a It ^^0^ %.^" *^.< C'^V'* "%*^^'/* \'^^*./ •. %.*' -^ nly rule of Ufe 1 17 Is that rule defective 1 Why 1 CHAP. IV. LAW OF GOD. IS I. It omits many duties, as not objects of compulsion. Foi as it never speaks but to command, and commands only where it can compel; voluntary duties, such as piety to God, bounty to the poor, &c. must necessarily be omitted, as beyond the reach of the law. II. It permits, or rather does not punish, many vices, be cause they are incapable of positive description ; for in- stance, prodigality, disrespect to parents, &c. For either it must define accurately the crime to be punished, or it must leave to the discretion of the magistrate the application of a vague description to the individual case ; and thus lead the way to the tyrannical abuse of power. In all cases, where the uncertain nature of the act defies a previously fixed de- scription, the law, in free states, chooses rather to leave men at liberty, than to invest the magistrates with a power so full of danger. CHAP. IV. LAW OF GOD, Whoever expects to find in the Scriptures a specific solu- tion of every doubtful point of moral conduct, looks for more than he will meet with. Had it been otherwise, the volume would have been too bulky to be read, much less circulated ; and, in the language of St. John, the world itself would not have contained all the books necessary to be written. This will appear manifest from considering, that the laws of Eng- land alone, with its acts of parliament and decisions of the courts, occupy nearly one hundred folio volumes ; and yet in not one instance out of ten, when looking for a particulai case, can you find one exactly in point ; to say nothing of 18 "What duties does the law of the land omit ] 19 What kind of duties are not objects of compulsion 1 20 Can there be law without compulsion 1 21 What class of vices go unpunished by the laws of the land % 22 Mention a few examples. 23 What are the only two methods that will lead to their punish raent 1 24 We have said that the first cannot be done. Would it be propei to trust to the discretion of the magistrate 1 Why 7 25 Is it done in free states 1 26 What is the consequence of not granting that power 1 27 Can we find in the Scriptures a particular rule for every act ol morality % 28 Why is that the case 1 29 What evidence have we that particular rules would render the Scriptures too bulky 1 20 PRELIMINARY CONSIDERATIONS. BOOK I. other numerous doubtful cases, on which the law neither does nor professes to state and thing positive. So far, then, from imitating the particularity of human laws, by which the bulk, not value, of the volume would have been increased ; the Scriptures teach morality by general rules, relating to piety, justice, benevolence, and purity ; such, for instance, as to worship God in spirit and in truth ; 'to do as we would be done by ; to love our neighbor as ourself ; and, that pol- lution arises, not from what goes into the mouth, but what comes out of the heart. These rules are illustrated hy fictitious examples, as in the parable of the good Samaritan ; or by real events, as in Christ's praise of the widow's mite ; or by answers to ques- tions put to Christ or his disciples, as in the case of the young man who asked, " What lack I yet?" This plan of instruction is, in fact, the same that is pur- sued in the practical sciences ; where certain rules are laid down, and examples subjoined, not with a view to embrace every possible case, but merely to explain the principle, and to exhibit a specimen of its application. In the Scriptures, however, there is this difference ; that neither the rules nor examples are given methodically, but as occasion suggested the one or the other ; and thus both carry with them a feel- ing of vividness far superior to the coldness of a regular sys- tem. Besides, as the Scriptures are addressed to persons not quite ignorant of the principles of natural justice, they do not so much teach new rules of morality, as enforce the practice of it by new and better motives. Thus, for instance, extor- tioners are condemned by the Scriptures, while the act of ex- tortion is supposed to be known, and consequently not de fined there. Thus much has been said to pro^ve^ that, if the Scriptures be deficient, they are so from design ; and that they do not supersede the use of a science by which such deficiency can be best supplied. 30 How is morality taught in the Scriptures 1 31 How are these rules illustrated 1 32 How does the scriptural plan of instruction agree with that pursued in practical science 1 33 Is there any difference between the two plans 1 34 What is supposed in scriptural instruction 1 35 Give an example. 36 What is the object of scriptural instruction ? 37 What has been intended by these remarks on the scriptures ? CHAP. V. THE MORAL SENSE. 21 CHAP. V. THE MORAL SENSE. The father of Caius Toranius, having been proscribed by the triumvirate, concealed himself in a place known only to his son ; and by this son, who soon after came over to the interests of the triumvirate, he was betrayed. The old man, more anxious for his son's safety and advancement, than about his own danger, inquired of the officers who seized him, whether his son was well, and had done his duty as a eoldier? "That son," said the officer, *' so dear to thee, has betrayed thee ; and to him," striking the old man with a poniard, " thou owest thy death." The unhappy parent fell, affected not so much by his fate, as by the treachery of tiis child. If this story were related to a savage, uninfluenced by the modes of thinking and acting common to civilized life, would he feel that sentiment of disapprobation of yoiing Toranius* conduct which a civilized being feels ? They who maintain the existence of a moral sense, or an instinctive love of virtue and hatred of vice, affirm that he would ; they who deny the existence of such a sense, assert that he would not. [" To those who are at all acquainted with the history of this dispute, it must appear evident that the question is here completely misstated ; and that in the whole of Dr. Paley's subsequent jirgument on the subject, he combats a phantom of his own imagination. Did it ever enter into the mind of the wildest theorist to imagine that the sense of seeing would enable a man brought up from the moment of his birth in utter darkness, to form a conception of light and colors ? But would it not be equally rash to conclude, from the ex- travagance of such a supposition, [that of a savage as above,] that the sense o^ seeing is not an original part of the human 38 What is the intention of the author in chapter 51 Ans. To ascertain whether there is a natural moral sense or conscience. 39 How does he commence the inquiry 1 40 What answer would be given by those who believe that conscience is a part of our nature 1 41 Who assert that he would not? 43 Is Dr. Paley's supposition concerning the last two assertions a pro- per statement of the case "? 43 By what parallel question is the absurdity of Paley's statement shown 1 44 What is the point of Stewart's argument 1 22 PRELIMINARY CONSIDERATIONS. BOOK 1. frame ?" — Stewards Philosophy of the Active and Moral Powers of Man. Book ii. chap, ii.] [" It is necessary, for the supposition above, that the sa- vage should understand, not merely what is meant by the simple relations of son and father, and all the consequences of the treachery of the son, but that he should know also the additional interest which the paternal and filial relation re- ceives from the whole intercourse of good offices from infancy to manhood. The author of our mere being is not all which a father, in such circumstances, is, — ^he is far better known and loved by us as the author of our happiness in childhood and youth, and the venerable friend of our maturer years." — Brown's Philosophy of the Human Mind, LeC' ture 75.] ["In contending for the independence and originality of our moral feelings," says Dr. Brown, " I do not contend that we are capable of these feelings at a period in which we are incapable of forming any conception of the nature and consequences of actions : — that, for example, we must feel instant gratitude, to our mother or our nurse, for the first sustenance or first cares which we receive, before we are conscious of any thing but of our momentary pleasure or pain. We only assert, that when we are capable of under- standing the circumstances of actions, we then have feelings of moral approbation or disapprobation." — lb. Lecture 79.] As the experiment with the savage before mentioned, has never been made, and is not likely, even if it were possible, to be made, the event can be decided from probable reason alone. They who contend for the affirmative, say that we ap- prove of virtue, and condemn vice, on the instant and with- out deliberation, unaffected by personal interest, and unable even to give a reason for such approbation ; and that as this feeling is universal, it can arise only from* an instinctive moral sense. 45 What does Mr. Brown say is necessary for Paley's supposition 1 Whyl 46 If a person has this knowledge, can he be called a savage I 47 What follows from this fact \ 48 What is not contended for, by the advocates of instinctive con- science 1 49 What do they assert 1 50 In what manner should we be obliged to judge of the event, if the supposition was correct 1 Why % 51 What reasons have they who would answer in the affirmative 1 CHAP. V. THE MORAL SENSE. 23 To this it has been replied, 1 . That this feeling is not universal; that there is scarcely a single vice,Vhich is not countenanced in some age or country ; that, for instance, in one place aged parents are supported, in another destroyed by their children, under the same plea of affection ; that sui- cide was in Rome heroism, is in England felony ; that theft, which is punished here, was praised in Sparta ; that, in fine, many things reprobated by civilized nations are practised without reserve by savages. Nor is this difference confined to different nations ; even persons living in the same place view the same acts in a different light ; and their different opinions, depending on the accidental circumstances of sex, age, or station, cause some to consider forgiveness of injuries as magnanimity, while others deem it a meanness ; and so of other acts, which are approved and condemned according to ever varying fashion, unstamped with the steady hand and in- delible characters of universal nature. [" But the historical facts which have been alleged to prove, that the moral judgment of mankind are entirely fac- titious, will be found, upon examination, to be either the effects of misrepresentation or to lead to a conclusion directly the reverse of what has been drawn from them : — proper allowance being made, 1. For the different circum- stances of mankind in different periods of society ; 2. For the diversity of their speculative opinions ; and, 3. For the different moral import of the same action, under different systems of external behavior." — St ew ar f s Outline of Mo- ral Philosophy. — Mr. Stewart also says, " It is sufficient to refer, on the origin of infanticide, to Mr. Smith's Theory on Moral Sentiments ; and, on the alleged impiety among some rude tribes of children towards their parents, to Char- ron Sur la Sagesse, and to an excellent note of Dr. Beattie's in his Essay on Fable and Romance."] [" Again, the same action (if that can truly be called the same action, which is performed, perhaps, with very diffe- rent views or in different circumstances) is, as we might 52 What reply has been given to these reasons 1 53 What examples have been adduced to substantiate the reply "l 54 What differences are mentioned as found among those who may be supposed to associate together ? 55 What does Mr. Stewart remark concerning the examples her© mentioned 1 56 What allowances does he require to be made 1 24 PRELIMINARY CONSIDERATIONS. BOOK I. naturally have supposed, capable of exciting in us different emotions, according to this difference of views or circum stances. It may excite our approval in one case ; or, in an- other case, be so indifferent as to excite no emotion whatever ; and in another case, may excite in us the most vivid disap- probation. The action is nothing, but as it relates to the agent himself, having certain feelings, and placed in certain circumstances." — Br owrC s Philosophy of the Human Mind, Lecture 73.] [" There are many cases in which the result of actions is complicated by a mixture of good and evil, and in which we may fix upon the good, and may infer the intention in the agent of producing this good, which is a part of the mixed result ; while others may fix on the partial evil, and conceive him to have had in view the production of that. The same actions, therefore, may be approved and disapproved in dif- ferent ages and countries, from the greater importance at- tached to the good or to the evil of such compound results, in relation to the general circumstances of society, or the in- fluence, perhaps, of political errors, as to the advantage or injury to society of these particular actions ; and in the same age, and the same country, different individuals may regard the same action with very different moral feelings, from the higher attention paid to certain partial results of it, and the different presumptions thence formed as to the benev- olent or injurious intentions of the agent. All this, it is evident, might take place without the slightest mutability of the principle of moral sentiments ; because, though the action which is estimated may seem to be the same in the cases in which it is approved or condemned, it is truly a different action which is so approved and condemned." — Ib» Lecture 75.] [On this principle, theft might be approved in Sparta, because it led to those habits of vigilance and activity, which that warlike people supposed highly necessary ; murder 57 What two reasons may cause the same action at different times tc excite in us different feelings of right and wrong ? 58 How then must an action be esteemed 1 59 Is the result of every action always completely good or entirely evin I ■ 60 What different views, night this occasion from different indivi- duals ? 61 What would follow from this ? 62 Does this argue a changeableness of conscience % CHAP. V. THE MORAL SENSE. 25 might be looked upon in the primitive states of society as ne cessary, because the checks of law and magistrates were un known. ' In some countries honor is associated with suffering, and it is reckoned a favor to be killed with circum- stances of torture. Instances of this occur in the manners of some American nations, and in the pride which an Indian matron feels when placed on the funeral pile of her deceased husband.' In such cases an action may have to ns all the external marks of extreme cruelty, while it proceeded from a disposition generous and affectionate;] [" But one argument more. That a rule of virtue has been * slighted and condemned by the general fashion,'' is no sort of evidence that those who joined in this general fashion did not still know that it was a rule of virtue. There are many duties which, in the present day, are slighted by the general fashion, and yet no man will stand up and say they are not duties. * Suicide, in one age of the world, has been heroism, in another felony ;' but it is not every action that a man says is heroic that he believes is right. ' Forgiveness of injuries and insults is accounted by one sort of people magnanimity, by another meanness ;' and yet they who thus vulgarly employ the word meanness do not imagine that forbearance and placability are really wrong. " After all, the uniformity of human opinion respecting the great laws of morality is very remarkable. Sir James Mackintosh speaks of Grotius, who had cited poets, orators, historians, &;c. and says, ' He quotes them as witnesses, whose conspiring testimony, mightily strengthened and con- firmed by their discordance on almost every other subject, is a conclusive proof of the unanimity of the whole human race on the great rules of duty and fundamental principles of morals.' " — Dymond' s Essays on the Principles of Morality. Essay 1. chap. 6.] 2. Granting that some general decisions are made with- out deliberation on points of conduct, and those, too, without any inducements of interest on our part ; yet such apparent rapidity of judgment is no proof of the existence of an in- 63 Give a few examples which may be explained by this principle. 64 Is a general perpetration of a vice, any evidence that individual consciences do not condemn if? 65 Mention a few examples. 66 Is there in fact a great diversity of opinion respecting right and wrong 1 67 What is the second argument against the idea of a moral sense "^ C 26 PKELIMINARY CONSIDER ATIOIS'S. BOOK I. stinciive moral sense. Because, this phenomenon may be ea- sily accounted for, by remarking the facility with which the mind draws general conclusions from insulated facts ; and by noticing how readily the sentiment, which was the result of reflection as applied to the first case of a moral question, ac- quires the force of an habitual sentiment, when applied to a subsequent similar case. Of this continuance of a feeling, even when the reason for it has ceased, the example of the miser is remarkably in point; who, when in years, and without ties of blood or friendship, continues to add to his hoard, and although he may even be sensible of his folly, still carries on his pursuit with all the ardor of an incipient passion, or the dread of im- pending starvation. By such means, the custom of approving or disapproving certain actions commences : and the custom, once established, grows stronger and stronger by the various modes of social intercourse, such as censure and encouragements, the tenden- cy of books and conversation, &c. ; until the lesson of the child, repeated by the man and scarce forgotten in dotage^ produces that uniformity of sentiment, which is felt by all, though traced by few during its progress of association to the real principle of imitation. Of the power of this principle the most conspicuous in- stance is afforded by children, in whom the propensity to imitate is, if any thing deserves the name, an instinct. By this very power, children learn first the words and then the ideas attached to the terms connected with the feelings of love and hatred, and of praise and censure, and thus exemplify, both in theory and practice, the generation of a moral sense. [" But it is admitted that our moral powers, like all our other powers, may be influenced by education, by passion, by habit, by association, and by political arrangement ; but by no circumstances can man be brought to view pure bene- volence and deliberate malice with the same feelings, or to regard all the actions of voluntary agents with the same 68 What example is given to prove that conscience proceeds from habit 1 69 How is it said that the custom of approving certain actions is con- tinued 1 70 To what ultimate principle is it ascribed ? 71 What is said of imitation 1 72 Do the advocates of the moral sense admit that it may be influenced Z 73 To what length in this admission will they not go 1 CHAP. V. THE MORAL SENSE. 27 equal indifference." — Btwar^s Elements of Christian Ethics, Book ii. chap. 9.] Another objection to the system of moral instincts is, that its maxims do not bend to circumstances. Veracity, which seems to be, if any, a moral duty, is not in that system per- mitted to be violated, as it ought to be. For as the obligation of a promise depends on the circumstances under which it was made, it cannot be enforced, if it was unlawful at .the time in which it was made, or if it has become so since, or if it was extorted. It has been further objected to the same system, that, if there existed an instinctive moral sense ; a clear idea also would have existed of the object connected with such in- stinct. For the instinct and object are of necessity insepara- ble, both in imagination and reality ; that is, if it were an instinct to approve an act, we should have (what we have not) a clear conception of such act. As the preceding argument, however, if true, would deny the existence of instinct even in brutes, it will hardly carry conviction, although it cannot easily be answered. [On this subject, Dr. Brown remarks, *' I am astonished, that Paley should have stated this as an objection,. to which * it is difficult to find an answer ;' since there is no objection to which the answer is more obvious. There is not a feel- ing of the mind however universal it may be, to the exist- ence of which, precisely the same objection might not be opposed. There is no part of the world, for example, in which the proportions of number and quantity are not felt to be the same. Four are to twenty as twenty to a hundred, wherever those numbers are distinctly conceived; but, though we come into the world capable of feeling the truth of this proportion, when the numbers themselves shall have been previously conceived by us, no one surely contends that it is necessary, for this capacity, that we should come into the world with an accurate knowledge of the particular num- bers." — Lee. 74.] But Dr. Paley continues, — It seems to me, either that there is no instinctive moral 74 What other objection has been brought against moral instincts ] 75 What virtue is adduced as example 1 76 What is said to be the obligation of veracity 1 77 What argument is brought from the nature of instincts 1 78 What would this argument tend to 1 79 How does Dr. Brown answer it 1 S8 PRELIMINARY CONSIDERATIONS. BOOK I. sense, or if there is, it is not to be distinguished from habit ; and consequently it is unsafe to found on such uncertain data a system of ethics ; or to determine on the right or wrong of certain actions by appealing to impulses, which may or may not exist, instead of looking, as we ought, to the general tendency of such actions. [This is the conclusion to which Paley has arrived. But the opposite opinion is maintained by the generality of modern writers. It is hut just to Dr. Paley to suppose that he was ' combatting a phantom of his own imagination.' He probably considered the moral sense as a supposed in- fallible arbiter of action^ while the true definition refers it only to the intention of the actor. We will subjoin a few authorities.] [" Conscience is an original and inherent faculty in man, and is universal in its operation. If any doubt had remained as to the existence of the moral faculty, or conscience, as an original power in human nature, that doubt would be removed by the explicit testimony of the apostle, which I am about to quote. The passage which contains this testimony must have escaped the notice of Paley, otherwise he would not have hesitated, as he has done, in admitting that man is en- dowed with a moral capacity. 'For when the Gentiles, which have not the law, do by nature the things contained in the law, these having not the law, are a law unto them- selves : which show the work of the law written in their hearts, their conscience also bearing witness, and their thoughts the meanwhile accusing, or else excusing one an- other.' " — Dewar^s Elements of Christian Ethics. Chap. 9.] [" The moral faculty is an original principle of our con- stitution, which is not resolvable into any other principle or principles more general than itself; in particular it is not resolvable into self-love or a prudential regard to our own interests." — Steivarfs Philosophy of the Active and Moral Powers of Man. Book ii. chap. 3.] [" In tracing our moral feelings to an original su^ eptibility 80 What is Dr. Paley's conclusion relative to the point i* A«bate 1 8 1 Is this the opinion of other writers ? 82 What probably occasioned this decision of Paley's 1 83 Give Dr. Dewar's opinion. 84 What S ^ripture does he quote as authority "* 85 What is Stewart's opinion ] CHAP. V. THE MORAL SENSE. 29 of the mind, we may be considered as arriving at a principle like that which Dr. Hutcheson, after Lord Shaftesbury, has distinguished by the name of moral sense. The phrase mo- ral sense, however, I consider as very unfortunate. But whether the feeling that attends the contemplation of certain actions admit of being more justly classed with our sensa- tions, or perceptions, or emotions; there is still a suscepti- bility of this feeling, or set of feelings, original in the mind, and as essential to its very nature, as any other principle or function, which we regard as universally belonging to our mental constitution ; as truly essential to the mind, indeed, as any of those senses among which Dr. Hutcheson would fix its place." — Brown on the Human Mind. Lee. 82.] Aristotle presumes that nature intended that barbarians should be slaves ; and deduces from this maxim conclusions in favor of the slave-trade, which then prevailed ; and the same maxim is doubtless self-evident to those who are now engaged in a similar traffic. Now in this example it is plain that the laws of custom have been mistaken for the order of nature ; and as nothing is so easy as to mistake a maxim, when in unison with the pre- judices of the maker ; Dr. Paley argues that it is to be feared a system of morality, founded on instincts and impulses, would only find out excuses for established practices rather than reasons for correcting them. (^This is another evidence that Dr. Paley mistook the nature and the intention of the moral faculty. It is not considered as establishing a system of practical morality by passing sen- tence upon each moral act in detail ; but merely enforcing general duties, and leaving our own understandings to decide what particular duties should be inferred from them. — See the following.'] ["An action is (as a moral object) not the mere produc- tion of good or evil, but the intentional production of good or evil. It has no moral meaning whatever, but as it is significant of the frame of mind oi the agent himself, willing 86 What does Dr. Brown says that his speculations lead to 1 87 What is his opinion of the phrase moral sense 1 88 What example does Dr. Paley bring to show that the laws of custom may be mistaken for the order of nature "? 89 What principle does he deduce from this 1 90 Would this be a correct deduction from acknowledging the moral faculty in its true nature 1 91 What makes any action moral or immoral 1 30 PRELIMINARY CONSIDERATIONS. BOOK I and producing a particular result." — Broivn on the Human Mind. Lecture 79.] [" The epithets right and wrong, virtuous and vicious, are applied sometimes to external actions, and sometimes to the intentions of the agent. It was to obviate the confusion of ideas that arises from this ambiguity of language, that the distinction between absolute and relative rectitude was in- troduced into ethics. And as the distinction is equally just and important, it will be proper to explain it particularly ; and point out its application to one or two questions which have been perplexed by that vagueness of expression which it is our object at present to correct. " An action may be said to be absolutely right, when it is in every respect suitable to the circumstances in which the agent is placed. Or, in other words, when it is such as, with perfectly good intentions, under the guidance of an en- lightened and well-informed understanding, he would have performed. " An action may be said to be relatively right, when the intentions of the agent are sincerely good, whether his con- duct be suitable to his circumstances or not. " According to these definitions, an action may be right in one sense, and wrong in another ; an ambiguity in lan- guage which, how obvious soever, has not always been attended to by the writers on morals. "It is the relative rectitude of an action which determines the moral desert of the agent ; but it is its absolute rectitude which determines its utility to his worldly interests and to the welfare of society." — Stewart^ s Active and Moral Pow- ers of Man. Book iv. chap. 5. Also, Outlines of Moral Philosophy. Lecture 5.] Dr. Paley proceeds in his argu- ment, which we will insert, although it appears to be foreign to our subject. Granting the existence of moral instincts ; what is their power ? The power, it is said, of conscience, whose remorse the ill-doer feels. But if he does not feel that remorse, or if 92 To what are the terms nght and -wrong, virtuous and vicious ap- plied \ 93 What remedy has been used for this ambiguity of language % 94 When is an action said to be absolutely right ? 95 When is an action said to be relatively right ? 96 What ambiguity in language do these definitions occasion 1 97 What kind of rectitude determines the moral desert '\ 98 What kind determines the utility of an action 1 CHAP. V. THE MORAL SENSE. 31 he holds it liglit, when balanced against the pleasure or pro- fit of a wicked act ; (on which point, the sinner who feels both the pleasure of the sin and the pain of remorse, is the best judge ;) the advocate for a moral instinct has no motive sufficiently high to offer. For should he say that such in- stincts are indications of God's will, and a presage of a fu- ture state ; we reply, he resorts to a rule and motive ulterior to instincts, and which the believer in the Scriptures arrives at by a surer road ; at least so long as the question remains unsettled whether there is an existence or not of instinctive maxims. This question is, therefore, in our system one of mere curiosity ; and left to those who are more inquisitive than ourselves about the natural history of man. [But Bishop Butler says, " The practical reason of insist- ing much upon the natural authority of conscience, is, that it seems in a great measure overlooked by many, who are by no means the worse sort of men. It is thought sufficient to abstain from gross wickedness, and to be humane and kind to such as happen to come in their way. Whereas, in reality, the very constitution of our nature requires that we bring our whole conduct before this superior faculty ; wait its determination ; enforce upon ourselves its authority ; and make it the business of our lives, (as it is absolutely the whole business of a moral agent,) to conform ourselves to it. The observation that man is thus, by his very nature, a law to himself, pursued to its just consequences, is of th? utmost importance. Because, from it will follow, that though men should, through stupidity or speculative scepticism, be igno- rant of, or disbelieve any authority in the universe to punish a violation of this law ; yet, if there should be such autho- rity, they would be as really liable to punishment, as though they had been convinced beforehand, that such punishment would follow. Because it is not foreknowledge of the pu- nishment, which renders obnoxious to it ; but merely violat- ing a known obligation.^'' Preface to Sermons on Human Nature.] [The object of Dr. Paley, in his preceding remarks, ap- 99 In conclusion, what does Dr. Paley say of this question 7 100 Has Bishop Butler the same opinion 1 101 What would follow from determining that conscience is a law tr man'? 102 What is it that renders us liable to punishment 1 103 What was the object of Dr. Paley in his remarks on the moBal sense 1 32 PRELIMINARY CONSIDERATIONS. BOOK I pears to have been, to show that the moral faculty should not be Our guide in regulating our duties. But nearly all modern moralists have come to a different conclusion.] [Dr. Dewar says, " This is the monitor which God has superadded to reason, which, while it shows us the essen- tial distinction between what is right and wrong in ac- tions, between virtue and vice, reminds us of the high and glorious purposes for which our nature has been formed." — Elements of Christian Ethics. Book iii. chap. 2.] [Mr. Stewart says, " Every being who is conscious of the distinction between right and wrong, carries about with him a law which he is bound to observe." And in support of this proposition, he has quoted passages from many authors. — Philosophy of Active and Moral Powers of Man. Book ii. chap. 6.] [Mr. Dymond says, " With respect to the authority which properly belongs to conscience as a director of indi- vidual conduct, it appears manifest alike from reason and from Scripture, that it is great. When a man believes, upon due deliberation, that a certain action is right, that action is right to him. And this is true, whether the action be or be not required of mankind by the moral law. The fact that in his mind the sense of obligation attaches to the act, and that he has duly deliberated upon the accuracy of his judgment, makes the dictate of his conscience upon that subject an authoritative dictate. The individual is to be held guilty if he violates his conscience, — if he does one thing, while his sense of obligation is directed to its contrary. These principles respecting the authority of conscience are recog- nised in Scripture. ' One belie veth that he may eat all things : another who is weak eateth herbs. One man es- teemeth .one day above another ; another esteemeth every day alike.' Here then are differences, nay, contrarieties of conscientious judgments. And w^hat are the parties direct- ed, severally to do ? ' Let every man be fully persuaded in his own mind ;' that is, let the full persuasion of his own mind be every man's rule of action. Thus again : ' I know 104 Do other moralists agree with himl 105 What does Dr. Dewar say is shown by conscience'? 106 What does Stewart say of our observing its dictates? 107 What does Mr. Dymond say of its authority 1 108 What makes an action right in his opinion ] 109 What does he think makes a man guilty 1 110 What two examples does he bring from scripture 1 CHAP. V. THE MORAL SENSE. 33 and am persuaded by the Lord Jesus, that there is nothing- unclean of itself ;' therefore absolutely speaking, it is lawful to eat all things : ' but to him that esteemeth any thing to be unclean, to him it is unclean.' Rom. xiv. The question is not whether his judgment was correct, but what that judg- ment actually was." — Prin. of Morality. Essay 1. ch. 6.] [Dr. Paley himself says in his sermons, " Conscience, our own conscience, is to be our guide in all things." — " It is through the whisperings of conscience, that the spirit speaks. If men are wilfully deaf to their consciences, they cannot hear the spirit. If hearing, if being compelled to hear the remonstrances of conscience, they nevertheless decide and resolve and determine to go against them ; then they grieve, then they defy, then they do despite to, the Spirit of God."] [But as Dr. Dewar says, " Though conscience is an original and inherent faculty in man, and universal in its operation, it requires, in order to discharge its office fully, to be enlightened by moral and religious truth. Our moral powers, like all our powers, may be influenced by education, by passion, by habit, by association, and by political arrangements. And it is not to be denied that this power of human nature is affected with the corruption of the race ; and that this cor- ruption shows itself by moral insensibility. Hence in the Scriptures, persons under the dominion of hardness and im- penitency of heart, are likened to the deaf adder that stop- peth her ear, which will not hearken to the voice of the charmer, charm he never so wisely ; and they are said to have the understanding darkened, being alienated from the life of God through the ignorance that is in them, because of the blindness of their heart, and who are past feeling." — Elements of Christian Ethics. Book ii. chap. 9.] [But further, in the words of Mr. Stewart, " A strong sense of duty will induce us to avail ourselves of all the talents we possess, and of all the information within our reach, to act agreeably to the rules of absolute rectitude. And if we fail in doing so, our negligence is criminal. Not- 1 1 1 Did Dr. Paley always hold to the same sentiments that he has ad- vocated here 1 112 Can our moral powers be affected by any circumstances ? 1 1 3 What does Dr. Dewar say is rendered necessary by this 1 114 Will not conscience, if it has its perfect work, correct itself in thiss respect 1 115 If we do not fulfil this duty, what is the consequence'? 34 PRELIMINARY CONSIDERATIONS. BOOK I withstanding, however, the truth and the importance of this doctrine, the general principle already stated remains incon- trovertible, that in every particular instance our duty con- sists in doing what appears to us to be right at the time ; and if, whUe we follow this rule, we should incur any blame, our demerit does not arise from acting according to an erro- neous judgment, but from our previous' misemployment ot the means we possessed for correcting the errors to which our judgment is liable." — Philosophy of the Active and Mo- ral Powers. Book iv. chap. V. sec. 3. Outlines, Lecture 5.] [The business of ascertaining the rules of absolute recti- tude is the most important part of the science of ethics. " In- deed without this study, the best dispositions of the heart, whether relating to ourselves or to others, may be in a great measure useless." This is the study which is to be pursued in the subsequent part of this work.] THE CULTURE OF THE MORAL FACULTIES. [Mr. Stewart gives the following as the difference between conscience and moral faculty. *' Conscience refers to our own conduct alone ; whereas, the moral faculty is meant to express also the power by which we approve or disapprove of the conduct of others." — Active and Moral Powers of Man. Book iv. chap. 2. " The moral faculty, like the faculty of reason, (which forms the most essential of its elements,) requires care and cultivation for its developement ; and, like reason, it has a gradual progress, both in the case of individuals and of soci- eties." — lb. Book iv. chap. 5. sec. 4. " While God has so formed our nature as to be capable of admiring and practising virtue, he has intrusted the cul- ture of our moral powers to our own care ; and has reminded us that for our diligence in improving this noblest part of our stewardship, we are to give an account at his tribunal." — Dewar^s Christian Ethics. Book ii. chap. 9. There are several methods by which our consciences may be cultivated ; and, 116 Where in such circumstances would our guilt fall ] 1 17 What then is the most important part of ethics 1 118 How does the moral faculty differ from conscience 1 119 Can the moral faculties be improved 1 120 Is it our duty to improve them? 121 What is the first means of training our moral faculties 1 CHAP. V. CULTURE OF THE MORAL FACULTIES. 35 1. By the virtuous influence of others. The infant mind is formed by the care of our early instructors, and for a long time thinks and acts in consequence of the confi- dence it reposes in their superior judgment. All this is un- doubtedly agreeable to the design of nature ; and, indeed, if the case were otherwise, the business of the world could not possibly go on. For nothing can be plainer than that the multitude, condemned as they are to laborious employments, inconsistent with the cultivation of their mental faculties, are wholly incapable of forming their own opinions on the most important questions which can occupy the human mind." But the authority of this influence must not be too much re- lied upon. For, "it is evident that as no system of educa- tion can be perfect, many prejudices must mingle with the most important and best ascertained truths." — Stewart, 2. By a continual solicitude that our opinions and con- duct should conform to the principles of moral rectitude. " Let any honest man," says Butler, " before he engages in any course of action, ask himself. Is this I am going to do, right, or is it wrong ; is it good, or is it evil ? I do not in the least doubt but that these questions would be answered agreeably to truth and vij-tue, by almost any fair man, in al- most any circumstances." 3. The study of the Scriptures, and a firm adherence to the precepts they contain.* " Man in his present state," says Dick in his Philosophy of Religion, " can be directed 1 22 Is this influence in accordance with the design of nature 1 123 Is it necessary"? Why 1 124 Is this influence always on the side of virtue? 125 What is the second help in moral culture 1 126 Would this disposition lead to truth 1 1 27 What is the next great help in teaching us pur duty 1 * To some, this article may seem as foreign to the subject. But its application where revelation is known is unavoidable. The intermediate truths, of the being and government of God, the revelation of his will to mankind, and his wisdom and holiness in willing that which is right, is considered, in this work, as assented to. We wish to state, however, in the language of Mr. Dick, " That the laws of God are not the commands of an arbitrary sovereign, but are founded on the nature of things, and on the relations which exist in the intelligent system." And again, in the language of Dr. Dewar, "The law of God is the explicit announcement of the nature and extent of those obligations devolving upon men, which had previously existed, and would have existed though no such announce- ment had been made." 36 PRELIMINARY CONSIDERATIONS. BOOK I. only by positive laws, proceeding from the Almighty ; whose comprehensive mind alone can trace all their con- sequences to the remotest corners of the universe, and through all the ages of eternity. These laws are contained in the Scriptures ; and we know, in point of fact, that in every country where these laws are either unknown, or not recognised, there is no fixed standard of naorals ; and vice, in its various ramifications, almost universally prevails." 4. " Finally an habitual effort to cultivate a sense of the Divine presence, and an habitual desire to have the whole moral condition regulated by this impression." — " He who earnestly cultivates this purity within, feels that he requires continual watchfulness, and a constant direction of the mind to those truths and moral causes which are calculated to in- fluence his volitions. He feels further that he is in need of a might not his own in this high design ; but for this he knows also he can look, with humble confidence and hope, when, under a sense of moral weakness, he asks its power- ful aid." To these may be added the assistance which conscience may receive on particular occasions, as Mr. Stewart says, *'from the exercise of reason ; especially when there appears to be an interference between different duties, and where, of course, it seems necessary to sacrifice one duty to another ; and also, when the ends at which our duty prompts us to aim, are to be accomplished by means which require choice and deliberation."] CHAP. VI. HUMAN HAPPINESS. "Happy" is a relative term, and regards an individual as compared either with others or himself. In the one case the comparison is with the lot of man generally ; in the other with the individual's own previous or subsequent condition. Strictly speaking, that condition may be called happy, in which the aggregate of pleasure exceeds the amount of pain. The quantity of such excess is the measure of the degree 128 What is the state of morals where the Scriptures are not the standard 1 129 By what desire should we be actuated in all our doings? 130. What feelings would this occasion 1 131 In what cases may the exercise of reason assist us 1 132 How is the word " happy" applied 1 133 What condition may be called happy 1 CHAP. VI. HUMAN HAPPINESS. 37 of happiness ; and the greatest quantity attainable by man is what we mean to express, when the phrase human happi- ness is employed in our discourse. In this inquiry it is needless to enlarge on the dignity of man, of the superiority of the intellect over the body, of the delicacy and refinement of some pleasures, or of the grossness and sensuality of others ; because pleasures in fact differ only in degree, and not in kind; and it is from a view of their intensity, or of their continuance, that every question respecting human hap- piness must receive its decision. It will be our business merely to show, i. What human happiness does not con- sist in ; and, ii. What it does consist in. 1. Happiness does not consist in the pleasures of sense ; that is, gratification of animal appetites, admiration of works of art, and exercise in active sports. For, 1st, these pleasures are short-lived, especially the grosser kind ; and much more so when considered independently of the aid derived from prepa- ration and expectation. 2dly, they lose their charm by repe- tition ; for, as the nerves, by which we receive pleasurable sensations, lose their sensibility by frequent exercise ; in the same way the mind becomes indifferent to a gratification no longer new. 3dly, the eagerness for intense delights de- stroys the relish for others less intense ; and as such high gratifications occur seldom, time must hang heavy on our hands. From no delusion do men suffer so much as from the ex- pectation of intense pleasure. The very expectation spoils the anticipated delight. Even when the enjoyment does come, efforts are made to persuade ourselves of the reality of the pleasure, instead of our finding that the pleasure is produced without effort ; and the delight we aimed at is gene- 134 What is meant by the phrase human happiness ? 135 Do pleasures really differ in kind 1 136 What two considerations must enter every question on happi- ness? 137 What does the author propose to show 1 138 What is his first remark on the negative 1 1 39 What does he call pleasures of sense 1 139 What is the first reason ? 140 What is the second reason 1 How so ? 141 What is the third reason 7 What follows from that? 142 What is said of the expectation of intense pleasure 1 143 When enjoyment does come, how is it accompanied 1 144 Do we experience the delight we aimed at 1 D 38 PRELIMINARY CONSIDERATIONS. BOOK I. rally supplanted by the secret grief of having missed our aim. Besides, the habit of seeking powerful stimulants prevents the relish for less intense delights, whose variety and suc- cession alone supply the stream of continued happiness. They, whose whole business is the pursuit of pleasure, unrestrained by conscience or want of means, are still de- voured by ennui. With a restless passion for variety, they become fastidious in the choice of pleasure : and though languid in the enjoyment, are miserable under the want of it. Their pleasures soon reach their limits, from which they as soon decline, because the organs of perception cannot long remain on the stretch. And in the endeavor to compensate for the brevity of the pleasure by its frequency, more is lost than gained, through the fatigue of the faculties and the dimi- nution of sensibility ; which, as age advances, are felt the most by the voluptuary, who, teased by desires that can never be gratified, is tortured still more by the memory of pleasures fled never to return. After all, these pleasures have some value ; and although the young are always too eager in their pursuit of them, the old are sometimes too studious of their ease to take that pains for them which they really deserve. 2. Happiness does not consist in the absence of pain, bodily and mental, when that absence is accompanied by no kind of exertion. For such a listless state, like the opposite restless state of the voluptuary, brings with it the same feel- ing of ennui ; and oppresses first the mind with imaginary evils, and afterwards the body with real ones. Hence the disappointment felt by those persons, who seek for happiness by a retirement from the bustle and glare of active life, to the leisure and tranquillity of a country house. Where the cause of uneasiness is known, by removing the cause, the uneasi- ness is cured. But where the distress is imaginary, (and, for 145 What kind of delights occasion continued happiness ? 146 How do our anticipations affect the relish for them ? 147 What is the general feeling of those whose professed pursuit is pleasure ? 148 What is said of their pleasures 1 Why is that the case 1 149 Can their brevity be compensated by their frequency 1 Why 1 150 Are pleasures of this kind really valueless 1 151 How do the aged and the young differ in their pursuit of them 1 152 What is the second assertion on the negative 1 1 53 What effect has the absence of exertion ? 154 What disappointment does this account for ] CHAP. VI. HUMAN HAPPINESS. 39 the want of a real, imaginary distress is frequently substi- tuted, and felt as keenly as the real,) the cure, from the igno- rance of the cause, becomes impracticable ; unless the at- tention of the party so suflering be turned from the ima- ginary to a real pain. This is a method of mitigation employed by nature. For instance, a fit of the gout will some- times cure the spleen. In like manner, the active excitement of hope and fear leads men of liberal minds to gaming, and other spirit-stirring pursuits, to prevent the fatigue they would : therwise feel from the dead calm of passionless inaction. 3. Happiness does not consist in an elevated station of ife. For if all superiority afforded pleasure, the greater the number over whom such superiority is found to be, the greater would be the quantity of happiness enjoyed. But superiority is a term of confined import, and relates only to a comparison amongst persons who deem themselves gene- rally equal. The shepherd is not pleased with his superior- ity as compared with his dog, nor the prince as compared with a peasant. Where no competition exists, the superior- ity is lost; a fact little noticed by most men. But if the rustic can excel fellow-rustics, or the prince fellow-princes, in points where they respectively contend for mastery ; then, and only then, does the idea of superiority bring with it ac- tual satisfaction. Hence the pleasure of ambition is not confined, as generally thought, to men of high rank in life, but is in reality common to all conditions. The farrier, who is in the greatest request for his veterinary skill, pos- sesses the delight of distinction, as truly and substantially as the prime-minister does whose skill is required to settle the afifairs of the nation. In either case, it is not the object of competition, but the consciousness of overcoming a rival, that constitutes the pleasure of superiority. Philosophers smile at the contempt shown by the rich to 155 What is said of imaginary .distress 1 156 What is the natural method of curing a trifling ailment 1 157 W^hat pursuits are accounted for on this principle ? 158 What is the third negative assertion 1 159 What would be the result if all superiority afforded pleasure] 160 What is necessary to make superiority a pleasure 1 161 What kind of superiority does yield satisfaction 1 162 Where does this fact show the pleasures of ambition to hel Give an illustration. 163 What do philosophers think of contempt shown by the rich, con cerning ambitious strifes among the poor? Why "? 40 PRELIMINARY CONSIDERATIONS. BOOK I. the petty rivalries of the poor ; which, after all, are quite as reasonable as the squabbles of the rich themselves, to whom and to the poor the pleasure of success is the same. That happiness, then, of the great, which depends on the pleasures of ambition, is not greater than the happiness of the vulgar. But whether the pursuits pf ambition in any case can a source of happiness, is a question both irrelevant and doubtful. In those pursuits, the pleasure of success is exquisite ; but so also is the anxiety of pursuit, and the pain of disappointment if that should happen. But what is worse, the pleasure when obtained is short-lived. Rivals that are left behind are less regarded than those in view before ; a succession of new struggles is kept up as long as an oppo- nent remains ; and when there is none, the pleasure and the pursuit are both at an end. Happiness, then, does not consist in the pleasures of sense, in the absence of pain, or in the pursuits of ambi- tion. II. We are now to consider in what happiness does con sist. In life, the great art is to know beforehand, what will please for a time and continue to please. But this fore- knowledge is difficult of attainment. Some pleasures, allur- ing at a distance, become, when possessed, insipid or short- lived ; while others start up unthought of. The necessity of this foreknowledge is the greater, because it is commonly impracticable to change, after an experiment has been tried ; and were the change more practicable, it would be unadvi- sable, as such shifting is unfavorable to the happiness of any condition. Through the great variety of taste in man, arising from every different shade of original structure and accidental situ- ation, it is impossible to devise a plan of universal happiness. All that can be attempted is, to describe a mode of life, in which the majority will seem the happiest; for though the apparent happiness is not the true indication of what is real, it is the best we can arrive at. 164 Is there happiness in any ambition? 1 65 Give some description of the pursuit of it. 166 What is the conclusion of this section of the chapter ? 167 What is the great art in seeking for happiness 1 168 Why is this foreknowledge difficult 1 169 What increases the necessity of this knowledge? 170 Will any plan of happiness be adapted to all 1 Why 1 171 What is our best criterion of happiness "I CHAP. VI. HUMAN HAPPINESS. 41 With this maxim as the guide, happiness will be found to consist — 1. In the exercise of the social affections. Good spirits are a proof of apparent, if not of real happiness. Now as they who lead a social life, surrounded by objects of affection, possess better spirits than they who pass a solitary life, it is fair to infer that they are more happy. In like manner, the exercise of social sympathies increases the sum of happiness by connecting the individual with the rest of mankind, through the refreshing medium of acts kindly done and grate- fully acknowledged. 2. In the employment of our faculties in some interesting distant object. No fulness of present pleasure can insure a continuance of happiness, unless the mind has something to look forward to. Hence we see alacrity of spirits in those men who are engaged in objects of engrossing interest ; and dejection in those, whose faculties have not been exerted at all, or have become exhausted from a too violent use of them. To avoid this insupportable vacuity of mind, re- course is had to practices destructive of health, fortune, or character; and objects are sought for with trouble, which could without trouble be obtained. But though hope, by giving rise to continued exertions, is of so much importance as an ingredient in happiness; care must be taken, else it may fret the mind into impatience, or destroy it by despair. To provide, then, ourselves with a succession of pleasurable engagements, there is need of judgment to choose the end adapted to our opportunities, and of imagination to transfer the idea of pleasure to the means used for obtaininff that end. ^ Hence the pleasures most valuable are those productive not of most intensity of fruition, but of activity in their pursuit. 172 What is first mentioned as necessary to happiness? 1 73 What proof have we that social affections produce happiness 1 174 What is next mentioned as necessary to happiness ? 175 What is necessary to insure the continuance of present happi- ness 1 ^ ^^ 1 76 What is an illustration of this 1 177 What does a v&cuity of mind lead to ? 178 Is it necessary to temper our hope 1 Why 1 179 What two things are necessary for our happiness' 180 What pleasures are most valuable ? d3 42 PRELIMINARY CONSIDERATIONS. BOOK I. Herein has the man, who is in earnest in his endeavors after a future state, the advantage over all the M^orld. His pursuit is one of constant activity, and, unlike other pursuits, ends only w^ith his life. Yet even such a man must have many ends besides the far one. But all such other ends are only subordinate to and co-operate w^ith the main object of his fondest and firmest hopes. Occupation is every thing. And it is the better as it is the more connected with our social state, with reference either to mankind or to individuals ; and as exhibited in stre- nuous endeavors to better in some way others or one's-self. But if faculties or opportunities be wanting to exert our- selves on a large scale or extensive sphere ; any engagement, however trifling, provided it be innocent, is better than none. For so long only as the mind is employed, it is happy. Misery is the inevitable result of a mind not fixed for the time being to one pursuit. 3. In the prudent formation of habits. The grand secret in the art of human happiness is to set the habits so that every change may be for the better. But as whatever is ha- bitual is easy, and a return to an old habit after an occasional departure is also easy, those habits are the best, from which a deviation is an indulgence. To the habitually luxurious, dainties are of less worth, than is to the peasant his habitual homely fare ; from which when the latter deviates, he finds a feast ; while the former must be well entertained to escape disgust. They who sit at cards, and they who follow a plough, so long as both are mtent on their respective em- ployments, are equally happy ; but to the card-player, in- terruption is a pain ; to the ploughman a pleasure ; and hence the Sabbath is a day of rest to one, of restlessness to 181 How does this fact affect a man who lives for a future state Why is this the case 1 182 Can we suppose that any man lives solely for eternity 1 183 Of what character are the other objects of a good man 1 184 What enhances the value of occupation ? 185 What is the value of trifling engagements ? 186 What circumstances will render us happy, and what miserable 1 187 What is mentioned in the third place as necessary for happi ness? ' 188 How are such habits set ? What is this prudence called 1 189 What habits are best 1 Why 1 1 90 Give some illustrations, in the case of the peasant ; — of the labor «r ; -of one accustomed to retirement ; — of a reader of scientific works 1 CHAP. VI. HUMAN HAPPINESS. 43 the Other. He who has learned to live alone, enters into company with hilarity, and leaves it without regret ; while he who only lives in a crowd, enjoys in company only what the other does alone, habitual gratification. Remove, by a want of health or means, the one from his usual haunts, and he will find in solitude the horrors of melancholy ; while the other can find there all the charm of repose. The one, restless through the day, is happy only when asleep ; to the other, the day, being furnished with employment for every hour, is never too long ; or if unemployed in body, he enjoys a kind of dreamy existence, with a mind at ease and hanker- ing after nothing. In like manner, he who has been accus- tomed to read works of science and depth of thought, finds in lighter literature a relaxation and relish which is unknown to the reader who, with the desire of novelty alone, is rather seeking amusement than actually amused. And the latter also, quickly exhausting the scanty stock of publications to his taste, is left without objects of interest in the . extensive field of intellectual enjoyment. Again, as far as money brings happiness, it is not the in- come, but its increase, which gives the pleasure. Two per- sons, one of whom begins with a large and ends with a small income, while the other begins with a small and ends with a large one, may, in the course of the same time, spend the same sum ; but their satisfaction will be different, de- pending on the fact whether they respectively began at the end of the ascending or descending scale. 4. In the enjoyment of health. By health is here meant not only freedom from bodily ailments, but the possession of good spirits ; which, though dependent on the state of the body generally, are not usually included in the definition of that word. In this comprehensive sense, health is the one thing needful ; and no sacrifice of rank and fortune, business or amusement, will be considered too great for its attainment, by him who pursues his happiness in a rational manner. It is a pleasure independent of all others ; and of which we can only say that it is the gift of a benevolent Deity; and seems 191 How does money produce pleasure 1 192 Give an illustration. 193 What is the fourth requisite for happiness ? 194 What is meant by the health here spoken of? 195 Is all this generally included in the idea of health ? 196 What is said of this kind of health ? 44 PRELIMINARY CONSIDERATIONS. BOOK I. to constitute the sole happiness of many animals, which, like oysters, possess no visible means of enjoyment. From this view of happiness we may infer, what moral- ists have not proved : — 1. That happiness is pretty equally distributed in civil society ; 2. That vice has no advantage over virtue, even in this world. CHAP. VII. VIRTUE. Virtue is the doing good to mankind in obedience to the will of God, and for the sake of everlasting happiness. In this definition, the " good of mankind" is the subject ; the " will of God," the rule ; and "everlasting happiness," the motive of virtue. [^Concerning the first part of this definition, Mr. Stewart says, " It has been supposed by some moralists that the obligation of all our moral duties arises entirely from their apprehended tendency to promote the happiness of society. Notwith- standing the various appearances in human nature, which seem at first view to favor this theory, it is liable to unsur- mountable objections."— Ow^/mes of Moral Philosophy. Part ii. chap. 2. sec. 2.] [Concerning the latter part of the definition. Dr. Brown says, " Virtue he defines to be, ' the doing good to mankind, in obedience to the will of God, and for the sake of ever- lasting happiness.' The last part of the definition is the ihost important part of the whole. For, the knowledge of this everlasting happiness he supposes to be all which con- stitutes moral obligation ; meaning, by obligation, not any feeling of moral love, but the influence of happiness as an object of physical desire, and of pain as an object of physi- cal aversion; one or other of which is to follow our obedience or disobedience to the command of the power who is the supreme dispenser of both. That part of the system of Dr. Paley, then, which makes the sole motive to virtue the happiness of the agent himself, is false." — Phi- losophy of the Human Mind, Lecture 79.] 197 What two inferences are deduced from the positions advanced in this chapter 1 198 How does Dr. Paley define virtue 1 199 What does he says is the subject of virtue 1 What the rule 1 What the motive 1 200 Does Mr. Stewart agree with the first part of this definition 1 201 What does Dr. Brown say is all the obligation which the latter part of the definition supposes 1 What does he say it lacks ] 202 Does he think that this is according to truth 1 CHAP. VII. VIRTUE. 45 [Mr. Stewart also says, " The system which makes virtue a mere matter of prudence leads to consequences which suffi- ciently show that it is erroneous. Among others it leads us to conclude, 1. That the disbelief of a future state absolves from all moral obligation, excepting in so far as we find virtue to be conducive to our present interest : 2. That a being inde- pendently and completely happy, cannot have any moral perceptions or any moral attributes." — Outlines of Moral Philosopliy. Section 6.] [For remarks on the rule im- plied in this definition, see the chapter on utility.] [" As to the motive,''^ says a writer in Rees' Cyclopedia, " this is still more objectionable than the subject ; for it ex- cludes, not only the virtuous actions of those who do not believe in a future state, but even those which spring from a disinterested regard to the welfare of others, to the will of God, or to the dictates of conscience ; that is, when an ac- tion becomes the most virtuous, then, according to the defi- nition which Paley has adopted, it ceases to be virtuous.'^] [The following is Mr. Dymond's definition of virtue, " Virtue is conformity ivith the standard of rectitude; which standard consists primarily in the expressed will of God."] Virtue has been divided into benevolence to propose good ends ; prudence to suggest the best means for their at- tainmenl^; fortitude to encounter the difficulties and dangers attending our undertaking; and temperance to bear down the opposing feelings from within. For instance, benevolence leads us to assist an orphan ; prudence teaches us how to assist him best ; fortitude enables us to bear the evils result- ing from such act of assistance ; and temperance keeps down every selfish consideration likely to interfere with the end proposed. Virtue has been also divided into prudence and benevo- lence ; the former, attentive to our own interest, the latter to that of our fellow creatures ; and both directed to the increase of universal happiness. '203 What conclusions does Mr. Stewart say the last part of the defi nition leads to 1 204 What does another wnter say that it excludes 1 What follows from this 1 205 What is Mr. Dymond's definition of virtue "? 20 G How does Dr. Paley say that virtue has been divided 1 Give an illustration. 46 PRELIMINARY CONSIDERATIONS. BOOK I. The four Cardinal Virtues are, Prudence, Fortitude, Tem- perance, and Justice. But the division of Virtue, in modern times, is into duties : I. Piety, &c. towards God : 2. Justice, &c. towards our fel- low-creatures : and, 3. Temperance, &;c. towards ourselves. GENERAL OBSERVATIONS ON THE REGULATION OF CONDUCT. Man acts more from habit than reflection. On few poinis of moral conduct do men think at all; on fewer still do they wait for the result of reflection. The opinion is generally determined by a sudden impulse, which is the result of pre- vious habits. This conduct, though apparently wrong, is really right, and the best suited to the weakness of human nature. In the rapid events of life there is little leisure for reflection : and were there more, he who reasons when he ought to act, is sure, in case of temptation, to reason wrong. But if man is thus passive under his habits, where, it is asked, is the exercise of virtue and the guilt of vice ? We answer, in the formation of such habits. Hence arises the necessity of doing or omitting many things for the sake of habit alone. For instance, a person in apparently great distress begs for charity. If we asked ourselves, whether the object be really deserving, whether charity so bestowed be not to encourage idleness, whether the money could not be better applied ; we should, perhaps, doubt of giving relief at all. But when we reflect that the distress exists, that the feeling of charity ought to be cul- tivated, that if it be not cultivated, selfishness will spring up ; when we consider all this, we will, if we are wise, do for our own sake what we would not do for the beggar's, and act generously rather than do violence to a habit so generally useful. Again, a man is in the habit of strict veracity. But an occasion occurs where a devia- tion from truth seems excusable for the sake of gratify- 207 What are called the four cardinal virtues 1 208 What is the modern division of virtue "? 209 What is the great principle of human action 1 210 What influence has the understanding generally on opinions 1 211 How then are they formed 1 212 Is this right? Why 1 213 What question does this give rise to 1 How is it answered 1 214 What nile results from this 1 Give an example. 215 How would a good man act in such circumstances'? 216 Give another example. Why woiild "not indulgence be allowable in that case 1 CHAP. VII. REGULATION OF CONDUCT. 47 ing others and himself. The lie he has to tell is harmless, and also amusing. Why then should he not indulge in it ? The answer is, it will destroy his previous habit of strict vera- city ; that similar occasions may return, where the tempta- tion is less, the mischief more ; and as his scruples will wear away by a few transgressions, the habit of lying will be induced, and then yielded to whenever it suits his purpose. Hence, too, may be explained the nature of habitual vir- tue ; through the operation of which a man may perform various acts of virtue, although he may be uninfluenced by, or even ignorant of, the subject, rule, or motive of virtue. How so ? it will be asked. Precisely, it will be replied, as a man may be a very good servant, without being conscious of studying at every turn his master's interest. But then he must for a length of time have been under the actual influ- ence of such motives ; and in that previous habit his present virtue consists. Man is, in truth, a bundle of habits. Every virtue and every vice, every modification of word, thought, and deed, can and does become a habit ; nor is there a quality or func- tion of the body or mind, that is not influenced by this great law of human nature. II. Christianity has not defined the precise quantity of virtue necessary for salvation. As all revelation must be transmitted through the ordinary vehicle of language, this objection will not require an an- swer, until it be shown that any form of words could ex- press this quantity ; or that a standard of moral conduct could exist, adapted to the capacities and circumstances of different men. It is enough for us to know from Scripture* that the rewards and punishments will be so fitted to every degree of virtue and vice, that none may labor in vain. It has been objected, that God acts unjustly in admitting one part into heaven, and condemning the other to hell, because 217 What may be explained from what has been said *? 218 What is habitual virtue % How is it occasioned 1 219 What is man as it regards habits 1 220 Has habit much influence over his body and mind 1 221 What is our second general observation 1 222 What tw^o barriers hinder this from becoming an objection ? 233 What can we learn from Scripture 1 * Markix. 41. Luke xii. 47; xxi. 16. 2 Cor. ix. 6. 48 PRELIMINARY CONSIDERATIONS. BOOK I. there can be little to choose between the worst man received, ^nd the best man rejected. But may there not be as little to :*.hoose in their conditions ? This is not the place to anticipate the detail of Scripture morality. But the following positions may be here ad- vanced with safety : ' ' 1. That a state of future happiness cannot be expected, except for conduct designedly or habitually prompted by regard to true virtue. For were it otherwise, the sanctions of morality and religion would possess neither use nor au- thority. 2. That a state of happiness cannot be expected by those who are in the habitual practice of committing one sin, or omitting one duty. Because, 1. every command of God is equally binding ; 2. by such allowance every sin would in turn be committed with impunity ; and, 3. such laxity of morals is directly denounced by Scripture, where duties are recited* collective- ly, and vicest disjunctively ; thus proving that single virtues cannot gain, though single vices may lose, God's approba- tion. Nor can such expressions as " charity shall cover a multitude of sins,":]: and, " he who converteth a sinner, shall hide a multitude of sins,"|) be reasonably extended to sins committed habitually. 3. That a state of mere unprofitableness will not go un- punished. As this doctrine has been laid down expressly by Christ in the parable of the talents, § all further reasoning is unne- cessary ; and it is only requisite to direct attention to the language adopted on the occasion, where the servant is cen- sured for being " slothful," and ordered to be " cast out into outer darkness" as an " unprofitable servant." 224 What is the first general position of Scripture morality"? 225 Why must that be the fact? 226 What is the second general position 1 227 What three reasons are given for this position 1 228 Are there any texts which seem to favor a contrary opinion ' Wliat is said of them 1 229 What is the third general position of Scripture morahty 1 230 Who has tauarht this doctrine 1 Where 1 * 2 Pet. i. 5. t 1 Cor. vi. 9. ^ 1 Pet. iv. 8. U Matt. XXV. 14. § James v. 20. CHAP. VII. REGULATION OF CONDUCT. 49 III. In every question of doubtful conduct, we are bound to take the safe side. Suppose, for instance, that it were doubtful, in the mind of a reasoner, whether suicide be lawful or not ; still a man ought not to commit it, because he can have no doubt that it is lawful to let it alone. This, it is replied, is only the pru- dent side of the question, and does not touch the legality of the act. We assert, on the contrary, that the act is not law- ful to the reasoner^ so long as he may have any doubts of its legality. This is the decision of St. Paul* on a similar case ; and with that we may rest contended : — " I know that there is nothing unclean of itself; but to him that esteemeth it unclean, to him it is unclean. Happy is he that condemn- eth not himself in that thing which he alloweth." 231 What is the third general observation 1 Give an example. 233 Whose decision have we upon such subjects % State it. * Rom. xiv. 14, and also 22, 23. E (50) BOOK II. MORAL OBLIGATIONS. CHAP. I. THE QUESTION, WHY IS A MAN OBLIGED ? CONSIDERED. The reasons assigned for this obligation, although va- rious, ultimately coincide, whether founded on " right," or "the fitness of things," or "a conformity with reason and truth," or " the promotion of public good," or, lastly, on " obedience to God's will." The ultimate result in all cases is " happiness." , For, by " the fitness of things" is meant their fitness to produce happiness ; by " the reason of things" is meant the principle by which is formed a judgment of the power of things to produce happiness, and *' truth" is a result of this judgment. Hence, what promotes general happiness is agreeable to the fitness of things, to reason, and to truth. And, again, as " the will of God" requires only what pro- motes general happiness, whatever leads to that end must needs be "right;" by which term is merely meant a con- formity with the rule of moral conduct, whatever that may be. [On this subject Dr. Dewar has well said, " The will of God does not create moral distinctions, but is the expression of distinctions which eternally and unchangeably exist ; and which are founded in his own nature." And again, "The distinctions of right and wrong are necessary, immutable, and founded in the nature of things." — Book iii. chap. 4.] But it may be asked, why is a man obliged to do what is 1 What are the several answers to the question "why is a man obliged" "? 2 What may be said of them all 7 3 What is meant by fitness of things 1 — the reason of things 1 4 What is agreeable to all these % 5 Does the will of God coincide with rule 1 Why 1 6 What is the meaning of the term right ? 7 What does Dr. Dewar say of the will of God 1 8 What does he say of the distinctions of right and wrong 1 CHAP. II. MEANING OF OBLIGATION. 51 right, or suited to the fitness of things, or to nature, reason, and truth, or to promote public good, or to obey the will of God? To answer this question, it is necessary to inquire, 1. What is meant by saying that a man is obliged to perform any act ; and, 2. Wliy he is obliged to perform that act. And we will propose for example, the act of keeping his word. CHAP. II. THE MEANING OF THE WORD "OBLIGATION." [An obligation is "that which constitutes legal or moral duty, and which renders a person liable to coercion and pu- nishment for neglecting it." — Webster.'] A man is said to be obliged, when he is urged by a vio- lent motive which results from the command of another. The motive must be violent. For, if not, his acquiescence will be voluntary, and not compulsive ; and consequently, there will exist no obligation to perform the act in question. The act must be done at the command of another. For, if a man is actuated by the hope of a gratuity, he is not obliged, but induced or prevailed upon. But as no command can be effective unless accompanied by the hope of reward for obedience, or the fear of punish- ment for disobedience ; the obligation to do what is right is referred at once to the violent motives of expected pleasure or pain, which are to result from obedience or disobedience to the will of God. [On this subject Mr. Stewart says, " The notions of re- ward and punishment presuppose the notions of right and wrong. They are sanctions of virtue, or additional motives to the practice of it ; but they suppose the existence of some previous obligation. " It is absurd, therefore, to ask, why we are bound to 9 After all the reasons that are given, what question may still be asked T 10 In order to answer this question, what two inquirie? are neces- sary 1 1 1 How does Dr. Webster define the word obligation % 12 When is a man said to be obliged 1 13 Of what quality must that motive be % 14 What is the result called when the motive is not violent ? 15 For what reason must the act be done 1 16 What do we say of it if there is an expectation of reward 1 17 To what motives is the obligation referred ] Why] 18 What does Mr. Stewart say of these motives ] 52 MORAL OBLIGATIONS. BOOK II. practise virtue ? The very notion of virtue implies the no- tion of obligation. Every being, who is conscious of the distinction between right and wrong, carries about with him a law which he is bound to observe ; notwithstanding he may be in total ignorance of a future state." — Outlines. Part ii. chap. 1. sec. 6.] From the preceding view of the question, it appears that when a man is said, in one case, to be induced to perform any act, and in another, to be " obliged" to perform it, we do not suppose that he is impelled by different kinds of mo- tives ; but only if he is obliged, he is influenced by a strong inducement which results from the command of another. In like manner, an act of prudence differs from an act of obliga- tion only in a degree still further removed ; for in the former, we consider what we shall gain or lose in this world ; in the latter, we think of the pleasures and pains of the world to come. CHAP. III. THE QUESTION, WHY AM I OBLIGED TO KEEP MY WORD? To the question, " TFIiy am I obliged to keep my word ?" the answer will be. Because I am " urged to do so by a violent motive," (namely, the expectation of future reward if I do, and of future punishment if I do not ;) and that " this motive results from the command of another;" that is, of God. This recurrence to the hopes and fears of a future state as the grounds of moral obligation, has been and may be still objected to, but to no purpose ; unless the objectors can show that virtue leads always to happiness here, or at least to a greater share than its opposite vice ever attains. [Concerning these hopes and fears, a writer in Rees's Cyclopedia says, " Here then we come to the ultimate, or (as we should prefer saying) the remotest obligation of vir- 19 Doe? he think one bound to do right, if he does not beUeve in a future state ! Why ] 20 Do we suppose the motives for inducement, and those for obliga- tion to be different in kind 1 How do they differ ] 21 How does prudence differ from obligation ] 22 Why am I obliged to keep my word 1 23 What is the motive 1 At whose command is it ? 24 Are these motives agreed to by all? 25 In order to dispose of them, what must th*e objectors show ? 26 What are these hopes and fears called in Rees's Cyclopedia? CHAP. IV. THE WILL OF GOD. 53 tue ; and from this point we shall proceed, till it appears that the end of human existence will be best answered by resting at a somewhat nearer and equally stable ground of obligation. And we cannot forbear observing, that it will clearly appear, from carefully considering the laws of our mental frame and the circumstances of mankind, that the love of God, of man, and of duty, (in other words, the affections of piety and benevolence, and a regard to con- science,) should be our primary aim, since he will be most happy, in whom those principles exist with the greatest strength and vigor."] Since, then, we cannot dispense with the doctrine of a future state of rewards and punishments, as the ground of moral obligations, we have to inquire, 1. If there be, in reality, such a state ; and, 2. What actions will be rewarded, and what will be pu nished. Of these questions, the first relate to the evidences for the truth of the Christian religion ; the second to the detail of the code of Christian morality. Both questions are too much for one work ; and the first is, therefore, taken for granted in the present treatise. CHAP. IV. THE WILL OF GOD. As the will of God is our rule, the whole business of Christian morality turns upon our knowledge of what that will is ; and that once known, our duty is known also. Now the will of God is known, 1. By the express words of Holy Writ; and, 2. By such inferences as are drawn by the light of nature from the works of God. When an ambassador has his instructions in his pocket, it would be strange if he did not look into them. When those instructions are clear and positive, there is an end to all deliberation concerning his duty. In the same manner, the Scriptures, as far as they go, must be our rule of conduct. 27 Should our actions be governed directly by them ? 28 What should be ova primary aim in our duties 1 29 What two great inquiries are necessary to form a code of mo- rality] 30 How is the first settled 1 — Of what does the second consist 1 31 What is the whole business of forming a moral code 1 32 What two means are there of knowing the will of God 1 33 Give an example of the first method. What does it teach 1 54 MORAL OBLIGATIONS. BOOK II. Thus religion, natural and revealed, go hand in hand ; and as the object of both is the same, to separate them is an absurdity ; since it matters not how we discover the will of God, if we only do discover it. Of the modern scheme of thus uniting ethics with Christianity, Hume and others have complained. But have the complainants been able to make any thing of morality without such union ? The ninth section of Hume's Treatise on the Principles of Morals contains the practical application of his system. Let any one read it, and say whether the motives there proposed are sufficiently " violent" to correct the bad passions of our nature. If not, the reader will see, with us, the necessity of stronger mo- tives. But this is not the present question. For if Chris- tianity be true, there is a state of future rewards and punish- ments ; and such motives cannot be neglected ; least of all by a Christian moralist, who should leave to those who re- ject the Scriptures, to build up, if they can, morality without their aid. Where the Scriptures are silent or dubious, we must resort to the light of nature. The method of discovering the will of God by the light of nature, is only to inquire into the tendency of any act to promote or diminish general happi- ness. For as this rule rests on the presumption that the Creator wishes the happiness of his creatures, such actions as promote such wishes must be agreeable to him ; and vice versa. On this presumption our whole system rests. The rea- sons, therefore, on which it rests, must be explained. CHAP. V. THE DIVINE BENEVOLENCE. When God created mankind, he wished either their hap- piness or their misery, or he was unconcerned about both. Had he wished the misery of man, he would have made all the present sources of pleasure sources of pain. Had he 34 What is mentioned as an absurdity 1 Why 1 35 Do those moral treatises which discard the Scripture's prove to be effectual 1 36 But can a Christian moralist neglect them 1 37 When must we resort to the light of nature 1 38 How shall we discover the will of God by that ? 39 Upon what presumption does this rule rest 1 40 What may be said to be the mind of the Creator when he made man"? 41 Suppose he had wished the misery of man 1 CHAP. V DIVINE BENEVOLENCE. 55 been indifferent to the happiness or misery of man, the capa- bilities for pleasure and pain must have been the result of accident ; for all design is, by the supposition, excluded. But as accident could not have ritted all objects to the senses, so that the one should impart and the other receive uniformly corresponding impressions, the supposition of accident must be excluded. Consequently, God must, when he created man, have wished his happiness, and made provision ac cordingly. Again, contrivance proves design ; and the tendency of the contrivance indicates the intention of the designer. The world abounds with contrivances directed to purposes of good. But though evil exists, it is not the design of the contrivance. Teeth are contrived for the purpose of eatings yet they ache ; but their aching is not the design of the con- trivance, but incidental to it. Even, for the sake of argument, we will admit it is a proof of defective contrivance. So, in the case of human instruments, a sickle is contrived to reap corn ; and though from its form it occasionally cuts the reaper's fingers, such is not the design of it, but an accident from its use. On the other hand, instruments of torture are contrived with the design of giving pain. Nothing similar to this is found in the works of God. No anatomist, for in- stance, ever discovered any organ in the body, whose design could be shown to be only the infliction of pain ; nor does he, if he meets with a part whose use he knows not, even sus- pect that its design is to annoy. Since, then, contri- vances indicate that God designed man's happiness, and as there are no proofs of any change in such design ; we must in reason believe in its continuance. Although a view of universal nature is apt to bewilder the mind, there is, however, always one bright spot in the pros- pect, on which the eye rests with complacency ; and thus a 42 Suppose he had been indifferent ] Is this reasonable 1 43 What follows from rejecting these two suppositions 1 ■ 44: What other argument is there 1 45 What is the purpose of the divine contrivances 1 46 Is evil one of their designs 1 Give an illustration. 47 What is said of human instruments when intended for good, ana when intended for torture 1 48 What is said of the anatomist 1 49 What conclusion follows from this 1 50 Does the eye judge best when looking upon a whole prospect oi on a single spot in it ? What is compared to this 1 56 MORAL OBLIGATIONS. BOOK II. single example will produce a conviction which many united would fail to effect. To me it seems that the benevolence of the Deity is more clearly seen in the pleasures of children than in any thing else. The pleasures of grown persons are the result of their Own seeking, by the cultivation of talents aided by accidental circum'stances ; but those of a healthy infant are so evidently furnished by the hand of «n- other, that the sight of a child at play affords to me sensible evidence of the intentional benevolence of the Deity. Having thus proved that the Creator wished and still wishes the happiness of his creatures, we proceed to inves- tigate the rule built upon such fact, that " the method of knowing God's will as shown by the light of nature, is to inquire into the tendency of any act to promote or diminish general happiness." CHAP. VI. UTILITY. Actions, then, are to be estimated by their tendency.* Whatever is expedient is right ; and the utility of a moral rule constitutes its obligation. [Dr. Dewar remarks on this assertion, " Though we ad- mit that utility be the rule by which the Deity conducts his government, it is a rule utterly unsuited to man. How can he, with his limited faculties, and with his comparative ig- norance of the nature and qualities of beings, and the ten- dency of actions, be capable of making expediency the law of his conduct ? It is only for Him who sees the end from the beginning, to know all the consequences of a single ac- tion, and to determine the way in which the good of that 51 What example was most evident to Dr. Paley 1 53 What is proved from the foregoing 1 53 What rule is built upon this fact 1 54 How are actions to be estimated 1 55 What constitutes the obligation of a moral rule 1 56 What does Dr. Dewar say of utiUty 1 Whyl * Actions in the abstract are right or vn-ong, according to their ten- dency ; the agent is virtuous or vicious, according to his design. Thus, if the question be, Whether to relieve common beggars be right or wrong, we inquire into the tendency of such a conduct to public advantage or inconvenience. If the question be, Whether a man, remarkable for this sort of bounty, is virtuous for that reason, we inquire into his design, whether his liberality springs from charity or from ostentation. Our concern is with actions in the abstract. CHAP. VI. UTILITY. 57 universe which he has formed shall be secured." — Book iii. chap. 6.] [But Mr. Dymond well says, " It may easily be shown that regard to utility is recommended or enforced in the ex- pression of the divine will. That will requires the exercise of pure and universal benevolence ; which benevolence i^ exercised in consulting the interests, the welfare, and the happiness of mankind. It is the use of reason to discover what is useful and expedient for these ends ; and to say that to consult utility is right, is almost the same to say it is right to exercise our understandings. It is obvious that in this view, a reference to expediency is consistent with the will of God ; and in conforming to it, so long as we hold it in subordmation to his laws, we perform his will."] [It is plain that Dr. Paley, in this part of the work, really intended to teach that utility was subordinate to the Scrip- tures ; as in chapter iv. he says, " Where the instructions are clear and positive, there is an end to all deliberation." Whether the same opinion is manifested in the succeeding part of his work is another question.]} I3ut to the maxim of utility, it may be objected, that many acts which are useful in themselves are decidedly not right. For instance, it might be useful that a possessor of a great estate, who abuses the influence of his property, should be murdered, and a better owner put in his place ; it might be useful to rob a miser, and to give his money to the poor, whose quantity of pleasure by such acquisition would be greater than the pain of the miser from his loss ; it might be useful to obtain political power through perjury, with the view to advance the good of the state. Must we, then, justify assassination, plunder, and perjury, on the ground of utility ? or must we give up our principle that utility is right? Neither is necessary. The true answer is, that such acts, 57 What does Mr. Dymond say to this rule 1 58 What is required by the will of God 1 59 How do we find what is expedient for these ends 1 60 What follows from this ] 61 What is his conclusion upon this subject 1 62 Is not this the intention of Dr. Paley 1 63 What objection may be urged against the doctrine of utility"? Give some examples. 64 What question is asked from these examples J What is its tme anrwer 1 58 MORAL OBLIGATIONS. BOOK II though in appearance useful, are really not useful ; and on that account alone are wrong. The consequences of actions are twofold, particular and general. The former refers to the mischief produced by an action, taken singly ; the latter to the mischief produced by the violation of a rule generally useful. Thus, for instance, the particular mischief produced by the murder would be the loss of life, as dear to a bad as to a good man ; while the general mischief produced, is the vio- lation of the law against murder. Hence, although in such murder the particular good might outweigh the particular evil, yet it would not be useful, be- cause it would produce a general mischief; and so of the cases of robbery and perjury above stated. But as this decision presupposes the necessity of ge- neral rules in morals, such necessity must be demonstrated. CHAP. VII. THE NECESSITY OF GENERAL RULES. Acts of the same kind cannot be partly permitted and partly forbidden. They must all be embraced under one ge- neral law ; and the evidence, which proves that the universal permission of them is injurious, is the ground of the law -which forhids them all. Thus, in the case of the murder before spoken of, should the assassin say he killed the rich rascal, because he thought his life pernicious ; such a plea, if admitted in this case, must be admitted in all similar cases. And the consequence would be general mischief, by putting the life of any man in the power of his neighbor. The necessity, then, of general rules in human govern- ment is apparent. But must the Deity also regulate future rewards and punishments by general rules ? Yes. Because, as every government, whether human or di /ine, intends to 65 How many classes of consequences result from actions, and what are they ? 66 Describe the particular. Describe the general. 67 What is the particular bad consequence of mu' der 1 68 What are its general mischiefs 1 69 Which class of consequences determines the n-orality of an act ? 70 Upon what is this decision founded ] 71 What is said of all acts that have a common tmdency 1 72 What follows from proving the pernicious efi.3cts of permitting all of them 1 Give an example. 73 What is rendered apparent by this ? 74 Will this necessity extend to the divine government 1 Why ? CHAP. VII. ON GENERAL RULES. 59 influence the conduct of reasonable beings ; if two similai acts be not similarly treated, the consequence of such neglect of general rules would be, that mankind would no longer know what to expect, or how to act. Rewards and punish- ments, distributed at random, might, like a blank or a prize in a lottery, bring pain or pleasure for the moment ; but, from the uncertainty of the event, could produce no influence on the conduct. Hence, if there is to be a distribution of future rewards and punishments, such distribution must proceed on general rules. But it will be said, that on this system of general con- sequences, the guilt of a bad action consists in the example ; and consequently, if the act be done in secrecy, since it fur- nishes no bad example, part of the guilt drops off". In the case of suicide, for instance, if the act be done so that none can know or suspect it, the example can do no mischief; nor can a punishment for this deed be necessary merely to save a general rule from an exception. But such reasoning, if adopted, would introduce a rule the least to be endured ; namely, that secrecy can justify an act. Besides, there would be reason to fear that people would be disappearing perpetually. But before this plea of secrecy can be admitted, we ought to be satisfied respecting the following queries — 1. Whether the Scriptures do not teach us that the most secret actions will be brought to light.* 2. Whether such acts will not be the objects of future re- wards and punishments. 3. Whether they will not, when brought to light, be treated, like other acts, by general rules. 75 Without general rules, what would be the effect of rewards and punishments 1 What does this argue 1 76 What circumstances have been thought a palUative in crime? What is the example 1 77 What principle would result from this reasoning 1 What else would it lead to 1 78 How do the Scriptures affect this argument? [The pupil shouldf in all examples like this, be able to recite the passage."] 79 Why will those acts be brought to light ? How will they then be treated ? • Rom. xi. 16. 1 Cor. iv. 5. 60 MORAL OBLIGATIONS. BOOK II. CHAP. VIII. ON GENERAL CONSEQUENCES. It has been said that the general consequences of an act may be known, by considering what the consequences would be if it were generally committed. But to this it has been objected, that the guilt of one act cannot justly be charged with the accumulated guilt of many similar acts. We reply, that the reason for prohibiting the act, and the measure of its guilt, is in proportion to the mischief which would arise by the general allowance of actions of the same sort. What- ever is expedient, is right. But then its expediency must be seen in all its ramifications, direct and remote. By this habit of viewing the consequences of single acts, the intensity of crimes apparently insignificant is best seen, and the severity of laws, apparently inhuman, fully justified. For instance : in coining or forgery, the particular mis chief is the trifling loss of the sum to the person who received the counterfeit money or forged paper; the general mis- chief would be to abolish the use of money or of paper in commerce. In sheep or horse-stealing and burglary, the particular mischief is the loss of the sheep, or horse, or chattels, to its owner ; the general mischief would be the insecurity of any property necessarily exposed. In smuggling, the particular mischief is the trifling loss to the revenue from the duty unpaid; the general mischief would be the ruin of more honest traders in the same article who had paid the duty. In a captive's breaking his parole, the particular evil is his escape ; the general consequence of the act is the refusal of the indulgence of a parole to other captives. Hence, in many cases, the punishment for two diflerent commissions of a similar crime is the same, although the in- dividual injury done be not the same. For the general con 80 How may we estimate the general consequences of an act ? 81 What objection has been brought against this 1 How is it an- swered 1 82 In what respect must an action be expedient ) 83 What will this habit of viewing consequences lead to 1 84 Give the example in counterfeiting or forgery. In stealing, and in breaking into an uninhabited house. In smuggling. In parole break- ing. 85 What principle in human laws does this explain 1 CHAP. IX. OF RIGHT. 61 sequences may be the same from any two acts that differ only in degree. From the want of this distinction between a particular and a general consequence, the ancient moralists have been com- pelled to introduce a new rule of conduct, designated to pre- pon, or honestum ; by which they meant a measure of right distinct from utility. While the principle of utile corres- ponded to their notions of rectitude, they went by it ; but when that failed, they resorted to the other, honestum; and the only account they could give of the matter was, that acts similar to those detailed in chap. vi. might be useful ; but as they were not also honesta, they were not to be deemed right. There is a maxim in every body's mouth, and in most men's without meaning, "not to do evil, that good may come." The caution not to do a particular good through the violation of a general rule is salutary ; for the good would seldom balance the evil. But strictly speaking, if good comes, evil cannot, except as we have shown in the preceding views of particular and general consequences. To this it may be added, that if an act produces little effect as regards the many, so will the punishment of such act be little as re- gards the quantity of general misery. CHAP. IX. OF RIGHT. Right and obligation are reciprocal. Thus, if one man has a " right" to an estate, others are " obliged" to yield it up ; or if parents have a " right" to respect from their child- ren, the children are "obliged" to pay it. Now as moral obligation depends on the will of God- " right," the reciprocal to it, must depend on it also, and means, therefore, " consistency with the will of God." But if "right" be only the will of God, how can we con- ceive that his acts, which are merely a manifestation of such 86 What perplexity has been occasioned by the want of this distinc- tion 1 87 When was the rule of honestum brought in % 88 How did they account for it 1 89 What is said of the maxim, not to do evil that good may come 1 90 What reflection is added to these remarks 1 91 What is said of right and obUgation ? Illustrate. 92 To what doctrine concerning right will this fact lead ] 83 What question will this give rise to 1 How is it answered 1 F 62 MORAL OBLIGATIONS. BOOK II. will, can be *' wrong ?" The answer is, that from the two prin- ciples, — that God wills the happiness of his creatures, and that his will is the measure of right, — we form in our minds cer- tain rules of right and wrong, which we habitually apply to all acts, and finally even to those of the Deity himself; because at the time of the application we do not perceive that such rules are deduced from the Divine will itself. Right is a quality of persons or of acts ; of persons, as of a man who has a right to an estate, or of one who has not the right over his own life ; of acts, as of a state which has a right to punish murder by death, or of one which has not the right to punish a debtor by imprisonment. In the latter case, the definition which we gave above can be substituted directly for the term "right ;" as itis " right," or " consistent with the will of God," to punish murder with death. But when we speak of persons, the substitution is imperfect. Thus, in the expression, " a man has a right to an estate," we can only mean, "it is not inconsistent with the will of God" for such a man to have the estate in question. CHAP. X. THE DIVISION OF RIGHTS. The rights, of persons are, i. Natural or adventitious ; II. Alienable or inalienable ; iii. Perfect or imperfect. I. Natural rights are such as would belong to man not in a state of society ; adventitious are such as belong to man in a state of society. Natural rights are a man's right to life and liberty, to the use of his limbs and the produce of his labor, and to the en- joyment of air, light, and water ; for if any number of men were cast together on a desert land, they would all be entitled to these rights. Adventitious rights belong to a state of society which pos- sesses the right to make any and all laws for the regula- tion of such society ; none of which would exist in a newly inhabited island. 94 Of what is right a quality 1 95 Explain it as a quality of persons. Of actions. 96 When the term right is a quality of acts, what phrase may we use instead of if? 97 How must the phrase be varied when speaking of the rights of persons 1 98 Of how many classes are the rights of persons 1 99 What is the difference betAveen natural and adventitious rights 1 100 Give a few examples of natural rights. Of adventitious rights. CHAP. X. THE DIVISION OF RIGHTS. 63 But how can adventitious rights be created by man, if right itself depends only on the will of God ? This question may be answered by appealing to the principle, that God wills the happiness of mankind. Consequently, acts, which lead to happiness in a social state, are right, although, as they do not produce the same effect in a state not social, they would, out of civil society, be wrong. Hence, adventitious rights, made by men, are not less sacred than natural rights, ordained by God ; for both rest on the same foundation, — the will of the Creator. Hence, it would be no less sinful than it is illegal, to dispossess a man by violence of an estate for which he can show as a title the right of law ; although he cannot, as the twelve tribes could do, assert his claim to it as a gift from God. II. Rights are alienable or inalienable ; i. e. can or cannot be transferred from one person to another. The right possessed over things is alienable ; over per- sons, inalienable. A man may transfer his cattle, for in- stance, to another, but not his wife. Thus, too, he may transfer his right to his own liberty, but not his right over the liberty of other persons. III. Rights are perfect or imperfect. Perfect rights can be asserted by personal force, or the force of Taw; imperfect cannot. For instance, a man may resist, by personal force or by the law, violence done in his own person, or in the destruction of his house; and can compel by law the restitution of an estate, or of portable goods, injuriously taken from him. On the other hand, im- perfect rights cannot be enforced. For instance, a poor man has a right to relief; yet if it be refused, he must not extort it. Children have a right to affection and care from their parents, and parents from their children ; yet if the rights be with- held on either side, they cannot be recovered compulsorily. But it may be asked, how can a person have a right to a thing, and yet want the right to use means to obtain it? 101 What question naturally arises concerning adventitious right*? ? How is it answered 1 102 What authority does this answer confer upon adventitious rights '' 103 Give an example. 104 What is the difference between alienable and unalienable rights % 105 Give an example of their application. 106 What is the difference between perfect and imperfect rights! 107 Give an example of perfect rights. 108 Of imperfect rights. 109 What difficulty attends the doctrine of imperfect rights 1 64 MORAL OBLiaATIONS. BOOK II. The answer is by referring here, as elsewhere, to the princi- ple of the general rule, which forbids the use of force for the attainment of an object in itself indeterminate, through the fear of the consequence it would lead to, by the introduction of force in cases where no right existed. For instance, a candidate, the best qualified, has a right to success ; but as the qualifications are of an indeterminate nature, there must be some person to determine them before he can demand success by force. Now such person cannot be the candi- date himself, or any of his party, unless we extend the same allowance to other candidates. If we do that, «// would re- sort to compulsion. In like manner, although the poor man has a right to relief, yet as the mode, time, and quantity of the relief are circumstances not ascertained, the relief must not be prosecuted by force. For to allow the poor to judge for themselves in such cases, would lead, as a consequence, to the general insecurity and loss of property. Where the right is imperfect, so is the obligation ; for the terms are, as shown before, reciprocal. Obligations are here called imperfect, because they are call- ed so by other writers. The term is, however, ill chosen ; for it leads to the notion, that there is less guilt in the violation of an imperfect obligation than of a perfect one ; which is a groundless opinion. For the degree oi guilt is determined by circumstances unconnected with the distinction between a perfect and imperfect obligation ; that distinction being used merely to determine, whether violence may or may not be used to enforce the obligation. He who discourages a worthy candidate commits a greater crime than he who picks a pocket ; although, in the former case, he violates an imper- fect, but, in the latter, a perfect obligation. As positive precepts are often indeterminate, and as the in- determinateness of an obligation renders it imperfect, posi- tive precepts can merely produce an imperfect obligation ; and, contrariwise, negative precepts, being precise, consti- tute perfect obligations. The fifth commandment is posi- tive, and its duty is imperfect ; the sixth is negative, and its 110 How is it solved ] Illustrate by example. 111 Of what kind is the obligation when the right is imperfect 7 112 Is that a well chosen term 1 Why is it used 1 113 What opinion does it lead to ] Is that correct ] Whyl 114 What precepts produce imperfect obligations 1 Why 1 115 Do negative precepts have the same effect I Give examples. CHAP. XI. GENERAL RIGHTS OF MAN. 65 duty perfect. Religion and virtue find their voluntary exer- cise among the former ; the laws of society compel the exer cise of the latter. CHAP. XI. THE GENERAL RIGHTS OF MAN. These rights, belonging collectively to the species, are — 1. To the fruits of the earth. The insensible parts of the creation are incapable of feel- ing hurt ; and as God has given to man both the desire of food and the means of obtaining it ; he, of course, intended us to use the fruits of the earth as food. 2. To the flesh of animals. This is a different claim ; and, as a reason is necessary for depriving animals of their liberty and life, and for inflict- ing pain, to gratify the appetite ; it has been said,— 1 . That as brutes prey on each other, so man, a species of brute, only obeys the general law in preying on other brutes. 2. That if animals were not destroyed by man, they would overrun the earth, and drive man from the occupation of it. But, first, the analogy between man and brutes is not cor- rect. Carnivorous brutes cannot live by other means, man can ; and, as in the case of the Hindoos, actually does live without tasting flesh of any kind. Secondly, the calculated increase of animals would not take place naturally ; since many are forced into existence for the express purpose of subsequent destruction. Besides, as in the case of fish, how is man's occupation of the earth endangered by their unlimited increase ? The only real defence of such a right is in the permission granted by God to Noah, in the words, " every moving thing shall be meat for you ; even as the green herb have I given you all things ;" — which last alone was included in the original grant to Adam, in the words — " every green herb shall be meat for you." But although this extension of the grant over the beasts of the earth, the fowls of the air, and fish of the sea, did not take place till 116 What motives induce the fulfilment of either kind of obligations 1 117 What is meant by general rights 1 118 What is the first general right 1 How proved 1 119 What is the second general right 1 Is it evident ? 120 What two reasons are given in vindication of it ? 121 What is observed of the first reason 1 Pf the second ^ 122 Where is our only permission of that right 1 123 Was this given in the time of Adam ? F 2 66 MORAL OBLIGATIONS. BOOK II. after the. flood, we are not told whether the antediluvians re- frained or not from the flesh of animals. Abel, we read, was a keeper of sheep ; but for what purpose, except for food, it is difficult to say, unless it were for sacrifices. If so, it is probable that Noah, with some other antediluvians, was scrupulous on this point, and consequently received a per- mission to do what he previously deemed sinful ; for God would not have given as a new grant, a permission to do what had been practised long before without dispute. But even such a permission to destroy will not warrant the liberty of studied or wanton cruelty to brutes. From reason, then, and revelation, it appears that God in- tended the fruits of the earth for man's support ; but as he did not intend any waste or misapplication of those produc- tions, such acts are, like others more expressly mentioned, wrong, as contrary to God's will. Hence, the conversion of corn-fields into parks for deer, or covers for foxes ; the non-cultivation of lands by parties in possession, or the refu- sal to let them to those who will cultivate them ; the destruc- tion or waste of food with the view to increase the price of stocks on hand ; the expending on superfluous dogs and horses the sustenance of man ; or the conversion of grain into ardent spirits. These, and, in short, all acts, by which the food of man is diminished either in quantity or quality, are sinful, as opposed to God's desire for the happiness of his creatures. This lesson Christ probably intended to inculcate, when he bade his disciples gather up the fragments, that nothing might be lost : and this lesson men ought to bear in mind, when scheming plans for their own individual advantage; as they are apt to forget that it is their duty to obtain the greatest quantity of food from their estates, and that not to do so is a sin. From the same view of the intentions of the Deity, we . 124 Might it not be allowed without being incorporated with Scripture history 1 125 With that supposition, what is the probable reason that the per- mission was given to Noah 1 126 What are we taught concerning the fruits of the earth 1 127 What would oppose such intentions 1 128 Give a few examples. 129 What would be the nature of such acts 1 130 What negligence would this lesson reprove 1 PHAP. XI. GENERAL RIGHTS OF MAN. 67 prove that nothing ought to be exclusive property, that can be enjoyed in common. For example, two or more persons, throvirn on a desert island, find an apple-tree loaded with fruit : each may take enough for his own immediate use, and every one plead the general intention of the Supreme Pro- prietor. But none can claim the whole tree ; for it must be previously shown that God intended the tree to be given to one or a few individuals. Now this intention can be proved only by showing that the fruit cannot be enjoyed with the same advantage when distributed to all, as when confined to one or a few. But this will be true only, when there is not enough for all, or where the article in question requires labor for its preservation and production. But where no such rea- son obtains, it is an usurpation of general right to confine the use to one or to a few. If a medical spring, sufficient to supply all who wished to use it, were discovered on ground belonging to an indi- vidual ; the owner of the ground, and the discoverer of the spring, if it was found by laborious search, may merit compensation and reward ; but no human law would justify the owner in confining to himself the use of God's general gift. In like manner, all attempts to appropriate inexhausti- ble fisheries to individual nations is an encroachment on the general rights of man. On the same principle may be settled the contested ques- tion, whether the sea be free or not ? What is necessary for each nation's safety may be allowed, even to the extent of three leagues from the coast; a limit far beyond the reach of any implements of war, by which the safety of the coast might be endangered. 3. The last universal right is the right of necessity ; that is, the right to use or destroy another's property, when it is necessary to do so for self-preservation. For instance, to take, without the leave, and against the consent of the owner, goods or chattels, when we are in danger of perishing through want of them ; a right to throw goods overboard to save a ship from sinking, or to pull down a house to stop the 131 What seems to be another intention of the Deity 1 132 When can a reason be given to show that this is not his intention 1 133 What is said of a medicinal spring 1 — of fisheries'? — and of the seal 1 34 What is the last miiversal right 1 135 What is meant by that right 1 Give examples. 68 MORAL OBLIGATIONS. BOOK II. progress of a fire. This right is founded on the principle, that the institutions relating to property were intended to benefit all, even if it should happen to be at the expense of a few; and, consequently, the partial mischief result- ing from the violation of a general rule is overbalanced by the immediate advantage. Restittition, however, is due, not to the full value of the property so destroyed, but to the value which it possessed at that time ; and as it was in danger of perishing, that value might be but little. 136 On what is this right founded 1 137 But what should always follow such destruction ^ 1 38 What amount of restitution would be due 1 (69) BOOK III. RELATIVE DUTIES. CHAP. I. ON PROPERTY. If you should see in a field of corn a flock of pigeons, ali of whom, save one, were engaged, not in choosing for them- selves the best food, but the worst, and reserving the best for that single pigeon, the weakest and perhaps the worst of the flock ; and if, while that single pigeon was devouring or wasting at pleasure, you should see, when another hungry and hardy pigeon touched a grain of the hoard, all the other pigeons fly on the intruder, and peck it to death ; you would then see nothing more than what is practised every day among men. In civilized society, many persons toil to find superfluities for one, sometimes the least deserving of his spe- cies ; and in the mean time get for themselves only the worst and smallest share, and quietly look on, while they see the fruits of their labor spent or spoiled by that single one or his minions. They will even join to hang a man, whose neces- sities may have led him to take the smallest particle from the hoard so unequally distributed. CHAP. II. THE USE OF THE INSTITUTION OF PROPERTY. This institution, which, from the view just given of it, seems so unnatural, still possesses advantages enough to counterbalance its apparent absurdity. The principal advan- tages are the following. I. It increases the produce of the earth. In climates where the earth produces little without labor, no one would sow if all might reap. Hence, the spon- taneous productions of the earth, such as acorns, berries, game, and fish, would be the only food of its inhabitants ; and a handful of men would thus starve on waste lands 1 Illustrate the distribution of property by an example. 2 How is the example applied 1 3 What is said of the institution seemingly so unnatural ? 4 What is the first advantage 1 Why so "? 5 What would follow from not cultivating the earth ? 70 RELATIVE DUTIES. BOOK III. which, if cultivated, would feed thousands. In soils natu- rally fertile, or on coasts where fish abound, and in climates where clothes are unnecessary, a large population may sub- sist without property in land ; but in less favored spots, the want of food arising from the want of institutions to secure property, leads people even to devour each other. II. It preserves the produce of the earth to maturity. If, under a system which is intended to be favorable to the security of property, we find the fruit of a tree which is exposed to depredation always plucked before it is ripe ; it is fair to infer that, where there is a community of property, corn, if sown, would never be permitted to come to maturity, nor would lambs and calves grow up to sheep and cows ; because each would think he had better take what he could get, than leave it to another to enjoy. III. It prevents contests. Where there is not enough for all, and where no rules exist to settle the share of each, it is plain that contests alone can regulate the distribution. IV* It improves the conveniences of life. As each man is secure in the produce of his own labor, he is enabled to direct his attention to a particular art, and to ex- change the productions of that art for those of another. Thus is introduced the subdivision of labor, by which each man becomes a proficient in his own art, which he could not be, if his time were taken up by all the diff'erent occupations necessary to his subsistence. By this arrangement, articles of necessity and ornament are improved in their manufac- ture ; and as new wants are created, fresh exertions are made and remunerated ; so that they, who are the worst off" where the laws of property prevail, are better off than the best are where all things are in common. 6 Where would this state of things be not disadvantageous 1 7 Wliat has it led to in some situations 1 8 What is the second advantage 1 9 By what example is this proved 1 What inference from it 1 10 What is the third advantage 1 1 1 Would there be contests if there were no right to property 1 12 What is the fourth advantage *? 13 What preHminary step for that does it occasion 1 14 What does the entire attention to one art occasion 1 15 What is the result of this arrangement'? 1 6 Then what opinion may we form concerning those who aie sub- ject to the institution of property ? CHAP. III. HISTORY OF PROPERTY. 71 The great inequality of property which is found in civi- lized nations, abstractedly considered, is an evil ; but it is an evil which flows from a greater good ; and is to be rectified only when it is unconnected with such good. CHAP. III. THE HISTORY OF PROPERTY. The first objects of property were the fruits a man gathered, and the animals he caught; then the hut he built, and the tools and weapons he made ; and, subsequently, his flocks and herds. Even Abel, the second from Adam, was a keeper of sheep, which, with oxen, asses, and camels, composed the wealth of the patriarchs, as they now do that of the Arabs. The next object of property was probably a well of water ; which, in the countries of the east where the world was first peopled, was from its value a source of frequent contentions ;* and to dig or discover one was deemed an act worthy of honorable record. Land, at present so important as to be alone called real property, was, when more plentiful, little thought of; but as the people increased, and tillage was resorted to, it rose in value. The first partition of an estate on record is that which took place between Abram and Lot; and the terms of it are the most simple : "If thou wilt take the left hand, then I will go to the right ; or if thou depart to the right hand, then I will go to the left." There are no traces of property in land in Caesar's account of Britain ; little in the history of patriarchal times ; and none of it is found amongst the savages of America or of Australia. Even the ancient Scythians, who appropriated houses and cattle, are expressly said to have left their lands in common. Even for some time property in immovables was confined to temporary occupancy : for as soon as a man quitted his hut or cave, and the feeding ground of his cattle ; another en- tered on them by the same title as his predecessor. It is pro- bable that a permanent property in lands, not cultivated by 17 What is our final opinion of inequality of property 1 18 Mention the first objects of property, one after another. 19 What was the next object of property, and why was it made sol 20 What is said of land 1 What is the first partition of land 1 21 In what history are there no accounts of landed property 1 22 What was the tenure of property in immovables originally 1 * Gen. xxi. 25 ; xxvi. 18. 72 RELATIVE DUTIES. BOOK III. the resident proprietor or his agents, was fl^st settled by the laws of the people, or the will of the ruler alone. CHAP. IV. IN WHAT THE RIGHT OF PROPERTY IS FOUNDED. To explain the right of property in land, consistently with the law of nature, is no easy task : for as the land was once common to all, by what right could any part of it be taken by one person, to the exclusion of all others ? Many different and consequently unsatisfactory reasons have been given. One says that the right of the first possessor rested on the tacit consent given by his contemporaries to such possession, which consent, being once granted, could not be revoked by the relinquishing parties. But consent cannot be presumed from silence, where the party said to be consenting knows nothing of the matter in question. It is true, the parties in the neighborhood of the spot where such appropriation took place, might have con- sented : but that very consent is as much an infringement on the general rights of mankind as the occupancy of the in- dividual himself ; and cannot bind other portions of mankind who are ignorant of such transactions between the appropri- ator and his neighbors. Locke says, that the right to property rests on the natural right of a man to tbe produce of his own labor ; for by cul- tivation consequent on the occupancy, the labor bestowed on the soil is so mixed up with it, that the man cannot be de prived of one without the loss of the other which is mani festly his own. But this reason will hold good only where the value of the labor gives nearly the whole value to the ground ; as in the case of a waste, which a man should pare, burn, and plough for the growth of corn not previously produced ; or where the labor confers the greatest part of the value, as in the case of 23 How did such property first become permanent 1 24 What is said of the right of property in connection with the law of nature 1 25 Has there ever been any explanation 1 26 What is the first account of it 1 27 What is said of this reason 1 28 What reason is given by Locke ■? 29 When is this reason applicable 1 CHAP. IV. RIGHT OF PROPERTY. 73 game or fish, which, till caught, are of no value to anybody. But the right to possess, founded on the labor bestowed, can give no right to the possession of a tract of country as is claimed by discoverers, or to the fencing in of a piece of ground for a cattle pasture, or to hold in perpetuity even a farm when the cultivation and its effects shall have ceased. Another and better reason is, that, as God has provided the ground for all, he has given leave to any to take what he pleases, (if not previously possessed,) without any kind of consent from others. But this permission can apply only to so much as would yield the necessaries of life ; and not to any superfluous wealth which may be enjoyed by the individual, at the ex- pense of others, who, by such appropriation, may be pinched for food. Such are the reasons usually assigned; but were they perfectly unexceptionable, they would scarcely vindicate the present claim to a right of property in land, unless it were also shown that the possession did actually take place in some of the ways here supposed, and that justice has been done in every subsequent transmission. For if one link in this evidence fail, no title posterior to such failure can be held to be good. The real foundation of our right is the law of the land. God intended the earth for man's use. This intention can- not be fulfilled without establishing property : he therefore willed the institution of property. But such institution can- not be effected, if the law of the land does not regulate the distribution ; consequently it is "right," or consistent with the will of God, for any individual to possess as much as the law of the land gives him. And, consequently, as the right does not depend on the manner or justice of the original acquisition, nor its subsequent transmission ; so neither can it be taken away for any defect in the title which is not cogni- zable by law. 30 Is it suited to every case 1 31 What better reason has been given 1 32 Hovsr far vi^ill this apply, and how far will it not 1 33 How far will all these reasons affect our present claims 1 34 What is the real foundation of our right in landed property 1 35 In our argument for this, what do we suppose to be the intention of the Deity 1 36 After supposing this, mention the train of reasoning that shows our right to be perfect 1 37 What follows from this proof ? G 74 RELATIVE DUTIES. BOOK III. Nor does the owner's right depend on the expediency of the law. An estate on one side of a brook may descend to the eldest son, on the other side to all the children conjoint- ly. The claims of both inheritances are founded equally in law, though the expediency of the law itself cannot be the same in both cases. But it will be said, that as the right of property depends only on the law of the land, a man may rightfully keep whatever the law will not compel him to restore ; and by this rule, since, in some states, if a debt be not demanded for six years the law exonerates the debtor, he is not bound in duty to pay it ; or if a minor contracts a debt which the law will not compel him to pay, he is not only legally but mo- rally relieved from paying it. The answer in this and similar cases, is that no rule of law, intended for one purpose, is to be applied to another. For instance, this limitation of time was intended to protect men from demands so antiquated that the evidence of their discharge was probably lost. If then a man be ignorant or doubtful on this point, he may with strict justice plead in bar the legal limitation, but not, if he knows the debt to be undis- charged ; because in the one case he does, in the other does not, apply the law for the purpose for which it was intended. Again, in the case of the minor, the limitation of the law was intended to guard the inexperience of youth against im- positions. If, therefore, a minor has contracted a debt, which carries with it the suspicion of imposition on the part of the creditor, he may justly plead his minority ; but not so, if there be no such ground of objection. As property is the principal subject of "the determinate relative duties," it has been first discussed. From these we proceed to CHAP. V. PROMISES. 1. Whence the obligation to perform promises arises. 2. In what sense promises are to be interpreted. 3. In what cases promises are not binding. 38 What effect upon the owner's right has the utility of the law % Give examples. 39 To what conclusion would this lead at first thought 1 Examples. 40 What is the application of such laws 1 41 What are the three subjects of debate in the article of promises 1 CHAP. V. PROMISES. 75 I. The advocates of a moral sense suppose the obligation to keep promises an innate sense : but, as this is disputed, we may easily deduce the necessity of the obligation from its utility. Men act from expectation, which is generally determined by the assurances of others. Unless, then, such assurances are certain, the conduct which they regulate must be uncer- tain also. To prevent, therefore, the dependence of conduct on chance, a confidence in promises is essential to social in- tercourse. But there would be no confidence in promises, unless men were obliged to perform them. The perform- ance, therefore, being essential to general happiness, becomes an obligation. But it has been said, that if promises were never kept, a general distrust would take place equally useful. But this has been said by those who do not perceive how much in every hour man must and does trust to others. On the strength of such confidence each man regulates his actions ; and the very dinner we eat depends on the trust we repose in the butcher to send the meat as ordered in, the cook to dress it, and the servant to put it on the table by a stated time. And so in the most important events of life, the intervention of promises and the necessity of keeping them, are really not greater than in these familiar occurrences, though the acci- dental circumstance of form causes them to appear so. [On this subject Mr. Dymond says, " Doubtless fulfilment is expedient; but there is a shorter and a safer road to truth. To promise and not to perform, is to deceive ; and deceit is peculiarly and especially comdemned by Christianity. A lie has been defined to be 'a breach of promise ;' and since the Scriptures condemn lying, they condemn breaches of pro- mise."] II. In what sense promises are to be interpreted. AVhere a promise admits of more interpretations than one, 42 Whence arises the obligation to perform promises 1 43 What is the first proposition towards the proof of this] What next] 44 What does this show to be essential 1 And in what only way can it be obtained ? 45 How may some suppose that expediency might lead to the con- trary 1 46 What answer may be given to this ] 47 What does Dymond say of this obligation ] 48 In what sense are promises to be interpreted ] 76 RELATIVE DUTIES. BOOK III it is to be performed " in the sense in which the promiser apprehended that the promisee received it." The sense which the promiser actually intended to act by, cannot always govern the interpretation of an equivocal promise ; because, at that rate, the promiser might raise ex- pectations even intentionally, Which he would not be under obligation to satisfy. Much less can it be the sense in which the promisee actually received the promise ; for then the promiser might be drawn into engagements which might never enter his mind. It must, therefore, be taken in the remaining sense, viz. that in which the promiser believed the promisee accepted it. It is evident that this last sense will always agree with the intention of the promiser, except where a collusion is intended through the equivocal nature of the words of the engagement. Temures promised the garrison of Sebastia, that if they would surrender, no blood should be shed. The garrison surrendered, and Temures buried them all alive. But al- though the agreement was kept literally, still as it was not kept in the sense in which Temures knew the garrison re- ceived it, he was guilty of a breach of promise. Since, then, the obligation to perform a promise depends on the expectation knowingly excited ; any act likewise, by which expectations are designedly raised, partakes of the nature of a direct promise, and creates a similar obligation for its due performance. He, for instance, who takes a poor child, and educates him to fill the situation of a child not poor, is bound to give him the means to fill such situation, as much as if he had directly promised to do so. And a minister of state, who by his coniplaisance raises in a de- pendant an expectation of patronage, is bound by such notice to provide for the dependant. On this principle rests the obligation of tacit promises. An intention may be declared either simply, or conjointly with an engagement to perform. In the former, the duty is 49 Why not in the sense of the promiser's intended acts 1 Give examples. 50 Why not in the sense the promisee received it 1 51 What is evident concerning the rule that we have given 1 51 What is said about a mere acf? Give examples. 52 What are such acts called 1 53 May an intention be declared in one manner only ■? 54 What is said of a simple declaration 1 CHAP. VI. PROMISES. < 77 satisfied, if you were sincere at the time, though the inten- tion be subsequently changed : in the latter, the power to change exists no longer. But, in popular understanding, most declarations of present intention amount to absolute promises. If, therefore, there is a wish of reserving a liberty to change, such declarations should be qualified by such ex- pressions as, at present, if I do not alter, or the like. And, after all, a wanton change of intention, as it has excited some expectation, is always wrong. III. In what cases promises are not binding. 1 . Promises are not binding where the performance is im- possible. This excuse for non-performance is valid only, if the im- possibility be unknown to the promiser when he makes the promise ; otherwise, he is guilty of fraud in leading the pro- misee to expect what he, the promiser, knows cannot be performed ; as in the case of a father, who promises a mar- riage gift with his daughters, when he knows that his whole property is secretly mortgaged. In such cases, as the pro- mise cannot be performed in fact, the promiser must repair the loss done to the promisee from such non-performance. When the promiser himself occasions the impossibility, he is guilty of a direct breach of promise ; as, for instance, when a soldier maims himself to get discharged. 2. Promises are not binding where the performance is un- lawful. 1. Where the illegality is known. If, for instance, a person promises to murder another, or betray his interests ; as the performance would be an unlaw- ful act, the engagement is void from its commencement, in consequence of a prior engagement not to do such act. There may be guilt in making such promises, but there can be none in breaking them. And moreover, if in the interval between the promise and its performance, any illegality presents itself, the promise ought to be broken. 54 What is said of an engagement % 55 What is said of most declarations of present intention 1 56 Is it right to change our intention when once made known % 57 What is the first case in which promises are not binding 1 58 What is said of this excuse 1 Give an example. 59 Suppose the promiser himself occasions the impossibility 1 60 What is the second case in which promises are not binding? 61 Give an example of a case where the illegality is known at the time of promise, 62 What is said of such cases 1 g2 78 RELATIVE DUTIES. BOOK III 2. Where the illegality is not known. If, for instance, a woman promises marriage ; but, previous to the marriage, discovers that her intended husband has al- ready a wife living, the promise becomes void : for, as it was given and received on the supposition that the perform- ance was lawful, the legality -becomes a condition of the promise, and on its failure the obligation ceases. So in the case of Herod's promise to his daughter-in-law, the promise was not unlawful, in the sense in which Herod intended it to be taken ; but the illegality attending its literal perform- ance discharged Herod from the obligation of such perform- ance in consequence of a superior previous obligation. The rule that promises are void when the performance is unlawful, extends also to imperfect obligations. (Book ii. chap, iii.) Thus, if a vote be promised to one candidate, and on the appearance of a better, it is found that the elec- tors are bound by oath to select the most deserving, the pre- vious obligation of the oath cancels the obligation of the pro- mise. The specific performance of promises is a perfect obli- gation ; and some moralists have decided, that where a perfect and imperfect obligation clash, the imperfect must yield ; whereas, in such a case, the obligation which is prior in time ought to prevail. As the validity of a promise is destroyed by the unlawful- ness of its performance and not of the motives which led to it ; it frequently happens that the first condition of a con- tract is not obligatory, but the promised recompense is, if that first condition be fulfilled. Thus, the promised reward of a crime should be paid after the crime is committed ; for after the mischief has been once done, it is not increased by the payment of the reward. Hence, if the motive be even criminal, the obligation is not canceled ; as in the case of a person, who, having promised to marry a woman after the 63 Give an example, in which the illegality is unknown at the time of promise. 64 Why does the obligation cease in such cases ] 65 What celebrated promise was of this kind, and what is said of it 1 66 To what does this rule extend? Give an example. 67 What if two obligations are contradictory 1 68 What follows from the second rule of canceling promises 1 Give an example. 69 What is the obligation of a promise that is made with a criminal motive 1 Give an example. CHAP. VI. PROMISES. 79 death of his wife, then sick, refused, when the wife was dead, to fulfil the engagement ; — correctly, said a moralist, to whom the case was referred ; but incorrectly, on the princi- ples stated above. For, though the motives might be im- moral which led to the promise, its performance was law- ful, and therefore obligatory. A promise cannot be deemed unlawful where it produces, when performed, no effect beyond what would have taken place had no such promise been made. Hence promises of secrecy ought not to be violated, although the public would derive advantage from the discovery. For, as the informa- tion would not have been imparted on any other condition, the public do not lose by the performance of the promise, any thing which they would have gained without it. 3. Promises are not binding when they contradict a former promise. . Because the performance would be then unlawful. 4. Promises are not binding before acceptance, i. e. before the promisee has knowledge of it. For the obligation to perform rests on the known expec- tation raised. But there can be no expectations, where there is no knowledge of the promise. Nor is the perform- ance obligatory, even if the promisee has obtained a know ledge of the promise, but through the medium of a party not empowered to communicate it : for that which constitutes the essence of a promise is here wanting, an expectation raised voluntarily. 5. Promises are not binding when they are released by the promisee. This is evident ; although it may not be evident who the promisee is. The doubt may however be solved by consi- dering that if a promise be given to A direct, for the benefit of B, then A is the promisee ; but if to A only indirectly, as a messenger to convey the promise to B, then B is the pro- 70 What fulfilment of a promise is not unlawful, let the consequences be what they may 1 Mention a case. 71 What is the third case in which promises are not binding 1 Why] • 72 What is the fourth case 1 Why 1 73 But suppose the promisee has been informed of the promise 1 74 What is the fifth case in which promises are not binding 1 lib What doubt may arise here ] 76 How may it be solved "^ 80 RELATIVE DUTIES, BOOK III. Promises to one person for the benefit of another are not released by the death of the promisee ; for his death neither makes the performance impossible, nor implies his consent to release the promiser. 6. Erroneous promises are not binding. 1. Where the error proceeds -from the misrepresentation of the promisee. For instance, a beggar solicits charity by a story of distress, and a promise of relief is given. But previous to the per- formance of the promise, the distress is found to be ficti- tious. The promise is canceled. For it was given on the supposition of the truth of the story ; but that condition fail- ing, the promise ceases to be obligatory. In like manner, the business of an oifice has been represented to a person, and he makes a promise to undertake it ; but if the labor be greater than the promisee represented, the promiser is re- leased. 2. When the promise is given on a supposition not abso- lutely expressed, but understood both by the promiser and promisee ; and that supposition turns out to be false. For instance, if a father, hearing the news of his son's death, promises to make his nephew his heir, he is, on the news proving false, released from his promise ; because, as the nephew knew that the promise was in reality condi- tional though not so expressed, the ejfpectations raised were subject to a condition which formed an essential part of the promise. In other cases, no errors on the part of the promiser can cancel the engagement. For example, a vote is promised to one candidate ; afterwards another oifers himself, whom the promiser would prefer ; but his vote must follow his pro- mise. [Unless the last candidate is actually better. See page 78.] The error was on the part of the promiser, who must abide by his error : the promisee, who made no mis- take, must not suffer by it : as the promise was given with- 77 What would be the obligation if the promisee in the first case should die? Why] 78 What is the sixth class of promises that are not binding ? 79 What is the first kind of erroneous promises ] 80 Why should they be canceled ? Give examples. 81 What is the second kind of erroneous promises'? 82 Why are such promises not binding ? Give examples. 83 What if the error is only on the part of the promiser 1 Give examoles. CHAP. V. . PROMISES. • 81 out a condition, it cannot be affected by a subsequent event- Hence, if a man promises a certain fortune with his daugh- ter, he is bound to perform the promise, even though his means be less than he thought them to be when he made the promise. The case, however, of erroneous promises is attended with this difficulty, that if every mistake be allowed, the rule becomes too loose ; but if the rule be drawn too tight, the result must be hardship and absurdity in its application. Whether promises which are extorted by fear are binding, has been long held as a doubtful point. For as the obliga- tion of all promises rests on the utility of mutual confidence, whatever tends to check that confidence is wrong ; but if, on the other hand, such confidence leads to general- mischief, it ought not to be insisted on ; and it is in the balance of op- posite good and evil that the difficulty rests. For instance, a man, threatened with death, saves his life on his promise to give the threatener at a future day a sum of money. This safety is a good consequence of the confidence which is placed by the promisee in the promiser. But the per- formance of promises thus extorted by fear, leads to a repe- tition of such acts of violence. This is a bad consequence. Between these two consequences moralists have to choose — a choice not yet decided on. [But is this not settled by rule 2, page 79 ?] In other cases, where a prisoner is suffered to go at large on promise of good behavior, such a promise is binding, not, as some moralists say, because the imprisonment is just, but because the utility of confidence in such promises is the same as the utility of confidence in the promises of persons at liberty. Promises to God are called vows. The obligation to keep them depends, not on the principle which regulates other promises, but on the want of reverence to the Deity, which want is indicated by their non-performance. The Scriptures give no encouragement to make vows, much less to break them when made. The few vows we 84 What difficulty is attendant on this kind of promises ? 85 What is thought of promises that are extorted by fear ? 86 What is the argument for the affirmative I For the negative 1 87 Apply these arguments to an example. 88 What is a plainer case in extorted promises ? 89 What are vows ] And why should they be kept \ 90 Is there Scriptural authority for vows ? Contracts of 82 RELATIVE DUTIES. BOOK: III. read of in the New Testament were religiously observed. Of Jephthah's vow, as commonly understood, the obligation was not binding ; because, by its performance, an act pre- viously unlawful was committed. CHAP. VI. CONTRACTS. A contract is a mutual promise. Therefore, the law which regulates promises regulates contracts also. Hence, as in promises the obligation is measured by the expectation raised voluntarily by the promiser ; so in contracts, whatever is expected on one side, and known to be so expected on the other, is a condition essential to the contract. The several kinds of contracts may be exhibited at one view, thus : — Sale. Hazard. J ^ C Inconsumable Property oan ^Money. rService. T b J ^Commissions. j Partnerships. LOffices. CHAP. VII. CONTRACTS OF SALE. The rule which requires to be most strictly inculcated IS, that the seller is bound to disclose the faults of what he offers for sale. To tell a direct falsehood in recommendation of our wares, is confessedly an immoral act. And from this we argue that concealing the truth, by not saying that they pos- sess the bad qualities which they do, is likewise an immoral act. Because, as the moral qualities of actions differ only in their motives and effects ; if the motives and effects be the same, the actions also are, morally speaking, the same. But as in these cases the motives are the same, viz. benefit to the seller from the higher price ; and the effects the same, viz. injury to the buyer from an inferior article, or at least not. 91 What is a contract'? — and by what law is it regulated T 92 What should always be considered as a condition in a bargain 1 93 Name the several kinds of contracts. 94 What is an important rule of justice in contracts of sale 1 95 From what do we deduce this fact 1 How do we prove it 1 CHAP. VII. CONTRACTS. 83 such as the representation warranted ; it is manifestly as much a fraud to magnify the qualities of wares, as to con- ceal their defects. The obligation is greater, and, if that is performed, the honesty greater also, to tell the truth, Avhen the goods are such that the faults cannot be detected except by their use. From this charge of dishonesty are to be excepted sales of goods, where the silence of the seller implies some fault in the article ; as in the case of a horse sold without warranty, on which account it brought an abated price. Connected with this principle of dishonesty is the prac- tice of passing off bad money. For this act it has been pleaded, that, as it was received for good, it may be passed for good ; a plea similar to that given by a person, who having been robbed himself, reimbursed his loss by robbing another. When no monopoly or combination exists, the market price is always the fair price ; which may, therefore, be fairly demanded. Hence, to say provisions are at an un- reasonable price, is an absurdity ; for if the price were un- reasonable, none would give it. If a man asks for goods more than the market price, such a demand is deemed dishonest ; yet, as the goods are the man's own property, he may say he has a right to put what value he pleases on them. Still, as the very act of tendering goods for sale carries with it the implied condition of their being to be sold at the market price, and as he knows that customers enter his shop with that belief; he is bound to sell them at such a price, unless there be a specific un- derstanding between the parties of a contrary nature ; and in that case, any price may be asked without any imputation of dishonesty. If the article sold be accidentally destroyed or injured between the sale and delivery, the loss must fall on the party 96 What renders the obUgation more necessary 1 97 In what cases is it not dishonest to be silent of faults 1 98 What has been pleaded for passing counterfeit money 1 99 Is it a good plea 1 100 How should we determine the price of a commodity 1 101 Why may one suppose a higher demand is not dishonest ? 102 How can you prove that it is dishonest 1 103 When may a person ask a higher price than customary 1 104 After a thing is sold, on whom must fall any loss that may hap- pen to it '' 84 RELATIVE DUTIES. BOOK III. who undertook the risk of its safe custody. For instance, if, after the purchase, the seller offers to deliver it, and the safe delivery forms a part of his responsibility ; on its failure, payment may be resisted or reclaimed. But if the buyer requests the seller to keep charge of the article, he takes the responsibility on his 'own shoulders, and cannot resist or reclaim payment, except for injury done wilfully. But in this, as in other cases, custom determines, if not more correctly, at least more effectually, than casuists can. Not that custom of itself possesses any authority to decide between right and wrong ; but only that the contracting par- ties are presumed to have in view all the tacit conditions of similar contracts. Hence, frequently, by custom alone can it be decided, at what moment the risk of the buyer ends, and that of the seller commences. CHAP. VIII. CONTRACTS OF HAZARD. By contracts of hazards are meant Gaming and Insu- rances. Some say that one side in this kind of contracts ought not to have any advantage over the other ; but this is scarcely possible. For that perfect equality of skill and judgment, which this rule requires, is seldom, if ever, to be met with. Nor is it requisite, if practicable. For one party may, it ne pleases, give the whole stake, and of course B.part of it; or, in other words, he may assent to the natural inequality of the parties, and allow to his opponent an advantage in the chance of winning the whole. The proper restriction is, that neither side have an advan- tage unknown to the other. For though the event be still uncertain, such advantage has its value ; and so much of the stake as that value amounts to, is taken from the other party without his knowledge or consent. If, for instance, in a game of whist, one party has greater skill ; the other knows that such a superiority is possible, and takes his measures 105 Give an example for each side 1 106 How are such cases generally determined 1 Why 1 107 What are contracts of hazard ] 108 What has been thought of this kind of contracts 1 109 Can that well happen ? Why 7 110 Is it actually necessary, if it could happen 1 Why ? 111 What is a proper restriction 1 Why 1 CHAP. IX. CONTRACTS OF LOANS. 85 accordingly. But if the superiority be not in skill, but in acts unknown to, and not even suspected by, the other, such as looking into his opponent's hand, or making concerted signals with his partner, the advantage is an act of disho- nesty, and the contract to pay the loss is void. And so in other cases where chance enters, all advantage obtained, ex- cept from sources which one party previous to the contract knew or suspected that the other might possess, vitiates the contract. Hence, in the case of insurances, where the under- writer enters on the risk, dependent solely on the represen- tations of the insured, if such representations be designedly incorrect, the policy becomes void ; because the insured has not, in fact, completed his part of the contract, which is to tell the whole truth. CHAP. IX. CONTRACTS OF LOANS OF PROPERTY INCONSUMABLE. When the article lent is to be itself restored, as a book or horse, the loan is of property inconsumable ; in contradis- tinction to consumable property, when not the thing itself, but its value is to be returned, as money, or articles in their nature perishable. If the article which is lent be damaged, the loss of the da- mage will fall on the lender, provided such damage occur by using the article in the proper manner, for such purposes as the article was lent for ; because the lender contemplated the possibility of such damage previous to lending. But if the damage accrue by the negligence of the borrower in the use of the article lent, or in its misapplication to other and new purposes, the borrower must sustain the loss ; for here the lender neither knew nor suspected such misapplication of the loan. In the case of an estate or house lent on lease for a term of years, the increase or diminution of its value may be such as to make the rent a positive gain or loss either to the land- 112 Give an example of honest and dishonest advantage. 113 Does this principle hold in all contracts of hazard 1 114 How will it apply to insurances 1 115 What is inconsumable property? 116 On whom must the damage of such property fall 1 117 In what cases will the borrower be accountable for it 1 118 What case may be stated, in which the value may b6 eventually ncreased or diminished 1 H 86 RELATIVE DUTIES. BOOK III. lord or to the tenant. To ascertain to whom the advantage or disadvantage belongs, we must inquire if the alteration was expected by the parties. For if so, the hirer must take the consequences of benefit or loss ; if not, the owner. For in- stance, as the uncertainty of produce in successive seasons is expected by both parties, the "hirer both receives the bene- fit of a good, and suffers the loss of a bad season. But if the loss be occasioned by an event, which the parties could neither foresee nor avert, as any convulsion of nature, or the irruption of an enemy, the loss shall fall on the owner ; who, in like manner, is to receive the benefit that might arise from similar unexpected changes. This determination rests on the reason that events foreseen form a part of the con- tract ; but that with respect to events not foreseen, the con- tract is as if none had been made. CHAP. X. CONTRACTS OF MONEY-LENDING. The loan of money, like that of other property convertible into money, may be paid for. The objection to usury or interest, (for they formerly meant the same,) once prohibited by law in Christendom, arose from the Mosaic enactment ; " Thou shalt not lend on usury to thy brother. To a stranger thou mayest lend." Deut. xxiii. 19, 20. But this prohibition is now supposed to be a part of the polity intended peculiarly for that nation, which was calculated to preserve in the same family its share of the property originally distributed to each tribe ; and it is therefore ranked in the same class with the law which required a man to marry his brother's widow if left childless, and with another law which enacted that in the year of jubilee, alien- ated estates should revert to the original proprietor. This interpretation is confirmed by the distinction made between the brother and a stranger ; a distinction which God would hardly have made, had he intended the law to be of universal application. The Roman law once allowed twelve per cent, as the rate of interest, but Justinian afterwards reduced it to four. In 119 What is the rule of justice in such cases 1 Give an example. 120 Why do we arrive at this determination 1 121 What is thought of the law of Moses that prohibits interest 1 122 How is this interpretation confirmed ] 133 What have been the rates per cent. 1 CHAP. X. CONTRACTS OF MONEY-LENDING. 87 the reign of Elizabeth, the first act which tolerated usury- restrained the rate to ten per cent., which, in the time of James I., was reduced to eight; then, by Charles II. to six, and by Anne to five, on pain of forfeiture of treble the amount. [In the United States the rate is generally six per cent., though in some states it is seven.] The policy of these regulations is to give the borrowers the power to obtain aid at a moderate rate, and to guard them against the extortions of avaricious money-lenders. Compound interest, though sometimes forbidden by law, is not contrary to natural equity ; for if interest has been any time due, it is actually a sum lent. Whoever borrows money is bound to repay it ; and in order to effect such repayment, he is also bound to make every sacrifice of a pecuniary kind, by turning into money all available assets, lessening his family expenses, and employ- ing all the lawful means he can devise, the moment he per- ceives no reasonable prospect of satisfying his creditor with- out such sacrifice. Nor has the debtor the right to delay the repayment ; for by such delay the creditor depends on the uncertain contingency of the debtor's life ; a condition which neither party anticipated originally in the contract for the loan. The law which authorizes the imprisonment of an insol- vent debtor has been represented as a gratuitous cruelty, which benefits neither the creditor nor community. If the incarceration of the debtor were merely to satisfy the credi- tor's feelings of revenge, the motive and the act would be equally unjustifiable. But if it be viewed as a public punish- ment, its justice will be apparent. The frauds relating to insolvency are as necessary to be punished as frauds of other kinds. Nor is the obstinacy of debtors who will not pay their debts when they can, less deserving of punish- ment. The only question is, whether the power of imprison- ment should rest with the exasperated creditor. Now the 124 "What is the intention in making these rules ? 125 Is compound interest lawful 1 126 To what -ananagement is a borrower bound 1 127 Has he the right of procrastination in payment 1 Why 1 128 What has been thought of imprisoning debtors 1 129 When is it wrong ] When is it just 1 Why 1 130 Why should the power of punishment be in the hands of the cre- iitor ] 88 RELATIVE DUTIES. BOOK III. frauds are so various and versatile, that discretionary power alone can reach them ; nor will such power be effectually exercised, unless intrusted to the creditor alone. But as imprisonment is a punishment, and as punishment presupposes crime, the imprisonment for insolvency, when such insolvency is the result of acts over which the debtor had not any or only a small control, is a manifest wrong ; and for a creditor, provoked by such loss, to relieve his own pain by inflicting a greater on the creditor, is inhuman. Any alteration of the law, which should distinguish be- tween fraudulent or non-fraudulent acts of insolvency, would be an improvement ; but a total repeal of the law would be a greater hardship to the needy than even its present rigor. For as the power to coerce is a kind of security to the credi- tor, the loss of that, as in the case of a repeal, must be sup- plied by some other security, which the needy, though honest, would be unable to give, and therefore would be deprived of the aid of the loan. Now as persons without capital must buy on credit before they can sell ; in the absence of loans, both he who has and he who wants the funds for trading would be unemployed. Hence, a greater evil would accrue from the sufferings of the niney-nine wanting a loan, than from those of the remaining hundredth, who, after having obtained a loan, becomes insolvent, and is then left to the vengeance of an exasperated creditor. CHAP. XI. CONTRACTS OF LABOR SERVICE. In this country, service of citizens is voluntary and by contract. But as the contract involves many particulars as to work, food, treatment, and indulgences, as well as pecu- niary recompense ; only a few leading points are noticed in the contract, and the rest are left to the known custom in such cases. A servant is not bound to obey the unlawful commands of 131 When should this act of punishment be resorted to 1 133 What may be said of the law on this subject ] 133 What would be the eifect of repealing the law, and why % 134 What would be the general effect 1 135 Does the contract for services embrace all the particulars of the bargain "? Why 1 136 How are the omitted points determined? 137 What is a servant not bound to obey 1 CHAP. XI. CONTRACTS OF LABOR, SERVICE. 8.9 his master ; for the obligation depends on his promise ; but that does not extend to unlawful acts. Chap. v. § 3. Hence, the master's authority is no justification of a servant in doing wrong; for the servant's own promise, on which that authority is founded, would be none. Clerks and apprentices ought to be employed only in the business which they Avere to learn. For, their hire is instruction; and to deprive them of the opportunities of that, for the purposes of their employer, is to rob them of their wages. The master is responsible for acts done by his servant in the ordinary course of employment ; for they are done under a general authority equivalent to a specific command. Thus a iDanker is responsible for money paid to his clerk, but not if paid to his footman ; because it is not the business of the latter to receive money for his master. So if a ser- vant be sent by his master to a shop to buy goods on credit, whatever goods he may afterwards obtain for himself, so long as he is in the same service, the master is answerable for ; because the seller cannot tell whether the goods are, or are not, required for the master. In other cases, the law, rather than moral justice, ordains that the master be responsible for the. acts of his servant, even when the servant is a free agent ; as, for instance, when an innkeeper's servant robs a guest, or a farrier's man lames a horse, or a coachman injures a passenger or passer-by ; the innkeeper, farrier, and coachman's master are respec- tively liable. Connected with the contract for service, is the duty of giv- ing a character to a servant ; in the performance of which, most persons through mistaken views of kindness do in truth act wrong. A character, if not true to the letter, is a fraud on the party who accepts it ; and the act is the more unge- nerous as the person who is deceived by it is a stranger. But to misrepresent secredy a person's character to others, 138 If a servant does wrong for his master, is he justified by being commanded 1 Why 1 139 How are clerks and apprentices to be employed? Why? 140 When is the master responsible for his servant's acts? Why ] 141 Give a few examples, with their reasons. 142 To what extent docs the kw enact on such subjects 1 143 What is our duty in the matter of giving characters 1 144 How is considered the act of injuring a servant's character? h2 90 RELATIVE DUTIES. BOOK Ili with the view of retaining for one's own use the services of such employee, is cruel, immoral, and cowardly ; cruel, be- cause the injury is done without the power of remedy ; immoral, because it destroys the motives to good conduct ; and cowardly, because a similar act in the case of equals, would by the law of honor expose the party offending to the loss of character or life. A master of a family is bound not to permit among his domestics any vices which he might restrain. This arises from our duty at all times to prevent misery, of which vice is the inevitable forerunner. This care of his household on the part of Abraham met with the approbation of God ;* and indeed no authority is so well adapted for this purpose, be- cause none operates on the subjects of it with an influence so direct. The language of the Christian Scriptures, touching the re- lative duties of masters and servants, breathes a spirit of libe- rality which has always been but little known in ages when servitude was slavery ; and which must have resulted from the habit of viewing both parties in a common relation to their Creator, and a common interest in a future state. " Servants, be obedient to your masters, as unto Christ ; not with eye-service, as men-pleasers, but doing the will of God from the heart ; with good-will doing service as to the Lord, and not to men, knowing that whatsoever good thing any man doeth, the same shall he receive of the Lord, whether he be bond or free. And, ye masters, do the same thing unto them, forbearing threatening: knowing that your Master also is in heaven ; neither is there respect of persons with him."t Nor is the policy of this view less than its libe- rality ; for by teaching servants to consider God as their pre- sent task-master and future re warder, a steady and cordial obedience is produced, in place of that constrained service which cannot be trusted out of sight, and is therefore well called eye-service ; while the exhortation to masters to con- sider themselves accountable, is equally seasonable. 145 To what is the master morally bound 1 Why is it thought so ? 146 What else confirms this opinion 1 147 What are the scriptural directions to servants ? 148 What directions to masters 1 149 What may be thought of these directions 1 Why 1 * Gen. xviii. 9. f Eph. vi. 5—9. CHAP. XII. CONTRACTS OF LABOR, COMMISSIONS. 9 J CHAP. XII. CONTRACTS OF LABOR, COMMISSIONS. He who undertakes another's business engages tacitly to employ on it the same care as if it were his own ; but he promises no more than this. If he has done so much, he has discharged his duty, even though it should afterwards appear that greater exertion would have benefited his em- ployer more. The chief difficulty of an agent is to decide whether he may or may not depart from his instructions, when the object of the commission presents to his mind a view differ- ent to that which he knew his employer had, when he, 'the agent, was charged to execute such commission. The lati- tude allowed must vary according to circumstances. For instance, an attorney, sent to complete the purchase of an estate at a certain price, finding the title defective, refuses to pay the money ; and properly so. On the other hand, an officer is ordered to perform a particular duty, which he is satisfied his commander would not have ordered, had he known the real state of affairs : yet he is bound to follow implicitly his instructions. What is trusted to an agent may be lost or damaged by accident when in his possession. If he receives no pay, he is not answerable for the loss : for he gives his labor for nothing, and cannot be expected to give security for nothing also. But if he receives any pay, the decision respecting his responsibility will rest on the apprehension of the par- ties respecting the terms of the engagement ; and this again is regulated by custom. For instance, whether a carrier be or be not liable for the loss of goods intrusted to him, when the loss is not imputed to any fault or neglect of his, is a question of custom alone. But if the carrier stipulates that he will not be accountable for goods of a certain description, he engages, in fact, to be accountable for all others of any other description ; because the limitation of one part is the 150 What does an agent promise in his contract 1 151 What may limit his exertions'? 152 What is the chief difficulty experienced by an agent ? 153 In such cases, is the judgment of the agent always trusted to? 154 Give examples of both cases. 155 How is an agent without pay to be affected by accidental injuriea to his charge 1 156 How is he to be affected if he is paid for his agency? Give some examples. 92 RELATIVE DUTIES. BOOK. III. non-limitation of others. On the other hand, any caution taken by the owner to guard against risk exonerates the carrier, by showing that the sender was aware of the risk, and that he took it on himself. Universally, unless a proinise, either express or tacit, be proved against the agent, the loss*must fall on the owner. The agent may accidentally suffer in person or purse by the business he undertakes ; still he can claim no compensa- tion for such loss. For if the danger was not foreseen, neither the agent nor his employer thought of such compen- sation, and consequently none is due. If it was foreseen, the business was undertaken with the knowledge of the risk, the remuneration was of course regulated with reference to such risk, and a part of the remuneration is in fact a com- pensation for the loss incurred. Of course, the loser can require nothing extra. . CHAP. XIII.^CONTRACTS OF LABOR, PARTNERSHIP. On the subject of partnership, the only point of doubt is the division of profits, where one party contributes money, and the other labor. Rule. From the value of the partnership-stock deduct the sum advanced ; and the remainder is the profit. Divide that between the two partners, in proportion of the interest of the money to the wages of the labor ; allowing such in- terest as money might fetch on the same security, and such wages as would be given for the same labor. But if there be no profit, then the moneyed partner loses his interest, and the working one his labor. If the original stock be dimi- nished, the working partner loses only his labor, whereas the moneyed partner loses his capital and interest ; but for this disadvantage, must be set off the chance of greater profit arising from the rate of interest in his favor. It is true, the proportion, in which the profits are to be divided, is generally expressed in the contract itself. But the agreements, to be equitable in such cases, must pursue the principle here laid down. All the partners are bound by the act of one ; for that one is supposed to be the agent of the others. 157 What effect has a caution from the owner ] 158 What is the general rule in agencies 1 159 What claims has an agent for personal injury 1 Why ] 1 60 What is the moral rule for partnership 1 tJHAP. XIV. CONTRACTS OF LABOR, OFFICES. 93 CHAP. XIV. CONTRACTS OF LABOR, OFFICES. In many offices, such as professorships, principals of schools, and managers of corporate bodies, there is a two- fold contract ; one has regard to the origin of the office, the other to the electors to it. With regard to the origin, the officer is bound to do all that is appointed by the charter, deed of gift, or will of the founder. The contract with the electors, is to do all that has been customarily done by the person in office ; for such is the known expectation of the electors, and the officer elected must satisfy them, or previous to election, stipulate for their non-perfomance. The electors can excuse the officer from the performance of these customary duties only : for as their power cannot annul the positive injunctions of the original deed, so neither can they stipulate with the candidate for the non-perform- ance of those duties which such positive injunctions imply. It is difficult and yet important, to know what offices may be performed by deputy. But the cases need only be stated where a deputy is not allowable. An office may not be discharged by deputy, 1. Where a particular confidence is placed in the judg- ment and conduct of the individual; as a judge, commander- in-chief, or a guardian of property or persons. 2. Where the custom hinders ; as in the case of tutors. 3. Where the deputy cannot legally perform all the acts of the principal ; as for instance where he lacks the legal authority. 4. AVhere general mischief would result to the service from such substitution of the deputy for his principal ; as for example, the discouragement of military merit if superior officers in the army might employ substitutes. 161 What kind of contract is made in the case of some offices ? 1 62 To what is the officer bound by the origin of the office 1 1 63 To what is he bound by contract with the electors 1 Why ? 1 64 How far can he be excused by the electors 1 Why 1 165 What difficult and important question arises here ] 166 What is the first case in which an office cannot be discharged by deputy ? 167 Give the second, and an example. 168 State the third, with its example. 169 The fourth, and an example. 94 RELATIVE DUTIES. BOOK III. CHAP. XV. LIES. A lie is a breach of promise ; for he who speaks seriously to another, tacitly promises to speak the truth ; because he knows the truth is expected. Or, the obligation to veracity may rest on the ill conse- quences resulting from a breach of it. The ill consists in some specific injury to an individual, or the general injury to society, by the destruction of mutual confidence. Hence, a lie may in its tendency be mischievous, and therefore criminal, though harmless in its individual application. All falsehoods are not criminal. 1. Where no one is deceived ; as in parables, fables, tales, &c. where the speaker means to divert merely ; or in ser- vants denying their master; or an advocate asserting the jus- tice of his client's cause ; because in these and similar cases no confidence is destroyed, for none was reposed ; no pro- mise violated, for none was given to speak the truth. [Concerning the practice of requiring servants to " deny" their masters, Mr. Dymond says, " This childish and sense- less custom has had many apologists, I suppose because many perceive that it is wrong. It is not always true that such a servant does not in strictness lie : for, how well soever the folly may be understood by the" gay world, some who knock at their doors have no other idea than that they may depend upon the servant's word. Of this the servant is sometimes conscious, and to these persons, therefore, he who denies his master, lies. An uninitiated servant suffers a shock to his moral principles when he is first required to tell these falsehoods. It diminishes his previous abhorrence of lying, and otherwise deteriorates his moral character. Even if no such ill consequences resulted from this foolish custom, there is this objection to it, which is short, but suf- ficient, — nothing can be said in its defence."] 2. Where the person to whom you speak has no right to know the truth, or more properly, when little or no incon- 170 What is a lie 1 Why ] What follows from this 1 171 For what other reason are we bound to speak the truth 1 172 What is the ill effect of lying ? 173 Are all falsehoods criminal ? J 74 What is the first class that are not 1 Why 1 175 What does Mr. Dymond say of the practice of denying masters 1 176 What is the second class that are not lies 1 Give examples. CHAP. XV. LIES. 95 venience can arise from the want of confidence ; as, to tell a falsehood to a madman for his OAvn advantage ; to a robber to conceal your property ; to an assassin to defeat or divert him from his purpose. For, here the inconvenience is only to individuals, which is balanced by the advantage gained by individuals also ; nor can any consequences generally hurt- ful be drawn from such insulated falsehoods. Hence, it is allowable to deceive an enemy by false colors, false intelligence, and other deceptions, in time of war but not during a truce ^ for in the latter period, confidence is, in the former is not, placed in the acts of either party. Hence, too, the immorality of falsehood in hoisting feigned signals of surrender or distress ; for, on the faith of such signals, one opponent lays down the character of a foe for that of a friend, and supposes that the other has done so likewise. Here then is a deception during a period of apparent truce, and consequently it is wrong ; because the general consequences of such conduct would be to disbelieve such signals, and to increase the sum of the misery of towns besieged, or of ships in distress. On this article Dr. Dewar remarks, [" A rule thus founded on the principle of expediency, allows, or rather authorizes us, to utter falsehoods as often as we can induce ourselves to believe that little inconve- nience will result from the want of confidence. Can we con- ceive any maxim more anti-scriptural, or more immoral in its tendency ? It is substituting as the rule of moral conduct, in room of the will of God, our own limited and partial views of the consequences of actions." And Mr. Dymond says, " Such a doctrine would be equivalent to saying that we are at liberty to disobey the Divine laws when we think fit. And if I may tell a falsehood to a robber in order to save my property, I may commit parricide for the same pur- pose ; for lying and parricide are placed together and jointly condemned in the revelation from God." — 1 Tim. i. 9, 10.] 177 Why does Dr. Paley think that they are not criminal 1 178 What is allowed by the laws of war ] What is not 1 179 What is said of feigned signals of distress or surrender] 180 What does Dr. Dewar say that this principle of expediency will lead to 1 181 What else does he remark of it 1 182 What does Mr. Dymond say of it 1 96 RELATIVE DUTIES. BOOK III. Some lies, harmless in their motive, may become mis- chievous in their effects, and consequently are to be avoided, as morally wrong ; such, for instance, are the false- hoods told by those persons who give exaggerated accounts of acts performed by themselves or others. Such falsehoods, if inoffensive in other points, are wrong, because they tend to produce in the speaker the habit of lying. Disregard to truth, shown by a person in matters of no importance, tends to destroy confidence in his veracity where his narra- tions are connected with the promotion of his own interests, or the depreciation of others. Now, since much of. the pleasure, and all the benefit of conversation, depends on the existence of such confidence, the want of it will only serve to perplex the hearer, who is uncertain to what extent he ought or ought not to believe. Pious frauds, as they are improperly called, such as the forgery of new, and the interpolation or castration of old books, counterfeit miracles, and pretended inspirations, even if they should be done with a good design, are both foolish and immoral ; immoral, because they tend to destroy confidence in documents really genuine ; and foolish, because they miss the very object aimed at. Christianity has suffered more injury from this than from all other causes put together. As there may be falsehoods which are not lies, so there may be lies without the appearance of direct falsehood. Of this kind are prevarications, which are falsehoods in reality, though not in appearance, on account of being disguised under the ambiguity of language. But it is the wilful deceit that makes the lie ; and the deceit is wilful when the words are not true in the sense in which the hearer does and must take them, according to the custom of the language. A man may also act a lie, as by pointing to a wrong direc- tion, when asked the road ; or where a tradesman shuts up his windows to induce his creditors to believe that he is 183 What is said of exaggeration 1 Why is it wrong 1 184 What is said of disregard to truth in small matters'* 185 What effect has it upon the hearer l 186 What is the character of pious frauds 1 187 Why are they immoral 1 Why are they foolish 7 188 Can there be a lie without a direct falsehood ? 189 What makes the he 1 And when is the deceit wilful 190 What must the words of truth be according to '? 191 How may a man act a lie 1 Why 1 •HAP. XVI. OATHS. 97 abroad ; for to all moral purposes, speech and action are the same, the former being only a mode of the latter. There are also lies of omission. For instance, if an histo- rian of the reign of Charles I. wilfully suppresses evidence of that prince's despotic measures, he may be said to lie by omission ; for, by the very title of his book, he tacitly pro- mises to tell all the truth he knows of the events of that period. CHAP. XVI. OATHS. I. Forms of oaths, ii. Signification, iii. Lawfulness. rv. Obligation, v. What oaths do not bind. vi. How oaths are to be interpreted. 1. The forms of oaths, like other religious ceremonies, have in all ages varied, consisting generally of certain words accompanied with a bodily action.* Amongst the Jews, the juror held up his right hand to- wards heaven. Hence, we find in the 144th Psalm, " Whose right hand is a right hand of falsehood." The same form is retained in Scotland still. An oath of fidelity was taken amongst the Jews by the servant putting his hand under the thigh of his lord, as Eliezer did to Abraham, Gen. xxiv. 2 ; whence, probably, is derived the form of doing homage, by putting the hands between the knees and within the hands of the liege ; as is done in some places. Amongst the Greeks and Romans, in private contracts, the parties took hold of each other's hand, whilst they swore to the performance ; or they touched the altar of the god by whose divinity they swore. But on more solemn occasions, they slew a victim ; and as the beast was struck 192 What is the last-mentioned class of lies ] Give an example. 1 93 MTiat is the general form of oaths ? 194 What was the form among the Jews 1 195 Is this practice continued among other nations 1 196 What was the form among the Greeks and Romans 1 * It is commonly thought that oaths are denominated corporal oaths from the bodily action which accompanies them, of laying the right hand on a book containing the four Gospels. This opinion, however, appears to be a mistake ; for the term is borrowed from the ancient usage of touching, on these occasions, the corporate, or cloth which covered the consecrated elements. I 98 RELATIVE DUTIES. BOOK III. down with certain ceremonies, the parties were said, as in English, "to strike a bargain."* The forms of oaths differ in Christian countries ; but in none do they convey either the meaning or sanctity of an oath worse than in this country and in England. Here the juror, after repeating the promise or affirmation which the oath is intended to strengthen, adds, "So help me God." The force of this formula rests in the particle so ; that is, on condition of my speaking the truth, or performing the pro mise, may God help me ; otherwise, not. The juror, while he hears or repeats the words of the oath, holds his right hand on a Bible, or other book containing the four Gospels, and, at the conclusion of the oath, kisses the book : but this act seems to be done rather out of reverence to the book, than as forming a part of the oath. But it is not so much the form of the oath, as the levity with which it is administered, that has produced a general disregard to the sanctity of the obligation ; to say nothing of the multiplicity of frivolous oaths, especially those connected with the revenue. A pound of tea, for instance, cannot travel from the ship to the consumer without costing half a dozen oaths ; and the highest and lowest functionaries in the state are equally sworn into office. If some security be- yond a man's word be required, let the law annex, if it will, to direct falsehoods and indirect prevarications, penalties pro- portioned to their mischiefs ; but let it spare the solemnity of an oath. II. Whatever may be the form of an oath, its significa- tion is the same. God is called to witness, or to notice, what we swear ; and it is " invoking his vengeance or renouncing his favor, if what we say be false, or what we promise be not performed." III. Quakers, Moravians, and many others refuse to swear at all, in obedience to Christ's prohibition, " Swear not at all." Matt. V. 34. 197 What is said of the forms in this country ? 198 On what word rests the strength of the oath ? 199 What besides the form of the oath has occasioned a disregard of it? 200 How might the evil be remedied ? 201 What is the signification of an oath ? 202 Why do many refuse to swear 1 * In Greek, Ts^vav ogxov : in Latin, " ferire pactum." CHAP. XVI. OATHS IN EVIDENCE. 09 But this prohibition, it would seem, was not meant by Christ to extend to judicial oaths. For, the whole passage runs thus. " Ye have heard that it hath been said by them of old time, Thou shalt not forswear thyself, but shalt perform unto the Lord thine oaths. But I say unto you, swear not at all ; neither by heaven, for it is God's throne, nor by the earth, for it is his footstool ; neither by Jerusalem, for it is the city of the Great King. Neither shalt thou swear by thy head, because thou canst not make one hair white or black. But let your communication be yea, yea ; nay, nay : for whatsoever is more than these cometh of evil." And, 1. It does not appear that the Jews, in judicial oaths, ever swore " by heaven," " the earth," "Jerusalem," er "their heads;" and, consequently, it is probable that judicial oaths were not alluded to here. 2. The prohibi- tion expressed by " not at all" is to be understood as in con- junction with, not separated from, the succeeding words, "heaven," "earth," "Jerusalem," and "head:" that is; Do not swear, says Christ, by any of these forms, for all are equally reprehensible. He seems to suppose that some made a distinction between swearing by the name of God, which is an oath forbidden in the Decalogue, and swearing by other oaths not forbidden there. In opposition to which, he tells them, that because all those things bear the same relation to God that his name does, to swear by any of them was in effect and substance to swear by hi7n. For which reason he says, " Swear not at alW^ that is, neither directly by God, nor indirectly by any thing related- to him. 3. Our Saviour himself did not make any objection to a judicial oath, when adjured by the living God to say whether he was the Christ or not. And St. Paul also calls on God to witness to the truth of his assertions, and thus in reality takes an oath : and lastly the author of the epistle to the Hebrews, vi. 16, speaks of the custom of swearing judi- cially, without any mark of disapprobation. 203 Does Dr. Paley think that Christ's prohibition extended to judicial oaths'? 204 What is his first reason 1 The second 1 205 What does he think occasioned this prohibition ? 206 What is the third reason ' 100 RELATIVE DUTIES. BOOK III The prohibition, then, was meant to apply not to judicial oaths, but to the practice of vain, wanton, and unauthorized swearing in common discourse. [To this Mr. Dymond replies, " From an investigation of the passage, it appears manifest that all swearing upon all occasions is prohibited. Yet the ordinary opinion, or rathei perhaps the ordinary defence is, that the passage has no re* ference to judicial oaths. — Dr. Paley explains " our Sa- viour's words to relate, not to judicial oaths, but to the practice of vain, wanton, and unauthorized swearing in common dis • course." To this there is one conclusive answer. Our Saviour distinctly and specifically mentions, as the subject of his instructions, solemn oaths ; the whole prohibition sets out with a reference, not to conversational language but to solemn declarations on solemn occasions. Oaths ** to the Lord," are placed at the head of the passage ; and it is too manifest to be insisted upon, that solemn declarations, and not e very-day talk, were the subject of the prohibition. *' It hath been said of old time, Thou shalt not forswear thyself." Why refer to what was said of old time ? For this reason assuredly ; to point out that the present requisi- tions were different from the former ; that what was prohi- bited now was different from what was prohibited before. And what was prohibited before ? Swearing falsely,-— swearing and not performing . What then could be prohi- bited now ? Swearing truly, — even, swearing and perform- ing : that is, swearing at all ; for it is manifest that if truth may not be attested by an oath, no oath may be taken. In acknowledging that this prefatory reference to the former law is, in my view, absolutely conclusive of our Christian duty, I would remark, as an extraordinary circumstance, that Dr. Paley, in citing the passage, omits this introduction and takes no notice of it in his argument. " Dr. Paley says that the high-priest examined our Sa- viour upon oath, ' by the living God,' which oath he took. But what imaginable reason could there be for examining 207 What is his concluding remark on this subject l 208 How does Mr. Dymond reply to this remark 1 209 What does he say is manifest by the subject of the prohibition 1 210 What inference does he draw from the commencement of the 211 What is his reply to Dr. Paley's opinion of our Saviour's exami- nation upon oath 1 CHAP. XVI. OATHS IN EVIDENCE. 101 him upon oath ? Who ever heard of calling upon a prisoner to swear that he was guilty ? Nothing was wanted but a simple declaration that he was the Son of God. With this view the proceeding was extremely natural. Finding that to the less urgent solicitation he made no reply, the high- priest proceeded to the more urgent. Schleusner expressly remarks upon the passage, that the works * I adjure,' do not here mean * I make to swear, or put upon oath,' but ' I so- lemnly and in the name of God exhort and enjoin.' This is evidently the natural and the only natural meaning ; just as it was the natural meaning when the evil spirit said, ' I ad- jure thee by the living God that thou torment me not.' The evil spirit surely did not administer an oath. *' Paul says, ' God is my witness that without ceasing I make mention of you always in my prayers.'* That the Al- mighty was witness to the subject of his prayers is most true ; but to state this truth is not to swear. Neither this language nor that which is indicated below contains the character- istics of an oath, according to Paley's definition, i. e. an 'in- vocation of God's vengeance.' Similar language, but in a more emphatic form, is employed in writing to the Co- rinthian converts. It appears from 2 Cor. ii., that Paul had resolved not again to go to Corinth in heaviness, lest he should make them sorry. And to assure them why he had made this resolution, he says, ' 1 call God for a record upon my soul that to spare you I came not as yet unto Corinth. 't The expression appears to me to be only an emphatical mode of saying, God is witness ; or, as the expression is sometimes employed in the present day, God knows that such was my endeavor or desire. " The next and last argument is founded upon silence. Will it then be contended that whatever an apostle mentions without reprobating he approves ? The same apostle speaks just in the same manner of the pagan games ; of running a race for prizes, and of * striving for the mastery.' Yet who 212 With what other text does he compare it ? 213 What does he say concerning the supposed oaths taken by Paul 1 214 What does he say concerning 2 Cor. i. 231 215 What are his remarks concerning Heb. vi. 16 ? * Rom. i 9 See also 1 Thess. ii. 5, and Gal. i. 20. f 2 Cor. i. 23. I 2 102 RELATIVE DUTIES. BOOK III- would admit the argument that because Paul did not then censure the games, he thought them right ? The existing customs both of swearing and of the games are adducea merely by way of illustration of the writer's subject."] IV. Oaths are nugatory, unless we believe that God will punish false swearing more severely than he will a common falsehood. And that he will do so, is probable, from consi- dering that, 1. Perjury is a more deliberate sin. The juror confesses to his belief in God and in the sanctions of religion ; and there- fore his perjury implies his contempt of God's knowledge, power, and justice. But with a common falsehood, is con- nected neither the belief of God's existence, nor contempt of his power. Hence its less culpability. 2. Perjury violates a greater confidence. Men must trust one another ; and the highest security for veracity is an oath. Now, as the security of reputation, property, and even of life itself, is connected with dependence on oaths, the con sequence of continued perjuries would be the loss or de- struction of the greatest interests on this side of the grave. A simple lie cannot do the same injury, because the same credit is not given to it. But it may be well to state that the affirmation of one who is unwilling to swear, is held equal to the oath of another person ; and in that case a lie partakes of the nature and guilt of perjury. V. Promissory oaths are not binding, when the promise itself without the oath would not be binding. VI. As oaths are intended for the security of the imposer, they must be interpreted and performed in the sense which the imposer intended; for, otherwise, they would be no security to him. Hence the meaning and reason of the rule, ** jurare in animum imponentis.'* 216 When are oaths nugatory ] 217 What may be said of the sin of peijury 1 218 Is this the case with a common falsehood ? 219 What degree of confidence does perjury violate ? 220 What may be the consequence of perjury ] Why 1 221 Has a lie the same effect 1 222 When does a simple declaration become equal to an oath 1 223 When are promissory oaths not binding 1 224 What must be the interpretation of an oath 1 CHAP. XVII. OATHS IN EVIDENCE. 103 CHAP. XVII. OATHS IN EVIDENCE. The witness swears " to speak the truth, the whole truth, and nothing but the truth." To conceal designedly a part of the truth which relates to the matter in question, is as much a violation of the oath, as to testify to a positive falsehood. For as there are two kinds of oaths relating to evidence, by one of which* the witness is required to answer truly to all questions asked ; and by the othert " to tell the whole truth ;" it is evident that in the latter case, where there is no restraining to the question that shall be asked, the law intended the witness to tell the whole truth, even though he is not questioned to the extent of his knowledge. So that it is no excuse for not giving the court full information, to say, "Because it was never asked me." The only exception to this rule is, when the witness, by such full disclosure, would criminate himself; for, as the law compels no man to be his own accuser, the oath is im- posed with this tacit reservation. But such reservation extends only to cases where the law of the land permits such concealment of the truth. Hence, a delicacy with re- ference to the subject matter, or tenderness towards the per- son accused, are no pleas for concealment; for justice would thus be made to depend on the personal feelings of witnesses, rather than on the administration of the laws. A full disclosure is also required from a person admitted to give evidence against his accomplices ; because his im- munity from punishment depends on the tacit engagement to tell the whole truth. If answers be required to questions, respecting which the witness has doubts, as likely to affect himself or others, he ought to refer his doubts to the court. And as it is the bu- 225 What does a witness swear that he will do 1 226 What effect has this upon designed concealment 1 Why 1 227 What is the only exception to this rule 1 228 Why is that an exception 1 229 To what cases does this exception extend I 230 What in particular will it not excuse ? Why 1 231 What is its bearing in the case of evidence against accomphces 1 232 What if a witness thinks a question irrelevant 1 233 Why is the answer of the court any authority ? • Called technically voir dire. f Used in examinations in chief. 104 RELATIVE DUTIES. BOOK III. siness of that to declare what the mind of the law is, its answer will be of sufficient authority to release the witness ; but only in cases where he believes that such release is not at variance with the intention of the person imposing the oath. CHAP. XVIII.— iWILLS. The question is, Are wills a natural or adventitious right? or, in other words, Is the right to devise property founded on the law of nature, or on the law of the land? As a man's labor is his own property, so is the produce of his labor ; such as the utensils which he manufactures, the tent or hut that he builds, and the flocks or herds that he rears. And, as he may give such property away when alive, he may leave them at his death to whom he pleases ; because there is nothing to limit the continuance of the right, or to restrain the alienation of it. But property in land stands upon a different foundation. For the right to a spot of ground arises, in a state of nature, from the right to apply a part of what is common to all, to an individual's own wants and use ; and as the wants and use cease at death, so does the right cease also. Consequently in such state, the family of the first occupier have, in the right of possession, a preference not by inheritance ; but by becoming the first occupiers after him, and by succeeding to the same want and use. Again, as natural rights cannot, like rights created by law, expire at the end of a certain number of years ; if the testa- tor had a natural right to dispose of landed property for one moment after his death, he might direct the disposition of it for ever ; which would be absurd. The right, then, to will landed property is adventitious, or founded on the law of the land. And this inference is con- firmed by the fact, that in most countries the power to make wills has been given only by the laws of the state ; as by the laws of Solon at Athens, and at Rome by the twelve 234 Is it so in all cases 1 235 What is the question relative to wills 1 236 What kind of property may a man leave to whom he pleases 1 237 Does all property stand upon the same footing by iJie law of nature 1 Why is this the case 1 238 What absurdity would follow from the natural right of willing landed property 1 239 On what then is that right founded'? How is that proved'? CHAP. XVIII. WILLS. 105 tables. And even in England, the prohibition against the divisal of land existed from the Conquest till near the close of the reign of Henry VIII., when the privilege was restored by law. No doubt, many beneficial purposes are attained by ex- tending the owner's power over his property beyond his life and beyond his natural right. It invites to industry, it encourages marriage, and it secures the dutifulness and de- pendency of children. As wills are the creatures of the law, so they have no power except from the law. Hence, if the will be informal, it is the same as if it had never been made. By an informal will, I mean a will that lacks some formality that is required by the law, though no doubt is entertained of its meaning and authenticity. For instance, if a man devise his freehold estate to his sister's son, and if the will be not attested by witnesses, and the law requires that attestation ; then the heir-at-law is le- gally authorized to seize the estate, although aware of the testator's intention to cut him off; and the sister's son is morally bound to give up the estate, as soon as he finds this flaw in the will. For the intention of the testator can signify notliing unless he have a right to govern the descent of his estate. Now, as the right to convey is clogged with certain conditions, it is evident that if such conditions be not fulfilled, the right is virtually given up ; and the heir-at-law is placed only in the situation, where he would be if there had no will been made. For, the intended will is so much waste paper, from the defect of right in the person who made it. And as the retention of the estate by the sister's son would be contrary to law if the flaw were known to the legal heir, so it is against morality not to give it up, although the flaw be known only to the illegal possessor. Had wills been founded on natural rights, the decision in this case would have been just the reverse ; for, then the requirements of 240 What are the advantages of wills 1 241 What is meant by saying a will is informal ? 242 Of what eflfect is such a will 1 Why 1 243 Give an example. 244 Why must not the intention of the testator be followed 1 245 How is this right lost ] 246 What is the consequence of such loss "? 247 What rule of morality will tliis lead to 1 248 Would this be the case if the devising of land was a natural right ? Why ] 106 RELATIVE DUTIES. BOOK III the law would seem rather to refuse its assistance to enforce the right of the devisee, than to deny or work any alteration in the right itself; and consequently, I should consider them unjust. ["The transmission of property by hereditary descent, from the parent to his children, is the dictate of the natural affections ; and Doctor Taylor holds it to be the general di- rection of Providence. And nature and policy have gene- rally concurred to introduce and maintain this primary rule of inheritance, in the laws and usages of all civilized nations. But the distribution among the children has varied greatly in different countries ; and no two nations seem to have agreed in the same precise course of hereditary descent ; and they have very rarely concurred, as we have done, in establishing the natural equality that seems to belong to lineal descend- ants standing in equal degree." — Kenfs Commentaries, vol. 4, page 376.] In the disposal of property, the regard due to kindred not lineal, arises either from the presumed intention of the ancestor from whom we received our fortune, or from the expectations we have encouraged. The intention of the an- cestor is presumed with greater certainty, in proportion to, the nearness of the relation. For instance, it may be pre- sumed to be a father's intention, that the inheritance which he leaves for one son, should, if that son dies childless, remain a provision for the families of his other children. Whoever, therefore, gives to strangers what he has received from kindred, is guilty, not so much of unkindness to the parties not receiving, as of ingratitude to the party from whom the property came. Where a man has acquired pro- perty by his own exertions, and at the same time has re- frained from exciting the expectations of relations, he is perfectly at liberty to dispose of his property, uninfluenced by consanguinity and affinity ; for these are merely forms of speech, imposing no moral obligation to do any particular act. 249 What is said of hereditary descent 1 250 By what has this primary rule been sustained 1 251 Has this distribution always been equal ] 252 Is it the case in this country 1 253 By what is occasioned the descent of property to those who are not lineal descendants 1 Give an example. 254 What follows from this view of the subject % \ 255 What right has a man in devising property which he has ac- quired himself 1 CHAP. XVIII. WILLS. 107 There is, however, one particular reason for providing for poor relations, which is, if we do not, no one else will. ["In this country we have much statute regulation on the subject. There is no doubt that the testator may, if he pleases, devise all his estate to strangers, and disinherit his children. This is the English law, and the law in all the states, with the exception of Louisiana. Children are deemed to have sufficient security in the natural affection of parents, that this unlimited power of disposition will not be abused. If, how- ever, the testator has not given the estate to a competent de- visee, the heir takes, notwithstanding the testator may have clearly declared his intention to disinherit him. The estate must descend to the heirs, if it be not legally vested else- where." — Kenfs Commentaries, vol. 4. page 525.] To neglect to make a will is a culpable omission, when it occasions an equal distribution of what ought to be distri buted unequally on account of fhe situations of the parties, or where it leaves an opening for litigation. As the right of succession is founded on law alone, so the claims of succession in cases where there is no will, must be regulated by law alone. These regulations ought to be guided by the duty and pre- sumed inclinations of the deceased. The law of descent, which is founded on the English statute of distributions, is sufficiently equitable. It assigns one-third to the widow, and two-thirds to the children ; in case of no children, one-half to the widow, and the other half to the next of kin : where neither widow nor lineal descendants survive, the whole to the next of kin, and to be equally divided amongst kindred of equal degree, without distinction of whole blood, and half- blood, or of consanguinity by the father's or mother's side. ['* In a majority of the states, the descent of real and of per- sonal property is to the same persons, and in the same propor- tions. Such a uniform rule in the descent of both real and personal property, gives simplicity and symmetry to the whole doctrine of descent. The English statute of distributions, 256 Has a man a right to disinherit his children 1 257 When is it wrong to neglect making a will 1 258 How is succession regulated if there is no will 1 259 On what principle should the law be formed 1 260 What is the English statute of distributions ? 108 RELATIVE DUTIES. BOOK III being founded in justice, and on the wisdom of ages, and fully and profoundly illustrated by a series of judicial de- cisions, was well selected, as the most suitable and judicious basis on which to establish our American law of descent and distribution." — Kenfs Commentaries, vol. 2. page 427. 261 What is Kent's remark concerning that statute? 262 What was occasioned by these good qualities I (109) BOOK III.— PART II. RELATIVE DUTIES, WHICH ARE INDETERMINATE. CHAP. I. CHARITY. By charity is here intended, not bounty to the poor, nor, as St. Paul means, benevolence in general ; but the promoting of the happiness of inferiors. Charity, in this sense, is the result of religion, or virtuous habits ; for while worldly interests regulate our behavior to superiors and equals, humanity alone can influence our con- duct to those beneath us. The happiness of inferiors may be promoted by, 1. thie treatment of dependents ; 2. professional assistance ; 3. pecu- niary bounty. CHAP. II. ON TREATMENT OF DEPENDENTS. A party pursuing a journey together, find it for their interest that one should wait on the rest, a second seek out lodging, a third take charge of the horses and baggage, and a fourth bear the purse, and regulate the route ; not forgetting that they were equals at the commencement, and will be so at the end of the journey. In this case, he whose lot it is to direct the rest, finds himself bound to study the feelings of his fellow- travelers, by giving his commands mildly, and using their service discreetly. So in the journey of life, they whom the Creator has made dependents, ought to be treated with the consideration due to equals in the eye of God. Some think that the obligation from the inferior to the supe- rior is greater than contrariwise ; but this is a mistake. The rich man does not maintain his servants, tradesmen, tenants, and laborers ; the truth is, that in one sense, they maintain 263 What is meant here by the term " charity 1" 264 From what does this kind of charity spring ? 265 By what is our behavior regulated in general 1 266 What are the three principal methods of promoting the happineea •f inferiors 1 267 How may the subject be illustrated 1 268 What treatment of dependents does this illustration teach 1 269 Is social obligation, from the rich or from the poor 1 K 110 RELATIVE DUTIES. BOOK III. PT. 2. him. It is by their industry that his food, house, dress, and luxuries, are obtained. It is not the estate, but the labor employed on it, that pays the rent. The proprietor merely distributes what others produce. Others, in extenuation of unkiiid conduct to inferiors, say, that kind usag'e is thrown away on persons of low estate ;— - that they are insensible of kindness, and incapable of grati- tude. But all men, high or low, have, and must have the , same perception of the manner in which they are treated ; though all may not exhibit similar perceptions of gratitude, either in kind or degree. As we are bound to refrain from diminishing the sum of human happiness, we have no right to increase the uneasiness of domestics and dependents, by unnecessary occupations, or by ill treatment in deed or word, or by the refusal of harmless amusements. CHAP. III. SLAVERY. Servitude differs from slavery in this, that the servant con- tracts to work for his master, while the slave is, without such contract, compelled to labor ; but in both there is the same obligation on the part of the master, not to diminish, beyond absolute necessity, the sum of human happiness. ^; Hence, as slavery may arise from, 1. crimes; 2. war; 3. debt ; it must cease as soon as the crime is expiated, or the quarrel settled between the nations at war, or the creditor legally satisfied. But the slave-trade is not advocated on any of these princi- ples, and consequently it is morally wrong. Yet even if the purchase were defensible, the trade is still chargeable, 1. with the crime of exciting the native slave- sellers to war and rapine for the purposes of trade ; and, 2. with the cruel treatment shown to the slaves in their pass- age from Africa to America. 270 What is another erroneous opinion '] Why is it erroneous ? 271 Frora what are we forbidden by the rule of not diminishing the sum of human happiness 1 272 What is the difference between servitude and slavery ? 273 What requirement resting on the master is common to them both 1 374 What three causes may justly occasion slavery 1 275 How long must it continue under each case 1 276 On which of the three principles is the A" follows from this fact 1 . 277 With what two crimes is it chargeable t CHAP. IV. PROFESSIONAL ASSISTANCE. Ill But necessity, the name under which if just war? 641 What is Dymond's conclusion relative to war of any kin4 ? THE END. S350 LEJa'19 O' CL * ^f-'-o'^ ^*^*'T'^'' *^ cy * 'h. ♦. . -f ^_ ♦-•• ,^- °t. *'"'\,f";.. .,/%*••••,%* /. > V « ' • •- O, r. ^^- ..* ■ /^Va"' ■*«. «.** .*«iei»'. -Sit. A^- . ,** ..-J,L% *^ ^^-^ V A ^ -^'-^^ <^ 'O • fc • .0' ,V .^'-. ^^ :. -n^o^ r. V •*• A^* ... ^* *^^^> . <^.. '•••• .*«•* .. \ ■>^ ."••• .*' ..".-. "'»* ,0* •iV./'^c o^ •;•• **' -^^ *^ >. • ./ **"•*:. °' <^. .*'^°- > ^ 5»-'>. .• **' ^^ ^^^'J^ ,0' "V '-.To' ■ ,■?,''■ ^°^**'"*' J.0 "^ '^O' • - o '* .'^'^ ^-^ O^ M!DDi.ET--/VN. PA APRJL 82 A^