HI # fottf* ot {fee ®**»Wwt jl . %4 PRINCETON, N. J. % BL 181 .B38 1877 Barry, Alfred, 1826-1910. What is natural theology? Shelf. BOYLE LECTURES, 1876. WHAT IS NATUEAL THEOLOGY? AX ATTEMPT TO ESTIMATE THE CUMULATIVE EVIDENCE OF MANY WITNESSES TO GOD,', ALFRED 'BARRY, D.D. PRINCIPAL OF KING'S COLLEGE, LONDON; CANON OF WORCESTER ; AND HONORARY CIIAPLATN TO THE QUEEN. LONDON: CHRISTIAN EVIDENCE COMMITTEE OF THE SOCIETY FOR PROMOTING CHRISTIAN KNOWLEDGE SOLD AT THE DEPOSITOEIES : 77, GEEAT QUEEN STREET, LINCOLN'S INN FIELDS ; 4, EOYAL EXCHANGE; 48, PICCADILLY; AND BY ALL BOOESELLEES. The Christian Evidence Committee of theS.P.C.K., while giving its general approval to this work of the Christian Evidence Series, does not hold itself responsible for every statement or every line of argument. The responsibility of each writer extends to his own work only. \ CONTENTS. LECTURE I. PAGE THE UNIVERSAL BELIEF IN GOD ..•••! LECTURE II. THE METHOD OF THE KNOWLEDGE OF GOD • • .41 LECTURE III. THE MANIFOLD CORD OF NATURAL THEOLOGY. . .74) LECTURE IV. THE THEOLOGY OF THE INTELLECT : CAUSATION . . 104 LECTURE V. THE THEOLOGY OF THE INTELLECT : THE EVIDENCE OF 141 DESIGN x ^ x LECTURE YT. THE THEOLOGY OF THE IMAGINATION .... 182 LECTURE YII. THE THEOLOGY OF THE CONSCIENCE .... 217 IV CONTENTS. -::tur3 viii. PAGE THE THEOLOGY CI THE AFFECTIONS ... SUMMARY Or THZ AKGUKEN1 PKIHCE1 a. ijk aU \f jul u a a v -*■ PREFACE. The Lectures here published were in substance delivered as the Boyle Lectures of 1876. But, on the one hand, they have been since con- siderably enlarged, and in part rewritten for publication, in order to obviate the limitations imposed by homiletical delivery on the develop- ment of various parts of the argument : and, on the other, they contain what has long in prin- ciple engaged my best thought and study. In considering (as a Boyle Lecturer is bound to do) the practical condition of the great con- troversy between Christianity and the various rival or antagonistic forms of thought, two con- siderations have forced themselves on my mind, which I have endeavoured to embody in the following pages. The first is that, while it is necessary to deal with special attacks or difficulties, our great strength lies in the exhibition in all its fulness Vlll PREFACE. been sufficiently applied in Natural Theology, it is perhaps because the tremendous issues of the inquiry after God make the mind impatient of anything' but immediate intuition, in any direc- tion in which it may chance first to move. Such impatience although theoretically indefensible, is yet sufficiently powerful in practice to need con- stant warning that it demands the impossible. The present series of Lectures attempts simply a sketch of the cumulative force of the various lines of Natural Theology. I trust hereafter to dwell on the relation of Revelation to Natural Theology as being " Supernatural not Preter- natural ; " and to attempt a similar sketch of the cumulative force of the positive Evidences of Christianity as such. Believing that the principles which I have endeavoured to set forth are true — while I am deeply sensible of the defects of their treatment and of the responsibility attaching to all witness for God — I trust that, by His blessing, they may suggest thoughts, not wholly unfruitful for the purpose for which these Lectures were instituted. A. B. King's College, London, August, 1877. LECTUEE I. THE UNIVERSAL BELIEF IN GOD. I.— THE CLAIM TOR THEOLOGY OF THE CHARACTER OF SCIENCE, NECESSARY FOR THE ULTIMATE INQUIRIES OF HUMAN THOUGHT. II. THE VARIOUS BRANCHED OF THE ARGUMENT. III.— THE UNIVERSAL BELIEF IN GOD, AS EXEMPLIFIED IN THE RELIGIONS OF THE WORLD. | (a) THE PROGRESS THROUGH POLYTHEISM AND DUALISM TO MONOTHEISM. - (b) THE SELF-CONDEMNATION OF BUDDHIST NIHILISM. IV.— THE UNIVERSAL BELIEF IN GOD EXEMPLIFIED IN LAN- GUAGE, AS AT ONCE INSTINCTIVE AND PERMANENT. V.— THE METHOD OF THE GROWTH OF THIS BELIEF IN GOD, SIMILAR TO THE GROWTH OF ALL LAWS OF THOUGHT, INTELLECTUAL AND MORAL. VI —THE TRUE SENSE OF THE PHRASE NATURAL RELIGION. "At the mouth of two witnesses, or at the mouth of three witnesses, shall the matter be established."— Deut. xix. 15. In all Science there are two kinds of work, corresponding to the capacities of two different kinds of workers. There is, on the one hand, B 8 THE UNIVERSAL BELIEF IN GOD. the work devoted absolutely and exhaustively to one especial branch of science ; with a view, first to a complete understanding of its theory, both in principle and in detail, and a complete prac- tical mastery of all its powers ; and next, if it may be, to some original research, which shall carry the banner of truth one stage onward in the path of conquest. There is, on the other hand, the work of combination and comparison of the various lines of science, so far as they have been already worked out, pausing thought- fully to consider how they bear upon each other, either for mutual correction or mutual illustration, and what light they throw on that great problem of Being, which, whatever be the complexity of its parts, is in essence one. These two kinds of work, though practically all but inseparable, are yet perfectly distinct. The history of all science proves, perhaps that there are epochs of alternate predominance of each — epochs (as they have been called) of expansion and of verifi- cation — certainly that there are individuals capable of doing good work in one, yet in- capable of active service, possibly even of appre- ciative judgment, in the other. Few, perhaps, are the minds, the leaders of each generation, in which the two powers are harmoniously com- bined. In that combination they reflect some- THE UNIVERSAL BELIEF IN GOD. 3 thing of the Divine Mind, which first made all all things, each in its place and order, and then beheld all that He had made, and contemplating it as a whole, pronounced it to be "very good." I. Now it is certainly as a part of true science, that a Boyle Lecturer is bound to regard theology. The founder of these lectures was, as we know, one of the original members in 1663 of the Royal Society of Literature and Science. He foresaw and rejoiced in the future advance of the science, both of nature and of man, in many directions. He knew, perhaps, the in- herent tendency in each branch of scientific thought to usurp regions beyond its rightful empire — "to bear no brother/' still more no superior, " negr its throne/' He desired that the old science of Theology — necessarily, if existent at all, the queen of sciences — should maintain its own proper ground, amidst all the growing claims, and the changeful aspects, of other forms of thought. Well he knew, as his own life shows, 1 at once by the knowledge of its 1 In his will, referring to the Koyal Society, he " yvishes them a happy success in their laudable attempts to dis- cover the true nature of the works of God," and prays " that they and all other searchers into physical truth may cordially refer their attainments to the glory of the great Author of Nature and to the comfort of mankind."— See B 2 4 THE UNIVERSAL BELIEF IN GOD. reality, and by the experience of its temporary loss, that religion is more than theology, that Christianity is not merely a science, but a life." But still, as in his own works, so in the lecture- ships which he founded, he maintained the per- petual vitality of theological science. 3 What he Birch's "Life of Eobert Boyle," prefixed to the quarto edition of his works (London, 1772). 2 There is a remarkable passage quoted by Maurice in Ins " First Boyle Lecture " from an autobiography of Boyle, under the name of Philaretus, which describes how on a visit to the Grande Chartreuse in his youth, " the devil, taking advantage of that deep raving melancholy befitting so sad a place, his humour, and the strange stories and pictures of Bruno, the father of the Order, suggested such strange and hideous thoughts, and such distracting doubts of some of the fundamentals of Chris- tianity . . • that nothing but the forbiddingness of self-de- spatch hindered his acting it." The dark hour passed ; " at last it pleased God, one day he had received the Sacra- ment, to restore unto him the withdrawn sense of His favour." But he adds he "derived from this anxiety the advantage of groundedness in religion," from being forced " to be seriously inquisitive of the very fundamentals of Christianity."— See Birch's " Life," p. 23. 3 Among his works we find in vol. iv. pp. 1 — 66, a con- sideration of "the Excellency of Theology as compared with Natural Philosophy, as objects of Man's Study;" in vol. v. pp. 158 — 255, a " Free Inquiry into the vulgarly- received Notion of Nature " (as a substitute for our recog- nition of God, or as an intervener between us and Him) ; and in vol. v. pp. 508 — 550, "The Christian Virtuoso, showing that by being addicted to Experimental Philo- sophy a man is rather assisted than indisposed to be a good THE UNIVERSAL BELIEF IX GOD. 5 called u Sermons/' have, by force of propriety, assumed the name and character of Lectures, till at times we almost doubt whether they have a right still to claim their place in Church. He had no idea of relegating Christianity to the realms of feeling and practice. To his mind this would be to do either too little or too much — too little, if Christianity be false — too much, far too much, if it be true. Surely, simply as a philosopher, he was right. Theology must aspire to the character of a science, if our recognition of God is to have any living power. By the twofold light of inte^udconsciousness and external observation, man discerns two worlds around him, to both of which in different degrees he belongs — the world material of things to which he is linked in body — the world spiritual of persons, in which he claims a place in virtue of his mind. In the knowledge of both he is not content, till crude in- stinct and practical familiarity have risen into science. But yet he cannot possibly rest on the science, however exact, of these two as separate. For he Christian," with " a Discourse on the distinction which represents certain things as above Season, but not con- trary to Reason.' 1 THE UNIVERSAL BELIEF IN GOD. knows that they are not separate, because prac- tically they act and react on each other. Neither can he refuse to recognise them as distinct; for they resist all efforts, however daring and ingenious, to make them actually one, whether by materializing spirit or by spiritualizing matter. Distinct they are, yet not separate, neither producing, yet each implying, the other. What can this mean ? The conception of some power — call it what you will, Nature, Fate, God — over both, creating, ruling, uniting both, is an absolute necessity of thought. Yet the moment you grasp it, you enter upon the sphere of theology ; earliest, no doubt, as modern philosophy declares, of human conceptions, in the " first thoughts " of simple intuition ; perhaps put aside, at least from exclu- sive sway, by the " second thoughts " of meta- physical idea and physical observation; but inevitably recurring, both in theory and in fact, in those "third thoughts" of mature reflection, which, according to an almost invariable law of knowledge, have to correct and enlarge by the aid of the second thoughts the simple intuition of the first. Take, indeed, what path you will, all science ends, as was long ago truly said, in mystery. Who can fathom the mystery of the ultimate THE UNIVERSAL BELIEF IN GOD. nature and origin of matter ? 4 Who can lay Lis finger with unerring certainty on the essential characteristics and the genesis of spirit ? Who, by searching, can so find out God, as to reduce the infinite within the com- prehension of the finite intelligence ? Yet in every line of thought, this necessary limitation of science does not prevent it from being, as far as it goes, true in theory and fruitful in result. It is again true, that as we ascend in the scale of being — from the science of inorganic nature to the science of organic life, the science of humanity, the science of God — at each step we find that science becomes in its results less definite and measurable, and yet more subtle, more profound, nearer the heart of our life. At every step, more truly is human science rightly described, as u the knowing " in part " that which/' in respect of full comprehension, "passeth knowledge.''' But yet not without a sense of a law, " setting all things one against another, " we observe that, as science thus becomes 4 See a remarkable passage on this subject in tbe Bishop of Carlisle's " Oxford and Cambridge Sermons," Sermon II. p. 47, and an interesting Appendix on some of the theories on the subject. He says truly that "it is possible to involve one elf in such a puzzle concerning the constitution of matter, as almost to be driven to take refuge in the eccentric supposition, that it does not exist at all." 8 THE UNIVERSAL BELIEF IN GOD. more complex, additional powers of ascertaining its first data are afforded to us. To the mere observation, which alone can operate in the physical sphere, is added, in the sphere of humanity, the witness of internal consciousness ; and the twofold witness of observation and con- sciousness, striving upwards to God, is met, as men have always believed, by some distinct reve- lation of His very self, and (as we Christians believe) by His manifestation in the Person of the Lord Jesus Christ. I follow, therefore, at once the principle on which these Lectures were founded, and the dictates of all sound reason, in claiming for theology the right to be treated as a science, as real as the science of nature and of man, al- though doubtless more difficult and mysterious than either ; and, moreover, as at once infinitely more important than either to the true life of the soul, and as imperiously demanded by the necessity of harmonizing both. I hold such a claim absolutely necessary to any permanent and universal reality of religion itself. In an individual life, religion may exist as simply an inspiring sentiment and a practical power ; even in the Church there may be times when inquiry into first principles seems to sleej). But for the race of man, and the whole life of humanity, a THE UNIVERSAL BELIEF IN GOD. power which shuns the test of reason, bidding men escape from thought into the cloudland of sentiment or the busy excitement of work, necessarily abdicates all claim to permanent su- premacy over man. II. Treating, therefore, Theology as a science, we may rightly discern in it that twofold division of intellectual labour, at which I have already glanced. It is possible, as many illustrious exam- ples in this very Lectureship have shown, to take up some one line of theology, and so to work it out, as to make such work a landmark m the history of thought. It is possible, on the other hand, without attempting this original work, to survey the various lines of evidential theo- logy, as worked out already, in order to form some conception of their relation to one another— to see whether they really converge to one com- mon point, and whether their testimonies have those marks, at once of independence and coinci- dence, which have made men acknowledge as an universal rule of testimony, that " in the mouth of two or three witnesses every word shall be estab- lished." It is to this latter branch of the work, that I propose, if God will, to devote the Lectures of this year. If it be, as probably it is, the humbler branch, yet perhaps it may be pleaded, that it suggests considerations, apt to be some- 10 THE UNIVERSAL BELIEF IN GOD. what neglected in days of excessive division of intellectual labour. Certainly it may be urged, that ; if its conclusion be in any way established, it is one which comes home with remarkable force to the minds of men in general ; and there- fore may be not unsuitable to a time in which speculation in theological subjects is diffused, in popular form, through the mass of educated and half-educated society. Now, in the work proposed for these Lectures by their founder/ there is a threefold division. First, the truth of religion in general — that is the recognition of a personal God, having com- munion with man — is to be maintained against Atheism, whether in veiled or unveiled forms. Next, the need of some definite revelation, and of a permanent creed based upon it, is to be maintained against those whom the founder calls " Theists/' but who are popularly and less accurately known as Deists. Lastly, the essen- tial and unique Truth of Christianity is to be maintained against the claims of other esta- blished religions of the world. Our opponents in the last two branches of the argument, are our 5 The founder's will directs that " eight sermons should 1)0 preached every year for proving the Christian religion againsl notorious infidels, to wit, Atheists, Theists, Pagans, Jews, and Mahommedans." THE UNIVERSAL BELIEF IN GOD. 11 allies in the first. It is to the first that I would confine your attention now. I would ask you to consider the convergent force of the various lines of what is called Natural Theology, as bear- ing upon the truth which Deists, Pagans, Jews, Mohammedans hold in common with Christians with various degrees of fervour and certainty. The truth so sublimely embodied in the words, iC Hear, O man, the Lord our God is One Lord," is no unfruitful faith. In proportion to the cer- tainty with which it is held, will the inference be drawn, " Thou shaft love the Lord thy God with all thy heart, and all thy mind, with all thy soul, and with all thy strength/'' Whatever other gulfs of division may sunder men from one another, there is none comparable to the fundamental opposition between the life where God is, and the life where He is not. III. Now in regard to this fundamental prin- ciple, I would ask you to note that the foundation of these Lectures, while it directs the preacher to aim at " proving the Christian religion/'' evidently imposes on him the task, not of establishing its truth de novo, but of defending it against " any objections and difficulties which may be started." In the true meaning of this direction, I trace the recognition of a great fact, ol which the reality, indeed, cannot be doubted, 12 THE UNIVERSAL BELIEF IN GOD. but the whole force may be, and often is overlooked — the fact that the belief in God is universally (if I may so express it) in possession of the ground of human thought. It is on the Atheist or Pantheist, rather than upon the Theist, that the onus j) rob an di rests. He must account for the existence of this belief, which is undoubtedly as instinctive and wide-spread, and as apparently ineradicable, as the recognition of the existence of right and wrong, or as the con- sciousness of the freedom of human will. He will, indeed, and on his own premisses he reason- ably may, deny the conclusiveness of the old axiom, that in man te nothing can be frustrate," — that to every belief there must correspond an objective reality, and to every spiritual craving a satisfaction. For that axiom implies in the universe the design, the wisdom, the goodness of a Personal God. 6 But (I repeat) he has the judgment of mankind against him. Either he must leave men at peace in possession of this universal and natural belief, or he must show cause for expelling it from the throne in the realm of thought, which it has occupied from the beginning. How comes it there ? It certainly is no answer to refer 6 See Hooker, book i. chap. xi. 4. See Aristotle de Coelo, u debs Kal i) (fivais ov$(v /xdriju itoiovgi. THE UNIVERSAL BELIEF IN GOD. 13 its existence to an "inveterate tendency to personification." For the question immediately follows, "Whence came that inveterate tend- ency ?" "An inveterate tendency " is another name for a natural law of thought. If the existence of such a law is not a prima facie argument of a corresponding truth, then all reasoning is at an end. I am, indeed, not unaware that the fact itself has been questioned. No man can deny the existence of various forms of religion, covering the whole area of humanity both in space and time ; but, just as in morality it is argued that the actual variations in the conceptions of what is right and what is wrong, discredit the belief in a power to recognise right and wrong in the abstract, so it is maintained in religion that the various forms of the idea of God are so many, so startling, so mutually antagonistic, that they may be held to destroy each other. I cannot think that, in either morality or religion, this view can possibly stand the light of investiga- tion and serious thought. Glance at the religions of the world, from the lowest Fetichism to the highest and purest Monotheism ; you find this one element common to all — the belief in a personal power, a mind and a will, governing the world of things and 14 THE UNIVERSAL BELIEF IN GOD. of men. Even if what we call the powers of nature be worshipped, the light, the heaven, the earth — the Ato? aWrjp, UafjL/jirjrcop re Tf), — they are invariably personified ; and be it ob- served that this personification rapidly passes through so many forms, that at last the concep- tion of personality alone remains, and the original connexion is lost. As man becomes conscious of the inherent superiority of spirit in himself to the grandest forces of material nature, the recognition of a Divine personality increases in its definiteness, although it may clothe itself in attributes belonging to imperfect humanity. 7 7 This is surely obvious enough in the interesting re- searches into " Compai-ative Mythology " made of late years. See, for example, Max Miiller's " Chips from a Ger- man Workshop," vol. ii. pp. 1 — 144 Thus the myths of ancient Greece are obviously traced to an origin in the per- sonification of Physical Powers and metaphorical descrip- tions of Physical Phenomena. But in their development there is an equally obvious admixture of a true human element. The legend of the labours of Hercules may have as its germ the mythical description of the passage of the sun through the signs of the zodiac. But who, reading it in the full beauty of its development, can fail to see that it has become a spiritual history of the heroic soul, conquer- ing nature, conquering self, and at last made perfect by death ? To resolve all this, and other noble legends, into '•sun-myths" seems almost an outrage on common sense. We might as well suppose the Zeus of Homer to bo merely the sky, because the epithet vfcpeKriyepera refers to an older THE UNIVERSAL BELIEF IN GOD. 15 As he comes to see that the supreme ruling 1 power is something greater than physical force and humanity, he speaks of it, it may be, under vaguer and more mysterious names. But every- where he personifies still. He may call it Nature, Law, a " Something not ourselves," but he speaks of it, he thinks of it, as an agent. According to the suggestive satire of the old Greek dramatist, he may dethrone Zeus, but the " vortex " of unknown law and force which he holds to be primeval, he turns, consciousty or unconsciously, into a personal God. 3 All the various corruptions of the religious idea fail utterly to destroy this fundamental element, this conception of a Personal Ruler. The faith, which the Epistle to the Hebrews describes, seems as instinctive as reason, con- science, affection themselves. 9 Man " endures personification of the Heaven. Personification lias passed into Personality. 8 Aristophanes, "The Clouds/' 1454, Aluos fiaviXevei 9 It is remarkable that the definitions of Faith given (in Heb. xi. 1), iXTU^ofxevoov inrotTTaais, TrpayfxaTcov eheyxos ov 8\€7rofxevctiv (which perhaps in modern language is best described as the " realization of the Invisible''), is in itself applicable to the action of all the human faculties in the discovery of Truth, whether speculative, moral, or aesthetic. It is the peculiarly human attribute, essentially distin- guishing us from the highest brute instinct, and lying on the threshold of all true science. It is only in v. 27 16 THE UNIVERSAL BELIEF IN GOD. as seeing-/'' though it may be through mists of doubt and distorting mirage of superstition, "Him who is invisible/'' The belief, moreover, that the Supreme Will, thus universally recog- nised, is glided by the wisdom and righteousness and love, which are the highest attributes of a spiritual nature, is equally universal, although it may be liable to greater obscuration and perver- sion. In the earlier and ruder stages of thought, that Will may be supposed to make the produc- tion of obedience and worship the one thing need- ful, and accordingly to hold prayer and. sacrifice higher than purity and truth, or to supersede by personal favour towards individuals the uni- versal dictates of righteousness. This idea be- longs to the stage of thought, immature but surely not unnatural, which, as in childhood, finds its only virtue in the submission to wisdom and power greater than our own. Occasionally, again, men may, in their sense of confusion and contradiction in the world, actually attribute to the Supreme Power (or at least to supernatural powers) the faults, the blindness, the partiality, of which they are conscious in themselves. But these defects where the action of faith is described as upwv, not rb &6pa.Toi>, but rbv aSparop, that the differentia of Faith in its reference to a Personal object is introduced. THE UNIVERSAL BELIEF IX GOD. 17 gradually clear up, especially as we advance to- wards Monotheism. The supreme personal will, in the creation of things, is recognised as acting by design ; and in the government of men is acknowledged as guided by moral principles. When once progress is made in this direction, there are no steps backward. The truer and grander conception destroys all others. How- ever imperfectly, the mind of man acknowledges a God, not only of power, but of wisdom and goodness. But yet, if even the belief in a Personal will be accepted, the passage to Monotheism — ex- plicit or implicit — seems but a question of time. (a) Polytheism — the belief in many gods — is but a brief halting-place in thought. Begotten of the sense of multiplicity of power, it vanishes before the discovery of a unity underlying it. Examine what system of polytheism you will, Greek, Latin, Teutonic, you always come to one God, — it may be a Primal God, from whom all others proceed ; it may be a Supreme God, to whom all others bow. The "gods many and lords many," so long as they are thought of as divine, are only superhuman created beings. The Christian, who believes that there are such beings, and who sees no reason why the teach- c 18 THE UNIVERSAL BELIEF IX GOD. ing of the Old Testament,, which attributes to them ministerial functions even in the physical sphere,, should be mere metaphor/ will not fail to see in the errors of a real polytheism a sub- stratum of distorted truth. But in that curious form of polytheism, to which the name of " Henotheism " or "■ Cathenotheism " has been given (itself probably a phase of transition towards the commoner forms), in which each deity is, in turn, represented as independent of the rest, as the only deity present to the mind of the worshipper at the time of his prayer (as in the religion of the Vedic poetry of India), 2 we see still more clearly that we have 1 I refer not to poetical passages, but to such passages as Exod. xii. 23'; 2 Sam. xxiv. 16; 2 Kings xix. 35. Bound the simple idea has been woven a strange fantastic fabric of speculation and legend. But the idea itself is surely not a priori improbable ; it is only the carrying out, in a higher degree, and in ways to us inconceivable, what Ave know of God's use of human agency in the realm of Nature ; it is, at least, not inconsistent with those appearances of conflict and isolated imperfections, overruled to a general purpose, which Science believes itself to trace in the physical sphere. 2 See Max Midler's " Chips from a German Workshop," vol. i. p. 27. In his Lecture on the Vedas the author shows that "Agui" (the fire), "Indra" (the day), " Va- runa" (the .sky), are alternately exalted as the Supreme Deity. " All the rest disappear for the moment . . . and He only stands in full light before the eyes of the wor- shipper." lie adds, "The consciousness that all the THE UNIVERSAL BELIEF IX GOD. 19 but ttoWwv ovofiarcov /J THE THEOLOGY OF THE CONSCIEXCE. principle, having no concrete reality. Since there is no tie between us and it, its nature may be wholly unlike our own. Hence, while the intellect discerns some creative power, that power may be a physical force, and not a living person ; or, if a person, still one as absolutely removed from us as the gods of Epicurus, too far off or too great to care whether we recognise and serve Him or not. But with the Conscience or Moral Sense it is not so. If it leads to the recognition of any object, that object must have necessary moral relations to us ; else Conscience has as little to do with it, as it could have to do with the supposed inhabitants of another planetary world. That object must be a Personal Object ; for to talk of the moral recognition of a Force or a For- mula of Regularity, is simply absurd. That object must have a moral nature ; for all moral obligations are reciprocal, and even to a Supreme Intelligence, if absolutely heartless, no duty on our side could attach. In the case, therefore, of the moral lines of Natural Theology, the very first conditions of our inquiry are different. With the Intellect the recognition of some Supreme Power is all but axiomatic; the one question is, What is its nature ? With the Conscience the one THE THEOLOGY OF THE CONSCIENCE. 225 question is whether it recognises the Supreme Power at all ; if it does, the nature of that Supreme Power follows as a thing of course. It is possible that our moral sense may regard only our own self and our fellow-men, knowing no- thing of the Supreme Power. But if this is not so, if Conscience bear any witness at all of the Supreme Power, that Power must have a personal being, a relation to us, and a moral nature. The point, therefore, which is ultimate in the investigations of the intellect, is the very starting-point in the testimony of the Conscience; and from that starting-point this testimony unfolds the idea of righteousness and goodness in God, which is but faintly indicated in the earlier investigations. (Jj) I may add, moreover, that it is this line of Natural Theology, which protests most forcibly against a lifelong scepticism, or a con- tented Agnosticism. So long" as the under- standing alone is concerned, these mental posi- tions may be defended, though it is hard to conceive how men can glory in them. But if the moral sense testifies of even the probability of any moral relations between us and God, then it is bound by its very nature to be impatient, till these relations are examined, known, and acted upon. It cannot treat it as an open 226 THE THEOLOGY OF THE CONSCIENCE. question, whether we have, or have not, a King*, a Father, a Saviour. The unlimited suspension of belief, to an intellectual student far from in- tolerable, becomes to the servant of duty, almost as distasteful as misdirection of belief itself. 2 III. The great question then is, Does the Conscience realty lead us to God ? To answer it, let us first ask, " What is the action or actions of Conscience itself?" This Conscience is a practical Reason. What are the principles which, as reason, it recognises ? What are its deductions which by reasoning it draws from them ? The text places the subject very clearly before us. There is (says St. Paul) the " work of the Law," that is, the substance of Moral Truth, 2 This is the point so gravely and frequently dwelt upon by Butler. The duty of examining and acting upon even imperfect evidence, and the fact that in some cases the performance of this duty under difficulties may be our chief moral probation, are urged by him in his "Analogy" (part ii. chap, vi.), in a chapter which has a peculiar force and interest, as apparently describing his own spiritual experience. Hence the paradox, referred to by Dr. New- man in his " Grammar of Assent," that where only two modes of alternative action are possible, the practical decision may be the same, whether on demonstrative or probable evidence, whether on a high or a low probability. The difference will lie in the amount of enthusiasm we can throw into our actioD, and the amount of sacrifice we are ready to make for it. THE THEOLOGY OP THE CONSCIENCE. 227 " written on the heart/''. First, " the Conscience bears witness to it/" that it exists ; next, in regard to special actions "the reasoning's of men (Xoyia/^ol) accuse or excuse one another," according as such actions agree or disagree with it. These two actions of Conscience in man are clearly distinct, though perhaps all but insepar- able. 3 Our older Moralists called them by different names. The recognition of moral prin- ciples they named the ^wnqprjai^ (or " Moral Sense"), and the application of those principles the Sweden? (or " Practical Conscience"). Call them by what names we will, we must be careful to distinguish them from each other. The former is of the nature of a " form of thought " in the moral sphere, existing in capacity in the mind, but worked out into actual energy, and by the very process defined, through practical experience. It stands to the deductions from it, as an axiom to the propositions of Geometry, or (perhaps 3 See, for example, Sanderson, " De Obligatione Con- scientige" (Prselectio I. 12), a book too little known and studied; for, although too scholastic in form for modern tastes, it is marked by singular accuracy and vigour. So Jeremy Taylor, " Ductor Dubitantium " (book i. chap. i. sect. 24), "The ffvvrrjprjais, or the first act of Conscience St. Hierome calls scintillam conscientice, the spark or fire put into the heart of man. The } and " inhuman 3> — is branded (that is) as a disobedience to a Law of Humanity as profoundly natural as the right of freedom and the sense of duty themselves. But the same connexion is shown in a different way in that other great class of ties, which we form for ourselves, and yet having formed, cannot at our mere will break. The tie of friendship, sometimes closer than brotherhood ; the tie of voluntary association, social, political, religious ; the tie, above all, of love, consecrated in marriage, voluntary in its origin, yet superseding all national ties — these also imply a true likeness of nature (not perhaps usually the simple likeness of unison, but the subtler likeness of harmony) shown by the pursuit of common objects, the belief in common truths, the love of common principles. Love, therefore, implies not only necessary re- lations to one another in actual life, but a certain unity of Nature. In this witness it undoubtedly goes far beyond the sense of duty. For duty may exist without sympathy. It involves a sense rather of likeness than unity of nature. Love not only bears witness to this unity, but makes such witness a primary, even an absorb- THE THEOLOGY OF THE AFFECTIONS. 283 ing, idea. Duty, iirst recognises our own individuality, and our own freedom, rights, and powers ; and then proceeds to ask, " What ought I to do with them ? What do I owe to others ? " Thus the sense of Righteousness and Truth is the guard of man's proper individuality, in his rela- tions to his fellow-men. On the other hand, the natural impulse of Love is to forget, to sink and (in the true sense of the word) to " deny " self. 3 It asks, not " What ought I to do, or what must I do?" but "What may I do for others ? " In proportion as any consciousness of self is present to the soul, even in craving return of affection, Shakespeare has shown us in his "King Lear/' how the bloom of love is faded, and its glow is chilled. Love, therefore, is the witness of unity against excessive indi- viduality. It is not a little instructive that Plato's celebrated definition of Righteousness is the ra eavrov Trpdrren/ — the doing by each man of the part which he sees to be his own, in the confidence that all others will do the like 5 It is singularly unfortunate that the word " self- denial, which our Lord makes the test of discipleship (Matt. xvi. 24), should have been, in common parlance, lowered from the idea of self-sacrifice to the idea of mere self-discipline and self-control. Like all errors of phrase, it has avenged itself by bringing in error of idea as to the leading principle of Christian life. 234 THE THEOLOGY OF THE AFFECTIONS. towards him ; 6 St. Paul's definition of Love is that it ov fyrel ra eavrfjs — " seeks not her own things/' and " looks "(as it is elsewhere ex- pressed) in every man "upon the things of others." Righteousness bids te each man bear his own burden;" Love adds, "Bear ye one another's burdens/' for another's burden is really your own. 7 The temptation of the merely righteous man is to hard self-concentration ; the temptation of Love is to an officiousness in doing good, which may even sap responsibility and sacrifice the true individuality of the person loved. We talk of the ties of Duty and the ties of Love. But they are of a different kind. Duty is as a golden cincture, keeping many separate units in mutual contact, and so in mutual action. The ties of Love are like the net-work of a living organism, by which one single life throbs through many members. This witness to unity is the true signifi- cance of the great principle of Love in man. It is well called " the bond of perfectness." No Society can well live without it, If a family is merely kept together by the tie of common interest, or even of mutual duty, its common 6 See Plat. Pep. iv. p. 433 : — rh ra avrov TrpaTTeiv Kal jxtj xoXvirpo.yiJ.ove'iv hiKaioavvt] iffri. 7 See 1 Cor. xiii. 5; Phil. ii. 4; Gal. vi. 2. 5. THE THEOLOGY OF THE AFFECTIONS. 285 life wants warmth and beauty, and eventually is likely to be broken up under any severe pressure. If a nation loses the glow of patriot- ism and the inspiration of loyalty, history tells us how its tone is coarsened and degraded, and the first seeds of its decay are sown. If our action towards human kind is guided only by the recognition of mutual advantage, which is the soul of Commerce, and the cold sense of duty between man and man, we know too well how little what we rightly call " humanity " can stand against selfishness and passion. A Power, which is so integral and essential a factor in the history of the world, must surely have a profound significance in all that concerns the highest life of man. IV. What is that significance, when in thought we pass, from the world of self and the world of Humanity, to the consideration of the Higher Power, which is above both ? To answer this question, we must follow in great degree the same line of thought, which was our guide in the consideration of the Moral Sense of Righteousness. We must dwell, first, on the origin, the scope, and the basis of the abstract principle of Love in itself; and, next, on the process of its education in its concrete forms. 2S6 THE THEOLOGY OF THE AFFECTIONS. (a.) What shall we say of its origin? The power to love is one of the highest attributes of man. In harmony with the sense of Right, and clothing the firm skeleton of Duty with living flesh and blood, it is perhaps the best means of softening, purifying, ennobling the moral nature of man. Its enthusiasm is often the surest safeguard against the debasing temptation of appetite, and the hardening influence of selfish- ness and pride. Even for the perfection of the individual nature, what can be an adequate substitute for the spirit of love ? But, besides this, we recognise the energy of love in its various forms as probably the deepest and strongest of all the influences, which actually rule the world as a whole. We observe that the whole network of physical relationship and of social polity subserves it, and is held to fail in its object, unless it supplies an organization through which the currents of love may flow. Love, therefore, is a high spiritual law in the individual nature and in the society of human- kind. Whence came it ? The Supreme Creative Power must be the source of it, as of every power in the world. Of it, therefore, as of Conscience, we ask, " Is it possible for us to imagine this high spiritual capacity of love developed out of physical force or mere animal THE THEOLOGY OF THE AFFECTIONS. 287 life ?" Both these powers are, no doubt, pressed into its service; both may supply its lower elements ; both may at times, like other servants, rebel against their true master, and either over- bear his right authority by brute force, or travestie themselves under his likeness. But the power of love is itself a spiritual and moral power. The mind revolts against the idea of tracing it to a physical parentage, as monstrous and in- credible in theory, as destitute of all evidence in practice. Yet, if this be so, what must the Supreme Power be ? The answer must be the answer of the text, " God is Love f and the human love in all its varieties is but the shadow of the Divine. Yet in that answer is not the whole of a true Theology involved ? If we once give it, then we know God as a true Divine Person— as perfect in the two great Moral Attributes of Righteousness and Love — as im- planting those moral powers in -us, in order to impress on our nature the image of Himself. (6.) But let us pass from the source of Love in man to the scope of its exercise. What shall we say here ? We must say, as we said of the Conscience, that it cannot be satisfied, either in the little world within, or in the world of men ; and that as Love, like Du ty, is one of the highest faculties of our naturej it would be strange 288 THE THEOLOGY OF THE AFFECTIONS. indeed, if it had no scope in our relation to the Supreme Power. But we may (I think) urge both these considerations here with even greater force. Love, even less than Duty, can find full scope, if it ignore God. For, first, it is clear that far less than duty has it any reference to the little world within. The phrase, " the love of self," can hardly be under- stood in the strict literality, in which we can speak of duty to self, self-respect, and the like. To be absorbed in the thought of self — to gaze with passionate enthusiasm on our own beauty, physical or moral, to delight ourselves in our own intellect or character, to be devoted to our own self-culture and our own happiness — is rightly held to be akin rather to vice than to virtue. It is a madness and an inhumanity, in which (as the old fable of Narcissus teaches) the soul will pine by a moral atrophy and die. Love by its very nature looks without : if it be intro- spective, it is diseased. Then, again, if we look to the world of humanity, it is an acknowledged truth — to which both the individual consciousness of every full-grown life, and the collective verdict of human literature bear witness — that man's capacities of love are at once educated by human relationships, and unsatisfied by them. For Love THE THEOLOGY OF THE AFFECTIONS. 289 undoubtedly needs for its continued life, the con- viction of the beauty and goodness of the object on whom it rests, and of the existence of some reciprocity of love in him. Now, so far as it assumes the attitudes of superiority and equality, it may possibly find on earth the scope it needs, although even in these it is constantly baffled, wounded, and disappointed, by the proof of the defects, and by the experience of the ingratitude, of its objects. But it has its attitude of inferi- ority, on which such disappointment especially throws it back. Its deepest consciousness, by which, indeed, it is properly and naturally educated in the first instance, is that of loyalty and worship of a superior being. Can it here find full scope of exercise, in relation either to the individual or to the society of men ? Even less (I repeat) than duty. Personal affection has its idolatries ; but, with a shock affecting our whole moral being, it awakes to find that no human being is wise enough, good enough, loving enough, to deserve unqualified devotion of love ; and that even if such a being existed, yet the imperfect mutual knowledge of man and man, which never penetrates to the inmost depths of being, would prevent us from being able fully to recognise, and therefore adequately to love him. Men (I know), offer us, as a sub- u 290 THE THEOLOGY OF THE AFFECTIONS. stitute for the acknowledged imperfection of personal affection,, loyalty to a family, a sove- reign, a nation, or enthusiasm for humanity at large ; but all these equally fail. Here, as in the last Lecture, we must remark that the sum of finite affections will not make a true infinity. The spiritual defects, which forbid absolute devo- tion to each individual, are not obliterated, but intensified by aggregation; the unity between the individual and society is less perfect than between man and man, and, in consequence, the extension of the area of affection simply dilutes its power ; the devotion to the various societies to which man belongs — the family, the nation, and the race— are constantly liable to a conflict, in which it is hard, if not impossible, to decide between the intensity of the narrower, and the grandeur of the wider unity. But besides this we must add — what concerns Love in virtue of the law of needful reciprocity, — that the want of an adequate return of love from society itself is fatal to its claims on our allegiance. The igno- rance in society of its true benefactors is pro- verbial ; the capricious fickleness and perversion of popular gratitude have been felt by all who have, sought to serve their fellows; tardy re- pentance, paying to a man's senseless body or to his memory the tribute which it denied to the THE THEOLOGY OF THE AFFECTIONS. 291 living man, is the favourite theme of satire. Duty may stand up against this. But although some transcendental philosophers hold it essential to an enthusiasm for Humanity that it should equally endure, it is at least doubtful, whether in the absence of all reciprocity love can remain for ever, unless through men it looks to God, and for the sake of the Father loves His children. For all these reasons we urge that no enthu- siasm for humanity can have a right to " all the mind, and all the soul, and all the strength." There is much that we cannot render to the Csesar, whether of individual royalty, or of col- lective humanity. In every soul, which realizes its own individuality, there must be still a vast unoccupied residuum of the capacity of Love. Men in all ages, as all religions and many of the noblest philosophies show, have believed that it belonged of right to the Supreme Power, and that (as St. Augustine long ago expressed it) u God had made the heart for Himself, and therefore it was unsatisfied till it found Him." Have they been wrong ? They looked to the world of things, and traced on it the lines of foreordained usefulness and beauty, obscured indeed, but certainly not obliterated, by the mystery of evil. In their own action they u 2 292 THE THEOLOGY OF THE AFFECTIONS. knew that to produce these things for others, was the first instinct of Beneficence, and the highest delight of Love. Such action thev found to be one of the most effective ways of being fellow-workers with the Supreme Power, ruling the world. When they looked at the works of Nature, then of the lower creatures they believed, and of the race of men they knew, that all was ordered to minister to happiness ; they saw that, if only man's own sin could but be rooted out, this world would be even now a Paradise; they readily believed what Religion taught again and again, that all the blight which rests on it now is simply the poisonous miasma of sin. There went up from the souls of men, in- voluntarily and perpetually, a Hymn, not only of wonder and admiration, but of thanksgiving and praise. Surely it would need much to make us believe that it went up to the deaf ear of Physical Force or Impersonal Law. This un- ceasing homage of Love, even in regard to the world of Nature, is surely witness to a living God. But if this be questioned in relation to that world (chiefly by those who dwell on exceptional evil, till they allow it to obscure the normal good), what shall we say of the world of persons ? In this, as I have said, the soul has always felt itself at once stimulated and unsatisfied. Look- THE THEOLOGY OF THE AFFECTIONS. 293 ing through, all human relationship s, it fixes on Fatherhood as the one primeval and imperish- able relation of superiority, implying Wisdom, Power, Protecting Love. From the finite and imperfect fatherhood of the world, it ascends to " Our Father whicli is in Heaven," as a truer and more ultimate title of the Supreme Power, than even the Universal Creator, King, and Judge. There and there only it finds the rest which it needs, for the understanding in thought, for the conscience in allegiance, for the heart in love. 8 8 Hooker's treatment of the subject is singularly beau- tiful and profound. In the Ecc. Pol., Book I. chap. v. he argues that the perfection of man is his chief good ; that all things which conduce to it are secondarily good for us ; but that, since all perfection is but a shadow of the Divine perfection, " all are said to seek the highest, and to covet more or less the participation of God," which he explains to be likeness to God, in " continuance/' in " constancy and excellency of operation," in " the knowledge of Truth," and the "exercise of virtue," — that is, of energy. In chap. xi. he goes on to argue that we desire or love good things in proportion to their goodness. But " Nothing may be infinitely desired but that good which is indeed infinite. No good is infinite but God, therefore is He our felicity and bliss. Moreover, desire tendeth to union with that which it desireth. If, then, in Him we be blessed, it is by force of participation and conjunction with Him. Again, it is not the possession of any good thing that can make them happy that possess it, unless they enjoy the thing wherewith they are possessed. Then are we happy 294 THE THEOLOGY OF THE AEFECTIOHS. (c.) But let us next pass, as before, from the consideration of the origin and scope of Love, to consider the ground of its sacredness, through which it is different in kind from an appetite or passion, and has, like Conscience, an authority as well as a power. Here also, as before, we shall have to pass from the answer of the Intuitionist or Utilitarian to an answer which rests on God. With the one we shall hold that Love is a supreme law of our nature ; with the other that its working is a tendency essential to the supreme good of Humanity. But we shall add that we cannot understand such a law without a Personal Creator to write it on the heart, or such a tendency without a Moral Governor. In all this we have but mutatis mutandis to retrace the ground which we have already trodden in the previous lecture. V. But if we ask, " What is the true basis of Love/'' in the sense of asking, "What is its significance as to our nature and being?" — then we shall find out what is its peculiar func- tion in the witness to God. (a.) Its existence in the soul shows that the individual nature is not self-centred and self- thorefore, when wo fully enjoy God, as an object wherein the powers of our souls arc satisfied even with everlasting delight." THE THEOLOGY OP THE AFFECTIONS. 295 sufficing — that it must have some spiritual unity with another nature like its own. Hence,, first, the existence of love to man implies*what we call " a common humanity," in spite of all individual peculiarities, and all the local and national peculiarities, which outward circum- stances and past history have impressed on 'men. The intensity of love varies with the closeness of the unity between man and man, either by blood or by sympathy. We may love all men ; but to love all equally is unnatural and impos- sible. There are " kindred souls," whether by natural kinship or the kinship of harmony of character, in whom the common humanity is most vividly realized, and therefore love most vividly felt. "Whence comes that common humanity ? At first sight it may seem reasonable to reply that it comes from a common human parentage, developing its effects through that series of natural ties, of the power of which we have experience every day in hereditary pecu- liarities, in family likeness, in national character. But this common parentage, however true his- torically, does not account for the whole of the facts. For in each man there is also an individu- ality of character, in respect of which he is more or less than his parentage, and which, unsatisfied with natural bonds of unity, shows itself (as I 296 THE THEOLOGY OF THE AFFECTIONS. have said) as creative of a new unity, by the origination of that other series of voluntary ties, which co-exist with and at times supersede the other. In virtue of this, each soul is inde- pendent of human parentage, and is (so to speak) in direct connexion with the source of spiritual being. 9 The unity, therefore, which exists between all these distinctly individual natures is something more than the mere existence of a common human parentage would account for. Whence (again we ask) can it come? There can be but one answer — that, both in the origin of the race, and in the birth of each individual soul, there is impressed upon human 9 The co-existence of these two elements of common nature, and distinct individuality, is the ground of the old controversy of Traducianism and Creatianism (of which a brief sketch will be found in Liddon's " Elements of Re- ligion/' Lecture III.). It applies certainly to man's nature as a whole, for it is impressed on the body as well as the soul. No one who has studied human nature, in the whole widtli of society or in the narrow limits of family life, can possibly be either a mere Traducianist or a mere Crea- tianist. Just as under the Darwinian theory, no one doubts the transmission of characteristic properties, and yet no account (except the belief in a Creative Will) can be given of the first individual variations, from which the differentiation of species starts ; so in human nature, especially in the spiritual nature of man, there is a co-ex- istence of unity and individuality, which nothing but tLo same belief can account for. THE THEOLOGY OF THE AFFECTIONS. 297 nature one eternal type by the hand of Him who made it ; and (as we have already said) that type, being of a moral and spiritual nature, can be im- pressed only by a moral and spiritual Being. Thus the unity between man and man, which human love implies, must have its source in the Creative Will of God. The knowledge of it, therefore, leads us up to a Moral Creator of Humanity. Even in this witness it carries by implication the inference of a likeness between Him and us. (b.) But we have already urged that, over and above the love of man to man, there is a love of man to God, not only possible to man, but universal in man ; and in this alone the soul can sink the individuality, which always rightly limits the capacity of love to men. What can this love indicate except a real unity of nature between God and man ? The type, which we have already concluded to be impressed on all human creatures, alike in the origin of the race, and the birth of the individual soul, must, we now see, have a likeness to the Creator Himself, must be " the image of God." In one -of the greatest Epistles of St. Paul, 1 we are taught that the 1 See Eplies. v. 22 — vi. 9. The characteristic of the Epistle is its tendency to deal with human nature as a whole, as regenerate in Christ, and hence to dwell on the 298 THE THEOLOGY OF THE AFFECTIONS. three great relationships of human society — father and child, hushand and wife, master and servant — are sacred, as shadows of the relations of God to man in the Lord Jesus Christ. No such completeness of view can be gained by mere Natural Theology ; but the very witness of love to God leads up at least to some conception of a true Fatherhood of God, under which the brotherhood of all men is realized, and which at the same time has a close relation to each indi- vidual life, guarding its freedom and sacredness. It is in this that the peculiar force of the Theology of Love consists. It agrees with the Theology of Conscience in recognising in the Supreme Power a true Personal God, a Moral Creator, a Moral Governor. So far the two witnesses simply coincide. But, while Con- science tells of man's individuality before God, Love witnesses to a true unity of nature and a communion with God, on which we may rest " all our heart and all our mind, all our soul and all our strength/'' That witness is not lost in the conception of God's greatness and our own littleness; it is not destroyed, though it is obscured, even by the sense of sin and judg- relations which underlie society as natural, and to bring out the doctrine of that society supernatural, which we call the Catholic Church of Christ. THE THEOLOGY OF THE AFFECTIONS. 299 ment. On the contrary, in the communion of the soul with God, Love is the element which grows and gradually supersedes the elements of simple wonder and fear ; just as in the conception of God we accept as the ultimate truth, not " God is Power," " God is Light," " God is Righteousness" — although all these be true — but « God is Love." VI. Yet I must add that there is one other point, in which this witness of the affections has a peculiar beauty and power of its own in such a world as this. We have had to speak again and again of the awful mystery of the existence of evil — physical suffering, intellectual blind- ness, moral sin — as the one great disturbing influence along all the lines of conviction which lead up to God. We cannot deny that it crosses us here also. We ask in wonder, " How can God, who is Love, create beings, who can be so wretched, blind, sinful, that it were better for them had they never been born?" To that question, as to the parallel question of the Con- science, no full and adequate answer can, from the nature of the case, be given. Nor, again, is it doubtful that, just in proportion to the existence of moral evil in the soul, the love of God is exchanged for a fear, "hiding itself among the trees of the garden j" and, just in 300 THE THEOLOGY OF THE AFFECTIONS. proportion to the actual power of moraj evil to desolate the world, the belief in God's Love, as well as His Righteousness, is shaken. Sin therefore, weakens this moral witness, as it weakens the other moral witness, to God. Were it not so, their combined testimony would be absolutely irresistible. But still it is through this conception of Love that we have the brightest gleam of light from Natural Theology to penetrate the darkness of sin. For, in the first place, love being the measure of unity with God and likeness to Him, we feel that, so long as we have any love in us, our nature cannot be quite estranged from Him or utterly degraded. There is the Divine Image in us, showing itself both in love to man and in love to Him : we cannot but hope that it will con- quer all that obscures it and fights against it. But more than this. In the conception of God's Love there is an undying hope. For love, as we know, even in ourselves, contains, in relation to those who sin against us, the quality of Mercy ; and we hold that this quality belongs necessarily to superior being. It is enthroned in the hearts of kings, It is an attribute to God Himself. Accordingly, we know that towards erring and THE THEOLOGY OF THE AFFECTIONS. 301 sinful children an earthly father shows mercy, almost as a thing of course, carries not out the strict law of Righteousness against them, but delights to wipe away their tears of penitence, and to swallow up in the gladness of reconciliation all the suffering of the past. If God be Love, we have hope that He will be better than an earthly father to His prodigal sons, that thus the sin of man will be pardoned, and all the cloud of evil vanish away. We hope this : without Revelation I dare not say that we know it. 2 For even the Love of God cannot destroy the responsibility of man. 3 Sin must be atoned for ; there must be repentance, if there is to be pardon. Yet every day in this life we seem to see souls utterly hardened and reprobate, dead to all sorrow for sin, and all desire of righteousness. If there is always pardon to the penitent, can there be always penitence for the sinner ? 2 On this solemn subject, see Butler's weighty and un- answerable remarks in the " Analogy," part ii. chap. v. 3 ISTote the profound teaching of our Lord in John xii. 47, 48, in which His will for salvation and the inevitable responsibility of man are contrasted. " If any man hear My words, and believe not, I judge him not : for I came not to judge the world, but to save the world. He that re- jecteth Me, and receiveth not My words, hath one that judgeth him : the word that I have spoken, the same shall judge him in the last day." 302 THE THEOLOGY OF THE AFFECTIONS. We cannot be sure, that, beyond a certain point, human souls may not be utterly and eternally estranged from God. But we have hope — a hope that has expressed itself in every religion — and that hope comes not from the Reason and the Conscience, but from the Affections. Its very existence is a signal proof of the truth, that " he who loveth not, knoweth not God." VII. I have spoken hitherto mainly of the principle of Love in the abstract, corresponding to what we call the Syrderesis in the Moral Sense of Righteousness. But it is far more difficult here to distinguish the abstract principle from the concrete application of it. For since the sense of Righteousness bids us first realize our own individuality and then the duties, which, in virtue of that individual responsibility, we owe to others, it is possible to consider the principle of Duty in its abstract purity and grandeur, as we stand face to face with it in the great question, " For what purpose am I what I am?" Love, on the other hand, being essentially relative and self- forgetful, it is all but impossible to realize it, except in its con- crete forms, in close and necessary connexion with the external objects to which it tends. The distinction, therefore, which in the examina- THE THEOLOGY OF THE AFFECTIONS. 303 tion of Conscience was natural and necessary, is somewhat artificial here. But still there must here also be a similar consideration of the need of education of the principle of Love, and the inferences to be drawn therefrom. That the capacity of Love, like the capacity of Righteousness, needs to be educated, and that provision is made for its education by the ex- istence of human society and natural relation- ships, is too obvious to need proof or enforce- ment. The only difference is that in the educa- tion of Love the lower or coercive element of law has no place, and that the spiritual element is not so much the power of direct teaching, as the magic of example and personal influence. The growth of Love must necessarily be free. It is stimulated by the power of example, be- getting an inevitable reciprocity — with a power stronger here than even in respect of Duty; for it is an all-sufficient ground for loving men that "they first love us." It grows with singular rapidity and certainty by its own action ; for it is well known that we love most those for whom we have had the opportunity of doing most, fully understanding that ff it is blessed to give rather than to receive." It may be added that the culture of the Imagination and of its delight 304 THE THEOLOGY OF THE AFFECTIONS. in the beauty, which we rightly call " loveli- ness/'' plays a more important part in the educa- tion of Love than in the education of Duty. But these differences do not touch the main point of similarity — that the affections, like the Con- science, need to be educated, and are in part educated by man. From this, therefore, exactly as before, we go on to two inferences, — First, that this education by man, being a law of human life, is a part of the moral government of God, and that, there- fore, of His nature Love as well as Righteous- ness is a chief attribute. Next, that there are depths in the capacity of Love, which no human power, either of the individual or of society, can reach, or, indeed, ought to reach. For these there is an educating power which must reach them from on high. Not in this case the power of Law. In the sense of Law — that is, of God's Will enforcing and avenging itself — lies the source of fear, whether it be the lower fear of punishment, or the higher fear which is akin to reverence. "Per- fect love casts out fear ;" it cannot, therefore, be fostered by Law. We fall back entirely on the voice of the Spirit in the soul. As He is the awful Spirit of Righteousness, so is He also the sweet Spirit of Love. As by the presence THE THEOLOGY OF THE AFFECTIONS. 303 of a Divine Righteousness, in rebuke and judg- ment, He trains the Conscience, so also by the sense of a Divine Love, in its beneficence, its sympathy, its mercy, He trains the capacity of Love. It may indeed be noted that, in accordance with that less introspective and more expansive character of love, on which we have already dwelt, the Voice of God in the soul seems here, more than in its appeal to the conscience, to make use of impressions from the outer world. Thus it tells marvellously on the soul through the imagination by the sense of the beauty of Nature. In that relation, even a Christian poet calls it " Nature's Voice,'"' whether he hears it in the bright freshness of the morn- ing, or the calmer peacefulness of the evening, in the silence of the quiet valley or the grandeur of the mountain storm. But it is really a voice within the soul; and the most prosaic mind knows well how at times it melts the heart to tender- ness, and tills the eyes with the tears of an adoring love. It is the voice of a true Personal Being; for none other can call out a real answer of love. Nor can we doubt that the very atmosphere of human affection — in itself, as we have already seen, a powerful educating influence — suggests the existence behind and 306 THE THEOLOGY Ob 1 THE AFFECTIONS. through it of a higher love of the God who ordained it as one of the great ruling forces of humanity. What Keble again says of the sense of human sympathy in the hour of re- pentance — " They love us : will not God for- give?" — is true of all the various forms of human affection. As by it we first learn to conceive of the love of God, so through it we afterwards learn to feel that higher love ; for in it the voice of the Divine Spirit of Love speaks to us through human voices. But yet that Voice, perhaps oftener still, comes home to the soul directly. It breathes first the conviction of God's goodness and especially His mercy; it suggests next the yearning of the soul for Him and for His like- ness ; it calls out lastly the answering current of a conscious love. By the testimony of indivi- dual consciousness and of all human literature, we know that this Voice, thus speaking directly, is heard in the secrets of the soul, — generally the more clearly in proportion to the greater sensi- tiveness and purity of that soul itself. In the education of the capacity of love, as in its origin, its scope, and its basis, we know a present God. VIII. Thus, it would seem, the Theology of Love completes the harmony of the many voices which testify of God. THE THEOLOGY OF THE AFFECTIONS. 307 Closely parallel to the Theology of Conscience, yet certainly coming* from an independent faculty in the soul, it testifies by the convergent force of coincidence to a Personal, a Moral, a Loving God. Of the two great truths correlative to each other — the spirituality of man, and the Being of a true God, having communion with man — we may hold that the sense of Righteous- ness is the chief guardian of the one, the sense of Love the chief witness to the other. But the two truths must stand or fall together; and the two lines of Moral Theology, perhaps in different proportions, testify of both. Their witness, after all, is more powerful than any other ; for it comes home with a direct and vivid force to the individual Conscience, stirring it not only to know, but to do ; and it tells more or less upon all, not needing research into the past, or abstract reasoning on the first principles of Being, but dealing with the present realities and the present needs of life. Their witness is more fruitful than any other ; for it discloses to us in its measure and degree, not only that God is, but what He is — unfolding to us the Moral Attributes most clearly belonging to Personality, and most intimately affecting our own life in rela- tion to Him. Therefore it is that our Lord pro- mises the blessing of" seeing God/' not to keen- 80S THE THEOLOGY OF THE AFFECTIONS. ness or subtlety of intellect, but to the " purity of heart/' which grows out of the "hunger Lind thirst after righteousness."" Therefore it is that, as the crowning perfection of Gospel teach- ing, it is declared that " he that loveth not, knoweth not God/' and that they who are " rooted and grounded in love 3> shall " know what passeth knowledge, and be filled with all the fulness of God." SUMMARY OF THE ARGUMENT. I._(«) SUMMARY OF THE GENERAL POINTS OF THE ARGU- ME NT. (b) THE RELATION OF BELIEF IN HUMAN PERSON- ALITY TO BELIEF IN GOD. ( C ) TEE GREAT ANTITHESIS BETWEEN THEISM AND PANTHEISM. II —THE TWO GROUPS OF SPECULATIVE AND MORAL THEO- LOGY: THEIR MUTUAL RELATIONS AND COMBINA- TION. I XI. THE ULTIMATE CONCLUSIONS — (a) THE EXISTENCE OF A GOD. (6) THE INDUCTION OF HIS (RELATIVE) INFINITY, (c) THE CONCEPTION OF THE ABSOLUTE. XV.-THE RELATION OF NATURAL THEOLOGY TO REVELATION. CONCLUSION. The brief outline of a great subject is now com- pleted. It remains to sum up the leading con- clusions, to which the course of the argument has led. 310 SUMMARY OF THE ARGUMENT. I. (a.) We start 1 from an all-important fact, which must in some way be accounted for — that the belief in a Personal Godhead is all but uni- versal over the field of humanity , both in space and in time. With the one great exception of Buddhism — which is itself unable really to main- tain its Theoretic Nihilism, and which yet, in virtue of that very Nihilism, is incompatible with any activit}^ or progress of man — no belief which excludes a Personal Deity is able to maintain itself as a practical belief, fit for the wear and tear of life ; and no belief in a Personal Deity fails (after perhaps a brief halt in some theory of Dualism) to assume, explicitly or implicitly, the form of a belief in One Eternal God. The evi- dences of our Natural Theology have, therefore, to maintain a vantage-ground already our own against assailant forces, rather than to win for the faith in God a new position in human thought and faith. 2 Their office, indeed, is to 1 See Lect. I. 2 In strict accordance with the laws of human nature, Holy Scripture (1 Pet. iii. 15) directs us to be able to give on inquiry " a reason for the hope which is " already " in us," wrought out in the soul, not by abstract reasoning, but by our own instinctive faith and by the teaching of men, which God has ordained on all lines of knowledge to be the two influences of actual education. The command applies to the evidence both of Eeligion as such, and of Chris- SUMMARY OF THE ARGUMENT. 311 draw out, into explicit forms the principles im- plicitly involved in the universal and instinctive belief of mankind. But what is the true character and province of Natural Theology ? 8 In itself, when it pro- ceeds beyond the bare demonstration of the existence of a First Cause, it is, and from the nature of the case we maintain that it must be, an Inductive Science — proceeding (as all other Inductive Sciences proceed) by observation, generalization, verification, and resulting at last, not in demonstration, but in moral certainty. If it leads us to a Personal Being, then, although our powers of observation are enlarged by sym- pathy, yet all analogy shows us that, for any- thing like adequate knowledge of Him from Himself, some Self-Revelation is needed, com- plementary to the searchings of Natural Theo- logy, taking up its various lines and carrying them on to the central Unity. To the knowledge of Science, therefore, must be added the know- ledge of Faith. It is important accordingly at the outset to consider what is the force, and what the limitation, of Natural Theology. Those who believe in a Revelation, Supernatural but not tianity itself. It shows us clearly the true function of Evidence in relation to Faith. 3 See Lect. II. 312 SUMMAUY OF THE ARGUMENT. Preternatural, will be prepared at once to esti- mate that force, and to expect that limitation. To these preliminary considerations we next add 4 — what it is the special object of these lectures to enforce — first, that there are various lines of Natural Theology, corresponding to the Intellect, to the Imagination, to the Conscience, and to the Affections of man ; next, that no one of these various lines can be considered alone, or expected alone to bear the whole stress of proof : thirdly, that, in virtue of the Law of Conver- gence, so well known in the estimation both of scientific evidence and of human testimony, the aggregate result of these various lines of Theology is infinitely greater than the mere sum of their separate evidences; lastly, that, since each has at once its points of agreement with the others, and its peculiarity of some exclusive witness, this confirmatory power of Convergence applies, primarily, indeed, to the points in which all agree, but secondarily also to the testimony which each bears alone. From these main considerations we proceed to work out more in detail each of these lines of thought, as defending the fortress of instinctive Faith. (Jj.) But before doing so, it is important to 4 See Lect. III. SUMMARY OF THE ARGUMENT. 313 notice what are the principles of that defence. Everywhere the belief in God, and the conscious- ness of all that makes a true Personality in man, are in the closest connexion with each other. No Theology is possible apart from the recognition of a free will in man, guided by Reason, specula- tive and practical, and in some mysterious way harmonized with the Supreme Power. The con- verse would probably be found to be true — that, without belief in God, the believer in man's true personality will find it all but hopeless to under- stand how this needful harmony can be possible, and so will hardly maintain his own conviction, as a living and acting power. But with this we are not at present concerned. The point, which must be clearly represented to our mind, is this, that we start in the search after God from the conviction, so deeply engraven on the individual consciousness and on the whole history and litera- ture of the world, of a true personality in man. With those who deny this we have no common ground. But wherever it is acknowledged, we believe that the evidence of Natural Theology is fairly irresistible. On the premiss itself, we appeal at once to the first principles of our inner consciousness, and to the exigencies of the outer life in which " we are treated as if we were free." We have no fear that any imperious 314 SUMMARY OF THE ARGUMENT. demand for logical comprehensiveness of system, or any impressions, however powerful, of the Majesty of Law, will ever rob mankind of it. (