, limit
the extent of the distinction between truth and error,
and so far as the business of religion 1s concerned deny
the validity of the understanding. We blame them, not
for not finding, but for not seeking truth in religion. If
philosophy be the pursuit of truth, of all truth, we
demand a reason why one department of truth is put
under a ban. This exclusion can be justified only on
one or other of these grounds: because there is no such
thing as religious truth; or because its discovery is so
difficult it is hopeless to try; or because when found it
would be next to worthless.
As to the first, philosophy herself cannot prove a ne-
gative. And in regard to the second, granting even,
which we do only for the sake of argument, that religi-
ous truth were so very hard to find as some represent or
misrepresent, the consciousness of this difficulty would
prove to the genuine philosopher only an additional
stimulus to prosecute his search and promulgate its re-
sults. As to the third, even supposing that religious
truth when found would scarcely repay the labour of
seeking it—a supposition which any man would blush to
avow—still it is directly at variance with the noble spirit
of science to keep aloof from any field of inquiry, simply
because it promises no immediate practical good to the
student. Truth for its own sake is the watchword of
philosophy. Why then have philosophers avoided the ~
domain of truth in religion, as sailors keep clear of a
TRUTH AND ERROR. 95
sunken rock? The fact is as undoubted, as the inferred
inconsistency is incontrovertible.
As the most skilful pilot will sometimes be at fault, so
philosophers do sometimes, either from constraint or com-
placency, take up a religious topic. They are occasion-
ally observed mourning over the moral desolations of
religious controversy. Alas! with too much reason.
Men professedly in pursuit of religious truth, instead of
a friendly rivalry, have waged the fiercest warfare with
each other, and that not only in an irreligious spirit, but
often too about irreligious trifles. The men on the
mount of calm contemplation, who see and lament the
miseries endured by the toiling masses in the plains be-
low, surely lie under a strong obligation to recall their
fellows from such vain and guilty contests by searching
for the great realities of religion, and endeavouring to
place them in a brilliant light, and pointing the ignorant
and erring and unhappy to their benignant effulgence !
Have philosophers done so, or made one worthy effort to
do so? By ignoring in religion the distinction between
truth and error, which they hold to be so important in
every thing else, they are convicted of self-inconsis-
tency. By refusing to help their fellow-men, or if they
could not help them, to sympathise with them in their
religious conflicts, they betray a sad lack of affection.
And by deliberately and systematically preferring to
pursue truth everywhere but in the religious sphere,
they have placed themselves in a position, for the occu-
pation of which they will have to render an account to
the God of Truth.
96 DIALOGUE I.
If an individual having the true knowledge of God
refuse to submit his will to the Supreme, this refusal,
inasmuch as his knowledge of God’s character in its more
immediate relations to himself is correct and sound, is
exceedingly flagrant and criminal. If, on the other
hand, an individual has lost the true knowledge of his
God, it shows that he has proceeded no little distance in
the downward path of guilt and error. And in neither
case, we feel more and more persuaded, can a man
actually throw off his allegiance to the Most High, with-
out setting up something or other in His place and before
Him. In most of our philosophical writers, even when
they are defending the existence of God and illustrating
His attributes, there is a gross ignorance or strange dis-
regard of the most vital and commanding distinction
which man can ever hope to comprehend,—the distinction
between the character of God as He is in his relations to
us, and that character misrepresented. There is also in
most of the current literature of the day of all sorts—for
religion has become a common topic of late—a similar
ignorance or disregard of a distinction which is the first
we should know and the last we should forget,—the dis-
tinction between the religion of the man whose will is in
subjection to the Divine will, and the religion of the man
whose will is not in subjection to that will, or, in other
words, between true religion and false religion. Even
Plutarch could write, I would rather have men say that
there is no Plutarch, than that Plutarch is wicked; so I
reckon it worse to think evil (erroneously) of God, than
to deny that God exists,
TRUTH AND ERROR. 97
Philosophy and Literature, to repel this charge, will
draw themselves up in a most dignified mien, and while
professing to pursue truth in the composure of unrufiled
seclusion, and to be desirous of having it elicited by the
healthy excitement of friendly debate, will protest against
the dishonour of soiling their hands or disarranging their
robes in the turmoil of heated controversy, and least of
all will they consent to be defiled with the mire, or ex-
posed to the perils, of religious strife. This plea is false
in fact, and it is futile in philosophy. It is in fact false,
for literary and philosophical controversies have neither
been few in number, nor wanting in a keen and rancorous
spirit. And admitting that religious contentions have
been still more numerous and more embittered, it is only
what might reasonably be expected on account of the
higher interests at stake. The plea is, moreover, worth-
less on philosophical principles; for it eviscerates the
distinction between truth and error of all meaning and
value. Better not to admit the distinction at all, than
having admitted it in one instance, deny it in another,
or, what is worse, depreciate its significance even to
nought, and that, too, in the most important of its appli-
cations. All argument, and all effort too, are forever at
an end, unless truth, yea all truth, be precious—so pre-
cious, that in the legitimate pursuit of it we may and
ought to put forth our utmost strength, and in defence of
it when found incur the utmost hazard.
DIALOGUE II.
KNOWLEDGE AND BELIEF.
Celsus.—It has been the opinion of many Christians
that men should believe what they do not understand.
Origen.—It is not unreasonable to ask men to act in
religious matters on the same principle on which they
act in matters of common life. You believe in the union
of the soul and the body of a man, although you do not
comprehend it.
Celsus.—But our belief is not independent of our
understanding or reason in any instance, far less con-
Does Belict a. “Ary to it. Let me put the question in
Ee eretigzon this form: May our belief in any case be
pe considered legitimate, when it is not found-
ed upon knowledge ?
Origen.—* The truth is, that both Reason and Faith
are coeval with the nature of man, and were designed to
dwell in his heart together. They are, and ever were,
and, in such creatures as ourselves, must be, reciprocally
complementary ; neither can exclude the other. It is as
impossible to exercise an acceptable faith without reason
for so exercising it,—that is, without exercising reason
KNOWLEDGE AND BELIEF. 99
while we exercise faith,—as it is to apprehend by our
reason, exclusive of faith, all the truths on which we are
daily compelled to act, whether in relation to this world
or the next.” !
Celsus.—I do not quite understand you. Do reason
and faith invariably act together, or not? If they do
not always accompany each other in the act of being
exercised, when do they accompany each other, and
when do they act separately and independently? If
they are constantly found to be reciprocally complemen-
tary, do they act contemporaneously, or if not, which of
them precedes the other? Does knowledge precede faith,
or does faith precede knowledge ?
Origen.—But this argumentation is based upon “ the
fundamental vice,” which “ consists in the application of
purely logical or inductive conceptions to moral truth,
while this truth in its very nature transcends the grasp
of logic. It makes itself good in the inner spiritual con-
sciousness, but it cannot be inductively seized and ac-
counted for. The attempt so to seize it necessarily ter-
minates in misapprehending it.” ?
Celsus. — Then, of course, there can be no such thing
as moral science. But, passing this, Christians them-
selves begin the attempt to discriminate between belief
and knowledge. Nay, you are forced to do so by your
own Bible. You cannot maintain that your Christian
1 Reason and Faith: their Claims and Conflicts. By Henry
Rogers. London. Fourth Edition. 1854. P. 1, 2.
? Theism, p. 342.
100 DIALOGUE Il.
faith is reasonable, without shewing that it is founded
upon knowledge, Is it so in every instance, or is it
not ?
Origen.—* If in the actual course of our education for
another state of existence we give an unchecked ascend-
ency to either reason or faith, we vitiate the whole pro-
Gess.”}
Celsus. — But in some instances at least you give, if
not an ascendency, at least a decided priority, to the
exercise of reason ; — in those cases, I mean, in which
you contend for the reasonableness of your belief. In
what instances may belief take ascendency or priority of
the exercise of reason or the understanding? If there
be such cases, we shall have not a reasonable belief, but
a believing, confiding, or implicit knowledge. Is there
such a thing as knowledge resting upon faith; while that
faith does not itself rest upon knowledge ?
Origen. — “ All knowledge must rest upon intuitions,
or self-evident truths, or upon faith in the veracity of
the faculties. Man enters upon the use of his reasoning
faculty, already furnished with the principles on which
all knowledge must be built. In his first experience,
reason and feeling unite and are inseparable from one
another.’’?
Celsus.—But even in this case the “ feeling ” is pecu-
liar and quite distinct from our common feelings :—what
the same author calls a “conscious feeling.”3 Of the
* Reason and Faith, p. 3.
* Christian Theism, vol. 1, p. 844. * Ib., vol. 2, p. 373.
= ee ee ee ee ee ea eS eee
KNOWLEDGE AND BELIEF. 101
most elementary or fundamental truth, is it not correct
to say, that we believe it, only inasmuch as we know it,
rather than, that we know it, because we believe it ?
Lheologus.—The conclusion, then, seems not unlikely
to be this, that knowledge invariably precedes belief.
Human mindde. 2/490 — But this conclusion leaves us
terminator of reti- without defence against the modern Ger-
oo man school, ‘‘ amid whose bewildering and
shifting speculations, one thing is especially observable,
namely, that the human mind is made the determinator
of religious truth, and that no weight is given to the ex-
ternal facts and evidences of revelation except in so far
as they harmonize with the inward sentiments and con-
ceptions.” }
Celsus.—You will at least go thus far, that a man can-
not receive on external testimony or evidence of any sort,
what contradicts his inward conceptions and sentiments.
Origen.—Granted ; for “faith and philosophy are not
enemies by nature.”
Celsus.—There are some of your friends
who admit or contend that the harmony
between a man’s inward sentiments and judgments on the
one hand, and the Bible on the other, is a most essential
and indispensable element of the evidence that proves the
Bible to be of divine origin. You must, therefore, either
abandon the internal evidences entirely and for ever, or
admit that in a valid and important sense the human
mind is the determinator of religious truth.
Internal evidences.
1 Infidelity, &c., p. 363.
102 DIALOGUE II.
Origen.—You cannot, however, go so far as to main-
tain, that “first principles must be settled on philosophi-
cal and dogmatic grounds, before the interpretation of
the Scriptures can take effect.” *
Celsus.—Then you do not agree with your friend who
says, “ Christianity is not a religion for the religious, but
a religion for man. I do not accept it because my tem-
perament so disposes me, and because it meets my indi-
vidual mood of mind, or my tastes. I accept it as it is
suited to that moral condition in respect of which there
is no difference of importance between me and the man I
may next encounter on my path.”? Well now, you must
either accept of Christianity thus, or accept of it without
knowing whether it be suited to your moral state or not.
If the knowledge of its adaptation to the common moral
condition of men be supposed necessary prior to its being
accepted, and as an essential element in the ground on
which it is accepted, this implies that a knowledge of the
moral state of man, as man, has been attained, before
interpreting or even receiving the Scriptures. The first
principles of ethics are thus settled independently of the
Bible; nay their settlement is indispensable to a belief in
the Bible ; and if they have not been settled on “ philo-
sophical and dogmatic grounds,” they have been loosely
and popularly assumed. But is there not an attempt
among Christians to settle the first principles of morals
on strictly philosophical grounds ?
| Infidelity, p. 365.
* The Restoration of Belief. Cambridge, 1855. _p. 325.
KNOWLEDGE AND BELIEF. 103
Theology andPhi- Origen.—Yes; there have been many
ssopby ar vanines. attempts, but not with much success. But,
then, you know, “ There might be a false philosophy in
our colleges, and yet a true theology might retain a
strong hold on the hearts of our people.”!
Celsus.—That is very convenient, truly. If the philo-
sophy and the theology relate to distinct matters and
questions, the remark is out of place. But if the philo-
sophy and the theology referred to relate to the same
matters, and be really inconsistent with each other, then
the people think differently from their religious teachers,
or the teachers themselves are false either to their phi-
losophical or their theological principles.
Origen.—-Do you concede that “the moral judgment
is often found to be limited ?
Mere ot Celsus.—It were most absurd to deny
pavement. that it is not limited. The sole question is,
what are its limits?
Origen.—* There is no infallible criterion of right and
wrong. The law is not always written in clear and intel-
ligible characters. Man is not, in fact, as God created
him: different tribes and individuals sink to different
depths of moral degeneracy.” 2
Celsus.—Well, then, do any sink so low as to be desti-
tute entirely of “ moral judgment?”
Origen.—Probably some do; but certainly not all.
Celsus.—Then those who do sink so low, as to be des-
titute of all moral judgment, and “who have forfeited
* Infidelity, p. 361. * Christian Theism, vol. ii. p. 224.
104 DIALOGUE II.
the right of being enumerated with the human race,’’'
cannot be held as responsible, and to preach the gospel
to them is, of course, a work of supererogation. Again,
if “the judgments and feelings of mankind, notwith-
standing the prevalence of vice, are all but unanimous in
favour of virtue,”? then, we must know what virtue is,
and consequently we have a criterion, if not an universal,
at least a limited, “criterion of right and wrong.”
Origen.—But that criterion is not infallible.
Celsus.—It is just as infallible, as the validity of the
understanding, or the veracity of reason, can make it.
Christians themselves say so—let me read from the same
book. “ We can often be sure of the distinction between
right and wrong, between good andevil. Conscience has
a natural preference for virtue and benevolence, and gives
ug some acquaintance with our duty to each other and
to God. We have also an experience of the needs and
aspirations of the soul. So far, then, as our moral know-
ledge extends, we are able to judge of the internal evi-
dences of Christianity ; and may, by the light of nature,
discover its superiority to systems of false religion.’’”
When this author says, there is no infallible criterion of
right and wrong, one feels curious to know what more is
needed, than “ to be sure of the distinction between right
and wrong.” If the evidence of Christianity rest upon
“moral knowledge,” attained “by the light of nature,”
that knowledge must be somewhat like infallible before
it can sustain, as you believe, such a weight.
1 Christian Theism, vol. ii. p. 73. 2 1b., p78) 7 Deas
KNOWLEDGE AND BELIEF. 105
Theologus.—The simplest way to bring the question to
an issue, is to ask for an example, in which a legitimate
faith is not based upon knowledge.
Origen.—Well, Columbus believed in the existence of
America, before he knew it.!
Praia Celsus.—Did he not believe in it, after
peawedse. he knew it? Was not his belief in it
after he knew it, very different from his belief in it before
he knew it? Is your belief in Christianity, like his
belief in it before he knew it—a guess, a conjecture /
But surely you do not pretend to say, that Columbus’
expectation, or belief, of finding a great western conti-
nent, was utterly baseless in his own mind. It did rest
upon patient and learned investigation, — upon know-
ledge.
ee. Origen.—But faith itself is a source of
ofknowledge- knowledge. You must believe in first
principles before you can acquire much knowledge ;
and our Christian faith leads us into much knowledge.
Celsus.—But our belief in first principles, as formerly
remarked, is not without a knowledge of these principles,
a knowledge that they are true. We could not believe
them, unless we knew their self-evident truth.
Theologus.— A similar remark is applicable to the
_ Christian’s faith. A Book or Person whom we know to
__ be worthy of our confidence may convey to us important
information, which we could not obtain elsewhere ;
but in this case our faith in the Person or book is based
‘See Reason and Faith, p. 22.
G
106 DIALOGUE II.
upon our knowledge of his or its credibility. Correctly
speaking, therefore, it is not faith that is a source of
knowledge, but the object of that faith.
Reet! 0 Origen.—But is it not a fact, “ that all
ledge without the civilised nations of ancient or modern
eet: times, can be shewn to have deriwed
instruction, either from the Scriptures or from Scriptural
traditions? The people who have been found destitute
of such traditions aad beyond the reach of the Christian
revelation, are always reduced to a savage condition ;
and they who have possessed the traditions alone, with-
out the aids of more recent revelations, give evidences in
their history, or in their records, sometimes in very dis-
tinct terms, that their nation has passed through a course
not of development, but of degradation.” ?
Celsus.—In the first place, this is reasoning from what
man has done, to what man might do, and ought to do.
Now it is unfair to apply this principle to the heathen and
not to to the Christian world. If it be good in the one
case, it is good in the other. If the contradictions
and vices of the heathen prove that they could do no
more than they have done,—that the moral and religious
knowledge attainable by reason and nature independently
of the Christian Scriptures is nought, then the contradic-
tions and vices of Christendom prove that Christianity
can do no more than it has accomplished, and the moral
and religious knowledge attainable from the Bible is next
to nought. Hvangelical Christians are a small minority
1 Christian Theism, v. ii. p. 263.
KNOWLEDGE AND BELIEF. 107
amongst their brethren. In the second place, this
reasoning invalidates the internal evidences of Christi-
anity.
Theologus.—There seem to be two methods of argu-
ment open to the defenders of the Christian religion.
They may, in the first place, rest the whole weight of
the evidence upon méracles, as some do. If miracles
alone cannot sustain the whole weight, as others think,
they may, in the second place, associate with miracles
the judgments or intuitions, or whatever other name they
receive, of man’s moral nature. But if man’s moral
nature in any of its developments is to be brought into
_ court to prove the divine origin of Christianity, it must
be such developments as are independent of Christian
influences. Whoever asserts that all our moral know-
ledge is derived from the Scriptures, necessarily excludes
that moral knowledge as evidence in favour of Chris-
tianity.
Origen —We firmly believe that “ truth must lie be-
neath all the monstrous systems of Pagan theology.” }
Celsus.—Very good; but if all the truth that lies
beneath the systems of Paganism be derived, directly or
indirectly, from the Christian Scriptures, that truth can-
not be fairly adduced in attestation of the Bible. The
above reasoning, moreover, invalidates the whole argu-
ment of Natural Theology. For if all our instruction, all
that we possess beyond those who are ina savage con-
* Christian Theism, v. ii. p. 315.
108 DIALOGUE II.
dition, be derived from the Bible, our laboured treatises
on Theism are so much waste paper.
Origen.—“ There is a revelation of God in man and
nature, yet it has not been interpreted without super-
natural aid.” !
Celsus.—If that revelation could not be interpreted
without supernatural aid, then, while it remains alone, it
cannot be regarded as a revelation at all. Besides, if
the Christian Scriptures be necessary to interpret God’s
revelation of Himself in man and in nature, this revela-
tion can give no independent or valid testimony in favour
of the Christian Scriptures.
Theologus.—It is scarcely correct to say, that, even
with supernatural aid, this revelation has been inter-
preted ; for we have already seen that Natural Theology,
as at present expounded, is full of contradictions. If it -
be an obvious inconsistency in the unbelievers “ to receive
from Jesus Christ the highest truth they know of God,
and then reject the God whom He reveals ;”? it is as
gross an inconsistency in the believer to appeal to man’s
moral nature, to his ethical knowledge and judgment, in
proof of the character of God, and in attestation of the
pure morals and divine origin of the Bible, and then,
when the occasion is different, to turn round and say,
that without the Bible man is only a savage, without any
moral knowledge, and utterly destitute of the means of
improvement.
* Christian Theism, v. ii. p. 167. 2 Ths px Qt.
——
KNOWLEDGE AND BELIEF, 109
Belief in what is | Origen.—Are we, then, to believe no-
evesemers- thing which we do not understand? Is
faith never above reason and beyond knowledge ?
Celsus.—If you were always satisfied with this demand,
we should have less difficulty in reasoning out the matter
with you. N othing will satisfy some Christians, but to
put out the eye of reason altogether.
Theologus.—To contend that religious faith is belief in
the truth, and therefore reasonable, and, at the same
time, admit or assume, tacitly or openly, that, in any
instance, it is independent of knowledge, or contrary to
the understanding, is inadmissible as a clear contra-
diction.
Origen.—But this is not answering the question.
Pheologus.—Well, the question which you propose,
and which involves a serious difficulty which has been
often felt, may be answered by attending to the fact that
there are two distinct kinds of knowledge.
Origen.—What new distinction is this, that is to work
such wonders ?
Theologus.—The distinction does not appear to be
either novel or obscure. It has not certainly been gene-
rally applied to the case in hand; but in itself it is an
old acquaintance to most people. |
Origen.—Ha! Railroads were not so much indebted to
a@ new principle, as the novel application of an old one.
Theologus.—A proposition or statement may be known
simply to be true, while it is not known how or why it is
true. Another proposition I may not only know to be
110 DIALOGUE II.
true, but I may also know how or why it is true. We
may know a fact without knowing its explanation. We
may know another fact, and not only itself, but its ex-
planation also. We know the size of the earth, and its
position in relation to the sun ; but we do not know why
it is so large, no larger and no smaller. We know how
far it is from the sun; but we do not know why it was
not placed nearer or further off. We know that water
rises in a pump to a certain height; and we also know a
reason why it rises exactly so high, neither more nor
less. Since we cannot know the reason or manner of a
fact, without knowing first the fact itself, the one of these
knowledges, the complex one, always presupposes and
implies the other, or the simple one. But the simple
one may be found without the complex. |
Origen.—How will this distinction help us?
Theologus.—We should never believe a statement till
we know that it is true, that it states a fact, or an un-
doubted principle. We must often believe statements,
because we know them to be true or to announce facts,
although we are entirely ignorant of the manner or mode
of the fact, and utterly incapable of understanding how
or why the principle which we believe is true.
Peis Origen.—Has faith, then, no difficulties
ores with which to contend, and over which to
achieve a triumph ?
Theologus.—What do you consider to be the difficul-
ties that lie in the path of belief ?
Origen.—“ The evidence is sufficient to justify our
———
KNOWLEDGE AND BELIEF. Ti
faith, but it is not irresistible. There are other facts
which seem to conflict with the doctrine. Darkness and
difficulties, which have been felt by the best men in
every age, beset us in this field of inquiry. But what is
the darkness to the light?” }
Celsus.—I always thought that light dispelled dark-
ness. Or after all are Christians still in a field where
light and darkness mingle,——in the twilight ?
Theologus.—If facts really conjlict with your belief, it
cannot be a very steady or satisfactory one. If facts
only seem to come into collision with your belief, while
there is actually no collision at all, I am at a loss to per-
ceive what difficulty or darkness there is in such a cir-
cumstance, except the difficulty of getting at the truth.
As to the evidence not being irresistible, that is saying
nothing. It only amounts to this, that man is a free
agent, and responsible.
Origen.—‘ Faith is a moral act, and, while resting on
a strong ground-work of proof, it must have some diffi-
culties over which to triumph. Origen (the Christian
Father whose name I unworthily bear), speaking of
the difficulties in the Bible revelation, and of those
in the revelation of nature, says: ‘ In both we see a
self-concealing, self-revealing God, who makes Himself
known only to those who earnestly seek Him; in both
are found stimulants to faith, and occasions for un-
belief?’ ”’ 2
Theologus.—So far well. But still there is no very
1 Infidelity, p. 328. 2 Tb. p. 329.
EW DIALOGUE II.
explicit statement of difficulties. How can what God
conceals be a difficulty worth naming to our cordially
receiving what He reveals of Himself ?
Origen.—But is it not very perplexing to faith to re-
concile the painful facts transpiring in the world—war,
oppression, slavery, sickness, and poverty, as well as
many statements in the Bible, with the Equity and
Benevolence of God?
Theologus.—I can understand how you feel these to
be trials to your intellect ; but how do they affect your —
faith, so far as you believe only what you are satisfied is
true? Or does your faith embrace statements which
you do not even know to be true ?
Origen.— What may seem a paradox in itself is in fact
a great principle applicable to this matter. “¢ When
there is no reason to doubt, there can be none to believe.
Faith ever stands between conflicting probabilities ; but
her position is (if we may use the metaphor) the centre
of gravity between them, and will be proportionally
nearer the greater mags.” !
Celsus.—If this were the universal opinion of Chris-
tians, we should not have so much trouble in overthrow-
ing Christianity ; as the position of this centre of gravity
is obviously one of unstable equilibrium. How differ-
ently the matter is put by another writer.—“ Whoever
charges himself with such a task as that of conveying to
the intelligence and reason of others a system or body of
truth—of whatever kind—must be understood to have
* Reason and Faith, p. 22.
ee
ih eo? pe
BGP ee
/
a Oe ee ld ae SL ee ee ee ae ee oe
KNOWLEDGE AND BELIEF. Pe
come upon his ground in some such manner as this: that
is to say—he professes to understand the subject of
which he is to treat; and those to whom he speaks must
believe that he does understand it, and that he is fa-
miliar with all parts of it, including its most difficult
problems. They must listen to him on the belief that
what he affirms to be true, he knows to be demonstrable ;
and they must believe too that he is prepared, at the
last, to meet and remove all reasonable objections. There
is nothing in the circle of philosophy, of criticism, of
history, or of physical science, that can fairly be set
forth and established, unless, formally or virtually, as
much as this is postulated on the one side, and is cheer-
fully allowed on the other.”! In this way, faith cer-
tainly does not “ stand between conflicting probabilities.”
Origen.—Are there no difficulties in the way of exer-
cising faith ? )
Theologus. — A reasonable objection to the truth of
what is believed is not properly a difficulty in the way of
exercising faith, but a prohibition against its exercise in
that particular case. An unreasonable objection should,
of course, go for nothing.
Pea tiotion: to Origen. — You expect, then, at least,
cee satisfaction to your intellect. I thought
no one but an infidel would dispute the wise remarks of
Dr Arnold. “ Here is the moral fault of unbelief—that
a man can bear to make so great a moral sacrifice, as is
implied in renouncing God. He makes the greatest
1 Restoration of Belief, p. 259, 260.
114 DIALOGUE II.
moral sacrifice to obtain partial satisfaction to his intel-
lect: A believer ensures the greatest moral perfection,
with partial satisfaction to his intellect also: entire satis-
faction to the intellect is, and can be, obtained by nei-
ther.”
Celsus. — The sacrificing of one part of our nature to
another is what we sedulously avoid ; because we believe
it to be wrong. To do so is the creed of certain Chris-
tians. Morals separate from, or independent of reason,
is only another name for prejudice and superstition.
Theologus.—To deny that man can obtain entire satis-
faction to his intellect, is ambiguous and dangerous. If
by “entire satisfaction” you mean a knowledge of all
things; that satisfaction is unreasonable and absurd.
But that man can and may obtain a proper, legitimate,
and, therefore, complete, satisfaction to his intellect, is
neither at variance with common sense nor Christianity.
And if there be not in this sense an entire satisfaction to
our understanding in believing the gospel of Christ as
true, we have little hope of escaping from the mists of
superstition, and of seeing the world converted to the
Lord Jesus.
Origen.—What then do you call a reasonable and
entire satisfaction to the intellect ?
Theologus.—We shall be able to obtain full and legiti-
mate satisfaction to the intellect, if we allow that the
intellect acts properly under these two conditions: First, —
that every man who duly seeks the truth on any point
1 Infidelity, p. 825.
KNOWLEDGE AND BELIEF. 115
shall not err on that point; and, secondly, that when we
know a statement or proposition to be true, we believe
it, although we do not know how or why it is true.
Origen. — According to this representation, faith has
no difficulties to struggle with whatever.
Theologus.—Plenty, my friend, plenty. Are there no
difficulties in seeking and finding the truth? Are there
no difficulties in acting consistently upon the truth when
found? It may not be precisely correct to say, that
faith has difficulties to master ; but the man who would
believe the truth and act upon this belief, has them in
formidable abundance. To suppose that doubt must
ever mingle with our faith itself, is not to try it, but to
_ strangle it.
Origen.—But what advantage is gained by your as-
sertion that faith ought to be invariably based upon what
you have called simple knowledge ?
ceed Dheplogusi= Wt you: once abandon this
position, or impair its integrity, you have
no defence against superstition, enthusiasm, or mysticism,
or whatever else it may be called.
Origen.—The transition from superstition to infidelity
has been often made; but you do not mean to plead that
this transition is allowable and legitimate, or that the
superstitions of the pious justify the unbelief of the un-
godly ? 7
Celsus.—If superstition be found in the statement of
Christian doctrine or of its evidences, the presence of that
superstition does not of itself indeed justify our infidelity,
116 DIALOGUE II.
but you must allow that it so far weakens and damages
your own cause.
Origen.—How would you describe superstition ?
Lheologus.—It cannot be better described than in
language suggested by our present conversation. Belief
in a proposition or statement which the believer does not
know to be true, or belief which. does not rest upon know-
ledge, is superstitious. So far as this principle is not
recognised distinctly and broadly, or so far as it is not
acted upon in the details of religious life, so far does
Christianity suffer at the hands of its friends.
Origen.—Y our definition or description of superstition
will Apply almost equally well to infidelity.
Theologus.—How so?
Origen.—Because, when any man denies one or more
of the truths of the Bible, and is on that account reckoned
an infidel, his denial implies a belief that such or such a
doctrine is not true, and we of course affirm that his
belief does not rest upon knowledge.
Theologus.—Your remark is well-founded, and shows
us that infidelity and superstition are so far the same,
that they both have their roots in self-deception, or, more
precisely, in mental dishonesty and insincerity. Their
developments, however, endlessly vary with the circum-
stances in which men are placed, and the peculiarities of
individual character. ,
Origen.—You formerly spoke of abnormal knowledge ;
—what difference is there between that, and belief with-
out knowledge ?
a
ney a a ee
KNOWLEDGE AND BELIEF. IT?
Theologus.—None. It appears to us that belief and
knowledge are correlative. What a man believes, he
knows; and what he knows, he believes. Normal know-
ledge is accompanied by a normal belief; and abnormal
knowledge by an abnormal belief. If, as we saw, a man
honestly and diligently seek to know the truth, he will
not err on that point to which his attention is thus
directed. Then his knowledge and belief will be nor-
mal. He will not only know and believe what is true,
but he will also be conscious and certain of knowing
and believing the truth. When, on the contrary,
an individual takes up an opinion loosely or carelessly,
or at second hand, if the opinion be false, he thinks
he knows, when he does not know. His knowledge
and belief are both abnormal. Even the light which
is in him is darkness.- This is the case to which refer-
ence is made above when we speak of belief not based upon
knowledge.
Origen.—But what do you say of the case in which a
man takes up an opinion carelessly or loosely or at second
hand, while yet the opinion is really and in itself true ?
You cannot then say that the individual thinks he knows
when he does not know.
Theologus.—Of course, not. The case, however, is
easily described. A proposition may be true in itself,
and a person may profess to believe and know it to be
true, while in fact he has never paid due attention to it,
or given it impartial consideration. This is an obvious
case of self-deception as really as the former ;—accepting,
118 DIALOGUE II.
or rather pretending to accept, as true, what we do not
know oh its own merits to be true.
Origen.—lIf superstition and infidelity be thus funda-
mentally the same, namely, abnormal knowledge and
belief in one form or another, is not the genuine disciple
of Christ free from superstition as he is from infidelity ?
Theologus.—A man may be a genuine disciple of the
Lord Jesus, without being immediately or absolutely
delivered from all erroneous knowledge. He may reject
some truth, or accept some error in religion, without for-
feiting salvation ;—on this principle, that a man may be
diligent and upright in seeking the truth on one ques-
tion, but not equally so in seeking it on another ques-
tion. One thing is needful, and if a man be conscientious
and vigilant on that point, he will be “a saint;” if on
that point he lack candour or assiduity, he may go off
either into the desert of unbelief, or the swamp of super-
stition.
Origen.—You once said that no man is wrong on every
topic, and now you affirm that no man is right on every
question. How can that be? You maintain that the
Christian is, or may be, wrong on some points; and you
have contended that no more can be said against the
infidel than that he is wrong only on some points, not on
all. Pray, what difference, then, is there between
them ?
Fesentialandnon. _eologus.—The consequences of being
essential truth. qn error on any topic depend upon the
value and importance of that topic. If a man lives and
le
KNOWLEDGE AND BELIEF. 119
dies in error on the main question between God and his
own soul, his error is fatal and irretrievable. If a person
is right on that question, which is to every one the first
and chief, he is not necessarily exempted from error on
other questions of secondary moment. While yet error
on any one question whatever cannot but be delete-
rious.
Origen.—You adopt, then, the distinction between
essential and non-essential truth. But how is this dis-
tinction to be reconciled with the eternal and immutable
antithesis between truth and error?
Theologus.—The expression, essential and non-essen-
tial truth, is loose, and apt to mislead. Every truth,
regarded in itself, is essential. But one truth may be
more important to a person in certain circumstances than
another. When an individual is labouring under a fatal
disease, the knowledge of an effectual remedy is of all
things else most precious to him. So to mankind as
guilty before God, the knowledge of the gospel, that is,
of pardon and salvation through a crucified Redeemer, is
beyond all else needful and important.
Origen.—- You deny, then, the salvability of the
heathen, or of men who are from their circumstances un-
avoidably ignorant of the gospel of Christ.
Theologus—By no means. For there is a double
ambiguity in the distinction between essential and non-
essential truth. Every truth, as was remarked, is in
itself equally essential; and moreover, it cannot be said
of any one truth, that a man will perish everlastingly
120 DIALOGUE II.
through ignorance of it, if his ignorance were in his con-
dition altogether unavoidable and necessary.
Origen.—What is the use, then, of sending the gospel
to the heathen, if they can be saved without it ?
Theologus.—No man can be saved but through the
blood of Christ. It is one thing to say, that salvation is
only through Christ, and quite another thing to affirm, |
that it is only through a knowledge of Christ. You
admit, I presume, that infants are saved by Christ with-
out their knowing Him. The cases in which there is a
possibility of salvation open to men ignorant of the gospel
are only those, in which ignorance is entirely unavoid-
able, so far as the personal efforts of the parties im-
mediately concerned extend. It can never be maintained
that a man shall be condemned for lack of knowledge,
which he had not the means of attaining.
As to the uses of sending missionaries to Pagan lands.
To send them is the command of the Lord Jesus; where
the gospel is unknown, heathen ignorance will be required
at the hands of indolent Christians ; and though the poor
pagan who gropes after God in the dark, “calling upon
the name of the Lord” (Rom. x. 18), shall be saved, no
sinner can obtain present peace with God but through a
knowledge of his crucified Saviour. This peace is of in-
estimable value fh itself, as well as the foundation, not
of ethical knowledge or responsibility, but of every ex-
cellency in moral or holy character.—There is surely
nothing to alarm you in the statement, that while the
objective ground of salvation remains for ever unchanged,
3
.
KNOWLEDGE AND BELIEF. 12}
the subjective conditions of salvation may vary, at least
in their developments with the varying circumstances of
men.
| Origen.—W hat truths, then, are essential, and which
are non-essential ?
Theologus. —They who hold the distinction may
answer your question. I have already said, that every
truth is in itself equally essential ; and if at any time one
truth be more needful or useful to one person than to
another, this must depend entirely upon the characters
and circumstances of the parties.
Origen.—Then you abandon the distinction between
essential and non-essential truths, as it is generally
understood.
Theologus.—How is it generally understood ?
Origen.—In some such way as this. There are some
truths which a man cannot neglect without endangering
his salvation, while there are others which he may safely
leave alone.
Lheologus.—It seems to me that there are no truths
whatever, which an individual ought to know and which
he might know, that he can with safety leave alone.
This is a doctrine which is often proclaimed ; but none is
more derogatory to truth, or dangerous to the church.
Of course, if you take up the case of any one individual,
it is most undoubtedly correct to say, that there are some
truths a knowledge of which is essential to him,—essen-
tial to his responsibility and essential to his salvation.
Will you assert that the amount of knowledge which is
H
i273 DIALOGUE II.
essential to one man,—an ignorant and unprivileged man,
is all that is expected or will be required of other men —
possessed of better advantages ?
Origen.—What, then, is essential to salvation ?
Theologus.—— Objectively, the atonement of Christ is
essential to every man’s salvation, and subjectively, it is
essential that a man earnestly and habitually strive to add
to his knowledge, and also to act up to the knowledge
which he has attained.
Origen.—Do you intend to assert that Christianity or
the true religion is a constant state of flux, and that the
terms of man’s acceptance with God is subject to ceaseless
change ?
Theologus.—Will you deny that man’s knowledge of
the true religion or Christianity has been in a constant
state of ebb and flow? Have not nations that once
knew it sunk into ignorance or error regarding it? Did
not Paul know more of it than Abraham, and Luther
than Jerome? The ground of pardon through the blood
of Christ alone is not altered or set aside, by supposing
that God demands more knowledge from a man of supe-
rior advantages than from one of inferior privilege, and
that too as involved in the very terms or condition of his
personal salvation.
Origen.—That is, what is essential truth to a man
educated among evangelical Christians, or the truth with-
out a knowledge and belief of which he cannot be saved,
is not in all its extent essential to the papist of Italy or
Spain; and what is essential to such a papist is not in its
KNOWLEDGE AND BELIEF, 123
whole compass essential to a person born and nurtured in
the midst of heathen idolatry.
Theologus.—Precisely so. And hence the truth a
knowledge of which may be essential in this age of
Christianity, is more than what was essential in the last.
As the human race advances in knowledge, collectively
or individually, the possible range of superstition becomes
in this way less and less, and the possible range of infi-
delity becomes wider and wider. Many of the supersti-
tions which in bygone ages have corrupted Christianity
are exploded for ever, and can never return to the light
of day. Christianity is thus from age to age presenting
a more extended front and a sharper outline, and her
open enemies are finding more numerous points of attack.
Origen.—I now perceive, also, how to explain the fact
that has been often witnessed of men rushing from the
frivolities of superstition to the blasphemies of infidelity,
or, vice versa, from the apathy of unbelief to the excesses
of enthusiasm.
Celsus.—It is time enough to talk in that vaunting
style, when you have purged yourselves of all supersti-
tious prejudices.
Origen.—When we have found a portion of the truth,
my friend, we may surely utter it. There is only one
way of course in which a man can be right—namely, to
* seek the truth as silver, and search for her as for
hid treasures,” and having found the truth to act upon
it. There seem to be, at the same time, these two great
trunk-roads of evil-doing, in one or other of which every
134 DIALOGUE II.
“ fool,” and every “ simple one” (Prov. i. 22), will be
found. The man who “ does not obey the truth, but
obeys unrighteousness,” has only this wretched alterna-
tive before him, to amuse and stupify his conscience either
by the mummeries of superstition or the sophisms of
infidelity. Nor is it difficult or uncommon when the
mind has proved the worthlessness of the one remedy to
make a desperate trial of the other.
Theologus.—You may also notice that both of these
high roads have many by-ways, which are constantly
crossing and re-crossing each other. A sensitive mind
when awakened to a perception of some superstitious
observance or opinion clinging to the Christian com-
munity in which he finds himself, is easily tempted to
reject with that superstition some fundamental truth.
Again, a strong mind when disgusted with the extrava-
gancies of enthusiasm prevailing around him, may heed-
lessly take refuge on the barren rock of Atheism,—and
when tired of his heartless sojourn there, may seek satis-
faction in mystic observances. And so on in many dif-
ferent ways. |
Origen.—< The proper and best defence of Christi-
anity is, that it be understood.” ;
Theologus.—Most clearly. Hence so long as anything
superstitious—any thing that is not “ true, or honour-
able, or just, or pure, or lovely, or of good report,” is
found attached to Christian modes of worship, or forms
of government, or authorised creeds, as well as to Chris-
tian conduct, Christianity herself is so far burlesqued or
SS ee a
KNOWLEDGE AND BELIEF. 125
defamed before the world, and so far also her defences
are impaired or removed.
Origen.—W hat, then, are some of the leading super-
stitions that have damaged the cause of Christ ?
Theologus.—The statement of those belonging to past
ages is the work of the ecclesiastical historian; the ex-
posure of those now prevalent is perhaps not the duty of
any one man. If Christians would feel the importance
of examining anew their respective positions, and would
humbly seek the truth on every controverted question,
scrupulously suspending their judgment till the clear
sunshine of truth beamed on their understanding, much,
very much would speedily be done to improve and in-
crease the church of Christ, and to bless the unbelieving
world.
Celsus.—Perhaps you will favour us with some of your
thoughts on the superstitions of the present day.
Theologus.—I should not like to do so, without, at the
same time, endeavouring to expose some of the more
latent forms of infidelity.
Origen.—Well, well, let us have both.
Theologus.—Let us, then, assume this as our funda-
mental position, that to be reasonable is to be religious,
and a man is religious only so far as he is reasonable.
It follows from this, or is involved in it, that sacred truth
and secular truth, though not identical, are specifically
the same. They differ, and yet they agree; they are
varieties of one species. This view may be disregarded,
and error introduced in two ways; either by denying
126 DIALOGUE II.
the specific agreement, or asserting the absolute identity,
of religious truth and other truth. In the former case,
these two varieties of truth will be placed in a hostile
attitude towards each other; in the latter, they will be
amalgamated; and in both cases serious injury will be
the result. Each of these errors, moreover, assumes two
distinct forms, according as the preference is given to the
one variety of truth over the other. When sacred and
secular truth are identified, one party will merge the
sacred in the secular, and become rationalistic or infidel ;
another party will merge the secular in the sacred, and
become superstitious. When the specific unity of sacred
and secular truth is denied, religion will sometimes be
found bleeding at the altar of rationalism, and reason
will sometimes be found bleeding at the altar of super-
stition.
Rationalisticanta. 0 ™— What then do you regard as
gonism betweenrea- some manifestations of the rationalistic
Wick ser antagonism between Science and Chris-
tianity ? |
Theologus.—To treat Christian or religious truth, as
if it did not, or could not, form one of the sciences, but
stood on lower ground, is evidently unphilosophical. For
the learned to be ignorant or neglectful of it, to an extent.
that they would be ashamed of in their treatment of any
other science, is to act inconsistently with their own prin-
ciples. An individual of any pretensions to learning
would blush to avow an entire ignorance of the leading
facts and general principles of any branch of knowledge.
KNOWLEDGE AND BELIEF. 127
Although every one has his own favourite pursuit, who
would consent to be always confined to it? True philo-
sophy, then, forbids that any one who has pretensions to
science, should remain unacquainted with true religion—
that is, Biblical Christianity.
The force of this statement is to a great extent felt
and acknowledged at the present time. There are few,
if any, intelligent men who have not had the claims of
the Christian Revelation forced upon their attention in
such a way, that they cannot continue to occupy a posi-
tion of neutrality. When the alternative of receiving or
rejecting the Christian Scriptures is seriously contem-
plated, the majority of minds tremble at the thought of
rejection; for a moment’s consideration is enough to
satisfy the reflecting man, that to renounce the Bible, is
to renounce not only all religion, but all science too.
Hence there are very few philosophers now, who do not
manifest towards the Bible respectful deference; and
there are comparatively few treatises or lectures of the
many that are making science popular, in which, as occa-
sion offers, some suitable allusion to the Bible does not
occur.
But is the treatment of the Bible, and of the God of
the Bible, consistent throughout? It is admitted to be
a canon of modern science, that no branch of knowledge
can with propriety or consistency be neglected by the
human mind. Philosophers have often felt themselves
under the necessity of contending for this principle, in
opposition to those who would disparage certain depart-
128 DIALOGUE II.
ments of study, under the plea that they are not import-
ant to the general cultivation and industrial advancement
of the human family. It is a puerile presumption to
attempt to affix a stigma to certain researches, and pro-
scribe them as “purely theoretical ’’—unworthy of
notice or investigation. Reason emphatically condemns
such a contracted notion, and experience has amply
evinced its vanity. The investigation which promises
least to-day, may perform most to-morrow. The artizan
and tradesman have sneered at as futile, or smiled at as
simply amusing, the abstruse studies of a Davy or a
Laplace, which, by and by, however, have issued in the
most astonishing and beneficial discoveries. Under a
precisely similar and equally erroneous notion, scientific
men have been found sneering or smiling at the Christian
student, as engaged in a pursuit hopeless, unprofitable,
and dull, while their own cherished principles could tell
them, that possibly from that very study the weightiest
and grandest results may be evolved. If it be unreason-
able, as it clearly is, to think of drawing a veil over any
portion of God’s works,—if each footstep of the Almighty
has, prima facie, an equal claim upon our earnest atten-
tion,—if His operations are all equally worthy of devout
examination, then the facts of the Bible demand as care-
ful a consideration at least as the facts of Geology, and
the page of inspiration as rational and reverential a con-
templation as the face of the firmament.
The human body is an object of science, on which
many thousands of hours and volumes of investigation
5 MA Pn ee eee ea
KNOWLEDGE AND BELIEF. 129
have been lavished. Its varities, its size, its colour, its
nutrition, its reproduction, all its organs and all their
uses, its diseases and its dissolution, have become the
themes of intellectual inquiry. May it, then, be affirmed
that its ultimate and eternal destiny is a matter with
which reason has little or nothing to do? It may be
said, that reason has no appropriate means by which
she may become acquainted with that matter. Is there
not a telescope, by the use of which that far distant
object, our body’s everlasting destiny, may be discovered
and examined? Are there not accurate and accessible
tables of computation, by a reference to which the future
events that await different bodies may be foretold? This
telescope is Divine Revelation; these tables are the laws
of God. Is it objected that these are not scientific instru-
ments? The answer is obvious and conclusive,—science
refuses no instrument whatever which discovers or authen-
ticates facts.
Nor is any fact removed from the field of science by
its remoteness in space, or by its distance in time, by the
minuteness of its object, or by the difficulty of its expla-
nation. Remoteness in space only fixes the philosopher’s
gaze more intently; distance in time only summons all
his energies to the task; minuteness of parts only tests
his untiring patience; difficulty of explanation only fires
his genius; while each of these stimulates to seek the
improvement of instruments and the development of
resources. Littleness waxes great under the microscopic
lens; distance is annihilated by the gigantic telescope ;
130 DIALOGUE II.
intricacy has well-nigh disappeared under the wand of
the infinitesimal calculus; and centuries look like hours
in the eye of the geologist. If the Bible were an instru-
ment of human invention or construction, and possessed
its present power of giving nearness to what is distant,
and visibility to what is unseen, and certainty to what is
doubtful, there is no tyro of any scientific school but
would labour to purchase and long to employ it. Which
is the greater folly, to decline the aid of a human inyen-
tion, or that of a Divine gift ?
But some will say, where is this fallacy manifested in
practical life? It pervades the more intelligent classes of
society. For. example, it seems to us to be clearly
involved in the very constitution of our Philosophical and
Mechanics’ Institutions. Their object is to instruct the
people in everything that is interesting, profitable, and
true. Variety is sedulously sought after in literature,
history, and sciences, so that everything may be intro-
duced which can either touch human feelings, or aug-
ment human enjoyments, or extend human prospects.
But one subject is silently, yet carefully and universally,
excluded, namely, religious truth, as embracing man’s
relations to his God, his present peace and his future
destiny. What is the reason of this exclusion? It can-
not with any force or propriety be maintained, that this
religious truth has nothing to do with a design to please
and profit the mass of the people. Is it because there is
a stronger and more obvious necessity for promoting
literature and science among the million, than true reli-
KNOWLEDGE AND BELIEF. 131
gion? Although there were, that would not justify an
absolute interdict being placed upon religious truth. Is
it because men cannot agree in their opinions upon reli-
gion, as they do upon other matters? This answer,
which perhaps would be very generally adopted, goes
upon the very assumption, whose fallacy we are endea-
vouring to expose, that, in fact, there is no such thing as
religious truth, or if there be men cannot find it—that
there is some antagonism or incompatibility between
sacred and secular truth, the sinister cause of which lies,
not in science, but in Christianity.
Let any one examine the constitution and proceedings
of the British Association for the advancement of science,
and consider whether or not they involve an unphiloso-
phical divorce between religious truth and other truth.
It is impossible not to perceive that all the laws and
doings of that great society are founded on the hypothesis,
that the page of the Bible and its bearings on human
character and conduct and destiny, do not belong to
science. If true knowledge, specially its diffusion among
mankind, be the object of that noble association, why
should it set aside one kind of true knowledge? The
assumption on which this procedure is founded may
indeed be regarded as so plain and incontrovertible as to
need neither statement nor explanation. To impugn it
will only provoke asmile in many. Nevertheless it may
in fact be one of the most profound and injurious fallacies
of the present day.
These suggestions will not appear so strange as they
th DIALOGUE II.
might otherwise do, if you endeavour to realise the follow-
ing train of thought. Philosophers have united with
poets in expatiating with delight, upon the benefits which
men in every age and clime have obtained by holding
communion with nature, as well as carefully unfolded the
pleasures and advantages to be derived from scientific
observation and discovery. Whether we linger in rich
meadows teeming with exuberant fruitfulness, or climb
the mountain brow to inhale the fresh free air of Heaven,
or wander on ocean’s shore to listen to the music of its
waves, everywhere the mind is impressed with a sense of
nature’s grandeur, or pleased with its loveliness, or charmed
with its variety. The contemplation of nature’s beauties
suggests to the happy mind many elevating thoughts,
while it aids in calming the troubles of a vexed and
wearied spirit, as well as soothing and healing the heart
which has been broken by affliction. The vigorous pur-
suit of scientific truth sends a glow of purest delight
through the mental framework, and strengthens and
develops the intellectual faculties, besides augmenting
indirectly by successful investigations the physical well-
being of mankind. Thoughtful men have always rejoiced
in extracting for themselves such blessings from the study
of nature, and in inviting others to seek like precious
solace where they themselves have found it. Literature
summons all her resources to recommend and disseminate
this rational and unalloyed enjoyment. Philosophy adds
her august sanction to a frequent participation in this
feast of the soul. The Bible withholds not approbation, :
KNOWLEDGE AND BELIEF. 138
but benignantly smiles upon all who partake freely of the
ambrosia at nature’s banquet.
But granting all this to be true, it is not only a legiti-
mate but necessary inquiry—Is this enjoyment strong
and deep enough to meet and remove the uneasiness for
which it is often prescribed? Is it rich and abundant
enough to satisfy our large desires? The negative
answer, which will be universally returned to this ques-
tion, indicates the existence of a painful phenomenon in
all human experience. Philosophy may not, surely,
ignore this fact. The learned men who will not give it a
place among their studies are obviously under the influ-
ence of prejudice or bigotry. How stands the case?
There is a fountain of sorrow in every human breast and
in every social circle, ever welling up its bitter waters.
To sweeten this fountain of wormwood, the only specific
that the prevailing philosophy can recommend is com-
munion with nature and the study of science. This
remedy, though not unattended with some good effects,
is undeniably powerless on the whole and insufficient.
If this philosophy then were consistent with her own
principles, would she not call loudly and incessantly for
the consideration of these ominous facts, namely, the
general prevalence in humanity of a virulent disease, and
the ineflicacy of the most potent remedies which are
resorted to in her schools? If this disease, which cannot
be concealed, cannot also be cured, then benevolence
would weep over the miseries of our race, and her hot-
test tears would be shed over the failure of the antidotes,
134 DIALOGUE II.
which human wisdom has devised to expel or neutralise
the poison of human grief.
Is there, then, another and unfailing antidote to be
found? To overlook this enquiry, or to treat it unwor-
thily, as has been done by almost every school in philo-
sophy, is a grave and fundamental error, even judging
philosophers on their own principles. If it be asserted
on anything like a plausible ground, that there is an
effectual remedy for the sorrows of the human heart, is
philosophy not bound in self-consistency to take up the
assertion, and give some deliverance as to its truth or its
falsehood ? When an individual, or a school, or an insti-
tution of any sort, professes to be philosophical, and does
in fact take up and discuss for the pleasure and profit of
men innumerable questions on every kind of subject, and
all the time is profoundly silent on this one point, the
omission, to say the least, is a glaring inconsistency. It
really seems to proceed upon the assumption, that there
is some deep and secret opposition between one sort of
truth and another. If it be indeed a fact, that there is
a remedy, and only one, which can heal radically and for
ever our aching hearts and dry our burning tears, the
self-styled philosophy that continues ignorant of this
precious and powerful balm, is more than half-blind; and
the philosophy that knows of this remedy, and yet pur-
posely or carelessly conceals its knowledge, — nay, that
does not proclaim its existence to the world, and teach
its celestial virtues, must be pronounced to be both de-
ceitful and cruel.
i
;
:
q
a
f
i
be
3
ie
:
yi
5
3
A
KNOWLEDGE AND BELIEF. L385
Origen.—These are the remarks of one who seems
desirous of digging about the deepest roots of infidelity.
Sone Celsus. — But you intimated that you
tagonism between had also some observations to make on the
tiie superstitious antagonism between one truth
and another.
Theologus.—There is undoubtedly a superstitious, as
well as a rationalistic, antagonism between reason and
religion. While some would exclude Christianity from
the pale of philosophy and science, and treat it under
that pretext unworthily, others as unwisely acquiescing
silently in the propriety of this exclusion, can cling to
the Bible and religion, only by cherishing a secret or
avowed dislike and suspicion of philosophy, or by making
religion, not so much a matter of the understanding and
the reason, as of the heart and the affections. For
example, it has been said of the Bible: ‘“ It appeals not
to our logical consciousness, but speaks at once to the
religious nature, or, as we more often term it, to the
heart.” It would be strange indeed if the Word of God
did not speak to our feelings, but it would be equally
sirange if it did not speak to the feelings through the
understanding. The Bible surely speaks to us as intelli-
gent beings, and its appeals are based upon rational
grounds. What may be meant by “logical conscious-
ness,” it 1s perhaps not very easy to determine. Man
has but one faculty of understanding to be employed on
different objects. That the Bible speaks to reason on
its practical side, no one will question; and it seems
136 DIALOGUE II.
equally plain that the Word of God ought to be made
an object of philosophical study as well as His works.
When a philosopher begins to patronize the Christian
religion in the style of the above quotation, granting it
a sort of special license, as if it were of too delicate a con-
stitution to be tested as everything else is tested, its
enlightened friends will protest against such treatment
as involving a real indignity.
There is a numerous class of theologians, who, in ex-
posing the depravity of man and exalting the claims of
the Bible, virtually undermine the authority of the hu-
man understanding on all moral and religious questions.
It is unnecessary to quote illustrations of this statement,
they are so abundant. ‘The infidel, fully aware of the
advantage to be derived from this error on the part of
his opponents, has made frequent and effective use of the
taunt: “ The Christian makes the Bible the judge of
reason.” It is painful to hear from the pulpit and the
press sentiments such as the following, uttered and
penned by men who stand high in the Christian world.
*“‘ Reason has often deceived us but Scripture cannot.”
“See what comes of reasoning instead of believing.”
The fallacy involved in such representations is easily
made apparent. Men have been misled by erroneous
interpretations of Scripture as well as by false arguments.
If it be said, erroneous interpretations are not Scripture ;
neither are false arguments reason. Apart from the use
of his reason, to understand what is fundamental and to
prove what is susceptible of proof, man cannot legiti-
ch Sia vee
ee ee OR ONT a ee a
KNOWLEDGE AND BELIEF, 137
mately believe a single proposition. Reason abused is
plainly the parent of many errors; reason rightly used
is the perfection of an intelligent being.
That this error is deeply-seated and widely spread in
the Christian community, is apparent in many ways.
Nothing is more common than to talk of speculative
philosophy as a cause of infidelity. Speculation, doubt-
less, has given occasion to the expression and advocacy
of atheistical and irreligious sentiments, and the abuse of
speculative inquiries has confirmed the prevalence of
loose and ungodly principles. But there never was a
case in which the cause was more clearly taken for the
effect. Infidelity is far more frequently the cause of a
false philosophy, than a false philosophy the cause of
infidelity. When, therefore, we are told again and again
by respectable authors, that philosophical speculation has
been co-extensive with civilization, and is not in itself to
be regarded as an evil, and are shortly afterwards in-
formed that it is also a cause of infidelity ; this incon-
sistency, which in certain circumstances might be con-
sidered as nothing more than a slip of the pen, seems in
the present case to be indicative of a general and inve-
terate prejudice.
In such ways as these, sacred and secular truth are
frequently found in unnatural opposition. Although it is
generally admitted in theory, that any clashing between
reason and religion is improper and injurious, yet prac-
tically and in detail, as we have seen, the claims of both
are by no means amicably or righteously adjusted. To
I
138 DIALOGUE II.
tell some Christians, that the study of philosophy em-
braces Christianity as it embraces other objects, would
excite their direst fears and provoke their hottest jeal-
ousy. To tell some philosophers, that their philosophy
is partial and defective, unless it make them humble,
self-denying, heavenly-minded disciples of Jesus, would
awaken their bitterest scorn. To tell some pious people,
that there is a science of religion, and that to study it
would make them better Christians, and to tell some
scientists that their science is inconsistent unless it be
crowned with evangelical piety, is to expose oneself to
a cross-fire from superstitious and secular bigotry. To
assert that Christianity has not a stronger foundation to
rest upon than any of the sciences, will seem to some a
profane attempt to shake the very pillars of religious -
faith. While, on the other hand, to insinuate that science
has not a more rational or more certain conclusion to
teach than such as these: “ If any man love the world,
the love of the Father is not in him,” “ The friendship
of the world is enmity with God,”—will appear to others
an enthuiastic attempt to drive reason from her throne.
Notwithstanding all the prejudices of unbelieving reason
and of unenlightened faith, the Bible is an object with
which reason must deal as it deals with everything else.
The word of God must be entered in the inventory of
the inductive sciences ; it must be examined and tested
by suitable instruments and methods, as the human mind
examines and tests all other things; and its solemn and
precious statements are to be received with the reverence
SE a en ne ae
KNOWLEDGE AND BELIEF. 139
demanded by a message from the Most High, because
the volume itself is first received with the confidence due
to the deductions of reason. While we thus trace the
stream of knowledge to its fountain-head, we find that
every doctrine of science, and every doctrine of religion,
is equally authoritative and equally reasonable.
Celsus.—You also spoke of the amalga-
Superstitious 5 ‘
amalgamation of Mation, as well as the antagonism, of sacred
sacred and se-
and secular truth, and of those who super-
cular truth.
stitzously merge the latter in the former.
Theologus.—In the days of medizeval darkness, which
have been called the stationary period of the inductive
sciences, the minds of meditative men were disposed to
regard the spheres of theology and of natural philo-
sophy as identical. Their knowledge of nature was very
imperfect, and their methods of investigation and rea-
soning were loose and inconclusive; hence it is not sur-
prising, that they fell into the error of supposing, that
all science is to be found in the word of God,—that the
_ Bible is not only true, but contains all truth,—that it
not only announces a message of mercy, but unfolds the
mystery of nature. The prevalent opinion was thus ex-
pressed by Scotus: true philosophy is true religion, and
true religion is true philosophy. The injurious influence
of this error was considerable. The ancient dogmas of
philosophy, which had remained unquestioned for many
centuries, were covered from assault under the egis of
divine authority ; while every discovery was branded as
a pestilent heresy. To doubt the teaching of Aristotle
140 DIALOGUE II.
was equivalent to disputing the inspiration of Paul, and
the popular language of the word of God was adduced,
to justify an anathema against the true theory of the
motion of the heavenly bodies. This error led by a sort
of reaction to the strange assertion, that what is philo-
sophically true may be theologically false.
A similar error is frequently met with in the present
day. There are certain matters, such as geology and
moral philosophy, which are common property to the
inspired volume and to the book of nature, or, in other
words, on which we have information both in the written,
and in the unwritten, revelation of God. Now it is the
practice of some minds to set aside the information which
we have from one of these sources, and crudely and
erroneously to generalise the information derived from
the other source. The Bible is thus misinterpreted, and
hastily pledged to views which it does not sanction.
Whenever an attempt is made, however, to examine and
digest the information of the unwritten revelation, and
to bring it into harmony with the statements of the
Word, immediately a ery of heresy and impiety is raised
in certain quarters, because old prejudices are assailed
and cherished errors exposed.
| Origen.—But is religious truth never
Spee ee merged into secular truth with an infidel
secular and Sa.
- ?
ered trath tendency af
Theologus.—Undoubtedly. Many who
laugh at their forefathers for resolving natural science
into Christianity, are rushing into the opposite extreme,
KNOWLEDGE AND BELIEF. 141
and resolving Christianity into natural science. Their
knowledge of the Bible is so meagre and shallow, that it
is not very wonderful to find them fancying that true reli-
gion is contained in the enlarged and accurate sciences
of our day,—that modern philosophy is the only success-
ful expounder of mysteries,—that it has so improved the
habits of society and increased social comfort, that man-
kind need no other rule of life,—that in the deductions
of reason, unaided by written revelation, are to be found
the essence and the cream of all theology. ‘These opi-
nions are openly avowed by a few who say, that science
is the providence of life. They form, however, the
cherished and guiding principle of many more, who would
perhaps blush to avow them.
To neglect or mystify the facts of nature, by a sum-
mary and unfair reference to the statements of Scripture,
was the folly of medizeval sophists, and is still a delusion
of many pious people; to neglect or nullify the state-
ments of Holy Scripture, by inordinate devotion to the
study of nature, is the heresy of modern philosophy.
Implicitly to receive antique philosophic dogmas, and
attach to them the authority of written revelation, is
the grievous mistake of many now as of the scholastic
doctors of old; implicitly to receive the lessons of re-
ligion inculeated in youth, and then to confound them
with, or to merge them in, the conclusions of modern
science, is the fatal error of many of our accomplished
savans. Numbers still are the disciples of the monks, in
disregarding or distorting nature, out of a professed de-
ference to the words of inspiration; many of our learned
B52 DIALOGUE II.
men are disregarding or distorting divine declarations,
out of a pretended deference to philosophy. The dream-
ing, drowsy ascetics of the past—and the race is far from
being extinct—flattered themselves that the Bible was the
only reservoir of science; the eager, active scientists of
the present are not unfrequently persuading themselves
that their discoveries are the most satisfactory interpre-
tation of the Bible,—or something better. Centuries
ago the monks would not study nature as they studied
the Bible, and they have still many followers; there are
thousands now who have never studied the Bible with
the zest, the patience, and the vigour, which they have
expended on some domain of nature.
Men may reach the same quagmire by different and
even opposite roads. We can suppose two men agreeing
professedly in the statement, that all organized beings
are animals. But it may turn out on examination that
the one allows those beings only who possess the power of
locomotion to be organized; while the other allows those
beings who are destitute of this power to be animals.
So by unduly magnifying the place and the claims of
Christianity, or by depreciating science, men may come
to believe that every truth is a part of religion; by which
they mean, that they cannot be pious and deyout with-
out being at the same time adepts in science. Again, by
erroneously magnifying the position and importance of
science, or by depreciating Christianity, men may come
likewise to believe that every truth is a part of religion ;
by which they mean, that the student of science cannot
but be an acceptable worshipper of God.
DIALOGUE IIL.
BELIEF AND RESPONSIBILITY.
Celsus.—The fundamental assertion of Christianity,
that man is to be saved by faith, bears an absurdity on
the face of it.
Origen.—How so?
Celsus.—Because our belief, as we have just seen, is
always, or ought always to be, based upon knowledge,
and our understanding is not under our control; for we
must judge of any matter just as it appears to us at the
time to be.
Origen.—Our reason is certainly not directly under
our control; but very little consideration will shew that
it is under our power, to some extent at least, indirectly.
We can examine a matter, or refuse to examine it, at our
pleasure. Besides, we may examine it in two very different
ways, with prejudice or without prejudice. Surely, then,
we are responsible for the manner in which we use our
intelligence; and, consequently, we are responsible for
our belief. ;
Celsus.—If this reasoning proves anything at all, it
proves that man is responsible for all his beliefs, for one
as well as for another.
144 DIALOGUE III.
Origen.—I cannot go the length of saying, that man is
responsible for all his beliefs.
Celsus.—Why not? How, then, do you distinguish
between those beliefs for which you are responsible, and
those for which you are not responsible ?
Origen.—* Our opinions, in so far as they are influ-
enced by our dispositions, our beliefs, in so far as they
are controlled by our inclination, are legitimate subjects
of responsibility.”
Celsus.—You cannot mention a single belief, that may
not at one time or another be controlled by our incli-
nation.
Origen.—Our belief in mathematical truth is not.
Celsus.—Many a youth has crossed the pons asino-
rum, because he was influenced by the ambition of excel-
ling, or the desire of obtaining a prize, who otherwise
would never have mastered the proposition referred to,
or intelligently believed its conclusion.
Origen.—* Inclination has nothing whatever to do in
believing that two and two make four, or that the three
angles of a triangle are equal to two right angles. A
man in his senses could not believe otherwise. But incli-
nation has much to do in receiving or rejecting moral
and religious truth.” ?
Celsus.—Indeed! Pray what has inclination to do
with believing that it is wrong to steal, or that it is right
for the child to honour his father and his mother? Can
men in their senses believe otherwise ?
" Infidelity, by Pearson, p. 269. *Th. p.269.
BELIEF AND RESPONSIBILITY. 145
Theologus.—Unless the distinction be made clearly
out between our responsible and irresponsible beliefs, the
assertion of such a distinction will undoubtedly favour
and promote that “ weakened sense of responsibility,”
that “ utter absence of anything like the religious obliga~
tion of belief,’ which are asserted! to be characteristics
of infidel “ indifferentism.”
Origen.—We effeetually expose that indifferentism by
maintaining that “ Reason and Scripture unite their tes-
timonies, in establishing the position, that responsibility
is in proportion to the means of information and the
weight and clearness of evidence.” °
Celsus.—-This criterion applies equally well to any one
belief as to any other. If a man is to be blamed for
neglecting or perverting evidence or information on one
question, why not on another question? You must, there-
fore, cease to hold us responsible for what you are pleased
to call our disbelief, till you hold yourselves responsible
for all your beliefs. We have reason to throw back
upon yourselves the taunt, that you have pointed against
others : “ the doctrine of responsibility, in its high import,
is either denied, or fluctuating and feeble.” *
Origen.—The truth for which we contend may be
stated in another form. ‘So far as false opinion arises
from the influences of the conduct upon the mind, it is
unquestionable that man must be responsible for it.’’*
Celsus.—Does conduct here include inclination, as
1 Infidelity, by Pearson, p. 253. 2 Tb. 276.
> Ib. p. 286. 4 Christian Theism, vol. ii. pp. 872, 373.
146 DIALOGUE III.
given in your former statement? In that statement, did
inclination include conduct? May we not complain of
looseness in the expression of your fundamental position?
But passing that, we are as far from a settlement of the
question as ever. Is every false opinion found to arise
from the influence of bad conduct on the mind? And if
not, how shall we distinguish those that arise in this
manner from those that do not so arise ¢
Origen.—This is metaphysical quibbling.
Celsus.—It is no such thing. It is a most momentous
practical question, at least in your estimation. You affirm
that [ am responsible for my belief. Your affirmation is
worthless, unless you maintain that you and I are respon-
sible for all our beliefs, or shew me by some plain mark,
for which of my beliefs I am responsible, and for which
of them I am not responsible.
Origen.—* Man cannot justly be punished for what is
not dependent upon the will, and it is true that the
reception of truth or error is seldom immediately depen-
dent upon it.”!
Celsus.—This is a good specimen of the vague misti-
ness, in which the author you quote indulges, and espe-
cially on some of the most momentous questions. If this
be his ultimatum on the question before us, nothing can
be more unsatisfactory. It is a mere truism to say that
“man cannot justly be punished for what is not depen-.
dent upon the will;” unless indeed it be at variance with
your doctrine of original sin. As to his other remark,
* Christian Theism, vol. ii. p. 373.
BELIEF AND RESPONSIBILITY. 147
nothing could be more beautifully indefinite, or palpably
false. It certainly implies, that the reception of truth or
error is sometimes immediately dependent upon the will;
—an assertion made by no other writer of any name.
The general import of the remark is, that we are res-
ponsible for some beliefs and not for others ;—a shallow
reiteration of this “ glorious uncertainty.”
Origen.—Stay now, I think I can answer your ques-
tion. That arduous responsibility which attaches to
tee ten man, . . - . is at once relieved, and
error. effectually relieved, by the maxim—the
key-stone of ethical truth—that only voluntary error
condemns us ;—that all we are really responsible for, is
a faithful, honest, patient investigation and weighing of
evidence, as far as our abilities and opportunities admit,
and a conscientious pursuit of what we honestly deem
truth, wherever it may lead us.’”!
Celsus.—In the first place, this does not meet my
demand. It amounts to this. I am responsible for
yoluntary errors, and not for involuntary errors; which
seems to come to no more than this tautology: [am res-
ponsible for the errors for which I am responsible. In
the second place, the statement is one quite to our liking.
If after ‘“‘a faithful, honest, patient investigation and
weighing of evidence,” I come to a conclusion, believing
it to be true, while, notwithstanding, it is really erroneous,
how can I be sure that in any case know the truth? In
asserting that there is such a thing as this involuntary
1 Reason and Faith, p. 22.
148 DIALOGUE III.
error, how do you know that you are not in an inyolun-
tary error in making the assertion? Error that is in-
voluntary is, of course, as sages have long affirmed, in-
vincible. For ought that you can tell, your belief in
Christianity may be an invincible and involuntary error.
Theologus.—The doctrine of involuntary and invincible
error undoubtedly implies, that a man may be in error
on any point whatever without any possibility of his
escaping from it, or of knowing that he is entangled in
it. To know that we are in an error, is in fact to be free
from that error. If this doctrine, then, be “the key-
stone of ethical truth,” the edifice will be nothing better
than “‘ the baseless fabric of a vision.”
aes Origen.—In maintaining, as you have
conraTety been doing, Mr Umpire, the validity of
the human understanding, and in now denying the
existence of involuntary error, what becomes of the doc-
trine of original sin and the depravity of man ?
Theologus.—In denying the validity of the human
understanding, you deny the responsibility of man,—you
represent his understanding not merely as darkened, but
as utterly destroyed. If you do away with man’s res-
ponsibility, you annihilate both original and actual sin.
Again, in maintaining the culpability of error in every
instance, we are driven by logical necessity to the doctrine
of original sin; whereas by admitting the common philo-
sophical dogma of invincible and involuntary error, we
must either affirm the blamelessness of error, or cast the
blame of it from the creature upon the Creator.
BELIEF AND RESPONSIBILITY. 149
Celsus. —We have always felt that Christians, in deny-
ing the veracity of reason or the trustworthiness of the
understanding, were fighting with us at an enormous dis-
advantage. The very weapon they wield breaks in their
grasp. Besides, our doctrine of Pantheism needs no better
defence, than the ancient and universal belief in involun-
tary and invincible error. In our estimation it zs “ the
key-stone of ethical truth;” that is, of all that you can
ever expect to get as ethical truth.
Origen.—You deny, then, the moral in-
ability of fallen man, as distinguished from
physical inability.
Moral inability.
Celsus.—Your assertion of this distinction is an awk-
ward attempt to save yourself from the pantheistic con-
clusion involved in your own principles. One of your
friends says, “ Nor does the necessitarian appear to have
any escape from a semi-pantheism, in the distinction be-
tween physical and moral necessity. It would be more
consistent with the facts of life, to speak of chains of im-
moral necessity.” *
Theologus.—H the moral necessity under which man
as a fallen creature is represented as lying, or his moral
inability, or whatever else it may be called, involve ir-
responsibility, man’s nature is destroyed. If this moral
inability involve blameworthiness, the doctrine of original
sin is conceded, including in it man’s responsibility for all
his beliefs. What is called moral inability has no meaning
that we can perceive, unless it imply irresponsibility on
1 See Infidelity, p. 266. ? Christian Theism, v. i. p. 197.
150 DIALOGUE III.
the one hand, or guilt onthe other. If it imply irresponsi-
bility, there is no retreat from the slough of pantheism.
And if it involve culpability, to call it inability or neces-
sity, or any such name, is a pure contradiction, and leads
to endless confusion.
Origen.—Granting that a man is responsible for all his
beliefs, so far as they are the result of his own personal
free agency, how can you maintain that we are responsible
for erroneous beliefs, which are the result of the free
agency of our forefathers ?
Celsus.—If you deny that you are held responsible for
your erroneous beliefs in which you are entangled in
consequence of the sins of your progenitors, pray what
do you mean by the famous doctrine of original sin and
human depravity ?
Origen.—But you cannot hold a man responsible in the
same degree, or to the same extent, for hereditary errors,
as for errors into which he has led himself ?
Celsus.—On your own principles you cannot deny his
responsibility for both sorts of error ; and the distinction
between greater and lesser sins is a sorry refuge for a
man who professes to believe in the Bible. Thus it ap-
pears that our creed, that we are not responsible for our
belief at all, is about as reasonable and far more consistent
than the Christian’s creed, that he is responsible for some,
and not for others, of his beliefs.
Theologus.—But if you maintain that you are in no
sense or degree responsible for your belief, you exclude
from the sphere of responsibility the most important
On Re en a Oe ee ee ee
BELIEF AND RESPONSIBILITY. 151
function of your nature, you eviscerate the distinction
between truth and error of all meaning, you take refuge
in a self-immolating scepticism, to reason with which is
utter folly. But what objections do you urge to the state-
ment, that man is responsible for all his beliefs ?
Celsus.—To admit this, and then think of the numer-
ous and serious errors of mankind, is more than enough
to make me wish that man had never existed.
The Spirit's infu. Ortiger.—Man does exist, and the prob-
Ence. lems involved in his existence must be dis-
cussed. Your views, Mr Umpire, are totally at variance
with the Christian doctrine of the influences of the Holy
Spirit.
Theologus. — The doctrines of the Spirit’s work and
man’s degeneracy have generally been regarded as cor-
relative, so that whatever views enhance the one, in the
same degree, enhance the other. And we have already
noticed how human depravity is virtually denied, by
refusing either the validity of the human understanding
or the responsibility of man for every one of his beliets.
Origen.—But if reason never deceive us, and if we by
our own strength can avoid or escape from every wrong
belief, what room is there for the gracious work of the
Divine Spirit ?
Theologus. — When we speak of “ our own strength,”
we do not mean, nor have we ever said, that it is our
own strength independent of Divine assistance. Nothing
has been advanced by us to exclude the necessity of that
Divine Agent aiding and guiding us in searching for the
152 DIALOGUE III.
truth, and strengthening us to act according to the
truth.
ae Cais Origen.—Do you mean to affirm, that it
believe. is possible for a man to know and believe
the truth, and yet not act upon it ?
Celsus. — If you grant me that a man always acts on
his belief,—always does in his conduct just as he believes
in his heart,—and that his belief 1s, we know not how
frequently, involuntary, I shall construct as nice a sys-
tem of Pantheism as any of the most popular projects of
the day.
Theologus.—W hat is sin? my friend.
Origen.—Sin is any want of conformity unto or trans-
gression of the law of God.
Theologus.—Very well. The transgressor of the law
knows and believes what the law is when he transgresses
it, or he does not. If he knows the law in transgressing
it, he acts contrary to his knowledge or belief. If he
does not know the law which he transgresses, he must
have been made in that condition, or he must have
brought himself into it. He could not have been made
in that condition. - Hence we are led to this conclusion,
that acting contrary to one’s knowledge or belief is direct
guilt, or presumptuous sin, and acting according to
almormal knowledge or erroneous belief is indirect guilt,
or a sin of ignorance.
Celsus.—If, then, amid an elaborate description of Infi-
delity in all its forms and causes, no express mention be
made of man’s acting contrary to his knowledge and
BELIEF AND RESPONSIBILITY. lias
belief, we have a tolerably good scheme of Pantheism
under a Christian guise. For if wickedness and irreli-
gion be nothing more than erroneous belief, and may
| always be resolved into it, and if erroneous belief be, we
know not when, involuntary and invincible, then it fol-
lows, that error and wickedness are the natural and
necessary developments of the Deity.
Theologus.—We are sorry to observe that this remark
applies to a book under the name of “ Infidelity,” to
which frequent reference has been made in this discus-
sion. Indeed we know of no book in defence of Chris-
tianity, in which it is maintained as the foundation of the
argument, that men may act contrary to their belief, and
in doing so incur guilt, and that all erroneous beliefs are
culpable, as the consequents of presumptuous sin. Unless
these principles be assumed, tacitly or avowedly, there
seems to us to be no escape from pantheism.
Origen.—But in your zeal to escape pantheism, do not
reject Christianity. The Bible teaches us the necessity
of the Holy Spirit’s work on the hearts of men, but there
can be no necessity for this work, if, as you affirm, the
validity of the human understanding be admitted, and the
ability of man to escape, or keep away, from all errone-
ous sentiments.
Theologus.—You affirm the culpability of the man
who does not believe in Christ, or who believes that Christ
is not his Saviour, and you acknowledge that it is through
the help of the Divine Spirit alone that any man‘believes
in the Saviour. Very well, then, if your assertion re-
K
154 DIALOGUE III.
garding one erroneous belief that it is culpable does not,
on your own admission, interfere with the Spirit’s
agency, how does the assertion that every erroneous
belief is culpable, interfere with the necessity of the
Spirit’s work to lead us into all truth ?
Origen.—* It is the doctrine of Holy Scripture, that
the deeds of men are acceptable to God, only when their
motives originate in a Divine influence” '—* the mind has
no power of virtuous action but through Divine influ-
ence.”?”
Theologus.—If by Divine influence you mean, the
influence of the Creator on the creature, by which we
live and move and have our being, then without this
influence men have no power of vicious action even, as
well as no power of virtuous action. If by Divine influ-
ence you mean that gracious influence which is the pur-
chase of Christ’s atonement, then you must mean what
have been called, the common, or the saving, influences
of the Spirit. If you mean the Spirit’s common opera-
tions, your statement is not true. If you mean the
saving operations of the Holy Spirit, your mode of ex-
pression is not very precise. Taken in any way, your
assertion is certainly not available in the present argu-
ment, unless you mean to state, that the grace of the
Spirit is always irresistible, that there is no such sin as
grieving and quenching the Divine Spirit, and that those
who are destitute of this influence are irresponsible and
guiltless.
* Christian Theism, vol. i. p. 198 2 Tb.p.263.
BELIEF AND RESPONSIBILITY. 155
Celsus. —It seems to me a self-evident truth, that
where there is no power of virtuous action, there can be
no power of vicious action. I am at a loss to perceive
the consistency of the author just quoted, when I com-
pare the sentiments of his already given with such as
those that follow: ‘“‘ What can be expected when moral
training is withheld, and moral power denied, under the
pernicious notion, that they can be of no use, till God’s
time shall come; to shed some extraordinary effusion of
Divine light within the heart, which shall overpower the
vicious affections, and constrain the finite will by Sove-
reign Grace?”?!_ How can “moral power ” be more ex-
pressly “denied,” than by the assertion that there is
“no power of virtuous action but through Divine influ-
ence! ”
Theologus.—The only way to steer clear of such con-
tradictions is to carry along with us the very important
principle, that the mode of the Divine agency in conver-
sion (and also in miracles, prophecy, and inspiration)
is altogether unknown to us, and consequently always in-
volves a mystery ; but that this agency leaves the mind
of man to act according to its own laws without interfer-
ence or disturbance, being simply something added or
given to the individual which he immediately assimilates.
“The supernatural ever bases itself on the natural.”
Celsus.—Christians in attempting to refute the various
forms of infidelity, as they say, tell us, “that responsi-
bility remains indestructible amid all objections from
1 Christian Theism, vol. ii. p. 394.
156 DIALOGUE III.
original temperament and external influences.” Now
they so represent the doctrine of original sin by making
it subversive of the veracity of reason, and the doctrine
of grace as it is called, by making it subversive of our
moral power, as to cause both of these, the one an origi-
nal temperament and the other an external influence, to
destroy our responsibility.
Theologus.—We saw that the doctrine of original sin
has no meaning, unless we receive both the validity of the
understanding and the culpability of every erroneous
belief. It may now be remarked, that if there be some
shew of reason in denying both of these positions in
regard to heathens and men destitute of the promise and
presence of the Holy Spirit, it appears to be utterly un-
tenable to deny them in regard to Christians. If it be
inadmissible to suppose an idolater so utterly degraded
and lost, that in an honest effort to distinguish between
truth and error, he cannot be sure but that he may be
wrong, how much less can this be supposed to be the
state of a man who is “ regenerated,” “created anew,”
“enlightened,” and “led” by the Spirit of God, the
Spirit of truth? If the erroneous beliefs entertained by
the savage and the cannibal must be considered culpable
and blameworthy, especially if we adhere to the tenet of
hereditary corruption and guilt, how can we hesitate about
the guilt of the erroneous beliefs held by Christians,
whose boast and privilege it is to possess the word of
God, which “is profitable for doctrine, for reproof, for
‘Infidelity, p. 278.
BELIEF AND RESPONSIBILITY. 157
correction, for instruction in righteousness ; that the man
of God may be perfect, thoroughly furnished unto all
good works?” The Spirit is given to help our infirmi-
ties, to rectify and restore our nature to its primitive in-
tegrity and beauty ; surely, then, even although the case
of the pagan were given up, the case of the Christian
might be different. If we do not know assuredly right
from wrong, can it be said that sanctification has begun ?
If our erroneous beliefs, all of them, are not to be
purged away, what does the sanctifying process consist
of? Is it a mere physical cleansing, or is it partial and
incomplete ?
Origen.—Do you then deny the sincerity
of the infidel? for we never thought of
going so far as this.
Sincerity.
Celsus.—When you admit our sincerity, it is done in
such a way as to be a very equivocal compliment.
Origen.—How so?
Celsus.—Because you admit it in form, and virtually
deny it.
Origen.—Can anything be more explicit than such a
statement as this: ‘As to what is written or spoken
ingenuously and sincerely, or as we say ‘ in good faith,’
with the avowed intention to loosen or subvert Religious
Belief, I will never call the author of such utterances my
enemy.” ! Hear the same author’s meaning which he
attaches to sincerity, when he speaks of “ our modern
sense of the stern obligation of religious sincerity ;” ? or,
1 Restoration of Belief, p. 9. 2 1b: pase
158 DIALOGUE III.
again, when he speaks of the “ marked simplicity, grave
sincerity, and quietness of tone,” in which “ the early
Christian writers” speak of Christ, their Lord. Else-
where the same writer says: “I shall impute no bad
motives to you as a cover to my chagrin in finding that
I do not bring you over to my side: I shall not tell you
that your resistance to my reasoning is nothing but an
immoral obduracy, springing from the corrupt wishes of
an unregenerate heart.”
Celsus.—But what value is to be placed on the import
of the word sincerity, when in the same volume we read
of “the sincere idealist,” 2 who is not unlikely to slide
off from the path of morality, of “ sincere gainsayers,” *
and of ‘sincere but unstable souls, wont to beguile them-
selves.” > In one place, indeed, he supposes himself to
be addressing “a reasonable and ingenuous opponent ;” °
and in another place, remarks: that ‘“ candour is sorely
tried in supposing that educated men are honest when
they put forth what is so frivolous, 50 captious, and so
nugatory, as that which they advance in behalf of their
disbelief. I converse with those who profess this disbe-
lief, and instead of rigid argumentation—serious in its
tone, and ingenuous—I am met by a style of reasoning
which is unanswerable, only because it is vague, misty,
evasive, and sentimental.” 7
Theologus.—It is obvious that the meaning of the
words sincere, ingenuous, and so forth, is by no means
‘ Restoration of Belief, p. 107. 7 Tb. p. 114. 5 Ib. p. 148.
1b. pias Abe psL63; ° Ib. p. 239. 7 Th. p. 340.
BELIEF AND RESPONSIBILITY. 159
fixed. To say the least, it is perplexing to find great
weight placed in the Christian argument upon the
sincerity of the martyrs, and to find the same qua-
lity of mind freely granted to the rejecters of Chris-
tianity.
Celsus.—When we are told that “no one who, in a
spirit of industry and honesty, would inform himself con-
cerning the ‘ Evidences of Christianity,’ the ‘ authenticity
and genuineness of the Gospels and Epistles,’ or any
kindred subjects, need be at a loss in finding books,
learnedly and conclusively written, where he may meet
with more than enough of proof and argument to satisfy
every seriously-minded and educated reader,” \—when
we are spoken of in this strain in one place, to suppose
in another place the case of an ingenuous opponent, or a
sincere unbeliever, seems to justify the charge of fanati-
cism and hypocrisy which has sometimes been brought
against Christians.
Theologqus.—Had we not better endeavour to settle
the meaning of sincerity ? |
Celsus.—A. writer of some eminence has said, that it
means one of two things. It may mean honesty and con-
sistency in expressing and maintaining our opinion; or
again, it may mean diligence and candour in forming our
opinion. To allow that we are sincere in the first sense
is a poor compliment; to allow that we are sincere in the
second sense is fatal to the exclusive claims of Chris-
tianity. We could multiply proofs to shew how we are
1 Restoration of Belief, p. 23; also 219, 257.
160 DIALOGUE III.
in name allowed to be sincere, while the reality is denied
to us.
Theologus.— The distinction which you have men-
tioned in the two meanings of the word sincere, and such
like words, is very clear and very important. The first
meaning, or guilelessness and simplicity in expressing
our views, can have little to do with the present discus-
sion. But it is a most vital question, can a man be sin-
cere, that is, thoroughly honest and laborious, (not in
holding, but) in adopting and forming an erroneous judg-
ment ?
Celsus.—Many of our friends, holding that Chris-
tianity is not true, cannot regard Christians as sincere in
embracing it. And many more of them, beholding so
many Christians not only insincere, as they think, in
embracing it, but also inconsistent in holding it, are
tempted to regard the whole as a delusion and a cheat.
Origen.—But you would never “ make sincerity or
earnestness the test of truth and moral greatness.” }
Sincerity the test Ce/sus.—In making this assertion, you
euth. virtually give up the position that he who
honestly and diligently seeks to know the truth respect-
ing Christianity will find it to be true, and you con-
tradict yourself when you trace infidelity, both specu-
lative and practical, in all its forms, and in each case “to
the same moral cause—the repugnance in human nature
to what 1s purely spiritual and divinely authoritative.” *
We lay no claim to the sincerity and earnestness, which
' Infidelity, p. 67. 2 Ib. p. 333.
BELIEF AND RESPONSIBILITY. 161
do not exclude a repugnance to what is spiritual and
divine. If that is the sincerity which you allow to us,
we do not regard it as a compliment, but as an insult.
And if others attribute that sincerity to Christians, what
right have you to complain?
Origen.—When we appeal to the since-
rity of the primitive Christians and mar-
tyrs, in proof of the truth of their testimony, it is to be
remembered, that “ the matter in relation to which their
evidence is adduced was one to be resolved, not by the
understanding, but by the senses.”
Martyrs.
Celsus.—In the first place, we observe in reply to this
statement, the senses without the aid of the understand-
ing can resolve no question; in the second place, it
implies that the senses do not deceive us, but that our
understanding may deceive us; and in the third place, it
implies that there can be no true martyrdom, unless in
relation to a matter which can be resolved solely by the
senses.
Origen.—Our position may be stated in another form.
We believe the facts recorded by the writers of the New
Testament, on account of the undoubted sincerity of
these writers, that is, *‘ because hostile criticism hath
hitherto failed in shaking their character, either in
respect of their conscientiousness—of their meaning to
tell the truth—or in respect of their competency—of
their having within reach the materials of truth, and
being qualified to form a correct judgment of it.”
Celsus.—It seems to me that if you controvert a man’s
162 DIALOGUE III.
opinion, or judgment, on any question whatever,—if you
affirm to be true, what he affirms to be false, or vice
‘ versa, it is sheer absurdity to suppose that both of you
are equally competent and conscientious, in so far, at
least, as that particular question is concerned. Do you
admit the conscientiousness and competency of the pan-
theist, so far as he is a pantheist?
Origen.—Why, no. For “ pantheism expresses the
astonishment of reason to see nature separate from God.
It is the speculation of the soul which ought to be one
with the Eternal, but is robbed of the Divine Treasure,
and cannot realise her loss,”’ '
Celsus.—But you are yourself a pantheist; unless you
mean what you have not very precisely expressed,
namely, that the soul is not robbed by another, but robs
herself of the Divine treasure, and will not, rather than
cannot, realise her loss. What, then, can you mean by
saying, that the author of ‘“ The vestiges of the Natural
History of Creation,” is “sincere” in “making a con-
stant and reverent profession of theism;”? or how can
you maintain, that Blanco White treated the question
between supernaturalism and rationalism with much
closeness of reasoning, and “ with perfect sincerity,”
while yet there is “a great mistake at the foundation of
his arguments.” 3
Lheologus.—It is plain that a man’s error on any point
must be traced directly to his want of competency or of
1 Christian Theism, vol. i. p. 204. TD. pe Fiz,
* Ib. vol. ii. p. 204; compare pp. 376, 378, 396, 414.
BELIEF AND RESPONSIBILITY. 163
conscientiousness in respect to that point. He who is in
error must be so, because he cannot, or because he will
not see it. To talk then of a “sincere mistake” is non-
sense.
Origen.—But do you deny that there are sincere
Roman Catholics, who may be saved, in spite of the
errors of their pernicious system ?
Theologus.—God forbid, that I should doom any man
to wrath, or affirm that no adherent of an apostate church
can be saved. I do not believe that there is such a thing
as “a sincere papist,” or a sincere errorist of any kind.
To examine a question with competency and conscientious-
ness, and yet call light darkness—it is impossible. But
a man may be sincere on one point, and be destitute of
that sincerity on another point. Anda sincere Christian,
though entangled among many of the errors of popery,
will be saved.
Origen.—But may we not speak of the grievous errors
held by an individual, and “ decline to speculate” “ from
what cause proceeding ” in his case? “I am no judge of
the heart, and do not wish to judge it.”'
~ Celsus.—But your friends often speculate about the
cause of infidelity, and proceed, I presume, upon the
principle, that when the cause is found it applies to indi-
vidual cases. Those again who in words decline the
speculation, carry it out in reality. The very author
you refer to, says, on the next page but one, “I knew,
indeed, that it was possible for a man hastily to adept and
1A Defence of the Eclipse of Faith, p. 7.
164 DIALOGUE III.
abandon any opinions, if he took but half of a seventh
of a tenth of a thirteenth of a survey of the evidence ; but
here I could not find that there was any survey of evi-
dence at all.” And yet weare to believe that he declines
to speculate as to the cause of a grievous error in any
individual case !-
Origen.—Well, well; I act on the principle of imputing
no ill motives,’ and even in the use of ridicule of leaving
motives untouched. 2
Celsus.—Of course, to complain of our “ acrimony and
petulance,” ? and “ presumptuous jargon”’* and so forth,
is not imputing ill motives!
Origen.—All this is carping at incidental expressions.
Celsus.—W ell, then, taking up the matter in its broad
outlines, how can any man who opposes the true religion
be sincere, if “ the evidence which substantiates any true
theory of religion must be, at least, tolerably appreciable
by every man who sincerely examines it.’””®
Origen.—But, then, everybody believes that “ the
genuine sceptic” is distinguished by “a love of doubt
itself,—a prejudice in favour of the ‘nothing true;’” &
and that “if there be such a thing as a bona fide atheist
—who is not also mad, argument with him, in any shape,
is a very hopeless sort of an affair.” 7
* A Defence of the Eclipse of Faith, p. 16. 4Th2 pe2%e
AUS PAE * Ib. p. 43; see also pp. 61, 62, 120, 133, 139.
5 Tb. p. 149, et alibi, 188, 228.
° Edinburgh Review, No. 193. Genius and Writings of Des-
cartes, p. 9. 7 Tb. p. 40.
BELIEF AND RESPONSIBILITY. 165
Celsus.—It is obvious, then, that if, as you say, the
true Christian is distinguished from the formalist by his
sincere love of truth, and the genuine sceptic by his sincere
love of doubt, and the bona fide atheist by his sincere
madness, the ordinary unbeliever cannot be sincere in
any sense.
Theologus.—But has no case been alleged, in which
an individual is in error, neither through incompetency
nor unconscientiousness ?
Origen.—I have just laid my hands on one. ‘“ The
predisposition to find everywhere the germs of the yet
future sensational schools in Locke as their fountain head,
often leads M. Cousin, as we cannot but think, into ex-
treme injustice to our great countryman. This we are
far from attributing to any unworthy spirit of deprecia-
tion, for M. Cousin often gives frank expression to his
admiration of Locke’s sagacity and genuis. As little can
we impute it to ignorance, for he has evidently studied
the great work of Locke diligently, and cites him pro-
fusely.”’ !
Oelsus.—Ah, well; how is this extreme injustice to be
accounted for, if it can be traced neither to ignorance nor
to an unworthy spirit? Does not such an opinion savour
of Pantheism ?
Origen.—This is the way in which it is accounted for :
1 Edinburgh Review, No. 202. Locke’s Character and Philo-
sophy, p. 411. See A Defence, &c., pp. 233, 234, where the
author approves of the two articles in the Edinburgh Review from
which we quote.
166 DIALOGUE III.
“ we can attribute it only to what is but too apt to adhere
to the critic and historian of philosophy—the spirit of
system. Having laid it down that the roots of the sensa-
tional schools were to be found in Locke’s writings, he
unconsciously perverts or exaggerates whatsoever seems
to favour that hypothesis.” '
Celsus.— What a poor innocent a critic and historian
of philosophy is, according to this statement. The fact
that he is too apt to adhere to a spirit of system leads
him to commit extreme injustice, while all the time there
is no ignorance (not to say, no error), in his mind on the
matter in hand, and no improper desire in his heart. We
are told that he perverts and exaggerates unconsciously.
The defence can only be complete by asserting, that in
“laying it down that the roots of the sensational schools
were to be found in Locke’s writings,” he did so uncon-
sciously, and that he was sincerely unconscious. Here,
then, we have a case of extreme injustice, of which no
one is guilty. If Pantheism consist in the destruction or
relaxation of responsibility, as you affirm, what is this?
Theologus.—If there be a great deal of infidelity, in “a
want of stern fidelity to doctrines” which are “ theoreti-
cally admitted,”* there is plainly some need to recast
certain portions of the Christian argument, as well as to
reform certain parties in the Christian church.
Origen.—If men be, indeed, responsible for all their
beliefs, it will scarcely be true, that the great problem
1 Edinburgh Review, No. 202. Locke’s Character and Philo-
sophy, p. 411. * Infidelity, p. 251.
BELIEF AND RESPONSIBILITY. 167
of the Religious Obligation of Belief was solved for us by
the martyrs of the primitive church.
Theologus.—We cannot estimate too highly the advan-
tages that have flowed from their practical and powerful
exemplification of the principle; but it is a very different
thing to suppose that, till then, it was unknown, or that
now it is fully understood.
Origen. —You do not allow, therefore,
that the “great Law of Conscience” has
been “ defined,” and that it is it “ which places the modern
29]
Law of conscience.
mind in so great an advance beyond the ancient mind.
Theologus—To suppose that the Law of Conscience
was both originated and perfected by the early martyr
church, is to degrade the ancient world beneath the level
of responsibility, and to elevate modern and medieval
Christians higher than they deserve.
Celsus.—I have not been able, even yet, to find any
where a definition of the Law of Conscience.
Origen. —So you never heard the text of Scripture:
“ We ought to obey God rather than men.”
Oeclsus.—Have you never heard of its contradictory
interpretations or applications ¢
Origen.—It is plain beyond dispute, that no one ought
to be punished by the civil magistrate for his conscien-
tious opinions.
Celsus.—If it be the conscientious opinion of the civil
magistrate that he should punish some of his subjects
for holding an opinion which they regard as conscientious,
1 Restoration, p. 79.
168 DIALOGUE III.
what is to be done? Is the conscience of the magistrate
to overbear the conscience of his subject? Or is the con-
science of the subject to overmaster that of the throne ?
Or are the two consciences to be in everlasting conflict, or in
a state of equilibrium, the one exactly balancing the other ?
Origen.—Nothing can sustain uninjured such meta-
physical manipulation.
Theologus.—The questions are most relevant and fair.
They bring us to the same conclusion to which the other
parts of the discussion lead, namely, that a really con-
scientious Judgment will be a true one. If men plead
conscience, when conscience has not been consulted, they
act with insincerity and disingenuousness. If conscience
be really consulted, if men seek the truth sincerely, that
is, with honesty and diligence, they will not err. Two
honest consciences, therefore, cannot come into collision.
And the Law of Conscience is not liberty to think as we
choose, or to suspend the arm of the magistrate by the
plea of conscience, but liberty to think truly, to form our
judgments in accordance with truth. No conscience is
at liberty to believe error. No man can deliberately
adopt error without deceiving himself.
Origen.—lIs sincerity, then, a test of truth ?
Theologus.— Unquestionably.
Origen. — Is a man’s dying in attestation of his sin-
cerity in holding a certain opinion, sufficient evidence of
his sincerity ¢
Theologus.—Generally it will be so; but it cannot be
affirmed universally.
BELIEF AND RESPONSIBILITY. 169
Origen. — There may have been martyrs for a false
religion on that supposition.
Theologus. — The principles stated allow, we think,
the possibility of such an event. But when the cha-
racter of the martyr is properly defined, nothing can be
more erroneous or deleterious than the loose way of
speaking in which many indulge, allowing every reli-
gious system to have its martyrs. A martyr accurately
conceived of, is one who lays down his life rather than
renounce his belief, even while the option is before him
to renounce it and live. We are not aware of any well
authenticated case of such a sort of martyrdom, except
in connection with Christianity.
Origen. — Is such a martyrdom proof positive of the
truth of the martyr’s belief ?
Theologus. — It is a strong presumption. It is not
absolute proof, not because sincerity is not a test of
truth, but because even a voluntary submission to death
may occur through opinionativeness or pride.
é Origen. — What room can there be for
Charity. Cah
the exercise of charity, if we assume that
every man that is in error is insincere ?
Celsus. — What room is there for the exercise of
charity between your party and ours, if the following
statement, or such as it, be admitted. “In a manner
which is perfectly conspicuous, and which no man of
clear intellect can misunderstand, the religious contro-
versy of this passing time is bearing us forward toward
a single issue. The alternative, the only alternative now
L
170 DIALOGUE III.
in front of the cultured branches of the human family, is
this—Christianity or Atheism. One feels that this alter-
native, and nothing short of it, is near in front of us,
because, on the one side, those many ill-judged and crazy
schemes for effecting a compromise with infidelity, which
of late have been propounded by intelligent Christian
men, all carry upon them the indications of their origin
in faltering belief, in mistaken discretion, and in con-
fusedness of brain. We may be sure that no such slender
devices as these can have power to check that mighty
movement to which we are all of us committed, or can
save us from its issue. On the other side —the side of
Disbelief—the endeayours that are making by Theists to
pack and float a raft a-head of Niagara would be purely
matter of ridicule, if the consequences to these schemes
were not what they are.’’!
Theologus.—It seems to us that there is just as much
room for the exercise of charity between Christians, on
the supposition that we are responsible for each one of
our beliefs, as on the admission of such views as the fol-
lowing. “ This is that sifting of spirits—this is that fiery
trial which, with a peculiar intensity, is going on at this
time, and is putting to the severest proof the loyalty —
the religious allegiance, of many minds born and trained
within the pale of Christian influence. To each of us, in
a more or less pointed manner, the critical question
is now put, whether we will stand by Heaven — by
Truth —by Goodness; or will range ourselves with
* Restoration, pp. 248, 249.
BELIEF AND RESPONSIBILITY. Tid
primeval rebellion, and be compromised with those
whose quarrel with God may be older than the moun-
tains?” !
Religious intoler- | Origen. — It is perfectly true that we
os must “earnestly contend for the faith
which was once delivered unto the saints,” but this opi-
nion that every error implies guilt and insincerity will
open the floodgates of “religious intolerance,” which “is
the most odious and insufferable of all.”
Theologus.—When two parties contradict each other,
if each of them immediately concludes that his neighbour
is wrong, and insincere and guilty, and acts on this con-
clusion, charity would be seriously outraged. But if
each of them will suspect himself of error and insincerity,
and re-examine the point in dispute with greater care,
both truth and charity would be gainers.
Celsus. — What is religious intolerance but one man
telling another man, that he is wrong and insincere, and
that on the most vital question of all ?
Origen. —No, my friend; you are now confounding
religious intolerance with “an enlightened attachment to
the truth itself.”
Theologus.—W ell, do you not see, that attachment to
the truth itself, cannot be enlightened, unless it be an
attachment to the truth, as truth, the whole truth, and
nothing but the truth? If it be possible in one question
to discriminate between intolerance and zeal for truth,
why not in every question ?
1 Restoration, p. 370.
Le DIALOGUE III.
Origen. — Yes, but when every man begins to call
his crotchet true, and to treat as insincere all who
smile at him and it, we shall have old scenes renewed
in tenfold extravagance, and Christianity itself will be-
come “an inconceivably paltry, troublesome, intolerant
thing.”
Theologus.—Our principle sanctions no man in calling
his crotchet true. It is our principle alone that makes a
man guilty for elevating a whim into a doctrine or truth
to be defended even unto blood. Admitting the usual
maxim about involuntary error, there is no reasonable
means of guarding against the absurdity of men’s mag-
nifying mole-hills into mountains, and turning traditions
and fancies into commands of God. Truth being thus
sacrificed, charity is falsely inflated to conceal the wrong.
When once you look upon your neighbour as the hapless
victim of involuntary error, there is no room in your
bosom for that charity towards him which “ rejoiceth not
in iniquity, but rejoiceth in the truth ;? you must regard
him either with that bigotry which denies him, in one
form or another, the privileges of manhood, or with that
latitudinarianism which immolates truth at the shrine of
a pseudo-benevolence.
Celsus. — “I will be tolerant of everything else, but
every other man’s intolerance.”
Origen.—* The worst of it is, that this latitudinarian
charity is apt to degenerate into a curious sort of bigotry.
It is always vehement enough against any opinions that
imply that opinions are of any importance, or indeed
BELIEF AND RESPONSIBILITY. ITS
against any opinion eawcept the opinion that no opinions
are of any.”
Theologus.—All that I contend for is, that this senti-
ment be applied to every case to which it is fairly appli-
cable. Every truth is vastly important; wherever,
then, truth is involved and a conflict arises as to where
the truth is to be found, forbearance and kindness to each
other need not compromise ardour for the truth. Since
zeal for truth is only legitimate and consistent when
based upon the utmost diligence and candour in seeking
truth, the duty of charity itself will not be correctly
appreciated apart from this zeal. No one will profess to
care for a base counterfeit charity ; what we all want is
the true genuine charity. There is no such charity.
apart from truth. Without the love of truth, no one
can understand the true charity. Hence when any one
by a hasty and inconsiderate decision on any question
whatever, injures or opposes truth, he is the very person
who is likely to wound charity also in one of two ways,
according to his temper and his circumstances, — either
by intolerance and bigotry, or by pusillanimity and soft-
ness, in one or other of their thousand shapes. The
charity of truth and of the Bible breathes nothing but
tenderness and love to the person of every man, while
opposing with stern inflexibility every vice and every
error without respect of persons.
Celsus.—Though you thus refuse to acknowledge that
there is a sincere denier of the truth of Christianity, you
1 A Defence, pp. 28, 29—Note.
174 DIALOGUE III.
are prepared to allow that a man may sincerely doubt its
claims. For unless you concede this, how can there be
a patient and honest investigation ?
Theologus.— Unquestionably. We would much rather
see a sincere doubter on any question, than a hurried
profession of the truth itself, without due examination.
At the same time, the sincere doubter and inquirer will
soon find more or less of the rock of truth beneath his
feet. There is far too little of this ingenuous hesitation
and childlike investigation on both sides of the contend-
ing hosts. There would be far less infidelity without the
Christian church, if there were less dogmatism within it.
Origen.—It is easy to bring a sweeping charge; it is
‘more difficult to substantiate it.
Celsus.—Do you dispute what one of your own friends
has advanced, when he says, “ Do you imagine that I
can so think of the good Christian folks of this present
time, as to their judgment, as to their intelligence, or as
to their conscientious diligence, as that I could be willing
to leave Christianity in their hands, undisturbed and
irresponsible ? far from it.”? It is some consolation to us
to find, that even on the shewing of your advocates, we
are, on the whole, ethically and spiritually, not much
worse than the mass of professing Christians.
Theologus. — Has it never struck you as a singular
fact, that our denominational differences are almost as
hereditary as an entailed estate, or as Mohammedanism
and Hinduism? The young people born and educated in
* Restoration, p. 246.
BELIEF AND RESPONSIBILITY. ss
one denomination are sure, almost universally, to adopt
the peculiarities of that denomination. Thus sectarian
controversies are perpetuated, which would die a natu-
ral death, if the rising generation, and especially students
for the ministry, would “ prove all things, and hold fast
that which is good.” The Christian church will never
preach this text with effect to the world, till they prac-
tise it more themselves.
Origen.—Might I now ask you to explain a little more
fully what you mean by admitting “sincerity to be the
test of truth?”
Theologus.—Taking sincerity as already
Sincerity shewn rs 5
to be the test of explained to signify, not consistency or
es firmness in adhering to our view, but care
and conscientiousness in adopting it, the position seems to
be free from difficulty. Light is the test of the eye, and
the eye is the test of light. That is dark, which to a
sound eye is dark; and that is light which to a sound
eye is light. The eye to which darkness is not darkness,
or light not light, is not healthy. So also, that is true
which to a sincere mind is true, and that ts error which
to a sincere mind is error. The mind to which truth is
not truth, or error not error, is not sincere,—not honest
with itself, if it have the power of intelligence. If by a
sincere mind be meant a mind which honestly desires to
know the truth on a given point, and which will not say
or think that a proposition respecting that point is either
true or false without due attention and sufficient evidence,
it seems impossible to avoid the inference, that sincere
176 DIALOGUE III.
belief is belief of the truth, and belief of the truth is sin-
cere belief. It is well to notice, that there may be a
mere professed belief of the truth, which being without
sincerity is no real belief of the truth at all. So also
there may be an empty profession of sincerity, which
shall prove itself to be empty by denying truth or affirm-
ing error.
To maintain that an individual is responsible for some
of his beliefs, while at the same time it ig admitted, that
he may sincerely and unblameably believe error to be
truth on any subject, is a clear contradiction. For if a
man be lable in any instance to affirm as true an erro-
neous proposition,—that is, to mistake intellectual dark-
ness for intellectual light, it must be, either because he
is not able, or because he is not willing, to perceive the
distinction between truth and error in that particular
case. If he be unable to perceive the distinction, then
in that matter being destitute of the privilege of intelli-
gence, he is exempt from the obligation of responsibility.
But if while a man is able in anything to distinguish
between truth and error, he will not, then he is at once
intelligent, responsible, and culpable.
If it be no matter what a man believes, as is broadly
stated, and loosely assumed, and craftily insinuated,
times without number, then truth is an empty name. But
this opinion is a hackneyed phase of scepticism; for the
proposition that would make all other propositions worth-
less, makes itself worthless too, If, then, there be value
in truth, in all truth, and in some truth value incal-
ye ee ee
BELIEF AND RESPONSIBILITY. Vaz
culable, to suppose that mankind should be so consti-
tuted, that while they feel an obligation to eschew error
and embrace the truth, and while their welfare actually
depends upon their doing so, both in thought and in
action, they should yet without any fault on their part
mistake the one for the other, is surely to impeach the
character of their Creator. He who would attempt to
screen himself from the guilt of insincerity behind a
mere verbal orthodox creed, and he who would palliate
his erroneous belief by the plea of sincerity, are equally
endeavouring to vindicate themselves by criminating the
Most High.
It is a matter of profound regret, that in the contro-
versies regarding the Divine existence and character, the
contending parties should so frequently have taken hold,
the one of the one side of this truth, and the other of the
other side. It has been a main position of one party,
that his sincerity will acquit a man, whatever he may
believe. Their opponents, after granting that a man
may sincerely believe in error, have vainly bent their
efforts to the establishment of objective truth. For what
use can there be in displaying the truth objectively, if
the sincere and upright mind may contemplate without
recognising her? The plea of inward sincerity being
equally valid with the plea of outward truth, the warfare
between the occupants of these two impregnable citadels
must be endless. Let the defenders of the existence of
God and a divine revelation once refuse to grant that
sincerity is a test of truth, and start their apology with
178 DIALOGUE III.
the affirmation or concession that a man may be consci-
entious in a bad cause as well as in a good one, and they
not only give their opponents an argument which, as we
have just seen, nothing can refute, but they also thereby
unwarrantably resign one of the most powerful weapons
of assault, and at the same time introduce into the very
camp of truth itself confusion and anarchy.
By this concession the only effective weapon of assault
falls from the Christian’s grasp. Let the position that
error regarding the Divine character, and the rejection
of Christianity, involve a want of sincerity and candour,
and consequent criminality—have once its integrity im-
paired, or its firmness shaken, or its prominence veiled,
and wherewithal can the theist, but especially the Chris-
tian, make an aggressive movement upon the unbelieving
world’ He may talk of miracles, and manuscripts, and
morals, of the glories of creation, and the wonders of
redemption, and the terrors of judgment—these are only
so many levers, which without some such point as that
now indicated to form a fulcrum on which to work, are
utterly powerless in hig hand.
Celsus.—* When you begin by assuming broad dis-
sent to be manifest guilt, it can matter little what you
say to such a man, or how you treat him.”
Lheologus.—Far from it; a very great deal depends
upon the manner in which a statement is made, and upon
the different modes in which even the manifestly guilty
may be treated.
Celsus.—< It becomes mere hypocrisy or complicity to
BELIEF AND RESPONSIBILITY. 179
reciprocate courtesies with one whom you believe to be a
wilful criminal.”
Theologus.—Assuredly, and for the best of all rea-
sons; that if we do not protest against and resist rebel-
lion, when it is avowed and acted in our presence, we are
ourselves, by our very silence and inactivity, constituted
rebels. But there may, and there ought to be, a vast
difference between our deportment to a rebel whose trial
is passed, and sentence pronounced, and doom decided,
and our deportment to another whose timely submission
may yet restore his tarnished honour, and retrieve his
forfeited inheritance; the more especially when we are
free to confess, that we ourselves have but very recently
escaped from that condition, by availing ourselves of
what is as open to him as to us, heaven’s amnesty.
Origen.—You said, that to deny sincerity to be the
test of truth, is to throw discord into the camp of truth.
How is that?
Theologus.—In this way : when it is formally admitted
that a man may be sincere in error, sanction is virtually
though secretly given to the wide spread and calamitous de-
lusion, that belief in the truth, apart from sincerity, is the
way of acceptancewith God. Ifthere be such a thing as sin-
cerity in error, it is of course worthless, or next to worth-
less. How, then, can it be shewn that sincerity in the truth
isin any degree better? Mental honesty and candour thus
become degraded and ruined. The way is prepared for
professing the truth, without possessing it. The very
utterance of truth is turned into a lie; for the words of
180 DIALOGUE III.
verity are frequently found upon the lips, while the reali-
ties of verity are far from the heart. The profession
even of religious truth may thus, alas! become, what we
fear it often is, nothing but a subtle superstition. This
hypocritical conduct finds its sanction or excuse in the
insult offered to sincerity. If my neighbour may be
conscientiously wrong, why should I toil at the hopeless
task of being conscientiously right? If all diligence and
candour will not preserve me from error, I must find a
short cut to the truth, or be content with what comes
first to hand. By such retorts as these, the injury done
to sincerity is avenged. And we thus perceive, that
when Christians attempt to exalt objective truth at the
expense of subjective uprightness, the consequences are
most disastrous; the outworks of infidelity are buttressed,
and genuine religion is virtually betrayed.
Might we be allowed to speak of the union between
the mind and the truth, as having all the security and
sacredness of the marriage relation? By unfaithfulness
on either side the bond is broken. There are truths
which will enter that mind only which proves itself
worthy of their reception. The mind that deliberately
embraces error prostitutes itself. The latitudinarian
charity of the day is based upon the assumption that
this prostitution is lawful. To deny, therefore, that sin-
cerity is the test of truth, and truth the test of sincerity,
is to leave no vestige of dignity, or purity, or strength,
either to eternal truth or to the human mind.
Origen.—The dignity, purity, and strength of the
BELIEF AND RESPONSIBILITY. 181
human mind!! What, then, do you make of the doctrine
of human depravity ?
Theologus.—lIf you assert that there is “ no vestige of
dignity, or purity, or strength, in the human mind,”
inasmuch as it is depraved, in asserting its corruption,
you deny its intelligence and responsibility.
Origen.—In what, then, does the depravity of man
consist ?
Theologus.—In such circumstances as these, the de-
rangement and corruption of our desires and affections ;
the erroneous beliefs in which every man is involved
through the sins of his progenitors; the weakened tone
of the ethical sentiment or conscience; and the dimi-
nished power of the will, as compared especially with
the temptations to which we are exposed.
As to the indissoluble union between outward truth and
inward sincerity, it seems to be the very turning point
of every controversy, especially of the one that is now
agitated. On one hand, men may be observed extenuat-
ing the distinction between error and truth, till it becomes
a mere convenience or a petty conventionality ; and, on
the other hand, stretching their brotherly-love in such a
generous mood as to overlook all real diversity of inward
character. But all distinctions cannot be abolished ; con-
sistent communism is an actual, as well as a theoretical
absurdity. Nothing remains to be done, therefore, but
to erect this and the other fashionable foible of the day
into the partition-wall of human society. To stop short,
however, of the lowest degree of communism, to acknow-
182 DIALOGUE III.
ledge diversity of some substantial kind among men, to
halt on this side of extremest pantheism, and admit that
any one thing is more divine than another — to refuse
to bury all the distinctions of taste, art, literature, and
science, in one huge, common, loathsome grave, while the
distinction between truth and error,—religious truth and
religious error, between sincerity and insincerity, or virtue
and vice, is really denied, or coldly admitted, or denuded
of its proper and supreme authority, and of its lasting
and weighty results,—to do so is surely inconsistent.
It is an inconsistency, moreover, involving the most
serious consequences. If sincerity may be divorced from
truth and wedded to error, then truth may not condemn
error, and virtue may not abhor vice. If the man, who
in some case of moment is possessed of true knowledge
and genuine virtue, may not speak of the man of erroneous
knowledge and spurious virtue in terms plain and forcible,
which are as far removed from drivelling charity as from
rancour and ill-will,—without incurring the charge of
acerbity and malice; it is solely because error claims to
be truth and vice to be virtue. To extend our Charity,
therefore, beyond the landmarks of truth and the bul-
warks of virtue,—-and sincerity, in the sense that has been
assigned to it, is of the essence of both, is not merely to
be inconsistent, or to nullify or obliterate the distinction
between truth and error and virtue and vice ;—it is more,
it makes error truth and vice virtue. The culprit seats
himself by some dexterous exploit upon the bench, and
has the audacity to summon the judge tothe bar. Truth
BELIEF AND RESPONSIBILITY. 183
is scorned because she will not sympathise and associate
with error. Virtue is censured because she keeps her
robes unsullied. The good man for confronting and
withstanding the bad man, forfeits his goodness. Actual
manifestations of this spirit are constantly occurring in
social life; for while wickedness and ungodliness exist
they are altogether unavoidable. There are some who
on this path reach the very climax of folly and of crime ;
inasmuch as the Almighty himself has been spoken of as
the guiltiest of all, for inflicting without mercy everlasting
punishment on those, who to the last hour of their pro-
bation continue resolute and impenitent in guilt.
Origen.—Some additional explanation of
your views on Charity, in connection with
the matter just discussed, seems desirable.
Theologus.—Let us suppose that a number of indi-
viduals meet regularly together to prosecute various
studies. Their union is based on the principle of loving
truth, and loving one another. Their inquiries proceed,
and they rejoice in the mutual recognition of fascinating
and important doctrines. Their conjoint investigation of
weighty facts, and common assiduity in watching the
results of rare experiments, knit them together in closest
sympathy. One after another is successful in making a
valuable discovery ; and the joy of each is shared by all.
In this peaceful and prosperous way, while truth is
developed, friendship is cemented. If, however, after a
tume one of this group of scientific brothers shall come to
look upon a certain truth, which is recognised as such by
Charity explained.
184 DIALOGUE III.
his companions, to be of vastly greater moment than they
have been accustomed to regard it, or shall come to receive
something, which they do not receive, not only as true,
but also of unspeakable importance, will not this change
of opinion unavoidably produce considerable change of
feeling ?
It would obviously be the duty of him who believed he
had made an all-important discovery, to communicate to
his fellows a statement of his new belief, with the grounds
on which it rested. To conceal it would be unfaithfulness
to truth, dishonour to himself, and unkindness to his
friends. It is possible he may err in the manner of
making the avowal, but make it he must. If his friends
on considering his statement shall regard it as unfounded
and extravagant, and refuse to adopt the new view, their
respect for him will very much diminish, as will also his
respect for them. Thus a change of sentiment, such as_
has been indicated, must, from the very nature of the cir-
cumstances, seriously disturb and mar the longest and
most fraternal friendship.
Celsus.—‘ The chief lesson that man has to learn, is to
entertain contempt and aversion for all fanaticism in phi-
losophy as in every thing else, and to acquire the habit
of tolerating and even respecting all the theories which
are the legitimate offspring of the human mind and human
liberty.”
Theologus.—There is much and dangerous error, as
you admit, in the theories or systems you speak of ;—I
have yet to learn how to entertain respect for error.
me,
;
ee ea aoe
BELIEF AND RESPONSIBILITY. 185
Charity commands us not merely to tolerate but to love
men; truth forbids us to tolerate their errors.
Celsus. —‘* The most gifted of our brethren are no
more than the fragments of a larger and (as yet) ideal
manhood. Even Shakspeare is only a poet. But when
the fragmentariness becomes extreme, and when little men
insult over our endeavours to emancipate ourselves from
a littleness of ours, perhaps still less than their own, we
do well to be angry. And we do better still to assert
that the technical classes, from the mere shoemaker up
to the mere naturalist, and from him to the mere
theologian, could not do better than join our institution,
and listen to the broad and general prelections of men like
———. If they soon discover that our instructors,
how well soever they may know the subjects they sever-
ally teach, do most notoriously differ from one another
in their more central views of things, then so much the
better ; for it does us all good to deal closely with the
heterodox on the neutral ground of the impersonal intel-
lect and the catholic feelings of our nature.”
Origen. — To speak of “heterodoxy” on “neutral
ground” seems something like a contradiction in terms.
Nor can we admit catholicity to be a test of truth, and
forget one of whom we have read :—
‘* faithful found
Among the faithless, faithful only he ;
Among innumerable false, unmoved,
Unshaken, unseduced, unterrified,
His loyalty he kept, his love, his zeal,
Nor number, nor example, with him wrought
M
186 DIALOGUE III.
To swerve from truth, or change his constant mind,
Though single.”
Theologus.—It may be added, that the only sense in
which the “ impersonality of the intellect” can be main-
tained implies, that its aberrations are personal and
culpable. But let us return to the point more immediately
in hand. That there is a real and immeasurable differ-
ence between taking God Himself to be our God and
taking that which is not God to be our god,—-our idol,
will not surely be denied. The existence of the distine-
tion, and its weighty import too, have been often acknow-
ledged. Calvin, for instance, in the fifth chapter (§ 11)
of the first book of his Institutes, reasons thus: “* When
we direct our thoughts by means of God’s works to medi-
tate upon Him (which all must do,) having rashly formed
some conception of Deity, we immediately yield to some
wild or depraved imagination of our flesh, and corrupt
the pure truth of God with our folly. And although
every one has some peculiar error of his own, in this we are
all alike that we fall away from the one true God to mon-
strous conceits. In which disease not only common and dull
minds are involved, but also the shrewdest and most ex-
cellent.” Although Calvin in his further remarks
includes Plato by name in this sweeping censure, it is
true that the latter has himself recognised the very prin-
ciple on which the remarks of the former are founded,
and for which we are contending. Plato held that to
attempt to propitiate the gods toward criminal conduct
was a kind of blasphemy. This opinion evidently sup-
BELIEF AND RESPONSIBILITY. 187
poses that to seek to approach Deity under a serious
misconception of His character, is equivalent to approach-
ing an idol, and thus offering indignity to the true God.
Let it be granted, then, as at least possible, that one
man may have a true knowledge of God, and also be
earnestly desiring and striving to have his will in obe-
dience to the will of God, while another man, his neigh-
bour, has not the true knowledge of God, or if he have,
cares not to have his will in habitual subjection to the
will of the Most High. What must be the state of feeling
between two such individuals? Both parties will feel
that there is an awful chasm between them; and if any
one shall by some means or other pass from one side of
that chasm to the other, it cannot but involve a sacrifice
of former companionships. The man who holds an opinion
to be as plain and certain as any proposition can be, and
at the same time unspeakably momentous, must appear
in some sort intolerant to all those who disagree with
him in that opinion. To deny that there are true opinions
of this description, is to deny the possibility of man know-
ing and serving his Maker, or to deny that there is any
such thing as guilt and ungodliness in the earth. If a
man know and hold to a truth which is not only most
luminous but weighty, affecting obviously and directly
the personal interests of every individual, though he speak
of this truth in the most gentle and courteous manner,
yet if he really does justice to the truth itself, his state-
ments will inevitably excite the most uneasy and painful
feelings in all with whom he differs.
188 DIALOGUE III.
They who are cither theoretically or practically reckon-
ing as God, that which is not God,—the ungodly and
idolatrous of all shades,—have little patience with the
godly man, who knows and fears with all his heart God
as He is, when he begins to speak in their presence of
the errors in which they are entangled. The difference
between two such parties is so marked and so momentous,
that the subject is commonly avoided in their conversa-
tion: for it cannot be discussed without intensest feeling
upon both sides, and it is only in special circumstances
that the pious man may legitimately force it upon the
attention of the other. If the one would make any abate- .
ment in his averments, either as to the perfect plainness of
the truth or as to its untold value,—neither of which he
can do, the other might tolerate his opinions. If a traitor
and a loyal subject be thrown together for a season, they
must either avoid conversing about their common monarch,
or their conversation (unless one of them, indeed, conceal
his real views) will afford obvious evidence of the dread
diversity of their sentiments. The truth respecting the
character of God in his more immediate relation to our-
selves, is so clear and so precious, that to doubt or disre-
gard it is the greatest folly or the highest crime. This
must be the claim and bearing of intelligent devotion,
wherever she is found. This self-assertion she cannot
and dare not qualify. It is her life,—her essence; and
all compromise is impossible. Consequently she finds in
every man, with whom she forms anything like an inti-
mate acquaintance, either an enemy or a friend.
BELIEF AND RESPONSIBILITY. 189
But when this high claim is allowed—a, claim which,
need we add, can be reasonably and effectually urged by
any individual upon his fellows, only by able arguments
and self-denying love, not by harsh words or haughty
looks, far less by pains or penalties—when the Divine
character is known and honoured in its essential integrity,
there will be a special and intense affection among all
those who agree in this fundamental position, while they
will feel compassion for all who differ from them. The
fact that this claim has been so often assumed, and by
parties so diverse, is proof sufficient that there is one party
to whom it rightfully belongs. To refuse to determine
who this party is among numerous competitors, is to run
the risk, whatever that risk may be, of disallowing the
supremacy of that which is supreme. True religion, then,
asserts, and must ever assert, the possession of the high-
est authority ; she claims the unfeigned and unqualified
submission of every man. Towards all who withhold this
submission she is intolerant, not physically, but morally
—not proudly, but meekly.
If there be no such thing as the true knowledge of
God in the world, then dismal indeed is the condition of
humanity. But if there be, it may not be compared
with speculations that are yet unsettled; neither may it
be placed on a level even with the established doctrines
of science ; for while as certain as they (on the principle
that all true knowledge is equally certain), it transcends
them immeasurably in value. True religion, therefore,
must be confessed to be the choicest of our acquisitions,
190 DIALOGUE III.
and her crown may not be dishonoured. But her rai-
ment is love. She breathes unbounded kindness to all
men, and inspires the strongest mutual confidence and
esteem among those who yield her due respect. To
those who decline and resist, she is inflexibly and awfully
severe. She frowns in all her divine dignity on the man
who will not pay her homage. There cannot, therefore,
be anything worthy of the name of harmony or sym-
pathy among those who are not substantially at one in
their views of the Divine character; while among those
who are thus at one, there will be not only the closest
intimacy, but large and rational forbearance, when they
differ in opinion on subordinate topics.
This forbearance, however, even on points of inferior
moment, cannot rest on the supposition, that men may
sincerely contradict each other on any matter whatso-
ever. This were to return to the quicksands of unbelief.
Christian forbearance is based on the principle, that
direct collision of sentiments implies blameworthiness in
one of the parties or the other ; and inasmuch as it does
so, this collision ought to be avoided to the very utter-
most by the sacrifice of everything but truth itself, and,
when collision does arise, each party should first suspect
himself of being the censurable cause of the conflict.
And even when we have found some truth, and know we
have found it, without deceiving ourselves, that truth
should be always uttered in the meekness of wisdom.
It is thus apparent, that Truru, all truth, has at once
a repellant and an attractive force,—a dissevering and an
BELIEF AND RESPONSIBILITY. 191
uniting tendency. She not only binds together those
who know her, but excludes from their fellowship those
who deny her. Is it proper that ignorance of sacred
truth only shall not invalidate a man’s claim to scholar-
ship? Is it seemly that it should be indifference to reli-
gious truth only that does not injure any one’s preten-
sions to be a man of letters? There cannot be a graver
inconsistency than to set aside truth in religion at the
eall of a counterfeit charity, especially when it is done so
seldom in anything else. Is not the engineer who makes
a scientific error in constructing or conducting a steam-
boat or a railway, and thereby causes the loss of life or
the ruin of property, considered guilty of a high mis-
demeanour? Does charity save him?
Nothing can be more insidious and dangerous, than
the attempts which are constantly made at present, both
within and without the pale of the Christian church, to
ignore the repellent force and disallow the dissevering
tendency of truth. There are many who can scarcely be
regarded as belonging to the Christian church, who —
never cease their sentimental harping on the attractive
power and uniting influence of charity, as if religion, that
is, the correct knowledge and habitual fear of God as He
as, or the only means by which man can be restored to
that high wposition, were some curious contrivance to
gather together without discrimination everything that
comes in its way,—or a solvent to dissolve into one
putrid mass the ill-assorted and corrupt materials of
human society! Is it not more worthy of God, more
192 DIALOGUE III.
needful to man, and more consistent with reason, to con-
ceive of religion as a fire, which shall purge the dross,
and thereby send forth a mass of purest gold ?
In like manner, there are not a few Christians who
fancy that the best way in which their union may be
accomplished, is to excavate to a sufficient depth, and
thus provide a grave of forgetfulness, wherein to entomb
all the contradictory and clashing opinions of the disciples
of Christ. Having finished the interment, they would
erect on the same spot of ground, and in commemoration
of the event, the temple of Christian concord. The build-
ing might be beautiful, but it would not be lasting. The
buried and hushed-up controversies at its foundation
would prove so many charges of inflammable material,
which any accident might ignite and lay the temple in
ruins. These controversies must be resolved by Chris-
tians seeking, and finding, and agreeing in the truth
which each controversy involves ; for as genuine charity,
whether it be brotherly affection for the good or com-
passion for the erring, must fall unless supported by
truth, so also is it on the immoveable rock of truth alone,
that the temple of Christian union can be erected in its
full proportions and in enduring splendour.
DIALOGUE IY.
MYSTERY AND CONTRADICTION.
Celsus. — Since it has been established in this discus-
sion, that reason rightly used never deceives us, we can-
not be expected to accept a religion, unless it make good
its pretensions to be thoroughly reasonable.
Origen. —What do you mean by thoroughly reason-
able ?
Celsus.—‘* What the light of your mind, which 1s the
direct inspiration of the Almighty, pronounces incredible,
—that, in God’s name, leave uncredited ; at your peril
do not try believing that.”
Origen.—Faith may embrace what reason rejects.
_Celsus.—How is this ?
Origen.—I shall explain what I mean by an example.
«¢The doctrines of prayer and predestination are often
regarded as inconsistent, and by many Christians are
not reconciled but by explaining away either the moral
agency of man or the Sovereignty of the Creator. At
first sight, they will generally appear to be incompatible;
but cease to be so to those who have laid aside false
notions of infinite wisdom.”’’
1 Christian Theism, vol. ii. p. 214.
194 DIALOGUE IV.
Celsus. — Your statement is not very clear. Do you
regard the doctrines of prayer and predestination as
simply not incompatible, or do you regard them as re-
conciled ? You first speak as if they could be reconciled,
and afterwards seem to think it enough if they cease to
appear to be incompatible.
Origen. — The distinction is perhaps of little conse-
quence.
Celsus.—So it would appear to be in the estimation of
the author from whom you have just quoted. For in one
page he remarks that, “‘ between the inflexible laws of
nature, and a Providence who answers prayer, there is
no inconsistency of opposite doctrines; but only an in-
competency of the human understanding, to know how
they co-exist.” While in the next page, he endeavours
to show how they co-exist, or how God “can answer
prayer consistently with the laws of nature, and by
means of them.”! It seems rather puzzling to find such
a distinction formally introduced, and immediately dis-
carded.
Lheologus.— The distinction is a most important one,
and has been already adverted to. The only difficulty
lies in clearly apprehending its import, and consistently
adhering to it in our discussions. |
Origen. —It is a distinction, as some think, of vital
moment in the theistic argument, which may be shortly
stated thus: “The question of the origin of nature is
one which we cannot possibly evade. It forces itself
* Christian Theism, vol. ii. p2ikyet2:
MYSTERY AND CONTRADICTION. 195
upon the reason, and presently involves it in a dilemma.
But it is not, as is commonly thought, a dilemma of oppo-
site incomprehensibles, but between an incomprehensible
and an absurdity; between a conclusion above reason
and one contrary to it. We cannot but shrink from the
absurdity, the incomprehensibility 1s no more than was to
be expected.”’?
Celsus.—It seems to me that a man should shrink as
much from an incomprehensible conclusion, as from an
absurd one. If a conclusion be above my reason, how
can my reason accept it ?
Theologus.—This remark shews us the
Mystery and / :
contradiction necessity of clearly understanding what an
oa incomprehensibility or mystery is, and how
it is to be distinguished from an absurdity or contradic-
tion. A mystery is not found in a fact or proposition
taken by itself. For if a fact or proposition be in itself
mysterious, how can it be known at all? A mystery
may attach itself to a proposition in two ways. The
proposition may express a fact, whose explanation is
incomprehensible or mysterious; or one proposition,
known to be true, may stand in an evident but icom-
prehensible relationship to another proposition known
to be true. A mystery, therefore, can be affirmed with
propriety, not of a conclusion, but only of the eaplana-
tion of a fact, or of the relation between two truths. A
conclusion or proposition is absurd, when it contradicts
another proposition, which is believed by the party
1 Christian Theism, v. i. p. 282.
196 DIALOGUE Iv.
drawing the conclusion, or which is conceded to be
true.
Origen.—But is there not something mysterious in the
very statement, that all things were made by God, who
is infinite in all His perfections ?
Lheologus. —It may seem trivial to some, but it is
really of great consequence, to distinguish between a
statement that is mysterious, and one that is connected
with, or implies, a mystery. A mystery is something
not known. A proposition cannot be believed, unless we
know its meaning, and also know that it is true. To
say that a mysterious proposition may be believed is
absurd, for it makes ignorance identical with knowledge.
Origen. —Do you then know the meaning of the
infinite ?
Theologus.—I know that there is an infinite Being ;
but the explanation of this fact, the mode of His exist-
ence, is tome a mystery. Infinity is to my mind simply
equivalent to the non-finite, that which is without limits,
—a negative conception. Every thing around me exists
under conditions; I think of the absolute Being as simply
without conditions, unconditioned. The positive concep-
tion of the infinite or absolute is what I have not; it is
to me unknown, a mystery. Hence those who affirm
that they have an intuition of the unconditioned seem to
involve themselves in a contradiction. A whole is some-
thing made up of parts; if, then, I affirm the absolute to
be a whole without parts, I simply contradict myself.
If I affirm the infinite to be a whole whose parts are
a a
MYSTERY AND CONTRADICTION. 197
numberless, I again oppose myself; for so long as the
parts are really unnumbered the whole is incomplete.
Celsus.—I regard the command im-
puted to God to extirpate the nations of
Canaan to be “incredible, because it contradicts my
moral and spiritual convictions of what God would do.
It attributes to God what would be ‘harsh, cruel, and
b)
The Canaanites. }
unjust in man;’ and therefore I must reject it.”
Origen.—Is not God good, even in permitting war,
tyranny, slavery, earthquakes, shipwrecks, volcanoes,
sickness and death? ‘Yes, I say; yes, with an un-
faltering faith ; but I believe it, and cannot see it; these
things are what we should call ‘harsh, cruel, and unjust
in man,’ and are utterly incomprehensible to our ‘little
wisdom,’ and ‘ little goodness,’ and ‘little love ;’ just as
His command to exterminate the Canaanites, though not
so perplexing, nor a tenth part so perplexing, is also in-
comprehensible. But I believe that God is good in
spite of these facts.’’!
Celsus.—It is hard to conceive how there can be two
degrees, far less ten, in things unknown and incompre-
hensible. But passing that, and assuming that when you
speak of the command itself as incomprehensible, you
mean the relation between the command and the charac-
ter of God, you surely have forgotten that the Bible
itself does not speak of it as incomprehensible, but
attempts to explain and vindicate God’s proceedings in
1A Defence of the Eclipse of Faith, p. 44.
198 DIALOGUE IV.
the matter.—(See Levit. xvii. 24-30; Deut. xx. 10-18;
Josh. ii. 12-14, xi. 19, 20.) By calling it an incompre-
hensible mystery, you virtually admit that this explana-
tion and vindication are incomplete and unsatisfactory.
If this command utterly to destroy the people of Canaan
involve a real mystery, it cannot be expounded and
defended and brought to the level of the human under-
standing. But your Scriptures themselves endeavour to
do so; if they fail in this endeavour, and according to
your statement they have failed, we do not see how you
can complacently receive these Scriptures as the word
of God in spite of this failure. Not that this failure
destroys positive independent evidence, but it opposes
and neutralises it, and must leave the mind in that state
of believing doubt, or doubtful belief, in describing
which many grow eloquent.
Origen.—“ The Christian believes, from -an immense
variety, complexity, and convergence of proof, that the
Book which contains Christianity, and the system it re-
veals, never came from man. Particular objections to
portions of it, nevertheless—both as respects doctrine
and history—may, like the correspondent difficulties in
the outward universe, be attended with unanswerable
perplexities ; but the Christian listens to them just as he
would to a judge, who, in his summing up, tells the jury
that there can be no doubt that the evidence—nine parts
out of ten—will justify them in bringing in one, and only
one verdict ; though he says there may be one, two, or
three points on which the evidence is conflicting, and on
MYSTERY AND CONTRADICTION. 199
which neither himself nor mortal man can give or even
suggest any plausible solution.’
Celsus.—The force of this reasoning depends entirely
‘ on the nature and value of the point or points on which
the evidence is conflicting. If the evidence on some main
point in the charge be at variance, or if the contradictions
of witnesses implicate the moral character of one of their
number whose testimony is important, will any judge
affirm that in such a case there is but one verdict, and
there can be no doubt about it? Now the command to
exterminate the Canaanites, does involve directly and
deeply the character of God; and since the Bible itself
does not treat it as a mystery, you are bound to afford a
sufficient explanation and defence thereof, or greatly
modify, if not entirely abandon, your faith in the Chris-
tian Scriptures.
Theologus.—The assertion that the Divine command
wholly to extirpate the inhabitants of the land of Canaan
involves a mystery, and connot be explained, or vindi-
cated to the moral sense of mankind, throws the Chris-
tian advocate into more than one serious disadvantage.
Whenever we appeal to the events of Providence, or the
statements of the Bible, to justify God’s ways to men,
our appeal is legitimately arrested, unless we extend it to
all these events and all these statements. To allow that
some of them, and these the most forcible and critical,
remain hopelessly inexplicable, is virtually to abandon
our defence of the character of the Almighty.
1A Defence, &c., p. 181.
200 DIALOGUE IV.
Again, it is certainly the fact, as has been stated, that
in the Bible itself once and again are found arguments
and representations, which are evidently intended to
manifest the righteousness and holiness of God in His
dealings towards the exterminated people.
Further, when the Christian assumes that some of
God’s proceedings toward men are mysterious,—in other
words, that men can learn nothing from these proceed-
ings, the unbeliever, basing his reply upon the truth
which this assumption denies, namely, that it is absurd to
expect that intelligent beings can learn nothing of the
Divine character from the actions of the Deity towards
themselves, is able, with the power thus attained, to
carry confusion into his opponent’s line of argument, and
give to his assertion that the command in question is
immoral, a point and a force otherwise unattainable.
Origen.—< Objections to the doctrine of
ec 4h) Redemption generally rest on false views
of the competency of man’s moral judgment. On such
a subject the Divine conduct cannot be within the reach
of human criticism.” !
Celsus. —Does not God himself invite and demand cri-
ticism on his conduct ?’—(See Isa. i. 2, 8, 18; Jer. ii. 12,
13; Rom. v. 6-9).
Origen.—‘* We cannot sufficiently know those prin-
ciples of eternal morality, which have their foundation in
the Divine nature, to be able to apply them, in judgment
of His dealings with a fallen world. We have not ac-
Christian Theism, v. ii. p. 309.
"MYSTERY AND CONTRADICTION, 201
quaintance with universal nature, to perceive the effects
of the fall, or to pronounce what will be the agency of
Infinite Holiness and Love to the fallen. Human reason,
or human morality, is quite inapplicable to the ques-
tions.” '
Celsus.—If, then, you hold the doctrine of the Atone-
ment as a fact, and regard its explanation as a mystery
(and I perceive no other meaning that may be attached
to your words), then you regard as inconclusive and
unsatisfactory the thousand attempts that have been
made to shew the wisdom of that procedure on the part
of God; and what you will make of one half or so of the
New Testament itself, I am at a loss to conjecture. N ay,
the author from whom you quote immediately contradicts |
himself. After reiterating his assertion in these words:
—‘“ The Divine conduct in the Redemption of the world
is thus wholly beyond the criticism of reason;” he pre-
sently begins to criticise, that is, to explain and vindicate
what he professes not to understand. ‘“ The revelation,”
he says, “of the Divine Perfections in Scripture, and
especially in the doctrines of Christianity, is consist-
ent with the inferences of natural theology. The Chris-
tian’s God is therefore both the God of nature, and the
God and Father of the Lord Jesus Christ. It scarcely
falls within our subject, to examine the direct evi-
dences which confirm the doctrine of the Atonement.
But its importance may justify a short notice of some of
them.” ? )
* Christian Theism, v. ii. p. 309. * 1b. ppv ote, 314;
N
202 DIALOGUE IV.
Theologus.—If the assertion that the destruction of the
Canaanites is morally incomprehensible be extravagant
and perilous, much more so is the statement that the rela-
tion between the sacrifice of the Lord Jesus and the cha-
racter of His Father, Jehovah, is mysterious. The
remarks which we formerly offered on the first case apply
more forcibly to the present one. It seems almost un-
accountable how any Christian apologist could say, that
‘‘human reason, or human morality is quite inapplicable
to the question.” Is not God’s gift of His own Son—His
best and greatest gift, the clearest and most impressive
manifestation of the Divine character? Is it not here,
more than anywhere else, that Divine wisdom, love, and
righteousness, are most conspicuously displayed? And
is it not this very display of God’s Holiness and mercy,
that is the fittest and most effectual means in working
upon men’s obdurate hearts, to bring them to their right
mind, and win them back to their God? To tell us that
the Atonement is a mystery, is to give a death-blow to
intelligent practical Christianity, and plunge us in the
depths of superstition.
Then as to the mere logic of the question, if an intel-
ligent being thinks that the Great God acts toward him-
self on principles which he does not and cannot understand,
his worship will be blind, and his confidence, if confidence
there be, that of a slave. When a Christian speaks of the
mysteries of Providence, he means, or he ought to mean,
not that he cannot now reconcile the events referred to
as mysterious with God’s infinite wisdom, love and power,
MYSTERY AND CONTRADICTION. 203
but simply that they form part of a large plan which he
does not comprehend in all its details. For to the godly
man there is properly speaking no mystery connected
with his sufferings, however sharp or long continued ; the
consciousness of his guilt ever harmonises his tribulation
with the righteousness of his God. The hypothesis, then,
that the principles on which God deals with us, even in
any instance, and much more in the case of “not spar-
ing his own Son, but delivering him up for us all,” are
unknown to us or unapproved by our intelligence, re-
duces us to fatalism, and confounds slavish submission to
mere power with childlike submission to mercy and wis-
dom. Ona hypothesis like this, how can Theism, much
less Christianity, be successfully defended? The pal-
ladium of true religion is all but abandoned into the
enemy’s hand. )
It thus appears that it is necessary to be always care-
ful in distinguishing a mystery from a contradiction.
When we have a doctrine which involves a real mystery,
as that of the Trinity, taken by itself, or those of the
Divine Foreknowledge and man’s responsibility taken
together, we must be cautious in the use of language, lest
we involve ourselves in a verbal contradiction and give
an advantage to the gainsayers. On the other hand, to
plead as a mystery, what is not a mystery, is sure to land
usin a self-inconsistency, as we have just seen in the cases
of the Atonement and the destruction of the Canaanites.
Origen.—It will not be denied that the
Moral Evil, i 2 :
best method of settling the disputes in re-
204 DIALOGUE IV.
gard to the relation between God’s character and the
prevalence of evil in the world, is to treat moral evil as a
profound mystery.
Theologus.—One mystery is as profound as any other,
if you adhere to the definition given above; and the best
method in every case is the method that is according to
truth.
Origen —Let me explain myself. “ All that we can
know is, that the possibility of sin lies in the fact of
personality ; in other words, in the fact of human freedom.
And as this fact is wholly inexplicable, so is equally, the
sin which has sprung from it. As to the final difficulty of
the origin of evil, it admits in its nature of no solution.
It presents an impenetrable mystery.” }
Celsus.— When one fact can be traced to another fat,
it 1s not usual to call the former inexplicable; for 7¢ is
explicated by the latter. Again, whoever assumes that
the origin of evil is an impenetrable mystery, thereby
precludes himself from attempting any explanation of it,
and rejects the explanation offered by others. With —
what consistency, then, can the writer you have quoted
afterwards say, “ Having acknowledged to the full ex-
tent the awful mystery of sin, we might rest our answer
on this mystery?” Clearly, if it be a mystery, the answer
must rest there. But he adds: “ Wholly inscrutable,
there is nothing about it more inscrutable than its -con-
tinued power of resistance to the gospel—than its oppo-
sition to the truth bearing upon it at every point, and
' Theism, pp. 348, 344.
MYSTERY AND CONTRADICTION. 205
summoning it to surrender. A few words of explanation,
however, suggest themselves.” ! It is curious, indeed, to
hear the explanation of what is inscrutable and un-.
known, |
Origen.— But the existence of evil in the world does
not affect the inference which we draw from the good
that is in the world in regard to the Beneficence of Deity.
“ It is certainly puzzling that the works of a good Being
should be in any respect marred by unhappiness. Yet
the partial unhappiness cannot for a moment be entitled
to set aside the prevailing happiness.” ?
Celsus.—If the existence of the partial unhappiness be
an awful and inscrutable mystery, as many of your
friends affirm, so also will be the existence of prevailing
happiness ; unless we act like children who reject the
bitter medicine, and suck the sugar plum. If the good
that is in the world justify some belief in Divine good-
ness, the evil that is in the world must affect our estimate
of the Divine character.
Origen.—“ The very utmost that can be demanded is,
that the more serious aspects of misery which exist in
human life be recognised as difficulties in the way of the
complete theistic inference.” 3
Celsus.—If you even grant, that the evils in the world
are “ negative presumptions,” which “ leave the conclu-
sion of absolute goodness (in God) uncertain on the mere
sphere of nature,”* you abandon the notion of their
mysteriousness ; you allow them to have weight and
+ Theism, p..363. ? Ib. p. 801. *Ib.p.301. .4 Ib. p. 300.
206 DIALOGUE IV.
meaning in the argument; and till they are satisfactorily
explained without detriment to the Divine character,
your conclusion is confessedly uncertain. We observe,
then, a plain.contradiction in this author when he after-
wards asserts: “ It is only the evil (not the good in the
world) that is utterly unintelligible.”’ How can it be
utterly unintelligible, if it be ‘a negative presumption,”
rendering the theistic conclusion uncertain? Neither is
it unintelligible, if, as other Christians affirm, it can be
reconciled with the Divine Goodness. On either suppo-
sition its mysteriousness 1s given up.
Origen.—* But if we could see the whole plan (of
Divine government) in its extended development, many
things that now seem to us exceptional and contradictory ©
might lose this character altogether, and even expand
into special means of advance in the ever-enlarging dis-
play of the Divine beneficence. The mystery which
every where encompasses our finite sphere of observa-
tion, may only conceal from us the wisdom and the good-
ness that are really present in many phenomena where
we cannot even trace them. The limitation of our facul-
ties is thus recognised as in some manner explanatory of
the difficulties that meet us in regard to our subject ;
and it is quite validly so held in a general sense.” ?
Celsus.—In these remarks you speak as if a mystery
must necessarily be an argumentative difficulty. That I
do not understand. We have just seen in a special in-
stance that if the evil in the world be a difficulty in the |
* Theism, p. 303. 2 Th. p. 801, 302.
MYSTERY AND CONTRADICTION. 207
theistic argument it is not a mystery. And if it be a
mystery it cannot be a difficulty. It is an abuse of lan-
guage to affirm, that something which we cannot know,
or do not know, is a difficulty or stumbling-block in re-
gard to what we do know. The reason why a mystery
is supposed to involve a difficulty is, because it is con-
founded with a contradiction, as is done in the above re-
marks. What is unknown or mysterious may be dis-
covered or revealed, and thus “ lose its character,” and
untold to us “ the wisdom and the goodness that are
really present in many phenomena, where we cannot
even trace them” now. But what is “ contradictory ”’
ean never lose its character. ,
Origen.—The author referred to, however, qualified
his observation, thus: ‘ many things that now seem to
us exceptional and contradictory might lose this charac-
ters’:
Celsus.—This only makes the matter worse; it is
strange that so often in our best writers a mystery and
a seemmng contradiction are regarded as synonymous.
Let it be said plainly that a mystery and a contradiction
are the same; and there is an end of the matter—-an
end of all truth, argument, and religion to finite beings.
If this be so, to speak or write as if a mystery were a
seeming contradiction—an incomprehensible, a seeming
absurdity ; 1s a most palpable mystification. You might
as well say, that a guinea is apparently brass. Because,
if what is called a seeming contradiction be a real contra-
diction, why not say so openly and at once, and avow the
208 DIALOGUE IV.
identity of the absurd and the mysterious? If what is
called a seeming contradiction be not a real contradiction,
it is improper to call it a seeming contradiction, except in
speaking of those parties who take it to be what it is not;
and whose error it would be praiseworthy to point out.
Theologus.—Certainly. A mystery is not a contra-
diction, nor, if viewed aright, is it an apparent contradic-
tion. Hence it involves no real or legitimate difficulty.
As to the argument about the prevalence of evil and
misery in this world, it may be observed, that if we are
to base our knowledge of God’s character on the consi-
deration of what God has done, we are bound to take an
impartial view of all the Divine works. It will not do, .
when some facts go against our theory, to set them aside
as mysterious. Our theory must rest on all the facts.
Unless, therefore, we can reconcile the existence and pre-
valence of evil with the Holiness of God, our argument
is uncertain or incomplete. The Bible and reason effect
this reconciliation by referring moral evil to the free
agency of the creature.
Origen.—But is not free agency itself a
mystery ? |
Celsus.— What is more precisely the meaning you in-
clude in this statement ?
Free Agency.
Origen.—* The fact of human freedom is in its very
character inexplicable. This fact transcends the condi-
tions of the logical faculty. It is not only not wonderful
that we cannot understand freedom, but the fact is such
in its very idea that it is impossible we ever can under-
a =) =
tal ec ~~ ew
MYSTERY AND CONTRADICTION, 209
stand it, transcending as it necessarily does that logical
power of which it is the condition. We have no claim to
comprehend it, for (as logicians) we do not contain it—
it contains us.” !
Celsus.—This language seems to mean that the fact
itself is mysterious ; we cannot, then, have even a simple
knowledge that it is true. Unless the fact of liberty can
be expressed in an intelligible proposition, no man can
believe or accept it. How can the author referred to use
the words which you have quoted, and in the very same
page affirm, that “ this fact is to be reasoned from. It
stands at the head of our rational nature as its source ?”
How can we “reason from” a fact, which “ does not
come within the conditions of our logical faculty, but
transcends these conditions?”
Origen.—That author, perhaps, meant that it is the
explanation of the fact that is mysterious; it is ultimate,
and cannot be referred to any other fact.
Celsus.—Does he, then, deny that man is created by
God? Is not our moral liberty referred by theists to
the Creating fiat of Him they «all the Almighty ?
Origen. — He must simply mean that the relation
between God’s sovereignty and our free agency is
mysterious.
Celsus.—If that were his meaning his language is
somewhat inappropriate. Besides, in a few pages further
on he distinctly speaks of this relation and its imcompre-
hensibility ; and therefore, it is the more probable that
1 Theism, p. 260. :
210 DIALOGUE IV.
he really means to say, that the fact of moral freedom
itself is incomprehensible.
Theologus.—This much, at all events seems to be ©
granted, that there is a mystery in the relation between
the freedom of the intelligent creature and the foreknow-
ledge and Sovereign control of the Almighty Creator.
Origen.—This is not generally admitted, for the neces-
sarian scheme of philosophy, which is held by many, is
an attempt to explain as well as defend the prescience of
the omniscient.
Celsus.—But it is the opinion of others, as competent
probably as those you refer to, that this scheme defends
foreknowledge in God by abandoning free agency in
man. This will better appear if we consider the ques-
tions regarding the Providence ascribed to God in the
working of miracles and answering prayer.
Is the mode in which God effects a
miracle, mysterious in your estmiation or not ?
Origen.—The point you mention is mysterious to this
extent at least, that man cannot distinguish between one
mode of the Divine efficiency and another. “To suppose
that, because the order of nature is fixed to us, the
Divine Father cannot exercise through that order a
special providence towards His children, is simply a pre-
sumptuous imagination of the most unworthy kind. To
conceive of any order of events, or any facts of nature,
as less directly connected than others with their Divine
Author, is an absurdity. Only suppose the Deity
equally present in all his works, equally active in all,
Miracles.
re
MYSTERY AND CONTRADICTION, pay
and Providence no longer admits of a twofold apprehen-
sion.” }
Celsus.—This is a fair inference from the principles of
necessity, which assert that in the moral as in the
physical world, every event has for its cause another
event, till we go back to the first fiat of the Almighty
“in the beginning.” If you admit this theory, and the
consequence from it which has just been stated, that a
twofold apprehension of Providence its impossible, then
it is equally impossible to distinguish a miracle from a
common event, or an answer to prayer from the pros-
perity of fools. Ifthe reality of miracles and the effi-
cacy of prayer be given up, you must admit that man’s
free agency is in some danger.
Origen. —“ Because God, for obvious reasons, main-
tains the forth-puttings of His Efficient Energy, after
certain modes which, collectively, we call Nature, why
should this exclude new and special forth-puttings of that
energy, when He may see meet—in other words, when
fitting occasions may arise? Why should such fresh
expressions of Creative Power be supposed to be irregu-
larities, ‘interferences’ in the great plan of creation—
and not, as according to the genuine theistic conception
they truly are, parts in the development of that great
plan contemplated from the first ?”’? | |
Celsus.—If these “ new and special forth-puttings” of
Divine energy do not give us “a twofold apprehension”’
of Providence, we must begin to doubt if one and one
1Theism, p. 66, 67. SUE Pinyin
212 _ DIALOGUE Iv.
make two. Suppose we witnessed ‘‘a fresh expression
of Creative Power,” it must have-something to dis-
tinguish it from the older “ forth-puttings of His Efficient
Energy which we call nature.” If there be “fresh ex-
pressions of Creative power,” “the order of nature is
fixed to us,” not universally and to the last iota, but only
an a limited degree, and one event must be “less directly
connected than ” another with God.
Origen.—Any supposition, similar in its features to
the theory of development, which embraces the causes of
all change and progress, and is limited in its application
to the material world, is not incompatible either with
theism or with Christianity. For the manner in which
these causes have been communicated by the Creator to
matter, whether through occasional interventions or by
continuous agency, may be, in the main, but a secondary
question. It may be known or conjectured that these
different notions of the Divine agency have no ultimate
difference of objective signification, and are equally
true. !
Celsus.—Y our mode of speech is peculiar, and liable to
objection, although it has an air of modesty. Why do —
you say, “It may be known,” “may be a secondary
question?” If it is known, why not say so? if it is not
known, how do you learn that it may be known? But
as to the merits of the question, if a development theory,
embracing “ the causes of all change and progress,” be
limited to the material world, it can be so only on the
* See Christian Theism, vol. i. pp. It1,'4:28,
MYSTERY AND CONTRADICTION. B18
supposition that the moral world has no influence over
the material world. Is this supposition consistent with
facts? Does not the conduct of man, who is a moral
agent, modify and control, to a great extent, the phy-
sical events that take place on the globe? The Deluge
that happened in the time of Noah, had, as you believe,
a moral cause, and it materially affected the changes and
progress of animal and vegetable life. Looking at the
entire range of Providence, as we are bound to do, is
there no difference between an “ occasional intervention”
and a “ continuous agency ?”
Origen.—There seems no ground to affirm a difference.
For “the question of motives internal to the Divine
Nature is manifestly out of our sphere. Reason can bear
us to a Great First Cause, but cannot look into His un-
searchable Nature, much less affirm that the connection
of causes and effects, which is universal within the sphere
of our observation, is in any way applicable to the Divine
Essence.” }
Celsus.—The plea of ignorance is very convenient ; but
is not always valid. The very conception of a miracle
is impossible ; unless you admit a distinction between the
occasional agency of God, and his continuous agency in
general laws. And that occasional agency is impossible,
if “the connection of causes and effects” be “ universal
within the sphere-of our observation.”
Origen.—* But it is here necessary to bear in mind
the distinction between a physical and moral necessity.
* Christian Theism, vol. i. p. 334.
Dt4 DIALOGUE IV.
A doctrine which regards the Divine Agency as neces-
sarily determined by the eternal attributes of Wisdom
and Goodness, and in conformity with their eternal moral
law, is something very different from an evolution of phy-
sical causes.” !
Celsus.—Then this distinction between moral and phy-
cal causes, you regard as determined and without excep-
tion?
| Origen.—Not exactly. “It is worth consideration,
whether the doctrine of human necessity do not verge on
pantheism, at least when the determining causes of the
will, whether physical or moral, are derived by necessity
from the Divine Sovereignty. To deny all originating
power of the will, must be to place the primordial and
necessary causes of all things in the Divine Nature.” *
Celsus.—To deny this distinction in humanity, of which
we know something, and assert it of Deity, into “ whose
unsearchable nature” reason “ cannot look,” is a double
inconsistency. The confusion is only intensified by add-
ing :—‘ Whether it be choice or necessity, that a good
and powerful Being does that which is good, is nothing
more than a question of words.” Nor is the darkness
lessened, when the same author says elsewhere, “ with-
out doubt it must be morally necessary that God will do
what is good and right.” 4. The argument indeed is not
directly affected by the contradiction involved in the two
last quotations. It concerns a man himself alone to assert,
* Christian Theism, vol. i. p. 195. * Ib. p. 196.
* Ib. pp. 195, 196. MAG poe.
MYSTERY AND CONTRADICTION. 215
first, that the distinction between choice and necessity in
Deity is one of words, and secondly, to maintain that
“ without doubt” God “ must” act necessarily. But it
does concern the argument, when in the next page he
writes thus: “It may still be asked,—Does this moral
necessity, that God will do what is good and right, extend.
to the whole agency of the Almighty, and determine His 7
work in the universe to be in all things exactly what it
is? We have here,” he says, “it is evident, a curious
and a useless question.” Now this curious and useless
question is exactly the question between the Pantheist
and the Christian.
Theologus.—To a great extent it is. ‘Io deny the pos-
sibility of miracles is to affirm pantheism. Till we obtain,
therefore, a clear and accurate notion of what a miracle
is, we are certainly not free from the entanglements of
pantheism. And since scarcely two Christian men agree
in their conceptions of a miracle, the intellectual conflict
between pantheism and Christianity is yet undecided. ° It
has yet to be determined in some of the higher questions,
what is the line which separates the most important truth
from the most seductive error.
Origen.—What can be more explicit on the question
than such a statement as this :—“ If the whole pheno-
mena of the universe be one chain of necessary develop-
ment; if man and his actions are strictly inevitable pul-
sations of the one great source of being, then what is
properly called moral evil has no existence.” *
1 Infidelity, pp. 71, 72.
216 DIALOGUE IV.
Celsus.—This writer does not say whether he means
by necessary development, a physical or moral necessity.
He probably meant a physically necessary development ;
and elsewhere you would find him pleading for a moral
necessity. In stating the distinction between these two
necessities, however, he would find the same difficulties
as have now been pointed out in others.
Theologus.—The truth seems to be, that when men
plead for necessity as ruling in the affairs of the universe,
it makes little matter whether it be called moral or phy-
sical; for on either supposition it follows, “that the chain
of endless causation cannot be broken ;” hence miracles
are impossible, and pantheism is unavoidable. |
Origen.—“ But even when it is admitted that the
Divine agency is always ordered according to fixed laws,
which may be called laws of nature, it is a great mistake
to take for granted that these laws are either indepen-
dent of the Deity, or unfit to authenticate a special reve-
lation of His Will.” }
Celsus.—It seems to me self-evident, that if the Divine
agency be always ordered according to fixed laws, it is
impossible that these laws can authenticate a special reve-
lation.
Origen.—Surely “it is no less a miracle, when the
lower law of nature is modified by the higher law, at the
exact time at which it pleases God to make a revelation
of His Will, than if the nature which is known to us were
modified by His immediate interference, Thus, to illus-
* Christian Theism, vol. ii. p. 201.
MYSTERY AND CONTRADICTION. O17
trate by the calculating engine of Mr Babbage, it is no
less a proof of knowledge and of power superior to the
engine itself, to predict that a law which has held good
for a million and one instances will change at the million
and second, than to be able to produce such a change,
by interfering with the movements of the machine.” !
Celsus.— But the prediction of such a change is as
inconsistent with the original supposition as is the effect-
ing of such a change. If the prediction is included in
the Divine agency, which is “ ordered according to fixed
laws,” then the engine should predict the change, or the
illustration fails in the most important point of the com-
parison. If it be granted that the prediction is not the
work of the machine, the assumption that the Divine
agency is always-ordered according to fixed laws is aban-
doned. Besides, the author referred to openly departs
from this assumption, when in the same page he says :—
“after all, it is impossible to ascribe the knowledge of
Joshua that the sun and moon would obey so extraordi-
nary a command, to anything less than an immediate
revelation from heaven.” An immediate revelation must
mean a direct interposition as distinguished from the
working out of an eternal law.
Theologus.—The conclusion to which we are led seems
to be this. The Providence of God must be recognised
as operating sometimes by gencral laws, and sometimes
by special interpositions. And as there is properly
speaking only one kind of necessity, this necessity must
! Christian Theism, vol. ii. pp. 201, 202. %
)
218 DIALOGUE IV.
be denied both of human and Divine actions. We believe
in the necessity of the Divine existence without extending
it to the Divine works; as Augustine says, God changes
his operations but not his purpose ;! and thus we obtain
a well-defined line between Pantheism and a Personal God.
It is our own personality alone that gives us any con-
ception of a personal God. And our power over matter
by working in harmony with the laws of matter may give
us some notion of God’s power to change events, without
changing laws, but by new interpositions in accordance
with these laws or independently of them. If we exclude
special interferences from Divine Providence, and reduce
it all to the carrying out of laws, eternal and immutable,
what mystery remains in the relationship between the
subordinate actions of man and the sovereign control of
God? Liberty, as well as mystery, is altogether ex-
cluded, and nothing but fatalism remains. Fatalism is
not a deep mystery, as some Christians would say; but
a horrid lie, a black contradiction. On the other hand,
admit occasional interpositions of the hand of the Almighty
among the doings of mankind, and there is plainly room
for miracles and pr ophecy and inspiration and answers to
prayer, and there is also before us the unapproachable
mystery, before which we would stand in silent awe,—
How can we be free and yet the Most High predict our
actions ? How can we do our will, and God do His will,
however contrary they may be? How can man purpose,
and plan, and act, as if there were no God, while God
* Conf. Lib. i. ¢. 4.
MYSTERY AND CONTRADICTION. 219
controls his plans and thoughts, no less than his actions ?
Origen.—In attempting to escape from
Scylla you will fall into Charybdis. If
you assume the occasional agency of God to find an
Prayer.
answer to prayer, you must abandon “ the uniformity of
the laws of nature,”—you must deny that “all things are
bound in unerring laws.”
Theologus.—The principle of special manifestations of
Divine power, in addition to His agency through general
laws, does not at all interfere with the uniformity of these
laws. Man can influence the course of events without
changing laws; so surely God can. Afany “ things are
bound in unerring laws,” because there are some laws,
and these laws are uniform. But to assert that “ all
things are bound in unerring laws” is sheer pantheism.
This sentiment, extending the “ inflexible laws of nature,”
“the fixed course of nature,” and so forth, universally to
every event or change which is diffused through our
Christian Theology, cannot be distinguished from the un-
blushing Pantheism which affirms, “ that the forces in-
herent in matter, and those which govern the moral
world, exercise their action under the control of prim-
ordial necessity” —for after all the thing is really the
same whether it be called physical or moral necessity.
Christian theism thus becomes, in reality as well as in
name, ‘‘a pantheism of goodness.”! Pantheism being
the denial of the distinction between good and evil, for
“the possibility of evil is the alternative of pantheism,” ”
* Christian Theism, v. i. p. 198. 2 Ib. p. 203%
220 DIALOGUE IV.
a pantheism of goodness is of course equivalent to a pan-
theism of evil.
Celsus.—How do you account for an answer coming to
prayer on the supposition that all events are fixed by
primordial laws ?
Origen.—Many hypotheses have been framed to meet
this difficulty.
Celsus.—Indeed ! So Christians are at variance on this
point as well as on others.
Origen.—Some regard the reconciliation of these two
facts—the divine response to prayer, and the necessary
concatenation of all events, as impossible, and the relation
between them as mysterious to man.
Celsus.—But the remarks that have been made show
that these two alleged facts are really contradictory and
in opposition to one another. For if the answer to prayer
be the ordinary result of an eternal law, then the event,
which is affirmed to be in reply to a petition, would have
happened independently of the prayer, or else the prayer
itself is only another link in the unbroken chain. And if
your supplications, as well as the events which are called
their answers, be fixedly predetermined from all eternity,
or, in other words, take place according to inflexible laws,
then our responsibility and personality are a mere name,
and Providence resolves itself into a necessary develop-
ment of Deity. |
Origen.—* The divine agency need not be occasional,
fo answer occasional prayers, because infinite wisdom
takes account of all occasional events of finite wills, in
MYSTERY AND CONTRADICTION. 221
the foundation of its eternal plans. Hence the Almighty
does not contravene the laws of nature; He can answer
prayer consistently with them, and by means of them.
All the changes of endless time were spread before Him
in the first constitution of things. That vast plan took
account of all the revolutions of the material world, and
all the movements of the capricious wills of men, and
contained provision for every particular emergency. It
included an answer to every true prayer.”’!
Celsus.—The author should have added ;—It included
also every prayer, true as well as untrue, and his pan-
theistic scheme would have been completed. No pan-
theist ever denied the wisdom of the development of the
Deity in the universe; or, in other words, that this
development is systematic and according to a plan.
Nor has the absolute goodness of this system or plan
been ever questioned. And as to its vastness, that is the
key-stone of the pantheistic doctrine; every change,
mental and material, is included in its universal sweep.
Theologus.—That all the changes of endless time were
spread out before God in the beginning, is involved in the
attribute of omniscience. To reconcile this truth with
the free agency of man, is the question. To us it seems
to be a mystery ; and nothing more can in propriety be
said about it. If it be a mystery, any attempt to dispel
its mysteriousness,—to fathom its depth,—to defend it
by explaining it, will only lead, as we have just seen by
two examples, to self-contradiction.
1 Christian Theism, vol. ii. p. 212.
pe DIALOGUE IV.
Mistakes through Origen. — Still I cannot but think, that
SPACE ARCH: an absurdity and an incomprehensible, —
a mystery and a contradiction, are more nearly related
than you have represented. Maya man not go seriously
wrong through ignorance? “ It has come to be felt and
seen, and to be acknowledged too, on all sides, that
TRUTH, in relation to any particular subject, touching
immediately or remotely the well-being of men — either
the individual man, or the social—can be only one por-
tion of, or one aspect of, UNIVERSAL TRUTH; and that if
we would secure ourselves against mischievous mistakes
and illusions as to that single subject, whatever it may
be, we must know, not merely the whole of itself, but
what it borders upon, and then the bordering of those
remoter neighbours, one upon another ; and so onward
and round about must we advance, until we have fairly
made the circuit of all things, or of all things which it is
granted to man to measure and compass.”!
Celsus.—If we can know nothing accurately and surely
till we have made the entire circuit of human knowledge,
the mass of mankind must be doomed to infidelity or
implicit faith. If our only reasonable security “ against
mischievous mistakes and illusions,” be the possession of
“universal truth ”—a knowledge “ of all things which it
is granted to man to measure and compass,” then indeed
ignorance and error are confounded, and there is no dif-
ference between what is above or beyond our reason and
what is opposed to reason. On this supposition, it is
* Restoration of Belief, p. 4.
MYSTERY AND CONTRADICTION. 205
vain to profess our belief in any truth, till we find, and
profess our belief in, all truth ; and the author you have
quoted departs from his own principle, when he says
elsewhere: “I would not be thought disposed to treat
slightly the catalogue of difficulties that attach to the
Christian argument, at specific pots. Real are some of
these difficulties ; and some are fatal to certain gratuitous
assumptions, held to on the Christian side: not one of
them should be inconsiderately dismissed. But not one
of them touches the integrity of our faith; nor can the
mass entire avail at all to abate the confidence of our
persuasion, that the GospEeL or CurisT is from HEAVEN,
and carries with it an AurHority which time does not
impair, and which eternity shall unfold and confirm.’ !
The presence of difficulties most certainly proves igno-
rance. If this ignorance does not impair “the integrity
of your faith,’ mere ignorance on one point does not
necessarily entail “a mischievous mistake ” on another
point.
Origen. — But these intellectual or logical difficulties
are not so easily got quit of. JI understand the argu-
ment, that if they be mysteries, they are properly speak-
ing no difficulties at all; and if they are contradictions
or absurdities, they lie not in the objects of our thoughts,
but in our thoughts themselves, and are not to be tole-
rated, but cleared away. Still may not these difficulties
be something else than a mere absurdity or incompre-
hensible ?
1 Restoration of Belief, p. 110.
224 DIALOGUE IV.
Theologus.—W hat else may they be?
Origen. — “ The very same body of facts concerning
the woes and disorders — hopeless as they are, and pur-
poseless as they seem, which press upon humanity—
these facts, rudely regarded by the sages of pagan an-
tiquity, and which impelled them to reject the hypothesis
of a Supreme wisdom, benevolence, and power — come
before us now, unchanged or scarcely mitigated, and they
not merely perplex the reason—they do more, they dis-
tract us, because we have been long trained in the medi-
tative converse with an Idea of the Supreme Wisdom,
Benevolence, and Power, immeasurably surpassing any
conception of these attributes which the ancient mind
had ever entertained. That which was an insoluble
problem to the ancient classic reason, is also, to the mo-
dern mind, a problem insoluble ;—but it is more than an
intellectual stumbling-block, for it puts at fault our con-
sciousness of first Truths.”!
Celsus.—Just so, I understand you. These difficulties
are not a sheer absurdity, or we might and ought to
shake ourselves free of them. Neither are they a blank
and fathomless mystery, or else we might, as we ought,
patiently stand humble and self-abased before it. But
they are something, which peels the reason” in such
a way, and so “ distract us,” as not only to present “ an
insoluble problem,” but “an intellectual stumbling-block,”
which “ puts at fault our consciousness of first Truths.”
The only interpretation which I can assign to this de-
* Restoration of Belief, p. 367. ‘
S
MYSTERY AND CONTRADICTION. 225
scription is, that these difficulties are the result and evi-
dence of the fact that consciousness in-man is not trust-
worthy, and that human reason is inherently invyalid—a
sentiment which, as you know, is the ne plus ultra of
scepticism.
Origen. — But whatever may be the nature of these
difficulties, the Bible shews us how to bear them. The
Great Teacher “does not propound the main articles of
a Theistic belief, or speak of them as if they needed to
be ascertained or defended. Much less does He recog-
nise, as if they were a burden upon that belief, the stag-
gering difficulties which oppress us of this age, and with
which the thoughtful in all times have so vainly striven.
That heavy load of troubled speculation which weighs us
down, does not seem to have come into His view when
He invites the weary to seek their rest in Him. This
* Man of sorrows,’ and ‘acquainted with griefs,’ gives no
expression to those griefs which, to many of the thought-
ful and sensitive among His followers, have outweighed
the pressure of the most extreme personal sufferings, so
that they have been tempted to say —‘I am indeed
é afilicted — yet would endure all with cheerfulness, if the
thick darkness that overspreads these heavens were with-
drawn, or if only I could see a verge of the dawn upon
the cloud.’ And yet if we do not find in the teaching of
Christ that which we should so gladly find, we find at
least the rudiments of peace, and a remedy against dis-
traction, which, if we will accept it and use it, brings
with it as much acquiescence as is to be had, in the
226 DIALOGUE IV.
nature of things, on earth; and as much, perhaps, as is
to be found even among those that have encircled the
Eternal Throne since the morning hours of the Crea-
tion.” }
Celsus. — And is this the conclusion of the whole
matter? You admit, that there are “ staggering diffi-
culties which oppress us,’”’ with which it is vain to strive ;
you confess to a “heavy load of troubled speculation |
which weighs us down,” which to the sensitive and
thoughtful “ outweighs the pressure of the most extreme
personal sutferings,” and which drives the earnest and
reflecting wellnigh to the very brink of despair ;—and
then in philosophic mood calmly acknowledge that this
bitter root of mental distress and anguish was left un-
noticed almost, and certainly unmedicated, by Him of
whom you boast as the Great and Able Physician. And
your only solace is the one borrowed from the fatalist and
the atheist, that what little bits of comfort you can pick
up is as much as is to be had “in the nature of things.”
And if this is not enough, console yourself with the
thought, that you are, perhaps, as well off as the best of
your brother creatures. Is this the climax of Theism
and of Christianity ?
Lheologus.—When an individual’s thoughts and senti-
ments are in disorder and mutual conflict, it is a serious
evil. When a man’s meditations upon the grandest and
most important themes are antagonistic and self-contra-
dictory, the more sensitive and reflecting his mind, the
* Restoration of Belief, pp. 371-373.
MYSTERY AND CONTRADICTION. 227
more intolerable will he feel the burden; the more poig-
nant the anguish. It seems to be an undoubted fact,
that through this excruciating ordeal some of the finest
spirits of our race have age after age been observed to
pass. It is well to know precisely the cause of such a
painful and general phenomenon. That we are beset
with mysteries, cannot account for it. That our con-
sciousness deceives us, only makes the darkness deeper
still, and utterly hopeless. That men’s opinions are con-
tradictory, arises from the circumstance of our being in-
volved in many erroneous beliefs, in consequence of our
own and our fathers’ guilt.
There is an obvious and adequate reason to account
for the fact, that the Lord Jesus does not directly notice
or meet the difficulty in question. God in his dealings
towards men seems to act on the principle of parsimony.
He never affords extraordinary means for the accomplish-
ment of an end, which may be accomplished by ordinary
means. The painful confusion and contradiction of
thought which prevail among reflecting men is an evil,
which can be corrected by reason itself. The resources
of the understanding, independently of any special reve-
lation or direct supernatural aid in addition to what the
gospel provides for us as fallen creatures, are of them-
selves sufficient, when diligently and properly employed,
to clear away the intellectual mists which perplex and
bewilder us; and, therefore, these collisions of thought
formed no proper subject for the direct teaching or
immediate interposition of the great, Prophet of mankind.
228 : DIALOGUE IV.
Origen.—By what means then can men deliver them-
selves from the burden of their conflicting thoughts, and
avoid the entanglements of self-contradiction ?
Theologus.—By choosing to be in ignorance, rather than
in error; and preferring “a prudent nescience” to a
false knowledge. |
Celsus.—But people do not like to be found in igno-.
rance, and are ashamed to profess it.
Theologus.—To wish to appear what we are not is
hypocritical; and it is only a morbid modesty that
blushes to acknowledge a normal or proper ignorance.
Origen.—Men won’t distinguish between a commend-
able and a culpable ignorance.
Theologus.—Men are constantly making the distinc-
tion in daily life. Those who refuse to observe it in re-
ligion must bear the consequences.
Origen.—What a revolution it would produce in our
philosophies, if our learned men ceased to be dogmatic
when they should suspend their judgment !
Celsus.—What a revolution would the application of
the same rule effect in the Christian community !
Origen. — Well, no doubt, Christians are often too
hasty in forming their judgment, and plead a conscien-
tious conviction in defence of a rash decision. But our
creeds and confessions are always held in subordination
to the word of God; and we cannot go wrong in follow-
ing the Bible.
Celsus.—May you not go wrong in interpreting the
Bible? Moreover, your creeds and confessions are in
MYSTERY AND CONTRADICTION, 229
great measure a theological reflection of different philo-
sophical schools. The charge, therefore, which you
brought against philosophers resiles upon theologians.
Moreover, not to speak of the ambiguities and doubtful
assertions which Christian creeds certainly contain, how
many a young or half-instructed man is called upon to
pronounce a solemn and dogmatic assertion on points, on
which a suspense of judgment would be more manly and
reasonable.
Lheologus.—It is not only in the improper use of
ecclesiastical symbols, that this evil manifests itself. That
man is prone to swallow a contradiction, rather than
stand silent and humble before a mystery—ready to pro-
fess a knowledge and belief in any thing, and assign the
shallowest reason for his belief, rather than delay deci-
sion while diligently and candidly seeking the truth, is
evident in a thousand forms. Even in those Christian
societies where there is no authoritative or recognised
creed, there may sometimes be found a stereotyped mass
of sentiment, which answers many of the purposes of a
creed, and which may also entail more serious evils. In
all classes of society, and in all the affairs of men, we find
this intellectual malady. The prevalence of premature
judgments, unauthorised decisions, and crude sentiments,
is an evil both general and inveterate. Nor is it lessened,
because it is so commonly concealed, or palliated, or de-
fended, under various pretences, such as patriotism, phil-
anthropy, and religion. Men would surely, if not
speedily, extricate themselves from the most painful and
230 DIALOGUE IV.
perplexing of their inconsistencies, if they would use their
understanding, as they use their feet, and follow the -
prudent maxim of Burke :—“ where he did not see his _
way clearly, he would tread cautiously.”
In making some of the above statements, our design
may be misunderstood. It is not to overthrow, or de-
stroy, but to remove “ those things that are shaken, that
the things which cannot be shaken may remain.” In the
creeds of the churches, written and unwritten, there is
much invaluable truth in which all are agreed, but to make
this agreement manifest a winnowing process is required.
In building up the Christian Evidences, sctentzfically,
or rather in collecting materials for such a building,
much, very much has been well and validly done,
though the structure is by no means complete. And if
some readers have thought us tardy in expressing our
respect for the men whose works we have ventured to
criticise, it is not because we have not felt such emotion
deeply. Christian advocates and Christian arguments
have so much solid truth on their side, that they pass
with advantage through the most rigorous sifting and the
severest purgation. We do wish “ the wood and the hay ©
and the stubble” to be burnt up; but nothing more.
Our motto is, Onward.
DIALOGUE V.
PRACTICAL AND SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGES.
Lheologus.—As to the distinction between practical and
scientific or speculative views, is it not one, which is fre-
quently resorted to by the advocates of Christianity ?
Origen.—We do indeed adduce scientific or dogmatic
proof. ,‘ But, after all, to use the weighty words of Dr
Arnold, ‘ the real proof is the practical one; that is, let
a man live on the hypothesis of its falsehood, the prac-
tical result will be bad; that is, a man’s besetting and
constitutional faults will not be checked ; and some of his
noblest feelings will be unexercised, so that if he be right
in his opinions, truth and goodness are at variance with
one another, and falsehood is more favourable to our
moral perfection than truth ; which seems the most mon-
strous conclusion which the Hens mind can possibly ar-
Five at.’ ” }
Celsus. —If I understand your statement aright, it
amounts to this: that the practical and best evidence in
favour of Christianity consists in an individual's acting
upon its principles, or on the supposition that it is true,
* Infidelity, by Pearson, p. 38.
Zon DIALOGUE V.
and that the reasonableness and sufficiency of this evi-
dence is manifested by the fact, that whoever acts upon
the supposition of its falsehood is reduced to the mon-
strous conclusion that truth and goodness are opposed to
each other. Admitting the force of this reasoning, it will
be necessary to find a clear and satisfactory answer to
these three questions: 1. How shall we
distinguish practical from scientific evi-
dence? 2. Is the practical evidence or proof sufficient of
itself, independently of the scientific ? and, 3. If so, what
additional or specific advantages follow from the scientific
Three questions.
proof ?
Theologus.—It is perfectly fair and most necessary
that these three questions should be distinctly ayswered.
This much will be conceded by all, that anything that
deserves the name of practical proof, must be such, as to
be appreciable by the mass of mankind, without literary
lore or scientific research, and if there be no such prac-
tical evidence in favour of the Christian religion, or if
this evidence by itself be not reasonable in its nature and
sufficient in quantity, the Christian belief of the common
people must be regarded as unintelligent and blind.
Celsus.—It was just now asserted that “the real proof
is the practical one.” Does this mean that by itself it is
sufficient and reasonable ?
Origen. —‘‘ The external and internal evidences of
Christianity constitute a mass of proof fully sufficient to
justify our belief in its truths; and, as if aware of the —
force of it, our modern infidels attack one part of it, and * —
PRACTICAL AND SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGES, 230
represent us as if resting on that, to the exclusion of the
rest.” !
Historical evidence Celsus.—Nay, my friend, it is not we
—Is # practical? ho do so alone, but the author from whom
you quote does so, when he says that “the read proof is
the practical one.” That many Christians rest on part
of the proof which is offered by others, to the exclusion
of the rest, or independently of the rest, is notorious.
Some illustrations of this fact have occurred in this dis-
cussion, and many more might be given. For example,
not a few have asserted that the historical evidence is
the sheet-anchor of your cause,—that it, and it alone,
is sufficient. Is it, then, scientific or practical? If it be
the only. satisfactory and impregnable proof, and yet be
not practical, but scientific, the faith of the common people
is nothing better than superstition.
Origen.—< What means this constant insinuation, that
historical evidence must be wholly without value to men
not learned in history? Is it not manifestly the senti-
ment of our nature—a sentiment so common and rooted
as to seem to be instinctive, that there is a credibility in
historical testimony, even as relating to the mass of man-
kind, sufficient to bring the remote past into a certain and
living connection with the present? Not only is it a fact,
that the least learned are influenced by historical testi-
mony as truly, if not as immediately, as the most learned,
_ but it is manifestly a law of Providence that it should be
so; and it remains to be shewn why the law which em-
* Infidelity, p. 330.
P
234 DIALOGUE V.
braces testimony to this effect concerning Cromwell or
Alfred, should not embrace testimony to the same effect
concerning Paul and Esaias.”!
Celsus.—These statements are not precisely to the
point in hand. It is freely granted that ‘there is a
credibility in historical testimony, even as relating to the
mass of mankind, sufficient to bring the remote past into
a certain and living connection with the present.” The
question is, what is the nature of that connection? It is
admitted by you, that the unlearned are influenced by
historical testimony, not directly but only mediately ; is
that medium such as to be within the reach of the masses,
and is it such as will bear the pressure that is laid upon
it? Is the knowledge which a working man can attain
of Cromwell and Alfred, to use your own illustration, so
precise and authentic, as to be able to support all the
weight of his duty to God, and of his everlasting interests ?
The question is this: Are the historical evidences of
Christianity so palpable and accessible as to be within the
cognizance of the unlettered commonalty, and that in such
a shape as to form a reasonable and sure foundation for Pi
their religious belief? Besides, if there be a practical
evidence real and sufficient independently of the historical
evidence, as is often maintained, why the frequent effort
to make out that the historical is indeed practical proof ?
Origen.—* Beier and Hisrory God has joined, nor
shall man, to the end of time, succeed in effecting a divorce.
Religion, disjoined from History, is a flickering candle,
* Infidelity, p. 186. .
PRACTICAL AND SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGES. 235
held in the hand of one who looks back upon utter dark-
ness behind him, and looks into the blackness of darkness
in front of him,” !
Celsus.—These remarks are somewhat loose, and there-
fore of little argumentative value. Please to explain
yourself more at length.
Origen.— Culture has much to do with that faculty
of the understanding on which history lays a firm hold.
Apart from a certain amount of culture, we do not find
that history, as a reality past, comes home to the intel-
lectual consciousness. Hence springs a disadvantage attach-
ing, in the nature of things, to the labours of those who aim
to impart an historic belief to the masses of the people,
in the way of definite proof. The process finds an indis-
pensable quality wanting in those who are the subjects
of it; hence too, of course, comes that poor advantage
which is snatched at by those whose aim it is to loosen
an historic belief from the minds of the same classes.
There is nothing of arrogance in what is here alleged.” ?
Celsus.—According to this representation of the case,
I can conceive of an intelligent martyrdom in the primi-
tive age of Christianity among the uninstructed classes
of society, but I perceive no room for such a martyrdom
among the same classes in later times.
Origen.—How so ?
Celsus.—State the ground which supported, as you
- suppose, the primitive martyrs in their fiery trial.
Origen.—“ The ground of that Christian fortitude
1 Restoration of Belief, p. 14. 2 1b. pada
236 DIALOGUE V.
which, in the end, prevailed over the polytheism of the
State, was a Beier toward a PERSON; it was not an
opinion as to a doctrine: and here we should take care
to distinguish between the various motives that might
come in to sustain the courage of a martyr in his extre-
mity of suffering, and the onE Grounp on which his
constancy rested. Considerations of personal honour, or
the fear of eternal punishment, or other motives, would
have shewn little intrinsic force, if they had rested upon
an opinion: their power sprang from their connection
with a definite historic belief.” !
Celsus.—Well, then, if “a definite historic belief” be
the “ one ground” of an intelligent martyrdom, hew can
a martyrdom of this character be found among the mass
of modern professing Christians, when the very “process
of imparting an historic belief to them finds in them an
indispensable quality wanting ? ”
Origen.—* Tn all departments of knowledge it is the
Resutts that are for the many ; but the Proczss through
which results have been reached are for the few. Espe-
cially must it be so in the departments of history and
criticism. Results may be rendered into the vernacular ;
and when thus translated they become public property.
Processes of inquiry are carried forward in symbol, and
these signs always imply that a knowledge is already
possessed, ten times outmeasuring that to which the bare
symbol gives expression. The imperfectly educated suf-
fer no real damage on this ground, so long as they are
* Restoration of Belief, pp. 77, 78.
PRACTICAL AND SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGES. 237
not tampered with by sophists. Where the Press, the
Pulpit, the Platform, the Class-room, are quite free,
popular incompetency, as to matters of science or of
learning, as it cannot be much abused by the privileged,
so should it not be wrought upon, flattered, and cajoled
by ambitious declaimers.” !
Celsus.—These statements reveal distinctly the diff-
culty which I have been endeavouring to explain. It is
maintained, that the historical evidences are the most, if
not the only, available and valid proof, and that, of
course, they are practical and popular; while at the same
time it appears that there is a “ popular incompetency,”
in dealing with these evidences; and that “ the imper-
fectly educated suffer no real damage on this ground,”
only ‘so long as they are not tampered with by sophists.”’
It is mere trifling to tell us, that this “‘ popular incom-
petency” “should not be wrought upon, flattered, and
cajoled by ambitious declaimers.” When it 7s so wrought
upon, what are the people to do? Is the following apos-
tolical injunction not addressed to the common people, or
has it been recently repealed :—‘‘ Beloved, believe not
every spirit, but try the spirits whether they are of God?”
Origen.—These things cannot be altered, and ‘“ the
inference hence resulting is just this—that, knowing
_ these things, the well-informed, the honestly-intending,
the seriously-minded, will scorn the easy triumph of
trampling in the dust the Religious Belief of the people
—the uneducated and the half-educated.” *
' Restoration of Belief, p. 18. 2 The p.20:
238 DIALOGUE V.
Celsus.—And this is the conclusion of the whole mat-
ter— “it is an easy triumph to trample in the dust the
Religious Belief of the people!” Is this not quite as
bad in your estimation as what the German philoso-
phy says about the blind and unintelligent faith of the
masses ¢
Theologus.—It thus appears, that what are generally
known as the historical evidences of Christianity are not |
so patent to the popular mind, as to form by themselves
a sure and reasonable ground of their belief. Before
eee eee proceeding to inquire, is there no such
dence—how far sci- practical evidence? it may be well to ask,
oe what is the scientific value of the histo-
rical evidences ?
Origen.—It will not be doubted that “ history is solid
ground; or, to exclude exceptions, let us say that, within
the region it embraces, perfectly solid ground is dis-
coverable in all directions.” |
Celsus.—Explain what you mean by “ solid ground.”
Origen.—Solid ground is manifest, “ when certain his-
toric positions are brought into comparison, as to their
demonstrative value, with any assumed principles of ab-
stract science (not mathematical). It is certain that the
Normans brought the Saxons under their sway in the
eleventh century; but it is questionable whether a chi-
valrous race will always succeed in vanquishing an agri-
cultural and a trading people.” 2
Celsus.—Strictly speaking, the certainty of history, as
* Restoration of Belief, p. 16. SID poli
Sirti:
PRACTICAL AND SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGES. 239
history, lies wholly in its facts. Religious Belief includes
the ought, as well as the is. But you can never deduce
what ought to be solely from the things that are or have
been. The question may be stated otherwise, thus If
miracles, looked upon merely as works of power, be suf-
ficient in themselves to establish the truth of Christianity,
then your historical evidences may be symmetrical and
strictly scientific. But if the structure of your religion
be made to rest upon miracles only in conjunction with
certain moral principles or spiritual congruities, then, till
these principles or congruities be stated and vindicated
in a scientific form, your proof 1s, of course, to be
regarded as scientifically incomplete. Either the whole
weight of Christianity rests upon its miracles alone, or
whatever else is associated with miracles to support your
religion has to be logically expounded.
Origen.—I am aware that many eminent men take
the one side of this alternative, and many as eminent
take the other.
Oelsus.—So here again there is a vital and funda-
mental contradiction among the defenders of Chris-
tianity! Which side do you take?
Origen.—* I can imagine myself to have so profound
a sense of primary moral truths, as that miracles would
be confluent with the deep movements of the soul, and
» 4]
would produce no surge. “ The miracles of the evan-
gelic history come to us with the force of CoNnGRUITY,
. just so far as we can bring ourselves morally within the
1 Restoration of Belief, p. 224.
240 DIALOGUE V.
splendour of those eternal verities which are of the sub-
stance of the Gospel.”’ “Throughout the epistles (of
the New Testament) morality is made to rest upon the
solid basis of universal and permanent religious considera-
tions.” ? The writers of these epistles “do not throw
the stress of any ethical argument upon the supernatural
attestations of their message.”* “It is my steadfast
conviction that Christianity will not henceforth maintain
its ground, as related to the present intellectual condi-
tion of instructed communities, so long as ‘ Christian
apologists’ (so called) take up a position upon the ‘ out-
works,’ or spend their efforts upon the well-meant but
fruitless endeavour to put forward the ‘ Historic Evi-
dences,’ apart from that Princrpa Trutu, which forms
the substance of the Gospel. So long as this Principal
Truth does not occupy its due position in the mind and
faith of the writer, and so long as it is not boldly pre.
sented to the mind of the reader, there is a conscious-
ness, on both sides, of an interior incoherence in the Sys-
tem itself: there is a painful and perplexing feeling of
incongruity, which sets these evidences a jarring, as
well in a logical as in a moral sense, one against an-
other.” 3
Oelsus.— Very good. It is abundantly obvious, then,
that till this Principal Truth be not only found, but
found to be “a truth ;” till « the solid basis of universal
and permanent religious considerations” be laid bare to
inspection ; till the “eternal verities which are of the
’ Restoration, p. 224. * Tbhopp: 173,174: 5 Ib. p. 81%:
a
PRACTICAL AND SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGES. 241
substance of the Gospel,” or “ primary moral truths,” be
investigated, and stated and vindicated, the historic evi-
dences must be considered as scientifically incomplete ;
and you are necessarily driven in defence of Christianity
to speculative or ethical Philosophy.
Origen.—God forbid; for, “however abundant may
be the means available for constructing a Theistic Doc-
trine, and however irresistibly conclusive the argument
may be on this ground, yet, if we rigidly deduct from it,
as we ought, all aids and materials that are due, directly
or indirectly, to the Hebrew and Christian canonical
books, we then find ourselves in an undefended—an in-
defensible position as towards the very darkest of those
surmises which take their rise from that spectacle of
misery and disorder which the human family has every-
where, and has always, presented. On this road, has
not the Terminus been reached long ago? If it were
required of us “to report progress” in the department
of Abstract Philosophy, let me be told whether, as honest
men, we could affirm that those who profess to shake off
every restraint of theological bias and religious preju-
dice, have at length reached a scientific position, which
is so solidly based, and which is so well defined, as that
it commands the assent, and may boast the adherence of
all well-constituted and disciplined minds? If there be
any such Philosophy which is now available as a resting-
place for the human mind, it must surely be easy to
name it. No such Philosophy can be named.” *
1 Restoration, pp. 318, 319.
242 DIALOGUE V.
Celsus.—But it is unquestionable that till such a Phi-
losophy can be named your historical argument is defec-
tive and inconclusive on your own shewing. You have
reduced yourself to the necessity of travelling on this
road, and if the Terminus be already reached, and be so
dark and dreadful as you have represented it to be,
Christianity should no longer refuse to shake hands with
infidelity as her sister and friend.
Theologus.—It is a mere gratuitous assumption, to say
that the Terminus has been reached,—that men can
achieve no more than has been already done in the field
of abstract thought or ethical science. It is another illus-
tration of the fallacy, which reasons from what has been
done in moral questions, to what might have been done,
or what ought to be done, or what may yet be achieved. ©
There is, and there can be, no resource against philoso-
phical scepticism, but in the satisfactory establishment of
the Fundamental Principles of human belief. If this
work is not yet performed, it must be done; and the
sooner the better.
Origen.—* You will not tell me that a consciousness is
unreal, merely because I fail in my endeavours to give it
intelligible expression, or indeed to put it into words at
all. Do not the uncultured minds around us possess a
genuine consciousness, as to moral principles, in behalf
of which, either to explain or to defend them, they would
not have a word to say?” }
Celsus.—You are now away from the scientific argu-
* Restoration, p. 226.
eit
PRACTICAL AND SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGES. 243
ment, and taking refuge in the practical. You are aban-
doning the position which the same author thus marks
out :—“ The earliest developed of the beneficial results
of an outburst of Infidelity is this, that it compels intelli-
gent Christian men to look anew to the ground on which
they stand, to sift the ‘Evidences,’ and thus to regain
logical possession of their religious persuasion.” ' Here,
then, it is distinctly avowed that your controversy with
us tends to enable you to regain in another form what
you already possessed. You were persuaded of the truth
of Christianity before you ever listened to an infidel ar-
gument. Your investigation of these arguments does not
shake your faith, but gives you a logical possession of
that faith. Now, we have just seen that a logical pos-
session of that faith implies a knowledge not only of
certain historical facts, but of certain “primary moral
truths” also. And when we ask for a logical statement
of these primary moral truths, we are referred, on the
one hand, to the dense and troubled darkness of Abstract
Philosophy, and on the other hand, to the misty vague-
ness of the popular consciousness. Is this not an evasion ?
Origen.—Let us, then, take the practical view of the
case.
Celsus.—You cannot do so, without ad-
journing, for the time being, its scientific
aspect; and in doing so, we beg to recall your attention
to the three questions proposed in the earlier part of this
dialogue.
Practical Evidence.
1 Restoration, p. 247.
244 DIALOGUE V.
Origen.—* Those of our convictions upon which we
are accustomed to act with the most unhesitating confi-
dence, and to which we commend ourselves without fear,
when life itself, or estate, is at risk, are not, or seldom
are, those which we may obtain by processes of catenary
deduction ; or by a course of reasoning which, in a tech-
nical sense, is logical. It is not so. Man, such as we
find him, on the beaten road of real life, is no such syllo-
gistic automaton, as that he should bring propositions in
threes to bear upon the business and conduct of every
day. Pedants do this, and break their heads in conse-
quence.” !
Celsus.—Ha! So you think some other men break
their heads as well as infidels? What, then, is your
practical reason for being a Christian—a reason, which
shall stand clear and independent of all learned lumber
and misty abstractions, and which shall be palpable and
satisfactory to an untutored mind ?
Origen.— It is on no ground of its abstract credi-
bility, that this fundamental fact of the Christian life
(the Resurrection of the Lord Jesus) is accepted by those
in whom that life has indeed had its commencement. As
to those of them who are informed and intelligent, they
can at all times fall back upon that body of evidence
which secures them against disbelief. But going far
beyond any such merely intellectual persuasion, Christ’s
true disciples have a sense of the import of His resurrec-
tion, which renders them, except as towards others, indif-
* Restoration, pp. 220, 221.
¢ * ee
PRACTICAL AND SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGES. 245
ferent to logical methods of proof. Ask them for a reason
of their faith, and they can well meet the challenge; but
having done so, they retire to a ground of consciousness,
concerning which no distinct conveyance can be made
from mind to mind, through the medium of language.
Verbal propositions do not represent those intuitions
within the circle of which this conviction takes place.” !
Celsus.—If I understand the statements which you
have adduced, they amount to this, that the true and
powerful reason why a man becomes a Christian is to be
found, not in “ processes of catenary deduction,” but ina
“sense,” or feeling, which renders believers, so far as they
are themselves concerned, “ indifferent to logical methods
of proof.” An individual becomes a Christian, not by
“bringing propositions in threes to bear upon the busi-
ness,” but on ‘‘a ground of consciousness concerning
which no distinct conveyance can be made from mind to
mind, through the medium of language.”
Celsus.—Much more might be quoted from this author
in confirmation of these views; but like many others he
does not adhere consistently to his principles. Having
admitted only one kind of certainty in human knowledge,
he speaks elsewhere as if that certainty had suffered a
total shipwreck. For example, he says, ‘man has in
himself no infallible criterion of right and wrong, and can
1 Christian Theism, vol. i. p. 162. hep 16. 2 Ao an ey
286 DIALOGUE VI.
have none, not even from revelation, because what is in-
fallible in itself, becomes fallible in his interpretation of
it.”! If we understand this, it means that human cer-
tainty is not a genuine but counterfeit certainty, and
when we feel certain, we are only certainly deceived.
If no human interpretation of the Bible be infallible, or,
which is the same thing, true, your certainty is but a
broken reed; if every reflection of the glory of your
God (to use your own metaphor) from the mirror of his -
word carries a distorted image to every eye that looks
upon it, the mirror must be imperfect, or is the same to
you as if it were imperfect.
Theologus.—Certainty, when legitimately attained, must
be held in all cases to be infallible—otherwise you pro-
claim a divorce between eternal immutable truth and the
human mind. An individual man is fallible, inasmuch as
he is responsible,—that is, has the power to use aright, or
wantonly abuse, the faculties of his mind. To cast any
doubt or uncertainty upon the conclusions of the under-
standing, when it is properly employed, is one of the
snares of scepticism into which it is marvellous to find
so many Christians falling.
Origen.—What objection can possibly be taken to the
following statement: “We affirm that the kind and
amount of evidence offered in support of Christianity
suffice to meet the demands of reason, inasmuch as we
are involved in many more, and much greater difficulties,
by the rejection, than by the admission, of the proof
* Christian Theism, vol. ii. p. 80.
CERTAINTY AND PROBABILITY. 287
tendered to us. And this is the highest kind of moral
demonstration that the subject will admit of.” !
Celsus. — This admission of difficulties, which need to
be compared and weighed, so as to have their respective
values estimated and a balance struck between them,
brings us back to the old ground of preponderating evi-
dence, and degrades your religion from the eminence of
certainty to the changing sands of probability, where only
a few of its modern advocates are contented to leave it.
And when you are pleased to add that “ this is the
highest kind of moral demonstration that the subject will
admit of,” the remark is a rebuke to some of your own
friends rather than an assault upon us.
Origen.—How are we to get out of this dilemma?
Is religious know. Leologus.— The course of argument
ledge certain? = nurgued in these discussions suggests a way
of escape. If the difficulties referred to be mysteMes,—
depths which we cannot fathom, they are not, properly
speaking, argumentative difficulties at all. If these diffi-
culties be conflicting statements in the evidence or con-
tradictory principles in reasoning, they must suspend our
judgment so far as they extend. Jf it be really the case
that such difficulties do attach themselves to the great
Christian argument, viewed scientifically, the conclusion
must be regarded as no more than probable. But then
it is not to be allowed to be unlikely, far less impossible,
that these difficulties shall be cleared away. On the con-
trary, it is to be hoped that we shall ere long find our-
1 Bases, p. 256.
288 DIALOGUE VI.
selves in possession, even speculatively, of a certain know-
ledge of the Truth, through humble and unwearied
investigation. Meanwhile, so long as these difficulties shall
beset our path, and constrain us to admit that our conclu-
sion in favour of Christianity is, philosophically, only
probable, we have the practical certainty on which to fall
back, namely, the indubitable principle universally ac-
cepted by mankind in the affairs of life, that in dealing
with probabilities it is dutiful and wise to take the safe
side, and avoid all needless risk.
Origen.—lIt does, after all, seem to be extravagant to
reduce all our religious and moral knowledge to a pulpy.
mass of probability. For what can be more obvious than
this, that “reasoning proceeds from the known to the
unknown — from what is certain to what is proble-
matical?” ’ So that if we had no certainty in religion
we could not have a probability either.
Celsus.—It is an equally clear inference from what has
been advanced, that if there be no certainty apart from,
and independent of, a written revelation, that revelation
cannot confer certainty.
Origen.—There is, of course, certainty in many de-
partments of knowledge independently of the Bible;
and it is easy to draw the line between matters of pro-
bability or opinion and matters of certainty in history
and in the sciences both mathematical and physical. For
“itis a mistake, and a prejudice, fertile in errors, to ima-
gine that opmton belongs to one department, and
1 Bases, p. 6.
Eg et ee
—
CERTAINTY AND PROBABILITY. 289
CERTAINTY to other departments; as if the honours and
immunities of an exemption from the toils of controversy
were the class-privilege of this or that aristocratic
science.” !
Celsus.—This is very good, and is a severe castigation
of those whose sentiments were formerly noticed, and who
seemed to rest satisfied without that certainty in religion
‘and morals which is possessed in other branches of know-
ledge. You now claim the same, or a similar, certainty
in your Christian belief, as is acknowledged to belong to
the sciences, even the mathematical. The question which
I would now propose for your consideration is this : Does
On what does reli- YOur religious certainty rest solely and
gious certainty rest? entirely on what you call the written
revelation ?
Origen. — One palpable mark of distinction between
heathen and Christian nations surely is to be observed in
the fact, that the latter possess what the former are
destitute of, religious certainty.
Theologus.—It ought to be remembered that the ques-
tion is not now regarding the objective truth of Christian-
ity and heathenism (certainty is sometimes used in this
sense); but the question is, have Christians a feeling of
certainty in their hearts respecting the truth of their
religion which heathens do not experience?
Celsus.— Many Christian writers are loud in their la-
mentations over the comparative lethargy and lukewarm-
ness of protestants, as contrasted with the self-denial and
Restoration, p. 117, &c.
290 DIALOGUE VI.
devotedness of papists and idolaters in their religious
services. One of your poets has expressed it thus: “In
Christian hearts, oh! for a pagan zeal.” Religious zeal
and religious certainty have surely some connection with
each other.
Origen.—You are forgetting that there is a false zeal,
and a false certainty too.
Celsus. — What, then, is the difference between the
false certainty and the true ?
Dee Theologus.—The principles brought out
ra a ai in the course of this discussion may, per-
haps, answer your question. When a man
embraces error in any form whatever, he cannot do so
without at the same time doing some violence to the
better portion of his nature, —without practising, somehow
or other, deception upon himself. He may, of course,
work himself up into a certain persuasion that his error
is truth ; but this certainty will ever retain infallible indi-
cations of its spurious origin. It will ever be of a totally
different character and constitution, the man himself
being judge, from that simple and genuine assurance
which is the result of thorough honesty. The zeal which
springs from legitimate certainty will be just and kind,
calm and irrepressible. The spurious zeal of a counter-
feit certainty will be passionate, fickle, and cruel. The
religious assurance of the Christian believer, even in its
modesty, is thus easily distinguished from the blustering,
intolerant, or malignant zeal of every enthusiast.
Origen.—It will not be denied, however, that at least
CERTAINTY AND PROBABILITY. 291
in some states of the heathen world, the characteristic
feature of society has been that of a painful want of cer-
tainty in religion. For example, in the days of Alex-
ander Severus, Emperor of Rome, when Christianity
was about to win one of its most important triumphs,
“ uneversal incertitude was the chacteristic of the times ;
the gloom of that moral dismay which comes upon cul-
tured minds, when they abandon in despair the long-
cherished hope of seizing upon truth and certainty — of
knowing something beside the theorems of Euclid — of
grasping in the hand a stay immoveable. . . . Let
any one whose course has not been altogether sensual,
or merely busy, but who has known what are called
‘exercises of mind,’ go back to those moments of his life
when convictions, beliefs, persuasions of every kind,
were passing from his view, and when nothing remained
to him but a dread uncertainty, and the feeling that
never again should he grasp a truth. In the recollection
of such a season one would not reject the figure as inap-
propriate, if it were called the night-time of the soul ;
and not less so, although all the splendours of literature
and science were then glittering around him. It must
be so: for the first necessity of man’s higher nature is
TRUTH, and the despair of finding it is indeed — a dark-
ness that may be felt.” }
Celsus.—It. has been already conceded, that if a man
has no knowledge whatever of truth, he can have no
responsibility. To speak of the dread uncertainty of
1 Restoration, pp. 47, 48.
292 DIALOGUE VI.
never being able again to grasp a truth, must be either
an extravagant statement, or the description of a most
morbid feeling. If an individual has some true know-
ledge, he has some certainty. If a man has no know-
ledge of truth, and no certainty in himself, till a book is
put into his hands, that book can communicate neither
certainty nor truth. What use can an unintelligent bemg
make of a book ?
Theologus.—The whole perplexity will disappear, if
we bear in mind that the Bible comes to us, not only
as revealing some truths that are unknown, but also as
assuming other truths as known to man. This statement
has been strangely overlooked, although it is plainly
implied in the very character of a revelation from God
to responsible and intelligent beings, and is confirmed by
almost every page of the Bible itself. As there is no end
to the vagaries of error and the follies of mankind, it is
a very possible thing for persons to work themselves up
into any conceivable state of madness or despondency.
We would not, therefore, for a moment question the
accuracy of the alleged fact, that some individuals, more
or less, may be found, whose real condition, or fancied
condition, is one that cannot be otherwise described
than that of total doubt or blank despair. As to the
few who may be in such a state, it will not be denied
that such a state is the result of personal or heredi-
tary guilt, and that its horrible darkness will not be
long protracted, provided an individual deal honestly
with himself.
CERTAINTY AND PROBABILITY. 293
Origen.—But do you mean to affirm that we can
joes attain any sort of religious certainty
tainty apart from the without the aid of the Bible and Chris-
ee tianity ?
Theologus.—To assert that any one could attain a cer-
tain knowledge of God’s mercy in Christ, and the way
of salvation, except through Divine revelation, were
indeed fool-hardy ; for this is one of the great truths, if
not the greatest, specially revealed. But do you deny
or doubt, that every man may, and that many men do,
attain a certain knowledge of their guilt and wretched-
ness without any Biblical assistance? Can it be ques-
tioned that the word of God, over and over again,
asserts or assumes the validity of the divine law writ-
ten on the human heart? The validity of this law,
not only in man’s pristine condition, but even now
and in the densest darkness of heathenism, as avail-
able to guide a man’s footsteps so far, and to con-
demn him if not obeyed, is plainly implied in many
passages of the Bible. From the very nature of the
case it must be so.
Origen.—But the great mass of men who are ignorant
of Christianity have not this certain knowledge of their
guilt and misery.
Theologus.—You cannot, however, infer from this,
that therefore they have not the means of attaining
it. They may have the means without employing
them; just as a great number of those who may
be said to know Christianity are equally destitute
294 DIALOGUE VI.
of this certain knowledge of their wretchedness and
sin.
Origen.—On what, then, does the certainty of our
knowledge rest ?
Theologus.—It can rest on nothing else
than the immutability of Truth, and the
validity of the human understanding. Truth itself is
eternal and unchangeable. When any truth is found by
the mind while honestly and diligently seeking for it, the
mind is conscious of having found the truth. The clear
Grounds of certainty.
and satisfactory consciousness of having found truth is
the only possible, and an amply sufficient, basis of cer-
tainty.
Celsus——So you agree with us, that “the basis of
certitude lies in the essential characteristics of the intui-
tions themselves—in their distinctness, in their unifor-
mity, and, under due influences, in their universality ;
not in their symbolical representation upon the sacred
page.”
Origen. And you take part with the enemies of the
gospel in removing the basis of religious certitude
“from the Bible page to the religious consciousness of
humanity.” By your decision “ the test is shifted from
the inspired Book—the law and the testimony—to a
comparison of inward experiences.” '
Theologus.—Your conclusions are rather too hasty,
my friends. ‘Truth, as formerly explained, presupposes
in every instance an object known as well as a subject
1 Infidelity, pp. 211, 212.
=—s
CERTAINTY AND PROBABILITY. 295
knowing, being the agreement of the thought within us
with the object about which we think. A clear con-
sciousness, then, that we know any object which is exter-
nal to ourselves, implies that by some means or other we
have got beyond ourselves, and come into intercourse or
contact with that object, so as to know it. Hence, there-
fore, the basis of certitude does not lie in the essential
_ characteristics of purely subjective intuitions. Knowledge,
or what is worthy of the name of knowledge, never is,
and cannot be, purely subjective. Knowledge is the act
of the knowing agent going forth upon, seizing, and
holding the object known; it is a transition from the
subjective to the objective. Normal or true knowledge
consists in making this transition in a due and proper
manner. And certainty consists in the consciousness that
we have done so.
Now, this representation of the case does not remove
the basis of religious certitude from the Bible page to
human consciousness. But this language conveys alto-
gether an inaccurate conception of the matter. For sup-
pose a truth which we know independently of the Bible
entirely, such as the fact that guilt prevails in human
society, and that we ourselves have been offenders
over and over again, our certainty as to this truth lies
plainly in the distinct and unhesitating consciousness
that our understanding has gone beyond its own im-
mediate precincts, by some medium or other, and
grasped events in the external world. In this case
it is altogether irrelevant to talk of our certainty
296 DIALOGUE VI.
being “removed from the Bible page to human con-
sciousness.”
Some one may now say, oh! but I know that man is
a sinner, just because the Bible says so. Very well. But
remember, that whoever says there is no other means of
knowing that men are guilty, but the statements of the
Bible, contradicts the Bible itself. And even if you
believe in the depravity of man simply and soely because
the Bible inculcates this doctrine, it is incorrect to say
that the ground of your certainty is not human con-
sciousness, but the page of the Bible. The real basis
of your certitude in this instance, is unquestionably
your own consciousness that such is the teaching of the
Bible. |
Lastly, as to those all-important truths which man has
no means of knowing but through the page of inspira-
tion, such as justification by faith, and sanctification
through the Holy Spirit, to set the page of the Bible
against human consciousness in discussing the ground
of our certain knowledge and belief of these saving doc-
trines, is sheer folly. The foundation of our assurance
as to these precious truths is, and can be, nothing else
but our vivid and unembarrassed consciousness that the
Bible is indeed the word of God, and that these glorious
and blessed doctrines are revealed therein. In stating
these views, we appeal to those who feel “that it is not
a greater happiness to inherit a good religion, than it is
a fault to have it only by inheritance; that it is the
greatest of follies to neglect any diligence that may pre-
ae *;
4 =
=
7
CERTAINTY AND PROBABILITY. 297
vent the being mistaken where it is the greatest of
miseries to be deceived ; and that how dear soever things
taken upon the score are sold, there is nothing worse
taken up upon trust than religion, in which he deserves
not to meet with the true one that cares not to examine
whether or no it be so.”
DIALOGUE VIL
THE STANDARD OF MORALITY.
Origen.—* In none of the classic schools do we find a
moral doctrine at once adequate and consistent. This is
only to be found in the revelation of Jesus Christ.” }
ways Celsus.—In order to feel yourself com-
Is there a criterion? i
petent to pronounce this decision, you must
be in possession of some standard of morality. Being in
possession of that standard, you test by means of it, first,
the moral doctrine of the classic schools, and next the
moral doctrine of the New Testament, and then pronounce .
your verdict, that the first comes short of the standard,
and that the second comes up to it. Just as a merchant
cannot determine the respective lengths of two pieces of
silk, till he apply to both the standard measure.
Origen.— Well, of course, we have a standard, if such
you choose to call it, namely, conscience; to which we
appeal in proof of the existence and character of God.
“It is not merely to the fact of a divine power that con- ’
science testifies, but eminently to the character of that —
power. The moral law, which it reveals, is not simply —
1 Theism, pp. 351, 352.
THE STANDARD OF MORALITY. 299
the expression of a supreme Will, but of a Will which is
essentially good and righteous.” '
Celsus.—In these remarks you base Theism upon the
moral law given by conscience; and elsewhere it isasserted,
“that morality only finds a valid basis in a theistie doc-
trine.” ?
IT hambly submit, that some explanation is here
required. Religion and morality may be allowed in their
practical working mutually to support each other ; but ulti-
mately you must rest the one upon the other, or give to
both an independent foundation. So also, when you affirm
that there is “in the teaching and character of Christ a
rare exhibition of wisdom and goodness,” that “ He taught
a pure and exalted morality,” and remind ‘those who re-
pudiate the Divine authority of Christianity,” that they
do not deny these assertions,* is it not plain that you
appeal to some criterion in morality, independent of the
Christian Scriptures, whose authority is acknowledged in
common by you and by us? What is that criterion ?
Theologus.—The question is perfectly legitimate and
fair. And it is one of the weakest points in the Christian
apologetics, that this question is not only not satisfactorily
answered, but not even calmly and courteously enter-
tained.
Is conscience the Ortgen.—Is not conscience the criterion ?
as * All the authority of this faculty is on the
side of righteousness and truth; it has sanctions for the
enforcement of its utterances; it approves the good, and
denounces the evil.”’4 Have we not a standard “in the
+Theism, p. 274. 7 Ib. p. 373. *%Ib. 350. 4 Infidelity, p. 33.
300 DIALOGUE VII.
supremacy of conscience, enthroned, as it were, above the
whole (of our faculties), and ever uttering her voice on
the side of whatsoever things are true, and lovely, and of
good report, and against their opposites; and not only
so, but rewarding well-doing, and punishing wrong-
doing ?”}
Celsus.—In every such appeal as this which is made
to Conscience, you are doing the very thing which you’
blame us for doing. You affirm that something subjec-
tive, something within us, it matters not whether it be
called reason or conscience, “is to be umpire in every
dispute ;” that “there are laws of the mind, which are
exact and uniform, and which are absolute tests to man,
and by means of them the pretensions of every doctrine
must be decided.” 2 If consicence really be what you
have now claimed it to be, then why sneer at us for
maintaining, “that each man possesses in his own mind
the power of discerning the absolute truth, so that every-
thing supposed to be included in religion is to be tested
by this intuitive susceptibility or power?” You tell us
that we exchange “an infallible Bible for an infallible
Self.”* In your description of conscience you make it
infallible; for otherwise you could never reach an infal-
_ lible Bible. When you have reached an infallible plat-
form, to deny the assistance, or destroy the ladder, by
which you ascended, is not the best way to persuade
others to join you. . 3
Origen. —“ Two things are here confounded: the
’ Infidelity, p. 34. ? Ib. p. 166. * Ib. p. 169. ‘Ib. p. 170.
THE STANDARD OF MORALITY. 301
capacity for receiving religious truth, and the capacity of
unaided reason to discover it.”?
Celsus.—You have claimed for conscience, as is con-
stantly done by others, a great deal more than a simple
capacity for receiving religious truth. It will dono good
to confound what you have now distinguished. But if
you deny to man independently of the Bible, all moral
and religious knowledge, and assert that he has only a
capacity to receive it when the Bible comes before him,
then, how with any consistency can you speak of “ the
clear imperishable utterances of our moral nature,”? and
express your willingness “ to abide by a fair trial of the
contents of the revelation itself;”2 inasmuch: as the
“nature of the doctrine must be taken into account, as
well as the external evidence which attests it? 2
Theologus.—The key to the whole is found in the fol-
lowing statement, which I am afraid has not recieved due
attention from either party. “It is not enough for our
author to say, as all sensible men have ever said, that
our knowledge of ‘the true, the beautiful, and the good,’
coines to us in part from our intuitions; he is peremptory
in asserting that it comes to us only from that source—a
doctrine which can never be made to harmonize with any-
thing deserving the name of philosophy ; and which must
prove eminently hostile to the purity of religion.”? This
is the gist of the whole controversy. Christians are con-
stantly affirming we have no moral or religious know-
1 Infidelity, p. 173. “1h. ern eae
* Quotation in Infidelity, pp. 201, 202.
302 DIALOGUE VII.
ledge without the Bible; and infidels are perpetually
crying, the Bible can give us no additional knowledge to
what we have without it. Both statements, we appre-
hend, are wrong.
et Origen.—It is affirmed that mankind
Baer ener have no moral and religious knowledge
except what they derive from the Bible,
and that for two substantial reasons. First, In point of
fact nobody can tell us what that knowledge is; and
secondly, the supposition of its possession is unnecessary
in conducting the Christian argument. If men possessed
religious knowledge and a moral law independently of
the Bible, these might be allowed to form a criterion, if
we only knew what they were. ‘‘Are not the vast
majority of men at this moment—have they not been in
all ages—bowing down to stocks and stones ; worshipping
all sorts of false deities, and honouring them with rites
well worthy of them? Has there not been among vast
communities for unknown ages, the easiest reception of
the most hideous superstition, the most unshrinking, un-
questioning perpetration of the most horrible cruelties
and pollutions in obedience to even the falsest pretensions
of priestcraft? Is it not the rarest thing to find men
evincing any capacity for criticising the religious and
moral systems by which their faculties have been swathed
and bound from infancy? It is plain they do not.”!
Celsus.—The facts are admitted as you describe them.
They are, however, of no avail in the argument, unless
1A Defence of the Eclipse of Faith, p. 104.
4
ph
:
Mf
4
‘i
w
S
a
.:
ig
f
>
‘
|
THE STANDARD OF MORALITY. 303
you infer from them, as your author does, that the
heathen could not do any better than they did, and con-
sequently are not guilty and worthy of condemnation,
but are simply objects of commiseration and pity. Now
your Bible affirms that they are guilty ; and Iam surely
right in inferring that they could have done, and ought
to have done better. Moreover, the author referred to is
constrained to admit that men have, or may have, some
knowledge independently of divine revelation, when he
says that we are allowed “partially to judge of God’s
character, rights, and jurisdiction.” !
Origen.—Well, then, do tell us what your standard is;
set before us “the fixed basis of morality,” ‘ the common
conscience and heart morality.” _“ Is it an absolutely in-
variable standard, or a variable one that is spoken of? or
is it a measure of India rubber that will hold three
bushels or one? Whose ‘fixed moral basis?’ That of
the New Zealander, or of a Hottentot, or of an ancient
Greek, a Roman, a Jew, or of a Hindoo, or of a Chinese,
or of an Englishman? For all these have had very dis-
cordant notions on many points of morals, and therefore
(as well as for other reasons) about God. Or is every
body in general meant, and nobody in particular?” *
Celsus.—Your argument has two edges. The Bible is,
of course, your criterion or basis. But the Bible is no-
thing to anybody except as it is understood or inter-
preted. Now, pray, whose interpretation of the Bible is
your fixed moral and spiritual basis? Which doctor is
1A Defence, &c., p. 48. 2 Tby p. 105.
304 DIALOGUE VII.
your authority? Whose doctrine is your standard—
that of Arius or Luther; that of John Knox or John
Wesley; that of Canterbury or the Vatican; that of
Calvin or Arminius; that of the Quakers or Moravians;
that of Sandemanians, or Hutchinsonians, or Swedenbor-
gians, or Muggletonians, or Fifth-monarchy men ?
Lheologus.—The mere fact that a moral and religious
standard is not known, or not recognised, or not obeyed,
whether among heathens or Christians, cannot be ad-
mitted as evidence that there is in reality no such stan-
dard at all, or that it cannot be found by a diligent and
honest search.
Origen.—But the existence of a moral standard, inde-
pendently of the Bible, is quite irrelevant to the Chris-
tian argument. For “the first principle of morals is
the implicit submission of a creature to the Creator,
absolute surrender of the finite to the Infinite, whose
declared will is of itself all-sufficient authority.” ! “The
authority of God is of itself, even if no reasons were
given, and none were imaginable but his will, the suffi-
cient and all-sufficient authority.” ?
Celsus.—Your principle, then, is this, that actions are
right, simply because God wills them; and you reject
the other principle, that God wills them because they are
right. On this supposition, our argument would clearly
be at an end, provided you adhered to your own
assumption. But this you cannot do. If actions are
right, simply because God wills them, then God cannot
+ A Defence, &c. p. 107. aie sae Sty
THE STANDARD OF MORALITY. 305
manifest his righteousness to his intelligent creatures.
But you say that “the Bible theory . . . . does
not shut the door against the possibility of God’s proving
himself a moral Governor; on the contrary, assures us
that he He will prove himself an exact one.”! And in
the very next page of the same book an appeal is made
to “the general convictions of men in all ages,” and to
certain “moral intuitions,” to shew that such a being as
some persons call God “is not the God of human con-
sciousness.”
Origen.—We admit, of course, the receptivity of the
human mind; its power to acquire know-
me ledge. “I see that men have moral capa-
cities; but I see also with my own eyes, and other men
see it too, that those capacities, as they are variously
developed, lead to the most various and erroneous ‘ moral
judgments,’ and consequently also to the most various
and erroneous conceptions of the Deity. They are in
every man, as is the instrument that has developed them,
yarying between the wide limits of a ‘Hottentot and a
StrPaul?)*
Celsus.—Our moral capacities “are in every man, as
is the instrument that has developed them!!” If nothing
be due to our use or abuse of the instrument, and of our
capacities too, you should have said so distinctly ; and
we could have recognised at once in your statement the
logic of Spinoza or of the Koran. Nay, more, if in any
case the instrument be a bad one, who is the author of
1 A Defence of the Eclipse of Faith, pp. 60, 61. Ip: pe li2
306 DIALOGUE VII.
it? If you say God is its author, you make him the
originator of evil. If you affirm that man is its author,
you attribute to him something more than mere capa-
city.
Origen.—* The concession of the principle, that from
without there may come a light which may develope into
act the latent moral and spiritual capacities of our nature,
is sufficient for the overthrow of the dogma, ‘that an
authoritative external revelation of moral and spiritual
truth is essentially impossible to man.’ ? }
Celsus.—It is granted that man’s capacities or powers
are developed only by coming into contact with objects
external to himself. What we maintain is this, that if
our moral and spiritual capabilities are not developed at
all till the Bible developes them, then are we not respon-
sible beings till this development takes place. And we
further maintain, that whatever external object is the
first instrument to develop our moral capacities, it can-
not, in so far as it is the instrument of development, be
invested with authority; for the very conception of autho-
rity, and the rightfulness of submission thereto, implies
some development of our spiritual faculties.
Origen.—Notwithstanding all that can be said, it is
plain, that “amidst the variety of human judgements, a
jxed basis of morality may easily be shewn to be a quick-
sand, without any personal God.” 2 |
Celsus.—You are surely not ignorant of the fact, that
many cannot find a personal God except on the basis of
* A Defence, &e. p. 93. ? Ib. pp. 63, 64.
THE STANDARD OF MORALITY, 307
man’s moral nature. Nor is there any escape from this
inference, that if man without the Bible be entirely with-
out light, he “is inwardly so dark that he cannot pos-
sibly have any religion but what he receives blindly.”
Origen.—Then you believe that there are “ definite @
prior? notions, which everywhere enable man at once to
pronounce on the truth or falsehood of whatever pro-
fesses to be an external revelation.” *
Theologus. — Some indeed have conten-
Bible assumes
some truths and eq for such a position ; but it seems to be
reveals others,
loosely worded, and is somewhat extrava-
gant. The conclusion to which we are now led by the
discussion is this; the necessities of the Christian argu-
ment constrain us to admit, that there is in mankind, in-
dependently of written revelation, some knowledge of
religion and morality, which implies something like a
standard or criterion ; and that the difficulty of pointing
to that standard does not prove its non-existence, or the
impossibility of finding it. We have been led to perceive
also, that the Bible is intended to reveal to man some-
thing additional to what he knew before, and very pre-
cious in itself; and the very possibility of such a revela-
tion implies, as the terms in which the revelation itself is
couched show, that those to whom it is made not only
have moral capacities, but also have these capacities to
some extent developed, as intelligent beings, in the exer-
cise of their responsibility.
Celsus.—I have just found a passage in the work of a
1A Defence, &c., p. 94.
308 DIALOGUE VII.
Christian advocate, which if I could not show you the
page where it is printed, you would have asserted, I am
sure, to be from the pen of an opponent of Christian-
ity. ‘If men’s religious sensibilities were already awake
—if the spiritual life had already been begotten in them
—if their souls were on the point of detaching themselves
from the low and the trivial interests of the hour, and
were on the earnest look-out for objects to gratify their
higher instincts, and to nourish their diviner capabilities
—this material universe would, no doubt, exhibit a ful-
ness and a force of symbolic significance adequate not
only for instructional, but for emotional improvement
and elevation. We make no question that there have
been occasional instances, and that there are still, al-
though rare indeed, in which the Father of Spirits has.
looked in upon the human soul through the medium of
Nature, and has won from it an inarticulate response
which, rightly interpreted, would be, ‘ Let me come to
thine arms —let me rest on thy bosom — let me lose
my littleness in thy greatness, and merge my will in
thine.’ ””1
Theologus. — It is necessary to maintain on the one
hand the integrity of man’s responsibility under all cir-
cumstances, and, on the other, the peculiar preciousness
of God’s revealed mercy. While, therefore, it is held
objectively, that not one of the sinful children of men can
be pardoned and accepted of God except on the ground
of Christ’s atoning death, it must also be maintained sub-
* Bases of Belief, pp. 102, 103.
THE STANDARD OF MORALITY. 309
jectively, in the first place, to preserve man’s respon-
sibility, that men destitute of a knowledge of the gospel,
may and ought to “seek the Lord, if haply they might
feel after him and find Him” (Acts, xvii. 27), because
‘God is no respecter of persons: but in every nation he
that feareth Him, and worketh righteousness, is accepted
with Him ” (Acts, x. 34, 85). And in the second place,
to vindicate the glory of the gospel, it must be conten-
ded, that no man can jind God except through believing
in the Lord Jesus Christ, — that no one can become ac-
quainted with the method of reconciliation between guilty
man and his righteous Sovereign, and be filled “ with all
joy and peace in believing,” except through the know-
ledge of “ the glorious gospel of the blessed God,” which
is a matter of pure revelation.
Celsus.—These views are materially different from what
some have told us of Christianity ; which is represented
as “an expedient, not to zmpart new religious ideas, but
to vivify pre-existent ones—not so much to convey some-
thing beyond reach to the intellect, as to stimulate
dormant affections and subjugate the will.”! “We have
already said enough to show that mankind needed not so
much a directive as a suasive revelation of God’s will. It
is a special characteristic of the manifestation of God in
Christ, as given us in the New Testament, that its leading
design is, not so.much to instruct our race in duties, as
to supply a motive for their performance.” ?
Origen — These statements are very loose and un-
1 Bases of Belief, p. 74. 2 Tipe bon
310 DIALOGUE VII.
warranted ; and few, if any, among Evangelical Chris-
tians have any sympathy with them. “The eternal life,
which is offered to me in the Gospel—the Gospel being
interpreted as it is in my creed, and therefore not to be
thought of as if it were a superfluous announcement of
known moralities, but as a revelation of Truths quite un-
attainable by reason—is of universal aptitude, in relation
to human nature in its actual condition; and it must be
so thought of even although in fact it were but one in
millions that should accept it.” }
Celsus.— You now contend, then, for these three posi-
tions. First, that in the Bible there is a manifestation or
discovery of new and otherwise unobtainable truths.
Secondly, that there is an aptitude or fitness between this
revelation and the moral nature of man. And thirdly,
that though millions should not acknowledge or act upon
this agreement and aptitude, you would still maintain
that it exists. In the last point you have conceded a
great principle, that we cannot judge of what man can
do, or should do, by what he has done. Do you still
adhere to the second point, and to this plain inference
which it sustains, that if there be a fitness or aptitude in
what you affirm to be a divine revelation in relation to
man’s nature, there must be in the actual or possible pos-
session of man, even while destitute of that revelation,
some standard of morality and some religious knowledge?
Origen.—The inference is legitimate. ‘ Christ, as the
reformer of the human system in its secular aspect, takes
* Restoration of Belief, p. 325.
THE STANDARD OF MORALITY. oUt
up and authenticates those well understood principles
which as soon as they are heard approve themselves to
the consciences of men, and which the sages of all times
have recognised and taught. That the teaching of an
ethical reformer should be consentaneous with the better
feelings and convictions of men, as embodied in the say-
ings and teachings of minds of the highest order, is what
we should look for as the First requirement in one who
comes forward to regenerate a world that has fallen into
disorder.”
Celsus.—Was Pliny, the younger, then,
innocent or guilty in persecuting the early
Christians? Did he know, or might he have known, that
he was doing wrong?
Pliny.
Origen.—* This enlightened Roman gentleman, well
conversant as he was with whatever had been said and
taught by the philosophers of Greeee or Rome, was con-
scious of no humiliation, he did not blush when these
stupid symbols had been poised near him, and he, prompt-
ing the form of appellation—praeunte me—pointed to
them as fit objects of devout regard.” ? ‘The severities
to which Pliny had allowed himself to have recourse were
prompted entirely by his own sense of public duty.” °
Celsus.—If Pliny could go to such lengths in cruelty
and degrading idol-worship, “ conscious of no humiliation,”
while yet he was fully acquainted with “those well-
understood principles which approve themselves to the
consciences of men,” those “better feelings and convic-
1 Restoration of Belief, p. 269. 2 Ib. p20: 3 Tb. peed:
oLe DIALOGUE VII.
tions, embodied in the sayings and teachings of minds of
the highest order,” and notwithstanding this be reckoned
“an enlightened Roman gentleman,” “‘ prompted entirely
by his own sense of duty,’—where shall we look for
those “ sophistically constituted, or sophisticated and
debauched minds, that do succeed in reasoning themselves
out of their instinctive beliefs ;—men who, with a suicidal
wantonness, having applied logical scissors to the nerves
of the moral life, do, and may, with truth declare that
they are conscious of no impulse leading them to look to
the supreme power or mercy ?”’!
Theologus.—Do you, then, admit, or do you not, that
there is amongst mankind some standard of morality inde-
pendently of written revelation? Is it too much to ask
you to be consistent with yourself either in its admission
. or rejection ?
Origen.—We, of course, appeal to such a standard in
maintaining the internal evidences of the Bible. Take,
for example, the First Epistle general of Peter. “The
calm majesty, the fervour, the bright hopefulness, and
the intense moral import of the Epistle carry it home to
every ingenuous mind as an embodiment of whatever is
the most affecting in theology, and the most effective and
salutary in ethics. With those—if there are any, who
have no consciousness of these qualities in the writing
before us, I should not court controversy. In any such
instance nature must have dealt in a very parsimonious
manner with the mind and heart, and sophistry must
’ Restoration, p. 274.
THE STANDARD OF MORALITY. 313
have greatly overdone her part.”! “This Epistle, if
judged of purely on the ground of its intrinsic merits,
carries home to our understandings and best feelings an
irresistible impression of the goodness, wisdom, and sim-
plicity of the writer. Search the entire compass of ethi-
cal writings, ancient and modern, we should not find even
one that carries more decisively upon it the character-
istics of sincerity and truthfulness.”2 Similar remarks
apply more or less to every page of the Bible.
Celsus.—Here then you appeal to heathens and infi-
dels to judge of “ the intrinsic merits” of the Bible, and
even decline to have any controversy with those who are
so degraded by vice or so deficient by nature, as to be
unable to perceive and appreciate its moral and spiritual
excellences, which of course they cannot do without
obtaining a conception of these excellences from some ~
other source. Elsewhere you say as to the heathen, that
in the course of the arduous martyr struggle of the early
Christians, “a New Principle came to be recognised and a
New Feeling came to govern the minds of men; which
principle and feeling conferred upon the individual man,
however low his rank, socially or intellectually, a dignity,
unknown to classical antiquity ; and which yet must be
the basis of every moral advancement we can desire, or
think of as possible.”* If, then, there be a principle and
feelmg which “must be the basis of every moral ad-
vancement,” and which confer a dignity unknown to
the most refined and cultured heathens, because they
’ Restoration of Belief, p. 186. be pari. PIDY fel0G:
U
314 DIALOGUE VII.
ean be produced by Christianity alone,—“ which neither
Phlny nor any man of his time had thought of, or could
have been made to comprehend,” ! how can you ask such
men to sit in judgment upon the intrinsic merits and
‘moral excellences of the Bible ?
As to unbelievers in Christianity, or those who decline
to admit its claims when pressed upon them, you smile
at their complaint of suffering a sort of martyrdom for
their opinions, or their convictions, as they would call
them, and you remark :—“ A claim, in behalf of the gos-
pel, must be made of what is its own, and which these
writers, without leave asked, have appropriated. As to
Is there teuth or CVCTY Word and phrase upon which the
conscience in man significance of this their profession (of suf-
Re fering for the truth) turns, it must be given
up, leaving them in possession of so much only of the
meaning of such phrases as would have been intelligible
to PLuTarcn, to Porruery, and to M. Aurgentius. A
surrender must be made of the words Conscience, and
Trutu, and Rigurrousnsss, and Sry; and, alas! mo-
dern unbelievers must be challenged to give me back
that one awe-fraught Name which they (must I not
plainly say so’) have stolen out of the Boox: when they
have frankly made this large surrender, we may return
to them the Te @zio of classical antiquity. Yet this pla-
giarism, as to terms, is the smaller part of that invasion
of rights with which the same persons are chargeable.
When those who, after rejecting Christianity,
* Restoration of Belief, p. 73.
—
OS oy nn ee
j
fy
THE STANDARD OF MORALITY. 315
talk of suffering for the ‘truth of God, and speak as if
they were conscience-bound ‘toward God,’ they must
know that they not only borrow a language which they
are not entitled to avail themselves of, but that they
invade a ground of religious belief whereon they can
establish for themselves no right of standing.”! But
let me ask you in all candour how, after we have made
‘this large surrender,” and confessed that we have bor-
rowed, or rather “stolen,” from the Bible, not only the
terms, but the meaning of the terms, “ Conscience, and
truth, and righteousness, and sin,” and after penitently
acknowledging our worst plagiarism of all in respect to
the name of God himself, how can we be considered
capable of sitting in judgment, as you ask us to do, upon
“the calm majesty, the fervour, the bright hopefulness,
and the intense moral import” of a portion of the Bible,
and to acquiesce in your decision that it is “an embodi-
ment of whatever is the most affecting in theology, and
the most effective and salutary in ethics?” J can under-
stand you when you say that you should not court con-
troversy with those who have no consciousness of those
qualities. But for that very reason I do not see that
there can be any controversy at all, if a consciousness of
these qualities is only to be had through the Book itself.
You blast the very rock on which you build.
Origen.— Christianity must be looked at in its own
hght.” *
Celsus.—Very good. But what I have said is this,
1 Restoration, pp. 92, 93, 94. abe pa2s.
316 DIALOGUE VII.
that if Christianity be the only moral and religious light
in the world, controversy between us is vain; and the
very arguments which you use, and on which you rest
the greatest weight, are absurd. ‘“ You assume the truth
of Christianity, in order that you may shew it to be
true.” !
Origen.—‘ I admit that it is so, in great measure, and
it must be so in the nature of things. So long as your
mood of mind is this, that you will grant nothing which
it 1s possible for you to deny, you will catch only a
glimpse of things, disadvantageously presented to the
eye. But if you allow me to exhibit the same objects in
their true position, and in their natural proportions, you
will yourself see them to be real. After this you will
not ask me to follow you from point to point in so rigid
a manner. If I undertook to teach you the modern
astronomy, and you would at once grant that my inter-
pretation of the visible heavens is the true one, I should
be able to convince you that it is so in much less time,
and by a far less painful process, than as if you make it
a point of honour to dispute every inch of ground,” }
Celsus.—It appears, then, that you yourself admit the
substantial accuracy of my position, namely, that you
have been begging the question at issue. And you now
assert that in assuming the truth of Christianity in order
to prove that it is true, you are yielding to necessity ;
“it must be so, in the nature of things.” The assumption
of such a necessity is scepticism in its subtlest and most
Restoration, p. 236.
THE STANDARD OF MORALITY. ola
malignant form. Iam no such sceptic as that. Unbe-
liever in Christianity though I be, I profess this belief;
namely, that if Christianity be true, it is possible so to
represent it to the human mind as to be free from incon-
sistencies and contradictions in itself, and in its proofs
or evidences unbetrayed by vicious argumentation.
As to the parallel which you draw between Christianity
and the modern astronomy, I grant that in a loose and
popular sense your remark is correct enough. But why
not do in Christianity what has been done in astronomy,
and make good your ground “from point to point in the
most rigid manner?” Why not do so, especially when
there are individuals who do “make it a point of honour
to dispute every inch of ground?” Even though the
process be tedious and painfal, let us have it, that truth
may not suffer but be fully vindicated. To take refuge
in the bare assertion, that this achievement cannot be
effected, looks like a pusillanimous betrayal of the truth,
or a clumsy effort to conceal your own incompetency.
Theologus.—Why should not Christians honestly ac-
knowledge that the scientific argument for Christianity
in its present state of development is incomplete? And
resting the strength of their cause, in the meantime, on
its practical defences, they might set themselves to a
vigorous prosecution of the truth in its scientific aspect.
Origen.—W ell, supposing that we have not yet reached
the goal, it may be asked, how far are we on the way,
and is it possible to compute the distance between us and
the goal?
518 DIALOGUE VII.
Theologus.—One of the first things to be done is evi-
dently to determine the moral criterion in some form or
other. ven the practical argument demands the estab-
lishment, of course in a practical shape, of the moral
standard.
The practical cri. Ovigen.—How would you state the cri-
Re terion in morals for practical purposes?
Lheologus.—It might perhaps be stated thus: Every
responsible being such as man has true knowledge of his
moral and religious obligations to some extent, more or
less ; and the man who does not act up to the knowledge
which he has is guilty. As to the first point in this state-
ment, it will not, we think, be disputed. “For neither
do the spirits damned lose all their virtue ;” that is, they
do not cease to be ethical or responsible beings, and as
such they must have some moral intelligence and con-
science left to them. How much more the children of
men in their present state of probation! As to the second
point, his present amount of knowledge is made the guide
in moral questions to every individual man. Conscience,
so commonly pleaded, cannot be considered the standard
in morality, generally or scientifically, because it is cor-
rupted and one man’s professed conscience contradicts
another. But his own conscience, honestly followed, is
to every man a practical guide, inasmuch as it is always
near him, and is not wholly blinded; and he who follows
the ight which he has, is in the way of obtaining more.
Origen.—How do you apply this principle in defence
of Christianity ? .
THE STANDARD OF MORALITY. 319
Theologus.—Simply thus: There is more than prima
facie evidence to show that Christianity is entitled to a
fair hearing. When Christianity obtains from any man
a fair hearing, there is a congruity or harmony between
it and the dictates of his conscience, which brings him
under an obligation to believe and obey.
Origen.—If any one disputes this position what would
you say to him?
Theologus.—This is my ultimatum or stand-point, and
I cannot reason with the man who disputes it. If any
one affirms that he has carefully and conscientiously ex-
amined Christianity, and has found in it no beauty to
attract his affections, no truth to arrest his soul, no autho-
rity to subdue his will, with such an one I can enter into
no controversy.
Celsus.—Ah well, that makes short work of it. As to
the scientific view of the question, have you anything to
advance ?
Theologus.—In this case the difficulties, as we have seen,
are numerous and formidable. Nor do I feel that I as
an individual, or as occupying my present position, am
under any special obligation to answer this question.
Celsus.—Has anything been done towards a solution of
this question, or is anything likely to be accomplished ?
Origen. —- Much has been attempted at
least. Here is a definition of sin to begin
with. ‘The line must be drawn in theory, as we may
be sure it will in the Divine Judgment, between the na-
tural disorder of human nature, and the wilful sins of the
What is sin?
320 DIALOGUE VII.
individual; but there can be nothing objectionable, if we
consider the perfection of the Divine Nature and Agency, —
in defining sin to be, whatever, in the nature or agency
of intelligent beings, is in opposition to the Divine Will,
or in discord with the harmony of His works, whether in
any particular instance it be voluntary or involuntary.” '
Celsus.—Passing the objection that this seems to re-
solve the distinction between vice and virtue into a
Divine volition, I am at a loss to perceive how sin or
guilt can in any case be involuntary. To say that some
sins are voluntary and some involuntary is “most ad-
mired confusion.” The guilt that is involuntary in the
creature, must be ascribed to God himself, or to some
Manichean eternal principle of evil.
Origen. — Ah, you don’t understand me. « Every
one knows that prolonged habits of vice destroy the
power of the will, and enslave reason to passion; yet
none would refuse to call an action sinful, because com-
mitted by a man who has become the slave of sin.” 2
Celsus.—Of course such an action is guilty ; but who
would call it involuntary, when it is plainly the result of
the former acts of the will, even supposing that the man
was the most fettered slave when he committed it ?
Theologus.—There is obviously a distinction between
what is voluntary directly and voluntary indirectly, which
will clear up the present question. Many sins can only
be regarded as indirectly voluntary ; to call them invo-
luntary seems altogether inadmissible.
* Christian Theism, vol. ii. p. 249. 21D) pr 2501
THE STANDARD OF MORALITY. bal
Origen. —“ Evil is, at the most, a deprivation of
good.” |
Celsus. — Does this mean that all sin is involuntary ?
\ Please to explain yourself.
Origen. — “ If, notwithstanding the Perfections of the
Creator, sinfulness and imperfection be inseparable from
the creature, it cannot give a higher view of the Divine
Character, to regard sinfulness and imperfection as ori-
ginal in every man, than as transmitted from generation
to generation.”* “It is not improbable that the deal-
ings of God with the race of mankind are, in some way,
dependent upon the original weakness and frailty of
human nature.’”’3 “Evil abounds in finite beings.” *
Celsus. —If I understand your language, you identify
the necessary imperfection of the finite creature with
evil and guilt. This interpretation of your words is the
only one which will bear the inference which you draw,
and which, you say, is confirmed by revelation, namely,
«that every man will be accountable for his own works,
and will not be responsible for any hereditary taint of
evil.’>5 Is this indeed the doctrine held by the Protes-
tant Churches? Leaving them and you to settle that
question, I go on to observe that you do not adhere con-
sistently to your own opinion. At one turn of the con-
troversy you hold this opinion; at another turn you
espouse an opinion exactly the reverse. For example,
you say, ‘“‘ morally, a creature must surely be considered
1 Christian Theism, vol. ii. p. 141. ?Ib. p. 251. *Ib., p. 358.
* Tb. p. 366. ib pazay
g22 DIALOGUE VII.
perfect, when it is in exact adjustment to universal na-
ture, in all the relations of the position in which God has
placed it; when its faculties, to the extent of their power,
combine in harmonious action in themselves and with the
world which environs it; and all its agency is directed,
within its sphere, to fulfil the Will of God. Such moral
perfection is certainly conceivable, and, reason naturally
conjectures, is the actual condition of all the creatures as
they proceed from the hands of the Creator.”! And still
more explicitly do you contradict yourself when you
remark, ‘“ The difference between the Scriptural doctrine
of the fall, and the opinion that man was originally im-
perfect, may seem, at first sight, to be one of little im-
portance. But it touches the foundation of the whole
system of revelation, and extends to the question of
Christianity or infidelity.” 2
Theologus.—The result of this discussion seems to be,
that in order to establish the evidences of Christianity
on a scientific basis, it is necessary to settle the preli-
minary question, what is the ethical criterion, or in
other words, what is the difference between virtue and
vice, or between sin and holiness. Though this ques-
tion be encompassed with serious difficulties—though
the road thus indicated as the one in which we must
travel be rugged and steep, yet inasmuch as it is the
only legitimate one to our destination, we should nerve
our minds and gird up our loins to perform the jour-
ney.
* Christian Theism, vol. ii. p. 248. 7 Thy pe206.
THE STANDARD OF MORALITY. §23
Origen.—Can you tell us, then, what is the criterion
in morals ?
Theologus.—We do not by any means profess to solve
the problem. But there must be some considerations,
not far to seek, which will afford some material aid in
any attempt to reach a solution.
Origen.—What are these considerations ?
Theologus.—At your request I have no objections
to state briefly some thoughts upon this topic, which I
may take another opportunity of unfolding and illus-
trating.
There is, however, another question which takes pre-
Man's fandamen. ce“ence of that respecting the ethical eri-
ueeene terion, and which forms the first and great
topic in philosophy. ‘The solution of this question is the
creat desideratum of modern speculation, as it may be
shewn to be common to all the sciences. Scientific or
strictly logical evidence on any subject must have for its
foundation a definition of terms and a statement of first
principles. Without an exact apprehension of what is
assumed, as well as a correct conception of what is to be
proved, it is impossible to produce evidence that shall be
satisfactory to a reflecting mind. Looking at matters in
this light, it is observed that all human knowledge divides
itself into two branches: Assumptions and Inferences,—
truths which are taken for granted, and truths which
are not assumed but proved. Aristotle stated this dis-
tinction with great precision, and it has been universally
acknowledged. The problem, therefore, may be pro-
324 DIALOGUE VII.
posed to draw a line between these two sorts of truths,
which have been designated noetic and dianoetic, by
embodying the former in verbal statements. To express
simply and orderly whatever is taken for granted in the
various departments of human learning, seems to be the
very first duty of philosophy. The want of such a state-
ment must multiply and aggravate disputes, and fre-
quently retard the progress of knowledge. There are
truths which we legitimately believe, which we cannot
but believe, but which we cannot prove by falling back
upon anything simpler or surer than themselves. What
are these truths? No question can be more distinct or
more important.
A little reflection. may convince us that a clear state-
ment of our primary notions and first principles would
tend to dispel many clouds from man’s intellectual firma-
ment. A map of the elevated table-land, whence all the
sciences, like fertilising streams, take their rise, would
confer immense advantage on every inquiring mind; it
would accelerate the discoveries of the thoughtful, and
facilitate the instruction of the thoughtless. If a philo-
sopher shall attempt to prove by argument one of our
fundamental assumptions (and how often has this been
done’), his conclusion will be true, and may be admitted
by all; but his logic will be at fault. In such a case, the
mind is resting on a truth, which it has reached by a
forced and illegitimate road. Again, if a philosopher
shall assume what needs to be proved (and has this never
been done?), his whole demonstration will be like a house
THE STANDARD OF MORALITY. 325
upon sand. If his fundamental position be not only illo-
gically assumed, but in itself false ;—not only formally,
but really, erroneous, the superstructure will be nothing
better than rubbish. The confounding, then, of assump-
tions and inferences,—of what cannot be proved and
what must be proved,—the want of some well-defined
line between these two widely different domains, has not
only given support and vigour to numerous errors, but
throws a dimness on the scientific or speculative aspect
of every truth which mankind have hitherto embraced.
No one proposition can be expounded and defended in a
thoroughly scientific form till we can distinctly say: So
much we assume; so much we prove or demonstrate by
the help of these assumptions.
It is our conviction that the proposition which asserts
the existence of God will be found to be itself one of our
fundamental truths, or to be an immediate and obvious
inference from them. Proceeding, then, on the hypo-
thesis that this is the actual state of the case,—that
God exists, and that He is the Creator of man, we
shall throw out a few hints in regard to the ethical cri-
terion.
The scientife eri. Lhe first pot to be settled in this
terion. investigation is, What are the objects, of
all which, and of which alone, virtue or vice (sin or holi-
ness) is predicated. We shall call these objects ethical,
to distinguish them from non-ethical objects, or those
which are neither right nor wrong, and unworthy of
either praise or blame. Ethical objects, we conceive, are
326 DIALOGUE VII.
those living beings whose constitution is found to embrace
the various elements of ethical discussion, such as, desire,
action, volition, intelligence, and conscience. The ethical
quality, or the function of accountability, attaches not to
this or the other part of man, to this or that development
of his nature, but to man himself. The question, then,
what is the difference between virtue and vice, resolves
itself into a more manageable question, what is the dif-
ference between a moral and an immoral being ?
To answer this question, we must inquire what sort of
a creature man is, as an ethical or responsible agent. As
such he appears to us to be possessed of Desires, Actions,
Intelligence, Will, and the Ethical Sentiment or Con-
science.
As to the Desires of mankind they are either proper
or improper, or to use words which may be found more
precise, normal or abnormal. If there be harmony and
agreement between the object which is desired, and the
constitution and situation of the agent desiring it, the
desire is suitable or normal. If there be no such accor-
dance between ourselves and the things which we are
desiring and wishing, our desires are unworthy and
abnormal.
In regard to Actions, they admit of the same two-fold
division as desires, for action, we are disposed to consider,
is nothing else than the gratification of desire. Man
never acts without a desire of some sort. If the desire
gratified by an action be abnormal or normal, so is the
action. It is well to notice that this distinction of our
THE STANDARD OF MORALITY. 327
desires and actions extends to every action and every
desire. The inference is clear and weighty, that no
action of an ethical or responsible being is indifferent.
The Intelligence possessed by an accountable being has
such functions as the following to discharge. 1. To dis-
tinguish between his normal and abnormal desires and
actions, and between the relative values of two normal
desires when the gratification of both is impracticable.
2. To determine the fit and proper means to obtain the
gratification of his desires. 3. To determine what are
the final desires or ultimate aims worthy of his immortal
nature.
Now in a responsible being desire does not pass into
action without the interposition of his Well. In any case
when the desire is passing into action, the agent either
knows or he does not know, whether the desire he is con-
templating the gratification of be normal or abnormal,
If he does not know whether the desire be normal or ~
abnormal, his ignorance is avoidable or unavoidable. If
his ignorance be unavoidable, he is not responsible; if it
be avoidable he is blameworthy. We suppose, therefore,
that when an ethical being is about to will the gratifica-
tion of a desire, he knows whether that desire be normal
orabnormal. On this supposition four distinct manifesta-
tions of ethical agency will emerge. 1. The desire of
the agent may be normal and his belief or knowledge
respecting it may also be normal; that is, the desire may
be really good and the agent be right in believing it to
be good. Let such a volition as this be called normal.
328 DIALOGUE VII.
2. The desire may be abnormal and the belief regarding
it normal ; that is, the desire may be actually bad, and the
agent know very well that it is bad, and yet gratify it.
Let such a volition be called directly abnormal. 3. It is
possible that while the desire is in itself normal, the belief
of the agent respecting it may be abnormal; that is, an
action may be lawful enough in itself, while an individual
believes it to be unlawful. The commission of an action
in such circumstances involves guilt. This volition must
be designated like the former directly abnormal. 4. Itis
very common for a desire to be abnormal and a man’s
belief regarding it abnormal too; in other words, an
action may be wrong and the agent may consider it right.
This volition will be recognised as abnormal indirectly.
This statement assumes it to be a fact, that the will of
a responsible being does not always follow the dictates of
his understanding in gratifying his desires, and also that
in this neglect to obey the voice of reason hes the essence
of guilt. We are thus led to such conclusions as the
following :—
The first guilt of an ethical being consists in gratifying
an irregular or abnormal desire, while he knows that it
is such, and has power to refrain from the gratification.
One abnormal volition, or one guilty action as just
described, constitutes an ethical being immoral; or,
conversely, he only is a moral or virtuous agent all
whose volitions are normal, or who has never committed
a transgression.
A moral agent, without any marvellous stretch of his
THE STANDARD OF MORALITY. 329
understanding, but in the ordinary and easy use of it,
while believing that his actions are normal, believes at
the same time, that they are agreeable to the will of God
and conducive to his own best welfare.
The only way in which an ethical being can certainly
know what is normal or right in desire and action is by
the use of his understanding in examining the nature of
himself and the objects of his desire, or by some autho-
rised manifestation of his Maker’s will.
The only legitimate way in which man, as a respon-
sible being, can pursue his good upon the whole is by pur-
suing what he knows to be right, in the manner just in-
dicated.
It would occupy too much of your time at present to
specify the various features of the immoral agent, or to
state the different steps by which we have been led to
these conclusions. Let it suffice to sum up the character
of the virtuous or moral agent. It consists not only in a
permanent and paramount desire to conform, but also in
actually conforming, in every thing, to the dictates of his
reason or to some authentic promulgation of the will of
his Maker, by which course, as he knows, his own true
welfare is best consulted. The dictates of his reason may
be supplemented, but are never opposed, by the mani-
fested will of God. By a perpetual and dutiful attention
to the good and righteous pleasure of the Most High
when made known, or, in the absence of such, to the
teaching of his own understanding, an individual will con-
tinue in that state of happiness and perfection, of which
x
330 DIALOGUE VII.
his nature is capable, and which his Creator intended
that he should enjoy. Every movement of this perfect
creature will reflect honour upon Him whose workman-
ship he is. The moral being will perceive that such is
the fact, and will desire that so it should be. His every
act, whether simply in accordance with the understand-
ing which God has given him, or in obedience to some
express Divine command, is thus homage directly and
worthily rendered to Deity. Whether, therefore, the
issue of his conduct or the intention of his heart be con-
sidered, it would appear that whatever the moral agent
does, he does it to the glory of his God.
These principles may be vindicated, we think, on
strictly philosophical or scientific ground. Grant us
these, or some such principles as these, and we feel as if
we might hopefully undertake, with the aid also of the
conclusions to which we have been brought in the different
preceding discussions, to vindicate the cause of Christian-
ity against all deistical objections. If, however, every-
thing in the form of an ethical basis or moral criterion,
which is supposed to be common to both parties be
refused, the controversy, as we have been led to see by
actual observation, must prove to be endless and unsatis-
factory.
CONCLUSION.
REASON AND FAITH;
THEIR CLAIMS WITHOUT CONFLICT.
(Theologus loquttur.)
TuErE are two facts which have been elicited in these
discussions, and which cannot but be familiar to the
readers of the higher literature of the age, and which are
as pregnant with interest as they are palpable to obser-.
vation. The first of these facts 1s this, that, in the dis-
cussion of religious and ethical questions, those who hold
the same conclusions, or contend -for the same great
truths, are not substantially agreed in their statements of
the main arguments by which their common position is
supported. The second fact that obtrudes itself, and
which is probably a consequence of the first, is this, that
on some points, which are generally and justly regarded
as of the utmost practical importance, the most intelli-
~ gent and religious among mankind are found to be not
only of various sentiments, but in actual collision and
conflict.
Those who maintain the validity of natural religion,
ao2 CONCLUSION.
for example, are not agreed as to the doctrines which it
embraces ; and what is more, they are not at one in
stating the evidence of those doctrines which they in
common believe it to embrace. This want of agreement
consists not merely in variety of language and illustration,
or in a different arrangement of topics, or in any other
diversity of inferior moment, but also not unfrequently in
direct and unqualified contradiction. Some, for instance,
deny that the assertion of Divine existence either requires
or admits of proof; some again affirm that proof is
needed and must be adduced. Among the latter class
one finds sufficient evidence in himself; another denies
this, and finds sufficient evidence only in the material
universe; and a third rejects both opinions, and finds his
belief in Deity warranted only by taking a conjoined view
of himself and the world of matter. The conclusiveness
of the argument from design is maintained by some and
refused by others.
In hke manner, if we look into the literature which
expounds the evidence in favour of Christianity being a
religion from God, we observe not only diversity but op-
position, not only variety but contradiction. Some con-
tend that sufficient evidence for the divine origin of the
Bible lies, and must lie, within the book itself. Others
maintain that the historic evidence is at once necessary
and of itself sufficient. These last, moreover, are by no
means harmonious in their modes of developing the his-
toric argument. Some assert that miracles are of them-
selves sufficient to authenticate a divine commission or
CONCLUSION. Soa
message ; while others affirm that the evidence of
miracles is imperfect, and requires to be supplemented
by the virtuous character of the messenger, and the veri-
similitude of his message.
This repugnance or contrariety of sentiment and judg-
ment appears not only in unfolding the evidences of reli-
gion, but also in explaining and inculcating religious
truths ; that is, not only in discussing more abstruse and
speculative problems, but also in enforcing the most
fundamental and onerous duties. The question, what 1s
faith, gives rise to much controversy, and carries us im-
mediately into the depths of philosophy and among the
momentous practical realities of our responsibility. The
ingenuous mind, while yet standing on the threshold of
Christianity and trembling on the confines of eternal
bliss or woe, is perplexed and almost confounded by
noticing, that among the most reputable disciples of
Christ contradictory opinions prevail, as to what that
act is by which he should become a Christian. Some
doctors assure him that it is in itself a mere intellectual
act, while others protest against this view as most errone-
ous and dangerous. We need only allude to such con-
troversies as those respecting the freedom of the will, the
extent of human depravity consequent on the fall of
Adam, the nature of Divine inspiration, the extent of
Christ’s atonement, and the duty of Civil Government in
relation to Christianity. Conflicting opinions have not
only been adopted on these and other points, but the
holders of these contradictory sentiments have each
334 CONCLUSION.
believed and maintained, that the reception of his own
view and the rejection of its opposite was identified
with the integrity of truth and the weightiest interests of
men. Hence it appears that the most intelligent and
devoted followers of Christ, even with a written revela-
tion of the divine will in their hands, are frequently
found to be mutually and diametrically opposed, while
discussing the most significant truths and enforcing the
most urgent duties.
The contradictions prevalent among Christian men
resolve themselves, however, into disputes in speculative
philosophy, ethical science, or grammatical interpreta-
tion. Whatever disadvantages, therefore, Christians
labour under in consequence of the mutual repugnance
of some of their views, they occupy an intellectual posi-
tion in no respect inferior to that occupied by the gene-
ral students of philosophy, ethics, and language. The
controversies, that have disturbed schools and colleges
and learned men, are necessarily transferred to the arena
of the Christian Church, or spring up spontaneously
there, because the topics of discussion are fundamentally
common to both those parties.
While revolving these facts the question arises, is there
any. reasonable prospect that these controversies, some
or all of them, shall terminate,—these contradictions dis-
appear, — and the truth, hitherto half-concealed, shine
forth in a form so distinct and in colours so brilliant as
to win the conviction of every honest mind? A full and
satisfactory answer to this: question involves many con- —
CONCLUSION. anu
siderations, and calls for the removal of some weighty
objections. But that the question must be answered in
the affirmative will on reflection be doubted by few.
Every thoughtful man will at once reject the supposi-
tion, that conflicting sentiments, especially on the mat-
ters that have been specified, should continue for ever
unreduced, and fill human society with distraction. Such
a supposition seems to imply, that one chief end for
which intelligent beings like men have been created, is to
be intellectual gladiators. We may indeed admit that
intellectual conflict will be eternal, if it be also conceded,
that the ground of conflict will be ever changing, that
whenever a dispute is terminated by the establishment of
truth, a new contest will arise only to issue in a fresh
victory. But to imagine that intelligent beings shall
exhaust their immortal energies in mutual contradictions
on questions of moment is monstrously absurd. If
through the lapse of countless ages there will always be
found problems to exercise man’s increasing powers, and
if controversies will be ever emerging to stimulate his
powers to their utmost intensity, it can only be by new
difficulties appearing after the old have vanished. No
drudgery can be conceived more painful or degrading,
than endless disputation and collision on a vital problem
that shall remain for ever unresolved.
While our speculative or theoretic contradictions are
in themselves intolerable to every well-constituted mind,
they assume a graver and more urgent character, when
they are seen in many cases to be identified with our
336 CONCLUSION.
practical quarrels, and thus form the most formidable
difficulty in the way of social improvement. The mutual
antagonism of professed friends is, in every sphere of
human life, always more disastrous than the attacks of
open enemies. It is the internal weakness or inherent
inconsistency of many promising schemes of usefulness,
rather than the outward force of opponents, that defeats
them, and consequently retards the amelioration of
society. Philanthropy herself, therefore, is pleading
and waiting, bathed in tears, for the cessation of strife,
and the propitious announcement that the friends of
truth have sheathed their internecine swords, and are
marching one in hand, and one in heart, because they
have become one in knowledge and belief, to overcome
and bless the world. While we are looking for this
great consummation, it is not irrelevant to ask, how is it
that in so many cases the truth is so slow in triumphing
and the conflict so fiercely prolonged? One reason not
uninfluential will, we apprehend, be found to be this, that
he who holds the truth in one particular, in others holds
what is erroneous; in other words, the defender of one
special truth is not, in all his opinions or convictions, con-
sistent with himself and with truth.
Truth, we must assume, is a whole of many parts,
which are neither disconnected nor disjointed, neither
isolated nor thrown together in confusion. ~As there isa
profound harmony between each truth and every other
truth, so every erroneous proposition will come into con-
flict, more or less directly, with one or more propositions
CONCLUSION. 337
that are true. If then on any occasion a particular truth,
held intelligently by one man, be assailed or denied by
another man, the strength of the assault will he very mate-
rially in the false assumptions or erroneous propositions held
by the defender of the truth, and introduced in the course
of his defence. Leta truth be distinctly stated, let its evi-
dence be sufficient and fairly marshalled, and let the mind
give due attention to that evidence, and the intellect will
yield acquiescence, From the very nature of the case,
then, it would appear, that the chief or only ground on
which the denial of any truth can make a plausible and
effectual stand is the error or errors that are mingled
with the defence and exposition of that truth. All ex-
perience seems to confirm the correctness of this remark.
Besides, the only conceivable way in which a man can
be rationally convinced of being in error is by making
manifest to himself his own inconsistency. If an indi-
vidual can be led to see that one of his beliefs contradicts
another of his beliefs, or, which is much the same thing,
that the evidence which he admits in one case he refuses
in another case, or that the principle which he applies in
one instance he rejects or ignores in another instance, he
is thereby constrained to acknowledge his error; and in -
no other possible way can he be induced, at once freely
and intelligently, to make such an acknowledgment.
Every real difficulty, therefore, with which man as an
intelligent being has to contend, will, we think, be found
resolving itself, more or less speedily, into a self-contra-
diction. What we do not know can never come into
338 CONCLUSION.
conflict with what we do know. An unsolved question
cannot shake or unsettle a question that is solved. Ab-
normal ignorance, or not knowing what we should know,
issues In transgression, which is a practical error. But
error in all its forms impinges against truth. The clashing
of two knowledges or beliefs in the mind, (as well as col-
lision between outward conduct and inward conviction), is
the effectual test of the presence of error, and is the one
great danger which an intelligent being has to fear.
Scepticism, whether religious or philosophical, is best
refuted, nay, can be effectually refuted only, by its own
inconsistency. Universal doubt destroys itself. To affirm
an universal negation is obviously suicidal. On the other
hand, there is not probably a single man living who is
not a disbeliever or sceptic in part,—that is, there is no
man of whom it may be said that he is ignorant of no
truth which he might and ought to believe, or that he
holds no error which he might and ought to reject. But
when any one becomes a professed sceptic, or makes it
his business to assail truths which are held intelligently
by his fellows, the vigour of the assault lies in the errors
which are received by them. It is difficult to conceive
how pure truth in its abstract discrete state, should be
attacked argumentatively by an intelligent being; but
it is easy to perceive how it may be opposed in a concrete
or agglomerate condition. If these views be at all correct,
it appears that the only foothold of scepticism, excepting
that of unblushing wickedness and vice, is the blunders
and mistaken admissions of the friends of truth. The
CONCLUSION. 339
only seasoned or dressed food of Disbelief consists in the
self-inconsistencies and mutual contradictions of those
who Believe.
It has been said, as we have seen, with too much ac-
curacy, that the argument, that is, the scientific argu-
ment, in favour of Christianity may be summed up in this
statement, that there are fewer difficulties in receiving,
than in rejecting, the Bible. But then what is meant by
a difficulty? It means either an incomprehensibility, a
mystery, something too high for the understanding to
scale; or it means an inconsistency, a contradiction, some-
thing that the understanding rejects. It has been shewn
- that to affirm that there are fewer mysteries in Christi-
anity than in infidelity, is no argument in favour of the
one against the other. For there are mysteries on our
right hand and on our left wherever we go. Nor is at
all an unlikely thing that truth may have more mysteries
than falsehood. To affirm that Christianity has fewer
contradictions than infidelity is not true. There are no
contradictions or self-inconsistencies in the Christian
religion itself; if there were, it ought not to be be-
lieved. But there are contradictions in scepticism; and
these contradictions form the only available argument for
its refutation. To affirm that the arguments usually
urged in favour of Christianity have fewer contradictions
than the arguments against Christianity, is, we fear, too
correct. The urgent inference from which is this, that
the defenders of Christianity will most effectually meet
and repulse the assaults of unbelief and disbelief, by re-
340 CONCLUSION.
examining their own positions and banishing from their
camp every traitorous error.
The following is the closing sentence of ‘‘ The Restora-
tion of Belief.” “If now the question be put to me,
whether my Christian Belief enable me to rid myself of
that burden of far-reaching care and trouble which I
share with the thoughtful of all ages,—my reply is this—
In truth I have not found the means of ridding myself of
this burden; but in the Gospels I have found Him in
communion with whom I am learning how to bear it;
and thus I hope to bear it to the end, still retainmg my
faith and trust in God as supremely Good and Wise —
‘a Just God and a Saviour.’ ” Now this burden is com- —
posed of mysteries or of contradictions ; it is something
that merely transcends, or something that rudely shocks,
our intelligence. If the former, it is no burden at all,
at least it ought not to be felt as such. It is no hardship
to be a finite creature. But if it be the latter, and it is
the latter, and not the former, which has been, and still
is, the real burden shared by all the thoughtful, then
while the Gospels teach us how to bear even that burden
whilst it rests upon us, they teach us also how to labour
and hope for its removal.
There is a considerable number of able and intelligent
men who affirm, that we cannot get quit of our contra-
dictions, that we cannot even hope to escape from them,
—that we must believe in propositions which contradict
each other, or which at least seem to do so. For
example, it has been said, “the theologian, like every
CONCLUSION. 341
other deep thinker, must believe and act upon proposi-
tions that seem contradictory to intelligence because it is
finite, and that can be proved to seem thus in consequence
of its finitude.’’! Here we have the old fallacy which
confounds ignorance and error, — contradiction and
mystery. As finite creatures, we must be in ignorance
of many things. But if it be said that as the direct and
necessary consequence of our being created, and not un-
ereated, we believe in contradictory statements or in
error, we asperse the Divine character, or entirely des-
troy finite intelligence. But the quotation does not say
“‘ propositions that are contradictory ;”’ it says “ proposi-
tions that seem contradictory.” This evasion has been
already exposed. If the propositions are contradictory
in appearance only, and not in reality, how do we know
this? Supposing that we do know that their contradic-
tion is a mere shddow without a substance, then they are
not contradictory, and why should they seem to be what
they are not ? Why should they seem to us to be what
we know they are not? If the propositions which we
must accept as true be contradictory only in appearance,
we ought to make them appear as they really are. To
believe propositions that in fact contradict each other, is to
be in error.
It cannot, therefore, we think, for a moment be
doubted that it is not only highly desirable, but also
strongly obligatory upon all the friends of truth, that
they endeavour to extricate themselves from their an-
1 Fraser’s Essays in Philosophy, Edin. 1856, pp. 319, 320.
342 CONCLUSION.
tagonistic opinions and beliefs,—that is, from prominent
and prejudicial errors, which they, or some of them
at least, are embracing. It will as little be doubted that
the proper and effectual method to secure this auspicious
consummation, is for each lover of truth, each genuine
philosopher, each honest believer, to seek devoutly and
diligently to disencumber himself of his own inconsisten-
cies.
Suppose now that an individual sets himself to the
noble but arduous task, of eliminating from his stock of
knowledge all contrariety, and rejecting from among his
beliefs all contradiction, what is the process which he
must pursue, and what the first step which he must take?
He must analyse his knowledge, reduce it to its ele-
mentary parts, and assort them in order. When we have
to deal with a number of articles, we can avoid confusion
only by adopting an accurate arrangement. In like
manner discord can be banished from the mind only by
a systematic classification of our beliefs. If a man’s be-
liefs are lying in his mind in a disorderly and random
state, he may easily and frequently contradict himself
without immediate consciousness of the contradiction, and
find out his blunder only by tasting the bitterness of its
fruits. But if our beliefs be methodically digested and
disposed, a collision between any two of them will be
readily and sensibly felt, and if not entirely prevented
~ may be checked with comparative ease.
In attempting to arrange our knowledges or beliefs,
the most prominent classification that occurs is this :—
CONCLUSION. 343
Some of our beliefs are primary, fundamental, self-evident,
independent; others are derived from, or dependent
upon, the first, and are, therefore, secondary, demon-
strable, or susceptible of proof extraneous to themselves.
It thus appears that the only effectual and reasonable
way in which man, as an intelligent being, can hope to
avoid self-ticonsistency is by attempting to determine what
are his primary or original beliefs.
The well-informed reader will at once perceive that
this statement of the manner in which our knowledges
are to be harmonized, and the burden of our contradic-
tions removed, is precisely the statement of the great
problem of speculative philosophy. There are, as all
perceive, certain principles without the admission of
which all reasoning is impossible. It seems, therefore,
to be the preliminary question in philosophy to deter-
mine what these principles are. Every one of the modern
sciences is based upon some of these principles virtually,
if not avowedly. It may, therefore, with propriety be
affirmed, that any science which proceeds without stating
these assumed principles, but taking them for granted
silently, and probably in a loose and inaccurate form, is
so far unscientific. An orderly and correct enunciation
of first principles would, as we have already had occasion
to remark, obviously contribute to the stability and
enlargement of the stock of human knowledge, while it
is urgently demanded by the intellectual instincts of our
nature, and is the only achievement that can give some-
thing like symmetry and completion to our philosophy.
,
344 CONCLUSION.
Bit few vigorous and well-directed attempts, we fear,
have been made to meet this want; and hence it would
not be difficult to shew, that in all the physical sciences,
and even in the pure mathematics, which is the most
exact science of all, there are assumptions found whose
language is vague, and of which no methodical account is
rendered. Moreover, as new discoveries in the sciences
are constantly bringing us to higher and more extensive
principles, and as each science has more or less intimate
connection with every other science, the unavoidable result
of progress in the Inductive sciences, both of mind and mat-
ter, is to force upon our attention the problem of our
fundamental beliefs, and to conduct us onward towards
at least an approximate solution.
The question, then, of our primary beliefs cannot be
evaded, unless we are willing to arrest the progress
of philosophy, abandon the hope of attaining self-con-
sistency, and despair of being able to act intelligently
and rightly in the more complicated and perplexing cir-
cumstances of practical life. These primitive beliefs or
knowledges are found in a conerete state, pervading the
common sentiments of mankind. The opinions of the
vulgar and illiterate are interwoven with them; they
are the warp of all our knowledge. There is an im-
plicit, undeveloped metaphysic or philosophy in every
man’s mind; and if it be not the true, it is a false philo-
sophy.
The remarks that follow are intended as a contribution
towards the solution of one of the elements of this great
CONCLUSION. 345
problem, namely, to elucidate the true nature of know-
ledge and faith, in one of their aspects.
The antithesis, truth, error, is obtained, as we have
already stated, by observing that a proposition agrees or
disagrees with its object. If the affirmation and negation
involved in the proposition be exactly in accordance with
the object, and, so far as it is described, describe it as it
is, this agreement is truth, and the proposition so agree-
ing with its object is true. On the other hand, if the
object spoken of do not precisely tally or correspond
with what is affirmed and denied respecting it, this dis-
agreement is error, and such proposition Is erroneous.
Every proposition is thus either true or erroneous.
There is no possible exception. The proposition is as its
object, or it is not. In the one case, it is true; in the
other case, it is erroneous or false.
‘The objection taken by Kant to this definition of truth
seems to be unfounded. “ If truth,” he says, “ consist in
the accordance of a cognition with its object, this object
thereby must thus be separated from others; for a cog-
nition is false, if it do not agree with the object to which
it refers, although it contains something which may cer-
tainly be valid for other objects. Now, a general crite-
rion of Truth would be that which was valid for ail
cognitions, without distinction of their objects. But it is
clear, that as we make abstraction by this of all content
of cognition (reference to its object), and Truth relates
exactly to this content, it is quite impossible and absurd
to inquire after a mark of the truth of this content of
S
346 CONCLUSION.
cognitions,—and consequently, that a sufficient, and,
moreover, at the same time, general characteristic of the
truth, cannot possibly be given. As we have already
before called the content of a cognition its matter, we
are thus compelled to say that no universal charac-
teristic can be expected of the truth of the cognition in
respect to its matter, since this is in itself contradic-
tory.”! This argument is based upon the author’s doc-
trine of pure reason, and must stand or fall with it. It
cannot stand, if Sir W. Hamilton’s doctrine of perception
be admitted, and if consciousness be regarded as trust-
worthy. If a man can know an object immediately (pre-
sentative knowledge), whether internal or external to
himself, and if in thus knowing he does not necessarily
deceive himself, then the statement that truth consists
in the agreement between our knowledge, or the pro-
position in which that knowledge is expressed, and
its object, affords an obvious rule or canon, and the
only conceivable one, by which all minds can test the
accuracy of all knowledge. Hence, also, to consider
“ cognitions without distinction of their objects,” in-
stead of leading us to a “ general criterion of Truth,”
actually ignores and excludes the truth. Has Kant
ever told us what truth is? In denying the possibility
of a sufficient and general characteristic of the truth,
he virtually denies that there is any such thing as
truth.
Kant’s own criteria, which he gives in the next para-
1 Kant’s Critic. Trans. by Haywood. London, 1848, p. 54.
CONCLUSION. 347
graph, extend, as he acknowledges, only to the form of
knowledge, and amount to this, that a man’s thoughts
are to be consistent with each other. We do not know
that he provides or points out means by which one man’s
views may be known to be in harmony with his neigh-
bour’s. To do this would be empiricism ; it would cast a
spot upon the purity of reason. To be self-consistent is
a great attainment; but it is eviscerated of all meaning
and value, if the condition of its attainment be a complete
isolation of each individual from all around him ;—if
each possessor of ideas be the universe, and the universe
a bundle of ideas. It was vain for Kant to go in search
of Truth, after he had in his fundamental principles
ignored, or rather excluded it. The same great error
runs through the bulk of the German Philosophy.
More particularly, first, as to knowledge. It is clearly
impossible for an intelligent being to take a true propo-
sition to be erroneous, or an erroneous proposition to be
true, at the very time that he perceives the true proposi-
tion to be true, or the erroneous proposition to be erro-
neous. If, then, there be such a phenomenon as a man’s
taking an erroneous proposition to be true, and such a
phenomenon 1s, alas! too common, it implies, that though
the proposition be really erroneous, the man in making
or accepting it does not perceive, or think, or know, that
it is erroneous.
The fact now stated being admitted, as it will un-
doubtedly be, it is no empty question to inquire, how is
348 CONCLUSION.
this phenomenon to be accounted for? It must be traced
either to an original defect in the constitution of the
mind that adopts such a proposition, or to the abuse of its
undefective powers by the mind itself. Since a proposi-
tion in itself erroneous can never be embraced as such,
or directly, by an intelligent being ; in other words, since
a man can never call white black, knowing it to be white,
the phenomenon generally named error must be the
inevitable yet indirect result of some weakness or per-
version in the understanding; and this weakness or
perversion in the understanding must either be connate
and constitutional, or self-induced in some way or other
by intelligent beings themselves. If it be affirmed that
the weakness or defect of mind which leads a man to call
an erroneous proposition true is constitutional, and
belongs to him as a creature in the state in which he
came from the hands of his Creator, it is obvious that a
serious charge is thus brought against the most High
God. But if we affirm that such a perversion of intellect
is in some form or other self-induced, inasmuch as such
self-injury involves a degree of folly and guilt, we shall
be able to vindicate the character and government of
God by throwing the criminality upon the creature.
Assuming that there is no question'which of these two
theories is to be preferred, we are led to the distinction
which has been already introduced to your consideration,
namely, that knowledge which takes a true proposition
to be true, and an erroneous proposition to be erroneous,
is normal, and that knowledge which takes an erroneous
CONCLUSION. 349
proposition to be true, or a true proposition to be erro-
neous, 1s abnormal.
It is worthy of special notice, as we saw, that zgno-
rance, as well as knowledge, may be either normal or
abnormal. When a man is ignorant of the truth or
erroneousness of a proposition, or, which is the same
thing, ignorant of an object, which by a little care he
might and ought to have known, his ignorance is abnor-
mal and culpable. Since, on the other hand, there are
many objects which we have no means of knowing, many
propositions of which, using all diligence, we can affirm
neither the truth nor the falsehood, in regard to these
objects or propositions, ignorance is proper and becom-
ing, and therefore normal. We agree with those who
regard it as one of the greatest philosophical problems
of the day, and one of our most urgent practical necessi-
ties, to determine when we should be ignorant,—to fix
the limits of a “ prudent nescience.”
As it is not by any means uncommon to confound
error, or what we have just called abnormal knowledge,
with ignorance, so the distinction between normal and
abnormal ignorance is perhaps as frequently overlooked
or disregarded. These two mistakes have a tendency to
produce and reproduce each other, and they both lead,
especially when combined together, as they have often
been, to the most perplexing and painful consequences.
Illustrations of this have been given, and more could be
easily found, but we must hasten to our conclusion.
It now becomes a most important question, has an
350 CONCLUSION.
intelligent being the power of distinguishing between his
normal and abnormal knowledges, and between his nor-
mal and abnormal ignorances? If he has not, what is
the meaning of intelligence? T'o deny that a man who
will act uprightly and deal fairly with himself can cer-
tainly distinguish between what he knows he knows, and
what he only thinks or fancies that he knows, is surely
to make the understanding something like an unsubstan-
tial shadow or an empty shell, or to extinguish it alto-
gether. The great and chief function of intelligence can
be none else than to discriminate the true and the false.
When intelligence is legitimately used, it makes this dis-
crimination infallibly, or feels that it cannot make it.
When the true and the erroneous are not accurately dis-
tinguished by the understanding, or when the under-
standing attempts to distinguish them in cases that are
beyond its power, the understanding is abused. But,
then, it is impossible to conceive of intelligence apart
from consciousness ; and if consciousness be not fallacious,
when a man misuses his intelligence he must know that
he is doing so; and therefore all men, if they will act
conscientiously, may succeed in severing their normal
knowledge and normal ignorance from what is abnor-
mal.
By consciousness is meant a man’s knowledge of
everything that takes place within himself. Whatever
a man does or says or thinks or knows, he knows what
he is doing, saying, thinking, or knowing. This know-
ledge is immediate; whatever a man does, then and
CONCLUSION. 351
there he knows what he is doing; it is not the know-
ledge of what he did yesterday, but of what he is doing
now. The knowledge of consciousness 1s universal in
regard to the individual himself; if it do not compre-
hend the whole sphere of our activity, to the extent of
this deficiency we shall cease to be responsible. For
unless we know what we are doing, so as knowingly to
come up to, or fall short of, what we know to be right,
we cannot in such a case be regarded as accountable.
Consciousness is infallible ; for if 1 deceive us, it deceives
us either always or only occasionally. If consciousness
always deceives us, our knowledge is in every instance
abnormal, and truth is for ever hidden from our eyes ;
for then when we know an object, we do not know that
we know it, and when we do not know an object, we know
that we know it. If consciousness deceive occasionally
only, then we can distinguish between the occasions in
which we are deceived and those in which we are not
deceived, or we cannot distinguish between them. If we
can distinguish between them, that is, if we know when
we are misled and when we are not, then in fact con-
sciousness does not deceive us at all. But if we cannot
distinguish between them, then we shall be found trust-
ing consciousness when we should distrust her, and dis-
trusting her when she should be trusted. On this sup-
position, intelligence is a mockery and the possession of
it a pure misfortune.
If it be the proper function of the understanding to
adopt true propositions, to reject erroneous propositions,
ooo CONCLUSION.
and to pause and be ignorant when neither the truth nor
erroneousness of a proposition is known, there is an obvi-
ous and not unimportant sense in which reason may be
said to be ¢mpersonal. To call anything impersonal may
mean—I, that it is not a person; or 2, that it does not
belong to any person; or 3, that it does not belong to
any one individual or class of persons exclusively.
When Victor Cousin pleads, as he so earnestly does,
for the impersonality of reason, he chiefly uses the word
in the first or the second of the three meanings just
specified. His opinion seems to be that reason is not a
person, or rather does not even belong to a person, but is
identical with the eternal substance before it comes to
self-consciousness or personality in the creation of the
world. His doctrine of the impersonality of reason is
closely connected with his distinction between spontane-
ous and reflective reason, and with the monism and tran-
scendental intuition of the German school. For the re-
jection of all these views many and weighty arguments
might be easily adduced.
Reason is impersonal in this sense that it does not
belong to any one individual or class of persons exclu-
sively. Truth is universal, eternal, and immutable ; what
is once true, is true everywhere and always. Reason,
inasmuch as it is conversant with truth, is not peculiar to
one individual or one class, but is common to all minds.
Truth is not the creature of my volition, or of any voli-
tion. Neither is intelligence, abstractly considered, the
creature of volition, but the means, and the only instru-
CONCLUSION. abo
ment or means, by which truth can be perceived and
- appreciated.
My possession of a certain degree of intelligence is the
eift of God, and my responsibility lies in the use which I
make of this gift. The way, then, in which we shall
employ our reason being the hinge of our responsibility,
and, therefore, a matter of choice, the actual employment
of it may be either legitimate or illegitimate. In the
legitimate or proper use of the understanding all our
knowledges and ignorances are of course normal. But
when we use our reason improperly, then what is true is
confounded in our minds with what is not true, and what
we may know with what we cannot know. Since truth
is catholic and unchanging, and ever consistent with her-
self, so also will reason or intelligence be in all her teach-
ings so long as she is used legitimately. Men using their
understandings aright would never contradict themselves
nor contradict one another. The exclusion of contradiec-
tion from our sentiments is not to be understoed, you
will remember, as excluding all sorts of diversity and
variety of opinion in matters of probability. Reason,
then, when duly exercised, cannot be supposed to teach
truth which shall be held as the peculiar property of any
party ; and her real impersonality consists simply in this,
that her doctrines, however numerous or varied, are
always catholic to the sincere, and harmonious with each
other.
On the other hand, when reason is misused, her teach-
ings, or rather what passes for her teachings, are found
354 CONCLUSION.
to be contradictory with each other. But error is not
universal in any of its forms; much less in one of them.
To employ reason illegitimately by attempting to pass
the due limits of knowledge, or by confounding truth and
error within those limits, is not characteristic of all intel-
higent beings, but is limited to some of them, and is,
therefore, peculiar and personal. Abnormal knowledge
or erroneous judgment, then, is not to be traced to any-
thing that God has given, or failed to give, to an intelli-
gent being, but to the improper use which that intelligent
being has chosen to make of the gift of God, and, there-
fore, in an obvious sense personal. }
Though the exercise of our understanding, whether
legitimate or illegitimate, be thus dependent upon the
will or voluntary, it must not be forgotten, as already
intimated, that, no erroneous judgment whatever can be
voluntary directly. For to take an erroneous proposition
to be true, knowing it to be erroneous, is impossible. But
the common opinion that any error is involuntary and
invincible, as it is generally held, is equally inadmissible.
This opinion not only asperses the character of God, but
is, strictly speaking, self-contradictory. Nothing seems
to be plainer than this mode of stating the case, that if
an intelligent creature in forming his sentiments con-
founds what is true with what is erroneous involuntarily,
inevitably and unblamably, the intelligent Creator must
be held responsible for the defective character or unpro-
1“ Tu fecisti eum, et peccatum non fecisti in eo.” God made
man, and did not make sin in him.—Augustine. Conf. Lib. i. ¢. 7.
CONCLUSION. aug
pitious circumstances of his creature. But more than
this, if erroneous judgment be, even in a single instance,
strictly and absolutely involuntary and invincible on the
part of him who adopts it, there are no means left to him
whereby he may distinguish the erroneous from the true.
If, notwithstanding the use of all proper diligence and
precaution on my part, I may yet, without the consent of
my will and altogether unconsciously, take what is true
to be erroneous or what is erroneous to be true, then I
can never feel certain that I have found the truth. On
such a supposition, consciousness itself deceives me, and
my very nature is a lie.
We shrink not, therefore, from the assertion that
human reason rightly or conscientiously employed is at
once supreme and infallible.
By reason, however, we mean reason practical, as well
as reason speculative. Truth is the end of the latter,
action of the former. In the one case we know that we
may know; in the other, we know that we may act.
These two functions of the understanding, however, are
not to be subordinated the one to the other, as they
have often been, and with the most ruinous consequences.
They are to be considered not only as distinct, but also
as co-ordinate in authority ; and hence it is nothing but
a vain, proud boast to say, that “ philosophy is the
light of all lights, the authority of all authorities.”
The human understanding has two fields in which to
expatiate, the written and the unwritten revelations of
God; she has two volumes to study, the Bible and the
356 CONCLUSION,
book of nature. Reason, moreover, entirely severed
from both of these, can learn nothing and know nothing,
It is, therefore, an equal perversion of the plain facts of
the case, to set reason against the word of God, or the
word of God against reason; or to set the volume of
nature against the volume of inspiration, or the volume
of inspiration against the volume of nature.
Reason per se has nothing that can by any possibility
be contrary to the statements of the Bible or to the facts
of nature; her function lies simply in the reception and
apprehension of both of them. And there cannot be a
greater absurdity than to suppose, that what the under-
standing learns from one divine revelation may be con-
tradicted by what it learns from another divine reyela-
tion. But though the declarations of Scripture fairly
interpreted can never be in conflict with the fair deduc-
tions of natural science, it is worse than childish to deny
that reason can learn from the one revelation truths
which she could never learn from the other. It ought
never to be forgotten, moreover, that reason may gather
in both revelations many propositions, of which we
clearly and surely know that they are true, while we feel
altogether baffled and confounded in the very attempt to
know how they are true.
It follows from what has now been said, that while
reason cannot possess a higher authority than the
word of God, neither does the word of God possess
a higher authority than reason. The authority of
reason is the infallibility of consciousness, which, in
CONCLUSION. 857
other words, is the belief that God would not make us so
as to trustalie. The authority of reason, therefore, and
the authority of the Bible, are identical; they are both
divine. How then can we speak of the one as supersed-
ing the other ?
It still further appears that reason in itself is not the
source of any knowledge whatever. This is the proper
answer to those who represent Scripture to be unneces-
sary, on the ground that reason is the only source of
knowledge, or, as they say, the arbiter of all truth. To
repel this objection, it is sufficient to say, that knowledge
is not derived from the faculty of reason in an isolated
state, but is acquired by the employment of reason on
its appropriate objects. These objects, we have seen, are
the all things within our intellectual range, mental and
material. To deny that the Bible is one of those objects,
and a most important one, is surely a delusion.
It is equally futile to assert that there is no certainty
to man apart from the word of God. On those par-
ticular matters, of course, with which Scripture is spe-
cially conversant, we can expect certain knowledge only
from written revelation. But if reason could not attain
certainty in some things without the Bible, neither could
she attain certainty in other things by means of the
Bible. Nay, more, there are special truths lying at the
foundation of all Bible teaching, which the inspired
writers do not so much authoritatively announce as un-
obtrusively take for granted. And apart from these
fundamental truths, the peculiar doctrines of the word
358 CONCLUSION.
of God would lose all their significance. Many of the
defenders of revelation in the present day, as well as its
opponents, would do well to study the masculine writings
of such men as John Howe. Speaking of the “non
scripta, sed nata lex,” he remarks, ‘“ when we say the
Scripture is a complete rule, we do not mean as severed
and cut off from the law of nature, or in opposition to
that, or as excluding that, but as including it, and as
excluding only the unnecessary and arbitrary inventions
of men, and the additions that they think fit to subnect
to it.”
There is another grave mistake prevalent in some
circles, when what is called mere reason is opposed to
reason assisted by the grace of God. When our under-
standing 1s assisted by the gracious aid of our Maker, it
is assisted but to fulfil its proper function, and not to
transcend it. If our mental powers were in our present
circumstances sufficient of themselves to lead us to the
knowledge of all needful truth, Divine aid would neither
be required nor given. If our intellect leads us astray, it
is no lonyer mere reason, but perverted reason. But the
only legitimate and effectual way in which those who
accept the proffered assistance of divine grace can mani-
fest the necessity and realization of this heavenly help,
is by shewing that their opinions or convictions are agree-
able to reason, and that the opposite opinions espoused
by those who deny or reject this help are contrary to
reason. If mere reason be pure or right reason, then,
in man’s corrupt state, it is only found in alliance with
CONCLUSION. 359
God’s Holy Spirit. But if mere reason be reason reject-
ing that divine aid which is both needed and offered, to
suppose that it is right reason is absurd. And if it be
not right reason, but reason abused, it is incumbent on
the disciples of truth to trace it through all its wander-
ings, and expose its manifold errors. To assert that any
one is wrong in all his opinions, is to deny his intelli-
gence or responsibility. But there are certain important
questions on which men can form accurate sentiments only
by the aid of the Holy Spirit. Those who ask and accept
this aid should be able to shew that on these questions
their opinions are reasonable, and that the contrary
opinions of those who reject this aid are unreasonable.
Hence we obtain an all-important conclusion, that not
only Error and Truth, but also the adherents of error
and the adherents of truth, ever are, and ever must be,
in antagonism and conflict. To state the case more pre-
cisely, when of two intelligent beings the one takes a
proposition to be true, and the other takes it to be false,
each of them feels not only that there is a difference or
contradiction between them of less or greater moment
depending upon the nature of the question in dispute,
but also that this opposition must be traced to a defect
of judgment, or to a deficiency of candour in himself or
in his opponent. In every controversy each disputant
proceeds, and must necessarily proceed, on the assump-
tion not only that his adversary is wrong, but also that
if he would listen without prejudice to the arguments
360 CONCLUSION.
adduced he would perceive his error and change his sen-
timents. It would be an act of intellectual suicide to
attempt to convince another, unless we are well assured
that our representations are such as will win to our opi-
nion an honest and unbiassed mind.
It is one of the great heresies of the age to forget or
deny this twofold antagonism between truth and error.
This heresy has, as we have seen, two sides, both of
which are almost equally fatal to philosophy and virtue.
To allow that every man’s opinion is true is no graver a
mistake, than to allow that those who hold conflicting
opinions are equally capable and equally conscientious in
(not holding but) adopting their opinions. A deficient
capacity exempts from responsibility ; a deficient con-
scientiousness incurs guilt. In every vital and moment-
ous dispute the opposing parties are seen to be driven,
as by some unceasing necessity, to charge each other
with a serious defect in intelligence or in honesty. No
believer in Christianity allows that the unbeliever has,
with ordinary ability, and due diligence and integrity,
examined the Christian evidences. While a glance at
infidel publications and arguments is sufficient to perceive
the correctness of the remark, that “ Christians must be
fools or knaves, for the ease and comfort of those who
reject Christianity.” The same result is developed in
every urgent and weighty discussion, though not always
with the same unambiguous distinctness.
As this result seems to be replete with the most serious
a ee ee
CONCLUSION. 361
inconveniences, having an apparently strong tendency to
repress everything like good feeling, and to excite vari-
ance and hatred in society, the legitimacy of the result
has been more or less openly negatived or evaded in a
thousand forms. Many illustrations might be selected
from our current literature, but we prefer one of older
date. Locke, in his “ Letter concerning toleration,”
goes so far in vindicating every man’s right to think for
himself, as virtually in some places to base this right
upon the assumption that every man’s opinion is true. |
This is clearly the case in his definition of heresy, which
both in its scriptural and ecclesiastical sense means, and
must mean, an opinion or opinions opposed to and sub-
versive of the great and simple truths of the New Testa-
ment, on the intelligent and honest reception of which
the salvation of those possessing the Bible depends.
“ Heresy,” says Locke, “is a separation made in eccle-
siastical communion between men of the same religion,
for some opinions no way contained in the rule itself.
Amongst those who acknowledge nothing but the Holy
Scriptures to be the rule of faith, heresy is a separation
made in their Christian communion for opinions not con-
tained in the express words of Scripture.” Locke here
virtually, if not expressly, denies that there is such a
phenomenon as a man professing to hold the exact words
of Scripture, and rejecting the truths contained in these
words; or, which is the. same thing, that every man’s
interpretation of the Bible is sound and correct, or that
each man’s opinion is to all intents and purposes right.
Vs
362 CONCLUSION.
It would be easy to multiply examples of the pre-
valence of this mistake on its other side. Nothing is
more common than for disputants to exchange cowpli-
ments of mutual respect, to allow concerning each other,
not only that they are in their general character honour-
able men, but also conscientiously and earnestly seeking
the truth in the particular matter under dispute. This
mode of procedure is unexceptionable, provided no one
holds any fixed sentiments at all, or all men regard every
conclusion with like indifference. But as soon as men
adopt principles, which are felt to be at once unspeak-
ably momentous and directly antagonistic and exclusive,
to reciprocate conventional phrases of sincerity, integrity,
and honour, is to mock the majesty of truth and insult
poor suffering humanity, as if truth and error were inter-
changeable epithets, or as if there were no perceptible
or worthy difference between the mind that embraces
truth and the mind that embraces error.
In connection with this point you will recollect that
the proper foundation and nature of the virtues of charity
and forbearance were in some degree made manifest.
Having thus endeavoured to point out the distinction
between abnormal and normal knowledges, we now pro-
ceed, secondly, to advert to a similar distinction between
our beliefs. Belief seems to us to be the immediate and
invariable consequent of knowledge. Different kinds of
belief will thus entirely depend.upon the different kinds
of knowledge ; and since knowledge may be always ex-
pressed in a proposition, there will be no belief without
CONCLUSION. 1 0ys)
a proposition believed. It is, however, obviously impro-
per and unusual to speak of believing a proposition when
we only understand its meaning and do not know whe-
ther it be true or erroneous. To profess to believe a
proposition to be true or erroneous without even per-
ceiving its meaning, is as great hypocrisy as to profess to
believe it to be true while regarding it as erroneous. ‘T’o
believe a proposition, then, clearly implies both that we
comprehend its import and perceive it to be true; but
not by any means that we know how it is true. Belief
in a simple proposition containing one unambiguous affir-
mation is the most elementary form which faith assumes,
to one or more instances of which every variety of trust
or confidence may be easily reduced.
Some have supposed that belief should be restricted
to those propositions whose truth we know by other
means than by our own direct personal effort. This
isage is not universal, nor is it founded on any obvious
or sufficient reason. For it is quite as correct, gramma-
tically and logically, to speak of belief resting on the
evidence of our own senses, or on argument and deduc-
tion of our understanding, or on an intellectual intuition,
as on the testimony of witnesses or on the declarations of
divine authority. _
Some, again, have proposed to limit the application of
faith or belief to propositions connected with religion or
the Bible. But this restriction is equally destitute of the
sanction of reason and custom. Indeed the objects of
belief are co-extensive with the objects of knowledge.
364 CONCLUSION.
If belief is to be classified by its objects, there will be no
end to the division. All beliefs are, subjectively and
fundamentally, one and the same—the acceptance by the
mind of a proposition known to be true. For example,
there seems to be no valid distinction between theologi-
cal faith and metaphysical or philosophical faith. Theo-
logical faith is belief in a proposition which we know to
be true on the authority of the Word of God. Meta-
physical or philosophical faith is belief in a proposition
which we know to be true on the authority of our own
understanding. In both cases we must know that the
proposition is true; in neither case may we know how
it is true. The proposition believed must be known as
true, but may also involve something incomprehensible.
There is obviously no real difference between these two
beliefs; for we cannot trust our understanding without
trusting God whose gift it is, nor can we trust the Word
of God without trusting our own understanding, by which
alone we can comprehend the declarations of God.
Misbelief cannot be distinguished from disbelief, which
is the denial that a proposition (believed by others) is
true. Unbelief or doubt is properly the state of mind in
regard to a proposition which is not perceived to be either
true or erroneous. Hence we infer that belief or faith
imphes an affirmation or knowledge that a proposition is
true; desbelief or misbelief implies the knowledge that a
proposition is erroneous; while unbelief or doubt is the
immediate and invariable consequent of ignorance, or the
refusal of the mind to make an affirmation either as to
CONCLUSION. 365
the truth or erroneousness of a proposition. Disbelief
and unbelief, like error and ignorance, are often used
indiscriminately, with the not unfrequent result of much
confusion and evil.
Belief and its compounds are often used objectively,
that is, for the matter accepted or rejected by the mind.
This is a secondary use of the words, with which we have
at present nothing to do.
Since faith or belief, as we have seen, always presup-
poses knowledge, it cannot be a source of knowledge.
«No man can apprehend as true, what he does not ap-
prehend at all.” It is a contradiction to say that a man
can believe what he does not know to be true. And
though, as has been already remarked, we must be often
content to believe without knowing the mode, the how,
the philosophy of what we believe; yet are we traitors
to truth, and to our own understanding, and to God him-
self, when we believe, or rather profess to believe that,
of the truth of which we have not an intelligent per-
suasion.
Some have distinguished between knowledge and faith
as if the former implied or was equivalent to certainty,
and the latter could boast of nothing higher than pro-
bability. The remarks already made are sufficient to
shew, that though these words may be sometimes so used .
in popular discourse, such usage is not general nor un-
attended with disadvantage ; nor are there any arguments
sufficient to justify it, or render it universal.
We have seen that there are normal and abnormal
366 CONCLUSION.
knowledges; corresponding to these there are normal
and abnormal beliefs. If we have succeeded in proving
that there is no such thing as involuntary or invincible
error, it follows that there is no such thing as an irre-
sponsible belief.
In addition to what has been already advanced against
the doctrine of involuntary error, it may be further main-
tained, that if it be conceded that man is responsible for
any of his beliefs, it will follow that he is responsible for
all his beliefs, unless some important and well-marked
distinction can be pointed out between the beliefs for
which we are responsible and those for which we are not
responsible. Now, no such distinction has, in fact, been
pointed out and substantiated ; nor do we think that it is
possible to do so.
No man believes a proposition, whatever he may pre-
tend, till he knows or fancies that it is true. If the
proposition be actually true, then an individual in know-
ing it, and believing it, to be true, acts the proper part
of an intelligent being, and worthily acquits himself of
his responsibility. But if the proposition be not really
true, and notwithstanding this an individual allow him-
self to think that it is true, then undoubtedly his know-
ledge and belief are both abnormal, and who shall say
that guilt is not incurred. That when knowledge and
belief are thus abnormal, guilt is frequently at least in-
curred, is generally admitted, and we shall therefore for
the present take this for granted. If it be said that when
belief is abnormal guilt is not always incurred, then on
eS a.
CONCLUSION. 367
what ground does the distinction rest? Is it said, that
“in some cases a man is able to perceive the truth, and in
other cases that he is not able? If unable to perceive
the truth, or if from any cause the truth be not perceived,
then ignorance and not knowledge, unbelief and not
belief, should be his state of mind. Is it said, that he is
constrained by force external to himself to think that
what is true is erroneous? The supposition is inconsis-
tent with the possession of intelligence. Is it said, that
belief in what is false is sometimes invincible and involun-
tary? The assertion, as has been shewn, renders every
belief doubtful and nugatory. There is only one consis-
tent conclusion left for our adoption, namely, that in every
instance abnormal knowledge and its corresponding belief,
being voluntary indirectly, involves a responsible being
in culpability and liability to punishment.
This conclusion, however, is not unattended with an
apparent difficulty of the most formidable character. Tor
it will be asked, how can any man living hope to escape
from all erroneous sentiments! or how can men be re-
garded as culpable, who have done what they could to
reach the truth !
It is not maintained that in the present state of human
society every man who acts conscientiously will amime-
diately attain exemption from erroneous judgments and
self-inconsistency. But the cases in which this immediate
exemption is not attainable, may be so specified and ex-
plained as to vindicate the correctness of the principle
that has been announced.
368 . CONCLUSION.
The understanding of a child being, like his body, im-
mature, his mind is dependent upon the instructions of
his parents, as his body is sustained by their care. If
the child did not believe, on the authority of those who
are charged with his education, what he himself by his
own intelligence does not and cannot know to be true, he
would never grow up to bea man. Thereis accordingly
in children a natural instinct or disposition suitable to
their cireumstances, which leads them to believe the
word, or trust the authority of their parents, without
questioning and without hesitation. If, then, human
society be fallen and corrupt, as it undoubtedly is, young
persons who are brought up among prevailing erroneous
sentiments, and are legitimately bound while in their
minority to accept their beliefs on the authority of their
natural guardians, will be inevitably led, notwithstanding
any efforts which they might make to the contrary, to
adopt not a few erroneous principles. Having, in this
manner, adopted false opinions, and having moreover
often acted upon them, it is not to be expected that, do
what they may, they will easily or quickly extricate
themselves from the maze of error in which they have
been trained.
Besides, when such individuals reach full maturity,
even though they may be conscious of being involved in
error, and be intensely anxious to escape from it, and to
know the truth on every subject, they are not at liberty
to dismiss all their beliefs and suspend all action, till they
shall have calmly and at liesure examined every needful
=— SS, aoe
CONCLUSION. 369
topic for themselves, and adopted a ripened judgment.
They are urged on irresistibly by the pressure of events,
the eagerness of desire, and the calls of duty, to reason
and decide and act, even while there minds are prepos-
sessed and governed by prejudices and erroneous prin-
ciples. Here, then, is a well-marked class of cases,
whose features may be easily discriminated and recog-
nised. We must, therefore, expect to meet with many
individuals adopting and acting upon false principles,
Srom which no personal consceentiousness on their part
could have saved them. Neither must it be forgotten,
that these false principles were not conscientiously adopted,
but simply received on hereditary authority. The fact
that the first reception of these prejudices was legitimate
enough, and that afterwards no fair opportunity was
afforded for revising and considering them on account of
the urgent pressure of circumstances, may qualify the
personal culpability of those who are thus situated, but
it cannot alter the nature of error or of erroneous judg-
ment.
Making every allowance, then, for such cases as the
above, it still remains true, that every man is bound to
avail himself of every proper opportunity to examine
with all diligence and scrupulosity the accuracy of his
beliefs. Moreover, it is only a strong and practical
necessity which can in any degree excuse a man for hold-
ing, and acting upon, a hereditary belief, which he has
not examined for himself and found on satisfactory
grounds to be true. And more specifically it cannot be
370 CONCLUSION.
denied, that when a man deliberately examines a ques-
tion, and avows his opinion after due and _professedly
impartial consideration, maintaining that the belief which
he has adopted is necessary to secure the welfare of him-
self and others, he cannot be mistaken in this belief
without justly incurring censure.
It is no doubt proper to distinguish between those of
our abnormal beliefs which are the result of our own per-
sonal derelictions, and those which are hereditary and
may be traced entirely to our circumstances; but it is
no less proper to notice their connection and agreement.
It may be easily shewn that both kinds of abnormal
belief imply guilt. Guilt is twofold; direct and indirect.
Direct guilt is incurred by doing what we know at the
time of doing it to be wrong. Indirect guilt is incurred
by doing what we know or think at the time of doing it
to be right, but which is in reality wrong. Erroneous
or abnormal belief, therefore, is the distinguishing peculi-
arity of indirect guilt. To deny that abnormal belief
involves guilt is to deny the guilt of infanticide, sutteeism,
and a thousand abominations. To shift the guilt of
abnormal belief from the creature is to cast it upon
the Creator. Abnormal belief is culpable indirectly,
not only because it leads, or may lead, to improper
actions, but also because it is always the result of direct
guilt.
We fully admit the distinction between the abnormal
beliefs which may be traced to our own personal trans-
gressions, and those which may be traced to the trans-
CONCLUSION. ST
gressions of our forefathers. In practical life, however,
it is not always easy to distinguish between them. Be-
sides it is the duty of every man to endeayour to escape
from both these sorts of erroneous judgments, and it is
the ultimate destiny of every honest man to effect a full
and final escape from them all. Moreover, while we
are implicated in them, we find ourselves exposed to
suffer the penalties of the one sort as well as of the
other.
For it is an undoubted fact, that guilt or liability to
punishment is found attaching itself to an erroneous
judgment, over which the individual who holds it has had
little or even no personal control at all, being strictly
hereditary, as well as to one which is the unquestionable
result of his own carlessness, apathy, or wilful prejudice.
This fact involves the principle that among a race of
beings constituted as men are, individuals may be seri-
ously implicated in the guilt of their progenitors, inde-
pendently of their own will and without their own con-
sent. In this simple statement of the case as it actually
exists in the world around us, we have a strong confirma-
tion of our assertion that every abnormal belief is culpable.
And though many attempts have been made to deny or
soften the painful fact just alluded to, they have all been
manifestly unsuccessful. And if it be indeed the case,
that every erroneous judgment is culpable, and that men
are justly held responsible for such, it follows that the
most honest and effectual method for the Christian
Church to refute Infidelity and Popery and to con-
Bie CONCLUSION.
vert the nations, is just to do herself what she exhorts
others to do, ‘‘ Buy the truth, and sell it not.” When
she does so, her schisms will be healed, and the world,
seeing her union, will believe that God has sent His
Son.
THE END.
PRINTED BY JOHN HUGHES, 3 THISTLE STREET, EDINBURGH.
i
Books Publiahed
REW ELLIOT,
15_PRINCES STREET, EDINBURGH.
Black’s (Dr Alexander) Exegetical Study of the Original
Scriptures, considered in connection with the Training of Theo-
logical Students. Demy 8vo, 1s,
Charlie Forest, the Embryo Missionary. 18mo, sewed, 2d.
The Crimea: Its Towns, Inhabitants, and Social Customs,
By a Lady resident near the Alma. Foolscap 8vo, 2s 6d.
Cuthbert’s (Rev. Alexander, Bathgate) Infants Asleep in
Jesus: or, Light on Little Graves. Small 8vo, cloth, 2s 6d.
Cuthbert’s (Rev. Alexander) Flowers of Paradise; or, Little
Ones Gone Home. 18mo, 4d.
Dill’s (Dr Edward M.) Gathering Storm; or, Britain’s
Romeward Career. Foolscap 8vo, cloth, 1s 4d.
Dill’s (DrEdward M.) Mystery Solved; or, Ireland’s Miseries;
the Grand Cause and Cure. Foolscap 8vo, 2s 6d.
Doig’s (Mary) Stories of Stars and Star-Gazers. Crown 8vo,
with numerous illustrations, cloth elegant, 2s.
Dove's (P. Edward) Romanism, Rationalism, and Protestant-
ism, viewed Historically in relation to National Freedom and National
Welfare. 12mo, 9d.
Drinking Customs of Scotland: Their Cost, Cause, Effects,
and Cure. By an Excise Official. Demy 8vo, 6d.
Early History of Philip 0’Flaherty, the Young Soldier, with
Graphic Notices of the War, and of his intercourse with Turkish
Officers. Crown 8vo, cloth, ls; or in Two Parts, 6d each.
The Everlasting Kingdom. 18mo, sewed, 4d.
Family Life; or, Masters and Servants as they were, are, and
ought to be. By the Rev. Drs Hetrnerineron and Txomson.
18mo, sewed, 8d; cloth, Is.
“« We very earnestly recommend this very interesting little work.”—Christ. Witness.
“The right book, at the right time, and from the right men.”—Scottish Review.
“© We like this volume exceedingly.”—British Standard.
Hain’s (Adolph) Poems. Post 8vo, price 6s. Written in the Ger-
man Language. i
‘‘ Display a very fine and delicate vein of poetic feeling, accompanied with grace
and elegance and simplicity of expression, and an easy unaffected rythm.”—Pro-
fessor Blackie.
Hetherington’s (Rev. Dr) Constitution of the Family Circle.
18mo, 4d.
PUBLISHED BY ANDREW ELLIOT.
ote. me 4
Holidays at the Cottage; or, A Visit to Aunt Susan. Foolscap
8vo, with two Bewaieal Vinodcute, 3s 6d. Adapted to the capacities
of Young People between the ages of Nine and Fourteen.
Hume’s (George) Waifs of Womanhood: A Plea for Unfor-
tunates. Second Edition. Crown 8vo, 9d.
Killen’s (Rev. J. M., Comber) Our Friends in-Heaven; or,
The Mutual Recognition of the Redeemed in Glory Demonstrated.
Fifth Edition. Crown 8vo, 4s 6d.
“A full, earnest, able, and conclusive investigation of the entire subject.”—Bri-
tish and For eign Ev angelical Review.
“ Its execution is as good as its design is excellent.”—Journal of Sacred Literature.
Kitty Brown Beginning to Think. By the Authoress of “The
Manse of Sunnyside.” 18mo, cloth, 1s.; cloth elegant 1s 6d.
Links of Sacred Story; or, Lessons from the Prophets.
By the Author of “ Charlie Forest.” 18mo, 4d.
Lumsden’s (Professor) Infant Baptism ; Its Nature and Ob-
jects. Foolscap 8vo, Is.
Macfarlane’s (Rev. Dr) Altar-Gold; or, The Worthiness of
the Lamb that was Slain to Receive Riches. Third Edition. 18mo,
6d,; cloth, Is
‘* At once felicitous in design and brilliant in execution.”—United Presbyterian
Magazine.
‘¢ Jt has an originality and rareness of expression that are quite refreshing and
delig htful.”—N onconformist.
Macpherson’s (Peter, A.M.,) Song of Songs; Shown to be
constructed on Architectural principles. Demy 8vo, 6d.
Manse of Sunnyside; or, Trials of a Minister’s Family.
18mo, 8d.; cloth, 1s.; cloth elegant, Is. 6d.
«« A most interesting story.”_—Witness. “te Very instructive.”—British Messenger.
Meikle’s (Rev. James) Edenic Dispensation, with Strictures
on Certain Opinions of the late Rev. George Payne, LL.D. Fool-
seap 8vo, 3s 6d,
Meikle’s (Rev. James) Nature of the Mediatorial Dispensa-
tion. Crown 8vo, 6s.
Miller’s (Hugh) Testimony of the Rocks ; or, Geology in its
bearings on the Two Theologies, Natural and Revealed. Post Svo.
profusely illustrated with wood engravings, 7s 6d.
Miller’s (Hugh) Strange but True: Incidents in the Life of Dr
John Kitto. 18mo, sewed, 2d.
Miniature Series of Books, 1d. each, or 1s. a packet.
1. Spots upon the Sun; or, Blemishes in the Christian Character,
By the Rey. John Newton, Olney.
2: Little Jessie ; or, the Death-bed of a Young Believer.
3. Affliction; Why it Comes, and What it Teaches. By Rev. Dr
Morgan, Belfast.
4, Old Jeddy. ‘“'There’s Rest at Home.”
5. The Little Grave. By the Rev. Alexander Cuthbert, A.M.
6. A Few Words on Prayer. Addressed by a Sabbath School
Teacher to his Class.
PUBLISHED BY ANDREW ELLIOT,
Miniature Series of Books— Continued.
7. The World as Seen by One Leaving it.
8. Our Friends in Hell; or, Fellowship amongst the Lost. By Rey.
J. M. Killen, A.M.
9. The Lord’s Supper. By the late Rev. John Willison, Dundee.
10. A Woman’s Plea for Temperance. By H. S. C., an Officer’s
Widow.
11. Poor Tom. The Publican’s Victim.
12. Awake Thou that Sleepest. By Rev. Dr Knox.
Miniature Series of Tracts for all Classes, adapted for Envelope
Distribution. Royal 32mo, price ls. The Packet contains jive
copies of each of the following Tracts :—
Family Worship—Its Power.
. Why is the World not Converted. By the Rev. Dr Nevins.
The Useful Christian. By the Rey. Dr Chalmers.
Man’s Responsibility for his Belicf. By the Rev. Dr Chalmers.
. The Anxious Inquirer. By the Rev. Dr Chalmers.
. There is another Man. By the Rey. Dr Guthrie.
. I am but One! But I am One !—8. I will Keep Thee—9.
Wark! Work!—10. He is a Christian.—1l. Is He a Chris-
tian ?—12. Lost Leaves.—13. Speak the Truth.—14. Why
should we Pray ?—15. The Prayer-Meeting.—16. Think on
these Things.—17. “He afflicts.” By the Rev. Dr Guthrie.—
18. The Cloud with the Silver Lining.—19. The Bible in my
Trunk.—20. Found Dead. By the Rev. John Hall, Armagh.
Morgan (Rev. Dr) Your Child’s Baptism; 18mo, sewed, 2d.
Morgan (Rev. Dr) The Lord’s Table, Why it is Spread, and who
are Invited. 18mo, sewed, 2d.
Muir’s (Rev. A. Stuart) Glimpses of Prophet Life. Meditations
on the History of Jonah. Crown 8vo, 3s 6d
Packet of Books, 18mo, price 1s 4d. Containing the following :—
1. Flowers of Paradise ; or, Little Ones Gone Home. By Rev. A.
Cuthbert, A.M.
2. The Constitution of the Family Circle. By Rev. Dr Hetherington.
3. Friendly Counsels to Female Servants. By Rev. Dr Andrew
Thomson.
4. The Master and the Servant. By Rev. Dr Thomson.
Packet of Twopenny Books, 18mo, with Vignettes, price 1s. The
Packet comprises the following :—
1. Strange but True: Incidents in the Life of Dr John Kitto: By
the late Hugh Miller.
2. Look before you Leap: A Story for Boys. By W. Burns Thomson.
3. Charlie Forest: The Embryo Missionary.
4, The Lord’s Table: Why it is spread, and who are invited. By
the Rev. Dr Morgan, Belfast.
5. Your Child’s Baptism ; An Address to Parents. By Dr Morgan.
6. The Three Legged Penny: or, The Power of Littles.
Portraits.
The Rev. Horatrus Bonar, D.D., from Drawing by J. Ballantyne,
and Engraved by Robert G. Bell. First Provufs, 31s 6d; Proofs,
2ls; Prints, 10s 6d.
YO TUR OOD
PUBLISHED BY ANDREW ELLIOT.
Portraits— Continued.
The Rev. Rosrrr S. Caypursn, D.D., from Chalk Drawing by Faed,
taken from Photograph by Popowitz, and Engraved by Francis
Holl, Autograph Proofs, 42s; Proofs, 21s; Prints, 15s.
The late Rev. Toomas Cuatmers, D.D., LL.D., from Photograph
by Claudet, and Engraved by R. T. Ryall. First Proofs, 42s ;
Proofs, 21s ; Prints, 10s 6d.
The Rev. Witi1am Cunninenam, D.D., from Painting by John
Faed, Engraved by Ed. Burton. First Proofs, 63s ; Proofs,
42s ; Prints, 21s.
The Rev. D. T. K. Drummonp, from Daguereotype by Claudet,
Engraved by James Faed. First Proofs, 31s 6d ; Proofs, 21s ;
Prints, 10s 6d.
Hvueu Miter, Esq., Engraved by Bell, from Photograph by Turner.
First Proofs, 5s; Prints, 3s 6d.
Joun Knox, the Scottish Reformer, from Portrait in possession of
the Right Hon. Lord Torphichen, and Engraved by J. Talfourd
Smyth. First Proofs, 42s; Proofs, 21s ; Prints, 15s.
James Y. Simpson, M.D., F.R.S., from Daguereotype by Popowitz,
and Engraved by J. Talfourd Smyth. Artist’s Proofs, 42s ;
Autograph Proofs, 31s 6d; Proofs, 21s; Prints, 15s.
Religion in Earnest: Tales Illustrative of Christian Life in
Germany. Translated from the German of Baron Strauss by Mrs
Stanley Carr. With Prefatory Notice by Rev. W. Hanna, LL.D. 4s.
Thomson’s (Rev. Dr. Andrew) Friendly Counsels to Female
Servants, especially to such as profess to be the Servants of Christ.
18mo, with Woodcut, price 4d.
Thomson’s (Rev. Dr) Master and Servant. 18mo, 4d.
Thomson’s (W. Burns) Look before you Leap. A Story for
Boys. 18mo, price 2d.
The Three Legged Penny; or, the Power of Littles. 18mo.
sewed, 2d.
View of Edinburgh, from Painting by W. H. Williams.
Engraved in Line by William Miller. Proofs, 6s; Prints, 3s 6d.
What is Criticism? and whose Property are Letters Written
for the Press after they have reached their Destination; being Re-
port of Jury Trial, Rev. Nathan Davis v. the Proprietors of “The
Witness.” With Introductory Remarks by Hues Mintur. Post
8vo, 6d.
Wight’s (Rev. Geo.) Bible and the. Turf A Discourse for the
Times. Crown 8vo, 4d.
Wylie’s (Rev. Dr) Papacy; Its History, Dogmas, Genius,
and Prospects. Third Edition. Demy 8vo, 8s. 6d.
Wylie’s (Rev. Dr) Pilgrimage from the Alps to the T2%er ;
or, The Influence of Romanism on Trade, Justice, and Know! 1ge.
Post 8vo, cloth. elegant, price 7;. 6d.
““Dr Wylie s sketches of Austria and Papal Italy are replete with interest.” —
Athenzeum.
Princeton Theological Seminary-Speer Library
1
MQ
iS 5 mt ip
i | t ey Ub ey iy ]
‘ Pore a ed ‘'
Baek: vio f
ry 4 ak i]
ensihe va oD ak
Ht
nae
: @ oP ae
. eestor
TS x :
: mre
feietaseeeas tines
Serica
Sees
estbetonseesed
Shascotiart
Let fiers
lee
see
estmers paras
3 eee
SSSSSe
mate
Ste eas
peas,
emia enaas
epee erences s : | ?
rs = ee
: | — 5" aos