Section 
 

Digitized by the Internet Archive 
 in 2017 with funding from 
 Princeton Theological Seminary Library 
 
 https://archive.org/details/problemofhumanpeOOquin 
 
THE PROBLEM 
 
 OF 
 
 HUMAN PEACE 
 
BY THE SAME AUTHOR. 
 
 CATHOLICISM AND THE MODERN MIND 
 
 A Contribution to Religious Unity 
 and Progress. 
 
 London : EDWARD ARNOLD. 
 
 " We commend a perusal of this book to all thoughtful 
 Catholics .” — Catholic Herald, 
 
 “ This book is a system of theology. Theological 
 students of all sorts might well be advised to study it.”— 
 Church Timet. 
 
 “ In a masterly fashion the needs of the age are 
 revealed, the claims of Catholicism analysed, criticized 
 and justified, and the Catholic faith restated in the light 
 of modern thought — restated without giving up a single 
 essential .” — The Christian Commonwealth. 
 
 “ One who studies this singular pronouncement as a 
 whole, whether from the point of view of a devout 
 Catholic or of a scientific agnostic, may come to the 
 conclusion that it is the most drastic — certainly the most 
 intelligible — and perhaps the most rational form of that 
 ‘ Modernism,’ the task of which is to show how current 
 Christianity can be brought into a line with modern 
 thought.” — Frederic Harrison in the English Review. 
 
HUMAN PEACE 
 
 STUDIED FROM THE STANDPOINT 
 OF A SCIENTIFIC CATHOLICISM 
 
 BY 
 
 MALCOLM ''QUIN 
 
 Author of ** Catholicism and the Modern Mind,” 
 “ Aids to Worship,” etc. 
 
 " Agnus Dei, qui iollis peccala mundi, dona 
 nobis pacem.”— C anon of the Mass. 
 
 " Agir par affection, el penser pour agir .” — 
 
 Auguste Comte. 
 
 NEW YORK 
 
 E. P. DUTTON AND COMPANY 
 681 FIFTH AVENUE 
 1917 
 
Printed i; 
 
 Great Britain 
 
 [All rights reserved] 
 
PREFACE 
 
 It may prevent misapprehension with regard to the 
 following work if I say at once that it is not concerned 
 with any merely special and temporary questions, 
 commanding and urgent as they may seem in them- 
 selves, arising out of the present European war^ — as, 
 for instance, the causes which may be held to have 
 immediately led to it, or the conditions of peace by 
 which it ought to be followed. Before this treatise 
 appears in print the war may conceivably be ended, 
 and these particular questions will have lost their 
 importance. But questions still greater will remain — 
 the question of how far it may be possible to prevent 
 the recurrence of such a war, and maintain the 
 lasting peace of the world ; the question of the bearing 
 of so stupendous an event upon man’s conception of 
 himself and his destiny, under the conditions of 
 modern thought and life. These questions are not a 
 mere problem of politics, or statesmanship, in the 
 ordinary view of them. They are not questions only 
 for a particular country, or a particular class, or a 
 particular party — questions to be decided by the vic- 
 tories of the soldier, or by the resolutions of a Par- 
 liament or Congress, or by exercises in journalism, or 
 by increasing the number of voters, or by strengthen- 
 ing what is vaguely called the ‘‘ democracy.” They 
 are fundamental and universal questions— in every 
 sense of the word, catholic questions^ — of man’s mind 
 and fate. As such, they are questions for the scien- 
 tific thinker and teacher, extending the scope and 
 processes of science, as they must now be extended— 
 and as since the time of Comte it has been possible to 
 extend them — to the spheres of man’s social and 
 religious life. 
 
VI 
 
 PREFACE 
 
 It is from this point of view that I have endeavoured 
 here to treat them, and it is for this reason that I have 
 studied the Problem of Peace as the problem of a 
 “ Scientific Catholicism.” This world-wide and appal- 
 ling war hashad among its other great consequences this 
 — that it has caused a large number of serious minds 
 to ask themselves what must be the effect of such a 
 catastrophe on our ordinary conceptions of Chris- 
 tianity, and what ought naturally to be the part of a 
 religion of vision and prevision in the promotion of 
 peace. Some have answered this question in one 
 way, and some in another. Some have professed to 
 believe that the war would revive and deepen men’s 
 religious convictions, according to our traditional 
 Christianity ; others have openly and frankly said 
 “ this war has made us atheists.” My own answer 
 to this question will be found in the following pages. 
 I am sure that a religion which cannot show man, 
 with the certainty and breadth of science, his real 
 place and needs in the universe, and which, as a 
 consequence, is powerless to give him a right inspira- 
 tion and practical direction in his life on earth — I am 
 sure that such a religion, whatever its claims for 
 itself, will eventually be dismissed from the human 
 mind. I am sure, too, that Christianity, in all its 
 forms, has, throughout the nineteen hundred years 
 of its existence, exhibited this intellectual and social 
 incapacity, and never more signally than in regard 
 to the present war. But I am equally sure that in 
 Catholicism — the religion of man in his highest spheres 
 of development, following after his noblest ideals— 
 there is a positive and permanent content of goodness, 
 beauty and truth, which, scientifically understood and 
 completed, may carry him on in his pursuit of his own 
 perfection, and, as a consequence, towards the attain- 
 ment of a Human Peace. 
 
 That is the subject of the present work. It is 
 naturally a two-fold subject. It calls, first, for an 
 exposition — so far as the limits of this work allow, and 
 
PREFACE 
 
 Vll 
 
 relatively to the question of peace — of those religious 
 conceptions which I here denote by the expression 
 “ a Scientific Catholicism.” Secondly, it involves a 
 statement of the principles of international policy 
 derived from this Catholicism, which would, as I 
 hold, in their complete, continuous application, estab- 
 hsh a Human Peace. Many of those who cherish the 
 ideal of such a peace will probably say that to make 
 it dependent, as I have done, on the scientific trans- 
 formation and completion of Catholicism, is to indefi- 
 nitely postpone its reahzation. They do not believe 
 in the possibility of such a change. And in the 
 absence of it they consider it useless to appeal to 
 CathoHcism or to Christianity in any form for the 
 purposes of peace. 
 
 If, however, we are not to look to “ the Church,” 
 in any conception of it, for a Human Peace, from 
 what are we to expect it ? Some look for it to some 
 international understanding, or to the increased power 
 of what they call “ the democracy,” or to the spread 
 of Socialism, or perhaps even to some form of “ inter- 
 national Government.” Now, these various expec- 
 tations rest on one of two assumptions — either, first, 
 that from the unchanged human mind, which, during 
 three thousand years, has continually given forth the 
 forces of war, the force of a universal peace is now 
 somehow suddenly to proceed ; or, secondly, that a 
 change has actually been wrought in it which at last 
 makes such a peace possible. 
 
 The first of these assumptions we need not discuss. 
 Is there, in the history of mankind as a whole, or in ■ 
 the special history of the last hundred years, anything 
 which warrants the second ? That period is the period 
 which separates us from the Battle of Waterloo. It 
 has been the age — if there has ever been such an age 
 — of the democracy. It has seen the extension of 
 universal suffrage in almost every country of Europe. 
 It has been a time of widespread education, lower and 
 higher. It has witnessed an unexampled develop- 
 
PREFACE 
 
 viii 
 
 ment of international trade, and a growth of human 
 intercourse such as never before existed. It has, too, 
 seen the spread of Socialism throughout the world. 
 Yet it has also seen almost every civilized nation, 
 European and American, repeatedly at war, and it 
 has ended with a war vaster in its range, and more 
 monstrous in its processes and carnage, than any that 
 has ever been waged. 
 
 We are driven back, then, to this — that the estab- 
 lishment of a Human Peace demands a profound and 
 lasting change in the mind of man. A change so 
 great requires a power of corresponding greatness to 
 bring it about — not a short-sighted and shifting states- 
 manship, subject to the conflicts and oscillations of an 
 anarchic public opinion, and concerned at most for the 
 exclusive interests of competing nationalities, but an 
 international Spiritual Providence, the voice and guar- 
 dian of an undivided Humanity, capable of giving 
 counsels of inspiration and guidance throughout the 
 world, and of breathing forth influences of reconcilia- 
 tion and co-operation in every country, and in every 
 sphere of the life of man. Such a work cannot be the 
 work of the politician ; it is the natural task of the 
 Catholic Church, with the Pope at its head, risen out of 
 a sectarian exclusiveness into a right realization of 
 its own universahty, boldly freeing itself from the 
 trammels of nationality, class and party, and under- 
 standing its doctrines and its human mission in the 
 light of science and the fully-developed Modern Mind. 
 
 Malcolm Quin. 
 
CONTENTS 
 
 Preface 
 
 Religious Introduction 
 
 CHAP. 
 
 I. Science and the Problem of Peace 
 
 II. The Meaning of a Human Peace 
 
 III. The Good of a Human Peace 
 
 IV. Catholicism and a Human Peace 
 
 V. War and the Spiritual Life 
 
 VI. War and Political Life 
 VH. Industrial Imperialism . 
 
 VIH. Catholicism and Imperialism 
 IX. A Catholic Policy of Peace 
 X. The Republic of Peace . 
 
 V 
 
 II 
 
 64 
 
 79 
 
 lOI 
 
 125 
 
 154 
 
 172 
 
 190 
 
 209 
 
 226 
 
 252 
 
THE PROBLEM OF 
 HUMAN PEACE 
 
 RELIGIOUS INTRODUCTION 
 I 
 
 One consequence of the stupendous and awful war 
 through which the world is passing is that it has 
 inspired a deeper and wider interest in what may 
 be called, broadly and generally, the Problem of 
 Peace. When the word “ peace ” is used in this 
 absolute way it means, we may suppose, what through- 
 out the following pages is called a Human Peace — the 
 universal and permanent peace of mankind. It is 
 peace in this sense, however vaguely conceived, that 
 has long been, for a certain number of serious minds, 
 an ideal, a great cause and hope, to which patiently 
 and faithfully they have dedicated themselves. 
 Commonly, indeed, when men speak of peace as a 
 good, and war as an evil, they are understood to 
 imply that peace is a permanent good, and war is an 
 evil, for humanity as a whole, and not merely for 
 some particular portion of it. 
 
 By “ peace,” therefore, in this treatise, I mean not 
 a temporary or partial peace, such as, in all experience 
 hitherto, has followed after every war, but a Human 
 Peace, world-wide and continuous. It is the Problem 
 of Peace in this sense that I have proposed to myself 
 
12 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 to study. In studying such a problem we are called 
 upon to do something more than rest in a state of 
 sentimental enthusiasm. Sentimental enthusiasm in 
 regard to any good, or supposed good, of man does not 
 carry us very far, although, as a preliminary state of 
 mind, it may be indispensable and beneficent. It is 
 not enough for us, as individuals, to say simply that 
 we “ love peace,” or that peace, a human and enduring 
 peace, is a beautiful and inspiring ideal, to which the 
 energies of mankind should be directed. We have, 
 in relation to a Human Peace, to show, first, what it 
 is that we precisely and practically mean by it. We 
 have, in the second place, to show that it is possible. 
 We have, in the third place, to show that it is desir- 
 able — desirable, that is to say, in reference to some 
 fundamental interest of man, which, as a civilized 
 and developed being, and in a full conception of 
 himself and his destiny, he cannot disavow. We 
 have, in the fourth place, to show that, being desir- 
 able, it is also possible. We have, lastly, assuming, 
 or proving, its possibility, to indicate the means 
 necessary for its attainment. 
 
 I have, in the following pages, discussed these 
 various aspects of a Human Peace. In this Intro- 
 duction I propose to myself to make somewhat clearer 
 than I have there done the standpoint from which I 
 approach it. I here assume, that is to say, what I 
 afterwards make some attempt to prove — that a 
 Human Peace, in that general view of it which I have 
 now indicated, is a high common good of mankind. I 
 assume, too, its possibility — that man is not, by some 
 
RELIGIOUS INTRODUCTION 
 
 13 
 
 insuperable power acting upon him or within him, 
 prevented from pursuing and attaining it, any more, 
 for example, than we suppose him to be prevented, by 
 such a power, from pursuing and attaining an ideal 
 chastity or sobriety, or from following after and 
 realizing health and beauty. Assuming these two 
 things in regard to a Human Peace, I limit myself 
 now to considering the means at our disposal for 
 bringing it about. 
 
 This is a question of science — using the word 
 “ science ” here to represent the spirit and methods 
 which men have successfully employed — in so far as 
 they have mastered the truths of system and action — 
 in the interpretation of experience in Nature and life. 
 Science, so understood, is, so far as ordered explana- 
 tion is concerned, our supreme resource in the fields of 
 social and moral conduct, as it is in the fields of 
 physics, chemistry, and biology ; for science, so 
 understood, means the developed mind of man, dis- 
 passionately and faithfully examining his situation 
 and himself, and bringing all orders of positive know- 
 ledge and all the powers of human reason to bear on 
 the construction of a stable synthesis. It is for 
 science in this complete sense, and for nothing else, to 
 determine what it is that we mean by a Human 
 Peace, how far such a peace is a great good of man, 
 to be followed after and attained, as health or chastity 
 is, and what are the right means to be adopted for 
 its attainment. Science, in this conception of it, 
 speaks as a master. Against its judgments, when they 
 have once been surely delivered, neither ecclesiastical 
 
14 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 authority, nor national prejudice, nor political par- 
 tizanship, nor the claims of class, can be pleaded. The 
 sphere of science is universal truth, and the good to 
 which, in its universality, it points us — if it points us 
 to a good at all — is the good of humanity. 
 
 II 
 
 Considering the Problem of Human Peace in the 
 temper and from the standpoint of science, I come to 
 the conclusion that the great natural instrument for 
 its attainment and maintenance is the Catholic 
 Church, bringing to bear on the organization and 
 direction of human life a Scientific Catholicism. It 
 is necessary that these important terms should be 
 precisely and clearly understood. By the expression 
 “ the Catholic Church ” I mean, to begin with, the 
 Church of Rome — its doctrine, its worship, its insti- 
 tutions, including, of course, the Papacy. These 
 things constitute Catholicism. I mean by it also, 
 however, for the purposes of the present work, all 
 other Christian Churches, in proportion as they 
 actually contain within themselves Catholicism and 
 wield its force. All of them contain something of it — 
 some of them much, some little. All of them, in 
 principle at least, exist to bring that ideal, or Divine, 
 Humanity which was given to the world by Christ 
 into the life of man ; all of them, in degree, and in 
 whatever form, employ in doing this a system of 
 teaching, a system of worship, a system of discipline, 
 or life. The non-Catholic Churches are in this sense 
 Catholic, The true Catholic, or Roman, Church is 
 
RELIGIOUS INTRODUCTION 
 
 15 
 
 the whole of which the different non-Catholic bodies — 
 Anglican, Lutheran, Presbyterian, and other — are 
 separated and unrelated parts, holding varying por- 
 tions of the total truth of Catholicism. It may be 
 considered that it would be better, instead of “ Catholic 
 Church ” and “ Catholicism,” to use the words 
 “ Christian Church ” and “ Christianity.” That, 
 however, is not so. In a strict scientific sense there 
 is no such thing as “ the Christian Church,” considered 
 as an organic, unified religious society. In the same 
 way, there is no such thing as “ Christianity,” con- 
 sidered as a definite, uniform system of belief, repre- 
 senting all who call themselves Christian. We cannot 
 reason scientifically with such terms, which con- 
 stantly change their meaning according to changing 
 points of view. We can reason scientifically with the 
 term “ Catholic Church,” understood as representing 
 the Church of Rome, and we can reason scientifically 
 with the word “ Catholicism,” understood as denoting 
 the doctrine, worship, and discipline of that Church. 
 Further, having before us in Catholicism this definite 
 type, or order, of religious theory and practice, we can 
 see how far the non-Catholic bodies are in relation 
 with it and represent it. For the sake of simplicity 
 and convenience, therefore, I shall generally through- 
 out this treatise use the words “ Catholic Church ” 
 and “ Catholicism ” as indicating the Church of Rome, 
 considered, not exclusively, but as representing the 
 non-Catholic Churches, in proportion to their actual 
 correspondence with it. It follows that what I have 
 to say of the Catholic Church, in its strength and 
 
1 6 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 weakness, applies, mutatis mutandis, to the non- 
 Catholic Christian bodies. 
 
 The explanation which I have given of my use of 
 the word “ Catholicism ” sheds a natural light upon 
 the expression “ a Scientific Catholicism.” Accord- 
 ing to a conception which I have elsewhere more 
 fully unfolded,* the religious synthesis which is to 
 direct the future of mankind will be formed by the 
 transforming operation of the Modern Mind upon the 
 whole content of Catholicism — its theology, its 
 liturgy, its morals and social policy, its ecclesiastical 
 order. That transforming operation will be, in 
 a positive sense, at once critical, preservative, and 
 developmental. It will demand an effort of both 
 analysis and construction. It is, as I hold, to 
 this transformed, developed, and completed Catholi- 
 cism that we must look as the great instrument for 
 bringing in and maintaining a Human Peace. Such a 
 Catholicism I shall, for purposes of simplicity and 
 convenience, here call a Scientific Catholicism. This 
 expression, however, standing alone, might be mis- 
 leading. It might suggest some wholly new Catholi- 
 cism — supposing such a thing to be possible — sud- 
 denly springing into existence, and consciously and 
 deliberately systematic throughout its entire range. 
 It is necessary to guard against such a misapprehen- 
 sion. By science, in one view of it, we mean a precise 
 and orderly interpretation of experience, in its various 
 categories, expressing itself in verifiable statements, 
 
 * “ Catholicism and the Modern Mind ” : London, Edward 
 Arnold. 
 
RELIGIOUS INTRODUCTION 
 
 17 
 
 and subserving, in the field of action, the ends of 
 practice. It is evident, however, that experience — 
 man’s observant and discriminating relation to the 
 order of Nature, including the facts of his own sensi- 
 bility and consciousness — precedes the formal scien- 
 tific interpretation of it, and expresses itself intuitively, 
 empirically and symbolically before it can express 
 itself analytically and systematically. An unculti- 
 vated mother, nursing her children, has no formal 
 theory of love, or of parental duty, or of the various 
 physical processes which she employs, but her experi- 
 ences, outer and inner, are, within their range, real, 
 and her intuitive and empirical expressions of them 
 have the value of aU spontaneous utterance concerning 
 the known facts of life. The biologist and the moralist, 
 dealing afterwards with such expressions analytically 
 and systematically, determine how far they are an 
 accurate representation of real experiences, and, for 
 their own purposes, substitute for them their own forms 
 of statement. Science, as Huxley said, and as Comte 
 had said before him, is only systematized common sense. 
 
 By the expression “ a Scientific Catholicism,” 
 therefore, I do not mean a whoUy new Catholicism ; 
 I mean the persisting positive contents of historic 
 Catholicism — the actual experiences of Nature and 
 human nature which it has intuitively, empirically, 
 and symbolically expressed — discerned, and incor- 
 porated for practical purposes into a full synthesis of 
 human knowledge, according to the developed powers 
 of the Modern Mind and the systematic methods of 
 science. It is for science, become mature and com- 
 
1 8 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 plete — embracing the total experiences of man’s 
 social and moral life, as well as the phenomena of the 
 external world — to determine how far Catholicism 
 represents real experience, and to correct and supple- 
 ment it where it fails to do so. In this special rela- 
 tion, and for the practical purposes of human life, 
 science — the ordered manifestation of the Modern 
 Mind — is, as I have elsewhere said, sovereign, and 
 Catholicism is subordinate. We may express this 
 canonically by saying that Catholicism, throughout 
 its whole extent, — in doctrine, worship, and discipline 
 — must live or die according to its ratification by 
 modern science. If we were to assume that the 
 verdict of science — the tested experience and mind 
 of man — would be ultimately against Catholicism, 
 then we should have to conclude that Catholicism, 
 including aU forms of Christianity, would disappear, 
 as ancient European “ Paganism ” disappeared. It 
 is, however, upon the contrary supposition that I am 
 now proceeding. I hold that there is, by reasonable 
 presumption, a universal positive content in Catholi- 
 cism, spontaneously expressed in empirical and sym- 
 bolic forms. Upon this content — an order of mind — 
 science, in its completeness, can operate, precisely as 
 it operates upon the order of Nature ; and in the one 
 case, as in the other, it will accept in order to operate, 
 and operate to interpret and supplement. 
 
 Ill 
 
 It is, then, neither to Catholicism, as it exists in 
 contemporary life, or as it has shown itself in history. 
 
RELIGIOUS INTRODUCTION 
 
 19 
 
 nor to some wholly new Catholicism, that we must 
 look as the great instrument of a Human Peace, but, 
 once more, to a Scientific Catholicism, both con- 
 tinuous and progressive. As this principle is funda- 
 mental and governing in the following pages, it is 
 necessary to set it in a clear light, and to consider not 
 only what may be said for it, but what may be said 
 against it. 
 
 And, first, as to historic or unscientific Catholicism 
 — using the word “ unscientific ” to denote, not some- 
 thing in which there is no content of experience and 
 reason, but something in which that content has not 
 been verified and systematized, according to the pro- 
 cesses of the Modern Mind. What is it that we mean 
 by this Catholicism, in a positive and practical con- 
 ception of it — such a conception of it as admits of 
 being demonstrated and rationally discussed, as we 
 demonstrate and discuss any proposition of astronomy 
 or biology ? We mean by Catholicism, in this posi- 
 tive conception of it, a continuous and organized 
 attempt, individual and social, to realize in the life 
 of man an ideal, or type, of Perfection, considered 
 as being given and symbolized in Christ, either as He 
 is represented in the New Testament poems, or as He 
 had established Himself, a fixed yet developing 
 Image, in the early Christian minds which produced 
 those poems. Such an attempt demanded — ^what 
 religion for its purposes always demands — -a system 
 of doctrine, a system of worship, a system of conduct, 
 or life. The threefold system which we call Catholi- 
 cism — and which was called Catholicism for no other 
 
20 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 reason than because it eventually won for itself a 
 certain relative “ universality ” — was a slow and pro- 
 gressive construction of the human mind, operating 
 with a limited knowledge of the world and man, with 
 imperfect and untested methods of investigation and 
 proof, and in accordance with the then existing state 
 of intelligence. 
 
 It is to the constructive human mind, occupied 
 with the thought of Christ — a “ human mind ” con- 
 stituted by a co-operation, conscious and unconscious, 
 of men and women of every degree of capacity and 
 incapacity, of knowledge and ignorance — that we 
 owe, first, the Christian Scriptures, and the establish- 
 ment of their relation with the Jewish Scriptures ; 
 secondly, the conception of Christ as God, and the 
 consequent development of the idea of the Trinity ; 
 thirdly, the creeds, the elaboration of Christian 
 theology, the exaltation of the Blessed Virgin, the 
 doctrine of Heaven, Hell, and Purgatory, the venera- 
 tion of the Saints, the Mass, the Sacraments, the 
 growth of the Christian life, the organization of the 
 Church, and the order of the Catholic Hierarchy, 
 under the supremacy of the Pope. 
 
 The foundation of this great construction — a con- 
 struction of various minds, of various countries, of 
 various ages — was, of course, the conception of 
 Christ as God. The word “ God,” as is obvious, does 
 not represent an outward constant physical fact, such 
 as we may see with our eyes, or hear with our ears. It 
 immediately represents an inner image of man’s social 
 mind — an image which feeling, reason, imagination, 
 
RELIGIOUS INTRODUCTION 
 
 21 
 
 and will, in relation to human experience, external 
 and internal, all co-operate in creating. This image 
 varies with varying stages of culture and mental 
 development. The Jews had one such image ; the 
 Greeks, Romans, and other “ Gentile ” nations a 
 number of different ones. The immediate outward 
 foundation of it may be a river, or a tree, or the sun 
 and moon, or an animal, or a human being, or the 
 infinite universe, including man as at once a con- 
 stituent and interpreter of it. Whatever the nature 
 of its foundation, that foundation is a fact of experi- 
 ence, external or internal, transformed by the shaping 
 mind of man, according to its progressive knowledge 
 and development, anthropomorphically conceived of 
 as a being of intelligence, feeling, and power, and 
 invested with the name, or symbol, “ God.” Man, 
 who is the lord of language, calls things what he will, 
 and thinks of them in virtue of such capacity of thought 
 as he possesses, in the different stages of his mental 
 evolution. Catholicism, scientifically and historically 
 speaking, owes its existence to the fact that at a 
 given point in time man, who had called many things 
 and many beings “ gods,” named with the name of 
 God, and invested with the attributes of a God, the 
 image of the Man Jesus Christ which had progressively 
 and in different ways established itself in his mind. 
 From this root sprang the living, widespread tree 
 which we call ChristendonL 
 
 Christ, who is God according to Catholicism, is, as 
 we say, an Image of Perfection — of a perfect man, and, 
 as a consequence, of a perfect human society. Man, 
 
22 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 who gives to words their meanings, gives its meaning 
 to the word “ perfection,” as to the word “ God.” 
 It means what he decides that it shall mean, and what 
 he decides that it shall mean depends upon his own 
 variations in experience and culture. It certainly 
 lies within his capacity to form a conception — a 
 progressive conception — of a perfect human being, 
 transcendently complete and beautiful in physical 
 form, in love, in intelligence, in will, and in the 
 capacity to accomplish his ends, external and internal. 
 He may if he pleases — and he frequently does — take 
 any one constituent of this many-sided Perfection and 
 concentrate special attention upon it, to the tem- 
 porary exclusion, or subordination, of the others. 
 He may, in this way — and he frequently does — thus 
 concentrate attention upon moral, or intellectual, or 
 practical perfection, and yield to it a predominant 
 homage. For a complete perfection of personal 
 humanity, however — and, therefore, for a complete 
 social perfection — what is necessary is the due develop- 
 ment of all the distinctive sides of human nature in an 
 active co-operation and harmony, determined by the 
 subordination of the lower to the higher. This ideal 
 harmony, or unity, is never actually and absolutely 
 realized by man, but it is always pursued by him. It 
 is the character of the Divine, or God-like. It rests 
 on a synthesis of feeling, knowledge, and action. In 
 other words, it rests on religion, in which man proposes 
 to himself an ideal Perfection, and follows after it — 
 more or less consciously and with more or less fidelity 
 and power — in worship, doctrine, and discipline. 
 
RELIGIOUS INTRODUCTION 
 
 23 
 
 Now Christ is, in Catholicism, God. That is to 
 say. He is an Image and Symbol of Divine, or com- 
 plete, Perfection — a coalescent, transcendent per- 
 fection of Love, Wisdom, Will, and Power — ^held in 
 the mind of man to establish a corresponding type of 
 humanity, individual and social. The chief external 
 presentation of this Image is contained in the New 
 Testament poems, and Catholicism, in its historic 
 working, is the continuous and developing attempt, 
 individual and social, to convert this Image into an 
 order of mind and life. In relation to this Image, in 
 relation to the representation of it in the New Testa- 
 ment poems, and in relation to Catholicism, as an 
 attempt to bring man into correspondence with it, 
 the Modern Mind — -let us say the mind of Western 
 humanity in the twentieth century, complete in 
 experience and culture — occupies a position of sove- 
 reign authority. It can, if it pleases, decide not to 
 have a “ religion ” at all — that is, not to follow after 
 an ideal Perfection by the way of a systematic doc- 
 trine, worship, and discipline. A very large number 
 of men and women in the modern world have, as we 
 know, in this sense, ceased to be “ religious.” A stiU 
 larger number may conceivably follow their example. 
 Again, the Modern Mind may decide that it will still 
 follow after Perfection, and, therefore, remain “ reli- 
 gious,” but that it can no longer accept Christ as its 
 God, or as the Image and Symbol of Perfection. It 
 is as free to do this as were the Jews, Greeks, and 
 Romans of primitive Catholicism to turn from the 
 ancient conceptions of the Divine, and embrace a 
 
24 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 new conception. As a matter of fact, a considerable 
 number of persons at the present time occupy exactly 
 this position. They are “ religious ” ; they follow, 
 in their own way, after an ideal Perfection ; but they 
 say that Christ no longer represents it. In other 
 words. He has, for them, ceased to be “ God.” 
 
 But, again, the Modern Mind may hold that Christ 
 still remains for it an eternal Image and Symbol of 
 transcendent and complete Perfection — that He is 
 still its “ God ” — but that the historic conception and 
 realization of that Image are defective, and that a 
 new conception and realization are called for. Such 
 a view may find expression in the rejection, or sup- 
 posed rejection, of Catholicism, and the adoption of 
 some form, or modification, of “ Protestantism,” or 
 in the acceptance of Catholicism itself, subject to its 
 scientific interpretation and development, throughout 
 its whole domain, by the Modern Mind. Another 
 view, again, rejecting all the doctrinal principles of 
 all historic religions, may find, or endeavour to find, 
 for itself expression in entirely new symbols — such, 
 for example, as Comte constructed in his “ Religion 
 of Humanity.” What is of fundamental importance, 
 in connection with these and other similar alternatives, 
 is to recognize that the Modern Mind, in the fulness of 
 its experience and culture, has a natural freedom and 
 sovereignty. It summons all the religions of mankind 
 to its judgment seat. It sees in all of them modes of 
 representing and pursuing an ideal of human per- 
 fection, personal and social. It compares one with 
 another, just as it compares creations in poetry and 
 
RELIGIOUS INTRODUCTION 
 
 25 
 
 art, schools of philosophy, national literatures, or 
 methods of industrial production. It has its own 
 indefeasible power of deciding for itself which of 
 them is in most complete relation to the ideal of per- 
 fection which it is the business of religion to pursue, 
 and how far each has failed in pursuing it. It can, 
 in principle, dismiss them one and all much more 
 completely than ancient Paganism was dismissed 
 from the mind of Christianity, for it has a fuller and 
 surer knowledge of itself, a wider social and historic 
 outlook, and more accurate instruments of rejection 
 and selection than the early Christians possessed. 
 But it can also decide that one or other out of the 
 various religions of mankind has, by its conceptions, 
 doctrines, modes of worship, and practical institutions, 
 made the greatest contribution to human perfection, 
 and that progress towards a fuller perfection wiU 
 best be accomplished by correcting that religion where 
 it needs correction, and completing it where it needs 
 completion. 
 
 It may be said that in this view of the relation of 
 the Modern Mind to the different systems of religion 
 there is an implication that man has a natural power 
 to choose his God, or to choose whether he shall have 
 a God at all. Undoubtedly there is, and undoubtedly 
 he has. As a matter of fact, in this region of ideas, 
 men, from the beginning of recorded history to the 
 present time, have done little else than choose their 
 gods. There are many things that they do not and 
 cannot choose. They do not choose their own 
 earth, or their own sun and moon, or the sea and sky. 
 
26 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 or whether fire shall burn, or water wet, or whether 
 they shall eat and drink and propagate their species — 
 supposing they decide, what they certainly have the 
 power to decide, that they shall live rather than die. 
 But there are also many things which they can 
 choose. Amongst them is whether they will have a 
 God, and if so, what kind of a God it shall be. The 
 early Christians exercised this power when they 
 passed from “ Paganism ” or Judaism and chose 
 Christ as their God. Christian missions at the present 
 day depend on no other principle than the power of a 
 Hindu, or Buddhist, or Confucianist, or Mohammedan 
 to choose one God rather than another. The creeds 
 of Catholicism are, in one view of them, formulas of 
 religious choice. When we say “ I believe ” we say 
 “ I choose.” Further, for the individual mind, in 
 relation to the social mind— or the mind of the 
 Church — such a declaration means, to begin with, not 
 the construction of an Image of God for itself, but 
 the acceptance of an Image proposed to it. Simi- 
 larly, the recital of a historic creed in any one age 
 means that that age continues to accept the Image 
 proposed to it by the past. The early Christians, as 
 is well known, had to defend themselves against a 
 charge of “ atheism,” and this because “ belief in 
 God ” then practically meant, as it always means, 
 acceptance of some dominant social Image of God, 
 and “ unbelief ” rejection of that Image. 
 
 We come back, then, to this obvious principle — 
 that the mind which says “ I believe ” can also say 
 “ I do not believe,” or that the mind which says “ I 
 
RELIGIOUS INTRODUCTION 
 
 27 
 
 choose ” can also say “ I refuse.” The Modern Mind 
 — the mind of Western man in the twentieth century — 
 is no more bound to continue to worship Christ than 
 the mind of the first century was bound to continue 
 to worship Jehovah or Apollo. That Mind, moreover, 
 unlike the mind of antiquity, is free to decide whether 
 it will worship a God or not, and what kind of a God — 
 that is, to say what kind of an Image of Perfection — 
 if any, it shall choose for itself. The modern “ Theist,” 
 or Unitarian, dismisses, or supposes himself to dismiss, 
 the Divinity of Christ, but he clothes Divinity in 
 some way with an image of his own. The religious 
 Positivist similarly shapes a new symbol for Per- 
 fection, and calls it, not “ God,” but “ Humanity.” 
 
 I proceed here, however, upon the assumption that 
 the Modern Mind, in the exercise of this its indefeasible 
 power and freedom, will continue to choose Christ 
 as its God, and Catholicism — the doctrine, worship, 
 and discipline of the Roman Church — as the indi- 
 vidual and social fulfilment of Christ. But it will do 
 this according to its own development and culture, 
 and for its own practical ends. The Modern Mind, as 
 I here conceive it, is, in a complete sense, scientific. 
 It is consciously and systematically synthetic. While, 
 therefore, it has the same freedom as was possessed 
 by the ancient world when it rejected Apollo and 
 accepted Christ, it will not make the same use of its 
 freedom. The rise of Christianity was a revolution. 
 It was, in principle — although, of course, not in 
 practice — the subversion of the existing religious 
 order. The Modern Mind — according to the view 
 
28 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 of it which I am endeavouring to establish — does not 
 aim at a revolution but at an evolution. It sees in 
 Catholicism an order not to be subverted, but to be 
 developed. It brings to bear on it principles of 
 criticism and comparison, of rejection and acceptance, 
 as it brings them to bear on any other religion, or on 
 any other product of culture. It sees it in its relation 
 to the total mind and life of man, and, finding in it 
 truth amidst error, goodness amidst evil, weakness 
 amidst strength, ugliness amidst beauty, and acquisi- 
 tion of real experience and reason expressed spon- 
 taneously and symbolically, it exercises its own 
 analytic and constructive power to discern, to pre- 
 serve, and to complete. In other words, it “ chooses ” 
 to retain Catholicism, but chooses also to make it 
 scientific. 
 
 IV 
 
 We come now to consider the bearing of such a 
 Catholicism upon a Human Peace. By a Human 
 Peace, once more, we mean a peace universal and 
 continuous — not such a temporary cessation of strife 
 as comes at the end of every war, and as is due to 
 victory in arms, or to the common exhaustion of all 
 the combatants, or to mere weariness of bloodshed. 
 By a Human Peace we mean a peace deliberately 
 chosen and planned, as a common good of mankind, 
 and maintained through policy and co-operation by 
 the predominant nations of the world. Now, assum- 
 ing such a Peace to be possible at all — possible, that 
 is, in view of man’s situation and continuous nature — 
 
RELIGIOUS INTRODUCTION 
 
 29 
 
 what reason, it may be asked, have we to suppose 
 that it can be brought in and upheld by the Catholic 
 Church, in any conception of it ? An answer to this 
 question must be found, and it must be given not 
 according to the methods of ecclesiastics and theo- 
 logians — ^who commonly limit themselves to affirming 
 propositions which they cannot prove and denouncing 
 evils which they cannot prevent — but according to the 
 methods of science, which at least confesses its ignor- 
 ance when it does not know, and acknowledges its 
 incapacity when it is powerless to act. 
 
 First, if a Human Peace — defined as I have defined 
 it — is, as we assume, a great human good, it is a good 
 which does not stand by itself, out of relation with 
 the various other ends which man, as a being of 
 affection, reason, and will, living in the social state, 
 proposes to himself. It is plain, for example, that so 
 long as we have nations following after what they 
 consider some good of the “ State ” — such as indus- 
 trial ascendency, or territorial expansion, or dynastic 
 aggrandizement, or political overlordship — ^we cannot 
 have a Human Peace. It is plain, too, that these 
 common causes of war are in close connection with 
 the ordinary needs and desires of men and women in 
 their physical, intellectual, and moral life. Stating 
 the same truth more generally, but not less obviously, 
 man is a complex whole, and the various parts of his 
 nature act and react one upon another. If, then, we 
 are to consider a Human Peace as a good, and as a 
 good to be brought about and maintained by choice 
 and policy, it is a good which enters into that con- 
 
30 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 tinuous but developing ideal of Perfection, individual 
 and social, which, as we have seen, it is the business of 
 religion — or of man as a religious being — to pursue. 
 
 Secondly, Catholicism, scientifically considered, is 
 a continuous organized effort, individual and social, 
 to realize in the life of man the Divinity, or Perfection, 
 of Christ. But Catholicism is not an accomplished 
 Perfection. It is the pursuit of an ideal ; it is not its 
 fulfilment. By “ Catholicism,” practically under- 
 stood, we simply mean a continuous company of 
 human beings, a succession of generations, following 
 after a certain end, according to their conception of 
 it, and with such instruments and methods as, at 
 given stages of their progress, they have thrown up. 
 But of the end itself which they pursued — Perfection 
 in Christ — Catholics, being ordinary men and women, 
 have had only an imperfect conception. This was 
 inevitable. Catholicism — the acknowledgment of 
 Christ as “ God,” the confession of His Perfection as 
 a rule of life — arose in an age when it was not possible 
 for men to have an orderly and complete view of the 
 universe in which man lives, and of man in relation 
 to that universe. They had, some of them, great 
 gifts — intuitions of genius, imagination, poetic sensi- 
 bility and power, an instinct for moral beauty, a 
 right feeling for what was noble in man and woman, 
 a sense of the greatness and mystery of human 
 life, moments of profundity, moments of spiritual 
 ardour, moments of ecstasy, a capacity for subtle 
 dialectic and metaphysical refinement, and also a 
 power of heroic self-sacrifice and religious effort. 
 
RELIGIOUS INTRODUCTION 
 
 31 
 
 They had, however, along with these high qualities, 
 ignorance of many things that are now commonly 
 known— of the earth, of its inhabitants, of its history, 
 of the solar system into which it enters, of the physical 
 and vital forces which surround man, and of man 
 himself, in his nature, powers, limitations, and destiny. 
 Further, an immense proportion of the men who 
 became “ Catholics ” — ^who in some sense and degree 
 received into their minds the Image of Christ — were 
 rude, barbaric, violent, superstitious, sensual, and 
 selfish — or perhaps raised only a little above mere 
 animal torpor ; and this great persisting social body 
 constituted a predominant force, which told not only 
 upon the practical fulfilment of the Divine Perfection, 
 but also upon the conception of that Perfection. 
 
 This is all elementary. Catholicism — either as we 
 see it in history, or as it shows itself in contemporary 
 life — does not represent a perfection perfectly realized, 
 or even a perfection perfectly understood. Intel- 
 lectually considered^ — allowing for individual intuition 
 and genius— it represents something infantile, imma- 
 ture, empiric, incomplete^ — a vague and limited view 
 of man and his universe, and therefore of “ God,” or 
 Perfection ; practically considered, it represents, along 
 with a partial empirical success, both the failure 
 necessarily resulting from the want of science and the 
 failure due to the pressure of passions and inclina- 
 tions antagonistic to the Perfection confessed. With 
 this latter kind of failure we are not here immediately 
 concerned. It is, in varying degree, inevitable, and 
 would, in a certain measure, remain inevitable even 
 
32 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 if Catholicism became, what it is necessary for it to 
 become, scientific. Men who are dishonest or drunken 
 or unchaste commonly sin in this way, not because of 
 their want of “ science ” — because they are unaware, 
 for example, that drunkenness and dishonesty are 
 evils, and carry with them certain evil consequences — 
 but because of the strength of their lower inclinations, 
 and the absence, or relative weakness, of the higher. 
 This ordinary failure of men to come into correspond- 
 ence with an ideal, or law, which they yet acknow- 
 ledge must be allowed for in any just historic estimate 
 of Catholicism, on its practical side. 
 
 What we are now concerned with, however, is not 
 the failure of Catholicism to realize its own vision of 
 Perfection, such as it has been, but its failure in 
 vision itself — its failure, in other words, in science and 
 motive, in the capacity to represent to man the true 
 nature of the order of things in which he is placed, 
 and his own nature, as an active, modifying con- 
 stituent of that order. This failure in science and 
 motive of course has in part been compensated for 
 by intuition, genius, common sense, and empirical 
 wisdom, learning from its actual discharge of the 
 tasks of life. Nevertheless, it has been a failure, and 
 one of a fundamental character, the effect of which 
 has been necessarily felt not only in the region of 
 theory, but in the region of practice also. This is 
 what the Modern Mind — the mind of a fuller experi- 
 ence, of a complete development, constituted by the 
 religions, the sciences, the arts, the industry, the 
 social expansion of the whole of humanity — is now 
 
RELIGIOUS INTRODUCTION 
 
 33 
 
 able to see. It recognizes that in its conception of 
 Perfection — that is to say, of God in Christ, and conse- 
 quently in its scriptures, doctrines, creeds, sacraments, 
 system of worship, and system of conduct — Catholi- 
 cism has largely been the expression of a human 
 nature ignorant, immature, untrained, misconceiving 
 itself, and its world in relation to itself. By 
 Catholicism we here mean the whole order of the 
 Catholic Church, theoretic and practical, from the 
 earliest apostolic age to the Council of Trent and the 
 subsequent definitions of the Vatican Council. This 
 whole order, we say, rests on spiritual intuition, on 
 religious genius, on empirical wisdom, on a partial 
 experience, inner and outer. It represents, spon- 
 taneously and symbolically, a provisional and incom- 
 plete synthesis — the synthesis of undeveloped but 
 developing man. It must be converted into a com- 
 plete synthesis — the conscious and systematic syn- 
 thesis of developed man. Once more, it must 
 become, what it may become, scientific. It must no 
 longer remain the religion merely of the ancient mind, 
 or of the medieval mind, but must become the religion 
 of the Modern Mind, entering into the ancient and 
 medieval minds, understanding them, interpreting 
 them, and making all their positive acquisitions its 
 own. It is not for the less developed to impose its 
 law on the more developed ; it is for the more 
 developed to follow its own law and impose it on the 
 less developed. 
 
 The central point of Catholicism, scientifically con- 
 sidered, is, of course, its conception of God — that is 
 
 H.P» 
 
 C 
 
34 the problem OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 to say, of ideal or transcendent Perfection — in Christ. 
 In simpler terms, it is its conception of the Divinity of 
 Christ. By the Divinity of Christ, positively under- 
 stood, we mean a Perfect Humanity, personal and 
 social. Man has it in his capacity to form an image of 
 himself as a complete Humanity — complete, and com- 
 pletely unified, in feeling, knowledge, and power. For 
 the realization of this Perfect Humanity what is needed 
 is a synthesis — not only full and right knowledge, or 
 science, but love and will working in accordance with 
 science. Catholicism, as it has existed in history, has 
 not constituted such a synthesis. It has not even con- 
 ceived it. It has been an intuitive, partial, tentative, 
 and empirical movement towards it. It is for the 
 Modern Mind, in its natural, indefeasible freedom and 
 sovereignty, to dismiss Catholicism, as Catholicism 
 itself dismissed “ Paganism,” or to convert it into a 
 real synthesis. I here assume that it will do the latter. 
 
 V 
 
 There are five cardinal and connected points in 
 Catholicism — and, of course, in all other forms of 
 Christianity in proportion as they are “Catholic” — on 
 which the modern interpretation of it, and therefore 
 the modern transformation of it, must turn. They are, 
 first, the conception of Christ as Divine, or as a 
 norm of human Perfection ; second, the consequent 
 conception of “ this world ” in relation to the “ next ” ; 
 third, the conception of miracle ; fourth, the con- 
 ception of sin ; fifth, the conception of prayer. 
 
RELIGIOUS INTRODUCTION 
 
 35 
 
 These connected points are all of fundamental 
 importance in relation to a Human Peace. 
 
 If Christ is to remain, for the Modern Mind, a type, 
 or ideal, of Perfection — in other words, if He is to 
 remain its God — then His Perfection must be under- 
 stood as the perfect nature and state of man, indi- 
 vidual and social, living under the demonstrable con- 
 ditions, or laws, of the world which we know. It must 
 be the Perfection of Humanity as science sees it, in 
 relation to a Universal Order of which science, 
 according to its progressive capacity, unfolds the 
 constitution and forces. The word “ God ” has always 
 represented an Image of the constructive and trans- 
 forming mind of man, operating upon its experiences, 
 either of external nature, or of its own inner nature, in 
 relation to the external world. In other terms, it has 
 symbolized the whole Order of things, cosmic, vital, 
 and human, visible and invisible, in so far as that 
 Order was apprehended and understood. It will, to 
 the Modern Mind, as I conceive it, continue to repre- 
 sent this Order, according as it is apprehended and 
 understood by science in its maturity and complete- 
 ness. God in Christ, however, or Christ as God, con- 
 denses and symbolizes this Universal Order as an 
 Order of Human Perfection, personal and social ; and 
 just as man’s conception of the cosmic order has 
 become more complete and exact in the degree in 
 which his powers, intellectual and practical, have 
 expanded, so his conception of the human order, 
 personal and social, symbolized by Christ, has de- 
 veloped also. The doctrine, or science, of this twofold 
 
 C 2 
 
36 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 order, of the world and man, is ever becoming a 
 larger body of ascertained truth, a fuller synthesis — 
 in other words, a Greater Catholicism ; but its 
 symbols — God, Christ, His Holy Spirit, the Trinity, 
 the Blessed Virgin, the Creeds, the Sacraments — 
 remain, by the choice and will of the Modern Mind, 
 the same. 
 
 By the Perfection, or Divinity, of Christ, therefore 
 — which is painted for us in the poems of the New 
 Testament as it was conceived, according to their 
 varying capacity, by its various writers — a Scientific 
 Catholicism understands a Perfect Humanity, per- 
 sonal and social. It means by it man with his 
 characteristic nature and powers — physical, moral, 
 ntellectual, practical — fully developed and har- 
 moniously ordered by the continuous predominance 
 of what is higher in him over what is lower. It means 
 man, with his capacity for bodily order and health, 
 with his capacity for unselfish love, with his sense of 
 goodness, his sense of beauty, his sense and pursuit 
 of truth, his genius for social organization, his indus- 
 trial mastery, and his command over the forces of 
 Nature — it means man, so considered, in the com- 
 plete expansion and many-sided unity of his total 
 being, ever fulfilling himself and fulfilling himself more 
 completely, individually and socially, throughout the 
 ages. It means, too, as one condition sine qua non of 
 the pursuit and attainment of this Perfection 
 — the establishment and maintenance of a Human 
 Peace. 
 
RELIGIOUS INTRODUCTION 
 
 37 
 
 VI 
 
 This modern Catholic conception of God in Christ — 
 a conception in which the Divinity of Christ sym- 
 bolizes a Perfect Humanity, personal and social, sum- 
 ming up in its own order the Universal Order, visible 
 and invisible— this conception, in proportion as it is 
 attained, serves as a natural criticism of what, for 
 purposes of distinction, we may call the traditional 
 and unscientific idea of God in Catholicism. I use 
 the word “ criticism,” of course, not as equivalent to 
 mere hostility or disparagement, but as representing 
 the reasoned judgment of a mature intelligence upon 
 the ideas of an intelligence immature. 
 
 The Modern Mind which I am here supposing to 
 consciously and deliberately hold within itself the 
 ancient and medieval minds, for the purposes of a 
 religious synthesis — the Modern Mind, so constituted, 
 looks at the whole humanity of the past precisely as 
 it looks at the solar system, or at the phenomena of 
 physics and chemistry, with a dispassionate recog- 
 nition, informed by the aims of practice. It sees 
 that when the traditional conception of Christ’s 
 Divinity was shaped the sciences were not formed ; 
 history, as we now understand it, was almost non- 
 existent ; industry was in an infant condition ; our 
 European social order had not yet come into being ; 
 vast parts of the earth and a vast part of mankind 
 were unknown ; and the immense majority of men 
 and women were steeped in barbaric ignorance and 
 superstition. 
 
38 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 These conditions, in their fundamental character, 
 governed the minds not merely of what we should 
 now call the “ common people,” but of the various 
 founders and thinkers of Catholicism — including, of 
 course, the writers of the New Testament. To them 
 God — like the Jehovah of the Jews, the Zeus of the 
 Greeks, the Jupiter of the Romans — was “ a magnified 
 and non-natural man,”* “ the Father,” seated on a 
 throne in the sky. With this image Catholicism 
 associated “ the Son,” sitting at the right hand of the 
 Father, the “ Holy Spirit,” “ proceeding ” from the 
 Father and the Son, and the Mother of God, exalted 
 and glorified. Along with these images there grew 
 up the conceptions of Heaven, Purgatory, and Hell — 
 “ the next world,” taking the place of similar Pagan 
 ideas. There can be no doubt, too, that to the early 
 Christians “ this world ” was a region soon to dis- 
 appear, and “ the next ” was a “ place ” or “ state ” 
 soon to come. Such ideas and expectations are 
 stamped visibly upon the New Testament writings, 
 and whatever these writings are, or are not, they are 
 certainly a witness to the state of mind of those who 
 composed them, and to the social and intellectual con- 
 ditions under which they arose. Those who founded 
 Catholicism — considered as a vast, persisting system 
 of doctrine, worship, and policy — founded it uncon- 
 sciously, and because they were forced, by the nature 
 of man’s life upon earth, to convert their apocalyptic 
 visions, their fanciful eschatology, their moral ideal- 
 ism, their spiritual ecstasy, and their metaphysical 
 * Matthew Arnold : “ Literature and Dogma.” 
 
RELIGIOUS INTRODUCTION 
 
 39 
 
 bewilderment into something that might serve as a 
 rule of action, wide enough for the needs of man. The 
 “ Kingdom of Heaven,” they learned, was not to be 
 in the sky, and to proceed from a sudden catastrophe, 
 but was to be — if ever it was to be — a slow creation of 
 man’s mind and will, painfully, reluctantly working 
 upon Nature and human nature, and inspired by a 
 progressive sense of Perfection. 
 
 VII 
 
 A scientific and historic estimate of Catholicism 
 cannot, of course, be drawn from any one of its ages 
 exclusively, or from its popular mind alone, without 
 taking account of its learned mind, or from one school 
 of theology by itself, without taking account of others. 
 We are on sure ground, however, when we say that 
 Catholicism, throughout all its ages, and in all its 
 schools — at any rate, since its development into a 
 dogmatic and organic system — ^has rested on the 
 conceptions and instruments which I have just 
 enumerated — its conceptions of God in Christ, of the 
 New Testament as an “ inspired Revelation,” of the 
 Trinity, of the Blessed Virgin, of Heaven, Hell, and 
 Purgatory, and of “ this world ” and “ the next.” 
 It is, of course, true that these terms are not, in 
 themselves, positive and definite, and that while 
 there has been a common agreement, within the 
 Church, to accept and use them, it has never been 
 possible to exactly measure the state of mind which 
 corresponded with them. It is, for example, of the 
 essence of such a symbol as the Nicene Creed that 
 
40 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 it is built up of a number of statements to which any 
 individual mind may pledge itself, and which a number 
 of persons may consent to rehearse in common, but 
 to which none of those who repeat them may be able 
 to attach any precise and practical significance. A 
 whole society of men and women may go on saying “ I 
 believe in God the Father, Maker of Heaven and 
 Earth ” without in the least knowing what they mean 
 by “ belief,” or by “ God,” or by God as “ the 
 Father,” or, in such a connection, by “ Maker,” or by 
 “ Heaven.” The one word in this sentence which they 
 can so use as to understand it themselves, and to com- 
 municate their understanding of it to others, is the 
 word “ Earth,” and this they can thus use because a 
 positive and common experience enlightens them, and 
 because this common experience has been invested by 
 science with the authority of exactness and proof. 
 
 Now, we may say, quite simply and broadly, that 
 the general principle which the Modern Mind applies 
 to Catholicism, in its pursuit of religious continuity 
 and development is this — that just as it is possible to 
 attach a demonstrable and practical meaning to 
 such a word as the word “ Earth ” in the Nicene 
 Creed, and in other theological statements, so it must 
 become possible, in degree, to attach a similar meaning 
 to such terms as “ God,” the “ Trinity,” “ Heaven,” 
 “ Hell,” “ Purgatory,” “ the future life,” “ the Scrip- 
 tures,” the “ Sacraments,” and “ the Church.” In 
 so far as no such meaning — a meaning of proof and 
 use — can be attached to these terms, they will pass 
 from the speech of man, as the verbal symbols of 
 
RELIGIOUS INTRODUCTION 
 
 41 
 
 “ Paganism,” except for historic and literary pur- 
 poses, have passed from it, and Catholicism or 
 Christianity will, therefore, cease to have a social 
 importance. This cardinal principle of a Catholic 
 “ modernism ” — if we are to use a somewhat objec- 
 tionable word — is, of course, one which ordinary 
 ecclesiastics and theologians, affirming propositions 
 which they cannot prove, and denouncing evils which 
 they cannot prevent, may, at first, dislike and reject. 
 But they must end by accepting it. They cannot 
 help themselves. The movement of the human mind, 
 continuous, unified, and universal, is not to be 
 arrested. The modern man is not the medieval man, 
 or the ancient man. He is himself. He is the heir 
 of the Past ; he is not its slave. If he elects to remain 
 Catholic he will remain Catholic in his own way — 
 according to his new vision, his new needs, his new 
 powers — and any Catholicism, or “ Christianity,” 
 representing simply the vision, needs, and powers of a 
 former age will necessarily become a lapsed creed. 
 
 In the light of this controlling principle of a 
 Scientific Catholicism — not a negative principle, which 
 simply disallows and rejects, but a positive principle, 
 which transforms and uses — it is easy to determine its 
 attitude towards such fundamental conceptions as 
 those of “ the other world,” “ miracle,” “ sin,” and 
 “ prayer.” All of these related conceptions, as it is 
 hardly necessary to say, have a bearing upon the 
 problem of a Human Peace, for this problem cannot 
 rightly be dissociated from man’s view of himself and 
 his life. According to the official doctrine of Catholi- 
 
42 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 cism, or “ Christianity,” in any of its organic forms, 
 “ this world ” is, in principle, of importance only as 
 a prelude to “ the next.” It is a vale of tears. It is a 
 state of trial and probation. In itself it is worthless 
 and contemptible, whether we consider it in its 
 character, or in its duration. For the human species 
 as a whole it means an indefinite period of misery and 
 disappointment, to be ended by a general confla- 
 gration, in which the whole of the visible universe 
 will, somehow, be resolved into nothing. For the 
 individual man or woman it means a brief season of 
 life on earth — varying from a few seconds to, perhaps, 
 a hundred years — followed by “ eternal life ” in a 
 place of torment called “ Hell,” or in a place of 
 felicity called “ Heaven,” to be reached, as a rule, 
 after a longer or shorter sojourn in another place of 
 torment called “ Purgatory.” During this life of 
 man on earth — the continued, indefinite Hfe of the 
 human species, the limited life of individual men and 
 women — God, the “ magnified and non-natural Man,” 
 sits as a spectator on His throne in “ Heaven,” with 
 “ the Son ” and the ‘‘ Holy Spirit ” and the Blessed 
 Virgin in indissoluble association with Him, for ever 
 watching the play of human affairs, listening to the 
 prayers of men, for ever judging individual “ souls ” 
 as they “ ascend ” to Him at death, and waiting for 
 that indefinite time when He shall cause a trumpet to 
 be sounded for the general judgment, and the total 
 annihilation of the universe. 
 
 Now, first, we may say that, assuming such a con- 
 ception of a future Hfe,” or of the “ next world,” to 
 
RELIGIOUS INTRODUCTION 
 
 43 
 
 be in any sense thinkable, it has no necessary relation 
 to that end which Catholicism, according to the 
 Modern Mind, proposes to itself. That end is a many- 
 sided, positive, human Perfection, individual and 
 social, symbolized, inspired by the transcendent Per- 
 fection, or Divinity, of Christ. The traditional con- 
 ception of a future life has a relation to merely one 
 side of perfection — its moral side — and this only in an 
 exclusive and limited sense. Certainly, moral per- 
 fection is the most important of all, and, rightly 
 understood, is the basis and condition of all others. 
 It is for this reason especially that Christ is confessed 
 as God. In Him we see the whole order of things 
 summed up and typified in a human and personal 
 order, constituted by the ascendency of a spiritual and 
 self-sacrificing love. From this point of view moral 
 perfection may be said to contain within itself the 
 total perfection of man, for it means his highest 
 nature — what is Divine in him — ruling and ordering 
 throughout the complex unity of his being, emotional, 
 intellectual, practical, and this not merely by a 
 suppression of the bad, but by an expression of the 
 good. For practical purposes, however, we have to 
 recognize a distinction between moral perfection and 
 intellectual and practical perfection, and to say that 
 the ideal, or perfect, man is the man whose many-sided 
 nature is full-flowering, unified, and consummate in 
 the social state. 
 
 With this positive conception of perfection the 
 conception of a future life, as it is contained in our 
 traditional Catholicism, has no assignable relation. 
 
44 the problem OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 According to that conception, man is a “ sinner.” He 
 is a sinner as soon as he is born — before even he can 
 shape a thought or perform an action. He is “ saved ” 
 from this congenital sin — or, rather, from the penal- 
 ties due to it — by the magic of the baptismal rite, in 
 the absence of which he will be punished by being 
 excluded eternally from “ Heaven.” When he grows 
 up he is a sinner by his own conscious will and act. 
 By “ sin ” is meant the contravention of certain 
 elementary moral commands, or the neglect of certain 
 ecclesiastical ordinances — as, for example, the obliga- 
 tion to hear Mass. Man is inevitably throughout 
 life, in varying degree, in this sense a sinner, and, 
 therefore, deserving of punishment in a future life. 
 However much and however long he may sin, never- 
 theless, he can escape the eternal punishment, and 
 limit the temporal punishment, due to him in a future 
 life by repentance, confession, and absolution, and by 
 virtue of the principle of indulgences. The wickedest 
 of human beings, in fact, being contrite, is, by means 
 of the Sacrament of Penance and a Plenary Indul- 
 gence completely exempted from the consequence of 
 all sin, both original and personal, and, if he dies in 
 this “ state of grace,” goes straight to Heaven, and 
 becomes immediately the associate of saints and 
 angels. 
 
 Such a conception of a future life has, as is evident, 
 no connection with a positive idea of perfection — the 
 pursuit and realization of a beautiful humanity, 
 individual and social — even if we think only of moral 
 perfection, in a distinctive and exclusive sense. Still 
 
RELIGIOUS INTRODUCTION 
 
 45 
 
 less has it any bearing upon Perfection in its total 
 significance — the harmonious manifestation of a full- 
 fiowering humanity, physical, moral, intellectual, 
 practical, individual, and social. The “ salvation of 
 the sinner ” — that is to say, escape from the just 
 punishment of sin, and the attainment, in spite of it, 
 of eternal felicity in “ another world ” — is not the 
 same thing as the Divine spirit of man, ruling itself, 
 and realizing itself in every sphere of his being. The 
 “ sinner ” who is “ saved ” and goes to Heaven may 
 be, in everything except contrition, utterly worth- 
 less — in morals depraved, in intelligence stupid and 
 ignorant, in his social and civic conduct incapable 
 or inefficient. He may be ugly, deformed, brutal, 
 drunken, profligate, useless in the family, useless in 
 the State, useless in the workshop, useless in the 
 school, with no feeling for the arts or sciences, with 
 no sentiment of worship, with no power of practical 
 service — and yet in “ Heaven ” he is at once magically 
 transformed and becomes a friend and companion of 
 God. From such a point of view what we call the 
 evils or imperfections of human life are of no import- 
 ance — disease, ugliness, ignorance, poverty, crime, 
 war ; and even sin, in principle the greatest of evils, 
 is not so much an evil in itself as in its personal 
 chastisement, from which escape is easily possible 
 by a moment of sufficient contrition and the perform- 
 ance of a ritual act. 
 
 But while this traditional conception of a “ future 
 life ” is thus out of relation with any positive ideal 
 of perfection, the greater consideration remains. The 
 
46 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 conception itself, in any merely objective and external 
 interpretation of it, has ceased to have meaning and 
 validity for the Modern Mind — except such a historic 
 and relative meaning as attaches, for example, to the 
 Elysium of the ancient Greeks, or to the Valhalla of 
 the Scandinavians. Upon this subject, from the 
 point of view of science, discussion is both impossible 
 and useless. It is, from this point of view, impossible 
 and useless because we know nothing whatever of the 
 Catholic “ future life ” — Heaven, Hell, and Purgatory 
 — and, in the total absence of knowledge with regard 
 to it, are not even able to assign a rational objective 
 meaning to these three terms. They are symbolic 
 terms of the human mind ; they are not terms of the 
 external and visible cosmos. They are terms of inner 
 experience ; they are not terms of outer experience. 
 This is acknowledged, quite plainly and unequivocally, 
 by Catholicism itself. It does not profess to “ know ” 
 anything of Heaven, Hell, and Purgatory — “ what ” 
 they are, or “ where ” they are. These ideas, it 
 admits, do not lie within the region of reason or 
 demonstration. They are “ of faith.” They are 
 not to be understood ; they are to be received, and 
 received on no other ground than that “ the Church ” 
 affirms them. 
 
 To the Modern Mind, however, faith and reason are 
 not antithetic. Faith to it is not a mystic process of 
 apprehending occult truths which lie wholly outside 
 the sphere of experience and demonstration ; it is 
 an attitude of mind and will — one of extreme value 
 and importance — ^which is as much capable of a 
 
RELIGIOUS INTRODUCTION 
 
 47 
 
 positive explanation and designation as any other, 
 and which has an assignable relation to knowledge and 
 life. The Modern Mind, therefore, does not recognize 
 a fundamental and perpetual distinction between the 
 things of “ faith ” and the things of experience and 
 reason. Its Catholicism — the only Catholicism which 
 it will accept — is in doctrine scientific, and its terms 
 or statements must, therefore, in a last resort, be 
 subject to the ordeal of proof and use. This does not, 
 of course, necessarily mean that the Catholic concep- 
 tion of Heaven, Hell, and Purgatory is to be dismissed 
 from the Modern Mind, although that mind, in the 
 exercise of its natural, indefeasible sovereignty, has 
 undoubtedly the power to dismiss it ; it means that 
 the sense and use of these expressions, as of all Catholic 
 ideas and terms, are to be determined by the Modern 
 Mind itself and not by the medieval mind. It means, 
 too, that the value assigned to them must be such as 
 is capable of entering into a synthesis of positive and 
 demonstrable truths, and of visibly contributing to 
 the ideal and pursuit of human perfection. 
 
 What is true of the traditional Catholic conception 
 of a future life is, of course, true also of the traditional 
 ideas of miracle and prayer. In a modern scientific 
 Catholicism — occupied with the pursuit of a positive 
 human perfection, individual and social, symbolized 
 by Christ — miracle has no place. It is not necessary 
 to discuss it, any more than it is necessary to discuss 
 the Elixir of Life, or the processes of witchcraft, 
 except in connection with the history of the human 
 mind. It does not, in fact, lie within the region of 
 
48 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 rational discussion. Perfection, positively understood, 
 means man ruling himself and fulfilling himself, in- 
 dividually and socially. It means love, goodness, 
 health, beauty, wisdom, power, a mastery of natural 
 forces, a right distribution of material wealth, a 
 prescient and high direction of human life towards 
 universal peace and concord. In relation to these 
 ends religion in the modern world must declare itself 
 and test itself. The only Catholicism that can 
 now live is a Catholicism consciously and intention- 
 ally directed towards them, and judging all its con- 
 ceptions and instruments by their capacity to con- 
 tribute to their fulfilment. 
 
 Now perfection, in all its spheres — in love, good- 
 ness, health, beauty, knowledge, power, in social order, 
 in industry, in art, in science — is the result of a con- 
 tinuous effort, individual and social. This effort 
 entails sacrifice of certain things and the pursuit of 
 others. It requires prescience, will, and courage. It 
 is maintained from age to age of human life. It 
 demands the co-operation of successive generations. 
 It is subject to hindrances. It meets with dis- 
 couragement. It is apparently often interrupted and 
 frustrated. It has its heroes and martyrs. It has 
 its seasons of sorrow and despair, as of joy and hope. 
 This effort, in fact, is the life of man, as we see it in 
 history. In that life, according to the conception of 
 a Scientific Catholicism, miracle has no place. Miracle 
 does not till the fields, or procure for men warmth, 
 clothing and housing, or compose a poem, or paint a 
 picture, or build a church, or construct a science, or 
 
RELIGIOUS INTRODUCTION 
 
 49 
 
 promote education, or maintain the family life, or 
 organize and direct a nation. It adds nothing to the 
 force of love ; it gives no new power or range to 
 reason. It removes no difficulty from the path of 
 man. It does not exalt his inner nature ; it does not 
 enlarge his outer capacity. If he is wretched, dis- 
 eased, poor, ignorant, and helpless, miracle brings him 
 no permanent resource, and in a world of war miracle, 
 in its evident impotence, is incapable of pronouncing 
 the word of peace. 
 
 Those, therefore, who in the modern world, invoke 
 the power of miracle in reference to any of the con- 
 tinuous aims of human life — physical, moral, intel- 
 lectual, industrial, or social — are as much out of 
 relation with the sanity of their age as was Don 
 Quixote when he donned the helmet of Mambrino, or 
 attempted the restoration of chivalry by an encounter 
 with a windmill. They are, in this respect, as a 
 consequence, in proportion to their influence upon 
 the minds of men, an actual hindrance to social order 
 and development, since — allowing for their value and 
 excellence in other respects — they tend to confuse and 
 misdirect the human spirit, and prevent it from under- 
 standing itself, the nature of its fundamental aims, 
 and the right means of their attainment. The 
 greatest single instrument of perfection is prayer, for 
 in prayer, according to a scientific and ideal conception 
 of it, man consciously renews in his mind an Image 
 of Perfection, a Divine Ideal, acknowledges its beauty 
 and lordship, measures himself in relation to it, con- 
 fesses his shortcomings, invokes, by a process of 
 
 HtP. 
 
50 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 spiritual imagination and will, the power necessary 
 for its realization, and prepares himself, in feeling, in- 
 telligence, and action, to come into practical corre- 
 spondence with it. Prayer, therefore, is a first form 
 of spiritual effort. It is an exercise in religious life. 
 It is an act of vivifying and renovating communion 
 with the Supreme Good, comparable with the act by 
 which we deliberately place ourselves in relation with 
 some spectacle of beauty in Nature, or some visible 
 nobleness in humanity, or some great creation in art, 
 and undergo its influence of inspiration and renewal. 
 But in prayer, according to this scientific conception 
 of it, miracle — the suspension or subversion of the 
 natural order, cosmic or human — ^has no place. 
 Prayer, therefore, in all its forms — ^whether in private 
 or public worship, in the baptismal rite, in the conse- 
 crations of the Holy Eucharist, in the ordination of 
 priests, in the marriage service, or in any other sacra- 
 ment — has no magical force. It is the acknowledg- 
 ment and instrument of an ideal Humanity, and it 
 has a value proportioned to the rational apprehension 
 of that ideal, and to the degree in which it actually 
 calls forth in men the forces of feeling, intelligence, 
 and active will essential to its realization. 
 
 VIII 
 
 We are now — sufficiently for our present purpose — 
 in a position to understand what it is that we mean 
 by a Scientific Catholicism. We do not mean by it 
 a new sect, or a “ new religion,” or some arbitrary 
 construction of an individual thinker. We mean by 
 
RELIGIOUS INTRODUCTION 
 
 51 
 
 it, first, that the Modern Mind, being synthetic — 
 holding within itself the powers, experiences, and 
 acquisitions of a total humanity, past and present — 
 is of sovereign authority, and that to this mind it 
 now falls to determine the sense of such words as 
 “ God,” Christ, the Trinity, sin, the Scriptures, the 
 “ future life,” the creeds, prayer, the sacraments, and 
 the Church. We mean by it, secondly, that to the 
 Modern Mind Catholicism, throughout its entire range, 
 is the confession and pursuit of an ideal perfection, 
 individual and social — a perfection continuously 
 centred and symbolized in Christ as God, but not to be 
 limited by the conception of His Divinity proper to 
 any one age or stage of Catholic development. 
 
 It is to Catholicism in this sense that we are to 
 look for the installation and maintenance of a Human 
 Peace. To a merely traditional or unscientific 
 Catholicism — to a Catholicism representing an imma- 
 ture condition of the human mind — ^we cannot so 
 look. The reasons for this may be simply assigned. 
 They follow from all that we have now said. Catholi- 
 cism has never, in fact, been able to give to man a 
 right representation of himself and of the universe in 
 relation to himself. It has given him a representation 
 intuitive, conjectural, imaginative, incomplete, ex- 
 pressing itself in metaphysical statements lying beyond 
 the region of proof or disproof, and having no direct 
 application to life and conduct. This provisional 
 synthesis of things has not been, by its own nature — 
 considered as a theory or theology — practical and 
 social, but has been rendered, in some degree, prac- 
 
52 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 tical and social by the active mind of man, pursuing 
 his destiny in presence of the actual conditions and 
 needs of his nature. In proportion as he has done 
 this — in proportion as he has gained the experiences 
 and acquisitions characteristic of a developed and 
 complete humanity — he has tended to outgrow the 
 CathoHc synthesis, in what we may call the unscientific 
 or infantile conception of it. It is now, in this con- 
 ception of it, the synthesis of children, or of ignorant 
 and incapable minds. No rational being now believes 
 — if any rational being ever really believed — that 
 there is “ a God,” in the sense of a “ magnified and 
 non-natural man,” sitting somewhere on “ a throne ” 
 in the sky, or “ beyond ” the infinite visible universe^ 
 and eternally occupied, in this infinite universe, in 
 watching the affairs of our little planet, and “ judg- 
 ing ” the “ souls ” of its inhabitants as they indi- 
 vidually “ ascend ” to Him at death. No rational 
 being believes — if any rational being ever really 
 believed — in any objective and literal sense, in the 
 Catholic Heaven, Hell, and Purgatory as places or 
 “ states ” “ somewhere ” and “ sometime ” to be 
 discovered. These, we now see, are symbolic, or 
 poetic, conceptions and terms, representing a spiritual 
 reality. They have exactly the value which the 
 human mind, in its progressive capacity and know- 
 ledge, chooses to assign to them ; and the mind which 
 now gives them their meaning — disallows them alto- 
 gether, or uses them in its own way, and for its own 
 purposes — is the synthetic, sovereign Modern Mind, 
 self-conscious, self-scrutinizing, analytic, practical. 
 
RELIGIOUS INTRODUCTION 
 
 53 
 
 The place of a merely traditional, or immature, 
 Catholicism, relatively to the mind and life of man 
 — and relatively, therefore, to the problem of Human 
 Peace — is shown by its actual position in our con- 
 temporary world. That position is at once a fulfil- 
 ment and representation of historic Catholicism, con- 
 sidered on its practical and social side. Catholicism 
 in itself — as a “ supernatural ” doctrine, and apart 
 from the practical construction and use of it upon 
 which man has been forced by his continuous needs — 
 has never shown man how to do the things which, 
 for the purposes of his life on earth, he has been 
 compelled to do. It is science — ^including that com- 
 mon-sense empiricism which precedes and supple- 
 ments formal science — which has done this. One 
 consequence of this has been that men have more 
 and more ceased to appeal to Catholicism as such, or 
 to Christianity in any shape, in relation either to the 
 acquisition and communication of knowledge, or to 
 the practical conduct of human life. At the present 
 time no responsible man ever thinks of turning to 
 CathoHcism or Christianity — in other words, to pro- 
 fessed Christian teachers, as such — for guidance either 
 in international relations, or in domestic national 
 policy, or in industrial concerns, or in the arts and 
 sciences, or in education. All these great fields of 
 human effort have passed from the control of “ the 
 Church ” as such, in so far as they were ever under it, 
 to the control of “ the State ” — the secular mind of 
 man, working in a neutral sphere of social need, and 
 according to the dictates of practical reason. Even 
 
54 the problem OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 in the domain of personal morals — the special and 
 supreme domain, as was once supposed, of “ the 
 Church ” — it is now the State, the organ of “ believer ” 
 and “ unbeliever ” alike, which decides and shapes 
 things. It regulates, or attempts to regulate, the 
 drinking habits of society. It legislates on questions 
 of sex. It deals with the smoking mania. It modi- 
 fies, or abrogates, the law of the Church as regards 
 marriage and divorce. It controls, or tries to control, 
 industrial morality. In France it has ostentatiously 
 dismissed religion from public life, and where it has 
 not been thus openly and systematically dismissed, it 
 is dismissed by implication and indifference. 
 
 Catholicism, therefore, — and once more, in such a 
 connection, I mean Christianity in all its forms — has 
 come, actually and practically, to occupy the position 
 which Comte contemptuously proposed to it more 
 than sixty years ago. It has become exclusively the 
 religion of the “ next world ” ; it has ceased to be the 
 religion of “ this.” It has, in fact, worked out its 
 own metaphysic. From the point of view of the 
 “ next world,” which is Eternity, it does not, as we 
 have seen, much matter whether in “ this world,” 
 which is Time, man is diseased or healthy, ugly or 
 beautiful, sane or insane, ignorant or instructed, 
 stupid or wise, steeped in abject poverty, or a master 
 of material resources, versed in the arts and sciences 
 or utterly illiterate, a lord of industry and civil 
 policy or a helpless barbarian, in a state of social 
 peace, or perpetually involved in a bloody and waste- 
 ful war. It does not, from this standpoint, even 
 
RELIGIOUS INTRODUCTION 
 
 55 
 
 matter whether man is or is not a “ sinner,” provided 
 only that he makes use of the means which the Church 
 holds out to him for escaping the eternal punishment 
 of sin and securing “ salvation.” The “ next world ” 
 will put everything right that is wrong in “ this 
 world,” and, in fact, it is only “ the world ” which 
 we do not know that is “ real,” while the world which 
 we know is “ unreal.” This “ next world ” is a fairy- 
 land of supernatural enchantments, to come somehow 
 into “ existence ” when the infinite universe has been 
 resolved into nothing, but which somehow, neverthe- 
 less, “ exists ” already ; and in it the vilest or most 
 abject of men, being “ penitent,” is at once magically 
 transformed into an inconceivable something incon- 
 ceivably noble and beautiful. 
 
 A second consequence of the scientific incapacity of 
 Catholicism, or Christianity — its inability to rightly 
 represent to man himself and the universe in relation 
 to himself — is that in our modern world it has been 
 deliberately and openly rejected as a synthesis of 
 things by an immense number of thinking minds. 
 They are confessedly agnostics or atheists. A third 
 consequence is that Catholicism has never been really 
 Catholic, in the sense of being a universal religion of 
 mankind. It is now certain that, in the traditional 
 conception of it, it will never become this. The non- 
 Christian religions of the world, doctrinally considered, 
 rest, in principle, as Catholicism itself rests, on a 
 number of metaphysical conceptions and statements 
 lying beyond the region of proof or disproof. They 
 are, as our traditional Catholicism is, unscientific. 
 
56 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 Catholicism, as a metaphysical theology, has nothing 
 to offer the adherents of these non-Christian religions 
 but its own indemonstrable affirmations in exchange 
 for theirs. It can no longer claim for these affirmations 
 that they have the authority of the mind and life of 
 civilized Christendom. Civilized Christendom, as we 
 see, not only rejects or neglects them, in practice, in 
 its own social life, but, in an ever-increasing degree, 
 deliberately dismisses them from its mind. The 
 missionaries of the Western world are now proposing 
 to the East a religion which has ceased to be the 
 religion of the Western world. 
 
 IX 
 
 From what I have called a traditional or unscientific 
 Catholicism, therefore, we have no grounds for expect- 
 ing a Human Peace. It is, as a religion of social order 
 and progress, now practically disregarded or theoreti- 
 cally rejected in the chief theatre of its own develop- 
 ment. This is so true that to most independent 
 thinkers it will doubtless seem absurd to connect an 
 argument for the peace of the world with Catholicism, 
 or Christianity, in any conception of it. The prac- 
 tical mind, occupied with the living interests and 
 causes of man, looks to “ the State,” or the Govern- 
 ment, as its expression and instrument, or to some 
 special social agencies acting outside the sphere of 
 “ the Church.” The priest — here using this word to 
 embrace the Protestant minister as well as the 
 Catholic — -is now, speaking generally, a Sunday officer 
 
RELIGIOUS INTRODUCTION 
 
 57 
 
 only. That is the day of the “ next world.” It is on 
 that day especially that he works his miracles, or 
 offers up his prayers, or sets forth his metaphysical 
 doctrine of “ sin ” — the only doctrine that in any 
 sense belongs to him. On the other days of the week 
 — the days in which men labour, or learn, or teach, 
 or heal disease, or occupy themselves with the arts 
 and sciences, or live their social life, or engage in the 
 great affairs of citizenship and policy — on these other 
 days, the priest, as such, has no place or function, 
 allowing for what may be called his ceremonial and 
 philanthropic activities. 
 
 It is for this reason that many minds — especially 
 among those who have actually to bear the burdens 
 and do the work of the world — are beginning to ask 
 themselves whether the priest, or religious minister, 
 is not now a mere incubus or parasite, maintained 
 by the active life of man, but contributing nothing 
 whatever to its nourishment or guidance. The 
 Catholic priest is, of course, the representative priest 
 of the world. He works miracles — the sacramental 
 miracles, for example, of baptism, transubstantiation, 
 ordination, absolution. The practical, honest minds 
 of the present day, however, comparing one thing 
 with another, do not see that the Catholic priest, who 
 is miraculously “ ordained ” to work miracles, is in 
 any way intellectually superior to the men who have 
 not been so ordained. They know, in fact, that he is 
 frequently inferior to them. They see, too, that 
 even in the priest himself a certain secular education 
 and, perhaps, a university degree are of more prac- 
 
58 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 tical importance than that “ gift of the Holy Spirit ” 
 which is the priest’s special distinction — that in the 
 absence of such an education, indeed, this magical 
 gift, even in the estimation of the Church which 
 makes an exclusive claim to it — counts for just 
 nothing at all. In the same way the practical, 
 honest minds of the present day, using their eyes, and 
 seeing things as they are, do not find that the average 
 man or woman who attends mass in the Catholic 
 Church, or who receives the Blessed Sacrament, or 
 who goes to confession is — judged by any recognized 
 moral, intellectual, or practical test — in any way 
 superior, for example, to the average Quaker, who 
 does none of these things. So, too, these honest, 
 practical minds recognize that in the Catholic Church, 
 which insists that matrimony is a “ sacrament,” and 
 which condemns a formal divorce, the marriage tie 
 has not, in fact, been more sacred than in non- 
 Catholic bodies, and the realities of divorce are as 
 common as elsewhere. 
 
 To the honest, practical mind, therefore, the 
 Catholic priest, or Protestant minister, in the tra- 
 ditional or unscientific conception of his office — 
 working miracles that do not matter, or affirming 
 propositions which he cannot prove, or offering up 
 prayers which have no assignable relation to the 
 knowledge and life of man, or denouncing evils which 
 he does not prevent — makes a smaller contribution 
 to the real good of the world than the humblest 
 labourer in the fields, actually facing the forces of 
 Nature, and bringing to bear on them the transform- 
 
RELIGIOUS INTRODUCTION 
 
 59 
 
 ing power of a human mind and will. From such a 
 point of view it may seem useless, and even fantastic, 
 to invoke Catholicism, or Christianity, as the instru- 
 ment of a Human Peace. Catholicism, or Chris- 
 tianity, has not, in fact, from the age of Constantine 
 to the present time, been a power of peace. It has 
 not even aimed at the prevention of war. It has 
 sanctioned and blessed all wars as they arose — even 
 the wickedest and most stupid. It has frequently 
 been a cause of war itself. The priest, with rare 
 exceptions, has been, and is, the subservient apologist 
 of the soldier or the ruler. He has been wanting 
 in spiritual courage, as he has been destitute of 
 social insight and prevision. Throughout its sixteen 
 centuries of official ascendency Catholicism, or Chris- 
 tianity — meaning by this especially its theological doc- 
 trine and directing hierarchy — ^has complacently pre- 
 sided over a long succession of wars ; and to-day, in 
 presence of the bloodiest catastrophe in the life of 
 man, the “ Christian Church ” exhibits itself to the 
 world as a discredited company of helpless and 
 wrangling sects, excluded, by common consent, from 
 every real sphere of thought and action, and impo- 
 tently occupied in disputing about conceptions and 
 terms to which they are wholly unable to assign a 
 practical meaning. This, as it is hardly necessary to 
 say, is not due to any merely personal defects of 
 priests and ministers, many of whom are devoted 
 social servants, of a noble spiritual seriousness and 
 high intellectual quality. It is the inevitable effect 
 of a theological doctrine which, in the traditional 
 
6o THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 interpretation of it, has ceased to be in practical 
 correspondence with the mind and life of man, and 
 which, therefore, among those who are called upon 
 to profess it, gives to the capable an effect of 
 incapacity, and to the honest an appearance of dis- 
 honesty, while largely nullifying the positive beauty 
 and truth of Catholicism itself. 
 
 X 
 
 In face of these conclusions — conclusions which 
 find their proof in the social history of Christianity, 
 and in its visible position in our contemporary world — 
 it may appear useless to appeal to Catholicism, or 
 “ Christianity,” as the inspiration and directing mind 
 of a Human Peace. To many, indeed, it will seem 
 that the Catholic Church — embracing under this 
 expression, for our immediate purpose, all Christian 
 Churches — is now, in degree, an atheistic Church. The 
 earliest Christian apologist, as we have seen, had to 
 defend his co-religionists against a charge of atheism. 
 That was natural. What we call “ belief in God ” 
 means simply the acceptance of some particular con- 
 ception of Divinity, or connotation of the word 
 “ God,” which happens, at a given time, to be nomin- 
 ally and officially ascendant in the world. Our Lord 
 Himself was, to the Scribes and Pharisees who cruci- 
 fied Him, an atheist, or blasphemer. In the same way 
 Justin Martyr’s Christian contemporaries were, to the 
 Pagan mind, atheists, for the obvious and sufficient 
 reason that they rejected conceptions of the Divine 
 which were, in substance, practically universal in the 
 
RELIGIOUS INTRODUCTION 
 
 6i 
 
 ancient world. The early Christians had, as we now 
 see, a good answer to this charge. They were, it is 
 true, subverting — or they had the intention to subvert 
 — all the religious beliefs of antiquity, but they were 
 bringing in a new and nobler belief. They were 
 actually “ atheists ” relatively to the Pagan concep- 
 tions of the Divine, but they were setting forth a 
 higher and more beautiful conception, and, in presence 
 of this conception, it was the Pagan world itself, 
 resting in lower views of Divinity, and denying the 
 higher, which was atheistic. 
 
 In exactly the same way we may say that at the 
 present day it is the Catholic Church — with all 
 Christian Churches in proportion as they are Catholic 
 — ^which is in danger of becoming atheistic. The 
 word “ God,” in its abstract and continuous meaning, 
 stands for the Infinite Controlling Order, or Reality, 
 visible and invisible — including the Order of Humanity 
 — ^with which man is in progressive relation, according 
 as that Order is conceived and interpreted by 
 his developing mind. In the modern world it is 
 the Modern Mind — not a mind disruptive or revo- 
 lutionary, but a mind evolved and synthetic — ^which 
 gives its meaning to the word “ God.” That meaning 
 is a meaning of science. The rejection of this meaning 
 is as much, 'pro tanto, atheism as was the rejection of 
 Christ’s Divinity by ancient Paganism. In other 
 words, it is the assertion of a lower and lapsed con- 
 ception in presence of a higher and living conception. 
 It is the denial of Truth, which can never mean any- 
 thing else than the continuous, progressive, and 
 
62 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 tested affirmations of man’s social mind concerning 
 the sum of his real experiences, outer and inner — 
 affirmations which are subject, in the last resort, to 
 the criterion of practice and use. The denial of 
 science, the denial of the conception of God following 
 upon the development of science, is, therefore, in our 
 modern world, atheism. 
 
 We come back, then, to the principle — the funda- 
 mental principle governing the following pages — that 
 for the installation and maintenance of a Human 
 Peace what is needed is a Scientific Catholicism. A 
 Scientific Catholicism, once more, will not be a 
 wholly “ new ” Catholicism. It will not maintain 
 the relation to our historic and traditional Catholicism 
 which that Catholicism, in principle, maintained to 
 the faiths of the ancient world. We can see now that 
 our common Christian criticism of those faiths is as 
 absurd and ungrateful as it is devoid of historic 
 truth — that the essential foundations of religion were 
 broadly and deeply laid, whether by Judaism or 
 Paganism, long before Christianity arose, and that 
 what we call “ Paganism ” — to say nothing of 
 Judaism — was a thing of noble spiritual seriousness, 
 of a many-sided intellectual vitality, of a spacious 
 artistic beauty, and of a vast social and practical 
 power, which has continued to govern the mind and 
 life of Humanity down to the present hour. We see 
 that a later age in the progressive life of man rests 
 upon its earlier ages. The Modern Mind brings this 
 principle to bear on our traditional Catholicism itself. 
 It is not the first nor the last. In so far as it claims 
 
RELIGIOUS INTRODUCTION 
 
 63 
 
 to be this it is a denial of science ; it is atheistic. The 
 Modern Mind builds upon it consciously, intention- 
 ally, and systematically, as a primitive Christianity 
 built unintentionally and spontaneously upon the 
 religions of the ancient world. The Modern Mind 
 enters into the whole positive truth of Catholicism — in 
 scripture, doctrine, creed, worship, sacrament, and 
 institutions — and reinforces it with truths which an 
 atheistic Catholicism has denied, or neglected, or been 
 incapable of incorporating in its own synthesis. The 
 old, continuous purpose of Catholicism remains — Per- 
 fection, according to the Divinity of Christ, the King- 
 dom of Heaven. Heaven to the Modern Mind is not 
 “ a place ” of magic and enchantment in the sky, or 
 beyond the visible universe, with “ God,” as a magni- 
 fied and non-natural man, seated on a throne, and 
 looking “ out ” or “ down ” upon the life of mankind 
 on earth, and upon illimitable hosts of men and 
 women, suffering the pangs of Hell and Purgatory. 
 The Kingdom of Heaven to the Modern Mind, as to a 
 Mind which we are not accustomed to consider modern, 
 is within us, and, being within us, it will flow out upon 
 the whole life of Humanity, individual and social, as 
 a concord of goodness, beauty, truth, and power, of 
 which a Human Peace is a first and indispensable 
 condition. 
 
CHAPTER I 
 
 SCIENCE AND THE PROBLEM OF PEACE 
 
 The question which we are to consider in this 
 essay is not the question — important as that, at a 
 given time, may be in itself — of the special settle- 
 ment, or “ terms of peace,” which may follow from 
 a particular war : it is the question, far-reaching and 
 fundamental, of the maintenance of a permanent 
 peace among all the nations of mankind. Such a 
 peace we may call a “ Human Peace ” — a peace 
 embracing in its continuing concord the whole 
 external life of humanity, from one age to another. 
 After every war there is a peace of some sort — longer 
 or shorter, and involving, frequently, certain terri- 
 torial rearrangements. This we may describe as a 
 politician’s or diplomatist’s peace. It is more or less 
 satisfactory to those concerned in it. It is imposed 
 by the victors upon the vanquished, or, where there 
 is something like a balance of forces, is the result of a 
 compromise ; and, in all human experience hitherto, 
 it has been followed after a time by another war, to 
 be succeeded in its turn by a similar peace. Speaking 
 broadly, it may be said that such an ebb and flow of 
 peace and war has characterized the life of mankind 
 for three thousand years. It may seem, therefore, 
 that, given the essential continuity of human nature, 
 we may reasonably expect the same state of things 
 
SCIENCE AND THE PROBLEM OF PEACE 65 
 
 to continue indefinitely in the future, and that, 
 consequently, it is useless to discuss such a problem 
 as that of a permanent Human Peace. Nevertheless, 
 as men, differing though they do, in their conception 
 of “ goodness,” still, in some sort, continue to pursue 
 it, notwithstanding their failures to realize it, and as 
 they do not cease to follow after beauty and truth, 
 although, throughout aU history, man has been con- 
 tinuously involved in ugliness and error, so we may 
 say that the peace of the world, the continuous Human 
 Peace, is an ideal — ^if an ideal we are to consider it — 
 which, after all, and in spite of all, we must ever put 
 before ourselves, as a Paradise, or a heaven upon 
 earth, still somehow, and at some time, to be gained. 
 
 For the Modern Mind — a mind conscious of itself, 
 and resting, in its full development, upon the accumu- 
 lated experience of mankind — the question of a 
 Human Peace is a question of science, to be studied 
 and discussed just as any problem of mathematics, 
 physics, and biology is studied and discussed. The 
 Modern Mind, so understood, may, of course, deceive 
 itself and be deceived, but its wish is to see things 
 as they are — to know what the universe actually is, 
 in so far as this admits of being known, and what are 
 man’s place and power in it. To see things as they 
 are, to know what is to be known, to recognize what 
 is unknown and unknowable, to act where action is 
 possible, to resign ourselves where it can be shown 
 to be impossible, to investigate with patience and 
 exactness, to infer with sobriety and care, to com- 
 pare and verify, and to bring all conclusions 
 
66 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 eventually to the test of experience and practice — this 
 in its essential spirit and methods, is science ; and as 
 it is science in this sense that has given us all the sure 
 knowledge of external nature which we actually 
 possess and use, so it will give us such sure knowledge 
 as is possible of man, as an individual and social 
 being, in relation to the universe. If there is any way 
 to a Human Peace, it is the way of science — showing 
 us what we are, where we are, what we can do, and 
 how to do it. 
 
 To this truth — a truth sovereign and unassailable 
 amidst all the distractions and uncertainties of the 
 Modern Mind~-it is, however, necessary to add certain 
 others. First, we must recognize that science — ^in 
 other words, the developed reason of man, resting on 
 the sum of human experience, outer and inner, and 
 interpreting that experience by definite methods — 
 can, from the nature of the case, only solve the prob- 
 lem of peace, in one way or another, when it is itself 
 complete. Science must become the Science of 
 Humanity, in a full sense-— the science of man as a 
 social and moral being, Hving in dependence upon 
 the Universal Order — before it can exhibit to us the 
 real nature of that problem and open to us the way 
 of its solution. To the lower sciences of inorganic and 
 organic nature we must add the higher sciences of 
 human nature — the sciences of sociology and morals 
 — if we are to bring into a right relation aU the 
 elements that enter into the question of peace, and 
 decide whether such a thing as a Human Peace is 
 possible. This was conclusively shown more than 
 
lENCE AND THE PROBLEM OF PEACE 67 
 
 half a century ago by Auguste Comte, who, in spite 
 of his inevitable failures and mistakes, remains to-day, 
 what he was then, the greatest of social thinkers, and 
 who more than any other man has brought to bear 
 on our perplexed modern world that full synthetic 
 survey which is indispensable to its right apprehension 
 and direction. 
 
 In the second place we must recognize — ^what also 
 Comte ought to have the credit of having shown — 
 that science alone, however much we may elevate and 
 complete it — is, while it is indispensable, insufficient 
 to solve the problem of a Human Peace. Science is, 
 in one view of it, tested and ordered knowledge, and, 
 in another view of it, the temper and method by 
 which we reach such knowledge. On any view of it, 
 however, it is merely an intellectual exercise or 
 acquisition. It represents, by itself, only one of the 
 three constituents of human nature — feeling, intelli- 
 gence, and will. It enables man to understand — in so 
 far as they admit of being understood — his nature, 
 his situation, his powers, his duties, but it does not, 
 by itself, decide whether he is to follow one or another 
 of the various conflicting purposes of human life. It 
 exhibits to him the character and antagonism of his 
 different desires, but it does not, in doing so, deter- 
 mine whether he is to live his life under the domina- 
 tion of a high desire or a low. The drunkard has at 
 least so much “ science ” as to know that drunkenness 
 involves him in physical and moral degradation, and 
 imperils his social life ; but his mere knowledge of 
 this does not, by itself, cause him to remain sober, 
 
68 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 although it may be a powerful inducement to him to 
 become so. The profligate is “ scientific ” to the 
 extent of understanding that his vices are a dissi- 
 pation of his best forces and an injury to other human 
 beings, but this does not suffice to make him moral. 
 The thief is commonly aware that he is breaking a 
 social law, and exposing himself to punishment, but 
 this does not cause him to become honest, either in 
 intention or in fact. The Christian knows, or believes, 
 that a certain line of conduct will procure him 
 “ eternal felicity,” and a certain other line “ eternal 
 damnation,” but this does not prevent him from 
 following the latter. Theology is, as has been con- 
 sidered to be, a science. It is the Science, or Doc- 
 trine, of God — unfolding to men the nature, the 
 laws, the will of the Supreme Being, in relation to 
 man — according to such conceptions of Him as have 
 established themselves in the human mind at given 
 stages of its development. But this science, by 
 itself, is far from having brought men into conformity 
 with what they have supposed to be the Divine Will, 
 and has, indeed, failed to do so, even when associated 
 with all the powers of worship and discipline. 
 
 While, therefore, it is true that science — science 
 become complete enough to embrace the social and 
 individual life of man — must open up to us the way 
 of peace, it is also true that it can, by itself, do no 
 more than this. It cannot cause men to pursue that 
 way, any more than a mere knowledge of the laws, or 
 conditions, of physical health can cause a glutton or 
 a drunkard, or a sensualist to abandon an immediate 
 
SCIENCE AND THE PROBLEM OF PEACE 69 
 
 and easy gratification, and follow after a difficult and 
 distant good. Up to the present, indeed, it may be 
 said that science — at any rate the science of inorganic 
 nature — ^has been the handmaid of war rather than 
 of peace. From the date of the invention of gun- 
 powder to the date of the invention of the machine- 
 gun and the submarine, the genius of science has been 
 dedicated more to the construction and perfection of 
 instruments of slaughter than to the promotion of 
 pacific aims, as such. Even such scientific creations 
 as might, in themselves, have seemed favourable to 
 human concord^ — the art of printing, the mariner’s 
 compass, the steamship and locomotive, the electric 
 telegraph — are far from having brought peace to 
 mankind, and it is in an age of the greatest scientific 
 development that the world has seen the greatest 
 and most awful of wars. Science in itself, in fact, 
 is like a mercenary soldier. It is the servant of any 
 cause. It is man’s reason, wrought into an instru- 
 ment of high efficiency, but ministering with equal 
 readiness and effect to what is low in him and what 
 is high. It may be the sword of Justice, but it may 
 also be the dagger of the assassin. It nails the thief 
 to the Cross, but side by side with him it places the 
 Saviour. 
 
 Nevertheless, it is by the power of science — the 
 developed and disciplined reason of man, resting upon 
 the sum of human experience, knowing himself, and 
 therefore knowing the world with which he is in 
 relation — that a Human Peace, if there is ever to be a 
 Human Peace, is to be brought about. Our reason 
 
70 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 for saying this is plain. It is true that science, by 
 itself, is not necessarily a force of good. It may be, 
 and often is, a force of evil. But whether it is a force 
 of good or of evil, it is a force. It is as the sun shining 
 on the just and on the unjust, but it is still a sun. 
 Science, whether it ministers to a good purpose or a 
 bad, yet, in proportion to its sureness and develop- 
 ment, accomplishes the aims to which it is directed. 
 If our object is to measure the planets and determine 
 their course, it enables us to do this. The physicist 
 puts steam and electricity into our hands and shows 
 us how to command them. The chemist does not 
 merely indulge in vague speculations about causes 
 and effects, but gives us the hands of Briareus, with 
 which we can work upon the forces of Nature and 
 make them subservient to human arts. The biologist 
 opens up the world of life to us, as far as it can ever be 
 opened up, and enables us to see the structure and 
 activities of living beings, from those of the humblest 
 of microscopic organisms to those of man himself. In 
 a word, in science there is hope, because in science 
 there is light and power. Science knows things and 
 does things. It is, of course, incomplete. Its last 
 word is not yet spoken. It has left problems unsolved 
 and insoluble. It is still face to face with tasks unat- 
 tempted or impossible. But what we actually know 
 we know because of science ; what we have actually 
 done we have done through the power of science ; and 
 what is still unknown and undone we may hope to 
 know and to do through the instrumentality of science 
 — the developed, disciplined reason of man, resting on 
 
SCIENCE AND THE PROBLEM OF PEACE 71 
 
 the sum of his experiences and achievements — -in so 
 far as human capacity extends, The means by 
 which he has unveiled the laws and mastered the forces 
 of what we call “ Nature ” — the world of inorganic 
 matter and of the vegetable and animal kingdoms — 
 are the means by which he may reasonably expect to 
 gain understanding and lordship in the world of his 
 own nature as an individual and social being. The 
 power and methods of mind which have built up the 
 positive sciences from mathematics to biology will 
 also build up the positive sciences of sociology and 
 morals ; the science which, serving the impulses of 
 destruction and slaughter, has given new arms and a 
 new force to war will also, serving the purposes of 
 construction and concord, prepare the way for the 
 victories of peace. 
 
 There are two main means by which it will do this : 
 First, science, become completely human, will, in its 
 application to the question of peace, deliver us from 
 the confusion of mind resulting from the clash of 
 national passions, and from the struggles of classes, 
 sects, and parties within the nation. Science, as 
 such, is international, and it lifts us out of the nar- 
 rowness of any exclusive social interest. Its concern 
 is to discover forces and laws — the real relations of 
 things, in their constancy and recurrence. It is 
 international alike in its temper, its processes, and 
 its results. It is not English, French, German, or 
 Russian. It is human and universal. If, therefore, 
 we study the problem of peace — of a peace world- 
 wide and enduring — according to the disposition and 
 
72 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 methods of science, we are, by that very fact, placed 
 at a point of view which is common to men of every 
 country — in so far as they are scientific ; and any 
 conclusions at which we arrive will have as much an 
 international validity as those of physics and biology. 
 We may put the same truth in a different way by 
 saying that science is essentially Catholic — that it 
 brings to bear on the mind and life of man exactly 
 the same breadth and dispassionateness, the same 
 capacity to lift men out of what is partial and tem- 
 porary into what is universal and eternal, as the 
 Roman Catholic Church would exhibit, if it were 
 completely in fact what it is in principle, a living 
 international spiritual authority. Upon this natural 
 affinity between science and Catholicism we have 
 elsewhere commented.* It is of high importance, 
 and it is nowhere of greater importance than in 
 relation to the problem of peace which we are now 
 discussing. 
 
 In exactly the same way, science, as such — always 
 understanding by this word not merely the pro- 
 visional sciences of external nature, but also the final 
 sciences of human nature, dominating and co-ordinat- 
 ing all others — delivers us from the standpoint of 
 party, sect, and class in the national economy. It is 
 neither “ Conservative ” nor “ Liberal,” neither aris- 
 tocratic nor democratic, neither monarchical nor 
 republican. Its object is to discover — assuming it 
 to be possible to discover — some way of ordering the 
 life of the nation which may bring to bear on it the 
 * “ Catholicism and the Modern Mind,” p. 205. 
 
SCIENCE AND THE PROBLEM OF PEACE 73 
 
 whole high experience of mankind, with a view to its 
 pacific and harmonious advance in future. In the 
 pursuit of this inquiry it does not assume that either 
 what is called “ aristocracy ” or what is called 
 “ democracy ” is, absolutely and exclusively, a right 
 word of social order and progress, or that it represents 
 some final form of national organization. One of its 
 tasks, indeed, is to clarify these terms themselves — to 
 give to them a definite and fixed significance, so that 
 they may become serviceable in scientific reasoning. 
 When this has been done it may be possible to deter- 
 mine how far, for example, what we vaguely call 
 “ democracy ” is in consonance with a sound science 
 of political organization, and how far it may be neces- 
 sary to bring in some other term and a different con- 
 ception of a rightly-directed State. 
 
 The second important service which science will 
 render in relation to the question of peace will be in 
 exhibiting its connection with other great questions 
 of man’s mind and life. If we suppose it to be suc- 
 cessfully carried into the regions of man’s social and 
 moral nature — if, in other words, we place ourselves 
 at the point of view of what may be broadly called a 
 Science of Humanity — then it is clear that we shall 
 survey the whole life of man in the light of a complete 
 synthesis. This synthesis will exhibit to us man, or 
 humanity, as a conscious and self-conscious being, 
 placed in a Universal Order of which he is both a con- 
 stituent and an interpreter, which is external to him 
 and yet contained in him, and which he is able, with- 
 out him and within him, to modify while yet he is 
 
74 the problem OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 dependent upon it. It is clear that from the point 
 of view of this synthesis such a question as the 
 question of peace is in inseparable connection, imme- 
 diate or remote, with a number of other questions 
 presenting themselves for solution. It is evidently 
 in such a connection, for example, with questions of 
 morals or religion, with questions of education, with 
 questions of industry, with questions of class con- 
 flict, with questions of general domestic politics. No 
 fundamental treatment of the problem of peace is, 
 therefore, possible which sets aside and disregards the 
 other great problems of humanity, and treats it as 
 a sort of isolated political problem, to be solved by 
 itself. 
 
 We may say generally, in short, that the question 
 of peace is a part of the supreme, eternal question of 
 the aim of man’s life upon earth. That question, 
 once more, is, intellectually considered, a question of 
 science, but of science in a complete sense, as repre- 
 senting the ordered, ordering reason of man, looking 
 out upon his world, looking in upon himself, and 
 bringing to bear upon humanity the whole of human 
 experience, tested and interpreted according to those 
 methods which have given to us our inheritance of 
 sure and exact truth. It is for science, in this sense, to 
 determine for man his conception of himself, and of 
 the governing aim of his life upon earth. Stating the 
 same truth in other words, we may say that it is for 
 the Modern Mind — the Modern Mind, at any given 
 time, being simply man in his highest and fullest 
 development — to determine what is the nature, place, 
 
SCIENCE AND THE PROBLEM OF PEACE 75 
 
 and destiny of humanity, and to order all human 
 activities with a view to its fulfilment. What, by 
 contradistinction, we may call the ancient mind and 
 the medieval mind could not, and cannot, do this, 
 great as have been their contributions to the sum of 
 truth. Man’s conception of himself is necessarily 
 determined by the totality of his experiences, outer 
 and inner. He cannot dispossess himself of his pos- 
 sessions, or nullify his acquisitions, or unthink his 
 developed thoughts, any more than he can abrogate 
 the sun and moon. His view of the heavens cannot 
 now be what it was in the pre-Copernican period ; his 
 view of the earth cannot be what it was before the 
 discovery of America and Australia ; his indus- 
 trial processes and his modes of locomotion cannot 
 be the same as before his mastery of steam and elec- 
 tricity. 
 
 What is true of the mind of man in relation to what 
 we may call the Natural Order is necessarily true 
 of it also in relation to the Human Order — the 
 order of man’s mind itself and of his social and moral 
 life. Here also his thinking is conditioned by the 
 sum of his experiences. It is conditioned by these 
 great commanding facts, among others — first, that 
 there has grown up, in the ages, a vast body of positive 
 science, inclusive of the whole history of humanity, 
 which helps to determine both the actual contents of 
 the human spirit and its modes of investigating and 
 ascertaining truth ; second, that human industry has 
 developed on an immense scale, both in its processes 
 and in its results, and has come to depend on a world- 
 
76 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 wide and complex co-operation ; third, that as a con- 
 sequence of this industrial development the mass of 
 the workers — what we now call the proletariat — is 
 becoming the predominant class in the social con- 
 sensus, ever rising high and higher in its consciousness 
 and in its aims ; fourth, that all the various nations 
 and races of mankind — Western and Eastern, black, 
 yellow, and white, Christian, Mohammedan, Hindu, 
 Buddhist, Confucian — have at last been brought into 
 a close companionship, so that just as man now looks 
 out and measures the solar system, with its central, 
 unifying force, and looks out and measures the whole 
 of his earth, so he also looks out and measures a 
 single undivided humanity, the various constituents 
 of which, by processes of mind and matter — by science, 
 religion, industry, politics — are ever being brought 
 into a more intimate and organic relationship. 
 
 The mind which enters completely, and with a right 
 power of observation and inference, into all these 
 orders of experience, seeing them in their distinctness 
 and as a whole, and in their organic dependence upon 
 one another — such a mind is a Modern Mind, developed 
 and mature ; the mind which is unable to do this — 
 whether it is the mind of an individual man or of a 
 statesman shaping the policy of a nation, or of an 
 ecclesiastic, giving forth the oracles of a Church — is a 
 mind incomplete and undeveloped, which may repre- 
 sent the view of an exclusive individualism or of an 
 exclusive sect, or of an exclusive class or party, or of 
 an exclusive people, or of an age that is past, but which 
 cannot represent the reason and the needs of a modern 
 
SCIENCE AND THE PROBLEM OF PEACE 77 
 
 humanity, pressing forward, consciously and delibe- 
 rately, to the fulfilment of a foreseen destiny. To 
 such a mind, therefore, we cannot go for a conception 
 of the aim of man’s life on earth — that conception 
 which sheds an indispensable light on the problem of 
 Human Peace. That problem would have presented 
 itself in one way, if present at all, to the ancient mind ; 
 it would have presented itself in another to the 
 medieval mind ; it necessarily presents itself in still 
 another to the Modern Mind. The Modern Mind, 
 holding within itself all the experiences, all the 
 acquisitions, all the culture of mankind, is face to face 
 with a known universe, with a known earth, with a 
 known humanity. It is in reference to these that it 
 shapes, and must shape, its conception of the end of 
 life. It is in reference to these that it determines the 
 meaning of a Human Peace, its desirability, and its 
 possibility ; and it is in virtue of a synthesis of 
 truths and an assemblage of powers which never 
 before existed in the world that it looks to the solution 
 of a problem which has never yet been solved. There 
 is no sure ground of hope in relation to this old 
 problem except in the possession of a new power. 
 This new power now exists, and it is exactly the 
 power which was needed for the solution of the prob- 
 lem. It is the power of completeness — the power of 
 science become synthetic, the power which man has 
 gained from having measured the solar system and 
 measured his earth, and measured humanity, and 
 from having brought these great contents of his 
 experience into a unity. The peace of the earth 
 
78 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 must come, if it is ever to come, from the peace of 
 the directing human soul, illumined by its conception 
 of the Perfect Good ; and this peace of the soul — its 
 right survey of its world and of itself — ^has been pre- 
 pared by thirty centuries of moral expansion, of 
 intellectual development, and of practical sacrifice 
 and achievement. 
 
CHAPTER II 
 
 THE MEANING OF A HUMAN PEACE 
 
 By a “ Human Peace,” as we have seen, we here 
 understand, in general terms, a peace universal and 
 continuous, conceived of as ultimately embracing all 
 the nations of mankind. The office of science in rela- 
 tion to such a peace, is, first, to determine, exactly and 
 practically, what it is that we mean by it ; secondly, to 
 consider how far it may be held to be desirable ; 
 thirdly, to discuss its possibility ; and, lastly, having 
 assumed or shown that it is both desirable and pos- 
 sible, to examine our means for bringing it about and 
 maintaining it. 
 
 The word “ peace ” is, as we all know, used in 
 different senses. To the statesman or diplomatist 
 it has one meaning and to the moralist or religious 
 thinker another ; while it is also a term of industry, 
 of the relations of social classes within the nation, 
 and of the family life. What we are immediately, 
 and in the first instance, concerned with is peace 
 according to the conception of it common among 
 statesmen and diplomatists, although it will after- 
 wards be necessary to consider how far any one of its 
 meanings, in a fundamental discussion of the Human 
 Peace, can rightly be separated from others — how far 
 the peace of the individual human soul, or of the 
 various social classes, or of industrial life, inevitably 
 
8o THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 enters into the question of what, for the purposes of 
 distinction, may be called a diplomatic, or inter- 
 national peace. 
 
 By a diplomatic peace we do not here mean, how- 
 ever, as has already been said, such a peace, good or 
 bad, shorter or longer, as necessarily follows after 
 every war. We mean a permanent peace, in the 
 widest political sense of the word, brought about and 
 maintained by the deliberate policy and co-operation 
 of the various countries of the world. Such a peace 
 would be a Human Peace. We may, on a full con- 
 sideration of it, decide that it is undesirable or 
 impossible, but before we can accept it or reject it we 
 must understand, exactly and practically, what it is. 
 A state of peace — such a peace as statesmen and 
 diplomatists have in view— may be defined, to begin 
 with, in negative terms. It may be said to be con- 
 stituted simply by the absence of war. A state of 
 peace, in this sense, existed in Europe, for example, 
 from 1871 to 1914. With a peace of this kind, how- 
 ever, whatever its character and advantages, we are 
 not now concerned, and this for two reasons : First, 
 this was a peace — like all others which have hitherto 
 existed — following upon a war, and due, not to the 
 avowed intention or policy of a Human Peace, but 
 to the absence of some sufficient immediate cause 
 of conflict ; secondly, it was what is commonly called 
 an “ armed peace ” — a state of things in which almost 
 all the nations of Europe live in the expectation and 
 apprehension of war, and are burdened with the 
 weight of vast naval and military preparations. In 
 
THE MEANING OF A HUMAN PEACE 8i 
 
 such a situation there is, of course, peace in the sense 
 of the mere absence of war. It must be allowed, too, 
 that something at least of the good of peace it secures, 
 and some of the evils of war it avoids. 
 
 But by a Human Peace we do not, once more, mean 
 a peace following, as a sort of unavoidable and tem- 
 porary consequence, upon war, or a peace due merely 
 to the absence of any immediate cause of conflict, or 
 an armed peace, securing, perhaps, something of the 
 good of peace, but characterized also by some of the 
 disadvantages of war ; we mean a peace brought 
 about and upheld by the foresight and consent of the 
 chief nations of mankind — a peace inspired by the 
 common conviction that international concord is a 
 human good, and a good so universal and commanding 
 that its pursuit and maintenance ought properly to 
 control all other objects of policy. From the presence 
 of this common conviction, passing into and directing 
 national action, certain great practical results would 
 necessarily follow. First, it would involve the accept- 
 ance of a given international status quo, such as it 
 might be, as one not to be subject to possible dis- 
 turbance ; secondly, it would bring about a general 
 disarmament ; thirdly, it would carry with it the 
 determination, on the part of the various nations 
 concerned in it, not for themselves, or in their own 
 supposed interest, to prosecute purposes contrary, in 
 their inevitable consequences, to the international 
 good of peace. 
 
 Whether a Human Peace, in this conception of it, 
 is possible we cannot at present determine, but we are 
 
 B.F. 
 
82 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 entitled to say, scientifically speaking, that it is 
 impossible for it ever to be established unless these 
 specific conditions are realized, and realized in their 
 right combination. It is clear, however, that such a 
 realization of them presents difficulties so stupendous 
 that they may naturally seem to be insuperable. Let 
 us take the first of them first. What we are funda- 
 mentally concerned with, of course, is the state of 
 the human mind as it expresses itself in national 
 action. If we are believers in a world-wide peace, in 
 that general conception of it which we have now 
 elucidated, and are desirous of furthering it, we have, 
 to begin with, to bring in such a state of the human 
 mind that the promotion and maintenance of that 
 peace may become the great controlling motive of 
 national policy — a motive so evidently and incon- 
 testably supreme that in comparison with it all other 
 motives, valid and high as they may seem in them- 
 selves, ought to be held subordinate to it. This 
 disposition of the human mind must be brought in, 
 not in one country alone, but in all — or at any rate in 
 all the great, predominant nations. It must be 
 brought in, too, not merely as a beautiful and attrac- 
 tive ideal — a platonic confession of peace as an 
 ultimate good which somehow and at some time is to 
 come to mankind. It must be brought in as a con- 
 tinuing, prevailing condition of thought and will, of 
 such inherent and persisting strength as to be capable 
 of giving a steady direction to national policy, amidst 
 all the disturbing and resisting forces to which it may 
 be^subject. 
 
THE MEANING OF A HUMAN PEACE 83 
 
 Such a state of the human mind has, as we say, to 
 be “ brought in ” or created. We cannot assume that 
 it already exists. We must, from a scientific point 
 of view, assume the contrary. We are, in fact, not left 
 to any mere conjecture or hypothesis in the matter. 
 What the state of the human mind is in regard to 
 peace and war we know from experience — the experi- 
 ence of three thousand years, given in history. Those 
 three thousand years have seen peace following upon 
 war, and war following upon peace, in every age, in 
 every country, savage and civilized, under all religious 
 beliefs — Christian and non-Christian, under all con- 
 ditions of culture and education, amongst all the 
 races of mankind, white, yellow, black, and red, in 
 every state of industry, under every form of military 
 organization, and under every mode of government, 
 imperial, monarchical, republican, aristocratic, and 
 democratic. War has, in fact, been one of the most 
 persistent, or persistently recurrent, of all social 
 phenomena. It has changed in its methods and 
 instruments, but it has remained essentially the same 
 in its processes and results, from the age of bows and 
 arrows — to go no further back — to the age of the 
 machine gun and the submarine. Poets, from the 
 time of Homer to the time of the versifiers of the 
 twentieth century, have sung its praises. The priests 
 of almost every faith have given it sanction and 
 consecration, even when they have not actually 
 caused it. Rulers and peoples alike have applauded 
 it. It has opened up to men the shortest way to 
 honour and ascendency ; and down to the present 
 
84 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 moment those nations which are universally styled 
 the “ Great Powers ” of the world are great precisely 
 because, actually or potentially, they are held to be 
 masters in war. 
 
 It is plain, then, that so far as the life of mankind 
 has proceeded up to the present, there is nothing in 
 human experience to warrant the supposition that 
 the desire for peace, as such — considered simply as 
 the absence of war — is in itself of such a nature and 
 inherent strength in the human mind as to be capable 
 of mastering the motives of war. On the contrary, all 
 history — ancient, medieval, and modern — shows that 
 nothing has ever been so easy as for a Government, 
 whatever its character or purposes, to carry a people 
 into war ; and while there have often been insurrec- 
 tions and revolutions, from one cause or another, 
 there is, perhaps, not a single instance of a nation’s 
 having refused to participate in a war, or even of its 
 having successfully opposed a policy on the part of its 
 rulers which was visibly carrying it towards war. If, 
 therefore, the coming of a Human Peace is dependent, 
 as it is, upon the existence of a deliberate and con- 
 tinuing choice of it, as a supreme, indisputable good, 
 in the mind of man, it is clear that this choice, this 
 controlling disposition and policy of peace, has yet to 
 be created and maintained. Upon this point it is — 
 if we are believers in a Human Peace — of the first 
 importance that we should not deceive ourselves. Our 
 study of the problem to be solved must be, in the 
 strictest sense of the word, scientific. We must see 
 things as they have been, and as they are, if we wish 
 
THE MEANING OF A HUMAN PEACE 85 
 
 to see them as they are to be, or may be. If we are 
 ever to bring in — supposing it to be desirable and 
 possible to bring in — a state of enduring international 
 concord, we must dismiss, as an illusion of meta 
 physical sentiment, the assumption that there is i 
 the human mind some instinctive horror of war, some 
 inherent love of peace, as peace, which in itself is 
 sufficiently strong and constant to preserve us from 
 bloodshed. 
 
 What, in relation to peace and war, history shows 
 us — as it shows us in relation to all the other high 
 interests of man — is that in the human mind there is 
 a constant conflict of motives. Just as, in the moral 
 and social spheres, men alternate between selfishness 
 and unselfishness, between love and hatred, between 
 passion and purity, between temperance and excess, 
 between energy and indolence, between the desire for 
 knowledge and the disinclination to sustained mental 
 effort, so in the sphere of international policy — ^in so 
 far as this can be separated from the other spheres 
 of man’s reason and will — they alternate between the 
 motives which carry them into war and the motives 
 which would maintain them in peace. If history 
 shows us war as a persistent or persistently recurrent 
 phenomenon, it shows us also that — from the ages ' 
 of the Old Testament, Homer, and Virgil, down to the 
 present time — peace, considered simply as external 
 concord, as the absence of strife and bloodshed, has 
 always been a human ideal. The spiritual problem 
 of man — as a conscious and self-conscious being, 
 exercising his mind and will upon himself, and 
 
86 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 deliberately shaping his action, amidst the play of 
 external and internal forces, for the attainment of 
 certain foreseen ends — consists precisely in this con- 
 flict of motives. In its absence there would be no 
 such problem. It is for this reason that, as we have 
 seen, there can be no fundamental discussion of a 
 Human Peace — as distinguished from the merely 
 diplomatic peace that inevitably follows after every 
 war — which does not connect it with the problem of 
 the commanding, co-ordinating aims of man’s life 
 upon earth. What we have to determine is whether 
 it is possible to so change the human mind as it 
 enters into national policy — or to so alter the balance 
 of its characteristic forces — that peace, which has 
 always been one of its ideals, may become a command- 
 ing, practical purpose, strong and constant enough to 
 impose a uniform direction upon international action. 
 
 This problem, once more, is a scientific problem. 
 It is for science, in the high and complete sense — the 
 right reason of developed man, resting upon the sum 
 of his experiences and exactly representing to himself 
 the forces of Nature and human nature — to unfold 
 to us its true character, and to point us to such a 
 solution of it as is possible. Now, the disposition of 
 human nature, in relation to peace and war, being 
 given in history, it is, as we have seen, scientifically 
 certain that a universal peace will never be estab- 
 lished unless we can secure either a new and more 
 efficacious action of the forces which have hitherto 
 made for peace, or bring in the operation of some new 
 force, surer and more potent than any which has 
 
THE MEANING OF A HUMAN PEACE 87 
 
 worked in the past. If we are to have a new hope, 
 grounded on reason, it must be based on our posses- 
 sion of a new power — either the surer exercise of one 
 which has always existed or the fresh controlling 
 energy of a new one. On the more effective action 
 of an old force, just as it was or is, we cannot, scien- 
 tifically speaking, count. What has constantly failed 
 before we may reasonably expect to fail again. On 
 the other hand, what has succeeded before we may 
 expect to succeed again. The thing which has, in 
 human experience, succeeded is science, in its various 
 degrees. It hits the mark. It accomplishes its aims, 
 whether they are, morally considered, good or bad. 
 It is, therefore, science that must open up to us the 
 way of peace, if such a way there is. Science, of 
 course, is not a wholly new thing. It is a thing of 
 slow growth and development. It is, however, in 
 this sense new, that, in its full synthetic, modern 
 form, it gives to us a measure of man, and of the 
 universe in relation to man, such as belongs properly 
 to our own age and has belonged to no other. It is 
 from science, in this complete conception of it, that 
 we may gain the power of a Human Peace. 
 
 Now the question of peace is, once more, a question 
 of the mind of man as it passes into national and 
 international action. A nation is made up of cities 
 and families, and, from another point of view, it is 
 composed of different social classes, and sometimes 
 of different races. When, for our present purposes, 
 we use the word “ nation ” we must be understood as 
 employing it to denote a distinct political aggregate. 
 
88 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 a sovereign State, occupying its own territory, and 
 possessing an independent co-ordinating Government. 
 We do not use it, as it is often sentimentally and 
 inaccurately used, to describe, for example, such 
 lapsed or subordinate nationalities as Scotland, 
 Ireland, and Wales, which, for political purposes, 
 and especially for international purposes, have long 
 been absorbed into the dominant nationality, “ Eng- 
 land,” or into the composite nationality, “ United 
 Kingdom.” 
 
 The question with which we are occupied is the 
 question of bringing in such a state of the human 
 mind, as it passes into national action, that the 
 predominant countries of the world may concur in 
 promoting and maintaining a Human Peace as a 
 supreme good for mankind, and concur in it, first, by 
 accepting a definite international status quo as one 
 not to be subject to forcible disturbance ; secondly, 
 by a common disarmament ; thirdly, by refraining 
 from the adoption of such national action, whatever 
 its apparent justification, as would tend to bring 
 about war, and by the consistent adoption of a policy 
 of peace. It is, however, not by the fulfilment of 
 any one of these conditions alone, but by the fulfil- 
 ment of them all, in a right combination, that the 
 Human Peace can be constituted. Even if we 
 suppose such a change in the mind of man to have 
 been wrought that the desire for peace — the dis- 
 inclination to conflict and bloodshed — has become 
 stronger than the desire for war, still it will be neces- 
 sary for such a change to take practical effect at some 
 
THE MEANING OF A HUMAN PEACE 89 
 
 given moment, and in some given international 
 situation. By a Human Peace we do not mean an 
 ideal peace, in the sense of such territorial and political 
 arrangements among the various nations of the 
 world as would be absolutely and finally satisfactory 
 to them aU. For the purposes of a Human Peace 
 we must, to begin with, if the paradox is permissible, 
 be satisfied with something unsatisfactory. We must 
 move towards a higher state by way of a lower. The 
 Human Peace, in other words, must be based on the 
 common acceptance of the principle that the main- 
 tenance of a given status quo, evil as in certain 
 respects it may be, is not so great an evil as would 
 be its disturbance by war — or, stating the same 
 principle differently, that the general good to be 
 derived from the preservation of international peace 
 is greater than any particular good to be gained by 
 war. It may conceivably be impossible to bring 
 about an international acceptance of this principle, 
 and the adoption of the practical measures and 
 policy involved in it. What is certain, however, is 
 that so long as this is impossible a Human Peace is 
 impossible, and that we can have at best such a 
 peace, longer or shorter, as inevitably follows upon 
 a war, and is due, not to the rise of a new foresight 
 and will in the human mind, but to the old, recurrent 
 processes of victory and defeat. 
 
 The acceptance of this principle — the decision to 
 base the Human Peace on some specific status quo — 
 would be, in certain respects, as is obvious, only an 
 application to the international order of mankind of 
 
90 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 opinions which have long been acknowledged and 
 operative within the limits of the national order. 
 There is, throughout the civilized world, a general 
 agreement that the continuous preservation of domes- 
 tic peace — in the limited sense of the mere avoidance 
 of physical strife and bloodshed — is a great good. 
 We all hold it to be for the common advantage that 
 causes of personal dispute should be decided by courts 
 of justice rather than by private encounters, and that 
 our political and industrial conflicts should take the 
 form of continual controversy and of appeals to the 
 electors rather than of civil war. This does not mean 
 that we necessarily consider that the national order, 
 as it exists at any given moment, is a perfect order. 
 It does not mean, even, that we believe that absolute 
 justice is always represented by the decisions of a 
 judge, or that the struggle of classes, sects, and 
 parties in the national economy is the wisest con- 
 ceivable way of bringing about political changes. As 
 a matter of fact, we know that, within what may be 
 called the national peace, there exists every evil which 
 afflicts mankind, except the one evil of war itself, 
 considered simply as a process of physical conflict and 
 bloodshed. Peace, as it prevails within the nation, 
 does not represent a high ideal. It stands merely for 
 a certain ordered outward calm — for the absence of 
 such a chronic unsettlement and violent disturbance 
 as would make the conduct of life impossible. Duelling 
 in England and some other countries has now fallen 
 into desuetude, and its discontinuance has always 
 been considered to be a social good. No one would 
 
THE MEANING OF A HUMAN PEACE 91 
 
 say, however, that the causes which once provoked 
 duelling — ill-temper, quarrels, slanders, jealousy, per- 
 sonal affront, and the like — are no longer operative, 
 or even that they are necessarily less operative than 
 before. All that has happened, in this particular 
 connection, is that men have ceased to seek satis- 
 faction for wounded honour or reputation in a 
 physical encounter, and that in the case of serious 
 injuries they now look for redress to the law courts. 
 
 When, however, we say that the establishment of a 
 Human Peace would involve the application to the 
 international order of principles which are already 
 operative within the national order, it is necessary to 
 bear in mind two important considerations. In the 
 first place, we must recognize that the preservation 
 of domestic peace itself — in so far as it is maintained 
 by the temporal power of government, as distinguished 
 from the spiritual power of feeling and opinion — is 
 dependent, in the last resort, upon the use of exactly 
 the same means as are employed in a war of nations. 
 It is dependent upon the use of the police and, in 
 certain cases, of the military. Behind the statutes of 
 a Parliament, or the decisions of a judge, there is 
 always the armed force of the State, and to this 
 force, as it is hardly necessary to say, an appeal has 
 often to be made — as, for instance, in the case of 
 criminals resisting capture. Again, it sometimes 
 happens that the conflict of classes and parties within 
 the nation becomes so intense as to break down the 
 whole system of domestic order and to take the form 
 of civil war. Even in a country like England, which 
 
92 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 has a longer experience of “ constitutional ” and 
 “ democratic ” methods than any other, there has 
 recently, as we all know, on more than one occasion 
 been a near approach to this state of things. Under 
 such circumstances a Government — ^which is not only, 
 within the political sphere, a co-ordinating authority, 
 organizing the national consensus, but also an enforc- 
 ing authority, concerned to make the will of the 
 social whole prevail against the will of its resistant 
 parts — is bound to act, within the national sphere, in 
 proportion as the need arises, precisely as it would 
 have to act in a war against a hostile nation. In 
 other words, the internal peace of the nation — in so 
 far as it rests on a purely governmental or temporal 
 foundation — depends ultimately upon processes of 
 war, potential or actual, ranging from those by which 
 an ordinary criminal is arrested and made amenable 
 to the law to those needed for the suppression of some 
 dangerous industrial disorder, or for victory in some 
 actual civil strife. When a given Government ceases 
 to be capable of discharging these functions — ^when it 
 no longer represents the national consensus and wields 
 the predominant national force — it has to give way 
 to a new Government, and there is, in one form or 
 another, a revolution. 
 
 In the second place, it is necessary to bear in mind, 
 what by advocates of peace is often forgotten, that 
 the international order — the permanent pacific rela- 
 tions of the various countries of the world — is, by its 
 inherent character, different from the national order, 
 and that this difference between them cannot, by the 
 
THE MEANING OF A HUMAN PEACE 93 
 
 nature of things, be abrogated. A nation, as we have 
 here defined it, is an independent social unity, with 
 its own territorial situation, and its own Government, 
 acting, within the sphere of practical politics, as the 
 organ of a consensus and as a co-ordinating and 
 enforcing authority. It is free and sovereign. To 
 use a single, simple word, the nation is an order 
 dependent internally upon law — upon a body of per- 
 manent social agreements, implicit and explicit, with 
 recognized instruments of interpretation and applica- 
 tion. The international order, in so far as it exists, 
 rests on a different foundation. It is true that we 
 are accustomed to use the expression “ international 
 law,” and that many elaborate treatises have been 
 written upon the subject. There is, however, in 
 reality, no such thing. It is a metaphysical figment. 
 Where there is no Government, no recognized co- 
 ordinating and enforcing authority, there is, for 
 practical purposes, no law. We could only have inter- 
 national law if we had an international Government ; 
 and international government— to say nothing of 
 its practical impossibility — is incompatible with the 
 principle of nationality itself. It is a contradiction 
 in terms. 
 
 In the absence of law, in the strict sense, inter- 
 national relations rest on custom, usage, human good- 
 will, intellectual community, reciprocal convenience, 
 industrial advantage, and a number of specific con- 
 ventions and treaties, more or less permanent. These 
 conventions and treaties, however, have, for practical 
 purposes, exactly the validity and duration which 
 
94 the problem OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 are voluntarily given to them by the various countries 
 entering into them. A nation is, within the limits of 
 its actual force, a law unto itself. It may refuse to 
 have any relations whatever with other countries. It 
 may decline to admit within its own borders either 
 their inhabitants or their commodities, or to admit 
 them except under certain specific conditions and 
 restrictions. This, as it is hardly necessary to say, is 
 a right which is actually at the present time main- 
 tained and exercised, in varying degree, by every 
 civilized nation in the world. In many of them it 
 has, of late years, been exercised in an increasing 
 degree. A nation, so long as it preserves a real 
 independence and is free and sovereign, may have its 
 own language, its own religion, its own moral code, 
 its own political institutions, its own social customs, 
 just as it has its own territory and its own physical 
 characteristics. If it ceases, in whatever degree, to 
 maintain its freedom, it may, of course, have the 
 ideas and customs of some other country — within 
 certain limits at least— imposed upon it ; but this 
 simply means that it has then lost, to that extent, its 
 independence, and become subject to an enforcing 
 authority other than its own. In other words, it is 
 no longer a nation. 
 
 These, undoubtedly, are elementary considerations, 
 but it is none the less indispensable to recall them for 
 the purposes of anything that may deserve to be 
 called a scientific study of the Human Peace. It is 
 the more necessary to do this because some advocates 
 of peace at the present time overlook this funda- 
 
THE MEANING OF A HUMAN PEACE 95 
 
 mental distinction between the national order and the 
 international order, and speak as if peace could 
 somehow be brought about by an indefinite exten- 
 sion of law and government, in the true senses of 
 these words, throughout the world, or as if the 
 expression “ international law ” represented a prac- 
 tical, administrative reality, instead of being, what it 
 is, an illusory phrase of metaphysic. Even within 
 the national order — the sphere of law, in the strict 
 sense — the power of government, its capacity to act 
 as an enforcing authority, is, as we have seen, depen- 
 dent upon its continuing to represent an active and 
 predominant consensus ; and at a given moment, in 
 given states of the public mind, it may lose that 
 power. In such circumstances law, which is a sort 
 of indirect, pacific, and symbolic expression of force, 
 ceases to be operative, and there is a direct appeal to 
 the arbitrament of war. In the international order, 
 where the range and variety of conditions and in- 
 terests is vastly greater than in any single country — 
 where numberless differences of climate, situation, 
 proximity, race, language, religion, morals, political 
 traditions and institutions, social customs, and indus- 
 trial development have all to be taken into account — - 
 it is clear that the difficulty of securing anything like 
 a permanent, active consensus, with a common co- 
 ordinating and enforcing authority, is so great as to 
 be insuperable. 
 
 The problem of the Human Peace, then, is, in the 
 strict sense of the word, an international problem. 
 It is the problem of securing continuous agreement 
 
96 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 and co-operation in the absence of an enforcing 
 authority, among a number of independent nation- 
 alities, each remaining free and sovereign, this agree- 
 ment and co-operation being directed to specific and 
 limited practical ends. It is, in other terms, the 
 problem of maintaining a certain state of the human 
 mind, in feeling, opinion, intention, and will, as that 
 mind enters into national action and governs inter- 
 national relations. Further, the purpose of peace, 
 taking shape as an ordering policy, must, as we have 
 seen, proceed by the acceptance of a given status quo, 
 good or bad, just as the maintenance of domestic 
 peace rests on the acceptance of an internal status quo, 
 not because it is in itself considered to be ideally 
 good, but because its evils are less than would be the 
 evil of its forcible disruption, or are evils which 
 would not be remedied by such a disruption. But, 
 for the installation of the Human Peace, this accept- 
 ance must carry with it a consequence of common and 
 voluntary disarmament, by land and sea. In the 
 absence of such an agreement this disarmament 
 would, of course, be inconceivable, but, conversely, 
 in the absence of the disarmament the agreement 
 would be unreal and have no effect. The disarmament 
 must, in fact, be regarded both as an indispensable 
 sign and proof of the agreement, and as a consequence 
 following from it of almost infinite practical import- 
 ance. This is self-evident, but it becomes increas- 
 ingly clear in proportion as we consider the question 
 of the good of peace — the motives and aims which 
 may conceivably, in the present stage of human 
 
THE MEANING OF A HUMAN PEACE 97 
 
 development, lead to its international establishment 
 and maintenance. 
 
 But the establishment and maintenance of a 
 Human Peace demands something more even than 
 the conditions which we have already specified — 
 first, a change in the human mind by which the 
 motives of peace dispossess the motives of war ; and, 
 secondly, such a consequent acceptance of a given 
 status quo that disarmament may follow from it : 
 it demands also that national policy be brought per- 
 manently under the control of these conceptions — 
 that the predominant nations of mankind, especially, 
 concur in so ordering their action as to make it sub- 
 servient to the common concord. It is not, perhaps, 
 impossible to conceive of the chief European and non- 
 European States as coming, at a given moment, under 
 the impulse of a high and disinterested choice of 
 peace, to some understanding favourable to its pro- 
 motion, and as adopting certain consequent measures 
 of disarmament. Even, however, so great a change 
 as this in disposition and policy would not by itself 
 suffice to maintain peace, although it might be sup- 
 posed sufficient to institute it. So long as what we 
 now call nationality exists in the world — a number 
 of independent sovereign States, living and expanding 
 — it will be necessary for those States, if peace is to 
 be preserved, to make its preservation a deter- 
 mining purpose of policy, rather than the satisfaction 
 of their own exclusive aims. It is obvious that 
 relations between human beings, few or many, which 
 proceed from the growth of a certain reciprocal state of 
 
98 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 mind, are dependent for their continuance on the con- 
 tinuance of that state of mind. A man and woman 
 entering into marriage commonly carry into it a dis- 
 position of community and co-operation, but it is a 
 matter of ordinary experience that this disposition 
 sometimes breaks down, and gives place to fatal 
 estrangement and antagonism. In the same way, the 
 various races, classes, parties, and sects composing 
 the peace of a nation may for hundreds of years live 
 and work together in an orderly citizenship, and yet 
 at the end of that time they may be involved in civil 
 war. 
 
 It is clear, therefore, that even international dis- 
 armament, brought about by the common adoption 
 of a policy of peace, and following upon the acceptance 
 of a given status quo, would not, by itself, be a 
 guarantee of a Human Peace, a peace universal and 
 continuous. War, as we all know, existed before the 
 rise of standing armies and conscription, and might 
 conceivably break out again even if all the military 
 and naval establishments of the world were abolished 
 to-morrow. A nation does not cease to be, in a 
 military sense, “ great ” simply because it is unarmed. 
 It is great, in this sense, by its numbers, its territory, 
 its natural resources, its physical situation and inde- 
 pendence, its industry, its temper and intelligence, 
 its place in the scale of civilization. If all the coun- 
 tries of the world were suddenly placed, in regard to 
 arms, on a footing of equality, this would neither 
 make them equal in power, nor would it necessarily 
 prevent a powerful country from entertaining and 
 
THE MEANING OF A HUMAN PEACE 99 
 
 prosecuting hostile designs against its neighbours. 
 Nothing is so easy as for a strong man or a strong 
 people to procure weapons, of whatever kind, with 
 which to prosecute a quarrel. We cannot have a 
 greater security for international peace than we 
 already have for peace within the internal economy 
 of a nation ; and, as we have already said, and as a 
 quite recent experience in England has shown, such 
 a peace itself may, in the clash of social classes or 
 political interests, be in danger of giving way to 
 civil war. 
 
 We come, then, to this conclusion, that a Human 
 Peace, such as we are here considering, can, if it is 
 ever to be possible, only become possible under 
 certain conditions. It demands, first, that at a 
 given moment the purposes of such a peace should, 
 in the predominant nations of mankind, displace and 
 supersede the motives of war ; secondly, that their 
 common adoption of a policy of peace should take 
 effect by the acceptance of a given international 
 status quo, whatever its character, as one not to be 
 subject to a forcible disturbance ; thirdly, that this 
 acceptance should, as a necessary practical conse- 
 quence, carry with it a general disarmament ; lastly, 
 that the state of the human mind, relatively to 
 national action, which has led to the establishment 
 of the Human Peace should be afterwards main- 
 tained, so that every nation may continue to order its 
 own life, external and internal, with a view to securing 
 the persistence of international concord. A Human 
 Peace, so conceived, may seem to us a thing impos- 
 
100 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 sible, or a thing so remote and contingent, that we 
 ought, for the present at least, to dismiss it from our 
 minds as a dream or Utopian ideal. In that case we 
 must content ourselves for an indefinite future with 
 what we have had throughout the past — a given 
 peace, shorter or longer, following after a given war, 
 and due, not to any high intention and prescience of 
 international concord, but to processes of victory and 
 defeat in the conflict of arms. We are here, however, 
 proceeding on the assumption that a Human Peace, 
 difficult as it may be of attainment, is yet not impos- 
 sible ; and we are proceeding upon this assumption 
 because, in our modern world, man has at last gained a 
 new power and a new hope — the power and the hope 
 of science become developed and complete, showing 
 him himself, his situation, his strength, his limitations, 
 the nature and greatness of his aims upon earth, and 
 the capacity which he naturally possesses to so con- 
 sciously order and direct himself as to give to these 
 aims unity and persistence. Whether this assumption 
 will prove to be justifiable, not prophecy, but experi- 
 ence alone, can determine. 
 
CHAPTER III 
 
 THE GOOD OF A HUMAN PEACE 
 
 The problem of bringing about and maintaining a 
 Human Peace turns, as we have seen, in the first 
 instance, on the fundamental question of whether it is 
 possible to so change the mind of man, as it enters into 
 national action, that such a peace may seem to it, and 
 continue to seem, a supreme good which ought, by its 
 own nature, to control and direct that action. Now, 
 this question is one which is evidently in a high degree 
 intricate and far-reaching. Whether a Human Peace 
 would be a human good — so great a good as to be 
 entitled to give order and purpose to the life of man- 
 kind — this, of course, cannot be determined by any 
 individual mind, occupied with a vision, or ideal, of 
 social perfection ; it must be determined by the mind 
 of humanity, in its fullest extent. An individual 
 mind may be, or may suppose itself to be, prophetic. 
 It may be the mind of a dreamer of dreams. What 
 we are now concerned with, however, is the science 
 of things ; and although the science of things — the 
 science especially of the mind and life of humanity — 
 must certainly take account of dreams and prophecies, 
 it recognizes that they only acquire a practical 
 importance in proportion as they pass into the life 
 of man and keep their place there. 
 
 Consequently, the problem to be solved is not 
 
102 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 whether the conception of peace as a supreme good can 
 be made the conception of a particular religious sect or 
 a school of thought, but whether it can be so fixed in 
 the mind of man as to become an overmastering 
 motive of national policy. This question, we say, 
 calls for a certain limitation. It is, in its full extent, 
 too complex, too vast, for treatment here. By the 
 mind of man,” in this connection, we mean the 
 mind of humanity, since it is all the nations of the 
 world — Western and Eastern, Christian and non- 
 Christian, civilized and uncivilized — that are ulti- 
 mately concerned in a Human Peace, and since, 
 indeed, unless they are all in some way brought into 
 it, it cannot exist at all. We may, however, for 
 both scientific and practical purposes, simplify the 
 problem, to begin with, by drawing the obvious dis- 
 tinction between those nations which constitute what 
 we call “ The West ” and those which lie outside it. 
 This distinction, broadly speaking, is equivalent to 
 the distinction between Christendom and non-Christen- 
 dom. It is true that Russia and some other Christian 
 countries are not, properly considered. Western, and 
 this is a fact of great social and political importance, 
 since into many of the dominant interests and tra- 
 ditions of Western Europe Russia, for example, has 
 scarcely entered. Allowing, however, as it is essen- 
 tial to allow, for this fact, we may, for the sake of 
 scientific precision and convenience, use the term 
 “ The West ” as if it were equivalent to Christendom. 
 The amount of correction which such an assumption 
 needs it will not be difficult afterwards to supply. It 
 
THE GOOD OF A HUMAN PEACE 103 
 
 might conceivably be such an amount as would make 
 it necessary, for certain specific practical purposes, 
 to consider Russia as lying wholly outside the 
 Western order. 
 
 Our problem, then, is, in the first place, to bring 
 into the “ mind of man ” — that is, into the mind of the 
 West, or Christendom, including Russia — a concep- 
 tion of peace, as a supreme international good, such 
 that all external national action must be considered 
 subservient to its promotion and maintenance. If 
 this is possible, a Human Peace is possible ; if it is 
 not, then the attainment of such a peace, if it is ever 
 to be attained, must be held to belong to some remote, 
 indefinite future, for which, in the present, we can 
 only prepare. Our reason for saying this is a reason 
 of science — a plain reason of history and experience. 
 If we place ourselves at the point of view of military 
 force and ascendency — and where questions of peace 
 and war are concerned such a standpoint is naturally 
 predominant — it is clear that, in the relations of 
 West and East, the West, or Christendom, has pre- 
 vailed, and the East, or non-Christendom, has suc- 
 cumbed. In Asia, in Africa, in America, in Aus- 
 tralasia, Christendom — using this expression for the 
 moment rather as an expression of political or social 
 than of religious distinction — has, in its encounter 
 with non-Christendom, conquered. In other terms, 
 the higher civilization has prevailed against the 
 lower, or against barbarism. We are not now, of, 
 course, discussing the ethics, or wisdom, which has 
 entered into the action of the developed nations of 
 
104 the problem of HUMAN PEACE 
 
 the world— of the West, or Christendom — upon the 
 undeveloped. That is an independent question. We 
 are simply ascertaining the facts of history ; and 
 history shows us that the fuller and higher develop- 
 ment has, in the field of force, mastered the lower. 
 The most conspicuous example of this, as is obvious, 
 ■is the rule of the English in India, where three hundred 
 millions of persons, in a vast continent, are held 
 subject by a small number of aliens, coming from 
 an island in the West. The result of the Russo- 
 Japanese war may be said to be an example to the 
 contrary. First, however, it must be admitted that 
 it is too soon to base any permanent conclusions on 
 what may have been an exceptional event ; secondly, 
 Russia, although, from a certain point of view, we 
 have to include her in the West, is yet not, in any 
 high sense. Western. The final issue of the Crusades, 
 again, may be said to represent a failure of the West 
 as against the East, but the Crusades were the action 
 of a Europe still only incompletely developed, and 
 certainly not completely united. 
 
 If, further, we place ourselves at the point of view 
 of culture and progress — a point of view which is 
 also essential in our argument—it is not less clear 
 that the West, in the broad sense, as compared with 
 the East, is the power predominant and victorious in 
 the sphere of mind, as in the sphere of arms. In 
 religion, in art, in literature, in science, in industry, 
 in social and civic organization, the West, Christen- 
 dom — allowing for unimportant exceptions — teaches 
 and leads ; the East follows and learns. The West 
 
THE GOOD OF A HUMAN PEACE 105 
 
 is in fact, developed humanity, carrying the East 
 itself in its expanding consciousness and vitality ; 
 the East, the non-European, the non-Christian, is 
 humanity in an arrested development, waiting for 
 some quickening, directing, co-ordinating force from 
 without to lift it into the high plane of the world’s 
 movement. 
 
 Whether, therefore, we place ourselves at the point 
 of view of the temporal power or the spiritual — at the 
 point of view of military force, or at that of the force 
 of mind which ultimately governs and directs it — ^we 
 come to the same conclusion : the peace of the world, 
 the Human Peace, if there is ever to be such a peace, 
 must proceed, in the first instance, from the concord 
 of the West — from the order of nations constituting 
 Christendom, or Christian civilization. It is there 
 that that change in the mind of man is first to be 
 wrought — assuming it to be possible to effect it — 
 which is the essential condition precedent of this 
 peace. If we assume it to be so wrought — if we 
 assume the predominant Powers of the West to have 
 reached a static concurrence and co-operation in 
 regard to a Human Peace, then they will have no 
 serious difficulty in permanently imposing peace on 
 the world, supposing it to be ever challenged, beyond 
 the sphere of their governing authority. They can 
 impose it and maintain it both by the force of arms 
 and the force of mind. The problem of a Human 
 Peace, then, is essentially a problem of Christendom, 
 or the West. 
 
 We are, consequently, in the first instance, con- 
 
io6 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 cerned with the mind of man as it passes into national 
 action within the limits of the West. Within those 
 limits themselves, however, it is obvious that we are 
 only called upon — at any rate to begin with — to 
 consider the case of those countries which we call 
 the Great Powers. They represent both the mind 
 of the West and its predominant force. If they were 
 actually, in intention and practice, concordant in 
 regard to peace — concordant, that is to say, in recog- 
 nizing and accepting those essential conditions of 
 peace which we have specified — then the peace of the 
 West, and therefore the peace of the world, would be 
 secured. Now, the mind of man, as it passes into 
 national action in Western Europe — and in the 
 Great Powers of Western Europe especially — is not, 
 of course, a mind wholly separate and different 
 from what we find it to be elsewhere. It is in 
 West and East, in Christendom and non-Christen- 
 dom, fundamentally the same mind, only differing in 
 situation, in power, in the range and complexity of 
 its interests, in development. In the West, as in the 
 East, for example, man is moved by certain primary 
 persisting instincts — amongst others, the instinct of 
 nutrition, the instinct of sex, the instincts of destruc- 
 tion and combat. These instincts, indeed, are not 
 human only — they are animal ; but they are found 
 at work in the lowest barbarism as in the highest 
 civilization, in the most ignorant and undeveloped 
 man as in the master of religion and science. They 
 are part of the common stock of a universal human 
 nature. 
 
THE GOOD OF A HUMAN PEACE 107 
 
 When we are considering the possibility of bringing 
 in not a politician’s peace, wrought as a temporary 
 interlude, in war and confusion, but a Human Peace, 
 accomplished by the concurrent powers of the mind 
 of man in the exercise of its lordship over itself, 
 then we are bound to take these primary governing 
 instincts into account. Whether such a peace will 
 seem desirable and possible will depend partly — 
 although certainly not exclusively — upon the opera- 
 tion of these instincts, and upon the degree in which 
 they can be brought under the control of other forces 
 of human nature. We cannot, scientifically, discuss 
 the “ good of peace ” as if peace — the mere absence of 
 physical conflict and bloodshed — were an absolute 
 and unrelated thing. We must, from the standpoint 
 of science, seeing things as they are, when we speak 
 of the good of peace, recognize that in a given temper 
 or in a given situation, or from a given point of view, 
 war may seem the greater good. That there is in 
 human nature an instinct for destruction and a joy 
 in combat hardly needs to be demonstrated. All 
 history shows these forces at work. They are such 
 that when men have not actually been at war their 
 greatest delight has been in the shows and pastimes of 
 war. Games of war, poems of war, the music of war, 
 pictures of war, romances of war, have been the joy of 
 every age of man and every order of society, from the 
 time of Homer, or of the Roman gladiatorial en- 
 counters, or of the medieval tournament, down to the 
 time of the Spanish bull-fight or the modern English 
 boxing arena. At the present day, after nineteen 
 
io8 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 centuries of Christianity, quite the easiest thing a 
 statesman can do is either to plunge a nation into 
 war, or to prevail upon it to load itself with a vast 
 and continuous preparation for war. A change in 
 domestic policy commonly requires many years of 
 controversy and agitation to bring it about ; a war 
 between two great countries, whatever its immediate 
 pretexts may be, is resolved upon almost without 
 consideration or discussion. Conscription — under 
 which every man becomes liable to lose his life for a 
 cause of which few are able to judge, and to which 
 he commonly gives less attention than he would 
 bestow upon the purchase of a suit of clothes — belongs 
 to the age of the “ democracy,” the last hundred 
 years, and was the immediate outcome of the French 
 Revolution. 
 
 In so far, then, as men are mastered by this in- 
 stinct for destruction and this joy in combat, latent 
 or vigorously active, war, as war — an occasion or 
 theatre of military glory — will seem to them the 
 greater good, and peace, which demands the sup- 
 pression of these propensities, the smaller good, even 
 if a good at all. There is, in fact, nothing to which 
 religion has always been so ready to give its conse- 
 cration, and which the civic spirit has been so eager 
 to applaud, as mastery in war, and this quite irre- 
 spectively of the causes for which it has been waged. 
 The mind of man, however, although it contains these 
 military instincts, as they may perhaps be called, is 
 also worked upon by other forces. It is, for example, 
 moved by the instincts of nutrition and sex, and by 
 
THE GOOD OF A HUMAN PEACE 109 
 
 the nged for clothing, habitation, heat, and light, as 
 well as by those higher needs which enter into our 
 Western civilization — the needs of religion, affection, 
 domestic and civic life, art, literature, and science. 
 The question of whether peace or war is the greater 
 good is not, once more, an absolute question ; it is 
 a question relative to the greater or less ascendency 
 of any of these motives, or interests, in the complex, 
 continuous human mind, as that mind enters into 
 national action. If war is, or is supposed to be, sub- 
 servient to some need which, in a given situation, 
 is predominant, then war becomes the chief good 
 and peace a hindrance. On the other hand, if peace 
 appears to promise satisfaction to some controlling 
 purpose, peace, in its turn, becomes the good. 
 
 We are not now, of course, occupied with a merely 
 historic or archaeological problem. History is, for 
 our present purpose, only important because it is the 
 book of human nature, exhibiting it to us in its 
 persistent, developing forces. We need not, there- 
 fore, consider how far the various wars of the world, 
 ancient and modern, have, each in its turn, sprung 
 from the operation of particular instincts. What we 
 are concerned with is the present and the future — 
 the possibility, in the first place, of bringing the policy 
 of the chief Western nations, they being what they 
 are, under the control of motives making for peace. 
 Now, the social composition, or structure, of all 
 these nations — including, for our present purpose and 
 for the time being Russia — is essentially similar. It 
 is a composition which represents, in varying degrees, 
 
no THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 the governing propensities and aims of the human 
 mind, lower and higher, from the instincts of nutri- 
 tion, sex, and combat to the noblest purposes of 
 social, civic, intellectual, and religious life. The 
 working classes and employees of whatever kind ; 
 the capitalist classes — landowners, agriculturists, 
 manufacturers, merchants, shopkeepers, bankers, ship- 
 owners, and railway proprietors ; the military class, 
 including the police ; the intellectual classes — artists, 
 men of letters, scientists, teachers, lawyers, doctors, 
 and religious ministers — these, being agents and 
 functionaries of the social economy, are also instru- 
 ments of the human mind, as it aims at the satis- 
 faction of its own distinctive needs, or the needs of 
 the body. It is out of these co-operating classes and 
 functionaries, with women as the chief organs of 
 domestic life, that the national order is built up as a 
 developing vitality. In the political sphere its co- 
 ordinating and regulating authority is the Govern- 
 ment, strictly so-called ; in the industrial sphere it 
 is, at present, the capitalist ” ; in the spiritual 
 sphere it is the Church. As need hardly be pointed 
 out, however, each of these main authorities is, in 
 practice, supplemented by other agencies. 
 
 Beneath them all, and in them all, works what we 
 have called the “ mind of man ” — our common intel- 
 lectual nature. There is, of course, not one nature 
 of the capitalist classes and another of the working 
 classes, or one nature of “ the Church ” and another 
 of “ the State.” This is a truth elementary to the 
 point of being a truism, but as it is commonly over- 
 
THE GOOD OF A HUMAN PEACE in 
 
 looked in religious and political discussion it is neces- 
 sary to reaffirm it. The difference between one social 
 class and another is a difference of situation, interest, 
 function, degree, and development ; it is not a funda- 
 mental difference of human nature. This principle 
 is for our present purpose important ; because our 
 present purpose is to consider whether, among the 
 various motives working in human nature as it passes 
 into national action, it is possible for the motives 
 which make for peace to gain, and maintain, pre- 
 dominance. That this is not a mere question of 
 classes it is easy to show, although the question of 
 classes may be, on other grounds, one which it is 
 necessary to take into account. There is, for example, 
 in all the nations of Western Europe, among other 
 classes, a permanent military class — a body of men 
 whose special business it is to protect the country 
 against its foes, and to wage war when this becomes 
 desirable or inevitable. We may, if we please, say 
 that this class represents the military instincts — to 
 say nothing, for the moment, of other things which it 
 may represent — in the social economy. This is 
 true, but it is only true because the military instincts 
 are not peculiar to the military class. The soldier is 
 a vicar, or delegate. He is a representative man, 
 chosen and trained to fight, in our modern specializa- 
 tion of functions, because others must be occupied 
 with other offices. He is, in fact, doubly represen- 
 tative — first, because he is a social voice and func- 
 tionary ; secondly, because the army is formed from 
 all classes of the community. If, therefore, there is 
 
1 12 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 such a thing as “ militarism,” it is not confined to the 
 military. It is found, in varying degrees of activity 
 and manifestation, in the intellectual and industrial 
 classes, and amongst workmen as amongst capitalists, 
 as well as amongst soldiers. It is found, too, as it is 
 hardly necessary to say, among women, who, if they 
 have not been actually fighters, have been the first 
 to give honour and applause to soldiers, and who, in 
 their own way and according to their own methods, 
 often exhibit the same instincts and temper of combat 
 as constitute the military mind. 
 
 What is true of the military class and its relation 
 to the general social mass is, as is obvious, true of 
 other special classes. There would, for example, be 
 no priesthood — in the broad sense of this term — if 
 there were not, in the great body of society, the 
 instincts and needs which we call religious. The 
 priest has sometimes been spoken of, by fantastic, 
 shallow commentators upon human life, as if he in 
 some miraculous way sprang into existence and im- 
 posed himself upon men, irrespectively of their 
 nature and needs. He is, of course, what he is 
 because of their nature and needs. He is, as is the 
 poet, the musician, the painter, the architect, the 
 physician, or the lawyer, a minister of man, dependent 
 absolutely for his existence upon the extent to which 
 his office corresponds to some felt and continuous need 
 of the human spirit. All our special social classes 
 are, in fact, organic expressions, bodyings forth, of 
 the common mind of man. The soldier, as such — the 
 fighting man — exists as an articulate, distinctive 
 
THE GOOD OF A HUMAN PEACE 113 
 
 order, because the soldier is in the soul ; and he is 
 as much in the soul of a workman as of a capitalist, 
 and of an Englishman or Frenchman as of a German. 
 
 An even more important instinct than the military 
 instinct, in the permanent order and activities of 
 human society, is, of course, the nutritive instinct, 
 and it is important also in its bearing upon the causes 
 and motives of war. As this primary instinct works 
 in man it gives rise to the desire for material wealth, 
 although it is evidently by no means the only force 
 which begets that desire. Instead, however, of 
 speaking of the mere nutritive instinct as such, we may 
 speak broadly of that desire for wealth of which 
 this instinct is only the first and most potent feeder. 
 The desire for wealth finds its social and organic 
 expression in all Western nations in what we call the 
 capitalist class. That class represents this desire in 
 two ways — first, because it is especially devoted to 
 directing the production and distribution of wealth ; 
 secondly, because it is itself, as a whole, pre-eminently 
 characterized by the pursuit and possession of wealth. 
 From both these points of view, however, this special 
 class of capitaKsts, like the military or priestly class, 
 stands for a common and continuous mind. It is 
 only because the common mind~the mind of man — 
 is animated by the same desire for wealth, and con- 
 sents to a certain mode of organizing its production 
 and distribution, that the capitalist class exists. 
 There is, in regard to the possession of wealth, no 
 essential difference between the richest of capitalists 
 and the poorest of his workmen except this — that 
 
1 14 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 the capitalist desires it and possesses it while the 
 workman desires it and does not possess it. There 
 are other differences between them in other respects — 
 differences of situation, capacity, power, and function 
 — but so far as the desire for wealth is concerned they 
 are both in the same plane of human nature. What 
 we may call industrial Socialism, considered strictly 
 as such, proceeds upon a recognition of this truth, 
 and aims at satisfying, by its own methods, this 
 common desire for wealth in the non-capitalist classes. 
 The desire for wealth is, of course, to be distinguished 
 from the use of wealth. Two capitalists, or two 
 workmen, may be animated by an equal desire for 
 wealth, but they may have very different desires in 
 other respects, and, therefore, very different opinions 
 as to the uses of wealth. Industrial Socialism is, as 
 such, not a doctrine of human perfection. It is, in 
 itself, only an economic doctrine, advocating what it 
 conceives to be a juster distribution of material 
 resources, irrespective of the uses which may be 
 made of them. 
 
 What is true of the three special social classes which 
 we have now considered — the military class, the 
 priestly class, and the capitalist class — is true also 
 of what we may call the governing class. We cannot 
 draw a line of demarcation between these special 
 functional classes and society as a whole, as if there 
 were, on one side of this line, one kind of human 
 nature, on the other side another. These special 
 functional classes are social classes. They are thrown 
 up and maintained by the working of certain forces 
 
THE GOOD OF A HUMAN PEACE 115 
 
 in the human soul. They represent its different 
 persisting desires or propensities. When we speak 
 of the military class we commonly, no doubt, mean 
 most of all the officers of an army, because they are its 
 directing and organizing heads ; but an army is 
 drawn from the people, and is maintained out of the 
 purse of a whole nation. A workman, again, is only 
 a capitalist in petto. In exactly the same way, the 
 governing classes are, on a fundamental view of them, 
 representative, and this whether or not what we call 
 a “ representative government ” exists in a given 
 country. By the governing classes we mean especially 
 the classes which possess wealth and leisure. They 
 stand, in relation to the nation as a whole, as the officer 
 stands in relation to the army, or the priest in relation 
 to the Church, or the capitalist in relation to the 
 general body of workers. The Government of a 
 country is the organ, for political purposes, of the 
 total social consensus. It is the co-ordinating 
 authority of the nation, as such. It is the voice and 
 instrument of its patriotism. By patriotism, as is 
 plain, we do not mean the temper or disposition of the 
 Government, or governing classes, only. It is a 
 feeling or sentiment, such as it may be, animating, in 
 one way or another, the whole community. Patriot- 
 ism, we commonly say, is a love of one’s country. 
 Such a love, however, may show itself in various ways. 
 It may give rise to a heroic defence of national 
 freedom, but it may also give rise to a not less heroic 
 attack upon the freedom of some other nation. It 
 may inspire a policy of self-preservation, or a policy 
 
ii6 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 of conquest and empire. A man may be said to love 
 his country both when he fights to prevent it from 
 becoming subject to a foreign Power and when he 
 fights to enable it, as a foreign Power, to make a 
 weaker people subject to itself. In either case we 
 call him a patriot, and should commonly pronounce 
 him unpatriotic if, while willing to die in defence of 
 his own country, he were not also willing to die in a 
 war of aggression and usurpation against some other 
 nation. Of patriotism, in both these forms, the 
 Government is the central organ. It does not stand 
 outside the national life and impose itself upon it 
 from above. On the contrary, it springs from that 
 life and is sustained by it. It is an expression and 
 instrument of the mind of man as it passes into 
 national action. 
 
 We see, then, that whether peace — and above all 
 such a Human Peace as we are now considering — is a 
 supreme good is a question of its relation to other 
 motives of the mind of man, common and continuous, 
 which find for themselves expression and organization 
 in great distinctive social classes, but which are 
 nevertheless not peculiar to those classes. Amongst 
 these motives we have considered, as most important 
 for our present purpose, four — the military instinct, 
 the religious instinct, the desire for wealth, and the 
 national instinct, or patriotism, whether as it inspires 
 the defence of one’s own country or, in its impe- 
 rialistic form, as it dictates its aggrandizement by the 
 subjugation of other peoples. As it is hardly neces- 
 sary to say, among the innumerable wars which the 
 
THE GOOD OF A HUMAN PEACE 117 
 
 world has seen each of these four instincts, or interests, 
 has played a part. They have been the chief motives 
 of war in the past, and, if war is to continue, some of 
 them at least will be its chief motives in the future. 
 They are the more potent as causes of war because 
 they seldom work singly. They work, in fact, in 
 a greater or lesser degree, in combination. In almost 
 every war that is waged the military instinct, as such 
 — the passion for destruction and combat — finds itself 
 in a sort of natural alliance with the desire for wealth 
 and the desire for national preservation and aggran- 
 dizement ; while every nation, whatever the alleged 
 cause for which it enters into war, is sure of the 
 sanction of “ the Church,” the Church — considered 
 especially as a body of ecclesiastics — being of the 
 same essential social stock as that out of which the 
 various articulated portions of the community are 
 shaped. It may be said, therefore, that, although of 
 a given war any one of these four instincts or interests 
 may conceivably be the immediate or predominant 
 motive, the action of any one of them commonly 
 brings all the others into play. 
 
 It is, however, necessary to recognize that what 
 is at one time a motive of war may at others be a 
 motive of peace. Of these four governing instincts — 
 in spite of the fact that they have been the most 
 important causes of war— there is only one which 
 of necessity, by its native character and effect, brings 
 about war, and this only when it undergoes a special 
 development, or transformation. That instinct is the 
 instinct, or interest, of patriotism or nationalism, con- 
 
ii8 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 sidered in its imperialistic form. Patriotism, under- 
 stood simply as the love of country, may of course 
 exist and work in a time of peace, exhibiting itself, in 
 a hundred ways, as social self-sacrifice and devoted- 
 ness. Patriotism and imperialism, however — not the 
 love and service of one’s own country, but the desire 
 for its indefinite aggrandizement, to be brought about 
 and maintained by its forcible lordship over other 
 peoples — this is by its own nature and consequences 
 inevitably a cause of war. It brings it about in two 
 ways — first, because war is needed to effect the 
 conquest of an unwilling people ; secondly, because 
 the imperialism of one nation almost necessarily pro- 
 vokes the imperialism of its rivals, and produces com- 
 petition and collision amongst them. Such an im- 
 perialism may, of course, be considered to be a good. 
 It may be held to advance the interests of religion, or 
 civilization, or culture, or trade. It may beheld, too, 
 that although a people which is conquered by England, 
 Germany, or Russia loses its national identity and 
 liberty it still gains the advantage of coming under 
 the government of that Power, and that within the 
 limits of a particular empire peace at least — so long 
 as the empire holds together — is secured. A nation 
 being, as we have said, a law unto itself, may hold 
 that it is entitled to impose its law on others. We are 
 not, however, for the moment, considering either the 
 good or evil of empire. We are considering one 
 inevitable effect of imperialism ; and of imperialism 
 it may be said scientifically that so long as it con- 
 tinues to operate as a motive and policy the Human 
 
THE GOOD OF A HUMAN PEACE 119 
 
 Peace is impossible. That is, of course, not neces- 
 sarily a condemnation of imperialism. It may be 
 held that the advantages which a Human Peace 
 would bring in would not be such that they ought to 
 outweigh the good following from imperialism. It 
 is plain, however, that we cannot have both the good 
 of imperialism — if it is a good — and the good of a 
 Human Peace. 
 
 Of the other instincts, or propensities, which we 
 have ranked among the motives of war it may be 
 said that they differ from imperialism in this respect, 
 that they do not necessarily give rise to war. Even 
 what we have called the specific military instincts — 
 the passion for destruction and the joy of combat — 
 may find a large and beneficent satisfaction without 
 actual strife. They may be called up and exercised 
 in a strenuous encounter with the “ enemies of man ” 
 — the physical, intellectual, and moral evils which 
 afflict him. They may be transformed into a source of 
 generous emulation in the ways of peace. They may 
 be content, as in fact they ordinarily are, with the 
 mere shows and representations of conflict in pas- 
 times or in the arts. Religion, again, which almost 
 always blesses war when it is actually in progress, 
 and commonly does nothing to prevent it, is yet often 
 found putting forward a certain ideal, or conception, 
 of peace. Lastly, the desire for wealth, and for such 
 advantages as depend upon its possession, while it 
 is sometimes a motive of war may also be a motive of 
 peace — peace, of course, in this connection being 
 understood simply as the absence of destructive 
 
120 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 material conflict and bloodshed. If we suppose men 
 to be so dominated by the desire for wealth that other 
 motives of action become for them of subordinate 
 importance, then they will naturally choose war or 
 peace according as one or the other seems most 
 favourable to the satisfaction of that desire. It has 
 frequently been said — as, for example, by some recent 
 English political and industrial authorities — that 
 “ the trade follows the flag.” This principle has been 
 by others condemned as unsound. Those who hold 
 it to be valid have, however, as is evident, an indus- 
 trial ground for imperialism and war, while those who 
 reject it regard commerce as one at least of the 
 sanctions of peace. We may repeat, then, that while, 
 as all experience shows, we may have religion, or the 
 pursuit of goodness, without war, and trade, or the 
 pursuit of wealth, without war, and while even the 
 instincts of destruction and combat admit of a certain 
 pacific transformation and satisfaction, we cannot 
 without war have imperialism, since by imperialism we 
 mean, first, the forcible predominance of one country 
 over another, brought about and upheld by arms ; 
 secondly, the consequent competition and conflict of 
 rival States, all pursuing a similar policy. Impe- 
 rialism and war, in other words, stand necessarily in 
 a relation of cause and effect, while religion and war, or 
 industry and war, do not. It follows that if in the 
 mind of man the motives of international concord are 
 ever to gain a lasting supremacy, bringing it in and 
 maintaining it, this can only be, on the one hand, by 
 a total elimination of the motive of empire, and, on 
 
THE GOOD OF A HUMAN PEACE 12 1 
 
 the other, by the ascendency of such a conception of 
 the aim of man’s life upon earth that the military 
 instinct, the religious instinct, and the various personal 
 and social purposes which enter into the acquisition of 
 wealth, may become subservient to a Human Peace. 
 
 It is a corollary from this conclusion, and from the 
 various considerations by which we have been led to it, 
 that the Human Peace, assuming it to be desirable, 
 cannot be brought about simply by transferring 
 political power fron one social class to another, even 
 if we hold that this is in other respects desirable. It 
 is true that the various special classes — the official 
 military class, the capitalist class, the ecclesiastical 
 class, and the governing classes, considered as such — 
 have their own distinctive interests to promote, as 
 well as those general functional interests which may 
 be said to be the concern of the whole community- 
 A great military class, for example, although it has 
 been thrown up as a social organ, in the interests of 
 the national security or expansion, may naturally find 
 its own advantage in encouraging the temper and 
 poHcy of war, and in promoting expenditure on war. 
 Such a class, too, may, in given circumstances, be in 
 a sort of natural alliance with the other special 
 classes — capitalists, ecclesiastics, the secular pro- 
 fessions, and “ the Government.” They form together 
 what we call the “ upper classes ” — the classes of 
 wealth, leisure, education and ascendency — in con- 
 tradistinction to the “ lower.” All these classes are, 
 in certain respects, in a relation of intimate solidarity, 
 and they have therefore a tendency to secure and 
 
122 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 increase such advantages as they possess in common 
 even at the expense of the general good. 
 
 While this is true, however — and is a truth of great 
 practical importance — it does not affect the principle 
 that these distinct and separate classes are classes of 
 social organization and direction, which, so long as 
 they continue, are in greater or less correspondence 
 with the social mind — the mind of man. We cannot, 
 therefore, for example, bring in a Human Peace 
 simply by substituting what we call a “ democracy ” 
 for an “ aristocracy ” in the government of all the 
 Western nations. Such a substitution may con- 
 ceivably be on other grounds desirable, but it would 
 not, of itself, put an end to war. There has never 
 been a period when the “ democracy ” — if by the 
 democracy we mean the “ lower classes,” the great 
 social mass — had so much apparent power in Europe 
 as at the present time, and yet the present is an age 
 of almost universal conscription — a form of slavery — 
 and it has seen the vastest and bloodiest war in 
 history. Again, the mere abolition of the “ capi- 
 talist class,” and the substitution for it of a Socialist 
 industrial directorate, would not bring in a Human 
 Peace, so long as in any given country the need for 
 wealth, or the need for empire, still served as motives 
 for aggressive action against other countries. There 
 has been prosecuted in England for one hundred and 
 fifty years at least a steady and progressive pohcy 
 of imperialism — a policy which has been necessarily 
 a cause of aggression and bloodshed. During the 
 greater part of that time the power of the English 
 
THE GOOD OF A HUMAN PEACE 123 
 
 “ democracy,” the lower classes, has continuously 
 increased, and has sufficed to win from the upper 
 classes, one after the other, a number of important 
 concessions within the field of domestic affairs. 
 Against the policy of empire, however — which as 
 we have seen, is inevitably a policy of war and blood- 
 shed — this democracy has raised no protest. It has 
 sanctioned it, applauded it, co-operated in it, made 
 it possible, and indeed helped to make a contrary 
 policy impossible. The few voices which have, from 
 time to time, been raised against it have been silenced 
 by the clamours of an angry people. An English 
 Government has never been so certain of the con- 
 currence of the great body of the nation — upper 
 classes, lower classes, capitalists and workmen, priests 
 and people, teachers and taught, men and women — 
 as when entering into war, or prosecuting a policy 
 involving war. And, of course, what is true of the 
 English Government is true of all the principal 
 Governments of Western Europe. 
 
 The reason for this we have seen. The great 
 special social classes are expressions and organs of 
 the mind of man. They are man in his social mani- 
 festation, as he is moved by the military instincts, the 
 religious instincts, the desire for wealth, and the 
 things which wealth procures, the desire for national 
 expansion and domination. Militarism is not the 
 creation of a military class ; religion is not the 
 creation of a priestly class ; the desire for wealth is 
 not the creation of a wealthy class ; the desire for 
 national expansion and domination is not the creation 
 
124 the problem of human peace 
 
 of a governing class. It is these desires, on the 
 contrary, seated in the social mind, which have 
 thrown up and maintained these various classes. It 
 is not the soldier who produces war ; it is the instincts, 
 temper, purposes, and policy of war which produce 
 the soldier. If, therefore, there is ever to be a Human 
 Peace, the foundations of that peace must be laid, 
 where the foundations of war are to be found, in the 
 soul of man. The motives of peace must, by some 
 natural and effective process, be so developed and 
 strengthened that they may exercise a continuous 
 lordship over the motives of war ; and this, in the 
 first place, among those predominant Western nations 
 which, in international policy, decide the fate of the 
 world. In the absence of such a change, we are so 
 far from having a scientific guarantee against inter- 
 national conflict that we have not even, as we have 
 seen, a guarantee against civil war. A nation is only 
 an individual soul writ large ; and just as for an 
 individual soul — either within itself or in its relations 
 with others — peace is impossible except through the 
 harmonizing ascendency of some master motive, so 
 for a nation, within itself, and in its relations with 
 other nations, there can be no permanent peace unless 
 the purposes which make for it become supreme and 
 the purposes which make against it become con- 
 tinuously subordinate. If there is ever to be a 
 Human Peace — even in the limited sense of the mere 
 absence of strife and bloodshed — it must be recognized 
 throughout Europe to be the indispensable condition 
 of a common and supreme good. 
 
CHAPTER IV 
 
 CATHOLICISM AND A HUMAN PEACE 
 
 There is, as we have seen, only one sufficient reason 
 for supposing that a Human Peace, which has never 
 yet existed in the world, can, by an international 
 exercise of forethought and co-operation, be brought 
 in and secured. That reason is to be found in the 
 growth of science, science being understood to be the 
 mind of man in its complete development, resting on 
 the sum of human experiences and acquisitions, and 
 so become capable at last of gaining a true measure 
 of itself, and of the universe in relation to itself. The 
 office of science, in regard to international relations, 
 is to make known the forces of war as they exist and 
 work in the mind of man, and to show how that 
 mind, in the fulfilment of its spiritual lordship over 
 itself, may so master those forces as to make possible 
 the attainment and maintenance of a Human Peace. 
 
 The mind of man will gain this power of self- 
 command and self-direction — for the purpose of peace 
 as for all other purposes — through the ascendency of a 
 Scientific Catholicism. By a Scientific Catholicism 
 we mean the full experience and powers of the human 
 past brought to bear, in an order or synthesis of con- 
 ceptions, consciously employed, on the movement of 
 mankind towards the future. Neither the word 
 “ Catholicism ” by itself, out of relation with science 
 
126 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 or in opposition to science, nor the word “ science ” 
 by itself, and out of relation with Catholicism, repre- 
 sents a sufficient synthesis of human ideas and forces. 
 The two words taken together, however — each in its 
 fullest extension and each positively understood — 
 properly stand for such a synthesis. If it can ever 
 establish itself in the human spirit, a peace world- 
 wide and enduring — which, up to the present, neither 
 Catholicism nor science, by itself, has been able to 
 give to us — may at last become possible. 
 
 When, however, we say that it is from the stand- 
 point of a scientific Catholicism alone that we can 
 gain the right conception and power of a Human 
 Peace, it is necessary to employ both the term 
 “ Catholicism ” and the term “ science ” in a definite 
 and fixed sense, and to determine the relations of the 
 conceptions which they represent. By Catholicism 
 we here mean the doctrine, worship, discipline, and 
 organization of the Roman Church, including, of 
 course, the Papacy, considered in principle, or in their 
 ideal character — that is, apart from their actual 
 imperfections or abuses in practice at any given time, 
 and regarded as the social embodiment and fulfilment 
 of Christ. When we so use the word “ Catholicism,” 
 however, we do not, of course, mean that outside the 
 Roman Church none of the religious conceptions and 
 powers are to be found which this word represents. 
 Many of them are to be found in the Greek Church 
 and in the various Protestant bodies, including 
 Anglicanism. Some of them are to be found in 
 non-Christian and pre-Christian communions. It is 
 
CATHOLICISM AND A HUMAN PEACE 127 
 
 because of this that the Roman Church is, as we 
 have tried elsewhere to show,* pre-eminently the 
 Catholic Church, carrying in its life the whole religious 
 vitality of man, representing, directly or indirectly, 
 the religions of the East and of the West, of the past 
 and of the present, and standing even — so far as their 
 positive character is concerned — for the various sects 
 which have broken away from it. This Church is, in 
 fact, the spiritual mistress and voice of the world— 
 never to be dethroned or subverted unless religion 
 itself, in every conception of it which has hitherto 
 prevailed, passes from the being of humanity. It 
 follows that any conclusions which we may reach as 
 to the nature and powers of a Scientific Catholicism 
 wiU be conclusions which will apply, with varying 
 degrees of force, to non-Catholic religions, and espe- 
 cially, of course, to the various Christian communions 
 which have separated from Catholicism. Where, in 
 an intellectual and practical sense, the Catholic Church 
 is weak the other Christian Churches are weak also, 
 but where the Catholic Church is strong its strength 
 is largely its own. Its special ground of strength, of 
 course, is its possession of the Papacy, as the symbol 
 and organ of its continuous unity and its inter- 
 national life. 
 
 But if we say that Catholicism, scientifically under- 
 stood and completed, is to be the great power of a 
 Human Peace, we are the more bound to take account 
 of the various facts which seem to make against this 
 view — to take account of them and set them in a clear 
 * “Catholicism and the Modern Mind,” p, 282. 
 
128 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 light. We are considering the problem of peace from 
 the standpoint of science, in its application to the 
 mind and life of humanity. From this standpoint, 
 and in the interests of the very problem which we are 
 concerned to solve, it is indispensable that we should 
 see things as they are, allowing their full natural force 
 to such considerations as appear to go counter to the 
 principle which we are seeking to establish, or the 
 end which we desire to gain. Now, the peace which 
 we are supposing it to be desirable to bring in is the 
 peace of mankind, and it is evident that if such a peace 
 is to come it can only come by the concurrence, or 
 acquiescence, of all the countries of the world. But 
 Catholicism — although, as we have seen, it is, directly 
 and indirectly, the representative faith of humanity 
 — is, in its direct confession and acknowledgment, 
 actually the religion of merely a minority of the human 
 race. Judaism, Mohammedanism, Hinduism, Bud- 
 dhism, and Confucianism — to take only the greatest 
 of the world’s religions — lie beyond its jurisdiction. 
 Further, in Christendom itself, Catholicism — the 
 Catholicism which has, as its chief interpreter and 
 voice, the Pope — has no administrative authority over 
 the Greek Church and the various Protestant bodies. 
 Lastly, in Christendom — throughout all those pre- 
 dominant nations of the West in which, as we have 
 said, the controlling mind of peace must first be 
 brought in — there have now for hundreds of years 
 been manifest two great increasing movements bear- 
 ing upon the power and claims of Catholicism. One 
 of these, to use a single significant word, is a move- 
 
CATHOLICISM AND A HUMAN PEACE 129 
 
 ment of conscious and avowed atheism, directed not 
 against Catholicism alone, but against every form of 
 Christianity ; the other has been a movement, not 
 of open and explicit unbelief, but of what may be 
 called secularism— a movement of unbelief latent 
 and implicit, tending to take all the great concerns 
 and interests of human life — education, literature, 
 history, the arts, the sciences, the marriage laws, 
 politics, national and international, and industry — out 
 of the hands of all definite and organic religion, and into 
 the hands of what, for want of a better name, we may 
 call the State. Both of these great movements, indeed, 
 have now been so long continued, and are so univer- 
 sal, that it will probably seem to the vast majority of 
 thinkers and politicians that the very authority which 
 we are here invoking on behalf of Catholicism— the 
 authority of science — is one which is naturally and 
 decisively against it. 
 
 But it is not enough to say even this. It is to 
 Catholicism, become completely scientific, that we 
 are looking to give to the mind of man the prescience 
 and the will of peace. When we go back upon the 
 history of the world, however, we see that Catholicism 
 has not, up to the present, been a power of peace. If 
 we date its ofiicial status and authority from the 
 time of Constantine, we are bound to recognize not 
 only that it has never, in fact, prevented war, but 
 that it has not even attempted to do so. It would 
 hardly be an exaggeration to say that it has been on 
 the side of all the wars that have ever been waged in 
 Christendom, and has itself caused some of them to 
 
 H«P. 
 
 1 
 
130 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 be undertaken. This is true, of course, not only of 
 medieval Catholicism — the Catholicism of the undi- 
 vided Western Church — but of the Catholicism of 
 the Greek Church and the Protestant bodies. The 
 Christian Churches have, one and all, with the excep- 
 tion of the Quakers, been Churches of war. The 
 reason of this is, as we have already said, plain. 
 Catholicism does not stand, as an unrelated magical 
 power, outside the circle of human nature, compelling 
 it somehow, and in varying degree, into a passive 
 conformity to itself. It lies, in what it is or in what 
 it represents, within human nature, and is one, but 
 only one, of its working forces. If we say that it 
 stands for a high and constant instinct, or desire, of 
 man, that instinct has still as its companions others — 
 among them the instinct of destruction and the joy 
 of combat, the desire for wealth, the desire for national 
 expansion and predominance. Assuming, therefore, 
 that man, as he has hitherto expressed himself in 
 Catholicism, has had a right vision and conception of 
 a Human Peace — which, in fact, would be an unwar- 
 ranted assumption— it would still remain true that 
 in the practical pursuit of this ideal he has been 
 hindered and arrested by the operation of other 
 influences within him which have been antagonistic 
 to it. 
 
 The fact that Catholicism has, as a power of peace, 
 failed is, however, in itself, no right reason for dis- 
 missing it absolutely from our minds — assuming that 
 we have the power to do this — so far as the realization 
 of a Human Peace is concerned. We are trying, once 
 
CATHOLICISM AND A HUMAN PEACE 131 
 
 more, to consider this problem as a problem of science. 
 Now, from the standpoint of science we are bound to 
 ask ourselves what alternative we have to Catholicism, 
 considered as a principle of peace, supposing we dis- 
 miss it from our minds. We need not concern our- 
 selves with the non-Catholic forms of Christianity — 
 the Greek Church and the various Protestant sects. 
 They live, in so far as they live at all, with the life 
 of Catholicism, and if Catholicism dies they will die 
 also. If, therefore, we suppose ourselves called upon 
 to dismiss Catholicism from the argument of peace, 
 what is left to us ? That also is a question of science. 
 We are not entitled to assume that the word 
 “ science,” by its own natural and proper force, 
 necessarily represents the antithesis of Catholicism. 
 The word “ science ” represents the mind of man in its 
 full development, resting upon the sum of human 
 experiences and acquisitions, consciously scrutinizing 
 things external and internal, and possessing, so far 
 as its faculties allow, a complete measure of itself 
 and of the universe in relation to itself. From the 
 standpoint which science gives to us, therefore, we 
 are called upon to examine not only Catholicism, but 
 anti-Catholicism, or the alternatives to Catholicism. 
 Science shows to us our world and ourselves to our- 
 selves. This being so, it shows us how we should 
 stand, relatively to the question of peace, if all men 
 were to do what many have actually done — dismiss 
 from their minds Catholicism, and proceed as if it 
 were a thing extinct or dying. 
 
 We should then be left with atheism — either in its 
 
132 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 open and avowed forms, or in its implied and latent 
 form as secularism — the elimination of Catholicism, 
 in practice, from aU the great concerns of human life. 
 Now, atheism has, as such, no necessary bearing upon 
 peace at all, any more than upon gluttony or licen- 
 tiousness. As it is quite easy to show from experience, 
 when a war breaks out, some atheists in a given 
 country are in favour of it and some are against it. 
 In this respect their position is exactly the same as 
 that of Catholics. Further, when it is a question 
 not so much of whether a particular war is right or 
 wrong, but of whether peace, in itself, is an ideal 
 good, which may be pursued and realized in a definite 
 way, it is evident that atheism as such — the dismissal 
 or neglect of Christ and Catholicism — has no view 
 which is proper to it, or which follows from it, although 
 individual atheists may possibly have such a view. 
 Again, what we have called secularism finds its expres- 
 sion and organ in “ the State,” or “ the Government ” 
 — a power not creating or diffusing opinion, but 
 giving effect to it, in degree, in proportion to its actual 
 force, by certain processes of co-ordination and 
 organization. The State or the Government, how- 
 ever, has not, any more than the Church, been a 
 power of peace. It is the voice and instrument of the 
 passions and interests which, at a given time, are 
 dominant. It waged war before it was Catholic ; 
 it waged war when it was, or was supposed to be. 
 Catholic ; and it wages war now that it is increasingly 
 secularist. 
 
 If, therefore, we suppose ourselves to be in the 
 
CATHOLICISM AND A HUMAN PEACE 133 
 
 position to make a deliberate choice between Catholi- 
 cism and atheism, we have no reason, so far as a 
 Human Peace is concerned, from the point of view 
 of science, to choose atheism. It is plain that 
 atheism as such — the rejection, or disallowance, of 
 Christ and Catholicism — does not change the basic 
 contents of human nature — its instinct of nutrition, 
 its instinct of sex, its instinct of destruction, the joy 
 of combat, the desire for wealth, the desire for national 
 expansion and domination. If there are in man 
 certain continuing passions and propensities which 
 tend to urge him into war, they are, in themselves, 
 after the substitution of atheism for Catholicism, 
 exactly what they were before. Our recognition of 
 this, of course, is, in a scientific sense, neither a proof 
 of Catholicism not a disproof of atheism. The 
 instincts and passions of men existed before Catholi- 
 cism, as such, arose in the world, and at that time, 
 as afterwards throughout the history of Catholicism, 
 sometimes there was peace and sometimes war. In 
 the same way, if we suppose Catholicism to die out as 
 completely as the “ Paganism ” of Greece and Rome 
 has done, human nature, so far as its primary con- 
 stituents and forces are concerned, will still be a 
 persisting identity. Man, then, as now — no other 
 change in him having been effected — ^will eat and 
 drink. He will propagate his species. He will be 
 moved by the instinct of destruction and the joy 
 of combat. He will strive for wealth and pre- 
 dominance. He will sometimes make war and some- 
 times peace. He cannot, indeed, whatever his view 
 
134 the problem OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 of himself and his world, remain perpetually in a 
 state of conflict. He is a subject being, under the 
 discipline of an outer and inner necessity. He must 
 eat and drink, nourish and protect his offspring, 
 clothe himself, house himself, and warm himself ; 
 and in the stage of development which he has now 
 reached, although he may conceivably dismiss from 
 his mind Catholicism, together with all other forms 
 of religion, it is not probable that he will be able to 
 extirpate all those needs of comfort and luxury, 
 knowledge and art, which enter into an advanced 
 culture and civilization. The more such needs 
 become multiplied and common, the less will it be 
 possible for men to devote themselves to the merely 
 destructive operations of war. Nevertheless, in so 
 far as war might seem a means to a desirable end, 
 man after Catholicism, as before it, and during its 
 continuance, would tend from time to time to be 
 carried into it. Against this atheism, in itself, 
 would be no security. 
 
 In spite, therefore, of the failure of Catholicism, 
 relatively to the aim of peace, we have, relatively to 
 that aim, no ground, in science, for rejecting 
 Catholicism and choosing atheism. Atheism, in itself, 
 scientifically considered, is no more a thing of illu- 
 mination and promise relatively to the aim of peace 
 than it is, for example, relatively to the ideals of love 
 and purity, if these things are still to continue ideals. 
 Our hope is in science, illuminating and completing 
 Catholicism — the developed mind of man, resting on 
 the sum of his experiences and acquisitions, and 
 
CATHOLICISM AND A HUMAN PEACE 135 
 
 seeing himself and things in relation to himself as 
 they have been and are. The mind of man, thus 
 developed, is able to look at Catholicism, as it looks 
 at any other thing or thought — at the heavenly 
 bodies, at the air, at the sea and earth, with their 
 forms of vegetable and animal life, at the movement 
 of mankind in the ages, at the differing types of 
 religion and civilization, at the arts and sciences, at its 
 own consciousness, emotions, conceptions and ideals. 
 There is a sense, of course, in which man, the man of 
 any given generation, is inevitably the subject of his 
 own past, with a vitality nourished upon it, with a 
 mind enlarged by it, with a wiU and power penetrated 
 and confirmed by it. But there is also a sense in 
 which, because of his development and his possession 
 of a full view and measure of things, the modern man is 
 necessarily the master of his past, looking back upon 
 it and summoning it before his judgment-seat. It is 
 thus that he looks back upon, or out upon, Catholi- 
 cism. It is a part of himself — an expression of his 
 unchanged but developing identity. He sees the 
 world when Catholicism was not, and he sees it 
 when Catholicism came. He sees how Catholicism 
 grew and developed — how the ancient civilization, 
 with its religions, arts, philosophies, sciences, and 
 modes of life entered into it ; how the order of the 
 Middle Ages, in mind and policy, was shaped and 
 maintained ; how, in the six centuries of modern 
 history, there has, in the Western world, been a vast, 
 many-sided expansion of genius and power. He sees 
 how Catholicism stands to-day — its relation to the 
 
136 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 non-Christian religions, its relation to the Greek 
 Church, Protestantism, and unbelief, its relation to 
 the sum total of human culture, its relation to the 
 social and practical life of the world, including inter- 
 national action and the problems of peace and war. 
 
 Seeing these things, science — ^the developed and 
 synthetic mind of the modern man- — recognizes that 
 what atheism, as such, does not do, and cannot do, 
 Catholicism, as such, does and has always done. 
 Catholicism, as such, scientifically and positively 
 considered, proposes to man a supreme aim in life — 
 an aim continuous and universal, which, in its essen- 
 tial character, is not of one age alone, but of all ages, 
 and not of one nation alone, but of all nations, and 
 which by its proper nature is such that it may serve 
 to give to all his other aims meaning and unity. This 
 aim is an aim of developing personal and social per- 
 fection, according to the Perfection, or Divinity, of 
 Christ. We may characterize this aim in other 
 terms, and call it — as it has been called by one of the 
 forlorn and distracted spirits of the modern revo- 
 lution — a “ slave morality.” This is, although chosen 
 with an intention of contempt and rejection, a right 
 and happy designation. Catholicism is, indeed, a 
 slave morality — a morality which, finding man a 
 slave either to his own inner passions, or to the despot 
 classes which have risen into ascendency from their 
 working, offers to him freedom and lordship. This 
 slave morality aims at making the slave a master. 
 It pronounces words of freedom and light. Its 
 purpose is not to take from the few, but to give to 
 
CATHOLICISM AND A HUMAN PEACE 137 
 
 the many. It exists not to bring down the high to 
 the low, but to raise the low to the high. Where 
 there is an anarchy of animal passion it would bring 
 in a human order and calm. Where there is ignor- 
 ance it would bring in knowledge. Where there is 
 weakness it would bring in strength. Catholicism — 
 which, of course, is only man at a given stage of his 
 being, and in a given degree, recognizing himself, and 
 the Order to which he is subject, expressing himself, 
 commanding himself, and directing himself, according 
 to a Vision which has come to him — ^has been a 
 “ slave morality ” which has been a morality of 
 masters liberating slaves, and of slaves risen to the 
 dignity of masters. It has been the morality of 
 apostles, martyrs, saints, artists, philosophers, 
 thinkers, heroes, and rulers, as well as of the obscure 
 and uninstructed, during almost two thousand 
 years. The modern developed and synthetic mind, 
 science, sees it to represent within its own sphere 
 what is as much an order of forces, controlling and 
 beneficent, as is the solar system itself, or as are the 
 recurrent phenomena of the vegetable and animal 
 kingdoms, or the accomplished conquests of the arts 
 and sciences. In the presence of this order, as in the 
 presence of any other, man is strong when he submits 
 and uses, but weak when he revolts and repudiates. 
 In denying and rejecting what is positive and great 
 in Catholicism he denies and rejects what is greatest 
 in himself. He disowns the Divinity within him, and 
 turns his back upon his own noblest achievements. 
 
 It is because Catholicism, considered from the point 
 
138 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 of view of science, is what it is — an emanation and 
 expression of the mind of man, proposing to himself, 
 and pursuing, a master ideal — that it has a natural 
 bearing on the question of peace, while atheism, as 
 such, has no such bearing. Therefore, if we wish to be 
 delivered from war — assuming it to be possible for 
 us to be so delivered — ^we cannot turn to atheism to 
 deliver us. On the other hand, Catholicism, just as 
 it has been and is, cannot deliver man from war. 
 This history shows us. Catholicism, in spite of its 
 proclamation of an ideal of perfection, has, in fact, 
 made almost no direct contribution to the peace of the 
 world, and has, indeed, almost invariably sanctioned 
 and blessed its wars, whatever they were. In pre- 
 cisely the same way science — to which we are now 
 making our appeal — has not brought in peace. The 
 age greatest in applied science has been the age of the 
 greatest of wars. It may seem, therefore, that we 
 are helplessly involved in a vicious circle, since, 
 neither Catholicism, nor atheism, which is the anti- 
 thesis of Catholicism, nor science, which pre-eminently 
 stands for the Modern Mind, has apparently in it any 
 promise of peace. Nevertheless, it is to the union 
 of two things which, relatively to war, singly have 
 failed — Catholicism and science — that we look for 
 the power of concord. What Catholicism by itself, 
 apart from science, and science by itself, apart from 
 Catholicism, cannot do, the two together may do, 
 for the two together represent the developed, unified 
 mind of man, knowing itself, and knowing the world 
 in relation to itself. 
 
CATHOLICISM AND A HUMAN PEACE 139 
 
 It does not fall within the scope of this work to 
 determine the full meaning of a Scientific Catholicism. 
 The sense to be attached to this expression we have, 
 in part, attempted elsewhere to elucidate. We are 
 here concerned with that meaning only in so far as it 
 bears on the question of a Human Peace. Now, that 
 question is a great question of practical life. As such 
 it is representative. It is, moreover, not exclusive. 
 It does not stand by itself. It is one of a vast 
 number of interdependent questions of man’s mind 
 and life — questions so inseparably and closely con- 
 nected together that if we were to suppose Catholi- 
 cism, as a system of thought and conduct, to really 
 and finally fail in regard to any one of them, it would 
 fail in regard to them all. We see, in fact, as we go 
 back upon the history of Christendom, that Catholi- 
 cism, which has failed as a power of international 
 peace, has also failed — failed continuously, and on a 
 vast scale — as a power of personal conduct or morals. 
 We may, therefore, properly consider the question of 
 peace as a sort of test question in relation to Catholi- 
 cism — a question bringing it naturally to the judg- 
 ment-seat of the Modern Mind, and submitting it, 
 as it ought properly to be submitted, to the ordeal 
 of practice, or life. 
 
 It is not from Catholicism, just as it is, nor from 
 science, just as it is, but from a scientific Catholicism, 
 that we are to expect such a solution of this question 
 as is possible, and this, as we have said, because it is 
 a practical question of man’s life upon earth. The 
 general effect of the application to Catholicism of 
 
HO THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 science — the developed, synthetic mind of the modern 
 man — may be quite simply and broadly stated. In 
 so far as Catholicism enters into the domain of explana- 
 tion on the one hand, and the domain of practice on the 
 other, it enters into the sphere of science and becomes 
 subject to its jurisdiction. There may be things in 
 Catholicism which lie wholly outside one or other of 
 these two domains — statements to which no scientific 
 meaning is to be attached, precepts of conduct for 
 which no scientific reason can be given. As to this 
 we need here say nothing. What we are at present 
 concerned with is the relation of Catholicism to man’s 
 life, inner and outer, on earth ; and in relation to 
 this Catholicism, in so far as it professes to explain 
 things, or proposes to men to do things, comes within 
 the province of science, and must submit to its 
 authority. It follows from this that the whole of 
 Catholicism, considered as an explanatory and prac- 
 tical system — its terminology, its conceptions of God 
 and man, of earth and heaven, of the human soul, 
 of “ this world ” and “ the next,” of Our Lord and 
 Our Lady, of the Scriptures and the Church, together 
 with its principle of prayer, its creeds, its sacraments, 
 and its organization — is as much subject to science, 
 the ordered, ordering reason of developed man, as 
 are any of the phenomena of external nature, or any 
 of the constructions of the arts and sciences. Science 
 is not, as some have supposed it to be, atheism. 
 Science is explanation. It no more necessarily rejects 
 Catholicism because, in the degree in which this is 
 possible, it explains it, than it rejects the solar system, 
 
CATHOLICISM AND A HUMAN PEACE 141 
 
 or the other great forces of inorganic and organic 
 matter, because, in the investigation and interpreta- 
 tion of these things, it has thrown up astronomy, 
 physics, and biology. What it says, however — and 
 the more plainly and openly this can be said the 
 better — is that in the present state of the human 
 mind, and relatively to the practical ends of life, the 
 statements of ecclesiastics or theologians in regard 
 to Catholicism have no other significance and value 
 than that which is given to them by the experience 
 and reason of a developed humanity. Catholicism, 
 of course, may, in a sense, be accepted, as we say, 
 “ on faith,” without question or reservation. An 
 individual mind, that is, may be moved, by its con- 
 ception of its own good, and the good of mankind, 
 to submit itself to the living, authoritative Catholic 
 Church, saying simply what it orders to be said, 
 doing simply what it orders to be done, and entering, 
 according to its power, into the inheritance of its 
 spiritual life. This, with regard to the Catholic 
 Church, is, for certain men and for certain purposes, a 
 perfectly natural thing to do, although with regard 
 to any other Church in the world it would be impos- 
 sible. What we are now concerned with, however, is 
 a Catholicism which, among other great things, is 
 to be capable of giving peace to mankind. Such a 
 Catholicism must be the Catholicism of developed 
 man. It must be, for the purposes of explanation 
 and action, scientific. 
 
 It is such a Catholicism — no other, and nothing 
 else — that can now give to man that conception of a 
 
142 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 supreme end of life the pursuit of which makes a 
 Human Peace not only desirable but indispensable. 
 This end of life is not a new end. It is the same end 
 as Catholicism has always proposed to the world — 
 Perfection according to the Perfection of Christ. It 
 is the Kingdom of Heaven. It is the growth and 
 full-flowering of an ideal humanity. A scientific 
 Catholicism, however, conceives Christ, God in Man, 
 and therefore man himself, as an unscientific Catholi- 
 cism could not do. By a Perfect Humanity we mean 
 man with all the characteristic sides of his nature 
 developed, fulfilled, and wrought into a unity under 
 the presidency of a high master motive. What man 
 is, as an intellectual and social being, we do not learn 
 from the introspection of metaphysicians, engaged 
 in a microscopic analysis of themselves, and each 
 pouring contempt upon the conclusions of all the 
 others, while claiming certainty and authority for 
 his own. We learn what man is from his manifesta- 
 tion of himself in history — from language, from 
 religion, from the arts, from philosophy, from science, 
 from social manners and organization, from political 
 institutions, and from industry. These are man’s 
 witnesses of himself, and not the shifting subtleties of 
 psychologists, losing themselves in interior darkness 
 while the sun of revelation shines without. 
 
 From these witnesses we see that man — ^wherever 
 and whenever we behold him — is a continuous and 
 identical being, moved, in different degrees, by 
 various desires, and exercising certain powers. In 
 regard to our capacity for naming and distinguishing 
 
CATHOLICISM AND A HUMAN PEACE 143 
 
 these desires and powers we are dependent upon an 
 order of language, which has grown up in the ages, 
 and which we cannot subvert. We are not beginning, 
 and are powerless to begin, the process of human 
 evolution d,e novo. It has produced us ; we cannot 
 reproduce it. We live, feel, think, speak, and act 
 by entering into a Power which is ourselves and yet 
 not ourselves. Man, therefore, we may say, is a 
 being in whom there are instincts of nutrition and 
 sex, instincts of destruction and construction, a 
 tendency to love his fellow-beings, but a tendency 
 also to hate them, a sense of right and wrong, a sense 
 of beauty and ugliness, a power of imagination, a 
 discernment of truth and untruth, a capacity for 
 observation and inference, and a genius for effecting 
 great and difficult constructions in art, philosophy, 
 science, social organization, and industry. We may, 
 if we please, name all these things differently, and we 
 may resolve them aU, or suppose ourselves to resolve 
 them, into some ultimate impalpable material pro- 
 cesses, but when we have done this the things them- 
 selves remain, with persisting characteristics — uni- 
 form relations of resemblance and difference — recog- 
 nizable by the ordinary sane mind. A human being 
 and a pig, a star and a tree, a man and a woman, are 
 not, outside a lunatic asylum, the same thing, any 
 more then good and evil, or beauty and ugliness, or 
 disease and health, or sanity and insanity. 
 
 Our conception of the End of life, therefore, must 
 be based on our knowledge of man as he has been 
 and is, a moral, intellectual, and active organism, a 
 
144 the problem OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 conscious and self-conscious, unified whole, living in 
 the social state, and in a relation of action and reaction, 
 on every side of his nature, with what presents itself 
 to him as a Universal Order, at once external and 
 internal. If, consequently, we say that the End of 
 Man is Perfection in Christ — perfection according to 
 a Divine Image, or Exemplar — this statement must 
 be understood in a sense relative to man’s many- 
 sided persisting and developing nature, and to the 
 continuing conditions imposed upon his mind and 
 life. Man has, as his basic needs, air, light, heat, 
 activity, rest, food, health, the association of the 
 sexes, paternity, clothing, shelter ; he has the higher 
 needs of love, society, self-control and self-direction, 
 beauty, knowledge, imagination and worship, and 
 all that constitutes what we call culture and civiliza- 
 tion. When we speak of what “ man ” needs we are 
 not entitled to take as our type the lowest of men, 
 or the least developed. We ought, on the contrary — 
 and this especially when we have set out with such 
 an expression as “ Perfection in Christ ” — to take 
 the highest and most developed. The most developed 
 stands where the least developed may conceivably 
 come to stand. This is the principle of what we have 
 called the “ slave morality.” It is the principle of 
 that End of Life which we are supposing a Scientific 
 Catholicism to contain within itself and put forward. 
 If it is true that Catholicism has proposed to men, 
 and must continue to propose to them. Perfection in 
 Christ, this Perfection must be understood — and is, 
 in fact, by Catholicism, in principle, always under- 
 
CATHOLICISM AND A HUMAN PEACE 145 
 
 stood — as a thing not for a privileged class, or a 
 particular nation, but for all men and aU nations. 
 
 The first task of a Scientific, or modern, Catholicism 
 is to give to this expression a meaning relative to the 
 actual nature and needs of man, under the con- 
 tinuing conditions of his life upon earth. From this 
 point of view, it must re-examine and test its tra- 
 ditional statements and formulas. It is not sufficient 
 simply to repeat them. In simply repeating them, 
 without making any attempt to give them a practical 
 meaning and effect, we only exhibit our incapacity, 
 or perhaps our dishonesty. In the Lord’s Prayer 
 we say “ Give us this day our daily bread.” That 
 is a perfectly intelligible expression of need. It is 
 unequivocal. Bread is the first of man’s needs. He 
 needs it now, he needs it always. But all his other 
 real needs — needs, that is, which spring from his 
 characteristic and continuous nature, developing and 
 fulfilling itself — are in this respect precisely similar 
 to this basic and elementary need of bread. He does 
 not live by bread alone. His other needs are, once 
 more, and broadly speaking, the association of the 
 sexes, love, goodness, paternity, and the family life, 
 clothing, habitation, light, heat, health, beauty, 
 knowledge, a right social order and companionship. 
 These needs, like the need for bread, are needs for 
 “ this day,” this hfe, this earth. So far as our 
 present capacity extends, we are not in the least able 
 to say whether a single one of them would be needs 
 of man in some other “ life ” than this, “ lived ” 
 under some whoUy inconceivable conditions. To 
 
146 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 the word “ Heaven,” as the symbol of a perfect state, 
 according to the only conception of such a state 
 which we are able to form, it is quite possible to attach 
 a definite meaning, but to the word “ Heaven ” as 
 dependent for its objective significance on the abroga- 
 tion of the infinite universe, including man as we 
 know him, it is not possible to attach any significance 
 at all. It is, so used, as Catholicism teaches, not a 
 word of knowledge, but a word of faith. It is quite 
 necessary that all ecclesiastics, theologians, and meta- 
 physicians in the twentieth century — all men claiming 
 to take any part in the actual direction of human 
 affairs — should, in the present stage of the world’s 
 development, deal honestly with themselves and their 
 fellow-beings in regard to this, and practise a religious 
 sincerity in their statements. The time is past for 
 deception and self-deception in these respects. It is 
 above all indispensable to set aside all evasions and 
 illusions, all verbal subterfuges and mystification, 
 when we are considering the awful tragedy of war and 
 the good of peace ; but if with this great question, 
 then with all others bearing upon the actual being 
 and fate of humanity. Man lives in a mystery tem- 
 pered by knowledge, but the recognition of mystery 
 is not the same thing as the possession of knowledge. 
 
 A Catholic conception of the End of Life — that 
 conception in the light of which it becomes possible 
 to prosecute Peace as a Human Good — must, then, 
 be stated in positive terms of man’s nature and 
 situation. It is, for example, not enough to conceive 
 of man as an inevitable “ sinner ” and to say that 
 
CATHOLICISM AND A HUMAN PEACE 147 
 
 Catholicism exists to save him, not from sin, but from 
 some eternal, unimaginable “ punishment ” of sin 
 in a future state of which we are powerless to form 
 any idea. It is not enough, again, to say that by 
 Perfection in Christ we mean, not a terrestrial, but a 
 “ celestial ” perfection. The word “ Heaven,” if it 
 is to have a place in a Rule of Life, cannot be 
 suffered to remain a merely negative expression, 
 meaning only “ not earth,” “ not man,” “ not ex- 
 perience,” “ not knowledge,” “ not action.” It 
 must not be simply a symbol of human ignorance and 
 incapacity — ^like the expression “ God knows,” mean- 
 ing that no man knows, or “ God help us,” meaning 
 that no man can help us. The words “ heaven ” and 
 “ earth,” or “ this world ” and “ the next,” must not 
 be used as terms of antithesis and total antagonism. 
 They have, of course, never in Catholicism been 
 uniformly so used, but in so far as there has been 
 a tendency to place what we call “ the supernatural ” 
 and “ the natural,” the “ Divine ” and the “ human,” 
 in a relation such that the first is regarded as a 
 mere negation of the second, it has inevitably 
 nullified Catholicism as a Rule of Life. Such a 
 tendency, as is evident, goes counter to the Incarna- 
 tion, in which we see Perfection, the Divinity, 
 clothed with flesh, become Human and Personal, and 
 moving as a Model on the earth. It goes counter, 
 too, to the organic Catholic Church, which is simply 
 that Perfection realized, in degree, as a continuous 
 individual and social life. It goes counter, further, 
 to the Lord’s Prayer, for, unless the words “ Thy 
 
148 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 will be done on earth as it is in heaven ” are to be 
 supposed devoid of all intelligible and practical 
 significance, they must, for man who uses them, mean 
 that a high ideal of himself which he is, in a measure, 
 able to shape in his mind is somehow to be realized 
 in the world of which he is actually an inhabitant. 
 
 We cannot, therefore, say that Perfection in Christ 
 consists in escaping the eternal punishment of sin in 
 a future “ life,” or even in being “ sinless ” — in the 
 negative sense of never contravening certain elemen- 
 tary moral precepts ; or in entering finally into some 
 endless, inconceivable “ supernatural ” felicity, as a 
 consequence of having thus refrained from “ sin,” 
 or obtained absolution for it. We cannot, again, 
 say that such a perfection consists simply in “ renun- 
 ciation,” or in taking up the Cross, leaving all things 
 and following Christ. These are all great and beautiful 
 poetic words, which are not likely to lose their 
 spiritual meaning and value so long as man, being 
 what he is, proposes to himself a high and difficult 
 end to which certain impulses within him urge him 
 forward, and from which certain others hold him 
 back. When he has advanced only so high in the 
 scale of humanity as never to be a liar, a thief, or a 
 murderer he may begin to talk of dispensing with the 
 Ten Commandments ; and when he has cast the 
 words “ love ” and “ selfishness,” “ passion ” and 
 “ purity,” out of his vocabulary because, in his 
 accomplished and undisturbed perfection, he no 
 longer needs them, then, perhaps — provided he con- 
 sents to forget the price that has been paid for his 
 
CATHOLICISM AND A HUMAN PEACE 149 
 
 elevation in the ages of sacrifice — he may be free to 
 take down the Crucifix from its place. 
 
 We are not, at present, called upon to discuss such 
 a state of things, in which “ joy will be its own 
 security ” and Eden will have come again. We are, 
 for the purposes of this treatise, concerned with only 
 such an elementary and preliminary good as that men 
 should refrain from killing one another. It is, from 
 this point of view, essential that the Crucifix, which 
 is the symbolic summary of Catholicism, should be, 
 as we have elsewhere said,* regarded, not as the sign 
 of a negative, repressive, or punitive process, but as 
 an Image of spiritual conquest — of a Victorious 
 Humanity, subjecting the lower, indeed, but also 
 liberating and fulfilling the higher. It must be held 
 to be, what by the principle and intention of Catholi- 
 cism it has always been, a symbol, not of death, but 
 of life, of a transcendent Perfection, in which the 
 New Adam restores the Old. In other words, it 
 must cease to be a negative symbol and become a 
 positive symbol, denoting, not merely feelings to be 
 suppressed and thoughts to be rejected and actions 
 to be avoided, but a many-sided humanity, indi- 
 vidual and social, developing and accomplishing itself. 
 Further, it must not represent despair as the word for 
 “ this life ” and hope as the word for “ the next,” 
 or renunciation as the word till death and possession 
 as the word after death. Man is called upon to 
 repress the lower, but only as one condition of 
 possessing the higher. If we are to use the traditional 
 * “Catholicism and the Modern Mind,” p. 184. 
 
150 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 symbolism, he renounces the devil, but only that he 
 may embrace Christ ; and Christ is not the absence 
 of evil, but the presence of a Beautiful Good. 
 
 We must come back, then, to this — that Catholicism 
 proposes to men, as the End of Life, Perfection in 
 Christ, and that Perfection in Christ means the satis- 
 faction and fulfilment of man’s nature in its complete- 
 ness, as it has been given to him by God, and in a 
 situation in which God has placed him. Man’s nature 
 is physical, moral, intellectual, practical, individual, 
 and social. It needs “ bread ” — food, clothing, habi- 
 tation, air, light, warmth, health, the association of 
 the sexes, parentage, love, domestic life, civic and 
 national sympathies, beauty, knowledge, the worship 
 and pursuit of things Divine, a high social activity, 
 and such an ordered mastery over itself and the 
 world external to itself as may make the attainment 
 of these things possible. The possession of these 
 things, in a right relation and harmony — with what 
 is highest in them controlling and animating all that 
 is lower — this is Perfection in Christ. Its pursuit 
 is the pursuit of Perfection. That pursuit is Catholi- 
 cism. Christ’s “ Kingdom ” is the Catholic Church, 
 conceived of as an ideal society of human beings. 
 Into this society, however, not one man, but all 
 men, and not one nation but all nations, are, in 
 principle, to be brought. It is to be social, inter- 
 national, universal, continuous. 
 
 We may dismiss from our minds the conception of 
 such a society as a mere chimera, but if we do not 
 so dismiss it — if we hold it to be, what it is, in degree 
 
CATHOLICISM AND A HUMAN PEACE 15 1 
 
 at least, an attainable end — then, in a scientific view 
 of it, we can see that a Human Peace is an essential 
 condition of its realization. On a certain view of 
 Catholicism, it may be admitted that peace, in the 
 sense of the mere absence of war, is not for man an 
 indispensable good. If man is to be conceived of 
 only as a “ sinner ” — ^who is by nature bound to 
 break, and in practice continually breaks, certain 
 elementary moral commandments, and who achieves 
 eternal fehcity after death simply as a result of the 
 “ remission ” of sin — then, it is clear, whether there 
 is peace or war in the world is of comparatively small 
 importance. Whether this “ sinner,” man, dies at 
 twenty or at seventy, in bed or in the battlefield, 
 slaughtering or being slaughtered — this does not 
 really matter much. The essential thing is that he 
 should profess repentance for his sins and be absolved. 
 If he does this, he is sure ultimately of an eternal 
 heaven ; and if he is fortunate enough to be able to 
 take advantage of a plenary indulgence, he goes 
 there at once. This view of man, moreover, is one 
 which concerns the individual only. Nations and 
 Governments, as such, come under no moral rule. 
 They are neither “ sinners ” nor “ saints.” They 
 enter no confessional. They receive no absolution. 
 They do not, collectively, reach hell or heaven. No 
 statesman, even, is supposed to be “ damned ” by 
 his bad policy or “ saved ” by a good one, although 
 his bad policy may ruin a people, and his good one 
 may protect and ennoble it. In the same way, no 
 individual citizen, as such, is understood to be called 
 
152 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 to account for the misgovernment which he has 
 sanctioned, or for the unnecessary bloodshed in 
 which he has willingly taken part. The word “ sin ” 
 in short, has no political significance — ^has no mean- 
 ing for governing or governed, as such ; and two 
 nations may decimate each other in the battlefield 
 without its being possible for any recognized authority 
 to declare that anyone is morally responsible for 
 such a result. They cannot, as nations, be judged, 
 or judge one another. They can only fight and 
 recriminate. 
 
 We are, however, now only concerned with a Scien- 
 tific Catholicism, and with its relation to a Human 
 Peace — a Scientific Catholicism being conceived of as 
 one which, pursuing its ancient aim of Perfection 
 in Christ, understands this aim as the positive and 
 religious fulfilment of the total nature of man, 
 physical, intellectual, moral, individual and social, 
 national and international. Such a Catholicism will 
 bring its central and transcendent aim to bear upon 
 the whole economy and policy of human life. It will 
 consider the problem of peace, therefore, in the light 
 of that aim. It will become completely and syste- 
 matically, what spontaneously and in a certain degree 
 it has always been, both spiritual and practical. It 
 wiU be a voice and law for man the thinker, or man 
 the citizen, or man the worker, as for man “ the 
 sinner.” It will be this, and do this, in virtue of its 
 being scientific and “ modern ” — in other words, 
 because of its capacity to represent the developed 
 mind of man, resting on the sum of human experiences. 
 
CATHOLICISM AND A HUMAN PEACE 153 
 
 and so able to see himself and his world in their 
 true nature and relations. Such a Catholicism, in 
 its continuing, luminous universality, will deliver 
 men from the limits of individualism, nationalism, 
 party, class, and sect. It will be an authority on 
 the one hand, for all who are Catholics, pursuing the 
 Perfection of Christ as a living and expanding ideal, 
 and on the other, for all who acknowledge the claims 
 of science, the obligation to see things as they are. 
 If we are Catholics we must wish Catholicism to 
 possess the light and the power of science — man’s 
 mind in its fullest development ; and if we are scien- 
 tific, seeing man as he is, in relation to his world as he 
 knows it, we must recognize that in his confession of 
 Christ he confesses an indestructible ideal of himself, 
 as an individual and social being, which it is the task 
 of the Catholic Church — that is, humanity, ordering 
 itself for Perfection — to progressively realize. It is 
 from these two standpoints become one— the stand- 
 points of Catholicism and science — that the right 
 conception and pursuit of a Human Peace become 
 possible. 
 
CHAPTER V 
 
 WAR AND THE SPIRITUAL LIFE 
 
 According to the conceptions of a Scientific 
 Catholicism, such as we have now attempted to 
 define it, the problem of a Human Peace becomes a 
 part of the larger problem of bringing the Perfection 
 of Christ into the life of man. In other words, it 
 ceases to be an isolated political problem, and 
 becomes, in the full sense of the word, a religious 
 problem. It is a problem of the Catholic life. In its 
 general application to the Catholic life, in the modern 
 world, the office of science is twofold. First, it 
 indicates its actual nature in terms of practice ; 
 secondly, it makes clear the conditions of its realiza- 
 tion. It is in this way that science may be said to 
 be, by its own native character, religious and Catholic. 
 It is a form of honesty. It does not permit us to 
 deceive ourselves. It sees things and shows things 
 as they are. If the Holy Spirit, in the language of 
 the Gospel poems, is the Spirit of Truth, then it is 
 this Spirit that has built up all our great positive 
 sciences, from mathematics to morals ; and the 
 scientific thinker, patiently and exactly unfolding to 
 us the Universal Order, which is God, is more a voice 
 of the Holy Ghost than is an ordinary ecclesiastic 
 or theologian, giving forth unsupported and indemon- 
 strable statements concerning things visible and 
 
WAR AND THE SPIRITUAL LIFE 155 
 
 invisible. The sacrament of holy order, therefore, 
 has a symbolic value in proportion as it represents the 
 communication of this real power of the Holy Spirit, 
 the power of truth or science — the power which 
 enables man to see things as they are, without 
 deceiving himself, and to order his life accordingly. 
 
 It is from this point of view that we are able to 
 understand — what in relation to the Problem of 
 Peace it is most important that we should under- 
 stand — the nature of prayer, as an instrument of 
 Perfection in Christ. Prayer is, in Catholicism, a 
 thing of central significance. If it is not scientific, 
 Catholicism cannot be scientific. Prayer is, of course, 
 the expression of a need, but it is also a prelude to 
 action. In the Lord’s Prayer we say “ Give us this 
 day our daily bread.” That is the expression of a 
 need, but it is also a prelude to action. We ask for 
 bread, but we do not in the least expect it to be 
 “ given ” to us. We know that we must work for 
 it. We know also that we must work for it according 
 to science — that is to say, according to our experience 
 of natural operations and our knowledge of the pro- 
 cesses of agriculture. Lahorare est orare. But what 
 is true of the petition for bread is true also of every 
 other petition in the Lord’s Prayer — as, for instance, 
 when we say “ Lead us not into temptation.” Here 
 again we have an expression of need which is also 
 a prelude to action. We are not to place ourselves in 
 a position of temptation, and if we are in it we are to 
 withdraw from it. That is the science of prayer. 
 “ Prayer,” says Auguste Comte, “ is the ideal of life. 
 
156 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 for it is at once to feel, to think, and to act.” “ The 
 good man,” says Thomas a Kempis, “first lays out 
 inwardly the things which he is to do outwardly.” 
 When, therefore, we pray for peace our prayer is of 
 no value unless it is scientific — or, to use an equiva- 
 lent expression, unless we pray according to a right 
 theology. Peace is no more “ given ” to us, as 
 passive and receptive beings, than bread is so given 
 to us. In prayer we must not deceive ourselves. 
 If we are to pray effectually for peace, we must have 
 a sure conception and vision of peace in our minds, 
 and be prepared to take the steps — a right ordering 
 of ourselves and of national policy — ^which the 
 establishment of such a peace demands. Our prayer 
 for peace — and most of all for a Human Peace, uni- 
 versal and continuous — must be a prelude to action, 
 and to action in accordance with science. If it is 
 not, it will be, what so many prayers for peace are, 
 only a futile expression of a vague yearning — a mere 
 ritualistic rigmarole — or an exercise in self-deception, 
 compatible in practice with a recurrent surrender to 
 all the passions and illusions of war. It is a common 
 and wholesome saying of Catholic preachers that 
 “ God alone cannot save men.” This is only the 
 theological statement of the biological principle that 
 life is the action and reaction of organism and 
 environment, which, again, is equivalent to the 
 Pauline sentence that “ in Him we live and move 
 and have our being.” 
 
 The master aim of a Scientific Catholicism, con- 
 sidered as a living, shaping, human power, is to 
 
WAR AND THE SPIRITUAL LIFE 157 
 
 promote Perfection in Christ, and this in a positive 
 and practical sense, as a fulfilment of all the sides of 
 human nature, in a harmonious order, constituted by 
 the subordination of its lower forces to the higher. 
 This aim is, in the widest sense, social. It embraces 
 all humanity, national and international. It is true 
 that there are now in Christendom, in “ the West,” 
 a large number of men and women who are, by pro- 
 fession, or by want of profession, non-Catholic or 
 non-Christian, and that for such men and women the 
 problem of peace is, or may be, one of importance. 
 It is true, too, that our European statesmanship is, 
 as we have said, implicitly atheistic or secular, setting 
 aside Catholicism, or Christianity, in any form, in its 
 common arguments and action. It may seem, there- 
 fore, that the standpoint of a Scientific Catholicism, 
 Perfection according to Christ, is not one which is, in 
 our modern world, sufficiently representative, either 
 of the non-European or of the European world, for 
 the purposes of international action. First, however, 
 ^t must be borne in mind that, by a principle which we 
 have already established, it is from Christendom that 
 the power of a Human Peace must proceed ; secondly, 
 that a Scientific Catholicism, in the degree in which 
 it is really scientific, will, in relation to actual social 
 and practical interests, be able to appeal to a secular 
 citizenship and statesmanship, and even to those 
 who, for want of a better name, are classed as 
 agnostics, or unbelievers. It may be admitted that, 
 even within the circle of European civilization, 
 Catholicism, or Christianity, does not now, for the 
 
158 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 purposes of either thought or action, give us a common 
 or social standpoint. Science, however, does give 
 us such a standpoint. It has a sure universality. Its 
 demonstrated truths and its methods of investigation 
 are accepted by Christians and non-Christians. They 
 prove themselves by practice. In so far, therefore, 
 as Catholicism is scientific and practical, it will be 
 representative even of those who may not call them- 
 selves Catholics. 
 
 The dominant aim of life being, according to a 
 Scientific Catholicism, Perfection in Christ — the 
 ordered fulfilment of human nature — it is, in relation 
 to the problem of peace, necessary to convert this 
 abstract statement into statements concrete and 
 practical. The governing needs of man we have 
 already, in general terms, enumerated. In deter- 
 mining those needs we take, as our type of human 
 nature, not the lowest man, or even the “ average ” 
 man, but the highest man given in experience — the 
 complete, or completely-developed man. When we 
 speak of the general and permanent needs of “ man ” 
 it is such a man that we naturally have in view. 
 Now man, so understood, needs, as we have said, 
 food, clothing, habitation, health, air, light, heat, 
 locomotion, the association of the sexes, paternity, 
 love, domestic and social life, religion, beauty, know- 
 ledge, and the freedom and power to so act that he 
 may satisfy these various requirements of his nature. 
 Let us, for the sake of simplicity and convenience, 
 express the same truth in terms of institutions, and 
 say that man for Perfection in Christ, needs the home, 
 
WAR AND THE SPIRITUAL LIFE 159 
 
 the Church, the school, the workshop, the theatre, 
 and the State — using the word ‘‘ theatre ” as a com- 
 prehensive symbol for the various presentations of the 
 arts, and the word “ State,” similarly, for all forms of 
 political administration. These institutions, or instru- 
 ments, of his many-sided continuous nature man does 
 not need casually or intermittently. He needs them 
 always and everywhere for the fulfilment and satis- 
 faction of his total being. We may, in the interest 
 of perfect accuracy and explicitness, admit, once 
 more, that a large number of men now profess to have 
 no need of the Church. To that extent, therefore, 
 the Catholic ideal of Perfection — Perfection in Christ 
 — does not represent them. In other respects, how- 
 ever, it does, for although they might wish to strike 
 out the Church from the list of representative human 
 institutions, they would, for the most part, and in 
 some form, retain all the others which we have 
 mentioned. In regard to them, at least, they would 
 have common ground with a Scientific Catholicism. 
 
 Putting ourselves, however — as in this work we 
 have throughout done — at the point of view of such a 
 Catholicism, we may take the six representative 
 institutions which we have specified as emanations 
 of the nature of man and as instruments satisfying 
 his continuous needs. They are, therefore, institu- 
 tions and instruments of Perfection in Christ. They 
 are, further, social in the widest sense, national and 
 international. Now, it is plain that for the main- 
 tenance of these institutions — that is to say, for the 
 realization of the Catholic life — man is dependent on 
 
i6o THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 what he can get from the earth. It is as certain 
 that he gets the Church and the State, the home and 
 the theatre, from the earth as that he gets his bread 
 from it. He gets them, one and all, by labour. 
 The whole life of man, in its highest as in its lowest 
 forms, rests, as is obvious, ultimately upon agri- 
 culture — using this word for all modes of industrial 
 action, direct and indirect, upon the earth. That is 
 a truth, simple and palpable as it is, of which, 
 amidst the complexities of a developed civilization, 
 we frequently lose sight. It is, nevertheless, a truth 
 basic and controlling. It is no paradox to say 
 that Perfection in Christ, the complete Catholic 
 life, rests upon prayer and agriculture — on prayer 
 because in prayer man renews in his mind an 
 image of a Divine Humanity, individual and social, 
 which it is his will to realize in himself ; on agri- 
 culture because it is from the earth that all men, 
 from the savage to the saint, must get the material 
 means of life. Agriculture, therefore — that is to say, 
 the whole of our industrial action — gains meaning and 
 nobility from the fact that it is an indispensable 
 means to an end — the highest that man, in his 
 continuous and developed nature, proposes to himself. 
 
 It is from this standpoint that we are able, accord- 
 ing to a Scientific Catholicism, to gain a right view 
 of a Human Peace and of the policy to be adopted 
 for its establishment. Whether we consider a Human 
 Peace to be a good depends, as we have seen, on our 
 conception of the End of Life, or of the means to be 
 adopted for its attainment. The End of Life, as a 
 
WAR AND THE SPIRITUAL LIFE i6i 
 
 Scientific Catholicism understands it, is Perfection 
 in Christ — the ordered fulfilment of a many-sided 
 humanity — a Perfection demanding, as its institu- 
 tions, the home, the Church, the school, the workshop, 
 the theatre, and the State, or Government, and 
 resting ultimately upon the earth, and what man, by 
 his industrial action, can obtain from it. Now, 
 whether peace, regarded simply as the absence of 
 war, is, relatively to this end, a good depends, of 
 course, on the nature of war, and what it is that it is 
 in its power to accomplish. War is a good if it can 
 be shown to be, in some indispensable way, sub- 
 servient to Perfection in Christ, according to that 
 practical and social conception of it which we have 
 now elucidated ; it is an evil, and therefore a serious 
 evil, if it frustrates or hinders that Perfection. 
 When we thus speak of war as good or evil we are, 
 as is obvious, considering it as a thing to be chosen 
 or rejected by deliberate policy. Such a choice or 
 rejection may in part be due to the strength or 
 weakness of certain primary human passions — as, for 
 instance, the instinct of destruction and the joy of 
 combat — but, in our modern world at least, questions 
 of international action are questions of statesmanship, 
 and before the Government of any country enters on 
 a war, or prosecutes a policy carrying with it the 
 risks of war, it has usually come to the decision that 
 such a war, evil as it may be in certain respects, is 
 yet, for some definite purpose, necessary. 
 
 What we have therefore to consider is whether war, 
 regarded as a definite mode of human action, and 
 
i 62 the problem of HUMAN PEACE 
 
 being conceived of as lying within the sphere of 
 deliberate choice, is, in our modern world, indis- 
 pensable to the preservation of those high permanent 
 interests of man which we have summed up in the 
 words “ Perfection in Christ,” or the Catholic life. 
 This is, once more, not a historic question ; it is a 
 question of the present and the future. It may be 
 true that war, in various periods of the past, and 
 relatively to the then existing conditions, was some- 
 times a good, and yet that, relatively to existing con- 
 ditions, it is an evil. Again, we are not concerned to 
 discuss the question of whether war, being admitted 
 to be an evil, is yet an evil out of which good may 
 come. There is hardly any form of evil — a pesti- 
 lence, poverty, a shipwreck, an earthquake, a flood, 
 a famine, a conflagration, a persecution — ^which may 
 not afford occasions for the display of some high 
 quality of human nature. No sane man, however, 
 would propose that such occasions should be 
 deliberately created in order to give rise to such a 
 display. It is the ultimate purpose of Catholicism, 
 stated in traditional and symbolic language, to enable 
 men to get to “ Heaven,” where, as is supposed, they 
 will be exempt from every form of evil and suffering, 
 and enjoy eternal “ felicity.” We are not, therefore, 
 called upon to consider whether evil is good and good 
 evil, or whether war, being an evil, may not give rise 
 to an exercise of heroic patriotism, noble personal 
 devotedness, and beautiful charity. What we are 
 concerned with is the Catholic ordering of human life 
 for the ends of Perfection — or, if such a statement be 
 
WAR AND THE SPIRITUAL LIFE 163 
 
 preferred — man, in communion with Christ, exercising 
 his spiritual sovereignty for the fulfilment of a positive 
 ideal of himself. Relatively to such a purpose, a 
 good is only a good if it is a means indispensable to 
 its accomplishment, or such as, being free, we should 
 deliberately choose. 
 
 Now, the six representative institutions of the 
 Catholic life are, as we have seen, the home, the 
 Church, the school, the theatre, the State, and the 
 workshop, using each of these terms in a comprehen- 
 sive and symbolic sense. For the sake of simplicity 
 and convenience we may group together, on the one 
 hand, the first four of these institutions, and on the 
 other, the last two. The first four we may call 
 institutions of the spiritual and the last two insti- 
 tutions of the temporal life. Such an arrange- 
 ment and terminology must, of course, in many 
 respects, be arbitrary. The Catholic life, the life of 
 man, is a unity. All its parts, or factors, are inter- 
 dependent. Church and State, workshop and home, 
 act and react upon one another. This being recog- 
 nized and allowed for, however, there is still a certain 
 advantage, for our immediate purpose, in the double 
 grouping which we have suggested. The four 
 spiritual institutions, as we have called them, spring 
 especially out of four persisting moral and intellectual 
 needs of human nature — ^its craving for social love, 
 its craving for goodness, its craving for beauty, its 
 craving for knowledge or “ truth.” The two tem- 
 poral institutions are more directly concerned with 
 man’s need for action, or practical power, whether 
 
i 64 the problem OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 politically, in the organization of the State, or indus- 
 trially, in his operations upon the earth. 
 
 Understanding, then, by the “ spiritual life ” of 
 man the life in which he is more especially occupied 
 with the interests of love, goodness, beauty and 
 knowledge, and by his temporal life, that in which 
 he is more directly concerned with action in the 
 State and in industry, it is possible to determine the 
 relation of war, in the modern world, to these two 
 chief ends of his being. War is, of course, a perfectly 
 definite mode of human action. A European states- 
 man or citizen in the twentieth century has, as he 
 enters into war, a full consciousness of what it is and 
 what it implies. It is a special application of material 
 force, and is comparable, therefore, in certain respects, 
 with the processes of agriculture or shipbuilding. In 
 its essential immediate results war, of course, does 
 not differ in the twentieth century from what it was 
 in the age of Homer. It only differs in scale and 
 method — in being more deliberate, more systematic, 
 and better organized, in carrying with it a fuller 
 human science and prescience, in resting on a wider 
 and more adequate preparation, in employing a more 
 effective apparatus of slaughter, and, like industry, 
 in largely substituting mechanical agencies for the 
 direct and individual action of man. In other 
 respects, however, war is, at the end of three thousand 
 years, substantially what it was at the beginning. Its 
 immediate, or purely military, purpose is to kill men 
 and destroy human constructions ; its ultimate, or 
 political, purpose is to compel some one people either 
 
WAR AND THE SPIRITUAL LIFE 165 
 
 to accept the rule of another, or to surrender to it a 
 part of its territory and population, or its material 
 wealth, or to act, or refrain from acting, in a certain 
 way, according to the demands of the victor. 
 
 It is, then, for a Scientific Catholicism to deter- 
 mine, in the first place, how far war, being what it is 
 in its processes and objects, is demonstrably and 
 indispensably subservient to the Catholic life, which 
 is, on its spiritual side, a life of love, goodness, beauty, 
 and truth. Now, it is not necessary, so far as our 
 modern world is concerned, to say much upon this 
 subject. Within the limits of Christendom, at least, 
 wars are not now waged, and are not likely to be waged, 
 in the immediate interests of the spiritual life — the 
 interests of the home, or of the Church, or of the 
 school, or of the arts. To a great extent the interests 
 of Christendom in these respects, allowing for sub- 
 ordinate differences, are common, as are also the 
 conceptions and practical methods brought to bear 
 upon them. In so far as disagreement exists with 
 regard to them, although it may be a cause of dislike 
 and estrangement, it is not a cause of actual conflict. 
 In other words, no one, in our modern world, and so 
 far as Christendom is concerned, supposes that mere 
 differences in regard to religious belief, or in regard 
 to education and the arts, are likely, in themselves, 
 to be a motive of international war. There are 
 various reasons for this — one obvious reason being 
 that religious behef in Christendom is not now settled 
 and serious, another that Governments are, as we 
 have said, no longer organs of definite religious 
 
i66 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 opinions, but of a sort of neutral secularism. But 
 whatever its explanation, the fact itself is certain. 
 
 When we get beyond Christendom — to the relations 
 of Western Powers with non-Western peoples, or of 
 the higher civilizations with the lower — this is no 
 longer, to the same extent and in appearance, true, 
 although even here it remains true in essentials. A 
 Christian missionary, going from a powerful country 
 to a non-Christian people, may possibly bring about 
 war, if his preaching proves unpalatable to the 
 natives, and they actively molest him in the exercise 
 of it. Even in such a case, however, the armed 
 support that is given to him by his Government is 
 given not so much on religious as on political grounds. 
 He is supported, if at all, not as an agent of Christ, 
 but because he is a representative of his country, and 
 it is held to be necessary to enforce respect for him 
 as such. It is, in fact, from the political point of 
 view, often an advantage to his Government to give 
 him such support, as in doing so it commonly gains an 
 opportunity of interfering in the internal afiFairs of 
 the uncivilized people, and thus of creating for itself 
 a fresh sphere of interest, imperial or commercial, 
 and ultimately, perhaps, of annexing a new territory. 
 So far as the missionary is concerned, it limits itself 
 to affording him personal protection. It has no 
 concern with the special religious opinions which he 
 may represent. Missionaries are, of course, of all 
 creeds and schools, and wherever they go they carry 
 with them the domestic conflicts and doubts of 
 Christendom. They stand, in greater or less degree, 
 
WAR AND THE SPIRITUAL LIFE 167 
 
 for the European mind, in its present state of uncer- 
 tainty and disorder. Consequently, although, in a 
 given situation, a European Government may wage 
 war against a non-Christian people for the support of 
 a missionary, it still acts, as it acts in the sphere of 
 domestic politics, rather as a secular than as a 
 religious agency. 
 
 There are other obvious reasons why, in the future, 
 a war for the direct and avowed purpose of advancing 
 Christianity is not likely to be entered upon. One of 
 these reasons is to be found in the fact that some 
 non-Christian peoples — as, for example, the Japanese 
 — ^have recently proved themselves to be capable of 
 becoming so far “ Western ” as to adopt the Western 
 methods and machinery of war. This does not, as 
 we have said, afford ground for the supposition that 
 the West will lose its intellectual and practical lord- 
 ship in regard to the East, but it certainly gives to 
 the East a greater power of resisting encroachment. 
 Another, and perhaps more potent, reason is to be 
 seen in the alliances between Christian and non- 
 Christian peoples which have been a remarkable 
 characteristic of later European policy. Such alliances 
 have gone far, in a most important sphere of human 
 effort, to abrogate the distinction between Christianity 
 — ^in so far as Christianity, in any sense, now enters 
 into State action — and, for instance, Mohammedanism, 
 or what we have hitherto called the “ Pagan,” beliefs 
 of India and Japan. As “ misery makes men 
 acquainted with strange bedfellows,” so war, in the 
 wide world of our modern cosmopohtanism, has for 
 
1 68 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 its own purposes reduced all the religions of mankind 
 to a common level, and made Hindus and Moham- 
 medans the companions of European Catholics, 
 Protestants, and atheists in Western battlefields in 
 the operations of slaughter and destruction. It has 
 of course, in the same way, and within the same 
 limits, gone far to abolish the difference between 
 what we have been accustomed to call “ barbarism,” 
 on the one hand and “ civilization ” on the other. It 
 has set up a sort of international “ secularism,” in 
 which even the profoundest differences of belief and 
 morals have apparently lost their importance, in 
 comparison with what are considered to be the 
 exigencies of State and national expansion. 
 
 While, however, it is true, for these and other 
 reasons, that war, for the avowed purpose of promot- 
 ing Christianity, or the interests of the spiritual life, 
 is not now likely to be waged by Western nations, 
 it is still necessary to recognize that it cannot, in any 
 case, be regarded as directly and indispensably 
 auxiliary to that life. There is a sense, as we shall 
 presently see, in which it may be held to be, in given 
 circumstances, indirectly essential to its maintenance 
 and progress, but what we are now concerned with is 
 its immediate bearing on Catholicism, as a mode of 
 realizing Perfection in Christ— as a mode of exalting 
 and unifying in man the power of social love, the 
 power of goodness, the power of beauty, and the 
 power of truth. Now the life in Christ, the Catholic 
 life, is, as we say, spiritual. It is above all, and in the 
 first place, interior. It is a life of feeling, thought, 
 
WAR AND THE SPIRITUAL LIFE 169 
 
 imagination, finding its first outward expression in 
 prayer and worship, and passing afterwards into 
 action. In what way, it may be asked, are the 
 processes of war, as such~a special application of 
 material force, directed to the destruction of human 
 life and constructions—directly and indispensably 
 subservient to this interior life ? Whether what we 
 are concerned with is the maintenance and reinforce- 
 ment of domestic love, or the communication of the 
 Image and worship of Christ or Our Lady, or the 
 diffusion of ideas and principles in art or science, or 
 the presentation of the conceptions and creations of 
 the beautiful, it is clear that there is no relation 
 between the operations of war and the attainment 
 of these ends. We may take, as a high typical 
 instance of aU spiritual methods, the action of a 
 missionary proclaiming Christianity in a non-Christian 
 country. His task is to communicate to another 
 mind a conception, or image, which is in his own, and 
 so to communicate it that it may give rise to a new 
 love, a new insight, and a new life. This is a spiritual 
 task. In other words, it is a task of mind operating 
 upon mind—a task of education. For the accom- 
 plishment of such a task there are no means available 
 except sympathy, intelligence, a right use of language, 
 and the testimony of personal conduct, exemplifying 
 the rehgion that is being preached. War, or the 
 menace of war, has no assignable part in such a 
 process. War has its own methods, and accom- 
 plishes its own objects. It acts upon the body for 
 its destruction, not upon the mind for its illumination. 
 
170 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 The utmost that it can do for a missionary, in such a case 
 as we are now supposing, is to secure for him freedom 
 from molestation, and such a freedom, so secured, may 
 actually be a hindrance to his spiritual task. As it 
 is hardly necessary to point out, the noblest mis- 
 sionary achievements in the world — those of the apos- 
 toHc age, or of the Church after the fall of the Roman 
 Empire, or of the early Jesuits — ^were those of men who 
 enjoyed no such security, and had no other resources 
 than those of their own temper and intelligence, and 
 the beauty of the truth which they had to impart. 
 Against the use of arms, as a direct support to the 
 cause of religion, the Crucifixion — the greatest mis- 
 sionary event the world has ever known — bears its 
 eternal testimony. 
 
 So far, then, as what we have called the spiritual 
 life is concerned — the life of the home, the Church, 
 the school, or the theatre, as resting on an inner 
 state of feeling and intelligence — it cannot be shown 
 that war is a good, that it is a means indispensably 
 subservient to the ends which this life proposes to 
 itself. It can be shown, on the contrary, that war, 
 by its essential methods and objects — being methods 
 and objects of slaughter and destruction — ^is in natural 
 antagonism to the methods and objects of the 
 spiritual Hfe. But the Catholic life — by which we 
 mean, once more, the total, ordered Hfe of man — 
 has also, as we have seen, a temporal side. It is 
 concerned with what we call the State, with the 
 organization and maintenance of the nation, as such ; 
 it is concerned, too, ultimately, and fundamentally. 
 
WAR AND THE SPIRITUAL LIFE 171 
 
 with man’s action upon the earth. It is only arbi- 
 trarily and provisionally that one of these sides of 
 the Catholic life — of a full - flowering, ordered 
 humanity — can be separated from the other. They 
 are, in fact, indissolubly connected and interdepen- 
 dent. Therefore, if it can be proved that war is a 
 good, that it is inevitably necessary, relatively to 
 the temporal life, it must be held to be also necessary, 
 and a good, relatively to the spiritual life, even 
 although it does not directly enter into the aims and 
 methods of that life. Stating the same propositions 
 in another way, we may say that, although war is 
 not immediately subservient to the affections and 
 mind of the home, the Church, the school, and the 
 theatre, it may still be considered to be indispensable 
 to the security of the political and material foundation 
 on which they rest. A Scientiflc Catholicism, pre- 
 cisely because it is scientific, is bound to consider this 
 question. 
 
CHAPTER VI 
 
 WAR AND POLITICAL LIFE 
 
 It is, as we have said, the office of science, in regard 
 to Catholicism, to enable it to see things and represent 
 them as they are — the things of man and of the 
 Universal Order, with which he is in dependent and 
 modifying relation. This, up to the present, Catholi- 
 cism, being an expression of the mind of man, has not 
 been able to do, its conception of the world and 
 humanity, and therefore of God, having been shaped 
 and symbolized at a time when human experience 
 and reason were immature. Catholicism, however, 
 may now become scientific — that is to say, it may 
 stand for the total, developed mind of man become, 
 in its range of observation and inference, complete. 
 Catholicism, so understood, while it continues to use 
 its old scriptures, formulas, images, and institutions, 
 will know how far they are a right representation of 
 man in his maturity, how far they need to be 
 reinterpreted and supplemented. There is, for ex- 
 ample, in the Gospel poems a magisterial dictum 
 bearing upon the spiritual life which is, in a given 
 construction of it, profoundly and beautifully true, 
 but which is, in another sense, a sentence of evident 
 impossibility. That dictum is “ seek first the King- 
 dom of God, and His righteousness.” We have, in 
 this treatise, conformed to the principle which is 
 
WAR AND POLITICAL LIFE 
 
 173 
 
 thus set forth by first endeavouring to ascertain the 
 End of Life, and by then considering the question of 
 peace in relation to it. Such a method is plainly 
 imposed upon us when we are considering man as a 
 being of high intelligence and will, moved by an inner 
 vision of Perfection, and acting upon himself and his 
 environment with a view to its realization. God, 
 therefore — God being the Universal Order, contained 
 and presented to us symbolically and prophetically 
 in the human and personal Order of Christ — must 
 be seen to be the End of our being when we are con- 
 sciously and deliberately marshalling all our forces, 
 external and internal, and stamping them with 
 purpose. 
 
 In practice, however, we must adopt an inverse 
 method. The first Adam is of the earth — earthy. 
 In less parabolical language, man is, to begin with, 
 an animal. There is no disgrace in this — nothing to 
 be ashamed of ; at any rate, it is a fact. According 
 to the poem of Genesis, man was made an animal 
 and a companion of animals, but also a perfect 
 being and the companion of God. Before the Fall, 
 as afterwards, he had to eat and drink, and he had 
 as his associate a being of a different sex from himself. 
 Whatever our view of the Scriptures of the Old and 
 New Testaments, however, it is evident that man is 
 what he is — a being who must eat and drink, and who, 
 for the satisfaction of his own impulses, or the con- 
 tinuance of the human race, must be joined to a 
 being of a different sex from himself. The religious 
 celibate can so far order himself as to master his own 
 
174 the problem OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 passions, and determine that no other bodily life 
 shall proceed from his own, but even he cannot live 
 without eating and drinking, and he also requires 
 clothing and habitation, warmth and light. While, 
 therefore, it is true, as we have said, that the Catholic 
 life may be summed up as prayer and agriculture — 
 an order of Perfection in Christ, individual and social, 
 dependent on what man can get from the earth — 
 it is also true that, practically speaking, agriculture 
 must come first, or, as Comte expresses it, that “ the 
 higher order rests upon the lower.” To use the 
 familiar expression, while we ought not to live to 
 eat, we must eat to live. While, therefore, the 
 question of whether war is or is not a good depends 
 upon our conception of the End of Life, it is neces- 
 sarily also dependent on the relation of what is dis- 
 tinctively spiritual in the Catholic Hfe to the material 
 foundation on which it rests. 
 
 The problem of war is, as has been seen, immediately 
 connected with the problem of nationality, or the 
 external relations of the State. In a strictly scientific 
 sense, that is, as we have also seen, an insufiicient 
 view to take of it, for there have been, and may be 
 again, civil wars, and we may be forced upon the 
 conclusion that the causes which, in our modern 
 world, are provocative of international strife are in 
 intimate connection with those which might con- 
 ceivably bring about a civil war, and which do, in 
 fact, keep almost all European countries in a state 
 of constant political unrest and conflict. WTiat we 
 are immediately concerned with, however, is the war 
 
WAR AND POLITICAL LIFE 
 
 175 
 
 of States or nations. Now, whether war is, relatively 
 to the nation, a good is a question which itself admits 
 of being considered from two chief points of view. 
 One of these is an industrial point of view ; the 
 other is, in a more definite sense, political. Again, 
 it is necessary, for an orderly discussion of the 
 question, to draw the obvious distinction between 
 offensive and defensive war. There can, of course, 
 be no defensive war without offensive war, and a 
 war of defence evidently does not raise the same 
 questions of principle as a war of aggression. 
 Unless a given people has made up its mind to submit 
 to the demands or overlordship of another State, it 
 may be forced into a war, whatever its views as to 
 the abstract value of peace. The question of the 
 good of war is, then, the question of the good of 
 aggressive war — of a war deliberately and intention- 
 ally undertaken to promote some purpose of policy 
 which cannot, on the hypothesis, be otherwise 
 secured. 
 
 Again, it is important to recognize that if a given 
 aggressive war is, in this sense, a good — being the 
 indispensable means to a good — it cannot be held to 
 be an evil because it is contrary to our sentiments of 
 humanity. The execution of a murderer, or the 
 prolonged imprisonment of a thief, does violence to 
 certain sentiments of humanity, and yet we are 
 compelled to acquiesce in these evils for the sake of 
 what seems to us a social need. According to our 
 traditional conception of God, He is an Omnipotent 
 Being who permits the continuous misery of the 
 
176 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 human race in this life because He cannot abolish this 
 misery without destroying the good of free will, and He 
 destines a large part of it to eternal torment in a 
 future state because it is impossible for Him to act 
 otherwise without the violation of His own justice. 
 In the same way, we are told that at the battle of 
 Omdurman in 1898 a British army, under Lord 
 Kitchener, killed 11,000 Arabs and wounded 16,000 
 others in fifteen minutes.* Such a proceeding, in an 
 age when many persons protest even against animal 
 vivisection, might seem to be an odious butchery, 
 but, from another point of view, it may be regarded 
 as only an incident in the reclamation and pacification 
 of the Soudan ; and if the ascendency of England in 
 the world is a good, then, on a principle which was 
 at one time supposed to be exclusively Jesuitic, the 
 means which are indispensable to it must be held to 
 be justifiable. The lesser humanity must give way 
 to what appears to us the greater. We know, more- 
 over, that when a battle is in progress it is not the 
 object of the commander on either side to kill as few 
 of the enemy as possible, but to gain the victory — 
 a purpose compared with which all others are then 
 insignificant. He kills, therefore, few or many, 
 according to the exigencies of the combat, and he 
 is not in a position to enter on any scrupulous cal- 
 culations as to the amount of slaughter which may 
 be actually required. It is true that in our modern 
 world the machine-gun and the bayonet are com- 
 
 * “ The Life of Spencer Compton, Eighth Duke of Devonshire,” 
 by Bernard Holland, Vol. II., p. 44. 
 
WAR AND POLITICAL LIFE 
 
 177 
 
 monly accompanied by the surgeon, the nurse, and 
 the priest, who are, within certain limits, instruments 
 of benevolence and reparation ; but it is none the 
 less obvious that for the purposes of war, as such, the 
 feeling of humanity must be held in suspense. The 
 soldier, like the butcher or the executioner, is the 
 minister of what is believed to be a social need. 
 The difference between his function and theirs is 
 mainly a difference of scale and equipment, although 
 it may perhaps be said that the office of the butcher 
 is in this sense more important that he is directly 
 concerned with the nourishment of the human race. 
 
 When, therefore, we are considering whether war 
 is, from the point of view of the national life, an 
 indispensable good, we must, first, understand by 
 “ war ” a war voluntary and aggressive, planned and 
 undertaken for the accomplishment of a specific pur- 
 pose ; secondly, we must dismiss from our minds the 
 question of the “ inhumanity ” of war. If a proposed 
 war is, on a total survey of it, justifiable, we are 
 entitled to bring it about, and if we are entitled to 
 bring it about we must recognize that war is, by its 
 essential nature and processes, a suspension of the 
 law of humanity. It is a specific application of 
 material force directed to bloodshed and destruction. 
 It is this most of all in our modern world, in which 
 a battle is carried on by the use of a scientific mechan- 
 ism and a general is only an engineer of slaughter. 
 When we have recognized this, however, we must 
 also recognize that the question of whether a nation 
 is “ justified ” in bringing about a war, or in pursuing 
 
178 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 a policy such as must render war inevitable, cannot 
 be decided from the standpoint of the nation alone, 
 politically and industrially considered. It can only 
 rightly be determined, as we are trying to determine 
 it here, from the standpoint of a Catholicism become 
 scientific, and thus rendered capable of seeing the 
 relation of what we have called the temporal life — 
 the life of citizenship and industry — to the spiritual. 
 The distinctive institution of the temporal life is the 
 State, using this, for the sake of simplicity, as a 
 term inclusive of both political and industrial govern- 
 ment ; the distinctive institution of the spiritual life 
 is the Church. Now the mind of the Church is, 
 according to our conception of it, science. It sees 
 and foresees. It is, in principle, universal. It is 
 international, as is science in the ordinary and 
 accepted sense of the word — the science of the natural 
 order. It is for the Church, therefore — the developed 
 mind of man, pursuing Perfection in Christ — to give 
 its law to the nation, or State. It is clear that, apart 
 from such a Catholicism, the nation is, for inter- 
 national purposes, what in fact we see it at present 
 to be, a law unto itself, or is without law. Its only 
 rule of action is derived from what it believes to be 
 its own exclusive interest, and the power which it 
 possesses of enforcing it. If there is to be any other 
 rule of national action than this — which is a rule 
 secularistic and local — it must be one carrying men’s 
 minds beyond the limits of a particular country, and 
 enabling them to see the temporal order of the nation 
 as part of a spiritual order greater than itself. That 
 
WAR AND POLITICAL LIFE 
 
 179 
 
 greater spiritual order is the Catholic Church, con- 
 ceived of as representing and directing the whole life 
 of humanity, and with its centre and head in Rome. 
 
 From the point of view of international policy — ^the 
 only point of view which immediately concerns us — a 
 State has been defined as any people, or aggregate of 
 peoples, however dissimilar in language, religion, race, 
 or situation, having an independent and sovereign 
 character, and possessing a responsible, co-ordinating 
 Government, for internal and external purposes. In 
 such a use of it, the word “ State ” has a range of 
 meaning inclusive at once of the smallest of free 
 European nationalities and of so vast a political 
 conglomerate as the British or Russian Empire. The 
 question which we have to determine is how far for 
 any such State war may be so indispensable a good, 
 political or industrial, that it is entitled deliberately 
 to bring it about, or to pursue a policy which may 
 render it inevitable. This, of course, is quite distinct 
 from the question of the character and composition of 
 a particular State. From a certain point of view, it 
 may be held that the processes by which, for example, 
 the British and Russian Empires have been built up 
 and maintained are indefensible, but that is not our 
 present subject. We are supposing ourselves to start 
 from a given international status quo, however that 
 status quo may have been created, and whether or 
 not we consider it to rest on ideal relations, internal 
 or external. The installation and maintenance of a 
 Human Peace require that this status quo shall be 
 regarded as not to be subject to forcible disturbance. 
 
i8o THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 and that there shall be a consequent disarmament and 
 the common adhesion to a policy in harmony with 
 such a proceeding. What we have immediately to 
 decide is how far for any given State there may be 
 some political good, which it is entitled to set against 
 the assumed good of a Human Peace. 
 
 We may simplify the discussion of this question by 
 going back to what we have already said as to the 
 one policy which is, by its native character, inevitably 
 a cause of war. That policy we have called the policy 
 of imperialism. We must, however, for the purposes 
 of a practical discussion, understand the word 
 “ imperialism ” in a sense at once comprehensive and 
 specific. We shall, therefore, define it as a policy by 
 which any one State, or combination of States, seeks 
 to forcibly interfere with the possessions or domestic 
 action of any other State, whatever may be the 
 motives of this policy, and whether it is directed to a 
 temporary or a permanent purpose. The reason why 
 we call such a policy a policy of imperialism is plain. 
 It is, whatever its ultimate aims may be, a policy by 
 which one nation attempts to exercise a certain over- 
 lordship over another, and it cannot be accomplished 
 except by arms. It is an attack upon the freedom 
 and independence of one people by another, and it is 
 this whether it is inspired by what may be called a 
 high and disinterested intention, or by evident pur- 
 poses of territorial acquisition or conquest. We are, 
 to begin with, not entitled to use the word “ impe- 
 rialism ” as necessarily denoting what, from a certain 
 standpoint, might be considered an “ evil ” policy. 
 
WAR AND POLITICAL LIFE i8i 
 
 We use it because it is the right word for any policy 
 directed against the sovereign authority of an inde- 
 pendent people and carrying with it a consequence of 
 war. Such a policy may vary greatly in its professed 
 intentions and in its effects, but if it is stamped with 
 these two characteristics it is imperialism. 
 
 Let us, by way of illustration, take the policy 
 which has from time to time been pursued by various 
 Western Powers in regard to the relations between 
 the Turkish Government and some of its subjects. 
 We may, for the sake of argument, assume that this 
 policy was, on the part of all the Powers concerned in 
 it, entirely “ disinterested ” — that its only motives 
 were to satisfy a certain Western feeling in regard to 
 Turkish misgovernment and to put an end to its 
 abuses. Even so, it was a policy of imperialism — a 
 policy by which an external authority sought to 
 substitute itself, in degree, and for certain specific 
 purposes, for the internal authority of the Turkish 
 Empire. As such it was a policy which sooner or 
 later, if it was ever to be effective, was bound to bring 
 about war. There is, of course, in the constitution 
 of a sovereign State, nothing more fundamental than 
 the relation between its people and its Government. 
 It is vital. If that relation is interfered with from 
 without, even for temporary and limited purposes, the 
 independence of the State is infringed. No Govern- 
 ment, as is obvious, has any responsibility to the 
 Government of other countries for its action with 
 regard to its own subjects ; and in the same way no 
 people has any responsibility to any external authority 
 
1 82 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 for its proceedings with regard to its own rulers. The 
 relations between the Government and the governed 
 are organic. They are reciprocal. They spring 
 from the inherent life of a particular people, which 
 has its own situation, its own standards, its own 
 needs, its own evils, and its own natural remedy 
 for those evils. The Government of any sovereign 
 State ought to be free to govern, well or ill, 
 and its subjects ought to be free to submit to 
 it, or to revolt against it and change it, if they 
 have the power. It is clear that to bring in an 
 exotic agency, either to enable a Government to 
 rule, or to enable a people to resist, is to destroy the 
 integrity of the national life, and to substitute, in 
 greater or less degree, the authority of another State 
 for the authority of the State which is thus interfered 
 with. This is imperialism ; and it is none the less 
 imperialism because its professed and immediate pur- 
 pose may not be territorial acquisition or the expan- 
 sion of empire. It is a policy of usurpation and over- 
 lordship, involving war. Further, although it may 
 not be consciously directed towards empire, such a 
 policy almost inevitably creates new imperial responsi- 
 bilities, the one act of external intervention entailing 
 others, and leading eventually to the subjugation of 
 the people whose organic independence has thus been 
 impaired. 
 
 We have taken the case of Western action in 
 Turkey as an example of one form of imperialism, but 
 it is quite easy to conceive of others. Russia is, as 
 we have already pointed out, for certain purposes 
 
WAR AND POLITICAL LIFE 
 
 183 
 
 not to be reckoned among Western States. She 
 represents a late and immature civilization, and, as 
 is well known, her methods of domestic government 
 have often inspired disapproval and indignation in 
 Western countries — especially England. If, under 
 the influence of such sentiments, England were to 
 interfere with the internal administration of the 
 Russian Government, that would be an act of 
 imperiahsm. There is no probability of such inter- 
 ference, not because there may not seem to be, from 
 a certain point of view, a moral or political justifica- 
 tion for it, but because, from the nature of the case, 
 a successful imperialism — the effective intervention 
 of a foreign Power in the internal affairs of a sovereign 
 State — is only possible when that State is unable to 
 resist it. When it is a powerful empire, such as 
 Russia, or such as Japan has now become, it may be 
 subject, of course, to adverse external criticism, but is 
 exempt from actual interference. The same thing is 
 true of England. British rule in Ireland and India 
 has often been accused — even by some Englishmen — 
 of being unjust and injurious. We need not here 
 discuss the question of whether the charge is, or is 
 not, well founded. All that now concerns us is that 
 any attempt to adopt with regard to England such a 
 policy as England has adopted with regard to Turkey 
 would be an act of imperialistic encroachment. It 
 would be a policy involving war, for the simple reason 
 that it could only take effect by war. As in the case 
 of Russia, there is no probability that such a policy 
 will be adopted. England is at present too powerful 
 
1 84 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 a State for this to be possible. Such a supposition, 
 however, serves, along with the other considerations 
 which we have adduced, to place the policy of 
 imperialism in a clear light. It is a policy directed, 
 by its essential nature, against the independence of a 
 sovereign State. It can only take practical ejEect by 
 war. It can never be prosecuted, whatever its alleged 
 justification, except by a more powerful country 
 against a less powerful. It brings about a disruption 
 of the organic relations between the Government 
 which is interfered with and its subjects, and tends 
 to prevent their natural readjustment. It commonly 
 renders necessary still further external interference, 
 and it leads eventually to the open and complete 
 imperialism of territorial aggrandizement. 
 
 There is one other important consequence of such 
 an imperialism — whether directed against a country 
 like Turkey, or against some native State in Asia or 
 Africa — which, when what we are concerned with 
 is a Human Peace, it is necessary here to recall. 
 Given the existing international relations of Christen- 
 dom, the policy of imperialism, whatever its professed 
 purposes, cannot be adopted by any one of the 
 Western Powers without endangering its good rela- 
 tions with others. There is no disposition anywhere 
 to believe in a purely disinterested national action. 
 That is natural. The rule of “ interests ” — British 
 interests, German interests, Italian interests, French 
 interests, Russian or Austrian interests — is the avowed 
 and common rule of international policy. Whatever 
 may be the other alleged motives of his action, no 
 
WAR AND POLITICAL LIFE 
 
 185 
 
 European statesman can justify a policy which may 
 involve a sacrifice of blood and treasure except on 
 the ground that it is demanded by the security or 
 advantage of his own country. Further, almost all 
 experience goes to show that external interference in 
 the internal affairs of a country leads inevitably to 
 its further political enfeeblement and to its ultimate 
 absorption by the stronger State. Consequently the 
 imperialism of England or Russia gives rise to a 
 competing imperialism of France, Germany, and Italy. 
 It tends to bring about war, not merely between an 
 aggressive and a resisting nation, but between a 
 number of rival Powers, each holding itself entitled 
 to put forward some plea of civilization or progress 
 as the ground of its action, each having its own 
 “ interests ” to promote, each being a law unto itself} 
 and each being suspicious and jealous of others. It is 
 obvious that, as we have already pointed out, there 
 is now no rule of international action for any of the 
 Great Powers of Christendom except one which is 
 derived from its conception of its own responsibilities, 
 its own interests, and its own resources. To the 
 hostile judgment of other countries it pays no atten- 
 tion, unless this seems to point to some actual danger 
 attending the prosecution of its aims. At the time of 
 the English war against the South African Republics 
 there was undoubtedly a considerable body of Euro- 
 pean opinion unfavourable to British policy. It is 
 not here necessary to analyse the grounds of that 
 opinion. The essential point at present is that it 
 was opinion only, and had, therefore, no effect on 
 
1 86 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 English action. England was, and claimed to be, 
 her own judge. She was subject to no external 
 spiritual tribunal. She made war for her own cause 
 and in her own way. Exactly the same thing, of 
 course, would have been true of any other of the 
 European Powers in similar circumstances. They 
 may criticize one another and condemn one another, 
 but they are not in a position to judge one another. 
 For judgment there must be a competent, disinte- 
 rested, and recognized tribunal. In the case of private 
 conflicts such a tribunal exists within the limits of 
 the national life. In the case of international conflicts 
 it does not exist. Two hostile nations, therefore, can 
 only abuse one another and fight. 
 
 We have considered one particular type of imperial- 
 istic action — a type actually given in experience. 
 There are, however, various other types of the same 
 essential policy — a policy of aggressive interference, 
 involving war, and leading to territorial acquisition. 
 The motives of such a policy, for example, may be 
 aflinities of language, race, or religion between the 
 subjects of one State and the subjects of another, and 
 these motives, of course, become strengthened if the 
 inhabitants of a given country believe that those who 
 are in any way akin to them in another are suffering 
 under injustice or oppression. Conditions such as 
 these are naturally common. The great States of the 
 world have not been built up on what we should now 
 call a sociological principle — with an intention to 
 bring together under a single rule peoples having 
 natural ties of speech, or faith, or race, or culture. 
 
WAR AND POLITICAL LIFE 
 
 187 
 
 There has been no “ State planning ” comparable 
 with the “ town planning ” which, after towns have 
 grown as they could, has of late been proposed. 
 There has been no rule in the shaping of States 
 except the rule of force and conquest. That rule 
 has brought together a number of heterogeneous 
 and unassimilable elements in an artificial order, 
 which frequently, even after many centuries, has 
 remained unstable and insecure. Everyone can see 
 instances of this in the present composition of Europe. 
 In such a situation imperialism finds a natural 
 opportunity. It is, in this relation, an attempt by 
 force of arms to reverse or modify a state of things 
 which the force of arms has created. Even where 
 there is no urgent popular demand for such an attempt, 
 the Government of one country, recognizing the affini- 
 ties between some of its subjects and the subjects 
 of another State, has a natural inducement to take 
 advantage of them for the purpose of enlarging its 
 dominions. Here again, as it is hardly necessary to 
 say, we have a type of imperialism given in experience. 
 
 So far, the imperialism we have considered has 
 been of what may be called a distinctively political 
 character. The pretext of such a policy, of course, may 
 be one thing ; its actual motives may be quite another. 
 In all its forms, nevertheless, and whatever its pre- 
 texts or motives, this political imperialism has always 
 certain essential characteristics and effects ; it is 
 action directed by one country against the sovereign 
 independence of another, and it carries with it war 
 as a necessary consequence — a war which, in the 
 
1 88 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 modern intimacy and intricacy of international 
 relations, tends to become general. There is, how- 
 ever, a kind of imperialism even more important at 
 the present time than what we have called poHtical 
 imperialism. It is more important because it is more 
 universal and because, by its essential nature, it 
 raises questions which are fundamental and ever- 
 lasting in the economy of human Hfe. In contra- 
 distinction to a purely political imperialism, we may 
 describe it as industrial imperialism. A political 
 imperialism is professedly inspired by what we com- 
 monly regard as political objects — dynastic preten- 
 sions, the aggrandizement of a State, the correction of 
 abuses in some other country, the satisfaction of 
 religious, racial or linguistic affinities. Industrial 
 imperialism is immediately directed towards that 
 action upon the earth — that basic art of agriculture — 
 upon which, as we have seen, the Catholic life, the 
 life of individual and social Perfection in Christ, in 
 the last resort rests. It is not too much to say that 
 while political imperialism has played, and still plays, 
 an important part in bringing about war, the imperial- 
 ism of our modern world is essentially, and increas- 
 ingly, industrial. It is conceivable even that while 
 against a merely political imperialism a Scientific 
 Catholicism might create an international under- 
 standing, against industrial imperialism it would still 
 be powerless. 
 
 The reason for this is obvious. The motives 
 entering into a political imperialism — the splendour 
 and exaltation of a State or its rulers, or the satis- 
 
WAR AND POLITICAL LIFE 189 
 
 faction of national, religious, or linguistic affinities — 
 are of unequal force at different times and in different 
 classes of the same community. They are dependent 
 largely upon changing conditions of belief and culture. 
 They appeal most to the governing and military 
 classes of a nation, and least to what we call its 
 “ lower classes.” To the governing and mihtary classes 
 a mere extension of empire, as such, means increased 
 opportunities for gaining power and distinction — ^not 
 wealth only, but social ascendency and command. 
 The motives inspiring industrial imperialism are, on 
 the contrary, universal. They are of all classes. 
 They are, if we may use the expression, biological. 
 They are connected with the primary animal Hfe of 
 man. They are connected, too, with his highest 
 spiritual life, which necessarily rests upon the lower. 
 There can be no Church without the workshop. In 
 the Lord’s Prayer we confess our need for our daily 
 bread, but the prayer is only a prelude to action. It 
 is never “ granted ” until we grant it to ourselves. 
 What is granted, or given, is the earth, with heat and 
 light, air and water, and the mind and body of man, 
 the worker. If man, who prays for bread, cannot win 
 his bread from the earth he dies, just as any animal, 
 insect, or plant must die, unless it can gain from its 
 environment the means of life. Prayer is always, 
 in one of its aspects, an expression of need — ^whether 
 an immediate need of the body, or a high spiritual 
 need of the soul — and throughout the wide range of 
 its meanings it has no outward effect except where 
 it is a prelude to human action. The need which we 
 
190 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 express in the prayer for bread is so basic and impera- 
 tive that if it could be shown that, for its satisfaction, 
 war is indispensable, a Human Peace would be for 
 ever impossible, and a Scientific Catholicism, ordering 
 the total life of man for an end of Perfection, would 
 have to sanction war as one of its means. As, there- 
 fore, it is for such a CathoHcism to determine how far 
 the political exigencies of the State demand war, so 
 it must also consider whether it is rendered necessary 
 by man’s action upon the earth for the purposes of 
 the Catholic life. 
 
CHAPTER VII 
 
 INDUSTRIAL IMPERIALISM 
 
 It is the essential note of a Scientific Catholicism — 
 of a Catholicism resting on the fully-developed mind 
 of man, and fulfilling all the sides of his nature for an 
 end of Perfection — that it is, as we say, synthetic. 
 As such, it does not recognize any fundamental separa- 
 tion between man’s industrial action and the other 
 manifestations of his life. Into any one of the exer- 
 cises of his will the forces of his total being, such as it 
 is, and in degree, may be poured. Man, therefore, 
 labouring upon the earth, labours for Christ — that is 
 to say, for the realization of an ideal humanity. 
 Expressing the same principle in other terms, we may 
 say, again, that from what he gets from the earth he 
 has to build the workshop, the State, the theatre — 
 considered as a temple and symbol of the arts — the 
 school, the Church, and the home. Now, in our 
 modern world — the world in which a Human Peace 
 is to be wrought, if it is ever to be wrought — man is, 
 as he was never before, an inhabitant of the whole 
 earth. He may be, from the point of view of national 
 classification, a Frenchman, an Englishman, a German, 
 or a Chinaman, but he is also a citizen of the world. 
 This has ceased to be a figure of sentiment ; it has 
 become a fact of experience. There was a time when 
 almost any individual family could feed, clothe, and 
 
192 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 house itself within the limits in which it found itself. 
 Its members could live and die where they were 
 born, without being called upon to remove from their 
 own district. There was a time when what was 
 thus true of the family was also, in a great degree, 
 true of the city and the nation — so far at least as the 
 necessaries of life, as distinguished from luxuries, 
 were concerned. In so far as such conditions 
 obtained, a nation — here using the word “ nation ” 
 to denote an independent, organized, sovereign 
 people, exclusively occupying a definite territory — 
 was not only a law unto itself, but sufficient unto 
 itself. So long as it preserved its political freedom 
 it could live its own life, in every material and political 
 sense of this word, in its own way. Under such 
 circumstances “ man ” was not an inhabitant of 
 the whole earth. He was an inhabitant only of his 
 own country. He was, from a geographical point of 
 view, a Frenchman, an Englishman, or an Italian, as 
 the case might be. 
 
 It is one of the most obvious and elementary facts 
 of our modern experience that this has long ceased 
 to be the case. There is even now, of course, a 
 certain difference in the degree in which the various 
 nations of the world are able, within their own 
 borders, to procure for themselves what we call the 
 necessaries of life. Some are more dependent upon 
 other countries, some less. That is largely a question 
 of climate, soil, mineral resources, extent of popula- 
 tion, and industrial habit. Allowing for all such 
 differences, however, it still remains true that “ man,” 
 
INDUSTRIAL IMPERIALISM 
 
 193 
 
 in our modern world, has become, not in feeling only, 
 but in fact, ever less a merely national being, and 
 ever more an international being. From the stand- 
 point of mind of course — of that life of religion, art, 
 philosophy, and science which rests upon the lower 
 material life — the European man at least has been 
 progressively an international being, and not merely 
 a national being, from the time of the Roman Empire 
 onward. In his spirit he is, in proportion to his 
 culture, universal. What we are immediately con- 
 cerned with, however, is life in the lower, or biological, 
 sense of the term — the relation of the developed 
 human organism with its environment. Under- 
 standing the word “ life ” in this sense, it is clear that 
 an Englishman, for example, no longer lives in 
 England. He derives food, clothing, and even, in 
 degree, the means of habitation, from other countries 
 — some of them extremely distant ; and he is depen- 
 dent upon other countries almost in proportion to the 
 range and elevation of his life as a civilized being. 
 This is no new truth ; it is a truism ; but it is a 
 truth, or truism, the full significance of which, so 
 far as the constitution and policy of the world’s 
 nations are concerned, has hardly yet been sufficiently 
 recognized. We may hold, if we please, that this 
 change, or extension, in the habitat of the Englishman, 
 Frenchman, or German — a change reconcilable with 
 the actual fixity of the mass of the population — is 
 not a good but an evil. It is a change which certainly 
 involves an immense number of human beings in a 
 ceaseless nomad restlessness, detrimental to their 
 
194 the problem OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 social and civic life ; and it has increased the com- 
 plexity and instability of all industrial and political 
 relations. Such as it is, however, it is apparently 
 irreversible, and one of its effects is to make man, 
 wherever he may happen to be born and to live, 
 not so much a Frenchman or an Englishman as a 
 cosmopolite, dependent for his material nourishment, 
 as he has long been dependent for his intellectual 
 nourishment, on countries remote from his actual habi- 
 tation, and on the co-operating activities of mankind. 
 
 It is a certain recognition of this truth which has 
 no doubt been the main cause of the later industrial 
 imperialism of various European States. Industrial 
 imperialism, as distinguished from a purely political 
 imperialism, may be defined as an attempt by pro- 
 cesses of policy and conquest to secure for a nation 
 direct and wider command over the resources of the 
 earth, instead of the indirect command gained by 
 means of commercial exchange with other nations. 
 It is an artificial extension of the national environ- 
 ment, or, in terms of trade, the creation of a larger 
 subject area of supply and demand. Imperialism, 
 for such purposes, is of course not the same thing as 
 emigration or colonization. An emigrant may go 
 to a foreign country — as an Englishman or German 
 to the United States, or an Italian to Brazil — ^and 
 settle there as one of its citizens. A colonist may go — 
 as Europeans of all sorts have gone — to a partially- 
 occupied country, such as Australia or New Zealand, 
 and found there a new citizenship, superseding or 
 subordinating the native, uncivilized races. A colony 
 
INDUSTRIAL IMPERIALISM 
 
 195 
 
 which has been thus established may come in time to 
 be, especially for commercial purposes, a self-govern- 
 ing and independent country, and in this sense it 
 ceases to be a subject part of the empire with which 
 it is in nominal connection. It is to all intents and 
 purposes a new nation. These distinctions, obvious 
 and important as they are, are often overlooked in 
 political discussions, the word “ empire,” for example, 
 being employed to describe at once such a relation as 
 that between England and India and the totally 
 different relation which exists between England and 
 Canada or Australia. 
 
 The chief type of industrial imperialism — meaning 
 by this, once more, an imperialism directed mainly 
 to industrial as distinguished from political ends — is 
 to be found in the policy which England has, more 
 or less consciously and systematically, for many years 
 pursued. The reasons for this are obvious. England 
 is a relatively small country, with a large and expand- 
 ing population. She has the advantage, but also the 
 disadvantage, of an insular situation. She has a 
 high degree of social development, with a constant 
 increase in the range of her social needs. She is, by 
 her natural position, largely cut off from the rest of 
 Europe. The English people, therefore, have been 
 driven to look outside their own shores, and even 
 beyond Europe, for a wider environment — for a 
 fuller command over the resources of the earth. They 
 have been great emigrants, great colonists, but they 
 have been also great imperialists, in the sense of this 
 word which we have now established ; and they have, 
 
 N 2 
 
196 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 of late years especially, been influenced by the con- 
 ception of a world-wide “ empire,” comprising both 
 colonies and conquests, within which they may 
 exercise the same direct control over the earth as is 
 naturally exercised by a “ nation,” in the strict sense 
 of the word, actually occupying and cultivating its 
 own territory. There is no scientific probability that 
 the British Empire, thus constituted — the rule of a 
 small island over immense continents and hetero- 
 geneous populations thousands of miles remote from 
 it — will be permanent. The whole course of the 
 world’s development will be against it. That, how- 
 ever, is not our present subject. What we are now 
 concerned to recognize is, first, that British industrial 
 imperialism is only the chief type of a policy which 
 has been of late increasingly pursued by various 
 European nations, great and small ; secondly, that 
 this policy is, as is a policy of political imperialism, a 
 policy of war. This policy may be, from a given 
 standpoint, defensible. It may be regarded as indis- 
 pensable. But it is, by its essential character, a 
 mode of action which needs the force of arms to 
 give effect to it. 
 
 European industrial imperialism, as such, is, we 
 may say broadly, not directed immediately against 
 European territories. Almost all these territories are 
 now fully peopled. This has, for the time being, 
 ceased to be true of France, where there is now a 
 declining population, but it is sufficiently true of the 
 rest of Europe. Except, therefore, when the indus- 
 trial imperialism of a European State aims at access 
 
INDUSTRIAL IMPERIALISM 
 
 197 
 
 to the sea, its main concern is to gain command over 
 non-European territories rather than over contiguous 
 countries. One reason for this is to be found in that 
 natural ascendency of “ Christendom ” over “ non- 
 Christendom ” to which we have already referred. 
 Christendom represents the potency of a high civili- 
 zation — the power of mind, the power of capital. It 
 represents, too, the machine-gun — the immense 
 superiority in the weapons of destruction which is 
 possessed by a modern European State as compared 
 with a barbarous or backward people. The distinc- 
 tion between an industrial imperialism prosecuted in 
 Europe and one which seeks its fields in Africa or 
 Asia is, however, not vital. The essential thing to 
 be recognized in it is that wherever it is prosecuted it 
 means war. It means war, first, because no people, 
 however defenceless and backward it may be, will- 
 ingly submits to an alien rule within its own territory ; 
 secondly, because no one country can engage in such 
 a policy — a policy of industrial ascendency based on 
 constant territorial extension — without provoking 
 jealousy and competition, and without, therefore, 
 incurring the danger of a war with countries as power- 
 ful as itself. Industrial imperialism, consequently, 
 does not merely mean war between a great nation 
 and a small, or between a civilized State and a 
 barbarous one, or between Christendom and non- 
 Christendom ; it means a war of empires, in which 
 civilization and Christendom themselves become 
 involved, and it means this naturally and inevitably. 
 The competition in industrial imperialism is, like the 
 
198 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 competition in industry itself, at bottom biological, 
 or animal. It is a part of the struggle for human 
 existence. Its object is to gain a favoured place in 
 the environment — that basic command over the earth 
 on which the life of man in all its senses, lower or 
 higher, his material life, his Catholic, or spiritual, life, 
 in the last resort rests. 
 
 What a Scientific Catholicism has to decide with 
 regard to industrial imperialism, as with regard to 
 political imperialism, is how far it is indispensable — 
 how far, that is to say, it is necessary for that com- 
 mand over the resources of the earth which is requisite 
 for the ends of the Catholic life. This is, of course, a 
 scientific question, and it can only be determined 
 scientifically. We cannot determine it simply by 
 reaffirming the great spiritual purposes of Catholicism 
 and insisting on their value and beauty. If it is 
 true, as we have said, that the Catholic life can be 
 summed up as prayer and agriculture, it may be also 
 true that the life of agriculture is naturally restrictive 
 of the life of prayer. If it is true that imperialism 
 is impossible without war and that war is impossible 
 without a suspension of the law of humanity, still it 
 may be necessary for man, as a worker upon the 
 earth, to be an imperialist, to conquer his fellow- 
 beings, that he may live. We cannot solve this 
 problem any more than we can solve other problems 
 of human life, merely by denouncing what seems to 
 us evil and extolling what seems to us good. 
 
 The question of industrial imperialism, as we have 
 defined it — the attempt of a given nation to gain 
 
INDUSTRIAL IMPERIALISM 
 
 199 
 
 for itself an increased command over the resources 
 of the earth by an extension of territory — is in our 
 contemporary world, as it has been throughout 
 history, largely a question of the pressure of popula- 
 tion upon the means of subsistence. This, even in 
 its modern, theoretic form, is, of course, no new 
 question. There have been various proposals for 
 dealing with it— among others, the artificial limitation 
 of the family. This proposal has been by some 
 denounced, partly on what are considered to be moral 
 grounds, but also because they hold that the alleged 
 need for the restriction of population does not really 
 exist. It is this latter view of the matter which, 
 from the standpoint of a Scientific Catholicism, at 
 present chiefly concerns us. The view may be con- 
 veniently expressed in the familiar formula that 
 “ when God sends mouths He sends bread to feed 
 them.” Now before we can pronounce on the truth 
 or falsity of the assumption apparently contained in 
 this proposition we must do with it as we have, for 
 scientific purposes, to do with most other statements 
 in which the word “ God ” appears — convert it into 
 an intelligible statement in terms of experience. The 
 meaning of this word in this particular sentence is, 
 of course, relative to the ideas expressed. Let us, 
 for the sake of convenience, suppose that we are con- 
 cerned with the case of an English urban workman 
 who has at a given time a wife and two children and 
 whose total income is a pound a week. This income 
 represents the “ bread ” of the family — the immediate 
 share of the proceeds of agriculture on which its 
 
200 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 Catholic life, its life of positive, many-sided Perfection 
 in Christ, has to be based. It represents its inherit- 
 ance in the earth ; and from this inheritance its 
 total human life — its hfe of industry, citizenship, art, 
 education, religion, and domestic responsibility — has 
 to be fed. It is true that in our modern world what 
 we call “ the State ” is also an instrument, or channel, 
 by which culture reaches the workman, but this does 
 not affect the argument, since the State and all its 
 institutions have to be kept living by labour upon the 
 earth. 
 
 Now, let us further suppose that in the course of time 
 a third child is born into the family. According to 
 our proverbial formula “ God sends ” this child. 
 God, however, works in definite ways and by definite 
 instruments. In this instance, and relatively to the 
 procreation of the child. He works by its parents. 
 They may or may not wish for it, and in our modern 
 world they can decide whether or not it shall be born. 
 They are, in any case, if it is born, the proximate 
 authors of its being. So far, for practical purposes, 
 we can understand the immediate and relative 
 meaning of the word “ God.” It means the parents. 
 It may have, from other points of view and in other 
 connections a very different meaning, a meaning 
 transcendent and universal, standing for things 
 visible and invisible ; but just as the priest at the 
 altar represents the mind and power of God in the 
 consecration of the sacred elements, so the parent 
 represents His mind and power in the procreation of 
 a child. This being so, it remains to determine in 
 
INDUSTRIAL IMPERIALISM 
 
 201 
 
 what sense it is that God gives “ bread ” to the 
 mouth which He has thus sent. Its bread, we say, 
 is its father’s income. Relatively to that bread, or 
 income, God presents Himself to the father in the 
 person of his employer, who conveys to him, as the 
 Divine instrument or channel, a certain portion of the 
 produce of the earth in return for his labour. When 
 this new child is born, does the employer at once and 
 voluntarily offer to the father an increase in his 
 wages ? Or, if the father comes to the employer and 
 prays to him, saying, “ Give us this day our daily 
 bread,” does the employer, as God’s representative, 
 grant him his prayer ? We know that these things 
 do not happen. We know that, simply on the ground 
 that he has another mouth to feed, the workman 
 never gets an increase of wages ; that if he ever gets 
 it it is on other grounds, and because, by combination 
 with his fellow-workmen and by the exercise of a 
 form of compulsion, he is able to extort it from his 
 employers. Here too the Kingdom of Heaven suffers 
 violence. In the absence of this violence, although 
 a new human life has come into the world, needing 
 food, clothing, habitation, health, maternal care, and 
 all the other means of the Catholic life, there is no 
 corresponding increase in the provision of these 
 things. If, therefore, the father represents God as 
 “ sending ” the child he must also represent God as 
 feeding it. 
 
 We reach, as is obvious, a similar conclusion if, 
 instead of supposing the father to have, as is usual, 
 indirect access to the earth through a capitalist and 
 
202 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 by means of a complex of industrial processes, we 
 imagine him as having direct access to it as an inde- 
 pendent agriculturist, cultivating his own portion 
 of land. The word “ God ” — considered as standing 
 for a Power wholly external to himself — then no 
 longer represents an employer. It represents imme- 
 diately the land which he cultivates. If our proverb 
 expresses a truth, then every time that God, as a 
 power of procreation, acting through the parents, 
 sends a new child to the family, this piece of land, in 
 the absence of any additional culture, and without 
 any new capital being employed upon it, produces a 
 more abundant supply of the necessaries of life. We 
 know that this does not happen. We know that even 
 when a new intelligence, labour, and capital have been 
 brought to bear on the land there is no necessary 
 correspondence between the increase of its yield, if 
 there is any such increase, and the increased demands 
 upon it. We know, further, that although the action 
 of the agriculturist upon it may be regular, patient, 
 skilful, and hopeful, God — considered as the stars in 
 their courses — may be fighting against him, and that 
 an excess or defect of rain or sunshine may destroy 
 the results of months of laborious toil. We know, 
 again, that in various parts of the world the land 
 itself, as the consequence of a volcanic eruption or an 
 earthquake, may suddenly disappear from beneath the 
 cultivator’s feet, and that he and all his family may 
 be involved in a ruin for which he has no personal 
 responsibility. We know, also, that the mineral and 
 vegetable products of the earth do not increase in 
 
INDUSTRIAL IMPERIALISM 
 
 203 
 
 proportion as they are used — that coal once con- 
 sumed is consumed for ever, and that a tree which 
 has taken fifty years to grow may be cut down in 
 an hour. 
 
 We must, then, dismiss from a Scientific Catholi- 
 cism the assumption that man, who lives by prayer 
 and agriculture — by prayer, in which he receives into 
 his mind a Divine Image and proposes to himself an 
 End of Perfection ; by agriculture, in which he pro- 
 vides the material basis for the spiritual life — ^has a 
 relation to the earth which can be symbolized by the 
 formula that God, whenever He sends mouths, sends 
 bread to feed them. His relation to it is such that if 
 he increases his demands upon it he must himself, 
 in some way, increase his capacity to satisfy those 
 demands, and that if he is unable to do this he must 
 in some way diminish his demands. The difference 
 in this respect between an individual man or family 
 and the company of individuals and families consti- 
 tuting a nation is, of course, only a difference of degree. 
 There is, consequently, no necessary correspondence 
 between the demands which any European people 
 makes upon the territory which it occupies and its 
 capacity to satisfy those demands. As a matter of 
 fact, all European peoples have long lived — in the 
 material sense of the word “ life,” no less than in its 
 spiritual sense — outside their own limits. England 
 is the most conspicuous example of this, but is still 
 only a single example. In degree all other civilized 
 countries are now in a similar situation. They have 
 become, in varying measure, dependent upon other 
 
204 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 nations for access to the earth — for their command 
 over its products. It may conceivably be true, of 
 course, that this dependence need not in all cases 
 be so great as it actually is — that the full agricultural 
 resources of each of the European countries have not 
 yet been utilized, and that by the adoption of a 
 different social and industrial system they could all 
 gain a much greater support for themselves without 
 going beyond their own borders. Substantially the 
 same result would be reached if the population were 
 restricted throughout Europe as it now is in France — 
 although this, unless a similar limitation were prac- 
 tised in other parts of the world, might have serious 
 consequences in the relations between “ Christen- 
 dom ” and “ non-Christendom.” 
 
 It is not, however, here necessary to enter into these 
 various suppositions and contingencies. We must 
 come back to the elementary truth that man is now 
 an inhabitant of the whole earth, dependent on what 
 he can get from it for his power to live his life, lower 
 and higher, and that in the actual situation of 
 European nations they have ceased, in greater or less 
 degree, to be able to nourish themselves within their 
 territorial limits, and must stretch forth their hands 
 to the ends of the world. They have, as a conse- 
 quence, become largely dependent on the peoples by 
 means of which they gain access to the earth and pro- 
 vide themselves with the necessaries of life. Against 
 the possible political consequences of this relation 
 their new resource — ^which, of course, is at the same 
 time a very ancient one — is, as we have said, indus- 
 
INDUSTRIAL IMPERIALISM 
 
 205 
 
 trial imperialism, such imperialism, being understood 
 as action directed to the establishment of the political 
 supremacy of a State in a country upon which, in 
 whatever way, it is industrially dependent. Now 
 imperialism in all its forms, and whatever its motives, 
 means, as we have seen, war — first, between the 
 imperialist State and the country in which it is 
 seeking to establish itself ; secondly, between this 
 imperialist State and others prosecuting a similar 
 purpose. If industrial imperialism is a pohcy sound 
 and indispensable for any one of the great nations of 
 Europe, it is sound and indispensable for others in 
 similar circumstances. If it is good for England and 
 Italy it is good also- — or may be held to be good — for 
 Russia and Germany. A nation, as such, is, or may 
 suppose itself to be, concerned only for its own 
 “ interest.” It must live or die. It regulates its 
 international action exactly as an individual shop- 
 keeper, or manufacturer, in a given European town 
 regulates his commercial action. He does not con- 
 sider the good of his rivals and competitors ; he con- 
 siders his own good. He does not always, perhaps, 
 deliberately plan their extinction or effacement, but 
 he plans his own prosperity, leaving others to do the 
 same, successfully or unsuccessfully. He would not 
 deny that they have the right, if they can, to master 
 him in the market, but he claims an equal right 
 for himself. We are not entitled to consider such 
 a man as representing a “ low morality.” He 
 represents the average morality. He is the typical 
 business man. No other rule of action is, in the 
 
2o6 the problem of HUMAN PEACE 
 
 industrial world, recognized than that which he 
 adopts. 
 
 What we have called industrial imperialism, there- 
 fore — which is only the modern form of an ancient 
 and continuous struggle for the possession of the 
 earth — has its roots not in international relations, 
 but in the character and domestic relations of the 
 individuals and classes constituting a nation. This 
 struggle, even when there is no war properly so called 
 — a war of nations — is always in progress. It is a 
 war of industrial competition which is, amidst aU the 
 complexities and amenities of the social state, an 
 elemental conflict for the means of subsistence. In 
 the chief countries of Christendom, at the present time, 
 such a war, as we all know, is actively and incessantly 
 waged. In its largest apparent forms it becomes 
 what we describe as a class war — a war between the 
 rich and the poor, between capital and labour. There 
 are, to use the words employed by Lord Beaconsfield 
 many years ago in a memorable novel, the “ two 
 nations ” within the nation — two nations whose ever- 
 increasing antagonism and conflict have recently more 
 than once threatened to produce a civil outbreak not 
 in its motives different from the international wars 
 which are due to industrial imperialism. It is essen- 
 tial to recognize the connection between the two 
 things — to understand that international policy is 
 prepared in the domestic life of a nation, and 
 that the clash of empires in the wide arena of 
 mankind has its sources and feeders in the less 
 alpable but unending conflict between the in- 
 
INDUSTRIAL IMPERIALISM 
 
 207 
 
 dividuals and classes entering into the internal 
 economy. 
 
 It is necessary to recognize this for two chief 
 reasons — first, because otherwise we can have no 
 right measure of the natural strength of the policy of 
 industrial imperialism, and, therefore, of the forces 
 which move men to war ; secondly, because its 
 recognition can alone enable us to understand the 
 nature of the influences which, if the forces of war 
 are ever to be overcome, must be brought to bear 
 against them. Just as it is true that the policy of 
 industrial imperialism is not the policy of a single 
 nation, but of a number of competing nations through- 
 out the world, so it is true that it is not the policy of 
 a single class within the nation, but is, in its essential 
 motives, of aU its classes. The struggle between the 
 “ two nations ” within the nation — between the rich 
 and the poor — arises because they both aim at the 
 same thing, and because the one actually possesses 
 what the other wishes to gain. The desire for wealth 
 — for mastery of the products of the earth — is, as is 
 obvious, not confined to any one order of persons. 
 It is common to almost all men and women, to the 
 ignorant and the cultivated, to those who discharge a 
 temporal function and to those whose office is, in one 
 way or another, spiritual. If, therefore, the argu- 
 ment for industrial imperialism is a “ sound ” one — 
 that is to say, if this policy can be shown actually 
 to give such a command over the resources of the 
 earth as could not otherwise be obtained — it is an 
 argument which makes an irresistible appeal, not to 
 
2o8 the problem of HUMAN PEACE 
 
 the “ capitalist ” only, but to the workman, and it 
 is as seductive to a religious minister, a schoolmaster, 
 a professor, or an artist as to those who are directly 
 engaged in the production or acquisition of wealth. 
 A war of industrial imperialism, that is, carries with 
 it almost the complete consent and force of the nation 
 which enters into it — enlists substantially the same 
 motives on its behalf as are, with a greater or less 
 degree of consciousness, acknowledged and operative 
 in that daily struggle for wealth which constitutes 
 the common life of the people. 
 
 It is for this reason that there can be no force 
 adequate to overcome the motives of war — whether 
 drawn from political or industrial imperialism — 
 except one which, recognizing the character and 
 natural strength of those motives, is still able to call 
 forth, and raise into lasting predominance, the motives 
 which make for peace. Such a force we cannot find 
 in diplomacy alone, or in statesmanship alone, or in 
 mere political measures, of whatever kind, or simply 
 in the transfer of power from the hands of one par- 
 ticular class and placing it in the hands of another. 
 These instruments and changes may be, on other 
 grounds, necessary, but they cannot, by themselves, 
 bring in and maintain the Human Peace. It can 
 only be brought in and maintained by a Scientific 
 Catholicism. 
 
CHAPTER VIII 
 
 CATHOLICISM AND IMPERIALISM 
 
 From the point of view of a Scientific Catholicism 
 the word “ policy ” gains an elevation and range of 
 meaning such as in our ordinary statesmanship it 
 cannot possess. It means, first, the clear recog- 
 nition of a supreme, continuous End to be reached ; 
 secondly, the systematic employment of aU the 
 means, spiritual and temporal, inner and outer, 
 which, in a synthetic survey of Nature and human 
 nature, can be shown to be necessary to its attain- 
 ment. The End which Catholicism proposes to itself 
 is the perfection of a personal and social humanity — 
 a perfection given symbolically and prophetically in 
 Christ, and conceived of as a positive and harmonious 
 fulfilment of all the sides of human nature, in an 
 order constituted by the subordination of the lower 
 to the higher. This is the Catholic life. It is in 
 reference to this great aim that a Human Peace is, or 
 is not, a good, and war is, or is not, an evil. Now, 
 we have, in the consideration of this question, pro- 
 ceeded, as we have already said, by endeavouring 
 to descend from Heaven to Earth. We have tried 
 to put first the Kingdom of God and its righteous- 
 ness, and have then sought to ascertain the position 
 of man, as a dependent worker upon the earth, in 
 
210 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 relation to that Kingdom. We have considered him 
 not first as an animal and then as a Catholic, but first 
 as a Catholic and then as an animal. There is every 
 justification for such an order of inquiry, although 
 there may be a provisional justification for a different 
 order. Scientifically considered — unless we are to 
 exclude from the field of science the social and moral 
 nature of humanity — man is not an animal ; he is a 
 Catholic. He is a Catholic, first, because as we see 
 him in history he continuously presents himself to us 
 as a religious being ; he is a Catholic, secondly, 
 because even when, in our modern world, he does not 
 propose to himself the specific purposes which are 
 represented by the word “ Church,” he still commonly 
 proposes to himself the ends which are represented 
 by the words “ home,” “ school,” “ theatre,” “ State,” 
 and “ workshop.” He is, that is to say, never only 
 an animal, following mere impulses of appetite and 
 passion, but, completely or incompletely, a Catholic — 
 in some sense, and in some degree, a spiritual being, 
 acting upon his environment and upon himself for 
 the accomplishment of certain ends of beauty, reason, 
 and power. 
 
 But having followed this method of treatment, and 
 gained the standpoint which is proper to man in the 
 full development of his humanity, it is, we repeat, 
 allowable to adopt the inverse method and approach 
 the problem of peace rather from below than from 
 above. Now, what we have to determine is whether 
 there is some reason, in the nature of things, why 
 man, not being an animal but containing an 
 
CATHOLICISM AND IMPERIALISM 21 1 
 
 animal within him, must, for the satisfaction of 
 his primary, imperative instincts, go to war with 
 his fellow-beings. In other words, is the policy 
 of industrial imperialism, which proceeds from the 
 working of these instincts, within and without the 
 nation, a policy indispensable ? If it is, then war 
 may be, for a given nation and in a given situation, 
 a good and peace an evil. In its immediate bearing 
 upon the spiritual life, as we have seen, war — ^con- 
 sidered as a specific application of material force, 
 directed to destruction and slaughter — cannot be 
 shown to be a good. It visibly subserves none of the 
 purposes of that life. But it is a good — considered as 
 a means to an end-— if imperialism is a good, because 
 imperialism demands war. Imperialism has, as we 
 have seen, two main related forms — one which we 
 have called political, the other industrial. Neither 
 of the two forms, it is true, exists, as a rule, by itself. 
 The forces of war are, as we have shown, connected 
 and interdependent, and when one of them has been 
 called into operation almost all the others are also 
 summoned up. It is, however, possible and desirable 
 to distinguish one from the other, and to determine 
 their relative degrees of power and importance. Of 
 the two forms of imperialism the industrial is the 
 one upon which it is, in our modern world, most neces- 
 sary to concentrate our attention. It is this because 
 it is immediately connected with the question of man’s 
 command over the earth and its products. It is this 
 because in it all orders of men and women within the 
 nation are interested. It is this because it is a policy 
 
212 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 naturally connected with the constant conflict of 
 individuals and classes in industrial life. It is this 
 because if it is a policy for one nation it is a policy for 
 all, in proportion to their power. It is this because 
 our modern world is pre-eminently and increasingly 
 a world of industry. It is this because, whatever 
 may be the other alleged motives of imperialism, 
 its industrial motive is almost always at last 
 appealed to to sanction or reinforce them. It is 
 this because rulers and people, capitalists and work- 
 men, are alike susceptible to the appeal which it 
 makes to them, and because the Catholic life itself — 
 the spiritual and social life of religion or culture 
 — depends ultimately on what man gets from the 
 earth. 
 
 Now, industrial imperialism, according to our con- 
 ception and definition of it, has a perfectly plain and 
 distinctive character ; it is a policy of interference in 
 the internal concerns of a foreign country, directed 
 to industrial ends, involving war, local and general, 
 as one of its consequences, and commonly also leading 
 to conquest. As such it is, as we have said, to be care- 
 fully distinguished from movements of emigration 
 and colonization, which do not necessarily entail such 
 consequences. The question to be considered, stating 
 it specifically and practically, is whether this policy 
 of industrial imperialism is, for any of the nations of 
 Christendom and in our modern world, necessary — 
 necessary, that is to say, from the point of view of 
 that command over the resources of the earth which 
 is imposed upon man as a condition of both his 
 
CATHOLICISM AND IMPERIALISM 213 
 
 animal and his spiritual existence. We may, for the 
 purposes of this inquiry, assume — ^what, however, 
 strictly speaking, has not yet been demonstrated — 
 that it is impossible for any existing European people 
 to maintain itself, in a merely material sense, within 
 its own territorial limits — that it is called upon, in 
 varying degree, to live beyond those limits. We may 
 assume, too, that the population of Europe will con- 
 tinue to expand as, except in France, it has expanded 
 hitherto. We may even assume that it is, from various 
 points of view, undesirable, even if it were possible, 
 for a nation to be so completely self-supporting as 
 to be under no obligation to relate itself industrially 
 to the other nations of mankind. Each of these 
 assumptions, of course, itself raises important and 
 difficult questions, but we may, for our immediate 
 purposes, disregard them. 
 
 The object of industrial imperialism is to enable a 
 European nation to obtain an indispensable command 
 over the products of the earth in, let us say, Asia, 
 Africa, or America, which, on the hypothesis, it cannot 
 obtain within its own borders. The one question to 
 be decided, therefore, is whether such a policy is 
 necessary to secure the result — ^whether it is possible 
 to reach the same end in any other way. It is obvious 
 to begin with, that whatever may be the methods 
 adopted to reach it, a European nation can only secure 
 the products of any other country — whether in 
 Europe itself or in other parts of the earth — by a 
 process of exchange or trade. This process of 
 exchange must, for example, be carried on, within the 
 
214 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 limits of a world-wide State, such as the British 
 Empire, precisely as it is carried on beyond those 
 limits. England, when she receives corn and cotton 
 from her own distant possessions, has to pay for them 
 just as when she receives them from America or 
 Russia. There is, in this respect, no difference what- 
 ever between what may be called Imperial trade and 
 foreign trade. It is plain, too, that any European 
 nation drawing the necessaries of life from some 
 extra-European possession, is, in an economic sense, 
 as much dependent upon that possession as if it were 
 a foreign country. Any results which may follow 
 from such a dependence are, of course, not abrogated 
 even if there is, as we say, “ free trade within the 
 Empire.” The abolition of protective tariffs, for 
 instance, as between Canada or Australia and England, 
 would not diminish EngHsh economic dependence 
 upon those countries, or convert the United Kingdom 
 into a self-sufficing State. If we suppose this change 
 to have been brought about, it would still remain true 
 that the inhabitants of the British Islands — or of 
 Great Britain at least — could not subsist by such a 
 direct command over the earth as is to be gained 
 within their own limits. It is obvious, too, that the 
 economic needs of any imperial dependency — and 
 therefore its demand for the products of the govern- 
 ing State — are determined by the character of its 
 civilization and its social customs. If it is possible 
 for it to do what the Imperial nation is unable to 
 do, subsist entirely within its own limits, it may 
 have no such imperative needs as give rise to 
 
CATHOLICISM AND IMPERIALISM 215 
 
 foreign trade. It may, further, have no exporting 
 power, either because of the nature of its material 
 resources or because of the demands of its own 
 population. 
 
 A policy of industrial imperialism, therefore, cannot 
 abolish time and space, or nullify geographical conse- 
 quences. The economic effect of English dependence 
 upon a British possession is substantially the same as 
 that resulting from its dependence upon a foreign 
 country. In either case the material Hfe of the nation 
 is life in relation to an environment which is not its 
 own. And what applies to England applies, of course, 
 also to any other European country in similar circum- 
 stances. It is, however, not enough to say this. Not 
 only is it true that industrial imperialism does not 
 increase the economic independence of the State 
 which pursues such a policy, but it is also true that 
 the total imperial trade of a country in the position 
 of England — understanding by “ trade ” a command 
 of the resources of the earth effected by exchange — is 
 much less than its total trade with foreign countries. 
 This the statistics of British imports and exports are 
 sufficient to show. To accomplish its avowed or 
 imphed purpose — to enable England, for example, as 
 a great imperial State, to be economically self- 
 sufficing — “ free trade within the Empire ” would 
 have to be exclusive of all trade without the Empire. 
 England, under such circumstances, would have to 
 buy and sell only with its own non-European posses- 
 sions and to do no business in Europe at all ; and, once 
 more, not only would England have to maintain 
 
2i6 the problem of HUMAN PEACE 
 
 itself in such a position, but all other European 
 countries pursuing a similar policy would have to do 
 the same. They would, that is to say, have to sacri- 
 fice their immense body of trade — their wide command 
 over the resources of the earth- — outside the limits 
 of their own empire for the sake of the smaller body, 
 the smaller command, within those limits. Further, 
 they would be called upon, speaking generally, to 
 give up their trade with neighbouring countries in 
 order to trade exclusively with remoter countries. 
 Lastly, they would have to limit themselves to trading 
 with uncivilized or undeveloped countries, making 
 comparatively few demands upon the higher industries, 
 and to sacrifice their commerce with nations in much 
 the same plane of culture with themselves, and having 
 therefore, a wide and increasing range of social needs. 
 In a word, if the policy of industrial imperialism were, 
 in its logical development, a possible policy, and were 
 consistently and systematically maintained, it would 
 place each of the great “ empires ” of the world, 
 within its pohtical limits, in much the same position 
 as was at one time, in a certain degree, occupied by an 
 isolated and independent people supporting an exclu- 
 sive and rudimentary civilization on the products of 
 its own soil. 
 
 The policy of industrial imperialism is, however, 
 ideally considered and in its full development, an 
 impossible pohcy. It is an attempt to reverse the 
 results of the total evolution of mankind — to give to 
 England, France, Germany, or Italy, as an imperial 
 State, a position of economic isolation and indepen- 
 
CATHOLICISM AND IMPERIALISM 217 
 
 dence such as, strictly speaking, hardly any people 
 has ever absolutely maintained, even in the early 
 ages of civilization. It is an attempt, too, by political 
 and mihtary processes to nullify the forces of Nature 
 — to gain for a nation with certain inherent dis- 
 advantages of position, climate, soil, vegetation, and 
 mineral resources the same industrial power and 
 ascendency as if, in these respects, its situation were 
 entirely different. It is a policy which carries with 
 it the consequences of war without securing the 
 ends of industry to a greater extent than they would 
 be secured by a policy of peace. The ends of industry 
 are a command over the resources of the earth, for 
 the purposes of human life, lower and higher, material 
 and spiritual. It is, as we have said, conceivable that 
 each of the imperial nations of Europe has a much 
 greater capacity of directly supporting itself within 
 its own territorial limits than has yet been developed, 
 even if we assume a certain continuous expansion of 
 population. They have doubtless, in degree, been 
 driven beyond those limits not so much by a perma- 
 nent and absolute necessity as by a temporary and 
 relative necessity — not, for example, because they 
 are wholly unable to procure food and clothing 
 within their own borders, but because, at a given time, 
 they can procure them more readily and cheaply else- 
 where than at home. Actually, however, what we 
 see, to fall back upon our former expression, is that 
 “ man ” — whether he is the “ man ” of England, 
 France, Germany, or the United States — has, in our 
 modern world, become an inhabitant of the whole 
 
2i8 the problem of HUMAN PEACE 
 
 earth, commanding its resources, not directly by an 
 exclusive and immediate action upon that part of it 
 in which he is situated, but by means of his wide and 
 complex relations with the undivided territory and 
 life of mankind. 
 
 From the point of view of the Catholic Hfe, there- 
 fore — a life of positive many-sided perfection, sym- 
 bolized and inspired by the Perfection of Christ — it 
 cannot be shown that imperialism, the war policy, is 
 a good policy. To be good it must be indispensable — 
 indispensable for the attainment of certain great and 
 specific ends which man, as a continuous being, 
 developing and harmonizing the various sides of his 
 nature, progressively proposes to himself. But if it 
 is not in this sense good, it is evil, and evil in a high 
 degree. If war is not conducive to the Catholic life — 
 the life of religious exaltation, the life of spiritual 
 culture and fulfilment — it is, being what it is, the 
 greatest of hindrances to that life. War is a special 
 apphcation of material force, directed to purposes of 
 destruction and slaughter. If it is indispensable to 
 the Catholic life, either on its higher side or on its 
 lower, then against the supreme good which it secures 
 we are not entitled to set any evils which are asso- 
 ciated with it, great as those evils in themselves may 
 be. That men — to employ our traditional concep- 
 tions and symbolism — should, for some few years of 
 sin on earth, be condemned to eternal torment in 
 another world may appear to us horrible, but if this 
 is indispensable to the fulfilment of Divine justice, 
 we must reconcile ourselves with the horror. War 
 
CATHOLICISM AND IMPERIALISM 219 
 
 has its own character, which fulfils itself. What is 
 essential in regard to it is not that its evils should be 
 tempered, but that its objects should be attained. Its 
 evils are the price which we pay for the good which 
 we wish to secure. The price may be great, but it 
 can never be too great if the good is indispensable, 
 and if we can only secure it by paying the price. In 
 practice, men, in making war, have always, consciously 
 or unconsciously, acted on this principle. They have 
 known that war was a process of destruction and 
 slaughter — that it was wasteful, murderous, and, 
 from our ordinary point of view, revolting and awful. 
 This, however, has not prevented them from waging 
 it. They have refrained from entering into it either 
 when they believed themselves unable to prosecute it 
 successfully, or when they had no apparent purpose to 
 gain by waging it, and they have ended it when they 
 have been compelled to do so, or have secured the 
 objects for which they fought. But they have never 
 refused to enter into war, and they have never brought 
 war to an end, merely because of its waste or its 
 inhumanity. They have understood perfectly well 
 that waste and inhumanity are as inevitable in war as 
 are ploughing the land and sowing the seed in agri- 
 culture — to say nothing of the fact that into war, as 
 we have seen, enter the instinct of destruction and 
 the joy of combat. 
 
 This, in our modern world, is even more true than 
 in the earlier ages of mankind. The savage man, or 
 the man of a low civilization, is a man largely 
 governed by immediate impulses. He is not a 
 
220 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 “ being of large discourse, looking before and after.” 
 He has a small command of human experience. He 
 is heir to no great conquests of order and culture. He 
 is without a vision of the social future. He is unedu- 
 cated, improvident, unsystematic. He has com- 
 paratively little to lose by war ; he gains from it the 
 satisfaction of that fighting man^ — the man of animal 
 antagonism and conflict^ — ^who is contained and 
 restrained in the Catholic man. When he chooses 
 war, therefore, he chooses it, or is carried into it, by 
 the full and ready consent of all his instincts, and 
 with a limited consciousness and idea of responsibility. 
 If war is in any sense a sin, the savage man, the unde- 
 veloped or ignorant man, is least of all a sinner when 
 he wages it. The modern man— the man of Western 
 Europe in the twentieth century— is in a very 
 different position. He carries in his mind an ideal 
 of the Catholic life. The Divine Perfection of 
 Christ’s Humanity, the tender and immaculate 
 maternity of Our Lady, the unseen presences of the 
 saints, the precious creations of the arts and sciences, 
 the slow and great conquests of industry, the high 
 order of domestic and national life — -these things 
 shape him, sustain him, breathe upon him light, 
 beauty, and power, give to him an image and 
 prescience of ideal good; and when, therefore, he 
 enters into war he steps from the sanctuary into a 
 slaughter-house, and destroys in a moment of 
 anarchic passion the temple which a thousand 
 years of genius and achievement have hardly sufficed 
 to build. If war, therefore, is a sin, the modern 
 
CATHOLICISM AND IMPERIALISM 221 
 
 man as he wages it is a sinner in the highest 
 degree. He is as Satan descending from the Courts 
 of God to kindle the fury and devastation of 
 HeU. The higher we rise the lower, if we fall, 
 we fall. 
 
 The recognition and consciousness of this, however, 
 have not prevented man — the Western man of the 
 twentieth century — from entering into the bloodiest 
 and most wasteful war in history. Its bloodshed and 
 waste were inevitable, if the war was inevitable. 
 They were, indeed, planned and foreseen. The war 
 was an outcome of what we call peace. It was a 
 fruit of policy. It was a result of contrivance and 
 invention. The machine-gun, the torpedo, the sub- 
 marine, the aeroplane, the “ Dreadnought,” the 
 long-range artillery — these are not the extemporized 
 instruments of a sudden and barbaric passion, 
 hurrying men blindly to destruction ; they are a high 
 product of science and social order — the calm creation 
 of a vast intellectual and material capital. The men 
 who invented them, the Governments that sanctioned 
 them, the peoples that applauded them or acquiesced 
 in them, the tax-payers who provided the means for 
 them, the ministers of religion who prayed and 
 preached as usual while they were being perfected— 
 these all understood why such instruments of havoc 
 were being wrought, and what was the kind of havoc 
 which they would necessarily effect. Yet, in the 
 quiet and reflection of half a century, they witnessed 
 their production without a protest. The reason for 
 this is, as we say, plain. If war is a good — in the 
 
222 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 sense of being indispensable to some side or other of 
 the Catholic life, individual and national — then the 
 accompanying evils of war must be considered to be, 
 by comparison, insignificant. If the policy which 
 produces war is, on a total view of it, sound, then it 
 is sound with a soundness which makes the death of 
 a million men, or the destruction of a hundred archi- 
 tectural masterpieces, or the perpetration of a 
 number of “ cruelties ” or “ barbarities ” of small 
 relative importance. War being what it is, only an 
 indispensable good can justify it, and if it is justified 
 by an indispensable good, any evils which may attend 
 it are, real as they may be, of minor consequence. 
 The fundamental human choice with regard to war 
 is not the choice which mitigates its subsidiary 
 horrors, but the exercise of reason and will which 
 decides whether or not a policy shall be prosecuted 
 which makes it inevitable. All else is illusory senti- 
 ment, and is a sentiment which is so far from being 
 beneficent that it is — as is all sentiment divorced 
 from right intelligence — a hindrance to the very 
 purposes which it seeks to attain. It is not in regard 
 to the methods of war, but in regard to the policy — 
 the conscious intentional shaping of a nation’s life — 
 which produces or prevents war that a Scientific 
 Catholicism has, or has not, its guidance to give to 
 mankind. 
 
 If, however, we have come to the conclusion that 
 — or the policy of imperialism, political and 
 industrial, which provokes it — is not, from any point 
 of view, indispensable to the Catholic life, but is, on 
 
CATHOLICISM AND IMPERIALISM 223 
 
 the contrary, a frustration of that life, then it becomes, 
 in a transcendent sense, evil, for to the evil of blood- 
 shed and destruction, it superadds the greatest of aU 
 evils — that it stands between man and the Perfection 
 of Christ. And this must be the conclusion of a 
 Scientific CathoHcism. War — meaning always by 
 war aggressive war, rendered inevitable by a dehberate 
 pohcy — is not, in fact, in our modern world, indis- 
 pensable to the attainment of the Catholic aims, 
 higher and lower, which man proposes to himself. 
 The one basic, inevitable aim which might seem to 
 call for it — man’s command over the earth, as a con- 
 dition of his animal subsistence — is, as is now clear, 
 an aim which is so far from justifying it that this aim 
 is actually better fulfilled, for every European nation, 
 outside the Hmits of empire than within those limits, 
 and that the pohcy of industrial imperiahsm is, in 
 any complete sense, impossible. Man is, wherever he 
 is, economically an inhabitant of the whole earth, and 
 he is this exactly in proportion to the range of his 
 needs — to his elevation in the scale of intelligence, 
 culture, and social refinement. But of the whole earth 
 a modern European — a Frenchman, a German, an 
 Englishman, a Russian — can only, for industrial pur- 
 poses, gain a command in one of two conceivable ways 
 — either by a universal empire or by universal ex- 
 change. A universal empire is inconceivable. We are 
 not called upon to discuss it. There is only one thing that 
 can be universal, and that is exchange — an exchange 
 of man’s spiritual acquisitions, or Cathohcism, the 
 Spirit of God moving over the waters and lands 
 
224 the problem of human peace 
 
 and making humanity one — or an exchange of his 
 material acquisitions, rendering the Catholic life 
 possible. This double exchange means a Human 
 Peace. 
 
 It is in the presence of this conception — a concep- 
 tion not drawn from a sentimental idealism, but from 
 the governing realities of man’s industrial life, that 
 war — being not only unnecessary, but a visible frus- 
 tration of his lower and higher aims — becomes an 
 illimitable evil. To not a single one of man’s repre- 
 sentative and symbolic institutions — the home, the 
 Church, the school, the theatre, the State, the work- 
 shop — does it make a positive contribution. Through- 
 out the whole range of his hfe it is a form of waste 
 and dissipation. If the value of life can be expressed 
 in terms of love, goodness, beauty, truth, wisdom, 
 and power — if man is, in the conception of him given 
 continuously in the ages, a being holding in his mind 
 a vision of his own inner and outer perfection, after 
 which he always follows — then war is a mere anarchy 
 in the presence of a possible order. If the master 
 evils of human life may be summed up, as they may, as 
 sin, hatred, disease, ugliness, ignorance, penury, then 
 there is not a single one of those evils which war, 
 instead of decreasing, does not increase. If the chief 
 forms of good may be summed up, as they may, as 
 goodness, love, health, beauty, knowledge, and 
 material sufficiency, then there is not a single 
 one of them in relation to which war — an 
 application of material force, directed to slaughter 
 and destruction — is not a hindrance. The things 
 
CATHOLICISM AND IMPERIALISM 225 
 
 which man, in his moments of choice and pre- 
 science, would wish to do it prevents him from 
 doing ; the things that he would wish to avoid 
 it brings upon him. It is a mode of human mis- 
 carriage. 
 
CHAPTER IX 
 
 A CATHOLIC POLICY OF PEACE 
 
 It is now possible, going back upon the principles 
 which we have endeavoured to establish in this work, 
 to determine the attitude of a Scientific Cathohcism — 
 that is to say, of the developed, synthetic mind of 
 man, proposing to himself Perfection in Christ — 
 towards the problem of Human Peace. First, we 
 see that such a peace would be a good — a good so 
 supreme and universal that against it no good to be 
 atta ned by war can properly be pleaded. It is in 
 this sense a good because it is indispensable to the 
 Catholic life. The CathoHc life is a thing higher and 
 lower. In principle it begins with the soul ; in 
 practice it begins with the body. Before we can hve 
 this life we must have the vision of it clear and full 
 in our minds, so that we may master and order all 
 our forces for its realization. When we have gained 
 this vision, however, we see that the life of the 
 spiritual man must begin with the hfe of the animal 
 man — ^with man’s action upon the earth to secure 
 for himself a material subsistence. It is only in the 
 light of this comprehensive view of human nature — 
 showing to us man as a definite organism, in dependent 
 yet modifying relation with a definite environment — 
 that we can decide how far war is, or is not, necessary, 
 how far peace is, or is not, a good. We are entitled 
 
A CATHOLIC POLICY OF PEACE 227 
 
 to say that war is not necessary because it is not an 
 indispensable means to any of man’s continuous ends 
 — either those ends which are represented by the 
 words “ home,” “ Church,” “ school,” “ theatre,” or 
 those which are represented by the words “ State ” 
 and “ workshop.” We are entitled to say that, on 
 the contrary, not being necessary, it is a stupendous 
 evil, a process of anarchic destruction and waste, a 
 frustration of man’s right government and direction 
 of himself, in mind and body. We are entitled to 
 say that peace is a good because it is naturally and 
 demonstrably subservient to the ends of man — 
 because it is a state of order, of self-possession, of 
 self-direction, of organic constructive mastery over 
 the earth, as the basis of the Catholic life, and of a 
 full command and use of the things of the spirit, as 
 its apex and crown. 
 
 For a Catholic international policy, however, we 
 need something more than to be able to show, in this 
 general way, the evil of war, the good of peace. A 
 Scientific Catholicism must be both a principle and a 
 power of peace. It has, finding for itself voices and 
 organs, to so educate and transform the mind of man 
 — the man not of one country alone, but, in the first 
 instance, of all Christendom — that he may give to 
 peace the same place in his purposes as he has in the 
 past given to war, or to modes of policy and action 
 involving war. This it must do by convincing men— 
 the citizenship of England, France, Germany, Italy, 
 Russia, and other countries — not only that war is a 
 frustration of all the high spiritual ends of life, but that 
 
228 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 it is a frustration also of those lower material ends 
 on which the spiritual ends depend, and for which, 
 in our modern world, it is commonly waged. In other 
 words, here, as elsewhere, Catholicism can have no 
 capacity to shape the life of mankind unless it becomes 
 positive and practical — unless it can show men not 
 merely what they are to abstain from doing, but what 
 they are to do. It must cease to be, what hitherto 
 it has largely been, a mere voice of prohibition and 
 censure, or the proclamation of an abstract ideal, and 
 become a voice of guidance and application. It is 
 not enough to denounce war and praise peace. It 
 is necessary to prove to man that peace is indispens- 
 able to the attainment of the very objects for which 
 war is now commonly waged, and that the objects 
 which cannot be secured by peace are such as man, 
 pursuing the Catholic life, is not called upon to 
 propose to himself. 
 
 The Human Peace, as we have defined it — the 
 universal, continuous peace of man — must, as we have 
 said, be preceded by a Western Peace, the peace of 
 Christendom. For the purposes of such a Western 
 Peace — of a deliberate and systematic policy, designed 
 to bring it in and maintain it — we may place ourselves 
 at the point of view of any one of the Great European 
 Powers — France, England, Germany, or Italy. They 
 differ, of course, to some extent in situation, 
 character, and needs, but they are at the same time 
 sufficiently similar for us to be entitled to consider 
 any one of them, for our present purpose, as a repre- 
 sentative of all the others. It is only in so far as 
 
A CATHOLIC POLICY OF PEACE 229 
 
 their position and needs — their “ interests,” to use 
 the diplomatic expression — are identical that we can 
 expect them to adopt a common policy. It is, in 
 fact, because their aims are substantially the same 
 that, in the pursuit of them, they come into conflict ; 
 and an international policy of peace can only become 
 possible if they can arrive at a common understanding 
 that these aims, in so far as they are actually indis- 
 pensable, may be accomplished without war. 
 
 Such a policy begins with what we call the lowest 
 need of man — his material need. He lives, we say, in 
 the basic sense of the word “ life,” by his command of 
 the earth. Any one of the great nations of Europe, 
 considered as a continuous, organized society of 
 human beings, exists by virtue of this command — in 
 the first place, by its command over that portion of 
 the earth on which it is immediately seated. Whether 
 it can gain sufficient material support from its own 
 territory is a question of fact and experience. We 
 must, in relation to this, dismiss from our minds the 
 superstition embodied in the formula that “ when 
 God sends mouths He sends bread to feed them.” It 
 can have no place in a Scientific Catholicism, seeing 
 and representing things as they are. It has, in fact, 
 never been acted upon even by those who professed 
 to accept it, and it is contrary to all our experience of 
 living things, vegetable, animal, and human. It is 
 doubtless true, as we have said, that every European 
 nation has a greater power of existing within its own 
 territory than it has actually developed, and it may 
 well be a part of Catholic policy — understanding by 
 
230 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 Catholic policy the synthetic ordering of the whole 
 life of man for the realization of the ends of Per- 
 fection — to call forth and direct that power, indus- 
 trially and politically, to a much greater extent than 
 has hitherto been done. Still, it remains true that 
 the “ man ” of any European nation does not, in 
 fact, subsist on the produce of his own soil. Either, 
 therefore, he must increase its yield, or he must 
 decrease his demands upon it, or he must, in some 
 way, go beyond it and exercise a wide sovereignty over 
 the resources of the whole earth. 
 
 He does, in actual experience, employ all these three 
 processes. He increases the yield of his territory by 
 progressive industrial and political action. He de- 
 creases, or limits, his demands upon it, to a certain 
 extent, by emigration — to say nothing of the great 
 waste of human life that follows from disease, poverty, 
 and war. He goes beyond it by means of trade — 
 either the immense body of trade which we may 
 describe as international, or the smaller body which 
 we may call imperial, and which, although it is 
 imperial, is still dependent, as is international trade, 
 on free exchange. Now the first of these processes — 
 the increase of the domestic national resources by 
 the development of agriculture — does not, we say, 
 demand war. The same thing is true of emigration 
 and international trade. The same thing is true even 
 of imperial trade, in so far as it is trade within the 
 limits of an empire already established. If we put 
 ourselves, therefore, at the point of view of any par- 
 ticular status quo, the policy of industrial imperialism. 
 
A CATHOLIC POLICY OF PEACE 231 
 
 which is a war pohcy, must be understood as a policy 
 to extend an existing empire for the sake of an 
 increase of imperial trade. It must be recognized, 
 also, that imperial trade does not constitute a 
 monopoly. No one of the existing empires of the 
 world seeks to prevent its various rivals from doing 
 business with its own possessions. It may aim at 
 securing certain special advantages for itself, but 
 subject to these restrictions it acts on the assumption 
 that universality of exchange is a common interest of 
 all nations. Therefore, industrial imperialism is for 
 any European nation a policy which, being a war 
 policy, endangers its international trade, its greater 
 trade, for the sake of its imperial, or smaller, trade, 
 and this without securing a monopoly, even of the 
 imperial trade. In other words, it is for the sake of 
 the lesser command of the earth that it imperils the 
 greater, and makes the Human Peace impossible. 
 
 Let us assume that a universal command of the 
 earth, as distinguished from a merely local command, 
 is, for any European nation, indispensable. The 
 problem is how to secure it pacifically. Now, in 
 regard to this need for a command and use of the 
 earth, a broad and obvious distinction may be 
 drawn between those portions of the earth which are 
 adequately peopled and those which may be said to be, 
 for industrial purposes, unoccupied. Such a dis- 
 tinction has its domestic importance even within the 
 national hmits of an old country like England, 
 where, as we know, considerable tracts of land have 
 not yet been brought under culture. What we are 
 
232 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 now concerned with, however, is the international 
 problem that arises from the fact that vast portions 
 of the earth — as in Africa, North and South America, 
 and Australasia — are still manifestly under-peopled, 
 while others may be said to be relatively over- 
 peopled. Setting aside the question — a question 
 which is largely dependent on experience — of how 
 far the uninhabited, or under-inhabited, parts of the 
 earth are, from the character of their climate and 
 soil, uninhabitable, we may say broadly that they 
 constitute at present the chief danger-points of inter- 
 national order. If the policy of industrial imperial- 
 ism — ^which we have defined as a policy of imperial 
 expansion in the interests of industry — is still to be 
 prosecuted, it is towards such danger-points that it 
 will mainly, although not exclusively, be directed. 
 A Scientific Catholicism, aiming at a human peace, 
 will understand this. It will know where such 
 danger-points exist. Its aim, its policy, will be to 
 guard against the perils inherent in them. This it is 
 certainly not difficult to do. The map of the earth is 
 now familiarly known. The danger-points, as we 
 have called them, are visible and calculable. It 
 would be easily possible, in any international council 
 of the Western nations, to consider these specific 
 danger-points and to shape a common policy in 
 regard to them. Within certain limits such a policy 
 has already been adopted — as, for instance, in regard 
 to Africa. We are not now, of course, discussing the 
 question of whether such a policy has been, or might 
 be, in its actual application, ideally just or beneficent 
 
A CATHOLIC POLICY OF PEACE 233 
 
 to all concerned. We are assuming that a Human 
 Peace would be, from the point of view of the total 
 life of man, a good so great that against it any sub- 
 ordinate good or evil ought not to be pleaded, real as 
 it might conceivably be. 
 
 The chief danger-points of the earth, in relation to 
 industrial imperialism, are, we say, its unoccupied 
 portions, using the word “ unoccupied,” for the 
 sake of simplicity, so as to include also such as are 
 under-occupied. Now, we may lay down the principle 
 that as man, in our modern world, is an inhabitant 
 of the whole earth, it is, for the purposes of the 
 Catholic life, necessary that these unoccupied portions 
 should be, as far as possible, occupied and brought 
 under culture. What is certain is that even if we do 
 not assume a Scientific Catholicism to be shaping the 
 policy of Christendom, these unoccupied portions will 
 sooner or later, and in one way or another, be occupied 
 and be made to yield their tribute to human life. The 
 aim of a Catholic policy, pursuing a Human Peace, is 
 to make it possible to secure such a result without 
 war. From the point of view of such a policy, it is 
 not necessary to consider whether these unoccupied 
 portions of the earth are in the nominal possession of 
 “ Christendom ” or “ non-Christendom ” ; and it is, 
 in the same way, undesirable to complicate the ques- 
 tion with mere social considerations. The reasons for 
 this are obvious. In the first place, although, for 
 Europeans, it is natural to assume that the yellow 
 and black races are “ inferior ” to the white, it is 
 evident that these inferior races, even if they con- 
 
234 the problem OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 tinue to retain their present physical and intellectual 
 characteristics, must be reckoned with as integral, 
 persisting factors in the total life of mankind. They 
 may be modified, but no one supposes that they will 
 be extirpated. In the second place, we may assume 
 that it will continue to be the aim of Catholicism, by 
 missionary action, to transform the non-Christian 
 races, in some sense, into Christians, and, speaking 
 broadly, to raise the non-Western peoples, as far as 
 possible, into the Western plane of culture and 
 civihzation. In a certain degree, such a result has 
 already been brought about, and in proportion as it 
 is, by whatever agency, effected, the “ non-Western ” 
 demands upon the earth will approximate in character 
 and amount to the “ Western demands.” In other 
 words, the Catholic life, with its lower and higher 
 needs, will tend to become universal. Lastly, we 
 must recognize, once more, that some at least of the 
 Eastern and non-Christian races are now becoming 
 in this sense Western that they are able to defend 
 themselves even against the West, or “ Christendom.” 
 
 We may, therefore, so far as the aims of industrial 
 imperialism are concerned — and that need for the 
 command of the earth which is its principal motive — 
 disregard mere differences of religion and race, and 
 consider only the broad distinction between those 
 portions of the earth which are “ occupied ” and those 
 which are unoccupied. It is, as we say, a common 
 interest of mankind — and not of any one nation 
 exclusively — that they should be occupied, and made to 
 yield their proportion of produce to the support of the 
 
A CATHOLIC POLICY OF PEACE 235 
 
 human family. For this, however, it is not necessary 
 that the policy of imperialism should be adopted in 
 regard to them. There are now hardly any portions 
 of the earth which are, in a political sense, unoccu- 
 pied, although they may be unoccupied industrially. 
 Almost every part of it is under some sort of rule or 
 government — “ belongs ” to some people or nation, 
 even if it has not been brought fully under culture. 
 The natural resource of any European nation, in regard 
 to the unoccupied portions, of the earth is the ancient 
 resource of emigration — the method which has in fact 
 been adopted by all European nations for hundreds 
 of years past. Such a method is not necessarily a 
 method of war. The emigrant either goes to a country 
 which is under the rule, if only the nominal rule, of his 
 own Government, or to some possession of a foreign 
 power, European or non-European. An English 
 emigrant, for example, may go either to Canada, 
 Australia, South Africa, or to the United States, or to 
 Brazil. In either case, no question of war arises. He 
 passes from one dominion to another — becomes sub- 
 ject to the authority, such as it may be, of the place 
 in which he settles. That authority, of course, 
 exercises the natural “ right ” — a “ right ” which is 
 dependent on “ might ” — of saying whether, or on 
 what conditions, it will accept him, but when he has 
 once been accepted he becomes amenable to its rule, 
 and at the same time gains a certain power of citizen- 
 ship and control in regard to it. In some “ unoccu- 
 pied ” countries — ^where the existing population is 
 relatively small and the territory large — the body of 
 
236 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 emigration may in time become the controlling power, 
 and the land may virtually change its masters. The 
 older the world gets, of course, the less are these familiar 
 results of emigration and colonization likely to be re- 
 peated. There are, however, as is evident, still vast 
 regions of the earth which are, in a palpable sense, 
 under-peopled, and in relation to which a true emigra- 
 tion is possible. The essential thing to be borne in 
 mind here is that in our modern world a policy of 
 emigration need not be the same thing as a policy 
 of imperialism. It increases the total co-operative 
 command of the earth, but it does not necessarily 
 involve war. Emigration throughout the greatest part 
 of the world, within and without the limits of Europe, 
 now proceeds by acceptance of the local authority, 
 such as it may be. In so far as that principle is 
 observed war is avoided, and the cases in which it may 
 be impossible to observe it — cases in which the local 
 authority is inherently and continuously incapable of 
 maintaining social order — are now so few that it is 
 easily possible to provide for them by an international 
 understanding. 
 
 The human command of the earth, therefore — that 
 command on which the total edifice of the Catholic 
 life, including the life of the nation, ultimately depends 
 — cannot be shown to demand war. So far as the 
 greater body of trade — international trade — is con- 
 cerned it is actually obtained by peaceful exchange ; 
 so far as its lesser body, imperial trade, is concerned 
 it is obtained by the same essential process, without 
 securing a monopoly ; and so far as the “ unoccupied ” 
 
A CATHOLIC POLICY OF PEACE 237 
 
 or under-occupied parts of the earth are concerned it 
 may be obtained by emigration, recognizing and 
 accepting any existing local authority. A Catholic 
 policy directed towards the installation and main- 
 tenance of a Human Peace would found itself on these 
 considerations. It would prohibit industrial im- 
 perialism — and this not merely because imperialism 
 in all its forms means war, but because it is, in our 
 modern world, unnecessary to secure that command of 
 the earth for which it is prosecuted, and which we can 
 see to be indispensable to the Catholic life. It con- 
 demns and disallows this policy because by emigration 
 the two main connected purposes are secured which 
 industrial imperialism, explicitly or implicitly, seeks 
 to accomplish. First, it relieves what we may call 
 the European pressure upon the soil ; secondly, it 
 helps to complete man’s mastery over the earth, and 
 to give to his social and intellectual life the material 
 basis which it needs. It must, however, be under- 
 stood that emigration is only thus an alternative to 
 industrial imperialism, and a prevention of war, when 
 the emigrant assumes his true character. He cannot 
 be both a citizen of the country which he leaves and of 
 the country in which he settles. An Englishman, 
 even when, for example, he emigrates to Australia or 
 Canada, ceases to be an Englishman. He becomes an 
 Australian or Canadian. He is incorporated in a new 
 emerging national life, which in course of time, as 
 cannot be doubted, will become in form, what it already 
 largely is in fact, an independent sovereign State. 
 Even more is this principle important when the 
 
238 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 British subject settles, as often happens, not in a 
 British possession, but, for instance, in the United 
 States, or in one of the South American republics. 
 The general principle must be recognized that when a 
 European — an Englishman, a German, or an Itahan — 
 emigrates from his own country, and becomes the sub- 
 ject of another State, he passes wholly out of political 
 relation with his native land, and is then amenable 
 to the institutions of the country to which he goes. 
 
 Industrial imperialism we have defined as a policy 
 establishing, by force of arms, the supremacy of one 
 country over another for industrial purposes. Such a 
 policy is, by its nature and definition, a war policy. 
 There is, however, one form of industrial imperialism 
 which, because of its importance in the modern world, 
 needs to be especially considered. We may, perhaps, 
 for the sake of distinction, caU it the imperialism of 
 foreign investments. So considering it, we may dis- 
 tinguish between the strictly industrial character of 
 foreign investments and their possible political conse- 
 quences. Further, we may, for our present purpose, 
 disregard the questions — many of them certainly of 
 high difficulty and importance — of the exclusively 
 domestic effect of such investments either on the nation 
 lending or the nation borrowing. We are now only 
 concerned with their bearing upon the problem of 
 peace — with their relation to the policy of industrial 
 imperialism, and, as a consequence, to that command 
 of the products of the earth which this policy is 
 designed to subserve. In principle the export of 
 capital to a foreign country may be said to be only one 
 
A CATHOLIC POLICY OF PEACE 239 
 
 form of international trade or exchange. It is a form 
 of trade, however, which may easily give rise to the 
 particular political relations which constitute industrial 
 imperialism. These relations doubtless are not so 
 likely to arise when the financial transactions are 
 between two nations of something like equal standing 
 and power. In such instances, when the capitalists 
 of one country lend money to the inhabitants of 
 another, they accept the risks of the situation, as they 
 accept them in ordinary domestic business. They do 
 not count on a sort of political guarantee from their 
 own country. When, however, the transactions are 
 between a strong and a weak country the case is 
 different. Then what appears to be a purely indus- 
 trial enterprise on the part of the stronger State may 
 become political, and be the prelude to imperialism. 
 Any inability on the part of the weaker country to 
 meet its obligations may be a pretext for some form of 
 intervention and control in its affairs on the part of the 
 stronger. By such intervention its internal political 
 order is still further disturbed, its governing authority 
 is still further weakened, and a situation is created in 
 which additional interference on the part of the ex- 
 ternal power appears to be called for, an interference 
 preparing the way for ultimate annexation. 
 
 Just, therefore, as we can see that the unoccupied 
 or under-occupied portions of the earth are, from the 
 standpoint of a policy of peace, international danger- 
 points, which must be taken into account and guarded 
 against, so also the financial transactions between 
 States, and especially between States of unequal power. 
 
240 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 are danger-points, which may easily become points of 
 disorder and war. And here again a Catholic inter- 
 national policy needs to be founded on science, taking 
 complete and dispassionate account of the actual 
 forces and relations of man and his environment. It 
 cannot be founded on sentiment, however high. It 
 must be based on the principle that it is necessary for 
 “ man ” — the universal man of every nation — to 
 possess a command over the products of the earth. If 
 for such a command war is necessary, war — horrible 
 as it may seem from a certain standpoint — must be 
 accepted, but if it is not thus necessary, then, to a 
 scientific Catholic, pursuing a total human Perfection 
 according to Christ, it is not only evil, but senseless. 
 It is a form of aberration, moral, intellectual, and 
 practical. Now, war is a special application of 
 material force directed to slaughter and destruction. 
 It is, however, as is obvious, a force not immediately 
 employed upon the earth. It has no direct connection 
 with industry, which is always ultimately reducible 
 to agriculture. War does not plough the land, or sow 
 the seed, or gather in the harvest, or grind the corn, 
 or make the bread, or build the ships which transport 
 wheat from one country to another. In the same way, 
 it does not clothe or house men, or procure for them 
 heat, light, or locomotion. It does not, by its own 
 processes, enable them to live the Catholic Hfe, to 
 maintain the home, the Church, the school, the theatre, 
 the State, and the workshop. Nevertheless, war has 
 its victories as well as peace. It has no direct con- 
 nection with agriculture, but it can, in principle and in 
 
A CATHOLIC POLICY OF PEACE 241 
 
 its extreme form, enable a given society of agricul- 
 turists to entirely exclude another society from the 
 earth by killing them. It could enable a society con- 
 sidering itself “ higher ” or “ better ” to so exclude a 
 society considered to be “ lower ” or “ worse.” It 
 could, for example, enable aU the white races of man- 
 kind — ^assuming them to be sufficiently powerful — to 
 kill off all the yellow and black races. Then the white 
 races would remain the sole possessors of the earth, and 
 could proceed with its undisturbed culture, for the 
 purposes of the Cathohc life. 
 
 Such a supposition may seem in the last degree 
 extravagant. It is, however, not so extravagant as it 
 may appear. As a matter of fact, and historically 
 speaking, the relations between what we may broadly 
 call Europe and non-Europe, or between Christendom 
 and non-Christendom, have been largely based on the 
 assumption, or implication, that what considered itself 
 to be the higher humanity had no obligations towards 
 the lower, but was entitled, if it could, to conquer it, 
 take possession of its territory, and rule it for the advan- 
 tage of its conquerors. No other principle than this, 
 for example, has, down to the present day, governed 
 the action of England with regard to the native races 
 of America, Asia, Africa, and Australia ; and what is 
 true of England is true of almost every country in 
 Europe. But not only is it true of the relations of 
 Europe and non-Europe, of a higher civilization in 
 contact with a lower ; it is true also of the internal 
 relations of the rich and the poor, of the capitalists and 
 the working classes, in every European nation. What 
 
242 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 we call the higher, or upper, classes in a country exclude 
 from the earth — or, what comes to the same thing, 
 exclude from the adequate possession of its products 
 — the great mass of the community. Such an exclu- 
 sion is, in principle, not only accepted — it is upheld 
 and sanctioned by the general mind of the nation. It 
 is defended and justified by “ the Church.” In other 
 words, the perpetual existence of an “ aristocracy,” or 
 upper class, and a “ lower class ” — of a comparatively 
 small number of men basing an ample human life on a 
 large command of the earth and a vast number basing 
 a meagre life on a small command — this is, explicitly or 
 implicitly, held to be both inevitable and beneficent. 
 
 But if it is true that within the limits of a single 
 civilized nation the upper class, or the higher social 
 life, is entitled to maintain itself at the expense of the 
 lower, much more may it seem to be true that Western 
 civilization is entitled to maintain itself at the expense 
 of non-Western mankind, or Christendom at the ex- 
 pense of non-Christendom, or the white races at the 
 expense of the yellow and black. We may even hold, 
 as has been argued by various eminent thinkers, that 
 the best thing that can happen to the lower is to be 
 mastered and ruled by the higher, and that there- 
 fore, for example, no happier destiny could befall 
 the three hundred millions of British India than to 
 be under the government of the forty-five millions 
 of the United Kingdom. We may formulate the 
 general principle that that which conquers is, by the 
 mere fact that it conquers, proved to be higher — 
 higher, at least, in the qualities essential for social 
 
A CATHOLIC POLICY OF PEACE 243 
 
 command and co-ordination — and that the conquered 
 people is the lower people, whether by “ the people ” 
 we mean the working classes of a European nation, or 
 such native races as those of Africa and Asia, held 
 subject by British power. To this principle of racial 
 or class inferiority what we may call the Catholic 
 principle may, it is true, seem to go counter. The 
 Catholic principle is a principle of universal Perfection 
 in Christ. Catholicism, so understood, sees Christ, the 
 ideal man, in the humblest of human beings — in the 
 black man or the yellow man as in the white man. 
 Its aim is not to retain men in their inferiority, but 
 to raise them in the scale of being and make them 
 heirs of a total humanity. From this point of view, 
 imperialism, which aims at the forcible subjection of 
 inferiors by superiors, and thinks mainly of the good of 
 the best, may seem to be irreconcilable with Catholi- 
 cism, which would, as far as possible, raise inferiors 
 to the level of superiors, and thinks of the good of the 
 whole. Against this conception of Catholicism may, 
 of course, be urged the traditional view — that its Land 
 of Promise is heavenly and not earthly. According to 
 this view, the black and the yellow races, although they 
 may remain subject and inferior in this world, will 
 change their colour and status in “ the next ” ; and in 
 the same way the working classes and the poor of 
 European civilization ought to remain content with 
 their present lot till after death, because they may then 
 begin their entrance into a celestial kingdom. 
 
 It is, however, not at the standpoint of this tra- 
 ditional view — if it is the traditional view — of Catholi- 
 
244 the problem OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 cism, but at the standpoint of Catholicism become 
 scientific, and therefore in a complete sense Catholic, 
 that we are placing ourselves in this work. Such a 
 Catholicism sees things as they are — the universe and 
 man as he enters, age after age, into larger relation with 
 it and becomes the right interpreter of it and of himself. 
 Such a Catholicism, too, being in Christ both fixed 
 and progressive — finding in Him a continuing Abso- 
 lute which is always emerging into fuller significance — 
 knows nothing, in its moments of vision, of Europe 
 and non-Europe, or of white, yellow and black races. 
 It knows only man, and has as its first and last aim to 
 make him Catholic. It is in the light of this aim that 
 it examines imperialism, and war as its inevitable con- 
 sequence. It applies to war certain specific practical 
 tests which are also Catholic tests. War is conceivably 
 a good if it enables the white races of mankind, as the 
 “ higher,” to extirpate the yellow and black races, as 
 the “ lower,” and become the sole possessors of the 
 earth. Setting aside such a supposition as extrava- 
 gant and monstrous, war, we may say, is a good if it 
 enables the higher races not to extirpate but to sub- 
 jugate the lower, so that as labourers upon the earth 
 the lower may support their own limited life and at the 
 same time minister to the richer, fuller life of the higher. 
 From this point of view, the white races — or if not the 
 white races, the races of “ Christendom ” may be 
 regarded as the natural aristocrats of mankind, and as 
 thus entitled to rule over its other races and to organize 
 inferiority for the advantage of both inferiority and 
 superiority. It may be argued, also, that imperialism, in 
 
A CATHOLIC POLICY OF PEACE 245 
 
 this sense, need not always be a cause of war. We may 
 suppose the white races of mankind — the guardians 
 of what we call “ Christendom,” or Western civiliza- 
 tion — to agree among themselves as to a common line 
 of policy to be adopted in regard to the yellow and 
 black races, including, for the sake of convenience, the 
 whole of non-Christendom, Mohammedan or other. 
 Dividing mankind, then, into “ Christendom ” and 
 “ non-Christendom,” and using these terms as equiva- 
 lent to a “ higher ” and “ lower ” humanity, we may 
 consider it to be possible for the nations of Christen- 
 dom to agree to portion out the world of non-Christen- 
 dom among themselves, and to preserve a universal 
 peace by respecting each other’s “ sphere of interest.” 
 Within certain limits, as we know, this has already 
 been attempted, and it may be considered that if such a 
 “ world policy ” became complete and systematic, not 
 only would war be avoided, but a total human com- 
 mand of the earth would be gained, by which the 
 lower would live according to the needs of the lower 
 and the higher according to the needs of the higher. 
 This policy, too, it may be held, would naturally put 
 an end to imperialism. By imperialism, defined as we 
 have defined it, is meant, not the preservation of exist- 
 ing empires, but their further extension, whether for 
 political or industrial ends. Consequently, if the 
 nations of “ Christendom ” came to a pacific under- 
 standing for a final partition of non-Christendom 
 among themselves, and also to abstain from aggressive 
 attacks upon each other, imperialism, as a policy of 
 war, would end itself by fulfilling itself. 
 
246 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 While, therefore, it is true that war, considered as 
 a process of slaughter and destruction, has no direct 
 relation to the ends of industry, we may argue that 
 it has this important relation to them, that it may 
 enable the higher humanity to hold the lower in a 
 bondage which is proper to its natural inferiority, and 
 thus to make it instrumental to the good of the 
 higher, while gaining for itself all the good of which 
 it is capable. Against this conclusion, however, 
 certain important considerations may be adduced. 
 First, what we have broadly called “ non-Christen- 
 dom ” represents not a minority, but the great mass 
 of mankind. From the point of view of numbers 
 alone “ Christendom ” is, relatively to that immense 
 mass, insignificant. Secondly, this non-Christian 
 mass is not dead or stagnant. It is a living, moving 
 body of forces, which, as it cannot be annihilated, so it 
 cannot have arbitrary limits assigned to it by external 
 agencies. On the contrary, the external agencies 
 playing upon it are such as serve to quicken and 
 develop its power. Non-Christendom is, in our 
 modern world, gaining from Christendom a new 
 vitahty — mind, culture, a progressive capacity to 
 shape itself, to organize itself, and defend itself. 
 While it is true that Christendom, as the advanced 
 guard of mankind, is not likely to forfeit its historic 
 pre-eminence, it is yet more and more tending to lose 
 its ability to impose limits upon the expansion and 
 development of non-Christendom. Thirdly, there is 
 no probability, drawn from experience, that the 
 nations of Christendom will ever be able to maintain 
 
A CATHOLIC POLICY OF PEACE 247 
 
 a permanent peace among themselves based upon a 
 common mastery and exploitation of non-Christen- 
 dom. There is, for one thing, no such unity of mind 
 and purpose in Christendom itself as would be neces- 
 sary to ensure such a result. We have used the 
 broad terms “ Christendom ” and “ non-Christen- 
 dom ” as convenient expressions of sociological com- 
 parison, but “ Christendom ” does not denote a 
 settled order of thought and action. It stands, 
 among other things, for a world of hostile Churches 
 and sects, for a deep and growing antagonism of 
 belief and unbelief, for a strife of nations, for a 
 vast conflict of classes, for a constant clash of material 
 interests, for a perpetual, insatiable greed for wealth. 
 History and experience give no sanction to the view 
 that such a Christendom can bring in and maintain 
 a Human Peace, based on no other principle than that 
 of a common predominance over non-Christendom, 
 even assuming non-Christendom to remain for ever 
 inert or incapable. They rather make it certain that 
 those who can only agree to pursue a policy of im- 
 periaHsm are certain sooner or later to turn their 
 imperialism against one another, and that a mere 
 compact among the States of Europe to respect each 
 other’s conquests beyond the limits of Europe is no 
 guarantee against war in Europe itself. 
 
 But if this is true, then it is plain that the policy 
 of imperialism, being a war policy, is from beginning 
 to end, and however we test it, unsound. The one 
 justification that it might seem to have is that while 
 securing the predominance of the higher humanity 
 
248 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 over the lower, it would end itself by fulfilling itself, 
 and would bring in the peace of mankind by establish- 
 ing a sort of universal empire of Christendom over non- 
 Christendom. But to this justification, as we have 
 shown, it cannot lay claim. It is, however, not 
 enough even to say this. Not only is it true that 
 imperialism, being a war policy, cannot bring in the 
 ascendency and reign of the higher humanity — cannot, 
 in other words, subserve a positive, many-sided Per- 
 fection in Christ — but it must, from the nature of 
 things, hinder and frustrate it. War is not a subor- 
 dination of the lower and fulfilment of the higher ; it 
 is, on the contrary, a sacrifice of the higher and preser- 
 vation of the lower. It takes what is most perfect in 
 man and destroys it. It takes the men who are best in 
 body and leaves the worst. It takes the men who 
 are best in mind — masters of the spirit, ministers of 
 goodness, beauty, and truth, and reduces them to 
 the level of mere physical fighters, to kill or be killed. 
 It brings into a companionship of slaughter and 
 destruction the wise and the foolish, the educated and 
 the uneducated, the mediocrity and the man of genius, 
 the profligate and the pure, the sober and the drunken, 
 the provident and the spendthrift, the wife-beater 
 and selfish son and the devoted husband and father, 
 the man who may carry in his mind some high vision 
 and power of human good and the senseless sensualist, 
 who has lived as an animal lives, but who yet, on the 
 field of battle, dies as an animal dies, with an instinc- 
 tive unhesitating ferocity and courage. It does this, 
 too, not necessarily to subserve some great interest of 
 
A CATHOLIC POLICY OF PEACE 249 
 
 human life, spiritual or temporal — the home, the 
 Church, the school, the theatre, the State, and the 
 workshop — but perhaps to give effect to the ambition 
 of a monarch, or the mistakes of a statesman, or the 
 blindness of a people, or the designs of a governing 
 caste, or a common exorbitant desire for wealth, 
 or the mere suspicion and jealousy of contending 
 nations. 
 
 We must, then, from the point of view of a Scientific 
 Catholicism, come to this conclusion, not only that 
 war is, in our modern world, and relatively to the End 
 of Life, not a good, but that it is an immeasurable 
 evil — a hindrance and frustration of the very pur- 
 poses which a Catholic humanity must propose to 
 itself, whether we think of that indispensable com- 
 mand of the earth by which such a humanity must be 
 nourished, or of the high aims of love, goodness, 
 beauty, truth, and disciplined power to which it is 
 dedicated. In other words, war is for Catholic man — 
 the developed man of the modern synthesis, founding 
 a many-sided perfection on the total experience and 
 culture of the world — a miscarriage. It is a form of 
 lunacy. It is a mode of suicide. By it man, as the 
 Hving temple of God, a sanctuary and vessel of all 
 Perfection, consciously and intentionally destroys 
 himself. War, in our modern world, does not spring 
 from some insurgent impulse of passion in a barbaric 
 being. It is a product of foresight and system. It is 
 chosen and willed. It is the result of a policy de- 
 liberately pursued from year to year, ratified in the 
 counsels of statesmen, approved by the acquiescence 
 
250 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 of citizenship, sanctioned by the consent of religion. 
 To end war, if it is ever to be ended, to bring in the 
 Human Peace, if it is ever to be brought in, we must 
 end the policy which makes war inevitable, and bring 
 in the policy which has peace as its natural issue. 
 The war policy is imperialism — either the political 
 imperialism by which one nation interferes with 
 another to secure some alleged political end, or 
 industrial imperialism, such as we have now defined 
 it. If imperialism in either of these forms is necessary, 
 war is justifiable, and justifiable as aggressive war, 
 which any given nation, being a lord of its own life 
 and a judge in its own cause, is, from its own point 
 of view, entitled to bring about. Against such an 
 imperialism there is only one influence, one policy, to 
 which an effectual appeal can be made. International 
 law is, as we have shown, an international illusion. 
 Treaties have a validity and force which cease with 
 the weakness of the country upon which they have 
 been imposed, or the needs of those who have entered 
 into them. The mere sentiment of peace, the mere 
 sense of the waste and inhumanity of war, has never 
 prevented, and will never prevent, men from entering 
 into it. A mere political change — the transference 
 of the governing power from the “ aristocracy ” to 
 the “ democracy ; ” a mere industrial change, the 
 abolition of “ capitalism,” the establishment of 
 “ socialism ” — these, by themselves, inevitable or 
 desirable as they may otherwise be, cannot bring in 
 the Human Peace. It can only be brought in, if it is 
 ever to be brought in, by a Scientific Catholicism, 
 
A CATHOLIC POLICY OF PEACE 251 
 
 showing man to himself as an interpreting mind, as a 
 modifying will, in the universe in which he has been 
 set to work out his hfe, and making it clear to him 
 that war is a frustration of the ends which he con- 
 tinuously proposes to himself, and peace a condition 
 indispensable to their fulfilment. 
 
CHAPTER X 
 
 THE REPUBLIC OF PEACE 
 
 It is, as we have now seen, from the point of view of a 
 Scientific Catholicism, possible to show, not only that 
 war is, in our modern world, a frustration of the Ends 
 of Perfection, the high, continuous aims of human life, 
 but that the ends which seem to call for it and justify 
 it — and most of all man’s industrial command of the 
 earth — can only be secured by a systematic policy of 
 peace. Such a policy we may call a Catholic policy — 
 a policy taking account of the situation and total 
 needs of man, as a many-sided being, lower and higher, 
 pressing forward through the ages to a positive 
 fulfilment of himself in Christ. While, however, we 
 may, in this way, gain the conception of such a 
 policy — see how it follows from the very nature of 
 Catholicism, as a conscious and progressive move- 
 ment of man towards an ideal end — this, by itself, 
 cannot suffice to bring in the Human Peace. The 
 policy, in order to prevail, must gain a place in 
 the mind of the world — find for itself voices, organs, 
 and methods of application. In relation to this 
 subject, as in relation to the whole problem of a 
 Human Peace, it is essential that we should not 
 deceive ourselves. A Scientific Catholicism must at 
 least be scientific. It must recognize the character 
 of the forces — material, intellectual, moral — which 
 
THE REPUBLIC OF PEACE 
 
 253 
 
 have to be overcome, or controlled, before a Human 
 Peace can be established. It may, as we must admit, 
 be impossible ever to establish it. We have said that 
 its full command of science — that is to say, of the 
 ordered experience and power of a developed humanity 
 — ^will give to Catholicism, in the prosecution of its 
 unending aims, a resource such as it has never yet 
 possessed. That is our new and sure ground of hope 
 for the human future — a reason for believing that a 
 universal and continuous peace, which has hitherto 
 been impossible, may yet become possible. It is 
 obvious, however, that, even with this great resource 
 at our command, the only certainty we can have in 
 regard to a thing not actually given in experience is a 
 certainty of faith. Such a certainty, however, belongs 
 to the very genius of Catholicism. It is contrary to 
 its essential character to despair of man. It puts 
 forward, and has always put forward, the doctrine 
 of human responsibility. Such a responsibility, how- 
 ever, implies freedom. It implies power — a power in 
 man, for example, to order his elemental passions, and 
 make them subject to a rule of perfection. But if 
 such a power exists in one sphere, it exists in another. 
 If it exists in regard to the instincts of nutrition and 
 sex, it exists in regard to the forces, working within 
 the nature of man, which bring about war. And such 
 a capacity for self-control and self-direction we 
 affirm not merely in spite of its failures, but — if the 
 paradox may be allowed — because of them. 
 
 Therefore, if we say that the attainment of a Human 
 Peace may conceivably be impossible, this does not 
 
254 the problem OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 mean that man is, by any external or internal con- 
 straint, made necessarily subject to the forces of war, 
 or that the science of peace is not sure ; it means 
 only, what we all know, that the mere knowledge of 
 a truth is not sufficient to bring about its application, 
 and that men may see the way to peace as they see 
 the way to sobriety and chastity, and yet not pursue 
 it. It is the business of “ the Church ” — that is to 
 say, of man, as a mind and will, acting or reacting 
 upon himself for definite spiritual ends by means of 
 definite organs and institutions — to move them to 
 walk in it. This, however, can only be done by the 
 adoption of specific methods. The Catholic doctrine, 
 or policy, of peace we have now, in sufficient degree, 
 explained. This doctrine we have called scientific. 
 By this, however, we do not mean that it is, in its 
 essential spirit and purposes, new. Science is not an 
 invention of the new ; it is a revelation, an explana- 
 tion, of the old. What we have called the Catholic 
 doctrine of a Human Peace has been present in 
 Catholicism from the first, although present in spon- 
 taneous and immature forms — as “ the prophetic 
 soul of the wide world, dreaming on things to come.” 
 But Catholicism — Christ organizing Himself in the 
 life of man — has never existed as a thing absolute 
 and external to humanity. It has always existed, 
 and it still exists, as a part of the life of humanity, 
 gaining significance and character, limitation or 
 expansion, hindrance or help, from the nature of that 
 life, according to its seasons of comparative torpor or 
 progressive activity. Catholicism is, for contemporary 
 
THE REPUBLIC OF PEACE 
 
 255 
 
 practical purposes, what the great mass of Catholics 
 are at any given time. Therefore, a Catholic doctrine 
 of peace, scientifically sure as it is, and consonant with 
 the eternal spirit of Catholicism as it can be shown to 
 be, will not necessarily, at any given moment, com- 
 mand the immediate assent of “ the Church ” — the 
 Church being, at a given moment, nothing more than 
 the vast majority of average men and women, laity 
 and ecclesiastics, subject to their own incapacity, 
 their own ignorance, their own inertia, and to the 
 active prejudices of nation, class, party, and material 
 self-interest. 
 
 Such a doctrine, such a policy, must, consequently, 
 first find for itself a place and instruments in the mind 
 of the Church. The Church, as such, is a spiritual 
 power — a power operating upon the affections, intelli- 
 gence, and will. It does not, in the strict sense of 
 the word, compel. It educates. It persuades, and 
 it prays. It helps men to worship. It governs that 
 which is without by means of that which is within. 
 The Catholic doctrine of peace must in this way reach 
 the life of the world — through the teaching Church. 
 By the teaching Church, of course, we do not mean 
 merely its priests as such. The Church teaches by its 
 doctors — philosophers, scientific men, historians, men 
 of letters, and even its poets and artists, as well as 
 by its priesthood ; and when it is a question of bring- 
 ing into it a new impulse, a new vision, a new power 
 of progressive life, it is to the genius of the prophet, 
 in the large sense, that we must look, rather than to 
 the average priest, working within the limits of tra- 
 
256 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 ditional conceptions, and concerned with a routine 
 functional task. Nevertheless, the Church is a unity. 
 What is given to it from the mind of the prophet, the 
 scientific discoverer, the philosopher, the man of 
 genius, the poet, the musician, the painter, must, in 
 some measure at least, eventually be given forth again 
 by the mind of the priest. If there is a Catholic 
 science or policy of peace — ^as distinguished from a 
 merely sentimental confession of it as a good, or 
 platonic acknowledgment of it as an ideal — it must 
 breathe its spirit into worship and make itself felt 
 as a force of teaching. Every Catholic Church 
 must become, in a perfectly definite sense, a school of 
 peace — not leaving so great a cause to the chance 
 guardianship of itinerant orators, or individual pub- 
 licists, or political parties, but showing that it is the 
 cause of Catholicism itself, and that Catholicism 
 knows how to uphold and promote it. Such an 
 advocacy of peace needs, of course, not only know- 
 ledge, but courage. The Catholic priest, being a 
 teacher of social truth, must not be the Don Abbondio 
 of I Promessi Sposi, but its Cardinal Borromeo. If 
 the blind cannot lead the blind, still less can the 
 cowardly lead the courageous. It is as necessary for 
 a teacher in the modern world to be faithful to his 
 charge against the mere ascendency of wealth, or the 
 clamour of an angry mob, as it was for a priest of the 
 seventeenth century to withstand the brutality of 
 some petty tyrant. It is, of course, not his business 
 to denounce men, or inflame their resentment. The 
 office of a teacher is to teach ; but as he cannot teach 
 
THE REPUBLIC OF PEACE 
 
 257 
 
 without sympathy, tact, and knowledge, so also there 
 are occasions when he cannot teach without the 
 courage to proclaim unpopular or unacceptable truths. 
 
 We may, however, suppose that the Catholic doc- 
 trine of peace has established itself in the teaching 
 mind of the Church, as a thing congruous with its 
 persistent aims and essential to their complete ful- 
 filment. By “ the Church,” of course, we here mean, 
 in the first instance, the Church of Rome, the Church 
 which has the inestimable advantage of possessing 
 the Papacy as its head. This Church is an inter- 
 national Church — the only one that exists. It is, as 
 such, an independent Spiritual Power. It is a mind 
 capable of penetrating and regulating the whole body 
 of humanity. It is of East and West, of North and 
 South, of the Old World and the New. It has ad- 
 herents and voices in all the great races of mankind. 
 It is the one Church which is in a position to give 
 forth a universal religious message to men. We shall 
 suppose this Church — that is to say, its leading minds, 
 its thinkers and priests — to give forth such a message, 
 to proclaim a universal policy of peace — a policy, not 
 a sentiment only, not a Utopia, not an ideal, but a 
 definite, reasoned and practicable policy, such as a 
 responsible statesmanship may, if it is willing, adopt, 
 and such as an active citizenship may impose upon 
 it, if it should prove unwilling. Such a policy, from 
 the nature of the case, cannot be brought in by any 
 one nation alone, although any one nation, by its 
 own independent influence and action, may certainly 
 do much to promote it. It demands the consent and 
 
258 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 co-operation of all the predominant countries of the 
 world, and especially, of course, of Christendom. 
 The policy, being such as we have here defined it — ■ 
 depending, first, on the common acceptance of an 
 actual status quo, as not to be subject to forcible 
 disturbance ; secondly, on a consequent disarmament 
 by land and sea ; thirdly, on the general abstinence 
 from an aggressive imperialism, political or industrial ; 
 fourthly, on the realization of man’s command of the 
 earth by free international exchange and pacific 
 emigration ; fifthly, on the adoption of common 
 measures relatively to the “ danger-points ” of inter- 
 national order, of whatever kind — this policy, being 
 Catholic in its governing ends, and Catholic also in 
 the wide human agreement which it requires, needs to 
 be promoted in the various nations of Christendom 
 by an authority which, in degree at least, springs from 
 their common life and represents them all. Such an 
 authority is the Catholic Church, centred and directed 
 at Rome. 
 
 Even, however, if we suppose the international 
 mind of the Church, its teaching, or directing, mind, 
 to be penetrated by the conception of such a policy, 
 it still remains clear that great and continuous diffi- 
 culties must attend its common acceptance and 
 maintenance. Those difficulties arise from the essen- 
 tial character of the policy itself, and from its relation 
 to the nature of man, politically and morally con- 
 sidered. The war policy is, as we have seen, im- 
 perialism. The peace policy is the abandonment of 
 imperialism, and the attainment of its Catholic aims 
 
THE REPUBLIC OF PEACE 
 
 259 
 
 by pacific measures. But imperialism springs from 
 two main motives— one distinctively political, the 
 other distinctively industrial. We may, for purposes 
 of comparison, call its political motive nationalism, 
 understanding by nationalism the disposition to in- 
 terfere with the domestic freedom and possessions of 
 another country for the aggrandizement of one’s own. 
 So defining nationalism, we are able to distinguish 
 between it and patriotism. Patriotism we may con- 
 sider to be a disinterested and active love of one’s 
 own country. Such a feeling is not necessarily 
 exclusive. It is not, by its own nature, a source of 
 hostihty to other nations. It may be without 
 jealousy or suspicion. It does not demand war for 
 its satisfaction or manifestation. It may be noblest 
 and most beneficent in peace. It may uphold peace 
 as a high national good. It may condemn and resist 
 war as a supreme national evil. It may, when a war 
 has been brought about by a mistaken and short- 
 sighted policy, refuse to sanction it, and abstain from 
 all voluntary concurrence in it. It may represent the 
 sane, continuous mind of a nation, looking to its 
 permanent good, and continuing loyal to that good 
 amidst the passing passions of a given time, or the 
 misconceptions of party and class. 
 
 Of such a patriotism, in natural opposition to an 
 aggressive nationalism, a Scientific Catholicism — 
 being here, as elsewhere, only scientific in its right 
 discernment and expression of a principle which 
 Catholicism has always proclaimed — must be the 
 voice and organ. So long as an aggressive nationalism 
 
26 o the problem of HUMAN PEACE 
 
 exists war must exist ; and Catholicism, in its pursuit 
 of a Human Peace, has to lift men’s minds above it 
 and maintain them in a higher plane of vision and 
 effort. It is, as is clear, only the Catholic Church, the 
 international Church, that can do this, and it is also 
 clear that it cannot do it by a s.udden summons — by 
 the denunciation of an evil policy, or the proclamation 
 of a wise policy, in a time of crisis ; it can only do it 
 by education, by a prescient, constant direction of 
 the human mind to the ends, whether of the personal 
 or the civic Hfe, which Catholicism proposes to it. 
 In a time of crisis, and stiff more in a time of actual 
 hostilities, Catholicism, the Spiritual Power, is, as a 
 directing agency, almost effaced. That is the hour of 
 the statesman or the soldier — the hour when the 
 priest and the teacher, relatively to the causes and 
 issues of war, become nullities. It is in peace, and 
 by the methods of peace, that the peace of the world 
 is to be prepared. It is then only that the voice of 
 the Church can be heard. If, then, a Scientific 
 Catholicism is to overcome a restless and aggressive 
 nationalism, it must be by a continuous spiritual 
 process, the process of the teacher — exactly the same 
 process as that which is adopted by the scientific 
 thinker when he educates men to act upon the forces 
 of Nature, or as is employed by a professor when he 
 is seeking to give to his students the perceptions and 
 the capacity of a definite art. This, indeed, has 
 always been the characteristic method of the Church. 
 It does not wait until sin is committed before ex- 
 plaining its nature, or arousing men against it. Its 
 
THE REPUBLIC OF PEACE 
 
 261 
 
 provision against sin begins with life, and con- 
 tinues throughout life. In the same way, having 
 a doctrine of peace, it will educate men in peace for 
 the ends of peace, and overcome the spirit of an 
 aggressive nationalism by the spirit of Catholicism. 
 Recognizing that war is a sin against Catholicism, a 
 frustration of its purposes— that it is for man, pur- 
 suing the Perfection of Christ, a form of aberration 
 and suicide — ^it will not wait till it has actually 
 broken out before condemning it, but will aim at so 
 shaping the mind and conduct of men that it may be 
 possible for them to avoid it. 
 
 If it is evident that only by the action of the 
 international Church can an aggressive nationalism be 
 overcome, it is still more clear that only by such a 
 Spiritual Power can an aggressive industrialism, or 
 industrial imperialism, be transformed into a pacific 
 and world-wide human co-operation. The roots of 
 international policy, as we have already said, must 
 be sought in the national life, and the national life is 
 only a collective expression of the life of the soul. The 
 connection between public life and private life is, 
 indeed, so deep and indissoluble that we may seem to 
 be imprisoned in a vicious circle when we say that 
 it is from “ the Church ” alone — the Church being 
 simply human nature considered in a special relation 
 — that we can expect the direction of the mind of 
 man to the ends of peace. Quis custodict tpsos 
 custodes ? “ If the salt hath lost its savour, where- 
 with shall it be salted ? ” What we have called 
 industrial imperialism in the international sphere has, 
 
262 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 as we have shown, its foundation in the conflict of 
 classes and individuals in the national sphere. 
 Neither the one nor the other springs from the need 
 merely for such a right command of the earth as is 
 indispensable for the Catholic life. They spring 
 from a desire for monopoly, or ascendency, having 
 no necessary relation to that life. Stating the same 
 truth in other words, we may say that they spring 
 from an individual craving for material wealth irre- 
 spective of any spiritual and social use which is to 
 be made of it. The existence of such a craving, pro- 
 ducing such results, is, of course, one proof that 
 Catholicism, considered as a doctrine and organization 
 of the spiritual life, is unable to counteract the 
 pressure of what, from its own standpoint, we call 
 the lower instincts. And this again, in a last analysis, 
 means exactly what St. Paul means when he says : 
 “ The good which I would I do not ; but the evil 
 which I would not that I practise.” The inordinate 
 personal desire for wealth — apart from what we may 
 now call its Catholic uses — is not the characteristic 
 of any one nation, or of any one class, or of any one 
 individual ; it is to be found in every nation and 
 class and amongst almost all individuals. It is so 
 constant and potent a factor in the life of man that 
 in our so-called science of economics we assume its 
 inevitable and regular action, as in physics we assume 
 the action of gravity. Being such a factor, it works 
 in “ the Church ” — that is to say, among men and 
 women associated for certain spiritual ends — as it 
 works in “ the world,” and it works in the priest who 
 
THE REPUBLIC OF PEACE 263 
 
 proclaims the ideals of Catholic Perfection as it 
 works in the people to whom he proclaims them. 
 
 We may seem, therefore, in our reliance upon the 
 Church to deliver us from the craving for wealth, to 
 be involved in the dilemma of expecting grapes from 
 thorns, or figs from thistles — of being dependent on an 
 imperfect human nature, as it shows itself in both the 
 temporal and the spiritual spheres, for the very power 
 which is to save us from that nature. This dilemma, 
 too, may appear to be the greater in proportion as the 
 area of what we caU the Church is extended. An indi- 
 vidual man may be a “ saint ” — ^that is to say, he may 
 live an ordered, holy, beautiful life by a strong and 
 persistent resistance to an adverse social pressure. In 
 a monastery, or a religious order, or even in a restricted 
 and restrictive sect, men and women may, for a time 
 at least, continue in a high plane of spiritual being 
 without compromising their religious fidelity. But 
 when “ the Church ” is as wide as the world the distinc- 
 tion between the Church and “the world” — in other 
 words, between a disciplined and an undisciplined 
 life — becomes, to a great extent, abrogated. The 
 Catholic Church, which reprobates “ the world,” is 
 itself the world. We can only escape from this 
 dilemma by recognizing the two meanings — a lower 
 and a higher meaning — which naturally attach to 
 the word “ Church.” It represents, on the one hand, 
 the whole continuous body of the faithful such as 
 they, in disposition and practice, actually are, 
 including the priesthood ; it represents, on the other, 
 the high spiritual mind of this society, expressed in 
 
264 the problem OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 Scripture, creeds, sacraments, doctrines, and above 
 all in forms of prayer and worship. This mind is the 
 mind of the aristocracy, of the best, or it is the mind 
 of the many in their best moments. The progressive 
 life of man, as a Catholic, depends on the constant 
 reassertion and development of this nobler mind, in 
 opposition to the mind of the inert or resistant social 
 man, whether in the laity or in the priesthood. This 
 is a truth of aU religious experience, from the time of 
 Our Lord to the present day. The mere craving for 
 wealth, therefore, which is, as Our Lord Himself 
 said, in natural antagonism to the life of Perfection 
 — this craving which is in the Church, considered 
 as the whole body of the faithful, can only be 
 overcome by the Church, considered as the Spirit 
 of our Lord, living and working in the mind of 
 man. 
 
 This higher, or true Church, the Church of vision 
 and the ideal, will, as we here conceive it, have the 
 greater capacity to overcome this craving because it 
 will be the Church of a Scientific Catholicism, the 
 Church of developed man, resting on the total 
 experiences and acquisitions of the past, and moving 
 towards a complete humanity. As such it will not 
 use the language of mere censure or prohibition. In 
 its teaching the negative will be swallowed up in the 
 affirmative. It will no longer consider man, even in 
 his sins, simply as “ a sinner ” ; it will consider him 
 as a being called to Perfection— -to a many-sided 
 personal and social Perfection of love, goodness, 
 beauty, truth, and power. It will cease simply to 
 
THE REPUBLIC OF PEACE 
 
 265 
 
 denounce Mammon. It will aim at mastering Mam- 
 mon, recognizing that for man, as he is and where he 
 is, the command of the earth is a condition precedent 
 of the Catholic life, and that, eternal as is the truth 
 of renunciation, the common Catholic life cannot be 
 expressed merely in terms of renunciation, but must 
 be expressed in terms of possession and fulfilment. 
 Such a Catholicism, holding the old in the new and the 
 new in the old, will, in its opposition to imperialism, 
 have a power of appeal to those even who may seem 
 to be beyond its borders. It will be a scientific argu- 
 ment for an ideal human life. In principle, therefore 
 — allowing for the inevitable apathy or resistant 
 passions of man — its only real opponents will be the 
 “ sinners against the Holy Spirit.” In other words, 
 they will be the conscious and avowed opponents of 
 science and the ideal. The Catholic Church, as a 
 true teaching Church, will be in natural alliance with 
 all teachers of positive truth — even with such as may 
 appear at present to be out of relation with it. Its 
 international plea for peace, being not the abstract 
 proclamation of a vague sentiment, but a reasoned, 
 practical doctrine of man’s nature and needs, lower 
 and higher, will, in degree, appeal even to those who 
 are now classed as “ agnostics ” or “ unbelievers,” 
 They may not admit that the Church, as such, or as 
 they conceive it, is a need, but they will, as a rule, 
 recognize a lower and a higher life in man — a life of 
 mere animalism and a life of human aims and culture 
 — and they will acknowledge that this higher life 
 cannot be made secure and common so long as man 
 
266 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 wastes what is best in himself, physically and intel- 
 lectually, in war. 
 
 By virtue of its command of science, therefore, the 
 Catholic Church, in its teaching mind, will, as an 
 organ of peace, be able to give unity and guidance to 
 the life of Christendom — the Christendom of the 
 Roman communion, of the Greek Church, of the 
 Protestant Churches, and even of the agnostic world. 
 This, however, it will do not only positively by 
 becoming, in every country, a stimulating and co- 
 ordinating influence in social teaching, but negatively 
 by helping to discredit the incompetent and mischie- 
 vous teaching to which men are at present commonly 
 subject. So far as social action and citizenship are 
 concerned, the teacher in the modern world is for 
 the most part represented by the party politician and 
 the journalist. They are, of course, not, in any 
 strict sense of the word, teachers at all. They are 
 to some extent creators of public opinion, good or 
 bad, and to some extent also the exponents and 
 instruments of an opinion which has, by other 
 agencies, already been generated. They are, speak- 
 ing generally, the representatives and organs of some 
 of the very evils to which a Scientific Catholicism, if 
 it is ever to arise in the world, must put an end — of 
 an aggressive nationalism, of industrial imperialism, 
 of the gross greed for wealth, of sectarian narrowness 
 and strife, of class pretension and conflict, of party 
 antagonism. Their temper and methods are the 
 antithesis of the temper and methods required in 
 anything that deserves to be called teaching. They 
 
THE REPUBLIC OF PEACE 
 
 267 
 
 work in an atmosphere of perpetual controversy, ill- 
 will, abuse, and reciprocal misrepresentation. They 
 have arisen out of the disorder, spiritual and temporal, 
 of the modern world, and they tend to perpetuate and 
 increase it. The fundamental need of man, as a 
 terrestrial spectator and inhabitant of the Universal 
 Order in which he is placed, is that he should, as far 
 as possible, understand that Order, and himself in 
 relation to it, for the purposes of his own spiritual 
 and practical life. To the right satisfaction of this 
 need the party poHtician and the journalist con- 
 tribute nothing. They are partly the victims and 
 partly the exponents and ministers of a vast con- 
 fusion of mind. They stand neither for Catholicism, 
 in its historic and symbolic presentation of truth, nor 
 for science in the analytic discernment and ordered 
 application of it. They have, therefore, no concep- 
 tion of the human past from which man is travelling, 
 nor of the human future towards which he is moving. 
 They are not even in any true relation with what 
 is best in contemporary life. They represent its 
 obtrusive and noisy mediocrity, its vulgarity, its 
 superficiality, its untested assumptions, its impatience, 
 the passions and conflicts of nation and class, the 
 narrowness and illusions of sect, the restlessness and 
 disorder begotten of the pursuit of wealth. Above 
 all is this true of the journalist. The responsible 
 statesman has, in the modern world, a task of peculiar 
 difficulty, even when he happens to be a man of high 
 personal competence and impersonal sincerity. He 
 works in a situation of unstable opinions, conflicting 
 
268 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 interests, and antagonistic sects and classes. He has 
 to maintain some degree of order and development 
 tinder conditions of anarchy and antagonism. He 
 gains power, commonly, only after many years spent 
 in opposition and vituperation, and holds it precari- 
 ously for a short time, during which he is, in his turn, 
 subject to the opposition and vituperation of others. 
 The very nature of his task, however, as the cus- 
 todian, if only the temporary custodian, of vast and 
 complex social interests begets in him a sense of 
 responsibility and gives him a certain breadth of 
 outlook. He is, for the time being, at least an over- 
 seer of the republic, and not the mere representative of 
 some exclusive sect or class. 
 
 The journalist — using this word in a comprehensive 
 sense — is in a different position. He is supposed to 
 be, on the one hand, an organ of opinion ; on the 
 other, a contemporary historian. In both respects 
 his office, such as it is, has suffered a progressive 
 degradation. As an organ of opinion he is, of course, 
 the mere agent of a sect, party, or class, or perhaps 
 only of some sordid commercial enterprise. He is 
 dependent, irresponsible, and frequently anonymous, 
 and whatever his personal capacity and qualifications 
 may be, the conditions of every kind under which his 
 work is done are in the last degree unfavourable to 
 the formation and expression of disinterested and 
 competent judgments. They render such judgments, 
 in fact, impossible. As a contemporary historian, 
 exhibiting the life of the world as it is, the journalist 
 discharges a function which might conceivably be of 
 
THE REPUBLIC OF PEACE 
 
 269 
 
 high value, but which — largely owing to circumstances 
 for which he has no personal responsibility — is now 
 actually performed with less intelligence, order, 
 and good faith than in the early days of the Press. 
 Nothing is more necessary for a capable and effective 
 citizenship than an honest and intelligent record of 
 contemporary life, national and international, given 
 with the same exactness and veracity as are now 
 expected from every historian of the past. This does 
 not at present exist. The daily Press especially has 
 become increasingly the vehicle of a stupid and stupe- 
 fying sensationalism, dictated by the lowest needs of 
 commercial competition ; and the thing which is of 
 most consequence to the human mind — a right, 
 orderly understanding of itself and of the world in 
 which it works — has been rendered almost impossible 
 by the very instrument which apparently exists to 
 meet this need. 
 
 It will be one of the chief tasks of the teaching 
 Church, promoting the cause of a Human Peace by 
 the power of a Scientific Catholicism, to rescue the 
 great things of man’s mind and life from the hands 
 of the party politician and the journalist, and to 
 bring them within the domain of the thinker and 
 teacher, appealing to a common citizenship. While, 
 however, the Church — in that high conception of it 
 which distinguishes it from “ the world ” — is a 
 teaching mind, a Spiritual Power, acting upon the 
 forces of the spirit, it is not merely by formal and 
 abstract teaching that, in its scientific completeness, 
 it wiU create the power of peace. Catholicism, too, 
 
270 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 represents an “ interest ” as well as a doctrine. It 
 represents the interest of the Catholic life. The 
 Catholic life is, in its full and ideal extension, a life 
 universal. It is not a negative life of prohibition and 
 renunciation ; it is a positive life of many-sided 
 possession and fulfilment, in which the lower is made 
 subject to the higher. It is a life of progressive Per- 
 fection in Christ, and in terms of institutions it is 
 expressed by the home, the Church, the school, the 
 theatre, the State, and the workshop. It is a life also 
 dependent for its realization upon man’s common 
 command of the earth, national and international. 
 At present, so far as the great mass of the people in 
 Christendom are concerned, this command does not 
 exist. They are shut out from it. They cannot, 
 even if they wish to do so, live the Catholic life. They 
 can, indeed, live the negative Catholic life of pro- 
 hibition and renunciation. A dependent and home- 
 less pauper can be a good man in the sense of not 
 being a “ sinner,” and his poverty, of course, does not 
 exempt him from moral responsibility. But the 
 Catholic life of possession and use — the life of a full- 
 flowering humanity, in which the lower serves as a 
 foundation for the higher — this only becomes possible 
 by means of a command of the earth. 
 
 The Catholic Church — meaning by this expression, 
 in this connection, especially its spiritual aristocracy, 
 concerned with the realization of its highest ideals — 
 will, in its promotion of peace, be able to appeal to 
 the interest of that vast social mass which at present 
 possesses only a limited and precarious command of 
 
THE REPUBLIC OF PEACE 
 
 271 
 
 the earth, and for which the Catholic life is therefore 
 impossible. This interest cannot be said to be an 
 exclusive and material interest ; it is an interest 
 social and spiritual. It is, in a full sense, human. 
 It is true that a workman, like a capitalist, may- 
 desire wealth for merely ignoble ends, but it is also 
 true that, like the capitalist, he may desire it as the 
 condition precedent of a life of perfection. Further, 
 it is plain that in the absence of a certain command 
 of the earth, direct or indirect, this life is impos- 
 sible. As, therefore, it is the task of a Scientific 
 Catholicism to realize this life practically and uni- 
 versally, it must give its sanction to the just claim of 
 “ the people ” of Christendom — the great body of 
 those whom we call the workers — to possess their 
 due share of the proceeds of the earth. But it must 
 do more than this. The Church — the true Church, 
 the aristocracy of Catholicism, the mind of the Spirit 
 and the ideal — ^has to-day, in a time of science, the 
 same task to accomplish as in the first centuries of 
 Christianity, the time of intuition and vision : its 
 task is to raise human nature and keep it progressing 
 in a high plane. Its morality is, as we have said, a 
 “ slave morality ” — a morality which transforms the 
 slave into a master, giving him a command of himself 
 and of the earth, as the material basis of his being. 
 This morality, this high purpose, is none the less the 
 note of the Church because in practice it has not been 
 fulfilled. It has ever been professed ; it has never 
 been repudiated. It remains to be accomplished, and 
 it is the office of science, as a complete expression and 
 
272 THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 direction of the human mind, to point the way to its 
 accomplishment. 
 
 The Church, therefore, in this conception of it, will 
 not be satisfied with sanctioning the claim of the 
 people to a right possession of the earth ; it will 
 direct them to such a possession ; it will inspire in 
 them a Divine discontent — a discontent with all that 
 stands between them and the attainment of Divine 
 things. It will bless and encourage them in their 
 movement towards a total humanity. It is true — 
 whether in the case of a people, yearning to throw 
 ofi[ a foreign yoke, or of a class, seeking social emanci- 
 pation — that “ who will be free, themselves must 
 strike the blow.” It is a Catholic principle that 
 “ God alone cannot save men,” and that prayer, to 
 become efficacious, must be transformed into a force 
 of action. “ The people,” therefore, must save them- 
 selves, and this not merely by desiring the command of 
 the earth, but by desiring that Catholic life for which 
 the command of the earth is alone really valuable. 
 But it is the business of the Church, the true Church 
 of worship and science, to quicken in them these 
 desires, and to point the way to their fulfilment. It 
 will show that the Catholic life is impossible without 
 a Human Peace, and that the cause of a Human 
 Peace is, therefore, in a special sense the cause of the 
 people. It will show that we cannot have both war, 
 with its lunatic destruction and waste, and the social 
 realization of a positive Catholicism. It wiU show 
 that international policy has its roots in national 
 life — that imperialism in the one sphere has as its 
 
THE REPUBLIC OF PEACE 
 
 m 
 
 counterpart competition in the other. Under im- 
 perialism, in all its forms, we may have, indeed-— 
 what we have now-— a small social class, inordinately 
 possessed of wealth and political supremacy, with 
 an immense social body restlessly struggling for the 
 possession of these things. But under imperialism 
 we cannot have the Catholic life — the life of a fuU- 
 flowering humanity — for the whole republic. Im- 
 perialism means the ascendency of the few — the 
 ascendency of a governing class within the nation, 
 the ascendency of a governing State beyond the 
 nation. It means war because it means international 
 competition. One country striving for domination 
 beyond its own borders provokes and justifies the 
 rivalry of other countries striving for a similar 
 domination. And war is waste. It is a hindrance to 
 the higher things ; it is a fulfilment of the lower. It 
 is the suicide of humanity-— a destruction of its best 
 physical life, a recurrent frustration of its best 
 intellectual and moral life. 
 
 The Catholic Church, therefore, in its scientific 
 appeal for peace, will be able to awaken and direct 
 a force greater than any mere force of the schools— 
 the force to which Our Lord appealed, the force to 
 which Catholicism in its best moments has always 
 appealed, the force of the people, as distinguished 
 from the force of any special and exclusive class. The 
 cause of the people is the cause of the whole social 
 order. It is, therefore, not rightly represented by 
 the unfortunate and misleading word “ democracy.” 
 That word, historically, has arisen out of a continuous 
 
274 the problem OF HUMAN PEACE 
 
 class struggle, and it may stand, in practice, for a 
 disastrous attempt to make inferiors the lords of 
 superiors, or to give the mere power of numbers pre- 
 dominance over the power of mind. A Scientific and 
 teaching Catholicism cannot sanction “ democracy ” in 
 this sense. The ascendency of the best, in every sphere, 
 is for the good of the commonwealth. It is the word 
 “ republic,” and not the word “ democracy,” which is 
 the right expression of this principle. It is to the 
 Human Republic, national and international, that a 
 Scientific Catholicism will lead us — a Republic in 
 which there will no longer be any special hereditary 
 classes, land-owning or capital-owning, but in which 
 there will necessarily be special functionaries, pos- 
 sessing, for the advantage of the Republic, the free- 
 dom and power which all responsibility demands. 
 The Republic, in this conception of it, is only the 
 same thing as the living social Catholic Church. It is, 
 too, the same thing as the Human Peace, for, as we 
 have shown, without the Human Peace the Catholic 
 life, as a life common, in degree, to all men and 
 women, is for ever impossible. This Republic of 
 Peace — a free concert of independent, self-governing 
 nationalities — must, as we have also shown, be first 
 established in Christendom. When it has been estab- 
 lished in Christendom — in simpler terms, when the 
 Great Powers of Europe have given effect to an inter- 
 national policy such as we have here unfolded — it 
 will, for all practical purposes, have been established 
 in the rest of the world. Christendom is the war 
 centre. It is only necessary for it to become the 
 
THE REPUBLIC OF PEACE 
 
 275 
 
 peace centre in order to secure the concord of man- 
 kind. It is for the Catholic Church, the international 
 Church, the Church of the Papacy, the Church of the 
 Republic, the Church of Human Perfection, positive 
 and many-sided, the Church of the people — it is for 
 this Church, in its full command of science and in the 
 exercise of its high teaching authority, to bring in and 
 maintain this Human Peace — first, by fully confessing 
 it as its own cause, its own ideal, the natural realiza- 
 tion of the Kingdom of Christ ; and, secondly, by so 
 acting on the mind of the outside world that it may 
 be seen by every sect and school to be the ideal and 
 the cause of man. 
 
 BRADBURY, AONEW, & CO. LD., PRINTERS, LONDON AND TONBRIDGE. 
 
>V ■ 
 
 ' /'.l'- I'. '• 
 
 •'^'4 
 
 ■■' :■■■.■ ;, f .H'^-,-^. ? .'■■ ■ • • '4'( ^ '1, .;j v. ,4 A, ■ ■■* 
 
 >■: 4,;":',‘4'-:;>;';/4^4.-4' '^ l' V.V- :■■■■■': ' i'n4. j4'\4>"'">''’4.7'c'/'4 - ■'.V’, ■ 
 
 ' ' '/■ 
 '■. ',• •• ••jL'^' - 
 
 ... J'' 
 
 ■■' .:'p".' /.. 
 
 '• 4 '’. ' ., ■' ' ■i-i.yj- ' , - ^ 
 
 ■' yii.-U ..ii-.t- r 
 
 .' ’ . '••■ ■ '■ ' ..• , .,.’ "i: 'S' 
 
 7 --,' y^ -ym 
 
 V.;': 
 
 } h .V. ^ -rO' 
 
 , ' ■ .■■- ‘ ‘.'■' ■' ..V '4 :’■>'(■ -V', 
 
 7 ■•' ■ ■■ , j- y. ‘ ", ■ ■■■/' .- - 11 ^ 
 
 a 
 
 -''.""T'-i-'V 
 
 y .. V ' yy. 
 
 r 1 ; 
 
 
 '■■ I \ 
 
 
 r: 
 
 ' ■ ' ■-■'M 
 
 ■' ' ■- - f 4 > 
 
 " 'i' 4 
 
 .J ■'■■ 'tv 
 
 , I ■.'; .'' ■ ; , 
 
 :'¥'y ■ 
 
 ■■ 
 
 ,' ' '•■)’ 
 
 ,v 
 
 ■ 1 : 
 
 
 •■'^' 4 / 
 
 
 ;, V', 
 
 'v 
 
 ■'41 
 
 • .' I 1 # 4 • 
 
 
 > . 
 
 ' < 
 
 ':M 
 
 ! ' ' V’ V ■' • '-'■■ 
 ■•.' 1 ")..?%' '■} 
 
 ■ ' V -. ' . 4 
 
 ',,1: 
 
 ■^iVX 
 
 I' '< . 
 
 
 ■ ' 4^.7 
 
 ‘}: j' '"'-''ky^.: 
 
 • . •, .'f'. ' 
 
 4 ;,:“-; V^^'' 4 r 44 ' 4 ,^ /<:' 44 :' ’'./■■ 4 ''' 1 ^^ V 
 
 ' 1,4 VV' 4 ' ■. 4,'4. :^4:'7,C'^’^744 4 ‘■4-.4 l: , 7 7 ,:;7 ,.,^z 4' ' 
 
 ' ' ■ ;^'4 r 4^' .4'4:r;/ 4' .1 ■ 4^'^^.^v44:f,>n:'vfe4444iiJ^ 
 
 ■■'''■'"-■a', .' ^'7' •{■'f /'i '.- 
 
 . ■ • , .J ; . •' :'r • ‘ • . •• - a 
 
Date Due 
 
 FE 4*53 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
I