LIBRARY OF PRINCETON THEOLOGICAL SEMINARY THE SECOND TABLE OF THE COMMANDMENTS. LONDON EI) BY S P O T T I S \V O O D K A N 1 N"E\A'-.STRFET SQUARK THE SECOND TABLE OF THE COMMANDMENTS, A PEEFECT CODE of NATURAL MORAL LAW and of FUNDAMENTAL HUMAN LAW. THE CRITERION OF JUSTICE. BY DAVID '^KOWLAND, AUTHOR OF "LAWS OF NATURE, THE FOUNDATION OF MORALS. LONDON : LONGMANS, GREEN, AND CO. 1867. The right of translation is reserved. CONTENTS. CHAPTER I. THE NATURAL ENDOWMENT OF MAN, AND THE ORIGIN AND KISE OF HUMAN SOCIETY AND ITS INSTITUTIONS CHAPTER II. THE MORALITY OF THE COMMANDMENTS DESCRIBED AND DISTIN- GUISHED FROM SOCIAL AND PERSONAL DUTIES OF A MORAL KIND 14 CHAPTER III. OF THE FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLE OF THE MORAL GOVERNMENT, AND OF THE JURAL PRINCIPLE OF THE MORAL LAWS ... 24 CHAPTER IV. LIFE AND THE BODY ' THOU SHALT NOT KILL ' .... 30 CHAPTER V. MARRIAGE — THOU ' SHALT NOT COMMIT ADULTERY ' . . . .38 CHAPTER VI. PROPERTY ' THOU SHALT NOT STEAL ' 44 vi Contents. CHAPTER VII. Page the aoministration of justice — 'thou shalt not bear false witness' 55 CHAPTER VIII. fHE PERFECTION OF THE NATURAL AND RE^TALED CODE TESTED BY THE COMMENTARIES OF BLACKSTONE 65 CHAPTER IX. THE NATURAL AND REVEALED CODE AS THE BASIS OF JURISPRUDENCE CONSIDERED WITH REFERENCE TO THE WRITINGS OF JURISTS . 71 CHAPTER X. NATURE COMPARED WITH UTILITY AS THE FOUNDATION OF MORAL AND HUMAN LAW ; AND THE RESPECTIVE THEORIES TESTED BY THE WRITINGS OF PHILOSOPHERS 90 CHAPTER XI. JUSTICE, ITS ELEMENTS AND CRITERION; AND HUMAN JUSTICE AND GOODNESS COMPARED WITH OUR CONCEPTIONS OF THE JUSTICE AND GOODNESS OF GOD . . . . . • • . 1 J 3 POSTSCRIPT \'i\ THE SECOND TABLE OF THE COMMAKDMENTS. CHAPTER I. The Natural Endowment of Man, and the Origin and Rise of Human Society and its Institutions. The title of this treatise indicates that the pro- position which it affirms should be sustained by proof derived from l^ature, or from that exposition of Nature which discloses its identity with the will of God. It assumes that a system of morality exists, and that its author is divine. The endeavour is to unfold the theory of the moral laws of Sinai, and to show that they govern the world; and for that purpose to refer them to the principles on which they are based, to trace the objects which they were de- signed to accomplish, and to evince their adaptation to man in his individual and in his social condition ; and by this analysis to demonstrate that I^ature and Revelation unite in declaring one harmonious, B 2 Postulate of Natural Rights. perfect, and immutable code of moral and funda- mental liTiman law. The leading theory of the treatise is, the natural individuality of man ; that each human being is by Nature, and therefore by the will of the great Creator, owner of his, or her, body, with its life and all its powers, physical and mental ; with a natural right to use those powers for the individual benefit of their owner; but subject to the same natural ownership, powers, and rights in every other human being. The primary proof of that theory is found in the self-consciousness of man of that individuality and of that ownership, and of the possession of those powers and rights. That self-consciousness the whole course of nature is designed to confirm. It inspires a love of life, to be enjoyed through the instrumentality of the body, which instinctively leads to its preserva- tion ; and it incites a self-love which regards in the spirit of rivalry and enmity all who interfere with the pleasures or interests of the individual owner of the body. Nature casts on every human being advanced be- yond early infancy, an inevitable necessity to sustain life by the use of the powers of the body ; and for that purpose to strive and contend with other human beings under the same necessity. The employment Unity of Nature and the Commandments. 3 of the body for that purpose, through the action of natural impulses of which the individual alone is conscious, although they are general in the human race, inculcates a self-evident conception of a natural right to the body as the instrument of labour, and to the products of its labour for its sustentation. An instinctive conviction of the existence of these natural rights and powers is a leading motive of human action, and their preservation is necessary to human happiness. The moral government of God is in accordance with such individuality. The moral laws of the Commandments are directed to its preservation in terms which imply natural ownership and rights, and forbid invasion of them. Nature, in the way it works, through the instincts of man, declares laws identical with those of the Commandments ; for, how- ever authoritative the Commandments, God's moral government does not rest solely on the revealed moral laws, which do not, and which never did, reach the whole human race ; and therefore it is through I^ature we must necessarily suppose that the moral law was originally, as it is now perpetually, communicated to mankind. God has so constituted human nature, that through sentiments, instincts, feelings and affections implanted in man, He communicates His laws to him unceasingly ; and thus is given to mankind, as weU 4 The Course of the Inquiry. to those who receive Revelation, as to those who are excluded from it, moral laws of Nature, which Reve- lation declares ; that Law described by St. Paul by which the " Gentiles which have not the [revealed] law, do by nature the things contained in the law, these, having not the law, are a law unto themselves : which show the work of the law written in their heai-ts."^ A theory of "natural rights," so limited, so defined and so accordant with the self-consciousness of man- kind, may be considered so far determinate as to deserve inquiry into its social and moral action ; and so far a truth as to be spared the obloquy with which a suggestion of natural rights is frequently received. I shall venture to undertake that inquiry, with the purpose of developing the theory in action ; and as the first step in the inquiry I shall briefly trace the rise of human society from its original elements, and through its several natural stages, terminating in permanent institutions which, by the continuance of the original causes, are now, in civilised life, in full operation. And here it may be convenient to explain that I shall not encumber my treatise by accounting for departures from the moral laws either in un- civilised or in civilised nations, in early ages or in * Romans, ii. 14, 15. Ultimate Principles of the Human System. 5 modern times ; for it cannot be truly inferred from disregard or disobedience of the moral laws, at any time, or amongst any peoples, that the laws did not then, or that they do not now, universally exist ; and if we attempt to discover the moral obligation to which mankind is subject, we must assume as the standard of duty the highest moral condition which mankind has attained or which it is capable of attaining. It is a sound rule in philosophy, given by Cicero as a test of the completeness of philosophical investi- gation, to trace back the elements of the subject to the ultimate points to which they can be referred, but which themselves can be referred to nothinpr."^ The ultimate principles — taking man as the de- pository of the motive power, animal and mental, and the director of the will by which it is put in action — to which the human s^^stem can be referred, are the appetites of Sex and Hunger. These appetites, constituted by a physiological organisation in man and brutes so similar as to be almost identical, are invested with stimulative force and power that insure their unceasing action ; but with this wide and distinctive difference in the results of that action, evidently a mark of creative design, that whilst the appetites of brutes lead them into a * Cicero, De Finibits Bonorum et Malorum, Lib. i. § ix. 6 Divergence of Man from Brutes. uniform and unvarying round of instinctive existence from wliich no brute has ever emerged, upon the same appetites in man the great and complicated structure of human society is raised, and is preserved and perpetuated by the same appetites through successions of human beings. These powers, common to man and brutes, although more perfect in man, could not, as we clearly perceive from the confined ca]3acity of brutes, have been the basis of the human system, unless another and greater power had been given to man. The creation of man, and his intellectual divergence from the merely instinctive capacity of brutes, mark the epoch of the introduction of Eeason into the world, and of its combination with the animal nature. Man uses his physical powers under the direction of and in vital union with his mental powers ; and thus he is enabled to fulfil the higher destiny iri the world awarded to him than that of the lower animals. From the appetites spring the two vital elements of human society; from one the human beiQgs by whom the world is peopled ; from the other, food by which their lives are sustained. The appetite of sex is the provision of Nature for maiataining a succession of human beings, and there are various and peculiar instincts, feelings, affections, and sentiments in human nature, in the sequel more Sex, and the Family. 7 particularly pointed out, which appear to be designed to direct that appetite to marriage. From this insti- tution of Nature large numbers of human beings are daily brought into the world, and supply, and often exceed, the numbers which, with similar rapidity, are removed by death. But marriage has another im- portant purpose in the human system. It is the source and origin of families — the primitive element of human society in which the human race is trained for the performance of their social, moral, and re- ligious duties — in which they are taught to worship Him beside whom there is no other God, and to love their neighbour as themselves. From the aggregation of families arise the community, the state, society; and from the natural necessity of vesting the chief authority over the family in the father as the founder, the idea and perhaps the primary form of human government were communicated to mankind. The Second Table of the Commandments is appropriately commenced with the Fifth Commandment, which has a design beyond the simple inculcation of filial re- verence ; it points to the natural result of well-ordered families, their division into other families, and to the important place which they hold in society as elements of the state. The appetite of Hunger in its imperious demands for daily food is the origin of Proj)erty. Food, the 8 Hzmger, Food, Propej^ty. second vital element of human society, man is destined to procure by his labour ; and experience teaches him that he cannot sustain his life and maintain his children without making provision beyond the present day, by labouring for more than present sustenance, and by storing and preserving the surplus for the future. Such surplus is his own, proprium, his property by natural right, as the product of his natural powers ; and the term expresses a distinction between mine and thine that is universal throughout the human race. Property originated in the simplest exercise of those powers, in hunting, fishing, and gathering the spontaneous fruits of the earth. It naturally extended to portions of land on which cultivation through labour was bestowed, and to habitations, clothing, furniture, necessaries of life, and, in process of time, to the luxuries of life; but secondary to food, and superfluous unless food be supplied, and their value dej)reciating when food is scarce ; so that in case of famine the most luxurious and costly product of laboui- or art, the coveted gold or jewel, is as nothing Avhen com- pared with present food. Thus food, as it is the origin, so it is the ultimate standard of the value of property. From this great vital necessity of Nature, food, with its important but subsidiary necessaries, proceed all the various modes of producing and storing food. Natural Origin of Contract. 9 Agriculture, fishing, hunting, manufactures, naviga- tion, are expressions which cover whilst they enlarge the simple processes of natural art. But these natural arts and occupations cannot be made available in the constitution of society unless their products can be diffused from man to man, from family to family, from state to state. Circulation is, however, not merely a physical process ; it requires a motive, and it requires an instrument. The motive is supplied by the con- stant necessity for food, chiefly obtained by exchange of labour for food, of food for labour, and by the ad- vantage derived from the exchange between distant communities of the several varieties of theii* natural products. The instrument is Contract. The axis on which the whole human social system revolves is Contract. [Nature directed man to con- tract by so limiting the power of one man to obtain the property of another man, as to make contract the inevitable medium of its distribution. For there are three modes, and only three, by which one man can obtain the property of another man — gift, con- tract, or theft. Of these three modes, gift and theft, although morally distinct, are almost equally inefficient as modes of distribution. Gift is the natural mode by which a man may follow the dictates of the bene- volence and natural affection implanted in human lO Primitive Forms of Contract. nature which prompt men to do good to their fellow- creatures, and to those allied to them ; acts of kind- ness which are not enjoined as duties by positive law, but which are encouraged bj those precepts which teach us to love our neighbour as ourselves. But gift has to encounter the natural love of acqui- sition, and a disinclination to part with property obtained by individual labour and saving ; and although compassion may overcome these obstacles, gift is not commonly spontaneous except towards children or others in close natm^al relationship with the donor. Theft leaves the ownership of the stolen property unchanged ; and its recovery or restitution when practicable is seldom abandoned or released. But contract is agreeable to those feelings in man Avhich stimulate him to increase his wealth. He exchanges his property for a consideration which he hopes will prove a gain ; and his proprietary rights are recognised and protected when his will has freely assented to the contract he has made. The primitive form of contract of exchange was Barter, which, Aristotle remarked, " had its original beginning in Nature, from the fact that some men had a surplus, and others less than was necessary for them. Barter (he added) it is plain could have no place in the first community, that is to say, in the household, but must have begun when the number Barter and Contracts of Labour. 1 1 of those who composed the community came to be enlarged, for the former of these had all thmgs the same in common ; but those who came to be separated had in common many other things which both parties were obliged to exchange as their wants arose." "^ Contracts of Labour must have had a beginning equally primitive ; for in cases where the work to be done exceeded the power of the household, or where an individual sought to obtain immediate food in exchange for his labour, such contracts would natu- rally be resorted to. And although in ages and societies where labour was to a large extent supplied by slaves, whose employment practically diminished the number of contracts, yet circumstances must have continually occurred, where men were in any degree free, which forced such contracts into occasional, if not habitual use, as matters of unavoidable necessity. The social operation of the trifold chain by which property is bomid, is to protect the natural ownership by placing the power of disposal in the hands of the owner, either by gift or by contract, if he can pre- serve his property from theft. That it was designed specially for man is obvious from the fact, that to contract, or even to make a simple promise, is beyond the capacity of brutes. The natural complement of a social system based *■ Politics, book i. c. ix. 12 The State and Human Govern^iient. on and kept in action by physical forces of imperious energy, and dependent on tlie preservation of natural rights, is a State, which (Aristotle observed) " is first founded that man may live, but continued that he may live happil}^, for which reason every state is the work of Nature." * These forces require to be directed in accordance with natural rights, and to be encouraged, even if they may not be compelled, into the channels of labour and of the storing of food ; so that the products of industry and prudence may be insured to their natural owners against immoral appropriation by other men. That is the office of Human Government, which is the final cause of the state. The theory of natural rights Kas been developed by this analysis beyond the original postulate. It now appears that the powers of the body, physical and mental, are employed in the production of pro- perty, of which the primitive j)rinciple is food. The natural rights are, therefore (1) an individual right to the body with its life and all its powers — a right which being innate is complete in man although he remain inert in the use or exercise of his bodily powers ; and (2) the ownership of all property called into existence by each man, or acquired by lawful means, that is, by his labour, or by gift or by con- * Politics, book i. c. ii. FurtJier Development of Natu7^al Rights. 1 3 tract through the use of his natural powers, physical or mental. These constitute the primary natural rights ; all other rights are derivatives from these. What the latter are, and how the natural rights are restrained and controlled by the operation of the natural condition that they must be used and enjoyed by each individual subject to the same ownership, rights, and powers in all other human beings, will be considered in the progress of the work. The whole system of human society, it thus appears, is derived from I^ature. It is based upon original principles which determine the course of mankind, and lead them through the several natural stages of marriage, families, and communities, to the constitu- tion of society, and of the state, the depository of human government ; and through the several natural stages of labour, property, and contract to the attain- ment of those derivative elements of civilisation, trade, agriculture, and commerce, and the several arts and sciences connected with them. 14 The Subject- Matter of the Coi7imandinents. CHAPTER II. The Morality of the Commandments described, and distinguished from Social and Personal Duties of a Moral kind. The induction of tlie preceding chapter may liave led to the inference, if it has not demonstrated, that the subject-matter of the moral laws are the natural rights of human beings to their body and its life, with its powers, physical and mental ; and that the forces which require moral restraint and direction in accordance with natural rights, are the animal ferocity of man, and the appetites of sex and hunger ; the appetites, besides their own peculiar purposes, being generally the exciting causes of the animal ferocity, which is seldom carried to the extent of crime without such subsidiary stimulant. Life, marriage, and pro- perty, are exposed to human action which interferes with the enjoyment of them, and often threatens, as well as terminates, in individual cases, their existence. That action it is the purpose of the moral laws to restrain ; and it is a mark of the wisdom by which they are framed, that we find them directed against Misconception of their Moral Scope. 15 the most salient action destructive of each class of rights. But before proceeding further in the inquiry, it is necessary to define the limits of the term " morality," for a general application of it to every variety of responsible action is the cause of confusion in the treatment of moral subjects ; and from the same cause it is now not uncommon to find the Commandments pronounced imperfect as a code of moral law. A late eminent writer "^ described the Decaloofue as imperfect, because it does not contain all moral duties. " What is termed the moral law (he wrote) is certainly in no way peculiarly to be identified with the Decalogue, as some have strangely imagined. Though moral duties are specially enjoined in many places of the Law, yet the Decalogue most as suredly does not contain all moral duties, even by remote implication, and on the widest construction. li totally omits many such, as e.g. beneficence, truth, justice, temperance, control of temper, and others ; and some moral precepts omitted here are introduced in other places. But many moral duties are hardly recognised, e.g. it is difficult to find any positive prohibition of drunkenness in the Law. In one passage only an indirect censure seems to be implied. f * Christianity without Jiulaism, by Eev. Baden Powell, M.A., p. 104. t Deut xxix. 19. 1 6 The Morality of the Commandments. The prohibition in respect to the priests,"^ and the Nazarite vow, were peculiar cases." f The Decalogue assuredly does not contain all the " moral duties " suggested as absent from it in the quoted passage. That it is, therefore, imperfect or incomplete is a hasty assumption, esj)ecially when we consider the authority on which it rests ; an ex- amination of its laws may show that the Command- ments were not designed to contain all the duties alleged to be absent from it ; and we may separate the duties of mankind into their several varieties of class and obligation, and distinguish them by names. I. The moral laws of the Commandments are the fundamental laws of God's government of this world, and obedience to them takes the first rank amongst the duties of mankind. Their simple terms make it obvious that they are social laws designed for the government of men in their intercourse with each other in the common relations and business of life ; and the actions which they forbid are of that kind, that two parties at least must be concerned in them. It is, further, a necessary inference from the laws, that of the two parties one must have rights which the other intends to invade, or, when a law is violated, has invaded. The forbidden acts, when accomplished, become crimes, and the morality of the Decalogue is * Dcut. vi. 3. t Lev. i. 9. Objection that the Lazvs are Negative. 17 forbearance from crimes. To its laws it would be accordant with the primary rank of the Decalogue, to confine the expression " Moral Laws," to express its duties as " the Moral Duties," and to call the general responsibility to its laws, " Morality." The scope and range of the moral law of the Commandments, will be investigated in future chap- ters, when each law will be examined separately, and it is hoped that it will be apparent that they com- prehend all actions of which men are capable, that violate natural rights and are punishable by human government. Then it will be seen whether justice is absent from the Decalogue, and what ground there is for the objection to the completeness of the moral code. But another objection is made to it, that its law are negative ; that, in its precepts, "thou shalt not" predominates unduly over "thou shalt." That ob- jection will be changed to approbation by those who consider how much easier it is "not to do," than " to do," to be passive than to be active ; and they will feel grateful for legislation which casts upon us no positive duties. But, in order " not to do," it may be necessary " to do ; " and such indirect af&rmative provision is contained in the moral laws. Two of the chief personal duties of man are, to labour for present food, and to make provision of food for the future. c 1 8 Benevolence, or Social Duties. They are the preservatives of life and of social in- dependence. They are also the best preservatives against temptation to crime. Thus performance of these personal duties is implied in the law " thou shalt not steal ; " and they must come to a man's mind as the natural duties of his position, whenever he is in such a condition that to sustain his life he must either labour or steal. But as God has framed the moral laws as negative laws, and has formed His government on a negative system, we may conclude, from the absence of positive law, that positive action is not required as a moral principle. And from that inference ^ve may deduce another, that obedience to the moral laws is approved by God as sufficient for His design, and is, therefore a state of " good ; " although it may not, without the performance of other duties to be presentl}^ mentioned, be a state of perfect virtue. '' Good," therefore, not being called into existence by positive law, must exist antecedently in the nature of man ; in other words, it must be his normal state, for it is by disobedience to the laws that goodness is disturbed, and that its contraries arise.^ TI. Beneficence, or Benevolence, absent from the Decalogue, opens an entirely different class of socia * " Virtue is the natural law we are born under." — Bishop Butlers Sermon I. on Human Nature. Antithetical to those of the Decalogue. 19 actions ; so different as to be antithetical to the actions forbidden by the Decalogue. The latter are always evil, whilst benevolence is the source of actions which, in intention at least, are always good. The moral laws are exact in their terms, protecting defined rights ; the duties of beneficence are not called forth by rights : they are discharged by spon- taneous gifts. They do not admit of reduction to specific laws, and they are recommended by general precepts ; and here we find the formula " do," supply- ing the supposed defect in the moral system. But there is a yet greater antithesis between the duties of benevolence, and the Laws of the Decalogue — that the former appeal to mental principles, to affections implanted in the Mind of man, whilst the latter are directed against actions originating in the animal nature. The mind and the body are vitally united in the creature, man, and the greater portion of his actions partake of the characteristics of both natures ; but actions marked for their goodness or their wickedness generally disclose a preponderance of the peculiar qualities of their original sources. But if benevolence has no place in the Command- ments, it has a high place amongst the social duties of mankind. The benevolent affections have, in the mental nature, an office and a mode of action which resemble those of the passions in the animal nature. c 2 20 Social hnportaiice of Benevolent Duties, As the passions act as stimulants to the appetites, and to the actions which they originate ; so the benevolent affections stimulate the reason to more active operation for the good of our fellow-creatures, than would proceed from its generally slow and deliberate motion. They are the source of those refined principles of duty, which, rising above the appetites and the negative obedience due to the moral laws, urge human beings to positive good ; to love, compassionate, relieve, and comfort their fellow- creatures, and to the adoption of higher standards of virtue than simple abstinence from moral crime. The benevolent duties are not dissociated from the moral laws ; indeed, it is a part of the duty to take care that the act of benevolence shall not interfere with or have a tendency to counteract the primary authority of the moral law; that it does not en- courage omission to labour, and to save. This conflict of duty is one of the chief difficulties in the exercise of benevolence, in a concrete- form ; so that the duty, when treated as a moral duty, is often expressed as to be determined by " what we ought to do." No law of duty can be laid down other than in general preceptive terms : it lies with each man to make a law for himself, with regard to his duty of bene- volence, and to its specific acts ; in which his means, and the superior claims of his family and dependants, are elements in his determination. Ethical rather than Moral. 21 The benevolent duties being spontaneous and un- connected with rights, rest on a religious obligation, the duty being direct to God. But it is upon the performance or non-performance of these duties that the social character of a man is formed and is esti- mated by his fellow-men; the character being de- termined by the gradual growth of the virtues which spring from the cultivation and the practice of benevolence in its various kinds. The obligation to these virtues it would be consistent with Aristotle's philosophy to distinguish as Ethics, and their duties as ethical duties, for we learn from him that r]Qos^ which signifies moral virtue, arises from habit, Wos ; whence also it got its name. He also rejected the moral crimes from his philosophy, as inconsistent with his ethical system.^ These ethical, or bene- volent, duties, although widely distinguished from the moral duties of the Commandments, act on the conscience in respect of the law which each man makes for himself, according to his ability and cir- cumstances; "their conscience also bearing witness, and their thoughts accusing or else excusing " as in the case of a moral law. III. Other duties alleged to be omitted from the Decalogue are of a personal kind, of which the examples given are, want of control of temper, and drunkenness. Man is subject, through the pressure * Nicom. Eth. ii. 1. t Hem. ii. 6. 2 2 Personal Ditties. Sins. of the appetites and the force of the passions, to numerous self-indulgences that lower his social character, by diminishing* his power of doing his duty to those dependent on him, to society, and to his God. So long as these indulgences continue to be personal, not ending in violations of the rights protected by the Commandments, they are Sins for which the responsibility is direct to God. Truth, alleged to be absent from the Decalogue, is a personal duty. It is also absent from the Sermon on the Mount ; and its absence from both these high codes suggests the inference, that there are reasons in nature for the omission, and some will be offered for consideration in the sequel. " Want of control of temper," or anger, is not an unmitigated evil, nor its opposite an invariable duty. "No passion (said Butler) that God has endued us with, can be in itself evil." ^ If it is so uncontrolled as to lead to crime, for instance, murder, as its un- happy consequence, it brings the angered man within the sixth Commandment. But it is often a virtuous feeling, as when anger is roused by a sense of violated justice. It then stimulates a man to protect the injured, and to advocate and defend just rights and principles, which, without the stimulus of anger, might pass unregarded. * SiTinon on Rcsentnient. Religious Duties to God. 23 Drunkenness is a great evil, but in its nature it is a personal sin ; for the individual does not indulge in drunkenness to injure society, although that is the effect of drunkenness, but to gratify his own appetite. Its consequences to the drunkard are very serious, in the decay of his health, of his ability to labour, in the disorder of his affairs, and in the neglect of his family. As a stimulant to crimes, which are breaches of the moral laws, it receives its punishment, for it is not allowed by human government to excuse acts done under its influence which affect the natural rights and property of other men. These several classes or varieties of action — moral duty or morality, duties of benevolence or ethics, and duties of purity of life, failure in which is sin — are all comprehended in the paramount duty of obedience to God, as the Maker of mankind, their Law-giver and the ultimate Judge of their actions. There are, besides, religious duties to Him — worship, prayer and praise, thanksgiving, fear and love. If a man could perform aU these several duties, truly and faithfully, perhaps few would deny that he had attained a state of perfect virtue. 24 Tlie Natural Rights a Mental Stimulant. CHAPTER III. Of the Fundamental Principle of the Moral Government, and of the Jural Principle of the Moral Laws. The Almiglity Maker, when lie invested the mind of man with a consciousness of natural rights, created an efficient cause only secondary in intensity to the power of the appetites. These stimulate his animal nature to action ; but man might have remained as unprogressive as a brute if he had not been furnished with a mental stimulant, which brings his mind and body into joint action for a common purpose. An instinctive consciousness of unity as owner of his body and all ifcs powers, gives to each individual an interest separate from that of his fellow-creatures, but it does not preclude their co-action and co- operation. Thus furnished, man is constituted for society ; but again, we find his action there facilitated by the simple and unfettered form in which his na- tural rights are bestowed upon him. The rights are not correlatives of duties. No action is necessary Not Correlatives of Ditties, 25 to complete the rights. They are acquired by birth, and even previous to birth, for the crime of murder may be committed in the womb, and they never can be justly disputed, for each man knows by his con- sciousness of his own rights, their universality in the human race. Nor is there a positive moral duty, although it may be, and is, a social and benevolent duty to protect the natural rights of other men. Violations of rights are wrongs to the parties in- jured, not because the violation is a betrayal of duty, but because it spoliates a right which is a gift of God, by an act which is, or which is equiva- lent to theft ; and so an act of disobedience to God's law. The wrong is not augmented by failure in a correlative duty. If the moral oblig*ation arose out of correlative or reciprocal duty, a man might consent to be murdered by an acquiescence previously given; but neither individual man, nor human government, can release God's right to, or His creature's duty of obedience ; and therefore they cannot set aside the moral crimes of the Command- ments. This beneficent arrangement of natural rights is necessary to their enjoyment. If they were depend- ent on the observance or performance of similar rights in other men, they could not be exercised or enforced by the weak against the powerful — or 26 Correlative Rights arise from Contract. against the power of tyrannical government. These could always raise an issue whether some correlative duty had been performed ; and so the bulk of man- kind might be kept in perpetual slavery. But as rights independent of correlative duties, they give to each human being an invariable status, which can be affected only by the punishment awarded by human government for specific crime. The just punishment of crime restricts the natural rights, but it does not deprive the person under punishment of rights not affected by the sentence of punishment. Thus it is murder to kill a person under sentence only of imprisonment. But the Creator did not leave man solitary in his individuality and independence. The trifold chain by which rights and property are protected, furnishes the means by which reciprocal and interdependent rights and duties may be created between men. Contract founds a new moral relation between them. Through its operation they interchange their rights and property, and by mutual promise enter into obligations which result in rights and duties that are correlative and reciprocal. It effects a change of rights by mutual consent, and the rights so changed, or agreed to be changed, pass to and from the contracting parties, and become as natural rights protected by the authority of the moral laws. The yural Principle of the Moral Laws. 27 crimes and injuries to which natural rights give rise may be perpetrated under the concealment of a contract; and honest performance of it can only be tested by the principles of the moral laws. The effect of this variety of moral action is to divide moral crime into two classes: — (1) crimes open or public, and (2) crimes under the cover of contract. The most general physical principle into which the human system can be resolved, considering man as endowed with natural rights, and possessing appetites and desires that stimulate him to use his natural powers for his individual benefit, is Property. The most general antagonistic principle to propert}^, considering the chief moral danger to which it is exposed, is Theft; and theft, as antagonistic to rights and to property, is, therefore, the generic moral crime of society. The jural princii)le of the moral laws is restraint of theft, and restraint of theft, in its various modes and forms, is the essence and active principle of human law. The power of the abstract principle of property-, and of its protective law, pervades all human rela- tions. There is no other principle or law into which our natural or individual, or our political or social rights can be resolved. In our social dealings the inquiry to be made of our conscience is, have we taken or detained from our neighbour, openly or 28 Natural Moi^al Law evolved from Rights. covertly, " any thing that is his," affecting his life, body, family, or property? Have we given to him less than his right, or prevailed on him to accept less by false or deceitful representation, or by keep- ing him in ignorance of his due ? The principle and law are so ingrained by nature into our minds, that in our common social intercom-se, and in cases where no moral obligation exists, we introduce them into our speech, and by similar moral phrases, apply them to fancied rights and duties. Where a civility is received and not returned, we say we owe a return ; or we have not done our friend justice in our estima- tion of his accomplishments or powers of amuse- ment ; and we deprive him of his just merit, from an envious motive that partakes of the injustice of the law, " thou shalt not steal." The natural rights evolve moral laws by their automatic power. These are laws of Nature. Our next step in the investigation is to inquire whether they coincide with the moral laws of the Command- ments, of which true tests will be, that they contain within their scope all those actions, in their several varieties, which interfere with the natural rights, and which constitute wrongs. Property, in relation to morality, comprehends the natural rights, and all their products, physical and mental. It divides itself naturally into three classes, coiTesponding Three Classes of Property. 29 with the body and its appetites of sex and hunger. (1) Property in the body ; (2) property in relation to marriage and the family; and (3) property in the physical and mental products of the powers of the body. Under these divisions, with which the Divine laws correspond, an analysis of each of these three classes of property will be made, and of the corre- sponding crimes and wrongs, the completeness of which may be tested by our knowledge of human life, and by the proceedings of our Courts of Justice, which, displayed in our daily journals, describe every phase and form of social and moral action, in a nation which presents every kind of moral temptation and every variety of moral crime. T/ie Sixth Commandment. CHAPTEE rV. LIFE AND THE BODY. VI.— Thou shalt not kill. The sixth Commandment, "thou shalt not kill," appeals to the moral sense of mankind against the highest crime of humanity. The princij^le of pro- perty resolves the crime, high and heinous though it be, into the generic crime of theft, and the great law must be considered as a special application of " thou shalt not steal " to the protection of the life of man. The destruction of life by murder raises pecu- liar feelings in the human heart. The murderer is execrated not only for his cruelty, but for having taken from his human brother his most valued pos- session, w^hich no earthly power can restore. Nor does it admit of recompense to the victim, whereas crimes against material property or rights admit of restitution and of punishment, which may force, or be substituted for, restitution. It has the least excuse Punishment of Ahu^dei^ by Death. 3 1 of any crime ; for there is no natural impulsive appetite which desires the life of a fellow-creature to appease it. Adultery may be palliated by temptation ; theft may be excused by the pressure of hunger ; but the murderer, on the contrary, has natural feelings and sentiments adverse to murder, which must be stifled or overcome in order to work himself into the state of physical energy, whether of cool determination or of excited passion, which seems to be a necessary antecedent to an act of murder. The Law of Sinai is in perfect accordance with the law of Nature in every human heart. There is much difference of opinion in the present day concerning the proper punishment of the crime of murder. It was, until recent times, an axiom, " that the common feelings of mankind demand the blood of the murderer ; "^ but, in our day, dislike of capital punishment, engendered by its long and indiscrimi- nate use for minor crimes, has extended even to murder, and the advocates are numerous for its entire abolition. Revelation has given a precept or injunction, that " whoso sheddeth man's blood, by man shall his blood be shed," and for two different reasons ; (1) " for in the image of God made He man," and (2) " for the blood is the life." If the in- junction be considered independently of the authority * Gibbon's History. 32 Mttrder marked as the Highest Crime. it derives from revelation, the reasons, as criteria of its sacredness, are not without remarkable force as suggestive of their origin in God; for no earthly being could know, in the remote time of that re- velation, the high importance of the criteria to the progress of man as a social being, in the one case, and to his physical existence in the other. Reason, supposed to be " the image " referred to, has been developed to an extent which has raised the human race, in its most advanced civilisation, to knowledge and power which the earliest races of mankind could neither have foreseen nor imagined. The criterion " for the blood is the life," has peculiar relevancy, when viewed by the light of modern science; the theory being, that the blood is not merely the sub- stance which sustains life, but that it is, itself, a living, organised body.* But there is in nature a very remarkable distinction, in God's gift of life from all other natural property, even from the body of man as well as from material property produced by labour. The trifold chain by which i)roperty is bound, does not extend to life. As it must not be stolen by murder, so its owner cannot give it by free consent, take it himself, nor sell it by contract. The most heinous crime, next to murder, * Penny CyolopsDdia, art. " Blood." Brewster's Edinburgh En- cyclopaedia, 1830, art. " Physiologj'." Minor Offences against the Body. 33 is rape. The intending violator of woman's chastity may obtain his end and be spared his crime by the woman's gift of her person (which is not contrary to nature), or by a contract of marriage. The intending thief may be turned from his criminal purpose by a gift of the coveted property, or by a contract for its sale to him. This natural difference gives to murder an exceptional place in moral crime, that marks it as peculiarly under the ban of the Creator. For crimes less than murder capital punishment cannot be jus- tified ; but only experience can teach what the effect on the safety of human life would be of placing murder, in its punishment, on an equality with theft of property. To a murderer, advanced in life, im- prisonment for life, compared with the punishment of a thief for a term of years, might be merely a nominal distinction; and thus the crime of murder would, in regard to punishment, be eliminated from the human code, and decimated from the Command- ments. Minor offences against the body fall naturally under the power of human government, as offences against natural right, or as unjust interferences with natural property; and inasmuch as mutilation, wounds, and bodily injuries deprive the owner of the body of the use of limbs and other members, injure health, diminish strength, and prevent labour, D 34 Minor Crimes omitted from Comma^idments. and may thus reduce tlie owner to poverty and even death; such offences are necessarily restrained by laws of human government. Their omission from the Commandments may be regarded as an instance of the adaptation of the latter to human nature, with which nothing could be more inconsistent than laws specifically forbidding men from fighting, assaulting, or even frequently assailing their fellow-men, whether as enemies or as companions. Man derives from his animal nature the combative instinct in a high degree. He plumes himself on his courage, and despises a coward. All communities engage in warfare ; and civilisation cannot repress personal violences and fights even amongst friends and neighbours. It may reasonably be supposed that God left these offences for repression and punishment by human government, when His creatures were prepared for that restraint by civilisation. How slow the progress has been may be perceived from the fact that men, and those of the most educated class, have only recently overcome the animal passion for revenge which prompted them to call out their fellow-men (and that in disobedience to the laws of human government) to defend their lives in duel, for daring to impeach truth or repu- tation, under the chivalrous name of honour. The essence of the crime of murder, in the law of England, is that it be committed with premeditation, Mtcrder and Minor Crimes by English Laiv. 35 or " malice aforethonght," as to which there are legal distinctions of malice express or implied, which it is not necessary to enter into here. Murder, and the minor ferocious crimes, cannot be exhibited in their varieties by a more comprehensive classification than that of English law. Such crimes are there called "crimes against the person," and they comprise murder, manslaughter, attempts to murder, attempts to maim, rape, assaults with bodily harm, batteries and common assaults. The higher offences are distinguished as felonies, and the lower as misdemeanours. The crimes of the preceding list are those which we have distinguished as open crimes, but the great law, with its virtual declaration of man's natural ownership of his body and its adjuncts, has a civil as well as criminal category of forbidden actions. Between our natural division of open crimes and crimes under the cover of contract, are injuries to the body called Torts or Wrongs, in the Eoman Law, Delicta, which are not treated by English law as crimes punishable by bodily restraint, but as civil injuries, and they are redressed by civil action, and compensated by pecuniary damages proportioned to the injury; but in these minor offences we trace the generic crime of theft. Injury to good name or reputation is a tort or wrong, which, in its i> 2 36 Torts or Wrongs to the Body. nature, is theft. It is the offspring of civilisation, since good name has become important in business, or in society. In uncivilised communities anger, excited by calumny, was more naturally satisfied by castigation of the offender; and society has greatly advanced v^hen it can be said of slander or libel, that it is a more injurious theft to take away good-name than to steal a purse, which, in comparison with it, is "trash." Nuisances which rob a man of health, and other similar injuries, are treated by English law as torts, but if resolved into first principles as pri- vations or rights, they belong to the generic crime of theft. The rights and power's of the body, are also the sub- ject of Contract. The skiU acquired by its strength or by practice in manipulation, in various ways, be- comes a species of property. From the natui-al ownership of the body is derived the authority for those laws which award damages for loss of life or bodily injury, through neglect of ordinary care by persons who by contract undertake responsible duties, of which railway accidents are consj^icuous examples. The ownership of the body is violated by any action which interferes with its just liberty and freedom, whether affected by "false imprisonments," or by "kidnapping." Slavery is an unjust privation of natural liberty, which has largely prevailed, not- Stimtdmit Action of the Mind. 37 withstanding tlie universal sentiment, that men are by nature free and equal. It is of the highest moral criminality, for it deprives the slave not only of his person, but of the products of his labour. To an attempt to perpetrate that theft, nature prompts the last extremity of resistance. The mind, conscious of the ownership of the body, is the originator of political freedom, and the an- tagonist of tyranny. It points to equal laws, as the resultants of equal rights, and to the impartial ad- ministration of justice, as the corollary of equal laws. It encourages labour in science and art, its products being the property of the producer, as material pro- perty. It inspires noble and generous actions for the good of society, winning for the actor, as the fruit of such actions, personal esteem, and sometimes an im- perishable name. It demands freedom of thought and liberty of conscience as natural rights. 38 The Seventh Commandment. CHAPTEE V. MARRIAGE. VII. — Thou shalt not commit adultery. Marriage is the provision by which the sexes con- join their natural rights to their respective bodies, by a mutnal contract, induced by Nature, by which also the employment of their natural powers is redis- tributed with especial reference to the new duties which marriage calls into existence, for the nurture and education of the children of the marriage, and for the establishment of a family. Nature does not by force of circumstances which leave no choice compel her children to marriage ; but she persuades them by feelings and desires which they are seldom able to resist. The youth of both sexes, when they reach puberty, are inspired with a desire to pair. The passion of love is raised up, and, causing mutual selection, it is inflamed by admiration of the beauty or manly strength, the natural graces or mental qualities, which the enamoured pair exhibit Marriage a Contract of Nature. 39 to each, other; and they employ all their arts to obtain exclusive love, to be followed by marriage, as the natural consequence of the passion, and of the selection which it caused. In this mutual affiance, by a tacit but well-understood recognition of the ends and purposes of marriage derived from their feelings and experience, they agree to live together, to beget children, to nurture them, and to prepare them for taking their parents' places in the world ; and as these duties require the full period of life for their completion, the natural sentiment accords with that duration, in the young pair, and in their parents, to whose feelings it would be repugnant to give their daughter for a union less than life. But Nature does not leave her work to the sole action of the early sentiment of love. Children arrive in succession and become new ties of affection. The prolonged duties of human parentage contrast strikingly with the rapid discharge of parental duties by animals ; and such contrast is a remarkable instance of divergence in the details of Nature's plan when man was created. The parents have a joint property in their children, as they have in the persons of each other ; but nature distinguishes and divides the marriage duties between the wedded pair. To the woman is given the duty of nourishing the child- ren in their infancyj and of protecting and succouring 40 S?tasive Foi^ce of Nature to Marriage. them whilst growing up; and the marriage having placed the woman under the authority and protec- tion of the man, there is cast on him the duty of labouring for her support, and for the support of their children, and of bringing the latter forward in life. These duties, natural results of the marriage, confer correlative rights ; and as derived from Nature and enforced by natural sentiments, they have, as duties to the Creator, and as the expression of His will, the force of natural laws. With this suasive action of Nature the Decalogue wonderfully accords. It lays no command on man- kind to marry : it seems tb say, " If you marry you enter into a contract of the most sacred kind, by which you undertake to beget children, to rear and educate them, and to form with them a family, and so to do your part in furtherance of the Creator's plan for the well-being of the human race. Beware that you do not, by Adultery, vitiate your marriage." As in all human contracts and engagements there is failure, so marriage is not exempt, although entered into with ardent feelings of love and fidelity. Adultery occurs, and then there is imported into the conjugal home the usual characteristics of crime. Secrecy is maintained as long as possible, by artful caution, and the faithless partner lives in dread of the discovery of the acted lie. The moral sentiment Sexual Fidelity the Mean of Marriage. 41 is awakened, reflective of the natural law in tlie human heart, "thou shalt not commit adultery;" for the wisdom of God has made sexual fidelity the ^mean on which marriage rests. The wedded pair may be unsuited and unhappy; they may oppose each other's wishes, resist each other's will, even deny cohabitation; they may carry their mutual opposition to any extreme short of adultery, and yet neither of them may desire to separate; for that desire is counteracted by regard for the interests of their children, and by the moral opinion of their relations and friends. The unhappy pair is not impure, nor is their former love irrecoverable through returning good sense, or through the interference of friends. But if adultery be committed the marriage is vitiated and destroyed. The essence of the mar- riage contract, mutual fidelity, has been violated by the guilty partner, who has given to a paramour what was the exclusive right of the faithful partner. The paramour also has taken and enjoyed secretly and fraudulently the right and property of another ; and thus they have aided each other and conspired to terminate, and have ended unfitly and prematurely, the most important and most interesting of human contracts, and have also infringed the great principle of property that runs through all human afiairs. The marriage of pairs is not exclusively the order 42 Nature followed by Hiunan Laws. of Nature. Polygamy has long prevailed, and still prevails, amongst Asiatic nations. It is a contract which, has its type in the lower creation. But adultery attaches to polygamy as to a marriage of pairs, and by the laws of the Koran infidelity by the woman is punished with severity. Nature's laws relating to marriage act directty on human government. The loving pair having made in their solitude their natural contract, it is transferred to human government to give effect and publicity to it by such forms, religious or secular, as it may determine. It must give effect to the moral law by divorce, and by such punishment of adulterers as will make the law respected and visit the offenders with penal consequences. The English Legislature has accorded divorce to a wife in those cases only in which adultery by the husband, how- ever habitual and open, has been coupled with cruelty of a character so gross as to come within the defini- tion of " legal cruelty," or with desertion for a period of two years. And if human government has not found it expedient or possible to make adultery a felonious crime, it seems justified by those consi- derations which have made the natural impulse to marriage suasive and not mandatory. It is also within the province of human govern- ment to provide for the performance of the natural In Mainnage and as to Children. 43 duties of the married pair towards tlieir children. Their lives are protected by the sixth Commandment, and all the other duties of the parents are so defined by natural laws, that in this great branch of human legislation, there is no better guide than Nature's instincts. 44 The Fu7idainental Moral Law. CHAPTEE VI. PEOPERTT. VIII.— Thou shalt not steal. The seventh. Commandment " thou shalt not steal," lias before been stated to be the fundamental law of the moral system. It is applied by the two pre- ceding commandments to the crimes of murder and adultery ; and it comprises within its scope, as the subject-matter of the law, all rights and property that are not comprehended within those Command- ments, Its most comj)rehensive relation is to mate- rial property, and to rights connected with it ; but the moral law is not confined to these ; and we shall find that rights and duties of a personal kind, un- connected with material pro^Derty, are included within its jural scope and principle. The natural distinction before made, of open or public crimes, and of crimes under the cover of contract, is largely developed in the scojdc of this law. The most extensive duty of human govern- open Crimes against Property. 45 ment is to protect material property from theft ; for life, labour, trade, and most human blessings dej)end upon the security of property. English law distin- guishes wrongs against property into public crimes and civil injuries. The former, in the nomenclature of English law, are, robbery, burglary, arson, larceny, piracy, receiving stolen goods, embezzlement, false pretences, forgery and fraud, which are but varieties of the same crime, and infractions of the same fundamental law. But, as in the case of the body, so here there are, intermediate between public crimes and crimes under cover of contract, torts or wrongs, which, as trespasses or nuisances affecting property, or the en- joyment of property, not arising out of contract, are treated as civil injuries, and are compensated by damages, on the principle that, like torts against the body, they are unjustifiable privations of rights freely enjoyed before the tort or wrong was com- mitted, and, as such, they fall withm the generic crime of theft. All other injuries to material property and rights arise out of contract. If we examine the operation of contracts of labour, and contracts of sale or ex- change at the present day, we find that all the affairs of life are carried on, and all the wants of human society are supplied, by means of contracts. The 46 The Universality of Contract. houses in which we live, the furniture which makes them habitable, the servants who keep them in order, and who wait on us and prepare the food which we and they consume, the food itself, the clothing, and all other necessaries of daily life, the railways and carriages in which we travel, or take the air, the places of amusement where we recreate ourselves, are all supplied and kept in action by continually recurring contracts. The trades and pro- fessions by which we earn our incomes give occasion for another variety of contracts. Trade and com- merce, the creatures of the natural principle of contract, have called forth contracts of sale, of barter and exchange, of commission and agency, of bailment and trust, of letting and hiring, of sureties, of insurance, of partnershij), and the like. Agriculture, navigation, manufactures, and mining, have their peculiar contracts adapted to their peculiar operations. The artizans and labourers of every sort have no peculiar variety of contracts, but only more or less, according to their wages or their exchanging power acquired through their savings, of the con- tracts above sketched in relation to the wealthier classes of society. As the result of the trifold chain by which the distribution of property is confined to gift, contract, or theft, contracts which are fraudulent merge into Frauds through Contracts, Theft. 47 theft. Contracts, fraudulent in tlieir inception, or in their performance or non -performance, are the sources of immorality, which genericallj is theft. As to the inception of contract, jurists have laid down rules, that he who makes a contract about any- thing ought to make known the faults of the thing so far as he knows them, unless such faults are known to the party with whom he deals ; and that in the principal act of a contract this equality be re- quired, that more be not demanded than is equitable.^ Concealment of that which, if known, would change the face of the transaction — misdescription with in- tention to misrepresent; studied concealment of defects not known to the buyer nor discoverable by his vigilance — taint the contract with fraud, and make its dishonest products theft. But although the contract be free from taint of fraud in its inception, it may be made the cover of theft in the execution of it. Most of the contracts of daily life are implied contracts, in which, beyond the article and the quantity of it required and the price, all verbally stated, there are no express stipu- lations. It is implied that the goods delivered, or the work done, shall be of equal value with the price demanded for them; and, on the other hand, that the price shall be paid on the delivery of the goods, * Grotius de Jure Belli et Pacis, c. xii. 5, 9, 10, 11. 48 Implied and Expires s Contracts. or the completion of the work, or at the expiration of the credit. In express contracts these conditions are secured by actual stipulation. In the execution of these contracts, when inferior goods, or imitated or adulterated goods, or smaller quantities than those pui'chased, whether from false weights or want of proper care, or when inferior workmanship with in- ferior materials are fraudulently supplied ; such de- partures from the contract are a gain to the seller under the cover of the contract of more than it justly authorised, to the loss and injury of the buyer ; and such defalcation is the instrument of taking from the latter against his will — that is, neither by his gift, nor b}^ his contract, for that did not authorise it, and consequently by theft — that portion of the price paid which was gained by the delivery of in- ferior goods, or by inferior workmanship and mate- rials below the contract value. The higher contracts of commerce must be tested by the same prmciple — just performance of them according to the contract stipulations, implied oi* express. In contracts of commission or agency, the agent who, by neglect of duty, causes a loss to his employer, and notwithstanding such neglect takes his pay as if he had protected his principal's in- terests and preserved him from loss, is involved in a double fraud — the loss which his cmjoloyer has sus- Contracts of Commerce. 49 tained througli Ms neglect, and the pay or commis- sion which he has taken or received for services that were not only inefficient, but were injurious ; and, unless he makes restitution, the defalcation is theft. In like manner, he who uses money entrusted to him for a special purpose, for his own advantage, un- known to and unsanctioned hy him who confided the money to his care, is guilty of a fraudulent breach of trust and duty, which makes any loss to his em- ployer, not restored, theft. On the other hand, where the party to a contract who is to pay for goods, or work, or for services to be done or performed, receives the stipulated work or advantages with the intention not to pay for them, there can be no distinction made between such appro- priation and theft. And although the intention was not complete, but the buyer knew, and suppressed such knowledge from the other party, that there existed no means, nor any reasonable probability, of his paying the stipulated price when the credit expired, the moral difference from theft is very minute. Contracts, the performance of which is deferred to a distant time, are exposed to repudiation by the temp- tation which arises from a change of circumstances and altered interests to endeavour to withdraw from them, or to render them inoperative. A contract is a mutual promise, the effect of which is to change E 50 Deferred Contracts. the ownership in the subject of the contract imme- diately the promises are exchanged, or recorded ; what remains unaccomplished is the delivery of the property and of the money its price, to the new owners respectively created by the contract, at the time and place agreed. And as when one party delivers his goods, and the other fraudulently with- holds the goods or money which he promised to give concurrently in exchange, such withholding is a transparent theft ; so non-performance of deferred contracts, where the motive is fraudulent, and non- performance is not justified by circumstances of pre- vention or inability that have intervened since the contract, is a breach of the law " thou shalt not steal." If we could penetrate into the motive of a man who refuses, when able, to perform his contract, it would generally be found to be this — he would lose, instead of, as he hoped, gain ; and if he perseveres, he steals what the other party would have gained if the contract had been performed, and thus he adds an actual theft to an implied lie. It has before been remarked, that the jural prin- ciple of the law " thou shalt not steal," — restraint of theft — is the governing principle of human society, and that no other principle can be imagined, because the social condition of this world is based on rights and property. The same jural principle protects the Public Rights, Duties, and TriLsts. 51 rights conferred bj human government, and all other rights under the authority of human law. It also governs the performance of j)ublic duties and trusts, which, in relation to the public, are rights ; so that it is to this jural principle all rights and correlative duties must be referred, as the test of privation of rights or performance of duty. Honest performance of public duties is thus brought to the test of the moral law. A public servant, paid or unpaid, by undertaking public duties, virtually contracts with the state who ap- pointed him, and with its subjects for whose benefit he is appointed, to execute his duties faithfully and efficiently ; so that all rights, public and individual, committed to his care, may be preserved and duly distributed to those entitled to them ; and in so far as the public, or any individual, does npt receive their respective rights from the neglect or from the moral inefficiency of the trustee, or from a capricious and unjust official withholding of such rights, or from preferences in distribution where rights are equal, it is theft from the public, or from the indi- vidual, of the rights which they were entitled to, and which they would have enjoyed if the public affairs had been committed to a more scrupulous and more honest public servant. Bribery is a contract entered into for the purpose e2 52 Bribery. of producing breacli of trust or duty, and it is theft in him who receives the bribe — theft of the right which the public, or the state, or he who conferred the trust, had to honest performance of it, in con- formity with the principles of the trust, and also of the right of him who, but for the bribe, would have been preferred; and he who gains by a bribe that which, but for the bribe, would have been given to another, is the recipient of a gain or advantage acquired by theft. Bribery at parliamentary elections is, in its moral results, theft. Assuming the franchise to be a trust, the elector owes the duty to exercise it honestly to three distinct parties : (1) to the state ; (2) to his co- electors, and also to the non-electors, the elected being constitutionally the representative of the whole community ; and (3) to the candidates who, if the electors were incorruptible, would go to the poll with a moral certainty that the electors would make their choice and give their votes in conformity with con- stitutional principles of selection. The candidates are under a moral and constitutional duty to refrain from interference with the free choice of the electors, especially not to corrupt them; and they owe that (luty — (1) to the state ; (2) to the electors and non- electors ; and (3) to each other. But the vote cannot be brought to the test of legality on abstract prin- Daily Contracts in Great Britain. 53 ciples ; and, like treason, betrayal of elective trust can only be proved by overt act. Bribery is such overt act, and, if resolved into simple and general moral principles, it falls within tlie category of theft. As regards the candidate who, but for the bribe, should and would have been preferred, the theft of the vote from him is plain ; and as to the candidate who, by giving the bribe, obtained the vote, he is the recipient of a gain obtained through an illegal contract, the purpose of which was theft. As regards the state, and the pure electors and the non-electors, the con- tract with its results, was theft of their constitutional right to a choice in accordance with conscientious observance of legal and constitutional principles. Intimidation and undue influence have the same moral results ; they are even double thefts ; — theft of the right of the elector to the free exercise of his choice, and theft of his vote from the candidate, who, but for the intimidation or undue influence, would have received the vote; and that whether the vote be given to the rival candidate, or withheld through enforced neutrality. The great diffusion of contract throughout society, involving, both in making and executing contracts, moral duty of the highest kind, makes it worth while to try to form some conception of the extent of con- tract in this small island which is our home. The 54 liJiportance of Honesty in Contracts. census enables an approximate calculation to be made of the daily number of contracts in Great Britain. It may be taken that there are nearly 5,000,000 families, and on the average, five persons in each family ; and if we suppose that the adult members of both sexes in each family, in their domestic affairs, in their trades and professions, and in the management of their estates and proj^erty, enter into, or renew, or continue five contracts a day (one member of two families being assumed as engaged in each contract) then we have 25,000,000 as an approximate number of the contracts made daily in Great Britain. How vast is this field of operation for good or for evil ! How much general well-being and happiness depend on honest contract and honest performance of it ! Open crimes against property may not be so injurious to society, nor even so productive of immo- rality and disobedience to the Law of God, as secret dishonesty in its various forms. How can our duty be better defined, or our temptation to dishonesty be better restrained, than by testing every gain we are in pursuit of by the natural axiom, and by ask- ing ourselves, do we propose to get it by gift, by honest contract, or by theft ? The Ninth and Tenth Commandments. 5 5 CHAPTER YII. THE ADMINISTRATION OP JUSTICE. IX. — Thou shalt not bear false witness against tliy neighbour. The three Connnandments or moral laws that have been passed in review are those which the Creator ordained and thought sufficient for the moral govern- ment of mankind as members of society, and as fundamental laws of human government. We have seen that they are directly applicable to the vital elements of social life, the protection of the persons of men, of their families, and of their property derived through labour. It may have appeared that these laws form a complete and perfect system of moral and fundamental human law ; but as that may require further elucidation, it will be attempted in the next chapter. But here it will be convenient to remark that the tenth Commandment, "thou shalt not covet," does not enlarge the natural code. It declares no new principle, nor does it extend to new subjects of law. 56 Principle of Admi^iistration ofj^tsticc. It was interpreted by our Lord as " Defraud not,""^ which, admits of its being considered as an application of the law "thou shalt not steal" to the Ic^er degrees of theft, which, as we have seen, have such an extensive range in society through the natural instrument, con- tract. But although it declares no new principle, it confirms the princi]3le of individual rights. It is a clear declaration of a man's proj)erty in his house, in his wife, in his servants, in his ox, in his ass, and in everything that is his ; and not to covet these, may be interpreted as a direction to avoid the indulgence of desire for the property of our neighbours, which camiot be obtained without breach of moral and human law. The ninth Commandment, " Thou shalt not bear false witness against thy neighbour," most strikingly shows the perfection of the great Creator's code. It is not directed against any crime arising out of the body or its appetites, like the other laws, but is intro- ductory of a new principle, the essential principle of the administration of justice, which is a solemn inquiry by human government into the truth or falsehood of the allegations of parties contending for, or defending rights. It is designed to discover truth, and, when the truth is found, to distribute to each man his own according to his right, and to ordain * Markx. 19. Two Classes of Falsehood. 57 punislinient or redress for the injury committed. That proceeding necessarily requires the examination of persons cognizant of facts having relation to the inquiry — the testimony of witnesses. In such testi- mony this Commandment requires absolute truth from the witness, as far as he is capable of expressing the facts within his knowledge. But before con- tinuing the consideration of this law, we will attempt to give an answer to the objection made to the perfection of the Decalogue as a moral code, that it does not contain a law of Truth ; or, in the negative form of its legislation, a law forbidding falsehood and lies in ordinary communications between men, as well on those more solemn occasions when men are called upon, after the exercise of memory and thought, by deliberate speech and under the sanction of an oath, to give their testimony as witnesses on questions of right and wrong between man and man. It must not be inferred, because ordinary false- hood and lies are not expressly forbidden in the Com- mandments, that truth is not required in ordinary circumstances, nor that it is overlooked when it is connected with moral crime. Eecalling the distinction before made of the several classes of morality, false- hood and lies have two degrees of moral turpitude, and are divisible into two moral classes : (1) falsehood and lies, which are imiocuous to the party deceived, 58 Falsehood without Injustice. as regards his natural rights protected by the moral laws, where falsehood is of the nature of personal sin ; and (2) falsehood and lies which produce loss or injury to life, body, family, property, or good name, where it is moral crime. I. The first class of falsehood is not within the scope of this essay, but the moral distinction that has been made will be illustrated, and the general cause of truth may be served by resolving the distinction into the facts out of which it arises and on which it depends. The Sermon on the Mount coincides with the Commandments, in the absence of express teaching concerning truth, and the inference is strong, that the omission is in accordance with the necessity of nature. Our Lord urges the exclusion of oaths in conversation, but without expressly requiring that men's communications with each other shall be always true. But although truth is not enforced b}^ the two great codes of E-evelation, the love of truth is natural to man ; and his admiration of its bold assertion, in circumstances of peril, is as warm and unbounded as that excited by the display of heroic courage in circumstances of personal danger. The pursuit of truth in science and philosophy affords the purest and most exalted pleasure ; and in the common intercourse of life, the respect attained by good Natu7^al CatLses that disturb Trtith. 59 conduct is chiefly founded on the character acquired for truth and openness. But although the natural disposition is to truth, and it prevails largely in ordinary life, yet there are many disturbing causes ; and to maintain truth invariably, requires an effort and a will that exalt success into a virtue. Amongst the attributes of God is perfect Truth. We know that falsehood cannot be approved by Him ; and a true and obedient worshipper of God will strive to avoid falsehood, even though in circumstances that may be supposed to make it excusable. The disturbing causes are very numerous, and very powerful, as many of them are founded in nature. Imagination, hope, fear, love, hatred, vanity, emu- lation, produce exaggerations which misrepresent truth to the mind, even where no motive of injury or injustice, or even of deception prevails ; and these exaggerations excite the will to speech and action conformable to them. Lying is often used as a defence by men of de- pendent condition, to avert danger; as animals draw off the attention of their pursuers by the exercise of their natural instinct of cunning. A man in a humble and dependent social condition, having some necessary object to preserve, some danger to avert, some displeasure to remove, and fearing the power 6o Opinions of Divines and Philosophers. wMcli lie to whom lie lies has over him in his person, family, property, or in his labour for his daily food, resorts to a lie for his defence. For ordinary lying prevails most amongst men who are in dependence on more powerful men, and whose well-being is contin- gent on their pleasing their superiors exercising over them, perhaps, tyrannous authority; and fearless avowal of truth, openly spoken on all occasions, with- out regard to consequences, is, in general, only found in men whose social position, whether rich or poor, renders them independent of the power or caprice of other men. But concealment of thoughts by suppression of truth, and even departure from truth, are considered to be justified when occasions occur in which out- spoken truth would be more injurious than conceal- ment ; and divines and philosophers have expressed opinions and cited authorities even from the Scrip- tures, that simulation and dissimulation are not to be entirely removed from the scheme of human life. There is a dictum of Saint Augustine, "that it is lawful to conceal, in prudence, the truth under a certain dis- simulation." "^ We can easily imagine occasions where a justifiable concealment of plans or purposes, perfectly innocent in themselves, would be frustrated, if when * Cited by Grot ins, lil"). iii. 1, who disputed Cicero's assertion (I)e Offic. iii. 15),"cxomni vita simulatiouom dissinuilationcniquetollondam." Falsehood with Injustice. 6i questioned, we were required to state frankly and openly all our intentions to our opponents. These reasons account for the omission from the revealed codes of express laws, requiring truth on all occasions, and there are few so happily constituted, and so happily placed, as not to be thankful to per- ceive, in the absence of express law, a concession to the weakness of human nature, and why, in cases in which falsehood is innocuous to the party deceived, the offence has not been made punishable by human government, but cognizable as a sin by God alone, who knows all hearts. II. The second class of falsehood or lies, those which produce injury or injustice to life, bod}^ family, property, rights, or good name, have none of the mitigating circumstances that are excusatory in the other class ; but it is to be remarked, that falsehood in connection with injuries or wrongs, is but an in- strument of crime. Falsehood may be said to be an instrument or inherent in every crime; for every crime (unless done in open defiance) is planned and perpetrated in secrecy, and, so long as it is hidden or unconfessed, there is an acted lie. It may be used as false j)retence to obtain property by fraud, to effect the seduction of a wife, or to accomplish murder by deceiving the victim into a snare. In these offences the essence of the crime is the purpose accomplished 62 False-Witness 07" Perjitry. to which the lie was accessory; and in the heavier wickedness of the crime the minor instrument is ab- sorbed. The commandments and human government, following Nature in estimating the lie as an instru- ment, forbid the major crime, and so virtually for- bid the instrument also. This principle of interpretation has the authority of Mosaic law. In Leviticus^ it is written, " if a soul sin, and commit a tresj)ass against the Lord, and lie unto his neighbour in that which was delivered him to keep, or in fellowship, or in a thing taken away by violence, or hath deceived his neighbour ; or have found that which was lost, and lieth concerning it, and sweareth falsely . . . then he shall restore that which he took violently away, or the thing which he hath deceitfully gotten, or that which was delivered him to keep, or the lost thing which he found, or all that about which he hath sworn falsely." These were moral offences, in which the lie was an instrument either of accom23lishment or concealment of a major crime, robbing or fraud, and the punish- ment was restitution. When lying rises to false-witness or perjury, the case is altered ; lying is then the crime. The purpose of the investigation is the discovery of truth, in order to do justice between man and man ; and by implica- tion from the Commandment, truth is em2:>hatically * Chap. vi. ver. 2-5. Religious Pin^posc of the Oath. 63 required ' on all occasions when moral questions of right and wrong arise that are to be determined by human testimony, whether such testimony be given by words of simple assurance, or under the sanction of oaths. But there are always criminal motives at the bottom of designed false- witness. The testimony may be made the instrument of dii^ect crime, by the conviction and punishment of an innocent person. Lower but also criminal motives may be some advant- age to the witness himself, either by direct bribery, or a share in the gain expected from false testimony, or at least the advantage or pleasure of favouring a friend and protecting him from the consequences of his immoral act. The law, " thou shalt not steal," here forces itself on the attention and on the conscience of the witness ; and if he forswears himself, he acts in disobedience of the Commandment and of the natural law written in his heart. By means of the oath, a religious sanction has been added to the moral sanction of the natural and re- vealed law. Belief in a Deity who rewards and punishes men according to their moral deserts, may be said to be universal throughout mankind. It seems to be natural to call " G-od to witness," on occasions when it is wished to inspire confidence in promises, or belief in assertions which it is desired 64 Oath sanctioned by the Third Commandment. should be accepted, and acted upon as true. Oatlis have been in use from remote antiquity, among all peoples and in every age. By the oath the vritness solemnly calls on the Deity in whom he believes, and whom he worships, to give him Divine helj) to avoid false-witness ; and he recognises his liability to the punishment which, from the justice and power of God, awaits him, hereafter, who is false in his testimony ; and the third Commandment has made it known, that " God will not hold him guiltless who taketh His name in vain." Perfection of Natural and Revealed Code. 65 CHAPTEE VIII. The Perfection of the Natural and Eevealed Code tested by the Commentaries of Blackstone. The Moral Code consists of four laws : — N"ature and Revelation declare tlie same laws. The analysis of each law has probably made the deduction clear that it is the representative of a class or category of law, and that the separate categories, when com- bined, constitute a perfect moral code comprehend- ing every form of moral action. But it may not be superfluous to bring the combined classes of law to the test of a system of human law in actual opera- tion ; and there can be no better probation of the perfection and completeness of the Divine code de- duced from the analysis than a comparison of it with " the Commentaries of Blackstone," which, as a digest of the laws of England, contain all the laws, fonda- mental and municipal, which an ancient nation of the highest civilisation and most extensive commerce required for its government. 66 Tested by Blackstones Commentaries. The value of Blackstone's Commentaries as such a test is in the absence of all attempt by him to found his digest on principles of human nature, obtained by induction or by philosophical analysis. Admitting the necessity of founding his treatise on a methodi- cal division of the laws of England, he did not, in his preliminary treatise " on the Nature of Laws in general," adopt, or follow, or even name the Deca- logue as his guide: he only referred generally to the revealed or divine law found only in the Holy Scriptures ; precepts, when revealed, found upon com- parison to be really a part of the original law of nature, but their truths not attainable by reason in its present corrupted state, and until they were revealed hid from the wisdom of ages; yet of the same original with those of nature. Upon these two foundations, the law of Natm-e and the law of Eevela- tion (he wrote), depend all human laws. We have, therefore, in Blackstone's division of the law, the work of a learned jurist, who, whilst fully impressed with the value and importance of Revelation, followed the dictates of his own ex^Derience of the actions of mankind, as displayed in coui-ts of justice and else- where, and of the teachings of " the law written in the heart." He may, also, have been led to, or con- firmed in his jural division of law by a passage in the Institutes of Justinian, " Omne jus quo . '' Rights of Persons r 67 utininr, vel ad Personas attinet, vel ad Res, vel ad Actiones " — the latter being the legal process for enforcing the rights. Eemarking that " municipal law is a rule of civil conduct, commanding what is right and prohibiting what is wrong ;" and that " the primary and prin- cipal objects of law are rights and wrongs," Black- stone followed that division, which we have found to be fundamental in nature, and he subdivided the rights into "rights of persons," and " rights of things;" and the wrongs into "private wi'ongs," or civil injuries, and "public wrongs," or crimes and misdemeanours . To the same division of natural rights, (if we make a verbal correction of Blackstone's terms in which he has sacrificed accuracy to terseness, and which he would have avoided if he had followed Justinian,) to rights in respect of persons, and rights in respect of things, we have been led by our induction from the appetites of sex and hunger. The laws, "thou shalt do no murder," and "thou shalt not commit adultery," acting upon the natural rights of mankind to the body and its life, protect the rights of persons ; and the first book of the Commentaries which treats " of the absolute rights of individuals, such as would belong to their persons merely in a state of nature, and which every man is entitled to enjoy, whether out F 2 68 " Rights of Things:' of society or in it," describes the personal rights which we have deduced from Nature, and the Moral Laws ; the right of security and enjoyment of life, limb, body, health and reputation, the rights and the reciprocal duties of husband and wife, and the moral relation of parent and child. " The Eights of Things " are described in the second book of the Commentaries as "those rights which a man may acquire in and to such external things as are unconnected with his person." This subdivision of rights wholly relates to property; of which land or real property, and moveable property or personal property, are the natural as well as the social elements. The two first books of the Commentaries further contain digests of the positive or instituted law which it is the peculiar province of human government to provide and declare as supplementary to the moral law. These are — laws for the establishment and preservation of the government and the state, for providing and collecting the revenue, for appointing magistrates, for supporting the clergy, and forming and preserving the military and maritime powers; and besides these, laws for carrying out the natural rights — to regulate the alienation of property, by contract, and by gift, and by will, — a form of gift, — by inheritance, and by succession, and to define the Positive or InstitiUed Law. 69 rights acquired by marriage. The test of the justice of the positive or instituted law, supplementary to the , moral laws, is the natural law on which they must be founded. Human government must carry out and enforce the natural rights, and adopt the moral laws as jural principles in its legislation. Wrongs both public and private, are invasions of, or injuries to natural rights ; those which have been specified in our analysis of the moral laws. Lastly, the Commentaries treat of "Redress of private wrongs and punishment of crimes and mis- demeanours, and the modes of procedure in the administration of Justice." The juridical principle of the ninth Commandment is adopted. The wit- nesses give their testimony on oath, and the law is applied according to the testimony of the witnesses. We here make a break in our work. We have completed the direct proof which it is in our power to offer in support of the jDropositions affirmed, (1) that the moral laws declared in the Commandments are identical with laws of Nature ; and (2) that they, respectively, form a perfect code of moral law and of fundamental human law. The whole proof of the first part of the proposition has been obtained from facts of nature. It has started from natural rights, as a truth within the self-consciousness of man ; the subject-matter of the laws has been traced to ultimate o Completion of Proof, from Nature. principles in nature; and by the inductive method of discovering laws from facts, it has been found that the moral laws are corollaries evolved from the natural rights. The second part of the proposition has been proved by a copious analysis of each law ; which, com- pared with the practical jurisprudence of Blackstone, has shown the identity of the laws as moral laws,^and as fundamental laws of human government, and their completeness for the moral and for the himian govern- ment of mankind. We shall now proceed to consider sj^stems of jurisprudence and moral philosophy whose theories are opposed to the theory of natural law. By that means the other side of the great question — " what is the foundation of morals " ? — will be laid before my readers, who, by comparison of the system of Nature with its opposite system, — the theory of Utility — that morality was deduced by men from ob- servation and experience of what is useful to society or productive of general happiness, — may form their own judgment in which of these systems Truth is found. Human Government and yttrisprudence. 7 1 CHAPTER IX. The Natural and Eevealed Code as the Basis of Jurisprudence, considered with reference to the Writings of Jurists. Human goverimient opens a new moral relation between men based on the moral laws. It is the instrument by wbicli God executes His laAvs on earth ; by which He gives to them practical force. It is easy to imagine that its origin may have been the expansion of the family authority necessarily transferred by the increase of families into a com- munity, to a chief or to a number of elders. The form of government seems to be left open to the choice of mankind, or to the influence of circum- stances which determine the choice; but some government is a necessity of man's nature ; and in those countries of the world where no government exists, not even a chief, — for such there are, — the peo23le are in the lowest social condition it is possible to conceive. The relation of man to human government modi- fies his natural rights, and confers on him new, but 72 Restraining Action of Natural Rights. derivative, rights. Bj placing- himself under its pro- tection he diminishes the absoluteness of his natural rights. He must not be the judge of an alleged violation of them, nor punish the violator with his own hand. He must also submit to some deduction from his property or from the earnings of his labour, as his contribution to the expenses of the govern- ment; and he must yield some portion of his per- sonal freedom to protect his country when in war, and at all times when required for the protection of the community. The condition attached to the natural rights — that the enjoyment of them is sub- ject to the same natural ownership, rights, and powers, in every other human being — also exercises a restrictive effect. It restrains the natural rights to the limits of the individual rights and powers ; and its action is directed to that end by the an- tagonism which invasion of the rights of another instantly produces. Through this individuality which makes each man the natural protector of his own rights, an accumula- tion of vigilance is produced against unjust exercise of rights, which makes equal rights, instead of being destructive of society as is sometimes imagined, its greatest strength. The rights of each man must be so exercised that he does not take life, nor injure the body of another man, invade property or rights, On the People and on Government. "j^^ natural or acquired, by theft or fraud, nor violate marriage obligations. Man encounters tbese restric- tions in every place and at all times ; and it is sub- ject to these restrictions that he is free and equal with his brother. The natural rights are also the restraints of the power of human government, as well as the govern- ing principle of its authority. The jural principle of the moral laws must guide the action of the execu- tive government and be the criterion of its justice. It must import that principle into its laws ; and all positive or instituted law opposed to the natural rights is in excess of the authority of human go- vernment. It is this principle which marks the line of separation between the fundamental laws of human government, and its positive or instituted law. International law has the same natural boundaries. A state is but an aggregation of men with the same natural rights protected by the same moral laws; and so a state can have no rights but those of its individual members, against another state consti- tuted in the same manner. It may defend its rights by war, for between states there is no tribunal by which redress can be obtained but that of force. But a state cannot make war to steal territory, and, with it, its inhabitants, without a breach of the law "Thou shalt not steal." 74 ^>^^ Natiu^al Right to Government. There appears to be no natural right to the power of human government ; if such existed, every one having a natural and equal right to be supreme no one would acknowledge and obey an equal who dis- possessed him of his natural right, and government could not be. The natural right in relation to government, which is universal, is, to the protection of person and pro- perty ; and that protection human government was instituted to aflPord. We have seen that person and pro])erty constitute the whole subject-matter of hu- man law, as it does of moral law, and that besides the laws for their j)rotection there are not necessarily under human government any other laws than those instituted for the maintenance and support of the government itself. If men could enjoy their persons and property unmolested in a state of nature, there would be no necessity for human government ; nor, in civilised life, would it have any functions if these rights were invariably acknowledged and never dis- turbed. But although the protection of person and pro- perty is transferred from the owners of them in a state of nature to the chiefs of human government, the parties and the causes that made necessary pro- tection on the one hand and restraint on the other, remain the same under human government as in a Instihtted to Protect Natural Rights. 75 state of nature. The parties are the same, for it is still the protection of the people from one another ; and in every community, primitive or civilised, from causes which have their foundation in nature, the people become divided into two classes, possessors of property and non-possessors of property; with grada- tions between the extremes of both classes, but yet the several classes sufficiently marked and distinct to place the possessor and the non-possessor of property in different social positions as subjects of the state. The fundamental cause of that social division arises out of the natural distinction before explained, in the development of the natural rights ; ^ from the different manner in which people employ the powers of the body, physical and mental. There are doubt- less other natural causes, such as the difference in mental and physical ability amongst men, that render the employment of the natural powers more difficult to some men than to others ; but we here refer only to the conditions on which the natural rights are given to man, and it is clear that property is not an innate gift to man, but it must be worked for and secured by the employment of the mental and phy- sical powers which are innate, and by the exercise of the individual will. This distinction between the people affects their relation to the government of the * Suirra, p. 12. 76 Claims on its Protection not equal. communit}', and the amount of protection which they require from it ; through the diversity of inaction and action, one portion of them possesses only the natural right of person as an entity and the right of property as a potentiality, whilst the other por- tion i30ssesses both rights as entities. Monarchy affords protection to person and pro- perty free from any interest directly discordant with that of either class of the people, for all the people besides the monarch being the governed, and not partaking of the governing power whether they are possessors or non-possessors of property, the power of the monarch is uncontaminated by any political preference for either. Democracy transfers the ruling power to the go- verned under the monarchy, and by means of repre- sentatives elected by the peo2:)le the legislative and executive power of government is in the gift of the people. The protection it affords to property is in- complete. The two classes of people, possessors and non-possessors of property, share equally in the election of the representatives, and thus the ruling power is in the joint gift of tliose who in relation to property require restraint, and of those who require protection, or in a majority determined by a poll of these classes combined. It is said that men being equal by nature are Distrib2ttion of Political Pozuer. j^j entitled to equal political power. Men are equal in respect of natural rights, that is, they are equal as the governed. They are entitled from human govern- ment to equal protection of person and property, and to equal laws in relation to them; and when these are afforded, the people enjoy all that is most valuable in the institution of government — for these are the true practical tests of the goodness of a government. Wlien the ruling power is transferred from a single ruler to the people themselves, they will consult their own happiness if they require such a distribution of the elective franchise as will best produce and secure' equal protection and equal laws, and will prevent a preponderance of political power opposed to the natural rights. A just distribution seems to be an apportionment of the elective power between the people in relation to their claims on the protection of government ; that is, in relation to the entities before mentioned which they have acquired through the employment of their natural powers and rights ; for unless the government be so constituted as to have authority over both entities, it will fail in its original design and purpose. It should be re- membered that a combination of numbers exercising the power of government has no authority to di- minish the natural rights of a minority, otherwise than by laws which equally, or in a just ratio, affect 78 Uniformity of Moral Sentiment. the majority. In relation to natural rights, numbers may not do what an individual may not do — take life or property, or interfere with the natural powers, without committing moral crime. There is no power in human government to change the general equality of natural rights ; and no government can long exer- cise great and general injustice against natural rights, and escape being overthrown by revolution, or termi- nation in despotism. 1^0 theory of morality or jurisprudence can be complete uuless it accounts for the general uniformity of moral sentiments among mankind, and for the resemblance to such moral sentiments which positive law is compelled to take. I trust that sufficient causes of such uniformity and resemblance have been made apparent in the previous chapters ; in the automatic force of the natural rights, as neces- sarily developing ' in the human heart ' natural laws by which they are declared and protected. When our attention is called to an action of a moral nature, we immediately know whether it is conformable or not to the rights and to the moral laws within us, and moral sentiments, corresponding with the moral quality of the action, and reflective of the moral laws, instinctively and independently of our will, spring up in our minds. The constant action of this consciousness in the yurisprudence. 79 mind appears sufficient to account for, and it may be the true explanation of that faculty long the sub- ject of dispute amongst philosophers, the Conscience or Moral Sense. These rights cannot be invaded without a stinging sense of injustice in him whose rights are invaded, and generally a determination to enforce restitution, to which is often added re- venge ; and the invader of such rights knows what feelings he will call forth, and the danger to which his acts expose him. This consciousness, in its double action, produces the phenomena attributed to the conscience or moral sense."^ These principles seem to present a natural founda- tion for a science of jurisprudence, but a natural origin of the science, or one that rests it on immu- table principles, is scornfully rejected by modern jurists. The preference shown for utility as the foundation of morals, and consequently of jurispru- dence, has produced such contempt for a basis in nature, that to refer to it, merely using the phrase, is supposed to requu-e some boldness, and even some apology. t Yet it is admitted that jurisprudence has * It must be recollected, that we are here considering only the morality of the Decalogue, which has relation to rights. In the book mentioned in the title-page I have considered the varieties of the phenomena of the conscience, and I have attempted to explain how such varieties are brought under the action of conscience. See the Postscript at the end of this volume. t Phillips on Jurisprudence, p. 28. 1863. 8o Newton s Method of Philosophising. not been successfully treated as an art or science, tlie most distinguislied writer on it asserting that "what has hitherto stood in the place of a science has for the most part been a set of guesses." ^ Nothing ap- pears more remarkable in the history of moral philo- sophy than the absence of attempts to treat it on principles purely natural, unless it be the extreme repugnance to tolerate any attempts to derive its principles from nature. Yet the subject of the science is man as he is constituted by the hand of his Maker, and as he appears in the world ; and the purpose of the science is the knowledge of the moral and social laws or rules to which he is subject, and of the duties which are cast upon him in relation to his fellow-men as individuals and in society. Why should the method of philosophising used in physical science be discarded from use in moral science, and hypothesis substituted for inductive fact? "Newton, taught by Bacon to despise hypotheses as the fictions of human fancy, laid it down as a rule of philosophising, that no causes of natural things ought to be assigned but such as can be proved to have a real existence. He saw that all the length men can go in accounting for phenomena is to discover the laws of nature according to ^vliich they are produced ; and therefore * Ancient Law, p. 113. Historical Method of yurisprudence. 8 1 that the true rule of philosophising is this : From real facts ascertained by observation and experiment, to collect by just induction the laws of nature, and to apply the laws so discovered to account for the phenomena of nature." "^ The theories of jurisprudence most in favour are those of Utility and a system founded on that philosophy, called the Historical Method. f The theory of the latter is that morality and law origi- nated in the primitive ages of human society, and were progressive with its advance. The method is to trace the progress of law from the earliest point at which its history can be taken up ; to penetrate as far as we can in the history of primitive societies, and thus to commence with the simplest social forms in a state as near as possible to their rudimentary condition. The difficulty of grappling with the phenomena of early societies is represented as great, " but even if they gave more trouble than they do, no pains would be wasted in ascertaining the germs out of which has assuredly been unfolded every form of moral res- traint which controls our actions and shapes our con- duct at the present moment." % * Eeid on the Intellectual Powers, essay 2, c. viii. Hamilton's ed. p. 271. t Ancient Law ; its Connection with the Early History]of Society, and its Kelation to Modern Ideas. By Henry Sumner Maine, 1863. + Pp. 118-20. G 82 Historical Sources of Law. The hypothesis has not been supported from sources sufficiently primitive to make it a conclusive proposi- tion that every form of moral restraint originated in law, independently of what is " behind the law " — original natural causes which produced the law. It is conceded that the Twelve Tables and codes of the same class largely diffused over the Roman and Hellenic worlds at epochs not widely distant from one another, or jural phenomena which lie behind these codes and preceded them in point of time, are the earliest points at which the history of law can at present be taken up. " Not a 'few documentary records exist (it is added) which profess to give us information concerning the early phenomena of law ; but until jDhilology has effected a complete analysis of the Sanskrit literature, our best sources of knowledge are undoubtedly the Greek Homeric Poems, considered of course not as a Jhistory of actual occurrences, but as a description, not wholly idealised, of a state of society known to the writer." "^ Natural law is excluded with disdain from the his- torical method, and it is only conceived as associated with the wild views and revolutionary principles of Rousseau. " Theories plausible and comprehensive, but absolutely unverified, such as the Law of Nature or the Social Compact, enjoy a universal preference » P. 2. Natural Law Rejected. ^t^ over sober research into the primitive history of society and law ; and they obscure the truth not only by diverting attention from the only quarter in which it can be found, but by that most real and most important influence which, when once entertained and believed in, they are enabled to exercise on the later stages of jurisprudence." "^ The existence of natural law, the result of origi- nal principles of human nature, such as the natural rights before described, is not confuted by the rejection of the Social Compact of Eousseau. The operation of nature as the origin of society and law is, therefore, in no degree considered in this learned treatise. There is no enquiry into the existence of natural rights, or of appetites, instincts, desires, impulses, and feelings implanted in the bodies or minds of men, which may be the motive forces of their actions and conduct, and from which primitive society may have sprung, and natural law and human law may be deduced. The historical theory appears to be, that mankind, without any stimulating or directing impulses from nature, worked out for them- selves a moral system and a system of human law. I shall not enquire whether the Hindoo Code called the Laws of Menu has not been made known to English readers by translations, because a comparison * P. 3. G 2 84 Other Ancient Codes not Considered. of their laws with, existing law is omitted from the treatise, for the reason that although it is certainly a Brahmin compilation, yet in the opinion of the best contemporary orientalists it is, in great part, an ideal picture of that which in the view of the Brahmins oucjht to be the law."^ Even on that supposition some light might have been thrown by them on the his- torical theory. Nor shall I conjecture why the code of Sinai, of at least equal antiquity with any discoveries that can be expected from Sanskrit literature, and commonly supposed to be of superior authority, is altogether excluded from the historical method. But I shall ask, can the origin of morality and law be determined by the codes of primitive societies were such codes in existence ? Such codes, it may be anticipated, do not disclose the principles on which they were constructed. To be recognised as " the germs " of the morality and law which now control our actions and shape our con- duct, the law which they unfold must be homo- geneous with existing law. But being homogeneous, the question would remain midetermined, whether these primitive people were impelled to make their laws by implanted principles of nature, or by their simple unaided observation and exj)erience. It may be asked, also, what extent of retrospective research * P. 17. Difficulties of the Historical Method. 85 is necessary to determine arrival at the codes which, contain the germs of morality and law, and how snch codes are to be known when reached if they are homogeneous with existing law ? The longer and more remote the chain of continuity, and the wider the spread of ancient homogeneous law, the more complete the argument for a common origin in some natural principle " behind the law ; " as the cause of that general uniformity which every system of law is compelled to take. The discoveries expected from Sanskrit literature are a vain expectation, if we have traced law to its origin in natural rights, and in the appetites, as the ultimate principles of the human system. Varieties of positive law we may expect to find in such ancient codes, adapted to some peculiarity in physical circum- stances, climate, or condition of the governed. " Eor (said Bacon) there are in nature certain fountains of justice, whence all civil laws are derived but as streams ; and like as waters do take tinctures and tastes from the soils through which they run, so do civil laws vary according to the regions and governments where they are planted, though they proceed from the same fountains." ^ It is only the h^^pothetical origin of morality and law propounded in the treatise under consideration, * Of the Advancement of Learning, book ii. Works, vol. iii. p. 475. 86 Homc7nc Poems foundedin Nature. that I presume to question. The learning and juridical value of the expositions of Ancient Law are placed by public opinion beyond dispute. But I may point out that the subjects of disquisition are derivative not fundamental subjects of law. Primo- geniture, wills, widows' shares of moveables, aliena- tion of property, contract, even the nexum and patria potestas, are subjects of positive and instituted law in very close afinity with, and by the theory of this treatise they must necessarily be referred ultimately to an origin in nature. The Homeric Poems, fertile as they are supposed to be in ancient law, are not deficient in examples of natural law. The Iliad is founded on the moral principle expressed in the Seventh Commandment. Its action arises out of the jural principle of the laws of Revelation : the antagonism of rights and wrongs, and its natural result — desire to redress and punish moral delinquency. Chryses obeyed a natural prin- ciple, and enforced a natural right, when he demanded his captive daughter from Agamemnon. The Odyssey is founded on the same principle of nature. Penelope, in the absence of Ulysses, and in the hope of his return, resists the importunities of her numerous suitors, and Homer represents her as a chaste and faithful wife. There are not wanting distinguished philosophers Plato on Natural Law. %^ to suj)port a theory of natural law, whom it is no disgrace to follow into the field. Plato, in the Minos,* brings into discussion the question " what is the generic constituent of Noyu-os-, or Law ; what characteristic property it is which is common to all Law, and is implied in the name Law ? " The answer adopted after discussion is " that Law is not the aggregate of laws enacted or of customs held binding ; but that which lies behind these laws and customs, imparting to them their binding force." It is not stated what is the binding force which lies behind the laws ; but the principle is asserted that Law includes as a portion of its meaning justice, and that " there can be no such thing as bad pr wicked law." No weight is placed on differences between different nations, for " Law wishes or aims to be the finding out of real i by ; and if there are differences between different nations, this is because the poAver to find out does not always accompany the wish to find out." " As to the assertion that Law is one thing here, another thing there, one thing at one time, another thing at another — Sokrates contests it. Just things are just (he says) everywhere and at all times ; unjust things are unjust also. . . It is only the right, the true, the real . . . which is properly a law, and * Grote's Plato, vol. i. pp. 418-429. SS Aristotle and Grotius is entitled to be so called. That which, is not right is not a law, — ought not to be so called, — and is only supposed to be a law bjthe error of ignorant men."^ Aristotle in the Ethics marks the distinction between natural law and positive or instituted law. " Of the political just one part is natural, the other legal. The natural is that which everywhere is valid, and depends not upon being or not being received. The legal is that which originally was a matter of indifference, but which when enacted was so no longer; as the price of ransom, or the animals proper for sacrifice." f In the Rhetoric the dis- tinction is more remarkable : " Right and wrong are defined by laws of two kinds. One is Law proper, the other, universal Law. That is Law proper which is settled as law by each community for itself; that is universal which is accordmg to nature. For there is, as all feel, an inward persuasion by nature, a universal right and wrong, without any covenant or agreement being made among men to that effect. As the Antigone of Sophocles is made to say, that it was right in her to bury her brother Polynices, though forbidden, as being right by nature. " For this is not a law of yostorday, But an eternal ; nor its rise is known." t * riato, Minos, 317 C. f Nicom. Ethics, book v. c. 7. 1 "Rhetoric," book i. c. 13. on Natiu^al and Instituted Law. 89 Grotius laid down the necessity of separating natural or permanent law from instituted law in the construction of a science of jurisprudence. " Many in preceding times have designed to invest juris- prudence vdth the form of an art or science, but no one has done this. Nor can it be done except care be taken on that point which has never yet been properly attended to, to separate Instituted Law from ^Natural Law. For natural law, as being always the same, can be easily collected into an art ; but that which depends upon institution, since it is often changed, and is different in different places, is out of the domain of art, as the perception of indivi- dual things in other cases also is." ^ * Grotius "De Jure Belli et Pacis," Prolegomena. 90 Nahtre and Utility compared. CHAPTER X. Nature compared with Utility as the foundation of moral and human law, and the respective theories tested by the writings of philosophers. The theory of moral philosophy raost opposed to a theory of natural moral law is that of Utility. The marked preference shown for the latter by eminent philosophers and public writers at the present day brings me into conflict with formidable opponents. But I am encouraged when I reflect that what I write is the j^roduct of much thought and meditation for years past. It has afforded me the highest pleasure to contemplate the Moral System as the result of Natural Law, and to work out, slowly but patiently, my first crude conception of its origin and design, and to trace it, as I believe, to its Divine Creator. I feel a humble confidence that lam proceeding in the direction and on the foundation of Truth ; but I am far from expecting that long-established theories, however erroneous, will be quickly superseded by my lucubrations, or that nothing will remain to be added to the latter by other minds in order to make the truth complete. I trust, however, it wdll aj)pear to some of my readers that A ristotle. g i what lias been developed and described partakes of those qualities which Copernicus said should be pos- tulated by the philosopher — " the symmetry and sim- plicity of the Works of God." In selecting philosophers and quoting their works in support of, or in opposition to, my views, the pro- ceeding partakes of the character of a trial, where each party calls witnesses who give direct testimony in support of the issues, and also cross-examines the witnesses of his opponent, to weaken their testimony or to derive from them admissions of facts which cor- roborate his propositions. The witnesses to support the law of nature and Eevelation are Pagan philo- sophers of the highest celebrity, and Christian philo- sophers of no less eminence. I. Aeistotle is claimed as a supporter of Utility ; but from the Politics^ have been quoted passages which show him to be a supporter of Nature. I do not find in the Ethics or in the Politics any ex- press recognition of the existence of natural rights ; but in the Ethics there is his clear authority for the existence of fundamental and immutable moral laws, in the remarkable exception which he made from his ethical system of the mean state. "But (he remarked) it is not every action, nor every pas- sion, which admits of the mean state ; for some have * Ante, Chap. I. 92 Aristotle in support of the Moral Lazus. their badness at once implied in their name; as, for example, malevolence, shamelessness, envy ; and amongst actions, adultery, theft, homicide. For all these, and such as these, are so called from their beincr themselves bad, not because their excesses or defects are bad. In these, then, it is impossible ever to be right; but we must always be wrong. Nor does the right or wrong in such cases as these depend at all upon the person with whom, or the time when, or the manner in which adultery is committed ; but absolutely the doing of any one of these things is wrong . . however they be done sin is committed." ^ This is the positive, clear, and earnest dictum of a philosopher who never saw or heard of the Com- mandments, and therefore his positive and clear de- nunciation of these actions as indisputable crimes must have been derived from Nature. They are, too, the exact actions forbidden by the Commandments — adultery, theft, homicide ; and the omission of false- witness only slightly, if it at all, impairs the coinci- dence of the Pagan philosopher's moral code with the moral code of Eevelation ; for it has been shown f that the immorality of falsewitness is concentrated in its final result in one of the moral crimes which Aristotle pronounced impossible ever to be right. Cicero gave testimony to an invariable law of * Nicora. Ethics, book ii. c. G. Browne's Translution. f St'.^ra, Chap. VII. Cicero. Honesty an invariable Law. 93 justice with regard to property in tlie following manner : " There is nothing npon earth so contrary to nature, neither death, nor poverty, nor pain, nor whatever other evil can befal a man, either in his body or fortune, as to take away anything wrongfully from another, and to do one's self a kindness by injuring one's neighbour. For, in the first place, it ruins all manner of society and intercourse amongst men ; since it is plain, that if once men arrive at such a pass as to plunder and injure the rest of their neigh- bours out of hopes to procure some advantage to themselves, there must follow of course a dissolution of that society, which of all things in the world is most agreeable to nature . . . For though it is no more than what nature will allow of, that each man should look after himself in the first place, and furnish himself with the necessaries of life, before he takes care to provide for other people ; yet the same nature will by no means permit that any one should rise by thrusting down another, and increase his own fortune by the spoils of his neighbours. . . Nature and right reason, as being at once both a human and divine law too, command the duty of not thrusting down another to increase his own fortune with much greater authority ; and whoever obeys them (as all men must, who propose to live according to the rules of nature) will never be guilty of coveting what is 94 ^0 Extreme justifies TJieft. another's, or applying to his own use what had first been injuriously taken from his neighbour .... But what (perhaps some men will be apt to say) if a wise man be ready to perish for hunger, must he not take away victuals from another, though a perfectly useless and insignificant fellow ? Not at all, for life itself is not so dear to me as a settled resolution of doing no wrong for my private advantage. But suppose this good man, almost dead with cold, should have it in his power to take Phalaris' clothes away, one of the most savage and inhuman tyrants ; would you not have him to do it ? There is no great difi- culty in determining such cases ; for it is certain, if you take away anything from another, though never so useless and insignificant a creature, for no other end but to benefit yourself by it, it is an inhuman action, and plainly contrary to the laws of nature : but if you are one, who by living will do very great service to the Eepublic, or perhaps to the society of mankind in general, and for that reason only take something from another ; it is an action that is not to be found much fault with. But in all other cases, every man is bound to bear his own misfortunes, rather than to get quit of them by ^vronging his neighbour."^ Bacon: "We proceed now to Ethics which con- * Tully's Offices, book iii. c. 5 & 6 ; Dr. Cockraan's Translation. Bacon. Nature. Pleasure and Pain. 95 sidereth of the will of man.^ In the handling of this science those who have written seem to me to have made good portraitures of good, virtue, dntj, felicity ; but how to attain these excellent marks, they pass it over. For it is not the disputing that moral virtues are in the mind of man by habit and not by nature, or the distinguishing that generous spirits are won by doctrines and persuasions, and the vulgar sort by reward and punishment, and the like scattered glances and touches, that can excuse the absence of this part." " The reason of this omission I suppose to be that hidden rock whereupon both this and many other barks of laiowledge have been cast away ; which is, that men despised to be conversant in ordinary and common matters ; the judicious direction whereof nevertheless is the wisest doctrine (for life consisteth not in novelties or subtleties). . . For the nature of Good, positive, or simple, philosophers have set it down excellently, in describing the forms of virtue and duty. Again for the degrees and comparative nature of Good, they have also excellently handled it in the comparisons between a contemplative and an active life, in the distinction between virtue with reluctation and virtue secured, and the like. * De Augmentis Scientiariim, lib. vii. c. 1 .— Spedding, vol. i. p. 713, Translation; Spedding, vol. iii. p. 417. Abridged. 96 Locke 071 Moral Lazus of Nature. " Notwithstanding, if before tliey had come to the popular and received notions of virtue and vice, pleasure and pain, and the rest, they had stayed a little longer upon the enquiry concerning the roots of good and evil, and the strings of those roots, they had given, in my opinion, a great light to that which followed ; and specially if they had consulted with Nature they had made their doctrines less prolix and more profound." Locke distinguished laws of nature from his doctrine of innate -laws. " I would not here be mistaken, as if, because I deny an innate law, I thought there were none but positive laws. There is a great deal of difference between an innate law and a law of nature ; between something imprinted on our minds in their very original, and something that we being ignorant of may attain to the knowledge of, by the use and due application of our natural faculties. And I think they equally forsake the truth, who, running into contrary extremes, either affirm an imiate law, or deny that there is a law knowable by the light of nature, i. e. without the help of positive revelation." ^ The same great philosopher referred to " the Divine law, whereby (he observed) I mean that law which God has set to the actions of men, whether promul- gated to them by the light of nature, or the voice of * An Essay concerning Human Understanding, book i. c. 3. s. 13. Pkilosophers of Utility. 97 Revelation. That God has given a rnle whereby men should govern themselves, I think there is nobody so brutish as to deny. He has a right to do it, we are His creatures : He has goodness and wisdom to direct our actions to that which is best ; and He has power to enforce it by rewards and punishments of infinite weight and duration, in another life ; for no- body can take us out of His hands. This is the only true touch-stone of moral rectitude ; and by compar- ing them to this law it is, that men judge of the most considerable moral good or evil of their actions : that is, whether as duties or as sins, they are like to pro- cure them happiness or misery from the hands of the Almighty."-^ II. We now proceed to examine the works of philosophers whose theories are opposed to the exist- ence of natural rights, and of natural or revealed moral laws — those philosophers who base their moral systems on Utility or Happiness. This examination has two objects ; — 1, to find admissions in their works of the chief facts on which the theory of natural rights and natural laws rests ; and (2), to examine the principles of the system of Utility described in their works, and to compare them with the principles de- rived from nature by our induction ; or to show that in the constitution of their system the most important * Essay, book ii. c. 28, s. 8. H 98 Paley — admitted Nattiral Rights. motives of human action have been overlooked or undervalued. The chief facts above alluded to are — 1. The existence of natural rights. 2. The existence of natural moral laws equivalent with those of Revelation. Admissions, if found, of both these facts would clearly exclude any other than a natural basis for morality ; and an admission of either of them should produce the same result when we consider that natural rights and natural laws stand in such close relation to each other, that the admission of one necessarily implies the existence of the other, as correlative. Palet raised his system of philosophy on the theory of Utility ; but he admitted the existence of natural rights, such (he said) as would belong to a man, although there subsisted in the world no civil government whatever. " Natural rights (he continued) are a man's right to his life, limbs, and liberty ; his right to the produce of his personal labour ; to the use, in common with others, of air, light, and water. If a thousand different persons, from a thousand different corners of the world, were cast together upon a desert island, they would from the first, be every one entitled to these rights." "^ * The Principles of Moral and Political Philosophy, c. x. The Commandments he omitted. 99 This is an admission of natural rigMs as original human principles to the whole extent of their exist- ence claimed in this treatise — life, and limb, and liberty, as personal rights ; and the produce of labour as rights of property. But beyond the admission of natural rights there is no consideration of them ; they are not carried into the argument, which is wholly devoted to sustain the theory of Utility. A treatise which professed not to separate natural and revealed religion from each other, seems to require that the Commandments should be brought into the argument, if not for their authority for the purpose of showing that they are not opposed to the theory of Utility. But in the chapter on " The Scriptures " the Commandments are not mentioned, nor, although the I?Tew Testament is quoted, the confirmation of them by our Lord. Paley there explained that the Scriptures were unsuited for teaching morality, and therefore did not supersede the science of which he' professed to treat : but as he nevertheless made the Scriptures a source of his proof, he could not set aside the most important, clear, and direct of Scriptural authority, without at least showing that it did not affect his theory. Yirtue he defined to be " the doing good to man- kind, in obedience to the Will of God, and for the sake of everlasting happiness." "The methods (he I oo Natural and Revealed Religion. said) of coining to the Will of God are two (1), by His express declarations when they are to be had, and which must be sought for in Scripture ; and (2) by what we can discover of His designs and disposition of His works ; or, as we usually call it, the light of nature." But he pointed out the absurdity of sepa- rating natural and revealed religion from each other. "The object (he said) of both is the same — to discover the Will of God ; and provided we do but discover it, it matters nothing by what means." This second reference to Scripture for the express declarations of the Will of God, is not followed by any reference to the Commandments. As he did not refer to them as a body of Eevealed Moral Law, so he abstained (except indirectly) from reference to the law^s in detail when considering the special subjects of each law. His work does not contain a chapter on murder ; but in his chapter on duelling he mentions murder, and remarks simply, "murder is forbidden." In his chapter on adultery he says " Thou slialt not commit adultery, was an inter- dict delivered by God Himself." " Thou shalt not steal," does not appear in his work. His previous assertion of the natural right of every man to the produce of his labour — his property — is overlooked, and instead of it, we find that, the real foundation of our ri^ht is "the law of the land." "Thou Paleys Theory of Utility. loi shalt not bear false witness " is omitted from his chapters on oaths, even when perjury is under con- sideration. Having substituted " the law of the land " for nature, as the foundation of rights, and the founda- tion of law, he prepared the way for his theory of Utility; and the Commandments implying natural rights and laws derived from God, and therefore inconsistent with that hypothesis, were necessarily suppressed. Resuming his former postulate, that actions are to be estimated by their tendency to promote happiness, he declared the theory of Utility in its most naked form. " Whatever is expedient is right. It is the utility of any moral rule alone which constitutes the obligation of it ; " and that theory he illustrated by the following passage, which may be compared with the morality of Cicero : — "But to all this (he said) there seems a plain ob- jection, viz., that many actions are useful which no man in his senses will allow to be right. There are occasions in which the hand of the assassin would be very useful. The present possessor of some great estate employs his influence and fortune to annoy, corrupt, or oppress all about him. His estate would devolve, by his death, to a successor of an opposite character. It is useful, therefore, to dispatch such a one, as soon as possible, out of the way; as the I02 Bentham. neigliboiirhood would exchange thereby a pernicious tyrant for a wise and generous benefactor. It may be useful to rob a miser, and give the money to the poor; as the money, no doubt, would produce more happiness by being laid out in food and clothing for half-a-dozen distressed families, than by continuing locked up in a miser's chest. It may be useful to get possession of a place, a piece of preferment, or of a seat in parliament, by bribery or false-swearing ; as by means of them we may serve the public more effectually than in our private station. What then shall we say ? Must we admit these actions to be right, which would be to justify assassination, plun- der, and perjury ; or must we give up our principle, that the criterion of right is utility ? " It is not necessary to do either. The true answer is this, that these actions, after all, are not useful, and for that reason, and that alone, are not right." Bentham "^ had a theory of " Eights properly so- called," that they are the creatures of " Law properly so called," that is, not natural rights nor natural law, the supposed existence of which he denied with the utmost scorn. He further declares that " every law is an evil, for * Theory of Lopjislation. By Jeremy P>entliam. Translated from the French of Etienne Dumont by li. llildreth, 1864, Evil of Crime, General, not Individual. 103 every law is an infraction of liberty. Government has but the clioice of evils." If every law is an infraction of a riglit, the actions of murder, adultery, and theft, forbidden by the revealed moral law as declaratory of natural law, and prohibited by human government, are " rights properly so called," and thus the rights of Utility and the rights implied by the Commandments are the exact opposites of each other. The evil which government must consider before it makes laws infringing upon rights, is divided into many classes, but the two principal parts are (1), that which falls immediately upon individuals — which is called evil of the first order ; and (2) that which takes its origin in the first, and spreads through the entire community, or among an in- definite number of non-assignable individuals, which is called evil of the second order. " There are cases (it is said) in which if we confine ourselves to the effects of the first order, the good will be an incontestable preponderance over the evil. Were the offence con- sidered only under this point of view, it would not be easy to assign any good reasons to justify the rigour of the laws. Everything depends upon the evil of the second order ; it is this which gives to such actions the character of crime, and which makes punishment necessary. Let us take (he remarked) for example, I04 Empire of Pleasure and Pain. the physical desire of satisfying hunger. Let a beggar, pressed by hunger, steal from a rich man's house a loaf, which, perhaps, saves him from starving; can it be possible to compare the good which the thief acquires for himself, with the evil which the rich man suffers? The same is true of less striking examples. Let a man pillage the public treasury ; he enriches himself and impoverishes no- body. The wrong which he does to individuals is reduced to impalpable parts. It is not on account of the evil of the first order that it is necessary to erect these actions into offences, but on account of the evil of the second order." [N'atural law and natural rights are treated by Bentham with great disdain, as " fictions or meta- phors ; " but he has experienced the difficulty which he has not overcome of constructing a system of human society independently of nature. And so when he introduces his favourite fundamental theory, he begins, " Nature has placed man under the empire of 'pleasure and of pain. We owe to them all our ideas ; we refer to them all our judgments, and all the determinations of our life. He who pretends to withdraw himself from this subjection knows not what he says. His only object is to seek pleasure and shun pain, even at the very instant that he rejects the greatest pleasures, or embraces pains the An Admissioti of Power of Nature. 105 most acute. These eternal and irresistible sentiments ought to be the great study of the moralist and the legislator. The principle of utility subjects every thing to these two motives." To assert that pleasure and pain are the chief motives of human action, and to admit that they are " eternal " is to place their origin in nature, and through nature in God. But the question for the philosopher will still remain whether, admitting plea- sure and pain to be causes of human action, they are formal or ultimate causes, or only material causes carrying the ultimate causes into immediate action. In themselves, pleasure and pain are clearly effects, although they may be material causes in relation to actions which immediately result from them. But as material causes they cannot be the foundation of the moral system, which must be an ultimate cause "to which every thing may be referred but which itself can be referred to nothing." "^ Bentham ascribed to himself great merit for pre- paring, by great labour of analysis, a complete catalogue of the simple pleasures and pains. The simple pleasures he distributed into fifteen heads or categories ; the simple pains into eleven categories — one only of the former contains the pleasures of sense, one of the latter, the pains of sense. The remainder * Supra, p, 5. io6 Plcasmxs and Pahis of Sense. in both, categories are abstract qualities chiefly of a mental nature, and as such they are not entitled to consideration in philosophical reasoning- until they are resolved into their concrete elements ; and then one of these heads, which partakes of a physical nature — the pleasures of riches — would most as- suredly be resolved into the pleasures of sense. The " pleasures of sense " consist of those of taste, smell, sight, hearing, touch, health, and the pleasures of novelty. The " pains of sense," are those of hun- ger and thirst, taste, smell, touch, hearing, sight, excess of cold or heat, diseases, fatigue. Why hunger and thirst, in respect of their gratifi- cation, do not appear amongst the pleasures as well as amongst the pains of sense is not explained. But it is more incomprehensible why the sexual appetite is excluded from both categories, and is found only in a separate category of '^ pleasures ex- isting without having corresponding pains," where it appears as " the pleasures of love. The want of them (it is added) is not attended with positive pain, except when there is disappointment. Some tem- peraments may suffer from tliis want, but in general, continence is in the power of every one, and is very far from being a state of pain." These observations show that Bentham did not extend his analysis so far as to discover that the Austin. 107 appetites through their pleasures and pains, when referred to their original places in nature, are natural forces fertile of crime unless supplied according to their natural exigencies; and that in the profuse power which they possess and which they exercise over human beings, is placed the perpetuation of the human system, as the sources of life, and of the sustentation of life. A human mechanician invests his machine with power more than sufficient for its ordinary action, in order to ensure continuance of action when obstacles present themselves or resist- ance increases ; and we may reverently suppose that the great Creator had a similar purpose in so con- stituting the appetites as the motive forces of the human system that they should not cease to act for the accomplishment of His design from insufficient power. Austin.^ — The want of coincidence in original principles is very remarkable amongst the philoso- phers of Utility. Austin, an ardent supporter of the theory, admitted the authority of revealed laws as express commands, admitting also the existence of unrevealed laws, " the only laws set to that portion of mankind excluded from the light of Revelation; whilst both revealed law and law derived from the light of nature are binding upon us (who have access * The Province of Jurisprudence Determined. By John Austin. io8 Ansfms Theory of Nahtral and to the truths of Revelation) in so far as the revealed law has left our duties undetermined." This representation of the distribution of revealed lav7 and unrevealed law divides the human race into two portions, of which one is under both revealed law and unrevealed law, and the other is under un- revealed law alone. Further, that portion excluded from the light of Revelation cannot by the light of nature obtain knowledge of revealed law; for some duties we could not know without the help of Reve- lation, and these the revealed law has stated distinctly and precisely ; " and further " because unrevealed laws are the only laws which God has set to that por- tion of mankind who are excluded from the light of Revelation." Against the last dictum Aristotle may be produced as an illustrious example that the portion of man- kind excluded from Revelation, obtained without the help of Revelation knowledge of law identical with revealed law, and knew its duties by the light of nature. But neither Aristotle nor Cicero dis- covered by the light of nature the favourite doc- trine of Utility, and thus propounded also by Austin, thab theft is harmless or even useful when con- sidered by itself; " for example, if a poor man steal a handful from the heap of his rich neighbour, the act, considered by itself, is harmless or positively Revealed L a zv. — Mill. 1 09 good; and one man's poverty is assuaged with the superfluous wealth of another ; and it is only because if thefts were general they would be injurious to the security of property, would bring the rich to poverty, and what were a greater evil, would aggravate the poverty of the poor, that theft is evil." Mill — Mr. John Stuart. This eminent philoso- pher is the latest writer on Utilitarianism. His work with that title ^ was professedly written to correct mistakes that had arisen concerning the nature and principles of that philosophy. He does not, in his work, recognise either natural rights or natural moral laws; nor does he express the views of the previous philosophers of the positive good, or even of the harmlessness, of theft. He opposes his own system, which he says may be termed the inductive school of ethics, to that system of morality which he calls the intuitive school — dis- carding the opinion of the latter school that the principles of morals are evident a i^riori, requiring nothing to command assent excei)ting that the meaning of the terms be understood ; and holding, as the opinion of his school, that right and wrong, as well as truth and falsehood, are questions of observation and experience. "Both schools (he observes) recognise also, to a * Utilitarianism. By John Stuart Mill. 1861. I lo Creed of Utility great extent, the same moral laws ; but differ as to their evidence, and the source from which they derive their authority." That admission narrows the ques- tion of the orig-in of the moral laws to the issue raised in the present treatise, whether they proceed from God, through nature and revelation, or whether they were produced by the "observation and expe- rience " of men. The limitation of the coincidence between the two schools, to the " same moral laws," impliedly denies the deduction that the moral laws are complete and exhaustive; and it also leads to the inference that besides the moral laws there are, according to the philosophy of Utility, other laws morally binding upon mankind which have proceeded from " observation and experience." If that be so the following is the formula given by Mr. Mill for ascertaining moral actions a,nd constructing moral law. " The creed which accepts as the foundation of morals. Utility or the Greatest Happiness Principle, holds that actions are right in proportion as they tend to promote happiness, wrong as they tend to produce the reverse of happiness. By happiness is intended pleasure and the absence of pain ; by un- happiness, pain, and the privation of pleasure." Let us examine the creed by Cicero's rule of philosophising. If happiness be the ultimate end of reduced to Natu7^e. 1 1 1 human action, or the end for the sake of which and by which human action is called forth, human action must bear the test of being referable to nothing else ; that is, to no other or deeper principle than happi- ness. Love between the sexes is the efficient cause of human actions that produce happiness of greater extent, variety, and intensity, than any other motive principle — actions arising out of the conjugal, the parental, and the filial relations — yet happiness is not the ultimate end of actions proceeding from love between the sexes beyond which they can be referred to nothing, for their primary purpose is the procreation and perpetuation of the human race. The desire and necessity for food produce a very large proportion of the aggregate of human actions ; but happiness is not the ultimate end of actions originating in the appetite of hunger beyond which they can be referred to nothing; for there is the further and deeper princij^le that the appetite is the fundamental provision of nature for sustaining life ; and the actions of which it is the efficient cause are primarily accessory to that end. If we attempt to refer the appetites in which these actions originate to deeper principles, we pass beyond human causes, and necessarily arrive at the Great First Cause, the will of God. Thus these abstract qualities of Utility or Happiness 1 1 2 Utility tested by Nature. which, appear to be efficient causes of human action, give way when reduced to their concrete elements to physical principles of nature ; and with respect to the Greatest Happiness Principle — the greatest hap- piness of the greatest number — if carried so far as a principle of legislation as to divert from a minority their natural rights in order to favour a majority, it would be at variance with the equal ownership of such rights by nature. Utility may reasonably be required to produce by inductive reasoning from its own principles, a primary law which cannot be traced to an origin in nature ; and unless that be done it should bow to the Wisdom that gave the Commandments, natural and revealed, as all-comprehensive and universal Laws. Justice. 1 1 3 CHAPTER XI. Justice, its Elements and Criterion, and the human conception of Justice and Goodness, considered with reference to the Justice and Goodness of God. The nature of Justice has occupied mucli specula- tive thought from the time of Plato to our own day. Justinian defined it, — to give to every one his own ; and his interpretation has been chiefly followed by jurists. Justice is an abstract principle, having concrete elements. The concrete elements of justice are Rights. Rights may exist by nature, or they may be created by law. The rights which God established in man exist by nature; if human government confers rights, they exist by law. Rights by nature do not require confirmation by human law. Born with us, a mental conception of them soon grows up within us as our reason does ; and that being universal in mankind, a moral and instinctive conviction that it is wrong to invade the I 114 ^^^^ Equilibritmt of Rights. rights of others gi-ows up concurrently with a con- viction of the inviolability of our own rights, and has the force of natural law. Nature thus supplies the place of positive law; and the moral law, whether of nature or of Eevelation, which negatively forbids invasion of the natural rights, is the Criterion of Justice. The most perfect state of humanity is equal action of the natural rights. Unequal action is imperfection. Every act forbidden by the moral laws produces inequality of rights in two opposite modes ; by ex- ceeding rights, and by reducing them. To restore the natural equality is Justice, which is the Equili- brium of Rights. The forms of justice are the modes of restoring the equilibrium of rights. To do justice is to restore rights taken away, or where that cannot be done, to compensate for. the injury which the abstraction of them occasioned. To administer justice is to pro- duce the same effects by the judgment of an arbi- trator or of a court of law. Divine Justice is the Judgment of God for human wrong, and for dis- obedience of His moral laws. It has been said that " human morality, even in its highest elevation, is not identical with, nor adequate to measure the absolute morality of God." ^' That there is an Absolute Morality, based upon, or Human Morality identical with Divine. 1 1 5 rather identical with the Eternal [N'ature of God, is indeed a conviction forced upon ns by the same evi- dence as that on which we believe that God exists at all. But wliat that Absolute Morality is, we are as un- able to fix in auy human conception, as we are to define the other attributes of the same Divine Nature. To human conception it seems impossible that Absolute Morality should be manifested in the form of a law of obligation ; for such a law implies relation and subjection to the authority of a lawgiver. And, as all human morality is manifested in this form, the conclusion seems unavoidable, that human morality, even in its highest elevation, is not identical with, nor adequate to measure, the Absolute Morality of God.'"^ I. Human morality is embodied in laws which have relation to natural rights, the preservation of which from invasion is the end of the laws, and the attain- ment of the end is a state of justice. Those laws protect the natural rights by forbidding murder, adultery, theft, and perjury. God gave these laws to man as His laws in two ways — through nature and through Eevelation ; and, by His intervention, man, as constituting human government, promulgates the same laws throughout human society. The Divine and the human laws * The Limits of Religious Thought examined. By Henry Longuevill» Mansel, B.D., ed. 4, p. 135. 1 1 6 Human Morality identical with Divine. having the same origin and the same purpose their morality must be identical. If the laws proceed from God, the abstract principle of the laws must have been designed by Him. In its concrete form it is, " Thou shalt not steal ; " in an abstract form it is the inviolability of rights and pro- perty, and the unlawfulness of invading them. It is as impossible to conceive the ethical principle of these laws not to be axiomatic in the government of God, as it is to conceive that with Him " the whole is not greater than its part." It does not interfere with Divine and human coin- cidence ill the ethical principle of the Moral Laws that murder, adultery, and theft have relation to human conditions, which may not exist beyond this world. The principle is a]Dplicable to all God's worlds in which He has placed creatures, and en- dowed them with rights common to all. The Divine government of this world is founded on that ethical principle, and we have no difficulty in imagining it to be a universal and eternal principle. II. But it is said human morality is not adequate to measure the Absolute Morality of God. In pro- pounding the theory of Absolute Morality an objection to it is raised which is not removed, that " to human conception it seems impossible that absolute morality should be manifested in the form of a law of obliga- The ''Absolute Morality of God!' 117 tion ; for such a law implies relation and subjection to the authority of a law-giver." It might have been added that besides a superior it implies equals ; and either of these implications is fatal to the theory. For, it may be asked, what is meant by the absolute morality of God? Is He under any law? Has He equals with whom to contend, and who have rights that are equal to, and which may conflict with His? Is He under the influence of desires that may tempt Him to depart from the course marked out as right by His Wisdom and Goodness ? The human moral relation is not between God and man, but between man and man, God being the arbiter and the final judge of their actions, and the awarder of reward and punishment. The ab- solute morality of God is, therefore, non-existent ; and the predication of morality to Him, although doubtless intended to elevate our conception of the sublimity of His justice, reduces Him to the level of His creatures. It has been inferred that if " the absolute morality of God" transcends human morality even "in its highest elevation," man has no assurance that the moral laws and moral principles by which he strives to regulate his life are those by which God measures his conduct, or by which He will fijiaUy judge him. But although the relation of man to God be a 1 1 8 Divine Justice. relation of obedience and not a moral relation, it must necessarily be that, by the moral laws and moral principles given and declared by Him, through nature and Revelation for the government of man, men will be judged, for the laws and moral principles are adapted to man's nature and to his human con- dition. We have analysed moral crime, and have seen its small variety, its negative form — consisting almost exclusively of concrete acts on concrete substances — the most heinous crimes being acts committed upon the human body, and even contemplated crimes not carried into acts must be defined by the same elements. The conscience of man tells him for what crimes and by what laws he will be judged, unless he is forgiven. The justice of God in relation to man, as applying to the same elements, must, therefore, be of the same nature as human justice, although God's administra- tion of it, in regard to its perfection, will be as much above human justice as His Omniscience, and infinite wisdom and goodness excel the same finite qualities in human judges. But although we feel assured that God will judge His human creatures by the morality He has given to them, we cannot infer that His acts, as they appear to us in the phenomena of His Providence, can always be explained by, or brought to the test of, human morality.. But we are not, therefore, driven Phenomena of God's Providence. 1 1 9 to infer that there is an Absolute Morality incon- ceivable by men, for there are other attributes of God by which such phenomena may be explained, and to which they may be referred — His Infinite Wisdom and Goodness. The following passage, which has lately attracted considerable attention,^ seems to insist that such phenomena are incomprehensible unless upon the theory of Absolute Morality. " It is a fact which experience forces upon us, and which it is useless, were it possible, to disguise, that the representation of God after the model of the highest human morality which we are capable of conceiving, is not sufficient to account for all the phenomena exhibited by the course of His natural Providence. The infliction of physical suffering, the permission of moral evil, the adversity of the good, the prosperity of the wicked, the crimes of the guilty involving the misery of the innocent, the tardy appearance and partial distribution of moral and religious knowledge in the world — these are facts which no doubt are reconcilable, we know not how, with the Infinite Goodness of God, but which cer- tainly are not to be explained on the supposition that its sole and sufficient type is to be found in the finite goodness of man." t * See Mill's Examination of Sir W. Hamilton's Philosophy, p. 100. t Limits of Keligious Thought, preface to the fourth edition, p. 13. 1 20 God's Providence relates to the Universe. The highest human morality which we are capable of conceiving is concentrated in justice, the obser- vance of rights. The phenomena exhibited by the course of God's natural Providence cannot be brought to the test of human morality, for the contraries of these phenomena are not rights in mankind. If we refer the phenomena to the test of the ethical obligations and duties, we have the same result, for those duties are not correlatives of rights, nor are they of fixed obligation. To account for the pheno- mena as proceeding from God's natural Providence, it is necessary to take a wider field of view than is afforded by human morality. We must consider the phenomena, not simply in relation to this world and its inhabitants, but as involved in God's govern- ment of the Universe. The whole inquiry, therefore, is resolved into the question, how the phenomena exhibited by the course of God's natural Providence are reconcilable with the Infinite Goodness of God. It is admitted to be reconcilable, but we know not how ; and that con- cession makes it not presumptuous in any earnest and devout inquirer to offer his mite of thought to- wards an explanation of it. The asserter of a difficulty admitted to be soluble, but not solved, may not exclude the solution of it by the use of a particular hypothesis ; and I shall, Goodness, hifinite and Finite. 121 therefore, take tlie liberty of considering the ex- cluded hypothesis, " that the infinite goodness of God is not to be explained on the supposition that its sole and sufficient type is to be found in the finite goodness of man." That the finite goodness of man is the primary type of goodness is a proposition that may be dis- missed at once as irreverent and unphilosophical ; but it is not unimportant to consider the reverse of the proposition, whether the primary and infinite good- ness of God be not the type of the finite goodness of man. For unless man be endowed with goodness by the act of his Creator, how did he acquire it ? He did not derive it with his animal nature from brutes for they do not possess it ; and it being conceded that man possesses finite goodness, there can be no other source of his finite goodness than the Creator, who, as the possessor of infinite goodness, must have conferred on man goodness of which the type, in kind but not in degree, is Divine goodness; for if it is different in kind as well as in degree from Divine goodness, there being no other source of goodness, it is not goodness at all. The goodness of man must, like his moral duties, be employed upon subjects associated with his own nature and social condition, and it must take its forms and colour from them. That goodness is a I 2 2 Finite Goodness in Ma7is Nature. part of the constitution of man's nature, and that it has its duties in the social system, have before been shown."^ And although some take pleasure in denying their nature, and in deducing goodness as well as morals from self-love or self-interest — which is a denial of goodness, and a declaration that its duties are wrong, unless selfishness be right — the voice of nature and experience seem plainly to oppose the selfish theory. " The epithets, sociable, good-natured, humane, merciful, grateful, friendly, generous, bene- ficent, or their equivalents, are known in all lan- guages, and universally express the highest merit which human nature is capable of attaining." f These not being part of the animal nature — for brutes do not possess them — it does not appear how man acquired them unless they were implanted in his nature by his Creator. But although these qualities can only be exhibited by human beings in human forms, they may be re- solved into principles more universal. Experience shows that they have a range of power from parental and filial love to the j)hilantliropy which extends its benevolence to the whole human race. They may be applicable to creatures endowed with reason, in other worlds, under whatever form of existence ; and if we contemplate their relation to * Supra, ch. iii. t Hume's Essays, vol. ii. God's Goodness Universal. 123 God, their tendency is not to lower, but to elevate our concej)tion of His goodness. The Goodness of God has a range of action equal to His Universe, and equal to His Omnipotence. He sustains His worlds by physical laws, and He guides and restrains His human creatures by moral laws adaj>ted to the organisation of their bodies, to the purposes of their mundane existence, and to the degree of reason with which He has endowed them. The action of mankind is, therefore, subject not only to the moral laws but subordinate to the general physical laws of nature. " The infliction of physical suffering," is a phrase which suggests suffering from the effect of physical laws, and suffering from the organisation of the human body and its mundane condition. The physical forces of nature in their action often produce physical suffering in man, when he encounters them by ac- cident, in places or in circumstances where he can- not protect himself from the natural consequences of collision with them ; or when, as he often does, he wilfully and daringly exposes himself to them. But experience has given to man a certain and assured knowledge by which he is forewarned that if he encounters or exposes himself to the great physical forces of nature, he must, when their action is ex- tended to a sufficient degree, suffer in the unequal 1 24 Existence of Physical Suffering. contest. If he contends with them they are sure on some occasions to prevail over his strength, and alike over his knowledge as over his ignorance of their power and physical action. If he fall from a precipice the law of gravitation which preserves the worlds in their orbits, is not suspended for his benefit. If he descends into a mine and encounters there the gases evolved by natural laws, or set free by his mineral operations, their chemical affinities are not suj^pressed in his favour ; and he especially invites his fate if, in the confidence of escape, he supplies the gaseous fluid with the flame which, if it does not always produce the fatal explosion, it is only because occasionally the contact is not complete. So if man encounters the sea,, or the winds, or the frozen lakes, or if he employs the steam whose ex- pansive power he has discovered and subdued to his wiU, the physical laws must still prevail when by his inattention or his ignorance, natural causes excite them to man's destruction. But we must remember that it is from the study and developement of the physical forces of nature that cultivated man derives his highest pleasure and his chief reward ; and what but the gift of God, from His inflnite goodness through the instrumentality of man, are the dis- coveries of science, which by subduing the physical forces to man's will have increased the dynamic power Disease and Sickness. 125 at his command by substitnting for tbe thews and sinews of men and animals the physical forces of nature ? Physical suffering from disease and wounds is incident to the body, as well from the inefficient care and oftentimes rashness with which it is exposed to injury, as because it is the natural instrument of decay and death. Sickness and disease arrive at all periods of age, for the duration of life is not uniform, and it appears uncertain to us, in the Divine plan. The chief elements of health are air, water, and food obtained through labour which furnishes bodily exer- cise ; and there are few by whom these simple elements are not attainable by ordinary exertion and foresight. Health is the greatest blessing and the greatest source of enjoyment conferred on man. A sound mind in a sound body is an axiom that describes a perfect state of human felicity. It does not depend on riches if there is sufficiency of wholesome food ; large numbers enjoy such health ; it may be said to be the normal condition of the young. Injury to health proceeds in a large degree from intemperance, which produces present disease and sows the seeds of diseases that reach posterity. But there is a strong recuperative power in nature. Wounds heal and diseases subside when the morbid causes or the vicious habits are subdued. 126 Mora I Pu rpose of Sickness. But sickness has a moral purpose in the human system. It cuts off man from his sins and directs his mind to the contemplation of his future destiny. It caUs forth the aid and sympathy of those who witness the sickness, and it exhibits the tenderness of woman in the unceasing care and most unselfish devotion of the wife and mother, and of others who from pure humanity undertake the severe duties of the nurse. Medical science directs the energies of affection and devotion by its skill and experience ; and lately means have been discovered of suspending the pains of the sick and wounded, and of performing the most painful operations on the body without suffering, or even consciousness of the progress of the operation. Chloroform and other anaesthetics are agents sup- plied by God, through nature ; and their power over the brain is a discovery of science through His aid or permission ; and these, assuredly, are striking exam- ples of the goodness of God in close analogy with human goodness — desire to relieve the sufferer from his pains. " The permission of moral evil," is a phrase that does not accurately express God's relation to moral evil. He does not permit it. He forbids it. He has not given to mankind, through nature and revela- tion, laws which they cannot obey. Neither is moral Permission of Moral Evil. 127 evil a necessary consequence of the constitution of human nature, nor of the moral law which is given to man. For if it were a necessary consequence it would be universal; and much moral evil as there is in the world, there is a large number, and even a large proportion, of men and women who never rob their fellow-creatures of their natural rights, by murder, adultery, theft, or falsewitness ; but, on the contrary, are constantly engaged in actions of benevolence. The failures of men in the duties of benevolence, or their individual sins, we do not speak of, for they are not moral evil. " The adversity of the good and the prosperity of the wicked," are expressions not intended to represent the positive condition of the good and wicked, but the results of observation that worldly j^rosperity or adversity is not awarded to men according to the estimate of their character formed by other men. But such estimate is often founded on fallacious appearances, and it seems to be a clear lesson from human life in all its varieties of action that as a man sows he shall reap; and, therefore, the ad- versity of the good or the prosperity of the wicked is not determined in this life by their merits or demerits. But suppose it had been designed that the good should be always prosperous and the wicked always in adversity, how could human government 128 The Good and the Wicked. perform its duties, having two classes of men marked out by Providence as the good and the wicked? The good might be amiable, but the wicked would be the reverse, and no sentiments of love or charity could subdue the contests which would arise between them. We may more surely perceive that the Creator has had regard to the happiness of His creatures by reserving the distinction of "good" and "wicked" to His own determination, when the final account has been made up ; and by ordain mg that in the meantime the wicked and the good shall share pros- perity or adversity in worldly affairs according to their skill and knowledge, and their industry and prudence ; even although the wicked man may, for a time, mingle with those industrial qualities acts of moral evil. But these, if continued, soon commence retributory action. They produce suspicion of im- morality, which, as it increases, tarnishes the cha- racter, and diminishes the means of prosperity by separating the suspected rogue from honest men ; until at length exposure occurs, and involves him in utter ruin. But this final issue of dishonesty may be deferred ; for God gives opportunity of repentance and restitution, and it may be that He often reserves the sinner for His own judgment. The physical effect of moral evil — " the crimes of the guilty involving the misery of the innocent," is a Morality and Religion. 129 necessary effect of crime, which, generally consists in the abstraction of the life, property, or rights of an innocent person. Bnfc the injury and the misery that are results of crime appeal to the good feelings of an intending criminal not to involve those near and dear to him in the ruin which his crimes, if detected, will bring upon him. The uncertainty of the incidence of crime, also, rouses the vigilance of society to prevent and punish crime, and further to teach men the eternal laws which God requires them to obey. " The tardy appearance and partial distribution of moral and religious knowledge in the world," are subjects beyond the scope of man's insight. The only inquiry open to him, and it is one of deep significance and importance, is in what degree Morality and Religion, associated together in the Ten Commandments as they are in nature by an indissoluble bond, ' may have been retarded in their progress by the actions of men. These pages dis- close the inconsistency of the system of morality long taught in our colleges and schools with the system or with the authority of the second table of the Com- mandments ; and with regard to Religion, scholastic creeds and formularies, productions of men, have long divided Christians into sects, amongst which there are some that reject such creeds and formularies as K 130 The Conclusion. departures from the first fiindamental principle and from the First Law of the Ten Commandments. This humble attempt " to justify the ways of God to man," is but a human view of the phenomena of His Providence, derived from, and limited and con- fined to, such facts as nature discloses to the per- ception of man, to such ideas of goodness as are exhibited by his fellow-creatures, and to the prin- ciples of the moral laws. The suj)er-human relations of these phenomena are hidden from his sight, and are beyond his horizon. But what we are permitted to see and comprehend, suffices to show that if we could behold and contemplate the whole purpose and design of God's Providence, they would manifest His Infinite Wisdom, Goodness, and Justice. 131 POSTSCEIPT. I WISH to connect this little volume with its prede- cessor mentioned in the title-page, and below, ^ for they are both products of the same train of thought, and successive developments of it at different periods. The present work, as the latest, is the most advanced, and for that reason it stands first in the order of perusal. It is in advance of its predecessor by the adoption of Natural Rights as the foundation of the moral and social system, whereas in the first essay natural rights appear as results not as causes, and the Commandments as coincidences with Laws of Nature deduced from a more extensive induction of the facts of nature than was thought necessary where natural rights being postulated, natural laws protective of them are consequents of the rights. In the previous, as in this book, the moral laws deduced fi:*om the in- duction were compared with the laws of human * Laws of Nature, the Foundation of Morals. By David Rowland, Author of a Manual of the English Constitution. London : John Murray, Albemarle Street, 1863. 132 Postscript. government, and shown to be identical ; but not in a form so systematic or so comprehensive as in the present volume, where the origin of the laws and the application of them to morality and to human govern- ment are presented under one view. The other subjects of the previous book are those which must come under consideration in any attempt to construct a moral and ethical system. The present book is employed in developing the animal nature^ and tracing the rise of human society, and the origin and working of the moral laws ; the ethical duties of the mental nature being only slightly treated for the purpose of marking the distinctions between the several classes of duties which pertain to mankind. In the previous book the general subject is divided into two parts, the animal nature and the mental nature. In the first part, besides the subject common to both books but differently treated in each, moral evil is analysed and traced, in its several forms, to its sources in the animal nature ; and the passions, and the mode and the extent of their action in re- lation to moral evil are considered. In the second part the nature and office of reason in relation to morality is examined, with the view of proving that moral evil springs wholly from the animal nature ; and that from the mental nature, and from affections and feelings implanted there, arise the virtues of the Postscript. 133 human character ; and it has been there attempted to show the mode of action of the affections and the nature and extent of the obligation of the ethical duties which spring from them, and of the sanctions by which those duties are enforced. I have also in the previous volume offered a theory to explain the action of Conscience, and I have suggested other theories on the same principle to explain the varieties of the phenomena of the con- science, which have been considered as difficulties insurmountable against an uniform theory. The existence of natural rights has not disturbed the theory, but has on the contrary strengthened it, by the basis which they afford to the moral laws, as automatic consequents of natural rights. I believe that there are great truths in these books, but errors there also must be. The merit may, per- haps, be awarded to them of having opened a new line of thought on moral law and morality, and of having reasoned it, to an extent which explains their phenomena, and traces them to a common and ultimate cause. The merit of such a work does not, in the judgment of philosophers, wholly de- pend on the success of the reasoning. " A system of philosophy is of the highest value only when it embraces both these requisitions — when it is both true and reasoned. But a system which is 1 34 Postscript. reasoned without being* true, is always of higher value than a system which is true without being reasoned. The latter kind of system is of no value ; because philosophy is the attainment of truth hy the vjay of reason. That is its definition.""^ These prin- ciples are applicable to the criticism as well as to the construction of a philosophical system, but they are especially applicable to Moral Philosophy, the sci- ence " which relates to man himself ; " which a distinguished philosopher, well practised in the study of the science, has pronounced to be " the most com- plex and most difficult subject of study on which the human mind can be engaged." f * Professor Ferrier in " The Institutes of Metaphysie," sections 4 and 5. t Mill's System of Logic. " On the Logic of the Moral Sciences," book vi., vol. ii.. p.' 2 12. LONDON PRINTED BY S T O T T I 8 W O O D K AND CO. NEW-, STREET SQUARE 3916YB %\ 0G-10-04 32)80 MS Princeton Theological Seminary Libraries 1 1012 01262 0078