LIBRARY OF CONGRESS 
 
 00017^705^1 
 

 
 ***■ V** -Sfc X/ M- 
 
 .% * 
 
 jP** 
 
 
 
 
 4 o > 
 
 
 
 
 
 4y v ^ 
 
 
 IV of 
 
 V * T * ° 
 
 

 V* 1 
 
 °^ 'in' A. 
 
 v* .•; 
 
 
 v- 
 
 
 
 
 » u v 
 
 
 
THE FRAGMENTS 
 
 OF THE WORK OF 
 
 HEEACLITUS OF EPHESUS 
 
 ON NATURE 
 
 TRANSLATED FROM THE GREEK TEXT OF RYWATER. 
 WITH AN INTRODUCTION HISTORICAL AND CRITICAL 
 
 G. T. W. PATRICK, Ph.D. 
 
 PBOFE3SOK OF PHILOSOPHY IN" THE STATE I T NIVEBSITY OF IOWA 
 
 BALTIMORE 
 
 X. MURRAY 
 1889 
 
THE FRAGMENTS 
 
 OF THE WOKK OF 
 
 HEEACLITUS OF EPHESUS 
 
 ON NATURE 
 
 WITH AN INTRODUCTION HISTORICAL AND CRITICAL 
 
 G. T. W. PATRICK, Ph.D. 
 
 PEOFES30R OF PHILOSOPHY IN THE STATE UNIVERSITY OF IOWA 
 
 BALTIMORE 
 
 \ . MURRAY 
 
 1889 
 
N c 
 
 t>°r 
 
 - 
 
 [Eeprinted from the American Journal of Psychology, 1888.] 
 
 A Thesis Accepted for the Degree op Doctor of Philosophy in the 
 Johns Hopkins University, 1888. 
 
 press of Isaac Friedenwald, 
 BALTIMORE. 
 
01 (JSOlsZSZ. 
 
 All thoughts, all creeds, all dreams are true, 
 
 All visions wild and strange ; 
 Man is the measure of all truth 
 
 Unto himself. All truth is change, 
 All men do walk in sleep, and all 
 
 Have faith in that they dream : 
 For all things are as they seem to all, 
 
 And all things now like a stream. 
 
 II. 
 
 There is no rest, no calm, no pause, 
 
 Xor good nor ill, nor light nor shade, 
 Nor ess*, ice nor eternal laws : 
 
 For nothing is, but all is made. 
 But if I dream that all these are, 
 
 They are to me for that I dream ; 
 For all things are as they seem to all, 
 
 And all things flow like a stream. 
 
 Argal — this very opinion is only true 
 relatively to the flowing philosophers. 
 
 Tennyson. 
 
PREFACE. 
 
 The latest writers on Heraclitus, namely, Gustav 
 Teichmuller and Edmund Pfleiderer, have thought it 
 necessary to preface their works with an apology for 
 adding other monographs to the Heraclitic literature, 
 already enriched by treatises from such distinguished 
 men as Schleiermacher, Lassalle, Zeller, and Schuster. 
 That still other study of Heraclitus, however, needs 
 no apology, will be admitted when it is seen that these 
 scholarly critics, instead of determining the place of 
 Heraclitus in the history of philosophy, have so far 
 disagreed, that while Schuster makes him out to be a 
 sensationalist and empiricist, Lassalle finds that he is 
 a rationalist and idealist. While to Teichmuller, his 
 starting point and the key to his whole system is found 
 in his physics, to Zeller it is found in his metaphysics, 
 and to Pfleiderer in his religion. Heraclitus' theology 
 was derived, according to Teichmuller, from Egypt ; 
 according to Lassalle, from India ; according to Pfleid- 
 erer, from the Greek Mysteries. The Heraclitic flux, 
 according to Pfleiderer, was consequent on his abstract 
 theories ; according to Teichmuller, his abstract theo- 
 ries resulted from his observation of the flux. Pfleid- 
 fr^r says that Heraclitus was an optimist ; Gottlob 
 
VI PREFACE. 
 
 Mayer says that he was a pessimist. According to 
 Schuster he was a hylozoist, according to Zeller a pan- 
 theist, according to Pfleiderer a panzoist, according 
 to Lassalle a panlogist. Naturally, therefore, in the 
 hands of these critics, with their various theories to 
 support, the remains of Heraclitus' work have suffered 
 a violence of interpretation only partially excused by 
 his known obscurity. No small proportion of the 
 fragments, as will be seen in my introduction, have 
 been taken in a diametrically opposite sense. 
 
 Recently a contribution towards the disentanglement 
 of this maze has been made by Mr. Bywater, an acute 
 English scholar. His work (Heracliti Ephesii Reli- 
 quiae, Oxford, 1877) is simply a complete edition of the 
 now existing fragments of Heraclitus' work, together 
 with the sources from which they are drawn, with so 
 much of the context as to make them intelligible. 
 
 Under these circumstances I have thought that a 
 translation of the fragments into English, that every 
 man may read and judge for himself, would be the 
 best contribution that could be made. The increasing 
 interest in early Greek philosophy, and particularly in 
 Heraclitus, who is the one Greek thinker most in 
 accord with the thought of our century, makes such a 
 translation justifiable, and the excellent and timely 
 edition of the Greek text by Mr. Bywater makes it 
 practicable. 
 
 The translations both of the fragments and of the 
 context are made from the original sources, though I 
 
PREFACE. VII 
 
 have followed the text of Bywater except in a very 
 few cases, designated in the critical notes. As a 
 number of the fragments are ambiguous, and several 
 of them contain a play upon words, I have appended 
 the entire Greek text. 
 
 The collection of sources is wholly that of Mr. 
 Bywater. In these I have made a translation, not of 
 all the references, but only of those from which the 
 fragment is immediately taken, adding others only in 
 cases of especial interest. 
 
 My acknowledgments are due to Dr. Basil L. Gil- 
 dersleeve, of the Johns Hopkins University, for kind 
 suggestions concerning the translation, and to Dr. 
 G. Stanley Hall for valuable assistance in relation to 
 the plan of the work. 
 
 Baltimore, September 1, 1888. 
 
CONTENTS. 
 
 INTRODUCTION. 
 Section I. — Historical and Critical. 
 
 PAGE 
 
 Literature 1 
 
 Over-systemization in Philosophj*- 2 
 
 Over-interpretation in Historical Criticism 3 
 
 Exposition of Lassalle - 4 
 
 Hegel's Conception of Heraclitus 5 
 
 Criticism of Hegel's Conception : 6 
 
 Criticism of Lassalle 9 
 
 Exposition of Schuster 11 
 
 Criticism of Schuster 17 
 
 Exposition of Teichmiiller 23 
 
 Criticism of Teichmiiller 31 
 
 Exposition of Pfleiderer 39 
 
 Criticism of Pfleiderer . . . . 46 
 
 Section II. — Reconstructive. 
 
 I. 
 
 Can the Positions of the Critics be harmonized? 56 
 
 Heraclitus' Starting-point 57 
 
 Heraclitus as a Preacher and Prophet 57 
 
 The Content of his Message 58 
 
 The Universal Order 60 
 
 Strife 62 
 
 The Unity of Opposites 63 
 
 The Flux 65 
 
 Cosmogony 68 
 
 Ethics 69 
 
 Optimism 71 
 
CONTENTS. 
 
 II. 
 
 Cause of the Present Interest in Heraclitus 72 
 
 Passion for Origins 72 
 
 Greek Objectivity 73 
 
 Heraclitic Ideas 74 
 
 Relation to Socrates and Plato 75 
 
 Socrates • 76 
 
 Birth of Self-consciousness 77 
 
 Loss of Love of Beauty 78 
 
 Rise of Transcendentalism 79 
 
 Platonic Dualism ■ 80 
 
 Return to Heraclitus 82 
 
 Defeat of Heraclitus 83 
 
 Translation of the Fragments 84-114 
 
 Critical Notes 115-123 
 
 Greek Text 124-131 
 
INTRODUCTION. 
 
 Section I. — Historical and Critical. 
 
 Modern Heraclitic literature belongs wholly to the 
 present century. The most important works are the 
 following : — Schleiermacher : Herakleitos, der Dunkle 
 von Ephesos, in Wolf and Buttmann's Museum der 
 Alterthuinswissenschaft, Vol. I, 1807, pp. 313-533, and 
 in Schleiermachers Sammt. Werke, Abth. Ill, Vol. 2, 
 Berlin, 1838, pp. 1-146 ; — Jak. Bernays : Heraclitea, 
 Bonn, 1848 ; Heraklitisehe Studien, in the Rhein. Mus., 
 new series, VII, pp. 90-116, 1850 ; Neue Bruchstucke 
 des Heraklit, ibid. IX, pp. 241-269, 1854 ; Die Hera- 
 klitischen Briefe, Berlin, 1869 ; — Ferd. Lassalle : Die 
 Philosopkie Herakleitos des Dunkeln von Ephesos, 2 
 vols., Berlin, 1858; — Paul Schuster: Heraklit von 
 Ephesus. in Actis soc. phil. Lips. ed. Fr. Ritschelius, 
 1873, III, 1-397 ;— Teichmuller, Xeue Stud. z. Gesch. der 
 Begriffe, Heft I, Gotha, 1876, and II, 1878 ;— Bywater : 
 Heracliti Ephesii Reliquiae, Oxford, 1877 ; — Edmund 
 Pfleiderer : Die Philosophic des Heraklit von Ephesus 
 im Lichte der Mysterienidee, Berlin, 1886 ; — Eduard 
 Zeller : Die Philosophic der Griechen, Bd. I, pp. 566-677. 
 
 There may be mentioned also the following addi- 
 tional writings which have been consulted in the 
 preparation of these pages : — Gottlob Mayer : Heraklit 
 von Ephesus und Arthur Schopenhauer, Heidelberg, 
 : Campbell : Theaetetus of Plato, Appendix A, 
 Oxford. L883 ; A. W. Benn : The Greek Philosophers, 
 London, 1882. 
 
Z HERACLITUS. 
 
 After the introductory collection and arrangement 
 of the Heraclitic fragments by Schleiermacher, and 
 the scholarly discriminative work and additions of 
 Bernays, four attempts have been made successively 
 by Lassalle, Schuster, Teichmuller, and Pfleiderer, to 
 reconstruct or interpret the philosophical system of 
 Heraclitus. The positions taken and the results 
 arrived at by these eminent scholars and critics are 
 largely, if not wholly, different and discordant. A 
 brief statement of their several positions will be our 
 best introduction to the study of Heraclitus at first 
 hand, and at the same time will offer us incidentally 
 some striking examples of prevalent methods of his- 
 toric criticism. 
 
 One of the greatest evils in circles of philosophical 
 and religious thought has always been the evil of over- 
 systemization. It is classification, or the scientific 
 method, carried too far. It is the tendency to arrange 
 under any outlined system or theory, more facts than 
 it will properly include. It is the temptation, in a 
 word, to classify according to resemblances which are 
 too faint or fanciful. In the field of historic criticism 
 this evil takes the form of over-interpretation. Just 
 as in daily life we interpret every sense perception 
 according to our own mental forms, so we tend to read 
 our own thoughts into every saying of the ancients, 
 and then proceed to use these, often without dis- 
 honesty, to support our favorite modern systems. The 
 use of sacred writings will naturally occur to every one 
 as the most striking illustration of this over-interpre- 
 tation. Especially in the exegesis of the Bible has this 
 prostitution of ancient writings to every man's religious 
 views been long since recognized and condemned, and 
 if most recently this tendency has been largely cor- 
 
HISTORICAL AND CRITICAL. 3 
 
 rected in religious circles, it is all the more deplorable, 
 in philosophical criticism, to find it still flourishing. 
 Unfortunately, this vice continues, and it appears 
 nowhere more plainly than in the interpretation of 
 Greek philosophy. There is a great temptation to 
 modern writers to use the Greek philosophers as props 
 to support their own systems — a temptation to inter- 
 pret them arbitrarily, to look down upon them patron- 
 izingly, as it were, showing that what they meant was 
 this or that modern thought, having only not learned 
 to express themselves as well as we have. Among his- 
 torians of philosophy this appears as a one-sidedness, 
 so that it is commonly necessary in reading a history 
 of philosophy to make a correction for the author's 
 " personal equation." The histories of Schwegler and 
 of Lewes are examples — the one biased by Hegel- 
 ianism, the other by Positivism. Undoubtedly, a cer- 
 tain personal equation is unavoidable, and it is as 
 impossible for an interpreter of Greek philosophy to 
 make himself wholly Greek as it is unfair to represent 
 the ancient thinker as wholly German or English. 
 But when this becomes complete one-sidedness, or 
 blindness to all but one series of an author's thoughts, 
 or a willful or even unintentional perversion of his 
 words, vigorous remonstrance is called for. 
 
 This attempt to fully understand the ancients, to 
 make them speak in the phraseology of some modern 
 school, must be distinguished from the recent move- 
 ment, represented by Prof. Lagarde and others, in 
 interpreting historic thought and historic events 
 psychologically. This movement is certainly legiti- 
 mate, based as it is on the truth of the similarity of 
 constitution of all human minds, and the probability 
 that underlying all representative historic creeds are 
 great related if not identical thoughts. Even here, of 
 
4 HERACLITUS. 
 
 course, the attempt to express these thoughts in the set 
 phrases of any one people is inadequate. 
 
 We proceed, then, to look at some of the work done 
 upon the philosophy of Heraclitus. Here we shall not 
 attempt any examination of Zeller's exposition, since 
 his work, though it is perhaps the very best that has 
 been done in this field, is critical rather than recon- 
 structive, and like his whole history of Greek philos- 
 ophy, is a marvel of candor as well as of immense 
 research. Even Zeller, however, has not wholly 
 escaped the charge of one-sidedness, since Benn, in the 
 preface to his work on the Greek philosophers, has 
 accused him of never having outgrown the semi-Hege- 
 lian prejudice of his youth. 
 
 Lassalle. 
 
 Lassalle, in two ponderous volumes noted above 
 (page 1), made the first and most elaborate attempt 
 to reconstruct the system of the Ephesian philosopher. 
 His work exhibits immense labor and study, and 
 extended research in the discovery of new fragments 
 and of ancient testimony, together with some acuteness 
 in their use. Lassalle has a very distinct view of the 
 philosophy of Heraclitus. But it is not an original 
 view. It is, in fact, nothing but an expansion of the 
 short account of Heraclitus in Hegel's History of Phil- 
 osophy, although Lassalle makes no mention of him, 
 except to quote upon his title-page Hegel's well-known 
 motto, " Es ist kein Satz des Heraklit, den ich nicht 
 in meine Logik aufgenommen." Hegel's conception 
 of Heraclitus is, in a word, as follows : Heraclitus' 
 Absolute was the unity of being and non-being. His 
 whole system was an expansion of the speculative 
 thought of the principle of pure becoming. He appre- 
 hended, and was the first to apprehend, the Absolute 
 
HISTORICAL AND CRITICAL. 5 
 
 as a process, as the unity of opposites, as dialectic 
 itself. His great contribution was the speculative 
 transition from the being of the Eleatics to the idea of 
 becoming. Now how does Hegel support this position ? 
 There is in his Logic but one passage referring to Hera- 
 clitus. There he says, " Glancing at the principle of the 
 Eleatics. Heraclitus then goes on to say, ' Being no more 
 is than non-being'' (oijohiy ud/lov to ov tou tirj ovroc iart), 
 a statement expressing the negative nature of abstract 
 being and its identity with non-being" (Wallace, 
 The Logic of Hegel, p. 144 ; cp. Science of Logic, 
 Hegel's Werke, Vol. 3, p. 80). Hegel omits, in the 
 Logic, to give the reference to the above quotation, 
 but in his History of Philosophy (Werke, Vol. 13, p. 
 332) he quotes the same passage with the reference. 
 It is to Aristotle, Metaph. i. 4. We turn to the same 
 and find that it is a passage which Aristotle quotes 
 from the Atomists, Democritus and Leucippus, and 
 that it has not the slightest reference to Heraclitus, 
 who, indeed, is not mentioned in the same chapter. 
 This is rather discouraging, but the account in the 
 History of Philosophy, to which we now turn, is 
 scarcely less so. There Hegel begins his exposition 
 of Heraclitus as follows : 
 
 "1. Das allgemeine Princip. Dieser kiihne Geist 
 (Heraclitus) hat zuerst das tiefe Wort gesagt, ' Das 
 Seyn ist nicht mehr als das Nichtseyn,' es ist ebenso 
 wenig, oder, ' Seyn und Nichts sey dasselbe,' das 
 W. sen sey die Veranderung" (Gesch. d. Phil. Vol. 13, 
 p. :;. 
 
 Now it happens that Heraclitus said nothing of the 
 kind. As references Hegel gives Aristotle, Meta- 
 phys. i. 4: iv. 7; iv. 3. The first passage, as we have 
 already seen, is from the Atomists. The second turns 
 out upon examination to be simply the expression, 
 
6 HERACLITUS. 
 
 " All things are and are not" (ndura elvac xac firj ehcu), 
 and the third is a statement of Aristotle that some 
 people supposed Heraclitus to have said that the same 
 thing could both be and not be the same. Moreover, 
 neither of these passages is Heraclitic in form, and 
 they are not even mentioned in By water's edition. 
 The only expression of Heraclitus that resembles in 
 form the above passage from Aristotle is that of frag. 
 81, " Into the same river we step and we do not step. 
 We are and we are not." The over-interpretation by 
 which this simple passage, expressing incessant phys- 
 ical change, is transformed into the logical principle 
 of Hegel, " Das Seyn ist nicht mehr als das ISTicht- 
 seyn," " Seyn und Mchts sey dasselbe," is audacious 
 at least. Furthermore, we may say here in passing, 
 that neither the expressions to ov, /itj ov, nor even to 
 jqvofievov, occur in any genuine saying of Heraclitus ; 
 although if they did occur, it would be easy to show 
 that they could not mean at all what Hegel meant by 
 being, non-being, and becoming. Even the Eleatic 
 Being was not .at all the same with that of Hegel, but 
 was finite, spherical, and something very much like 
 that which we should call material. But Heraclitus, 
 who indeed preceded Parmenides, said nothing of 
 being nor of non-being, nor did he speak of becoming 
 in the abstract, although the trustful reader of Hegel, 
 Lassalle, or Ferrier, might well suppose he spoke of 
 nothing else. That which these writers mistook for 
 becoming was, as we shall see later, only physical 
 change. With the loss of this corner-stone, the Hera- 
 clitic support of the Hegelian Logic fails, and Hegel's 
 boast that there was no sentence of Heraclitus that 
 his Logic had not taken up becomes rather ludicrous, 
 especially if one will read through the remains of 
 
HISTORICAL AND CRITICAL. 7 
 
 Heraclitus' work on Nature and search for his rich 
 and varied thoughts in the Logic of Hegel. 
 
 Returning now to Lassalle, the above principles are 
 carried out more in detail as follows : The chief point 
 hi the philosophy of Heraclitus is that here first the 
 formal notion of the speculative idea in general was 
 grasped. With him first emerged the conception of 
 pure thought defecated of the sensuous. His ground 
 principle was the dialectical opposition of being and 
 non-being. The kernel and whole depth of his phil- 
 osophy may be expressed in the one sentence, " Only 
 non-being is" (Lassalle, Vol. 1, p. 35). The unity of 
 being and non-being is a unity of process (processi- 
 rende Einheit). It is the unity of opposites, the idea of 
 becoming, the divine law, the yvcoftq of the determining 
 God (Id. Vol. 1, p. 24). Fire, strife, peace, time, neces- 
 sity, harmony, the way up and down, the flux, justice, 
 fate, Logos, are all different terms for this one idea 
 (Id. Vol. 1, p. 57). Hence arises Heraclitus' obscurity. 
 It is not a mere grammatical obscurity, as Schleier- 
 macher, following Aristotle (Rhet. iii. 5, p. 1407, b. 14) 
 thought ; nor is it a willful obscurity, but it arises 
 from the very nature of his great thought, which could 
 not be enunciated in exact terms, but could only be 
 suggested by such words as fire, time, etc., and so he 
 labored on with one new symbol after another, vainly 
 trying to express himself. 
 
 The Heraclitic fire is a " metaphysical abstraction " 
 
 -a pure process, " whose existence is pure self -annull- 
 ing (sich aufheben), whose being is pure self-consump- 
 tion (sich selbst verzehren) " (Lassalle, Vol. 1, p. 18). 
 
 Most clearly, however, is the great thought of Hera- 
 clitus shown in "the way up and down," which does 
 not involve change of place, but only a logical process. 
 
8 HERACLITUS. 
 
 It is " nothing else " than the change from being into 
 non-being and the reverse. The way down is transi- 
 tion into being ; the way up is the return into the pure 
 and free negativity of non-being, motion in the undis- 
 turbed ideal harmony (Id. Vol. 2, p. 241 ff.). 
 
 God, in his adequate form, is " nothing else " than 
 pure negativity, the pure unity of process of opposites. 
 Nature is only the corporeal manifestation of the law 
 of the identity of opposites. It owes its existence to 
 privation (ddixea), that is, to the injustice which pure 
 becoming suffers when it becomes being (Id. Vol. 1, 
 p. 138). 
 
 The dvadofuaacQ of Heraclitus is not any vapor or sen- 
 sible exhalation, but is " nothing else " than the way 
 up, or the ixrrupcoa^, that is, the cessation of the sen- 
 sible and the particular and the assumption of the real 
 universal becoming. ' 'Avadopcwpevat, Lassalle says, 
 should be translated " processirend " (Id. Vol. 1, p. 144). 
 
 The Heraclitic flux is the same as the way up and 
 down. It is the dialectic of spacial being ; it is the 
 unity of being and non-being as spacial ; it is the here 
 which is not here. The nepdyov of Heraclitus is not 
 anything physical or spacial, but "the universal real 
 process of becoming," which works through the Logos 
 or law of thought (Id. Vol. 1, p. 306). 
 
 The Heraclitic Logos is the pure intelligible logical 
 law of the identity in process (die processirende Iden- 
 titat) of being and non-being. It is "nothing else" 
 than the law of opposites and the change into the same 
 (Id. Vol. 1, p. 327 ; Vol. 2, p. 265). 
 
 The substance of the soul is identical with the sub- 
 stance of nature. It is pure becoming which has in- 
 corporated itself, embraced the way down. The dry 
 or fiery soul is better than the moist because moisture 
 
HISTORICAL AXD CRITICAL. 9 
 
 is "nothing else'' than a symbol of the downward 
 way. The soul that is moist has descended out of its 
 pure self-annulling movement or negativity in process, 
 into the sphere of the particular and determinate 
 (Id. Vol. 1. pp. ISO,. 192). 
 
 Heraclitus. in his desperate labor to express this idea, 
 enters the sphere of religion. Dionysus and Hades 
 are the same, he says (see frag. 127). That is, says 
 Lassalle, Dionysus, the god of generation which repre- 
 sents the descent of pure non-being into being, is iden- 
 tical with Hades, the god of death ; and this fragment, 
 which is a polemic against Dionysus, is really a 
 polemic against being, which is inferior to non-being 
 (Id. Vol. 1, p. 208). 
 
 Knowledge consists in the recognition in each parti- 
 cular thing of the two opposites which constitute its 
 nature (Id. Vol. 2, p. 272). Of ethics, the formal prin- 
 ciple is self-realization or self-representation. It is the 
 realization of what we are in ourselves or according 
 to our inner nature. The ideal is separation from the 
 sensible and particular and the realization of the uni- 
 versal (Id. Vol. 2, p. 428 ft.). 
 
 Such in brief outline is what Ferdinand Lassalle 
 finds in Heraclitus' book On Nature. As an exposition 
 of Heraclitus it is not worth the space we have given 
 it, or any space, in fact ; but as one of the most beau- 
 tiful illustrations of over-systemization, it is extremely 
 valuable. Any formal refutation of his conception of 
 Heraclitus is unnecessary, for almost the whole of it is 
 without any foundation whatever. The expositions 
 which are to follow, or even a slight reading of the 
 fragments themselves, will sufficiently show how thor- 
 oughly fantastic and arbitrary are his interpretations. 
 salle seems to have been misled partly by Hegel's 
 
10 HERACLITUS. 
 
 misinterpretation of the passages from Aristotle not- 
 iced above, and partly by the principle of opposition 
 which runs through a number of the sayings of Hera- 
 clitus — an opposition which, as we shall see later, was 
 wholly physical, and far more simple than the abstruse 
 logical meaning given it by Lassalle. This German 
 scholar had no power or no wish to put himself in the 
 attitude of the Greek mind, which was as widely dif- 
 ferent from his as possible. It was a mistake for this 
 disciple of pure thought, bred in the stifling atmosphere 
 of a nineteenth century Hegelian lecture-room, and 
 powerless to transport himself out of it even in thought, 
 to attempt to interpret the sentences of an ingenuous 
 lover of Nature, who, five centuries before the Chris- 
 tian era, lived and moved in the free air of Ephesus. 
 In this we do not mean to say that the philosophy of 
 Heraclitus was purely physical rather than metaphys- 
 ical, for we shall see that such was not the case, but 
 primitive pre-Socratic metaphysics and the panlogism 
 of Lassalle are as wide asunder as the poles. On this 
 point, Benn, in the work already referred to, well says, 
 " The Greek philosophers from Thales to Democritus 
 did not even suspect the existence of those ethical and 
 dialectical problems which long constituted the sole 
 object of philosophical discussion " (Vol. 1, p. 4). 
 
 Those who wish to trace Lassalle' s errors further 
 may compare, on his mistaken conception of the Hera- 
 clitic fire, Zeller, Vol. 1, p. 591, 3 1 ; Grote : Plato, Vol. 
 1, p. 33, note. On " the way up and down," com- 
 pare Zeller, Vol. 1, p. 619, 1. On the flux, compare 
 Schuster, p. 201 ; Zeller, Vol. 1, p. 577, 1. 
 
 The characterization of Lassalle' s book as a whole 
 
 2 The references to Zeller in the following pages are to the fourth 
 German edition of Die Philosophie der Grieehen. 
 
HISTORICAL AND CRITICAL. 11 
 
 is. that it is a striking example of great philosophic 
 waste, turning as he does the rich and suggestive phil- 
 osophy of the Ephesian into a wretched mouthful of 
 Hegelian phrases. His citation of so many diverse 
 sentences of Heraclitus, drawn from theology, ethics, 
 nature, and man. and his discovery in all of them of his 
 single ever-recurring notion of " die reine umschlag- 
 ende Identitat von Sein und Nichtsein, impresses us 
 with the power which the tyranny of a single idea may 
 have to so blur one's vision as to cause him to see that 
 idea reflected in everything that is presented. It is 
 not true, as Lassalle's motto goes, that there is no sen- 
 tence of Heraclitus that Hegel has not incorporated in 
 his Logic, but it is not far from the truth that there is 
 no sentence of Heraclitus which Hegel and Lassalle 
 have not either willfully or ignorantly perverted. 
 
 Schuster. 
 We will mention now the work of Paul Schuster 
 (see above, p. 1). Schuster approaches the problem of 
 the interpretation of Heraclitus with the advantage of 
 a rich philological and historical knowledge. He suf- 
 fers a disadvantage, however, in the magnitude of the 
 task he undertakes, which is nothing less than the 
 reconstruction of the order and plan of the book of 
 Heraclitus itself. The interpretation of the f ragments^ 
 he justly observes, depends upon the connection in 
 which they occurred. It will be necessary, therefore, 
 if we will grasp their true sense, to recover the plan of 
 the original writing. Such a reconstruction Schuster 
 holds to be possible, since by the law of selection, the 
 fragments which have been preserved to us must have 
 been the central thoughts of the original work. Con- 
 trary to Schleiermacher, he accepts as trustworthy the 
 
12 HERACLITUS. 
 
 statement of Diogenes (Diog. Laert. ix. 5) that the 
 book of Heraclitus was divided into three parts or 
 Logoi, the first concerning "the all," the second poli- 
 tical, the third theological. On this basis Schuster 
 arranges the fragments, freely translated or rather 
 paraphrased, and interspaced with the restored pro- 
 gress of thought. The well known obscurity of our 
 philosopher, Schuster, contrary to all other critics ex- 
 cept Teichmuller, supposes to have been partly, at 
 least, intentional, as a precaution against persecution 
 for atheism. 1 
 
 The distinctive feature of Schuster's conception of 
 Heraclitus is that he was not a distruster of the senses, 
 but on the contrary the first philosopher who dared 
 to base all knowledge upon sense experience. He was 
 therefore the first of experimental philosophers. To 
 this idea the introduction of Heraclitus' book was 
 devoted. The majority of people, says the Ephesian, 
 have little interest in that which immediately sur- 
 rounds them, nor do they think to seek for knowledge 
 by investigation of that with which they daily come 
 in contact (Clement of Alex. Strom, ii. 2, p. 432 ; M. 
 Aurelius iv. 46 ; cp. frags. 5, 93). Nevertheless, that 
 which surrounds us is the source of knowledge. 
 Nature is not irrational and dumb, but is an ever 
 living Voice plainly revealing the law of the world. 
 This Voice of Nature is the Heraclitic Logos. The 
 thought which Heraclitus utters in the passage stand- 
 ing at the beginning of his book (frag. 2, Hippolytus, 
 Ref . haer. ix. 9 ; cp. Aristotle, Rhet. iii. 5, p. 1407, b. 14) 
 is no other than that which since the Renaissance has 
 
 1 Compare Plutarch. Pyth. orac. 21, p. 404 ; =: frag. 11 ; Clement of 
 Alex. Strom, v. 13, p. 699 ; r= frag. 116. The numbers refer not to 
 Schuster's numbering of the fragments, but to that of the present 
 work, which is the numeration of Bywater. 
 
HISTORICAL AXD CRITICAL. 13 
 
 inspired natural science and its accompanying specu- 
 lation, namely, that truth is to be won by observation 
 of the visible world. But the people, he complains, 
 despise the revelation which Nature offers us with 
 audible voice. Why, asks Heraclitus (Hippolytus, Ref . 
 haer. ix. 9 : cp. frag. 47), should an invisible harmony 
 be better than a visible ? It is not better, but, on the 
 contrary, whatever is the object of seeing, hearing, or 
 investigation, that I particularly honor (idem ix. 10 ; 
 cp. frag. 13). Men, therefore, must trust their eyes 
 (Polybius, xii. 27 ; cp. frag. 15) and not make reckless 
 guesses concerning the weightiest things (Diog. Laert. 
 ix. 73 ; cp. frag. -18). That Heraclitus' theory of knowl- 
 edge, therefore, based it upon sense perception and 
 reflection thereupon, is shown, continues Schuster, 
 not only by the above passages, but also by the fact 
 that the exaggerated form of the theory held by 
 Protagoras (cp. Plato's Theaetetus) must necessarily 
 have had its source in Heraclitus, his master. None 
 the less is this shown also by Parmenides' attack on 
 the empirical theory of knowledge (Sextus Empir. vii. 
 3), which could have been aimed only at the philoso- 
 pher of Ephesus (Schuster, pp. 7 and 13-42). 
 
 Turning now from the theory of knowledge to its 
 results, the first law which the observation of Nature 
 teaches us is the law of eternal and recurrent mo- 
 tion {izdvca yiooil xal obdhv fievet, Plato, Crat. p. 402 A). 
 The starting point and central position of our philoso- 
 pher we must find in this recurrent motion, rather 
 than in the primitive fire which itself held a subordi- 
 nate place in the system. But the Heraclitic motion 
 was not conceived as any absolute molecular change 
 in the modern sense, nor yet as that absolute insta- 
 bility which appeared in the nihilism of the later 
 
14 HERACLITUS. 
 
 Heracliteans. It was rather conceived in a simpler 
 way, as a general law that everything comes to an end 
 and there is nothing permanent. Under this was 
 included : 1) spacial motion, as of the flowing river ; 
 2) qualitative change, as in the human body; 3) a 
 kind of periodicity which brings everything under its 
 dominion. The last was the most emphasized. Birth 
 and death are universal; nothing escapes this fate. 
 There is no fixed or unmoved being above or outside 
 the shifting world, no divine heavenly existence that 
 does not change, but all is involved in the same 
 perpetual ebb and flow, rise and fall, life and death 
 (Schuster, p. 81 ff.). 
 
 But this life and death of the universe is literal, not 
 figurative. The world itself is a great living organism 
 subject to the same alternation of elemental fire, air, 
 and water. This thoroughgoing hylozoism which 
 Schuster attributes to Heraclitus, he bases principally 
 on the writing de diaeta of Pseudo-Hippocrates, who, 
 he believes, made a free use of the work of Heraclitus, 
 if he did not directly plagiarize from him. Comparing 
 this writing (particularly the passage, c. 10, p. 638) 
 with Plato's Timaeus (p. 40 A, also drawn from Hera- 
 clitus), he ventures to reconstruct the original as 
 follows : " Everything passes away and nothing per- 
 sists. So it is with the river, and so with mortal 
 beings ; in whom continually fire dies in the birth of 
 air, and air in the birth of water. So also with the 
 divine heavenly existence, which is subject to the 
 same process, for wp are in reality only an imitation 
 of that and of the whole world ; as it happens with 
 that so it must happen with us, and inversely we may 
 judge of that by ourselves " (Schuster, p. 118). 
 
 The life principle of the universe, as of the human 
 
HISTORICAL AND CRITICAL. 15 
 
 organism, is fire. This fire is everywhere present, so 
 that •'• : everything is full of gods and souls" (Diog. 
 Laert. ix. 7). The life of the body is sustained by the 
 breath which inhales the dry vapors kindred to fire. 
 At night, when the sun is extinguished and the world 
 becomes unconscious, we inhale the dark wet vapors 
 and sink into death-like sleep (Schuster, p. 135). 
 
 The sun, which is new every day, changes at night 
 into the surrounding air and then into the water of the 
 sea. The sea produces the daily sun, as it is the source 
 of all earthly phenomena. On a large scale this three- 
 fold change takes place with the universe, which will 
 ultimately be consumed in fire, again to become sea 
 and cosmos. This is " the way up and down " — not a 
 circular movement of the elements within the cosmos 
 (Zeller), but the periodicity of the world itself. The 
 way up and the way down relate only to the cosmogony. 
 The latter is the creation of the world by condensation 
 of fire into water, then earth ; the former is the reverse 
 process of vaporization (Id. p. 169). 
 
 This law or order is not dependent upon any divine 
 purposeful will, but all is ruled by an inherent neces- 
 sary " fate." The elemental fire carries within itself 
 the tendency toward change, and thus pursuing the 
 way down, it enters the " strife " and war of opposites 
 which condition the birth of the world (dtaxoofirjatc;), 
 and experience that hunger (yj>r t o ftoobw}) which arises 
 in a state where life is dependent upon nourishment, 
 and where satiety (xopoe) is only again found when, in 
 pursuit of the way up, opposites are annulled, and 
 "unity" and "peace" again emerge in the pure 
 original fire (ixTropwae^). This impulse of Nature 
 towards change is conceived now as "destiny," 
 "force," "necessity," "justice," or, when exhibited 
 
16 HERACLITUS. 
 
 in definite forms of time and matter, as "intelligence" 
 (Id. p. 182, 194 ff.). 
 
 The Heraclitic harmony of opposites, as of the bow 
 and the lyre, is a purely physical harmony. It is 
 simply the operation of the strife of opposite forces, by 
 which motion within an organism, at the point where 
 if further continued it would endanger the whole, is 
 balanced and caused to return within the limits of a 
 determined amplitude (Id. p. 230 ff.). 
 
 The identity of opposites means only that very dif- 
 ferent properties may unite in the same physical thing, 
 either by simultaneous comparison with different 
 things or successive comparison with a changeable 
 thing (Id. pp. 236, 243). 
 
 The second or political section of Heraclitus' work 
 treated of arts, ethics, society, and politics. It aimed 
 to show how human arts are imitations of Nature, and 
 how organized life, as in the universe and the indi- 
 vidual, so in the state, is the secret of unity in 
 variety. The central thought was the analogy existing 
 between man and the universe, between the microcosm 
 and the macrocosm, from which it results that the 
 true ethical principle lies in imitation of Nature, and 
 that law is founded on early customs which sprang 
 from Nature (Id. p. 310 ff.). 
 
 The third or theological section was mainly devoted to 
 showing that the names of things are designations of 
 their essence. That Heraclitus himself, not merely his 
 followers, held the (pvosi opdor/jQ ovofidztov, and used 
 etymologies as proofs of the nature of things, Schuster 
 believes is both consistent with his philosophy and 
 conclusively proved by Plato's Cratylus. Primitive 
 men named things from the language which Nature 
 spoke to them ; names, therefore, give us the truth of 
 
HISTORICAL AND CRITICAL. 17 
 
 things. Etymologies of the names of the gods was the 
 proof first brought forward, as in Plato's Cratylus ; 
 hence the name of this section of the work. To show 
 this connection of names and things was to prove the 
 intimate connection of man with Nature, and so to lead 
 to the conclusion that all knowledge is based on 
 experience, which, indeed, was the end he had in 
 view (Id. p. 317 ff.). 
 
 It is not our purpose to criticize in detail Schuster's 
 conception of Heraclitus. Much of it will commend 
 itself to the careful student of the remains, particu- 
 larly that which relates to the Heraclitic flux and its 
 relation to the primitive fire. Suggestive, also, if not 
 unimpeachable, is his conception of the relation of the 
 microcosm to the macrocosm, and of the harmony and 
 identity of opposites. In his exposition of these 
 doctrines, Schuster has rendered valuable service. 
 We can by no means, however, allow thus tentatively 
 to pass, Schuster's conception of Heraclitus as a purely 
 empirical philosopher. Before noticing this, a word 
 needs to be said in regard to Schuster's method as a 
 whole. As to the latter, the very extent of the task 
 proposed made over-systemization inevitable. In 
 criticism of Schuster's attempt, Zeller has well said 
 that with the extant material of Heraclitus' book, the 
 recovery of its plan is impossible (Vol. 1, p. 570, note). 
 Such a plan of reconstruction as that which Schuster 
 undertakes, demands the power not only to penetrate 
 the sense of every fragment, but also so to read the mind 
 of the author as to be able to restore that of the large 
 absent portions. The small number and enigmatical 
 character of the fragments which are extant, together 
 with the contradictory character of ancient testimony 
 to Heraclitus, makes such a task extremely hazardous. 
 
18 HERACLITUS. 
 
 It can be carried through only by the help of "unlim- 
 ited conjecture." Such conjecture Schuster has used 
 extensively. The necessity of carrying through his 
 plan has led him to find in some passages more mean- 
 ing than they will justly bear, while his apparently 
 preconceived notion as to the wholly empirical charac- 
 ter of the system has led him to distort the meaning 
 of many sentences. We shall see examples of this 
 presently. Incidentally, his method may be illustrated 
 by his connection and use of the two passages : 
 dvOpcoTiooq [isvec (Lnodavovzaz, cLaaa oux IhtovTai oudk doxeooac 
 (Clement of Alex. Strom, iv. 22, p. 630 ; cp. frag. 122), 
 and a! <fi^x ac oaptcovzac xad y adrjv (Plutarch, de Fac. in 
 orbe lun. 28, p. 943 ; cp. frag. 38). Schuster conjectures 
 that these passages came together in the original work, 
 and he renders and interprets them as follows : " There 
 awaits men in death what they neither hope nor 
 believe," namely, rest and the joy of a sleep-like con- 
 dition (!), so that even instinctively " souls scent out 
 death,"' desiring to obtain it (Schuster, p. 190). Not to 
 speak of the forced translation of the latter fragment, 
 only the most vivid imagination would think of using 
 these passages in this way, especially as Clement 
 himself, in his use of the first passage, refers it to the 
 punishments which happen to men after death (see 
 below, frags. 122 and 124, sources), and Plutarch, in 
 respect to the second, uses it as proof that souls in 
 Hades are nourished by vapors (see below, frag. 38, 
 sources). But Schuster's conception of Heraclitus did 
 not admit of belief in a distinct life after death, and it 
 was necessary to make these passages fit in with the 
 plan. The attempt to weave the fragments into a con- 
 nected whole, and their division into the three Logoi, 
 may be regarded on the whole as a decided failure. 
 
HISTORICAL AND CRITICAL. 19 
 
 Schuster finds only thirteen fragments for the con- 
 cluding theological section, although our knowledge 
 of Heraclitus and his times would rather indicate, as 
 indeed Teichmuller thinks probable, that the theo- 
 logical section was the principal portion of the book. 
 
 Turning now to the theory of knowledge, according 
 to Schuster, as we have seen, Heraclitus is an empiri- 
 cist and sensationalist and knows no world but the 
 visible. With this conclusion we cannot agree. Schus- 
 ter's argument that this doctrine must have arisen with 
 Heraclitus since it was held by Protagoras, his disciple, 
 has little weight. The order of development was rather 
 that pointed out by Plato himself in the Theaetetus 
 (p. 151 ff.), namely, that the sensational theory of 
 knowledge was the outcome of the Protagorean doc- 
 trine that man is the measure of all things, and that 
 this in turn grew out of the Heraclitic flux. No doubt 
 the sensational theory was implied by the Sophists, 
 but it was incipient with them and not yet formulated. 
 Much less can it be attributed to Heraclitus, whose 
 contribution to the theory began and ended with the 
 eternal flux. A sensational theory of knowledge, it is 
 quite true, was likely to be an outcome of the Ephe- 
 sian's philosophy, but he did not himself proceed thus 
 far. The question, theoretically considered, was be- 
 yond his time. There are passages which indicate 
 that he held, inconsistently it may be, quite the oppo- 
 site doctrine. " Eyes and ears," he says, "are bad 
 witnesses to men having rude souls" (Sextus Emp. 
 adv. Math. vii. 126 ;=:frag. 4 ; cp. frags. 3, 5, 6, 19, etc., 
 and below (p. 50). The passage which offers Schuster 
 the strongest support for his sensationalism is that 
 noted above (p. 13) from Hippolytus, "Whatever con- 
 cerns seeing, hearing and learning (jiddyeic, Schuster 
 
20 HERACLITUS. 
 
 translates " Erforschung "), I particularly honor" 
 (frag. 13). Adopting the simplest and most natural 
 meaning of this passage, it has no bearing on any 
 theory of knowledge, but means merely, as Pfleiderer 
 points out (Heraklit,p. 64, note), that Heraclitus prefers 
 the pleasures of the higher senses, as of seeing, hearing, 
 and the knowledge acquired thereby, to the sensual 
 pleasures of the lower senses which the masses pursue. 
 If, however, Schuster will take it in a theoretical 
 sense, then it comes into conflict with the other passage, 
 " The hidden harmony is better than the visible." The 
 contradiction is foreseen by Schuster, who deliberately 
 changes the latter into a question (see above, p. 13), 
 without a shadow of right, as may be seen by reference 
 to the context in Hippolytus (see below, frag. 47), who 
 expressly states that the two passages seem to conflict. 
 Further support for his interpretation Schuster seeks 
 in the following passage from Hippolytus : 
 
 Too 3k Xoyou rood' iovroq ahl a^uveroc yhovrae dvOpcorcot 
 xal npooOzv tj dxouaai xal dxohaavTZC, to npcoTOv. ytvofievcov 
 yap jrdvrcov xara top loyov Touda dneipococ ioixaai TZ&pmpzvm 
 xal inecov xal ipya)v toioutscov bxoiwv iycb dcTjyetjpa^ dcacpscov 
 ixdffTov xaTa (puacv xal (ppdZcov oxojq i%ec (Ref. haer. ix. 
 9 ; == frag. 2). 
 
 This is the passage of which Schuster says that if 
 Heraclitus had written nothing more it would have 
 given him a place of honor in philosophy, for here for 
 the first time appeared the thought that has inspired 
 speculation and modern science since the Renaissance, 
 that truth is to be sought in the observation of Nature. 
 But we are unable to find here any such meaning. 
 The sense of the passage depends upon the sense of 
 Logos. Of course, if Schuster is free to translate this 
 word in any way he chooses, he can get from the pas- 
 
HISTORICAL AXD CRITICAL. 21 
 
 sage almost any meaning. He chooses to render it 
 the Voice of Nature or the Speech of the visible world. 
 In this he is not supported by any other critics. By 
 ancient commentators of Heraclitus the Logos was 
 understood as Reason, and in this general sense it is 
 taken by modern commentators including Heinze, 
 Zeller, Teichmuller, and Pfleiderer, although more 
 specifically they see that, in harmony with the whole 
 Heraclitic philosophy, it is to be taken as Reason 
 immanent in the world as Order or Law. Schuster 
 objects that Logos could not mean Reason, since before 
 the time of Heraclitus it had never been so used, and 
 no author would venture to introduce at the very 
 beginning of his work words with new meanings. But 
 precisely the same objection applies to its meaning the 
 Speech of Nature, for the whole point in Schuster's 
 exposition is that this was an original idea with 
 Heraclitus. If the Logos is conceived as Order, this 
 objection is met, since this meaning is given in the 
 derivation of the word. Moreover, if Schuster could 
 show that the word meant " speech " or " discourse," 
 then the discourse referred to must have been not that 
 of Nature but of the author himself. Finally, if we 
 adopt Reason as the meaning of Logos here, the 
 whole passage, so far from supporting, directly refutes 
 Schuster's sensational theory of knowledge. Another 
 argument for the empiricism of Heraclitus, Schuster 
 seeks in his denunciation of the people for their failure 
 to interest themselves in acquiring knowledge by 
 empirical investigation of the things that surround 
 them, which he bases on a couple of passages from 
 Clement and M. Aurelius (see above, p. 12). Heraclitus, 
 in fact, said nothing of the kind; but Schuster, by 
 conjectural reconstruction of the text and an arbitrary 
 
22 HERACLITUS. 
 
 translation, extracts a theoretical meaning from simple 
 sentences which no one who had not a preconceived 
 theory to support would ever imagine to mean more 
 than a reproach upon the masses for their superficiality 
 and neglect of interest in a deeper knowledge of the 
 world (see Schuster, p. 17, and cp. frags. 5, 93). What 
 Heraclitus' theory of knowledge really was we shall 
 see more fully in the examination of Pfleiderer's posi- 
 tion later. Here it is sufficient to add that, whatever 
 empirical tendency his philosophy may have had, any 
 such positive doctrine as that which Schuster ascribes 
 to him was far beyond the time of Heraclitus. 
 
 Schuster's interpretation of the Heraclitic ip-qopLOGuvq 
 and xopoQ is also open to criticism. Zeller, indeed, has 
 given a similar explanation of these words (Vol. 1, p. 
 641), but Pfleiderer has understood them differently 
 (p. 176). From Heraclitus himself there remains only 
 the two above words (frag. 24). Hippolytus (Kef. haer. 
 ix. 10, cp. frag. 24, sources) says that the arrangement 
 of the world ((jtaxda/s/jcns'), Heraclitus called " crav- 
 ing" (xprjGfioouvfj), and the conflagration of the world 
 (ixnupwacc;) he called " satiety " (xopoq). Schuster, 
 therefore, understanding by dtaxbafrqact;, not the process 
 of world-building, that is, the passing of the homoge- 
 neous original fire into the manifold of divided exist- 
 ence, but the completed manifold world itself or the 
 xoapoz, interprets the " craving " or hunger as belong- 
 ing to the present differentiated world, which hungers, - 
 as it were, to get back into the state of original fire or 
 satiety. The testimony is too meagre to say that this 
 is not a possible interpretation, but it seems to be 
 wrong. For Schuster admits, as of course he must, 
 that the original fire carries within itself an impulse 
 to change and develop into a manifold world. But 
 
HISTORICAL AND CRITICAL. 23 
 
 this impulse to change is hardly consistent with a 
 state of perfect " satiety." If now Ave take dcaxoa^ac^ 
 in its primary signification denoting the action or pro- 
 cess of arranging, then craving becomes the designa- 
 tion of the world-building process itself. Craving then 
 is nothing but the original impulse to evolve itself, 
 contained in the primitive fire, while the reverse pro- 
 cess, the conflagration, is satiety, or better, the result 
 
 of satiety. 
 
 Teichmuller. 
 
 The work of Teichmuller (see above, p. 1) does not 
 profess to be a complete exposition of the philosophy 
 of Heraclitus, but to indicate rather the direction in 
 which the interpretation is to be found. Teichmuller 
 believes that the philosophy of the ancients is to be 
 interpreted by their theories of Nature. Physics came 
 before metaphysics. Particularly does this apply to 
 Heraclitus of Ephesus. His philosophy of Nature, 
 therefore, is the key with which Teichmuller will 
 unlock the secrets of his system (Teichmuller, I, p. 3). 
 
 But yet Heraclitus was not a naturalist. Of the 
 sun, moon, eclipses, seasons, or earth, he has little to 
 say. In the astronomy of Anaximander or the mathe- 
 matics of Pythagoras he took little interest. On such 
 polymathy he cast a slur(Diog. Laert. ix. 1; cp. frag. 16). 
 He went back to Thales and started from his childlike 
 conception of Nature. To Heraclitus the earth was 
 flat, extending with its land and sea indefinitely in 
 each direction. The sun, therefore, describes only a 
 semicircle, kindled every morning from the sea and 
 extinguished in it every evening. Moreover, the sun 
 is no larger than it looks (Diog. Laert. ix. 7). The 
 sun, therefore, cannot pass his boundaries (of the half- 
 circle), else the Erinyes (who inhabit the lower world) 
 
24 HERACLITUS. 
 
 will find him out (Plutarch, deExil. ii.p. 604; = frag. 29). 
 Up and down are not relative but absolute directions 
 (Teichmuller, I, p. 14). 
 
 Thus upon physical grounds we may interpret at 
 once some of the aphorisms. For instance, since the 
 sun is a daily exhalation from the earth, sun and earth 
 must have in part a common substance ; hence Diony- 
 sus and Hades are the same (Clement of Alex. Protrept. 
 ii. p. 30 ; cp. frag. 127), since the former stands for the 
 sun and the latter for the lower world. Likewise day 
 and night are the same (Hippolytus, Ref . haer. ix. 10 ; 
 cp. frag. 35), since they are essentially of the same 
 elements, the difference being only one of degree, the 
 former having a preponderance of the light and dry, 
 the latter of the dark and moist (Teichmuller, I, pp. 
 26, 56). 
 
 The four elements, fire, air, earth, and water, are not, 
 as with Empedocles, unchangeable elements, but in 
 ceaseless qualitative change are continually passing 
 into one another. Experience itself teaches this in 
 the daily observation of such phenomena as the drying 
 up of swamps, the melting of solids, and the evapo- 
 ration of liquids (Id. I, p. 58). 
 
 Fire is not a symbol, but is real fire that burns and 
 crackles. It is the ground principle, the entelechy of 
 the world, in which reside life, soul, reason. It is God 
 himself. It is absolute purity. It rules in the pure 
 upper air, the realm of the sun. Its antithesis is 
 moisture, absolute impurity, which rules in the lower 
 regions of the earth. The sun with his clear light 
 moves in the upper fiery air. The moon with her 
 dimmed light moves in the lower moister air. The 
 central thought, therefore, is purification, or "the 
 way up," from the moist and earthy to the dry and 
 fiery (Id. I, p. 62 ff.). 
 
HISTORICAL AND CRITICAL. 25 
 
 The psychology of Heraclitus is not analogous, but 
 identical with his physics. The soul is the pure, light, 
 fiery, incorporeal principle which burns like the sun. 
 Its degree of life and intelligence depends upon its 
 purity from moisture. The stupid drunken man has a 
 moist soul (Stobaeus Floril. v. 120 ; cp. frag. 73). " The 
 dry soul is the wisest and best " (frag. 71). In sleep the 
 fire principle burns low ; in death it is extinguished, 
 when the soul, like the sun at night, sinks into the 
 dark regions of Hades. Hence it follows that there 
 was with Heraclitus no doctrine of the immortality of 
 the soul (Teichmuller, I, p. 74 ff.). 
 
 Ethics, therefore, is purification, and in this thought 
 we see the origin of that general idea which as 
 1 ' Catharsis " became prominent in Plato and later 
 philosophy. Teichmuller finds it of the greatest 
 interest to have traced the history of this idea, with 
 its related one of "separation" or "apartness," back 
 to Heraclitus. "Of all whose words I have heard," 
 says the latter, " no one has attained to this — to know 
 that Wisdom is apart (xeycopcatievov) from all" (Sto- 
 baeus Floril. iii. 81 ; = frag. 18). This " separateness " 
 of "Wisdom, which was only another term for reason, 
 God or pure fire, reveals the origin of the distinction 
 of the immaterial from the material. With Hera- 
 clitus, to be sure, the idea of immateriality in its later 
 sense was not present, but fire as the most incorporeal 
 being of which he knew, identical with reason and 
 intelligence, was set over against the crude material 
 world. We have therefore here neither spiritualism 
 nor crude materialism, but the beginning of the dis- 
 tinction between the two. With Anaxagoras another 
 step was taken when fire was dropped and the Nous 
 was conceived in pure separateness apart even from 
 
26 HERACLITUS. 
 
 fire. Following Anaxagoras, Plato regarded the 
 Ideas as distinct and separate {elhxpwsq, xzy^ioptaphov). 
 In Aristotle it appears as the separation (icopcazov) 
 which belongs to absolute spirit or pure form. Finally 
 in the New Testament it is seen as the purity (elXrxpiveca) 
 which is opposed to the flesh (Paul, Epist. to Corinth. 
 II, i. 12; ii. 17). Human intelligence, according to 
 Heraclitus, attains only in the case of a few to this 
 greatest purity, this highest virtue, this most perfect 
 knowledge. They are the chosen ones, the elect 
 (hdexroi) (Teichmuller, I, p. 112 ff.). 
 
 The senses, since they partake of the earthy char- 
 acter of the body, give us only deceitful testimony as 
 compared with the pure light of Reason, which alone, 
 since it is of the essence of all things, that is, fire, has 
 the power to know all. Here therefore was the first 
 distinction of the intelligible from the sensible world 
 (Id. I, p. 97). 
 
 Again, in the qualitative change of Heraclitus we 
 discover the incipient idea of the actual and potential 
 first formulated by Aristotle. Since the elements pass 
 into one another, they must be in some sense the same. 
 Water is fire and fire is water. But since water is not 
 actually fire, it must be so potentially. To express 
 this idea, Heraclitus used such phrases as " self -con- 
 cealment," "sunset," "death," "sleep," "seed" (Id. 
 I, p. 92 ff.). 
 
 Moreover, inasmuch as we have a progress from the 
 potential to the actual, from the moist and earthy to 
 the dry and fiery, that is, from the worse to the better, 
 we find in Heraclitus the recognition of an end or 
 purpose in Nature, or a sort of teleology, subject, how- 
 ever, to the rule of rigid necessity (Id. I, p. 137). 
 
 The flux of all things Teichmuller understands not 
 
HISTORICAL AND CRITICAL. 27 
 
 as a metaphysical proposition, but as a physical truth 
 gained by generalization from direct observation of 
 Nature. Furthermore, it was nothing new, all the 
 philosophers from Thales on having taught the motion 
 of things between beginning and end (Id. I, p. 121). 
 
 That which was new in this part of Heraclitus' work 
 was his opposition to the transcendentalism of Xeno- 
 phanes. Over against the absolute, unmoved and 
 undivided unity of the Eleatic philosopher, Hera- 
 clitus placed the unity of opposition. In Xenophanes' 
 system, above all stood the immovable, transcendent 
 God. In Heraclitus' system there was nothing tran- 
 scendent or immovable, but all was pursuing the 
 endless way upward and downward. His God was 
 ceaselessly taking new forms. Gods become men, and 
 men gods (Heraclitus, Alleg. Horn. 24, p. 51, Mehler ; 
 cp. frag. 67). The immanent replaces the transcendent. 
 Here emerges the historically significant idea of unity. 
 Against the unity of Xenophanes, a unity opposed to 
 the manifold, Heraclitus grasped the idea of a unity 
 which includes the manifold within itself. "Unite 
 whole and part, agreement and disagreement, accor- 
 dant and disaccordant — from all comes one, and from 
 one all " (Arist. de mundo 5, p. 396, b. 12 ; =frag. 59). 
 Everywhere is war, but from the war of opposites re- 
 sults the most beautiful harmony (cp. frag. 46). Here 
 three principles are involved : 1). Through strife all 
 things arise ; the birth of water is the death of fire, the 
 death of water is the birth of earth, etc. (cp. frag. 68). 
 2). Through strife of opposites all things are preserved ; 
 take away one, the other falls ; sickness is conditioned 
 by health, hunger by satiety (cp. frag. 104). 3). There 
 is an alternating mastery of one or the other oppo- 
 site ; hence it follows that since all opposites proceed 
 
28 • HERACLITUS. 
 
 from one another, they are the same (Teichmuller, I, 
 
 p. 130 tr.). 
 
 What did Heraclitns mean by the visible and invis- 
 ible harmony ? Teichmuller censures Schuster for 
 failing to recognize that most significant side of Hera- 
 clitus' philosophy which is represented by the invisible 
 harmony — in other words, for reducing him to a mere 
 sensationalist. The visible harmony, according to 
 Teichmuller, is the entire sensible world, in which the 
 war of opposites results in a harmony of the whole. 
 But the invisible harmony is the divine, all-ruling and 
 all-producing Wisdom or World-reason, concealed 
 from the senses and the sense-loving masses and 
 revealed only to pure intellect. Thus Heraclitus, to 
 whom there was an intelligible world revealing itself 
 to intellect alone, and in the recognition of which was 
 the highest virtue, was the forerunner of Plato (Id. I, 
 pp. 154, 161 ff.). 
 
 By the Logos of Heraclitus was indicated Law, 
 Truth, Wisdom, Reason. It was more than blind law, 
 thinks Teichmuller, it was self-conscious intelligence ; 
 for self-consciousness, according to Heraclitus, who 
 praised the Delphic motto, "Know thyself," is the 
 highest activity of man, and how could he attribute 
 less to God, from whom man learns like a child ? (cp. 
 frag. 97). But this self-conscious reason is not to be 
 understood as a constant, ever abiding condition. 
 God, who in this purely pantheistic system is one with 
 the world, is himself subject to the eternal law of 
 ceaseless change, pursuing forever the downward and 
 upward way. But is not then God, Logos, Reason, 
 subject, after all, to some higher destiny {elfiapfiivrj) ? 
 No, says Teichmuller, for it is this very destiny which 
 it is the highest wisdom in man to recognize, and 
 
HISTORICAL AND CRITICAL. 29 
 
 which is. therefore, identical with the Wisdom which 
 rules all. The difficulty here he so far admits, how- 
 ever, as to acknowledge that this doctrine is " dark and 
 undetermined" (Id. I, p. 183 ff.). 
 
 Finally, says our author, there was no idea of per- 
 sonality of spirit in the philosophy of Heraclitus, as 
 there was not in any Greek philosopher from Xeno- 
 phanes to Plotinus (Id. I, 187). 
 
 In closing this part of his exposition, Teichmuller 
 calls attention to the relation of Heraclitus to Anax- 
 agoras. M. Heinze (Lehre vom Logos, p. 33), following 
 Aristotle, attributes to Anaxagoras the introduction 
 into philosophy of the idea of world-ruling intelligence. 
 But, says Teichmuller, this idea was present to 
 every Greek from Homer on. Its recognition by Hera- 
 clitus has been shown by the fact that everywhere 
 he attributes to his God, wisdom (aocp'td), intelligent 
 will (jvwfjaj), reason (cpopouv and (ppevype^, and recog- 
 nized truth (ioyoz). What then did Anaxagoras add ? 
 The history of the idea of transcendent reason turns 
 upon two characteristics, Identity (ra^ror^c) and Pure 
 Separation {eihxpevi<~). With Heraclitus both failed ; 
 the former, because the World Intelligence took part 
 in the universal change ; the latter, because it was 
 mingled with matter. For, in choosing fire for his 
 intelligent principle, although as Aristotle says he 
 chose that which was least corporeal (aacofmrcoraTov), 
 he did not escape a sort of materialism. The new that 
 Anaxagoras added, therefore, was the complete sepa- 
 ration of reason from materiality. In a word, while 
 the Logos of the Ephesian was at once world-soul and 
 matter in endless motion, the Nous of Anaxagoras was 
 motionless, passionless, soulless and immaterial. Iden- 
 tity, the other attribute, was added in the epoch- 
 
30 HEEACLITUS. 
 
 making work of Socrates when the content of reason 
 was determined by the definition, following whom 
 Plato established the complete transcendence of the 
 ideal world (Teichmuller, I, 189 fL). 
 
 Heraclitus assumed a world-year or world-period, 
 the beginning of which was the flood, and whose end 
 was to be a universal conflagration, the whole to be 
 periodically repeated forever. In this he was preceded 
 by Anaximander and followed by the Stoics. . This 
 general idea was adopted by the Christian Church, but 
 the latter limited the number of worlds to three, the 
 first ending with the flood ; ours, the second, to end with 
 the conflagration of the world ; the third to be eternal 
 (Epist. Pet. II, iii. 4 ff.; Clement of Rome, Epist. to 
 Corinth, i. 57, 58); (Teichmuller, I, 198 ff.). 
 
 In the second part of his work, Teichmuller enters 
 upon an exhaustive argument to show the dependence 
 of the Heraclitic philosophy upon Egyptian theology. 
 Heraclitus moved within the sphere of religious though t. 
 He praised the Sibyl and defended revelation and in- 
 spiration (Plutarch, de Pyth. orac. 6, p. 397 ; cp. frag. 
 12). His obscure and oracular style, like that of the 
 king at Delphi (cp. frag. 11), was in conformity with his 
 religious character. Observation of Nature he fully 
 neglected, depending for his sources more than any 
 other philosopher upon the beliefs of the older theo- 
 logy. Without deciding how far Heraclitus is directly, 
 as a student of the Book of Death, or indirectly by 
 connection with the Greek Mysteries, dependent upon 
 the religion of Egypt, he proceeds to indicate the 
 interesting points of similarity between them (Teich- 
 muller, II, p. 122). 
 
 Among the Egyptians the earth was flat and infi- 
 nitely extended. The visible world arose out of water. 
 
HISTORICAL AND CRITICAL. 31 
 
 The upper world belonged to fire and the sun. As the 
 sun of Heraclitus was daily generated from water, so 
 Hotub, as Ra of the sun, daily proceeded from Lotus 
 the water. As the elements with Heraclitus proceed 
 upward and downward, so the gods of the elements 
 upon the steps in Hermopolis climb up and down (Id. 
 II. p. 143). 
 
 With these illustrations, it is sufficient to say, with- 
 out following him further in detail, that Teichmuller 
 carries the comparison through the whole system of 
 Heraclitus, and parallels his actual and potential, his 
 unity of opposites, his eternal flux, strife, harmony, 
 purification, Logos, and periodicity of the world, with 
 similar notions found in the religion of Egypt. 
 
 In order to appreciate the worth of Teichmuller's 
 work, it is necessary to remember that, as we have said, 
 it does not profess to be a unified exposition of Hera- 
 clitus' philosophy, but a contribution to the history 
 of philosophic ideas in their relation to him. In afford- 
 ing this service to the history of ideas, he has thrown a 
 good deal of light upon the true interpretation of the 
 philosophy of Heraclitus. But the very purpose of his 
 task has caused him to put certain of the ideas into 
 such prominence, that unless we are on our guard, we 
 shall not get therefrom a well proportioned conception 
 of the system as a whole. We shall do well, conse- 
 quently, to make a short examination of the work out- 
 lined in the foregoing pages, to put the results, if we 
 can. into their fit relation to the whole. 
 
 Concerning Teichmuller's starting point, namely, 
 that the physics of Heraclitus is the key to his whole 
 thought, we must observe, in passing, the inconsist- 
 ency between the first part of Teichmuller's book, 
 
32 HERACLITUS. 
 
 where this principle is made the basis of interpretation, 
 and the second part, where it sinks into comparative 
 insignificance when he discovers that Heraclitus is 
 primarily a theologian and gets his ideas from Egyptian 
 religion. To say that we shall better appreciate a 
 philosopher's position if we understand his astronomy 
 and his theories of the earth and nature, is of course 
 true to every one. Moreover, that Heraclitus con- 
 sidered the earth as flat, the sun as moving in a semi- 
 circle and as no larger than it looks, the upper air as 
 drier than the lower, and the lower world as dark and 
 wet, there is no reason to deny. In fact, this cosmology, 
 as Teichmuller details it, is so simple and blends so 
 well with the Heraclitic sayings in general, that the 
 picture of' it once formed can hardly be banished from 
 the mind. But that it adds much to the explication 
 of the philosophy as a whole is doubtful. It is true 
 that physics came before metaphysics, if by that is 
 meant that men speculated about Nature before they 
 speculated about being. But this distinction has little 
 bearing on the interpretation of Heraclitus. . A prin- 
 ciple more to the point, and one that Teichmuller has 
 not always observed, is that religion, poetry and 
 metaphor came before either physics or metaphysics. 
 From the very fact, also, that physics came before 
 metaphysics, when the latter did come, men were 
 compelled to express its truths in such physical terms 
 as they were in possession of. He therefore who will 
 see in the sentences of Heraclitus nothing beyond their 
 physical and literal meaning, will miss the best part of 
 his philosophy. For instance, Teichmuller interprets 
 the saying that day and night are the same, as meaning 
 that they are made up of the same physical constitu- 
 ents (see above, p. 24). If possible, this is worse than 
 
HISTORICAL AND CRITICAL. 33 
 
 Schuster's explanation that they are the same because 
 they are each similar divisions of time(!), an explana- 
 tion which Teichmuller very well ridicules (Id. I, p. 49). 
 Xo such childish interpretations of this passage are 
 necessary when it is seen that this is simply another 
 antithesis to express Heraclitus' great thought of the 
 unity of opposites, on the ground that by the universal 
 law of change, opposites are forever passing into each 
 other, as indeed is said in so many words in a passage 
 from Plutarch which these critics seem to have 
 slighted (Consol. ad Apoll. 10, p. 106; see frag. 78). 
 Equally unnecessary and arbitrary is Teichmuller's 
 singular attempt to prove on physical grounds the 
 identity of the two gods, Dionysus and Hades (see 
 above, p. 21). 
 
 In pursuance of his method, Teichmuller supposes 
 that the Heraclitic fire was real fire such as our senses 
 perceive, fire that burns and crackles and feels warm. 
 Xo other critic agrees with him in this. Zeller espec- 
 ially opposes this conception (Vol. I, p. 588). It is not 
 to be supposed that Teichmuller understands . Hera- 
 clitus to mean that the present world and all its 
 phenomena are real fire. Fire he conceives to be, 
 rather, the first principle or dpffl, the real essence of 
 the universe, chosen as water was by Thales or air by 
 Anaximenes, only with more deliberation, since fire 
 has the peculiarity of taking to itself nourishment. In 
 a word, since anybody can see that our present earth, 
 water, and air, are not fire that burns and crackles, 
 all that Teichmuller can mean is that this kind of fire 
 was the original thing out of which the present world 
 was made. But there is not the least support for this 
 meaning in any saying of Heraclitus. In all the sen- 
 tences, fire is conceived as something of the present, 
 
34 HERACLITUS. 
 
 something directly involved in the ceaseless change of 
 the world. "Fire, (i. e., xepauvos, the thunderbolt)," 
 he says, "rules all" (Hippolytus, Ref. haer. ix. 10; 
 = frag. 28). "This world, the same for all, neither 
 any of the gods nor any man has made, but it always 
 was, and is, and shall be, an ever living fire " (Clement 
 of Alex. Strom, v. 14, p. 711; =frag. 20). "Fire is 
 exchanged for all things and all things for fire " 
 (Plutarch, de EI. 8, p. 388 ; =frag. 22). These passages 
 are sufficient to show that Teichmuller 's conception of 
 the fire is untenable. We may, however, mention the 
 fact noted by Zeller (Yol. I, p. 588), that both Aristotle 
 (de An. i. 2, 405, a, 25) and Simplicius (Phys. 8, a) 
 explain that Heraclitus chose to call the world fire 
 " in order to express the absolute life of Nature, and to 
 make the restless change of phenomena comprehen- 
 sible." 
 
 Another point that demands criticism is the idea of 
 actuality and potentiality which Teichmuller finds 
 hidden in Heraclitus' philosophy and metaphorically 
 expressed by sunset, death, sleep, etc. Since there is 
 a qualitative interchange of the elements, they must 
 be in some sense the same. Water is fire and fire is 
 water. But since water is not actually fire, it must be 
 so potentially. Therefore, water is potential fire. 
 Such is Teichmuller' s reasoning, as we have seen. Of 
 course, it can be reversed with equal right. Since fire 
 is not actually water, it must be so potentially. There- 
 fore, fire is potential water. Which is to say that we 
 have here a simple reversible series in which there is 
 not only an eternal progress (or regress) from fire to 
 water, but equally, and under the same conditions, an 
 eternal regress (or progress) from water to fire. 
 Either, therefore, may, with as good right as the other, 
 
HISTORICAL AND CRITICAL. 35 
 
 represent actuality or potentiality. In other words, 
 actuality and potentiality are superfluous ideas in this 
 system. In fact, this antithesis has no place in meta- 
 physics outside the philosophy of Aristotle, and he 
 who has failed to see that right in this connection lies 
 the main difference between the philosophy of Aris- 
 totle and that of Heraclitus, has missed the most vital 
 part of the latter. With Aristotle there is an eternal 
 progress but no regress. The potential is ever passing 
 into the actual, but not the reverse. To be sure, a 
 thing may be both actual and potential, but not as 
 regards the same thing. The hewn marble is potential 
 as regards the statue and actual as regards the rough 
 marble, but of course the hewn marble and the statue 
 cannot be reciprocally potential or actual. Matter is 
 eternally becoming form, but not the reverse. Thus 
 follows Aristotle's necessary assumption of a prime 
 mover, an inexhaustible source of motion, itself un- 
 moved — pure actuality, without potentiality. Hence 
 the mainspring of the peripatetic philosophy is the 
 unmoved moving first cause. But the philosophy of 
 the Ephesian is the reverse of all this. With him 
 there is no fixed being whatever (see Teichmuller him- 
 self, I, p. 121 : " Es bleibt dabei nichts Festes zuriick," 
 etc.), no unmoved first cause outside the shifting 
 world which is its own God and prune mover. Thus 
 Teichmuller, in identifying the Heraclitic fire with the 
 Aristotelian pure actuality, overlooked the slight differ- 
 ence that while the one is absolute motion, the other is 
 absolute rest ! We are glad, however, not to find this 
 Aristotelian notion, which, though prevalent in meta- 
 has never added a ray of light to the subject, 
 present in the philosophy of the Ephesian, and we see 
 here another case of over-interpretation by which 
 
36 HERACLITUS. 
 
 Heraclitus' innocent use of such terms as sunset, death, 
 and self -concealment, caused Aristotelian metaphysics 
 to be forced upon him. 
 
 In tracing the history of ideas, much emphasis has 
 been laid by Teichmuller, as we have seen, upon the 
 idea of purification (xdOapaco) as it appears in Hera- 
 clitus, and in connection therewith he has found the 
 beginning of the idea of the " apartness " or " separa- 
 tion " of the immaterial world, an idea so enormously 
 enlarged by Anaxagoras and Plato. As regards the 
 Catharsis proper, Teichmuller has rendered a service 
 by pointing out Heraclitus' connection with the idea ; 
 but in reading Teichmuller 's book, one would be easily 
 led to believe that the Catharsis idea is much more 
 prominent in Heraclitus than it really is, and as 
 regards the doctrine of " separation," it seems at once 
 so incongruous with the system as a whole that we 
 must inquire what foundation, if any, there is for it. 
 The student of Heraclitus knows, although the reader 
 of Teichmuller might not suspect, that the words 
 xddapaes, xaOapos, elhxpcviq^ sihxplveta, %copc<7Tov, ycopiadev^ 
 ixXexzoi, themselves do not occur in the authentic remains 
 of his writings. One exception is to be noted. The word 
 xtyoiptopkvov occurs in the passage from Stobaeus 
 already noticed (see above, p. 25). It is as follows : 
 ^Oxoocov Xoyooz yjxouaa oudees dipcxvierac ec touto, ware 
 jcvdxjxzcv ort oo<pov eart Tzdvrcov xey^coptapevov (Stobaeus 
 Floril. iii. 81). This passage Teichmuller uses as his 
 text in establishing the connection of Heraclitus with 
 the doctrine of " separation," unfortunately, however, 
 first because he has not found the correct interpreta- 
 tion of it, and second, because, if he had, it would 
 stand in direct contradiction to the doctrine of imma- 
 nence which he spends all the next chapter in estab- 
 
HISTORICAL AND CRITICAL. 37 
 
 lisliing for Heraelitus. locov in this passage does not 
 stand for the world-ruling Wisdom or Reason, or 
 Divine Law. of which Heraelitus has so much to say 
 in other passages. To assert the " apartness " of that 
 Law would he to disintegrate the entire system, the 
 chief point of which is the immanence of the Divine 
 Law as the element of order in the shifting world. It 
 does not follow that because to oo^bv is used in the 
 above larger sense in the passage from Clement of 
 Alexandria (Strom, v. 11, p. 718 ; =frag. 65), that oocov 
 cannot be used in quite the ordinary sense in the 
 present passage. That it is so is attested by the 
 agreement of Schuster (p. -12), Heinze (Lehre vom 
 Logos, p. 32), Zeller (Vol. I, p. 572, 1), and Pfleiderer 
 (p. 60). Lassalle, indeed, agrees with Teichmtiller. 
 Schuster, following Heinze, understands the sentence 
 to mean merely that wisdom is separated from all 
 (men), that is, true wisdom is possessed by no one. 
 Zeller, followed by Pfleiderer, renders it : " ISTo one 
 attains to this — to understand that wisdom is separated 
 from all things, that is, has to go its own way inde- 
 pendent of general opinion." Schuster's interpretation 
 is the most natural, so that the fragment belongs 
 among the many denunciations of the ignorance of the 
 common people — as indeed By water places it — and has 
 nothing to do with any theory of the " separateness " 
 of an absolute or immaterial principle. Neither is 
 there any other passage which supports this doctrine. 
 In further support, however, of the Catharsis theory in 
 general, Teichmuller alleges the passage from Plutarch 
 (Vit. Rom. 28), which speaks of the future purification 
 of the soul from all bodily and earthy elements, and 
 which Teichmuller thinks to have a strong Heraclitic 
 coloring. In this passage Heraelitus is quoted as 
 
38 HERACLITTTS. 
 
 saying that "the dry soul is the best," but beyond 
 this fragment it is a mere conjecture that it was taken 
 from him. The passage at any rate is unimportant. 
 What then remains to establish any connection what- 
 ever of Heraclitus with the "history of the idea of the 
 dfoxptv£s ,, Y Only the most general antithesis of fir< 
 and moisture, with the added notion that the former li- 
 the better and the latter worse. Since the divine 
 essence of the universe itself is fire, the way upwarc 
 from earth and water to fire is the diviner process, anc 
 pure fire is the noblest and highest existence. But this 
 is shown better in the ethical sphere. The soul itseh 
 is the fiery principle (Arist. de An. i. 2, p. 405, a, 25) 
 " The dry soul is the wisest and best" (frag. 74). Th( 
 soul of the drunken, stupid man is moist (cp. frag. 73), 
 The highest good was to Heraclitus the clearesl 
 perception, and the clearest and most perfect percep- 
 tion was the perception of the Universal Law of 
 Nature, the expression of which was pure fire ; an< 
 such perception was coincident with that condition of 
 the soul when it was most like the essence of the uni- 
 verse. This is the sum-total of the idea of the Catharsis 
 found in Heraclitus. It is worthy of notice, to be sure, 
 but it is not so different from what might be found in 
 any philosophy, especially an ethical philosophy, as to 
 make it of any great moment, either in the history of 
 ideas or in the exposition of this system. 
 
 We have studied now those parts of Teichmuller's 
 work which, either by reason of their incompleteness 
 or manifest error, most needed examination, namely 
 his method, his wrong conception of the Heraclitic 
 fire, his useless and unfounded theory of the actual 
 and potential and of the separateness of the imma- 
 terial, and his over-emphasized doctrine of the Cathar- 
 
HISTORICAL AND CRITICAL. 39 
 
 sis. Concerning* the other points, it is only necessary 
 in addition to call attention to the extreme value of 
 his contribution in his explanations of the relation of 
 Heraclitus to Xenophanes, to Anaxagoras and to Plato, 
 of the Heraclitic Logos, of the flux, of the unity of 
 opposites. and of the invisible harmony and the intelli- 
 gible world defended against the sensationalism of 
 Schuster. In the second part of his work also, though 
 its value is less, he has contributed not a little light 
 by his emphasis of the theological character of this 
 philosophy, though one doubts whether his laborious 
 collection of resemblances between the philosophy of 
 the Ephesian and the religion of Egypt has shed much 
 light on Heraclitus' position. It is seen at once that by 
 taking such general conceptions as war and harmony, 
 purification, periodicity of the world, etc., it would be 
 easy to make a long list of parallelisms between any 
 religion and any system of philosophy not separated 
 farther in time and place than Heraclitus of Ephesus 
 and the Egyptians. The resemblances, however, are 
 certainly not all accidental, but they are such as do 
 not affect the originality of the Ephesian, and unfor- 
 tunately do not add much to a better knowledge of 
 
 his philosophy. 
 
 Pfleiderer. 
 
 Dr. Edmund Pfleiderer comes forward in a recent 
 volume of 380 pages (see above, p. 1), with an attempt 
 to interpret the philosophy of Heraclitus from a new 
 and independent standpoint. He expresses dissatisfac- 
 tion with all previous results. Other critics have made 
 the mistake of starting not from the positive but from 
 the negative side, namely, from the universal flux (as 
 Zeller;, or from the law of opposites (as Lassalle). 
 But the hatred of the opinions of the masses which 
 
40 HERACLITUS. 
 
 Heraclitus exhibits, calls for some greater philosophical 
 departure than the above negative principles, which 
 indeed were already well known truths. Moreover, 
 if we take these for his starting point, we can get no 
 consistent system, for the doctrine of the universal 
 flux does not lead naturally to the law of opposites, but 
 rather the reverse. Again, neither the flux nor the 
 law of opposites harmonizes with the doctrine of fire. 
 Finally, the pessimistic, nihilistic tendency of the theory 
 of absolute change does not agree well with the deep 
 rationality and world-order which Heraclitus recog- 
 nizes in all things, nor with his psychology, eschat- 
 ology, and ethics (Pfleiderer, p. 7 ff.). 
 
 We must look elsewhere for his ground principle. 
 To find it, we must discover the genesis of this philoso- 
 phy, which did not spring into being spontaneously, 
 like Pallas Athena from the head of her father. It 
 could not have come from the Eleatics, for the chro- 
 nology forbids, nor from Pythagoras, whom Heraclitus 
 reviles, nor finally from the physicists of Miletus, with 
 whose astronomy Teichmuller has well shown our 
 philosopher to be unacquainted. Its source is rather to 
 be sought in the field of religion, and particularly in 
 the Greek Mysteries. In the light of the Orphico- 
 Dionysiac Mysteries, in a word, according to Pfleid- 
 erer, this philosophy is to be interpreted. Here is the 
 long-sought key. The mystic holds it, as indeed Dio- 
 genes Laertius says : 
 
 My rayhq ^HpayJetvoo ir? dfMpaXbv el'Aes fttftkov 
 ToiHpeaiou ' pala rot oua^aroc, drpaTccroq. 
 
 dp<pV7] Xal (TXOTOZ icTTCV dAa/JLTTSTOV ' 7JV Si GE fjJjGTTjC, 
 
 eioaydj'fa (pavepou lapTipozep ijelioo. — ix. 16. 
 
 With the religion of the Mysteries, in its older and 
 purer form, Heraclitus was in full sympathy. By his 
 
HISTORICAL AND CRITICAL. 41 
 
 family he was brought into close connection with it. 
 Ephesus, too, his city, was a religious centre. Dio- 
 genes (ix. 6) relates that he deposited his book in the 
 temple of Artemis. Heraclitus, indeed, was not a 
 friend of the popular religion, but that was because of 
 its abuses, and it was in particular the popular Olym- 
 pian religion that he attacked. The connection of the 
 Ephesian with the Mysteries may be considered as a 
 deep-seated influence which their underlying princi- 
 ples exerted upon him. These religious principles he 
 turned into metaphysics. His system as a whole was 
 religious and metaphysical (Pfleiderer, p. 32 f.). 
 
 With this introduction, Pfleiderer proceeds as fol- 
 lows. Heraclitus' starting point lay positively in his 
 theory of knowledge, which was a doctrine of specu- 
 lative intuition and self -absorption. In this sense our 
 author understands the fragment from Plutarch (adv. 
 Colot. 20, p. 1118 ; = frag. 80), 'Edefyedpyv ifiewurou, " I 
 searched within myself,'' that is, I wrapped myself in 
 thought, and so in this self -absorption I sought the 
 kernel of all truth. Hence his contempt for the masses 
 who act and speak without insight. But does not this 
 conflict with those Heraclitic sentences which place 
 the standard of truth and "action in the common or 
 universal (£wv6v) ? (cp. frags. 92, 91). Do these not lead 
 as Schuster holds, to the rule, Verum est, quod semper, 
 quod ubique, quod ab omnibus creditum est? No, 
 says Pfleiderer, the common here does not mean the 
 general opinion of the majority. All such interpret- 
 ations are sufficiently refuted by that other passage, 
 " To me, one is ten thousand if he be the best " (frag. 
 113). What Heraclitus really meant by the common 
 (£uvov) was "the true inward universality." Absorp- 
 tion into one's inner self was absorption into that 
 
42 HERACLITUS. 
 
 ground of reason which is identical with the divine 
 principle of the world. By this universal reason under 
 which he contemplated all things, Heraclitus meant 
 nothing different from what by Spinoza was expressed 
 by "sub specie aeternitatis," and in subsequent phi- 
 losophy by "intellectual intuition" and "the stand- 
 point of universal knowledge." Heraclitus fell back 
 upon that universal instinct which in the form of 
 human language is exhibited as the deposit of succes- 
 sive ages, and which again he did not distinguish 
 from the voice of the Sibyl, representative of divine 
 revelation. As respects the source of knowledge, 
 Heraclitus as little as Spinoza, Fichte and Hegel, 
 looked to himself as individual, but rather to that 
 singular and qualitative divine source in which the 
 individual participates (Pfleiderer, p. 46 ff.). 
 
 The senses, though they do not give us the whole 
 truth, yet furnish the sufficient data that are to be 
 interpreted by the light of reason. The errors of the 
 masses do not arise from trusting the senses, for the 
 latter give not a false, but a partial account. Their 
 error lies in missing the spiritual band which unites 
 the manifold of sense into the higher unity, an error 
 distinctive of the popular polytheism as against the 
 religion of the Mysteries (Id. p. 70). 
 
 The theory of knowledge, Heraclitus' starting point, 
 being thus disposed of, Pfleiderer proceeds to discuss 
 the material principles of his philosophy in their 
 abstract metaphysical form. The keynote here is the 
 indestructibility of life. The oscillating identity of 
 life and death, a truth adopted from the Mysteries, is 
 taken up by Heraclitus and elevated into a universal 
 and metaphysical principle. It is based on the simple 
 observation of Nature, which sees the life and light 
 
HISTORICAL AND CRITICAL. 43 
 
 and warmth of summer passing into the death and 
 darkness and cold of winter, only to be revived and 
 restored in the never-failing spring. So on a smaller 
 scale, day passes into night, but night ever again into 
 day. So everywhere in Nature nothing passes away 
 but to revive again. From this follows the hope of 
 the universality of this law, the indestructibility of 
 human life, and the resolution of the opposition be- 
 tween the light, warm life here above and the dark, 
 cold death below. This is the hopeful element which 
 characterizes the philosophy of the Ephesian. Over 
 against it was the hopeless creed of the masses, whose 
 complaint over the inexorable destiny of death found 
 expression from the earliest times in the despairing 
 lines of the poets. The common view does not see too 
 much continuance and constancy in reality, but too 
 little. ''What we see waking," says Heraclitus, " is 
 death, what we see sleeping is a dream" (Clement of 
 Alex. iii. 3, p. 520 ; =frag. 64). Which means, that like 
 the unreality and inconstancy of dreams is this ephem- 
 eral and perishing existence which we, the vulgar 
 people, see when awake. Reversing this gloomy view, 
 the Mysteries taught that Hades and Dionysus were 
 the same (cp. frag. 127). That is, the god of death 
 feared in the world below, is identical with the god of 
 life and joy of the world here above, which is to say 
 that the regenerative power of life persists even in 
 death and shall overcome it (Pfleiderer, p. 74 ff.). 
 
 From this theory of the indestructibility of the fire 
 force of life, Heraclitus passes to the ancillary truth of 
 the unity of opposition in general. Hence he asserted 
 the identity of day and night, winter and summer, 
 young and old, sleeping and waking, hunger and 
 satiety (cp. frags. 36, 78). His whole theory of the 
 
44 HERACLITUS. 
 
 harmony of opposites was, as it were, apologetic. If 
 life rules in death, why does death exist ? It was in 
 answer to this question that Heraclitus developed his 
 science of opposition and strife, by showing the pres- 
 ence here of a general law (Pfleiderer, p. 84 ff.). 
 
 In the same spirit Pfleiderer interprets the,, much 
 contested figure of the harmony of the world as the 
 harmony of the bow and the lyre (see frags. 45, 56). 
 Without rejecting the interpretation suggested by 
 Bernays (Rhein. Mus. vii. p. 94) and followed by most 
 other critics, which refers the figure to the form of 
 the bow and of the lyre, their opposite stretching arms 
 producing harmony by tension, Pfleiderer finds in the 
 comparison still another meaning. The bow and the 
 lyre are both attributes of Apollo, the slayer and the 
 giver of life and joy. Thus the harmony between the 
 bow and the lyre, as attributes of one god — symbols 
 respectively of death and of life and joy — expresses the 
 great thought of the harmony and reciprocal inter- 
 change of death and life (Pfleiderer, p. 89 ff.). 
 
 The Heraclitic flux of all things, says Pfleiderer, was 
 not antecedent to his abstract teachings, but the logi- 
 cal consequence thereof. The identity of life and 
 death led him to the identity of all opposites. But 
 opposites are endlessly flowing or passing into each 
 other. Hence from the principle that everything is 
 opposition, follows the principle that everything flows. 
 The universal flux is only a picture to make his relig- 
 ious metaphysical sentences intelligible (Id. p. 100 ff.). 
 
 The Heraclitic fire is real fire as opposed to the 
 logical symbol of Lassalle, but not the strictly sensible 
 fire that burns and crackles, as Teichmuller supposes. 
 It is rather a less definite conception, which is taken 
 now as fire, now as warmth, warm air or vapor. It is 
 
HISTORICAL AND CRITICAL. 45 
 
 the concrete form or intuitional correlate of the meta- 
 physical notion of life (Id. p. 120 ff.). 
 
 " The way up and down" refers not only to the trans- 
 mutations of fire, water, and earth, but holds good in 
 general for the oscillation of opposites, and particularly 
 for the polarity of life and death (Id. p. 140). 
 
 As one result of his investigation, Pfleiderer affirms 
 a strong optimistic element in the philosophy of the 
 Ephesian. He contests the opinion of Schuster and 
 Zeller that the endless destruction of single existences 
 is kindred to the pessimistic doctrine of Anaximander, 
 of the extinction of all individuals as an atonement 
 for the " injustice " of individual existence. The pro- 
 cess indeed goes on, but it has a bright side, and it is 
 this that Heraclitus sees. Life, to be sure, is ever pass- 
 ing into death, but out of death life ever emerges. It 
 is this thought, the powerlessness of death over the 
 indestructible fire force of life, which Heraclitus em- 
 phasizes (Id. p. 180 ff.). 
 
 Still more decided is his rational optimism, his un- 
 swerving belief in a world well ordered and disposed. 
 A deep rationality characterizes the universe (cp. frags. 
 2, 1, 91, 92, 98, 99, 96, 19). To express this idea, Hera- 
 clitus used the word Logos, which after his time played 
 so prominent a part in the older philosophy. This 
 word, passing even beyond its signification of " well 
 ordered relation," conveyed finally with Heraclitus, 
 as /<>)'<>; £uvbc, rather the idea of Reason immanent in 
 the world (Pfleiderer, p. 231 ff.). 
 
 In the invisible harmony we find the same general 
 thought. As distinguished from the visible harmony, 
 which meant that external order of Nature insuring to 
 the trustful peasant the never failing return of summer 
 and winter, heat and frost, day and night,— the invisi- 
 
46 HERACLITUS. 
 
 ble harmony was that all-embracing harmony which 
 is revealed to thought as the rational union of all 
 oppositions. Against this theodicy there is no valid 
 objection to be derived from the accounts which repre- 
 sent the Ephesian philosopher as sad and complain- 
 ing, nor from the passages descriptive of the evils 
 of life and the weakness of men (cp. frags. 86, 55, 112, 
 etc.). In all cases these refer not to the philosopher's 
 own opinions, but to the errors of the ignorant masses 
 (Pfleiderer, p. 235 ff.). 
 
 The future existence of the soul, though not consis- 
 tent with his physics and metaphysics, was neverthe- 
 less held from the religious and ethical standpoint. In 
 fact it was involved, as has been shown, in Heraclitus' 
 point of departure, so that we have less reason to com- 
 plain of inconsistency in his case than we have, in 
 reference to the same matter, in the case of the Stoics 
 later (Id. p. 210). 
 
 We have given, perhaps, more space to the exposi- 
 tion of Pfleiderer' s work than it relatively deserves, 
 because it is the last word that has been spoken on 
 Heraclitus, because, also, it has deservedly brought 
 into prominence the optimism and the religious char- 
 acter of his philosophy, and because finally it presents 
 another instructive example of over-systemization. It 
 claims our attention, too, because the view it proposes 
 is a complete reversal of the prevalent conception of 
 Heraclitus, and if seriously taken, changes the whole 
 tenor of his philosophy. 
 
 In what follows we shall examine chiefly the two 
 main points in Pfleiderer' s work, namely, the theory 
 of knowledge and the connection with the Greek 
 Mysteries ; the latter, because it is Pfleiderer's particu- 
 
HISTORICAL £ND CRITICAL. 47 
 
 lar contribution, and the former, because it will open 
 to us an important aspect of the Ephesian's philosophy. 
 In the first place, however, it can by no means be 
 admitted that the doctrine of the flux and the harmony 
 of opposites represent the negative side of his system, 
 and are secondary to his theory of knowledge and 
 his religious dogmas. The unanimous testimony of 
 the ancients cannot be thus easily set aside. That of 
 Plato and Aristotle alone is decisive. Pfleiderer objects 
 that Plato's purpose, which was to establish the 
 changelessness of noumena against the change of 
 phenomena, led him to emphasize the flux of Hera- 
 clitus. But if Heraclitus' positive teachings were, as 
 Pfleiderer says, first of all the theory of knowledge, 
 this and not the flux must have been emphasized in the 
 Theaetetus where the theory of knowledge was Plato's 
 theme. It is sufficient, however, here to note that 
 what Heraclitus has stood for in philosophy from his 
 own time to the present, is the doctrine of absolute 
 change, and this doctrine may, therefore, properly be 
 called the positive side of his philosophy. If what 
 Pfleiderer means is that the theory of knowledge and 
 not the flux was his starting point, he would have a 
 shadow more of right. It is, however, misleading to 
 say that his theory of knowledge was his starting- 
 point, for, as we have indicated in our examination of 
 Schuster's work, Heraclitus was not concerned with a 
 theory of knowledge as such. To state in a word what 
 his point of departure really was, regarded from a 
 common-sense view, it was his conviction that he was 
 in possession of new truth which the blindness and 
 ignorance of men prevented them from seeing (the 
 point of departure indeed of almost every one who 
 writes a book), and the three leading ideas in this 
 
48 heraClitus. 
 
 new truth were : 1. the absence of that stability in 
 Nature which the untrained senses perceive ; 2. the 
 unsuspected presence of a universal law of order ; 3. 
 the law of strife which brings unity out of diversity. 
 In one sense this may be called a theory of knowledge, 
 and only in this sense was it his starting point. 
 
 But concerning the theory of knowledge itself, we 
 cannot accept Pfleiderer's position. By placing it in 
 speculative intuition and self -absorption, he has rushed 
 to the very opposite extreme of Schuster's sensation- 
 alism, and in so doing has equally misrepresented 
 Heraclitus. Either extreme is forcing a modern theory 
 of knowledge upon the Ephesian of which he was 
 wholly innocent. What support has Pfleiderer for 
 his "self -absorption" theory ? None whatever. He 
 alleges the fragment ' Ed^yadfiyv ijueworou (cp. frag. 80), 
 which he arbitrarily renders, "I searched within 
 myself" (" Ich forschte in mir selbst"). This frag- 
 ment is from Plutarch (adv. Colot. 20, p. 1118), Diog- 
 enes Laertius (ix. 5 ; cp. frag. 80, sources), and others. 
 Plutarch understands it to refer simply to self-knowl- 
 edge like the rvwdi aauxbv at Delphi (similarly Julian, 
 Or. vi. p. 185 A). Diogenes understands it as referring 
 to self -instruction (similarly Tatian, Or. ad Graec. 3). 
 Diogenes says, " He (Heraclitus) was a pupil of no one, 
 but he said that he inquired, for himself and learned all 
 things by himself" (rjxooas r oL^evoc, dAX aurbv scpy 
 oc^rjaaadac xac fmOelv rcd^ra Ttap koorou). The latter 
 seems to be its true meaning, as is seen by comparing 
 the passage from Polybius (xii. 27; cp. frag. 15), " The 
 eyes are better witnesses than the ears." As here he 
 means to say that men should see for themselves and 
 not trust to the reports of others, so in the fragment in 
 question he means only that he himself has inquired of 
 
HISTORICAL AND CRITICAL. 49 
 
 himself and not of others (cp. also frags. 14, 13). But 
 Pfleiderer, in order to support a theory, has taken 
 these two innocent words and pressed them into a doc- 
 trine of contemplative intuition, by giving them the 
 meaning, " I wrapped myself in thought " (" Ich ver- 
 senkte mich sinnend und forschend," etc., p. 47). So 
 far is it from the case that Heraclitus sought the 
 source of knowledge by turning inward, that he ex- 
 pressed himself directly to the contrary. Thus we read 
 in Plutarch (de Superst. 3, p. 166; = f rag. 95): b'hlpd- 
 y./.ZiZiK cr t ac f zolz Irprrropbotu c\a /.at xoevbv xoofiov zlvac, rwv 
 os xoeftwfiivtov exaarov etc idtov d-oazpiipeadacy the sense of 
 which is well given by Campbell (Theaetetus of Plato, 
 p. 246), " To li^e in the light of the universal Order is 
 to be awake, to turn aside into our own microcosm is 
 to go to sleep.'' Again, the whole passage from Sextus 
 Empiricus (adv. Math. vii. 132, 133 ; cp. frags. 92, 2) 
 is conclusive. "For," says Sextus, "having thus 
 statedly shown that we do and think everything by 
 participation in the divine reason, he [Heraclitus] 
 adds. * It is necessary therefore to follow the* com- 
 mon, for although the Law of Reason is common, the 
 majority of people live as though they had an under- 
 standing of their own.' But this is nothing else than 
 an explanation of the mode of the universal disposition 
 of things. As far therefore as we participate in the 
 memory of this, we are true, but as far as ive separate 
 ourselves individually we are false. A more express 
 denial of any self-absorption or a priori theory of 
 knowledge would be impossible. Heraclitus is con- 
 stantly urging men to come out of themselves and 
 place themselves in an attitude of receptivity to that 
 which surrounds them, and not go about as if self- 
 included (cp. frags. 94, 3, 2). But what does Hera- 
 
50 HERACLITUS. 
 
 clitus mean by participation in the divine or universal 
 Reason ? Is not this just Pfleiderer's position when 
 he says that the Ephesian as little as Fichte or Hegel 
 looked to himself as individual, but rather to that abso- 
 lute reason in which the individual participates ? The 
 difference is radical and vital, but Pfleiderer, like 
 Lassalle, failed to see it because he did not free himself 
 from strictly modern theories of knowledge. The dif- 
 ference is simply this. The universal reason of which 
 Pneiderer is speaking is that in which man necessarily 
 and by his intellectual nature participates. That of 
 Heraclitus is the divine Reason, in which man ought 
 to participate but may not. Pfleiderer's universal 
 reason is universal in man. That of Heraclitus, out- 
 side of and independent of man. The latter, so far 
 from being necessarily involved in thought, is inde- 
 pendent of thought. It is that pure, fiery and godlike 
 essence, the apprehension of which gives rationality in 
 the measure in which it is possessed. No reader, 
 therefore, who can think of only two theories of 
 knowledge, a strictly a priori theory and a strictly 
 empirical theory, can understand Heraclitus. But, it 
 may be asked, if knowledge does not come from with- 
 out through the senses, nor from within from the 
 nature of thought, whence does it come ? Heraclitus, 
 however, would not be disturbed by such a modern 
 dilemma. There is reason, in fact, to believe, though 
 it sounds strange to us, that he supposed this divine 
 rational essence to be inhaled in the air we breathe 
 (cp. Sextus Emp. adv. Math. vii. 127, 132). It exists 
 in that which surrounds us (nepteyov) , and the measure 
 of our rationality depends on the degree in which we 
 can possess ourselves of this divine flame. There was 
 no conciseness of thought here, however, and Heracli- 
 
HISTORICAL AND CRITICAL. 51 
 
 tus seemed to think that it was partly apprehended 
 through the senses, that is, the most perfect condition 
 of receptivity to truth was the condition in which a man 
 was most awake. The stupidest man is he who is 
 asleep, blind, self -involved, and we may add, self- 
 absorbed (cp. frags. 95, 90, 77, 3, 2, 94). Hence, if 
 we have rightly interpreted Heraclitus here, a man 
 might wrap himself in thought forever and be no 
 nearer to truth. The source of knowledge did not lie 
 in that direction to any pre-Socratic Greek philosopher. 
 AbsorptioD into one's inner self, which Pfleiderer thinks 
 was Heraclitus' source of absolute knowledge, was the 
 one thing he most despised. 
 
 Let us now consider the connection of Heraclitus 
 with the Greek Mysteries, which Pfleiderer makes the 
 basis of his interpretation of the whole philosophy. 
 Pfleiderer has done a good work in emphasizing the 
 religious character of the philosophy of the Ephesian. 
 Lassalle and Teichmuller had already pointed it out. 
 Failure to recognize this is the gravest fault in the 
 critical work of Zeller. But as in Lassalle we found 
 over-systemization of the logical idea, in Schuster of the 
 empirical, in Teichmuller of the physical, so in Pflei- 
 derer there is great over-systemization of the religi- 
 ous element. More strictly, it is a vast over-emphasis 
 of one thought, namely, the indestructibility of life, or 
 the alternating identity of life and death, which Pflei- 
 derer claims to be a religious truth taken from the 
 Mysteries, and out of which, as we have seen, he 
 spins the whole philosophy of Heraclitus, including 
 the doctrine of the eternal flux, the unity of opposites, 
 and the fire. The slight grounds on which all this is 
 based must have already impressed the reader with 
 surprise that Pfleiderer should make so much out 
 
52 HERACLITUS. 
 
 of it. The fact that Heraclitus lived in Ephesus and 
 that Ephesus was a very religious city, is a fair speci- 
 men of the arguments by which he would establish a 
 connection with the Mysteries. There have been pre- 
 served only three fragments in which Heraclitus makes 
 any direct reference to the Greek Mysteries, all taken 
 from Clement of Alexandria (Protrept. 2, pp. 19, 30 ; 
 cp. frags. 124, 125, 127), and in these three passages 
 other critics have found no sympathy with, but stern 
 condemnation of the mystic cult. In the first passage 
 where the voxtctioXoc^ fidyoe, ftdx^oe, Xrjvac and juuazcu are 
 threatened with future fire, Pfleiderer admits con- 
 demnation of mystic abuses. But the third fragment, 
 relating to the Dionysiac orgies, is the one upon which 
 he most relies to establish the sympathy of our philo- 
 sopher with the Mysteries. The passage is as follows : 
 El fir] yap AiovuGw Tro/mrjv irrotsuvTO xac u/uvsov aa/ia 
 aidoiotoc, duaioiaraza eipyaaz av' wuto<z as ^AtdrjQ xac 
 Jtowffoz, orew [laivovrac xac XyvaiCoucrt. " For were it not 
 Dionysus to whom they institute a procession and 
 sing songs in honor of the pudenda, it would be the 
 most shameful action. But Dionysus, in whose honor 
 they rave in bacchic frenzy, and Hades, are the same." 
 Although this has usually been interpreted (by Schlei- 
 ermacher, Lassalle, and Schuster) to mean that the 
 excesses practiced in these ceremonies will be atoned for 
 hereafter, since Dionysus under whose name they are 
 carried on is identical with Pluto, the god of the lower 
 world, Pfleiderer, interpreting it in a wholly different 
 spirit, believes it to mean that these rites, although in 
 themselves considered they would be most shameful, 
 nevertheless have at least a partial justification from 
 the fact that they are celebrated in honor of Dionysus, 
 because since Dionysus and Pluto are the same, the 
 
HISTORICAL AND CRITICAL. 53 
 
 rites are really a symbolism expressing the power of 
 life over death and the indestructibility of life even 
 in death. These vile phallus songs are in fact songs 
 of triumph of life over death (Pfleiderer, p. 28). 
 Although somewhat far-fetched, this is a possible in- 
 terpretation of this obscure passage. This explanation 
 is perhaps not more strained than the others that have 
 been given (see below, frag. 127, crit. note). Granting 
 it. and granting that Heraclitus here expresses a cer- 
 tain sympathy with, or at least does not express 
 condemnation of the Mysteries, what follows ? Surely, 
 Pneiderer would not seriously ask us to conclude from 
 a single passage friendly to the religion of the Myste- 
 ries, that Heraclitus' whole philosophy or any part of 
 it was drawn from them. 
 
 But this fragment has another and more important 
 use for Pneiderer. In the religious truth here expressed 
 of the identity of Dionysus and Hades, that is, the 
 identity of life and death, he finds the germ of all 
 the Heraclitic philosophy. But the serious question 
 immediately arises whether the philosophy of oppo- 
 sites grew out of this identity, or whether this identity 
 was merely another illustration of the law of oppo- 
 sites. As Pneiderer has produced no sufficient reason 
 for believing differently, the natural conclusion is 
 that, as elsewhere we find the unity of day and night, 
 up and down, awake and asleep, so here we have the 
 unity of the god of death and the god of life, as another 
 illustration of the general law. To reverse this and 
 say that in this particular antithesis we have the 
 parent of all antitheses is very fanciful. Still further, 
 should infer from Pfleiderer's argument that the 
 identity of Dionysus and Hades was a well known and 
 ac-eepted truth' among the Mysteries, and that in the 
 
54 HERACLITUS. 
 
 above fragment we find it in the very act of passing 
 into the philosophy of the Ephesian. How much truth 
 is there in this ? So little that there is no record of the 
 identity of these two gods before the time of Hera- 
 clitus. Later, to be sure, something of the kind ap- 
 pears. Dionysus represented at least five different 
 gods, and in different times and places seems to have 
 been identified with most of the principal deities. In 
 Crete and at Delphi we hear of Zagreus, the winter 
 Dionysus of the lower world. No doubt other instances 
 might be shown where Dionysus was brought into 
 some relation or other with a chthonian deity. But 
 Heraclitus, if he had wished to develop a philosophy 
 from the alternation of summer and winter and the 
 mystic symbolism of life and death therein contained, 
 would hardly have chosen so dubious an expression of 
 it as the unity of Dionysus and Hades. We have no 
 reason to regard this as anything else than one of the 
 many paradoxical statements which he loved, of his 
 law of opposites. Indeed, the genesis of this law is not 
 so obscure that we need to force it out of a hidden 
 mystic symbolism. Zeller in his introduction to Greek 
 philosophy has well said that " philosophy did not 
 need the myth of Kore and Demeter to make known 
 the alternation of natural conditions, the passage from 
 death to life and life to death ; daily observation taught 
 it" (Vol. 1, p. 60). 
 
 The intrinsic weakness of Pfleiderer's position is 
 best seen when he attempts to pass to the doctrine of 
 the flux. It taxes the imagination to see how the 
 identity of life and death should lead to the universal 
 principle iravza x co P et xai oudkv juevec. Pfleiderer would 
 have us believe that the eternal flux was a subordinate 
 thought — a mere picture to help the mind to conceive 
 
HISTORICAL AND CRITICAL. 55 
 
 the primary metaphysical truth of the unity of oppo- 
 sites. We have already attempted to show that any 
 explanation of the Heraclitic philosophy must be wrong 
 which reduces the doctrine of the flux to a subordinate 
 position. Here it is sufficient to add that if Heraclitus 
 had been seeking a picture to illustrate the optimistic 
 endurance of life even in death, and the rational unity 
 and harmony of opposite powers, he could not possibly 
 have chosen a more unfortunate figure than the ever- 
 flowing river into which one cannot step twice. Pflei- 
 derer, in saying that Heraclitus chose the picture of the 
 evanescence of things to illustrate his law of opposites 
 and the endurance of life, seems to have forgotten 
 that on a previous page (above, p. 602) he said that the 
 hopeless creed of the masses, against which the Ephe- 
 sian was trying to establish the triumph of life, saw 
 not too much permanence and constancy in the world, 
 but too little. 
 
 We are forced, therefore, to conclude not only that 
 Pfleiderer has failed to establish any especial depend- 
 ence of Heraclitus upon the religion of the Greek Mys- 
 teries, but also that his supposed discovery that we 
 have here a metaphysical philosophy developed from 
 the material principle of the oscillating identity of life 
 and death, is an assumption without basis in fact. 
 
 In redeeming the Ephesian from the charge of pessi- 
 mism, Pfleiderer has done a good work. But here 
 again he has gone too far, in finding not only a well 
 grounded rational optimism in the doctrine of a world- 
 ruling Order, but also a practical optimism in the idea 
 of the indestructibility of life, an idea which, although 
 it appears on every page of Pfleiderer 's book, is not to 
 be found in any saying of Heraclitus or in any record 
 of his philosophy. 
 
5() HERACLITUS. 
 
 Section II. — Reconstructive. 
 
 I. 
 
 Having examined the four preceding fundamentally 
 different views of the philosophy of Heraclitus, and 
 having discovered that the opinions of modern critics 
 on the tenor of this philosophy furnish a new and un- 
 expected illustration of Heraclitus' own law of abso- 
 lute instability, it remains to be considered whether it 
 is possible to resolve, as he did, this general diversity 
 into a higher unity, and in this case to verify his law 
 that in all opposition there is harmony. If such a 
 unity is sought as that attempted by Lassalle, Schuster, 
 and Pfleiderer, it may be said at once that the task is 
 impossible. All such ambitious attempts in construc- 
 tive criticism in the case of Heraclitus are certain to 
 result, as we have seen, in over-interpretation, and 
 while they may leave a completed picture in the mind 
 of the reader, they do not leave a true one. Not only 
 is such a unified view of the philosophy of the Ephe- 
 sian unattainable, but it is unnecessary. It is quite' 
 certain that had we before us his original book in its 
 entirety, we should find therein no fully consistent 
 system of philosophy. Yet it is just this fact that 
 modern critics forget. While they point out errors 
 and contradictions by the score in the books of their 
 fellow critics, they allow for no inconsistencies on the 
 part of the original philosopher. Presuppositions of 
 harmony between all the sentences of an ancient 
 writer have led to much violence of interpretation. 
 Our interest in Heraclitus is not in his system as such, 
 but in his great thoughts which have historic signifi- 
 cance. These we should know, if possible, in their 
 
RECONSTRUCTIVE. 57 
 
 original meaning and in their connection with preced- 
 ing and succeeding philosophy. Before concluding 
 this introduction, then, it will be of advantage to re- 
 capitulate the results of the foregoing criticism, and 
 to place together such conclusions concerning the chief 
 Heraclitic thoughts as we have draAvn either from the 
 agreement or the disagreement of the various critics. 
 We shall best understand Heraclitus if we fix well 
 in mind his immediate starting-point. As we found 
 above in the examination of Pfleiderer's position (p. 
 4: . the Ephesian philosopher was first and primarily 
 Si preacher. To him the people almost without excep- 
 tion, were blind, stupid, and beastly. Heraclitus 
 hated them. They got no farther than crude sense 
 perception (cp. frags. 4, 6, 3), failing not only to recog- 
 nize the invisible harmony of the changing world, but 
 even the change itself (cp. frag. 2). They believed 
 things were fixed because they appeared so at first 
 sight. They preferred the lower passions to the higher 
 senses (cp. frag. 111). He is from first to last a misan- 
 thrope. He despises the people, yet as if constrained 
 by a divine command, he must deliver his message (cp. 
 frags. 1,2). To understand Heraclitus we must free our 
 minds from conceptions of every other Greek philoso- 
 pher, except, perhaps, his fellow Ionians. Never after- 
 wards did philosophy exhibit such seriousness. "We 
 can no more imagine Heraclitus at Athens than we 
 can think of Socrates away from it. Although, as we 
 shall see, the philosophy of Plato stood in vital con- 
 nection with that of Heraclitus, no contrast could be 
 greater than the half playful speculative style of the 
 former, and the stern, oracular and dogmatic utter- 
 ances of the latter. yWe shall find no parallel except 
 in Jewish literature. Indeed, Heraclitus was a pro- 
 
58 HERACLITUS. 
 
 phet. As the prophets of Israel hurled their messages 
 in actual defiance at the people, hardly more does the 
 Ephesian seem to care how his words are received, if 
 only he gets them spoken. Not more bitter and mis- 
 anthropic is Hosea in his denunciation of the people's 
 sins (cp. ch. iv. 1, 2 ff.), than is our philosopher in his 
 contempt for the stupidity and dullness of the masses. 
 At the very opening of his book he says, from his lofty 
 position of conscious superiority : " This- Law which I 
 unfold, men insensible and half asleep will not hear, 
 and hearing, will not comprehend" (frag. 2 ; cp. frags. 
 3, 5, 94, 95). 
 
 Now what was the prime error of the people which 
 so aroused the Ephesian, and what was the message 
 which he had to deliver to them ? Zeller is wrong in 
 saying (Vol. 1, p. 576) that, according to Heraclitus, the 
 radical error of the people was in attributing to things 
 a permanence of being which they did not possess. In 
 no passage does he censure the people for this. What 
 he blames them for is their insensibility, for looking 
 low when they ought to look high — in a word, for 
 blindness to the Divine Law or the Universal Reason 
 (frags. 2, 3, 4, 51, 45, 14). He blames them for 
 not recognizing the beauty of strife (frag. 43), and 
 the law of opposites (frag. 45). He blames them 
 for their grossness and beastliness (frags. 86, 111). 
 Finally, he blames them for their immorality (frag. 
 124), their silliness in praying to idols (frag. 126), 
 and their imbecility in thinking they could purify 
 themselves by sacrifices of blood (frag. 130). We 
 see therefore how wholly impossible it is to under- 
 stand Heraclitus unless we consider the ethical and 
 religious character of his mind. Thus Zeller, in as far 
 as he has attempted to give us a picture of Heraclitus' 
 
RECONSTRUCTIVE. 59 
 
 system, has failed by starting with the doctrine of the 
 flux and overlooking the religious motive. This is not 
 to say, as Pfleiderer has done, that the flux was 
 merely a negative teaching. Next to the recognition 
 of the Eternal Law, it was the most positive of his 
 teachings, and was the ground of his influence upon 
 subsequent thought. As such it is of chief interest to 
 us : but as far as we wish to get a picture of Heraclitus 
 himself, we must think first of his religious and ethical 
 point of departure. Thus the content of Heraclitus' 
 message to his countrymen was ethical. It was a 
 call to men everywhere to ivake up, to purify their 
 pappdpouz ^'r/v.z, and see things in their reality. 
 
 What now was this reality which he with his finer 
 insight saw, but which ruder souls were blind to ? 
 This brings us to the theoretical side or the philo- 
 sophical content of Heraclitus' message. Here comes 
 in the contribution of Teichmuller, who, as we saw,. 
 clearly pointed out that the great new thought of the 
 Ephesian was the unity in the manifold, as opposed to 
 the unity over against the manifold', taught by 
 Xenophanes. It was the unity of opposition, the 
 harmony of strife. It was Order immanent in cease- 
 less change. To use a phrase of Campbell's, " The 
 Idea of the universe implies at once absolute activity 
 and perfect law" (Plat. Theaet. Appendix, p. 244). This 
 was the central thought of Heraclitus, k ' the grandeur 
 of which,*' says Campbell, "was far beyond the com- 
 prehension of that time." But, it may be said, if we 
 have rightly apprehended Heraclitus' position as a 
 prophet and preacher, this was rather strong meat to 
 feed the masses. But the noXkoi with Heraclitus was a 
 broad term. It included everybody. The arro- 
 gance of this man was sublime. Neither Homer nor 
 
60 HERACLITUS. 
 
 Hesiod nor Pythagoras nor Xenophanes escaped his 
 lash (cp. frags. 16, 17, 119, 114). He had especially 
 in mind the so-called "men of repute," and said they 
 were makers and witnesses of lies (cp. frag. 118). The 
 whole male population of Ephesus, he said, ought to 
 be hung or expelled on account of their infatuation 
 and blindness (cp. frag. 114). Addressing such an 
 audience, indeed, his message had to be pitched high. 
 We have in the Ephesian sage a man who openly 
 claimed to have an insight superior to all the world, 
 and the history of thought has vindicated his claim. 
 Furthermore, it must be remembered that Heraclitus 
 did, in a measure, try to make the world-ruling Law 
 intelligible. He pictured it now as Justice, whose 
 handmaids, the Erinyes, will not let the sun overstep 
 his bounds (frag. 29) ; now as Fate, or the all-determin- 
 ing Destiny (Stobaeus, Eel. i. 5, p. 178 ; cp. frag. 63) ; 
 now as simple Law (frags. 23, 91), now as Wisdom 
 (frag. 65), intelligent Will (frag. 19), God (frag. 36), 
 Zeus (frag. 65). Respecting the latter term he ex- 
 pressly adds that it is misleading. So we see that 
 Heraclitus did what some modern philosophers have 
 been blamed for doing — he put his new thoughts into 
 old religious formulas. But it was more justifiable in 
 the case of the Ephesian. He did so, not to present a 
 semblance of orthodoxy, but to try to make his idea 
 intelligible. In fact, Heraclitus, no less than Xeno- 
 phanes, was a fearless, outspoken enemy of the popular 
 anthropomorphisms. " This world, the same for all," 
 he says, " neither any of the gods nor any man has 
 made, but it always was, and is, and shall be, an ever 
 living fire, kindled and quenched according to law" 
 (frag. 20; cp. frag. 126). 
 At this point it is natural to ask ourselves what, 
 
 
RECONSTRUCTIVE. 61 
 
 more exactly considered, Heraclitus meant by his Uni- 
 versal Order, his Divine Law. xor^b; Aoyoz, etc. This 
 inquiry fair criticism will probably not allow us to 
 answer more concisely than has already been done. 
 We have found ample reason for rejecting the notion 
 that it was of a logical nature, or any objectification of 
 that which is inherent in human thought. Yet it was 
 not without human attributes. As fiery essence, it 
 was identified with the universe and became almost 
 material. As Order, it approached the idea of pure 
 mathematical Relation or Form (cp, frag. 23, and Zel- 
 ler, Vol. 1, p. 628, 3, and 620). As Wisdom, it was pic- 
 tured as the intelligent power or efficient force that 
 produces the Order. When we reflect what difficulty 
 even at the present day we find in answering the 
 simple question, What is Order ? we are less surprised 
 to find that the Ephesian philosopher did not always 
 distinguish it from less difficult conceptions. We are, 
 however, surprised and startled at the significance of 
 the thought which this early Greek so nearly formu- 
 lated, that the one permanent, abiding element in a 
 universe of ceaseless change is mathematical relation. 
 At any rate, while recognizing the want of perfect 
 consistency and coordination in Heraclitus' system 
 here, we shall be helped by keeping this in mind, that 
 the system was pure pantheism. Too much stress can- 
 not be laid upon Teichmuller's exposition of the history 
 of the idea of Transcendent Reason, which first arose, 
 not in Heraclitus, but in Anaxagoras. To the latter 
 belongs the credit or the blame, whichever it may be, 
 of taking the first step towards the doctrine of imma- 
 teriality or pure spirit, which has influenced not only 
 philosophy, but society to its foundations even to 
 the present day. Heraclitus was guiltless of it. To 
 
62 HERACLITUS. 
 
 him the world intelligence itself was a part of the world 
 material — itself took part in the universal change. 
 
 In close connection with the Heraclitic Universal 
 Order stands the doctrine of strife as the method of 
 the evolution of the world, and the doctrine of the har- 
 mony and ultimately the unity of opposites — thoughts 
 which were not only central in Heraclitus' system, 
 but which, being too advanced for his time, have 
 waited to be taken up in no small degree by modern 
 science. It is unnecessary to repeat here the explana- 
 tions of Schuster (above, pp. 15, 16), and particularly 
 of Teichrnuller (above, p. 27), which we found to indi- 
 cate the correct interpretation of these thoughts. These 
 principles are to Heraclitus the mediation between 
 absolute change and perfect law. That which appears 
 to the senses as rest and stability is merely the tempo- 
 rary equilibrium of opposite striving forces. It is har- 
 mony by tension (cp. frags. 45, 43, 46). This law, 
 elementary in modern physics, is yet, as we shall pres- 
 ently see, not the whole content of the Heraclitic 
 thought, although it is its chief import. But in the 
 equilibrium of opposite forces we have at least relative 
 rest, not motion. And of molecular motion Heraclitus 
 knew nothing. How then did he conceive of apparent 
 stability as absolute motion ? This question supposes 
 more exactness of thought than we look for in the 
 Ephesian. The eternal flux was more generally con- 
 ceived as absolute perishability. Nothing is perma- 
 nently fixed. All is involved in the ceaseless round of 
 life and death, growth and decay. Strictly, however, 
 there is no contradiction here, since the rest of balanced 
 forces is only relative rest. It is possibly not going 
 too far to accept an illustration given by Ernst Laas 
 (Idealismus u. Positivismus 1, p. 200) of Heraclitus' 
 
RECONSTRUCTIVE. 63 
 
 conception of absolute change under the dominion of 
 law. He compares it to the actual path of our planets, 
 which move neither in circles nor in exact ellipses, but 
 under the influence of the attractive forces of moons 
 and of other planets, or of comets, continually change 
 both their course and their velocity, and yet all accord- 
 ing to law. 
 
 In addition to the explanations now given, how- 
 ever, there is something more to be said concerning 
 the unity or sameness of opposites. This teaching is 
 very prominent in the Heraclitic fragments (cp. frags. 
 35, 36, 39, 43, 45, 46, 52, 57, 58, 59, 67, 78). This 
 prominence was no doubt less in the original work, as 
 the paradoxical character of these sayings has encour- 
 aged their preservation. But all the critics have failed 
 to notice that we have in these fragments two distinct 
 classes of oppositions which, though confused in Hera- 
 clitus' mind, led historically into different paths of 
 development. The first is that unity of opposites 
 which results from the fact that they are endlessly 
 passing into one another. It must not be forgotten 
 that this is a purely physical opposition, as has been 
 pointed out by Zeller, Schuster and others, in refuta- 
 tion of the opinion of Lassalle, who fancied that he 
 had found here a Hegelian logical identity of contra- 
 dictories. As examples of this class of oppositions 
 may be mentioned the identity of day and night (frag. 
 35), gods and men (frag. 67), alive and dead, asleep and 
 awake (frag. 78). The identity of these oppositions 
 means that they are not in themselves abiding condi- 
 tions, but are continually and reciprocally passing 
 into one another. As Heraclitus plainly says, they are 
 the same because they are reciprocal transmutations 
 of each other (frag. 78;. But now we have another 
 
64 HERACLITUS. 
 
 class of opposites to which this reasoning will not 
 apply. "Good and evil," he says, "are the same" 
 (frag. 57). This is simply that identity of opposites 
 which developed into the Protagorean doctrine of 
 relativity. The same thing may be good or evil 
 according to the side from which you look at it. The 
 passage from Hippolytus (Kef. haer. ix. 10 ; cp. frag. 
 52, sources) states the doctrine of relativity as plainly 
 as it can be stated. ' • Pure and impure, he [Heraclitus] 
 says, are one and the same, and drinkable and undrink- 
 able are one and the same. • Sea water,' he says, ' is 
 very pure and very foul, for while to fishes it is drink- 
 able and healthful, to men it is hurtful and unfit to 
 drink.' " (Compare the opposition of just and unjust, 
 frag. 61 ; young and old, frag. 78 ; beauty and ugli- 
 ness, frag. 99 ; cp. frags. 104, 98, 60, 61, 51, 53.) This 
 simple truth is so prominent in the Heraclitic sayings 
 that we see how Schuster could have mistaken it for 
 the whole content of the theory of opposites and ig- 
 nored the more important doctrine of the other class. 
 We see further that Plato's incorrect supposition that 
 the Protagorean subjectivism was wholly an outgrowth 
 of the Heraclitic flux, resulted from his insufficient 
 acquaintance with the Ephesian's own writings. It 
 was a characteristic of Heraclitus that, in a degree 
 surpassing any other philosopher of antiquity, and 
 comparable only to the discoveries of Greek mathema- 
 ticians and of modern physical philosophers, he had an 
 insight into truths beyond his contemporaries, but he 
 knew not how to coordinate or use them. Having hit 
 upon certain paradoxical relations of opposites, he 
 hastened to group under his new law all sorts of oppo- 
 sitions. Some that cannot be included under either of 
 the above classes appear in a passage from Aristotle 
 
RECONSTRUCTIVE. G5 
 
 (de Mundo, 5, p. 396 b 12 : cp. frag'. 59, sources ; cp. 
 Eth. End. vii. l. p. 1-235 a 26 : frag. 43), where in the 
 case of the opposites sharps and flats, male and female, 
 the opposition becomes simple correlation and the 
 unity, harmony. 
 
 The order of treatment brings us now to the Hera- 
 clitic flux, but we have been compelled so far to anti- 
 cipate this in discussing the Universal Order and the 
 Law of Opposites that but one or two points need be 
 considered here. As we have seen in the study of 
 Schuster and Teichmtiller, the Heraclitic doctrine of 
 the flux was a thoroughly radical one. Heaven and 
 earth and all that they contain were caught in its fatal 
 whirlpool. It exempted no immortal gods of the poets 
 above us, no unchangeable realm of Platonic ideas 
 around us, no fixed Aristotelian earth beneath us. 
 It banished all permanence from the universe, and 
 banished therewith all those last supports which men 
 are accustomed to cling to. It introduced alarm into 
 philosophy, and set men, even to the present day, 
 asking. What can be saved from this general wreck ? 
 What is there absolutely permanent in the universe ? 
 This question, as we have seen, did not trouble Hera- 
 clitus himself, for, consistently or inconsistently, he 
 had a foundation rock in his Universal Law, Reason 
 or Order, which was his theoretical starting-point. 
 Furthermore, concerning the flux, it is doubtful 
 whether he ever pictured to himself such absolute 
 instability as his words imply. 
 
 But we are tempted to ask, Is his system here 
 really, as it first appears, inconsistent ? Mr. Borden 
 P. Bowne in his Metaphysics (p. 89) says that the 
 Heraclitic theory of change thus extremely conceived 
 " is intelligible and possible only because it is false." 
 
66 HEKACLITUS. 
 
 Let us look at Mr. Bowne's argument. He has first 
 shown in the same chapter that the Eleatic conception 
 of rigid being without change is impossible, since in a 
 world of absolute fixity, even the illusion of change 
 would be impossible. Furthermore, he has shown that 
 the vulgar conception of changeless being with 
 changing states is untenable, since the " state of a 
 thing expresses what the thing is at the time." 
 Changing states would be uncaused and undetermined 
 except as the being changes. There can be therefore 
 no fixed useless core of being. In general there is no 
 changeless being. All is change, all is becoming. Is 
 there then, he asks, any permanence or identity what- 
 ever, or is the extreme Heraclitic position true ? It is 
 false. Why? Because, as in a world of Eleatic 
 fixity, even the illusion of change would be impos- 
 sible, so in a world of absolute change, even the appear- 
 ance of rest would be impossible. There must be some 
 abiding factor, that change may be known as change. 
 There must be something permanent somewhere to 
 make the notion of flow possible. This permanent 
 something Mr. Bowne finds in the knowing subject — 
 the conscious self. Having proceeded plainly up to 
 this point, here he becomes mystical. The permanence 
 of the conscious self, he continues, does not consist in 
 any permanent substance of the soul. The soul forever 
 changes equally with other being. The permanence 
 consists in memory or self -consciousness. "How this 
 is possible," he says, " there is no telling." The per- 
 manence and identity of the soul consists, however, 
 only in its ability " to gather up its past and carry it 
 with it." 
 
 In this argument, Mr. Bowne's first fallacy is in 
 saying that in a world of absolute change there mast 
 
RECONSTRUCTIVE. 67 
 
 be some permanent factor in order that the change 
 itself may be known. This is meaningless. Perma- 
 nent as regards what ? Permanence as regards other 
 moving factors is simply relative difference of change. 
 Mr. Bowne seems to have committed the primitive 
 error of supposing that because all things seem to 
 move, he alone is fixed — like the earth in the Ptole- 
 maic astronomy. According to his argument, if he 
 were in a moving car and should meet another moving 
 car, the perception of movement would be impossible. 
 His reasoning assumes that by absolute change is 
 meant uniform change all in one way, which would 
 not be change at all, but absolute fixity. Difference 
 is the essential element in change, and difference is 
 all that is necessary to the idea of change. The 
 assumption of permanent personality in order to make 
 change itself possible is unnecessary. Mr. Bowne says 
 that what constitutes permanence in the conscious 
 self is its ability to gather up its past and carry it with 
 it. But a stratifying rock or growing tree gathers 
 up its past and carries it with it. But the apparent 
 permanence in the case of the rock or tree is a tempo- 
 rarily abiding form or temporarily abiding spacial 
 relations. The apparent permanence of personality 
 may similarly consist wholly in a temporarily abiding 
 form or relation, must in fact consist in this, since 
 Mr. Bowne rejects any abiding soul substance. But 
 temporarily abiding relations, the extreme Heracli- 
 teans do not deny, certainly not Heraclitus, to whom 
 apparent rest was due to the temporary equilibrium 
 of opposite balancing forces. We conclude, therefore, 
 that Mr. Bowne's charge of falsity against the theory 
 of the Heraclitic flux is not well substantiated. Here 
 as ever we see the difference between modern and 
 
68 HERACLITUS. 
 
 ancient philosophy. The former looks within, the 
 latter without. Mr. Bowne seeks the abiding within 
 himself. Heraclitus looked away from himself to the 
 Universal Order without, which determined all things 
 and himself. 
 
 But though the Heraclitic absolute flux is vindicated 
 from objections of the above character, the question 
 still remains unanswered whether the doctrine is con- 
 sistent with his conception of absolute Order. Did 
 not Heraclitus make the common mistake of hyposta- 
 sizing law ? Did he not conceive of law as something 
 by which the action of things is predetermined, rather 
 than as a mere abstraction from the action of things ? 
 No doubt he did even worse than this, for he ascribed 
 to his xocvoq Xoyoc;, attributes which led Bernays and 
 Teichmiiller to believe that it was a self-conscious 
 being, (a conclusion questioned by Zeller, Vol. 1, p. 
 609, 3). But yet again he saved his consistency here 
 by identifying his Absolute with fire and thereby 
 bringing it after all into the all-consuming vortex of 
 endless change. But in the face of this all-embracing 
 flux, the one idea which stands out most prominent in 
 Heraclitus is the deep rationality of the world — the 
 eternal Order. Nor in the last analysis are these two 
 at variance, for any world must be rational to the 
 beings in it, for the rationality of the world to us is 
 only our adaptation to the world, which is involved in 
 the very fact of our existence. 
 
 Concerning the cosmogony, it is worth while to re- 
 call the suggestive thought contained in the ipqa p.0Gbvrj 
 and xopoc; of Heraclitus. In our examination of Schus- 
 ter's work we found reason to believe that the word 
 Ip-qofioabv-q, which we may render " craving" or " long- 
 ing," was used by the Ephesian to denote the charac- 
 
RECONSTRUCTIVE. GO 
 
 ter of the impulse or motive force by which the primi- 
 tive world matter or fire evolved itself into the world 
 of individual things. The records are too meagre to 
 warrant much enlargement upon this idea ; neverthe- 
 less it is important historically and in itself interesting. 
 It is the beginning of that line of thought which finds 
 the analogy to the original motive or creative power of 
 the universe, not in man's intellectual but in his emo- 
 tional nature, not in pure thought but in pure desire. 
 It is opposed to the conception of Aristotle that the 
 absolute first mover is pure intellect, the thought of 
 thought (^or^acz w/jcrsco:), and to the modern German 
 enlargement of the same which began with the intel- 
 lectual monads of Leibniz. On the other hand, it is 
 in agreement with the idea brought out by Plato in 
 his Symposium, the idea of Love as the source of devel- 
 opment and immortality, and it reminds us later of 
 Plotinus, who refuses to predicate thought or reason of 
 the One but identifies it with the Good. The Hera- 
 clitic-Platonic notion is no less anthropomorphic than 
 the Aristotelian-Leibnizian ; but if the human mind 
 must furnish forth some faculty to be singly hyposta- 
 sized into God, we much prefer the richer emotional 
 side to that of pure dry intellect or reason. 
 
 We come now to the Heraclitic ethics, the freshest 
 and most vital part of his philosophy, but most misun- 
 derstood by all the critics. The practical ethical rule 
 with Heraclitus is to follow the law of the state, 
 which again is dependent upon the Divine Law (frags. 
 91, 100). From his standpoint this agrees with his in- 
 junction to live according to Nature (frag. 107). More 
 broadly stated, men should follow the Universal as 
 opposed to individual whims. " The Law of Eeason 
 is common, but the majority of people live as though 
 
70 HERACLITUS. 
 
 they had an understanding of their own " (frag. 92). 
 This leads us directly to the theoretical ethical prin- 
 ciple which lay at the root of all Heraclitus' philosophy, 
 and which we have outlined above (p. 58) in defining 
 his starting point as that of a preacher and prophet. 
 The highest good was not contentment (evapioTTjocs), a 
 statement taken from a single indefinite passage in 
 Clement of Alexandria (Strom, ii. 21, p. 417 ; Clement 
 is followed by Theodoretus, iv. p. 984, ed. Halle), and 
 which, though adopted by Zeller, is as silly and impos- 
 sible as the better authenticated statement that Hera- 
 clitus wept over everything. Such an ethical principle 
 is at variance with every sentence of the Ephesian. 
 He continually exhorts men, as we have seen, to arise, 
 get out of their lethargy and wake up. His most 
 pungent sarcasm is directed against the people who 
 are in a state of indifference, sleepiness, contentment 
 (frags. 2, 3, 5, 94, 95, etc.). The highest good with Hera- 
 clitus, therefore, is the greatest intellectually activity, 
 the greatest receptivity to the divine reason around 
 us, the greatest freedom from individual peculiarities 
 and the greatest possession of that which is universal. 
 " Human nature," he says, " does not possess under- 
 standing, but the divine does " (frag. 96). We must 
 look away from ourselves to Nature around us. We 
 must follow the universal Reason therein expressed. 
 Proximately for men this is best found in the common, 
 the normal, the customary, finally therefore in public 
 law. 
 
 It will thus be noticed that we have in Heraclitus 
 an emphatic expression of the type of ethics peculiar 
 to the Greeks. Of the individual he thought little. 
 " To me one is ten thousand if he be the best " (frag. 
 113). He blamed the Ephesians for their declaration 
 
RECONSTRUCTIVE. 71 
 
 of democracy (frag. 114). He would not have been 
 able to appreciate those modern systems of ethics 
 which make a moral law out of individual conscience 
 and justify actions by good intentions. Heraclitus, as 
 well as psychologists of recent times, seemed to appre- 
 ciate the dangers of self -in volution. His whole sys- 
 tem is a protest against individual intensification. He 
 will not have men roll themselves into a cocoon of a 
 single system, or revolve in the circle of a single set of 
 ideas. He will have them throw themselves open to 
 the common light, keep every sense open and recep- 
 tive to new impressions, and thereby attain truth, 
 which is found in the universal alone. 
 
 The optimism which Pfleiderer justifies for Hera- 
 clitus does not stand in contradiction to the misan- 
 thropy that we have found to characterize him. His 
 optimism was thoroughly Leibnizian. It was reasoned 
 optimism, resulting in the strong conviction that the 
 world is good, rational and orderly. Most men, to be 
 sure, are fools, but it is their own fault, as they will 
 not put themselves in right relation to the world. 
 Gottlob Mayer, in a pamphlet entitled " Heraklit von 
 Ephesus und Arthur Schopenhauer," has been at pains 
 to prove that Heraclitus is a Schopenhauer pessimist. 
 TVe cannot regard his attempt as successful. Our 
 study of the Ephesian philosopher in the preceding 
 pages has shown nothing more clearly than that the 
 logical result of his metaphysics is not, as this author 
 claims, pessimism, but quite the opposite. None of the 
 iges which he cites (cp. frags. 86, 55, 81, GG, 20, 
 111; can be made to yield any pessimism beyond mis- 
 anthropy, unless possibly the one from Lucian (Vit. 
 Auct. c. I4t 9 -—QNHTH2. ti yao b acwv iarcu; HPA- 
 KAEITOE. ~a~.z nacrous, Tteaaeuwv, dea(pepo/j£vo<;, cp. frag. 
 
72 HERACLITUS. 
 
 79), where Time is compared to a child at play, now 
 arranging, now scattering the pebbles. And yet noth- 
 ing is conclusive from this. It refers evidently to 
 the periodic creation and destruction of the world. 
 Whether this world building is a pastime of Jove, or 
 the product of fate or of love, makes no difference in 
 this case, provided only the resulting world is one well 
 disposed and rational. 
 
 II. 
 
 What has given rise to the reviving interest in Hera- 
 clitus attested by the monographs which have lately 
 appeared ? The modern world hardly hopes to get any 
 new light from his oracular sayings gathered in muti- 
 lated fragments from Philo and Plutarch, from Cle- 
 ment and Origen. Such unhoped for light, however, 
 as our introductory study has shown, may for some 
 minds be found breaking in after all. But the interest 
 in the philosopher of Ephesus is historical. The new 
 discovery of the present half century is that the way 
 to study philosophy is to study its history, and especi- 
 ally its genesis. The passion for origins has carried 
 the interest back to Greek philosophy, and finally back 
 to the beginnings of Greek philosophy. But there is 
 still another reason for going back. In the confusion 
 arising from the fall of the idealistic philosophy in 
 Germany, it was first thought that it would be neces- 
 sary to return to Kant and secure a new footing ; not 
 that any new light was seen emanating from Kant, 
 but error having arisen, it was necessary to trace it to 
 its source. 
 
 This movement has neither been successful nor does 
 it promise to be. In fact, there is a certain weariness 
 in philosophy of the whole modern subjective method. 
 
RECONSTRUCTIVE. 73 
 
 The result has been that thinkers have turned away 
 from it to the one objective side of modern philosophy, 
 namely, the sciences. Those, however, who still retain 
 their love of philosophy in its larger sense, are going 
 back farther than Kant. They see that the whole 
 Hume-Kantian-Fichtean movement was a digression, 
 a sort of branch road, which to be sure had to be 
 explored before philosophy could go on in safety, but 
 which was found to lead nowhere in particular, and 
 that, having thanked these investigators for their ser- 
 vices rendered, we may decline to concern ourselves 
 further with this digression, but go on with our search 
 for objective results. In this search our starting point 
 must be from that philosophy which is most free 
 from this whole subjective tendency. Such is the 
 philosophy of Greece. Considering therefore that the 
 introspective method has not proved so fruitful as 
 was hoped, and that it is at least more modest if not 
 more rational to regard man as a part of Nature, rather 
 than Nature as a part of man, students of philosophy 
 are turning their attention to the Greek philosophers 
 where the freer and more ingenuous conception rules. 
 
 These two causes, therefore, the former, the passion 
 for studying the origin and development of thought and 
 the connection of different systems of thought, the 
 latter, the need of disinfecting our minds from all the 
 germs of a pathological introspective habit, and putting 
 ourselves as an experiment in the position of those 
 who took it for granted that Nature was larger than 
 man, have led us back to Greek philosophy and 
 especially to its sources. 
 
 In either of these aspects Heraclitus is important. 
 He is a perfect, by all means the most perfect, illustra- 
 tion of those qualities which are usually supposed to 
 
74 HERACLITUS. 
 
 characterize the Greek mind, namely, receptivity, un- 
 prejudiced freedom of thought, love of order, and trust- 
 ful confidence in the unity of man and Nature. Of all 
 the Greek schools these qualities were best represented 
 by the Ionian thinkers who, coming before what has 
 been called " the fall of man in Socrates," were free 
 from the later dialectical disturbances. And of the 
 Ionians, Heraclitus, the last, best incorporates them. 
 But it is in the other aspect that the philosopher of 
 Ephesus is most important, namely, in the origin and 
 history of ideas. Let us notice summarily what has 
 come from him. 
 
 To Heraclitus we trace the philosophy of change, 
 prominent in subsequent Greek philosophy as yc(vbp.&jov, 
 the indirect cause of the counter movement of Socrates 
 and Plato with its powerful determining influences, 
 central in modern times as motion in the philosophy 
 of Hobbes and the ground principle in the important 
 system of Trendelenburg, and finally in a logical trans- 
 formation, prominent in both German and English 
 thought as Werden or Becoming. To Heraclitus we 
 trace the notion of Relativity, the central point in the 
 doctrine of the Sophists, which by withdrawing every 
 absolute standard of truth, threatened to destroy all 
 knowledge and all faith, and which sent Socrates 
 searching for something permanent and fixed in the 
 concepts of the human mind, and so led to the finished 
 results of Plato and Aristotle. To Heraclitus we trace 
 some of the fundamental doctrines of the Stoics, 
 namely, their abrogation of the antithesis of mind and 
 matter and their return to pre-Socratic monism, their 
 conception of Nature as larger than man and his com- 
 plete subjection to it, and finally their doctrine of the 
 future conflagration of the world, later an influential 
 factor in Christianity. 
 
KECOXSTRUCTIVE. 75 
 
 These were the thoughts which were most important 
 in their determining influence upon subsequent philo- 
 sophy. The following, while in themselves no less im- 
 portant, were less directly involved in the history of 
 opinion. Of these the first is the notion of Law and 
 Order absolute and immanent in the world, an idea so 
 large that no Greek follower could grasp it, and yet 
 vital to Heraclitus' system, for without it his philo- 
 sophy becomes the philosophy of desperation, the source 
 among the ingenuous Greeks of the nihilism of Gor- 
 gias or the universal doubt of the skeptics, and among 
 the brooding moderns the source of the pessimism of 
 Schopenhauer. To Heraclitus again we trace, as 
 Teichmiiller has shown, the closely related doctrine of 
 the immanence of God in the world, so that we have in 
 him one source of the pantheistic systems. To Hera- 
 clitus, finally, we trace the physical law of opposites, 
 the thought that all order and harmony and apparent 
 permanence are the result of opposite tension, the bal- 
 ance of centrifugal and centripetal forces. Less in- 
 volved in the history of philosophy, though most im- 
 portant to Heraclitus, and in themselves most interest- 
 ing to us of modern times, are his great ethical thoughts 
 which we have already outlined. 
 
 The determinative ideas of the Ephesian may be 
 summed up in a word by saying that they represent 
 all that way of thinking against which Socrates and 
 Plato raised the whole weight of their authority. 
 Without repeating here the facts, well enough known 
 to everybody, of the Socratic reaction in Greek philo- 
 sophy, we must sketch one or two phases of it in order 
 to establish the influence and explain the final defeat 
 of the Heraclitic philosophy. In Socrates, Plato, and 
 Aristotle, philosophy underwent a change more radical 
 
76 HERACLITUS. 
 
 than any other in its history, a change that was ulti- 
 mately to revolutionize all thought, and through its 
 influence on Christian theology, to enter as a large 
 determining element into all western civilization. 
 Heraclitus is the representative of what philosophy 
 was before that change. 
 
 Socrates said he could not understand the book of 
 Heraclitus. That was not strange. The Ephesian 
 could have told him the reason why. The man who 
 could learn nothing from the fields and trees (see 
 Plato's Phaedrus, p. 230), who spent all his time in 
 the Agora conversing with other men about virtue, 
 and who never seemed to realize that there was a 
 world above the heads and under the feet of men, 
 was not likely to understand the book of Heraclitus. 
 Could the Ephesian philosopher have taken the Atheni- 
 an logician out and given him a few lessons from Nature 
 at first hand, could he have induced him to desist for a 
 while from his boring into human intellects in search 
 of a definition, and got his gaze lifted up to the clouds 
 and stars, and put him in actual contact with the 
 nepesyov, he would have been an apter scholar with the 
 book. But it is quite impossible even in fancy to 
 think of these two men together. The communer 
 with Nature, the stern misanthropic sage and prophet 
 of Ephesus had no points in common with the society- 
 loving Athenian sophist. They were radically differ- 
 ent, and on this difference hangs the secret of the 
 development of philosophy for two thousand years. 
 Socrates was not a Greek at all. He denied the most 
 characteristic traits of his nation. He was a modern 
 in many true senses. He was a curiosity at Athens, 
 and consequently very much in vogue. 
 
 Socrates represents the birth of self -consciousness. In 
 
RECONSTRUCTIVE. 77 
 
 practicing his maieutic art to this end, he little thought 
 that he was giving the death-blow to the most beauti- 
 ful trait of his countrymen, namely, the instinctive, 
 the unconscious, the naive. No doubt this new birth 
 had to take place some time, but under Socrates' 
 direction it was premature. The old methods were 
 not yet dead. Here historians of philosophy err. They 
 say the pre-Socratic philosophers of Nature had in vain 
 tried to solve the problems of the world, and it was high 
 time for a critical philosophy that should begin- with 
 man. In vain, indeed ! Had the naturalists labored in 
 vain when the foundation of the atomic philosophy had 
 been laid in Abdera, that of mathematics in Italy, and 
 a far-seeing metaphysics and ethics in Ephesus ? Soc- 
 rates and Plato took fright too easily at the Sophists. 
 Their philosophy would have died with them. Not so 
 that of Democritus, Pythagoras, and Heraclitus. Soc- 
 rates was a professor of clear thinking. Clear thinking 
 is in itself well, but two solid centuries of clear think- 
 ing from Descartes to Hegel have in modern times 
 ended in failure. We long to know what natural 
 thinking would have accomplished if it had been left 
 an open field a while longer in Greece. Then again 
 clear thinking was overdone. It was, to be sure, not 
 Socrates' fault that his method was afterwards abused, 
 but as a matter oi fact it took in later history a patho- 
 logical turn that has resulted in wide-spread evils. 
 Over self-consciousness, too much inwardness and 
 painful self-inspection, absence of trust in our instincts 
 and of the healthful study of Nature, which in ethics 
 are illustrated in modern questions of casuistry, and 
 in philosophy in Cartesian doubt and the skepticism of 
 Hume, characterize our worst faults. The philosophy 
 and ethics of Heraclitus, as we have seen, stood in 
 vital opposition to all these traits. 
 
78 HERACLITUS. 
 
 But there was another respect in which the fall of 
 man took place in Socrates. The love of beauty and 
 form, and particularly beauty of the human body, 
 characterized all the Greeks until Socrates, but char- 
 acterizes modern people in a relatively small degree. 
 Socrates cared nothing for outward beauty, but to the 
 surprise of his fellow-citizens laid all the emphasis 
 upon moral beauty. (We will say he was too large 
 hearted to have had a personal motive for so doing.) 
 It may be that the Greeks estimated physical beauty 
 relatively too high, but the rebound has been too 
 great. Caught up by the genius of Plato and inten- 
 sified by the tenor of his philosophy, and met six 
 centuries later in Alexandria by a powerful current 
 of the same tendency from Judea, it effected the com- 
 plete destruction of the Greek idea, and with it of 
 course of Greek art. In the medieval church, inherited 
 moral deformity was a sin of such extreme import, 
 that for it a man was to be forever damned ; but inher- 
 ited physical deformity was not only not a sin, but 
 often a blessing, teaching him as it did the relative 
 worthlessness of the earthly life and body. So far was 
 the Greek idea reversed that the body, instead of being 
 the type of beauty, became the type of impurity, and 
 from being the support of the soul, became its con- 
 taminator. The " flesh," indeed, was the symbol of 
 evil. The results in modern life are only too well 
 known. Among them may be mentioned the loss of 
 appreciation of the worth of the present physical life 
 in itself, failure to recognize the close connection of 
 soul and body, and that the health of the former 
 depends on the health of the latter, resulting in all the 
 strange devices to secure the welfare of the soul in the 
 face of persistent disregard of the laws of physical 
 
RECONSTRUCTIVE. 79 
 
 health, or in such attempts as that of sustaining the 
 moral status of a community where all hygienic laws 
 are violated. This idea has been ground into the 
 popular mind by so long education that modern 
 educators find it a serious problem how to correct it. 
 It is not merely physical education that is wanted, but 
 a reconstruction of our notions about the relation of 
 body and mind. The Socratic work must be in part 
 undone, and we must get back more nearly to the pre- 
 Socratic conception of balance, for to them physical 
 ugliness was no less an evil than moral ugliness. 
 
 But there is still another aspect of the Socratic 
 apostasy, as important as those we have mentioned, and 
 so far-reaching in its effects that it determines modern 
 thought even to the lowest ranks of society. In this 
 movement begun by Socrates, but perfected by Plato 
 and Aristotle, the central thought of the Heraclitic phi- 
 losophy was denied, and denied with such power that 
 now after twenty-two hundred years it hardly dares 
 assert itself. We refer, of course, to the Platonic tran- 
 scendentalism. It was designed to give the death-blow 
 to Heraclitus, and it succeeded ultimately beyond the 
 wildest hopes of its founders. Strictly it was begun by 
 Anaxagoras. We have already seen with Teichmuller 
 how the doctrine of transcendent reason gained its first 
 characteristic, Pure Separation, in the Nous of Anax- 
 agoras, its second, Identity, in the definitive work of 
 Socrates. But it was Plato who elevated it into a 
 great system and gave it to the world for a perpetual 
 inheritance. Finally, Aristotle, as if the fates con- 
 spired to make this doctrine immortal, took it up and 
 adapted it to unpoetical inductive minds. Heraclitus 
 in a wonderful conception of the world had abolished 
 every antithesis and enunciated a system of pure 
 
80 HERACLITUS. 
 
 monism. The Socratic school reversed his plan and set 
 up a dualism of universal and particular, noumenon and 
 phenomenon, mind and body, spirit and matter, which 
 has dominated all philosophy, religion and literature. 
 
 It is with the origin of this dualism that we are 
 concerned, not with the familiar history of its out- 
 come, but yet we may recall what to the student of 
 philosophy or even of history it is needless to more 
 than mention, how this dualism fastened itself upon 
 subsequent thought ; how as realism and nominalism 
 it divided the schoolmen ; how as mind and matter it 
 left Descartes in hopeless difficulty ; how Spinoza 
 founded a philosophy expressly to resolve it, but suc- 
 ceeded only by the artifice of terms ; how Leibnitz 
 solved the problem, though with too much violence, by 
 use of the same boldness with which its founders 
 established it ; how Kant finally left the antithesis 
 unexplained ; how again as the material and imma- 
 terial it fixed itself in the psychology of Aristotle, who 
 affirmed as the higher part of the human mind, the 
 active Nous or principle of pure immateriality, cogniz- 
 ant of the highest things, identical with the divine 
 Prime Mover, and immortal, thus constituting for 
 man the highest glorification that he ever received 
 from his own hand ; how Thomas Aquinas, spokesman 
 for a powerful church, adopted this psychology and fast- 
 ened it upon the modern popular world ; how finally, 
 in the sphere of religion proper, the transcendent- 
 alism of Plato has grown into the belief in pure Spirit 
 and spiritual existences, peopling heaven and earth, 
 and holding communion with matter and body, though 
 having absolutely nothing in common (if the paradox 
 may be excused) with them. Such has been in part 
 the wonderful expansion of the Platonic Idealism. 
 
RECONSTRUCTIVE. 81 
 
 And what was all this for in the first place ? It was 
 raised primarily as a barrier against the dissolving 
 power of the eternal flux of the Heracliteans. A philo- 
 sophy had arisen in Greece that denied all perma- 
 nence. Misunderstood by the Sophists and abused by 
 Cratylus, it called out the protest of Socrates, at heart 
 the sincerest man of his contemporaries. Man, im- 
 pelled by that very faculty which connects him most 
 closely with Nature, namely, the sense of dependence, 
 demands something permanent and unchangeable, 
 upon which he can base his laws, religion and philo- 
 sophy. If he cannot find it in Nature or in Revelation, 
 he will make it out of a part of himself. This is what 
 Socrates and Plato did. Socrates, seeking the perma- 
 nent for ethical motives, detesting Nature and failing 
 to find there anything fixed and abiding, turned to 
 man and man's manner of thinking. By analysis of 
 thought he separated out general concepts which ap- 
 peared to be the same for all. Plato, perhaps less in 
 earnest than subsequent ages gave him credit for, 
 hypostasized them, raised them into real objective 
 existences, henceforth to become idols, convenient 
 entities to fill all gaps in human reasoning, objects of 
 the dreams of poets and the worship of the religious, 
 archetypes from which a lazy philosophy could deduce 
 the universe. How, we naturally ask, could this auda- 
 cious piece of anthropomorphism, in which man delib- 
 erately took his own norms of thought, projected them 
 outward, and elevated them into gods, impose itself 
 upon the world as it did ? There are two answers. 
 First, it flattered men immensely, and like all anthro- 
 pomorphisms, thereby won half the battle. Second, it 
 did not succeed at once, but slumbered for four centu- 
 ries, and finally, in the decadence of all systems of 
 
82 HERACLITUS. 
 
 philosophy and the breaking up of the old civilization, 
 awakened to supply the groundwork of a religious 
 revival. Platonism fell dead on the Greek world. 
 Plato, and Aristotle as well, shot over the heads of 
 their fellows. The philosophy of the Academy was a 
 brilliant piece of speculation such as only the age of 
 Pericles could call out. After that, philosophy fell 
 back into the old ways. The Older Academy dragged 
 out a short existence and "died. Zeno, a Cypriote, but 
 in his desire for unity more Greek than Plato, studied 
 first with Polemo, head of the Academy, but disap- 
 pointed with Platonism, turned back to Heraclitus. 
 His school, as well as the Epicureans and Skeptics, 
 returned to the Heraclitic monism. These schools 
 loyally upheld for three centuries the Greek idea of 
 the unity of man and Nature. But philosophy itself 
 was doomed and fated to pass over into religion on the 
 one hand and mysticism on the other. Platonism was 
 admirably adapted to this end. In luxurious Alex- 
 andria, the weary inductive method of Aristotle, which 
 the Ptolemies had instituted in the Museum, soon 
 yielded to the fascinating lazy philosophy of Plato. 
 Philo the Jew, Plutarch the moralist, Yalentinus the 
 Gnostic, Origen the Christian, all yielded to it in 
 greater or less degree. In Plotinus it reached its full 
 fruitage. Porphyry, his pupil, relates that he was 
 ashamed of having a body and was careless of its 
 needs, so anxious was he ecstatically to absorb his 
 soul in the Supra-rational Transcendent One. Here 
 we have a last consequence of the Socratic doctrine of 
 mind. Here we have the extreme opposition to the 
 naturalism of Heraclitus which considered man as a 
 subordinate part of Nature. Greek philosophy ended 
 with the triumph of Socrates and the defeat of Hera- 
 
RECONSTRUCTIVE. 83 
 
 t 
 
 clitus. The wealth of Plato and Aristotle was the 
 bequest that was handed over to the coming centuries. 
 The Greek naturalists were forgotten. It was reserved 
 for the present century to revive and vindicate them. 
 In what has been said in setting in relief the philo- 
 sophy of Heraclitus, it is obvious that we have been 
 concerned with but two or three aspects of that of 
 Socrates and Plato, namely, its transcendental, ideal- 
 istic and subjective character. It is not necessary to 
 add that were we referring to other sides of it, as for 
 instance, the undeniable importance of Socrates' con- 
 tribution to ethics, and that of Plato to ethics and reli- 
 gion as well as to real scientific thought, the result 
 would be very different. And of the Idealism itself, its 
 very fascination and prevalence argue that it meets 
 some want of human beings. It is poetry, to be sure, 
 but as poetry it has been and will still be useful in saving 
 men from the dangers of coarse materialistic thought. 
 
84 HERACLITUS. 
 
 I 
 
 Heraclitus of Ephesus on Nature. 
 
 I. — It is wise for those who hear, not me, but the 
 universal Reason, to confess that all things are one. 1 
 
 II. — To this universal Reason which I unfold, 
 although it always exists, men make themselves in- 
 sensible, both before they have heard it and when 
 they have heard it for the first time. For notwith- 
 standing that all things happen according to this 
 Reason, men act as though they had never had any 
 experience in regard to it when they attempt such 
 words and works as I am now relating, describing 
 each thing according to its nature and explaining how 
 it is ordered. And some men are as ignorant of what 
 
 Soueces. — I. — Hippolytus, Ref. haer. ix. 9. Context : — Heraclitus 
 says that all things are one, divided undivided, created uncreated, 
 mortal immortal, reason eternity, father son, God justice. "It is 
 wise for those who hear, not me, but the universal Reason, to con- 
 fess that all things are one." And since all do not comprehend 
 this or acknowledge it, he reproves them somewhat as follows: 
 "They do not understand how that which separates unites with 
 itself ; it is a harmony of oppositions like that of the bow and of 
 the lyre" (=frag. 45). 
 
 Compare Philo, Leg. alleg. iii. 3, p. 88. Context, see frag. 24. 
 
 II. — Hippolytus, Ref. haer. ix. 9. Context : — And that Reason 
 always exists, being all and permeating all, he (Heraclitus) says in 
 this manner : " To this universal," etq. 
 
 Aristotle, Rhet. iii. 5, p. 1407, b. 14. Context: — For it is very hard 
 to punctuate Heraclitus' writings on account of its not being clear 
 whether the words refer to those which precede or to those which 
 follow. For instance, in the beginning of his work, where he says, 
 "To Reason existing always men make themselves insensible." 
 For here it is ambiguous to what "always" refers. 
 
 Sextus Empir. adv. Math. vii. 132. — Clement of Alex. Stromata, 
 v. 14, p. 716.— Amelius from Euseb. Praep. Evang. xi. 19, p. 540.— 
 Compare Philo, Quis. rer. div. haer. 43, p. 505. — Compare Ioannes 
 Sicel. in Walz. Rhett. Gr. vi. p. 95. 
 
 1 The small figures In the translation refer to the critical notes, pp. 115 ff. 
 
OX NATURE. 85 
 
 they do when awake as they are forgetful of what they 
 do when asleep. 2 
 
 III. — Those who hear and do not understand are 
 like the deaf. Of them the proverb says: "Present, 
 they are absent." 
 
 IV. — Eyes and ears are bad witnesses to men having 
 rude souls. 
 
 V. — The majority of people have no understanding 
 of the things with which they daily meet, nor, when 
 instructed, do they have any right knowledge of them, 
 although to themselves they seem to have. 
 
 VI. — They understand neither how to hear nor how 
 to speak. 
 
 III. — Clement of Alex. Strom, v. 14, p. 718. Context : — And if you 
 wish to trace out that saying, " He that hath ears to hear, let him 
 hear," you will find it expressed by the Ephesian in this manner, 
 "Those who hear," etc. 
 
 Theodoretus, Therap. i. p. 13, 49. 
 
 IV.— Sextos Emp. adv. Math. vii. 126. Context :— He (Heraclitus) 
 casts discredit upon sense perception in the saying, "Eyes and ears 
 are bad witnesses to men having rude souls." Which is equivalent 
 to saying that it is the part of rude souls to trust to the irrational 
 senses. 
 
 Stobaeus Floril. iv. 56. 
 
 Compare Diogenes Laert. ix. 7. 
 
 V.— Clement of Alex. Strom, ii. 2, p. 432. 
 
 M. Antoninus iv. 46. Context : — Be ever mindful of the Heraclitic 
 saying that the death of earth is to become water, and the death of 
 water is to become air, and of air, fire (see frag. 25). And remember 
 also him who is forgetful whither the way leads (comp. frag. 73) ; 
 and that men quarrel with that with which they are in most con- 
 tinual association (= frag. 93), namely, the Reason which governs 
 all. And those things with which they meet daily seem to them 
 strange ; and that we ought not to act and speak as though we were 
 asleep (= frag. 94), for even then we seem to act and speak. 
 
 VI. — Clement of Alex. Strom, ii. 5, p. 442. Context : — Heraclitus, 
 
 scolding some as unbelievers, says : " They understand neither how 
 
 to hear nor to speak," prompted, I suppose, by Solomon, " If thou 
 
 to hear, thou shalt understand; and if thou inclinest thine 
 
 ear, thou shalt be wise." 
 
86 HERACLITUS. 
 
 VII. — If you do not hope, you will not win that 
 which is not hoped for, since it is unattainable and 
 inaccessible. 
 
 VIII. — Gold-seekers dig over much earth and find 
 little gold. 
 - IX.— Debate. 
 
 X. — Nature loves to conceal herself. 
 
 XI. — The God whose oracle is at Delphi neither 
 speaks plainly nor conceals, but indicates by signs. 
 
 XII. — But the Sibyl with raging mouth uttering 
 things solemn, rude and unadorned, reaches with her 
 voice over a thousand years, because of the God. 
 
 VII.— Clement of Alex. Strom, ii. 4, p. 437. Context :— Therefore, 
 that which was spoken by the prophet is shown to be wholly true, 
 " Unless ye believe, neither shall ye understand." Paraphrasing 
 this saying, Heraclitus of Ephesus said, " If you do not hope," etc. 
 
 Theodoretus, Therap. i. p. 15, 51. 
 
 VIII.— Clement of Alex. Strom, iv. 2, p. 565. 
 
 Theodoretus, Therap. i. p. 15, 52. 
 
 IX. — Suidas, under word a/u(pL0-j3arelv. 'AfityioBaTtlv. evlol to afxtyicfirjT&v 
 "luveg de nai ayxifiarzlv, koX ayx L (^ aGLr l v 'Hpd/cAeirof. 
 
 X. — Themistius, Or. v. p. 69 (= xii. p. 159). Context : — Nature 
 according to Heraclitus, loves to conceal herself ; and before nature 
 the creator of nature, whom therefore we especially worship and 
 adore because the knowledge of him is difficult. 
 
 Philo, Qu. in Gen. iv. 1, p. 237, Aucher.: Arbor est secundum 
 Heraclitum natura nostra, quae se obducere atque abscondere amat. 
 
 Compare idem de Profug. 32, p. 573 ; de Somn. i. 2, p. 621 ; de 
 Spec. legg. 8, p. 344. 
 
 XI.— Plutarch, de Pyth. orac. 21, p. 404. Context :— And I think 
 you know the saying of Heraclitus that "The God," etc. 
 
 Iamblichus, de Myst. hi. 15. 
 
 Idem from Stobaeus Floril. lxxxi. 17. 
 
 Anon, from Stobaeus Floril. v. 72. 
 
 Compare Lucianus, Vit. auct. 14. 
 
 XII.— Plutarch, de Pyth. orac. 6, p. 397. Context :— But the 
 Sibyl, with raging mouth, according to Heraclitus, uttering things 
 solemn, rude and unadorned, reaches with her voice over a 
 
ON NATURE. 87 
 
 XIII. — Whatever concerns seeing, hearing, and 
 learning, I particularly honor. 3 iS 
 
 XI V. — Polybius iv. 40. Especially at the present 
 time, when all places are accessible either by land or by 
 water, we should not accept poets and mythologists as 
 witnesses of things that are unknown, since for the 
 most part they furnish us with unreliable testimony 
 about disputed things, according to Heraclitus. 
 
 XV. — The eyes are more exact witnesses than the 
 ears. 4 
 
 thousand years, because of the God. And Pindar says that Cadmus 
 heard from the God a kind of music neither pleasant nor soft nor 
 melodious. For great holiness permits not the allurements of 
 pleasures. 
 
 Clement of Alex. Strom, i. 15, p. 358. 
 
 Iamblichus, de Myst. iii. 8. 
 
 See also pseudo-Heraclitus, Epist. viii. 
 * XIII. — Hippolytus, Kef. haer. ix. 9, 10. Context : — And that 
 the hidden, the unseen and unknown to men is [better], he (Hera- 
 clitus) says in these words, "A hidden harmony is better than a 
 visible " (= frag. 47). He thus praises and admires the unknown and 
 unseen more than the known. And that that which is discoverable 
 and visible to men is [better], he says in these words, "Whatever 
 concerns seeing, hearing, and learning, I particularly honor," that 
 is. the visible above the invisible. From such expressions it is easy 
 to understand him. In the knowledge of the visible, he says, men 
 allow themselves to be deceived as Homer was, who yet was wiser 
 than all the Greeks ; for some boys killing lice deceived him saying, 
 " What we see and catch we leave behind ; what we neither see nor 
 catch we take with us" (frag. 1, Schuster). Thus Heraclitus honors 
 in equal degree the seen and the unseen, as if the seen and unseen 
 were confessedly one. For what does he say? " A hidden harmony 
 is better than a visible," and, "Whatever concerns seeing, hearing, 
 and learning, I particularly honor," having before particularly 
 honored the invisible. 
 
 XV. — Polybius xii. 27. Context : — There are two organs given to 
 us by nature, sight and hearing, sight being considerably the more 
 truthful, according to Heraclitus, "For the eyes are more exact 
 witnesses than the ears." 
 
 Compare Herodotus i. 8. 
 
88 HERACLITUS. 
 
 XVI. — Much learning does not teach one to have 
 understanding, else it would have taught Hesiod and 
 Pythagoras, and again Xenophanes and Hecataeus. 
 
 XVII. — Pythagoras, son of Mnesarchus, practised 
 investigation most of all men, and having chosen out 
 these treatises, he made a wisdom of his own — much 
 learning and bad art. 
 
 XVIII. — Of all whose words I have heard, no one 
 attains to this, to know that wisdom is apart from all. 5 
 
 XIX. — There is one wisdom, to understand the intel- 
 ligent will by which all things are governed through 
 all. 6 
 
 XX. — This world, the same for all, neither any of 
 
 XVI. — Diogenes Laert. ix. 1. Context : — He (Heraclitus) was 
 proud and disdainful above all men, as indeed is clear from his 
 work, in which he says, " Much learning does not teach," etc. 
 
 Aulus Gellius, N. A. praef. 12. 
 
 Clement of Alex. Strom, i. 19, p. 373. 
 
 Athenaeus xiii. p. 610 B. 
 
 Iulianus, Or. vi. p. 187 D. 
 
 Proclus in Tim. 31 F. 
 
 Serenus in Excerpt. Flor. Ioann. Damasc. ii. 116, p. 205, Meinek. 
 
 Compare pseudo-Democritus, f r. mor. 140 Mullach. 
 
 XVII. — Diogenes Laert. viii. 6. Context : — Some say, foolishly, 
 that Pythagoras did not leave behind a single writing. But Hera- 
 clitus, the physicist, in his croaking way says, " Pythagoras, son of 
 Mnesarchus," etc. 
 
 Compare Clement of Alex. Strom, i. 21, p. 396. 
 
 XVIIL— Stobaeus Floril. iii. 81. 
 
 XIX. — Diogenes Laert. ix. 1. Context : — See frag. 16. 
 
 Plutarch, de Iside 77, p. 382. Context : — Nature, who lives and 
 sees, and has in herself the beginning of motion and a knowledge of 
 the suitable and the foreign, in some way draws an emanation and 
 a share from the intelligence by which the universe is governed, 
 according to Heraclitus. 
 
 Compare Cleanthes H. in Iov. 36. 
 
 Compare pseudo-Linus, 13 Mullach. 
 
 XX. — Clement of Alex. Strom, v. 14, p. 711. Context : — Heracli- 
 tus of Ephesus is very plainly of this opinion, since he recognizes 
 
ON NATURE. 89 
 
 the gods nor any man has made, but it always was, 
 and is, and shall be, an ever living fire, kindled in due 
 measure, and in due measure extinguished. 7 
 
 XXI. — The transmutations of fire are, first, the sea ; 
 and of the sea, half is earth, and half the lightning 
 flash. 8 
 
 XXII. — All things are exchanged for fire and fire for 
 all things, just as wares for gold and gold for wares. 
 
 that there is an everlasting world on the one hand and on the other 
 a perishable, that is, in its arrangement, knowing that in a certain 
 manner the one is not different from the other. But that he knew 
 an everlasting world eternally of a certain kind in its whole essence, 
 he makes plain, saying in this manner, " This world the same for 
 all," etc. 
 
 Plutarch, de Anim. procreat. 5, p. 1014. Context : — This world, 
 says Heraclitus, neither any god nor man has made ; as if fearing 
 that having denied a divine creation, we should suppose the creator 
 of the world to have been some man. 
 
 Simplicius in Aristot. de cael. p. 132, Karst. 
 
 Olympiodorus in Plat. Phaed. p. 201, Finckh. 
 
 Compare Cleanthes H., Iov. 9. 
 
 Xicander, Alexiph. 174. 
 
 Epictetus from Stob. Floril. cviii. 60. 
 
 M. Antoninus vii. 9. 
 
 Just. Mart. Apol. p. 93 C. 
 
 Heraclitus, Alleg. Horn. 26. 
 
 XXI.— Clement of Alex. Strom, v. 14, p. 712. Context :— And that 
 he (Heraclitus) taught that it was created and perishable is shown 
 by the following, "The transmutations," etc. 
 
 Compare Hippolytus, Ref. haer. vi. 17. 
 
 XXII.— Plutarch, de EI. 8, p. 388. Context :— For how that (scil. 
 first cause) forming the world from itself, again perfects itself from 
 the world, Heraclitus declares as follows, " All things are exchanged 
 for fire and fire for all things," etc. 
 
 Compare Philo, Leg. alleg. iii. 3, p. 89. Context, see frag. 24. 
 
 Idem, de Incorr. mundi 21, p. 508.— Lucianus, Vit. auct. 14. 
 
 Diogenes Laert. ix. 8. 
 
 Heraclitus, Alleg. Horn. 43. 
 
 Plotinus, Enn. iv. 8, p. 468.— Iamblichus from Stob. Eel. i. 41. 
 
 •bius, Praep. Evang. xiv. 3, p. 720.— Simplicius on Aristot. 
 Phys. 6, a. 
 
90 HERACLITUS. 
 
 XXIII. — The sea is poured out and measured to the 
 same proportion as existed before it became earth. 9 
 
 XXIV.— Craving and Satiety. 10 
 
 XXV. — Fire lives in the death of earth, air lives in 
 the death of fire, water lives in the death of air, and 
 earth in the death of water. 11 
 
 XXVI. — Fire coming upon all things, will sift and 
 seize them. 
 
 XXIII.— Clement of Alex. Strom, v. 14, p. 712' (= Eusebius, P. E. 
 xiii. 13, p. 676). Context : — For he (Heraclitus) says that fire is 
 changed by the divine Reason which rules the universe, through air 
 into moisture, which is as it were the seed of cosmic arrangement, 
 and which he calls sea ; and from this again arise the earth and the 
 heavens and all they contain. And how again they are restored and 
 ignited, he shows plainly as follows, " The sea is poured out," etc. 
 
 XXIV. — Hippolytus, Ref. haer. ix. 10. Context : — And he (Hera- 
 clitus) says also that this fire is intelligent and is the cause of the 
 government of all things. And he calls it craving and satiety. And 
 craving is, according to him, arrangement (Standc/Livcis), and satiety is 
 conflagration (eKirvpooig). For, he says, " Fire coming upon all things 
 will separate and seize them" (= frag. 26). 
 
 Philo, Leg. alleg. iii. 3, p. 88. Context : — And the other (scil. 
 6 yovoppvfc), supposing that all things are from the world and are 
 changed back into the world, and thinking that nothing was made 
 by God, being a champion of the Heraclitic doctrine, introduces 
 craving and satiety and that all things are one and happen by 
 change. 
 
 Philo, de Victim. 6, p. 242. 
 
 Plutarch, de EI. 9, p. 389. 
 
 XXV.— Maximus Tyr. xli. 4, p. 489. Context:— You see the 
 change of bodies and the alternation of origin, the way up and 
 down, according to Heraclitus. And again he says, "Living in 
 their death and dying in their life (see frag. 67). Fire lives in the 
 death of earth," etc. 
 
 M. Antoninus iv. 46. Context, see frag. 5. 
 
 Plutarch, de EI. 18, p. 392. 
 
 Idem, de Prim. frig. 10, p. 949. Comp. pseudo-Linus 21, Mull. 
 
 XXVI. — Hippolytus, Ref. haer. ix. 10. Context, see frag. 24. 
 
 Compare Aetna v. 536 : quod si quis lapidis miratur fusile robur, 
 cogitet obscuri verissima dicta libelli, Heraclite, tui, nihil insuper- 
 abile ab igni, omnia quo rerum naturae semina iacta. 
 
ON NATURE. 91 
 
 XXVII. — How can one escape that which never 
 sets? 12 
 
 XXVIII. — Lightning rules all. 
 
 XXIX. — The sun will not overstep his bounds, for if 
 he does, the Erinyes, helpers of justice, will find him 
 out. 
 
 XXX. — The limits of the evening and morning are 
 the Bear, and opposite the Bear, the bounds of bright 
 Zeus. 
 
 XXXI. — If there were no sun, it would be night. 
 
 XXVII.— Clement of Alex. Paedag. ii. 10, p. 229. Context :— For 
 one may escape the sensible light, but the intellectual it is impossible 
 to escape. Or, as Heraclitus says, " How can one escape that which 
 never sets?" 
 
 XXVIII. — Hippolytus, Kef. haer. ix. 10. Context : — And he (Hera- 
 clitus) also says that a judgment of the world and all things in it 
 takes place by fire, expressing it as follows, "Now lightning rules 
 all," that is, guides it rightly, meaning by lightning, everlasting fire. 
 
 Compare Cleanthes H., Iovem 10. 
 
 XXIX.— Plutarch, de Exil. II, p. 604. Context :— Each of the 
 planets, rolling in one sphere, as in an island, preserves its order. 
 " For the sun," says Heraclitus, " will not overstep his bounds," etc. 
 
 Idem, de Iside 48, p. 370. 
 
 Comp. Hippolytus, Ref . haer. vi. 26. 
 
 Iamblichus, Protrept. 21, p. 132, Arcer. 
 
 Pseudo-Heraclitus, Epist. ix. 
 
 XXX. — Strabo i. 6, p. 3. Context : — And Heraclitus, better and 
 more Homerically, naming in like manner the Bear instead of the 
 northern circle, says, "The limits of the evening and morning 
 are the Bear, and opposite the Bear, the bounds of bright Zeus." 
 For the northern circle is the boundary of rising and setting, not the 
 Bear. 
 
 XXXI. — Plutarch, Aq. et ign. comp. 7, p. 957. 
 
 Idem, de Fortuna 3, p. 98. Context : — And just as, if there were 
 no sun, as far as regards the other stars, we should have night, as 
 Heraclitus says, so as far as regards the senses, if man had not mind 
 and reason, his life would not differ from that of the beasts. 
 Compare Clement of Alex. Protrept. II, p. 87. 
 
 Macrobius, Somn. Scip. i. 20. 
 
92 HERACLITUS. 
 
 XXXII. — The sun is new every day. 
 
 XXXIII.— Diogenes Laertius i. 23. He (soil. Thales) 
 seems, according to some, to have been the first to 
 study astronomy and to foretell the eclipses and 
 motions of the sun, as Eudemus relates in his account 
 of astronomical works. And for this reason he is 
 honored by Xenophanes and Herodotus, and both 
 Heraclitus and Democritus bear witness to him. 
 
 XXXIV.— Plutarch, Qu. Plat. viii. 4, p. 1007. Thus 
 Time, having a necessary union and connection with 
 heaven, is not simple motion, but, so to speak, motion 
 in an order, having measured limits and periods. Of 
 which the sun, being overseer and guardian to limit, 
 direct, appoint and proclaim the changes and seasons 
 which, according to Heraclitus, produce all things, is 
 the helper of the leader and first God, not in small or 
 trivial things, but in the greatest and most important. 
 
 XXXV. — Hesiod is a teacher of the masses. They 
 suppose him to have possessed the greatest knowledge, 
 who indeed did not know day and night. For they 
 are one. 13 
 
 XXXII.— Aristotle, Meteor, ii. 2, p. 355 a 9. Context :— Con- 
 cerning the sun this cannot happen, since, being nourished in the 
 same manner, as they say, it is plain that the sun is not only, as 
 Heraclitus says, new every day, but it is continually new. 
 
 Alexander Aphrod. in Meteor. 1. 1. fol. 93 a. 
 
 Olympiodorus in Meteor. 1. 1. fol. 30 a. 
 
 Plotinus, Enn. ii. 1, p. 97. 
 
 Proclus in Tim. p. 334 B. 
 
 Compare Plato, Eep. vi. p. 498 B. 
 
 Olympiodorus in Plato, Phaed. p. 201, Finckh. 
 
 XXXIV.— Compare Plutarch, de Def. orac. 12, p. 416. 
 
 M. Antoninus ix. 3. 
 
 Pseudo-Heraclitus, Epist. v. 
 
 XXXV. — Hippolytus, Eef . haer. ix. 10. Context : — Heraclitus says 
 that neither darkness nor light, neither evil nor good, are different, 
 but they are one and the same. He found fault, therefore, with 
 
ON NATURE. 93 
 
 XXXVI. — God is day and night, winter and sum- 
 mer, war and peace, plenty and want. But he is 
 changed, just as when incense is mingled with incense, 
 but named according to the pleasure of each. 14 
 
 XXXVII.— Aristotle, de Sensu 5, p. 443 a 21. Some 
 think that odor consists in smoky exhalation, common 
 to earth and air, and that for smell all things are con- 
 verted into this. And it was for this reason that 
 Heraclitus thus said that if all existing things should 
 become smoke, perception would be by the nostrils. 
 
 XXXVIII.— Souls smell in Hades. 15 
 
 XXXIX. — Cold becomes warm, and warm, cold ; wet 
 becomes dry, and dry, wet. 
 
 XL. — It disperses and gathers, it comes and goes. 16 
 
 Hesiod because he knew [not] day and night, for day and night, he 
 says, are one, expressing it somewhat as follows: "Hesiod is a 
 teacher of the masses," etc. 
 
 XXXVI. — Hippolytus, Ref. haer. ix. 10. Context: — For that the 
 primal (Gr. irp&rw, Bernays reads TTocTjrdv, created) world is itself the 
 demiurge and creator of itself, he (Heraclitus) says as follows : 
 " God is day and," etc. 
 
 Compare idem, Ref. haer. v. 21. 
 
 Hippocrates, ~epl dtairr/g i. 4, Littr. 
 
 XXXVIII.— Plutarch, de Fac. in orbe lun. 28, p. 943. Context :— 
 Their (scil. the souls') appearance is like the sun's rays, and their 
 spirits, which are raised aloft, as here, in the ether around the moon, 
 are like fire, and from this they receive strength and power, as 
 metals do by tempering. For that which is still scattered and 
 diffuse is strengthened and becomes firm and transparent, so that it 
 is nourished with the chance exhalation. And finely did Heraclitus 
 say that "souls smell in Hades." 
 
 XXXIX. — Schol. Tzetzae, Exeget. Iliad, p. 126, Hermann. Con- 
 text : — Of old, Heraclitus of Ephesus was noted for the obscurity of 
 sayings, ''Cold becomes warm," etc. 
 mpare Hippocrates, mpl diairqg i. 21. 
 
 Pseudo-Heraclitus, Epist. v. — Apuleius, de Mundo 21. 
 
 XL.— Plutarch, de EI. 18, p. 392. Context, see frag. 41. 
 
 Compare r^seudo-Heraclitus, Epist. vi. 
 
94 HERACLITUS. 
 
 XLI. — Into the same river you could not step twice, 
 for other <and still other> waters are flowing. 
 
 XLII. — fTo those entering the same river, other and 
 still other waters flow.f 
 
 XLIIL— Aristotle, Eth. Eud. vii. 1, p. 1235 a 26. 
 And Heraclitus blamed the poet who said, " Would 
 
 XLI. — Plutarch, Qu. nat. 2, p. 912. Context : — For the waters of 
 fountains and rivers are fresh and new, for, as Heraclitus says, 
 " Into the same river," etc. 
 
 Plato, Crat. 402 A. Context : — Heraclitus is supposed to say that 
 all things are in motion and nothing at rest ; he compares them to 
 the stream of a river, and says that you cannot go into the same 
 river twice (Jowett's transl.). 
 
 Aristotle, Metaph. iii. 5, p. 1010 a 13. Context :— From this 
 .assumption there grew up that extreme opinion of those just now 
 mentioned, those, namely, who professed to follow Heraclitus, such 
 as Cratylus held, who finally thought that nothing ought to be said, 
 but merely moved his finger. And he blamed Heraclitus because 
 he said you could not step twice into the same river, for he himself 
 thought you could not do so once. 
 
 Plutarch, de EI. 18, p. 392. Context :— It is not possible to step 
 twice into the same river, according to Heraclitus, nor twice to find 
 a perishable substance in a fixecLstate ; but by the sharpness and 
 quickness of change, it disperses and gathers again, or rather not 
 again nor a second time, but at the same time it forms and is 
 dissolved, it comes and goes (see frag. 40). 
 
 Idem, de Sera num. vind. 15, p. 559. 
 
 Simplicius in Aristot. Phys. f . 17 a. 
 
 XLII.— Arius Didymus from Eusebius, Praep. evang. xv. 20, p. 821. 
 Context : — Concerning the soul, Cleanthes, quoting the doctrine of 
 Zeno in comparison with the other physicists, said that Zeno affirmed 
 the perceptive soul to be an exhalation, just as Heraclitus did. For, 
 wishing to show that the vaporized souls are always of an intellectual 
 nature, he compared them to a river, saying, "To those entering the 
 same river, other and still other waters flow." And souls are 
 exhalations from moisture. Zeno, therefore, like Heraclitus, called 
 the soul an exhalation. 
 
 Compare Sextus Emp. Pyrrh. hyp. iii. 115. 
 
 XLIIL— Plutarch, de Iside 48, p. 370. Context :— For Heraclitus 
 in plain terms calls war the father and king and lord of all (= frag. 
 44), and he says that Homer, when he prayed—" Discord be damned 
 
ON NATURE. 95 
 
 that strife were destroyed from among gods and men." 
 For there could be no harmony without sharps and 
 flats, nor living beings without male and female, 
 which are contraries. 
 
 XLIY. — War is the father and king of all, and has 
 produced some as gods and some as men, and has 
 made some slaves and some free. 
 
 XLV. — They do not understand how that which 
 
 from gods and human race," forgot that he called down curses on 
 the origin of all things, since they have their source in antipathy 
 and war. 
 
 Chalcidius in Tim. 295. 
 
 Simplicius in Aristot. Categ. p. 104 A, ed. Basil. 
 
 Schol. Yen. (A) ad II. xviii, 107. 
 
 Eustathius ad II. xviii. 107, p. 1113, 56. 
 
 XLIY. — Hippolytus, Eef. haer. ix. 9. Context : — And that the 
 father of all created things is created and uncreated, the made and 
 the maker, we hear him (Heraclitus) saying, " War is the father and 
 king of all," etc. 
 
 Plutarch, de Iside 48, p. 370. Context, see frag. 43. 
 
 Proclus in Tim. 54 A (comp. 24 B). 
 
 Compare Chrysippus from Philodem. rr. ev<je(3eiac, vii. p. 81, Gomperz. 
 
 Lucianus, Quomodo hist, conscrib. 2 ; Idem, Icaromen 8. 
 
 XLY. — Hippolytus, Ref. haer. ix. 9. Context, see frag. 1. 
 
 Plato. Symp. 187 A. Context : — And one who pays the least atten- 
 tion will also perceive that in music there is the same reconciliation 
 of opposites ; and I suppose that this must have been the meaning 
 of Heraclitus, though his words are not accurate ; for he says that the 
 One is united by disunion, like the harmony of the bow and the 
 lyre (Jowett's transl.). 
 
 Idem, Soph. 242 D. Context: — Then there are Ionian, and in 
 more recent times Sicilian muses, who have conceived the thought 
 that to unite the two principles is safer ; and they say that being is 
 one and many, which are held together by enmity and friendship, 
 ever parting, ever meeting (idem). 
 
 Plutarch, de Anim. procreat. 27, p. 1026. Context: — And many 
 call this (scil. necessity) destiny. Empedocles calls it love and 
 hatred ; Heraclitus, the harmony of oppositions as of the bow and 
 of the lyre. 
 
 Compare Synesius, de Insomn. 135 A 
 
 Parmenides v. 85, Stein. 
 
96 HERACLITUS. 
 
 separates unites with itself. It is a harmony of oppo- 
 sitions, as in the case of the bow and of the lyre. 17 
 
 XLVL-— Aristotle, Eth. ]S T ic. viii. 2, p. 1155 b 1. In 
 reference to these things, some seek for deeper princi- 
 ples and more in accordance with nature. Euripides 
 says, " The parched earth loves the rain, and the 
 high heaven, with moisture laden, loves earthward to 
 fall." And Heraclitus says, " The unlike is joined 
 together, and from differences results the most beau- 
 tiful harmony, and all things take place by strife." 
 
 XL VII. — The hidden harmony is better than the 
 visible. 18 and3 
 
 XLVIII. — Let us not draw conclusions rashly about 
 the greatest things. 
 
 XLIX. — Philosophers must be learned in very many 
 things. 
 
 L. — The straight and crooked way of the wool- 
 carders is one and the same. 19 
 
 XL VI. — Compare Theophrastus, Metaph. 15. 
 
 Philo, Qu. in Gen. iii. 5, p. 178, Aucher. 
 
 Idem, de Agricult. 31, p. 321. 
 
 XLVII. — Hippolytus, Ref. haer. ix. 9-10. Context, see frag. 13. 
 
 Plutarch, de Anim. procreat. 27, p. 1026. Context : — Of the soul 
 nothing is pure and unmixed nor remains apart from the rest, for, 
 according to Heraclitus, " The hidden harmony is better than the 
 visible," in which the blending deity has hidden and sunk varia- 
 tions and differences. 
 
 Compare Plotinus, Enn. i. 6, p. 53. 
 
 Proclus in Cratyl. p. 107, ed. Boissonad. 
 
 XLVIII. — Diogenes Laert. ix. 73. Context: — Moreover, Hera- 
 clitus says, " Let us not draw conclusions rashly about the greatest 
 things." And Hippocrates delivered his opinions doubtfully and 
 moderately. 
 
 XLIX.— Clement of Alex. Strom, v. 14, p. 733. Context :— Philo- 
 sophers must be learned in very many things, according to Hera- 
 clitus. And, indeed, it is necessary that " he who wishes to be good 
 shall often err." ' 
 
 L. — Hippolytus, Ref. haer. ix. 10. Context : — And both straight 
 
OX NATURE. 97 
 
 LI. — Asses would choose stubble rather than gold. 
 
 LIL — Sea water is very pure and very foul, for, 
 while to fishes it is drinkable and healthful, to men it 
 is hurtful and unfit to drink. 
 
 LIII. — Columella, de Re Rustica viii. 4. Dry dust 
 and ashes must be placed near the wall where the roof 
 or eaves shelter the court, in order that there may be 
 a place where the birds may sprinkle themselves, for 
 with these things they improve their wings and 
 feathers, if we may believe Heraclitus, the Ephesian, 
 who says, " Hogs wash themselves in mud and doves 
 in dust." 
 
 LIY. — They revel in dirt. 
 
 and crooked, he (Heraclitus) says, are the same : " The way of the 
 wool-carders is straight and crooked." The revolution of the in- 
 strument in a carder's shop (Gr. yvaoeico Bernays, ypa&eiu vulg.) called 
 a screw is straight and crooked, for it moves at the same time 
 forward and in a circle. " It is one and the same," he says. 
 
 Compare Apuleius, de Mundo 21. 
 
 LI.— Aristotle, Eth. Nic. x. 5, p. 1176 a 6. Context :— The pleasures 
 of a horse, a dog, or a man, are all different. As Heraclitus says, 
 "'Asses would choose stubble rather than gold," for to them there 
 is more pleasure in fodder than in gold. 
 
 LIL — Hippolytus, Ref . haer. ix. 10. Context : — And foul and 
 fresh, he (Heraclitus) says, are one and the same. And drinkable 
 and undrinkable are one and the same. "Sea water," he says, " is 
 very pure and very foul," etc. 
 
 Compare Sextus Empir. Pyrrh. hyp. i. 55. 
 
 LIII. — Compare Galenus, Protrept. 13, p. 5, ed. Bas. 
 
 LIV.— Athenaeus v. p. 178 F. Context :— For it would be unbe- 
 coming, says Aristotle, to go to a banquet covered with sweat and 
 dust. For a well-bred man should not be squalid nor slovenly nor 
 delight in dirt, as Heraclitus says. 
 
 Clement of Alex. Protrept. 10, p. 75. 
 
 Idem, Strom, i. 1, p. 317 ; ii. 15, p. 465. 
 
 Compare Sextus Empir. Pyrrh. hyp. i. 55. 
 
 Plotinus, Enn. i. 6, p. 55. 
 
 Vincentius Bellovac. Spec. mor. iii. 9, 3. 
 
98 HERACLITUS. 
 
 LV. — Every animal is driven by blows. 20 
 
 LVI. — The harmony of the world is a harmony of 
 oppositions, as in the case of the bow and of the lyre. 21 
 
 LYII. — Good and evil are the same. 
 
 LYIII. — Hippolytus, Ref. haer. ix. 10. And good and 
 evil (soil, are one). The physicians, therefore, says 
 Heraclitus, cutting, cauterizing, and in every way tor- 
 turing the sick, complain that the patients do not pay 
 them fitting reward for thus effecting these benefits— 
 fand sufferings. f 
 
 LV. — Aristotle, de Mundo 6, p. 401 a 8 (rzApuleius, de Mundo 
 36 ; Stobaeus, Eel. i. 2, p. 86). Context : — Both wild and domestic 
 animals, and those living upon land or in air or water, are born, live 
 and die in conformity with the laws of God. " For every animal," 
 as Heraclitus says, " is driven by blows" {ttIvyv Stobaeus cod. A, 
 Bergkius et al.; vulg. r?> yfjv vijuerac, every animal feeds upon the 
 earth). 
 
 L VI. —Plutarch, de Tranquill. 15, p. 473. Context : — For the har- 
 mony of the world is a harmony of oppositions (Gr. rcaUvrovog apfiovirj, 
 see Crit. Note 21), as in the case of the bow and of the lyre. And in 
 human things there is nothing that is pure and unmixed. But just 
 as in music, some notes are flat and some sharp, etc. 
 
 Idem, de Iside 45, p. 369. Context :— "For the harmony of the 
 world is a harmony of opposition, as in the case of the bow and of the 
 lyre," according to Heraclitus; and according to Euripides, neither 
 good nor bad may be found apart, but are mingled together for the 
 sake of greater beauty. 
 
 Porphyrius, de Antro. nymph. 29. 
 
 Simplicius in Phys. fol. 11 a. 
 
 Compare Philo, Qu. in Gen. iii. 5, p. 178, Aucher. 
 
 LVII. — Hippolytus, Eef . haer. ix. 10. Context, see frag. 58. 
 
 Simplicius in Phys. fol. 18 a. Context : — All things are with others 
 identical, and the saying of Heraclitus is true that the good and the 
 evil are the same. 
 
 Idem on Phys. fol. 11 a. 
 
 Aristotle, Top. viii. 5, p. 159 b 30. 
 
 Idem, Phys. i. 2, p. 185 b 20. 
 
 LVIII. — Compare Xenophon, Mem. i. 2, 54. 
 
 Plato, Gorg. 521 E ; Polit. 293 B. 
 
 Simplicius in Epictetus 13, p. 83 D and 27, p. 178 A, ed. Heins. 
 
OX NATURE. 99 
 
 LIX. — Unite whole and part, agreement and dis- 
 agreement, accordant and discordant; from all comes 
 one. and from one all. 
 
 LX. — They would not know the name of justice, 
 were it not for these things. 22 
 
 LXL— Schol. B. in Iliad iv. 4, p. 120 Bekk. They say 
 that it is unfitting that the sight of wars should please 
 the gods. But it is not so. For noble works delight 
 them, and while wars and battles seem to us terrible, 
 to God they do not seem so. For God in his dispensa- 
 tion of all events, perfects them into a harmony of the 
 whole, just as, indeed, Heraclitus says that to God all 
 things are beautiful and good and right, though men 
 suppose that some are right and others wrong. 
 
 LXII. — We must know that war is universal and 
 strife right, and that by strife all things arise and fare 
 used.i 23 
 
 LIX. — Aristotle, de Mundo 5, p. 396 b 12 (rr Apuleius, deMundo 
 20 ; Stobaeus, Eel. i. 34, p. 690). Context : — And again art, imitator of 
 nature, appears to do the same. For in painting, it is by the mixing 
 of colors, as white and black or yellow and red, that representations 
 are made corresponding with the natural types. In music also, from 
 the union of sharps and flats comes a final harmony, and in gram- 
 mar, the whole art depends on the blending of mutes and vocables. 
 And it was the same thing which the obscure Heraclitus meant when 
 he said, " Unite whole and part," etc. 
 
 Compare Apuleius, de Mundo 21. 
 
 Hippocrates ~. -pogfjq 40 ; - Stalr^g i. 
 
 LX. — Clement of Alex. Strom, iv. 3, p. 568. Context : — For the 
 Scripture says, the law is not made for the just man. And Heracli- 
 tus well says, " They would not know the name of justice, were it 
 not for these things." 
 
 Compare pseudo-Heraclitus, Epist. vii. 
 
 LXL — Compare Hippocrates, ~epl diaiTqq i. xi. 
 
 LXII.— Origen, cont. Celsus vi. 42, p. 312 (Celsus speaking). Con- 
 — There was an obscure saying of the ancients that war was 
 divine, Heraclitus writing thus, " We must know that war," etc. 
 
 Compare Plutarch, de Sol. animal. 7, p. 904. 
 
 Diogenes Laert. ix. 8. 
 
100 HERACLITUS. 
 
 LXIII. — For it is wholly destined . 
 
 LXIV. — Death is what we see waking. What we see 
 in sleep is a dream. 24 
 
 LXV. — There is only one supreme Wisdom. It wills 
 and wills not to be called by the name of Zeus. 25 
 
 LXYI. — The name of the bow is life, but its work is 
 death. 
 
 LXVII. — Immortals are mortal, mortals immortal, 
 living in their death and dying in their life. 
 
 LXIII. — Stobaeus Eel. i. 5, p. 178. Context : — Heraclitus declares 
 that destiny is the all-pervading law. And this is the etherial body, 
 the seed of the origin of all things, and the measure of the appointed 
 course. All things are by fate, and this is the same as necessity. 
 
 Thus he writes, "For it is wholly destined " (The rest is 
 
 wanting). 
 
 LXIV. — Clement of Alex. Strom, iii. 3, p. 520. Context: — And 
 does not Heraclitus call death birth, similarly with Pythagoras and 
 with Socrates in the Gorgias, when he says, " Death is what we see 
 waking. What we see in sleep is a dream " ? 
 
 Compare idem v. 14, p. 712. Philo, de Ioseph. 22, p. 59. 
 
 LXV.— Clement of Alex. Strom, v. 14, p. 718 (Euseb. P. E. xiii. 
 13, p. 681). Context : — I know that Plato also bears witness to Hera- 
 clitus' writing, " There is only one supreme Wisdom. It wills and 
 wills not to be called by the name of Zeus." And again, " Law is 
 to obey the will of one " (=. frag. 110). 
 
 LXVL— Schol. in Iliad i. 49, fr. Cramer, A. P. iii. p. 122. Con- 
 text : — For it seems that by the ancients the bow and life were syn- 
 onymously called (3t6g. So Heraclitus, the obscure, said, " The name 
 of the bow is life, but its work is death." 
 
 Etym. magn. under word fiidg. 
 
 Tzetze's Exeg. in Iliad, p. 101 Herm. 
 
 Eustathius in Iliad i. 49, p. 41. 
 
 Compare Hippocrates, v. rpo<f>?jc 21. 
 
 LXVII. — Hippolytus, Eef. haer. ix. 10. Context: — And con- 
 fessedly he (Heraclitus) asserts that the immortal is mortal and the 
 mortal immortal, in such words as these, "Immortals are mortal," 
 etc. 
 
 Numenius from Porphyr. de Antro nymph. 10. Context, see 
 frag. 72. 
 
ON NATURE. 101 
 
 LXVIII. — To souls it is death to become water, and 
 to water it is death to become earth, but from earth 
 comes water, and from water, soul. 
 
 LXIX. — The way upward and downward are one 
 and the same. 
 
 Philo, Leg. alleg. i. 33, p. 65. 
 
 Idem, Qu. in Gen. iv. 152, p. 360 Aucher. 
 
 Maximus Tyr. x. 4, p. 107. Idem, xli. 4, p. 489. 
 
 Clement of Alex. Paed. iii. 1, p. 251. 
 
 Hierocles in Aur. carm. 24. 
 
 Heraclitus, Alleg. Horn. 24, p. 51 Mehler. 
 
 Compare Lucianus, Vit. auct. 14. 
 
 Dio Cassius frr. i — xxxv. c. 30, t. i. p. 40 Dind. 
 
 Hermes from Stob. Eel. i. 39, p. 768. Idem, Poemand. 12, p. 100. 
 
 LXVIII.— Clement of Alex. Strom, vi. 2, p. 746. Context :— (On 
 plagiarisms) And Orpheus having written, " Water is death to the 
 soul and soul the change from water ; from water is earth and from 
 earth again water, and from this the soul welling up through the 
 whole ether"; Heraclitus, combining these expressions, writes as 
 follows : " To souls it is death," etc. 
 
 Hippolytus, Ref. haer. v. 16. Context : — And not only do the 
 poets say this, but already also the wisest of the Greeks, of whom 
 Heraclitus was one, who said, ''For the soul it is death to become 
 water." 
 
 Philo, de Incorr. mundi 21, p. 509. Proclus in Tim. p. 36 C. 
 
 Aristides, Quintil. ii. p. 106, Meib. 
 
 Iulianus, Or. v. p. 165 D. 
 
 Olympiodorus in Plato, Gorg. p. 357 Iahn ; Idem, p. 542. 
 
 LXIX. — Hippolytus, Ref. haer. ix. 10. Context : — Up and down he 
 (Heraclitus) says are one and the same. "The way upward and 
 downward are one and the same." 
 
 Diogenes Laert. ix. 8. Context : — Heraclitus says that change is 
 the road leading upward and downward, and that the whole world 
 exists according to it. 
 
 Cleomedes, -. fj-ereupuv i. p. 75, Bak. 
 
 Maximus Tyr. xli. 4, p. 489. 
 
 Plotinus, Enn. iv. 8, p. 468. 
 
 Tertullian, adv. Marc. ii. 28. 
 
 Iamblichus from Stob. Eel. i. 41. 
 
 Compare Hippocrates, k. rpofifc 45. 
 
 M. Antoninus vi. 17. 
 
102 HERACLITUS. 
 
 LXX. — The beginning and end are common. 
 
 LXXI. The limits of the soul you would not find 
 out, though you should traverse every way. 
 
 LXXIL — To souls it is joy to become wet. 26 
 
 LXXIIL— A man when he is drunken is led by 
 a beardless youth, stumbling, ignorant where he is 
 going, having a wet soul. 
 
 LXXIY. — The dry soul is the wisest and best. 27 
 
 Philo, de Incorr. mundi 21, p. 508. 
 
 Idem, de Somn. i. 24, p. 644. 
 
 Idem, de vit. Moys. i. 6, p. 85. 
 
 Musonius from Stob. Flo. 108, 60. 
 
 LXX— Porphyry from Schol. B. Iliad xiv. 200, p. 392, Bekk. 
 Context : — For the beginning and end on the periphery of the circle 
 are common, according to Heraclitus. 
 
 Compare Hippocrates, w.. tottov rav kclt' avdporrov, 1. 
 
 Idem, 7T. diairrjq i. 19 ; tc. rpo<j)?jg } 9. 
 
 Philo, Leg. alleg. i. 3, p. 44. Plutarch, de EL 8, p. 388. 
 
 LXXI. — Diogenes Laert. ix. 7. Context : — And he (Heraclitus) 
 also says, "The limits of the soul you would not find out though 
 you traverse every way," so deep lies its principle (ovtg) fladvv loyov 
 ixei). 
 
 Tertullian, de Anima 2. 
 
 Compare Hippolytus, Ref. haer. v. 7. 
 
 Sextus, Enchir. 386. 
 
 LXXIL — Numenius from Porphyry, de Antro nymph. 10. Con- 
 text : — Wherefore Heraclitus says : To souls it is joy, not death, to 
 become wet. And elsewhere he says : We live in their death and 
 they live in our death (frag. 67). 
 
 LXXIIL— Stobaeus Floril. v. 120. 
 
 Compare M. Antoninus iv. 46. Context, see frag. 5. 
 
 LXXIV. — Plutarch, Romulus 28. Context : — For the dry soul is 
 the wisest and best, according to Heraclitus. It flashes through the 
 body as the lightning through the cloud (=fr. 63, Schleiermacher). 
 
 Aristides, Quintil. ii. p. 106. 
 
 Porphyry, de Antro nymph. 11. 
 
 Synesius, de Insomn. p. 140 A Petav. 
 
 Stobaeus Floril. v. 120. 
 
 Glycas, Ann. i. p. 74 B (compare 116 A). 
 
 Compare Clement of Alex. Paedag. ii. 2, p. 184. 
 
 Eustathius in Iliad xxiii. 261, p. 1299, 17 ed. Rom. 
 
ON NATURE. 103 
 
 LXXY. — |Tlie dry beam is the wisest and best soul.f 
 
 LXXYL — | Where the land is dry, the sonl is wisest 
 and best.t 27 
 
 LXXVII. — Man, as a light at night, is lighted and 
 extinguished. 28 
 
 LXXYIIL— Plutarch, Consol. ad Apoll. 10, p. 106. 
 For when is death not present with us ? As indeed 
 Heraclitus says : Living and dead, awake and asleep, 
 young and old, are the same. For these several states 
 are transmutations of each other. 
 
 LXXIX. — Time is a child playing at draughts, a 
 child's kingdom. 
 
 LXXV.— Philo from Euseb. P. E. viii. 14, p. 399. 
 
 Musonius from Stob. Floril. xvii. 43. 
 
 Plutarch, de Esu. earn. i. 6, p. 995. 
 
 Idem, de Def. orac. 41, p. 432. 
 
 Galenus, re. rav rf/g fvxvc ifl&v 5, t. i. p. 346, ed. Bas. 
 
 Hermeias in Plat. Phaedr. p. 73, Ast. 
 
 Compare Porphyry, a^opji. rrpbg rd vorj-d 33, p. 78 Hoist. ; Ficinus, de 
 Immort. anim. viii. 13. 
 
 LXXYL— Philo from Euseb. P. E. vi. 14, p. 399. 
 
 Idem, de Provid. ii. 109, p. 117, Aucher. 
 
 LXXYIL— Clement of Alex. Strom, iv. 22, p. 628. Context :— 
 Whatever they say of sleep, the same must be understood of death, 
 for it is plain that each of them is a departure from life, the one less, 
 the other more. Which is also to be received from Heraclitus : 
 Man is kindled as a light at night ; in like manner, dying, he is 
 extinguished. And living, he borders upon death while asleep, and, 
 extinguishing sight, he borders upon sleep when awake. 
 
 Compare Sextos Empir. adv. Math. vii. 130. 
 
 Seneca, Epist. 54. 
 
 LXXYIIL— Compare Plutarch, de EL 18, p. 392. 
 
 Clement of Alex. Strom, iv. 22, p. 628. Context, see frag. 77. 
 
 Sextus Empir. Pyrrh. hyp. iii. 230. 
 
 Tzetze's Chil. ii. 722. 
 
 LXXIX. — Hippolytus, Eef. haer. ix. 9. 
 
 Proclus in Tim. 101 F. Context : — And some, as for example 
 Heraclitus, say that the creator in creating the world is at play. 
 
 Lucianus, Vit. auct. 14. Context :— And what is time ? A child 
 at play j now arranging his pebbles, now scattering them. 
 
104 HERACLITUS. 
 
 LXXX. — I have inquired of myself. 29 
 
 LXXXI. — Into the same river we both step and do 
 not step. We both are and are not. 
 
 LXXXIL— It is weariness upon the same things to 
 labor and by them to be controlled. 30 
 
 Clement of Alex. Paedag. i. 5, p. 111. 
 
 Iamblichus from Stob. Eel. ii. 1, p. 12. 
 
 Compare Plato, Legg. x. 903 D. Philo, de vit. Moys. i. 6, p. 85. 
 
 Plutarch, de EI. 21, p. 393. 
 
 Gregory Naz. Carm. ii. 85, p. 978 ed. Bened. 
 
 LXXX.— Diogenes Laert. ix. 5. Context : — And he (Heraclitus) 
 was a pupil of no one, but he said he inquired of himself and learned 
 everything by himself. 
 
 Plutarch, adv. Colot. 20, p. 1118. Context : — And Heraclitus, as 
 though he had been engaged in some great and solemn task, said, 
 " I have been seeking myself." And of the sentences at Delphi, he 
 thought the "Know thyself " to be the most divine. 
 
 Dio Chrysost. Or. 55, p. 282, Reiske. 
 
 Plotinus, Enn. iv. 8, p. 468. 
 
 Tatianus, Or. ad Graec. 3. 
 
 Iulianus, Or. vi. p. 185 A. 
 
 Proclus in Tim. 106 E. 
 
 Suidas, under word Uoarov/ws. 
 
 Compare Philo, de Ioseph. 22, p. 59. 
 
 Clement of Alex. Strom, ii. 1, p. 429. 
 
 Plotinus, Enn. v. 9, p. 559. 
 
 LXXXI.— Heraclitus, Alleg. Horn. 24. 
 
 Seneca, Epist. 58. Context : — And I, while I say these things are 
 changed, am myself changed. This is what Heraclitus means when 
 he says, into the same river we descend twice and do not descend, 
 for the name of the river remains the same, but the water has 
 flowed on. This in the case of the river is more evident than in 
 case of man, but none the less does the swift course carry us on. 
 
 Compare Epicharmus, fr. B 40, Lorenz. 
 
 Parmenides v. 58, Stein. 
 
 LXXXIL— Plotinus, Enn. iv. 8, p. 468. 
 
 Iamblichus from Stob. Eel. i. 41, p. 906. Context :— For Heraclitus 
 assumed necessary changes from opposites, and supposed that souls 
 traversed the way upward and downward, and that to continue in 
 the same condition is weariness, but that change brings rest 
 (= fr. 83). 
 
 
OX NATURE. 105 
 
 LXXXIII. — In change is rest. 
 
 LXXXIY. — A mixture separates when not kept in 
 motion. 
 
 LXXXY. — Corpses are more worthless than excre- 
 ment. 
 
 LXXXVI. — Being born, they will only to live and 
 die. or rather to find rest, and they leave children who 
 likewise are to die. 
 
 LXXX VII.— Plutarch, de Orac, def. 11, p. 415. 
 
 Aeneas, Gaz. Theophrast. p. 9. 
 
 Compare Hippocrates, ~. Sialrifg i. 15. 
 
 Philo, de Cherub. 26, p. 155. 
 
 LXXXIII.— Plotinus, Enn. iv. 8, p. 468. 
 
 Idem, iv. S, p. 473. 
 
 Iamblichus from Stob. Eel. i. 41, p. 906. Context, see frag. 82. 
 
 Idem, p. 894. 
 
 Aeneas, Gaz. Theophrast. p. 9, Barth. 
 
 Idem, p. 11. 
 
 LXXXIY. — Theophrastus, de Yertigine 9, p. 138 Wimmer. 
 
 Alexander Aprod. Probl. p. 11, Usener. Context :— A mixture 
 (6 kvkeui), as Heraclitus says, separates unless some one stirs it. 
 
 Compare Lucian, Yit. auct. 14. 
 
 M. Antoninus iv. 27. 
 
 LXXXY.— Strabo xvi. 26, p. 784. Context :— They consider dead 
 bodies equal to excrement, just as Heraclitus says, " Corpses are 
 more worthless," etc. 
 
 Plutarch, Qu. conviv. iv. 4, p. 669. 
 
 Pollux, Onom. v. 163. 
 
 Origen, c. Cels. v. 14, p. 247. 
 
 Julian, Or. vii. p. 226 C. 
 
 Compare Philo, de Profug. ii. p. 555. 
 
 Plotinus, Enn. v. 1, p. 483. 
 
 Schol. Y. ad Iliad xxiv. 54, p. 630, Bekk. 
 
 Epictetus, Diss. ii. 4, 5. 
 
 LXXXYI. — Clement of Alex. Strom, iii. 3, p. 516. Context : — 
 Heraclitus appears to be speaking evil of birth when he says, 
 "Being born, they wish only to live," etc. 
 
 LXXXVIL— The reference is to the following passage from 
 •d : 
 
106 HERACLITUS. 
 
 Those who adopt the reading fjft&vroQ (i. e. at man's 
 estate, see Hesiod, fr. 163, ed. Goettling) reckon a gen- 
 eration at thirty years, according to Heraclitus, in 
 which time a father may have a son who is himself at 
 the age of puberty. 
 
 LXXXVIIL— Io. Lydus de Mensibus iii. 10, p. 37, 
 ed. Bonn. Thirty is the most natural number, for it 
 bears the same relation to tens as three to units. Then 
 again it is the monthly cycle, and is composed of the 
 four numbers 1, 4, 9, 16, which are the squares of the 
 units in order. Not without reason, therefore, does 
 Heraclitus call the month a generation. 
 
 LXXXIX. — In thirty years a man may become a 
 grandfather. 
 
 XC. — M. Antoninus vi. 42. "We all work together to 
 one end, some consciously and with purpose, others 
 unconsciously. Just as indeed Heraclitus, I think, 
 says that the sleeping are co-workers and fabricators 
 of the things that happen in the world. 31 
 
 XCI. — The Law of Understanding is common to all. 
 Those who speak with intelligence must hold fast to 
 that which is common to all, even more strongly than 
 
 evv'ea rot ^6et yeveag XanepvC,a mpfovr} 
 av<5f>G)v 7/(3g)vtov • e7ia<pog de re rerpanopav og 
 rpelg d' ekafyovg 6 nopal; yrjpaGKerat. avrap 6 (poiviij 
 evvea rovg nopanag ■ Sena (V q/xeig roiig (frolvinag 
 vv/Lityai evir?i6Ka/Ltot t novpai Aibg atyio^oco. 
 
 Censorinus, de D. N. 17. 
 
 Compare Plutarch, Plac. Philos. v. 24, p. 909. 
 
 LXXXVIIL— Crameri A. P. i. p. 324. 
 
 Compare Philo, Qu. on Gen. ii. 5, p. 82 Aucher. 
 
 Plutarch, de Orac. def. 12, p. 416. 
 
 LXXXIX.— Philo, Qu. in Gen. ii. 5, p. 82 Aucher. 
 
 XCL— Stobaeus Florii. iii. 84. 
 
 Compare Cleanthes H., Iov. 24. 
 
 Hippocrates, tt. rpo^g 15. Plutarch, de Iside 45, p. 369. 
 
 Plotinus, Enn. vi. 5, p. 668. Empedocles v. 231 Stein. 
 
 
ON NATURE. 107 
 
 a city holds fast to its law. For all human laws are 
 dependent upon one divine Law, for this rules as far 
 as it wills, and suffices for all, and overahounds. 
 
 XCIL — Although the Law of Reason is common, the 
 majority of people live as though they had an under- 
 standing of their own. 
 
 XCIII. — They are at variance with that with which 
 they are in most continual association. 
 
 XCIV. — We ought not to act and speak as though 
 we were asleep. 
 
 XCV.— Plutarch, de Superst. 3, p. 166. Heraclitus 
 says : To those who are awake, there is one world in 
 common, but of those who are asleep, each is with- 
 drawn to a private world of his own. 
 
 XCVL— For human nature does not possess under- 
 standing, but the divine does. 
 
 XCIL — Sextus Enip. adv. Math. vii. 133. Context : — For having 
 thus statedly shown that we do and think everything by participa- 
 tion in the divine reason, he (Heraclitus), after some previous expo- 
 sition, adds : It is necessary, therefore, to follow the common (for by 
 he means 6 Koiv6g t the common). For although the law of 
 reason is common, the majority of people live as though they had 
 an understanding of their own. But this is nothing else than an 
 explanation of the mode of the universal disposition. As far, there- 
 fore, as we participate in the memory of this, we are true ; but in as 
 far as we act individually, we are false. 
 
 XCIII. — M. Antoninus iv. 46. Context, see frag. 5. 
 
 XCIV. — M. Antoninus iv. 46. Context, see frag. 5. 
 
 XCV. — Compare pseudo-Pythagoras from Hippolytus, Ref. haer. 
 vi. 26. 
 
 Iamblichus, Protrept. 21, p. 132, Arcer. 
 
 X< VJ .— i trigen, c. Cels. vi. 12, p. 201. Context :— Nevertheless he 
 (Celsus) wanted to show that this was a fabrication of ours and taken 
 from the Greek philosophers, who say that human wisdom is of one 
 kind, and divine wisdom of another. And he brings forward some 
 phrases of Heraclitus, one where he says, "For human nature does 
 not possess understanding, but the divine does." And another, 
 "The thoughtless man understands the voice of the Deity as little 
 as the child understands the man" (—frag. 97). 
 
108 HERACLITUS. 
 
 XCVII. — The thoughtless man understands the 
 voice of the Deity as little as the child understands the 
 man. 33 
 
 XCVIIL— Plato, Hipp. mai. 289 B. And does not 
 Heraclitus, whom you bring forward, say the same, 
 that the wisest of men compared with God appears 
 an ape in wisdom and in beauty and in all other 
 things ? 
 
 XCIX. — Plato, Hipp. mai. 289 A. You are ignorant, 
 my man, that there is a good saying of Heraclitus, to 
 the effect that the most beautiful of apes is ugly when 
 compared with another kind, and the most beautiful 
 of earthen pots is ugly when compared with maiden- 
 kind, as says Hippias the wise. 
 
 C. — The people must fight for their law as for their 
 walls. 
 
 CI. — Greater fates gain greater rewards. 
 
 CII. — Gods and men honor those slain in war. 
 
 CHI. — Presumption must be quenched even more 
 than a fire. 33 
 
 XCVII.— Origen, c. Cels. vi. 12, p. 291. Context, see frag. 96. 
 
 Compare M. Antoninus iv. 46. Context, see frag. 5. 
 
 XCVIIL— Compare M. Antoninus iv. 16. 
 
 XCIX.— Compare Plotinus, Enn. vi. 3, p. 626. 
 
 Aristotle, Top. iii. 2, p. 117 b 17. 
 
 C. — Diogenes Laert. ix. 2. Context : — And he (Heraclitus) used to 
 say, " It is more necessary to quench insolence than a fire " (=: frag. 
 103). And, " The people must fight for their law as for their walls." 
 
 CI. — Clement of Alex. Strom, iv: 7, p. 586. Context : — Again 
 Aeschylus, grasping this thought, says, " To him who toils, glory 
 from the gods is due as product of his toil." " For greater fates gain 
 greater rewards," according to Heraclitus. 
 
 Theodoretus, Therap. viii. p. 117, 33. 
 
 Compare Hippolytus, Ref. haer. v. 8. 
 
 CII. — Clement of Alex. Strom, iv. 4, p. 571. Context : — Heraclitus 
 said, " Gods and men honor those slain in war." 
 
 Theodoretus, Therap. viii. p. 117, 33. 
 
 CIII. — Diogenes Laert. ix. 2. Context, see frag. 100. 
 
ON NATURE. 109 
 
 CIV. — For men to have whatever they wish, would 
 not be well. Sickness makes health pleasant and 
 good ; hunger, satiety ; weariness, rest. 
 
 CV. — It is hard to contend against passion, for 
 whatever it craves it buys with its life. 
 
 CVI. — fit pertains to all men to know themselves 
 and to learn self-control. f 
 
 CVll. — t Self-control is the highest virtue, and wis- 
 dom is to speak truth and consciously to act according 
 to nature. f 34 
 
 CVllI. — It is better to conceal ignorance, but it is 
 hard to do so in relaxation and over wine. 
 
 CIV.— Stobaeus Floril. iii. 83, 4. 
 
 Compare Clement of Alex. Strom, ii. 21, p. 497. 
 
 Theodoretus, Therap. xi. p. 152, 25. Context : — Heraclitus the 
 Ephesian changed the name bnt retained the idea, for in the place 
 of pleasure he put contentment. 
 
 CV.— Iamblichus, Protrept. p. 140, Arcer. Context .-—Heraclitus 
 is a witness to these statements, for he says, "It is hard to contend 
 against passion," etc. 
 
 Aristotle, Eth. Nic. ii. 2, p. 1105 a 8. 
 
 Idem, Eth. Eud. ii. 7, p. 1223 b 22. 
 
 Idem, Pol. v. 11, p. 1315 a 29. 
 
 Plutarch, de Cohib. ira 9, p. 457. 
 
 Idem, Erot. 11, p. 755. 
 
 Compare Plutarch, Coriol. 22. 
 
 Pseudo-Democritus fr. mor. 77, Mullach. 
 
 Longinus, de Subl. 44. 
 
 C VI.— Stobaeus Floril. v. 119. 
 
 CVIL— Stobaeus Floril. iii. 84. 
 
 V 111. — Plutarch, Qu. Conviv. iii. proem., p. 644. Context :— 
 Simonides, the poet, seeing a guest sitting silent at a feast and con- 
 versing with no one, said, " Sir, if you are foolish you are doing 
 wisely, but if wise, foolishly," for, as Heraclitus says, "It is better 
 to conceal ignorance, but it is hard," etc. 
 
 Idem, de Audiendo 12, p. 43. 
 
 Idem, Virt. doc. posse 2, p. 439. 
 
 Idem, from Stob. Floril. xviii. 32. 
 
110 HERACLITUS. 
 
 CIX. — fit is better to conceal ignorance than to ex- 
 pose it.f 
 
 CX. — It is law, also, to obey the will of one. 35 
 
 CXI. — For what sense or understanding have they ? 
 They follow minstrels and take the multitude for a 
 teacher, not knowing that many are bad and few good. 
 For the best men choose one thing above all — immortal 
 glory among mortals ; but the masses stuff themselves 
 like cattle. 
 
 CXII. — In Priene there lived Bias, son of Teutamus, 
 whose word was worth more than that of others. 
 
 CXIII. — To me, one is ten thousand if he be the best. 
 
 CXIY. — The Ephesians deserve, man for man, to be 
 hung, and the youth to leave the city, inasmuch as 
 they have banished Hermodorus, the worthiest man 
 among them, saying : " Let no one of us excel, and if 
 
 CIX.— Stobaeus Floril. iii. 82. 
 
 CX.— Clement of Alex. Strom, v. 14, p. 718 (Euseb. P. E. xiii. 13, 
 p. 681). Context, see frag. 65. 
 
 CXI. — The passage is restored as above by Bernays (Heraclitea i. 
 p. 34), and Bywater (p. 43), from the following sources : 
 
 Clement of Alex. Strom, v. 9, p. 682. 
 
 Proclus in Alcib. p. 255 Creuzer, — 525 ed. Cous. ii. 
 
 Clement of Alex. Strom, iv. 7, p. 586. 
 
 CXII. — Diogenes Laert. i. 88. Context : — And the fault-finding 
 Heraclitus has especially praised him (Bias), writing, "In Priene 
 there lived Bias, son of Teutamus, whose word was worth more than 
 that of others," and the Prienians dedicated to him a grove called 
 the Teutamion. He used to say, " Most men are bad." 
 
 CXIII.— Theodoras Prodromus in Lazerii Miscell. i. p. 20. 
 
 Idem, Tetrastich, in Basil. I (fol. k 2 vers. ed. Bas.). 
 
 Galenus, rrepl 6iayv6a£ug o(/)vyjuo)v i. 1 ; t. 3, p. 53 ed. Bas. 
 
 Symmachus, Epist. ix. 115. 
 
 Compare Epigramm. from Diogenes Laert. ix. 16. 
 
 Cicero, ad. Att. xvi. 11. 
 
 Seneca, Epist. 7. 
 
 CXIV. — Strabo xiv. 25, p. 642. Context : — Among distinguished 
 men of the ancients who lived here (Ephesus) were Heraclitus, 
 
OX NATURE. Ill 
 
 there be any such, let him go elsewhere and among 
 other people." 
 
 CXV. — Dogs, also, bark at what they do not know. 
 
 CXVI. — By its incredibility, it escapes their knowl- 
 edge. 36 
 
 CXVII. — A stupid man loves to be puzzled by every 
 discourse. 
 
 CXYIII. — The most approved of those who are of 
 repute knows how to cheat. Nevertheless, justice will 
 catch the makers and witnesses of lies. 37 
 
 CXIX. — Diogenes Laert. ix. 1. And he (Heraclitus) 
 
 called the obscure, and Herrnodorus, of whom Heraclitus himself 
 said, " The Ephesians deserve," etc. 
 
 Cicero, Tusc. v. 105. 
 
 Musonius from Stob. Floril. xl. 9. 
 
 Diogenes Laert. ix. 2. 
 
 Iamblichus, de Vit. Pyth. 30, p. 154 Arcer. 
 
 Compare Lucian, Vit. auct. 14. 
 
 Pseudo-Diogenes, Epist. 28, 6. 
 
 CXV. — Plutarch, An seni sit ger. resp. vii. p. 787. Context : — And 
 envy, which is the greatest evil public men have to contend with, is 
 least directed against old men. "For dogs, indeed, bark at what 
 they do not know," according to Heraclitus. 
 
 CXVI. —Plutarch, Coriol. 38. Context :— But knowledge of divine 
 things escapes them, for the most part, because of its incredibility, 
 according to Heraclitus. 
 
 Clement of Alex. Strom, v. 13, p. 699. Context, see Crit. Note 36. 
 
 CXVII.— Plutarch, de Audiendo 7, p. 41. Context :— They re- 
 proach Heraclitus for saying, "A stupid man loves," etc. 
 
 Compare idem, de Aud. poet. 9, p. 28. 
 
 < XVIII.— Clement of Alex. Strom, v. 1, p. 649. Context :— " The 
 most approved of those who are of repute knows how to be on his 
 guard {qv'/.accetv, see Crit. Xote 37). Nevertheless, justice will catch 
 the makers and witnesses of lies," says the Ephesian. For this 
 man who was acquainted with the barbarian philosophy, knew of 
 the purification by fire of those who had lived evil lives, which 
 afterwards the Stoics called the conflagration (ek~v(>ojcjiv). 
 
 ' XIX.— Schleiermacher compares Schol. Ven. ad Iliad xviii. 251 
 and Eustathius, p. 1142, 5 ed. Bom., which, however, By water does 
 not regard as referring to Heraclitus of Ephesus. 
 
112 HERACLITUS. 
 
 used to say that Homer deserved to be driven out of 
 the lists and flogged, and Archilochus likewise. 
 
 CXX.— One day is like all. 
 
 CXXI. — A man's character is his daemon. 88 
 
 CXXII. — There awaits men after death what they 
 neither hope nor think. 
 
 CXXIII. — And those that are there shall arise and 
 become guardians of the living and the dead. 39 
 
 CXXIV. — Mght-roamers, Magians, bacchanals, rev- 
 elers in wine, the initiated. 
 
 CXX. — Seneca, Epist. 12. Context : — Heraclitus, who got a nick- 
 name for the obscurity of his writing, said, " One day is like all." 
 His meaning is variously understood. If he meant all days were 
 equal in number of hours, he spoke truly. But others say one day 
 is equal to all in character, for in the longest space of time you 
 would find nothing that is not in one day, both light and night and 
 alternate revolutions of the earth. 
 
 Plutarch, Camill. 19. Context : — Concerning unlucky days, whether 
 we should suppose there are such, and whether Heraclitus did right 
 in reproaching Hesiod who distinguished good and bad days, as 
 being ignorant that the nature of every day is one, has been 
 examined in another place. 
 
 CXXI.— Plutarch, Qu. Platon. i. 2, p. 999. Context :— Did he, 
 therefore (viz. Socrates) call his own nature, which was very critical 
 and productive, God? Just as Menander says, " Our mind is God." 
 And Heraclitus, " A man's character is his daemon." 
 
 Alexander Aphrod. de Fato 6, p. 16, Orell. 
 
 Stobaeus Floril. civ. 23. Comp. pseudo-Heraclitus, Epist. 9. 
 
 CXXII.— Clement of Alex. Strom, iv. 22, p. 630. Context :— With 
 him (Socrates), Heraclitus seems to agree when he says in his dis- 
 course on men, " There awaits men," etc. 
 
 Idem, Protrept. 2, p. 18. Theodoretus, Therap. viii. p. 118, 1. 
 
 Themistius (Plutarch) from Stob. Floril. cxx. 28. 
 
 CXXIII. — Hippolytus, Ref. haer. ix. 10. Context: — And he 
 (Heraclitus) says also that there is a resurrection of this visible flesh 
 of ours, and he knows that God is the cause of this resurrection, 
 since he says, " And those that are there shall arise," etc. 
 
 Compare Clement of Alex. Strom, v. 1, p. 649. 
 
 CXXIV.— Clement of Alex. Protrept. 2, p. 18. Context .-—Rites 
 worthy of the night and of fire, and of the great-hearted, or rather 
 
ON NATURE. 113 
 
 CXXV. — For the things which are considered 
 mysteries among men, they celebrate sacrilegiously. 
 
 CXXTI. — And to these images they pray, as if one 
 should prattle with the houses knowing nothing of 
 gods or heroes, who they are. 
 
 CXXVII. — For were it not Dionysus to whom they 
 institute a procession and sing songs in honor of the 
 pudenda, it would be the most shameful action. But 
 Dionysus, in whose honor they rave in bacchic frenzy, 
 and Hades are the same. 40 
 
 CXXVIII. — Iamblichus, de Mysteriis v. 15. I distin- 
 guish two kinds of sacrifices. First, those of men 
 wholly purified, such as would rarely happen in the 
 case of a single individual, as Heraclitus says, or of a 
 
 of the idle-minded people of the Erechthidae, or even of the other 
 Greeks, for whom there awaits after death what they do not hope 
 (see frag. 122). Against whom, indeed, does Heraclitus of Ephesus 
 prophesy? Against night-roamers, Magians, bacchanals, revelers 
 in wine, the initiated. These he threatens with things after death 
 and prophesies fire for them, for they celebrate sacrilegiously the 
 things which are considered mysteries among men (= frag. 125). 
 
 CXXA*. — Clement of Alex. Protrept. 2, p. 19. Context, see frag. 
 124. 
 
 Compare Arnobius, adv. Nat. v. 29. 
 
 CXXYL— Origen, c. Cels. vii. 62, p. 384. 
 
 Idem i. 5, p. 6. 
 
 Clement of Alex. Protrept. 4, p. 44. Context :— But if you will 
 not listen to the prophetess, hear your own philosopher, Heraclitus, 
 the Ephesian, imputing unconsciousness to images, "And to these 
 images," etc. 
 
 CXXVII. — Clement of Alex. Protrept. 2, p. 30. Context :— In 
 mystic celebration of this incident, phalloi are carried through the 
 cities in honor of Dionysus. " For were it not Dionysus to whom 
 they institute a procession and sing songs in honor of the pudenda, 
 it would be the most shamful action," says Heraclitus. " But Hades 
 and Dionysus are the same, to whom they rave in bacchic frenzy," 
 not for the intoxication of the body, as I think, so much as for the 
 shameful ceremonial of lasciviousness. 
 
 Plutarch, de Iside 28, p. 362. 
 
114 HERACLITUS. 
 
 certain very few men. Second, material and corporeal 
 sacrifices and those arising from change, such as are 
 fit for those still fettered by the body. 
 
 CXXIX.— Atonements. 41 
 
 CXXX. — When defiled, they purify themselves with 
 blood, just as if any one who had fallen into the mud 
 should wash himself with mud ! 
 
 CXXIX. — lamblichus, de Mys. i. 11. Context : — Therefore Hera- 
 clitus rightly called them (scil. what are offered to the gods) " atone- 
 ments," since they are to make amends for evils and render the 
 souls free from the dangers in generation. 
 
 Compare Horn. Od. xxii. 481. See Crit. Note 41. 
 
 CXXX.— Elias Cretensis in Greg. Xaz. 1. 1. (cod. Vat. Pii. 11, 6, 
 fol. 90 r). Context : — And Heraclitus, making sport of these people, 
 says, " When denied, they purify themselves with blood, just as if 
 any one who had fallen into the mud should wash himself with 
 mud!" For to suppose that with the bodies and blood of the 
 unreasoning animals which they offer to their gods they can cleanse 
 the impurities of their own bodies, which are stained with vile 
 contaminations, is like trying to wash off mud from their bodies by 
 means of mud. 
 
 Gregory Xaz. Or. xxv. (xxiii.) 15, p. 466 ed. Par. 1778. 
 
 Apollonius, Epist. 27. 
 
 Compare Plotinus, Enn. i. 6, p. 54. 
 
CKITICAL NOTES. 115 
 
 CRITICAL NOTES. 
 
 Fragment 1. 
 Note 1. — Instead of Atfyov, MS has 66j,ua-og } corrected by Bernays, 
 followed by all critics except Bergk. 
 
 Fragment 2. 
 Note 2. — The teyog of Heraclitus stood for the element of order 
 or law in the ever-shifting world. Our word Reason may express 
 the same idea more in accord with the thought of that time (see 
 Introduction, p. 59 ff.). Zeller and Pfleiderer understand by it, 
 Reason ruling or immanent in the world ; Heinze, the objective 
 (unconscious) law of Reason ; Bernays, conscious Intelligence ; 
 Teichnmller, self-conscious Reason ; Schuster, on the other hand, 
 regards it as the "revelation offered us by the audible Speech of 
 Nature." In the present passage, Zeller is inclined to understand 
 by rov X&yov rovrfe, primarily the discourse of the author, but contain- 
 ing also the idea of the content of the discourse, i. e. the theory of 
 the world laid down in his book (Vol. 1, p. 572, 2). For fuller account 
 of the /o; of, compare Introduction, pp. 8, 12, 28, 45, 59, 61. 
 
 Fragment 13. 
 Note 3. — Bvwater reads, r Oauv dipig clkov fiddrjatg, ravra h/u rrporcfiecj ; 
 Compare Introduction, p. 19 f. 
 
 Fragment 15. 
 Note 4.— Compare Introduction, p. 48. Bernays (Rhein. Mus. 
 ix. 261 f.) offers the explanation that the eyes are more exact 
 witnesses than the ears, because by the eyes we have the only pure 
 cognition of fire, in the perception of which is the only true 
 knowledge. 
 
 Fragment 18. 
 
 Note 5. — See Introduction, p. 36 ff. 
 
 Fragment 19. 
 Note 6. — Common reading has iv to ao<pov eiriaraadai yvuurjv rjre ol 
 rvfjou -avra 6ta Tc&PTov. Schleiermacher, yvupqv oltj Kvpepvr/oei. 
 Bernays, §re ouuu&i. Schuster, tjre oln re nvfiepyf/oei. 
 
 Fragment 20. 
 Note 7. — The sense of dirAvrou is uncertain. In the citations 
 from Plutarch and Simplicius, the word is omitted ; they read 
 
116 HERACLITUS. 
 
 kSujuov lovds. Zeller, whose interpretation of the word we have 
 followed, takes it as masculine, referring to the gods and men, the 
 meaning then being, that since gods and men are included in the 
 world as part of it, they could not have created it. Schuster, on the 
 other hand, renders it as follows: "Die Welt, die alles in sich 
 befasst [die neben sich weder fur andre Welten noch fur einen 
 Schopfer Kaumhat]," etc. 
 
 Fragment 21. 
 Note 8. — HpyoTrjp is rendered by Schuster "fiery wind'" such 
 as forms the stars. Zeller (Vol. 1, p. 588, 1) believes it has essen- 
 tially the same signification as nepawSg in frag. 28, both words being 
 other terms for the world-ruling fire or formative principle of the 
 
 world. 
 
 Fragment 23. 
 
 Note 9. — Eusebius omits yv, and is followed by Lassalle and 
 Heinze. The former (Vol.2, p. 63) translates, "Das Meer wird 
 ausgegossen und gemessen nach demselben Logos, welcher zuerst 
 war, ehe es (selbst) noch war," and finds here a confirmation of his 
 interpretation of the Logos as the eternal preexisting law of the 
 identity of being and not-being. Heinze understands it as follows : 
 "Das Meer verwandelt sich in denselben Logos, also in dasselbe 
 Feuer, von welcher Beschaffenheit es vorher war, ehe es selbst 
 entstand." Schuster reads yfjv and translates, " Das Meer ergiesst 
 sich und mmmt sein Maass ein im selben Umfang, wie damals als 
 noch keine Erde war" (p. 129). Zeller reads yv and understands 
 the passage to refer to the return of the earth into the sea from 
 which it sprang. By loyog here he understands "proportion of 
 magnitude " or "size," so that eg rbv avrbv Xoyov means that the sea 
 returns "to the same size" as before it became earth (Vol. 1, p. 
 628, 3). 
 
 Fragment 24. 
 
 Note 10.— See Introduction, pp. 15, 22, 68. 
 
 Fragment 25. 
 Note 11. — This fragment is not accepted by Zeller, who holds 
 that air was not recognized by Heraclitus as one of the elements, 
 but that he accepted only the three, fire, water, and earth. Air 
 was added, Zeller thinks, by later writers, who confused it with 
 the " soul " of Heraclitus (Vol. 1, p. 615). Schuster, who thinks Hera- 
 clitus did not teach a specific number of elements after the manner 
 of Empedocles, regards the passage as trustworthy (p. 157 ff.). 
 Teichmuller gives to air an important place in the system of Heracli- 
 tus, distinguishing the upper pure air, which is not different from 
 fire, and the impure lower air (Vol. 1, p. 62). 
 
CRITICAL NOTES. 117 
 
 Feagmext 27. 
 
 Note 12. — Schleiermacher, followed by Mullach, reads riva for 
 rtc, so that the sense becomes, "How can that which never sets 
 escape any one?" This is unnecessary and violates the context in 
 Clement. That which never sets is the eternal Order or Law, con- 
 ceived here as Destiny or Justice. According to Zeller (Vol. 1, p. 
 590), that which never sets is fire. According to Schuster (p. 181), it 
 is Relation or Law. and the r«c refers to Helios, which, though itself 
 the centre of power and intelligence, is yet subject to law. Teich- 
 niuller (Vol. 1, p. 1S4) understands it to refer to Justice or Destiny, 
 which never sets like the sun, and which none can escape. 
 
 Feagmext 35. 
 
 Note 13. — W/.eiarun' may be taken as neuter: "Hesiod was a 
 teacher of the greatest number of things." On the unity of day 
 and night, compare Introduction, p. 32 f . 
 
 Feagmext 36. 
 
 Note 14. — The original text, which reads onorav ovfijutyy dva/Ltact, has 
 been variously corrected. As the subject of ovju/uc/y, Schuster inserts 
 I he sense then being that as wine is mixed with spices and labelled 
 as any one pleases, so God receives different names under different 
 forms (p. 188). Bywater, following Bernays (Rhein. Mus. ix. 245), 
 inserts Oiuua, and Zeller (Vol. 1, p. 602, 2) reads butog hijp for 'okugtcep. 
 Teichmiiller (Vol. 1, p. 67) attempts to save the original reading by 
 making 6 fteoc, (*. e. fire) the subject both of aKhnxmrai and ov/u[uyy. The 
 correction of Bernays is the most satisfactory ; the meaning then 
 being, that as when perfumes are mixed, the mixture is named 
 according to the scent that impresses each person, so God is named 
 according to the attribute that most impresses the individual. Com- 
 pare frag. 65. About the same sense, however, is derived from the 
 other readings. 
 
 Feagmext 38. 
 
 Note 15. — Schleiermacher and Zeller think it doubtful whether 
 any sense can be made out of this fragment. For Schuster's 
 fanciful explanation, see Introduction, p. 18 f. Bernays (Rhein. 
 Mus. ix. p. 265, 6) interprets it to mean that the perception of fire, 
 upon which depends the existence of the soul, is gained after death 
 and the extinction of the sense of sight, by the sense of smell, just 
 as the passage from Aristotle (frag. 37) teaches that in the conflagra- 
 tion of the world, all perception will be by the nostrils. Pfleiderer 
 - iggesta dcHowrat for bcfiiovrac. 
 
118 HERACLITUS. 
 
 Fragment 40. 
 
 Note 16. — Of this passage from Plutarch only the words oKidvyai ml 
 awdyei, Trpoaetai km anew, can with any certainty be attributed directly 
 to Heraclitus. The rest bears marks of later hands, as shown by 
 Bernays (Heraklit. Brief e, p. 55), and Zeller (Vol. 1, p. 576, 2). 
 
 Fragment 45. 
 
 Note 17. — Bernays' explanation of this passage (Rhein. Mus. vii. 
 p. 94 ; compare Introduction, p. 44 f .) has been followed by Zeller, 
 Schuster (partly), and Arnold Hug. According to this interpretation, 
 the association of the bow and lyre lies in their form, which in 
 the case of the old Greek or Scythian bow with its arms bent back 
 at the ends, was like that of the lyre. Hence we have in the bow 
 and the lyre, two distinct illustrations of harmony by opposite 
 straining tension. Lassalle (Vol. 1, p. 113) understands it to refer to 
 the harmony between the bow and the lyre ; the bow and the lyre 
 being symbols in the Apollo cult, the one of singularity and differ- 
 ence, the other, of universality and union. On Pfleiderer's modi- 
 fication of Lassalle' s view, see Introduction, p. 44. In place of 
 ro^ov ml /ivpvs, Bast reads rov btjiog te ml paphg. Bergk conjectures 
 t6£ov mi vsvpf/g. On the interpretation of this passage by Plutarch 
 and Plato's Eryximachus as the harmony of sharps and flats in 
 music, compare Hug (Platons Symposion, p. 77, 5) and Zeller (Vol. 
 1, p. 578, 2). Compare frags. 56, 43, 59. 
 
 Fragment 47. 
 
 Note 18. — Schuster (p. 24, note) reads k tI yap <pw'w, dp/novirj b<pav?/g 
 fyaveprjQ upelrrcov ; See Introduction, p. 20, and Zeller, Vol. 1, p. 604, 1. 
 
 Fragment 50. 
 
 Note 19. — MS reads ypa<pitov • Duncker and Bywater, yva^euv ; 
 Bernays, yva&elu. 
 
 Fragment 55. 
 
 Note 20. — The common reading is ^dv ipvrerbv ttjv yrjv ve^rac, which 
 Zeller retains, understanding it to refer to the beastliness of men, 
 who "feed upon the earth like the worm " (Vol. 1, p. 660). Pfleiderer 
 likewise accepts this reading, quoting Sallust, Catil. 1 : Vitam 
 silentio transeunt veluti pecora, quae natura prona atque ventri 
 obeclientia finxit. That irforyy, the reading of Stobaeus, followed by 
 Bywater, is correct, however, is shown by comparison with iEschylus, 
 Ag. 358, &ibg TTAaydv exovatv e'melv, and Plato's Criti. 109 B, Kaddrrep 
 TTOifieveg ktt/vt] 7TAr/-yy ve/uovreg. With this reading, the sense then 
 becomes that man is subject to eternal divine force or law. 
 
CRITICAL NOTES. 119 
 
 Fragment 56. 
 
 Note 21. — Compare frag. 45 and note 17. By water reads ttoMvtqvoz 
 apuoi'lr], here : but though in three passages, those namely given 
 under this fragment, -a/.ivrovoc is found in the MSS, yet the context 
 even in Plutarch, where sharps and flats are spoken of, calls for the 
 meaning "harmony of oppositions," as explained in note 17, for 
 which we should expect -a'/.ivrpo-og rather than waUvrovog. 
 
 Feagmext 60. 
 
 Note 22. — \Vhat is referred to by ravra^ " these things," has been 
 questioned. Teichmiiller, followed by Pfleiderer, has given the true 
 explanation. Tovra refers to some idea the opposite of "justice." 
 Clement is illustrating the Pauline principle that without law there 
 would have been no sin. For this, Heraclitus, whose prominent 
 thought was, no war without peace, no good without bad, etc., served 
 him as good authority. 
 
 Feag^iext 62. 
 
 Note 23. — The original text is as follows : El 6s xpv tov ttoXs/iov 
 
 eovra ^vvbv ml dinr/v epelv nal yivo/ieva rrdvra kcit' spiv nal xps&fieva. 
 Schleiermacher proposes elSkvai for el 6s and eptv for epslv, and has 
 been followed by Zeller, Bywater and others. Schuster retains the 
 MS form in the first clause. Xpsu^sva also gives trouble. Brandis 
 proposes cu^ousva. Schuster reads Karaxpsuusva, approved by Zeller. 
 Lassalle and Bywater retain ^ewuem. This passive use is unusual, 
 but possible, as shown by the analogy of mraxpe6/isva. The transla- 
 tions of Schuster and Lassalle are as follows : 
 
 Schuster (p. 198) — " In dem Falle muss man also dengemeinsamen 
 Krieg sogar Recht nennen und [sagen] das alles [nur] in Folge des 
 Streites entsteht und sich aufbraucht." 
 
 Lassalle — "Man muss wissen dass der Krieg das Gemeinsam 1st, 
 und der Streit das Recht, und dass nach dem Gesetz des Streits alles 
 wird und verwendet wird (or lit. und sich bethatigt)." 
 
 S in this passage has almost the signification "common good." 
 
 Feagmext 64. 
 Xote 24. — Critics have expended their ingenuity in trying to make 
 something out of this obscure fragment. Teichmiiller (Vol. 1, p. 97 
 ff .) says that we have here the distinction of the intelligible from the 
 sensible world. The former is the pure, light, fiery and most incor- 
 poreal being, compared with which the world of the senses is death. 
 Zeller (Vol. 1, p. 051) similarly refers it to the testimony of the 
 senses, which see the world as something "stiff and dead," when 
 really even-thing is in constant motion. Schuster (p. 276) labors 
 with a far-fetched interpretation to show that the passage does not 
 
120 HERACLITUS. 
 
 cast any disparagement upon the senses. For Pfleiderer's explana- 
 tion, see Introduction, p. 43. All these interpretations look for a 
 theoretical meaning, when it is quite possible that no theoretical 
 meaning was intended. It is simpler to compare it with frag. 2, and 
 refer it to Heraclitus' repeated charge against the people, of their 
 sleep-like condition when awake. 
 
 Fragment 65. 
 
 Note 25. — We have followed Schuster's punctuation of this frag- 
 ment. Bywater, with other critics, reads, n Ev to cocpbv fiovvov 
 Xeyeadai ovk kdeXei icai sdeAet, Zrjvbq ovvojua. To oo(f>6v, here, is the world- 
 ruling Wisdom or Order, to which Heraclitus applies many names. 
 (See Introduction, p. 60 f .) It wills and wills not to be called by 
 the name of Zeus, because that name, while it points towards 
 its true nature, yet but partly indicates it, or in part wrongly. 
 The variety of meanings, however, which have been drawn from 
 this fragment may be shown by the following translations. Schlei- 
 ermacher (and Lassalle) : "Das Eine Weise allein will nicht 
 ausgesprochen werden und will ausgesprochen werden, der Name 
 des Zeus." Schuster: " Nur eines ist die Weisheit ; sie lasst 
 sich nicht und lasst sich doch auch wieder benennen mit des 
 Zeus Namen." Bernays : " Eines, das allein Weise, will und will 
 auch nicht mit des 7>yv Namen genannt werden." The poetical 
 form Zrjvog is chosen, thinks Bernays, to indicate that the One Wise 
 is the source of "life." Zeller : "Eines, das allein Weise, will und 
 will auch nicht mit dem Namen des Zeus benannt werden." 
 Pfleiderer: "Als Eins will das weise Allwesen, Zeus genannt, nicht 
 bezeichnet werden und will es." Teichmuller : "Die Weisheit, 
 Zeus genannt, will allein eins heissen und will es auch nicht." 
 
 Fragment 72. 
 Note 26. — This fragment is connected by Schuster and Zeller with 
 the group of passages concerning rest in change (see frags. 82, 83), 
 and refers to the pleasure which the rest and change of death bring 
 to souls. They therefore reject the fj-v Odvarov of Numenius as not 
 Heraclitic. (Schuster, p. 191, 1. Zeller, p. 647, 2.) Pfleiderer, how- 
 ever (p. 222), retains the /u?) Odvarov as genuine, and explains that it 
 is a pleasure to souls to become wet, because so by pursuing the way 
 down into apparent death, they attain their new birth of life in 
 death. He therefore retains also the repipcv tie elvai avralg ri]v elg r?jv 
 ykveoLv TTTuoiv, of Nunienius, as expressing the true sense of the 
 passage. 
 
 Fragment 74. 
 
 Note 27. — The added clause of Plutarch, "It flashes through the 
 body like lightning through the clouds," is also regarded by Schleier- 
 macher, Schuster, Zeller, and Pfleiderer, as Heraclitic. 
 
CRITICAL NOTES. 121 
 
 The similarity of the three fragments 74, 75, and 76 suggests, of 
 course, that they are all corrupted forms of a common original. 
 Bywater, however, accepts the form of expression in frag. 74 as 
 surely Heraclitic and marks the other two as doubtful. Schleier- 
 macher, from the number of citations of each of these fragments, 
 concludes that Heraclitus had expressed himself in each of these 
 three forms. Lassalle, in agreeing with him, believes also that 
 Heraclitus, who was given to playing upon words (for further 
 examples of Heraclitus' puns, compare frags. 91, 101, 127, 66), not 
 without purpose chose the words ainj and aby/j, and sees in the use of 
 the latter word a reference to the lightning-like movement of the 
 soul (Vol. 2, p. 196 f .). Zeller thinks it difficult to determine the 
 original form, but he does not regard the proposition aby?) gyp?) tpvxv 
 GOQu-ari), as Heraclitic (Vol. 1, p. 643, 2). 
 
 Fragment 77. 
 
 Note 2S. — The original of this difficult and corrupted passage as it 
 appears in Clement, is as follows (unpunctuated), *Av8po)7rog kv eixppovy 
 <pdog drzTErai eavrti a-odavuv a^oa^Eaddg £c)v 6e dnreTat redtteuroq evduv 
 a-oc^Ecdelg 6\pEig kyprjyopug aTzrerat evdovrog. Various emendations and 
 translations of this have been made. Compare Schuster, p. 271 ; 
 Pfleiderer, p. 204, 1. Bywater, however, finally rescues as Hera- 
 clitic the form given above in the text. 
 
 Fragment 80. 
 Note 29. — That this fragment is to be taken in the sense in which 
 Diogenes understands it, rather than in that of Plutarch, is held by 
 Schuster (p. 61) and Zeller (Vol. 1, p. 654, 4). Lassalle (Vol. 1, p. 
 301), following Schleiermacher, takes it as Clement does, in the sense 
 of the Delphic inscription, "I have sought myself in the general 
 flux of things, I have striven to know myself." For Pfleiderer's inter- 
 pretation and the true meaning, see Introduction, pp. 41, 48. 
 
 Fragment 82. 
 Note 30. — Lassalle, following Creuzer, reads dyxeodai instead of 
 
 apxecVai (Vol. 1, p. 131.) 
 
 Fragment 90. 
 Note 31.— Lassalle (Vol. 1, p. 290) interprets this fragment as 
 follows : In waking, we distinguish our own representations from the 
 objective world common to all. In sleeping, they are one and the 
 same. Hence Heraclitus says the sleeping make their own world. 
 Similarly Pfleiderer (p. 202 f.) understands Heraclitus to mean that 
 the sleeper makes his own world, while the waking man is con- 
 scion- thai corresponding to liis world of ideas there is a common 
 
122 HERACLITUS. 
 
 objective world. Pfleiderer rejects ml owepyovc as an addition of 
 Aurelius. 
 
 Feagment 97. 
 
 Note 32. — This fragment has given trouble. Bernays (Heraclitea 
 15) proposes to substitute Safaovog for dai/iovog, but has not been followed 
 by other critics. Schleiermacher translates, " Ein thorichter Mann 
 vernimmt nicht niehr von Schicksal als ein Kind von einem Mann." 
 Schuster (p. 342) renders, "Der Mensch in seiner Kindheit hat (sie 
 [». e. the names]) von Gott gehort, wie (jetzt) das Kind von dem 
 Manne," and finds here support for the theory of the natural fitness 
 of names (see Introduction, p. 16), which primitive man learned 
 directly from Nature. Zeller (Vol. 1, p. 653) refers it to the childish 
 want of reason in man, which does not perceive the voice of the 
 deity. Pfleiderer (p. 51) renders, "Der unverstandige Mensch hat 
 von jeher nur soviel von der Gottheit gehort, als ein Kind vom 
 Manne." 
 
 Feagment 103. 
 
 Note 33. — "Tfipiv here is to be taken in the sense of excess of self- 
 assertion, the private will against the universal Law. Compare 
 frags. 92, 104, etc. 
 
 Feagment 107. 
 
 Note 34. — The latter clause may also be translated, "Wisdom is 
 to speak and act truly, giving ear to Nature." 
 
 Feagment 110. 
 Note 35. — Clementine MS reads j3ova?). Eusebius, followed by all 
 but Mullach, reads fiovli}. For Heraclitus' opinions on democracy, 
 see, further, frags. 114, 113. 
 
 Feagment 116. 
 Note 36. — The passage in Clement is as follows : alia rd fiev rfjq 
 yvcicecog fiadrj npimreiv aiucr'tr] ayaOrj, /ca0' 'Hpanleirov ■ cutict'it/ yap diatyvyyavet 
 fir) yiyvuGneodai, from which it is seen that the words of Heraclitus, dniariij 
 6ta(j)vyydvet (ir) yiyvuGaecdai, were differently understood by Clement and 
 Plutarch. Schuster (p. 72) accepts the Clementine form, and regards the 
 whole passage as Heraclitic, and renders, "Die Tiefe der Erkenntniss 
 zu verbergen, das ist ein gutes Misstrauen. Denn durch diese miss- 
 trauische Behutsamkeit entgeht man dem Schicksal durchschaut zu 
 werden," by which he accounts for the (intentional) obscurity of 
 Heraclitus' writings. Zeller (Vol. 1, p. 574, 2), following Schleier- 
 macher, rejects the Clementine version, and regards the words as 
 teaching that truth is hidden from the masses because it seems 
 incredible to them. A still different meaning may be found in the 
 words if we take aiuoTirj as subjective, referring to the want of faith 
 which prevents us from seeing truth. 
 
CRITICAL NOTES. 123 
 
 Fragment 118. 
 Note 37. — The common reading is, doneovruv 6 donifiu-aroc ytvacnei. 
 fvXaaaetv, which makes nonsense. Schleiermacher proposes doKtovra 6 
 doKtuoraroc y/vucKEiv dv/.dcaeiv. Schuster (p. 340) suggests, Sokeov-ov, 6 
 doKiuurarov yivercu, ytv&GKEt <pv/daoen>, and fancies the allusion is to the 
 poets, who from credible things accept that which is most credible. 
 Bergk, followed by Pfleiderer, reads $kv&oaeiv, to talk nonsense. 
 Bernays, followed by Bywater, reads Tzldaaeiv. 
 
 Fragment 121. 
 Note 38. — This fragment has been variously translated, but the 
 meaning seems to be that a man's God or Destiny depends not upon 
 external divine powers, but upon his own inner nature. Teichmiiller 
 finds here the further meaning that the essence of mind is the 
 essence of deity. 
 
 Fragment 123. 
 
 Note 39. — The meaning of this passage is very doubtful. We have 
 followed Bernays' reading instead of the common evda dedvn, which 
 Bywater retains, although he marks it uncertain. Schuster (p. 176, 1) 
 suggests \6aifxuv kdk\Ei\ hvdade kdvn hrzuGraadai ml (pvAatibg k. t. A. Zeller 
 (Vol. 1, p. 648, 4) regards it as a reference to the daemons who are 
 made protectors of men. Lassalle (Vol. 1, p. 185) thinks it refers to 
 a resurrection of souls. 
 
 Fragment 127. 
 
 Note 40. — For text and discussion of this passage, see Introduction, 
 p. 52 ff . Teichmiiller' s interpretation of it is as follows : " Wenn es 
 nicht Dionysus ware, demsiedie Procession fiihren und dabeidas Lied 
 auf die Schamglieder singen, so ware das Schamloseste ausgef iihrt. 
 Nun aber, ist Hades (der Sohn der Scham) derselbe wie Dionysus, 
 dem sie rasen und Feste feiern." This means, says Teichmiiller, 
 that the shameful and the becoming are the same (Identification 
 of opposites). For what is improper for men is proper for Dionysus, 
 because he is the same as Hades, and Hades is the same as shame, 
 which latter he attempts to prove from Plutarch, de Is. 29 b. Again, 
 Dionysus and Hades are the same, because the former stands for the 
 sun and the latter for the lower world, and as the sun is absorbed 
 into the earth at night and generated therefrom in the morning, 
 they must be essentially the same. (Neue Studien, Vol. 1, p. 25.) 
 
 Fragment 120. 
 Note 41. — That the use of this term was ironical, is made probable 
 by the following fragment. 
 
124 HERACLITUS. 
 
 HPAKAEITOY E$E2IOY 
 nEPI 3>Y2EQ2. 
 
 I. Ovk efiev dXXd tov \6yov aKovaravras Sfiokoyeeiv cro(pov eVrt, ev rravra 
 eivai. 
 
 II. Tov 8e Xoyov ravd iovTOS alel d^vveroi ylyvovrai dvdpeoTToi Ka\ 
 npoo-dep fj d<ovaai kol aKovaavTes to Trpcorov. yivopevoov yap ttuvtcov Kara 
 tov Xoyov TovBe cmzipoio~i ioiKaari napapevoi kou eirecov /cat epycov toiovtccov 
 oko'kov iya> dirjyevpai., diaipecov €<aaTov /caret (pvcriv kcu cppdfav okcos e^ei. 
 rovs 8e ciXXovs dv6pa>7rovs Xavddvei 6/cocm eyepdevTts ttouovo~i, o/ccooTrep 
 OKocra €v8ovt€? €7riXav6dvovTai. 
 
 III. 'AgvveToi aKovcravTes Kcocpolai eoUavi ' obdris avrolai papTvpeei 
 napeovTas direivai. 
 
 I V . Ka/cot pdpTvpes dv0pd>7roicri dcpdaXpol /cat cora, fiapfidpovs yjsvxds 
 exdvTwv. 
 
 V. Ov (ppoveovcri Toiavra noXXol OKoaoiai eyKvpe'ovo~i ovde paSovres 
 yivooo'Kovo'i, €(ovtoIo~i 8e doKeovcri. 
 
 VI. 'A/coOtrat ovk emorafievoi ovd sinew. 
 
 VII. 'Eav prj eXnTjat, dv£Xmo~Tov ovk e^evprjaei, dve^epevvrjTov ibv kcu 
 atropov. 
 
 VIII. Xpvabv oi 8i£rjpevoi yrjv noXXrjv opvacrovcri kcu euptV/covcri dXiyov. 
 
 IX. 'Ayxifia<rir}v. 
 
 X. Qvo-ts KpvTTTeadat cptAet. 
 
 XI. O aval; ov to fiavreiov eari to iv AeXqbols, ovre Xeyei ovtc Kpxmrei, 
 dXXd crrjpalvet. 
 
 XII. 2i(BvXXa 8e p.aivop.ev(o aTopari dyeXacrTa kcu a/caAXaOTtara /cat 
 dpvpicrTa (pdeyyopivr) ^tXtW eTeeov e£t/cyeerat Trj (fycovrj did tov 8z6v. 
 
 XIII. "Ocrcov oyjns a/coi) pdBrjais, ravra eyco 7rpoTipe<a. 
 
 XIV. PolybillS iv. 40 : tovto yap 'iBiov eon Toav vvv Kaipav, iv ols 
 
 ndvTcov 7tX(oto>v /cat nopevTtov ytyovoTaw ovk dv eVt irpeTiov etr/ noirjTa'is /cat 
 
TEXT. 125 
 
 p.v6oypdqbois xprjcrdat pdpTvat ircpi tcov ayvoovfievav, bnep 01 irpb fj/xcov TiepX 
 T<Mf 7rXei'crrcoz', drrioTovs dpcftta^TjTovpercov TTape\6p.evoi fiefiaiozTas Kara tov 
 'HpdickeiTov. 
 
 AN . '0(p$a.\[jLo\ Ttcv cotooi' aKpifieorepoi pdpTvpes. 
 
 AN I. TIo\vp.adii] voov e\etv ov ^LddaKd ' 'HcrioSov yap av tdida^e xa\ 
 H\Bay6pT)v avr'is re Sevocpdvea kci\ 'Enaralov. 
 
 A \ 11. Ill dayoprjs Mvr]o~dpxov laToplrjv rjo~Kr]o~e dv6pa>jroiv p,d\io~Ta 
 Trdi'Toiv. kci\ eK.\e£dp.evos ravras ras avyypcupas cVoujcre ecovrov crocpirjv, 
 — n\i padtrjv, KaKOT€\i'iT]v. 
 
 A \ 111. 'Okoctcov Xdyovs fjicovaa ovdels dcpiKveerai es tovto, wart 
 
 yild)(TK(ll> OTl aOCJiOV ioTl TTaVTCOV K^)(0ipl(TpeVOV. 
 
 aIA. Ej/ to aocpdv, eTTiaTncrdat yvd>p.rjv tj nvQepvarai ndvra did ndvrcov. 
 
 A A. Kdcrpov <C TovSe > tov avTov aTravTav ovre tis dewv ouTe dvOpchwcov 
 e~oirjae, aXX tjv alel kol eo~Ti kol earai rrvp deifaov, dnTop-evov p.eTpa Kal 
 d7Too-j3evvvp.evov p.€Tpa. 
 
 A A I. Ilvpbs TpoTToi TTpwrov 6d\aaaa ' BaXdaarjs 8e to pev rjpiav yrj, 
 to 8e rjpio~v 7rpr]crTT)p. 
 
 A A II. Ilvpbs dj/rapa/Sercu irdvTa Ka\ nvp dnavTcov, cbcnrep xP V0 ~°v 
 XpTjp,aTa Kal xp^pdrcov XP V<J ° S ' 
 
 AA.III. GdXacrcra Sta^eerai ko.\ perpeerai (S top clvtov \6yov oxolos 
 irpoaBev fjv *] yeve'aOai JyrjJ. 
 
 AA1\ . XpT]0~p,00-VVT] . . . <dpos. 
 
 AAV. Z]j jrvp rbv yr/s ddvaTov, koa dr)p £?/ top nvpbs Sdvarov' vdcop 
 & tov depos BdvaTOV) yrj rbv vdaTOS. 
 
 A AN I. Hdvra to ni/p eneXObv xpiveei Kai KaTaXij^/eraL. 
 
 AAV I J. To p.T) 8vVOV 7TOT€ TTOiS UV TIS XdOoi ] 
 
 A AN III. Td de navra olaK^ei xepavvos. 
 
 AAIA. ''HXtoy o&x imepftrjcreTai perpa ' el fie p.r}, 'Epivves piv diKrjs 
 (TTLKOvpoi f^evpr/aovo-L. 
 
 AAA. 'Hots' Acai eoTre prjs Teppura 1) &pKTOS t ku\ aVTtOP TTJS apKTOV ovpos 
 ulBpiov Aids. 
 
 A A A I. E< pi] rjKins rju, evrppdvt) uv rjv. 
 
126 HERACLITUS. 
 
 XXXII. Neoy i(p ypepr] rjXios. 
 
 XXXIII. Diogenes Laert. i. 23 : bo K el be (scil. eaX^s) Kard 
 
 rivas npcoTos d(rrpoXoyrjcrai Kal fjXiaKas eKXei\J/eis Kal r ponds rrpoemelv, &$ 
 (prjffiv ~Evbr)pos iv rrj nepl rcov darpoXoyovpe'voav Icrropia ' 66ev avrbv kcu 
 3evo(pdvr)s Kal 'Hpoboros 6avpd£ei, paprvpel §' avra> kcu 'HpdickeiTOS kcu 
 
 &T]pOKpiTOS. 
 
 XXXIV. Plutarchus Qu. Plat. viii. 4, p. 1007: oiW oZv 
 
 dvaymlav npbs rbv ovpavbv %x a>v (TvpivKoKqv kcu o~vvappoyr)v 6 xpdvos ovx 
 d7r\cos icrri Kivrjcris dXX , coanep eiprjrai, klvtjo-is iv rd£ei perpov ixovar} kcu 
 nepara kcu 7repiobovs. hv 6 tfXios iniardTTjs a>v kcu ckottos, opi^eiv kcu 
 ftpafieveiv kcu dvabeiKvvvai kcu dvacpaiveiv perafioXas kcu copas at ndvra 
 <pepovo~i, Kad 'HpaKXeirov, ovbe <pavXa>v ovbe piKpcov, dXXd ra>v peyiaroov 
 Kal Kvpicordrcov r&> fjyepovi Kal irpcorco deep yiverai crvvepyos. 
 
 XXX V. Aibdo-KaXos be irXeio-rfov 'Hcrt'oSoy ' rovrov emcnavrai nXelara 
 eibe'vai, octtis rjpeprjv kcu eveppovrjv ovk iyivoacrKt ' eo~ri yap ev. 
 
 XXX VI. *0 debs qpe'prj eveppovq, x €l t x " >v depos, noXepos elprjvrj, Kopos 
 Xipos ' dXXoiovrat be oKcoanep OKorav o-vppiyrj < dvcopa > dvapacri ' 
 dvopd£erai Kad fjbovrjv eKaarov. 
 
 XXXVII. Aristoteles de Sensu 5, p. 443 a 21 : boKel b } ivlois 
 
 r) Kanvdibrjs dvadvpiaois elvai oo-pr), ovcra koivtj yijs re Kal depos. Kal 
 7rdvT€s imcpepovrai irrl rovro nepl oaprjs ' bib Kal HpaKXetros ovrcos 
 e'lprjKev, &>$• el rrdvra ra ovra Kairvbs yevoiro, plves civ biayvoiev. 
 
 XXXVIII. At -v/ru^ai oapcovrai Kad' qbrjv. 
 
 XXXIX. Ta \jsvxpd deperai } deppbv ^u^erat, vypbv avalverai, Kap- 
 cpaXeov vorl£erai. 
 
 XL. 2K[8vr)(ri Kal crvvdyei, npocreiaL Kal a7re«7i. 
 
 XLI. Tlorapoto-i bis roiai avroloi ovk civ epfialrjs ' erepa yap < Kal 
 erepa^> imppeei vbara. 
 
 XJulI. *f Horapoio-i rolci avTolac epftaivovaiv erepa Kal erepa vbara 
 eivippel \. 
 
 XLIII. Aristoteles Eth. Eud. vii. *-, p. 1235 a 26 : Kal 'HpdK- 
 
 Xeiros eTTiripa r© Troii)<ravri' a)? epis €K re Qecov Kal dvOpcairuiv ottoXoito ' 
 ov yap dv eivai dppovlav pr) ovros d£eos Kal {5apeos } ovbe ra £<fa dvev 
 SfjXeos Kal dppevos, evavricov ovro&v. 
 
TEXT. 127' 
 
 XL J \ . JJoXepos navTcov pev 7rnr/;p icrri navTcov hk (3ao~iXevs, Kal tovs 
 p.kv deovs efiet£e tovs 8e dpdpcoTrovs, tovs fxev SovXovs eTroirjae tovs 8e 
 eXtvdepovs. 
 
 aL\ . Ov £vvlacri okcos diacfiepoucvov ((ovtoZ 6/zoAoye'a ' naXipTponos 
 dppOVlt) OK(00-7T€p to£ov Kal Xvprjs. 
 
 XLVI. Aristoteles Eth. Nic. viii. 2, p. 1155 b 1 : K al wept 
 
 avT&v TovTGiv dvooTepov €ni£r)TOvo-i Kal (pvo~iK<x>Tepov ' ILvpnriSrjs ftev 
 (f)do~KO)v epav pev op.j3pov yalav ^TjpavQelaav, epav 8e o~€p,vov ovpavov nXr]- 
 povpevov opfipov 7T€0~e'iv es yalav ' ko.1 'HpaKkeiTos to dvTi^ovv avp-Cpepov, 
 Kal (k tcov diacfrepovToov KaXXicrTrjv app-oviav, Kal ndvTa naT epiv ytveadai. 
 
 \L> V II. 'Appovirj (iqt)avr]S cpavepijs Kptlo-o'oov. 
 
 XL V III. Mj^Mki] nepl tcov p-eyio-Tcov o-vp.j3aXeop.tda. 
 
 XLlA. Xpr) eu p.dXa ttoXXqw laropas (piXocroqbovs dvdpas eivai. 
 
 L. Tvacpeoov 686s evdua kcu aKoXir) p.ia eort kcu tj avrr]. 
 
 Jul. "Ovoi crvpp.aT dv eXoiVTO p.dXXov r) %pvcr6v. 
 
 JL11. QdXaaaa vdcop KadapdoraTov Kal /juapeoTaTov, Ixdvai p,ev 7roTip.ov 
 Kal acoTrjpiop, dvdpomois t)e cittotov koi oXedpiov. 
 
 LIU. Columella de R. R. viii. 4 : siccus etiam pulvis et cinis, 
 ubicuuque cohortem porticus vel tectum protegit, iuxta parie- 
 tes repouendus est, ut sit quo aves se perfundant: nam his 
 rebus plumam pirmasque emendant, si modo credimus Ephesio 
 Heraclito qui ait: sues coeno, cohortales aves pulvere (vel 
 cinere) lavari. 
 
 LIV. Bnpfiopoo ^a/peti/. 
 
 L V . T\dv (pirtTov TrXrjyri vep-erai. 
 
 L \ I. HakivrpoTTos dpp.ovir) Koo~p.ov OKcoanep Xvprjs Kal to£ov. 
 
 L\ II. ' Ayadov Kal KaKov tovtov. 
 
 LV11L Hippolytus Ref. haer. ix. 10: Kal dyadbv Kal kuk6p 
 
 (SCll. ei/ f'crn)" ol yovv larpot, cprjalv 6 'Hpa/cXeirof, TtpvovTts KaiovTts 
 TTfivrr] jUacravl^ovres kokws tovs appooaTovvTas enaiTiwvTai p.rj8ev' Sl£iov 
 yuadov Xapfitiveiv Tiapa to>v dppoooTOvvToov, ravTa cpya£dpevot tu dyad a kcu 
 "' Tin v6vo\ 
 
128 HERACLITUS. 
 
 LIX. TZwd^reias ovXa Kal ov)(l ovXa, trvpcpepopevov biacpepopevov, 
 avvabov biabov ' eK irdvrcov ev Kal e£ evbs ndvra. 
 
 IjX. Alktjs ovvopa ovk av fjbeaav, el ravra prj rjv. 
 
 LXI. Schol. B. in II. iv. 4, p. 120 Bekk. : riV/Wr (paaiv, el 
 repvei rovs Beovs rroXepcov Bea. aXX ovk aTrpenes ' ret yap yevvala epya 
 repnei. ciXXcos re noXepoi kcu pd^ai rjp.lv pev beivd boKel, rco be Beep ovbe 
 ravra beivd. avvreXel yap diravra 6 Beds npds dppoviav rcov SXcov, oIkovo- 
 pcov rd trvpcfiepovra, direp Ka\ Hpa/cXetro? Xe'yet, cos rco pev Beep KaXa ndvra 
 ko.1 dyaOd Ka\ biKaia, avBpconoi be a pev abiKa vTreiXi-jCpacnv, a be biKaia. 
 
 LXII. ~Elbevai XP1 rov ndXepov eovra ^vvdv, koX btKrjv epiv ' ko.1 yivo- 
 
 , > j, \ 4. / 4. 
 
 peva Travra Kar epiv Kai j %pecopeva f . 
 
 LXIII. "Eoti yap elpappeva 7ravrccs * . 
 
 LXI V . Qdvards ecrri OKotra eyepBevres opeopev, 6/cocra be evbovres 
 
 V7TVOS* 
 
 LX V . Ei> to trocpdv povvov ' XeyecrBai ovk eBeXei Kal eBeXei Zrjvbs 
 ovvopa. 
 
 LX V I. Tov /3iou ovvopa (3tos, epyov be Bdvaros. 
 
 LX V II. 'ABdvaroi Bvrjroi, Bvrjrol dBdvaroi, £covres rov eKeivcov Bdvarov 
 rov be eKeivcov (3lov reBvewres. 
 
 LX V III. tyvxi)o~i yap Bdvaros vbcop yeve'crBai, vbari be Bdvaros yrjv 
 yevetrBai ' eK yr)s be vbcop yiverai, e£ vbaros be yj/vxr). 
 LXIX. 'Obos civco Kara) pia Ka\ covrrj. 
 LXX. Svvov apx?) Kal ire pas. 
 
 LiXXl. tyv^s Tveipara ovk av e^evpoio ndaav eTvnropevdpevos obdv. 
 LXXII. tyvxrjtTi repyjsis vyprjcri yevetrBai. 
 
 LXXIII. 'Avrjp okot av peBvaBrj, ayerai vtto naibos dvr](Sov trcpaXXd- 
 pevos, ovk e7ralcov okt) ftaivei, vyprjv rrjv y\rvx^]V e)(cov. 
 
 LiXXl V . Avrj yjsvxr) cTOCpcordrr) Kal dpicrrr). 
 
 L/XXV. J Avyrj £r)prj yjsvxr) aocpcordrrj ko.1 dpiarrjj. 
 
 JjXX V I. "f Ov yrj £r)pr), yf/vx^j cTocpcordrr] Kal aplcrrrj J. 
 
 LXXVII. "AvBpco7ros, okcos ev evcppdvrj cfidos, anrerai airoo-fievvvrai. 
 
 LXXVIII. Plutarchus Consol. ad Apoll. 10, p. 106: wore ydp 
 
 ev fjptv avro7s ovk ecrnv 6 Bdvaros ', ko.1 rj cpijaiv HpaKXeiros, ravr eivai 
 
TEXT. 129 
 
 (gov koi Te6prjKos, koi to eyprjyopos icai to Ka8ev8ou, na\ vtov nai ytjpaiov ' 
 Tiide yap peraneo-opTa eneivd f'ort KaKeipa ndXip peTinreaopTa Tavra. 
 
 LXXIX. At coy ncils eo~ri waifap ireo-aeviop ' rraiSbs fj /3acr 1X771/7. 
 
 LAAA. *E8i£r)0~dpr)p e'pecovTOP. 
 
 LXXXI. TloTapo'iai rotcri avTolai epfiaipopep re ko\ ovk ep.j3aipop.ev, 
 elpep re Kal ovk elpep. 
 
 LA A All. Kdparos eo~Ti tois avTols pox^elp kuI iipx*o~6ai. 
 
 LAAAI1I. MerafidXXop dpanaveTai. 
 
 LXAAlv . Kai 6 KVKeaiv dtioTuTai. prj Kipeopepos. 
 
 LXXX V . Neicves Koirplayp eK^XrjTOTepoi. 
 
 L AAA VI. Tepopevoi £d>eip edeXovai popovs r e\€iv ' paXXop 8e 
 dpaTraieaOai, koi iraldas KaTaXeiirovoi popovs yeptodai. 
 
 LXXXVII. Plutarchus de Orac. def. 11, p. 415: ol piv 
 
 " fjfavTOS " dpayipaaKOPTts (apud Hesiod. fr. 163 Goettling) cttj 
 TpiaKovra ttolovcti ttjp yepeap Kad HpaK.XeiTOP ' ip io xpopco yeppapra 
 naptx^i top e'£ avTov yeyepvqpepop 6 yepprjcras. 
 
 LXXXYIII. Io. Lydus de Mensibns iii. 10, p. 37 ed. Bonn : 
 
 6 TpuiKOPTa dpidpbs (pvaiKOiTaTos earTip ' b yap ip popdai Tpids, tovto e'p 
 deKaai TpiaKOprds. eVel Kal 6 tov prjpos kvkXos o~vpeo-TT)K€P ck Teaadpiop 
 tcov dno popddos e^rjs TtTpayaipiop a', 8', & , iC'. oBep ovk dno o~KOiroi 
 ' HpaK.XeiTos yepeap top prjva KaXel. 
 
 LXXXIX. Ex homine in tricennio potest avus haberi. 
 
 XC. M. AntoniuilS Vi. 42: Trdpres els ep dnoTeXeo-pa ovpepyovpev, 
 ol pep el8oTO)? Kal 7rapaKoXovdrjTiKcbs , ol 8e dpeTTio-TaTus ' coaTrep Kal tovs 
 Ka6ev8opTas, oipai, 6 'HpaKXeiTos e'pydras elpai Xeyei Kal avpepyovs tcov 
 ('v rep Korrpco yivopeviop. 
 
 XGI. "Evpop eori naai to (ppopeeiv. £vp poio Xeyopras lo-\vp'i(ea6ai 
 XPh TCO £vi/<ju ndpToip, OKOicnrep popio noXts Ka\ noXv la)(v pore pas. Tpe- 
 (poprat yap irdpres ol dpSpconeiot popoi vno epos tov Qelov ' Kpareei yap 
 tooovtop OKncrop eOeXei Kal e^apKeei ndai ko.1 nepiyipeTai. 
 
 A CI J. ToO Xbyov 8' e'bvTos £vpov, (woven ol ttoXXoi 10s 18itjp e\0VTts 
 q^pfhrjaip. 
 
 XCIII. 'fit pdXio-Tii 8irjveK(ios bpiXeovai } TOVTta 8ia(pepoprai. 
 
130 HERACLTTUS. 
 
 XOI V . Ov del cocmep Ka&evbovTas noielv <a\ Afc-yeii/. 
 
 XOV. Plutarchus de Superst. 3, p. 166 : 6 'HpdKXeiTos $770-1, 
 
 toIs eyprjyopoatv eva kcu koivov Kocrpov eivai, twv de KOipa>pe'va>v eKatrrov 
 els 'idiov dnoo-TpecpecrBai. 
 
 XC V I. 'H#os yap avBpameiov pev ovk e\ei yvo>pas, Belov he e^«. 
 
 XOV11. 'Avrjp vrjnios fjicovae jrpos datpovos oKaxnrep 7rals Trpos dvbpos. 
 
 XC VIII. Plato Hipp. mai. 289 B : rj ov ko.1 'HpaKXeiTos tuvtov 
 tovto Xeyei, ov crv endyei, oti dvBpwTrcov 6 crocpcoTaTos npbs Bebv niBrjKos 
 (pavelrai kcl\ aocpta kcu KaXXei Kai toIs aXXois ndaiv ', 
 
 XOIX. Plato Hipp. mai. 289 A : Z> avBpome, dyvoels oti to tov 
 VlpaickeLTOv ev e^«, cos apa TTiBfjKtiiv 6 ko.XXio~tos alo~xpbs dXXco yevei 
 avpfidXXeiv, kcu xyTpmv r) KaXXicrTi] alo~xpd TvapBevoov yevei crvpjSdXXeiv, &s 
 <pr)o~iv lmvlas 6 crocpos. 
 
 0. Md^ecrdai xph T0V drjpov vTrep tov vopov okcos vnep Tei^eos. 
 
 01. Mopoi yap pe^oves pe^ovas poipas Xayxdvovai. 
 
 Oil. ' Aprpcpdrovs Beo\ Tipacri m\ avBpanoi. 
 
 CIII. "Yfipiv xph cr^evvveiv pdXXov r) irvprnrfv. 
 
 01 V. ' Av9pdmoio~i yi vecrBai oKoaa BeXovcri ovk apeivov. vovaos vyieiav 
 eiroi-qare rjdv Ka\ dyaOov, Xipbs kopov, KapaTos dvdrravo-iv. 
 
 OV. Qvpco pdxeadai ^aXe7rdz/' 6 ti yap av XP^V ylveaBai, yj/vx^s 
 ojveeTai. 
 
 0V1. J ' AvBpconoicri 7Tarri perecrTi yiyvooo~Keiv eavTovs ko.1 o~axppovelv\. 
 
 OVII. j 2axppovelv aperr) peylo'Trj' ko.1 crocpir) aXrjBe'a Xeyew Ka\ Troielv 
 koto, cpvcriv eTTatovTas *f. 
 
 0VII1. y ApaBlr]v apeivov KpvTVTeiv ' epyov de ev avecrei ko.1 Trap* oivov. 
 
 01X. { KpvTTTtiv dpaBlrjv Kpearaov r) is to peo~ov cpepeiv J . 
 
 CX. Nopos Ka\ fiovXrj ireiBeo-Bai evos. 
 
 OXI. Tis yap avrojv voos r) <ppr)v ', idrjpoovj doidolai enovTai Kal 
 didacrKaXco xp^ a>vraL bpiXco, ovk eldoTes oti rroXXol kcikoi oXiyoi de dyaBoi. 
 alpevvTai yap ev dvTia navTcov oi apicrToi, KXeos devaov Bvr)Ta>Vy oi 8e noXXol 
 KeKoprjvTai oKcoo~7rep KTrjvea. 
 
 OXII. 'Ei> HpirjvT) Bias eyevCTO 6 TevTapeco, ov irXea>v Xoyos r] twv 
 aXXoiv. 
 
TEXT. 131 
 
 CXI1I. Els epol pvpiot, eav apio~TOS r/. 
 
 CXI^ . *A£iop 'Ecpeaiois rjfirjdop d7rdy£aa6ai iraai kol to7s avrj(3ois rrjv 
 ttqXip KctraXiTre'LV, otrives 'Eppodcopov aubpa ecovrcoi' optjio-top e£e(3aXop, 
 cbdpres ' i)pea>p fir]8e els 6pt)io~tos ecrrco, el fie pi], ciXXj) re K(i\ per oXXg»'. 
 
 tA\ . KiVe? Kol {3av£ovo~i op cip pj) yivcocrKcoai. 
 
 CX"\ I. 'Amorty dia(fivyydi>ei pj) yiuuxTKeadai. 
 
 C A \ II. B\a£ apdpcoTTOS eVi Tvavrl Xoyco €7TTorjcr$ai (piXeei. 
 
 CX \ III. AoKeorroz/ 6 doKipoiTdTOs yivuxTKiL TrXdo~o~eiP ' kol pevroi 
 kol 8ucrj KaTa\7]\j/€Tai yj/evdecop renTovas nai paprvpas. 
 
 CXIX. Diogenes Laert. ix. 1 : t6v & "Op-^pop ecpao-nep a&ov eV 
 
 tcov aycovoov eK.f$dXXecr6ai kol pa7n'£ecr#ai, nai ' ApxiXo^op opolios. 
 
 CXX. "Onus dies par omni est. 
 
 CXX1. H8os dv8po)7rai daipcov. 
 
 CXX 1 1. y Avdpco7rovs pevti Te\evTi]<ravTa.s aacra ovk eXrropTai ov8e 
 &ok€ overt. 
 
 CXXliI. *Ep6abe eopTas e7rapio~Tacr6aL kol (frvXaicas yivecrOai eyeprl 
 tcovruiv Kol veupcov. 
 
 CXXI \ . 'SvktutoXol, pdyoL, (3di<xoiy Xrjpai, pvarai. 
 
 CXXV. Ta yap vopi£6peva kcit dpdpanrovs pvcrTrjpia aViepcocrn. 
 pvevvTCU- 
 
 CXXY1. Kat rols dydXpaai TOvreoLai eu^oi/rai, okolop el tis Tuls 
 86uoio~l Xeo-xrjvevoiTO, ov n yipaxruaip deovs ovft rjpeoas, OLTives elo~u 
 
 CXXV 11. Ei prj yap Aiopvcraj TropTrrjp enoievPTO kcu vppeop aapa 
 aldoiotai, dpaibioraTa eipyacT np ' covtos fie 'Atdrjs kol Awpvctos, OTea> 
 uaipovrai nai Xr)pai£ovo-i. 
 
 CXXYIII. Iamblichus de Myst. y. 15: 0v<rtS>v rolwv rldrjpt 
 
 oittci etSr; " to. pep tcop drroKeKaOappepcop naprdnao'ip dpdpdmeop, oia e<fi 
 epos up 7tot€ yepniro anaplcos, ws <fir)(rip 'HpdicXeiTos, rj tipcop oXlycop 
 €vapi8pTjTo>p dpbpoip ' Ta fi' epvXa kcu aopaToeidrj kcu fiia peTaftoXrjs 
 (jvpiardpepa, oia rols en Kar€)(opepois vtto too awpaTos appo£ei. 
 
 CXX'X. "A/cen. 
 
 CXXX. Kcidaipoi'Tcn Oe aifUXTl piaivopepoi ayantp tip el ris es 7rr]Xop 
 r 7rr;Xc3 diroplpoLTn. 
 
(\^ 
 
 xb^ 
 
^* 
 
 
 Deacidified using the Bookkeeper process 
 vP Neutralizing agent: Magnesium Oxide 
 Treatment Date: July 2004 
 
 4 * 4* PreservationTechnologies 
 
 A WORLD LEADER IN PAPER PRESERVATION ^ 
 
 < <&• . o » 1 1 1 Thomson Park Drive 
 
 Cranberry Township, PA 16066 
 (724)779-2111 
 
 zemmrvzz 
 
 

 *»v -m^* ^ v % • 
 
 u ^ 
 
 
 DCCSS BROS 
 
 LIBRARY BINDING 
 
 
 
 
 ST. AUGUSTINE 
 
 n a 
 
 
 % FLA. 
 £§§^32084 
 
 
 
 ^ 
 -£