GlpghtN" COPWIGHT DEPOSIT. Part h Price, 25 cents, ELEMENTS OF PSYCHOLOGY, WITH SPECIAL APPLICATIONS TO THE ART OF TEACHING. ON THE BASIS OF "OUTLINES OF PSYCHOLOGY" FOR THE USE OF NORMAL SCHOOLS, HIGH SCHOOLS, TEACHERS' READING CIRCLES, AND STUDENTS GENERALLY. BY JAMES SULLY, M. A. NEW YORK: D. APPLETON AND COMPANY I, 3, AND 5 BOND STREET. 1886. FOUR VALUABLE BOOKS FOR TEACHERS. Education: Intellectual, Moral, and Physical. By IIerbert Spencer. 12mo, cloth, $1.25. Cheap edition, 12mo, paper, 50 cents. Contents : I, What Knowledge is of Most Worth ? II. Intellectual Educa- tion ; III. Moral Education ; IV. Physical Education. •' The keynote of this treatise is, that Nature has a method of intellectual, moral, and physical development, which should afford the guiding principles of all teaching. Its wise suggestions— for there is nothing dogmatic in its pages- are the result of not a little keen observation, and it has become an authority, because its indications liave been attested by common sense and verified as true by experience.'"— JVew York Mail. Education as a Science. By Alexander Bain, LL. D., Professor of Logic in the University of Aberdeen. (Forming a volume of " The International Scientific Series.") 12mo, cloth, $1.75. Contents: I. Scopeof the Science of Education ; II. Bearings of Physiology ; III. Bearinsrs of Pt-ycholoL'y ; IV. Terms explained; V. Education Values; VI. Sequence of Subjects: Psychological; VII. Sequence of Subjects: Logical: VIII. Methods; IX. The Mother Tongue; X. The Value of the Classics; Xf. The Renovated Curriculum ; XII. Moral Education ; XIII. Art Education; XIV. Proportions. Appendix, Further Examples of the Object-Lesson, Passing Ex- planations of Terms. Principles and Practice of Teaching. By James Johonnot. 12mo, cloth, $1.50. Contents: I. What is Education; II. The Mental Powers: their Order of Development, and the Methods most conducive to Normal Growtli ; III. Objec* live Teachiuii : its Methods, Aims, and Principles; IV. Subjective Teaching: its Aims and Place in the Course of Instruction ; V. Object-Lessons : their Value and Limitations ; VI. Relative Value of the Different Studies in a Course ot In- struction ; VII. Pfstalozzi, and his Contributions to Educational Science; VIIL Froebel and the Kindergarten ; IX. As'assiz ; and Science in its Relation to Teaching ; X. Contrasted Systems of Education ; XL Physical Culture ; XII. Esthetic Culture ; XIII. Moral Culture ; XIV. A Course of Study . XV. Coun* try Schools. The Art of School Management. A Text-book for Normal Schools and Normal Institutes, and a Reference- book for Teachers, School-officers, and Parents. By J. Baldwin, President of the State Normal School, Kirksville, Missouri. 12mo, cloth, $1.50. ^ Contents: I. Educational Instrumentalities ; II. School OrL^anizatioo ; 111. School Govpmment; IV. Course of Study and Programme; V. Study and Teaching; VI. Class Management and Class WorK; VII. Management of Graded Schools : VIIL Grading, Examinations. Records, and Reports ; IX. Profes- sional Education ; X. Educational Systems, Educational Progress, and School Siipemsion. ^ D. APPLET ON &> CO., Publishers, I, 3, 6- 5 Bond St., New York. WORKS BY JAMES SULLY. STUDIES OF CHILDHOOD. 8vo. O-^h. $2.50. "A storehouse of anecdotes and observations o — London Journal 0/ Education. CHILDREN'S WAYS. i2mo. Cloth, A condensation of "Studies of Childhood," revised. OUTLINES OF PSYCHOLOGY. New edition, re- vised and largely rewritten. i2mo. Cloth, I2.50. TEACHER'S HANDBOOK OF PSYCHOLOGY. On the Basis of " Outlines of Psychology." Abridged by the author for the use of Teachers, Schools, Read- ing Circles, and Students generally. i2mo. 590 pages. Cloth, ILLUSIONS: A Psychological Study. i2nio. 372 pages. Cloth, $1.50. PESSIMISM: A History and a Criticism. Second edition. 8vo. 470 pages and Index. Cloth, $4.00. THE HUMAN MIND. A Text-Book of Psychology. Svo. 2 vols. Cloth, $5.00. D. APPLETON & COMPANY, Publishers, New York. ELEMENTS OF PSYCHOLOGY, WITH SPECIAL APPLICATIONS TO THE ART OF TEACHING. ON THE BASIS OF "OUTLINES OF PSYCHOLOGY" FOR THE USE OF NORMAL SCHOOLS, HIGH SCHOOLS, TEACHERS' READING CIRCLES, AND STUDENTS GENERALLY. h Oy''\'(\ ./by V JAMES SULLY, M. A. NEW YORK: D. APPLETON AND COMPANY, I, 3, AND 5 BOND STREET. 1886. Copyright, 1886, By D. APPLETON AND COMPANY. PUBLISHERS' EXPLANATORY NOTE. The issue of a portion of Sully's new work in this form makes necessary the following explanation. Mr. Sully's large text-book, *' The Outlines of Psy- chology," published in 1884, gave such prominence to the application of psychology to education as to suggest the desirability of separating this portion from the main text, and issuing it in a cheaper and more convenient form for general use of teachers. As soon as this demand became apparent, the publish- ers at once communicated with Mr. Sully upon the sub- ject, and he replied that an abridgment of this kind was a thing he had already purposed to do, and would imme- diately undertake the work and complete it without delay, so that it might be ready the first of the year, as intended, and the announcement was widely published. Nothing has been permitted to hinder the progress of the work, but it has been found impossible to issue it in satisfactory shape as soon as anticipated. In the mean time, the publishers were repeatedly ap- plied to by those who wanted to be commissioned to edit the new edition of the " Outlines." The invariable reply to these parties was, that the author himself was the proper one to be consulted about any abridgment or reshaping of his own work, and, if he consented to do it, no proposi- tion for the publication of other editions could be enter- iv PUBLISHERS' EXPLANATORY NOTE. tained ; nor would they consent to issue any abridgment of his larger work without his approval and sanction. This explanation in most instances was satisfactory, and the propriety of it recognized ; but one of these parties has unwarrantably appropriated Mr. Sully's brain-work, and, having secured a publisher, has brought out an un- authorized abridgment of the original work. It is unnecessary to comment on this proceeding, but this explanation is due to the many teachers, members of reading circles, and others, who have been waiting for the promised abridgment of Sully's " Psychology." The present pamphlet contains a part of the author's abridg- ment, already adopted by the reading circles and normal classes that have thus far prescribed Sully's work, and it is therefore the only authorized edition published or to be published, and in many important respects is a new and improved book. The complete volume will be ready with- in a few weeks, and will be promptly announced. D. Appleton & Co. January, 1886. ELEMENTS OF PSYCHOLOGY, CHAPTER I. PSYCHOLOGY AND EDUCATION. Art and Science. — The doing of anything presup- poses some knowledge, for every action is the employment of certain agencies which stand in the relation of means to our particular end or object of desire ; and we could not select and make use of these means unless we knew be- forehand that they were fitted to bring about the fulfill- ment of our desire. This is evident even in the case of simple actions. Thus, if after sitting reading for some time and becoming cold I go out and take a brisk walk, it is because I know that by so doing I am certain to recover warmth. And it is still more manifest in the case of com- plex actions. The action of an engineer, of a surgeon, or of a statesman, involves a quantity of knowledge of vari- ous kinds. The knowledge which is thus serviceable for doing things or for practice is of two sorts. Thus, the knowl- edge implied in the above example, that muscular exercise promotes bodily warmth, may be knowledge that I have gathered from my own experience aided by what others have told me ; or it may have been obtained from a study of the bodily organism and its functions, and of the effects of muscular activity on the circulation, etc. The first kind of knowledge, being derived from what may be called un- 2 PSYCHOLOGY AND EDUCATION. revised experience and observation, is called empirical ; the second kind, being the outcome of those processes of re- vision and extension of every-day empirical knowledge which make up the work of science, is named scientific. The chief differences between empirical and scientific knowledge are the following: (i) The former is based on a narrow range of observation, and on observation which is apt to be loose and inexact ; the latter, on a wide survey of facts and on accurate processes of observation and ex- periment. (2) The former consists of propositions which have only a limited scope, and are never, strictly speaking, universally true ; the latter is made up of propositions of wide comprehensiveness, and of universal validity, known as principles or laws. (3) As a result of this the conclusions deduced from empirical knowledge are precarious, whereas the conclusions properly drawn from scientific principles are perfectly trustworthy. We call any department of practice an art when the actions involved are of sufficient complexity and difficulty to demand special study, and to offer scope for individual skill. Thus, we talk now of an art of cooking, because with our advanced civilization the preparation of food has become so elaborate a process as to call for special prepa- ration or training. Every art requires a certain amount and variety of knowledge. In the early stages of development the vari- ous arts were carried on by help of empirical knowledge. Thus, in agriculture men sowed certain crops rather than others in given soils, because they and their predecessors had found out from experience that these were the best fitted. Similarly in medicine, men resorted at first to par- ticular remedies in particular diseases, because their prac- tical experience had taught them the utility of so doing. Such guidance from empirical sources was found to be insufficient. Workers in the various departments of art asked for a deeper knowledge of the agencies they em- ART AND SCIENCE. 3 ployed and the processes they carried out, and so they had recourse to science. Thus the art of agriculture has profited from the sciences of chemistry and botany, and the art of medicine from the sciences of anatomy and physiology. Indeed, the demand for a fuller and more exact knowledge on the part of practical workers has been an important stimulus to the development of the sciences. The reason of this is plain from what has been said above. The characteristic imperfections of empirical knowledge become more and more manifest as an art de- velops. And these defects are the more conspicuous in the case of the more complex arts, and particularly those which have to do with living things. This is clearly illus- trated in the case of medicine. The organic processes going on in the human body are so numerous and compli- cated, there are so many variable circumstances which help to modify a disease in different cases, and so to inter- fere with a simple uniform effect of any given remedial agency, that the generalizations based on practical experi- ence are continually proving themselves to be inadequate and precarious. The great modern improvements in the art of healing have been the direct outcome of the growth of the sciences underlying the art. Hence we have come to employ in the case of all the more complex and intricate departments of practice the expression *' science and art." Thus we talk of the sci- ence and art of engineering, of agriculture, and even of politics. To this pair of correlated terms there corre- sponds the equally familiar couple, " theory and practice." For the term theory in this connection refers more par- ticularly to the principles or truths of a scientific rank which stand at the foundation of the art. It is important to understand the precise place and function of these scientific principles in their relation to practice. First of all, then, they do not take the place of empirical generalizations. These are at first, as already 4 PSYCHOLOGY AND EDUCATION. remarked, the only knowledge by which an art can guide itself ; and they always continue to form a valuable part of every theory of a practical subject. Science alone would never have taught men the best way to till the ground, to obtain metal from the soil, or to carry out any other set of industrial operations. The function of scien- tific principles is to supplement, interpret, and, where necessary, correct empirical knowledge. In this way the teaching of practical experience is rendered more precise and certain. But science renders to art a yet greater service than this. It greatly enlarges the range of practical discovery. When once we have our scientific principles we can de- duce practical conclusions from these, and thus anticipate the slow and uncertain progress of empirical discovery. Thus, in the art of surgery, the modern method of treating wounds is largely the direct outcome of scientific reflec- tion on the nature of wounds and of the natural process of healing. Such deductions must, of course, be verified by actual experiment before they can take their place among the assured body of knowledge making up the theory of the subject. So that here, too, the theory of a practical operation is constituted by two factors — an em- pirical and a scientific. The only difference between this case and the first is that here the work of science precedes instead of following the work of experience, and, in place of having to supplement and interpret this, has to be sup- plemented and verified by it. Art and Science of Education.— The above re- marks may help us to understand the fact that the art of education is now seeking to ground itself on scientific truths or principles. As an art, education aims at the realization of a par- ticular end. This end must, of course, be assumed to be clearly defined before we can repair to science to ascertain what agencies we can best employ in order to compass it. ART AND SCIENCE OF EDUCATION. 5 At first sight, however, it might seem that this condition is not satisfied. Writers have discussed at length what the true end of education is, and they have proposed very dif- ferent definitions of the matter. The reason of this uncertainty is apparent. Educa- tion, unlike such an art as cookery, has a large and com- prehensive object, viz., to help to mold and fashion in cer- tain definite ways no less complex a thing than a human being, with his various physical, intellectual, and moral capabilities, so as to fit him to fulfill his highest function and destiny. And to ascertain what the rightly fashioned man is like, and wherein consists his true work and serv- ice, is a problem of much difficulty. In truth, we can only satisfactorily settle this when we have determined the supreme ends of human action — in other words, the highest good of man. It is the province of the great practical science of ethics to ascertain this for us ; and the teachers of this science have from ancient times been divided into opposed schools. We need not, however, wait for the resolution of these grave and difficult problems. Men are to a large extent practically agreed as to what is right and wrong, though they have not settled the theoretic basis of these distinc- tions. In like manner educators are practically at one as to the' objects they aim at. In spite of ethical and theological differences, we agree to say that education seeks, by social stimulus, guidance, and control, to develop the natural powers of the child, so as to render him able and disposed to lead a healthy, happy, and morally worthy life. This is offered only as a rough approximation to a definition which may be generally accepted. In filling out this idea, different thinkers would no doubt diverge considerably, according to their conception of man's nature and destiny. Thus, to the firm believer in the Christian doctrine of a future life it must appear of the first consequence to de- velop those religious faculties and emotions the exercise of which con- stitutes man's highest function and the direct preparation for the larger 6 PSYCHOLOGY AND EDUCATION. and enduring after-life. But, while fully recognizing the truth that religious belief must throughout profoundly color a man's conception of the scope of education and the relative value of its several parts, one may assume that in practice educators of widely unlike theological views agree as to the main lines of education in its distinctly human aspects. A word or two as to the scope of our definition. In the first place, we take education as aiming at the formation of faculty, rather than at the giving of information or the communication of knowledge. In other words, education, as the etymology of the word tells us (Lat., educere), has to do with drawing out, i. e., developing the mind and its various activities, and not merely with putting something into the mind. This distinction is often spoken of as that between education and in- struction. But the word instruction (Lat., instruere) implies the orderly putting together of the materials of knowledge so as to form a structure. And, taken in this sense, there is no fundamental opposition between the two. The faculties of the intelligence can only be called forth and strengthened in the processes of gaining knowledge, and thus " educa- tion attains its end through instruction." The teacher may, however, fix his mind more on the educative result of his processes, viz., the ability to observe and reason about facts in the future, or on the im- mediate gain of school exercises in the shape of useful knowledge. And this difference in the teacher's point of view will deeply affect his ideas as to proper subjects to be taught, and even as to the best method of teaching them. Finally, it is to be noted that our definition does not stop short at the intellectual side of the mind, but includes the other sides as well. The supposition that education is only concerned with the intellectual faculties probably has its source in the common error that the educator and the schoolmaster are synonymous terms, whereas in reality the latter is only one among many educators. And even the schoolmaster will err if he thinks his business ends with a mere intellectual discipline of his pupils. But, while our definition is thus a wide one, it is less wide than that of some thinkers, e. g., J. S. Mill, who included under education the influence of external circumstances generally. Education is to us essentially the action of other human beings on the child, and this only so far as it is conscious and designed. Moreover, in its higher forms, education implies a systematic application of external forces and agen- cies according to a definite plan and an orderly method.* * On the difference between education and instruction, see Prof. Payne's " Lectures on the Science and Art of Education," Lecture I, ART AND SCIENCE OF EDUCATION. y As soon as we approximate to a definition of educa- tion, as in the above, we see that merely empirical knowl- edge will carry us but a little way in realizing our object. For the human nature which it is our special business to develop is plainly the most complex of all living things. It is at once something material and something mental ; and this mental part, again, is exceedingly composite in its constitution, being made up of a number of intellectual and moral capabilities and dispositions. Nor is this all ; we find that these several physical and mental powers are joined together and interact upon one another in a very intricate and puzzling manner. Closely connected with this peculiar complexity of the child's nature, we have its great variability, showing itself in the unique constitution or idiosyncrasy of each individual child. Owing to these circumstances, mere experience could never have led men far on the right educational path. And as a matter of history we know that the older methods of educating the young were faulty, and in some respects radically wrong, just because they were not arrived at by aid of a profound and scientific study of child-nature. Thus, to take an obvious instance, the cardinal error of making so much of intellectual instruction dry and unpalatable arose out of ignorance of the elementary truth of human nature, that the intellectual faculties are only fully aroused to activity under the stimulus of feeling in the shape of interest. That this was the real source of the blunder is proved by the fact that the modern educational reformers, who have set themselves to correct this and other defects of the older system, were guided to these reforms by a deeper study of children's minds. This remark applies alike to the ideas of practical workers, as Pestalozzi, and of pure theorists, as Locke.* p. i3, etc. On some alternative definitions of education, see Dr. Bain's " Education as a Science," chap. i. * On the effects of an ignorance of psychology in rendering con- 8 PSYCHOLOGY AND EDUCATION. What is really wanted as the groundwork of education is a body of well-ascertained truths respecting the funda- mental properties of the human being, from which the right and sound methods of training the young may be seen to follow as conclusions. This theoretic basis will consist of facts and laws relating to the child's physical and mental organization, its various susceptibilities, its ways of reacting on external agents and influences, and the manner in which it develops. And these universal truths must be supplied by some science or sciences. Divisions of Educational Science. — These prin- ciples are derived in the main from two sciences : physi- ology, or the science which treats of the bodily organism, its several structures and functions, and psychology, or mental science which deals with the mind, its several fac- ulties and their mode of operation. The former princi- ples, including certain applications of physiological science known as hygiene, underlie what is now called physical education, the training of the bodily powers and the fur- therance of health. The latter form the basis of mental — i. e., intellectual and moral — training. Within the limits of mental education we have certain subdivisions. Popularly we distinguish between intellect- ual and moral education ; but this twofold division is in- adequate. As we shall see by and by, the mind presents three well-marked and fundamental departments — viz., the intellect, the emotions, and the will. The develop- ment of it on any one of these three sides is to a certain extent a separate work, calling for its own particular mode of exercise, and, one may add, its own peculiar fitness in the teacher. These three directions of training are dis- tinguishable as intellectual, aesthetic, and moral education. They correspond to the three great ends: (i) the logical end of truth, (2) the aesthetic end of beauty, and (3) the temporary educational practices faulty and even vicious, see Herbert Spencer, " Education," chap, i, p. 24, and following. DIVISIONS OF EDUCATIONAL SCIENCE. 9 ethical end of virtue. The first aims at building up the fabric of knowledge, and developing the faculties by which knowledge is reached ; the second, at such a cultivation of the feelings as will best subserve the end of a pleasurable existence, and in particular the appreciation and enjoy- ment of beauty in nature and art ; and the third, at devel- oping the will and forming the character. In giving this assistance to education, psychology is supplemented by three sciences which are not purely theoretical like it, but have a more practical character, since they have as their special province to regulate the activity of the mind on each of these three sides. These are logic, which regulates our intellectual operations by supplying us with rules for correct reasoning ; aesthetics, which aims at giving us a standard of beauty and criteria by which we may judge of its existence in any instance ; and ethics, which fixes the ultimate standard of right and wrong, and determines what are the several duties and virtues. The scientific groundwork of the art of education may be made clear by the following diagram : Physical. n Physiolo^ together with Hygiene. Fig. I. Education. Mental. n Psychology- together with Logic, ^Esthetics, and Ethics. lO PSYCHOLOGY AND EDUCATION. Psychology and Education. — Of the sciences that contribute principles to education, psychology is plainly the most important. The teacher is most directly con- cerned with the development of the child's mind, and con- siders his bodily organism mainly in its connection with mental efficiency. / / Again, since the teacher is commonly supposed to have as his principal object the exercise of certain of the intel- lectual faculties — viz., those employed in the acquisition and retention of knowledge — it is clear that some portions of psychology will be of special value to him. Thus the laws governing the processes of acquiring and reproduc- ing knowledge will have a peculiarly direct bearing on the teacher's work. Such truths of mental science would seem to be specially fitted to supply principles of education. At the same time, it is clearly impracticable to select certain portions of psychology as exclusively applying to education. For, first of all, even allowing that education need busy itself only with instruction, or the communica- tion of so much useful knowledge, it may be said that the teacher still needs to study other faculties than the acquis- itive ; for psychology teaches us that no power of the mind works in perfect isolation. Thus, it has come to be recog- nized that, in order that a child should gain clear knowl- edge through words, his observing faculties must have undergone a certain discipline, so that his mind may have been stored with distinct and easily reproducible images of objects in his actual surroundings. Hence, one reason for including the training of the senses in modern systems of education. More than this, it will be found that there can be no adequate exercise of the intellect which does not take account of the feelings, in the shape of interest and a love of learning. It follows, then, that the teacher needs some general //acquaintance with the principles of psychology, even though he is aiming merely at the most rapid and effect- ADVANTAGE TO THE TEACHER. n ive method of storing the mind with knowledge. But it may be assumed that few teachers now limit their efforts to this object. Education, in its true sense, is commonly aimed at by intelligent teachers in the process of instruc- tion itself, which thus becomes, in a measure at least, a means to an end beyond itself. And some attention is paid, as time allows and opportunity suggests, to the cul- tivation of the feelings and the formation of good moral dispositions and habits. And this being so, a clear appre- hension of the different sides of mind, and of the way in which they interact one on another, may be said to be of immediate utiUty to the teacher. In other words, the principles of education must be derived from the element- ary truths of psychology taken as a whole. It follows, from what was said above concerning the relation of science to art, that there are two principal uses of mental science to the teacher : (i) An accurate ac- quaintance with the mental faculties, which are the mate- rial that the educator has to operate on and mold into shape, will supply him with a criterion or touchstone by which he may test the soundness of existing rules and practices in education. (2) the knowledge so gained may be made to directly suggest better educational rules than those in vogue, and so to promote the further devel- opment of the art. No doubt we may expect too much from a study of mental science. We may err by supposing that scientific knowledge will render practical or empirical knowledge superfluous, instead of merely supplementing and correct- ing it. And it may be well to remember, therefore, that, as a sciencej^psychology can only tell us what are the gen- eral characters of mind, and point out the best way of dealing with it in its general features and broad outlines ; it can not acquaint us with the manifold diversities of in- telligence and disposition, or suggest the right modifica- tions of our educational processes to suit these variations. 12 PSYCHOLOGY AND EDUCATION. Accordingly, the educator will always need to supplement his general study of mind by a careful observation of the individual minds which he is called upon to deal with, so as to properly vary and adapt his methods of teaching and disciplining. Even here, however, the student of psychology will find his scientific knowledge useful. For the work of get- ting to know an individual child is one not only of obser- vation but of interpretation. And in the performance of this a general acquaintance with mind will materially assist. It is evident, indeed, that we never understand an individual thing thoroughly except in the light of gen- eral knowledge. A botanist only comprehends a new plant when he classifies it — i. e., refers it to a general de- scription or head, and accounts for it by help of general botanical principles. Similarly we only understand a par- ticular child when we bring to bear on it a previous gen- eral knowledge of child and human nature. And while psychological knowledge thus aids us in reading the indi- vidual characters of children, it assists us further in deter- mining the proper modifications of our educational meth- ods to suit these variations^ Experience is without doubt our main guide here. Wh>at kind of punishment, for example, will be most efficacious and salutary for boys of a particular temperament, etc., is a problem which must be solved to a large extent by the results of actual trial. Still, our scientific principles are a valuable supplementary aid here also, not only by helping us to understand the different results of our educational treatment in different cases, but also by assisting us in lighting upon the required modifications. APPENDIX. On the scope and aim of education and its special relation to psy- chology, the student may consult : Prof. Payne's " Lectures on the Sci- ence and Art of Education," Lectures I and II ; Dr. Bain's " Education as a Science," chap, i ; Th. Waitz's " Allgemeine Padagogik," Ein- leitung, § I. CHAPTER II. SCOPE AND METHOD OF PSYCHOLOGY. Psychology, or mental science, may be defined as our general knowledge of mind, and more particularly the human mind, reduced to an exact and systematic form. In order to understand this definition, we must try to give precision to the term mind. Scientific Conception of Mind. — We commonly distinguish between a mind as a unity or substance and the several manifestations or phenomena of this substance. In every-day discourse, indeed, we talk of our own and others' minds as the subjects of various feelings, ideas, etc. Psychology as a science does not inquire into the nature of mind in itself, or as a substance, but confines itself to the study of its several states or operations. It is the different forms of activity of mind that we can observe in our actual mental experience or mental life that constitute the proper subject-matter of our science. And it is plain that this knowledge of the mind in actual operation, and of the various ways in which it manifests itself and works, is what we need for practical guidance, whether of our own or of others' minds. How, now, shall we mark off these mental facts from other phenomena which form the subject-matter of the physical sciences.'* We can not define such states of mind by resolving them into something simpler. They have nothing in common beyond the fact of being mental states. 14 SCOPE AND METHOD OF PSYCHOLOGY. Hence, we can only use some equivalent phrase, as when we say that a mental phenomenon is a fact of our con- scious experience or conscious life. Or, again, we may enumerate the chief varieties of these mental phenomena, and say that mind is the sum of our processes of knowing, our feelings of pleasure and pain, and our voluntary do- ings. Popularly, mind is apt to be identified with know- ing or intelligence. A man of mind is a man of intellect. But though intelligence is perhaps the most important part of mind, it is not the whole. In mental science we must reckon the sensation of pain arising from a bruise as a fact of mind. Or, finally, we may set mind in antithesis to what is not mind. Mind is non-material, has no exist- ence in space as material bodies have. We can not touch a thought or a feeling, and one feeling does not lie outside of another in space. These phenomena occur in time only. Hindis thus the inner smaller world (mikrokosm) as distin- guished from the external and larger world (makrokosm). Mind and Body. — While it is important thus to set mind in strong opposition to material things, we must keep in view the close connection between the two. What we call a human being is made up of a bodily organism and a mind. Our personality or " self " is a mind connected with or embodied in a material framework. As we shall see presently, all mental processes or operations are con- nected with actions of the nervous system. The most abstract thought is accompanied by some mode of activity in the brain-centers. Hence, while we must be careful not to confuse the mental and the material, the psychical and the physical, as though they were of the same kind (homogeneous), we can not exclude the latter from view in dealing with mind. We must always think of mind as attended by, and, in some inexplicable way, related to, the living organism, and more particularly the nervous system and its. actions. And this recognition of this close and constant companionship with body is a matter of great HOW WE OBSERVE AND STUDY MIND, 15 practical moment in seeking to train and , develop the mind. The Subjective Method.— There are two distinct ways of knowing mind. The first is the direct, internal, or subjective way.* By this method we direct attention to what is going on in our own mind at the time of its oc- currence, or afterward. We have the power of turning the attention inward on the phenomena of mind. Thus we can attend to a particular feeling, say emulation or sympathy, in order to see what its nature is, of what ele- mentary parts it consists, and how it is affected by the circumstances of the moment. This method of internal or subjective observation is known as introspection (" looking within "). The Objective Method.~In the second place, we may study mental phenomena not only in our own indi- vidual mind, but as they present themselves externally in other minds. This is the indirect, external, or object- ive way of studying mental phenomena. Thus we note the manifestations of others' feelings in looks, gestures, etc. We arrive at a knowledge of their thoughts by their speech, and observe their inclinations and motives by noting their actions. This objective observation embraces not only the mental phenomena of the individuals who are personally known to us, old and young, but those of others of whom we hear or read in biography, etc. Also it includes the study of minds in masses or aggregates, as they present themselves in national sentiments and actions, and in the events of history. It includes too a comparative study of mind by observing its agreements and differences among * "Subject" means the mind as knowing something, or as affected (pleasurably or painfully) by a thing. "Object" is that which is known, or which affects the mind in a certain way. The house I see, the flower I admire, are objects to me, who am the subject that sees and admires them. 1 6 SCOPE AND METHOD OF PSYCHOLOGY. different races, and even among different grades of ani- mal life. The study of the simpler phases of mind in the child, in backward and uncivilized races, and in the lower animals, is especially valuable for understanding the growth of the mature or fully developed human mind. Both Methods must be combined. — Scientific knowledge is characterized by certainty, exactness, and generality. We must observe carefully so as to make sure of our facts, and to note precisely what is present. And we must go on from a knowledge of the particular to a knowledge of the general. From this rough defini- tion of what is meant by scientific knowledge we may easily see that neither the internal nor the external method is complete without the other. To begin with : since we only directly observe what is passing in our own individual mind, some amount of introspection is the first condition of all certain and accurate knowledge of mental states. To try to discover mental phenomena and their laws solely by watching the external signs and effects of others' thoughts, feelings, and volitions, would plainly be absurd. For these external manifestations are in them- selves as empty of meaning as words in an unknown tongue, and only receive their meaning by a reference to what we ourselves have thought and felt. On the other hand, an exclusive attention to the contents of our indi- vidual mind would never give us a general knowledge of mind. In order to eliminate the effects of individuality, we must at every step compare our own modes of think- ing and feeling with those of other minds ; and the wider the area included in our comparison, the sounder are our generalizations likely to be. Each of these ways of studying mind has its character- istic difficulties. To attend closely to the events of our mental life presupposes a certain power of " abstraction." It requires at first a considerable effort to withdraw the attention from the more striking events of the external OBSERVATION OF CHILDREN'S MINDS. 17 world, the sights and sounds that surround us, and to keep it fixed on the comparatively obscure events of the inner world. Even in the case of the trained psychologist the work is always attended with a peculiar difficulty. On the other hand, there is a serious danger in reading the- minds of others, due to an excess of the propensity to project our own modes of thinking and feeling into them. This danger increases with the remoteness of the mind we are observing from our own. To apprehend, for example, the sentiments and convictions of an ancient Roman, or of an uncivilized African, is a very delicate operation. It implies close attention to the differences as well as the similarities of external manifestation, also an effort of imagination by which, though starting from some remem- bered experiences of our own, we feel our way into a new set of circumstances, new experiences, and a new set of mental habits. Observation of Children's Minds.— These diffi- culties are strikingly illustrated in the attempt to note and interpret the external manifestations of children's minds. This observation is of the greatest consequence to psy- chologists in general, for a sound knowledge of the early manifestations of mind is a necessary preliminary to a sci- entific explanation of its later developments. And to the educator this knowledge constitutes the most important department of the science of mind. Yet this is perhaps one of the most difficult branches of psychological inquiry. The reason of this can easily be seen. Children have their own characteristic ways of feeling, of regarding things, of judging as to truth, and so forth. And, al- though the adult observer of children has himself been a child, he is unable, except in rare cases, to recall his own childish experiences with any distinctness. How many of us are really able to recollect the wonderings, the terrors, the grotesque fancies of our first years ? And then chil- dren are apt to be misunderstood because they have to 1 8 SCOPE AND METHOD OF PSYCHOLOGY. use our medium of speech and often fail to seize its exact meaning. Nevertheless, these difficulties are not insuperable. They can be got over where there are present the qualifi- cations of a good observer and an earnest purpose. And it must be borne in mind that if there are special difficul- ties in the case, there are also special facilities. For chil- dren, as compared with adults, are frank in the manifesta- tion of their feelings, and free from the many little artifices by which their elders are wont, only half consciously perhaps, to disguise and transform their real thoughts and sentiments in expressing them to others. The special qualities needed for a close observation and deep understanding of the child-mind are good ob- serving habits and a strong, loving interest in childhood. Both of these are necessary. If we have only the first, we shall fail to see far into child-nature, just because we shall not take the trouble to place ourselves, in imagination, in the circumstances of children, so as to realize how they are affected by things. A warm, tender interest, leading to a habit of unfettered companionship, seems to be a condition of a fine imaginative insight into children's minds, and a firm grasp of the fact that their ways differ in so many particulars from our ways. On the other hand, if there is the kindly feeling without the trained faculty of observation, there is the risk of idealizing child- hood, and investing it with admirable traits that do not really belong to it. In the matter of child-observation the psychologist may look to the educators of the young, the parent and the teachers, for valuable aid. Some of the best observa- tions on the subject of the infant mind which we already possess have been contributed by fathers. And much may still be done by parents in the way of recording the course of development of individual children. At the same time, school-teachers, though coming into less inti- GENERAL KNOWLEDGE OF MIND. 19 mate relations with individual children, have the very great advantage of observing numbers. And from them we may reasonably ask for statistics of childhood. The dates at which certain faculties become prominent, the relative strength of the several feelings and impulses, the dominant intellectual and moral characteristics of children, these and other points are all matters about which teachers, who will take the trouble to note accurately, may be expected to supply the psychologists of the future with much valu- able knowledge.* General Knowledge of Mind. — As has been ob- served, science consists of general knowledge, or knowl- edge expressed in a general form. Hence, mental science seeks to generalize our knowledge of mind. In the first place, it aims at grouping all the phenomena observed under certain heads. That is to say, it classifies the end- less variety of mental states according to their resem- blances. In so doing it overlooks the individual differ- ences of minds and fixes attention on their common feat- ures. A sound scientific classification of mental states is a matter of practical importance, whether we are dealing with minds in the earlier or the later stages of develop- ment. Thus, the teacher will be in a far better position to deal with a child's mind, both in its several parts and as a whole, when he has reduced the tangle of mental manifestations to order and simplicity. In the second place, every science aims not only at ordering its phenomena, but at making certain assertions about them. There are general truths or laws which hold good of numerous varieties of phenomena. When the phenomena are occurrences in time, these laws have to do with the relation of events to other events preceding or * On the qualifications of an observer of children's minds, and on the literature of the subject, see the writer's Introduction to M. Perez's work, " The First Three Years of Childhood." London : W. Swan Son- nenschein & Co. 20 SCOPE AND METHOD OF PSYCHOLOGY. succeeding them. That is to say, they formulate the re- lations of causal dependence of phenomena on other phe- nomena. Mental science seeks to arrive at such truths or l^ws of mind. Its ultimate object is to determine the con^ ditions on which mental phenomena depend. Thus, the psychologist asks what are the conditions of retention, what are the circumstances which produce and favor the keeping of impressions in the mind. And it is this knowl- edge of conditions and of laws which is of greatest practi- cal value. For it is only by understanding how a mental product is formed that we can help in forming it, or inter- fere so as to modify the process of formation. Now, a little attention to the subject will show that mental phenomena are related in the way of dependence not only to other phenomena immediately preceding, but to remotely antecedent phenomena. For example, the quick response of a child to a command depends not only on certain present conditions, viz., attention to the words of the command, etc., but on past conditions, on the forma- tion of a habit, which process may have been going on for years. Hence, the consideration of relations of depend- ence leads on to the view of mind as a process of growth or development. The most important laws of mind, from the educator's point of view, are laws of mental development. Before we go on to consider the several groups of mental states in detail and the laws which govern them, we shall do well to look at mind from the physiological side, that is to say, at the way in which the mind as a whole is affected by its connection with the bodily organ- ism. This aspect of our subject will occupy us in the next chapter. APPENDIX. For a fuller account of the scope and method of psychology the reader is referred to my larger work, " Outlines of Psychology," Appen- dix A ; also to the works referred to in the appendix to Chapter II of that volume. CHAPTER III. MIND AND BODY. Connection between Mind and Body. — When we say that mind and body are connected, we are simply stating a fact of our every-day experience, and a fact which scientific observation and experiment are rendering more and more certain and precise. That is to say, we affirm that mental processes or operations are in some way conjoined with bodily operations. We do not make any assertion as to the ultimate nature of mind or of body, or seek to account for the apparent mystery of two things so utterly disparate as mind and body being thus united in one living being. These problems lie outside science altogether, and belong to the domain of philosophy or metaphysics. Keeping then to the phenofnena, or observable processes of mind and of body, we find first of all that these are clearly conjoined in time. That is to say, mental activity goes on along with bodily activity and always has this for its accompaniment. We know nothing of mental opera- tions that are unattended by physical changes in certain portions of the body. And some of these physiological processes appear to be perfectly simultaneous with the mental operations to which they correspond. In the second place, there is an apparent interaction between the mental and physical processes. As we shall see presently, there are certain organs of the body which are 3 22 MIND AND BODY. in a peculiar way subservient to the discharge of the several mental functions. According to their state at any- time will mental activity be lively or otherwise. More- over, by influencing these physical organs we may pro- duce changes in the correlated mental operations. Hence we are justified in speaking about these organs as the physiological support of mind, and of their activity as the condition of mental activity. On the other hand, mental processes react on the bodily organism. Thus excessive intellectual activity, violent grief, and so forth, are known to have far-reaching effects on the bodily functions. The Nervous System. — The particular organs which thus subserve our mental life are known as the nervous system, of which the brain is one of the most important parts. These are therefore known as the organs of mind.* The nervous system is a connected set of physio- logical structures, composed of a very fine or highly organized form of living matter. These fall into two main divisions : compact masses known as nerve-centers, lying protected within the bony covering of the skull and backbone ; and extensive thread-like ramifications known as nerves, connecting these central masses with outlying regions of the body. The nerves, which are bundles of exceedingly fine white fibers or threadlets, are the carrying portion of the nervous apparatus. They are of two classes. The first connect the centers with outlying surfaces, which are susceptible of being acted on by certain external agents or stimuli, such as mechanical pressure, heat, etc. Their function is to transmit the state of nervous activity pro- duced by this stimulation from the periphery to the center. Hence they are known as incarrying or afferent * The nervous system here means the cerebro-spinal system as dis- tinct from the sympathetic system which subserves the lower vital functions of the body. THE NERVOUS SYSTEM. 23 nerves. Since the central effect of this transmission of the active state is what we call a sensation, these nerves are also called sensory nerves, and the peripheral surfaces sensory surfaces. Such are the skin, the retina of the eye, etc. The other class of nerves connect the centers with muscles, or those bundles of fiber by the contractions of which the limbs are moved and the voice exercised. They carry nervous impulses from within outward,, and are known as outcarrying or efferent nerves. And since this outgoing activity immediately precedes and produces muscular contraction, and so movement, they are also called motor nerves. The nerve-centers are made up partly of gray masses having a minute cellular structure, and partly of bundles of nerve fiber, connecting these masses one with another, both laterally and longitudinally. They have as their peculiar function to transform sensory stimulation into movement, and to adjust the latter to the former ; also to bring to- gether the results of different sensory stimulations, and to ad- just complex groups of movements to groups of impression. These nerve-centers are arranged in a series or scale of growing complexity. The lower centers are those residing in the backbone and known as the spinal column. The higher centers lodged within the skull are called the brain. From this brief description of the nervous system, it will be seen that the general form of nervous action is a process of sensory stimulation followed by one of motor excitation. This may be represented by the diagram, Fig. 2. This scheme roughly answers to the simpler type of actions of ourselves as well as of the lower animals, the type known as reflex action, i. e., movement in immediate response to external stimulus. Thus, when a child asleep instantly withdraws his foot when this is pressed, the action is effected by means of the lower spinal centers. Such reflex actions, however, are not attended with any mental activity ; they are unconscious. 24 MIND AND BODY. Fig. 2. Sensory Surface 'Nerve-Centers* Muscles. The more complicated actions involve the co-operation of the brain as well. In this case we have to suppose that Fig. 3. Sensory Surface Higher Nerve-Centers. .1*1* Lower Nerve-Centers. Muscles. THE SPECIAL ORGANS OF MIND. 25 the sensory stimulation, instead of passing over at once into motor impulse, is propagated further, and engages a larger portion of the central structures. This may be represented by the diagram. Fig 3. Such complicated actions are accompanied by mental activity or consciousness. They may be illustrated by the act of relieving the pressure of a tight boot by stooping and taking it off. This action involves a distinct sensation of pressure, and the action of the will in resolving to get rid of the discomfort. The Special Organs of Mind. — We see from this that mental life is connected with the action of the higher centers, or the brain. Only when the brain is called to take part is there any distinct mental accompaniment. The brain thus stands in relation to the lower centers somewhat as the head of an office stands in relation to his subordinates. The mechanical routine of the office is car- ried on by them. He is called on to interfere only when some unusual action has to be carried out, and reflection and decision are needed. Moreover, just as the principal of an office is able to hand over work to his subordinates when it ceases to be unusual and becomes methodized and reduced to rule, so we shall find that the brain or certain portions of it are able to withdraw from actions when they have grown thoroughly familiar. This is illustrated in the actions which we perform with little consciousness because they have become easy and mechanical by repeti- tion and habit. According to this view, the activity of the brain, together with the mental life which accompanies it, intervenes between the action of ex- ternal things on the organism and the active response of this organism, and subserves the higher and more complicated adjustments of mus- cular movement to sensory stimulation. All the earlier and simpler forms of cerebral activity are excited by the action of external sensory stimuli, and are directed to the performance of external actions in the immediate future. The later and more complicated actions of the brain do not conform 26 MIND AND BODY. to this description. We carry out many processes of reflection which have nothing to do with the external surroundings of the moment, and which, moreover, are not directed to the immediate realization of any desire or purpose. Much of the intellectual life of educated people is of this internal character. But even this apparently isolated internal activity of the brain may be reduced to the same fundamental type, by considering it as indirectly excited by impressions from without, and as a preparation for remote actions, certain or contingent, in the future. Thus, the study of a science like chemistry or astronomy may be de- scribed as only a high stage of elaboration of materials obtained from sense, and as undertaken because of its remote bearings on our actions. Nature of Nervous Action. — The precise nature of nervous action is still a matter of uncertainty. It appears to be some form of molecular movement of a vibratory character, and propagated somewhat in the manner of other vibratory movements, as those of heat and elec- tricity. The nerve-centers are a storehouse of energy, and their action increases the force of the current of stimulation which passes through them. This originating action of the central structures is known as the nervous discharge, and involves the liberation of energy which was previously stored up in a latent condition. This setting free of nerv- ous energy is effected by a process of disintegration or dis- organization in which the highly organized matter of the brain undergoes chemical changes and enters into com- bination with the oxygen which is brought by the blood. The force thus liberated may accordingly be said to have been supplied by the process of nutrition, and to have be- come latent in the work of building up the organic sub- stance of the brain. The relation between brain-nutrition and brain-action has been illustrated by the following analogy. If we take a number of bricks and set them up on end in a row sufficiently near one another, a slight amount of pressure applied to the first member of the series will cause the whole to fall, each brick adding some- thing to the force of the transmitted impact. Our muscu- MENTAL ACTIVITY AND BRAIN EFFICIENCY, 27 lar work in setting up the bricks was transformed into latent or potential energy, viz., that involved in the un- stable position of the bricks and their liability to fall. According to this analogy, the organic substance of the brain is an unstable compound easily broken up, and so constituting a reservoir of force. We see from this that the nerve-substance is being ever unmade and remade, or disintegrated and redinte- grated ; and, further, that there is a necessary correlation between these two processes of decomposition and repara- tion, so that no nervous action is possible except nutrition has first done its work. Mental Activity and Brain Efficiency. — As already pointed out, mental activity is directly connected with the exercise of brain-function. When a child uses his mind in any way, either by trying to learn something or by giving way to great emotional excitement, his brain is at work. The greater the mental activity, the more the resources of the brain are taxed. This activity of the brain necessitates an increased circulation of the blood in the organ, both for supplying the nutritive materials re- quired, and for furthering the process of nervous action itself by an adequate supply of oxygen, and by a suffi- ciently rapid removal of the waste products. If the brain thus furnishes the physical support of mental activity, it is to be expected that this will vary in amount with the state of the organ. And this is what we find. We all know that if the nervous energy is lowered in any way, as by bodily fatigue, grief, etc., the brain re- fuses to work smoothly and easily. On the other hand, the action of stimulants, as alcohol, on the brain illustrates how the mental activity may for a time be raised by add- ing to the excitability, and so intensifying the activity of the brain. The amount of disposable energy in the brain at any time, and the consequent readiness for work, will vary 28 MIND AND BODY. with a number of circumstances, (i) Since the brain and nervous system as a whole are parts of the bodily organ- ism, that is to say, a system of organs closely connected with and powerfully interacting on one another, any con- siderable fluctuation in the condition of one of the other organs will tell on the efficiency of the brain. Thus the special demand on the digestive organs after a good meal, leading to a diversion of blood as well as of nervous ener- gy in that direction, interferes for the time with brain- work. Similarly great muscular exertion militates against mental application. Again, a disturbance of the proper function of the vital organs, such as a fit of indigestion or an impeded circulation of the blood, is known to be an obstacle to mental activity. Once more, all fluctuations in the condition of the organism as a whole, whether the periodic exaltation and depression of the physical powers which constitute the daily vital rhythm of the body, or the irregular changes which we call fluctuations of health, involve the brain as well. The organ of mind shares with the whole body in the vigor and freshness of the morning, and the lassitude of the evening ; and it shares in the fluctuating well-being of the body. Lastly, the mind, in conjunction with the body, passes through the longer pro- cesses of growth and decay which constitute the course of the individual life. Brain- Activity and Brain-Fatigue. — (2) While the efficiency of the brain thus depends on the state of the bodily organs, it is affected by the preceding state of the organ itself. Thus, after a period of rest, the nervous substance being duly renewed, there is a special readiness for work. It is this circumstance which explains the in- vigorating effects on the powers of the brain of sound sleep, and of less complete forms of mental repose, such as are found in the lighter intellectual recreations. On the other hand, all brain-work tends to exhaust the nerv- ous energy and so to lower the subsequent efficiency. OVERTAXING THE BRAIN. 29 If the work is light in character, the effects are of course less noticeable : nothing like brain-fatigue is induced, and we may be unaware of any falling off in power. On the other hand, after a severe application of the mind, even for a short time, we become distinctly aware of certain sensations of fatigue, as well as of a temporary falling off in vigor. In the case of children, whose stock of brain- vigor is much smaller, these effects show themselves much sooner. The physiological explanation of these facts is as fol- lows : In the lighter kinds of brain-activity, the consump- tion of brain-material being small, the process of recuper- ation easily keeps pace with it. On the other hand, in the heavier sorts of mental work, energy is consumed faster than it can be supplied ; the process of redintegration does not keep pace with that of disintegration. This points to the necessity of a frequent relaxation of the nervous strain, especially at the beginning of school-life. Effects of Brain- Activity on the Organism.— But this is not the whole effect of brain-activity. In cases where the powers of the organ are taxed for a prolonged period, other organs are liable to be affected. Thus, since prolonged brain-exercise draws off the blood in too large a quantity to that organ, it is apt to impede the general circulation, and so to give rise to the familiar discomforts of cold feet, etc. Graver results may ensue in the case of the too eager student who by using up nerve-energy too extravagantly in brain-work leaves too little for the other functions of the nervous system, and more particularly the regulation of the vital processes, and so becomes the sub- ject of chronic dyspepsia, etc. We thus see that while the state of the bodily organs influences that of the brain, there is an important reciprocal action of the higher organ on the lower ones. Overtaxing the Brain. — It follows from the above remarks that it is possible to exact from the brain more 30 MIND AND BODY, work than it is good for it to perform. Wherever brain- work is accompanied by a distinct feeling of fatigue, this points to an overstimulation of the organ. By overstimu- lation is meant, first of all, bringing pressure to bear on the brain so as to excite it to activity beyond the point at which recuperation keeps pace with expenditure of energy ; and, secondly, the exercise of the brain disproportionately, that is, in relation to the other organs of the body, more particularly the vital organs. It is exceedingly important to distinguish this second and more profound sense of the term overstimulation from the first. There can be overexercise of the brain when the local symptoms of brain-fatigue are not present. The brain, like the other organs, learns to adapt itself within certain limits to the amount of work required of it. A child, when first subjected to the prolonged and system- atic stimulation of the school, comes in a short time to feel less of the strain of mental application. This may mean a diminution of effort by the normal results of exercise and growth ; but it may also mean that the increased activity of the organ is due to an unfair distribution of the phys- ical energy, the organ of mind being enriched at the expense of the vital organs. Now, this risk is peculiarly great in early life, when a large fund of nutritive material is needed for the processes of growth. Severe exercise of any organ, by using up material in functional action, though it may further the development^ i. e., the higher structural condition of that organ, is directly opposed to the growth^ that is, the ex- pansion in bulk of the body. All severe exercise of the brain in early life is opposed to the laws of development of the child's being. Accord- ing to these the lower vital functions are developed before the higher. First comes the vegetal or nutritive life ; then the common animal life of sense and movement ; and finally the distinctly human life of mind. The develop- VARIATION OF BRAIN-EXERCISE. 31 ment of these higher mental functions is only normal and safe when a firm basis of physical strength and well-being has first been laid down. To try to force on the functions of the brain in advance of those of the vital organs is to endanger the whole organism, and along with this the or- gans of mind themselves.* In thus touching on the risks of educational pressure, it may be well to add that they are susceptible of being overrated as well as underrated. It is an error to suppose that all systematic teaching tends in the direction of over- excitation of the brain. So far from this being the case, it may be confidently said that within certain limits mental occupation is distinctly beneficial to the child. Every organ requires a certain amount of exercise in order to continue in a healthy and vigorous condition. Children deprived of the material for mental activity suffer from tedium, which may be viewed as a symptom that the mmd and brain are in need of exercise. Many children have become happier and healthier after entering on school-life, and this not merely because the school supplied healthier physical surroundings, but also because it supplied a healthier regime for the brain. To this is to be added that, as already pointed out, the brain, like other organs, grows stronger by exercise, and within certain limits it is per- fectly safe to carry on a progressively increasing stimula- tion of the organ. Remission and Variation of Brain-Exercise. — The great danger, especially with young children, is that of unduly prolonging the duration of the mental strain at one time. A short exertion even of great severity is in- nocuous, whereas an unbroken application of mind to a difficult subject for half an hour or more may be injurious. One of the greatest improvements in modern educational * On the injurious effects of excessive stimulation of the brain in retarding^ bodily growth, see Herbert Spencer, " Education," chap, iv, p. 165, and following. 32 MIND AND BODY. methods, considered both from a hygienic point of view and from that of mental efficiency itself, is the substitution of short for long lessons, and the frequent alternation of mental and bodily exercise. These breaks, though, in ap- pearance, occasioning a loss of time and adding to the teacher's labors in restoring order and recalling the pupil's minds to the calm attitude of attention, are in reality a true economy of time and force. Since the brain is a complicated group of structures, it is reasonable to suppose that different regions are specially engaged in different kinds of mental activity. And mod- ern science, while rejecting the definite mapping out of the brain functions proposed by the phrenologists, is dis- tinctly tending toward a new and carefully verified theory of localization of function. Adopting this view of brain- action as engaging special centers at different times, we may see that the due variation of school subject owes a part of its value at least to the circumstance that it fulfills in a subordinate manner the purpose of brain-rest. Thus, by passing from an object lesson to a singing lesson, the centers of vision are put into a condition of comparative rest, while other centers, the auditory and vocal, which have been recuperating, are called into play. And as sci- ence enables us to localize the brain functions more ex- actly, the theory of education will probably receive from it further guidance as to the best way of varying school exercises. Differences of Brain-Power. — The educator should bear in mind that children are endowed with very unequal cerebral capacity. The whole sum of vital force is a dif- ferent one in the case of different children, and the dis- tribution of this among the several organs is also different. Hence, an amount of mental exercise that would be quite safe in one case would be harmful in another. The indi- vidual co-efficient of brain-power is the limit set by nature to the teacher's efforts, and he can not afford to ignore it. DIFFERENCES OF BRAIN-POWER. 33 This co-efficient determines the amount of mental reaction to external stimulus. Just as one and the same physical stimulus will evoke very unequal amounts of muscular ac- tivity in the case of a vigorous and a feeble body, so the same quantity of intellectual stimulus will call forth very unlike mental reactions in the case of a robust and a weakly brain. This varying co-efficient of brain-power is seen very distinctly in the different rates of mental work of different children. It is not too much to say that the whole range of mental acquisition is in each case fixed from the first by the child's cerebral capacity. On the connection between body and mind in its educational bearings the student is referred to H. Spencer's " Education," chap. iv. ; Dr. Bain's " Education as a Science," chap. ii. ; Dr. Andrew Combe's '* Principles of Physiology applied to the Preservation of Health and to the Improvement of Physical and Mental Education," chaps, xi. to xiv., which, in spite of antiquated phrenological allusions, are still well worth reading. CHAPTER IV. KNOWING, FEELING, AND WILLING. Mental Phenomena and Operations. — As was pointed out above, mental science consists of an orderly- arrangement of the general truths, or laws which relate to mental phenomena. In order to arrive at these truths, we have first to ascertain what our phenomena are, and to arrange them in general groups or classes, based on funda- mental points of likeness. Mental phenomena are known by different names. They are commonly called states of mind, or states of consciousness. Since, however, they are phenomena in time, having a certain duration and a succession of parts, they are just as often spoken of as mental processes or operations. It is important, further, to distinguish be- tween a mental process or operation and its result or prod- uct. Thus we distinguish between a process of percep- tion, and its result, a percept ; a process of association and suggestion, and its product, a recollection ; between an operation called reasoning and its result, rational convic- tion, and so forth. Classification of Mental Operations. — If we com- pare our mental states at different times, we find them presenting very different characters. Sometimes we de- scribe ourselves as expenencing /ee/ings of joy, grief, etc., at other times as thinking about a matter, and so forth. And, if we look more closely at the contents of our mind KNOWING, FEELING, AND WILLING, 35 at one and the same time, we are commonly able to dis- tinguish between different ingredients, as emotions, recol- lections, desires. Common thought has long since distinguished between different classes or varieties of mental operation. Scien- tific research carries this process further, and seeks to reach the most fundamental differences among our mental operations. This is commonly described as dividing mind into its fundamental functions, and also as analyzing it into its elements. If we examine the every-day distinctions of popular psychology, we find that there are three fairly clear divis- ions which do not seem to have anything in common be- yond being all modes of mental activity. Thus we ordi- narily describe such activities as perceiving, remembering, and reasoning, as intellectual operations. So, again, we bring sorrow, joy, love, anger, and so on, under the general description of feeling or e?notion. And, finally, we gather up operations like purposing, deliberating, doing things, under the head of will. We broadly mark off these three sides of mind, and talk of men as exhibiting now one and now another aspect. Feeling, Knowing, and Willing.— Mental science adopts this three-fold division, (i) Under Feeling ^ we include all pleasurable and painful conditions of mind. These may be very simple feelings, having definite bodily causes, such as the painful sensations of hunger and thirst, or the pleasures of the palate. Or they may be of a more complex nature, such as love, or remorse. (2) Knowing, again, includes all operations which are directly involved in gaining knowledge, as, for example, observing what is present to the senses, recalling the past, and reasoning. (3) Finally, Willing or Acting covers all active mental operations, all our conscious doings, such as walking, speaking, attending to things, together with efi"orts to do things, active impulses and resolutions. The perfect type 36 KNOWING, FEELING, AND WILLING. of action is doing something for an end or purpose ; and this is what we ordinarily mean by a voluntary action. Opposition between Knowing:, Feeling, and Willing. — These three kinds of mental state are, as we have seen, in general clearly marked off one from another. A child in a state of strong emotional excite- ment contrasts with a child calmly thinking about some- thing, or another child exerting his active powers in doing something. If we take any one of these aspects of mind in a well-marked form, we see that it is opposed to the other aspects. Thus strong feeling is opposed to and precludes at the time calm thinking (recollecting, reason- ing), as well as regulated action (will). Similarly, the intellectual state of remembering or reasoning when fully developed at the moment is opposed to feeling and to doing. The mind can not exhibit each variety of function in a marked degree at the same time. This opposition may be seen in another way. If we compare, not different states of the same mind, but differ- ent minds as a whole, we often find now one kind of mental state or operation, now another in the ascendant. Minds marked by much feeling (sensitive, emotional na- tures) commonly manifest less of the intellectual and voli- tional aspects or properties. Similarly, minds of a high degree of intellectual capability (inquiring or inquisitive minds), or of much active endowment (active minds), are as a rule relatively weak in the other kinds of endowment. It follows from this that the training of the mind in any one of its three functions is to some extent a separate matter. Thus, intellectual education has its separate end, viz., the production of a quick, unerring intelligence, which end involves no proportionate development of the feelings or of the will. Connection between Knowing, Feeling, and Willing. — Yet while knowing, feeling, and willing are thus broadly marked off from, and even opposed to, one CONNECTION BETWEEN KNOWING, ETC. 37 another, they are in another way closely connected. A mind is not a material object which can be separated into distinct parts, but an organic unity made up of parts standing in the closest relation of interdependence. If we closely examine any case of feeling, we are sure to find some intellectual and volitional accompaniments. Thus when we experience a bodily pain (feeling), we instantly localize the pain or recognize its seat (knowledge), and endeavor to alleviate it (volition). Most of our feelings, as we shall see, are wrapped up with or embodied in intel- lectual states (perceiving, remembering, etc.). Again, intellectual operations, observing, thinking, etc., are com- monly accompanied by some shade of agreeable or dis- agreeable feeling, and they always involve voluntary ac- tivity in the shape of attention or concentration of mind. Finally, willing depends on feeling for its motive or im- pelling force, and on knowledge for its illumination or guidance. It will be seen from this that our threefold division of mind is a division according to the fundamentally distinct aspects which predominate at different times. Thus by intellectual states or processes we mean those modes of mental activity in which the cognitive function is most marked and prominent. This fact of the invariable concomitance of the three mental functions is of capital importance to the teacher. Misled by our habits of analysis, and our abstract ways of thinking, we are apt to suppose that in training the intel- lectual faculties we may disregard the emotional and voli- tional element altogether. But a deeper insight into the organic unity of mind corrects this error. One great law governing our intellectual activity is that we attend to what interests us, that is, to what excites feeling in some way and, through this, arouses the energies of the will. And just as educators have sometimes failed to make the best of children's intellectual powers, by overlooking the 38 KNOWING, FEELING, AND WILLING. necessary accompaniments of feeling and will, so they have failed to develop the highest type of will and char- acter, because they have not recognized the dependence of this on a certain mode of intelligence, and on the de- velopment of particular emotions. Species of Knowing, Feeling-, and Willing : Mental Faculties. — Popular psychology recognizes cer- tain divisions or species of knowing, feeling, and willing under the head of faculties, capabilities, or powers. More particularly we speak of intellectual faculties such as perception and imagination ; emotional capacities, or sus- ceptibilities, as love, anger ; and 2iZl\vQ powers and dispo- sitions, such as movement, choice, industry. These distinctions are valid so far as they go. The psychologist allows that perceiving and remembering differ in certain important respects. The first operation con- tains elements (e. g., actual sense-impressions) which the second does not contain. Thus there is a real psychologi- cal distinction involved, and the psychologist will find it here as elsewhere convenient to make this popularly recog- nized distinction the starting-point in a scientific treatment of the phenomena of mind. In adopting, these popular distinctions, however, the psychologist must not be taken to imply that the several processes of perceiving, remembering, etc., are distinct one from the other fundamentally, that is to say, with respect to their elementary parts. While we set out with these well-marked divisions of faculty, we seek to discover by a deeper psychological analysis certain more fundamental or primary distinctions, and to regard such diiferences as those between perceiving and remembering as second- ary. Primary Intellectual Functions.— The essential operation in all varieties of knowing is the detecting of relations between things. I know a tree, a period of English history, a demonstration in Euclid, when I know INDIVIDUAL DIFFERENCES. 39 its several parts in relation one to another, and also its relations as a whole to other things. The most compre- hensive relations are difference or unlikeness and agree- ment or likeness. All knowing means discriminating one impression, object, or idea from another (or others), and assimilating it to yet another (or others). I perceive an object as a rose only when I distinguish its several parts and features one from another ; and when, further, I see how it differs from other objects, and more especially other varieties of flower, and at the same time recognize its likeness to other roses previously seen. And so of other forms of knowing. Hence, discrimination and as- similation may be viewed as the primary functions of intellect. While these two primary functions constitute the main factor in intellectual operations, the exercise of them presupposes other capabilities. Thus the power of taking apart the objects presented to the mind, and confining the attention to certain details or particu- lars (analysis), together with the supplementary power of mentally grasping a number of objects together at the same time (synthesis), is clearly implied in all knowing. This power will be dealt with under the head of attention. In addition to this, there is the mind's capaci- ty of retention, that is, of conserving past impressions and recalling them for future use. Unless we could thus retain impressions, we should be unable to bring together before the mind facts lying in different regions of our experience, and so discover their relations. Moreover, the abiding knowledge of any subject plainly implies the re- tention of what we have learned. Individual Differences of Mental Capability.— The several mental operations do not present themselves in precisely the same manner in all minds. They vary in certain respects, and these variations are referred to differences of mental power or capacity. Now, as we have seen, psychology as science has to do with the gen- eral facts and truths of mind. It takes no account of individual peculiarities. Nevertheless, the practical im- portance of estimating individual differences has led psy- 40 KNOWING, FEELING, AND WILLING. chologists to pay considerable attention to this concrete branch of their subject. And the foregoing analysis of mental functions prepares the way for a scientific classifi- cation of individual differences. There are different ways in which individual minds vary. Thus, one mind may differ from another in respect of one whole phase or side. For example, we speak of one child as more intellectual or more inquiring than another. Similarly, one child is said to have more emotional sus- ceptibility or more active impulse or will than another. Again, we may make our comparison more narrow, and observe how one mind differs from another with re- spect to a special mode of intellectual (or other) activity. Thus, to find that individuals vary in respect of one of the primary intellectual functions, that one has a finer sense of difference or a keener sense of resemblance than an- other. Or, once more, we may vote and record differ- ences in the strength of some particular faculty, as obser- vation, or reason. Or, lastly, we may distinguish yet more narrowly, comparing individuals with respect to some special mode of operation of a faculty, as perception of form, or memory for words. In like manner we can distinguish between different degrees of strength of a special emotion, as anger or affec- tion, or of a particular active endowment, as endurance. All the innumerable differences which characterize in- dividual minds must ultimately resolve themselves into these modes. The problem of measuring these individual differences with something like scientific exactness will occupy us later on. Truths or Laws of Mind. — The classification of mental states prepares the way for ascertaining the gen- eral truths of mind. The most comprehensive of these truths are known as laws of mind. These laws aim at setting forth in the most general form the way in which mental states are connected one with another, and particu- CONDITIONS OF KNOWING, FEELING, ETC. 41 larly the way in which they succeed and act upon one an- other. The law that governs any mental operation unfolds the circumstances necessary to its accomplishment, in other words, its causal antecedents or conditions. It thus helps us to explain or account for the operation in any particular case. Here, too, mental science is seeking to improve on pop- ular psychology ; for observation has long since taught men that mental products, such as knowledge and charac- ter, presuppose certain antecedent circumstances and in- fluences. This is seen in the common sayings about mind and character, such as " Experience is the best teacher," " Love is blind," " First impressions last longest," etc. General Conditions of Mental Activity.— Some of these laws of mind embody the general conditions of mental operations, whether those of feeling, knowing, or willing. Reference has already been made to the com- mon physiological conditions of mental operations, viz., a vigorous state of the brain, etc. Among general mental conditions, attention is by far the most important. Atten- tion is presupposed alike in all clear knowing, vivid feel- ing, and energetic willing. The laws of attention, to be spoken of presently, are thus in a manner laws of mind as a whole. Conditions of Knowing, Feeling, and Willing. — Next to these universal conditions, there are the more special ones of knowing, of feeling, and of willing. Thus the laws of mental reproduction, or the revival of impres- sions, are in a peculiar manner laws of intellect. Similar- ly, there are laws of feeling which seek to formulate the conditions of pleasure and pain, as well as the effects of feeling on the thoughts and beliefs. Finally, we have special laws of willing, as, for example, that action varies with the intensity of motive force applied, that proximate satisfactions excite the will more powerfully than remote ones. It is to be added that in assigning the special con- 42 KNOWING, FEELING, AND WILLING. ditions of feeling, knowing, and willing, we should refer to the particular nervous structures engaged, so far as these are known. As truths of mind still more special, we have the enu- meration of the several conditions of a particular variety of operation, such as the intellectual act of observation or imagination. This gives us the law of operation of that particular faculty. Thus we explain or account for ob- servation by specifying its conditions, external and internal, such as the favorable position of the object, some special interest in it, etc. Here, too, we must include in our sur- vey the regions of the nervous system specially engaged. As already observed, this enumeration of co-operating conditions must in certain cases embrace remote as well as immediate antecedents. Thus, to account for a recol- lection, we need to refer not only to the suggestive forces acting at the time, but also to the influence of past ex- perience in associating that which suggests with that which it suggests. For a complete understanding of the way in which any variety of mental product arises, we need to take into ac- count the action of the whole mental state at the time, so far as it is favorable or unfavorable. Thus, calmness of mind, freedom from emotional excitement, and preoccu- pation of the attention, is an important negative condition of the more difficult intellectual processes. Finally, among the conditions of a perfect discharge of any mental function we presuppose a mind in which this power is strong and well developed. And it is often well to specify this. Thus, in setting forth the conditions of retention under any of its forms, such as the recollection of colors or places, we may specify a good natural reten- tive power in that particular direction. Importance of understanding the Conditions of Mental Activity. — The understanding of the laws that control the various forms of mental activity is a matter of IMPORTANCE OF UNDERSTANDING. 43 special consequence to the teacher. As already observed, we can only bring about any intellectual or other mental product when we see clearly into the conditions on which it depends. The educator, in seeking to exercise some faculty, say observation, is coming into a certain rapport with the pupil's mind. This relation is not like that of an external mechanical force to a passive material, as clay or sealing-wax. The teacher only succeeds in doing any- thing when he calls forth the learner's own mental activity. The very idea of stimulating the mind implies that the external agent calls forth a mental reaction, that is, ex- cites the mind to its appropriate form of activity. Hence, the teacher needs to have, at the outset, the clearest knowl- edge as to what this activity is, and what laws it uniformly obeys. Thus, for example, he requires to understand what the mind really does when it thoroughly grasps and assimi- lates a new truth. In the process of stimulating the mind the teacher ne- cessarily employs certain agencies, and it is of the greatest importance that he rightly understand their precise effect in furthering the mental activity he would excite. Thus, in giving a child verses to commit to memory, he should know to what extent and in what precise manner this em- ployment exercises the memory. And this he can only do when he has a clear scientific insight into the nature of the faculty and the laws of its operation. It is of great im- portance, too, that he should understand in what ways his appliances are liable to be counteracted by other influ- ences, such as an unfavorable state of the pupil's mind at the moment. In the appliances brought to bear by the educator there are two things to be distinguished : first of all, the material supply on which the pupil's mind is to exercise itself ; and, secondly, the motive force brought to bear in order to in- duce the learner to apply his mind to the subject. A wise choice of material presupposes a certain knowledge of the 44 KNOWING, FEELING, AND WILLING. intellectual faculties, and the laws which govern their op- eration. A wise selection of motive presupposes no less accurate a knowledge of the laws that rule in the domain of the feelings and the will. APPENDIX. The reader who desires to read further on the threefold division of mind is referred to my " Outlines of Psychology," chap, ii, and Ap- pendix B ; also, to the works of Sir W. Hamilton and Dr. Bain, there quoted. CHAPTER V. MENTAL DEVELOPMENT. Mental Development defined.— In the last chapter we were concerned with ascertaining the nature and con- ditions of the several kinds of mental operation, without any reference to the time of life at which they occur. But mental operations differ greatly in different periods of life, owing to what we call the growth or development of faculty or capacity. We have now to consider this far-reaching process of mental growth. We shall seek to distinguish between the successive stages of mental life, and point out how these are related one to the other. By so doing we may hope to account not merely for the single operations of a faculty, but for the mature faculty itself, viewed as the result of a process of growth. This part of our subject constitutes the theory of mental development. When speaking of the physical organism, we distin- guish between growth and development. The former is mere increase of size or bulk; the latter consists of structural changes (increase of complexity). While growth and development usually run on together, there is no proper parallelism between them. Thus, in abnormal growth, development is hindered. And an organ, as the brain, may develop long after it has ceased to grow. It is possible to apply this analogy to mind. We may say that mind grows when it increases its stock of materials. It develops in so far as its materials are elaborated into 5 46 MENTAL DEVELOPMENT. higher and more complex forms. Mere growth of mind would thus be illustrated by an increase in the bulk of mental retentions, that is, in the contents of memory : de- velopment, by the ordering of these contents in their re- lations of difference and likeness, and so on. But in general the two terms, mental growth and mental develop- ment, may be used as interchangeable. The characteristics of mental development are best seen in the case of the intellect. The growth of knowl- edge may be viewed in different ways : (i) Under one aspect it is a gradual progress from vague to distinct knowledge. The perceptions and ideas grow more defi- nite. This may be called intellectual differentiation. (2) Again, it is a progress from simple to complex processes. There is a continual grouping or integration of elements into organic compounds. In this way the child's knowl- edge of whole localities, of series of events, and so forth, arises. (3) Once more, it is a continual movement from external sense to internal thought or reflection. Or, as it is commonly described, it is a transition from \he presenta- tive, or what is directly presented to the mind through sense, to the representative ^ that which is indirectly set before the mind by the aid of internal ideas. (4) Lastly, this progress from sense to thought is a transition from the knowledge of individuals to that of general classes, or from a knowledge of concrete things to that of their ab- stract qualities,* This aggregate of changes, which constitutes the growth of mind, appears to resolve itself into two parts. On the one hand we see that the several faculties which operate in the case of the child have expanded and increased in vigor. On the other hand we notice that new faculties, * Reference is made here only to knowledge of outer things. As will be seen by-and-by, the growth of self-knowledge illustrates the same movement from outer sense to internal reflection, from the con- crete to the abstract. ORDER OF DEVELOPMENT OF FACULTIES. A7 the germs of which are hardly discoverable in the child, have acquired strength. We see, that is to say, that while the faculties have each grown singly, there has been a certain order of unfolding among them, so that some have reached mature vigor before others. Growth of Faculty. — The growth or improvement of a faculty includes three things, or may be regarded under three aspects : (i) Old operations become more perfect, and also more easy and rapid. Thus the recog- nition of an individual object, as a person's face, as also the recalling of it when absent, tends to become more dis- tinct, as well as easier, with the repetition of the opera- tion. This is improvement of a faculty in a definite direction. (2) New operations of a similar grade of com- plexity will also grow easier. Thus the improvement of the observing powers (perception) includes a growing facility in noting and recognizing unfamiliar objects ; that of memory includes a greater readiness in retaining and recalling new impressions. This is improvement of a faculty generally. (3) This general improvement is com- pleted by the attainment of the capability of executing more complex, intricate, and difficult operations. Thus the growth of memory means the progress of the capa- bility as shown in retaining and recalling less striking im- pressions and larger and more complex groups of impres- sions. Order of Development of Faculties.— One of the most valuable doctrines of modern psychology is that there is a uniform order of development of the faculties. There is a well-marked order in the growth of intellect, (i) The process of attaining knowledge sets out with sensation, or the reception of external impressions by the mind. Sense supplies the materials which the intellect assimilates and elaborates according to its own laws. Before we can know anything about the material objects which surround us they must impress our mind through 48 MENTAL DEVELOPMENT, the senses (sight, touch, hearing, etc.). (2) Sensation is followed by perception, in which a number of impressions are grouped together under the form of a percept, or an immediate apprehension of some thing or object, as when we see and recognize an orange or a bell. (3) After per- ception comes representative imagination, in which the mind pictures, or has an image of, what has been per- ceived. It may represent this either in the original form (reproductive imagination), as when we recall the face of a friend ; or in a new form (constructive imagination), as when we imagine some historical personage. (4) Finally, .we have general or abstract knowing, otherwise marked off as thinking. This includes conception, or the forma- tion of concepts or general notions out of percepts and images, such as "metal," "organism," "life," and so on ; judgment, or the combination of concepts, as when we assert that no men are omniscient ; and reasoning, or the combination of judgments, as when we conclude that a particular writer, say a journalist, is not omniscient, be- cause no men are so. Unity of Intellectual Development.— It has already been pointed out that modern psychology seeks to reduce the several operations of perception, imagination, etc., to certain fundamental processes, of which discrimination and assimilation are the most important. By help of this deeper analysis of intellectual activity we are able to re- gard the successive unfoldings of the faculties as one con- tinuous process. The higher and more complex opera- tions of thought now appear as only different modes of the same fundamental functions of intellect that underlie the lower and simpler operations of sense-perception. Thus the simplest germ of knowing involves the discrimi- nation of sense-impression ; and the highest form of know- ing, abstract thinking, is a higher manifestation of the same power. Again, the perception of a single object is a process of assimilating present to past impressions ; and GROWTH AND EXERCISE OF FACULTY. 49 abstract thinking is assimilating or classing many objects under certain common aspects. We may thus say that the several stages of knowing, viz., perception, conception, and so on, illustrate the same fundamental activities of intellect employed about more and more complex mate- rials (sensations, percepts, ideas, etc.). We thus see that there are no breaks in the process of intellectual development. It is one continuous process, from its simplest to its most complex phase. The distinc- tions between perception, imagination, etc., though of great practical convenience, as roughly marking the successive stages of growth, must not be taken as answering to sharp divisions. The movement of intellectual progress is not a series of separate leaps, but one unbroken and even movement. Growth and Exercise of Faculty.— The great law underlying these processes of development is that the faculties or functions of intellect are strengthened by ex- ercise. Thus the power of observation (perception), of detecting differences among colors, forms, and so on, im- proves by the repeated exercise of this power. Each suc- cessive operation tends to improve the faculty, and more particularly in the particular direction in which it is exer- cised. Thus, if the power of observation is exercised with respect to colors, it will be strengthened more especially in this direction, but not to the same extent in other di- rections, e. g., with respect to forms. Again, since perception, conception, and so forth, are only different modes of the same intellectual functions, the exercise of these in the lower form prepares the way for the higher manifestations. Thus, in training the senses, we are calling into play the power of analyzing a complex whole into its parts, also the functions of discrimination and assimilation, and so are laying the foundations of the higher intellectual culture. On the other hand, we must not suppose that by merely exercising the observing powers 50 MENTAL DEVELOPMENT, we can secure a development of the powers of abstract thought. In order that the successive phases of intelli- gence may unfold themselves, the separate exercise of the fundamental functions in each of these phases is necessary. That is to say, we require a special training for each of the faculties in due order. Growth and Retentiveness. — This growth of intel- lect by exercise implies retentiveness. By this term, in its widest signification, is meant that every operation of mind leaves a trace behind it, which constitutes a disposition to perform the same operation or same kind of operation again. This truth obviously underlies the generalization, " Exercise strengthens faculty." The increased power of observation, for example, due to repeated exercises of the faculty, can only be accounted for by saying that each successive exercise modifies the mind, adding to its capa- bility of acting, and strengthening its tendency to act in that particular mode. Growth and Habit. — This persistence of traces, and formation of a disposition to think, feel, etc., in the same way as before underlies what we call habit. By this term, in its most comprehensive sense, is meant a fixed tendency to think, feel, or act in a particular way under special cir- cumstances. The formation of habits is a very important ingredient of what we mean by intellectual development ; but it is not all that is so meant. Habit refers rather to the fixing of mental operations in particular directions. Taken in this narrow sense, habit is in a manner opposed to growth. By following out a train of ideas again and again in a certain way, we lose the capability of varying this order, of re-adapting the combination to new circum- stances. Habit is thus the element of persistence, of cus- tom, the co7tservative tendency; whereas growth implies flexibility, modifiability, susceptibility to new impressions, \)i\^ progressive tendency. We shall again and again have to distinguish between the effect of habit, as understood in GROUPING OF PARTS. 5 1 this narrow sense, and development in the full sense, as a wide or many-sided progress. The importance of the principle of habit will be illustrated more especially in the domain of action.* In order that the intellectual powers as a whole may be exercised and grow, a higher form of retentiveness is needed. The traces of the products of intellectual activity must accumulate and appear under the form of revivals or reproductions. The impressions of sense, when discrimi- nated, are in this way recalled as mental images. This retention and revival of the products of the early sense- discrimination is clearly necessary to the higher operations of thought. Images, though the product of elementary processes of discrimination and assimilation, supply in their turn the material for the more elaborate processes of thought. We thus see that the growing complexity of the intellectual life depends on the accumulation of innumer- able traces of past and simpler products of intellectual activity. Grouping of Parts: Laws of Association.— Closely connected with this fundamental property of re- tentiveness, there is another involved in this process of intellectual development. The growth of intellect, as we have seen, leads to an increasing complexity of the prod- ucts. This means that the several elements are com- bined or grouped in certain ways. This grouping goes on according to the laws of association. These laws will be fully discussed by-and-by. Here it is enough to say that there are two principal modes of grouping, and corre- * The term habit is commonly confined to actions which have grown customary, and so mechanical. But the principle of habit is illustrated in each of the three directions of mental development. Some writers distinguish between passive habits, the effects of custom on feeling, and active habits, its effects on action. In connection with education, Locke uses the term habit generally as expressing the result of practice. See "Thoughts concerning Education," edited by Rev. R. H. Quick; In- troduction, p. liv. 52 MENTAL DEVELOPMENT, spending laws of association of mental elements, (a) according to their nearness or contiguity in time, and {h) according to their similarity. The first mode will be the one principally illustrated in the earlier stages of develop- ment (perception and imagination) ; the second, the one mainly concerned in the later stages (thought). Development of Feeling and Willing. — While, for the sake of simplicity, we have confined our attention to the development of intellect, it is necessary to add that the same features and the same underlying principles are dis- coverable in the growth of feeling and will. The earlier feelings (bodily pleasures and pains) are simple and closely connected with the senses : the higher feelings (emotions) are complex and representative in character. Again, the first actions (bodily movements) are simple and external, being immediate responses to sense-impressions, whereas the later are complex, internal and representative (choosing, resolving, etc.). It will be found, further, that there is a continuity of process throughout the develop- ment of each. And the same laws or conditions, growth by exercise, retentiveness and association, are illustrated here as in the case of intellectual development. Interdependence of Processes. — We have so far viewed the growth of intellect, of feeling, and of volition as processes going on apart, independently of one another. And this is in a measure a correct assumption. It has, however, already been pointed out that mind is an organic unity, and that the processes of knowing, feeling, and will- ing in a measure involve one another. It follows from this that the developments of these phases of mind will be closely connected. Thus, intellectual development presup- poses a certain measure of emotional and volitional devel- opment. There would be no attainments in knowledge if the connected interest (curiosity, love of knowledge) and active impulses (concentration, application) had not been developed. Similarly, there can be no development of the GROWTH AND DEVELOPMENT. 53 life of feeling without a considerable accumulation of knowledge about Nature and man ; nor can there be any development of action without a development of feel- ing and the accumulation of a store of practical knowl- edge. The mind may develop much more on one side than on the others, but development on one side without any development on the others is an impossibility. This connectedness of one side of development with the others may be illustrated in the close dependence of intellectual growth on the exercise and improvement of the power of attention. Though related to the active or volitional side of mind, attention is a prime condition of intellectual operations. Mental activity includes in every case some form of attention ; and the higher kinds of mental activity illustrate the full exercise of the will in the shape of an effort of concentration. This being so, intellectual growth, which, as we have seen, is the imme- diate outcome of mental activity, is closely dependent on the development of will. It is the improvement of the power of voluntary concentration which makes success- ively possible accurate observation, steady reproduction, and all that we mean by thinking. This dependence of one phase of mental development on the other phases is not, however, equally close in all cases. Thus the growth of knowing involves compara- tively little of the emotional and volitional element. The growth of feeling in its higher forms involves considerable intellectual development, but no corresponding degree of volitional development. Finally, the growth of will is largely dependent on that of knowing and feeling. Hence, in the order of exposition, we set out with the development of knowing, passing then to that of feeling, and finally to that of willing. Growth and Development of the Brain.—Just as, in studying mental operations at a particular time, we have to include in our view nervous concomitants, so in 54 MENTAL DEVELOPMENT. studying mental de/elopment we must ask what changes in the nervous organism, and more particularly in the brain-centers, accompany these psychical changes. The brain, like all other parts of the organism, grows in bulk or size, and develops or manifests certain changes in its formation or structure, viz. : increasing unlikeness of parts and intricacy of arrangements among these. The two processes, growth and development, do not progress with the same degree of rapidity. The size nearly attains its maximum about the end of the seventh year, whereas the degree of structural development reached at this time is not much above that of the embryonic condition.* It may be added that the higher centers of thought and vo- lition develop later than those of sensation. The brain, being an organ closely connected with the rest of the bodily organism, would tend to grow to a cer- tain extent with the growth of the organism as a whole, and independently of any activity of its own. But such growth would be rudimentary only. Like all other organs, it grows and develops by exercise. This physiological law is clearly the counterpart of the psychological law that exercise strengthens faculty. Such exercises tend to modify the brain structures in some way, so as to dis- pose them afterward to act more readily in the same man- ner. Factors in Development. — The process of mental growth just traced out is brought about by the co-opera- tion of two sets of agencies or factors — the mind itself which develops, and the circumstances necessary to its development. These may be marked off as the internal and the external factor. (A) Internal Factor. — This consists first of all of the simple and fundamental capabilities of the mind. Thus it includes the several simple modes of sensibility to light, sound, and so on. Further, it embraces the fun- * See Bastian, " The Brain as an Organ of Mind," p. 375. THE SOCIAL ENVIRONMENT. 55 damental intellectual functions, discrimination, and assim- ilation. In like manner it will include the primary or fundamental capacities of feeling, and powers of willing. The internal factor includes, too, the mind's native im- pulse to activity and spontaneous tendency to develop- ment. (B) External Factor, (i) Natural Environ- ment. — In the second place, the development of an indi- vidual mind implies the presence and co-operation of the external factor, or the environment. By this we mean, in the first place, the physical environment or natural sur- roundings. The growth of intelligence presupposes a world of sights and sounds, etc., to supply the materials of knowledge. The mind of a child deprived of these would languish for want of its appropriate nutriment. Similarly, the development of the feelings, for example, of fear, awe, the sense of beauty, etc., depends on the pres- ence and action of natural objects. Finally, the will is called forth to activity by the action of the forces of the natural environment, and by the need of reacting on it and modifying it. (2) The Social Environment. — In addition to what we commonly call the natural or physical environ- ment, there is the human and social environment. By this we mean the society of which the individual is a member, with which he holds certain relations, and by which he is profoundly influenced. The social medium, like the phys- ical, affects the individual mind through sense-impres- sions (sights and sounds) ; yet its action differs from that of the natural surroundings in being a moral influence. It works through the forces which bind the individual to other individuals and to the community, such as imita- tion, sympathy, and the sentiment of obedience or author- ity. The presence of a social medium is necessary to a full normal development of mind. If it were possible to main- 56 M-ENTAL DEVELOPMENT. tain a child in bodily health and at the same time deprive him of all companionship, his mental development would be but rudimentary. The child comes under the stimulation, the guidance, and the control of others, and these influ- ences are essential to a normal mental development. Thus, his intellectual growth is determined by continual contact and interaction with the social intelligence, the body of knowledge amassed by the race, and expressed in every- day speech, in books, etc. Similarly, the feelings of the child quicken and grow under the touch of social senti- ment. And finally the will is called forth, stimulated and guided by the habitual modes of action of those about him. These social influences embrace a wider area as life pro- gresses. Beginning with the action of the family, they go on expanding by including the influences of the school, of companions, and finally of the whole community, as work- ing through manners, public opinion, and so forth. Undesigned and Designed Influence of Society. — A part of this social influence acts undesignedly, that is, without any intention to accomplish a result. The ef- fects of contact of mind with mind, of example, of the pre- vailing tone of a family or a society, all this resembles the action of natural or physical agencies. On the other hand, a considerable remainder of this influence is clearly de- signed. To this part belong all the mechanism of instruc- tion, the arts of suasion, moral and legal control, etc. Both kinds of social influence co-operate in each of the three great phases of mental development. Thus the in- tellect of a child grows partly under the influence of con- tact with the social intelligence reflecting itself in the structure of language ; and partly by the aid of systematic instruction. Similarly, feeling develops partly through the mere contact with other minds, or the agencies of sympa- thy, and partly by direct appeals from others. Finally, the will develops partly by the attraction of example and the impulses of imitation, and partly by the forces of sua- VARIETIES OF DEVELOPMENT. 57' sion, advice, reproof, and the whole system of moral dis- cipline. Scheme of Development.— The reader may perhaps be able the better to comprehend the above rough theory of mental development by help of the following diagram : Fig. 4. Varieties of Development.— While all normally constituted minds pass through the same typical course of development, there are endless differences in the details of the mental history of individuals. In no two cases, indeed, is the process of mental growth precisely similar. These diversities of mental history answer to the differ- ences between mind and mind spoken of in the previous chapter. Such differences of development may be referred to one or two causes of factors : (a) variations or inequali- 6 58 MENTAL DEVELOPMENT. ties of original capacity, or (^) differences in the external circumstances, physical and social. All differences in the final result, that is, the mature or developed aptitude or capacity, must be assignable to one (or both) cf these fac- tors. It is important to observe that differences of original capacity include all inequalities in mental energy and capability of development. As every teacher knows, the instruments of education applied to two children, at ap- proximately the same level of attainment, result in widely unlike amounts of progress. Such inequalities in capa- bility of mental growth turn mainly on differences in the degree of mental activity, and, next to this, on different degrees of retentive power. Differences of Original Capacity. — In ascertaining these we must be careful to separate off only what is strictly original, and not in any measure the result of pre- vious training or other kind of external influence. Now, we can not altogether eliminate the effect of early influ- ences ; yet we can reduce this to a minimum by taking the child soon enough, or by selecting for our experiment a sufficiently new mode of mental operation. Such a method of comparative measurement applied to young children would undoubtedly confirm the every- day observation of parents and teachers alike, that chil- dren are at birth endowed with very unequal degrees of capacity of different kinds. Each individual has his par- ticular proportion of aptitudes and tendencies, which con- stitute his nature or his natural character, as distinguished from his later and partly acquired character. This nat- ural character is doubtless very closely connected with the peculiar make of his bodily, and more particularly his nervous organism. The condition of the sense-organs, of the brain, of the muscular system, and even of the lower vital organs, all serves to determine what we call the na- tive idiosyncrasy or temperament of the individual. COMMON AND SPECIAL HEREDITY. 59 The Law of Heredity. — According to modern sci- ence these original differences are, in part at least, illustra- tions of the principle of heredity. This principle states that physical and mental peculiarities tend to be trans- mitted from parents to children. Just as bodily features reappear in parents and children, so intellectual and moral traits persist in the shape of inherited mental dispositions. These are handed down in connection with certain pecul- iarities of the brain and nervous system. Common and Special Heredity. — The principle of heredity manifests itself in different ways. In one sense we may say that our common human nature, with its typical physical organism and its several mental suscepti- bilities and capabilities, is inherited, that is, transmitted to each new member of the species. But, as customarily employed, the term heredity refers to the transmission of physical or mental peculiarities which have somehow been acquired by the individual's ancestors. This trans- mission of acquired characteristics assumes a wider or a narrower form. Its widest range is seen in the alleged fact that the offspring of civilized races have from the first a higher intellectual and moral endowment than those of uncivilized, having certain original or instinctive disposi- tions to think, feel, and act in the ways that have become habitual with civiHzed mankind. According to this view, as civilization progresses and education improves, native capacity tends to slowly increase, and this gradual increase constitutes one factor in the upward progress of the spe- cies. Again, members of one particular race or national- ity, as Celts or Frenchmen, appear to inherit distinct phys- ical and mental traits. Still more plainly the members of one family may often be observed to present similar mental as well as bodily characteristics through a number of generations. These mental peculiarities are partly in- tellectual, partly emotional, and partly active, referring to differences in strength of will, etc. An interesting exam- 6o MENTAL DEVELOPMENT. pie of this is occasionally to be met with in the transmis- sion of a definite kind of talent through generations of a given family, as, for example, of musical talent in the Bach family.* It is evident, however, that the members of one family show marked diversities as well as similarities. We often remark very striking contrasts of ideas, feelings, and incli- nations among children of the same family. Such con- trasts may sometimes be only another illustration of the action of heredity, some members of the family represent- ing certain ancestral traits, other members, other traits. But this can not be safely maintained in the majority of instances. In the present stage of our knowledge of the subject, heredity only helps us to account for a compara- tively few among the host of peculiarities which go to make up the natural basis of an individual character. We have to recognize along with this another tendency, namely, to individual variation. Varieties of External Influence. — While original peculiarities of nature or temperament thus play a consid- erable part in individual development, they are not the sole agency at work. Differences in the surroundings, physical and still more social, have a good deal to do with the differences of ability and character that we find among individuals. The important thing to bear in mind here is that no two individuals ever come under the same influences. Even twins, who are born into the same family at the same time, have an unlike social environment from the first. Their own mother is hardly likely to feel toward them or to treat them in quite the same way ; and others show this divergence of feeling and behavior very much more. As life progresses, the sum of external influences, serving to * For fuller illustrations of such transmission of definite ability, see Mr. F. Galton's work, " Hereditary Genius " ; cf. Prof. Th. Ribot's volume, "On Heredity." VARIETIES OF EXTERNAL INFLUENCE, 6 1 differentiate individual character, increases. The school, the place of business, the circle of friends, and so on, all help to give a peculiar stamp to the individual mind. That even such slight differences in surroundings must produce an effect follows from psychological laws. The mind grows on what it assimilates. The lines of its growth will be to some extent predetermined by innate capabili- ties and tendencies ; but these only broadly limit the pro- cess, they do not fix its precise character. The particular ideas and connections of ideas formed, the intellectual habits fixed, the peculiar coloring of the feelings, and the special lines of the conduct will all be determined by the character of the surroundings. It is impossible, in the present state of our knowledge, to say how much of the diversity of intelligence and char- acter that we find among men is referable to native dif- ferences, how much to the effects of surroundings, more particularly social surroundings. The older psychology of Locke overlooked the effects of native differences, of individual nature. To Locke all men were born- with equal abilities, and the differences were due to experience and education. The newer psychology rightly insists on the existence of these original differences, on the effects of "nature" as distinguished from "nurture."* There is no doubt that similar experiences and outer influences do not produce precisely identical results. At the same time, it is possible that we of to-day are apt to underesti- * The importance of original differences of mtellectual aptitude and emotional disposition has just been insisted on with great force of argu- ment by Mr. F. Galton in his curious volume, " Inquiries into Human Faculty and its Development." See '* Nurture and Nature," p. 177, etc. An illustration of the strength and pertinacity of original tend- encies is very clearly brought out in the " History of Twins," p. 216, et seq. Mr. Galton takes cases of twins who were much alike, and also of twins who were distinctly unlike, and he seeks to show that in both cases the final result is largely determined by nature and not by nur- ture. 62 MENTAL DEVELOPMENT. mate the effects of surroundings, and more particularly of early bringing up. It is true, of course, that there never is anything in the finished mental product, the mature mind and character, which was not present potentially at the outset. It is also true that all growth is the immediate outcome of the mind's own exertion and activity. Still, it may be said that the special external circumstances of the individual life were needed to evoke and nurture these latent germs of ability, and to call forth and direct that activity. It is common to say that men of genius are independ- ent of their surroundings, that their powers germinate and fructify in spite of unfavorable surroundings. This is true in a sense. The stronger the native intellectual bent, the more strenuous the mental exertions, the more independ- ent is the mind of its surroundings; or, to put it more accurately, the more readily will it create a favorable en- vironment (companions, books, etc.) for itself. In aver- age cases, however, when there is no such powerful and predominant impulse, it is the actual surroundings, and particularly the early influences of the home and the school, which determine which of the potential aptitudes and in- clinations shall be fostered into life and vigor. The Teacher and the Social Environment. — From the foregoing we see that education fulfills an im- portant function among the influences presupposed in development. The intellectual and moral culture of the home constitutes a prime ingredient in the sum of the influences of the social environment. The influence of the school-teacher, though much more restricted on the emo- tional and moral side, is the most important of the external stimuli to intellectual progress. As Pestalozzi has pointed out, the teacher stands in place of the parent, having to carry forward, in a more thorough and systematic manner, and to a much higher point than the qualifications and the opportunities of the parent commonly allow, the early TRAINING OF THE FACULTIES. 63 intellectual instruction of the home ; and, regarded in this light, his work is eminently a natural one, being the out- growth of the instinct of instruction which shows itself in germ in the lower animals, and in man is inseparately in- tertwined with the parental feelings and instincts. Viewed in another way, the teacher represents not merely the par- ent but the community. This he does by aiming at pre- paring the learner in intelligence, and, as far as possible, in character, to properly fill his future place in the com- munity ; and by bringing to bear for this purpose all the resources of the knowledge which has become the heritage of the present from the past, as well as a type of character which represents as clearly as possible the highest moral progress yet attained by man. Training of the Faculties. — The systematic pro- cedure of the teacher is implied in the word training. This involves the putting of the child in such circum- stances, and surrounding it by such influences, as will serve to call the faculty into exercise, or, as has already been pointed out, the supplying of the intellect with ma- terials to work upon, or nutriment to be assimilated, to- gether with the application of a stimulus or motive to exertion. It means, too, the continuous or periodic exer- cise of the faculty, with the definite purpose of strengthen- ing it, and advancing its growth. Such training must clearly be based on a knowledge of the laws of mental development. Thus it has to conform to the great law of all growth, that it is appropriate exer- cise which strengthens faculty. That is to say, it will aim directly at calling forth a faculty into its proper mode of action by supplying materials and motives adapted to the stage of development reached at the time. . Training may be said to be adapted when it supplies an adequate but not excessive stimulation of the faculty. By adequate stimulation is here meant an excitation of sufficient strength and variety to secure completeness of growth. A 64 MENTAL DEVELOPMENT. boy's memory or understanding is not properly trained if very easy tasks are assigned which fail to rouse the faculty to full activity. By excessive stimulation is meant an amount of excitation which forces the activity to such a point as is unfavorable to growth. Thus, when a boy is set to master a problem in Euclid beyond his powers of reasoning the task, by baffling effort and confusing the mind, is distinctly adverse to intellectual progress. It fol- lows that all good training must be progressive, the tasks becoming more difficult pari passu with the growth of ability. In the second place, the whole scheme of training should conform to the natural order of development of the faculties. Those faculties which develop first must be exercised first. It is vain, for example, to try to cultivate the power of abstraction, by subjects like grammar, before the powers of observation (perception) and imagination have reached a certain degree of strength. This self-evi- dent proposition is one of the best accepted principles in the modern theory of education, though there is reason to apprehend that it is still frequently violated in practice. Once more, a method of training based on scientific principles will aim not only at taking up a faculty at the right moment, but also at cultivating it up to the proper point, and not beyond this. By this point is meant the level which answers to its rank or value in the whole scale of faculties. Thus, for example, in training the memory or the imagination we should inquire into its precise importance in relation to the attainment of knowl- edge and intellectual culture as a whole, and give to its exercise and development a proportionate amount of attention. The perfect following out of this principle is that harmonious development of the whole mind on which Pestalozzi and others have laid emphasis. The educator must ever keep before him the ideal of a complete man, TRAINING OF THE FACULTIES. 65 strong and well-developed physically, intellectually, and morally, and, so far as practicable, assign a proportionate amount of time and exercise to the development of each side of the child's being. Finally, training, in order to be adequate, must be to some extent elastic, adapting itself to the numerous dif- ferences among young minds. Up to a certain point a common result, namely, a typical completeness of develop- ment, will be aimed at. It would not be well, for ex- ample, that any child, however unimaginative, should have his imagination wholly untrained. At the same time this typical plan of cultivation must be modified in detail. The greater the natural aptitude, the more eco- nomical the production of a given psychical result. Hence it would be wasteful to give as much time and thought to the training of a bad as of a good germ of faculty. Nor do the practical ends of life impose such a disagreeable task on the teacher. Variety of individual development is in itself valuable, and moreover answers to the highly elaborated division of life-work or differentiation of life- function which characterizes civilization. The problem of respecting individuality in educating the young, of secur- ing a sufficient diversity of studies in our school system, is probably one of the most urgent practical educational problems of the hour. APPENDIX. For a fuller account of the nature and causes of mental develop, ment the reader is referred to Mr. Spencer's " Principles of Psy- chology," especially vol i, parts iii and iv. A brief statement of the characteristics of development, as bearing on the work of the teacher, will be found in Mr. Spencer's essay, "Education," chap. ii. The subject has also been discussed from an educational point of view by Beneke, '* Erziehu/igslehre," i, p. loi, etc., and by G. F. Pfisterer, " Paedagogische Psychologic," § 2. CHAPTER VI. ATTENTION. Place of Attention in Mind. — Attention enters as an important condition into all classes of mental opera- tion. There is no distinct thinking, no vivid feeling, and no deliberate action without attention. This co-operation of attention is specially conspicuous in the case of intellect- ual operations. The objects which present themselves to our senses are only clearly discriminated one from the other, and classed as objects of such and such a class, when we attend to them. So again, present impressions only exercise their full force in calling up what is as- sociated with them when we keep them before the mind by an act of attention. Once more, all abstract thinking is clearly an active state of mind involving a voluntary fixing of the attention. We thus see that attention, though a form of action, and in its higher developments presup- posing an effort of will, stands in the closest relation to intellectual operations. It is co-operation of the active side of mind in intellectual processes, and it is one of the great determining forces of intellectual development. This being so, it is desirable to give a brief account of it before entering on the exposition of intellect, reserving the exposition of its higher forms till we come to consider the nature of volition. Definition of Attention. — Attention may be roughly defined as the active self-direction of the mind to any PLACE OF ATTENTION IN MIND, 6/ material or object which presents itself to it at the mo- ment.* It thus means somewhat the same as the mind's *' consciousness " of what is present to it. The field of attention, however, is narrower than that of consciousness. I may be very vaguely or indistinctly conscious of some bodily sensation, as hunger, of some haunting recollection, and so on, without making it the object of attention. At- tention involves an intensification of consciousness, a con- centration or narrowing of it on some definite and re- stricted portion of the mental scene ; or, to express it otherwise, it implies a turning of the mental eye in a par- ticular direction so as to see the objects lying in that quarter as distinctly as possible, f As an active tension of mind, attention is opposed to that relaxed state of mind in which there is no conscious exertion to fix the gaze on any particular object. This answers to what the teacher is wont to call inattention. It is a state of listlessness or drowsiness as compared with one of activity and wakefulness. Directions of Attention. — Attention follows one of two main directions ; that is, is directed to one of two great fields of objects, (i) The first region is that of ex- ternal impressions, the sights, sounds, etc., which make up the world of sense. When the teacher talks about "attending," he commonly means actively listening, or actively looking. This is the direction of attention out- ward, or external attention. (2) In addition to external impressions, internal images, ideas and thoughts, may be attended to. This constitutes the second main direction of attention, or internal attention. All intellectual atten- * The reader must be careful to distinguish between " object of attention" and "external object," as we commonly understand it. As we shall see presently, the former, though including the latter, is a much wider domain than this. •j" The idea of mental activity in the full sense, or mental tension, is directly suggested by the etymology of the word, ad tenderer to stretch (sc, the mind toward). 68 ATTENTION. tion, that is to say, attention engaged in the processes of learning or coming to know about things, is attention directed either to external impressions or to internal ideas. So far as we attend to feelings of pleasure and pain we appear to do so by fixing the attention on the ex- citing cause of the feeling, which must be either an exter- nal object or an internal idea. Finally, in attending to our actions, we fix our minds on the idea of the result which we are immediately aiming at. Thus, in every case, the object of attention is some external impression, or internal idea, or thought. Effects of Attention. — The immediate effect of an act of attention serves to give greater force, vividness, and distinctness to its object. Thus an impression of sound, as the tolling of a bell, becomes more forcible, and has its character made more definite, when we direct our atten- tion to it. A thought, a recollection, is rendered distinct by attending to it. The intensification of consciousness in one particular direction produces thus an increase of illumination, and so subserves the clear perception and understanding of things. Attention produces striking effects on the feelings. A serious bodily injury may hardly trouble our mind, if through some exceptional excitement it is hindered from attending to it. Thus it is known that soldiers wounded in battle have hardly felt any pain at the moment. On the other hand, a very moderate sensation of discomfort, as an irritation of the skin, grows into something intensely disagreeable if the attention is fastened on the particular bodily locality affected. Finally, our actions grow more vigorous and energetic as well as more precise when we give our attention to the objects aimed at.* Physiology of Attention. — The seat of attention appears to be situated in the higher region of the nerve- * For some curious illustrations of the effects of attention, see Dr. Carpenter's *' Mental Physiology," chap. iii. EXTENT OF ATTENTION, 6g centers in the cerebral hemispheres. The mechanism of attention probably involves an intensification of nervous activity in certain regions of the brain, which is effected by means of an impulse sent forth from the supreme con- trolling centers. In this way, for example, the nerve- centers employed in hearing are thrown into a state of exceptional excitabiHty when we listen to somebody read- ing or singing. Along with this concentration of nerve- energy in certain definite regions of the brain, the act of external attention involves important muscular adjust- ments, such as directing the eye to an object, which are necessary to the reception of distinct sense-impressions. Extent of Attention.— All attention is a narrowing of the range of mental activity and to a certain extent a concentration or focusing of the mind on a given point. But all acts of attention do not embrace equal areas or extents. Just as in looking at a landscape we may fix the eye on a smaller or larger portion of the scene, so the mind may direct itself to a smaller or larger area of object. In general it may be said that the more things we try to include in our mental gaze the less distinct is the result. This is seen plainly in all efforts to attend to a variety of disconnected things at one time, as when we are reading a book and listening to a conversation. " One thing at a time " is the law of mental activity, and the performing of distinct mental occupations is only possible where repetition and habit exempt us from close attention, as in carrying on some familiar manual operation and listening to another's words. Where, however, we have to do with a number of con- nected impressions or objects of attention, we are able to a certain extent to include them in one view. Thus we can attend to the features of a face in their relations of proportion, to a succession of musical sounds in their re- lations of rhythm, etc. This grasp of a number of parts, 7 70 ATTENTION. details, or members of a group, is greatly facilitated by a rapid transition of the mental glance from one detail to another, as in running over the various features of an artistic design, or the succeeding steps of an argument. On what the Degree of Attention depends.— The amount of attention exerted at any time depends on two chief circumstances : (a) the quantity of nervous energy disposable at the time; (b) the strength of the stimulus which excites the attention or rouses it to action. If there is great active energy, a feeble stimulus will suffice to bring about attention. A healthy, vigorous child, in the early part of the day, has a superabundance of energy which shows itself in attention to small and comparatively uninteresting matters. Indeed, his activity prompts him to seek objects of attention in his surroundings. On the other hand, a tired or weakly child requires a powerful stimulus to rouse his mental activity. External and Internal Stimuli. — The stimulus to an act of attention may be either something external, con- nected with the object attended to, or something internal. An external stimulus consists of some interesting or strik- ing feature in the object itself, or in its accompaniments, by reason of which the attention is said to be attracted and arrested, as when a child's attention is excited by the brilliance of a light, or the strangeness of a sound. An internal stimulus is a motive in the mind which prompts it to put forth its attention in a particular direction, such as the desire of a child to please his teacher, or to gain a higher place in his class. Non-Voluntary and Voluntary Attention.— When the mind is acted upon by the mere force of the object presented, the act of attention is said to be non-voluntary.* It may also be called reflex (or automatic) because it bears * The term non-voluntary is preferred to involuntary, as indicating the mere absence of volition, and not opposition to will or " unwilling- ness." LAW OF CONTRAST AND NOVELTY. 71 a striking analogy to reflex movement, that is to say, move- ment following sensory stimulation without the interven- tion of a conscious purpose. On the other hand, when we attend to a thing under the impulse of a desire, such as curiosity or a wish to know about a thing, we are said to do so by an act of will, or voluntarily. These two modes of attention, though properly distinguished one from an- other, are both acts of the mind, and will be found to shade off one into the other in our actual mental life. Reflex Attention. — This is the earlier form of atten- tion, and the one with which the teacher is specially con- cerned in the first stages of instruction. Here the direc- tion of the attention is determined for the mind rather than by the mind. It follows the lead of the attractive force which happens to work at the time. In its simplest form attention is a momentary direction of the attention due to the action of a powerful sensory stimulus, as a brilliant light, a loud sound, etc. Every teacher knows the value of a strong emphatic mode of utterance in commanding the attention ; and this effect is partly due to the action of strong sensuous impressions in rousing mental activity. Law of Contrast and Novelty.— This momentary direction of the attention is governed by the law of change or contrast. According to this principle, an unvarying impression, if prolonged, fails to produce a mental effect. The constant noise of the mill soon ceases to be noticed by one who lives near it. This is partly due to the fact that a prolonged powerful stimulus fatigues the nerve-cen- ter and renders it less responsive. But, in addition to this, a prolonged impression, even if a powerful one, loses its effect because it ceases to exert an attractive force on the attention. Hence, the teacher who continually or very frequently addresses his class in loud tones, misses the advantage of an occasional raising of the voice. On the other hand, a sudden change of impression, as 72 ATTENTION. when a light is brought into a dark room, or the report of a gun breaks the stillness of the country, acts as a power- ful excitant to the attention. For the same reason a strong contrast of impression, as between high and low, soft and loud in music, bright and dark colors, and so forth, is an excitant to the attention. Novelty, so powerful a force in childhood and a con- siderable force throughout life, is only a further illustra- tion of the law of change. For something new attracts the attention, because it stands in contrast with our ordi- nary surroundings and experience. It stimulates and ex- cites the mind very much as a startling contrast. Interest. — When it is said that we only attend to what interests us, there is a reference to the excitation of a cer- tain amount of feeling. This feeling acts as a force in ar- resting the attention and keeping it fixed for an apprecia- ble time. Attention to what interests us is thus always something more than the momentary direction of atten- tion. This feeling of interest may arise in different ways. (i) In the first place, interest is excited when the ob- ject is in itself pretty or beautiful, and so fitted to give immediate pleasure or gratification in the very act of attending to it. Thus, an infant will keep its eyes fixed for a time on the lamp brought into the room, because of its pleasurable effect. The production of pleasure, in con- nection with any mode of activity, tends, as we shall see by-and-by, to intensify and prolong this activity. This forms the germ of aesthetic interest. (2) Another great source of interest in things is their connection with what is pleasurable or painful in our past experience. The infant shows the most vivid interest in such sights as the preparation of its food, its bath, etc. A child will listen to whatever bears on its familiar pleas- ures, its favorite possessions and companions, its amuse- ments, etc. In all states of fear, again, we see the atten- tion closely engaged by that which bears on pain or suffer- FAMILIARITY AND INTEREST, ^73 ing. This effect of a connection or association with what is pleasurable or painful in riveting the attention underlies what we mark off as practical interest. (3) Lastly, interest may assume a more distinctly in- tellectual form, involving the germ of a wish to understand a thing, and the desire for knowledge as such. This intellect- ual interest is what we commonly call curiosity. It springs up in different ways. It arises most naturally out of a feeling of wonder at what is new, strange, and mysterious, as when a child sees a light go out in a bottle filled with car- bonic acid, and wants to know the cause. In many cases, however, it takes its rise in the feeling of delight produced by what is beautiful, as when a child is interested in know- ing about a lovely flower or bird. Finally, this intellectual interest is greatly promoted by the principle of associa- tion. The direction of children's curiosity follows to a large extent the lead of association. What is seen to have a bearing on the child's pleasures and practical aims tends to become the object of a genuine intellectual curiosity. Familiarity and Interest.— It follows from this that mere novelty, though a powerful stimulus to the at- tention, and capable of leading on to curiosity, is rarely if ever sufficient to detain and fix the attention in a pro- longed act or attitude. What is absolutely strange and consequently unsuggestive to the child's mind is apt to be a matter of indifference. In walking down a new street, for^ example, a child will as a rule notice those things which in some way remind him of, and connect themselves with, what he already knows and likes, e. g., the harness in the saddler's shop.* While, therefore, the principle of change tells us that perfect familiarity with a subject is fatal to interest, the laws of intellectual interest tell us that a measure of familiarity is essential. The principle * See the interesting account of the want of interest in London sights manifested by some Esquimaux who visited our capital, given by Miss Edgeworth, " Practical Education," ii, p. 118. 74 ATTENTION. of modern intellectual education, that there should be a gradual transition from the known to the unknown, is thus seen to correspond not only with the necessities of intellect- ual movement and development, but also with the natural laws of development of those feelings of interest which in- spire attention and so call the intellectual faculties into play. Transition to Voluntary Attention.— The devel- opment of interest and curiosity forms a natural transition from non-voluntary to voluntary attention. The prolonga- tion of the act of attention implies a germ of volition. Thus the maintenance of the expectant attitude of mind by a class, when the teacher is presenting interesting ma- terials, is due to a vague anticipation of coming gratifica- tion and a desire to realize this. Here, then, we see how gradually the earlier and lower form passes into the later and higher. In supplying interesting matter to his class, and exciting a feeling of pleasurable interest, the teacher is preparing the way for the exercises of the will in what is called voluntary attention. Function of the Will in Attention.— It is impossi- ble at this stage to explain the whole nature of voluntary attention. As a mode of will or volition it obeys the laws of volition, which will be expounded later on. Here it must suffice to indicate the effects of voluntary action in enlarging the sphere and otherwise modifying the charac- ter of attention. To begin with, then, what is called voluntary attention is not a wholly new phase of the process. After the ac- tion of the will has supervened, the forces of non-voluntary attention continue to be active as tendencies. And the range of the will's action is limited by these. Thus the student most practiced in abstraction finds that there is some force of external stimulus, as the allurement of a beautiful melody sung within his hearing, against which his will is impotent. Again, though we can undoubtedly (within certain FUNCTION OF THE WILL IN ATTENTION. 75 limits) direct our attention in this or that quarter at will, we have not the power to keep our attention closely and persistently fixed on any object which we (or somebody else for us) may happen to select. Something further is necessary to that lively interaction of- mind and object which we call a state of attention ; and this is interest. By an act of will a person may resolve to turn his atten- tion to something, say a passage in a book. But if, after this preliminary process of adjustment of the mental eye, the subject-matter opens up no interesting phase, no effort of volition will produce a calm, settled state of concentra- tion. The will introduces mind and object : it can not force an attachment between them. No compulsion of a teacher ever succeeded in making a young mind cordially embrace and appropriate by an act of concentration an unsuitable, and therefore uninteresting subject. We thus see that voluntary attention is not removed from the sway of interest. What the will does is to determine the kind of interest which shall prevail at the moment. The importance of this initial action of will, in deter- mining the direction of attention, depends on the fact that in many cases a strong interest is only developed after the mind and the subject-matter have remained in contact awhile. Many subjects do not disclose their attractions at once and on the surface, but only after they have been more closely examined. Thus the charm of a poem or of a geometrical problem makes itself felt gradually. Hence, if a child can be induced to exercise his will at the outset, under the influence of some internal motive disconnected with the subject, as the desire to please his parents or teacher, or to gain some tangible advantage from the study, he will often come under the spell of new and un- suspected varieties of interest. Indeed, the taking up of any new branch of study illustrates this gradual substitu- tion of an easy, agreeable activity for a comparatively hard and disagreeable one. ^6 ATTENTION. Growth of Attention : Early Stage. — After this account of the nature and laws of attention and its two chief forms, a few words will suffice to indicate the suc- cessive phases of its growth. As has been observed, the early form of attention is the reflex or non-voluntary. By frequent exercises of its activity in response to external stimuli the power attains a certain degree of development independently of any aid from the will. By this is meant that, after a certain number of exercises, less powerful stimuli suffice, in the absence of more powerful ones, to call forth attention. Thus, by directing his attention again and again to bright objects, as the candle, the infant is preparing to direct it (still non-voluntarily) to the mother's face, his own hands, etc., when these objects happen to come into the field of view. With the progress of life, too, many things at first indifferent acquire an interest. Thus the accompaniments of what is intrinsically interest- ing would acquire (according to the principle of associ- ation) a borrowed or derived interest. In this way the infant tends to watch the movements and doings of his nurse, mother, etc. ; the boy comes to take an interest in the construction of his kite, and so on. Not only so, the range of interesting objects would be greatly extended by the development of new feelings, such as the sense of the grotesque, the feeling for what is beautiful, affection, etc. Development of Power of controlling the At- tention. — While this exercise of the power of attention in the reflex form is thus going on, the child's will is also de- veloping. The simplest manifestation of voluntary atten- tion may perhaps be found in the continued gazing at an agreeable object, such as a brightly colored toy or picture, held before the eye ; for here, as pointed out above, there is a vague anticipation of further pleasure. A more dis- tinctly marked development of will-power is manifested in the attitude of expectation. From a very early period of life the will begins to manifest itself in a deliberate explor- ATTENTION TO THE UNIMPRESSIVE. 77 ing or looking out for objects to inspect or examine.* By- such successive exercises the activity of attention is little by little brought under perfect control. Although the full understanding of this process presupposes a knowledge of the growth of will as a whole, we may be able to antici- pate to some extent, and indicate the main lines of this progress. The growth of voluntary attention means a continual reduction of the difficulty of attending to objects. The law that exercise strengthens faculty applies to attention. What is first done with labor and sense of difficulty is, with repetition and practice, done more and more easily. At the same time more and more difficult tasks become possible. The growth of attention may be best treated by distinguishing between the several forms in which this progressive mastery of difficulty manifests itself. Attention to the Unimpressive.— Voluntary atten- tion is obviously a going beyond the range of powerful and directly interesting stimuli, and an embracing of a wider circle of comparatively unimpressive and only indirectly interesting objects. The progress of attention can be measured under this aspect. The child learns gradually to fix with his eye the less striking, prominent, and attract- ive objects and events of the world in which he lives. When no strongly impressive objects are present, the very- impulse of activity will insure a certain amount of atten- tion to less conspicuous and striking ones. Moreover, each successive exercise of the attention makes subsequent exercises easier, and the growth of mind as a whole implies * Prof. Preyer says that the child begins to explore the field of vis- ion in search of objects before the end of the third month. (" Die Seele des Kindes," p. 33.) He puts the first appearance of volition, properly so called, a month or two later. This suggests that the simple action here spoken of is a transition from the reflex to the voluntary form of attention. On the other hand, M. Perez thinks he discovers the germ of voluntary attention at the age of two months and six days. (" The First Three Years of Childhood," p. 112.) 78 ATTENTION, the constant addition of new needs and impulses which would insure a wider range of attention. Resistance to Stimuli. — A voluntary control of the attention involves, in the second place, the ability to resist the solicitations of extraneous and distracting objects. Voluntarily to turn the mind to a thing is to exclude what is irrelevant. This power of resistance has, of course, in every case its limits. Nobody can withstand the disturb- ing force of a sudden explosion. But the capabiHty of resisting such distractions varies considerably, and is greatly improved by practice. The child, when sent to school, finds it hard at first not to look at his companions, or out of the window, when a lesson is being given. By- and-by he will be able to fix his mind on his lesson, even when some amount of disturbing noise is present. The highest attainment of this power is seen in the student whose mind is " abstracted " from external impressions, being wholly absorbed in internal reflection. Keeping the Attention fixed. — Another aspect, under which the growth of attention may be estimated, is the ability to detain objects before the mind. As we have seen, reflex attention is, for the most part, a process of flit- ting from object to object. We found, indeed, that even here there is a force at work which tends to counteract the impulse to skip from one thing to another. But this would not of itself carry us very far. It is only as the attention comes under the control of the will that it shows any con- siderable measure of persistence. To attend to a thing voluntarily means commonly to keep the mind dwelling on it. The ordinary school exercises involve such a prolonged and sustained effort of attention. Thus, in counting, the mind has to keep steadily in view the result of each of the successive operations as it is reached. The wandering of the thoughts for an instant would be fatal to the achieve- ment of the whole process. So, in following a description, a demonstration in Euclid, and so forth. CONCENTRA TION, 79 Here, again, we have to recognize the existence of cer- tain limits in every case. Nobody can fix his mind on one and the same object — say a geometrical figure — for an in- definite time. When once the fresh interest of a thing is exhausted, a further fixing of the attention costs more and more effort. Nor can a pupil carry on a sustained effort of attention through an indefinitely long arithmetical or other operation. The brain is soon wearied by the pro- longed exertion, and attention flags in spite of the utmost effort. But the limit of fatigue is pushed further off as the will develops and the act of attention becomes more easy. Concentration. — The power of sustained attention grows with the ability to resist distractions and solicita- tions. The two capabilities are thus very closely con- nected with one another, and are both included in the term concentration. To concentrate the mind is to fix it persistently on an object or group of objects, resolutely excluding from the mental view all irrelevant objects. The great field for the early exercises of such concentra- tion is action. When the child wants to do something, as open a box, or build a pile of bricks, the strong desire for the end secures a prolonged effort of attention. The scholar patiently poring over a mutilated passage in an ancient MS., to the neglect of his appetite, or the natural- ist patiently observing the movements of insects or of plants, indifferent to cold and wet, illustrates a high power of prolonged concentration. A person's power of attention may be conveniently measured by the degree of persistence attained. Concentration and Intellectual Power. — It has often been said that great intellectual power turns on the ability to concentrate the attention. Newton based his intellectual superiority on this circumstance. Helvetius observed that genius is nothing but a continued attention. A proposition about which there is so general an agree- 8o ATTENTION, ment among those who ought to know may be safely ac- cepted as expressing a truth. Attention is a condition of all intellectual achievement, and a good power of pro- longed concentration is undoubtedly indispensable to first- rate achievement in any direction. The discoverers of new knowledge have always been distinguished by an unusual degree of pertinacity in brooding over a subject, and in following out trains of thought in this and that direction till the required explanation of fact, reconcili- ation of apparent contradictions, and so on, was found. But though these sayings undoubtedly embody an impor- tant truth, they only contain a part of the whole truth. No amount of attention simply will constitute intellectual eminence. The dull, slow, but exceedingly plodding child is a familiar type to the teacher. Success of the higher order depends on the possession of the intellectual functions (discrimination, etc.) in an exceptionally perfect form. On the other hand, good intellectual powers, when aided by a comparatively small power of prolonged atten- tion, may render their possessor quick and intelligent. Grasp of Attention. — As was pointed out above, the mind has a certain power of including a number of objects in one glance, and this power underlies the apprehension of all relations, such as symmetry of form, similarity be- tween objects, etc. The acquisition of this grasp is one of the most valuable results of the growth of the power of voluntary attention. Only as this power is developed will it be possible for the teacher to take his pupil on to the higher intellectual exercises, such as the understanding of geometrical relations of the more complicated kind, the processes of comparing a number of things with a view to abstraction, the logical analysis of sentences, arguments, and so forth. This form of attention, like the other forms, needs its own special modes of exercise to develop and improve it. We must distinguish this power of carrying the atten- VARIETIES OF ATTENTIVE POWER. 8l tion quickly over a number of connected details from another variety of attention closely akin to it, viz., the capability of transferring the mental glance from one thing to another and disconnected thing. This capability is illustrated in a striking form in the rapid movements of the versatile mind from one subject of conversation, one region of ideas to another. This power of rapid trans- ference, though valuable in many intellectual exercises, is of far less value than the power of mentally bringing a number of details together as parts of one whole. It is plain, too, that it is in a manner opposed to prolonged concentration upon one subject. Habits of Attention, — Voluntary attention, like vol- untary action as a whole, is perfected in the form of habits. By a habit we mean a fixed disposition to do a thing, and a facility in doing it, the result of numerous repetitions of the action. The growth of the power of attention may be viewed as a progressive formation of habits. At first vol- untary concentration of mind requires a spur and an effort. As soon as the pressure of strong motive is withdrawn, the young mind returns to its natural state of listlessness or wandering attention. A habit of attention first appears as a recurring readiness to attend under definite circum- stances, for example when the child goes into his class- room, or is addressed by somebody. This is what Miss Edgeworth calls a habit of associated attention. Later on there manifests itself a more permanent attitude of atten- tiveness. The transition from childhood to youth is often characterized by the acquisition of a more general atti- tude of mental watchfulness, showing itself in thoughtful- ness about what is seen and heard. The highest result of the working of the principle of habit in this region is illus- trated in the customary, and but rarely relaxed, alertness of mind of the artistic or scientific observer of nature. Varieties of Attentive Power.— It has been im- plied that the power of attention develops very unequally 8 82 A TTENTION. in different individual cases. With some this power never reaches a high point at all ; these are the children of slug- gish attention, the "saunterers," to use Locke's expression, who form the teacher's crux. Again, owing to differences of native endowment, as well as of exercise, we find well- marked contrasts in the special direction which the atten- tive power assumes. And these help, to a considerable extent, to determine the cast or character of the indi- vidual intelligence. Everybody knows the difference, for example, between the plodding child, able to concentrate his mind on an object for a long period, but slow to transfer and adjust his attention to new matter, and the quick but rather superficial child — the volatile genius, ac- cording to Miss Edgeworth, who finds it easy to direct his attention to new objects, though hard to keep it fixed for a prolonged period. There are many students who are capable of great intensity of concentration under favor- able circumstances, but whose minds are easily over- powered by disturbing or distracting influences. Finally, the ruling habits of attention will vary according to the character of the predominant interests. Thus, for ex- ample, a strong love of nature (whether scientific or artistic) will give a habitual outward bent to the atten- tion ; whereas a paramount interest in our own feelings, or in the objects of imagination and thought, will give a customary inward inclination to the attention. Training of the Attention. — All intellectual guid- ance of the young manifestly implies the power of holding their attention. Instruction may be said to begin when the mother can secure the attention of the infant to an object by pointing her finger to it. Henceforth she has the child's mental life to a certain extent under her con- trol, and can select the impressions which shall give new knowledge or new enjoyment. What we mark off as formal teaching, whether by the presentation of external objects for inspection through the senses, or by verbal TRAINING OF THE ATTENTION. 83 instruction, clearly involves at every stage an appeal to the attention, and depends for its success on securing this. To know how to exercise the attention, how to call forth its full activity, is thus the first condition of success in education. Mental science here, as in respect of the other faculties, can only point out the general conditions to be observed, and the natural order of procedure. It is plain, in the first place, that the laws of attention must be complied with. He would be a foolish teacher who gave a child a number of disconnected things to do at a time, or who insisted on keeping his mind bent on the same subject for an indefinite period. Yet, though these conditions are obvious enough, others are more easily overlooked. Thus it is probable that a more exact knowledge of the effects on the attention of novelty of subject and mode of treatment, on the one hand, and of total unfamiliarity on the other hand, would save teachers from many errors. Some of us can recall from our school-days the wearisome effect of an oft-recurring stereotyped illustration, as well as the impression of repellent strangeness produced by a first, and too sudden, introduction to a perfectly new branch of study. In the second place, it will be well to bear in mind that the young child's power of voluntary attention is rudi- mentary only, and that force must be economized by re- moving all obstacles and making the task as attractive and agreeable as possible. It would be idle to try to enHst his close attention if he were bodily fatigued, or if he were under the influence of emotional excitement, and agitated in mind and body. Again, it would be vain to expect him to listen to oral instruction close to a window looking out on a busy street. Children's (uncontrolled) attention flows outward to the sights and sounds of the actual external world, and is less easily diverted by the teacher's words toward the world of imagination and thought. 84 ATTENTION. Consequently, in teaching, everything should be done to reduce the force of outward things. The teacher would do well to remember that even so practiced a thinker as Kant found it helpful to prolonged meditation to fix his eye on a familiar and therefore unexciting object (a neighboring church-spire). Not only so, the subject and mode of treatment chosen should be such as to attract the learner's attention to the utmost What is fresh, interest- ing, or associated with some pleasurable interest, will secure and hold the attention when dry topics altogether fail to do so. Much may be done in this direction by preparation, by awakening curiosity, and by putting the child's mind in the attitude of tiptoe expectancy. As the pupil grows, more may of course be required in the shape of a voluntary effort to attend. It must never be forgotten, however, that all through life forced atten- tion to what is wholly uninteresting is not only wearying, but is certain to be ineffectual and unproductive. Hence, the rule to adapt the work to the growing intellectual and other likings of the child. Not only so, the teacher should regard it as an important part of the training of the attention to arouse interest, to deepen and fix it in certain definite directions, and gradually to enlarge its range.* Harder task-work, such as learning the com- paratively uninteresting letters of the alphabet, or the notes of the musical scale, must be introduced gradually, and only when the will-power is sufficiently developed. Great care must be taken further to graduate the length or duration of the mental application, both in a particular direction and generally, in accordance with the progress of the child's powers of voluntary attention. An ideal school-system would exhibit all gradations in this respect ; * Volkmann remarks that the older psedagogic had as its rule, " Make your instruction interesting" ; whereas the newer has the pre- cept, '* Instruct in such a way that an interest may awake and remain active for life " (" Lehrbuch der Psychologic," vol. ii, p. 200). TRAINING OF THE ATTENTION. 85 alternation and complete remission of mental activity be- ing frequent at first, and growing less and less so as the powers of prolonged concentration develop. APPENDIX. On the early development of attention, see Perez, " First Three Years of Childhood," chap. viii. The characteristics of children's at- tention and the laws of the growth of attention are well described by Waitz, "Lehrbuch der Psychologic," § 55 ; and by Volkmann, " Lehr- buch der Psychologic," vol. ii, § 114. On the training of the attention, see Locke, " Some Thoughts con- cerning Education," § 167 ; Maria Edgeworth, " Essays on Practical Education," vol. i, chap. ii. Beneke, " Erziehungs- und Unterrichts- lehre," 4th ed., vol. i, § 19 ; and Th. Waltz's " Allgemeine Paedago- gik," vol. i, § 23. CHAPTER VII. THE SENSES : SENSE-DISCRIMINATION. All knowledge takes its rise in the senses. No intel- lectual work, such as imagining or reasoning, can be done till the senses have supplied the necessary materials. These materials, when reduced to their elements, are known as sensations or impressions, such as those of light and color, which we receive by means of the eye, of sound, which we have by way of the ear, and so on. An examination of our most abstract notions, such as force, matter, leads us back to these impressions of sense. Our ideas respecting the nature and properties of things is limited by our sensa- tions. The want of a sense, as in the case of one born blind, means depriving the mind of a whole order of ideas. The addition of a new sense, if such a thing were possible, would enrich our minds by a new kind of knowledge re- specting the world. Definition of Sensation.— A sensation being an ele- mentary mental phenomenon can not be defined in terms of anything more simple. Its meaning can only be indi- cated by a reference to the nervous processes on which it is known to depend. Accordingly, a sensation may be defined as a simple mental state resulting from the stimu- lation of the outer extremity of an " incarrying " nerve, when this stimulation has been transmitted to the brain- centers. Thus the stimulation of a point of the skin by pressing or rubbing, or of the retina of the eye by light, gives rise to a sensation. GENERAL AND SPECIAL SENSIBILITY. 8/ These sensations have two broadly distinguishable as- pects, one of which is commonly predominant. The first is the emotional aspect, by which is meant the presence of a distinct element of feeling, pleasurable or painful. A sensation of bodily warmth, or of sweetness, illustrates this prominence of the element of feeling. The second aspect is the intellectual^ or knowledge-giving. By this is meant the presence of definite and clearly distinguishable prop- erties, which may be called marks or characters, because they serve as clews to the qualities of external things. The sensation experienced on touching a smooth surface, or on hearing a sound of a particular pitch and loudness, is an example of the predominance of the intellectual element. General and Special Sensibility.—All parts of the organism supplied with sensory nerves, and the actions of which are consequently fitted to give rise to sensations, are said to possess sensibility of some kind. But this prop- erty appears under one of two very unlike forms. • The first of these is common to all sensitive parts of the organ- ism, and involves no special nervous structure at the ex- tremity. The second is peculiar to certain parts of the bodily surface, and implies special structures or "organs." To the former is given the name common or general sensi- bility, and also organic sense ; to the latter, special sensi- bility, or special sense. The sensations falling under the head of common sensi- bility, or the organic sense, are marked by absence of definite characters. They are vague and ill-defined. Their distinguishing peculiarity is that they have a marked pleasurable or painful aspect. Such are the feelings of comfort and discomfort connected with the processes of digestion and indigestion, and with injuries to the tissues. These sensations are not directly connected with the action of external objects, but arise in consequence of a certain condition of the part of the organism concerned. Thus they give us no knowledge of the external world. They 88 THE SENSES: SENSE-DISCRIMINATION. are no doubt important as informing us of the condition of the organism ; but, owing to their vagueness, they give us very little definite knowledge even of this. The special sensations are those we receive by way of the five senses. They are marked off one from another by great definiteness of character. This peculiarity is connected with the fact that each sense has its own spe- cially modified structure or " sense-organ " such as the eye, or the ear, fitted to be acted upon by a particular kind of stimulus (light-vibrations, air-waves, etc.). Owing to this definiteness of character, the special sensations are much more susceptible of being discriminated and recognized than the organic sensations. Moreover, these sensations are (in ordinary cases) brought about by the action of ex- ternal agents or objects lying outside the organism, and are on that account called impressions, or, better, sense- impressions.* For these reasons they are fitted to yield us knowledge of the environment. Characters of Sensations.— The importance of the special senses depends, as we have seen, on their possess- ing certain well-defined aspects, whereby they are fitted to be marks of qualities in external objects as well as of the changes which take place in these. The two most impor- tant distinctions of character among our sensations are those of degree and of kind. By degree or intensity is meant a difference of strength, as that between a bright and a faint light, or a loud and a soft sound. All classes of sensation exhibit such differ- ences of degree. They are of great importance for knowl- edge. Thus the degree of pressure of a body on the hand helps to tell us of its weight. By a difference of kind or quality is meant one of na- ture, as that between sour and sweet, blue and red. These * The sense-impression which we are here concerned with is a w^«- /a/ phenomenon, and must not be confused with the physical " impres- sion," as, for example, the image of an object on the retina. THE FIVE SENSES, 89 too are marks of external facts. Thus we distinguish ob- jects by their colors, voices by their pitch, etc. The Five Senses. — Coming now to the senses in detail, we see that they do not all exhibit the same degree of definiteness or the same number of distinct characters. We usually speak of taste and smell as the coarse or un- refined senses, whereas hearing and sight are highly re- fined. By attending simply to the degree of refinement, we may arrange the senses in the following ascending order: taste, smell, touch, hearing, sight. A few words on the special function of each must suffice here. Taste and Smell. — These present a decidedly low measure of refinement. Indeed, the sensations of these senses may be said to approach the organic sensations in want of definiteness, and in the predominance of the ele- ment of feeling (pleasure and pain). These peculiarities are connected with the fact that these senses have as their function the determination of what is wholesome or un- wholesome to the organism as a whole. The very position of the organs, at the entrance of the digestive and respira- tory cavities, suggests that they are sentinels to warn us as to what is good or ill. The sensations of taste and smell are easily confused one with another, and can not be definite- ly distinguished either in degree or quality. For this and other reasons, they are of little importance as knowledge- giving senses. It is only under special circumstances, as those of the chemist, the wine-taster, and so on, that these " servants of the body " supply a quantity of exact knowl- edge about the properties of external objects. Touch. — By the sense of touch is meant the sensa- tions we receive through the stimulation of certain nerves terminating in the skin by bodies in contact with it. These are either sensations of mere contact or pressure, or those of temperature. These supply important elements of feeling. Thus, contact with smooth surfaces and with warm bodies is go THE SENSES: SENSE-DISCRIMINATION, one chief source of sensuous pleasure, especially in early- life. The chief importance of touch is, however, under its intellectual aspect. In its highest form as it presents itself at definite portions of the bodily surface, more particular- ly the hands, and especially the finger-tips (with which the lips may be reckoned), the tactile sensibility becomes a most important means of ascertaining the properties of bodies. The sensations of touch have a much higher de- gree of definiteness than those of taste and smell. The discrimination of degrees of pressure by the tac- tile sense is estimated by laying a weight on the hand or some other part, and then trying how much must be taken away or added in order that a difference may be felt.* It is found that the discriminative sensibility varies con- siderably at different regions of the bodily surface. For instance, on the anterior surface of the fingers the differ- ence of pressure detected is about one half of that recog- nized on their posterior surface. This discrimination of degrees of pressure by the skin is one of the means by which we obtain knowledge of the force exerted by bodies, e. g., the difference when a heavy and a light body press against us. It also assists in giving us information respecting the weight of bodies. In the case of touch we have a further difference of sensation which may be called local distinction of sensa- tion, or local discrimination. By this is meant the fact that we can distinguish a number of similar touches when different points of the skin are stimulated. This discrimi- nation of points, like that of degrees of pressure, varies at different parts of the bodily surface. It is much finer in the mobile parts of the body (hands, feet, lips, etc.) than * If the hand is the part selected, it must be supported by some object, as a table. Only in this way can we test the tactile sensibility to pressure apart from the muscular sensibility to be spoken of pres- ently. TOUCH. 91 in the comparatively fixed parts (the trunk). Again, it is finer on the anterior than on the posterior surface of the hand, and decreases rapidly as we recede from the finger- tips toward the wrist and elbow. We see from this that the finger-tips are specially marked out as the organ of tactile sensibility.* This local separation of tactile sensations is of the greatest consequence for knowledge. First of all, it is this capability, added to the discrimination of pressure, which forms the basis of our tactile discrimination of roughness and smoothness. A very rough surface, such as that of a piece of unplaned wood or of sand-paper, is appreciated as such by differences of pressure corresponding to eminences and depressions at various points of the surface. In esti- mating a rough surface, therefore, we must both distinguish the several points and the degrees of pressure at these. The sense of roughness and its opposite in their various degrees is of importance in ascertaining not only the na- ture of a surface, but also the texture of a substance, as the fibrous texture of wood, woven materials, etc. In the second place, this local discrimination forms the foundation of the tactile knowledge of what is called ex- tension, or the extendedness of outer things, by which is meant the fact that they have parts occupying different positions in space ; as well as the various modifications of this extendedness which constitute differences of form and magnitude in objects, as differences of direction and length of line, form and extent of surface, etc. It is by laying the hand or the two hands on the surface of an ob- ject, such as a book, that we learn something of its figure and size. Finally, under touch is commonly included the sense of temperature or the thermal sense. It is now known that this sensibility is connected with special nerve-structure * The tip of the tongue and the lips are also highly endowed with tactile discrimination. 92 THE SENSES: SENSE-DISCRIMINATION. distinct from those of the tactile sense proper, and not va- rying in the same way as this varies at different portions of the bodily surface. Hence the thermal sense is a sepa- rate sense. At the same time, we usually test the temper- ature of bodies by touching them, and this with the fin- gers. And the appreciation of temperature thus takes place in close connection with that of their tangible properties. The child learns to know a metal and to distinguish it from wood partly by the differences in the thermal sensa- tions.* Active Touch. — So far we have considered touch merely as a passive sense, i. e., as sensibility to the action of things on the tactile surface. But the fact that we speak of touching bodies as our own action shows that it is an active sense as well. In touching, we ourselves bring the organ into contact with substances, and so secure its exercise. In other words, the organ is supplied with mus- cles, the action of which is of very great importance as enlarging the range of our experience and knowledge. The first and most obvious advantage of this adjunct of muscular activity is the multiplication of tactile impres- sions. Just as the mobility of the insect's antennae en- ables it to gain many more impressions of touch than it would have if the organs were fixed, so the mobile arm, hand, and fingers of the child greatly extend the range of his tactile experiences. By such movements he is able to bring the most sensitive part of the organ (the tips of the fingers) into contact with a large number of objects, and further to gain impressions of these in rapid succession, and so discriminate them better one from the other. This widening and perfecting of passive impressions is, * This knowledge is less valuable than that of form or weight, partly because sensations of temperature are very variable, depending on the temperature of the organ itself, and partly because the temper- ature of bodies is a changing state, and not a fixed, invariable property, as weight. MUSCULAR SENSE. q3 however, only one part of the gain resulting from the high degree of mobility of the hand and the eye. Another and no less important part is the new experience which accom- panies these movements, and which constitutes a distinct and very important source of knowledge. This experience is known as the muscular sense. Muscular Sense.— By this expression is meant the sum of those peculiar " sensations " of which we are aware when we voluntarily exercise our muscles. These have well-marked characters of their own. They constitute distinctly active states. In singing, in moving the arm or leg, in pushing a heavy body, we have a sense of being bodily active, or of exerting muscular energy. The muscular sense is important both as a source of pleasure and as a means of knowledge. The child de- lights to exercise his muscles, to feel his bodily power. Certain modes of muscular exercise, as rapid rhythmical movement, are known to be specially exhilarating. It is, however, chiefly as a source of knowledge that we shall now regard it. The sensations which accompany muscular action may be conveniently divided into two main varieties. These are {a) sensations of movement or of unimpeded energy, and ip) sensations of strain or resistance, that is, of ob- structed or impeded energy. The first are illustrated in the sensations which attend movements of the arms or legs in empty space ; the second are exemplified in the sensations which accompany the act of pushing against a heavy object, or holding a heav/ weight in the hand. (a) Sensations of movement present two well-marked differences of quality: (i) In the first place, they vary in character according to the direction of the movement. The movement effected by one muscle or group of mus- cles is felt to be unlike that carried out by another. Thus the sensations attending the movements of the arm to the right and to the left, up and down, are qualitatively un- 94 THE SENSES: SENSE-DISCRIMINATION. like. And it is this difference in the sensations which enables us to ascertain what is the particular direction of any movement which we are executing. (2) In the second place, these sensations vary in character according to the velocity of the movement. The experience of moving the arm quickly differs materially from that of moving it slow- ly. And we are able to distinguish many degrees of ve- locity. {p) The sensations which arise when muscular energy is impeded, as when we push with the shoulder or arms against a heavy body, drag it, or lift it, have a distinct character of their own. They have been called sensations of resistance, or " dead strain." They exhibit, like those of movement, nice distinctions of degree. We experience a difference of sensation in pushing a heavy table and one less heavy, and in lifting a pound and twenty ounces. Each of these modes of muscular experience consti- tutes an important additional source of tactile knowledge. In truth, our information respecting the most fundamental properties of things would be very vague and rudimentary but for the addition of the muscular sense. In the first place, it is the sensations of resistance which give the child its immediate knowledge of the deepest and most characteristic property of material things, viz., what is known as impenetrability, under its various modes, as hardness, density, inelasticity, etc. The mere sense of pressure gained by way of an im- mobile organ, say a paralyzed limb, could never supply any distinct knowledge of this property ; this is directly revealed in the experience of exerting our own energy and finding it impeded by a force other than our own. All our customary estimates of the degrees of hardness, etc., of substances, are arrived at by the aid of muscular discrimination. Further, the discrimination of weight, though possible to a certain extent by way of passive touch, is much more accurate when the muscular sense is HEARING. 95 called in to help. If a person wants to estimate a weight nicely, he lifts it and judges by means of the degree of force he has to expend in so doing. In the second place, the sensations of movement are an important factor in the knowledge of the extendedness of things, of the relative position of points, and of the shape and size of objects. The rudimentary and vague knowledge obtainable by means of the local discrimina- tion of the skin needs to be rendered distinct and exact by means of movement. Thus, as any one can prove for himself, the idea of the shape and size of a small pencil, or of a ring, is made much clearer when we pass the finger-tip along it or round it, and so judge of it by the direction and length of the movements. The blind habitually examine the form of objects by the aid of movement. Hearing. — The sense of hearing ranks high both as a source of pleasure and as an intellectual or knowledge- giving sense. The sensations which form the material of music, those of pitch, together with their combinations in rhythm, melody, etc., are among the most agreeable of our sense-experiences. But the refined pleasures of music presuppose intellectual capability in the shape of the dis- crimination of notes, etc. The intellectual value of hear- ing is due to the high degree of definiteness of its sen- sations. In respect both of intensity and of quality fine differences are recognizable. The high intellectual character of hearing shows itself very conspicuously in the qualitative differences among sensations of sound. We have here the broad contrast between musical and non-musical sounds or noises. The former depend on regularly recurring or periodic vibra- tions of the air, the latter on irregularly recurring or non- periodic vibrations. In the case of musical sounds we have the remarkable phenomenon of a scale of quality. If we pass upward from a low note to a higher one 96 THE SENSES: SENSE-DISCRIMINATION. through all distinguishable gradations, we experience a continuous variation of sensation which is known as that of pitch or height. These differences of pitch answer to changes in the rate of vibration of the medium (the atmosphere) ; the higher the note, the more rapid are the vibrations. Our musical scale is made up of distinct steps or intervals of this continuous series of gradual changes. Along with this scale of pitch-quality, there are the differences known as timbre or "musical quality." These are the qualitative differences in sensations of tone an- swering to differences in the instrument, as the piano, the violin, the human voice. In addition to this wide range of musical sensation the ear distinguishes a vast number of non-musical sounds, the characteristic '' noises " of different substances, such as the roar of the sea, the rustling of leaves, and the crack of a whip. We distinguish noises as jarring, grating, ex- plosive, and so on. It is this side of hearing which is of value for the knowledge of external things. The child learns to recognize the characteristic sounds produced by moving objects, as the plash of water, the rumbling of wheels, etc. Finally, there are what are known as articulate sounds, those which constitute the elements of speech. These differ from one another partly in point of musical quality. Thus, it has been recently ascertained that the several vowel-sounds differ from one another in much the same way as the tones of different musical instruments. On the other hand, the differences of consonantal sounds are non- musical in character. In the ordinary classification of these into the gutturals, sibilants, etc., we find differences analogous to those among noises. Enough has been said to illustrate the high degree of refinement characterizing the sense of hearing. The deli- cate and far-reaching discrimination of quality, aided by SIGHT. gy the fine discrimination of duration, enables the ear to ac- quire a good deal of exact information, as well as to gain a considerable amount of refined pleasure. The delight of music sums up the chief part of the latter. The former is illustrated in the wide range of knowledge derived by- way of that system of articulate sounds known as language. As a set-off against these advantages, we see that hear- ing has very little local discrimination. We can not dis- tinguish two or more simultaneous sounds with any nicety according to the position of their external source. Nor is the organ of hearing endowed with mobility as the hand is. Hence, hearing gives us no direct knowledge of the most important properties of objects, their size and shape. Sight. — The sense of sight is by common consent allowed the first place in the scale of refinement. To this fact there corresponds the delicate and intricate structure of the organ, and the subtile nature of the stimulus (ether- vibration). The eye surpasses all other sense-organs both in the range and in the delicacy of its impressions. These are at once the source of some of the purest and most re- fined enjoyment, the pleasures of light, color, and form, and of some of the most valuable of our knowledge. In the first place, the eye is fairly discriminative of degree. These degrees answer to all distinguishable grades of brightness or luminosity from the self-luminous bodies which we are only just capable of looking at, down to the objects which reflect a minimum of light, and are known as black. This discrimination is very fine, as may be seen in our ability to note subtile differences of light and shade, and this delicacy is of the greatest importance in the visual discrimination of objects. In sight, again, we have numerous and fine differences of quality. Of these the most important are color-differ- ences. The impressions of color, like those of pitch, fall into a series of gradual changes. Passing from one ex- tremity of the spectrum (or rainbow) scale to another, the 98 THE SENSES: SENSE-DI SCRIMINATION. eye experiences a series of perfectly gradual transitions. These changes fall into the series, violet, blue, green, yel- low, orange, and red, together with certain finer distinc- tions, as indigo-blue, greenish blue. These differences of quality accompany (as in the case of pitch-sensations) changes in the rapidity of the vibrations of the stimulus, viz., the rays of light. The rays at the violet end have more rapid vibrations than those at the red end. These color-impressions, while an important element of artistic pleasure, are of great intellectual importance. The eye learns to know and to recognize things in pan by means of their colors. In addition to these differences of degree and quality in the sensations of sight, we hs.ve in this sense, as in that of touch, two endowments which furnish the basis of a perception of extension and space, including the form and magnitude of objects. The first of these is the discrimi- nation of points by means of the distinct nerve-fibers, which terminate in a mosaic-like arrangement in the retina. Owing to this endowment, we can distinguish two points of light, say two stars, when they lie very near one another. This discrimination of points is finest in the central region of the retina, known as the area of perfect vision. It is by aid of this local discrimination that we are able in one glance to distinguish a number of details of form, such as the various parts of a flower or the several letters of a word. Valuable as this retinal discrimination of points is in the perception of form, it needs to be supplemented by the muscular activity of the eye. The organ of sight is supplied with a system of muscles, by means of which it executes a large variety of delicate and precise movements. Sight is thus, like touch, an active sense. One result of this activity, as in the case of touch, is to bring the most sensitive part of the organ opposite the object we wish to examine. In fixing the eye on a point, we are obtaining a SENSE-IMPRESSIONS. 99 retinal image of it on the area of perfect vision. Another result is that, in the act of moving the eye from point to point of an object or of a scene, we bring the muscular' sense into play, and thus gain a better impression of the relative position of the visible points, and of the form and magnitude of objects. It is by tracing the path of a line with the eye that we can best appreciate its perfect straight- ness, or the exact degree of its curvature. In early life more particularly this is the customary mode of acquiring knowledge of form. Attention to Sense-Impressions.— For the pro- duction of clear sense-impressions it is not enough that the sense-organ be stimulated. There must be a reaction of the brain-centers and the co-operation of the mind in the act of attention. Till this reaction follows, the im- pression must, as pointed out in the preceding chapter, remain vague and indistinct. This direction of mental activity to an impression is the immediate condition of assimilating it as intellectual material. By fixing the men- tal glance on it, the intellectual functions are brought to bear on it, and so it is drawn into the store of our mental possessions, ready to be woven into the fabric of knowl- edge. Discrimination of Sensation.— At any one time we may be acted upon by a multitude of external stimuli, sights, sounds, etc. These present themselves at first as a blurred or confused mass. The direction of attention to any one of them separates it from the adjacent crowd and gives distinctness to it. This fact may also be ex- pressed by saying that it is " differenced " or discriminated. To have a clear and definite sensation is to distinguish it as something from the other sensations immediately pre- ceding and accompanying it. As we have seen, this dis- crimination is much finer in the case of the higher senses — touch, hearing, and sight. Identification of Sense-Impressions.— The direc- lOO THE SENSES: SENSE-DISCRIMINATION. tion of the attention to a sense-impression leads on not only to the discrimination of it. After the repetition of sensations of color, for example, a new sensation is at once identified, as one of yellow, green. This involves the persistence of traces of past similar sensations, and is a rudimentary form of that assimilation of new material to old on which all intellectual development depends. Identification is exact in proportion to the fineness of the discrimination. If a child can only say a certain col- or is red, without being able to identify the precise shade of red, he shows that his discrimination of color is only partially developed. Growth of Sense-Capacity.— From the above, it follows that there is an improvement of sense as life ad- vances. Although the child has the same sense-organs and the same fundamental modes of sensibility as the man, his sensations are more crude, vague, and ill-defined. The repeated exercise of the senses in connection with and under the control of attention leads to the gradual differentiation of the several orders of sense-impression, and the rendering of them definite in their character. This growth of sense involves two things : {a) an increas- ing power of sense-discrimination, and {fi) a growth in the power of identifying impressions through the cumulation of "traces." In other words, our senses become more delicate or acute in distinguishing impressions, and more quick or keen in identifying them. Improvement of Sense-Discrimination.— Of these two aspects of sense-improvement, the discriminative is the more important, since it limits the other. The infant's sensations are at first confused one with another. The first distinctions (next to that of the pleasurable and pain- ful) are those of degree or quantity. Thus, the visual im- pressions of light and darkness, of a bright and a dark surface, are distinguished before those of colors. As the senses are exercised, and attention brought to bear on VARYING SENSE-CAPACITY. loi their impressions, discrimination improves. With respect both to degree and to quality this improvement is gradual, beginning with the detection of broad and striking con- trasts, and proceeding to that of finer differences. Thus, the contrast of loud and soft, of heavy and light, is arrived at long before nice differences of loudness or weight. Similarly, the contrast of the reds with the blues is arrived at before the finer differences between the several sorts of red.* In this way the senses become more acute with ex- ercise. Differences of Sense-Capacity. — Striking differ- ences of sense-capacity present themselves among differ- ent individuals. These are of various kinds. Thus, A may be superior to B in respect of what is called absolute sensibility, or the quickness of response to stimulus. One child is much more readily impressed by a faint smell or sound than another. The tendency to respond to a very weak stimulus, coupled with good retentive or identifying power, would constitute a keen sense in the full meaning of the word, that is, one which readily notes and identifies impressions. From these differences we must carefully separate in- equalities in discriminative power. This is the important in- tellectual side of sense-capacity. It is found to character- ize the more educated and intellectual classes. It does not vary with absolute sensibility. A may be more quickly responsive to a stimulus than B, and yet not be more dis- criminative. These differences of discriminative capacity may be of a more general, or of a special kind. Thus, A may sur- * The exact order in which the colors are distinguished is not cer- tain, and probably varies somewhat in the case of different children. Prof. Preyer experimented with his little boy at the age of two, and found that he learned to identify colors on hearing their names in the following order : yellow, red, lilac, green, and blue. (" Die Seele des Kindes," p. 6, etc. ; cf. Perez, " First Three Years of Childhood," p. 26, etc.) I02 THE SENSES: SENSE-DISCRIMINATION. pass B in his average sense-discrimination. Or he may- surpass the other in some special mode of discriminative sensibility, as in the discrimination of colors or tones. These inequalities are partly native and connected with differences in the organs engaged. Good average discriminative power probably implies from the first a fine organization of the brain as a whole and special concen- trative ability, whereas a particularly fine sensibility to color, to tone, and so on, is connected rather with original structural excellence of the particular sense-organ con- cerned. It is this which fixes and limits the ultimate de- gree of delicacy reached. A child naturally dull in dis- tinguishing notes or colors will never become finely dis- criminative in this particular region. At the same time, the remarkable superiority of certain individuals (and race:) over others in respect of definite varieties of dis- criminative sensibility presupposes special concentration of mind and prolonged exercise of the discriminative func- tion in this particular domain of impressions. This is strikingly illustrated in the exceptional delicacy attained by those who have occasion to employ a sense much more than other people. In this way we account for the fine tactile sensibility of the blind, the delicate gustatory sensi- bility of wine- or tea-tasters, and so on. The Training of the Senses.~By the training or cultivation of the senses is meant the systematic exercis- ing of the sense-organs (and of the attention in connec- tion of these) so as to make them efficient instruments of observation and discovery. The first branch of this train- ing is the developing by suitable exercises of the discrim- inative side of the senses. The special object of this branch is to render the senses quick and exact in seizing the precise shades of difference among the several impres- sions presented to them. And the importance of this exercise in sense-discrimination depends on the fact that, in proportion as we discriminate our sense-impressions MENTAL ELEMENT IN SENSATION. 103 finely, shall we be able to distinguish and know objects accurately, and, as a result of this, be afterward able to call up distinct images of them, and to think and reason about them. Indeed, distinct and sharply defined sense- impressions are the first condition of clear imagination and exact thinking. The child that confuses its impres- sions of color, form, etc., will as a consequence be only able to imagine and think in a hazy and confused manner. The exercise of the senses implies the direction of attention on the part of the child to what is present. It is thus, strictly speaking, the exercises of the mind under the stimulus of sense-impressions. Sense-knowledge is gained by the young mind coming into contact with things immediately, and not mediately by the intervention of another mind. Hence the function of the educator in this first stage of the growth of knowledge is a limited one. A good part of the exercise of the senses in early life goes on, and it is fortunate that it does so, with very little help from mother or nurse. The child's own ac- tivity, if he is healthy and robust, will urge him to use his eyes, his hands, and other organs in exploring things about him. Nevertheless, a good deal may be done indirectly to help on this process of acquisition. The mother has the control of the child's surroundings, and may do much to hasten or retard the development of sense-knowledge by a wise attention to them or an indolent neglect of them. To supply children from the first with suitable materials for the exercise of their sense-organs, is the first and probably most important part of what is meant by train- ing the senses, at least in very early life. Next to this comes the more direct co-operation of mother, nurse, or teacher in directing their attention to unnoticed sights and sounds, etc., in their surroundings. Method of Training. — The training of the senses begins with the exercising the child in the discrimination 104 THE SENSES: SENSE-DISCRIMINATION. and along with this in the identification of impressions. This may be carried out in a less systematic way in the nursery. The infant's surroundings, the toys to be handled, the pictures to be looked at, and even the tones of voice used in addressing it, should be chosen with a view to a sufficient variety of impression. The natural order of sense-development must be followed, the first differences brought under his notice being broad contrasts, as that of a hard and soft material, blue and yellow colors, high and low tones, and finer distinctions following. With variety should go a certain amount of repetition of im- pressions, so that the pupil be exercised in identifying im- pressions. Hence the surroundings should not be con- tinually changed. A measure of sameness and perma- nence is necessary to thorough familiarity with the various sorts of sense-material. A more systematic procedure can be gradually intro- duced, aiming at a full and accurate knowledge of the several sense-elements. Thus, in training the color-sense the educator may best proceed by selecting first of all a few bright and striking colors, as white, red, and blue. Each of these must be made famiUar and its name learned. After being presented separately, they should be shown in juxtaposition, so that the differences may be clearly seen. This involves a rudimentary exercise of the faculty of comparison which in its higher form plays an important part in thought. Juxtaposition, or the bringing of two things side by side in space, or, as in the case of sounds, in immediate succession in time, is the most valuable instrument in exercising the senses. By seeing two colors side by side, the individual character of each is made more apparent, and the precise amount of difference ap- preciated. When a few elements have thus been thoroughly learned, new ones may be added. In this way the child will not only add to its stock of sense-materials, but will DANGER OF OVER-EXERTION. 105 have its former impressions rendered still more definite by a grasp of more numerous and finer differences. Thus, by adding yellow, orange, and so on, the learner will at- tain to more distinct ideas of what is meant by red. It must not be forgotten that these finer exercises in sense-discrimination imply a severe effort of attention, and are apt to be felt as a strain at first, both to the sense-organ concerned, and to the brain. And it is of the highest im- portance not to push them to the point of fatigue. Thus in training the eye to a minute detection of differences of form in letters, etc., and the hand to the nice reproduc- tion of these differences, there is special danger of over- stimulating the organ and inducing fatigue, and, if per- sisted in, of causing injury to the organ. If, however, the risk of over-exertion be avoided, it is possible, by proceeding judiciously, not only to keep these exercises from becoming wearisome, but even to make them positively agreeable. The main source of a pleas- urable interest here is the child's love of activity, mental and bodily. The very employment of the sense-organs is a pleasure to the healthy and strong child. This pleasure will be the greater when muscular activity is also enlisted, and an appeal made to the little one's nascent feeling of power. Thus, in training the color-sense, after presenting unlike and like colors to the child's notice, he may be en- couraged to select and sort the colors for himself. The active exercises of painting, drawing, and singing, in order to reproduce impressions of sight and sound, are the best means of training the corresponding senses. Training of the Several Senses.— All the senses need exercise, but in different ways. The lower senses, being of but little value as knowledge-giving senses, claim less consideration from the intellectual educator. The cultivation and control of the palate have, however, an im- portant bearing on physical education, on the disciplining of the body to healthy habits ; and the due limitation of 10 I06 THE SENSES: SENSE-DISCRIMINATION. the pleasures of taste, the checking of that common child- ish vice, Nascherei, is one of the most valuable among the early exercises in the virtue of temperance. Again, the cultivation of the sense of smell, of sensibility to the odors of flower and herb, pasture and wood, summer and autumn, is an important ingredient in the formation of aesthetic taste, and more especially the development of that love of nature which is a prime factor in all real en- joyment of poetry. From its great importance, touch claims special con- sideration in the education of the senses. The develop- ment of this sense is secured, to a large extent, by the child's own spontaneous promptings to handle and ex- amine things. Still, the teacher may supplement this irregular self-instruction by special systematic exercises. The Kindergarten occupations, such as stick-laying, paper- folding, modeling in clay, etc., all serve to increase the discriminative sensibility of the organ of touch on its pas- sive and on its active side. The teaching of the rudi- ments of drawing and writing completes this branch of sense-training. The perfect command of the hand in ex- ecuting movements with a nice precision is the outcome of a fine muscular sensibility developed by special con- centration of the attention, and by practice. The training of the ear is a well-acknowledged depart- ment of elementary education. In learning to articulate and to read, the child is called on first of all to distinguish a number of elementary sounds as well as to discriminate combinations of these. Along with this the muscular sense is exercised in so managing the organ of speech as to reproduce the precise sound required. Much the same holds good with respect to the systematic exercise of the ear in singing. Here, too, sounds have to be distin- guished and identified. The first condition of singing accurately is to have a finely discriminative ear which will instantly detect the slightest degree of flatness or sharp- TRAIMNG OF THE SEVERAL SENSES. 107 ness in the notes sung. And in conjunction with this, the vocal organ must be exercised so that the modifications answering to differences of pitch and force may be clearly distinguished and retained for future use. The eye calls for the most careful and prolonged train- ing, on account both of its intellectual and its aesthetic im- portance. A systematic training of the color-sense, some- what after the plan roughly sketched above, is a desidera- tum both as an element of taste and as a matter of prac- tical utility. And a careful discipline of the sense of form on its passive and actiye side is included in the recognized school exercises of reading, drawing, writing, etc. In truth, in this early stage of education the cultivation of the eyes goes on in close association with that of the hand. The whole fruit of this companionship will appear by-and-by. The separate exercise of the eye in the discrimination of form-elements is illustrated in learning to read printed let- ters as well as in the study of geometry. Nowhere, perhaps, is the limit of the teacher's power more plainly seen than in the education of the senses. Since discriminative power depends on concentration of mind and practice, the child's ability to discriminate col- ors, tones, elements of form, etc., may be improved by ju- dicious learning. Still, in every case a limit is sure to be reached in time, beyond which no further distinctions are possible. This limit, set by the structural perfection of the organ concerned, is a different one for different chil- dren. A child born note-deaf, for example, can never be drilled into a fine discriminator of tones. Hence the need of varying these exercises according to the capacity of the pupil and the results obtainable from the exercise. APPENDIX. A useful account of the senses, from a physiological point of view, is contained in Prof. Bernstein's "Five Senses of Man." On the im- portance of the exercise and improvement of sense-discrimination, the reader may consult Dr. Bain's " Education as a Science," chap. iii. CHAPTER VIII. THE senses: observation of things. Definition of Perception. — Sense-impressions are the alphabet by which we spell out the objects presented to us. In order to grasp or apprehend these objects, these letters must be put together after the manner of words. Thus, the apprehension of an apple by the eye involves the putting together of various sensations of sight, touch, and taste. This is the mind's own work, and is known as per- ception. And the result of this activity, i, e., the distinct apprehension of some object, is called a percept. We see from this that perception is an act of the mind. In the reception of the sense-impression, the mind is pas- sive, dependent on the action of an external force ; but in construing this as the sign of some external object, it is essentially active. Perception is mental activity employed about sense-impressions with a view to knowledge. The first stage of this activity was discussed in the last chapter, under the head of sense-discrimination. This corresponds to the learning of the several letters. We have now to consider the second stage, that corresponding to the learn- ing of words and their meanings. We have to explain how a child comes to regard its sense-impressions as signs of the presence of certain external objects, as, for exam- ple, certain sensations of sound as indications of a bell ringing, a dog barking, etc. How Percepts are reached.— The seemingly simple HO IV PERCEPTS ARE REACHED. 109 act of referring a sense-impression to an external object is the result of a process of learning or acquisition. As lit- tle as a child at first knows the meaning of a word till experience has taught him, so little is he able to construe his sense-impressions as the signs of objects. In the first weeks of life a child can not recognize the external source of the sounds that strike on his ear. He has not learned to connect the sound of the mother's voice with the mother he sees ; nor has he even learned to recognize the direc- tion of a sound, as is clearly shown by the blank, wonder- ing look of his face, and the absence of a proper move- ment of the head and eyes in the direction of the sound. The apprehension of an object, say a bell, by the ear, involves two mental processes : The first is the discrimi- nation and identification of the impression. In order to know that a particular impression of sound is that of a bell, it must be identified as this impression and not anoth- er, say that of a voice. This constitutes the first step in the process of perception. It may be marked off as the presentative or prehensive element. It presupposes pre- vious experience of the impressions. Thus the child can not identify a particular sound as that of a bell till after a number of repetitions of this impression. In the second place, the apprehension of the bell im- plies that this particular impression has been interpreted as coming from a particular object, viz., the bell. And this means that on hearing this sound the child recalls the ap- pearance of the bell to sight and its tactile qualities, hard- ness, weight, etc. That is to say, the one actual sensation of the moment, that of the sound, has recalled and rein- stated a whole group of impressions answering to the several features or qualities which constitute the object. This sec- ond step may be called the interpretative or apprehensive part of the process. And since the impressions recalled are not directly presented but only represented, this step is further known as the representative one. This act of no THE SENSES: OBSERVATION OF THINGS. construing or interpreting the impression presupposes that in the child's past experience the impression of sound has become connected with other impressions. We see from this that the interpretation of sense-im- pressions presupposes previous processes of a complex kind, viz., discriminating a number of sensations of differ- ent senses, and grouping or organizing these into a coher- ent whole. There are thus two stages in the development of percepts: (i) the initial stage of examining things, by- way of the different senses and learning to know them ; and (2) the final stage of knowing again or recognizing a thing. Special Channels of Perception. — The sensation of each sense tends to recall the other sensations of the group to which they belong, and so are capable of being interpreted by an act of perception. Thus, a child refers sensations of smell to objects, as when he says, " I smell apples," just as he refers sensations of light and color to objects, as when he says, " I see a candle." Nevertheless, when we talk of perceiving we generally refer to knowl- edge gained at the time through one of the higher senses, and more particularly sight. To perceive a thing means, in every-day parlance, to see it. Where sight is wanting, touch assumes the function of the leading perceptual sense ; and even in the case of those who see, touch is an important medium of apprehending objects. Sight and touch are thus in a special manner channels of perception. The reason why the senses of touch and sight are thus distinguished has been hinted at in the previous chapter. We there saw that they were marked off from the other senses by having local discrimination and an accompani- ment of muscular sensation. Owing to these circumstances, these two senses supply us with a wider and more varied knowledge of objects than the other senses. In smelling a flower, or hearing the noise of a passing vehicle, I can only seize one aspect or quality of a thing ; in looking at PERCEPTIONS OF TOUCH. m it I instantly take in a number of aspects, as its color, shape, and size. The additional knowledge, gained by means of local discrimination and movement, is, moreover, of a most im- portant kind. This includes first the knowledge of the position of things, and along with this a knowledge of their ''geometrical" or space properties, viz., figure and magnitude. And, secondly, it includes a knowledge of their " mechanical " or force properties, viz., resistance under its several forms of hardness, weight, etc., as made known by active touch. And these properties are the most essential, forming the kernel, so to speak, of what we mean by a material object. Touch and sight do not stand on precisely the same level as channels of perception. For, first of all, as we shall see presently, the knowledge of geometric properties is fuller and more direct in the case of touch than in that of sight. And, secondly, with respect to the important mechanical properties, hardness, weight, etc., our knowl- edge is altogether derived from touch. Hence, tactile apprehension is to be regarded as the primary and most fundamental form of perception. Perceptions of Touch. — These may be roughly di- vided into (i) perceptions of space and extension, and more especially the position, form, and magnitude of objects; and (2) perceptions of things as concrete wholes, such as a pebble, an orange, etc. The first kind of perception may be illustrated by the way in which a child learns the shape and size of a cube, say a small wooden brick. Here the sensibility of the skin to pressure, its local discrimination, and, lastly, the mus- cular sense, all combine in the development of the percept. The form of one of the surfaces is ascertained in different ways : (i) by moving the fingers over it in various direc- tions and noting how long the contact with the body lasts ; (2) by passing the fingers about the boundary of the sur- 112 THE^ SENSES : OBSERVATION OF THINGS. face and noting the uniformity of the direction of the movement along each edge, the length of the movement, and the change < f direction at the angles ; and (3) by plac- ing the extended hand over the surface and noting, by means of the local discrimination of the skin, where the edges touch the hand. The knowledge of any one of its surfaces would thus involve the grouping of many sense- elements together, and the knowledge of the whole cubical form would further involve the grouping of a number of these groups together and the completion of this aggregate of experiences by taking the brick into the two hands, and so gaining a clearer idea of its solidity. After repeating this complex act of tactile inspection again and again, the different members of the group would cohere so closely that the recurrence of a part would suf- fice to reinstate the whole. Thus the child, on merely taking the brick into his hands, would recall the successive experiences of movement just described. That, in this way, a child is able to gain very clear perceptions of form, is seen in the fact that the blind are capable of picturing and reasoning about geometrical forms with great clear- ness. And even in the case of children who have the use of their eyes, the earliest impressions of form are gained from tangible bodies, and to a large extent by the medium of active touch. In apprehending the presence of a whole concrete thing, as a pebble, this group of impressions would be taken up into a still larger aggregate. Thus, in learning what a pebble is, a child connects what he has observed respecting its form with the hardness, coldness, smooth- ness, and weight. His knowledge of the pebble is the re- sult of all this various sense-experience organized or united into a seemingly simple mental product. Where, as in the case of an apple or an orange, the other senses supply im- portant elements (color, taste, and smell), the group of tactile impressions is ample for a subsequent identification PERCEPTION OF FORM BY THE EYE. 113 of the object. The child, on touching an orange, instantly apprehends the thing as a whole, that is, recognizes it as an orange. Visual Perception.— As remarked above, sight is in normal circumstances the leading avenue of perception. This supremacy is due in part to the fact that in looking we can apprehend things at a distance as well as near, and also a number of objects at the same time, as the pictures on the wall, the buildings of a street, etc. To this must be added the fact that when we see things we can tell how they would appear to touch. In other words, we translate visual impressions into terms of the earlier and more ele- mentary experiences of active touch. Seeing is thus to a large extent a representative process and an interpretative act of the mind. Perception of Form by the Eye.— In the perception of form the eye is up to a certain point independent of the hand. Thus, in learning the direction and length of lines, and the form and magnitude of objects as they might be drawn on a blackboard, the organ of sight is developing its own mode of perception. This visual perception, it is plain, resembles the tactile perception in so far as it arises out of a number of experiences, passive and active. Thus, in finding out, by looking at the gable of a house, what a triangle is, the child combines the experience gained in moving the eye about the contour, with the composite im- pression obtained by the local discrimination of the several parts by the retina. The precise direction and length of each line presuppose these movements of the eye along the outline of the object. It is only when these have been executed many times that the perception of form by the eye at rest becomes distinct. And this means that in look- ing at a figure the impression of the retina suffices to recall the experience of the moving eye. The perception of any form, such as a cross, an ellipse, or the letter M, is the outcome of a process of combining 114 THE SENSES: OBSERVATION OF THINGS. a number of form-elements or details and clearly appre- hending their relations one to another. Thus, in appre- hending the form of the cross the learner must distinguish the vertical and horizontal arm, observing their directions as well as their relative lengths. The more exactly each element is discriminated, and the more clearly the rela- tions of position, proportion, and number are seized, the more perfect the final percept. This perception of form as plane form, or form as it can be represented on a flat surface, as a blackboard, is, however, fragmentary and abstract. The forms of real objects from which a child first gains his knowledge are those of solid bodies having the third dimension, thick- ness or depth as well as length and breadth. We see one part of the surface of a sphere nearer the eye or advanc- ing, another part farther off or receding. This discrimi- nation of a solid form as distinguished from a flat drawing involves the perception of distance. Perception of Distance and Solidity.— The modern "Theory of Vision," of which Bishop Berkeley was the author, tells us that the perception of distance, though apparently as direct as that of color, is really indirect and acquired. In seeing an object at a certain distance, we are really interpreting visual impressions by a reference to movement of the limbs and to touch. We can only real- ize the distance of an object by traversing, either with the arm or with the whole body, the space that intervenes be- tween us and it. According to this doctrine, children do not at first see things as we see them, one nearer than another. This is proved by the experience of blind children on first obtain- ing the use of their eyes. All objects appear to such as touching the eyes. And they can not distinguish between a flat drawing and a solid body. It is only after using their eyes for some time that they learn to distinguish near and far. The development of the perception of distance PERCEPTION OF DISTANCE AND SOLIDITY. 115 takes place by the use of sight and touch together. A child finds out how far a thing is from himself by moving his limbs. Thus, an infant sitting up at a table finds out the distance of something on the table by stretching out its hands and noting how far it has to reach before it touches the thing. When it is able to run about, the movements of its legs become another measure of distance. In carrying out these movements the eyes are also employed. The child notes the difference to the eye when the object is near and when it is farther away. Thus, he observes that he has to make his eyes turn inward or converge more in the former case, and that the object looks more distinct. After many repetitions he learns to connect these experi- ences of active touch and these changing effects on the eye. When this process of grouping or organizing experi- ences is complete, the recurrence of the proper visual ex- perience at once suggests the corresponding experience of movement and touch. Thus the sensation of muscular strain in looking at a near object instantly tells him that the object is near and within his reach. The visual sen- sation has become a sign of a fact known by the use of his limbs. Seeing distance is thus a kind of reading, and the meaning of the impression on the eye, like that of the letters in a book, has to be learned from experience.* The perception of solid bodies illustrates the same thing. Here, too, the child has to interpret his visual im- pressions by the aid of past experience and the knowledge gained by active touch. That the eye has little knowledge of solidity is seen in the fact that even an adult may easi- ly be deceived in taking flat drawings for solid objects (e. g., in the scenery of a theatre). The only way in which we can distinctly realize that an object has thickness is by taking it into the two hands. * The perception of the reai magnitude of an object, as distin- guished from the apparent magnitude which varies with the distance, is closely connected with that of distance. Il6 THE SENSES: OBSERVATION OF THINGS. The apprehension of solidity by the eye is effected by means of certain signs. Thus, we can move the eye from a near to a more distant part of an object, and note the difference in muscular sensations of the eyes. Even when we do not move the eye, we have something to guide us in the dissimilarity of the two retinal impressions. In look- ing at a flat picture each eye receives a precisely similar impression ; but in looking at a solid body their impres- sions differ. Thus, in looking at a book held a little in front of the face with its back toward us, our left eye sees more of the left cover, while the right eye sees more of the right. It is by noting this dissimilarity, and connecting it with the fact of solidity as known by active touch, that a child learns to recognize a solid object with the eyes.* Intuition of Things. — In looking at an object, as in touching it, we apprehend simultaneously a group of qualities. These include first of all purely visual features, as its degree of brightness, the distribution of light and shade on its surface, its color (or distribution of colors), and the form and (apparent) magnitude of its surface. Along with these come the closely organized combinations of sight and touch, viz., the solid shape, and the nature of the surface as rough or smooth.f This may be called the fundamental part of our intuition of a particular object. In looking at a new object, as a crystal or a botanical specimen, we instantly intuit or take in this group of qualities, and they constitute a considerable amount of knowledge about the object as a whole. ,In order to know the thing as a whole, so as afterward to be able to recog- nize it with the eye, this aggregate must be conjoined with other qualities known by touch and by the other senses. * The fact that the perception of solidity depends mainly on the presence of two unlike visual impressions is proved by the stereoscope, the two drawings of which, taken from different points of view, answer to the two retinal images of a solid body. \ This is made known to sight by differences of light and shade. PERCEPTION OF OUR OWN BODY. 17 Thus, in recognizing an orange a child invests it more or less distinctly with a particular degree of hardness, weight, and temperature, as well as with a certain taste and smell. The recognition of a thing as identical with something previously perceived is a complex psychical process. It involves not only the identification of a definite group of impressions, but also the germ of a higher intellectual process, namely, the comparison of successive impressions, and the detection of similarity amid diversity or change. Thus, a child learns to identify a particular object, as his mother, or his dog, at different distances and in different lights, and — a matter of still greater difficulty — according to the particular position and visible aspect of the object, as seen from the front or from the side, etc. Children require a certain amount of experience and practice before they recognize identity amid such varying aspects. And in this they are greatly aided by hearing others call the thing by the same name. Perception of our own Body. — In close connection with the perception of external objects the child comes to know the several parts of his own body. The sensa- tions which are not referred to external bodies are local- ized by us in some part of our organism. Thus, organic sensations, as skin-sensations of "creeping," muscular sensations of cramp or fatigue, are localized in some defi- nite region of the body, the arm, or the foot. And the deep-seated feelings of comfort and discomfort connected with the organs of digestion, etc., are also localized in a less definite and vague manner. Such references are not possible at the beginning of life. A child has to learn where his bodily sensations are located ; and this he does by learning to know the several parts of his body. The child's own body, like an external object, is known by means of the impressions it supplies to his senses, and more particularly touch and sight. An infant examines its legs, arms, etc., with its hands. By frequent excur- Il8 THE SENSES: OBSERVATION OF THINGS. sions of these over the surface of the body, the position, shape, and size of the several parts become known. The eyes, too, are engaged in these early observations, so that a visual picture is gradually put together and combined with the tactile perception. As this knowledge of the bodily form is developed the several bodily sensations become better localized. Thus, in inspecting his feet with his hands the child is producing sensations of pressure in the former. In this way the sensations having their origin in that particular region of the bodily surface come to be definitely connected with that part as known to touch and sight. After this, whenever the child receives a sensation by way of the nerves running to that part, he knows at once that it is his foot that is giving him the sensation. To a child his bodily organism is marked off from all other objects by the fact that it is connected in a peculiar way with his conscious life, and more particularly his feel- ings of pleasure and pain. The experience of pressing his foot with his hand differs from that of pressing a for- eign body, inasmuch as there is not only a sensation in the hand, but an additional one in the foot. Injuries to the several parts of the bodily surface, and the applica- tion of agreeable stimuli, as soft touches, come to be rec- ognized as causes of painful and pleasurable sensation. In these ways he comes to regard his body as that by which he suffers pain and pleasure. At the same time he learns that the movements' of his body are immediately under the control of his wishes, that his limbs are the instruments by which he reacts on his environment, alter- ing the position of objects, etc. Hence his body is re- garded as a part of himself, and in early life probably makes up the chief part of the meaning of the word *' self." It is contrasted with all other and foreign objects, and in a special way with the other human organisms he sees around him. Observation. — All perception requires some degree DISTINCT AND ACCURATE OBSERVATION, j 19 of attention to what is present. But we are often able to discriminate and recognize an object by a momentary glance, which suffices to take in a few prominent marks. Similarly, we are able by a cursory glance to recognize a movement or action of an object. Such incomplete fugi- tive perception is ample for rough, every-day purposes. On the other hand, we sometimes need to throw a special degree of mental activity into perception, so as to note completely and accurately what is present. This is par- ticularly the case with new and unfamiliar objects. Such a careful direction of the mind to objects is commonly spoken of as observation. To observe is to look at a thing closely, to take careful note of its several parts or details. In its higher form, known as scientific observa- tion, it implies too a deliberate selection of an object or action for special consideration, a close concentration of the attention on it, and an orderly going to work with a view to obtain the most exact account of a phenomenon. Hence we may call observation regulated perception. Distinct and Accurate Observation.— Good ob- servation must be precise and free from taint of error. Many persons' observations are vague and wanting in full- ness of detail and precision. The habit of close and ac- curate observation of things, their features and their move- ments, etc., is one of the rarest of possessions. It presup- poses a strong interest in what is going on around us. This is illustrated in the fact that a child always observes closely and accurately when he is very deeply concerned, as, for example, in scrutinizing his mother's expression when he is not quite sure whether she is talking seriously to him or not. Good observation presupposes two things: (i) the ac- curate noting of what is directly presented to the eye, or the perfect performance of the prehensive part of the pro- cess, and (2) a just interpretation of the visual impression, or the perfect performance of the second or apprehensive 120 THE SENSES: OBSERVATION OF THINGS. part of the operation. Defects in the first are very com- mon. Children fail to note the exact form and size of objects, their situation relatively to other objects, etc. To see a number of objects in their real order, so as to be able to describe them accurately, is a matter of close, painstaking observation. Any defect in the prehensive part of the process natu- rally leads on to faulty interpretation. Hasty and slovenly observation of color, form, or magnitude leads the young to false ideas of the objects they see, as when a child mis- takes a lemon for an orange, two boys romping for two boys fighting. And even if the visual element is carefully noted, there will be an error of interpretation when the impression of the eye has not been firmly connected with the tactile and other experiences to which it is related as parts of one whole experience. Thus, if a child after see- ing some simple experiments with metals fails to properly connect the several properties of malleability, fusibility, with the lead, iron, etc., the sight of a piece of one of the metals will be apt to reinstate the wrong properties. We thus see that accurate knowing or recognition depends on a careful learning or coming to know. Defective and inaccurate observation is hindered by mental preoccupation. Dreamy and absent-minded chil- dren are, as a rule, bad observers. They only see things indistinctly as in a haze. Anything, too, in the shape of excitement and emotional agitation is inimical to careful observation, because it is apt to excite vivid expectations of what is going on, and so to lead to delusive perception. Thus, if a child strongly desires to go out, it is disposed to think that the rain has ceased when it is really still fall- ing. Emotional children are very apt to read what they wish and vividly imagine into the objects before them. We see, then, that while perception has its representa- tive element, that while the child who distinguishes his visual impressions accurately but is unable to interpret ACQUIREMENT OF DISCRIMINATION. 121 them never attains to anything but useless scraps of knowl- edge, this representative factor has to be kept within due limits, and not allowed to hide from view what is actually before the eyes. The highest kind of observation combines accuracy with quickness. In many departments of observation, as watching people's expressions and actions, or the scientific observation of a rapid process of physical movement or change, such as an astronomical and chemical investiga- tion, rapidity is of the first consequence. Development of Perceptual Power. — Our analysis of perception has suggested the way in which our percepts are gradually built up and perfected. In the first weeks of life there is little if any recognition of outer things. The child receives visual impressions, but these are not yet referred to external objects. It is by the daily re- newed conjunctions of simple sense-experiences, and more particularly those of sight and of touch, that the little learner comes to refer its impressions to objects. By con- tinually looking at the objects handled, the visual percep- tion of direction becomes perfected, as also that of dis- tance within certain limits. The child learns to put out his hand in the exact direction of an object, and to move it just far enough.* The perception of the distance and solidity of more remote objects remains very imperfect before locomotion is attained. The change of visible scene as the child is carried about the room impresses * A child known to the present writer was first seen to stretch out his hand to an object when two and a half months old. The hand misses the exact point at first, passing beside it, but practice gives pre- cision to the movement. The same child at six months knew when an object was within reach. If a biscuit or other object was held out of his reach, he made no movement, but as soon as it was brought within his reach he instantly put out his hand to take it. On the other hand, Prof. Preyer says his boy tried to seize the lamp in the ceiling of a railway compartment when fifty-eight weeks old. (" Die Seele des Kindes," p. 38.) 122 THE SENSES: OBSERVATION OF THINGS, him, no doubt, but the meaning of these changes only be- comes fully seized when he begins to walk, and to find out the amount of locomotive exertion answering to the different appearances of things. It is some years, how- ever, before he begins to note the signs of distance in the case of remote objects. The same order shows itself with respect to the development of the perception of solidity. Thus a child learns in time to distinguish between the flat shadows of things on the walls and the pictures in his books, and real solid objects. But it is long before he learns that the distant hills and clouds are bulging, sub- stantial forms.* After many conjunctions of impressions children begin to find out the nature of objects as wholes, and the visible aspects which are their most important marks. That is to say, they begin to discriminate objects one from an- other by means of sight alone, and to recognize them as they reappear to the eye. Development follows here as elsewhere the line of interest. It is the objects of great- est interest, such as the bottle by which the infant is fed, that are first apprehended as real objects. After some months of tactile investigation the interpretation of visual impressions becomes more easy and automatic. Sight now grows self-sufficient. What may be roughly marked off as the touching age gives place to the seeing age. Hence- forth the growth of perception is to a large extent an im- provement of visual capability. At first this power of discerning the forms of objects with the eye is very limited. A child will note one or two prominent and striking features of a thing but overlook the others. Thus, in looking at real animals or at his toy * M. Perez (" First Three Years of Childhood," pp. 226, 227) re- marks that a child of six months will take a flat disk with gradations of light and shade for a globe. He also remarks that children of fif- teen months and more are liable to make absurd blunders as to the distance of remote objects, hills, the horizon, etc. DEVELOPMENT OF PERCEPTUAL POWER. 123 or picture imitations, he will distinguish a quadruped from a bird, but not one quadruped from another. Similarly, he will distinguish a very big dog from a small one, but not one dog from another of similar size. The progress of perception grows with increase of visual discrimination ; that is to say, of the capability of distinguishing one color, one direction of a line, and so on, from another. It presupposes, further, the growth of the power of attention which is the main ingredient in ob- servation. As experience advances, children find it easier to note the characteristic aspects of things and to recog- nize them ; and they take more pleasure in detecting their differences and similarities. In this way their observations tend gradually to improve in distinctness and accuracy. Not only so, an increased power of attention enables them to seize and embrace in a single view a number of details. In this way their first vague, *' sketchy " percepts get filled out. Thus, a particular flower or animal is seen more completely in all its details of color and its relations of form. At the same time they acquire the power of appre- hending larger and more complex objects, such as whole buildings, ships, etc. ; and, further, assemblages of many objects, as the furniture in a room, or the plants in a gar- den, in their proper relative positions. The observing powers may develop in different direc- tions, according to special capabilities and special circum- stances. The possession of a particular mode of discrimi- native sensibility in a high form, and a strong correlated interest in the particular class of impressions, will lead to a special consideration of things on that side. Thus the child with a fine eye for color will be specially observant of the color-side of objects. Again, the faculty of obser- vation may grow in rapidity of action, and in grasp of a multitude of objects, according to the individual's special powers of attention. Once more, the development of a particular interest in a class of objects, as animals, flowers, 124 THE SENSES: OBSERVATION OF THINGS, faces, etc., will determine a special acuteness of observa- tion in respect of these. Thus a boy with a marked love of horses becomes specially observant of their forms, ac- tions, etc. So a boy with a strong leaning to mimicry and a keen, humorous interest in the expression of people's faces, etc., will be particularly observant in this direction. It may be added that particular enlargements of tactile and other experience will serve to give a particular depth and richness of suggestion to the individual's percepts. Thus a person who acquires special knowledge of the tan- gible properties of natural substances, woven fabrics, etc., will see more in these objects than another person. Training of the Observing Powers. — This branch of intellectual training goes on in close connection with, and is at the same time the completion of, that training of the senses on their discriminative side which was con- sidered in the last chapter. The first years of life are marked out by nature as the age for exercising the observ- ing powers. The objects that surround the child are new and excite a vivid interest. He spontaneously spends much of his time in manipulating and scrutinizing things. The overflowing muscular activity of a healthy child is highly favorable to experimental investigation. The beginnings of the education of the observing powers belong to the nursery, and consist in supplying the child with ample room to move about and a good stock of objects of interest for manual and visual inspection. Nothing is more fatal to this early development than checking muscular activity, forbidding children to touch and examine things.* By a free exertion of activity the child will learn for himself to organize his tactile and visual experiences so as to become proficient in interpret- * As Miss Edgeworth observes, the best toys for the infant are things that can be grasped without danger, as ivory sticks, balls, etc., by help of which differences of size and form may be learned. (" Prac- tical Education," i, pp. 7, 8.) EXERCISE IN OBSERVING FORM. 125 ing the visual signs of distance, solidity, etc. The addi- tion of flat representations of solid objects in picture- books is a valuable supplement to this first domestic en- vironment, since they help to fix the child's attention in a new way on the purely visible side of things, the differ- ence and at the same time the similarity between the real solid thing and its pictorial representation. A more act- ive direction of the observing faculty is required when the child grows and is capable of better fixing his attention on objects. This is the moment for calling his attention to less obtrusive objects at a distance, and so carrying forward the process of self-education to a more advanced point. Exercise in observing Form. — The transition from the nursery to the school should be marked by a more systematic training of the observing powers. This properly begins with exercising the child in the more ac- curate perception of form. The Kindergarten system has this as its chief aim. The principles which govern this early department of training are as follows : (i) The per- ception of form is grounded on the child's active experi- ences and the use of the hand. It is by the spontaneous outgoings of his muscular energy in examining objects and constructing them that all perception of real form arises. (2) The development of the perception of form should proceed from a conjoint tactile and visual, to an inde- pendent visual perception. (3) The observation of form should be exercised conformably to the general laws of mental development, viz., passing from the rude and in- definite to the exact and definite, from the concrete to the abstract, and from the simple to the complex. The Kin- dergarten gifts and occupations clearly satisfy these con- ditions in general. Froebel was psychologically right in utilizing the child's spontaneous activity, in setting out with tangible objects, as the ball, etc., and in attaching so much importance to the exercise of the child's construct- 126 THE SENSES: OBSERVATION OF THINGS. ive activity in the reproduction of form by the occupa- tions of modeling, stick-laying, paper-folding, etc. All such exercises involve a recreation of form by actions of the hand similar to those by which the infant spontaneous- ly investigates the form of things. Hence they are to be regarded as the natural completion of the earlier training of the nursery. Such exercises do not, however, constitute all that is meant by training the child in the perception of form. From an early period he is interesting himself in the forms of natural objects, as animals, trees, flowers, etc., as well as buildings, articles of furniture, etc. And he should be exercised in a more close and exact observation of these forms. The child naturally observes at first only the more salient features of an object, such as the tallness of the poplar, the long neck of the swan, which may after- ward serve as a rough mark for identifying the object. How little he really notes may be seen by his first rude attempts at drawing the human figure, the horse, etc. The development of the perception of form proceeds analyti- cally, the rough outline being first apprehended, and then the several details. The educator should follow this order, and practice the observer in attention to the minuter de- tails of form. In this way the child will grow more dis- criminative in his perceptions of form and learn more about the minute parts of common and familiar objects. Here, again, the hand should be called in, in order to reproduce what is seen. The child's spontaneous impulse to imitate nature by drawing is one of the most valuable ones to the educator. Compared with modeling, drawing is to a certain extent abstract, since it separates the visible form from the tangible. Accordingly it is best taken up after modeling, building, etc. At the same time the child commonly manifests the impulse to draw at an early age, and the satisfaction of the impulse provides an excellent means of gaining a closer acquaintance with visible form. CONCRETE OBJECTS. 1 27 Not only so, by employing the hand in the production or creation of form by definite manual movements, drawing supplies a valuable additional means of training the eye and the hand in unison, and so of perfecting the connec- tions between touch and sight. A child who has become skillful in drawing has not only acquired a useful manual art, but has helped to develop his power of seeing^ i. e., of deciphering the symbols that present themselves to his eye. In these exercises the teacher should be satisfied at first with rough and approximate imitations of natural forms, and aim at making these more close and accurate by practice.* A more advanced stage in the visual perception of form is reached when the learner takes up the abstract consid- eration of form by a study of the elements of geometry. A knowledge of lines, curves, angles, etc., should distinct- ly follow a certain amount of exercise in the observa- tion and reproduction of concrete forms. To distinguish a straight line or a right angle is a dry and uninter- esting exercise compared with noting the form of some real object, and involves a certain development of the power of abstraction. Such exercises should be com- menced by references to concrete forms, as the window- frame, the edge of the house, its gable, etc. In this way the child will gain an interest in the subject, and at the same time further develop his perceptions of concrete forms by a clearer recognition of their constituent parts. The Object-Lesson. — After the exercise of the child in the perception of form comes the training of the senses as a whole in the knowledge of objects and their constituent qualities. The systematic development of this side of the training of the senses gives us the object- lesson. By this is meant the presentment to the pupil's senses of some natural substance, as coal, chalk, or lead ; * On the best way to exercise the child in drawing, see Mr. Spen- cer's "Education," chap, ii, p. 79, and following. 128 THE SENSES : OBSERVATION OF THINGS. some organic structure, as a plant or animal ; or, finally, some product of human industry, as glass or a piece of furniture ; and such a detailed and orderly unfolding of its several qualities, its capabilities of being acted on by, and of acting on, other things, its relations of depend- ence on surroundings, etc., as will result in the fullest and clearest knowledge of the object as a whole and its conditions. It is evident, from this general description, that the object-lesson makes a special appeal to the sev- eral senses, and, while thus exercising the senses separate- ly, helps to train the learner in the connecting and organ- izing of a number of impressions. Thus, in an object- lesson on one of the metals there is an appeal made to the sense of touch (sensations of hardness, smoothness, etc.), and in one on salt, an appeal to the sense of taste. The object-lesson thus falls into two parts: (i) the detailed exposition and naming of the various qualities, and (2) the summing up of the results in a description of the whole thing. The object-lesson is a training in close ob- servation of objects ; and, since the first stage of science is observation, including experiment, this form of instruc- tion constitutes a fit introduction to the study of physical science. Its value depends, first of all, on the extent to which the observing powers of the class have been made use of. The teacher must not tell the pupils what the object is, but stimulate them to observe for themselves. Again, it depends on the clearness and precision with which the several properties have been unfolded, so that a complete and accurate idea of the whole may be attained. Once more, it involves the proper use of juxtaposition, so as to exercise the observer's power of comparison and dis- crimination. And, lastly, it implies that the result of each separate observation has been carefully recorded by a suitable name. The object-lesson, properly carried out, is one of the best methods of developing in children a habit of observation and a taste for scientific experiment. PURPOSE OF THE OBTECT-LESSON, 129 The object-lesson aims at nothing beyond the training of the observing powers themselves. Its purpose is real- ized when the object has been accurately inspected and its properties learned. Hence it must be marked off from all appeals to the senses which subserve the better imagi- nation and understanding of a subject dealt with mainly by verbal instruction, such as the use of models and maps in teaching geography ; coins, pictures, etc., in teaching history ; and such an apparatus as Mr. Sonnenschein's in teaching the elements of number. All these exercises call in the aid of the senses according to the general prin- ciple of modern education, that knowledge begins with the apprehension of concrete things by the senses of the child. While the calling in of the pupil's observing powers is thus a characteristic of the right method in all branches of teaching, there are some subjects which exercise the faculty of observation in a more special manner. Thus, the study of geometry and of languages help, each in its own special and restricted way, to exercise the visual ob- servation of form. But the study which most completely and most rigorously exercises the faculty of observation is natural science. A serious pursuit of chemistry, mineral- ogy, botany, or some branch of zoology, as entomology, trains the whole visual capacity, and helps to fix a habit of observing natural objects, which is one of the most val- uable rewards that any system of education can bestow. It is not to be forgotten, however, that the best train- ing of the observing powers lies outside the range of school exercises. A habit of close observation of nature is best acquired in friendly association with, and under the guidance of, an observant parent or tutor, in hours of leisure. A daily walk with a good observer will do more to develop the faculty than the most elaborate school exercises. The training of the observing powers is indeed that part of intellectual education that most requires the aid of other educators than the schoolmaster. And one 130 THE SENSES: OBSERVATION OF THINGS. evil resulting from our modern aggregation into big towns, and our growing school demands on the time and ener- gies of children, is that so little opportunity and energy- remain for those spontaneous beginnings in the observa- tion of nature, the forms of hill and dale, the movements of stream, waves, etc., the forms and movements of plants and animals, which are the best exercise of the observing faculty ; and for those simpler and more attractive kinds of scientific observation, e. g., collecting birds' eggs, fossils, etc., which grow naturally out of children's play-activity. APPENDIX. On the training of the observing powers, the reader will do well to consult Mr. Spencer's " Essay on Education," chap, ii, and Miss You- mans's little work on the "Culture of the Observing Powers of Chil- dren." The function of the nursery in drawing out the observing faculty is well illustrated by Miss Edgeworth, " Practical Education," chap, i, " Toys." The difficult subject of the object-lesson is dealt with in a suggestive way by Dr. Bain, " Education as a Science," chap, viii, p. 247, etc. ; and by Mr. Calkins, " New Primary Object-Lessons" (Harper & Brothers), p. 359, etc. The German reader may with ad- vantage read Waitz, " Allgemeine Paedagogik," part ii, section i, " Die Bildung der Anschauung." D. APPLETON & CO/S PUBLICATIONS. THE HISTORY OF BIMETALLISM IN THE UNITED STATES. By J. Laurence Laughlin, Ph. D., Assistant Pro- lessor of Political Economy in Harvard University ; author of " The Study of Political Economy," etc. With Sixteen Charts and nu- merous Tables. One volume. 8vo. Cloth, $2.25. "Although the plan of this book was conceived with the view of presenting Blmply a history of bimetallism in the United States, it has been necessary, in the nature of the subject, to make it something more than that. And yet it was my hope that the effect of an historical inquiry in suppressing some of the theoretical vagaries of the day might be realized by showing what our actual experience with bimetallism has been in contrast with the assertions of some writers as to what it may be."— i?Vcwi Pr^ace. THE STUDY OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. HINTS TO STUDENTS AND TEACHERS. By J. Laurence Laughlin, Ph. D., Assistant Professor of Political Economy in Harvard University. 16mo. Cloth, $1.00. " The existence of this little book is due to an attempt to convey, by lectures to students, an understanding of the position which political economy holds in regard, not merely to its actual usefulness for every citizen, but to its disciplinary {)ower. . . . The interest which the public now manifests in economic studies ed me to put the material of my lectures into a general form, in order that they might assist inquirers in any part of the country."— J^/twi Preface. MILL'S PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY: ABRIDGED WITH CRITICAL, BIBLIOGRAPHICAL, AND EX- PLANATORY NOTES, AND A SKETCH OF THE HISTORY OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. By J. Laurence Laughlin, Ph. D., Assistant Professor of Political Economy in Harvard University. With Twenty-four Maps and Charts. A Text-book for Colleges. 8vo. 658 pages. Cloth, $3.50. " An experience of five years with Mr. Mill's treatise in the class-room con- vinced me, not only of the great usefulness of what still remains one of the most lucid and systematic books yet published which cover the whole range of the study, but I have also been convinced of the need of such additions as should give the results of later thinking, without militating against the general tenor of Mr. Mill's system; of such illustrations as should fit it better for American students, by turning their attention to the application of principles in the facts around us ; of a bibliography which should make it easier to get at the writers of other schools who offer opposing views on controverted questions ; and of some attempts to lighten those parts of his work in which Mr. Mill frightened away the reader by an appearance of too great abstractness, and to render them, if jiossible, more easy of comprehension to the student who first approaches Political Economy through this author."— ii^ro/w Preface. POLITICAL ECONOMY. By W. Stanley Jevons, Professor of Logic and Political Economy in Owens College, Manchester. ISmo. Flexible cloth, 45 cents. MONEY AND THE MECHANISM OF EXCHANGE. By W. Stanley Jevons. 12mo. Cloth, $1.75. New York: D. APPLETON & CO., 1, 3, & 5 Bond Street. APPLETONS' INSTRUCTIVE READING-BOOKS, NATURAL HISTORY SERIES. By Professor JAMES JOHONNOT, Author of " Principles and Practice of Teaching," " Geographical Reader," "How we Live," etc. No. 1. Book of Cats and Dogs, and other Friends. For Little Folks. No. 2. Friends in Feathers and Fur, and other Neighbors. For Young Folks. No. 3. Neighbors with Wings and Fins, and some Others. For Boys and Girls. No. 4. Neighbors with Claws and Hoofs, and their Kin. For Young People. No. 5. Glimpses of the Animate "World : Science and Literature of Natural History. For School or Home. The publication of " Appletons' Instructive Reading-Books " marks a distinct and important advance in the adaptation of special knowledge and general literature to the intelligent comprehension of pupils of all grades of attainment. The importance of this movement and its value to the present generation of school-children can not be overestimated. The Natural History Series contains a full course of graded lessons for reading upon topics and in a style that are of the most fascinating interest to children and young people, while training them to habits of observation, and storing their minds with useful information. D. APPLE TON & CO., Publishers, NEW YORK, BOSTON, CHICAGO, SAN FRANCISCO. APPLETONS' SCIENCE TEXT-BOOKS. D. Appleton & Co. have the pleasure of announcing that in repponse to the growing interest in the study of the Natural Sciences, and a demand for improved text-books representing the more accurate phases of scientific knowledge, and tlie present active and widening field of investigation, they have made arrange- i&ents for the publication of a series of text-books to cover the whole field Of science-study in High Schools, Academies, and all schools of similar grade. The author in each separate department has been selected with regard to his especial fitness for the work, and each volume has been prepared with an especial reference to its practical availability for class use and class study in schools. No abridgment of labor or expense has been permitted in the efl"ort to make this series worthy to stand at the head of all educational publications of this kind. Although the various books have been projected with a view to a comprehensive and harmonious series, each volume will be wholly independent of the others, and complete in itself. NOW READY. THE EliEMENTS OF CHEMISTRY. By Professor F. W. Clarke, Chemist of the United States Geological Survey. 12mo. Cloth, $1.40. THE ESSENTIALS OF ANATOMY, PHYSIOLOGY, AND HY- GIENE. By Roger S. Tract, M. D., Health Inspector of the New York Board of Health ; author of " Hand-Book of Sanitary Information for House- holders," etc. 12mo. Cloth, $1.20. A COMPEND OF GEOLOGY. By Joseph Le Conte, Professor of Geol- ogy and Natural History in the University of California; author of "Ele- ments of Geology," etc. 12mo. Cloth, $1.40. ELEMENTS OF ZOOLOGY. By C. F. Holder, Fellow of the New York Academy of Science, Corresponding Member Linnaenn Society, etc. ; and J. B. Holder, M. D., Curator of Zoology of American Museum of Natural History, Central Park, New York. l2mo. Cloth, $1.40. DESCRIPTIVE BOTANY. A Practical Guide to the Classification of Plants^ with a P(»pular Flora. By Eliza A. Youmans, author of "The First Boob of Botany," editor of " Henslow's Botanical Charts." 12mo. Cloth, $1.40. Other volumes to follow as rapidly as they can he prepared. New York: D. APPLETON & CO., 1, 3, & 5 Bonl Street. THE ORTH OEPIST: A PRONOUNCING MANUAL, Containing about Three Thousand Five ri:undred "Words, including a Considerable Number of the Names of Foreign Authors, Artists, etc., that are often mispronounced. By ALFRED AYRES. SELECTIONS FROM THE WORK. ab-do'men, not ^b'do- men. ac-crue', not -cru'. The orthoepists agree that u^ preceded by r iu the same syl- lable, generally becomes simply 00^ as in rude^ rumor, rural, rule. al-l5p'a-tliy; al-l5p'a- tliist* Ar'a-bic, not A-ra'bic. Asia — a'slie-a, not a'zha. ay, or aye (yes)— I. aye (always) — a. Bis'marck, not biz'-. At the end of a syllable, s, in German, has its sharp sound. Cairo — ^in Egypt, ki'ro ; in the United States^ ka'ro. dec'ade, not de-kad'. de-co'roiis. The authority is small, and is becoming less, for saying dec'o- rous, which is really as incor- rect as it would be to say son'o- rous. def i-cit, not de-fig'it. di§-dain', 7iot dis-. di§-li5n'or, not dis-. ec-o-n5m'i-cal, or e-co- n5m'i-cal. e-nerVate. The only authority for saying en'er-vdte is popular usage ; all the orthoepists say e-ner'vdte. ep'oeh, not e'p5€li. The latter is a Websterian pronunciation, which is not even permitted in the late editions. :^n-an-cier'. Rarely pronounced correctly. Hei'ne, not hme. Final e in German is never silent. honest — 5n'est, not -ist, nor -list. " Ronesf, honest Tago," is preferable to "honws^, honust lago," some of our accidental Othellos to the contrary not- withstanding. i§'o-late, or is'o-late, not i'so-lat. One volume, 18mo. Cloth. Price, $1.00. " The book is an exceHent one, which is likely to do more for the cause of good speech than any work with which we are acquainted." — Post. New York : D. APPLETON & CO., 1, 3, & 6 Bond Street APPLETONS' INSTRUCTIVE READING-BOOKS FOR SUPPLEMENTARY READING. THE NATURAIi HISTORY SERIES. By James Johonnot, author of "Principles and Practice of Teaching," "Geographical Reader," " ilow We Live," etc. No. 1. Book of Cats and Do§:s, and other Friends, For Little Folks. 12mo. 96 pages. Deals with the familiar animals of the house and farm-yard. No. 2. Friends in Feathers and Fur and other Neighbors. For Young Folks. 12mo. 140 pages. Gives an account of the chickens, ducks, and geese about home, and of the birds, squirrels, rabbits, and other animals found near home. No. 3. Neighbors with Wings and Fins and some others. For Boys and Girls. Interspersed with interesting stories, it gives descriptions of birds, reptiles, and insects, in such a way as to lead to scientific classification. No. 4. Neighbors with Claws and Hoofs and their Kin. For Young People. Begins with the familiar animals of house and field, and reaches out to a general description and classification of mammals. No. 5. Glimpses of the Animate World : Science and liiterature of Natural History. For School or Home. 12rao. 414 pages. Treats of special topics, and is made up of the literature of natural history. The articles are from the pens of some of our most distinguished scientists and literary writers. The publication of this series marks a distinct and important advance in the adaptation of special knowledge and general literature to the intelligent comprehension of pupils of all grades of attainment. The importance of this movement and its value to the present generation of school-children can not be overestimated. While in no wise tending to do away with the regular school-readers, philosophically constructed in accordance with correct educational principles, the " Instructive Read- ing-Books " introduce suggestive and valuable information and specific knowledge, covering many of the subjects which will eventually be more minutely investigated by the maturing of the pupil's mind. Natural History in the Instructive Reading Course is to be followed by History, Geography, Science, and the Industries — all topics to arouse attention in their turn, and to fill the mind with knowledge of the great- est use. These are now in preparation, and will be announced in detail from time to time. New York: D. APPLETON & CO., 1, 3, & 5 Bond Street. READING AND ORATORY, A GEOGRAPHICAL READER. A Collection of Geographical Descriptions and Narrations, from the best Writers in English Lit- erature. Classified and arranged to meet the wants of Geoirraphical Students, and the higher grades of reading classes. By James JoHONNOT, author of "Principles and Practice of Teaching." 12mo. Cloth. 418 pages. This Reader is not simply a compilation of dry statistics from the text-book of geography. It is a carefully selected and classified series of extracts from standard works of travel by well-known writers, giving spirited, entertaining, and instructive accounts of noted places, and the physical features of the globe, and are all of high literary merit. No more interesting or suitable work for reading classes in intermediate or grammar grades, or for home libraries, could be selected. AN" HISTORICAL READER, for Classes in Academies, High Schools, and Grammar Schools. By Henry E. Shepherd, M. A. 12mo. 845 pages. A collection of extracts representing the purest historical literature that has been produced in the different stages of our literary develop- ment, from the time of Clarendon to the era of Macaulay and Prescott. THE STANDARD SUPPLEMENTARY READERS. Ed- ited by William Swinton and George R. Cathcart. Comprising a series of carefully graduated reading-books, designed to connect with any of the regular series of Readers. They are attractive in appearance, and the first four books are profusely illustrated by Fred- ericks, White, Dielman, Church, and others. There are six books in the series, as follows : I. Easy Steps for Little Feet. Supplementary to First Reader. Cloth. 128 pages. II. Golden Book of Choice Reading. Supplementary to Second Reader. Cloth. 192 pages. III. Book of Tales. Supplementary to Third Reader. Cloth. 276 pages. IV. Readings in the Book of Nature, Supplementary to Fourth Reader. Cloth. 352 pages. v. Seven American Classics. ) Supplementary to Fifth Reader. VI. Seven British Classics. \ Cloth. 224 pages each. MANDEVILLE'S READING AND ORATORY, 12mo. 356 pages. MANDEVILLE'S COURSE OF READING. 12mo. 377 pages. HOWS'S HISTORICAL SHAKESPEARIAN READER. 12mo. 503 pages. HOWS'S SHAKESPEARIAN READER. 12mo. 447 pages. New York: D. APPLETON & CO., 1, 3, & 5 Bond Street. APPLETONS' STUDENTS' Library, Consisting of Thirty-four Volumes on Subjects in Science, His- TORY, Literature, and Biography. In neat i8mo vol- umes, bound in cloth. Each set put up in a box. SOLD IN SETS ONLY. PRICE, PER SET, $20.00. CONTAINING : Homer. By "W. E. Gladstone. \ 1 Shakespeare. By E. Dowden. j vol, English liiterature. By S. A. \ Brooke Greek Literature Jkbb. By K. C. Philology. By J. Peile. English Composition. NlCHOL. By J. ■t Geography. By G. Grove. Classical Geography. By F. TOZEE. ^ ^ ' ^ Introduction to Science 1 Primers. By T. H. Huxley. V Physiology. By M. Foster. ) Chemistry. By H. E. Roscoe. | Physics, By Balfour Stewart. J Geology. By A. Geikie. } Botany. By J. D. Hooker. f Astronomy. By J. N. Lockter. 1 Physical Geography. By A. \ Geikfe. ) Political Economy. By W. S. 1 Jevons. I liOgic. By "W. S. Jevons. j History of Europe* By E. A.'l Freeman. ' History of France. By C. YONGE. History of Rome. By M. Creighton. History of Greece. By C. A. FyrFB. Old Greek liife. By J. P. MAIIAFFr. Roman Antiquities. By A. S. WiLKlNS. Sophocles. By Lewis Campbell. | Euripides. By J. P. Mahafft. f Vergil. By Prof. H. Nettleship. \ L.ivy. By W. W. Capes. J Milton. By Stopford A. Brooke. I Demosthenes. By 8. H. Butcher, j The Apostolic Fathers and the Apologists. By the Eev. G. A. Jackson. The Fathers of the Third Century. By the Kev. G. A. Jackson. Thomas Carlyle ; His Life— his Books —his Theories. Yty A. H. Guernsey. Ralph Waldo Emerson. By A. H. Guernsey. 3Iacaulay: As Life— his Writiners. Bv C.H.Jones. ^ ^ Short IJfe of Charles Dickens. By C. H. Jones. Short Life of Gladstone. By C. H. Jones. Rnskin on Painting. The World's Paradises W. Benjamin. Town Geology. LEY. By S. G. By Chables Kings- By The Childhood of Religions. £. Clodd. History of the Early Church. By E. M. Bewell. The Art of Speech. Poetry and Prose. By L. P. Townsend. The Art of Speech. Eloquence and Logic. By L. P. Townsend. The Great German Composers. By G. T. Ferris. The Great Italian and French Composers. By G. T. Ferris. Great Singers. First Series. By G. T. Ferris. Great Singers. G. T. Ferris. Second Series. By Great Violinists and Pianists. By G. T. Ferris. New York : D. APPLETON & CO., 1, 3, & 5 Bond Street. APPLETONS' SCHOOL READERS, WM. T. HARRIS, LL. D., SupH of Schools, St. Louis, Mo. A. J. RICKOPF, A. M., SupH of Instruction, Cleveland, Ohio. MARK BAILEY, A. M., Instructor in Elocution, Tale College. CONSISTING OF FIVE BOOKS, SUPERBLY ILLUSTRATED. Appletons' First Reader. Child's Quarto. 90 pages. In the First Reader the combined word and phonic methods are ad- mirably developed and carefully graded. In the first 52 pages (Part I), in connection with beautiful and child-life reading-lessons, are taught the names of all the letters, the short sounds of the vowels, and the sounds of the consonants and diphthongs. In Part II are found a systematic mark^ ing of silent letters and the more easily distinguished sounds of vowels, and a continued drill in the sounds of consonants. The aim is to make the pupil acquainted with the forms and powers of letters, and the sound, construction, and meaning of words. The pictorial illustrations have been made a feature not only of unusual attractiveness, but are instruct- ive and interesting adjuncts to the text, as subjects for study and oral exercises. Appletons' Second Beader. 12mo. 143 pages. This continues the plan of the First, and gives a complete table of all the vowel and consonant sounds with their markings according to Webster — " A Key to Pronunciation." Preceding each reading-lesson the new words of that lesson are carefully marked for a spelling-exercise. This Reader gives prominence to the phonic analysis and the noting of silent letters, to the placing of diacritical marks, which must be learned by prac- tice in marking words ; also, to the spelling of words and to sentence- making, using the words occurring in the reading-lessons. Appletons' Third Reader. 12mo. 214 pages. In this Reader the plan of the Second is continued, with the addition of some important features, notably the lessons " How to read," placed at intervals through the book. They form the preliminary instruction in elocution which Professor Bailey has developed in this and the succeeding volumes in a masterly and unique manner. The selection of " comi)aratively common words," yet such as are easily and usually misspelled, niimbering about five hundred, given at the close, is a feature of very great practical value, and answers beyond cavil the question sometimes asked, " Ought not a speller to accompany or precede the series ? " [see next PAGK.J APPLETONS' SCHOOL i2^^i)£'i2/S'.— (Continued.) Introductory Fourth Reader. 12mo. Designed for those pupils who have finished the Third Reader, and are yet too young or too immature to take up the Fourth. Appletons' Fourth Reader. 12mo. 248 pages. It is here that the student enters the domain of literature proper, and makes the atquaintance of the standard writers of " English undeliled " in their best style. Having received adequate preparation in the previous books, he is now able to appreciate as well as to assimilate the higher classics now before him. A new and invaluable feature in the editorship of this and the next volume is the " Preparatory Notes " appended to each selection, for the aid of both teacher and pupil. The elocutionary work commenced in the Third Reader is continued and gradually advanced to the higher phases of the subject. Spelling- exercises are also appended, introducing " Words difficult to spell," with both phonic and what are usually known as orthographic principles for- mulated into rules. Beautifully engraved full- page illustrations embellish the interior of the book, and render it artistically chaste and attractive. Appletons' Fifth Reader. 12mo. 4Y1 pages. This Reader is the one to which the editors have given their choicest efforts. The elementary principles of the earlier volumes are not forgot ten in this, but are subordinated to matters germane to more advanced teaching. The '* Preparatory Notes " are more advanced than those of the preceding Reader, and seek to direct the mind more to style and the liter- ary character, and lastly to the logical element of the thought. Literary history and criticism are woven into the work in such way as to evoke thought and inquiry in the mind of the young. Extracts are given from Webster, Jefferson, Irving, Audubon, Cooper, Emerson, Wirt, and Wash- ington, along with others from De Quincey, Goethe, Victor Hugo, Byron, Shelley, Milton, Coleridge, and Shakespeare ; and with these is a vast amount of valuable information of every kind. It is, indeed, a text-book of belles-lettres^ as well as of reading and spelling. Professor Bailey's lessons in elocution are fuller than in preceding volumes, and can probably not be equaled in the language for perspicuous brevity and completeness. All the departments of recitation — the earnest and plain, the noble, the joyous, the sad — sarcasm, scorn, humor, passion, poetry — are given clearly and practically. The collection of " Unusual and Difficult Words " at the close comprises fifty-four lists of words which should always be kept in mind by the student. D, APPLETON & CO., Publishers, NEW YORK, BOSTON, CHICAGO, SAN FRANCISCO. DARWINISM STATED BY DARWIN HIM- SELF : CHARACTERISTIC PASSAGES FROM THE WRITINGS OF CHARLES DARWIN. Selected and arranged by Pro- fessor Nathan Sheppard. 12mo, cloth, $1.50. By means of a systematic selection of passages from the various writings of Charles Darwin, the reader of this volume is enabled to grasp readily the scope of Darwin's argument as to the origin and evolution of species. " I think you have done it well." — Professor Asa Gray. " It seems to me exceedingly interesting, and I will call the attention of those interested in such matters in this institution to the book." — Andrew D. White, LL. D., Freside7U of Cornell University. " It is done with great skill and judgment, and I shall be glad to make such use of the work as circumstances may allow."— F. B. Palmer, Ph. D., Principal of State Normal School, Fredonia^ N. Y. " The idea of culling Darwin's distinctive teachings from his many works, and giving an orderly statement of them in his own language, was a happy one, and ought to receive due recognition in a large demand for the book. I have taken pains to call the attention of our senior class to the book, and shall ask our Professors of Natural Science to make such use of it as they can in their instructions." — E. G. Robinson, D. D., LL. D., President of Brown University. " An intelligent and careful compilation of his (Darwin's) own state ments. These contain great and weighty truths, and, whether we accept his results as verified science or not, they are worthy of the careful study of all intelligent men."— M. B. Anderson, LL. D., President of Rochester University. " It is a real contribution to our knowledge of what the great English naturalist has to say. Very few will read at length his whole works; Very many will content themselves with second-hand information, always a misfortune. I shall be glad to recommend it." — E. Dodge, D. D., President of Madison University. D. APPLETON & CO., Publishers, New York. Boston. Chicago, San Fkancisco. hOV^ TO WRITE AND SPEAK CORRECTLY, THE ENGLISH GRAMMAR OF WILLIAM COBBETT. Carefully revised and annotated by Alfred Ayres. With Index. 18mo. Cloth, extra, $1.00. '• I know it well, and have read it with great admiration."— Richard Grant "White. "Cobbetfs Grammar is probably the most readable grammar ever written. For the purposes of self-education it is unrivaled. Persons that studied grammar when at school and failed to comprehend its principles— and there are many such — as well as those that never have studied grammar at all, will find the book specially suited to their needs. Any one of averai^e intelligence that will give it a careful reading will be rewarded with at least a tolerable knowledge of the subject, as nothing could be more simple or more lucid than its expositions."— .Fa-ow the Preface. THE ORTHOEPIST: A Pronouncing Manual, containing about Three Thousand Five Hundred Words, including a Considerable Number of the names of Foreign Authors, Artists, etc., that are often mis- pronounced. By Alfred Ayres. 18mo. Cloth, extra, $1.00. " It gives us pleasure to say that we think the author, in the treatment of this very difficult and intricate subject, English pronunciation, gives proof of not only an unusual degree of orthoepical knowledge, but also, for the most part, of rare judgment and taste."— Joseph Thomas, LL. D., in Literary World. THE VERBALIST: A Manual devoted to Brief Discussions of the Right and the Wrong Use of Words, and to some other Matters of Interest to those who would Speak and Write with Propriety, includ- ing a Treatise on Punctuation. By Alfred Ayres. 18mo. Cloth, extra, $1.00. " This is the best kind of an English grammar. It teaches the right use of our mother-tongue by giving instances of the wrong use of it, and showing why they are wrong."— T/ie Churchman. " Every one can learn something from this volume, and most of us a great deal."— Springfield Republican. New York: D. APPLETON & CO., 1, 3, & 5 Bond Street. EDUCATION IN RELATION TO MANUAL INDUSTRY. By Arthur Mac Arthur, LL. D. 12mo. Cloth, $1.50. " Mr. MacArthtir's able treatise is designed to adapt to the usual methods of instruction a system of rudimental science and manual art. He describes the progress of industrial education in France, Belgium, Russia, Germany, and Great Britain, and the establishment of their professional schools. The technical schools of the United States are next reviewed. Mr. MacArthur is anxious that the State governments should take up the subject, and enable every girl and boy to receive a practical education which would lit them for use in this world. This valuable book should be carefully read and meditated upon. The discussion is of higli importance."— P/iitorfe^y/^ia Fublic Ledger. " The importance of this book can not be too greatly urged. It gives a statistical account of the industries of various countries, the number of workmen and workwomen, and the degree of perfection attained. America is behind in native production, and. when we read of the importation of foreign workmen in simple manufacture such as glass, it is a stimulus for young men to train them- selves early as is done in foreign countries. The necessity of training-schools and the value and dignity of trades are made evident in this work. It is particu- larly helpful to women, as it mentions the variety of employments which they can practice, and gives the success already reached by them. It serves as a his- tory and encyclopaedia of facts relating to industries, and is very well written."— Boston Globe. "The advocates of iiidustrinl education in schools will find a very complete rcanual oi the whole subject in Mr. MacArthur's hook.''— Springfield Rejmblican. " A sensible and much-needed plea for the establishment of schools for indus- try by the state, supported by the practical illustration of what has been accom- plished for the good of the state by such schools in foreign countries. Great Britain has never regretted the step she took when, recognizing at the Crystal Palace Exhibition her inferiority in industrial art-work, she at once established the South Kensington Museum, with its annexed art-schools, at a cost of six mill- ion dollars."- The Critic. "The aim of the book is succinctly stated, as it ought to be, in the preface : 'What is industrial education ? What are its merits and objects, and, above all, what power does it possess of ministering to some useful purpose in the practical arts of life?' These are questions about which we are deeply concerned in this country, and the author has essiyed to answer them, not by an abstract discus- i^ion of technical instruction, but by giviuir a full and accurate account of the experiments ^n industrial trainiuir which have been actually and successfully carried out in Europe." — New York Sun. "A most interesting and suggestive work on a matter of immediate and universal importance." — New York. Laity Graphic. "An admirable book on a much-neglected s ibject. Those countries have made the most rapid advance in the line of new industries which have paid the most attention to the methods here recommended of primary instruction. The land that neglects them will sooner or later cease to be in the front ranks of applied science and the useful ans..'''—New York Journal of Commerce. For sale by all booksellers ; or sent by mail, post-paid, on receipt of price. New York: D. APPLETON & CO., 1, 3. & 5 Bond Street.