WartfeVl L'kar^ SYLLABUS -OF- PROF. PATTON'S LECTURES ON- THEISM irRXiTa?Ei3, 3^0 T 2=-crsxjis:^EiD. (Hje Jriiutton JP'^^^s. 1888. •yip^i^i^ Warlield Library SYLLABUS ^y PROF. PATTON'S LECTURES ON- THEISM I*DEaX2^rXEX), 3^0X I^XTSIjISHEXD. je Jriuctton grtBs. 188 8. DEC S9192i rii rHElSM INTODUCTOKY Theism iniiv be considered reliu^iously or philosophically. From the standpoint of relii^ious belief men may be re- garded as believing or not believini^ in God. Thus : 1. Theism. iPolytlioisni. r*aiitlieisin. Moiiotlieisni. = . Theism par exellencp. 3. Atheism. Theism, philosophically considered, is a theory of the universe afHrming the existence of one Infinite, Personal God ; the Creator, I'reserver, and Ruler of the Universe. The theistic conception of the universe implies three things: 1. A finite, personal, and permanent self; or ego. 2. A totality of objective phenomena; or cosmos. ' 3. An infinite personal author of all dependent existence; or God. Opposed to Theism in this view of the subject would stand Anti-theism in its various forms. Adopting this philosophical c()nce[)tion of Theism, we shall carry on the discussion under tliree main divisions : Historical ; Constructive ; Polemic. PART I. HISTORICAL. Three topics fall under this head : 1. The phenomenology of Theism. 2. The genesis of Theism. 3. The discussion of Theism. I. 'i'liE Phknomenology or Theism. A. The Theism of the three great historic monotheistic religions: Mohammedanism, C'bristianity, Judaism. The discussion here concerns tlie purely monotheistic character of Judaism. This has been attacked — though as Ochler (Theo. of O. T. ii. 150) shews, without success — by 2 a«em,)ting to prove („) Thnt .) ;vo..nnlv;. ^'"^ J*'"'" *''<-'t8 Of the or * <^:?s'ence of other Po]ythmsm seen, to bo tl.ese regarding Theism and thoisn.. '"'"^-^ *° '■'•■'"I'so mto idohnr^- or Poly , „,;-'^'"- of nature. "^-'"""-^ '"'^^■'' o.i an animistic "• -lliat a complex rdi.ri '"• o?the";':::;!i|:;?-"'^ Monotheism '•4osit!:;f'ti;;.:T"*'---na ^ionothei.m ""'"■>' ^'0™ '^M:;;c;jf:4r;jji-s«,.tcm, ,, . Slt-^od^-"'^^^^^^^ toliijP'K-'-'-' --on ot this... ,.,.,., •"• i lio Theism of comparative Th<. .1 Accon n<' to tini, , • "'""^e Ihoology. tion nr ''■''.'"'" '" t''e«e theis h. f/'''T'''''''''-^' "^ I'xlia 1 C. The Theism of speculative philosophy. Aocordiii,*;* to wliieh God is rc'ii;ur(le(l simply as a livpo- thesis for "-iviiii:: rational exi)laiiati()ii of the universe. ir. The Genesis of Theis.m. There are four generic theories in explanation of our idea of God, nam el}' : 1. Development. 2. Revelation. 3. Inference. 4. Intuition. These are to be considered in their order. First Theory. Development. By which is meant that Monotheism sustains genetic re- lations to antecedent impure or less pure forms of belief. This theory assumes several forms. A. Hume. Polytheism, according to II., is prior to Monotheism. The advance out of the one into the other is not due to philosophic reflection and a growing appreciation of the unity of nature, but is explained by the tendency to flatter a local deity, to impute greatness, and so by degrees to in- vest him with the attribute of inflnity. A view lacking every element of plausibility, and speculatively worthless. B. COMPTE. The theory under notice is credited to Compte, not because he is the originator of the term fetich, nor yet because he has given the best account of fetichistic religions — for this distinction is due to F. Schultze, (Fetichismus) — but because Compte flrst presented in reasoned form the doctrine that all religion begins in Fetichism and passes thence through Polytheism to Monotheism. Discussing the fetich-theory of religion (1) inquire into the origin and meaning of the word fetich, and (2) consider reasons for and against this view. Account of the word given in Max MuUer's ITibbert Lectures, p. 54. Introduced by De Bross, 1760. Origin of the word found in the custom of Portuguese navigators, who called the inanimate objects worshipped by the people of West Africa — feiticos. Word used, though improperly, with great latitude, Schultzc speaks of mountains, water, etc., as fetiches; Tiele, of Heaven as a feticli. Compte gives the doctrine of 'anima mundi as illustration of fetich worship. And so an ohject of special regard is termed a fetich ; a child's doll ; a lock of hair; and by way of reproach, a theological opin- ion; the Protestant's Bible; the Roman Catholic wafer. This is wrong. The word is properly used to describe the worship of tangible, inanimate objects. So regarding it, consider the reasons for calling it the earliest form of religion : a. It is the lowest form. What is lowest was anterior. But this needs proof. b. Savages and uncivilized races are types of primitive man. But this assumes there has been no degradation. 0. Empirical philosophy is under obligation to expound a natural history of religion. But this necessity is only condition by the exigencies of an erroneous philosophy. As to the value of the theory, it is, however, to be re- marked : 1. It does not satisfy one of the leading evolutionists, Mr. Spencer. 2. It is ditticult to determine, from the evidence furnished by savage tribes, whether the Fetich is a determina- tion of a general belief in God, or whether the larger belief in God is developed out of fetich-worship : whether belief in God is the logical prius of the fetich or vice versn. 3. And though the people of W. Africa had no knowledge of God at all, there is nothing to shov/ that this con- dition is not due to a degradation from a primitive faith. 4. Tlif literature of India [U'oves thiit there was a prim- iti\e Monotheism or l[enotheism lying back of the Polytheism of a later day. 6. Spencer's criticism is good. Before the savage can invest this or that stick or rag with life, he must have a general animistic conception. Spencer is trying to show that the ghost-theory is the true the- ory ami that belief in ghosts antedates belief in the fetirli. What is good against fetichism in favor of ancestor worship is good also against fetichism in fa- vor of primiti\«' Tlicism. C. Herbert Si'encer. The primitive rclijLcion, ucconliiiir to this thiiikcr, was ancestor-worship. llaving in droanis come to a knowl- edge ot liis second self, that is, having reached the helief in the soul, the step was easy to helief in the continued con- scious existence of the dei)arted. Hence ancestor- worship. And Mr. 8pencer is at great pains to show how what hegan as worship of ancestors in time took on the form of wor- ship [>aid to plants, animals, the heavenly bodies and finally the infinite God. Genenral Considerations. Spencer lias faced the question his philosophy required him to face, that of accounting for religion by natural causes. To fail here would be the destruction of his system. But to show that the origin of religion mai/ be as he describes it, does not furnish proof that such is ij:s origin. The theory of religion can have no more value than the ' First Princi- ples.' Again, among naturalistic theories of religion this must be considered the most thorouo^h-o:oinor : for while fetichism leaves unanswered the question how men came to worship a fetich, the theory of ancestor-worship [»rofesses at least to e.\[)lain how belief in tlie post mortem existence of ancestors came to be entertained. Omitting all reference to criticisms against the theory and against the philosophical system of which it is part, the most that could be claimed for it would be that it presents a plausible naturalistic theory of the origin of religion, as opposed to the supernaturalistic theory of Christianity. Special Considerations. Spencer has failed, however, to make out even so strong a case as this. 1. To prove his theory he should have showfi \hi>X when homage was paid to ancestors, no homage was paid to the gods. But the V'edahs seem to illustrate the contrary idea (Sociology 306). 2. It is important to show that filial piety is worship or such worship as is paid to the gods. Spencer talks very loosely in regard to this. 6 3. Because the savage regards God as his father, he is not therefore worshipping his ancestors. To make much of the case of Unkulunkulu in this direction would require him to draw a similar inference form our use of the Lord's Prayer. 4. The attempt to sliow how idolatry, animal worship and nature worship were related to ancestor-worship is an illustration of very far-fetched reasoning. Thus : fe- tich worship from identification of deceased with portions of his clothing: idol worship from the. habit of making images of the deceased ; animal worship from the frequenting of the home of the deceased by certain animals, or from the fact that the deceased hatl an animal name ; })lant-worshi[) from the intoxi- cating liquors produced from some plants, supposed in this way to be possessed by supernatural beings ; mountain worship and worship of the sea from the fact that their ancestors came from the mountain or over the sea — origin in this sense was mistaken for parentage. 5. The most ]»lausible argument in support of Spencer's view would be derived from Greek and Roman my- thology. Mr. Spencer is thoroughly committed to the Euhemeristic theory of nn'thology ; but he has to encounter the opposition even here of a very influ- ential sehool of mytliologists. 6. Mr. Spencer must answer more fully tlian he has al- ready done, the allegation that ancestor-worship is confined to the inferior races and that no Indo- European or Semitic nation, so far as we know, seems to have made a religion of worship of the dead. Mr. Spencer believes that the " divine man as conceived "had everywhere for antecedent a powerful man as perceircil " (Sociology, 438). This is supported by say- ing that the Jews worshipped an ancestor in Jeho- vah ; and this simple and absurd assertion is his an- swer to the objection just quoted. 1). lIi:<:iiL. There is notliiiig that calls for special remark so far as the theistic problem in the Hegelian philosophy is concern- ed. The d-'vclopiiicnt of Theism is a part of a system of development, and no criticism is called for beyond the crit- icism of the system itself, which is obviously out of place here. IIci::elianism is the idealistic form of the doctrine of develo})ment. It is the anti^xxles of the philosophy of Compte, yet presenting points of resemblance to it. In the one case the problem is : Given atoms, to make a cos- mos; and the solution is offered us in the First Principles of Herbert Spencer. In the other case the problem is : Given the Idea^ to explain the cosmos ; and for answer we are told of a process of successive evolutions ending in con- scious, thinking, praying num. Monotheism in this sys- tem, as in that of Compte or Spencer, is the result of a pro- cess which lias been going on silently through millenniums. E. Max Muller. It is not very easy to determine the position of this author in religious thought. His didactic position does not quite accord with that which his polemic would suggest. 1. In his attack on the Comptean theory of religion he has conclusively shown that fetichism is not the })rimitive religion. 2. In his Hil)bert Lectures he avows less heartily than in an earlier work his belief in a religious instinct; indeed he practically discards the idea. 3. The Max ^liiller of to-day is not the Max Miiller of Chips from a German Workshop, (Transactions of Victoria Institute, July 1881), and cannot be quot- ed as the advocate of primitive Monotheism or Henotheism. For while, as a student of literature, he tells us that Vedic Writings show that belief in one God (Henotheism) antedated Polytheism : as a psychologist, asking what religion a man can learn through his five senses, he tells us that whether Monotheism be or be not the primitive religion is of no consequence, since, before man had reached any belief in God, he "had already accomplished half his journey." The primitive Monotheism pointed to in the Vedas is thus made of no avail by the sug- gestion that the journey of progress was half done before men came to the idea of God. Max Miiller must be classed among the evolutionists; but it must be noted that his recent conclusions regarding primi- tive relit^ions are in cc^nliict with the testimony of the ancient literature of India which he has brought to the attention of English readers. F. SCIIELLING. Schelling held that i>riniitive man had an intuitive or instinctive knowledge of God ; but that his Theism was relative, not absolute. From this original relative Mono- theism have come two streams of tendency, one issuing in Polytheism, the other in absolute Monotheism. His reasons for this view are : 1. It furnishes a natural answer to the question how men became Polytheists. Belief in one God did not ex- clude belief in a i)lurality of gods. 2. Monotheism absolute, or belief in only one God, is said to be a generalization derived through contact with a previously existing Monotheism and through protestinij: aijainst it. Second Theory : Revelation. 1. Distinguish between revelation and tradition. The question is not how we came to believe in God, but how any belief in God originated. Tradition does not originate anything, and hence, a traditional the- ory ot the origin of religion is absurd. The genesis of a belief is one thing and the perpetuation of a be- lief another. 2. So distinguish between the correcting and the conserv- ing influence of the Bible in regard to Theism and the <^enesis of theistic belief. Doubtless our i)ure Theism is due mainly to the inspired Word, and we believe in one and only one God, be- cause we have a revelation from God; but this is not the question. 3. The question is wliether the genesis of primitive the- ism is due to revelation. A. Watson holds that man lirst knew God "by sensible converse with Him." Schelling objects to this view with great force, by declar- ing; that this would imj)ly "a previous Atheism of con- BciouHiiess." Cocker objects, by saying that if man had been devoid of the idea of (iod, it nexer c-oiild have been taught liiin. (Christianity and (ireek IMiilosophy, ]>. 95. "^ But Cocker (h)es not distinj^uisli sufficiently between ati in- tutitive knowledge of God and hilo8ophy we find Anax- agoras, who marks an advance in theistic discussion. Anaxagoras recognized not only the unity of the world, but also its order and adjustments*^; and these he accounted 13 for by affirnnnc; the existence of a world-ordering voDc. He is distinctly coniprnnented by Aristotle for this advance in the explanation of tlie universe. There is no good reason for denying to Anaxagoras the distinction of being the fa- ther of the doctrine of Final Causes ; and the fact that, for the most part, he explains plienoraena in a mechanical way, does not disprove the fact that, arguing from the analogy of his own intelligence, he referred the order of the uni- verse also to Intelligence. The Kleatic and the Anaxagorean doctrine differed thus : The Eleatic atHrmed the existence of one, necessary -Being, the ground of all phenomena ; Anaxagoras conceived of the world, not as an existence merely, but as such an existence, and suggested a voDc as its explanation. The Eleatic saw the world of multitude and sought the unifying }>rinciple : the Anaxagorean saw tlie world of ada[»tation and sought the organising principle. Socrates discussed Theism for practical ends; and Ikj was the first among the Greeks, says Oesterley, to do so. Ilia was not the Theism of speculation, but the practical The- ism, that had good morals as its motive. Ilis statement of the teleological argument is to be found in the Memorabilia, Bk. 1., Ca[». 4, and is familiar. Plato has been charged with Pantheism ; and his confused sense respecting Personality, his interchangeable use of the words God and Good, and his want of nice discrimination between the First and the Final Cause, constitute the basis of this charge, which Prof Jowett saj's is untrue. The Theism of Plato embraces the following points : 1. But for prevalent Atheism, there would be no need of proving God's existence. 2. The soul has a natural tendency to believe in God. 3. The orderly movements of the heavenly bodies sug- gested to him a Divine author and presence. The distinction now made between order and ends in nature was understood. This argument (the Cos- mological) is found in the tenth book of the Laws. 4. But in the Timaeus he argues teleologically, from the adaptation of means to ends in our bodily organism. 5. The a^tiological argument, pure and simple, was also recognized ; though it is the distinction of Aristotle to have developed it. 14 6. The inconiniensurable character of mind and matter leads to the argument for a universal mind. His view approaches the doctrine of the anima miindi, and this may be the basis of the allegation that he was a pantheist. But the doctrine of the anima mundi is not l*antheism. Aristotle found arguments for the existence of God in the religious consciousness of men, and in the order of the world. His great argument, howev^er, and the one most characteristic of his philosophy, is found in his doctrine of a First Mover. There is, he says, first that which is moved but does not produce motion ; secondly, tliat which both moves and causes motion ; and, thirdly, that which is un- moved and produces motion. This first mover is incorpo- real, immovable, without parts or passions. It is pure en- ergy ; Absolute Being; God. God has no end outside of Himself He is his own end. God's thought does not find its object out of Himself Thought and thinker are one. His thought is the thought of thought. Aristotle has given us, says Zeller, the first scientific foundation for Theism, inasmuch as in his system the defi- nite thought of a self-conscious intelligence in God is not due to a merely religious idea, but is rigidly deduced from the principles of his philosophical system. Yet, as Zeller goes on to shew, it is difficult to say what Aristotle held, regarding the relation of God to the world; and this difficulty has led some to say that his Theism was, in realitv, a Pantheism, that is to sav, was not Theism at all. No one has recognized finality in nature more distinctly than Aristotle. He was as cognizant as Paley of the adap- tation of means to ends. But finality in nature does not seem to shut him up to the necessity of conceiving God as a designer. Nature, he says, has a tendency to realize the good. God, says Aristotle, moves the world as the loved object moves the one loving. And this, by some, is con- strued to mean that God is the efficient cause, only as He is the final cause. This, again, is capable of being understood in a sense that destroys the distinction between God and the world ; that is to say, is a juircly ]>antheistic sense. Is God only another name lor the order, the finality, manifest in the world ? U so, the Aristotelian doctrine is pantheistic. 15 Or does the order and iiiiality exlii])ited in Nature exist as a jyrius in the thouizht of God? This woidd he theistic, and this seems to he Aristotle's idea, for he says " the world has its principle in God^and this j>rin('i})le exists, not merely as a form immanent in the world, like the order in an army, hut also as a self-existent suhstanee, like the general in an army." (Uebervveg, I, 163.) See, also, Sir Alex. Grant's Ethics of Aristotle, Vol. I., 283. The Ejncureans found their proof of God's existence in the universality of the hclief. This was not the argument e consensu ycnthim, nor was it, as Cicero su|)posed, the doctrine that belief in God is innate. The 7i()6):fj(l^c(: of the Epicureans was held to prove God's existence, by showing that the gods universally nuuiifested themselves to men by direct contact in sleep. The Stoics, with their doctrine of the aninia mundi, are frequently quoted as pantheists. Yet notice that they believed in the separate personality and immortality of the individual soul, as well as in an intelli- gent, world ordering soul of the world. The conflicting sentiments of the Stoics, Epicureans, and philosophers of the New Academy, were brought out in Cicero's JDe Natura Deorum, the one work on Natural The- ology that antiquity has furnished us. After the time of Cicero, Greek philosophy was affected by Oriental influ- ences ; but though it became more Theosophical, no con- tribution to theistic discussion seems to have been made. Among the church fathers, Clement and Origen denied the possibility of proving the existence of God, and placed this belief among the a priori elements of knowledge. Ath- anasius recognized the moral argument as the strongest. Augustine argues from the relatively good, great, and true to the absolutely and inflnitely good, great, and true. His discussion of the highest truth enters largely into the dis- cussions of a later day. Boethius, (474 A. I).), in his De Consolatione PliHosophiae^ enlarged upon the same idea. He was the precursor of Anselm in this field, and is said by Kostlin (Stud. u. Krit., 1875) to be the founder of onto- logical theistic proof. 2. SECOND PERIOD. The conditions did not exist in the ancient world for the production of a reasoned Theism and of elaborate treatises in Natural Theology. These conditions are. 16 1. The antithesis between Natural and Revealed Religion, tiie result of our having the Bible. 2. The existence of Dogmatic Theology. For when our knowledge of God is system^ized, the question whether God exists, at once becomes a locus. 3. The polemic relations of Theism to anti-theistic theo- ries. These conditions began to be realized in the Scholastic philosophy, and they have been realized increasingly ever since. The theistic discussions of Scholasticism are, for the most part, a repetition of the arguments found in Greek philosophy. Aristotle's argument based on motion, the argument based on the highest good, etc., etc. Two books, only, come to us from Scholasticism, devoted specially to Theism : Anschn's Fros-logium and the Theologia yaturalis, of Raymond De Sebonde. Scholasticism falls under two periods : John Scotus Eri- gena, Roscellin, Anselm, and Abelard mark the first period ; Thomas Aquinas, Occam, and Duns Scotus, the second. Phitonic pliil()S()j>hy was dominant in the first period. The Aristotelian in the second. Anselm and Aquinas, respec- tively, rei)resented these periods. Anselm was the heir of Augustine and Boethius; as the former had argued on the basis of the highest Truth, and the latter on the basis of the relative and the imperfect; so Anselm's Theistic proof in the Monologinm proceeded under the belief of the highest (iood. Dissatisfied with the Monologium, Anselm attempts in the Proshjgium to make a complete demonstration of the existence of God. The key to the argument is found in a phrase which he uses in the beautiful prayer with which the treatise begins : Thou art that ut we are thinking of a being than which a greater cannot be conceived. Again, God cannot be thought !iot to be. For if the Being of whom we 17 think can be thought not to be, we can think of a Being who cannot be thought not to be, and this would be greater. But we are thinking of a Being than wl)oni a greater can- not be conceived. (Jaunilo replies ])y saying, substantially, that what exists subjectively does not necessarily exist objec- tively. Between the greatest Being f/ioiff/lif as existing and the greatest Being '^r/<^^f/(y existing, there is a wide diti'erence. Then follows his famous illustration of the island. Ansehn replies by saying that his argument is unique ; that it a{)plies only to the Being, quo majns iio/i cogitari pos^ sit ; that if (launilo could find anything to which his rea- soning would apply except this being quo uiujus, etc., he would make him a present of tlie lost island. 2. Criticisms of the Anselmian proof. See Runze : Brr Ontoloc/ische Goitcsbeweis. (a) AsswuptioKS. Fortlage, Hasse, and others say the whole discussion depends on the Realism that underlies it. Others say that Anselm first gets his idea of God from Revelation, and then seeks to legitimate it by reasoning. Then again it is said that his argument is an attempt to give dialectical certitude to an idea derived through the witness of the Holy Ghost. (/>) The aim of the Anselmian proof has been criticised. Schelling says that Anselm tried to prove God's existence as if God were an individual to be coi^rdinated with other individuals, whereas He is the ground of all Being. But Anselm is not open to the charge of holding a merely me- chanical Theism. As little force is there in the objection that we cannot prove God's existence a priori and deductively, because God, being the suruymnn genus, cannot be included in a higher genus. (c) Objections based on the method of Anselm. It was a mistake to seek to prove God's existence by syllogistic process. God, says Fischer, is metalogical. Great unan- imity of thinkers on this point. In fact, however sure we are of God's existence, when we try to prove it, we only transfer, it is said, the assumption from the conclusion to the premises. But there is no corresponding unanimity in regard to the particular fallacy in the reasoning of Anselm. Identity of premises, circle, petitio principH, four terms, not to speak of other iallacies, have all been laid to his charge. 18 (licit statcnit'iit of the aeti()]()<;ical ar«^unioiit, 3. TliL* ar^mnoiit (.r possi/tili ut it gives no information concerning the nature of that being. It leaves experience in order to seek a con- ception adequate to that of a necessary being, and finds it in the ens reaUsa'unum. If now Kant had said there is an a priori as well as an a yosUriori element in the cosmological argument, no ob- jection could be made. But he says that in identifying the eiis rcallssiinnin with the necessary being, we are returning to the ontological argument. For, he continues, when we Bay that the conception of ens realissimum is adequate to the conception of a necessary being, we assume that we can infer the latter from the former. The argument which pro- 27 fosses to be cosmological and to proceed from ex})erieiice is thus covertly ontoloi^ical (Criti<[ue, Mt'iklcjoliir.s trann, p. 378). But tliis is not the case. The conception of an c/is real- issimum is that of a being necessarily existing. But that is no proot that the necessary being exists and the cosmo- logical argument does not proceed upon that assumption. The most that can be said is tliat the ontological argument gives us the conception of an ms re forms : . Ktiological, Cos- mological, Teleological. A. Thk JvriuLocicAi. AK«;rMi:NT. This treats phenomena sim[)ly as r! Thkistfc Inference in the Totality of Phe- XOMENA. Syllogism. Every effect has a cause. The world is an effect, cVc. Hut is the world an effect ? Difficult to prove this it' by 'world' we mean the substance of the world. Hence soine say the a'tiolofi:ical argument is useless because it assumes the non-eternity of matter. But we are not required to raise this question. The world of our experience is one of phenomenal successions in time and co-existences in space. Does this world demand a first cause; if so what cause ? Answer to this depends upon what is meant by causation. We notice therefore the leading theories ot cau- sation. 1. Mill's Theory. Mill (J. S.) says that '-the very essence ot causation is incompatible with a tirst cause." " The cause of any change is a prior change." " When I speak of the cause of a phenomenon I do not mean a cause which is not itself a phenomenon." By causation Mill means only the relationships of phenomena in time-successions. His theory being conceded the impossibility of inferring a first cause undoubtedly follows. But to his theory in its relations to theism we offer these objections. (a.) Cause and effect express relations (according to Mill) between phenomena. God as first cause is thus ruled out by definition. (/>.) Cause and efiect express time-relations of phenomena. It is the fact that A is the invariable predecessor under cer- tain circumstances of B that makes it possible to call A the cause of B. But the essence of causation is not in invariable relationshij* of succession for this invai'iability might be pre- served where there is no suggestion of cause and effect. (c.) Mill is shut u|> to an infinite regress of finite causes. A cause is oidy a [>henomenon and Qvvry phenomenon that ])eginK to l)e has a cause. {(/.) There can be no law of cause and effect under con- ditions where the law ol" the unilormity of nature is not in force. Were events to happen without regularity, there would be in Mill's view a susjjension of the law of cause and efiect. l>ut no: the occurrence of an event makes it imperative to call for a cause. It is the fact that the event /<(/.^ happnied, not that it has happened regularly that makes it necessarv to ask Ibi- its cause. 31 {( .) Mill viohitcs the |»riiici|>l('s of his own i'iii|.iricnl pljil- osouliy and (.ontradicts his (lociriiiu oi' causation hy appoal- \n shown, accordin*!^ to Mill's definition of cause, ever to discover a cause. For, accordin«^ to this doctrine, the cause of a phe- nomenon is not a sinjj^le antecedent and necessarily related phenomenon : hut that phenomenon as conditioned hy all the circumstances near and more remote which have effected it. MilTs doctrine amounts to sayini^ that the phvsical uni- verse at any one moment is the eff'ect of all j)liysical ante- cedents for all past time. Clearly from this view of causa- tion we can infer no first cause. W the only causes of [)}ie- nomena he themselves phenomena demanding causes in explanation of them, then an uncaused cause is ahsunh 2. Theory of pure physical causation. If the factors of the universe he matter and motion, then cause can only mean the t)henomenal antecedents necessary to certain conse- quents. And we conclude (1) every jdiysical phenomenon is necessarily determined l)y physical antecedents: (2) there has heen an infinite regress of physical antecedents: (3) all so-called free actions liave heen physically determined. A first cause in tlie sense demanded l)v theism is im|>ossil)le. Moreover the i'vae action of our own wills is ohliterhted and our volitions take their place in a row of physical an- tecedents. 3. Theory of the persistence of Force. As taught hy Spencer it is the doctrine that all forms of existence are the manifestations of a ]»ower at once omnijiotent and in- comjirehensihle. "In this consciousness of an omnipotent power w (' have that consciousness in which luligion dwells, and so we arrive at that jioint where lidigion and Science coalesce" (Spencer). We agree with !)iman in say- ing that the doctrine of a first cause has not heen wiped out hy the doctrine oi force. If the idea of causation yielded 32 this and iiotliiiii;- iiiorr, that there is an incomprehensible but omnipotent power that is the ultimate cause of all phe- nomenon, we should use thivS as the basis of a theistic ari^uuK'iit. I)nt there are objections to this view of causa- tion. It is half wav between theism and materialism. If Force be an entity distinct from matter and its manifesta- tions tile diti'erenee between this theory and theism is that force is not invested with the attributes of Intelligence. The theory as thus understood is semi theistic and consistency will require it to advance to the full theistic position. If on the other hand. Force be not an entity but a term ex- pressing rate or ratio of motion, work done, kc, the theory resolves itselt into that of pure physical causation. This again is physical determinism, and to be complete, must include mind and will. If, however, volition be not capa- ble of physical explanation, as it is not, then we have a large area of etfeets which cannot be explained by the doctrine of the persistence of Force. Physical causation in other words is not the only causation. 4. Accordingly we have the common doctrine of dual causation whieh recognizes will as a cause — a first cause, and physieal phenomena as second causes. It is held by many that [jersonal agency is the type of all causation : that we speak of physieal eauses because we impute to matter a power akin to that of whieh we are conscious when we effect change by the exercise of our wills. But whatever be the truth respect- ing the nature of physical causation the theistic argument based upon cause derives its force from our experience of personal agency. The ^etiological argument is simply the Aristotelian argument for a first mover. From our expe- rience of power and from our belief in regard to the inabil- ity of matter to orii^inate motion, we are led to believe that however related to one another physical phenomena may be, there must behind them all be a will as the original cause of motion. .'). Volitional theory of causation. It is held by many that the only real cause in the world is a will. Whether this volitional theory of causation be accepted or not, and whether an infinite i-egress of pliysical antecedents be thinkable or n(jt, it is certain that the mind naturally seeks for a case of real beginning. We are not satisfied with a cause that is also an effect. It is certain that the only thing in experience answering to this demand is our will. So that contemplat- 33 \n^ tlie world ol" pliciioniciia — anteccMloiit.s jiiid conscMiiifiits — we are left to ac'ce|tt an inliriite re«;ress ot" plivHical cauHefl, or to believe that jdivsical cliaiiue is diri'cth- or iiior«,' remotely related to tlic will. The arLTunient (f co/ifhif/cn/i/i mmuli concenis plu'uoineiia. It does not cojiccrn itself with the ([Uestion of suhstance or the eternity of matter. The non-eternity of matter may l)e argued on the i^round of the law of jiarsimony (that is, the- ism Ixiiii^- ( oiici'ded, thi'i'e is no need ol" helievin;^ in the eternity of matter), as followini^ i'rom the doctrine of the dis- sipation of enerii'y, or on tiie iz:round of a dynamic theory of matter: hut it is not necessary to know that atoms had a heginnin*]^ in order to come to the theistic inference through the doctrine of causation. We consider next : Basis of Thkistic rNFEKENCK in Spkcific Phenomena. Certain phenomena, because they cannot be accounted for by antecedent physical phenomena, suggest, if they do not require, the hyi)othesis of the divine intelligence for their ex- planation. Existence of life and the human mind are exam- ples of these. Arguments for divine existence based upon the human n;iiul have been presented in two forms; by John Locke and Sir Wm. Hamilton. Locke's argument, given in Part L, criticised l)y Physicus, who says that we liave no proof that only mind can ]>roduce mind ; and moreover, that it is as inconceivable tliat mind should be the cause o{' matter as that matter should be the cause of niind. This, however, is easily said, and for reply, each must refer to his own consciousness. Hamilton's argument is founded in the incommeasurable character of the attributes of mind and matter. From mind ill. man he found the [»assage easy to mind in nature. fLamilton erred in discouraging all other theistic proof. But iiis argument is not without force, and it cannot be answered except by teaching physical determinism. In other words, unless materialism succeeds in making men skeptical about their (^wn minds tliere will always be an open way from mind in man to the tnind of God. P). The Cosmoiaxjk'al Ak<;iment. Distinguish between the aigumeiit based on order and that based on filial causes. All cases of tinalitv are instances 34 of orcU'r, l>ut all instances of onk'r arc not a(la[>tatioiis of moans to eiuls. Neither the eosmological nor the teleolog- ioal art^^ument is affected hy a nieclianieal ex[>lanation of the facts ot tlie world. In cosniolo2:ical ari::ument we see order and infer a plan antecedently existing in an intellio:ent mind. In the telcoloirical arii-nnient we see adai)tation of means to ends and infer finality, and also infer mind as the cause of that finality. The cosmological argument, that is to say, the argument based upon order, proceeds upon the assumption that order is the prochict of mind. The order of the world is a great fact. Time, number, I'utc, ratio and volume, are all matters oi most definite and precise nature, and the j»liysical world is an exhibition on the grandest scale of inalhematical relations. The fact of order is undeniable. Some ex]»lanation of the fact is demanded. Theism is the natural explanation. Those, how^ever, who deny the theistic inference offer the following sul)stitutes for it: 1. The theory of Chance. Suppose we were to concede the possibility that by a purely fortuitous concourse of atoms the cosmos might have resulted. How much would theism be damaged ? We should say that the credulity of the atheist was amazing. "Imagine," sa3's Venn, "some being not a creator, but a sort of demiurgus who has a quantity of materials put into his hand and he assigns them their collo- cations and lines of action l)lindly and at ha|)liazard ; what are the odds tliat sucli a world as we actually experience should have been brought about in this way?" His answer is that " all the paper which the world has hitherto produced would be used uji before we got far on the way in writing them down." '2. The theory of \n\\. The Duke of Argyll sliows in his Jiti(/n of ]j(iir how we advance from the mere conception of order to the idea of force or power in explanation of the (»nler. We are not satisfied to say that bodies move with a certain regularity — we seek an ex[)lanation of this regularity and embody it in a forninla. Then we are not satisfied with tiie formula — but we impute the fact to a force which we call the Law of ( Jravitation. I>ut however the word Law is used, it does not affect theism, for if it be not used in some transcendental way it means only tlie order of sequence. If it means more than order it is because it has been hypos- tatiscd and treated as an entity. So that the idea of law leaves us when' we wen,* before. We must be content to do 85 Avitlioiit ail o.\i>laiiali(Hi of the world's ordur, or wu must find an explanation in Thoisni. The world's order is proof of mind. '' That whirh it rerpiires thuni^ht and reason to understand nuist itself he thought and reason. That whieh mind alone can investiicate or e.xpress must l)e itself mind." This is liadi'ii i*oweli's way of |)Uttin<; the eosmoloirieal argument. 3. Theory of the persistence ol force. A mechanical oonception of the universe is in the highest degree theistie provided that mechanical conception does not include mind. The ohjection made hy Physicus proceeds upon the assump- tion that mind has a physical genesis. The theory of tlic persistence of fort-e, carried to its logical conclusions, re- duees the universe to nnitter and motion. If mind in man be denied, the Divine mind, ol course, will not he believed in. No proof of the Divine existenee can survive belief in the human mitid. The theory of the persistenee of force when earried the length of materialisti*! monism, blots out the theistie argument as Physicus shows. It l)lots out belief by blotting out the basis of belief But it blots out the possibility of rational belief in anything including the per- sistenee of foree. C. Tei.eolocical AR(^.UMENT. Commonly known as argument from final eause or design. By iinal eause is meant the end for whieh a thing or an event exists. Distinguislied tlius from etlieient eause which always means the agency by which anytliing is brought about. Following Janet wo consider the teleologieal argu- ment by instituting two inquiries : 1. Is finality a law of nature? 2. What is the cause of this finality? T. Is JimiUlu a Inir of jSatior? Consider lirst, the nature of the process by which we are led to believe that there are ends in nature: Secondly, the specific proofs in supj^ort of finality; Thirdly, the objections to the doctrine of finality. 1. Nature of teleologieal argument. Porter holds (in- clusively) that the idea of final cause is an intuition. Mill says that it is an inductive argument according to the method of agreement. The latter view jjrobably correct. We are unde'r no necessity to ask for the final cause as we are for the efiicient cause of every phenomenon. In teleo- logieal reasoning we argue analogically. The argument 36 lias two stages. In the tirst lAave we know from our expe- rience that a certain ideal future to be brouglit about stands rehited to certain means necessary to the accomplishing of this result. A and B are related to each other as means and ends. Passing from our own consciousness to tacts outside of consciousness we see phenomena related in a way that irresistibly suggests the relation of means and ends: we say B was the final cause of A. The tirst stage in the argument ends in the realization of linality as a law of nature. The phenomena of the world look as if they were respectively means and ends. The next question is as to the cause of the finality. Again we revert to our experience and since the only finality of which he have any knowledge is that of a purposing mind — in other words, since finality im[)lies intentionality in our conscious experience the in- ference from finality to intentionality is rational if not necessary. 2. Specific evidence of finality. The proof of finality con- sists in the cumulative force of a great multitude of as ifs. It looks as if the wide domain of nature were a great sys- tem of ideals, as if striving toward an end were the great characteristic of nature. To prove finality we begin with the purposive action of which we are ourselves conscious. Then we see actions of our fellow men which seem to be dictated by purpose and directed to attain an end. Descending a step, the actions of the lower animals irresistibly impress us as purposive. Lower still we come to a point where the action as definitely suggests adaptation though we do not credit the animal with intention. Analogy thus suggests that action with reference to results whether consciously or unconsciously is every where manifest throughout animal life. We turn then to the relation of organ to function ; the relation of the eye to vision. We find that there is a close and apparently premeditated relation between organ and organism, organism and environment. We argue: These adaptations are not accidents. They are intentional. They l)es|)eak pur|)ose and designing mind. The same teleologieal trend of things is manifest in the world. Things in the world sustain a relation of lower and higher. Finality in nature is proved by showing that there is the closest analogy between the relation of |)art and part, and part and whole, in tlie organic world, that there is between means and ends in the sphere of our purposive action. 37 n. ( )li)L'cti()iis to tin- (InctriiH- <.r tiiinl caiiHeH, 'riichf tall niMk'i' tliivc classrs. 1. Ii Trli'vant oltjcctioFis : {l>"n'rti<»n «1(U'> not apply l«> linal cause as a fact, Imt to the seardi tor tiiial cause as useieiilitic method. All that liaeoti says may l>e coneedejl. {!).) 80 of Dos Cartes' ohjeetion. lie says wean* ii^noraiit of ends. 80 we ari'. And if we were pretrndiiii; to know the final cause of every event tiie ohjretion would l»e val'Hl. (<'.) Irrelevant, also, the ol)jeetion that the doctrine ot' final cause assumes that man is the final cause ot' creation. It is surely not necessary to hold that every thinir was nuule for man, hecause man's eye was made for sci-inir. ((L) Nor can we ij^et rid of final cjiuse, hecause somi* have abused it. Some have treated every possihlc tisc of an origan as an intended use, and in tiiis wjjy have heaped ridicule upon teleoloiry. 2. Biological objections. It is said that the doctrine of final lause is hard to recon- cile with the rudimentary and useless organs to he found in animals. To this objection it is rejdied : 1. It is not affirmed that (fay detail of organization was meant to serve a useful purpose. '2. Wc do not know that an organ has no uses because we do not see its uses. 3. Obvious finality in a multitude (»f cases is not set aside by apparent lack of linality in other cases. 4. These rudimen- tary organs are explaimd)le without denying teleology; and by some are so ex[)lained so as to give emphasis to the teleological idea. 3. Objections urged by the anli-teleological evolutionists. Whether evolution be true is not the ut the more important question is, whether evolution, in itself considered, is or is not antagonistic to teleology. This (piestion lias been speciiically raised in regard to Dar- win's doctrine of the Orifjia of Species. Upon this subject two things are to be said : (a.) That the unmodified Darwinian doctrine of tendency to indetinite variation in all directions as the foundation of species ends in giving us a chance world, so far as biology is concerned. It is anti-teleological, therefore. {h) That if variation be not in all directions; if there has been a law of variation ; a law of selection manifest ; if it is in accordance with some inner law of development that the present system of ordered life has grown up, there is a teleological principle evidently at work in nature. This view is held by nuiny, and this is what Janet means when he aifirnis that the doctrine of evolution cannot dispense with teleology. //. \V/"i/ is Ihe Expkinatlon of the Finality in Nature. To this (jucstion four answers have been given: 1. Sub- jective tinality. •!. Immanent finality. 3. Unconscious fin- ality. 4. Intentional tinality. 1. Subjective finality. This is Kant's doctrine which Jani't interprets to mean, that w^hile tinality is a necessary liypothesis given the conformation of the human mind, nothing warrants us to suppose that this hypothesis has an objective foundation in reality. Tliis is simply the doctrine of relativity. Upon this we remark : {(I.) If we were under the necessity of seeing hnality in every thitig, tlien subjective finality would be the best guarantee of objective finality. It would be an a priori ivwih. [h.) But there is no sucl) subjective necessity. And since we see finality in some tlTnigs and not in others, there must be some objective ground for this distinction. '1. Immanent tinality. The Hegelian doctrine affirms linality, but cre(lits it to the activity of luiture and denies a personal (iod. Kant paved the way for it by noticing two important points of distinction : First. That works of art and those of nature differ in this respect, that in the former 30 tlu' ai^oiit >iaiiiU (HiLsidf di Ins work; whili- iii naturr it in aiiu'reiit. Xaimi' lias a torinative, reparative ami repro- \- the woi'd maN' l)e considered under two heads. A. The Ethical Argument. Vro\'. Fhnt (h)es not think tliat tlie moral arij^ument is con- cerned with the questions now under discussion regarding' the genesis of conscience. His position seems to be that we must choose between theism and absolute slcepticism. If conscience tells the truth there is moral obligation and a moral governor; if conscience does not tell the truth authoritative morality is at an end. Professor Flint is probably wrong in supposing that this theistic discussion can ignore current debate on Ethical questions. The great topics of Ethical study are: 1. Duty; 2. The Good; 3. Virtue. {Janet Moral Science.) I. Ethical Argument Based on Idea of Duty. The two ideas under duty are Dtight and rif//tL If these ideas are ultimate, the theistic inference is natural. It i» held by some that they are not ultimate. Thus : 1. Some, as Schopenhauer, say there is no legitimate place in ethics for the word duty. It is claimed that we may describe' men as they are, and classify them as kind or cniel^ but tluit the word ought has no meaning. 2. The ideas ought and right are held to be derived from T^aw (Ilol)bes, Bain). Conscience is an imitation in the individual life of the social forces without. A human gov- ernment is a system of conimands and penalties. Moral law is derived from it. Ought means the expedient. A feeling that I ought not, is only " a strong sense of avoid- ance " — a dread of penalty. No theistic inference from Idea of I>nty, if this be (.'orrect view. 8. The rtilitarian theory. (Hentham, .Mill.) Kgoistic Hedonism makes that conduct right which makes me happy. 41 UniviMsalistic Hedonism ooiisidtTs tin* i^rcatrst liappiiie«rt of the greatest nuinl)cr. To K^oist'u- Hedonist von say, '*('()n- e«'k tlie i^ri-atest happinesH of the greatest numlicr." Hr postnhiti's ohhi;ati(»n in the Utilita- rian nnixim. Uiit Im- does not explain it. Kxplained it must he, liowevei-, it" intuitive morality is to i»e rtuecessfully attacked. Utilitarianism has t(> settle first whether tlie '' ^reatCHt Iiappiness" tin-mnla is a i^eiierali/ation expressiiiLC afi altru- istic instinct or a generalization expressing an altruistic duty. If the former, it ii^nores the idea of ouLrhtness ; if the latter, it postulates it. In neither case does it explain it. 4. The Kthics of evolution. .\ccordin<; to this theory, morality is simply the conduct necessary to the continued existence of society. It may he asked, however, first: how it happens that the idea of ohli«ration has i)een evolved in coimection with the evolution of a morality, which is only one of expediency. Second : what is to he said to the nnm who is told not to do wroni^ hecause (h)in«^ wroni^ will dam- age social tissue, if he says that he (h)es not care anythiui^ about social tissue ? Evolution ethics cannot he ()hli«xatory ; but evolutionists cannot get rid of the fact that the idea of obliscation is here. The word oue^ht is a stumhliuir-hlock in the way of all empirical thinkers. We i^rant that if oui^ht could he reduce(l to lower terms, it would he hard to l)ase a theistic ari^ument apon it. But the attempt so to reduce it has hitherto proved unsuccessful. The same may l)e said tor the word right. Oughtness and Rightness are the two irreducihle words concerned in the idea of duty. To what do they point ? 1. Some stop with the consciousness of ohiigation, and see no theistic implications in it. Tliey recognize the cat- egorical imperative as a psychological fact, without attempt- ing any metaphysical inferences. 2. Some say that Right means conformity to the fitness of things. -3. Some hold that there is a principle of right to which God and all moral things are coordinately related. 4. Others, again, say that morality depends upon the Divine will. 42 o. Wo holii've that the ideii of ouii^htiiess and Tightness hoth witness to tlio Divine existence. Assuming that God exists as a moral governor, these ideas would he the natural correlatives of that truth. The sense of oughtness would he tlie natural correlative of man's relati()n to God as a moral governor, and the sense of Tight- ness the natural correlative to God as the norm and model of his moral existence. II. Kthical Ar(Ument Based upon the Idea oe the Good. By the Good is meant the Desirable. What is the rela- tion of Good to Duty? (t. Does Duty supersede the Good? Is it not possible to have a law of duty defining conduct and also an unrealized ideal inspiring it? Duty, as a matter of experience, does not supersede Good. b. Is the Good subordinated to Duty ? Can we say the desirable is doing Right? Though Duty be regardless of consequences, consequences enter largely into the motives of life. There is in life an aspiration after the ideal as well as conformity to law. c. Can the Dutiful be subordinated to the Good? Is obligation conditioned by consequences? Can we say that we ought to do right because doing Right makes for our highest happiness? Xo. This resolves obligation into ex- pediency. This substantially is Janet's system of " rational Eudemonism." Duty and Good are coordinate. Both have place. What then is the (iood ? What is the Desirable? Is it wealthy power, iame, luxury? [n short is it pleasure? Suppose with Descartes and othei-s, we say it is the perfection of our being and its accom[)anying ha[)i>iness, then there is an ideal that we desire to realize? There is an ideal (lood. What are we to infer? The Pessimist will say that this is the misery of human nature that it sighs after unrealizable ideals. But if we ai'e not pessimists we shall regard the ii'resisti- ble idea of the (jood as prophetic of its realization. This caji only l)e if we are immortal. Immortality therefore, Hays Kant, is a postulate of our n)oral nature. This can oidy l)e through the agency of a purposing and all-con- trolling Being wlio shapes all ends. (Jod, says Kant, is the postulate of our nioi-al nature. 43 It is hard to sojmrate the thoiiLcht ot an ideal (iood as the iiieasiire of our pei'Cer'tion tVom tliat ot an Ahsohiti' (tood as of a heiiii^ wlio realizes ill liimselfall perfection. Seedaiiet: MordI Sriowi. Harris: l*liil()soi)hi((tl llnsis of Tlnism. Attain : The idea ot Duty re<^ardless of e()nse(iueiK'e8 and tlie idea of the Good eoneerned altogether with consequences are hoth factors in our moral life. They niiglit he in con- flict. Su})j)ose tlie felicitic conduct were tlie uronir conduct. Suppose doing right always made us miserahle. Ifow does it haj)pen that duty and the gocxl are in such complete accord ? We get hai)[)iness hy doing right, yet we are not to do right for the sake of happiness. 'Jlieism will account for this harmony. AV'^e do not know how otherwise it can be accounted for. If God proposes to hring about the blessed perfection of the individual it is not strange that what with Him is an end should be foreshadowed in man as the good. And if this perfection is to be brought about through per- formance of right conduct it is not strange there should be this harmony between Duty and Good. in. Ethical Ar(;ument Based on Idea of Virtie. Duty says what we ought to do. The Good wliat we de- sire to become. Virtue is the realization of Duty in cliar- acter. Under the word Virtue we have not the bare category Right, but the category tilled with content. We say this or that is right. How has this category of Right been tilled? How, for cxamj)le, do we know that trutli telling is right ? Is it by Intuition, Revelation or P^volution ? If through the tirst or second the theistic inference will not be doubted. Supjiose it is l)y tlie thir(L Then how does it ha})i)en that the same pro- cess of evolution which has named as virtues the linesof con- duct most promotive of social well-lieing has also generated the feeling that well-being is not the reason ti)r performing the con(bict. IR>w does it hai^pen that evolution has singled out certain felicitic conduct as virtue and lias also generated the maxim of obligation which tells us to(h>. The Religious Argument. Under this would properly be discussed : 1. The psycho- loo-y of reliicion. 2. The metaphysical inferences. It would api^ear that religion is not exclusively a matter of intellect, feelins: or life, but the synthesis of all. And the inference to a being the objective counterpart of the universal religi- ous tendency would be the outcome of the common argu- ment E coKsensa (jotiiinii. Division HI. Aikjument Based on the Idea of the Infinite. Distinguish between (1) the idea of the infinite, and (2) the theistic signiticance of the idea. 1. The iut whatever the conditions under which the idea emerges as a fact of consciousness, it complies with the canons of intuitionalism. The idea is not limited in applica- tion to time and space. We cannot conceive of any degree of knowledire as exhausting the knowable. We speak of infinite truth, holiness, justice. So used, the word infinite does not differ much from the perfect or the absolute. We cannot realise dependent, finite, contingent existence with- out tiiinking of infinite, perfect, absolute existence. We cannot conceive the infinite in the sense of making a mental image of it. On the other hand and in another sense, we cannot help conceiving of it. 2. Its Tiikistic Skinificanck. 1. Sc'lic'llini'" tanii:lit llial llic iiifiiiilc or absolute in iiiiuio- diatoly known. This view was repeated l»y Sir William Hamilton, wiio sliowed that aeeordini^ to tiie delinitioiis of the words absolute and infinite, the iidinite cannot know and cannot he known; cannot, because that a knowin«j: absolute and a known absolute, is no absolute at all. 2. Hamilton's doctrine of Xescieiice. See I)r. Ilod^^e's chai)ter, Can God be Knoicn? ILunilton tries to show that wo can have no knowledge of God; that we must take our choice between inconceivables, witli tiie assurance that these inconceivaldes being conti'adictory lu'opositions, one or the other must be ti'ue ; and ha\in