% tl :•>' • ^0- '%/: ■V ^ ■ ^'% -0' <, O0 1 rj •/' % "' WE " -~ .*** % V? M ? ^ ** '^, ^,%^ ; ^ -^ ,0o ^O0 N .0 ,0 > * V V % ^ V
0o.
// ^
O0 x
**. v
'"/* % V ^>^". " - ,^ 9 ,"< ./% ^
,0o.
^ v*
y ^
x°°
o N
3^ -*j
..^">
c'a *^
'**,. <*
^'
X^
•J- y
,0o
'o o^
^ ^
.
Philosophical Classics
Religion of Science Library No. 51
Price 40 cents (2s.)
DESCARTES' MEDITATIONS
AND SELECTIONS FROM THE
PRINCIPLES OF PHILOSOPHY
By
RENE DESCARTES
CHICAGO
THE OPEN COURT PUBLISHING COMPANY
1912
RENE DESCARTES
(1596-1650)
THE MEDITATIONS
SELECTIONS FROM THE PRINCIPLES
RENE DESCARTES
" (1596-1650)
TRANSLATED BY
JOHN VEITCH, LL. D.
LATE PROFESSOR OF LOGIC AND RHETORIC IN THE UNIVERSITY OF GLASGOW
WITH A PREFACE,
COPIES OF ORIGINAL TITLE PAGES,
A BIBLIOGRAPHY, AND AN ESSAY ON DESCARTES' PHILOSOPHY
BY L. LÉVY-BRUHL, MAÎTRE DE CONFÉRENCES
IN THE SORBONNE
CHICAGO
THE OPEN COURT PUBLISHING COMPANY
1913
3\S5Z
PUBLISHERS' PREFACE.
An authorized reprint of Veitch's translation of Descartes'
Discourse on Method has already been published as No. 38
of the Religion of Science Library. The present volume is
a reprint of the remainder of Veitch's translations of
Descartes' representative speculative treatises. The Medi-
tations on the First Philosophy are translated entire, and
the preface and the first part of the Principles of Phi-
losophy, together with selections from the second, third and
fourth parts of that work, corresponding to the extracts
in the French edition of Gamier, are also given, as well
as an appendix containing part of Descartes' reply to the
Second Objections {vis., his formal demonstrations of the
existence of Deity), and Veitch's notes. The translations
are based on the original Latin editions of the Meditations
and Principles, published respectively in 1641 and 1644.
Both works having been translated into French during
Descartes' lifetime, and personally revised and corrected by
him, the French text is evidently deserving of the same
consideration as the Latin originals, and consequently, the
additions and variations of the French version have also
been given — the additions being put in square brackets in
the text and the variations in the footnotes.
Dr. C. Guttler, of the University of Munich, has just
published (Munich: C. H. Beck. 1901) a new critical and
annotated edition of both the Latin and French texts of
the Meditations, and students desirous of consulting the
sources may be referred to this easily accessible book. Dr.
Guttler made use of the copy of the original Latin edition
(1641), preserved in the Bibliothèque Nationale at Paris,
and of the copy of the original French translation by the
Duc de Luynes (1647) found in the University Library
at Gôttingen. Literal copies of the title-pages of these orig-
inal editions, as given in Dr. Guttler's work, are also repro-
duced in the present volume. The most recent French edi-
tion of the Meditations is that of Emile Thouverez (Paris:
Belin Frères. 1898).
With a view to rendering the volume as complete and
serviceable as possible, the publishers have added by way
iv PUBLISHERS' PREFACE.
of a general introduction, Professor L. Lévy-Bruhl's essay
on- the philosophy of Descartes, which appeared in his
History of Modem Philosophy in France (Chicago: The
Open Court Publishing Co. 1899). A brief bibliography
of Cartesian literature has also been appended.
It merely remains for us to add a few remarks as to the
technical history of the Meditations, and to refer to the prev-
alent misconception that Descartes regarded his famous dic-
tum, Cogito, ergo sum, as having the force of a syllogism.
The first draft of the Meditations was written in 1629
while Descartes was sojourning at a chateau of a noble
family named Sjàrdama, in Franeker, a small university town
in Friesland. In a letter to Gibieuf, dated July 18, 1629,
Descartes speaks of a small metaphysical tract on which
he was engaged, and on April 15, 1630, he writes to Mer-
senne from Amsterdam that he had devoted the first nine
months of his stay in Holland to meditation on the prob-
lem as to how the proofs of the truths of metaphysics might
be rendered more evident than the demonstrations of geom-
etry. The treatise did not see the light however, until 1641.
In the meantime, the great work on The World was written
(1633) and suppressed, and the Discourse on Method and
the treatises on Dioptrics, Meteors, and Geometry (1637)
appeared. It was to offset the criticisms which were aimed
at these latter works by Fermât, Petit, De Roberval, Voët-
ius, Bourdin and others, that in 1639 Descartes took up
the draft of the old tract prepared ten years before, to
remodel it into an independent and systematic treatise on
metaphysics. To forestall all possible animadversions, and
to render his exposition explicit on all points, he submitted
his manuscript before printing, to a number of learned
men for examination and critical analysis. With the so-
called Objections, which these critics supplied, and Descartes'
answers, the book finally appeared on August 28, 1641.
The authors of the Objections were : Caterus, a theologian
of Louvain (First Objections) ; Mersenne, Desargues, and
anonymous critics (Second and Sixth Objections) ; Hobbes,
Arnauld and Gassendi (Third, Fourth and Fifth Objec-
tions). In later editions, other Objections were incorpor-
ated. The title Meditationes was chosen in contradistinc-
tion to the Quaestiones and Disputationes of scholastic liter-
ature.
PUBLISHERS' PREFACE. v
The frequent misconception that Descartes regarded his
famous cogito, ergo sum, as having the force of a syl-
logism also deserves brief mention. Descartes himself, al-
though not always careful as to his mode of expression on
this point, has explicitly anticipated the objection so often
made to his reasoning. In Meditation II. (see pages 30-33)
he omits the "therefore." In his reply to Gassendi's objec-
tion that cogito ergo sum implies qui cogitât est, a pre-
judgment, Descartes says:
"The term pre-judgnient is here abused. Prejudgment
there is none, when the cogito ergo sum is duly considered,
because it then appears so evident to the mind that it can-
not keep itself from believing it, the moment even it begins
to think of it. But the principal mistake here is this, that
the objector supposes that the cognition of particular prop-
ositions is always deduced from universals, according to
the order of the syllogisms of logic. He thus shows that
he is ignorant of the way in which truth is to be sought.
For it is settled among philosophers, that in order to find
it a beginning must always be made from particular notions,
that afterwards the universal may be reached ; although
also reciprocally, universals being found, other particulars
may thence be deduced." Again he says: "When we ap-
prehend that we are thinking things, this is a first notion
which is not drawn from any syllogism ; and when some one
says, / think, hence I am, or / exist, he does not conclude
his existence from his thought as by force of some syl-
logism, but as a thing known of itself; he sees from this,
that if he deduced it from a syllogism, he must before-
hand have known this major, All that which thinks is or
exists. Whereas, on the contrary, this is rather taught
him, from the fact that he experiences in himself that it
cannot be that he thinks if he does not exist. For it is
the property of our mind to form general propositions from
the knowledge of particulars."
In other places, also, Descartes has made the same dis-
tinct assertion.* Finally, Mr. C. S. Peirce, in The Open
Court of June 15, 1893, cites a passage in a letter to Cler-
selier :
"Je pense, donc je suis, ne suppose pas la majeure, Tout
ce qui pense existe." T. J. McCORMACK.
La Salle, 111., September, 1901.
(♦See M. Cousin's edition, T. I., 247, 403; T. II., 74, 333.)
ESSAY ON DESCARTES.
BY PROF. L. LÉVY-BRUHL.
With Descartes a new period of modern philosophy begins.
It is not, indeed, a beginning in a literal sense: there is no
such thing in the history of ideas, nor elsewhere. Descartes,
who came after the great scientific and philosophical illumi-
nation of the sixteenth century, had profited largely by it.
He owed much to the Italian Renaissance, and not less to
the Renaissance in France and in England. He was ac-
quainted with the discoveries of contemporary men of science,
such as Galileo, Torricelli, and Harvey. Even scholastic
philosophy, which he was to combat, left a lasting impression
upon his mind.
However, after we have considered all the influences, both
of the past and of the present, which were exercised upon
him, the originality of Descartes shines out all the more con-
spicuously, and we see the more clearly that he initiated a new
philosophic method. Hegel called him a hero, and this hyper-
bole may in a certain sense be justified. Descartes had, in-
deed, no vocation for martyrdom. But nature had endowed
him with that higher sort of courage which is love of truth
and devotion to science; and if the name of hero is due the
men whose exertions have laid open new paths for human
thought, Descartes is undoubtedly entitled to the name.
The attitude of Descartes toward the philosophers who pre-
ceded him is remarkable, — he deliberately ignores them. Al-
though well acquainted with their works, he builds his own
system as if he knew nothing of them. He wishes to depend
solely on his own method and reason. Not that he personally
holds in contempt either the ancient or the modern philoso-
phers. He is not so presumptuous as to believe that his mind
is superior to theirs. He even acknowledges that many
truths had been discovered before he created his method, but
these truths he does not wish to accept on tradition. He is
determined to discover them for himself. By means of his
vii
viii ESSAY ON DESCARTES.
method he proposes to obtain these truths, no longer mixed
pell-mell with the mass of doubtful or erroneous opinions,
but set in their right places, and accompanied with their
proofs. Thus only do they become valuable and useful. For
a truth, when isolated, sporadic, and floating and unconnected
with the truths that have gone before it, and consequently
powerless to develop those that are to come after it, is of
slight interest in itself. To acquire such a truth is not worth
the trouble we must take in order to understand ancient
books, and the time we lose in learning the ancient languages.
All this time were better employed in training our reason to
grasp the necessary concatenation of truths as deducible one
from another.
This is already a first motive, and a quite sufficient one,
for Descartes to dispense with erudition and to take no ac-
count of traditional doctrine. But he has another and more
weighty one. He seeks not what is probable, but what is
true.V'Now the first requisite in finding what is true he takes
to be the casting aside of the philosophy taught in his time,
which contented itself with probability and gave no satisfac-
tory demonstrations. Therefore, though he occasionally re-
tains the vocabulary of scholasticism (for instance in the
greater part of his Meditations), though he even borrows
some of his matter from it (for instance, in the ontological
argument, in the theory of continuous creation), nevertheless
Descartes broke distinctly and completely with the method
and spirit of the philosophy which had been handed down
from antiquity through the vicissitudes of the Middle Ages
and the struggles of the Renaissance. Even what he seems
to borrow from it, he really transforms. Cartesianism not
only has a positive meaning, which we shall presently study,
but it has to begin with a critical function, and proposes first
of all to do away with a philosophical system which, appeal-
ing to substantial forms and occult causes, claimed to ex-
plain everything and could demonstrate nothing.
There is accordingly something more in his attitude to his
predecessors than a mere protest against the authoritative
method, — a protest which had already been raised by eloquent
voices in the sixteenth century and even earlier. We have in
ESSAY ON DESCARTES. ix
it, in fact, a set determination to consider the generally ac-
cepted philosophy as null and void, and to replace it with
another which shall owe nothing to the former. A bold un-
dertaking, not merely of a reformative but of a revolutionary
nature. In England, Bacon, while combating the Scholastic
Philosophy in the matter of experimental method, neverthe-
less derived from it his conception of physical reality.
Hobbes, however much he may have freed himself from tra-
ditional metaphysics, is nevertheless the heir of the later great
English scholastics. In Germany likewise, the genius of Leib-
niz is one of conservatism as well as of innovation. He
openly disapproves of Descartes's excessive severity toward
scholasticism, of which, for his part, he preserves a great
deal, in his doctrine as well as in his terminology. Therefore
we see his successor Wolf restoring, so to speak, a new
scholastic system based on the philosophy of Leibniz. It
was this philosophy that Kant imbibed; and later on, after
Kant's Kritik, a kind of new scholasticism appeared (in the
school of Hegel for instance), indisputably related to that of
the Middle Ages. Thus, in Germany, the thread of philosoph-
ical tradition was never entirely broken.
In France, owing to Descartes, the case was altogether dif-
ferent. The Cartesian philosophy aimed at nothing less than
the utter destruction of its rival. It prevailed; and, as early
as the latter part of the seventeenth century, the victory was
complete. This was both favorable and unfavorable to the
progress of French philosophy. Of course, it was no small
advantage for the latter to free itself from the prestige of
antiquity, from the tyranny of scholasticism, to regain its
full independence, and to draw its inspiration freely from
the spirit of the mathematical and physical sciences, the in-
creasing power of which was a genuinely new element in the
life of mankind. To this the success of Cartesianism, and
the fact that its method persisted, even after the doctrine was
discarded, bear sufficient testimony. But on the other hand,
certain displeasing characteristics of French philosophy in
the eighteenth century may, at least in some measure, have
originated in this breaking with tradition. A taste for abstract
and too simple solutions, a conviction that it is sufficient to
x ESSAY ON DESCARTES.
argue soundly upon evident principles in order to discover
the truth, even in the most complex problems of social life —
in short, a lack of historical spirit, with which the French
philosophy of that period has been reproached — all these
faults are owing in some measure to the spirit of Cartesianism.
Certain it is that Descartes and his followers, in their contest
with tradition, failed to appreciate its value and necessary
function.
Nothing is so significant in this respect as the way in which
these writers speak of history. As it is not a science, it
cannot possibly be the basis of a school. It may entertain
us, but it cannot really teach us. It is even liable to beget
false ideas, and to be an encouragement to extravagant un-
dertakings. And, logically speaking, whatever rests on his-
torical claims only is insufficiently justified. This last maxim
may, in practice, have most serious consequences. Descartes
foresaw the attempt that would be made to extend its appli-
cation to political and social problems. He therefore openly
disclaims beforehand this application, which he personally
refuses to make. Yet if he wishes us to abstain from criti-
cising existing institutions, it is in his case, as in Montaigne's,
for reasons of utility alone. One can easily imagine circum-
stances in which considerations of utility would favor the
other side. It is, then, a mere question of expediency.
This tendency to claim that reason alone ought to be the
basis of opinion, because reason alone can demonstrate it to
be true, and the consequent tendency to make free use of
rational criticism, appear in the history which Descartes gives
us of his mind. Of all that he learned at school, nothing
satisfied him except mathematics. Hardly had he freed him-
self from the sway of his masters (the best, he says, there
were then in Europe), when he deliberately set about forget-
ting their teaching. He speaks only with irony of the various
sciences, or so-called sciences : medicine, law, philosophy, as
they were taught in his day. He coolly turns his back on
belles lettres, and holds history in contempt. Geometry alone
found favor in his eyes ; still he wondered greatly at its being
used only as an object of amusement for the curious, and
that "on so firm a basis nothing more lofty had been estab-
ESSAY ON DESCARTES. xi
lished." The ground was now cleared; Descartes could begin
to build.
According to some, Descartes is first of all a man of
science, and secondly a philosopher. According to others,
the philosopher in him predominates over the man of science.
In point of fact, philosophy and science were not separated
in Descartes's view. He seeks to establish the system of
truths accessible to man — a system which he conceived as
unique, and which may be figured as an endless chain. And
he seeks it in order to find the means of living as uprightly
and happily as possible. Thus the end which Descartes has
in view is a righteous and happy life : wherein he agrees with
the philosophers of his time, and, we may also say, of all
times.
In order to attain to this righteous and happy life, leaving
out of account the teachings of religion, Descartes sees no
sure way but the possession of truth or science. Now science,
in its turn, rests on metaphysics, or primary philosophy,
whence it derives its principles. Therefore Descartes pro-
poses to be a metaphysician; but this he will be for the sake
of science itself. Metaphysics is to him a road, but indeed a
road of paramount importance, since all the rest depends
upon the principles discovered therein. Besides, mathematics,
physics, and other theoretical sciences are also roads, the ter-
minal point lying in the applied sciences, to which they lead.
"The whole of philosophy," says Descartes, in the Preface to
the Principes de la Philosophie, "is like a tree, the roots of
which are metaphysics; the trunk is the science of physics;
and the branches shooting from that trunk are all the other
sciences, which may be reduced to three main ones, viz., medi-
cine, mechanics, and ethics, by which last I mean the highest
and most perfect ethics, which, since it presupposes a com-
plete knowledge of the other sciences, is the supreme degree
of wisdom."
Thus if Descartes is careful to make a distinction between
the sphere of action and that of knowledge, and if, before un-
dertaking the long and difficult task of seeking after truth, he
provides himself with a "provisional" ethics, which he un-
questioningly accepts from authority and custom, he never-
xii ESSAY ON DESCARTES.
theless proclaims the principles of action to be dependent
upon knowledge. It is the business of reason not only to
enlighten, but also to guide us. Descartes, believing in the
future progress of mankind, considers it to be dependent on
the development of the sciences. We even observe, in several
passages, that the progress of ethics appears to him subordi-
nate to that of mechanics and of medicine. But these in
their turn depend for their advancement upon the establish-
ment of a sound and rigorously demonstrated physical science.
Thus, although science is not its own end, the fundamental
problem of philosophy according to Descartes is finally re-
duced to the problem of the establishment of science.
Now there is no breach of continuity between metaphysics
and physics ; on the contrary, there is a natural and neces-
sary transition from the one to the other. Descartes at-
tempted to build up a system by means of which one could
proceed uninterruptedly from the first principles of cognition
and of being, in a word, from God, down to the most specific
scientific proposition of physiology or of ethics, without one
link missing in the chain. A bold conception, which domi-
nates the whole system and is inseparable from the famous
method of Descartes.
Up to this point mathematics alone appeared to Descartes
worthy of being called a science. It differs from everything
else he had learned in the perfect lucidity of its principles,
in the rigorous demonstration of its propositions, and in the
inevitable sequence of its truths. But to what does it owe
these characteristics, if not to the method from which mathe-
maticians make it a rule never to depart? Therefore, in
order to establish the science or philosophy sought by Des-
cartes, it was sufficient to find a method that should be to
philosophy what the method of mathematical deduction is to
arithmetic, algebra and geometry.
To apply to that universal science conceived by Descartes
the method so effectively employed in the above-mentioned
sciences would evidently be the simplest solution of the prob-
lem proposed. But this solution is impracticable. The mathe-
matical method, as we see it practiced in "the analysis of the
ancients and the algebra of the moderns" is a special method,
ESSAY ON DESCARTES. xiii
limited to the study of figures in geometry, and confined in
algebra to symbols and rules which hamper the mind. How
could one pass from these processes, which are especially
adapted to particular sciences, to the general method required
by general science or philosophy? Descartes would undoubt-
edly never have conceived such an audacious hope, had not a
great discovery of his set him on this track. He had invented
analytical geometry, or the method of expressing by means of
equations the properties of geometrical figures, or, inversely,
of representing determinate equations by means of geomet-
rical figures. In this way, Descartes substituted for the old
methods, which were especially adapted to algebra and geom-
etry as distinct branches, a general method, applicable to what
he called the "universal mathematical science," viz., to the
study of "the various ratios or proportions to be found be-
tween the objects of the mathematical 'sciences, hitherto re-
garded as distinct." Not only did this discovery mark a
decisive epoch in the history of mathematics, which it pro-
vided with an instrument of incomparable simplicity and
power, but it furthermore gave Descartes a right to hope
for the (philosophical method he was seeking. Ought not a
last generalization to be possible, by means of which the
method he had so happily discovered should become appli-
cable, not only to the "universal mathematical science," but
also to the systematic combination of all the truths which
our finite minds may permit us to attain?
Thus was formed in Descartes's mind the method which
he summed up in the Discours de la Méthode, and which was
destined in his plan to replace the useless and sterile ancient
logic . It is inexpedient here to explain these rules minutely. .
We must, however, observe that the first one, "Never to accept II
a thing as true which I do not clearly know to be such," is
not, properly speaking, a precept of method.! Such precepts
are set forth in a subsequent set of rules, where Descartes
successively prescribes analysis for dividing difficulties into
parts, and synthesis for constructing and expounding science.
But the first rule is quite different. It does not lay down a
process to be used in order to discover truth. It concerns
method only in so far as method is not separated from sci-
xiv ESSAY ON DESCARTES.
\ ence itself (and such indeed was Descartes's meaning). If
I such is the case, the first step of method — or of science — must
be to determine accurately by what mark we can recognize
what is to be regarded as true, and what is to be set aside as
being only probable or dubious. This mark is what we call
evidence. This first rule may have been suggested to Des-
cartes, as the others were, by mathematics. Even as in his
method he generalized the processes used for mathematical
researches and demonstrations, so in this formula he laid
down the regulating principle to which this science owes its
perfection, and which was also to become the regulating prin-
j ciple of the new philosophy.
Thus the famous rule of "evidence" reaches far beyond the
,' scope of a mere principle of method. Both from what it ex-
" eludes and what it implies, it may be looked upon as the
motto of the Cartesian philosophy. It rejects, to begin with,
any knowledge grounded upon authority alone (excepting the
truths of religion). Even though Aristotle and all his com-
mentators were agreed on one opinion, this would be no proof
of its being true; and should it really chance to be so, the
authority of Aristotle would count for nothing towards estab-
lishing its standing in science. Nothing can be admitted in
science but what is evident ; i. e., nothing but what is so clear
and plain as to leave no possible doubt, or is soundly deduced
I from principles which rest on such evidence. The whole
j system of scholasticism: metaphysics, logic, physics, thus
stand irretrievably condemned in toto. The so-called moral
sciences, which cannot attain to a degree of evidence com-
parable to that of mathematics, and which have to content
themselves with more or less strong probability, are likewise
rejected by the Cartesian formula; in fact, Descartes, as has
already been observed, had but little esteem for history and
erudition.
But what makes this rule of paramount importance is, that
it establishes reason as supreme judge of what is false or
true. Reason thus proclaims its own sovereign right to decide
without appeal. What we are to think, to believe, and to
do should be determined solely by evidence; and of that evi-
dence reason alone is judge (except in the case of urgency
ESSAY ON DESCARTES. xv
compelling us to immediate action). It is true, reason being
identical in all men, that such truth as becomes evident to one
of them becomes so to all other men likewise. Therefore
the assent given to evidence by one mind is by implication
equivalent to the universal consent of mankind; so that the
individual reason which distinguishes between true and false
is precisely the universal feature in every man.
Nevertheless, Descartes felt the danger that lay in his
formula. He foresaw the very serious misunderstandings to
which it might give rise, and he endeavored to prevent these
by taking multifarious precautions. First of all, the truths
of religion are carefully set apart and withdrawn from the
criticism of reason. They do not fall under its jurisdiction.
It is not ours to examine them, but to believe them. Ac-
cording to Descartes, we must seek neither to adapt them to
our reason, nor to adapt our reason to them. They belong
to another domain. Then Descartes makes a distinction be-
tween the sphere of knowledge and that of conduct ; he sub-
mits to provisional ethics, which is to be replaced by defini-
tive ethics only when science is completed, that is to say, in
a still remote future. Moreover, even in the province of
speculative thought Descartes refrains from touching upon
political and social questions. He censures "those blundering
and restless humours" ever ready to propose unasked-for re-
forms. Thus, after moral and religious problems, political
problems in their turn are cautiously set aside. Where, then,
shall the absolute sovereignty of reason be exercised? In
philosophy, in abstract sciences, in physics ; in short, wherever
men generally have no other interest but that of pure truth.
Well-meant precautions these were, no doubt, but vain pre-
cautions, too. Let reason rule supreme over this apparently
limited province, and by degrees it will inyade the others.
If we allow it, as a principle, the right to decide without
appeal between falsehood and truth, it soon will admit of
no restrictions but those it sets of its own accord through
the works of a Kant or of an Auguste Comte. In fact,
French philosophy in the eighteenth century was in the main
an endeavor to apply the spirit of the Cartesian method to
the very objects: politics, ethics, religion, which Descartes
xvi ESSAY ON DESCARTES.
had carefully set apart. By holding nothing as true until I
have evidence of its being so, do I not in advance deprive
all historical rights of the means of securing recognition; do
I not thereby summon all privileges, institutions, beliefs, and
fortunes to produce their title deeds before the bar of rea-
son? By solemnly paying homage to Descartes, the "As-
semblée Constituante" proved that the spirit of the Revolu-
tion was conscious of one of its chief sources.
Being now in possession of his method, did not Descartes
have all that was necessary to construct his philosophic sys-
tem with absolute mathematical certainty? No, for in
mathematics the foundation principles : axioms and defini-
tions, are so plain and evident that no reasonable mind will
question them. But philosophy had until his time been want-
ing in such principles, and the object which Descartes has
in view is precisely to establish them.
To attain this end, he first casts aside as false (at least
provisionally) all the opinions which he has hitherto held as
true, and which are only probable. In order to avoid tedious
enumerations, he proposes to consider opinions from the point
of view of their sources. "For instance," says he, "having
sometimes found my senses deceitful, I will distrust all
that they teach me. As I have sometimes erred with
regard to very simple reasoning, I will distrust the
results of even the most positive sciences. Lastly, I
may suppose that an evil genius, who is all-powerful, takes
delight in making me err, even when I believe I see the
truth most plainly. Therefore, by a voluntary effort, which
is always possible since I am free, I will suspend my judgment
even in cases where the evidence seems to me irresistible.
"Is there any proposition which is not affected by this 'hyper-
bolical' doubt? There is one, and one only. Let my senses
deceive me, let my reasonings be false, let an evil genius delude
me concerning things which appear to me most certain; if I
am mistaken, it is because I am — and this truth 'I think, there-
fore I am,' cogito, ergo sum,, is so self-evident and so certain
that the most extravagant doubt of skeptics is unable to
shake it." Here, then, is the first principle of philosophy
sought for by Descartes. And even as Archimedes asked only
ESSAY ON DESCARTES. xvii
a standing-place to lift the world, so Descartes, having found
a quid inconcussum, an indisputable proposition, set to work
to erect his whole system upon this foundation.
However, if according to the custom of philosophers we dis-
tinguish the sphere of knowledge from that of existence, this
proposition, or, as it is called, Descartes's cogito, is certainly
first in the sphere of knowledge ; for I may have doubts about
whatever I may think, but about my thinking I can have no
doubt, even in the very moment when I doubt. But in the
sphere of existence the Absolute — that is, God — comes first.
Therefore Descartes, as soon as he had established the cogito,
turned to demonstrating the existence of God. He knows
that he thinks, but he also knows that he doubts, and therefore
that he is imperfect; for not knowing instead of knowing is
an imperfection. He therefore has an idea of perfection.
Whence comes this idea? Descartes examines all the con-
jectures which may be made as to its origin; he eliminates
them one after another as inadequate until one only remains,
viz., that the idea of perfection cannot have sprung from ex-
perience, that we could not have it if the all-perfect Being —
that is, God — did not actually exist, and that therefore this
idea is as "the stamp left by the workman upon his work."
Descartes was bound to demonstrate the existence of God
at the very outset. Otherwise, the supposition of an evil
genius, who was able to deceive him even when he conceived
things with perfect clearness, would have cast suspicion upon
all propositions but the cogito ; the doubt which he himself
had raised would have paralyzed him. In "order to do away
with such a supposition, Descartes at once proceeds to dem-
onstrate the existence of an all-perfect God, who cannot pos-
sibly wish to deceive us. But is not this a syllogistic circle?
If the plainest argument, in order to be accepted as valid,
needs the guaranty of God, what will guarantee the argument
intended to prove the existence of God?
A syllogistic circle, indeed, had not Descartes escaped from
it with the help of the following reasons : God's guaranty
is necessary, not for the sake of the evidence, which is quite
sufficient in itself so long as it lasts (whereof the cogito is a
proof) ; but in order to assure me of the truth of propositions
xviii ESSAY ON DESCARTES.
which I remember having admitted as evident without remem-
bering for what reasons. It is necessary, in short, wherever
memory intervenes, but only in that case. Now if we have no
need of memory to know that we think, neither do we need
it to know that God exists. In spite of the syllogistic form
which Descartes gave to the proof of the existence of God,
this proof is rather intuitive than grounded on formal reason-
ing. In the act of conceiving the idea of the all-perfect Being,
I see at the same time the impossibility of His not existing.
The existence of all other things is looked upon as only pos-
sible ; but the existence of God appears as evidently necessary,
being comprised in the very notion of God. This is no argu-
ment, but rather an immediate apprehension. It is, as Male-
branche said shortly afterward, a proof "from mere vision."
The syllogistic circle therefore was only apparent. Descartes
was right in establishing the existence of God immediately
after the cogito. Henceforward he could in all confidence
make use of the faculties given him by God, who never de-
ceives. He only needed now to follow out his method care-
fully, and to link propositions together in the requisite order,
in order to arrive infallibly at the truth.
Now, the requisite order is, to begin with things which
are most general, simple and easy to grasp; that is, with the
primary principles from which the other truths are to be
deduced. Physics therefore is not to be studied until meta-
physics is well grounded. Acting upon this precept, Descartes
first established the existence of an absolute and perfect Being
— that is, God; for the same reason he now proceeds to
ascertain the essence of the soul and of the body. To reach
this end his starting-point is again the cogito.
I think, I am ; but what am I ? A creature that thinks ; that
is to say, judges, remembers, feels, imagines and wills; a being
whose existence is not linked to any place, nor dependent
upon any material thing. Descartes has just got out of his
universal doubt by means of the cogito. The only thing the
existence of which he can maintain at this point is his own
thought. Now, the existence of his thought does not appear
to him to be necessarily linked to that of his body and de-
pendent upon the latter. On the contrary, he may suppose
ESSAY ON DESCARTES. xix
that his body does not exist and that the perception of the
external world and of his own members is an illusion. He
is even unable for the present to reject this supposition; he
cannot do so till later on, and even then with some difficulty.
Nevertheless, since he thinks, he is certain he exists. But,
conversely, let him for a moment suppose that he ceases to
think; upon this supposition he ceases to exist, although all
external bodies and his own body should remain real. There-
fore, the cognition of his own being, which is his thought,
by no means depends on material things, the existence of
which is still problematic. Therefore his whole nature is to
think.
"You suppose," some opponent said to Descartes, "that
your own body does not exist, and you say that nevertheless
you continue to think. But should your supposition prove
true — that is to say, should your body and your brain be dis-
solved — can you affirm that even then you would continue to
think?" To which Descartes answered: "I do not assert
this — at least not now. My present object is not to demon-
strate the immortality of the soul. This is a metaphysical
question I am not now able to solve — for I know only one
fact as yet, viz., that I think (and also that God exists). The
whole question I am examining is merely : 'What am I ?'
Now it appears from what has been said that my existence is
known to me as that of a being endowed with thought and
endowed only with thought; for, whilst I am as certain as
possible of the existence of my thought, the existence of any-
thing else is still wholly doubtful to me. The existence of
this thought may possibly be actually connected with that of
the brain. I know nothing about that. I am not discussing
that for the present. One thing is certain : I know myself
as a thought, and I positively do not know myself as a brain."
This is one of the leading features of the philosophy of
Descartes, and one which may enable us to measure his influ-
ence, by comparing what had been thought before him with
what was thought after him. The cogito of Descartes dis-
placed, so to speak, the axis of philosophy. To the ancients
and to the scholastics (theology excepted) the thinking mind
appeared inseparable from the universe, regarded as the object
xx ESSAY ON DESCARTES.
of its thought, just as the soul itself was conceived to be the
"substantial form" of the living body. According to Descartes,
on the contrary, the existence of the thinking mind, far from
being dependent on any other existing thing, is the essential
condition of every other existence conceivable to us ; for if I
am certain of the existence of anything but myself, with far
better reason am I certain that I, who have that thought, am
in existence. The only reality I cannot possibly question is
that of my own thought.
Both the adversaries and the successors of Descartes started
from this point. All the modern forms of idealism, so utterly
different from the idealism of the ancients, have a common
origin in the cogito. The tempered and prudent idealism of
Locke, the Christian idealism of Malebranche, the skeptical
idealism of Hume, the transcendental idealism of Kant, the
absolute idealism of Fichte and many other doctrines derived
from these, which have appeared in our century, are all more
or less closely related to the foundation principle of the Car-
tesian philosophy. Moreover, the conception of nature in
modern science must also be connected with it. For, as we
shall see farther on, when Descartes set thought — that is, the
soul — so distinctly apart from everything extraneous to itself,
in so doing he made necessary a new conception of force and
life in the material world.
Now, let us add to the Cartesian formula, "I am a thing
which thinks," the following principle, "All that I conceive
clearly and distinctly is true." Then, since I conceive clearly
and distinctly that the nature of the body and that of the soul
have no attributes in common, therefore it is true that these
two natures or substances are separated one from the other.
Not only is there no need of my having any notion of the
body in order to comprehend the soul, but also the soul has
no need of the body in order to exist.
Descartes, therefore, had a right to infer that "the soul is
more easily known than the body." This does not mean that,
according to his doctrine, psychology is an easier science than
physics or physiology. Psychology as we conceive it has no
place in the system of Descartes; there is at most a mere
sketch of it in the Passions de l' Ame. But this maxim is
ESSAY ON DESCARTES. xxi
metaphysical, not psychological. It means that there is no
more evident knowledge than that which the soul has of itself,
since there is none which it is more impossible to doubt; that
the body, on the contrary, is known only representatively, and
that, far from our being unable to doubt its existence, we
cannot overcome such a doubt, when once raised, save by
means of laborious and complicated reasonings.
In order to make all this clearer still, let us remember Des-
cartes's oft-repeated caution to "cast off all the impressions of
the senses and imagination and trust to reason alone." There
are not two kinds of evidence : one which tells us that the
sun shines, that honey is sweet, that lead is heavy; and an-
other which informs us that if equals be added to equals the
sums are equal. Only the latter proposition is self-evident; the
former statements, in spite of any prepossession to the con-
trary, are not so. The impressions of the senses are vivid,
but confused; we cannot account for them, and nothing can
warrant them to be true. The water which is warm to me
seems cold to you. Cold and heat, as well as all other qualities
pertaining to bodies, with the exception of extension, are not
inherent in them; they are relative to the sentient subject.
Therefore, if we think we know bodies by what our senses
teach us of them, we fall into error, as will happen every
time when, through overhastiness or prejudice, we form a
judgment before the evidence is complete. For can I not
have in a dream all the perceptions I now have and be as
firmly persuaded of their reality? But whether I am dreaming
or waking it is true that two and two are four, and it is true
that I, who think so, am in existence.
Thus, previous to philosophical reflection, nothing seems to
us so well known as the body and its qualities, because we
form images of them continually and without any difficulty;
whereas it is not easy for us to realize what the soul is, seeing
that it is not an object for the imagination to grasp. The
first task of the philosopher consists precisely in disengaging
himself from the false light of the senses and seeking the true
light of reason. It is an effort akin to the one demanded by
Plato, when he termed philosophy the science of the invisible,
and recommended the study of mathematics as a preparatory
xxii ESSAY ON DESCARTES.
training. The body and the organs of the senses, far from
making us acquainted with what really is, are a hindrance
to the proper activity of the mind. Even matter, which we
fancy our hands, eyes, ears, etc., can apprehend immediately,
we really know only by means of our understanding. For
the latter alone can give us a distinct notion of it, viz., the
notion of a thing measurable in length, breadth and depth.
The other qualities of bodies are not really inherent in them.
"Look at this piece of wax; it has just been taken from the
hive ; it has not yet lost the sweetness of the honey it con-
tained; it still retains something of the fragrance of the flow-
ers from which it was gathered; its color, figure and size are
apparent; it is hard, cold, easily handled, and if you strike it
will give forth some sound. * * * But now, while I am
speaking, somebody brings it near the fire; whatever taste
remained in it is exhaled, the odor evaporates, its color
changes, its shape is lost, its size increases, it becomes liquid,
it is warmer, one can hardly handle it, and when we strike it,
it will no longer give forth a sound." And yet the same wax
is there. Therefore this wax was neither the honey-sweet
flavor, nor the pleasant flowery smell, nor the whiteness, nor
the form, nor the sound, but merely a body which, a short
time before, was apparent to my senses under these forms,
but now presents itself under other forms. Therefore all I
can conceive clearly and distinctly about this body is its ex-
tension.
Descartes's definition of the soul is "a thing that thinks" ;
of the body, "a thing that has extension." This doctrine is
strangely at variance with the metaphysics taught in his time.
The scholastic philosophers, who on this point followed the
teaching of Aristotle, regarded the soul as both the principle
of life and the principle of thought. The same soul which in
plants is purely nutritive, becomes locomotive, then sensitive
in animals, and lastly, in man, rational. And though such a
doctrine made the immortality of the soul a difficult thing to
conceive, it was no cause of embarrassment to the schoolmen,
for immortality to them was an object of faith, not of dem-
onstration. There is neither a nutritive nor a locomotive soul,
says Descartes. There is but one kind of soul, which is the
ESSAY ON DESCARTES. xxiii
thinking soul, for feeling is thinking. Nutrition and locomo-
tion are explainable simply by the laws of mechanics. Ani-
mals, which do not think, do not feel either. They may be
looked upon as automatons, and the perfection of some of
their actions may be compared to the perfection of the work-
ings of a clock. After this we can no longer suppose that
the destiny of man after death is the same as that of flies
and ants.
Scholastic physics likewise assumed the existence of forces
and occult causes inherent in matter, and thought the specific
nature of certain natural phenomena could not otherwise be
accounted for. Here again Descartes adopts the reverse of
their doctrine, rejecting in toto these assumed principles,
forces and causes, which to him are but confused notions,
hypotheses convenient to sluggish minds, explanations which
explain nothing, but merely repeat the enunciation of the
problem under another form. Given matter, that is, extension
as considered by geometricians, he wants no other data than
number, motion and duration. These are sufficient, he con-
siders, to account for all the phenomena which take place in
bodies either inorganic or living.
Thus Descartes's physical science is purely rational in char-
acter and in scrupulous accordance with the rule of his
method which forbids him to "accept anything as true unless
it appears by evidence to be so." It tends to assume a geo-
metrical form, and all questions of physics are reduced, at
least in principle, to problems of mechanics. "Give me matter
and the laws of motion," says Descartes, "and I will build a
universe exactly like the one that we behold, with skies, stars,
sun and earth, and on the earth minerals, plants and animals ;
in short, everything that experience introduces to us, except
the rational soul of man."
No doubt Descartes imagined all natural phenomena, and
in particular those of animated beings, to be less complicated
than they really are. His conceptions are those of a great
mathematician, living at a time when physics and chemistry
hardly existed and when biology did not exist at all. He
thinks he can determine a priori the number of the fixed stars.
He imagines he can describe accurately the formation of the
xxiv ESSAY ON DESCARTES.
foetus. He hopes, by taking due care of the human machine
and by repairing it when necessary, to protract the life of
man indefinitely, to conquer disease and even death. Scientific
men in our days are better acquainted with the difficulties of
such problems and are consequently less pretentious. But the
scientific ideal they aim at, though indefinitely removed from
that which we are considering, has remained pretty much the
same as Descartes conceived it : to discover the laws of every
phenomenon by reducing them, as far as possible, to number
and measure, and to discard every metaphysical hypothesis
meant to explain any class of physical phenomena.
This geometrical conception of the material universe was
repeatedly attacked by the successors of Descartes. Leibniz
endeavored to prove that the Cartesian definition of matter
was incompatible with the laws of motion. Leibniz is fond
of connecting Democritus and Descartes, and is wont to quote
them together. The parallel is an ingenious one, but should
not be followed up too closely. No doubt Descartes, like
Democritus, requires only matter and motion in order to
explain the genesis of the physical universe. But, to say
nothing of the very considerable differences between the ex-
planation of Democritus and that of Descartes, can anyone
forget that the physical science of Democritus and his meta-
physics are all one and the same thing? Atoms and vacuum
are to him the primal elements of all things, and, as was
objected to him by Aristotle, he does not take the trouble
even to explain the origin of motion. With Descartes, before
physics is begun a complete metaphysical system has first been
established, and it is from this that physics is to derive its
principles : the primordial laws of phenomena (for instance,
that light propagates itself in straight lines) are deduced from
God's attributes. Moreover, Descartes is not compelled by
his system, as Democritus is, to deny the existence of final
causes. On the contrary, he maintains their existence. It is
true that he forbids us to seek them out, but the reason is
that, according to him, it would be highly presumptuous in us
mortals to try to comprehend God's designs; the more so as
God's liberty is absolute and infinite, and since, in consequence,
His acts may be wholly unintelligible to our reason. And
ESSAY ON DESCARTES. xxv
lastly, far from looking upon matter as self-existent, Descartes
believes that bodies, as well as all other finite things, exist only
by God's express will and constant help. Should this help
cease for an instant all bodies would at once sink back into
nothingness.
The mechanical character of Descartes's system, if mechan-
ical it be, is therefore far removed from the materialism of
Democritus. Descartes firmly maintained the reality of free-
will, to which he ascribes an essential part in his theory of
judgment and of error. It is only as physicist, not as philoso-
pher, that Descartes may be termed mechanical. But in this
sense nearly all men of science are so, too ; for, to use F. A.
Lange's striking expression : "Mechanism is an excellent
formula for the science of nature."
But is not, however, the strictly deductive science con-
ceived by Descartes very remote from the modern science of
nature, which employs the experimental method with so much
zeal and success? True, Descartes often thought deduction
easy when it was difficult, and possible when it was imprac-
ticable. But this was a question of fact, not of principle. As
this or that branch of science (at least, of physical science)
is gradually brought nearer to perfection, we see it grow from
the experimental into the rational. Such has long been the
case with astronomy and celestial mechanics, and later, suc-
cessively with optics, with acoustics, with hydrodynamics, with
the theory of heat and electricity and other fields of physics,
all so many confirmations of the Cartesian ideal.
Moreover, Descartes himself assigned an important rôle to
the experimental method. Anecdotes depict him to us as ris-
ing very early, in Amsterdam, in order to choose in a butcher's
shop the joints he wished "to anatomize at leisure"; or an-
swering an inquirer who wished to see his library, "Here it
is," at the same time pointing to a quarter of veal which
he was busily dissecting. In the last years of his life he de-
voted only a few hours a year to mathematics, and not much
more to metaphysics. He busied himself almost exclusively
with experiments in physics and physiology. How could he
have failed to appreciate the importance of a method which
he was himself so assiduously putting into practice?
xxvi ESSAY ON DESCARTES.
"Anticipating causes with effects," is Descartes's felicitous
definition of experimenting. It clearly shows the functions he
ascribed to it. Were there only one way in which a certain
effect might be deduced from given causes, experimenting
would be unnecessary. But natural phenomena are so com-
plex, and the possible combinations of causes are so numer-
ous, that we may nearly always explain in several ways the
production of a given effect. Which is the right way? Ex-
periment alone can decide. Let us make a distinction between
science already developed and science which is developing.
To expound a developed science the suitable method is de-
duction, — descent from causes to effects. But science which
is developing cannot yet adopt this method; and to discover
unknown laws, it must employ the experimental method, must
anticipate causes with effects.
Descartes had written a Traite du Monde and was about to
publish it, when the condemnation of Galileo for heresies
concerning the motion of the earth altered his resolution.
Being, above all, desirous to work in peace, and to postpone
as long as he could a perhaps inevitable conflict with the
theologians, he published only a few fragments of his physical
theories, and put a summary sketch of it into the admirable
fifth part of the Discours de la Méthode. We must certainly
deplore the loss of this great work, which would throw light
upon many an obscure point in the Cartesian philosophy. But,
after all, the essential part of the doctrine did not lie here,
any more than in the well-known hypothesis of "vortices,"
which the Cartesian philosophers of the eighteenth century
vainly tried to set up in opposition to the principle of universal
gravitation discovered by Newton, and with which some
physicists now partly agree in their theories of matter.
The main interest lies elsewhere, viz., in the perfect charac-
ter of the science of nature, of which Descartes had such a
clear and precise notion, even though he was far from being
able to put it into practice save in a few points (for instance,
by his discoveries in optics). It is said that the man who in-
vented the plough still walks, invisible, beside the peasant
who drives his own plough in our days. I might almost say
that, in our laboratories, Descartes stands invisible and près-
ESSAY ON DESCARTES. xxvii
ent, investigating with our scientific men the laws of phe-
nomena.
If he had lived, would he have passed on from the sciences of
life to the ethical and social sciences, as he had done already
from mathematics to physics, and from physics to anatomy
and physiology? This may be doubted. To say nothing of
considerations of prudence, to which Descartes was most sus-
ceptible, he held in slight esteem the visionaries and political
reformers of the sixteenth century, and would have been
sorely vexed if any comparison had been drawn between
their fancies and his own doctrines. On the other hand, he
could not but find it extremely difficult to make social facts
fall in with his method, since, as Auguste Comte very aptly
observed, so long as biology is not sufficiently advanced, social
science must needs be out of the question. Now, in the time
of Descartes, biology was still unborn. Even ethics he does
not seem to have taken into deep consideration. He borrows
the rules of his provisional ethics from Montaigne and from
the Stoics. Stoicism, modified in some respects, also forms
the fundamental part of Descartes's moral letters to Princess
Elizabeth. It is a peculiarity of French philosophy, that it has
produced many moralists and few moral theorists. The rea-
son for this we shall seek elsewhere. Certain it is that Des-
cartes was not one of these theorists. Perhaps he believed
that scientific ethics (ethics not grounded on religious author-
ity) could not be established till the science of man was estab-
lished, and the connection of the physical and the moral better
known. To this knowledge he opened the way in his Traite
des Passions de l'Ame.
All the precautions taken by Descartes, all his prudence, did
not shield him from the attacks his philosophy was to bring
upon him, as being "subtle, enticing, and bold." After hes-
itating a long while, the Jesuits, by whom he had been
brought up at La Flèche, and among whom he had still some
friends, declared themselves against his philosophy. The sev-
enth series of Objections, by Father Bourdin, express the
opinion of this society. Descartes wrote a vigorous reply.
His quarrel with the Jesuits was one of his motives for not
living in France. He established himself in Holland, where
xxviii ESSAY ON DESCARTES.
he lived a long while in undisturbed peace. But as his philos-
ophy spread, attention was drawn to him, and as the univer-
sities of the country were beginning to quarrel about his
theories, he felt that his life there would soon become unbear-
able. He therefore resolved to yield to the entreaties of
Queen Christina, who earnestly urged him to come to Sweden.
But he could not endure the severe climate of that country,
and hardly six months had elapsed when he died of inflam-
mation of the lungs. Later, his body was brought back to
France.
The philosophy of Descartes was in accord with the lead-
ing tendencies of his time. The success which attended it
from the moment it appeared is a proof of its opportune-
ness, and it is difficult to determine whether it formed, rather
than expressed, the spirit of the age. Doubtless it did both.
As has been said, the seventeenth century in France was pre-
eminently the "age of reason."
Aimez donc la raison ; que toujours vos écrits,
Empruntent d'elle seule et leur lustre et leur prix,
said Boileau ; yet perhaps, had it not been for the Cartesian
philosophy, this taste for reason might not have asserted itself
so earnestly and have been so perfectly conscious of its exist-
ence.
This philosophy of "clear ideas" prevailed in France in the
second half of the seventeenth century, and from France its
influence spread over all Europe. Though vigorously attacked
in the eighteenth century, both as to its metaphysics and its
physics, it nevertheless remained discernible even in the meth-
ods of its adversaries. Locke, Hume, and Condillac had not
the same conception of evidence as Descartes ; but their empir-
icism was as fond of clearness as his rationalism had been.
Newton combated the hypothesis of "vortices," but he pre-
served the Cartesian notion of a mechanical explanation of
physical phenomena. For a thorough-going and express ne-
gation of the Cartesian spirit we must go to the end of the
eighteenth century. Then the German romantic writers spring
up, and maintain that the philosophy of clear ideas is false
from its very principle. According to them, reality is not
clear, and the more satisfactory a doctrine is to the human
ESSAY ON DESCARTES. xxix
understanding, the surer it is to reproduce only the surface of
things, while the essence of them is mysterious, intangible
and inexpressible. Whence it follows that religions, arts and
literatures are spontaneous philosophies, incomparably deeper
than the systems produced by the conscious labor of the un-
derstanding, even as the works of nature are artistically
superior to the articles manufactured by man.
The philosophy of Descartes, to tell the truth, affords but
little scope to sentiment, and still less to the imagination and
to the hidden and unconscious activities of the mind. It places
value on evidence alone, whose vivid, but glaring light, dispels
the chiaroscuro so dear to romantic writers. This fixed and
rigid purpose has its drawbacks, which were not long in mak-
ing their appearance among the followers of Descartes.
But apart from the fact that in Descartes himself the
rational effort was uncommonly sincere and vigorous, at the
time when this philosophy appeared it was really necessary.
It was a deliverer. It put an end to superannuated doctrines,
the domination of which was still heavily felt. It cleared
the ground, and set physics free, once for all, from the clogs
of metaphysical hypotheses. Lastly, it formulated problems
which needed formulation. Descartes wished to furnish
science not only with a powerful and flexible instrument such
as Bacon had already sought, but also with an unchanging
and immovable basis. Thence sprang the "provisional
doubt," with which his method bids him begin, which obliges
him to test all previously acquired information, and which
may be looked upon as the starting-point of all modern
theories of knowledge. For this doubt, which affects suc-
cessively perception, imagination, reasoning power, and stops
only before the immediate self-intuition of thought, is itself a
criticism of the faculty of knowledge. It studies it in its con-
nection both with the outward object and with the very mind
which is thinking ; in short, it heralds Kant's Critique of Pure
Reason.
An innovating and fruitful doctrine nearly always develops
in various directions. The various minds that receive it
gradually draw from it diverse and sometimes contradictory
conclusions, most of which were overlooked and would often
have been disapproved of by the founder of the system. This
xxx ESSAY ON DESCARTES.
is perhaps even truer of Descartes than of any other philoso-
pher. Being chiefly preoccupied with the method and struc-
ture of science, he did not hesitate to leave open, at least
temporarily, many important questions which his method did
not require him to solve immediately. Thus it happened that
metaphysical systems very different from one another were
soon founded on the Cartesian principles. Spinoza adopted
the definition which Descartes had given of soul and matter,
but in thought and extension he saw only two attributes of one
and the same substance. Beside this pantheism, appeared the
idealism of Malebranche, which proceeds no less directly from
Descartes; for did not the latter say that "truth is the same
thing as being?" And does not the theory of continued crea-
tion lead directly to that of occasional causes? Locke, who
combated Descartes on the subject of innate ideas, without
understanding him exactly, has on the other hand many points
in common with him ; the very idea of inventorying and exam-
ining the ideas in our minds is singularly akin to the critical
examination of our knowledge which, in Descartes, precedes
the cogito. And lastly, into the idealism of Leibniz the Car-
tesian element enters in large measure; for instance, the
notion of sensation being but a dim intellection, which is the
central point of Leibniz's theory of knowledge, had already
been clearly stated by Descartes.
The philosophy of Descartes is therefore a sort of cross-
road whence diverge the chief ways followed by modern
thought. Still, outside of France, his method has not been
followed without restrictions, and his philosophy has been
accepted only to be immediately combined with other elements
either traditional or modern. In France, the influence has
been far deeper and more enduring. There, while the Car-
tesian philosophy may have lost its prestige rather quickly, the
Cartesian spirit, owing, doubtless, to its close affinity with the
very genius of the nation, has never disappeared, and we
shall recognize its influence, not only throughout the whole
eighteenth century and in the French Revolution, but in all
the greatest thinkers of the nineteenth century.
CONTENTS,
PAGE
Publishers' Preface iii
Essay on the Philosophy of Descartes by Prof. L. Levy-
Bruhl vii
Title-pages of the original editions xxxi
L— THE MEDITATIONS.
Dedication i
Preface 9
Synopsis of the Meditations 15
Meditation I.
Of the Things of which we may Doubt 21
Meditation II.
Of the Nature of the Human Mind ; and that it is more
easily known than the Body 29
Meditation III.
Of God ; that he exists 42
Meditation IV.
Of Truth and Error 63
Meditation V.
Of the Essence of Material Things ; and, again, of God :
that he exists 75
Meditation VI.
Of the Existence of Material Things, and of the Real
Distinction between the Mind and Body of Man 84
CONTENTS.
IL— THE PRINCIPLES OF PHILOSOPHY.
PAGE
Preface 107
Dedication 126
Part I.
Of the Principles of Human Knowledge 130
Part II.
Of the Principles of Material Things. Sects, i. to xxv. . 175
Part III.
Of the Visible World. Sects, i. to iii. — 192
Part IV.
Of the Earth. Sects, clxxxviii. to ccvii 194
Appendix 215
Notes 224
Bibliography 249
THE MEDITATIONS
N>F
DESCARTES
TRANSLATED FROM THE LATIN AND COL-
LATED WITH THE FRENCH.
Renati Des-Cartes Mitaines
de Frima Fhilosopbia
In qua del existentia et animœ
immortalitas iemonstratur.
PARISIIS
Apud Michaelem Soly, via Jacobeâ, sub signo Phœnicis.
MDCXLI.
Cum Privilegio et Approbatione Doctorum.
Vignette: a phoenix with the inscription, „Aeternitatl soli".
Benati Dès-Cartes leditationes
In quibus Dei existentia, & animœ humanœ
a corpore distinctio demonstratur.
His adjunctsesunt varise objectiones doctorum virorum
in istas de Deo & anima demons trationes.
Cum responsionibus AuthorU.
Secunda editio septimis objectionibus antehac non
visis aucta.
AMSTELODAMI,
Apud IyUdovicum Elzevirium, 1642.
Vignette: Minerva beneath an olive tree: „Ne extra oleas".
LES
Meditations Métaphysiques
de René Des=Cartes
TOUCHANT LA PREMIERE PHILOSOPHIE
dans lesquelles l'existence de Dieu, & la distinction
réelle entre l'âme & le corps de l'homme,
sont demonstrées.
Traduites du Latin de V Auteur par
M. le D. D. L. N. 8.
Et les objections faites contre ces Méditations par
diverses personnes tres-doctes, avec les réponses
de l'Auteur.
Traduites par Mr, C. L. B.
A PARIS.
Chez la Veuve Jean Camusat,
ET
Pierre le Petit, rue S. Jacques,
à la Toyson d'Or.
M. DC. XL. VII.
AVEC PRIVILEGE DU ROY.
Vignette: Jason with the golden fleece and the dragon: „Tegltet quo»
""■ naurat".
TO
THE VERY SAGE AND ILLUSTRIOUS
THE
DEAN AND DOCTORS OF THE SACRED
FACULTY OF THEOLOGY OF PARIS.
Gentlemen,
The motive which impels me to present this Treatise
to you is so reasonable, and, when you shall learn its
design, I am confident that you also will consider that
there is ground so valid for your taking it under your
protection, that I can in no way better recommend it
to you than by briefly stating the end which I pro-
posed to myself in it. I have always been of opinion
that the two questions respecting God and the Soul
were the chief of those that ought to be determined
by help of Philosophy rather than of Theology; for
although to us, the faithful, it be sufficient to hold as
matters of faith, that the human soul does not perish
with the body, and that God exists, it yet assuredly
seems impossible ever to persuade infidels of the real-
ity of any religion, or almost even any moral virtue,
unless, first of all, those two things be proved to them
by natural reason. And since in this life there are
frequently greater rewards held out to vice than to
virtue, few would prefer the right to the useful, if they
were restrained neither by the fear of God nor the ex-
2 DEDICATION.
pectation of another life ; and although it is quite true
that the existence of God is to be believed since it is
taught in the sacred Scriptures, and that, on the other
hand, the sacred Scriptures are to be believed because
they come from God (for since faith is a gift of God,
the same Being who bestows grace to enable us to be-
lieve other things, can likewise impart of it to enable
us to believe his own existence), nevertheless, this
cannot be submitted to infidels, who would consider
that the reasoning proceeded in a circle. And, indeed,
I have observed that you, with all the other theolo-
gians, not only affirmed the sufficiency of natural rea-
son for the proof of the existence of God, but also,
that it may be inferred from sacred Scripture, that the
knowledge of God is much clearer than of many
created things, and that it is really so easy of acquisi-
tion as to leave those who do not possess it blame-
worthy. This is manifest from these words of the
Book of Wisdom, chap, xiii., where it is said, Howbeit
they are not to be excused; for if their understanding
was so great that they could discern the zvorld and the
creatures, why did they not rather find out the Lord
thereof ? And in Romans, chap, i., it is said that they
are zvithout excuse; and again, in the same place, by
these words, — That which may be known of God is
manifest in them — we seem to be admonished that all
which can be known of God may be made manifest by
reasons obtained from no other source than the in-
spection of our own minds. I have, therefore, thought
that it would not be unbecoming in me to inquire how
and by what way, without going out of ourselves, God
may be more easily and certainly known than the
things of the world.
DEDICATION. 3
And as regards the Soul, although many have
judged that its nature could not be easily discovered,
and some have even ventured to say that human rea-
son led to the conclusion that it perished with the
body, and that the contrary opinion could be held
through faith alone; nevertheless, since the Lateran
Council, held under Leo X. (in session viii.), con-
demns these, and expressly enjoins Christian philoso-
phers to refute their arguments, and establish the
truth according to their ability, I have ventured to at-
tempt it in this work. Moreover, I am aware that
most of the irreligious deny the existence of God, and
the distinctness of the human soul from the body, for
no other reason than because these points, as they al-
lege, have never as yet been demonstrated. Now, al-
though I am by no means of their opinion, but, on the
contrary, hold that almost all the proofs which have
been adduced on these questions by great men, pos-
sess, when rightly understood, the force of demonstra-
tions, and that it is next to impossible to discover new,
yet there is, I apprehend, no more useful service to be
performed in Philosophy, than if some one were, once
for all, carefully to seek out the best of these reasons,
and expound them so accurately and clearly that, for
the future, it might be manifest to all that they are
real demonstrations. And finally, since many persons
were greatly desirous of this, who knew that I had
cultivated a certain Method of resolving all kinds of
difficulties in the sciences, which is not indeed new
(there being nothing older than truth), but of which
they were aware I had made successful use in other
instances, I judged it to be my duty to make trial of it
also on the present matter.
4 DEDICATION.
Now the sum of what I have been able to accom-
plish on the subject is contained in this treatise. Not
that I here essayed to collect all the diverse reasons
which might be adduced as proofs on this subject, for
this does not seem to be necessary, unless on matters
where no one proof of adequate certainty is to be had ;
but I treated the first and chief alone in such a man-
ner that I should venture now to propose them as
demonstrations of the highest certainty and evidence.
And I will also add that they are such as to lead me to
think that there is no way open to the mind of man by
which proofs superior to them can ever be discovered ;
for the importance of the subject, and the glory of
God, to which all this relates, constrain me to speak
here somewhat more freely of myself than I have been
accustomed to do. Nevertheless, whatever certitude
and evidence I may find in these demonstrations, I
cannot therefore persuade myself that they are level
to the comprehension of all. But just as in geometry
there are many of the demonstrations of Archimedes,
Apollonius, Pappus, and others, which, though re-
ceived by all as highly evident and certain (because in-
deed they manifestly contain nothing which, consid-
ered by itself, it is not very easy to understand, and
no consequents that are inaccurately related to their
antecedents), are nevertheless understood by a very
limited number, because they are somewhat long, and
demand the whole attention of the reader: so in the
same way, although I consider the demonstrations of
which I here make use, to be equal or even superior
to the geometrical in certitude and evidence, I am
afraid, nevertheless, that they will not be adequately
understood by many, as well because they also are
DEDICATION. 5
somewhat long and involved, as chiefly because they
require the mind to be entirely free from prejudice,
and able with ease to detach itself from the commerce
of the senses. And, to speak the truth, the ability for
metaphysical studies is less general than for those of
geometry. And, besides, there is still this difference
that, as in geometry, all are persuaded that nothing is
usually advanced of which there is not a certain dem-
onstration, those but partially versed in it err more
frequently in assenting to what is false, from a desire
of seeming to understand it, than in denying what is
true. In philosophy, on the other hand, where it is
believed that all is doubtful, few sincerely give them-
selves to the search after truth, and by far the greater
number seek the reputation of bold thinkers by auda-
ciously impugning such truths as are of the greatest
moment.
Hence it is that, whatever force my reasonings may
possess, yet because they belong to philosophy, I do
not expect they will have much effect on the minds of
men, unless you extend to them your patronage and
approval. But since your Faculty is held in so great
esteem by all, and since the name of Sorbonne is of
such authority, that not only in matters of faith, but
even also in what regards human philosophy, has the
judgment of no other society, after the Sacred Coun-
cils, received so great deference, it being the universal
conviction that it is impossible elsewhere to find greater
perspicacity and solidity, or greater wisdom and in-
tegrity in giving judgment, I doubt not, — if you but
condescend to pay so much regard to this Treatise as
to be willing, in the first place, to correct it (for, mind-
6 DEDICATION.
fui not only of my humanity, but chiefly also of my
ignorance, I do not affirm that it is free from errors) ;
in the second place, to supply what is wanting in it, to
perfect what is incomplete, and to give more ample il-
lustration where it is demanded, or at least to indicate
these defects to myself that I may endeavour to rem-
edy them; and, finally, when the reasonings contained
in it, by which the existence of God and the distinction
of the human soul from the body are established, shall
have been brought to such degree of perspicuity as to
be esteemed exact demonstrations, of which I am as-
sured they admit, if you condescend to accord them
the authority of your approbation, and render a pub-
lic testimony of their truth and certainty, — I doubt
not, I say, but that henceforward all the errors which
have ever been entertained on these questions will
very soon be effaced from the minds of men. For
truth itself will readily lead the remainder of the in-
genious and the learned to subscribe to your judg-
ment; and your authority will cause the atheists, who
are in general sciolists rather than ingenious or
learned, to lay aside the spirit of contradiction, and
lead them, perhaps, to do battle in their own persons
for reasonings which they find considered demonstra-
tions by all men of genius, lest they should seem not
to understand them ; and, finally, the rest of mankind
will readily trust to so many testimonies, and there
will no longer be any one who will venture to doubt
either the existence of God or the real distinction of
mind and body. It is for you, in your singular wis-
dom, to judge of the importance of the establishment
of such beliefs, [who are cognisant of the disorders
DEDICATION. 7
which doubt of these truths produces] .* But it would
not here become me to commend at greater length the
cause of God and of religion to you, who have always
proved the strongest support of the Catholic Church.
* The square brackets, here and throughout the volume, are
used to mark additions to the original of the revised French
translation.
PREFACE TO THE READER.
1 have already slightly touched upon the questions re-
specting the existence of God and the nature of the
human soul, in the "Discourse on the Method of
rightly conducting the Reason, and seeking truth in
the Sciences," published in French in the year 1637;
not, however, with the design of there treating of
them fully, but only, as it were, in passing, that I
might learn from the judgments of my readers in
what way I should afterwards handle them : for these
questions appeared to me to be of such moment as to
be worthy of being considered more than once, and
the path which I follow in discussing them is so little
trodden, and so remote from the ordinary route, that
I thought it would not be expedient to illustrate it at
greater length in French, and in a discourse that might
be read by all, lest even the more feeble minds should
believe that this path might be entered upon by them.
But, as in the Discourse on Method, I had requested
all who might find aught meriting censure in my writ-
ings, to do me the favour of pointing it out to me, I
may state that no objections worthy of remark have
been alleged against what I then said on these ques-
tions, except two, to which I will here briefly reply,
before undertaking their more detailed discussion.
The first objection is that though, while the hu-
9
io PREFACE TO THE READER.
man mind reflects on itself, it does not perceive 1 * that
it is any other than a thinking thing, it does not follow
that its nature or essence consists only in its being
a thing which thinks ; so that the word only shall ex-
clude all other things which might also perhaps be
said to pertain to the nature of the mind.
To this objection I reply, that it was not my inten-
tion in that place to exclude these according to the
order of truth in the matter (of which I did not then
treat), but only according to the order of thought
(perception) ; so that my meaning was, that I clearly
apprehended nothing, so far as I was conscious, as be-
longing to my essence, except that I was a thinking
thing, or a thing possessing in itself the faculty of
thinking. But I will show hereafter how, from the
consciousness that nothing besides thinking belongs to
the essence of the mind, it follows that nothing else
does in truth belong to it.
The second objection is that it does not follow, from
my possessing the idea of a thing more perfect than I
am, that the idea itself is more perfect than myself,
and much less that what is represented by the idea
exists.
But I reply that in the term idea 2 there is here some-
thing equivocal ; for it may be taken either materially
for an act of the understanding, and in this sense it
cannot be said to be more perfect than I, or objec-
tively, for the thing represented by that act, which,
although it be not supposed to exist out of my under-
standing, may, nevertheless, be more perfect than my-
*The superior numerals in the text refer to the Notes at the
end of this volume, where will be found some notices of the
various terms that appeared to require comment.
PREFACE TO THE READER. n
self, by reason of its essence. But, in the sequel of
this treatise I will show more amply how, from my
possessing the idea of a thing more perfect than my-
self, it follows that this thing really exists.
Besides these two objections, I have seen, indeed,
two treatises of sufficient length relating to the present
matter. In these, however, my conclusions, much
more than my premises, were impugned, and that by
arguments borrowed from the commonplaces of the
atheists. But, as arguments of this sort can make no
impression on the minds of those who shall rightly
understand my reasonings, and as the judgments of
many are so irrational and weak that they are per-
suaded rather by the opinions on a subject that are
first presented to them, however false and opposed to
reason they may be, than by a true and solid, but sub-
sequently received, refutation of them, I am unwilling
here to reply to these strictures from a dread of being,
in the first instance, obliged to state them.
I will only say, in general, that all which the athe-
ists commonly allege in favour of the non-existence of
God, arises continually from one or other of these two
things, namely, either the ascription of human affec-
tions to Deity, or the undue attribution to our minds
of so much vigour and wisdom that we may essay to
determine and comprehend both what God can and
ought to do ; hence all that is alleged by them will oc-
casion us no difficulty, provided only we keep in re-
membrance that our minds must be considered finite,
while Deity is incomprehensible and infinite.
Now that I have once, in some measure, made proof
of the opinions of men regarding my work, I again
undertake to treat of God and the human soul, and at
12 PREFACE TO THE READER.
the same time to discuss the principles of the entire
First Philosophy, without, however, expecting any
commendation from the crowd for my endeavours, or
a wide circle of readers. On the contrary, I would
advise none to read this work, unless such as are able
and willing to meditate with me in earnest, to detach
their minds from commerce with the senses, and like-
wise to deliver themselves from all prejudice ; and in-
dividuals of this character are, I well know, remark-
ably rare. But with regard to those who, without
caring to comprehend the order and connection of the
reasonings, shall study only detached clauses for the
purpose of small but noisy criticism, as is the custom
with many, I may say that such persons will not profit
greatly by the reading of this treatise ; and although
perhaps they may find opportunity for cavilling in
several places, they will yet hardly start any pressing
objections, or such as shall be deserving of reply.
But since, indeed, I do not promise to satisfy others
on all these subjects at first sight, nor arrogate so
much to myself as to believe that I have been able to
foresee all that may be the source of difficulty to each
one, I shall expound, first of all, in the Meditations,
those considerations by which I feel persuaded that I
have arrived at a certain and evident knowledge of
truth, in order that I may ascertain whether the rea-
sonings which have prevailed with myself will also be
effectual in convincing others. I will then reply to the
objections of some men, illustrious for their genius and
learning, to whom these Meditations were sent for
criticism before they were committed to the press ; for
these objections are so numerous and varied that I
PREFACE TO THE READER. 13
venture to anticipate that nothing, at least nothing of
any moment, will readily occur to any mind which has
not been touched upon in them.
Hence it is that I earnestly entreat my readers not
to come to any judgment on the questions raised in
the Meditations until they have taken care to read the
whole of the Objections, with the relative Replies.
SYNOPSIS OF THE SIX FOLLOWING
MEDITATIONS.
In the First Meditation I expound the grounds on
which we may doubt in general of all things, and es-
pecially of material objects, so long, at least, as we
have no other foundations for the sciences than those
we have hitherto possessed. Now, although the util-
ity of a doubt so general may not be manifest at first
sight, it is nevertheless of the greatest, since it delivers
us from all prejudice, and affords the easiest pathway
by which the mind may withdraw itself from the
senses; and, finally, makes it impossible for us to
doubt wherever we afterwards discover truth.
In the Second, the mind which, in the exercise of
the freedom peculiar to itself, supposes that no object
is, of the existence of which it has even the slightest
doubt, finds that, meanwhile, it must itself exist. And
this point is likewise of the highest moment, for the
mind is thus enabled easily to distinguish what per-
tains to itself, that is, to the intellectual nature, from
what is to be referred to the body. But since some,
perhaps, will expect, at this stage of our progress,, a
statement of the reasons which establish the doctrine
of the immortality of the soul, I think it proper here
to make such aware, that it was my aim to write noth-
ing of which I could not give exact demonstration, and
that I therefore felt myself obliged to adopt an order
similar to that in use among the geometers, viz., to
15
ï6 SYNOPSIS OF THE
premise all upon which the proposition in question de-
pends, before coming to any conclusion respecting it.
Now, the first and chief pre-requisite for the knowl-
edge of the immortality of the soul is our being able
to form the clearest possible conception (conceptus —
concept) of the soul itself, and such as shall be abso-
lutely distinct from all our notions of body; and how
this is to be accomplished is there shown. There is
required, besides this, the assurance that all objects
which we clearly and distinctly think are true (really
exist) in that very mode in which we think them ; and
this could not be established previously to the Fourth
Meditation. Farther, it is necessary, for the same
purpose, that we possess a distinct conception of cor-
poreal nature, which is given partly in the Second and
partly in the Fifth and Sixth Meditations. And,
finally, on these grounds, we are necessitated to con-
clude, that all those objects which are clearly and dis-
tinctly conceived to be diverse substances, as mind and
body, are substances really reciprocally distinct; and
this inference is made in the Sixth Meditation. The
absolute distinction of mind and body is, besides, con-
firmed in this Second Meditation, by showing that we
cannot conceive body unless as divisible ; while, on the
other hand, mind cannot be conceived unless as indi-
visible. For we are not able to conceive the half of
a mind, as we can of any body, however small, so that
the natures of these two substances are to be held, not
only as diverse, but even in some measure as contra-
ries. I have not; however, pursued this discussion
further in the present treatise, as well for the reason
that these considerations are sufficient to show that the
destruction of the mind does not follow from the cor-
SIX FOLLOWING MEDITATIONS. 17
ruption of the body, and thus to afford to men the hope
of a future life, as also because the premises from
which it is competent for us to infer the immortality
of the soul, involve an explication of the whole prin-
ciples of Physics : in order to establish, in the first
place, that generally all substances, that is, all things
which can exist only in consequence of having been
created by God, are in their own nature incorruptible,
and can never cease to be, unless God himself, by re-
fusing his concurrence to them, reduce them to noth-
ing; and, in the second place, that body, taken gen-
erally, is a substance, and therefore can never perish,
but that the human body, in as far as it differs from
other bodies, is constituted only by a certain configura-
tion of members, and by other accidents of this sort,
while the human mind is not made up of accidents, but
is a pure substance. For although all the accidents of
the mind be changed — although, for example, it think
certain things, will others, and perceive others, the
mind itself does not vary with these changes ; while, on
the contrary, the human body is no longer the same if
a change take place in the form of any of its parts :
from which it follows that the body may, indeed, with-
out difficulty perish, but that the mind is in its own
nature immortal.
In the Third Meditation, I have unfolded at suffi-
cient length, as appears to me, my chief argument for
the existence of God. But yet, since I was there de-
sirous to avoid the use of comparisons taken from ma-
terial objects, that I might withdraw, as far as possi-
ble, the minds of my readers from the senses, numer-
ous obscurities perhaps remain, which, however, will,
I trust, be afterwards entirely removed in the Replies
i8 SYNOPSIS OF THE
to the Objections: thus, among other things, it may
be difficult to understand how the idea of a being abso-
lutely perfect, which is found in our minds, possesses
so much objective reality 3 [i. e., participates by repre-
sentation in so many degrees of being and perfection]
that it must be held to arise from a cause absolutely
perfect. This is illustrated in the Replies by the com-
parison of a highly perfect machine, the idea of which
exists in the mind of some workman; for as the objec-
tive (i. e., representative) perfection of this idea must
have some cause, viz., either the science of the work-
man, or of some other person from whom he has re-
ceived the idea, in the same way the idea of God,
which is found in us, demands God himself for its
cause.
In the Fourth, it is shown that all which we clearly
and distinctly perceive (apprehend) is true; and, at
the same time, is explained wherein consists the na-
ture of error; points that require to be known as well
for confirming the preceding truths, as for the better
understanding of those that are to follow. But, mean-
while, it must be observed, that I do not at all there
treat of Sin, that is, of error committed in the pursuit
of good and evil, but of that sort alone which arises in
the determination of the true and the false. Nor do I
refer to matters of faith, or to the conduct of life, but
only to what regards speculative truths, and such as
are known by means of the natural light alone.
In the Fifth, besides the illustration of corporeal na-
ture, taken generically, a new demonstration is given
of the existence of God, not free, perhaps, any more
than the former, from certain difficulties, but of these
the solution will be found in the Replies to the Objec-
SIX FOLLOWING MEDITATIONS. 19
tions. I further show, in what sense it is true that the.
certitude of geometrical demonstrations themselves is
dependent on the knowledge of God.
Finally, in the Sixth, the act of the understanding
(intellectio) is distinguished from that of the imagin-
ation (imaginatio) ; the marks of this distinction are
described ; the human mind is shown to be really dis-
tinct from the body, and, nevertheless, to be so closely
conjoined therewith, as together to form, as it were, a
unity. The whole of the errors which arise from the
senses are brought under review, while the means of
avoiding them are pointed out ; and, finally, all the
grounds are adduced from which the existence of ma-
terial objects may be inferred; not, however, because
I deemed them of great utility in establishing what
they prove, viz., that there is in reality a world, that
men are possessed of bodies, and the like, the truth of
which no one of sound mind ever seriously doubted;
but because, from a close consideration of them, it is
perceived that they are neither so strong nor clear as
the reasonings which conduct us to the knowledge of
our mind and of God ; so that the latter are, of all
which come under human knowledge, the most certain
and manifest — a conclusion which it was my single
aim in these Meditations to establish; on which" ac-
count I here omit mention of the various other ques-
tions which, in the course of the discussion, I had oc-
casion likewise to consider.
MEDITATIONS ON THE FIRST
PHILOSOPHY,
IN WHICH
THE EXISTENCE OF GOD, AND THE REAL DISTINCTION OF
MIND AND BODY, ARE DEMONSTRATED.
MEDITATION I.
OF THE THINGS OF WHICH WE MAY DOUBT.
Several years have now elapsed since I first became
aware that I had accepted, even from my youth, many
false opinions for true, and that consequently what I
afterwards based on such principles was highly doubt-
ful ; and from that time I was convinced of the neces-
sity of undertaking once in my life to rid myself of all
the opinions I had adopted, and of commencing anew
the work of building from the foundation, if I desired
to establish a firm and abiding superstructure in the
sciences. But as this enterprise appeared to me to be
one of great magnitude, I waited until I had attained
an age so mature as to leave me no hope that at any
stage of life more advanced I should be better able to
execute my design. On this account, I have delayed
so long that I should henceforth consider I was doing
wrong were I still to consume in deliberation any of
the time that now remains for action. To-day, then,
22 MEDITATION I.
since I have opportunely freed my mind from all
cares, [and am happily disturbed by no passions], and
since I am in the secure possession of leisure in a
peaceable retirement, I will at length apply myself
earnestly and freely to the general overthrow of all my
former opinions. But, to this end, it will not be neces-
sary for me to show that the whole of these are false
— a point, perhaps, which I shall never reach; but as
even now my reason convinces me that I ought not the
less carefully to withhold belief from what is not en-
tirely certain and indubitable, than from what is mani-
festly false, it will be sufficient to justify the rejection
of the whole if I shall find in each some ground for
doubt. Nor for this purpose will it be necessary even
to deal with each belief individually, which would be
truly an endless labour ; but, as the removal from be-
low of the foundation necessarily involves the down-
fall of the whole edifice, I will at once approach the
criticism of the principles on which all my former be-
liefs rested.
All that I have, up to this moment, accepted as pos-
sessed of the highest truth and certainty, I received
either from or through the senses. 4 I observed, how-
ever, that these sometimes misled us ; and it is the part
of prudence not to place absolute confidence in that by
which we have even once been deceived.
But it may be said, perhaps, that, although the
senses occasionally mislead us respecting minute ob-
jects, and such as are so far removed from us as to be
beyond the reach of close observation, there are yet
many other of their informations (presentations), of
the truth of which it is manifestly impossible to doubt ;
as for example, that I am in this place, seated by the
OF THE THINGS OF WHICH WE MAY DOUBT. 23
fire, clothed in a winter dressing-gown, that I hold in
my hands this piece of paper, with other intimations
of the same nature. But how could I deny that I pos-
sess these hands and this body, and withal escape be-
ing classed with persons in a state of insanity, whose
brains are so disordered and clouded by dark bilious
vapours as to cause them pertinaciously to assert that
they are monarchs when they are in the greatest pov-
erty; or clothed [in gold J and purple when destitute
of any covering; or that their head is made of clay,
their body of glass, or that they are gourds ? I should
certainly be not less insane than they, were I to regu-
late my procedure according to examples so extrava-
gant.
Though this be true, I must nevertheless here con-
sider that I am a man, and that, consequently, I am in
the habit of sleeping, and representing to myself in
dreams those same things, or even sometimes others
less probable, which the insane think are presented to
them in their waking moments. How often have I
dreamt that I was in these familiar circumstances, —
that I was dressed, and occupied this place by the fire,
when I was lying undressed in bed? At the present
moment, however, I certainly look upon this paper
with eyes wide awake; the head which I now move is
not asleep; I extend this hand consciously and with
express purpose, and I perceive it; the occurrences in
sleep are not so distinct as all this. But I cannot for-
get that, at other times, I have been deceived in sleep
by similar illusions ; and, attentively considering those
cases, I perceive so clearly that there exist no certain
marks by which the state of waking can ever be dis-
24 MEDITATION I.
tinguished from sleep, that I feel greatly astonished;
and in amazement I almost persuade myself that I am
now dreaming.
Let us suppose, then, that we are dreaming, and that
all these particulars — namely, the opening of the eyes,
the motion of the head, the forth-putting of the hands
— are merely illusions ; and even that we really possess
neither an entire body nor hands such as we see.
Nevertheless, it must be admitted at least that the ob-
jects which appear to us in sleep are, as it were,
painted representations which could not have been
formed unless in the likeness of realities; and, there-
fore, that those general objects, at all events, — namely,
eyes, a head, hands, and an entire body — are not sim-
ply imaginary, but really existent. For, in truth,
painters themselves, even when they study to represent
sirens and satyrs by forms the most fantastic and ex-
traordinary, cannot bestow upon them natures abso-
lutely new, but can only make a certain medley of the
members of different animals ; or if they chance to
imagine something so novel that nothing at" all similar
has ever been seen before, and such as is, therefore,
purely fictitious and absolutely false, it is at least cer-
tain that the colours of which this is composed are
real.
And on the same principle, although these general
objects, viz. [a body], eyes, a head, hands, and the
like, be imaginary, we are nevertheless absolutely
necessitated to admit the reality at least of some other
objects still more simple and universal than these, of
which, just as of certain real colours, all those images
OF THE THINGS OF WHICH WE MAY DOUBT, 25 #****
of things, whether true and real, or false and fantas-.. ' fji/c^f^"^
tic, that are found in our consciousness (cogitatio) 5 ^'^^^
are formed. ftta^Wr) ^
To this class of objects seem to belong corporeal na-
ture in general and its extension ; the figure of ex-
tended things, their quantity or magnitude, and their
number, as also the place in, and the time during,
which they exist, and other things of the same sort.
We will not, therefore, perhaps reason illegitimately
if we conclude from this that Physics, Astronomy,
Medicine, and all the other sciences that have for their
end the consideration of composite objects, are indeed
of a doubtful character; but that Arithmetic, Geome-
try, and the other sciences of the same class, which re-
gard merely the simplest and most general objects,
and scarcely inquire whether or not these are really
existent, contain somewhat that is certain and indubit-
able : for whether I am awake or dreaming, it remains
true that two and three make five, and that a square
has but four sides; nor does it seem possible that
truths so apparent can ever fall under a suspicion of
falsity [or incertitude].
Nevertheless, the belief that there is a God who is
all-powerful, and who created me, such as I am, has,
for a long time, obtained steady possession of my
mind. How, then, do I know that he has not ar-
ranged that there should be neither earth, nor sky, nor
any extended thing, nor figure, nor magnitude, nor
place, providing at the same time, however, for [the
rise in me of the perceptions of all these objects, and]
the persuasion that these do not exist otherwise than
as I perceive them? And further, as I sometimes
think that others are in error respecting matters of
26 MEDITATION I.
which they believe themselves to possess a perfect
knowledge, how do I know that I am not also deceived
each time I add together two and three, or number the
sides of a square, or form some judgment still more
simple, if more simple indeed can be imagined? But
perhaps Deity has not been willing that I should be
thus deceived, for He is said to be supremely good.
If, however, it were repugnant to the goodness of
Deity to have created me subject to constant decep-
tion, it would seem likewise to be contrary to his good-
ness to allow me to be occasionally deceived ; and yet
it is clear that this is permitted. Some, indeed, might
perhaps be found who would be disposed rather to
deny the existence of a Being so powerful than to be-
lieve that there is nothing certain. But let us for the
present refrain from opposing this opinion, and grant
that all which is here said of a Deity is fabulous:
nevertheless in whatever way it be supposed that I
reached the state in which I exist, whether by fate, or
chance, or by an endless series of antecedents and con-
sequents, or by any other means, it is clear (since to
be deceived and to err is a certain defect) that the
probability of my being so imperfect as to be the con-
stant victim of deception, will be increased exactly in
proportion as the power possessed by the cause, to
which they assign my origin, is lessened. To these
reasonings I have assuredly nothing to reply, but am
constrained at last to avow that there is nothing of all
that I formerly believed to be true of which it is im-
possible to doubt, and that not through thoughtless-
ness or levity, but from cogent and maturely consid-
ered reasons ; so that henceforward, if I desire to dis-
cover anything certain, I ought not the less carefully
OF THE THINGS OF WHICH WE MAY DOUBT. 27
to refrain from assenting to those same opinions than
to what might be shown to be manifestly false.
But it is not sufficient to have made these observa-
tions ; care must be taken likewise, to keep them in re-
membrance. For those old and customary opinions
perpetually recur — long and familiar usage giving
them the right of occupying my mind, even almost
against my will, and subduing my belief; nor will I
lose the habit of deferring to them and confiding in
them so long as I shall consider them to be what in
truth they are, viz., opinions to some extent doubtful,
as I have already shown, but still highly probable, and
such as it is much more reasonable to believe than
deny. It is for this reason I am persuaded that I shall
not be doing wrong, if, taking an opposite judgment
of deliberate design, I become my own deceiver, by
supposing, for a time, that all those opinions are en-
tirely false and imaginary, until at length, having thus
balanced my old by my new prejudices, my judgment
shall no longer be turned aside by perverted usage
from the path that may conduct to the perception of
truth. For I am assured that, meanwhile, there will
arise neither peril nor error from this course, and that
I cannot for the present yield too much to distrust,
since the end I now seek is not action but knowledge.
I will suppose, then, not that Deity, who is sover-
eignly good and the fountain of truth, but that some
malignant demon, who is at once exceedingly potent
and deceitful, has employed all his artifice to deceive
me; I will suppose that the sky, the air, the earth,
colours, figures, sounds, and all external things, are
nothing better than the illusions of dreams, by means
of which this being has laid snares for my credulity;
28 MEDITATION I.
I will consider myself as without hands, eyes, flesh,
blood, or any of the senses, and as falsely believing
that I am possessed of these ; I will continue resolutely
fixed in this belief, and if indeed by this means it be
not in my power to arrive at the knowledge of truth,
I shall at least do what is in my power, viz., [suspend
my judgment], and guard with settled purpose against
giving my assent to what, is false, and being imposed
upon by this deceiver, whatever be his power and
artifice.
But this undertaking is arduous, and a certain indo-
lence insensibly leads me back to my ordinary course
of life; and just as the captive, who, perchance, was
enjoying in his dreams an imaginary liberty, when he
begins to suspect that it is but a vision, dreads awak-
ening, and conspires with the agreeable illusions that
the deception may be prolonged ; so I, of my own ac-
cord, fall back into the train of my former beliefs, and
fear to arouse myself from my slumber, lest the time
of laborious wakefulness that would succeed this quiet
rest, in place of bringing any light of day, should
prove inadequate to dispel the darkness that will arise
from the difficulties that have now been raised.
MEDITATION IL
OF THE NATURE OF THE HUMAN MIND; AND THAT IT
IS MORE EASILY KNOWN THAN THE BODY.
The Meditation of yesterday has filled my mind with
so many doubts, that it is no longer in my power to
forget them. Nor do I see, meanwhile, any principle
on which they can be resolved; and, just as if I had
fallen all of a sudden into very deep water, I am so
greatly disconcerted as to be unable either to plant my
feet firmly on the bottom or sustain myself by swim-
ming on the surface. I will, nevertheless, make an
effort, and try anew the same path on which I had en-
tered yesterday, that is, proceed by casting aside all
that admits of the slightest doubt, not less than if I
had discovered it to be absolutely false; and I will
continue always in this track until I shall find some-
thing that is certain, or at least, if I can do nothing
more, until I shall know with certainty that there is
nothing certain. Archimedes, that he might transport
the entire globe from the place it occupied to another,
demanded only a point that was firm and immoveable ;
so also, I shall be entitled to entertain the highest ex-
pectations, if I am fortunate enough to discover only
one thing that is certain and indubitable.
I suppose, accordingly, that all the things which I
see are false (fictitious) ; I believe that none of those
objects which my fallacious memory represents ever
existed ; I suppose that I possess no senses ; I believe
29
30 MEDITATION II.
that body, figure, extension, motion, and place are
merely fictions of my mind. What is there, then, that
can be esteemed true? Perhaps this only, that there
is absolutely nothing certain.
But how do I know that there is not something dif-
ferent altogether from the objects I have now enum-
erated, of which it is impossible to entertain the slight-
est doubt? Is there not a God, or some being, by
whatever name I may designate him, who causes these
thoughts to arise in my mind ? But why suppose such
a being, for it may be I myself am capable of produc-
ing them? Am I, then, at least not something? But
I before denied that I possessed senses or a body; I
hesitate, however, for what follows from that ? Am I
so dependent on the body and the senses that without
these I cannot exist? But I had the persuasion that
there was absolutely nothing in the world, that there
was no sky and no earth, neither minds nor bodies ;
was I not, therefore, at the same time, persuaded that
I did not exist? Far from it; I assuredly existed,
since I was persuaded. But there is I know not what
being, who is possessed at once of the highest power
and the deepest cunning, who is constantly employing
all his ingenuity in deceiving me. Doubtless, then, I
exist, since I am deceived ; and, let him deceive me as
he may, he can never bring it about that I am nothing,
so long as I shall be conscious that I am something.
So that it must, in fine, be maintained, all things being
maturely and carefully considered, that this proposi-
tion (pronunciatum) I am, I exist, is necessarily true
each time it is expressed by me, or conceived in my
mind.
But I do not yet know with sufficient clearness what
OF THE NATURE OF THE HUMAN MIND. 31
I am, though assured that I am ; and hence, in the next
place, I must take care, lest perchance I inconsider-
ately substitute some other object in room of what is
properly myself, and thus wander from truth, even in
that knowledge (cognition) which I hold to be of all
others the most certain and evident. For this reason,
I will now consider anew what I formerly believed
myself to be, before I entered on the present train of
thought; and of my previous opinion I will retrench
all that can in the least be invalidated by the grounds
of doubt I have adduced, in order that there may at
length remain nothing but what is certain and indubit-
able. What then did I formerly think I was? Un-
doubtedly I judged that I was a man. But what is a
man ? Shall I say a rational animal ? Assuredly not ;
for it would be necessary forthwith to inquire into
what is meant by animal, and what by rational, and
thus, from a single question, I should insensibly glide
into others, and these more difficult than the first ; nor
do I now possess enough of leisure to warrant me in
wasting my time amid subtleties of this sort. I prefer
here to attend to the thoughts that sprung up of them-
selves in my mind, and were inspired by my own na-
ture alone, when I applied myself to the consideration
of what I was. In the first place, then, I thought that
I possessed a countenance, hands, arms, and all the
fabric of members that appears in a corpse, and which
I called by the name of body. It further occurred to
me that I was nourished, that I walked, perceived, and
thought, and all those actions I referred to the soul;
but what the soul itself was I either did not stay to
consider, or, if I did, I imagined that it was something
extremely rare and subtile, like wind, or flame, or
32 MEDITATION II.
ether, spread through my grosser parts. As regarded
the body, I did not even doubt of its nature, but
thought I distinctly knew it, and if I had wished to
describe it according to the notions I then entertained,
I should have explained myself in this manner: By
body I understand all that can be terminated by a cer-
tain figure ; that can be comprised in a certain place,
and so fill a certain space as therefrom to exclude
every other body; that can be perceived either by
touch, sight, hearing, taste, or smell; that can be moved
in different ways, not indeed of itself, but by some-
thing foreign to it by which it is touched [and from
which it receives the impression] ; for the power of
self-motion, as likewise that of perceiving and think-
ing, I held as by no means pertaining to the nature of
body; on the contrary, I was somewhat astonished to
find such faculties existing in some bodies.
But [as to myself, what can I now say that I am],
since I suppose there exists an extremely powerful,
and, if I may so speak, malignant being, whose whole
endeavours are directed towards deceiving me? Can
I affirm that I possess any one of all those attributes
of which I have lately spoken as belonging to the na-
ture of body? After attentively considering them in
my own mind, I find none of them that can properly
be said to belong to myself. To recount them were
idle and tedious. Let us pass, then, to the attributes
of the soul. The first mentioned were the powers of
nutrition and walking ; but, if it be true that I have no
body, it is true likewise that I am capable neither of
walking nor of being nourished. Perception is an-
other attribute of the soul; but perception too is im-
possible without the body : besides, I have frequently,
OF THE NATURE OF THE HUMAN MIND. 33
during sleep, believed that I perceived objects which
I afterwards observed I did not in reality perceive.
Thinking is another attribute of the soul ; and here I
discover what properly belongs to myself. This alone
is inseparable from me. I am — I exist: this is cer-
tain; but how often? As often as I think; for per-
haps it would even happen, if I should wholly cease to
think, that I should at the same time altogether cease
to be. I now admit nothing that is not necessarily
true : I am therefore, precisely speaking, only a think-
ing thing, that is, a mind (mens sive animus*), under-
standing, or reason, — terms whose signification was
■before unknown to me. I am, however, a real thing,
and really existent; but what thing? The answer
was, a thinking thing. The question now arises, am
I aught besides? I will stimulate my imagination
with a view to discover whether I am not still some-
thing more than a thinking being. Now it is plain I
am not the assemblage of members called the human
body; I am not a thin and penetrating air diffused
through all these members, or wind, or flame, or va-
pour, or breath, or any of all the things I can imagine ;
for I supposed that all these were not, and, without
changing the supposition, I find that I still feel assured
of my existence.
But it is true, perhaps, that those very things which
I suppose to be non-existent, because they are un-
known to me, are not in truth different from myself
whom I know. This is a point I cannot determine,
and do not now enter into any dispute regarding it. I
can only judge of things that are known to me : I am
conscious that I exist, and I who know that I exist in-
quire into what I am. It is, however, perfectly cer-
34 MEDITATION II.
tain that the knowledge of my existence, thus pre-
cisely taken, is not dependent on things, the existence
of which is as yet unknown to me : and consequently
it is not dependent on any of the things I can feign in
imagination. Moreover, the phrase itself, I frame an
image (effingo), reminds me of my error; for I should
in truth frame one if I were to imagine myself to be
anything, since to imagine is nothing more than to
contemplate the figure or image of a corporeal thing;
but I already know that I exist, and that it is possible
at the same time that all those images, and in general
all that relates to the nature of body, are merely
dreams for chimeras] . From this I discover that it is
not more reasonable to say, I will excite my imagina-
tion that I may know more distinctly what I am, than
to express myself as follows : I am now awake, and
perceive something real ; but because my perception is
not sufficiently clear, I will of express purpose go to
sleep that my dreams may represent to me the object
of my perception with more truth and clearness. And,
therefore, I know that nothing of all that I can em-
brace in imagination belongs to the knowledge which
I have of myself, and that there is need to recall with
the utmost care the mind from this mode of thinking,
that it may be able to know its own nature with per-
fect distinctness.
But what, then, am I? A thinking thing, it has
been said. But what is a thinking thing? It is a
thing that doubts, understands, [conceives], affirms,
denies, wills, refuses, that imagines also, and per-
ceives. Assuredly it is not little, if all these proper-
ties belong to my nature. But why should they not
belong to it? Am I not that very being who now
OF THE NATURE OF THE HUMAN MIND. 35
doubts of almost everything ; who, for all that, under-
stands and conceives certain things; who affirms one
alone as true, and denies the others; who desires to
know more of them, and does not wish to be deceived ;
who imagines many things, sometimes even despite
his will ; and is likewise percipient of many, as if
through the medium of the senses. Is there nothing
of all this as true as that I am, even although I should
be always dreaming, and although he who gave me
being employed all his ingenuity to deceive me? Is
there also any one of these attributes that can be prop-
erly distinguished from my thought, or that can be
said to be separate from myself? For it is of itself so
evident that it is I who doubt, I who understand, and
I who desire, that it is here unnecessary to add any-
thing by way of rendering it more clear. And I am
as certainly the same being who imagines ; for, al-
though it may be (as I before supposed) that nothing
I imagine is true, still the power of imagination does
not cease really to exist in me and to form part of my
thought. In fine, I am the same being who perceives,
that is, who apprehends certain objects as by the or-
gans of sense, since, in truth, I see light, hear a noise,
and feel heat. But it will be said that these presenta-
tions are false, and that I am dreaming. Let it be so.
At all events it is certain that I seem to see light, hear
a noise, and feel heat ; this cannot be false, and this is
what in me is properly called perceiving (sentire),
which is nothing else than thinking. From this I be-
gin to know what I am with somewhat greater clear-
ness and distinctness than heretofore.
But, nevertheless, it still seems to me, and I cannot
help believing, that corporeal things, whose images
36 MEDITATION IL
are formed by thought, [which fall under the senses],
and are examined by the same, are known with much
greater distinctness than that I know not what part of
myself which is not imaginable ; although, in truth, it
may seem strange to say that I know and comprehend
with greater distinctness things whose existence ap-
pears to me doubtful, that are unknown, and do not
belong to me, than others of whose reality I am per-
suaded, that are known to me, and appertain to my
proper nature ; in a word, than myself. But I see
clearly what is the state of the case. My mind is apt
to wander, and will not yet submit to be restrained
within the limits of truth. Let us therefore leave the
mind to itself once more, and, according to it every
kind of liberty, [permit it to consider the objects that
appear to it from without] , in order thai having after-
wards withdrawn it from these gently and oppor-
tunely, [and fixed it on the consideration of its being
and the properties it finds in itself], it may then be the
more easily controlled.
Let us now accordingly consider the objects that are
commonly thought to be [the most easily, and like-
wise] the most distinctly known, viz., the bodies we
touch and see ; not, indeed, bodies in general, for these
general notions are usually somewhat more confused,
but one body in particular. Take, for example, this
piece of wax; it is quite fresh, having been but re-
cently taken from the bee-hive ; it has not yet lost the
sweetness of the honey it contained ; it still retains
somewhat of the odour of the flowers from which it
was gathered ; its colour, figure, size, are apparent (to
the sight) ; it is hard, cold, easily handled; and sounds
when struck upon with the finger. In fine, all that
OF THE NATURE OF THE HUMAN MIND. 3;
contributes to make a body as distinctly known as pos-
sible, is found in the one before us. But, while I am
speaking, let it be placed near the fire — what remained
of the taste exhales, the smell evaporates, the colour
changes, its figure is destroyed, its size increases, it
becomes liquid, it grows hot, it can hardly be handled,
and, although struck upon, it emits no sound. Does
the same wax still remain after this change ? It must
be admitted that it does remain; no one doubts it, or
judges otherwise. What, then, was it I knew with so
much distinctness in the piece of wax? Assuredly, it
could be nothing of all that I observed by means of
the senses, since all the things that fell under taste,
smell, sight, touch, and hearing are changed, and yet
the same wax remains. It was perhaps what I now
think, viz., that this wax was neither the sweetness of
honey, the pleasant odour of flowers, the whiteness,
the figure, nor the sound, but only a body that a little
before appeared to me conspicuous under these forms,
and which is now perceived under others. But, to
speak precisely, what is it that I imagine when I think
of it in this way ? Let it be attentively considered, and,
retrenching all that does not belong to the wax, let us
see what remains. There certainly remains nothing,
except something extended, flexible, and movable.
But what is meant by flexible and movable? Is it
not that I imagine that the piece of wax, being round,
is capable of becoming square, or of passing from a
square into a triangular figure? Assuredly such is
not the case, because I conceive that it admits of an in-
finity of similar changes ; and I am, moreover, unable
to compass this infinity by imagination, and conse-
quently this conception which I have of the wax is not
38 MEDITATION IL
the product of the faculty of imagination. But what
now is this extension? Is it not also unknown? for
it becomes greater when the wax is melted, greater
when it is boiled, and greater still when the heat in-
creases; and I should not conceive [clearly and] ac-
cording to truth, the wax as it is, if I did not suppose
that the piece we are considering admitted even of a
wider variety of extension than I ever imagined. I
must, therefore, admit that I cannot even comprehend
by imagination what the piece of wax is, and that it is
the mind alone {mens, Lat., entendement, F.) which
perceives it. I speak of one piece in particular ; for, as
tp wax in general, this is still more evident. But what
is the piece of wax that can be perceived only by the
[understanding or] mind? It is certainly the same
which I see, touch, imagine ; and, in fine, it is the same
which, from the beginning, I believed it to be. But
(and this it is of moment to observe) the perception
of it is neither an act of sight, of touch, nor of imag-
ination, and never was either of these, though it might
formerly seem so, but is simply an intuition (inspec-
tio) of the mind, which may be imperfect and con-
fused, as it formerly was, or very clear and distinct, as
it is at present, according as the attention is more or
less directed to the elements which it contains, and of
which it is composed.
But, meanwhile, I feel greatly astonished when I ob-
serve [the weakness of my mind, and] its proneness to
error. For although, without at all giving expression
to what I think, I consider all this in my own mind,
words yet occasionally impede my progress, and I am
almost led into error by the terms of ordinary lan-
guage. We say, for example, that we see the same
OF THE NATURE OF THE HUMAN MIND. 39
wax when it is before us, and not that we judge it to
be the same from its retaining the same colour and
figure : whence I should forthwith be disposed to con-
clude that the wax is known by the act of sight, and
not by the intuition of the mind alone, were it not for
the analogous instance of human beings passing on in
the street below, as observed from a window. In this
case I do not fail to say that I see the men themselves,
just as I say that I see the wax ; and yet what do I see
from the window beyond hats and cloaks that might
cover artificial machines, whose motions might be de-
termined by springs? But I judge that there are hu-
man beings from these appearances, and thus I com-
prehend, by the faculty of judgment alone which is in
the mind, what I believed I saw with my eyes.
The man who makes it his aim to rise to knowledge
superior to the common, ought to be ashamed to seek
occasions of doubting from the vulgar forms of
speech : instead, therefore, of doing this, I shall pro-
ceed with the matter in hand, and inquire whether I
had a clearer and more perfect perception of the piece
of wax when I first saw it, and when I thought I knew
it by means of the external sense itself, or, at all
events, by the common sense (sensus communis), as it
is called, that is, by the imaginative faculty; or
whether I rather apprehend it more clearly at present,
after having examined with greater care, both what it
is, and in what way it can be known. It would cer-
tainly be ridiculous to entertain any doubt on this
point. For what, in that first perception, was there
distinct? What did I perceive which any animal
might not have perceived? But when I distinguish
the wax from its exterior forms, and when, as if I had
40 MEDITATION II.
stripped it of its vestments, I consider it quite naked,
it is certain, although some error may still be found in
my judgment, that I cannot, nevertheless, thus appre-
hend it without possessing a human mind.
But, finally, what shall I say of the mind itself, that
is, of myself? for as yet I do not admit that I am any-
thing but mind. What, then ! I who seem to possess
so distinct an apprehension of the piece, of wax, — do I
not know myself, both with greater truth and certi-
tude, and also much more distinctly and clearly? For
if I judge that the wax exists because I see it, it as-
suredly follows, much more evidently, that I myself
am or exist, for the same reason : for it is possible that
what I see may not in truth be wax, and that I do not
even possess eyes with which to see anything; but it
cannot be that when I see, or, which comes to the same
thing, when I think I see, I myself who think am noth-
ing. So likewise, if I judge that the wax exists be-
cause I touch it, it will still also follow that I am ; and
if I determine that my imagination, or any other
cause, whatever it be, persuades me of the existence
of the wax, I will still draw the same conclusion. And
what is here remarked of the piece of wax, is appli-
cable to all the other things that are external to me.
And further, if the [notion or] perception of wax ap-
peared to me more precise and distinct, after that not
only sight and touch, but many other causes besides,
rendered it manifest to my apprehension, with how
much greater distinctness must I now know myself,
since all the reasons that contribute to the knowledge
of the nature of wax, or of any body whatever, mani-
fest still better the nature of my mind? And there
are besides so many other things in the mind itself
OF THE NATURE OF THE HUMAN MIND. 41
that contribute to the illustration of its nature, that
those dependent on the body, to which I have here re-
ferred, scarcely merit to be taken into account.
But, in conclusion, I find I have insensibly reverted
to the point I desired ; for, since it is now manifest to
me that bodies themselves are not properly perceived
by the senses nor by the faculty of imagination, but by
the intellect alone ; and since they are not perceived
because they are seen and touched, but only because
they are understood [or rightly comprehended by
thought] , I readily discover that there is nothing more
easily or clearly apprehended than my own mind. But
because it is difficult to rid one's self so promptly of
an opinion to which one has been long accustomed, it
will be desirable to tarry for some time at this stage,
that, by long continued meditation, I may more deeply
impress upon my memory this new knowledge.
MEDITATION III.
of god: that he exists.
I will now close my eyes, I will stop my ears, I will
turn away my senses from their objects, I will even
efface from my consciousness all the images of cor-
poreal things; or at least, because this can hardly be
accomplished, I will consider them as empty and false ;
and thus, holding converse only with myself, and
closely examining my nature, I will endeavour to ob-
tain by degrees a more intimate and familiar knowl-
edge of myself. I am a thinking (conscious) thing,
that is, a being who doubts, affirms, denies, knows a
few objects, and is ignorant of many, — [who loves,
hates], wills, refuses, — who imagines likewise, and
perceives ; for, as I before remarked, although the
things which I perceive or imagine are perhaps noth~
ing at all apart from me [and in themselves], I am
nevertheless assured that those modes of conscious-
ness which I call perceptions and imaginations, in as
far only as they are modes of consciousness, exist in
me. A_nd in the little I have said I think I have sum-
med up all that I really know, or at least all that up
to this time I was aware I knew. Now, as I am en-
deavouring to extend my knowledge more widely, I
will use circumspection, and consider with care
whether I can still discover in myself anything fur-
ther which I have not yet hitherto observed. I am
certain that I am a thinking thing ; but do I not there-
42
OF GOD: THAT HE EXISTS. 43
fore likewise know what is required to render me cer-
tain of a truth? In this first knowledge, doubtless,
there is nothing that gives me assurance of its truth ex-
cept the clear and distinct perception of what I affirm,
which would not indeed be sufficient to give me the as-
surance that what I say is true, if it could ever happen
that anything I thus clearly and distinctly perceived
should prove false ; and accordingly it seems to me
that I may now take as a general rule, that all that is
very clearly and distinctly apprehended (conceived)
is true.
Nevertheless I before received and admitted many
things as wholly certain and manifest, which yet I
afterwards found to be doubtful. What, then, were
those? They were the earth, the sky, the stars, and
all the other objects which I was in the habit of per-
ceiving by the senses. But what was it that I clearly
[and distinctly] perceived in them? Nothing more
than that the ideas and the thoughts of those objects
were presented to my mind. And even now I do not
deny that these ideas are found in my mind. But
there was yet another thing which I affirmed, and
which, from having been accustomed to believe it, I
thought I clearly perceived, although, in truth, I did
not perceive it at all ; I mean the existence of objects
external to me, from which those ideas proceeded, and
to which they had a perfect resemblance; and it was
here I was mistaken, or if I judged correctly, this as-
suredly was not to be traced to any knowledge I pos-
sessed (the force of my perception, Lat).
But when I considered any matter in arithmetic and
geometry, that was very simple and easy, as, for ex-
ample, that two and three added together make five,
44 MEDITATION III.
and things of this sort, did I not view them with at
least sufficient clearness to warrant me in affirming
their truth? Indeed, if I afterwards judged that we
ought to doubt of these things, it was for no other rea-
son than because it occurred to me that a God might
perhaps have given me such a nature as that I should
be deceived, even respecting the matters that appeared
to me the most evidently true. But as often as this
preconceived opinion of the sovereign power of a God
presents itself to my mind, I am constrained to admit
that it is easy for him, if he wishes it, to cause me to
err, even in matters where I think I possess the high-
est evidence ; and, on the other hand, as often as I di-
rect my attention to things which I think I apprehend
with great clearness, I am so persuaded of their truth
that I naturally break out into expressions such as
these : Deceive me who may, no one will yet ever be
able to bring it about that I am not, so long as I shall
be conscious that I am, or at any future time cause it
to be true that I have never been, it being now true
that I am, or make two and three more or less than
five, in supposing which, and other like absurdities, I
discover a manifest contradiction.
And in truth, as I have no ground for believing that
Deity is deceitful, and as, indeed, I have not even con-
sidered the reasons by which the existence of a Deity
of any kind is established, the ground of doubt that
rests only on this supposition is very slight, and, so to
speak, metaphysical. But, that I may be able wholly
to remove it, I must inquire whether there is a God, as
soon as an opportunity of doing so shall present itself ;
and if I find that there is a God, I must examine like-
wise whether he can be a deceiver; for, without the
OF GOD: THAT HE EXISTS. 45
knowledge of these two truths, I do not see that I can
ever be certain of anything. And that I may be en-
abled to examine this without interrupting the order
of meditation I have proposed to myself [which is, to
pass by degrees from the notions that I shall find first
in my mind to those I shall afterwards discover in it],
it is necessary at this stage to divide all my thoughts
into certain classes, and to consider in which of these
classes truth and error are, strictly speaking, to be
found.
Of my thoughts some are, as it were, images of
things, and to these alone properly belongs the name
idea; as when I think [represent to my mind] a man,
a chimera, the sky, an angel, or God. Others, again,
have certain other forms ; as when I will, fear, affirm,
or deny, I always, indeed, apprehend something as the
object of my thought, but I also embrace in thought
something more than the representation of the object;
and of this class of thoughts some are called volitions
or affections, and others judgments.
Now, with respect to ideas, if these are considered
only in themselves, and are not referred to any object
beyond them, they cannot, properly speaking, be false ;
for, whether I imagine a goat or a chimera, it is not
less true that I imagine the one than the other. Nor
need we fear that falsity may exist in the will or affec-
tions ; for, although I may desire objects that are
wrong, and even that never existed, it is still true that
I desire them. There thus only remain our judg-
ments, in which we must take diligent heed that we be
not deceived. But the chief and most ordinary error
that arises in them consists in judging that the ideas
which are in us are like or conformed to the things
46 MEDITATION III.
that are external to us ; for assuredly, if we but con-
sidered the ideas themselves as certain modes of our
thought (consciousness), without referring them to
anything beyond, they would hardly afford any occa-
sion of error.
But, among these ideas, some appear to me to be in-
nate 6 , others adventitious, and others to be made by
myself (factitious) ; for, as I have the power of con-
ceiving what is called a thing, or a truth, or a thought,
it seems to me that I hold this power from no other
source than my own nature ; but if I now hear a noise,
if I see the sun, or if I feel heat, I have all along
judged that these sensations proceeded from certain
objects existing out of myself; and, in fine, it appears
to me that sirens, hippogryphs, and the like, are inven-
tions of my own mind. But I may even perhaps come
to be of opinion that all my ideas are of the class
which I call adventitious, or that they are all innate, or
that they are all factitious, for I have not yet clearly
discovered their true origin; and what I have here
principally to do is to consider, with reference to those
that appear to come from certain objects without me,
what grounds there are for thinking them like these
objects.
The first of these grounds is that it seems to me I
am so taught by nature ; and the second that I am con-
scious that those ideas are not dependent on my will,
and therefore not on myself, for they are frequently
presented to me against my will, — as at present,
whether I will or not, I feel heat ; and I am thus per-
suaded that this sensation or idea (sensum vel ideam)
of heat is produced in me by something different from
myself, viz., by the heat of the fire by which I sit. And
OF GOD: THAT HE EXISTS.
47
it is very reasonable to suppose that this object im-
presses me with its own likeness rather than any other
thing.
But I must consider whether these reasons are suf-
ficiently strong and convincing. When I speak of be-
ing taught by nature in this matter, I understand by
the word nature only a certain spontaneous impetus
that impels me to believe in a resemblance between
ideas and their objects, and not a natural light that af-
fords a knowledge of its truth. But these two things
are widely different ; for what the natural light shows
to be true can be in no degree doubtful, as, for exam-
ple, that I am because I doubt, and other truths of the
like kind: inasmuch as I possess no other faculty
whereby to distinguish truth from error, which can
teach me the falsity of what the natural light declares
to be true, and which is equally trustworthy ; but with
respect to [seemingly] natural impulses, I have ob-
served, when the question related to the choice of right
or wrong in action, that they frequently led me to take
the worse part; nor do I see that I have any better
ground for following them in what relates to truth
and error. Then, with respect to the other reason,
which is that because these ideas do not depend on my
will, they must arise from objects existing without me,
I do not find it more convincing than the former ; for,
just as those natural impulses, of which I have lately
spoken, are found in me, notwithstanding that they are
not always in harmony with my will, so likewise it
may be that I possess some power not sufficiently
known to myself capable of producing ideas without
the aid of external objects, and, indeed, it has always
hitherto appeared to me that they are formed during
48 MEDITATION III.
sleep, by some power of this nature, without the aid of
aught external. And, in fine, although I should grant
that they proceeded from those objects, it is not a
necessary consequence that they must be like them.
On the contrary, I have observed, in a number of in-
stances, that there was a great difference between the
object and its idea. Thus, for example, I find in my
mind two wholly diverse ideas of the sun; the one,
by which it appears to me extremely small, draws its
origin from the senses, and should be placed in the
class of adventitious ideas; the other, by which it
seems to be many times larger than the whole earth,
is taken up on astronomical grounds, that is, elicited
from certain notions born with me, or is framed by
myself in some other manner. These two ideas can-
not certainly both resemble the same sun; and reason
teaches me that the one which seems to have imme-
diately emanated from it is the most unlike. And
these things sufficiently prove that hitherto it has not
been from a certain and deliberate judgment, but only
from a sort of blind impulse, that I believed in the ex-
istence of certain things different from myself, which,
by the organs of sense, or by whatever other means it
might be, conveyed their ideas or images into my mind
[and impressed it with their likenesses].
But there is still another way of inquiring whether,
of the objects whose ideas are in my mind, there are
any that exist out of me. If ideas are taken in so far
only as they are certain modes of consciousness, I do
not remark any difference or inequality among them,
and all seem, in the same manner, to proceed from
myself ; but, considering them as images, of which one
represents one thing and another a different, it is evi-
OF GOD: THAT HE EXISTS. 49
dent that a great diversity obtains among them. For,
without doubt, those that represent substances are
something more, and contain in themselves, so to
speak, more objective reality [that is, participate by
representation in higher degrees of being or perfec-
tion], than those that represent only modes or acci-
dents ; and again, the idea by which I conceive a God
[sovereign], eternal, infinite, [immutable]-, all-know-
ing, all-powerful, and the creator of all things that are
out of himself, — this, I say, has certainly in it more
objective reality than those ideas by which finite sub-
stances are represented.
Now, it is manifest by the natural light that there
must at least be as much reality in the efficient and to-
tal cause as in its effect; for whence can the effect
draw its reality if not from its cause? and how could
the cause communicate to it this reality unless it pos-
sessed it in itself? And hence it follows, not only
that what is cannot be produced by what is not, but
likewise that the more perfect, — in other words, that
which contains in itself more reality, — cannot be the
effect of the less perfect: and this is not only evi-
dently true of those effects, whose reality is actual or
formal, but likewise of ideas, whose reality is only
considered as objective. Thus, for example, the stone
that is not yet in existence, not only cannot now com-
mence to be, unless it be produced by that which pos-
sesses in itself, formally or eminently 7 , all that enters
into its composition, [in other words, by that which
contains in itself the same properties that are in the
stone, or others superior to them] ; and heat can only
be produced in a subject that was before devoid of it,
by a cause that is of an order [degree or kind], at
SO MEDITATION III.
least as perfect as heat; and so of the others. But
further, even the idea of the heat, or of the stone, can-
not exist in me unless it be put there by a cause that
contains, at least, as much reality as I conceive exist-
ent in the heat or in the stone : for, although that cause
may not transmit into my idea anything of its actual
or formal reality, we ought not on this account to im-
agine that it is less real ; but we ought to consider
that, [as every idea is a work of the mind], its nature
is such as of itself to demand no other formal reality
than that which it borrows from our consciousness, of
which it is but a mode, [that is, a manner or way of
thinking] . But in order that an idea may contain this
objective reality rather than that, it must doubtless de-
rive it from some cause in which is found at least
as much formal reality as the idea contains of objec-
tive; for, if we suppose that there is found in an idea
anything which was not in its cause, it must of course
derive this from nothing. But, however imperfect may
be the mode of existence by which a thing is objec-
tively [or by representation] in the understanding by
its idea, we certainly cannot, for all that, allege that
this mode of existence is nothing, nor, consequently,
that the idea owes its origin to nothing. Nor must it
be imagined that, since the reality which is considered
in these ideas is only objective, the same reality need
not be formally (actually) in the causes of these ideas,
but only objectively: for, just as the mode of existing
objectively belongs to ideas by their peculiar nature,
so likewise the mode of existing formally appertains
to the causes of these ideas (at least to the first and
principal), by their peculiar nature. And although
an idea may give rise to another idea, this regress can-
OF GOD: THAT HE EXISTS. 51
not, nevertheless, be infinite ; we must in the end reach
a first idea, the cause of which is, as it were, the arche-
type in which all the reality [or perfection] that is
found objectively [or by representation] in these ideas
is contained formally [and in act] . I am thus clearly
taught by the 'natural light that ideas exist in me as
pictures or images, which may in truth readily fall
short of the perfection of the objects from which they
are taken, but can never contain anything greater or
more perfect.
And in proportion to the time and care with which
I examine all those matters, the conviction of their
truth brightens and becomes distinct. But, to sum
up, what conclusion shall I draw from it all? It is
this; — if the objective reality [or perfection] of any
one of my ideas be such as clearly to convince me, that
this same reality exists in me neither formally nor emi-
nently, and if, as follows from this, I myself cannot be
the cause of it, it is a necessary consequence that I am
not alone in the world, but that there is besides myself
some other being who exists as the cause of that idea ;
while, on the contrary, if no such idea be found in my
mind, I shall have no sufficient ground of assurance
of the existence of any other being besides myself ; for,
after a most careful search, I have, up to this moment,
been unable to discover any other ground.
But, among these my ideas, besides that which rep-
resents myself, respecting which there can be here no
difficulty, there is one that represents a God; others
that represent corporeal and inanimate things; others
angels ; others animals ; and, finally, there are some
that represent men like myself. But with respect to
the ideas that represent other men, or animals, or
52 MEDITATION III.
angels, I can easily suppose that they were formed by
the mingling and composition of the other ideas which
I have of myself, of corporeal things, and of God, al-
though there were, apart from myself, neither men,
animals, nor angels. And with regard to the ideas of
corporeal objects, I never discovered in them anything
so great or excellent which I myself did not appear
capable of originating ; for, by considering these ideas
closely and scrutinising them individually, in the same
way that I yesterday examined the idea of wax, I find
that there is but little in them that is clearly and dis-
tinctly perceived. As belonging to the class of things
that are clearly apprehended, I recognise the follow-
ing, viz., magnitude or extension in length, breadth,
and depth; figure, which results from the termination
of extension ; situation, which bodies of diverse figures
preserve with reference to each other; and motion or
the change of situation; to which may be added sub-
stance, duration, and number. But with regard to
light, colours, sounds, odours, tastes, heat, cold, and
the other tactile qualities, they are thought with so
much obscurity and confusion, that I cannot determine
even whether they are true or false ; in other words,
whether or not the ideas I have of these qualities are
in truth the ideas of real objects. For although I be-
fore remarked that it is only in judgments that formal
falsity, or falsity properly so called, can be met with,
there may nevertheless be found in ideas a certain ma-
terial falsity, which arises when they represent what is
nothing as if it were something. Thus, for example,
the ideas I have of cold and heat are so far from being
clear and distinct, that I am unable from them to dis-
cover whether cold is only the privation of heat, or
OF GOD: THAT HE EXISTS. 53
heat the privation of cold ; or whether they are not real
qualities : and since, ideas being as it were images, there
can be none that does not seem to us to represent
some object, the idea which represents cold as some-
thing real and positive will not improperly be called
false, if it be correct to say that cold is nothing but a
privation of heat; and so in other cases. To ideas of
this kind, indeed, it is not necessary that I should as-
sign any author besides myself: for if they are false,
that is, represent objects that are unreal, the natural
light teaches me that they proceed from nothing; in
other words, that they are in me only because some-
thing is wanting to the perfection of my nature ; but if
these ideas are true, yet because they exhibit to me so
little reality that I cannot even distinguish the object
represented from non-being, I do not see why I should
not be the author of them.
With reference to those ideas of corporeal things
that are clear and distinct, there are some which, as ap-
pears to me, might have been taken from the idea I
have of myself, as those of substance, duration, num-
ber, and the like. For when I think that a stone is a
substance, or a thing capable of existing of itself, and
that I am likewise a substance, although I conceive that
I am a thinking and non-extended thing, and that the
stone, on the contrary, is extended and unconscious,
there being thus the greatest diversity between the two
concepts, — yet these two ideas seem to have this in
common that they both represent substances. In the
same way, when I think of myself as now existing, and
recollect besides that I existed some time ago, and
when I am conscious of various thoughts whose num-
ber I know, I then acquire the ideas of duration and
54 MEDITATION III.
number, which I can afterwards transfer to as many
objects as I please. With respect to the other quali-
ties that go to make up the ideas of corporeal objects,
viz., extension, figure, situation, and motion, it is true
that they are not formally in me, since I am merely a
thinking being ; but because they are only certain modes
of substance, and because I myself am a substance, it
seems possible that they may be contained in me emi-
nently.
There only remains, therefore, the idea of God, in
which I must consider whether there is anything that
cannot be supposed to originate with myself. By the
name God, I understand a substance infinite, [eternal,
immutable], independent, all-knowing, all-powerful,
and by which I myself, and every other thing that ex-
ists, if any such there be, were created. But these
properties are so great and excellent, that the more at-
tentively I consider them the less I feel persuaded that
the idea I have of them owes its origin to myself alone.
And thus it is absolutely necessary to conclude, from
all that I have before said, that God exists : for though
the idea of substance be in my mind owing to this, that
I myself am a substance, I should not, however, have
the idea of an infinite substance, seeing I am a finite
being, unless it were given me by some substance in
reality infinite.
And I must not imagine that I do not apprehend the
infinite by a true idea, but only by the negation of the
finite, in the same way that I comprehend repose and
darkness by the negation of motion and light: since,
on the contrary, I clearly perceive that there is more
reality in the infinite substance than in the finite, and
therefore that in some way I possess the perception
OF GOD: THAT HE EXISTS. 55
(notion) of the infinite before that of the finite, that is,
the perception of God before that of myself, for how
could I know that I doubt, desire, or that something
is wanting to me, and that I am not wholly perfect, if
I possessed no idea of a being more perfect than my-
self, by comparison of which I knew the deficiencies of
my nature?
And it cannot be said that this idea of God is per-
haps materially false, and consequently that it may
have arisen from nothing, [in other words, that it may
exist in me from my imperfection], as I before said
of the ideas of heat and cold, and the like : for, on the
contrary, as this idea is very clear and distinct, and
contains in itself more objective reality than any other,
there can be no one of itself more true, or less open to
the suspicion of falsity.
The idea, I say, of a being supremely perfect, and
infinite, is in the highest degree true ; for although, per-
haps, we may imagine that such a being does not exist,
we cannot, nevertheless, suppose that his idea repre-
sents nothing real, as I have already said of the idea
of cold. It is likewise clear and distinct in the highest
degree, since whatever the mind clearly and distinctly
conceives as real or true, and as implying any perfec-
tion, is contained entire in this idea. And this is true,
nevertheless, although I do not comprehend the infinite,
and although there may be in God an infinity of things
that I cannot comprehend, nor perhaps even compass
by thought in any way ; for it is of the nature of the
infinite that it should not be comprehended by the
finite ; and it is enough that I rightly understand this,
and judge that all which I clearly perceive, and in
which I know there is some perfection, and perhaps
56 MEDITATION III.
also an infinity of properties of which I am ignorant,
are formally or eminently in Gocl, in order that the idea
I have of him may become the most true, clear, and
distinct of all the ideas in my mind.
B'ut perhaps I am something more than I suppose
myself to be, and it may be that all those perfections
which I attribute to God, in some way exist potentially
in me, although they do not yet show themselves, and
are not reduced to act. Indeed, I am already con-
scious that my knowledge is being increased [and per-
fected] by degrees ; and I see nothing to prevent it
from thus gradually increasing to infinity, nor any
reason why, after such increase and perfection, I
should not be able thereby to acquire all the other per-
fections of the Divine nature ; nor, in fine, why the
power I possess of acquiring those perfections, if it
really now exist in me, should not be sufficient to pro-
duce the ideas of them. Yet, on looking more closely
into the matter, I discover that this cannot be ; for, in
the first place, although it were true that my knowledge
daily acquired new degrees of perfection, and although
there were potentially in my nature much that was not
as yet actually in it, still all these excellences make not
the slightest approach to the idea I have of the Deity,
in whom there is no perfection merely potentially [but
all actually] existent; for it is even an unmistakeable
token of imperfection in my knowledge, that it is aug-
mented by degrees. Further, although my knowledge
increase more and more, nevertheless I am not, there-
fore, induced to think that it will ever be actually infi-
nite, since it can never reach that point beyond which
it shall be incapable of further increase. But I con-
ceive God as actually infinite, so that nothing can be
OF GOD: THAT HE EXISTS. 57
added to his perfection. And, in fine, I readily per-
ceive that the objective being of an idea cannot be pro-
duced by a being that is merely potentially existent,
which, properly speaking, is nothing, but only by a
being existing formally or actually.
And, truly, I see nothing in all that I have now said
which it is not easy for any one, who shall carefully
consider it, to discern by the natural light; but when
I allow my attention in some degree to relax, the vision
of my mind being obscured, and, as it were, blinded
by the images of sensible objects, I do not readily re-
member the reason why the idea ôf a being more per-
fect than myself, must of necessity have proceeded
from a being in reality more perfect. On this account
I am here desirous to inquire further, whether I, who
possess this idea of God, could exist supposing there
were no God. And I ask, from whom could I, in that
case, derive my existence? Perhaps from myself, or
from my parents, or from some other causes less per-
fect than God ; for anything more perfect, or even
equal to God, cannot be thought or imagined. But if
I [were independent of every other existence, and]
were myself the author of my being, I should doubt
of nothing, I should desire nothing, and, in fine, no per-
fection would be awanting to me; for I should have
bestowed upon myself every perfection of which I pos-
sess the idea, and I should thus be God. And it must
not be imagined that what is now wanting to me is per-
haps of more difficult acquisition than that of which I
am already possessed ; for, on the contrary, it is quite
manifest that it was a matter of much higher difficulty
that I, a thinking being, should arise from nothing,
than it would be for me to acquire the knowledge of
58 MEDITATION III.
many things of which I am ignorant, and which are
merely the accidents of a thinking substance ; and cer-
tainly, if I possessed of myself the greater perfection
of which I have now spoken, [in other words, if I were
the author of my own existence], I would not at least
have denied to myself things that may be more easily
obtained, [as that infinite variety of knowledge of
which I am at present destitute] . I could not, indeed,
have denied to myself any property which I perceive
is contained in the idea of God, because there is none
of these that seems to me to be more difficult to make
or acquire ; and if there were any that should happen
to be more difficult to acquire, they would certainly ap-
pear so to me (supposing that I myself were the source
of the other things I possess), because I should dis-
cover in them a limit to my power. And though I
were to suppose that I always was as I now am, I
should not, on this ground, escape the force of these
reasonings, since it would not follow, even on this sup-
position, that no author of my existence needed to be
sought after. For the whole time of my life may be
divided into an infinity of parts, each of which is in no
way dependent on any other ; and, accordingly, because
I was in existence a short time ago, it does not follow
that I must now exist, unless in this moment some
cause create me anew as it were, — that is, conserve me.
In truth, it is perfectly clear and evident to all who
will attentively consider the nature of duration, that
the conservation of a substance, in each moment of its
duration, requires the same power and act that would
be necessary to create it, supposing it were not yet in
existence ; so that it is manifestly a dictate of the nat-
ural light that conservation and creation differ merely
OF GOD: THAT HE EXISTS. 59
in respect of our mode of thinking [and not in reality].
All that is here required, therefore, is that I interrogate
myself to discover whether I possess any power by
means of which I can bring it about that I, who now
am, shall exist a moment afterwards ; for, since I am
merely a thinking thing (or since, at least, the precise
question, in the meantime, is only of that part of my-
self), if such a power resided in me, I should, without
doubt, be conscious of it; but I am conscious of no
such power, and thereby I manifestly know that I am
dependent upon some being different from myself.
But perhaps the being upon whom I am dependent,
is not God, and I have been produced either by my
parents, or by some causes less perfect than Deity.
This cannot be : for, as I before said, it is perfectly evi-
dent that there must at least be as much reality in the
cause as in its effect; and accordingly, since I am a
thinking thing, and possess in myself an idea of God,
whatever in the end be the cause of my existence, it
must of necessity be admitted that it is likewise a
thinking being, and that it possesses in itself the idea
and all the perfections I attribute to Deity. Then it
may again be inquired whether this cause owes its
origin and existence to itself, or to some other cause.
For if it be self-existent, it follows, from what I have
before laid down, that this cause is God; for, since it
possesses the perfection of self -existence, it must like-
wise, without doubt, have the power of actually pos-
sessing every perfection of which it has the idea, — in
other words, all the perfections I conceive to belong to
God. But if it owe its existence to another cause than
itself, we demand again, for a similar reason, whether
this second cause exists of itself or through some other,
6o MEDITATION III.
until, from stage to stage, we at length arrive at an ul-
timate cause, which will be God. And it is quite man-
ifest that in this matter there can be no infinite regress
of causes, seeing that the question raised respects not
so much the cause which once produced me, as that
by which I am. at this present moment conserved.
Nor can it be supposed that several causes concurred
in my production, and that from one I received the
idea of one of the perfections I attribute to Deity, and
from another the idea of some other, and thus that all
those perfections are indeed found somewhere in the
universe, but do not all exist together in a single being
who is God; for, on the contrary, the unity, the sim-
plicity or inseparability of all the properties of Deity,
is one of the chief perfections 1 conceive him to pos-
sess ; and the idea of this unity of all the perfections of
Deity could certainly not be put into my mind by any
cause from which I did not likewise receive the ideas
of all the other perfections ; for no power could enable
me to embrace them in an inseparable unity, without
at the same time giving me the knowledge of what they
were [and of their existence in a particular mode] :
Finally, with regard to my parents [from whom it
appears I sprung] , although all that I believed respect-
ing them be true, it does not, nevertheless, follow that
I am conserved by them, on even that I was produced
by them, in so far as I am a thinking being. All that,
at the most, they contributed to my origin was the giv-
ing of certain dispositions (modifications) to the mat-
ter in which I have" hitherto judged that I or my mind,
which is what alone I now consider to be myself, is en-
closed; and thus there can here be no difficulty with
respect to them, and it is absolutely necessary to con-
OF GOD: THAT HE EXISTS. 61
elude from this alone that I am, and possess the idea
of a being absolutely perfect, that is, of God, that his
existence is most clearly demonstrated.
There remains only the inquiry as to the way in
which I received this idea from God ; for I have not
drawn it from the senses, nor is it even presented to
me unexpectedly, as is usual with the ideas of sensible
objects, when these are presented or appear to be pre-
sented to the external organs of the senses ; it is not
even a pure production or fiction of my mind, for it is
not in my power to take from or add to it ; and conse-
quently there but remains the alternative that it is in-
nate, in the same way as is the idea of myself. And,
in truth, it is not to be wondered at that God, at my
creation, implanted this idea in me, that it might serve,
as it were, for the mark of the workman impressed on
his work; and it is not also necessary that the mark
should be something different from the work itself;
but considering only that God is my creator, it is highly
probable that he in some way fashioned me after his
own image and likeness, and that I perceive this like-
ness, in which is contained the idea of God, by the same
faculty by which I apprehend myself, — in other words,
when I make myself the object of. reflection, I not only
find that I am an incomplete, fimperfect] and depend-
ent being, and one who unceasingly aspires after some-
thing better and greater than he is ; but, at the same
time, I am assured likewise that he upon whom I am
dependent possesses in himself all the goods after
which I aspire, [and the ideas of which I find in my
mind], and that not merely indefinitely and potentially,
but infinitely and actually, and that he is thus God.
And the whole force of the argument of which I have
62 MEDITATION III.
here availed myself to establish the existence of God,
consists in this, that I perceive I could not possibly be
of such a nature as I am, and yet have in my mind the
idea of a God, if God did not in reality exist, — this
same God, I say, whose idea is in my mind — that is, a
being who possesses all those lofty perfections, of
which the mind may have some slight conception, with-
out, however, being able fully to comprehend them —
and who is wholly superior to all defect, [and has noth-
ing that marks imperfection] : whence it is sufficiently
manifest that he cannot be a deceiver, since it is a dic-
tate of the natural light that all fraud and deception
spring from some defect.
But before I examine this with more attention, and
pass on to the consideration of other truths that may
be evolved out of it, I think it proper to remain here
for some time in the contemplation of God himself —
that I may ponder at leisure his marvellous attributes
— and behold, admire, and adore the beauty of this
light so unspeakably great, as far, at least, as the
strength of my mind, which is to some degree dazzled
by the sight, will permit. For just as we learn by faith
that the supreme felicity of another life consists in the
contemplation of the Divine majesty alone, so even now
we learn from experience that a like meditation, though
incomparably less perfect, is the source of the highest
satisfaction of which we are susceptible in this life.
MEDITATION IV.
OF TRUTH AND ERROR.
I have been habituated these bygone days to detach
my mind from the senses, and I have accurately ob-
served that there is exceedingly little which is known
with certainty respecting corporeal objects, — that we
know much more of the human mind, and still more of
God himself. I am thus able now without difficulty
to abstract my mind from the contemplation of [sensi-
ble of] imaginable objects, and apply it to those which,
as disengaged from all matter, are purely intelligible.
And certainly the idea I have of the human mind in
so far as it is a thinking thing, and not extended in
length, breadth, and depth, and participating in none
of the properties of body, is incomparably more dis-
tinct than the idea of any corporeal object ; and when
I consider that I doubt, in other words, that I am an
incomplete and dependent being, the idea of a complete
and independent being, that is to say of God, occurs
to my mind with so much clearness and distinctness,
— and from the fact alone that this idea is found in me,
or that I who possess it exist, the conclusions that God
exists, and that my own existence, each moment of its
continuance, is absolutely dependent upon him, are so
manifest, — as to lead me to believe it impossible that
the human mind can know anything with more clear-
ness and certitude. And now I seem to discover a
path that will conduct us from the contemplation of
63
64 MEDITATION IV.
the true God, in whom are contained all the treasures
of science and wisdom, to the knowledge of the other
things in the universe.
For, in the first place, I discover that it is impossible
for him ever to deceive me, for in all fraud and deceit
there is a certain imperfection : and although it may
seem that the ability to deceive is a mark of subtlety
or power, yet the will testifies without doubt of malice
and weakness ; and such, accordingly, cannot be found
in God. In the next place, I am conscious that I pos-
sess a certain faculty of judging [or discerning truth
from error], which I doubtless received from God,
along with whatever else is mine ; and since it is im-
possible that he should will to deceive me, it is likewise
certain that he has not given me a faculty that will ever
lead me into error, provided I use it aright.
And there would remain no doubt on this head, did
it not seem to follow from this, that I can never there-
fore be deceived ; for if all I possess be from God, and
if he planted in me no faculty that is deceitful, it seems
to follow that I can never fall into error. Accord-
ingly, it is true that when I think only of God (when
I. look upon myself as coming from God, Fr.), and
turn wholly to him, I discover [in myself] no cause
of error or falsity : but immediately thereafter, recur-
ring to myself, experience assures me that I am never-
theless subject to innumerable errors. When I come
to inquire into the cause of these, I observe that there
is not only present to my consciousness a real and pos-
itive idea of God, or of a being supremely perfect, but
also, so to speak, a certain negative idea of nothing, —
in other words, of that which is at an infinite distance
from every sort of perfection, and that I am, as it were,
OF TRUTH AND ERROR. 65
a mean between God and nothing, or placed in such a
way between absolute existence and non-existence, that
there is in truth nothing in me to lead me into error,
in so far as an absolute being is my creator ; but that,
on the other hand, as I thus likewise participate in some
degree of nothing or of non-being, in other words, as
I am not myself the supreme Being, and as I am want-
ing in many perfections, it is not surprising I should
fall into error. And I hence discern that error, so far
as error is not something real, which depends for its
existence on God, but is simply defect; and therefore
that, in order to fall into it, it is not necessary God
should have given me a faculty expressly for this end,
but that my being deceived arises from the circum-
stance that the power which God has given me of dis-
cerning truth from error is not infinite.
Nevertheless this is not yet quite satisfactory ; for er-
ror is not a pure negation, [in other words, it is not the
simple deficiency or want of some knowledge which is
not due] , but the privation or want of some knowledge
which it would seem I ought to possess. But, on con-
sidering the nature of God, it seems impossible that
he should have planted in his creature any faculty not
perfect in its kind, that is, wanting in some perfection
due to it : for if it be true, that in proportion to the
skill of the maker the perfection of his work is greater,
what thing can have been produced by the supreme
Creator of the universe that is not absolutely perfect
in all its parts ? And assuredly there is no doubt that
God could have created me such as that I should never
be deceived ; it is certain, likewise, that he always wills
what is best ; is it better, then, that I should be capa-
ble of being: deceived than that I should not ?
66 MEDITATION IV.
Considering this more attentively, the first thing that
occurs to me is the reflection that I must not be sur-
prised if I am not always capable of comprehending
the reasons why God acts as he does ; nor must I doubt
of his existence because I find, perhaps, that there are
several other things besides the present respecting
which I understand neither why nor how they were
created by him; for, knowing already that my nature
is extremely weak and limited, and that the nature of
God, on the other hand, is immense, incomprehensible,
and infinite, I have no longer any difficulty in discern-
ing that there is an infinity of things in his power
whose causes transcend the grasp of my mind : and
this consideration alone is sufficient to convince me,
that the whole class of final causes is of no avail in
physical [or natural] things; for it appears to me that
I cannot, without exposing myself to the charge of
temerity, seek to discover the [impenetrable] ends of
Deity.
It further occurs to me that we must not consider
only one creature apart from the others, if we wish to
determine the perfection of the works of Deity, but
generally all his creatures together; for the same ob-
ject that might perhaps, with some show of reason, be
deemed highly imperfect if it were alone in the world,
may for all that be the most perfect possible, consid-
ered as forming part of the whole universe: and al-
though, as it was my purpose to doubt of everything,
I only as yet know with certainty my own existence
and that of God, nevertheless, after having remarked
the infinite power of Deity, I cannot deny that he may
have produced many other objects, or at least that he
is able to produce them, so that I may occupy a place
OF TRUTH AND ERROR. 67
in the relation of a part to the great whole of his crea-
tures.
Whereupon, regarding myself more closely, and
considering what my errors are (which alone testify to
the existence of imperfection in me), I observe that
these depend on the concurrence of two causes, viz.,
the faculty of cognition which I possess, and that of
election or the power of free choice, — in other words,
the understanding and the will. For by the under-
standing alone, I [neither affirm nor deny anything,
but] merely apprehend (percipio) the ideas regarding
which I may form a judgment; nor is any error, prop-
erly so called, found in it thus accurately taken. And
although there are perhaps innumerable objects in the
world of which I have no idea in my understanding, it
cannot, on that account, be said that I am deprived of
those ideas [as of something that is due to my nature],
but simply that I do not possess them, because, in
truth, there is no ground to prove that Deity ought to
have endowed me with a larger faculty of cognition
than he has actually bestowed upon me; and however
skilful a workman I suppose him to be, I have no rea-
son, on that account, to think that it was obligatory on
him to give to each of his works all the perfections
he is able to bestow upon some. Nor, moreover, can
I complain that God has not given me freedom of
choice, or a will sufficiently ample and perfect, since,
in truth, I am conscious of will so ample and extended
as to be superior to all limits. And what appears to
me here to be highly remarkable is that, of all the
other properties I possess, there is none so great and
perfect as that I do not clearly discern it could be still
greater and more perfect. For, to take an example, if
68 MEDITATION IV.
I consider the faculty of understanding which I pos-
sess, I find that it is of very small extent, and greatly
limited, and at the same time I form the idea of an-
other faculty of the same nature, much more ample
and even infinite ; and seeing that I can frame the idea
of it, I discover, from this circumstance alone, that it
pertains to the nature of God. In the same way, if I
examine the faculty of memory or imagination, or any
other faculty I possess, I find none that is not small
and circumscribed, and in God immense [and infinite].
It is the faculty of will only, or freedom of choice,
which I experience to be so great that I am unable to
conceive the idea of another that shall be more ample
and extended ; so that it is chiefly my will which leads
me to discern that I bear a certain image and simili-
tude of Deity. For although the faculty of will is in-
comparably greater in God than in myself, as well in
respect of the knowledge and power that are con-
joined with it, and that render it stronger and more
efficacious, as in respect of the object, since in him it
extends to a greater number of things, it does not,
nevertheless, appear to me greater, considered in itself
formally and precisely: for the power of will consists
only in this, that we are able to do or not to do the
same thing (that is, to affirm or deny, to pursue or
shun it), or rather in this alone, that in affirming or
denying, pursuing or shunning, what is proposed to us
by the understanding, we so act that we are not con-
scious of being determined to a particular action by
any external force. For, to the possession of freedom,
it is not necessary that I be alike indifferent towards
each of two contraries ; but, on the contrary, the more
I am inclined towards the one, whether because I
OF TRUTH AND ERROR. 69
clearly know that in it there is the reason of truth and
goodness, or because God thus internally disposes my
thought, the more freely do I choose and embrace it;
and assuredly divine grace and natural knowledge,
very far from diminishing liberty, rather augment and
fortify it. But the indifference of which I am con-
scious when I am not impelled to one side rather than
to another for want of a reason, is the lowest grade of
liberty, and manifests defect or negation of knowledge
rather than perfection of will ; for if I always clearly
knew what was true and good, I should never have
any difficulty in determining what judgment I ought
to come to, and what choice I ought to make, and I
should thus be entirely free without ever being in-
different.
From all this I discover, however, that neither the j
power of willing, which I have received from God, is/
of itself the source of my errors, for it is exceedingly
ample and perfect in its kind; nor even the power of
understanding, for as I conceive no object unless by
means of the faculty that God bestowed upon me, all
that I conceive is doubtless rightly conceived by me,
and it is impossible for me to be deceived in it.
Whence, then, spring my errors? They arise from
this cause alone, that I do not restrain the will, which
is of much wider range than the understanding, within
the same limits, but extend it even to things I do not
understand, and as the will is of itself indifferent to
such, it readily falls into error and sin by choosing the
false in room of the true, and evil instead of good.
For example, when I lately considered whether
aught really existed in the world, and found that be-
cause I considered this question, it very manifestly fol-
70 MEDITATION IV.
lowed that I myself existed, I could not but judge that
what I so clearly conceived was true, not that I was
forced to this judgment by any external cause, but
simply because great clearness of the understanding
was succeeded by strong inclination in the will ; and I
believed this the more freely and spontaneously in pro-
portion as I was less indifferent with respect to it.
But now I not only know that I exist, in so far as I
am a thinking being, but there is likewise presented to
my mind a certain idea of corporeal nature; hence I
am in doubt as to whether the thinking nature which
is in me, or rather which I myself am, is different from
that corporeal nature, or whether both are merely one
and the same thing, and I here suppose that I am as
yet ignorant of any reason that would determine me to
adopt the one belief in preference to the other : whence
it happens that it is a matter of perfect indifference to
me which of the two suppositions I affirm or deny, or
whether I form any judgment at all in the matter.
This indifference, moreover, extends not only to
things of which the understanding has no knowledge
at all, but in general also to all those which it does not
discover with perfect clearness at the moment the will
is deliberating upon them; for, however probable the
conjectures may be that dispose me to form a judg-
ment in a particular matter, the simple knowledge that
these are merely conjectures, and not certain and in-
dubitable reasons, is sufficient to lead me to form one
that is directly the opposite. Of this I lately had
abundant experience, when I laid aside as false all that
I had before held for true, on the single ground that I
could in some degree doubt of it. But if I abstain from
judging of a thing when I do not conceive it with suf-
OF TRUTH AND ERROR. 71
ficient clearness and distinctness, it is plain that I act
rightly, and am not deceived ; but if I resolve to deny
or affirm, I then do not make a right use of my free
will; and if I affirm what is false, it is evident that I
am deceived : moreover, even although I judge accord-
ing to truth, I stumble upon it by chance, and do not
therefore escape the imputation of a wrong use of my
freedom ; for it is a dictate of the natural light, that the
knowledge of the understanding ought always to pre-
cede the determination of the will.
And it is this wrong use of the freedom of the will
in which is found the privation that constitutes the
form of error. Privation, I say, is found in the act, in
so far as it proceeds from myself, but it does not exist
in the faculty which I received from God, nor even in
the act, in so far as it depends on him ; for I have as-
suredly no reason to complain that God has not given
me a greater power of intelligence or more perfect
natural light than he has actually bestowed, since it is
of the nature of a finite understanding not to compre-
hend many things, and of the nature of a created un-
derstanding to be finite ; on the contrary, I have every
reason to render thanks to God, who owed me nothing,
for having given me all the perfections I possess, and
I should be far from thinking that he has unjustly de-
prived me of, or kept back, the other perfections which
he has not bestowed upon me.
I have no reason, moreover, to complain because he
has given me a will more ample than my understand-
ing, since, as the will consists only of a single element,
and that indivisible, it would appear that this faculty
is of such a nature that nothing could be taken from it
[without destroying it] ; and certainly, the more exten-
72 MEDITATION IV.
sive it is, the more cause I have to thank the goodness
of him who bestowed it upon me.
And, finally, I ought not also to complain that God
concurs with me in forming the acts of this will, or the
judgments in which I am deceived, because those acts
are wholly true and good, in so far as they depend on
God ; and the ability to form them is a higher degree
of perfection in my nature than the want of it would
be. With regard to privation, in which alone consists
the formal reason of error and sin, this does not re-
quire the concurrence of Deity, because it is not a
thing [or existence], and if it be referred to God as to
its cause, it ought not to be called privation, but nega-
tion, [according to the signification of these words in
the schools]. For in truth it is no imperfection in
Deity that he has accorded to me the power of giving
or withholding my assent from certain things of which
he has not put a clear and distinct knowledge in my
understanding; but it is doubtless an imperfection in
me that I do not use my freedom aright, and readily
give my judgment on matters which I only obscurely
and confusedly conceive.
I perceive, nevertheless, that it was easy for Deity
so to have constituted me as that I should never be de-
ceived, although I still remained free and possessed of
a limited knowledge, viz., by implanting in my under-
standing a clear and distinct knowledge of all the ob-
jects respecting which I should ever have to delib-
erate ; or simply by so deeply engraving on my mem-
ory the resolution to judge of nothing without previ-
ously possessing a clear and distinct conception of it,
that I should never forget it. And I easily understand
that, in so far as I consider myself as a single whole,
OF TRUTH AND ERROR. 73
without reference to any other being in the universe, I
should have been much more perfect than I now am,
had Deity created me superior to error; but I cannot
therefore deny that it is not somehow a greater perfec-
tion in the universe, that certain of its parts are not
exempt from defect, as others are, than if they were all
perfectly alike.
And I have no right to complain because God, who
placed me in the world, was not willing that I should
sustain that character which of all others is the chief
and most perfect; I have even good reason to remain
satisfied on the ground that, if he has not given me the
perfection of being superior to error by the first means
I have pointed out above, which depends on a clear and
evident knowledge of all the matters regarding which
I can deliberate, he has at least left in my power the
other means, which is, firmly to retain the resolution
never to judge where the truth is not clearly known to
me: for, although I am conscious of the weakness of
not being able to keep my mind continually fixed on
the same thought, I can nevertheless, by attentive and
oft-repeated meditation, impress it so strongly on my
memory that I shall never fail to recollect it as often
as I require it, and I. can acquire in this way the habi-
tude of not erring ; and since it is in being superior to
error that the highest and chief perfection of man con-
sists, I deem that I have not gained little by this day's
meditation, in having discovered the source of error
and falsity.
And certainly this can be no other than what I have
now explained: for as often as I so restrain my will
within the limits of my knowledge, that it forms no
judgment except regarding objects which are clearly
74 MEDITATION IV.
and distinctly represented to it by the understanding,
I can never be deceived ; because every clear and dis-
tinct conception is doubtless something, and as such
cannot owe its origin to nothing, but must of necessity
have God for its author — God, I say, who, as su-
premely perfect, cannot, without a contradiction, be
the cause of any error; and consequently it is neces-
sary to conclude that every such conception [or judg-
ment] is true. Nor have I merely learned to-day what
I must avoid to escape error, but also what I must do
to arrive at the knowledge of truth ; for I will as-
suredly reach truth if I only fix my attention suffi-
ciently on all the things I conceive perfectly, and sepa-
rate these from others which I conceive more con-
fusedly and obscurely : to which for the future I shall
give diligent heed.
MEDITATION V.
OF THE ESSENCE OF MATERIAL THINGS ,* AND, AGAIN, OF
GOD ; THAT HE EXISTS.
Several other questions remain for consideration re-
specting the attributes of God and my own nature or
mind. I will, however, on some other occasion per-
haps resume the investigation of these. Meanwhile,
as I have discovered what must be done and what
avoided to arrive at the knowledge of truth, what I
have chiefly to do is to essay to emerge from the state
of doubt in which I have for some time been, and to
discover whether anything can be known with cer-
tainty regarding material objects. But before con-
sidering whether such objects as I conceive exist with-
out me, I must examine their ideas in so far as these
are to be found in my consciousness, and discover
which of them are distinct and which confused.
In the first place, I distinctly imagine that quantity
which the philosophers commonly call continuous, or
the extension in length, breadth, and depth that is in
this quantity, or rather in the object to which it is at-
tributed. Further, I can enumerate in it many diverse
parts, and attribute to each of these all sorts of sizes,
figures, situations, and local motions ; and, in fine, I
can assign to each of these motions all degrees of
duration. And I not only distinctly know these things
when I thus consider them in general ; but besides, by
a little attention, I discover innumerable particulars
75
76 MEDITATION V.
respecting figures, numbers, motion, and the like,
which are so evidently true, and so accordant with my
nature, that when I now discover them I do not so much
appear to learn anything new, as to call to remem-
brance what I before knew, or for the first time to re-
mark what was before in my mind, but to which I had
not hitherto directed my attention. And what I here
find of most importance is, that I discover in my mind
innumerable ideas of certain objects, which cannot be
esteemed pure negations, although perhaps they pos-
sess no reality beyond my thought, and which are not
framed by me though it may be in my power to think,
or not to think them, but possess true and immutable
natures of their own. As, for example, when I im-
agine a triangle, although there is not perhaps and
never was in any place in the universe apart from my
thought one such figure, it remains true nevertheless
that this figure possesses a certain determinate nature,
form, or essence, which is immutable and eternal, and
not framed by me, nor in any degree dependent on
my thought ; as appears from the circumstance, that
diverse properties of the triangle may be demonstrated,
viz., that its three angles are equal to two right, that
its greatest side is subtended by its greatest angle, and
the like, which, whether I will or not, I now clearly
discern to belong to it, although before I did not at all
think of them, when, for the first time, I imagined a
triangle, and which accordingly cannot be said to have
been invented by me. Nor is it a valid objection to
allege, that perhaps this idea of a triangle came into
my mind by the medium of the senses, through my
having seen bodies of a triangular figure; for I am
able to form in thought an innumerable variety of
OF THE ESSENCE OF MATERIAL THINGS. 77
figures with regard to which it cannot be supposed that
they were ever objects of sense, and I can nevertheless
demonstrate diverse properties of their nature no less
than of the triangle, all of which are assuredly true
since I clearly conceive them: and they are therefore
something, and not mere negations; for it is highly
evident that all that is true is something, [truth being
identical with existence] ; and I have already fully
shown the truth of the principle, that whatever is
clearly and distinctly known is true. And although
this had not been demonstrated, yet the nature of my
mind is such as to compel me to assent to what I
clearly conceive while I so conceive it; and I recollect
that even when I still strongly adhered to the objects
of sense, I reckoned among the number of the most
certain truths those I clearly conceived relating to
figures, numbers, and other matters that pertain to
arithmetic and geometry, and in general to the pure
mathematics.
But now if because I can draw from my thought the
idea of an object, it follows that all I clearly and dis-
tinctly apprehend to pertain to this object, does in
truth belong to it, may I not from this derive an argu-
ment for the existence of God ? It is certain that I no
less find the idea of a God in my consciousness, that is,
the idea of a being supremely perfect, than that of any
figure or number whatever : and I know with not less
clearness and distinctness that an [actual and] eternal
existence pertains to his nature than that all which is
demonstrable of any figure or number really belongs
to the nature of that figure or number ; and, therefore,
although all the conclusions of the preceding Medita-
tions were false, the existence of God would pass with
7 8 MEDITATION V.
me for a truth at least as certain as I ever judged any
truth of mathematics to be, although indeed such a
doctrine may at first sight appear to contain more
sophistry than truth. For, as I have been accustomed
in every other matter to distinguish between existence
and essence, I easily believe that the existence can be
separated from the essence of God, and that thus God
may be conceived as not actually existing. But, never-
theless, when I think of it more attentively, it appears
that the existence can no more be separated from the
essence of God, than the idea of a mountain from that
of a valley, or the equality of its three angles to two
right angles, from the essence of a [rectilineal] tri-
angle; so that it is not less impossible to conceive a
God, that is, a being supremely perfect, to whom exist-
ence is awanting, or who is devoid of a certain perfec-
tion, than to conceive a mountain without a valley.
But though, in truth, I cannot conceive a God unless
as existing, any more than I can a mountain without a
valley, yet, just as it does not follow that there is any
mountain in the world merely because I conceive a
mountain with a valley, so likewise, though I conceive
God as existing, it does not seem to follow on that ac-
count that God exists ; for my thought imposes no
necessity on things; and as I may imagine a winged
horse, though there be none such, so I could perhaps
attribute existence to God, though no God existed.
But the cases are not analogous, and a fallacy lurks
under the semblance of this objection: for because I
cannot conceive a mountain without a valley, it does
not follow that there is any mountain or valley in ex-
istence, but simply that the mountain or valley,
whether they do or do not exist, are inseparable from
OF THE ESSENCE OF MATERIAL THINGS. 79
each other ; whereas, on the other hand, because I can-
not conceive God unless as existing, it follows that ex-
istence is inseparable from him, and therefore that he
really exists : not that this is brought about by my
thought, or that it imposes any necessity on things,
but, on the contrary, the necessity which lies in the
thing itself, that is, the necessity of the existence of
God, determines me to think in this way : for it is not
in my power to conceive a God without existence, that
is, a being supremely perfect, and yet devoid of an ab-
solute perfection, as I am free to imagine a horse with
or without wings.
Nor must it be alleged here as an objection, that it is
in truth necessary to admit that God exists, after hav-
ing supposed him to possess all perfections, since exist-
ence is one of them, but that my original supposition
was not necessary; just as it is not necessary to think
that all quadrilateral figures can be inscribed in the
circle, since, if I supposed this, I should be constrained
to admit that the rhombus, being a figure of four sides,
can be therein inscribed, which, however, is manifestly
false. This objection is, I say, incompetent; for al-
though it may not be necessary that I shall at any time
entertain the notion of Deity, yet each time I happen
to think of a first and sovereign being, and to draw, so
to speak, the idea of him from the storehouse of the
mind, I am necessitated to attribute to him all kinds of
perfections, though I may not then enumerate them all,
nor think of each of them in particular. And this
necessity is sufficient, as soon as I discover that exist-
ence is a perfection, to cause me to infer the existence
of this first and sovereign being : just as it is not nec-
essary that I should ever imagine any triangle, but
8o MEDITATION V.
whenever I am desirous of considering a rectilineal
figure composed of only three angles, it is absolutely
necessary to attribute those properties to it from which
it is correctly inferred that its three angles are not
greater than two right angles, although perhaps I may
not. then advert to this relation in particular. But
when I consider what figures are capable of being in-
scribed in the circle, it is by no means necessary to hold
that all quadrilateral figures are of this number; on
the contrary, I cannot even imagine such to be the case,
so long as I shall be unwilling to accept in thought
aught that I do not clearly and distinctly conceive:
and consequently there is a vast difference between
false suppositions, as is the one in question, and the
true ideas that were born with me, the first and chief
of which is the idea of God. For indeed I discern on
many grounds that this idea is not factitious, depend-
ing simply on my thought, but that it is the representa-
tion of a true and immutable nature : in the first place,
because I can conceive no other being, except God, to
whose essence existence [necessarily] pertains; in the
second, because it is impossible to conceive two or
more gods of this kind ; and it being supposed that one
such God exists, I clearly see that he must have existed
from all eternity, and will exist to all eternity ; and
finally, because I apprehend many other properties in
God, none of which I can either diminish or change.
But, indeed, whatever mode of probation I in the
end adopt, it always returns to this, that it is only the
things I clearly and distinctly conceive which have the
power of completely persuading me. And although,
of the objects I conceive in this manner, some, indeed,
are obvious to every one, while others are only dis-
OF THE ESSENCE OF MATERIAL THINGS. 81
covered after close and careful investigation ; never-
theless, after they are once discovered, the latter are
not esteemed less certain than the former. Thus, for
example, to take the case of a right-angled triangle, al-
though it is not so manifest at first that the square of
the base is equal to the squares of the other two sides,
as that the base is opposite to the greatest angle; never-
theless, after it is once apprehended, we are as firmly-
persuaded of the truth of the former as of the latter.
And, with respect to God, if I were not pre-occupied
by prejudices, and my thought beset on all sides by the
continual presence of the images of sensible objects, I
should know nothing sooner or more easily than the
fact of his being. For is there any truth more clear
than the existence of a Supreme Being, or of God, see-
ing it is to his essence alone that [necessary and eter-
nal] existence pertains? And although the right con-
ception of this truth has cost me much close thinking,
nevertheless at present I feel not only as assured of it
as of what I deem most certain, but I remark further
that the certitude of all other truths is so absolutely
dependent on it, that without this knowledge it is im-
possible ever to know anything perfectly.
For although I am of such a nature as to be unable,
while I possess a very clear and distinct apprehension
of a matter, to resist the conviction of its truth, yet be-
cause my constitution is also such as to incapacitate me
from keeping my mind continually fixed on the same
object, and as I frequently recollect a past judgment
without at the same time being able to recall the
grounds of it, it may happen meanwhile that other rea-
sons are presented to me which would readily cause me
to change my opinion, if I did not know that God ex-
82 MEDITATION V.
isted ; and thus I should possess no true and certain
knowledge, but merely vague and vacillating opinions.
Thus, for example, when I consider the nature of the
[rectilineal] triangle, it most clearly appears to me,
who have been instructed in the principles of geom-
etry, that its three angles are equal to two right angles,
and I find it impossible to believe otherwise, while I
apply my mind to the demonstration ; but as soon as I
cease from attending to the process of proof, although
I still remember that I had a clear comprehension of it,
yet I may readily come to doubt of the truth demon-
strated, if I do not know that there is a God : for I may
persuade myself that I have been so constituted by na-
ture as to be sometimes deceived, even in matters
which I think I apprehend with the greatest evidence
and certitude, especially when I recollect that I fre-
quently considered many things to be true and certain
which other reasons afterwards constrained me to
reckon as wholly false.
But after I have discovered that God exists, seeing
I also at the same time observed that all things depend
on him, and that he is no deceiver, and thence inferred
that all which I clearly and distinctly perceive is of
necessity true : although I no longer attend to the
grounds of a judgment, no opposite reason can be al-
leged sufficient to lead me to doubt of its truth, pro-
vided only I remember that I once possessed a clear
and distinct comprehension of it. My knowledge of it
thus becomes true and certain. And this same knowl-
edge extends likewise to whatever I remember to have
formerly demonstrated, as the truths of geometry and
the like : for what can be alleged against them to lead
me to doubt of them? Will it be that my nature is
OF THE ESSENCE OF MATERIAL THINGS. 83
such that I may be frequently deceived ? But I al-
ready know that I cannot be deceived in judgments of
the grounds of which I possess a clear knowledge.
Will it be that I formerly deemed things to be true and
certain which I afterwards discovered to be false ? But
I had no clear and distinct knowledge of any of those
things, and, being as yet ignorant of the rule by which
I am assured of the truth of a judgment, I was led to
give my assent to them on grounds which I afterwards
discovered were less strong than at the time I imagined
them to be. What further objection, then, is there?
Will it be said that perhaps I am dreaming (an objec-
tion I lately myself raised), or that all the thoughts of
which I am now conscious have no more truth than the
reveries of my dreams? But although, in truth, I
should be dreaming, the rule still holds that all which
is clearly presented to my intellect is indisputably true.
And thus I very clearly see that the certitude and
truth of all science depends on the knowledge alone of
the true God, insomuch that, before I knew him, I
could have no perfect knowledge of any other thing.
And now that I know him, I possess the means of ac-
quiring a perfect knowledge respecting innumerable
matters, as well relative to God himself and other in-
tellectual objects as to corporeal nature, in so far as it
is the object of pure mathematics [which do not con-
sider whether it exists or not].
MEDITATION VI.
OF THE EXISTENCE OF MATERIAL THINGS, AND OF THE
REAL DISTINCTION BETWEEN THE MIND AND BODY
OF MAN.
There now only remains the inquiry as to whether
material things exist. With regard to this question, I
at least know with certainty that such things may exist,
in as far as they constitute the object of the pure
mathematics, since, regarding them in this aspect, I
can conceive them clearly and distinctly. For there
can be no doubt that God possesses the power of pro-
ducing all the objects I am able distinctly to conceive,
and I never considered anything impossible to him, un-
less when I experienced a contradiction in the attempt
to conceive it aright. Further, the faculty of imagina-
tion which I possess, and of which I am conscious that
I make use when I apply myself to the consideration of
material things, is sufficient to persuade me of their
existence: for, when I attentively consider what im-
agination is, I rind that! it is simply a certain applica-
tion of the cognitive faculty (facilitas cognoscitiva) to
a body which is immediately present to it, and which
therefore exists.
And to render this quite clear, I remark, in the first
place, the difference that subsists between imagination
and pure intellection [or conception]. For example,
when I imagine a triangle I not only conceive (intel-
ligo) that it is a figure comprehended by three lines,
84
OF THE EXISTENCE OF MATERIAL THINGS. 85
but at the same time also I look upon (intueor) these
three lines as present by the power and internal appli-
cation of my mind (acie mentis), and this is what I call
imagining. But if I desire to think of a chiliogon, I
indeed rightly conceive that it is a figure composed of
a thousand sides, as easily as I conceive that a triangle
is a figure composed of only three sides ; but I cannot
imagine the thousand sides of a chiliogon as I do the
three sides of a triangle, nor, so to speak, view them as
present [with the eyes of my mind]. And although,
in accordance with the habit I have of always imagin-
ing something when I think of corporeal things, it may
happen that, in conceiving a chiliogon, I confusedly
represent some figure to myself, yet it is quite evident
that this is not a chiliogon, since it in no wise differs
from that which I would represent to myself, if I were
to think of a myriogon, or any other figure of many
sides ; nor would this representation be of any use in
discovering and unfolding the properties that consti-
tute the difference between a chiliogon and other poly-
gons. But if the question turns on a pentagon, it is
quite true that I can conceive its figure, as well as that
of a chiliogon, without the aid of imagination ; but I
can likewise imagine it by applying the attention of my
mind to its five sides, and at the same time to the area
which they contain. Thus I observe that a special ef-
fort of mind is necessary to the act of imagination,
which is not required to conceiving or understanding
(ad intelligendum) ; and this special exertion of mind
clearly shows the difference between imagination and
pure intellection (imaginatio et intellect™ pur a). I
remark, besides, that this power of imagination which
I possess, in as far as it differs from the power of con-
86 MEDITATION VI.
ceiving, is in no way necessary to my [nature or] es-
sence, that is, to the essence of my mind ; for although
I did not possess it, I should still remain the same that
I now am, from which it seems we may conclude that
it depends on something different from the mind. And
I easily understand that, if some body exists, with
which my mind is so conjoined and united as to be
able, as it were, to consider it when it chooses, it may
thus imagine corporeal objects; so that this mode of
thinking differs from pure intellection only in this re-
spect, that the mind in conceiving turns in some way
upon itself, and considers some one of the ideas it pos-
sesses within itself ; but in imagining it turns towards
the body, and contemplates in it some object conformed
to the idea which it either of itself conceived or appre-
hended by sense. I easily understand, I say, that
imagination may be thus formed, if it is true that there
are bodies ; and because I find no other obvious mode
of explaining it, I thence, with probability, conjecture
that they exist, but only with probability ; and although
I carefully examine all things, nevertheless I do not
find that, from the distinct idea of corporeal nature I
have in my imagination, I can necessarily infer the
existence of any body.
But I am accustomed to imagine many other objects
besides that corporeal nature which is the object of the
pure mathematics, as, for example, colours, sounds,
tastes, pain, and the like, although with less distinct-
ness ; and, inasmuch as I perceive these objects much
better by the senses, through the medium of which and
of memory, they seem to have reached the imagination,
I believe that, in order the more advantageously to
examine them, it is proper I should at the same time
OF THE EXISTENCE OF MATERIAL THINGS. 87
examine what sense-perception is, and inquire whether
from those ideas that are apprehended by this mode of
thinking (consciousness), I cannot obtain a certain
proof of the existence of corporeal objects.
And, in the first place, I will recall to my mind the
things I have hitherto held as true, because perceived
by the senses, and the foundations upon which my be-
lief in their truth rested ; I will, in the second place,
examine the reasons that afterwards constrained me to
doubt of them ; and, finally, I will consider what of
them I ought now to believe.
Firstly, then, I perceived that I had a head, hands,
feet, and other members composing that body which I
considered as part, or perhaps even as a whole, of my-
self. I perceived further, that that body was placed
among many others, by which it was capable of being
affected in diverse ways, both beneficial and hurtful ;
and what was beneficial I remarked by a certain sensa-
tion of pleasure, and what was hurtful by a sensation
of pain. And, besides this pleasure and pain, I was
likewise conscious of hunger, thirst, and other appe-
tites, as well as certain corporeal inclinations towards
joy, sadness, anger, and similar passions. And, out of
myself, besides the extension, figure, and motions of
bodies, I likewise perceived in them hardness, heat, and
the other tactile qualities, and, in addition, light,
colours, odours, tastes, and sounds, the variety of
which gave me the means of distinguishing the sky,
the earth, the sea, and generally all the other bodies,
from one another. And certainly, considering the
ideas of all these qualities, which were presented to my
mind, and which alone I properly and immediately per-
ceived, it was not without reason that I thought I per-
88 MEDITATION VI.
ceived certain objects wholly different from my
thought, namely, bodies from which those ideas pro-
ceeded ; for I was conscious that the ideas were pre-
sented to me without my consent being required, so
that I could not perceive any object, however desirous
I might be, unless it were present to the organ of sense ;
and it was wholly out of my power not to perceive it
when it was thus present. And because the ideas I
perceived by the senses were much more lively and
clear, and even, in their own way, more distinct than
any of those I could of myself frame by meditation, or
which I found impressed on my memory, it seemed
that they could not have proceeded from myself, and
must therefore have been caused in me by some other
objects ; and as of those objects I had no knowledge be-
yond what the ideas themselves gave me, nothing was
so likely to occur to my mind as the supposition that
the objects were similar to the ideas which they caused.
And because I recollected also that I had formerly
trusted to the senses, rather than to reason, and that
the ideas which I myself formed were not so clear as
those I perceived by sense, and that they were even for
the most part composed of parts of the latter, I was
readily persuaded that I had no idea in my intellect
which had not formerly passed through the senses.
Nor was I altogether wrong in likewise believing that
that body which, by a special right, I called my own,
pertained to me more properly and strictly than any of
the others ; for in truth, I could never be separated
from it as from other bodies : I felt in it and on account
of it all my appetites and affections, and in fine I was
affected in its parts by pain and the titillation of pleas-
ure, and not in the parts of the other bodies that were
OF THE EXISTENCE OF MATERIAL THINGS. 89
separated from it. But when I inquired into the rea-
son why, from this I know not what sensation of pain,
sadness of mind should follow, and why from the sen-
sation of pleasure joy should arise, or why this inde-
scribable twitching of the stomach, which I call hun-
ger, should put me in mind of taking food, and the
parchedness of the throat of drink, and so in other
cases, I was unable to give any explanation, unless that
I was so taught by nature; for there is assuredly no
affinity, at least none that I am able to comprehend, be-
tween this irritation of the stomach and the desire of
food, any more than between the perception of an ob-
ject that causes pain and the consciousness of sadness
which springs from the perception. And in the same
way it seemed to me that all the other judgments I had
formed regarding the objects of sense, were dictates of
nature; because I remarked that those judgments were
formed in me, before I had leisure to weigh and con-
sider the reasons that might constrain me to form
them.
But, afterwards, a wide experience by degrees
sapped the faith I had reposed in my senses ; for I fre-
quently observed that towers, which at a distance
seemed round, appeared square when more closely
viewed, and that colossal figures, raised on the summits
of these towers, looked like small statues, when viewed
from the bottom of them ; and, in other instances with-
out number, I also discovered error in judgments
founded on the external senses ; and not only in those
founded on the external, but even in those that rested
on the internal senses ; for is there aught more internal
than pain ? and yet I have sometimes been informed by
parties whose arm or leg had been amputated, that
go MEDITATION VI.
they still occasionally seemed to feel pain in that part
of the body which they had lost, — a circumstance that
led me to think that I could not be quite certain even
that any one of my members was affected when I felt
pain in it. And to these grounds of doubt I shortly
afterwards also added two others of very wide gener-
ality : the first of them was that I believed I never per-
ceived anything when awake which I could not oc-
casionally think I also perceived when asleep, and as I
do not believe that the ideas I seem to perceive in my
sleep proceed from objects external to me, I did not
any more observe any ground for believing this of such
as I seem to perceive when awake ; the second was that
since I was as yet ignorant of the author of my being,
or at least supposed myself to be so, I saw nothing to
prevent my having been so constituted by nature as
that I should be deceived even in matters that appeared
to me to possess the greatest truth. And, with respect
to the grounds on which I had before been persuaded
of the existence of sensible objects, I had no great diffi-
culty in finding suitable answers to them ; for as nature
seemed to incline me to many things from which reason
made me averse, I thought that I ought not to confide
much in its teachings. And although the perceptions
of the senses were not dependent on my will, I did not
think that I ought on that ground to conclude that they
proceeded from things different from myself, since per-
haps there might be found in me some faculty, though
hitherto unknown to me, which produced them.
But now that I begin to know myself better, and to
discover more clearly the author of my being, I do not,
indeed, think that I ought rashly to admit all which the
senses seem to teach, nor, on the other hand, is it my
OF THE EXISTENCE OF MATERIAL THINGS. 91
conviction that I ought to doubt in general of their
teachings.
And, firstly, because I know that all which I clearly
and distinctly conceive can be produced by God exactly
as I conceive it, it is sufficient that I am able clearly
and distinctly to conceive one thing apart from another,
in order to be certain that the one is different from the
other, seeing they may at least be made to exist sepa-
rately, by the omnipotence of God ; and it matters not
by what power this separation is made, in order to be
compelled to judge them different; and, therefore,
merely because I know with certitude that I exist, and
because, in the meantime, I do not observe that aught
necessarily belongs to my nature or essence beyond my
being a thinking thing, I rightly conclude that my es-
sence consists only in my being a thinking thing, [or a
substance whose whole essence or nature is merely
thinking]. And although I may, or rather, as I will
shortly say, although I certainly do possess a body with
which I am very closely conjoined; nevertheless, be-
cause, on the one hand, I have a clear and distinct idea
of myself, in as far as I am only a thinking and unex-
tended thing, and as, on the other hand, I possess a
distinct idea of body, in as far as it is only an extended
and unthinking thing, it is certain that I, [that is, my
mind, by which I am what I am], is entirely and truly
distinct from my body, and may exist without it.
Moreover, I find in myself diverse faculties of think-
ing that have each their special mode: for example, I
find I possess the faculties of imagining and perceiv-
ing, without which I can indeed clearly and distinctly
conceive myself as entire, but I cannot reciprocally con-
ceive them without conceiving myself, that is to say,
92 MEDITATION VI.
without an intelligent substance in which they reside,
for [in the notion we have of them, or to use the terms
of the schools] in their formal concept, they comprise
some sort of intellection ; whence I perceive that they
are distinct from myself as modes are from things. I
remark likewise certain other faculties, as the power of
changing place, of assuming diverse figures, and the
like, that cannot be conceived and cannot therefore
exist, any more than the preceding, apart from a sub-
stance in which they inhere. It is very evident, how-
ever, that these faculties, if they really exist, must be-
long to some corporeal or extended substance, since in
their clear and distinct concept there is contained some
sort of extension, but no intellection at all. Farther,
I cannot doubt but that there is in me a certain passive
faculty of perception, that is, of receiving and taking
knowledge of the ideas of sensible things; but this
would be useless to me, if there did not also exist in
me, or in some other thing, another active faculty capa-
ble of forming and producing those ideas. But this
active faculty cannot be in me [in as far as I am but a
thinking thing], seeing that it does not presuppose
thought, and also that those ideas are frequently pro-
duced in my mind without my contributing to it in any
way, and even frequently contrary to my will. This
faculty must therefore exist in some substance differ-
ent from me, in which all the objective reality of the
ideas that are produced by this faculty, is contained
formally or eminently, as I before remarked ; and this
substance is either a body, that is to say, a corporeal
nature in which is contained formally [and in effect]
all that is objectively [and by representation] in those
ideas ; or it is God himself, or some other creature, of
OF THE EXISTENCE OF MATERIAL THINGS. 93
a rank superior to body, in which the same is contained
eminently. But as God is no deceiver, it is manifest
that he does not of himself and immediately communi-
cate those ideas to me, nor even by the intervention of
any creature in which their objective reality is not for-
mally, but only eminently, contained. For as he has
given me no faculty whereby I can discover this to be
the case, but, on the contrary, a very strong inclination
to believe that those ideas arise from corporeal objects,
I do not see how he could be vindicated from the
charge of deceit, if in truth they proceeded from any
other source, or were produced by other causes than
corporeal things : and accordingly it must be con-
cluded, that corporeal objects exist. Nevertheless
they are not perhaps exactly such as we perceive by the
senses, for their comprehension by the senses is, in
many instances, very obscure and confused ; but it is at
least necessary to admit that all which I clearly and
distinctly conceive as in them, that is, generally speak-
ing, all that is comprehended in the object of specula-
tive geometry, really exists external to me.
But with respect to other things which are either only
particular, as, for example, that the sun is of such a
size and figure, etc., or are conceived with less clearness
and distinctness, as light, sound, pain, and the like, al-
though they are highly dubious and uncertain, never-
theless on the ground alone that God is no deceiver,
and that consequently he has permitted no falsity in
my opinions which he has not likewise given me a
faculty of correcting, I think I may with safety con-
clude that I possess in myself the means of arriving at
the truth. And, in the first place, it cannot be doubted
that in each of the dictates of nature there is some
94 MEDITATION VI.
truth : for by nature, considered in general, I now un-
derstand nothing more than God himself, or the order
and disposition established by God in created things ;
and by my nature in particular I understand the assem-
blage of all that God has given me.
But there is nothing which that nature teaches me
more expressly [or more sensibly] than that I have a
body which is ill affected when I feel pain, and stands
in need of food and drink when I experience the sensa-
tions of hunger and thirst, etc. And therefore I ought
not to doubt but that there is some truth in these infor-
mations.
Nature likewise teaches me by these sensations of
pain, hunger, thirst, etc., that I am not only lodged in
my body as a pilot in a vessel, but that I am besides so
intimately conjoined, and as it were intermixed with it,
that my mind and body compose a certain unity. For
if this were not the case, I should not feel pain when
my body is hurt, seeing I am merely a thinking thing,
but should perceive the wound by the understanding
alone, just as a pilot perceives by sight when any part
of his vessel is damaged ; and when my body has need
of food or drink, I should have a clear knowledge of
this, and not be made aware of it by the confused sen-
sations of hunger and thirst : for, in truth, all these sen-
sations of hunger, thirst, pain, etc., are nothing more
than certain confused modes of thinking, arising from
the union and apparent fusion of mind and body.
Besides this, nature teaches me that my own body is
surrounded by many other bodies, some of which I
have to seek after, and others to shun. And indeed, as
I perceive different sorts of colours, sounds, odours,
tastes, heat, hardness, etc., I safely conclude that there
OF THE EXISTENCE OF MATERIAL THINGS. 95
are in the bodies from which the diverse perceptions of
the senses proceed, certain varieties corresponding to
them, although, perhaps, not in reality like them ; and
since, among these diverse perceptions of the senses,
some are agreeable, and others disagreeable, there can
be no doubt that my body, or rather my entire self, in
as far as I am composed of body and mind, may be
variously affected, both beneficially and hurtfully, by
surrounding bodies. .
But there are many other beliefs which, though
seemingly the teaching of nature, are not in reality so,
but which obtained a place in my mind through a habit
of judging inconsiderately of things. It may thus
easily happen that such judgments shall contain error :
thus, for example, the opinion I have that all space in
which there is nothing to affect [or make an impression
on] my senses is void ; that in a hot body there is some-
thing in every respect similar to the idea of heat in my
mind ; that in a white or green body there is the same
whiteness or greenness which I perceive ; that in a bit-
ter or sweet body there is the same taste, and so in other
instances ; that the stars, towers, and all distant bodies,
are of the same size and figure as they appear to our
eyes, etc. But that I may avoid everything like indis-
tinctness of conception, I must accurately define what I
properly understand by being taught by nature. For
nature is here taken in a narrower sense than when it
signifies the sum of all the things which God has given
me ; seeing that in that meaning the notion compre-
hends much that belongs only to the mind [to which I
am not here to be understood as referring when I use
the term nature] ; as, for example, the notion I have of
the truth, that what is done cannot be undone, and all
gô MEDITATION VI.
the other truths I discern by the natural light [without
the aid of the body] ; and seeing that it comprehends
likewise much besides that belongs only to body, and is
not here any more contained under the name nature, as
the quality of heaviness, and the like, of which I do not
speak, — the term being reserved exclusively to desig-
nate the things which God has given to me as a being
composed of mind and body. But nature, taking the
term in the sense explained, teaches me to shun what
causes in me the sensation of pain, and to pursue what
affords me the sensation of pleasure, and other things
of this sort ; but I do not discover that it teaches me, in
addition to this, from these diverse perceptions of the
senses, to draw any conclusions respecting external ob-
jects without a previous [careful and mature] consid-
eration of them by the mind ; for it is, as appears to me,
the office of the mind alone, and not of the composite
whole of mind and body, to discern the truth in those
matters. Thus, although the impression a star makes
on my eye is not larger than that from the flame of a
candle, I do not, nevertheless, experience any real or
positive impulse determining me to believe that the star
is not greater than the flame ; the true account of the
matter being merely that I have so judged from my
youth without any rational ground. And, though on
approaching the fire I feel heat, and even pain on ap-
proaching it too closely, I have, however, from this no
ground for holding that something resembling the heat
I feel is in the fire, any more than that there is some-
thing similar to the pain ; all that I have ground for be-
lieving is, that there is something in it, whatever it may
be, which excites in me those sensations of heat or pain.
So also, although there are spaces in which I find noth-
OF THE EXISTENCE OF MATERIAL THINGS. 97
ing to excite and affect my senses, I must not therefore
conclude that those spaces contain in them no body ; for
I see that in this, as in many other similar matters, I
have been accustomed to pervert the order of nature,
because these perceptions of the senses, although given
me by nature merely to signify to my mind what things
are beneficial and hurtful to the composite whole of
which it is a part, and being sufficiently clear and dis-
tinct for that purpose, are nevertheless used by me as
infallible rules by which to determine immediately the
essence of the bodies that exist out of me, of which they
can of course afford me only the most obscure and con-
fused knowledge.
But I have already sufficiently considered how it hap-
pens that, notwithstanding the supreme goodness of
God, there is falsity in my judgments. A difficulty,
however, here presents itself, respecting the things
which I am taught by nature must be pursued or
avoided, and also respecting the internal sensations in
which I seem to have occasionally detected error, [and
thus to be directly deceived by nature] : thus, for exam-
ple, I may be so deceived by the agreeable taste of some
viand with which poison has been mixed, as to be in-
duced to take the poison. In this case, however, nature
may be excused, for it simply leads me to desire the
viand for its agreeable taste, and not the poison, which
is unknown to it ; and thus we can infer nothing from
this circumstance beyond that our nature is not om-
niscient ; at which there is assuredly no ground for sur-
prise, since, man being of a finite nature, his knowl-
edge must likewise be of limited perfection. But we
also not unfrequently err in that to which we are di-
rectly impelled by nature, as is the case with invalids
98 MEDITATION VI.
who desire drink or food that would be hurtful to them.
It will here, perhaps, be alleged that the reason why
such persons are deceived is that their nature is cor-
rupted; but this leaves the difficulty untouched, for a
sick man is not less really the creature of God than a
man who is in full health ; and therefore it is as repug-
nant to the goodness of God that the nature of the
former should be .deceitful as it is for that of the latter
to be so. And, as a clock, composed of wheels and
counter weights, observes not the less accurately all the
laws of nature when it is ill made, and points out the
hours incorrectly, than when it satisfies the desire of
the maker in every respect ; so likewise if the body of
man be considered as a kind of machine, so made up
and composed of bones, nerves, muscles, veins, blood,
and skin, that although there were in it no mind, it
would still exhibit the same motions which it at present
manifests involuntarily, and therefore without the aid
of the mind, [and simply by the dispositions of its or-
gans], I easily discern that it would also be as natural
for such a body, supposing it dropsical, for example,
to experience the parchedness of the throat that is
usually accompanied in the mind by the sensation of
thirst, and to be disposed by this parchedness to move
its nerves and its other parts in the way required for
drinking, and thus increase its malady and do itself
harm, as it is natural for it, when it is not indisposed to
be stimulated to drink for its good by a similar cause ;
and although looking to the use for which a clock was
destined by its maker, I may say that it is deflected
from its proper nature when it incorrectly indicates the
hours, and on the same principle, considering the ma-
chine of the human body as having been formed by God
OF THE EXISTENCE OF MATERIAL THINGS. 99
for the sake of the motions which it usually manifests,
although I may likewise have ground for thinking that
it does not follow the order of its nature when the
throat is parched and drink does not tend to its preser-
vation, nevertheless I yet plainly discern that this latter
acceptation of the term nature is very different from the
other ; for this is nothing more than a certain denomi-
nation, depending entirely on my thought, and hence
called extrinsic, by which I compare a sick man and an
imperfectly constructed clock with the idea I have of a
man in good health and a well made clock; while by
the other acceptation of nature is understood something
which is truly found in things, and therefore possessed
of some truth.
But certainly, although in respect of a dropsical
body, it is only by way of exterior denomination that
we say its nature is corrupted, when, without requiring
drink, the throat is parched ; yet, in respect of the com-
posite whole, that is, of the mind in its union with the
body, it is not a pure denomination, but really an error
of nature, for it to feel thirst when drink would be hurt-
ful to it : and, accordingly, it still remains to be consid-
ered why it is that the goodness of God does not pre-
vent the nature of man thus taken from being falla-
cious.
To commence this examination accordingly, I here
remark, in the first place, that there is a vast difference
between mind and body, in respect that body, from its -
nature, is always divisible, and that mind is entirely
indivisible. For in truth, when I consider the mind,
that is, when I consider myself in so far only as I am
a thinking thing, I can distinguish in myself no parts,
but I very clearly discern that I am somewhat abso-
ioo MEDITATION VI.
lutely one and entire ; and although the whole mind
seems to be united to the whole body, yet, when a foot,
an arm, or any other part is cut off, I am conscious that
nothing has been taken from my mind ; nor can the
faculties of willing, perceiving, conceiving, etc., prop-
erly be called its parts, for it is the same mind that is
exercised [all entire] in willing, in perceiving, and in
conceiving, etc. But quite the opposite holds in cor-
poreal or extended things ; for I cannot imagine any
one of them [how small soever it may be], which I
cannot easily sunder in thought, and which, therefore,
I do not know to be divisible. This would be suffi-
cient to teach me that the mind or soul of man is en-
tirely different from the body, if I had not already been
apprised of it on other grounds.
I remark, in the next place, that the mind does not
immediately receive the impression from all the parts of
the body, but only from the brain, or perhaps even from
one small part of it, viz., that in which the common
sense (sensus communis) is said to be, which as often
as it is affected in the same way, gives rise to the same
perception in the mind, although meanwhile the other
parts of the body may be diversely disposed, as is
proved by innumerable experiments, which it is un-
necessary here to enumerate.
I remark, besides, that the nature of body is such
that none of its parts can be moved by another part a
little removed from the other, which cannot likewise be
moved in the same way by any one of the parts that lie
between those two, although the most remote part does
not act at all. As, for example, in the cord a, b, c, d,
[which is in tension], if its last part d, be pulled, the
first part a, will not be moved in a different way than
OF THE EXISTENCE OF MATERIAL THINGS, iox
it would be were one of the intermediate parts b or c
to be pulled, and the last part d meanwhile to remain
fixed. And in the same way, when I feel pain in the
foot, the science of physics teaches me that this sensa-
tion is experienced by means of the nerves dispersed
over the foot, which, extending like cords from it to
the brain, when they are contracted in the foot, con-
tract at the same time the inmost parts of the brain in
which they have their origin, and excite in these parts
a certain motion appointed by nature to cause in the
mind a sensation of pain, as if existing in the foot : but
as these nerves must pass through the tibia, the leg, the
loins, the back, and neck, in order to reach the brain, it
may happen that although their extremities in the foot
are not affected, but only certain of their parts that pass
through the loins or neck, the same movements, never-
theless, are excited in the brain by this motion as would
have been caused there by a hurt received in the foot,
and hence the mind will necessarily feel pain in the
foot, just as if it had been hurt ; and the same is true
of all the other perceptions of our senses.
I remark, finally, that as each of the movements that
are made in the part of the brain by which the mind is
immediately affected, impresses it with but a single sen-
sation, the most likely supposition in the circumstances
is, that this movement causes the mind to experience,
among all the sensations which it is capable of impress-
ing upon it, that one which is the best fitted, and gen-
erally the most useful for the preservation of the
human body when it is in full health. But experience
shows us that all the perceptions which nature has
given us are of such a kind as I have mentioned ; and
accordingly, there is nothing found in them that does
102 MEDITATION VI.
not manifest the power and goodness of God. Thus,
for example, when the nerves of the foot are violently
or more than usually Shaken, the motion passing
through the medulla of the spine to the innermost parts
of the brain affords a sign to the mind on which it ex-
periences a sensation, viz., of pain, as if it were in the
foot, by which the mind is admonished and excited to
do its utmost to remove the cause of it as dangerous
and hurtful to the foot. It is true that God could have
so constituted the nature of man as that the same mo-
tion in the brain would have informed the mind of
something altogether different: the motion might, for
example, have been the occasion on which the mind be-
came conscious of itself, in so far as it is in the brain,
or in so far as it is in some place intermediate between
the foot and the brain, or, finally, the occasion on which
it perceived some other object quite different, what-
ever that might be ; but nothing of all this would have
so well contributed to the preservation of the body as
that which the mind actually feels. In the same way,
when we stand in need of drink, there arises from this
want a certain parchedness in the throat that moves its
nerves, and by means of them the internal parts of the
brain ; and this movement affects the mind with the sen-
sation of thirst, because there is nothing on that oc-
casion which is more useful for us than to be made
aware that we have need of drink for the preservation
of our health ; and so in other instances.
Whence it is quite manifest that, notwithstanding
the sovereign goodness of God, the nature of man, in
so far as it is composed of mind and body, cannot but
be sometimes fallacious. For, if there is any cause
which excites, not in the foot, but in some one of the
OF THE EXISTENCE OF MATERIAL THINGS. 103
parts of the nerves that stretch from the foot to the
brain, or even in the brain itself, the same movement
that is ordinarily created when the foot is ill affected,
pain will be felt, as it were, in the foot, and the sense
will thus be naturally deceived ; for as the same move-
ment in the brain can but impress the mind with the
same sensation, and as this sensation is much more fre-
quently excited by a cause which hurts the foot than by
one acting in a different quarter, it is reasonable that it
should lead the mind to feel pain in the foot rather than
in any other part of the body. And if it sometimes
happens that the parchedness of the throat does not
arise, as is usual, from drink being necessary for the
health of the body, but from quite the opposite cause,
as is the case with the dropsical, yet it is much better
that it should be deceitful in that instance, than if, on
the contrary, it were continually fallacious when the
body is well-disposed ; and the same holds true in other
cases.
And certainly this consideration is of great service,
not only in enabling me to recognize the errors to
which my nature is liable, but likewise in rendering it
more easy to avoid or correct them : for, knowing that
all my senses more usually indicate to me what is true
than what is false, in matters relating to the advantage
of the body, and being able almost always to make
use of more than a single sense in examining the same
object, and besides this, being able to use my memory
in connecting present with past knowledge, and my un-
derstanding which has already discovered all the causes
of my errors, I ought no longer to fear that falsity
maybe met with in what is daily presented to me by the
senses. And I ought to reject all the doubts of those
104 'MEDITATION VI.
bygone days, as hyperbolical and ridiculous, especially
the general uncertainty respecting sleep, which I could
not distinguish from the waking state : for I now find
a very marked difference between the two states, in re-
spect that our memory can never connect our dreams
with each other and with the course of life, in the way
it is in the habit of doing with events that occur when
we are awake. And, in truth, if some one, when I am
awake, appeared to me all of a sudden and as suddenly
disappeared, as do the images I see in sleep, so that I
could not observe either whence he came or whither he
went, I should not without reason esteem it either a
spectre or phantom formed in my brain, rather than a
real man. But when I perceive objects with regard to
which I can distinctly determine both the place whence
they come, and that in which they are, and the time at
which they appear to me, and when, without interrup-
tion, I can connect the perception I have of them with
the whole of the other parts of my life, I am perfectly
sure that what I thus perceive occurs while I am awake
and not during sleep. And I ought not in the least de-
gree to doubt of the truth of those presentations, if,
after having called together all my senses, my memory,
and my understanding for the purpose of examining
them, no deliverance is given by any one of these facul-
ties which is repugnant to that of any other : for since
God is no deceiver, it necessarily follows that I am not
herein deceived. But because the necessities of action
frequently oblige us to come to a determination before
we have had leisure for so careful an examination, it
must be confessed that the life of man is frequently
obnoxious to error with respect to individual objects ;
and we must, in conclusion, acknowledge the weakness
of our nature.
SELECTIONS
THE PRINCIPLES OF PHILOSOPHY
DESCARTES
TRANSLATED FROM THE LATIN AND COLLATED
WITH THE FRENCH
LETTER OF THE AUTHOR
TO THE
FRENCH TRANSLATOR OF THE PRINCIPLES OF PHILO-
SOPHY SERVING FOR A PREFACE.
Sir, — The version of my principles which you have
been at pains to make, is so elegant and finished as to
lead me to expect that the work will be more generally
read in French than in Latin, and better understood.
The only apprehension I entertain is lest the title
should deter some who have not been brought up to
letters, or with whom philosophy is in bad repute, be-
cause the kind they were taught has proved unsatisfac-
tory ; and this makes me think that it will be useful to
add a preface to it for the purpose of showing what the
matter of the work is, what end I had in view in writ-
ing it, and what utility may be derived from it. But
although it might be my part to write a preface of this
nature, seeing I ought to know those particulars better
than any other person, I cannot nevertheless prevail
upon myself to do anything more than merely to give
a summary of the chief points that fall, as I think, to be
discussed in it : and I leave it to your discretion to pre-
sent to the public such part of them as you shall judge
proper.
I should have desired, in the first place, to explain in
it what philosophy is, by commencing with the most
common matters, as, for example, that the word
107
io8 LETTER OF THE AUTHOR.
philosophy signifies the study of wisdom, and that
by wisdom is to be understood not merely pru-
dence in the management of affairs, but a perfect
knowledge of all that man can know, as well for
the conduct of his life as for the preservation of his
health and the discovery of all the arts, and that knowl-
edge to subserve these ends must necessarily be de-
duced from first causes ; so that in order to study the
acquisition of it (which is properly called philosophiz-
ing), we must commence with the investigation of
those first causes which are called Principles. Now
these principles must possess two conditions: in the
first place, they must be so clear and evident that the
human mind, when it attentively considers them, cannot
doubt of their truth ; in the second place, the knowl-
edge of other things must be so dependent on them as
that though the principles themselves may indeed be
known apart from what depends on them, the latter
cannot nevertheless be known apart from the former.
It will accordingly be necessary thereafter to endeavour
so to deduce from those principles the knowledge of
the things that depend on them, as that there may be
nothing in the whole series of deductions which is not
perfectly manifest. God is in truth the only being who
is absolutely wise, that is, who possesses a perfect
knowledge of all things ; but we may say that men are
more or less wise as their knowledge of the most im-
portant truths is greater or less. And I am confident
that there is nothing, in what I have now said, in which
all the learned do not concur.
I should, in the next place, have proposed to con-
sider the utility of philosophy, and at the same time
have shown that, since it embraces all that the human
LETTER OF THE AUTHOR. 109
mind can know, we ought to believe that it is by it we
are distinguished from savages and barbarians, and
that the civilisation and culture of a nation is regulated
by the degree in which true philosophy flourishes in it,
and, accordingly, that to contain true philosophers is
the highest privilege a state can enjoy. Besides this,
I should have shown that, as regards individuals, it is
not only useful for each man to have intercourse with
those who apply themselves to this study, but that it is
incomparably better he should himself direct his atten-
tion to it ; just as it is doubtless to be preferred that a
man should make use of his own eyes to direct his
steps, and enjoy by means of the same the beauties of
colour and light, than that he should blindly follow the
guidance of another ; though the latter course is cer-
tainly better than to have the eyes closed with no guide
except one's self. But to live without philosophizing
is in truth the same as keeping the eyes closed without
attempting to open them ; and the pleasure of seeing all
that sight discloses is not to be compared with the satis-
faction afforded by the discoveries of philosophy. And,
finally, this study is more imperatively requisite for the
regulation of our manners, and for conducting us
through life, than is the use of our eyes for directing
our steps. The brutes, which have only their bodies
to conserve, are continually occupied in seeking sources
of nourishment ; but men, of whom the chief part is
the mind, ought to make the search after wisdom their
principal care, for wisdom is the true nourishment of
the mind ; and I feel assured, moreover, that there are
very many who would not fail in the search, if they
would but hope for success in it, and knew the de-
gree of their capabilities for it. There is no mind,
no LETTER OF THE AUTHOR.
how ignoble soever it be, which remains so firmly
bound up in the objects of the senses, as not some-
time or other to turn itself away from them in the
aspiration after some higher good, although not
knowing frequently wherein that good consists. The
greatest favourites of fortune — those who have health,
honours, and riches in abundance — are not more
exempt from aspirations of this nature than others ; nay,
I am persuaded that these are the persons who sigh the
most deeply after another good greater and more per-
fect still than any they already possess. But the supreme
good, considered by natural reason without the light of
faith, is nothing more than the knowledge of truth
through its first causes, in other words, the wisdom of
which philosophy is the study. And, as all these par-
ticulars are indisputably true, all that is required to
gain assent to their truth is that they be well stated.
But as one is restrained from assenting to these doc-
trines by experience, which shows that they who make
pretensions to philosophy are often less wise and rea-
sonable than others who never applied themselves to
the study, I should have here shortly explained where-
in consists all the science we now possess, and what are
the degrees of wisdom at which we have arrived. The
first degree contains only notions so clear of them-
selves that they can be acquired without meditation ;
the second comprehends all that the experience of the
senses dictates ; the third, that which the conversation
of other men teaches us ; to which may be added as the
fourth, the reading, not of all books, but especially of
such as have been written by persons capable of con-
veying proper instruction, for it is a species of conver-
sation we hold with their authors. And it seems to me
LETTER OF THE AUTHOR. in
that all the wisdom we in ordinary possess is acquired
only in these four ways ; for I do not class divine reve-
lation among them, because it does not conduct us by
degrees, but elevates us at once to an infallible faith.
There have been, indeed, in all ages great minds who
endeavoured to find a fifth road to wisdom, incompar-
ably more sure and elevated than the other four. The
path they essayed was the search of first causes and
true principles, from which might be deduced the rea-
sons of all that can be known by man ; and it is to them
the appellation of philosophers has been more especially
accorded. I am not aware that there is any one of
them up to the present who has succeeded in this enter-
prise. The first and chief whose writings we possess,
are Plato and Aristotle, between whom there was no
difference, except that the former, following in the
footsteps of his master, Socrates, ingenuously con-
fessed that he had never yet been able to find anything
certain, and that he was contented to write what seemed
to him probable, imagining, for this end, certain prin-
ciples by which he endeavoured to account for the other
things. Aristotle, on the other hand, characterised by
less candour, although for twenty years the disciple of
Plato, and with no principles beyond those of his mas-
ter, completely reversed his mode of putting them, and
proposed as true and certain what it is probable he him-
self never esteemed as such. But these two men had
acquired much judgment and wisdom by the four pre-
ceding means, qualities which raised their authority
very high, so much so that those who succeeded them
were willing rather to acquiesce in their opinions, than
to seek better for themselves. The chief question
among their disciples, however, was as to whether we
ii2 LETTER OF THE AUTHOR.
ought to doubt of all things or hold some as certain, —
a dispute which led them on both sides into extrava-
gant errors ; for a part of those who were for doubt, ex-
tended it even to the actions of life, to the neglect of the
most ordinary rules required for its conduct ; those, on
the other hand, who maintained the doctrine of cer-
tainty, supposing that it must depend upon the senses,
trusted entirely to them. To such an extent was this
carried by Epicurus, that it is said he ventured to af-
firm, contrary to all the reasonings of the astronomers,
that the sun is no larger than it appears.
It is a fault we may remark in most disputes, that, as
truth is the mean between the two opinions that are
upheld, each disputant departs from it in proportion to
the degree in which he possesses the spirit of contradic-
tion. But the error of those who leant too much to the
side of doubt, was not followed for any length of time,
and that of the opposite party has been to some extent
corrected by the doctrine that the senses are deceitful
in many instances. Nevertheless, I do not know that
this error was wholly removed by showing that certi-
tude is not in the senses, but in the understanding alone
when it has clear perceptions ; and that while we only
possess the knowledge which is acquired in the first
four grades of wisdom, we ought not to doubt of the
things that appear to be true in what regards the con-
duct of life, nor esteem them as so certain that we can-
not change our opinions regarding them, even though
constrained by the evidence of reason.
From ignorance of this truth, or, if there was any
one to whom it was known, from neglect of it, the ma-
jority of those who in these later ages aspired to be
philosophers, blindly followed Aristotle, so that they
LETTER OF THE AUTHOR. 113
frequently corrupted the sense of his writings, and at-
tributed to him various opinions which he would not
recognise as his own were he now to return to the
world ; and those who did not follow him, among whom
are to be found many of the greatest minds, did yet not
escape being imbued with his opinions in their youth,
as these form the staple of instruction in the schools ;
and thus their minds were so preoccupied that they
could not rise to the knowledge of true principles.
And though I hold .all the philosophers in esteem, and
am unwilling to incur odium by my censure, I
can adduce a proof of my assertion, which I
do not think any of them will gainsay, which
is, that they all laid down as a principle what
they did not perfectly know. For example, I
know none of them who did not suppose that
there was gravity in terrestrial bodies ; but al-
though experience shows us very clearly that bodies
we call heavy descend towards the center of the
earth, we do not, therefore, know the nature of grav-
ity, that is, the cause or principle in virtue of which
bodies descend, and we must derive our knowledge of
it from some other source. The same may be said
of a vacuum and atoms, of heat and cold, of dryness
and humidity, and of salt, sulphur, and mercury, and
the other things of this sort which some have adopted
as their principles. But no conclusion deduced from
a principle which is not clear can be evident, even al-
though the deduction be formally valid ; and hence it
follows that no reasonings based on such principles
could lead them to the certain knowledge of any one
thing, nor consequently advance them one step in the
search after wisdom. And if they did discover any
114 LETTER OF THE AUTHOR.
truth, this was due to one or other of the four
means above mentioned. Notwithstanding this, I am
in no degree desirous to lessen the honour which each
of them can justly claim ; I am only constrained to say,
for the consolation of those who have not given their
attention to study, that just as in travelling, when we
turn our back upon the place to which we were going,
we recede the farther from it in proportion as we pro-
ceed in the new direction for a greater length of time
and with greater speed, so that, though we may be af-
terwards brought back to the right way, we cannot
nevertheless arrive at the destined place as soon as if
we had not moved backwards at all ; so in philosophy,
when we make use of false principles, we depart the
farther from the knowledge of truth and wisdom ex-
actly in proportion to the care with which we cultivate
them, and apply ourselves to the deduction of diverse
consequences from them, thinking that we are philoso-
phizing well, while we are only departing the farther
from the truth ; from which it must be inferred that
they who have learned the least of all that has been
hitherto distinguished by the name of philosophy are
the most fitted for the apprehension of truth.
After making those matters clear, I should, in the
next place, have desired to set forth the grounds for
holding that the true principles by which we may reach
that highest degree of wisdom wherein consists the
sovereign good of human life, are those I have pro-
posed in this work ; and two considerations alone are
sufficient to establish this — the first of which is, that
these principles are very clear, and the second, that we
can deduce all other truths from them ; for it is only
these two conditions that are required in true princi-
LETTER OF THE AUTHOR. 115
pies. But I easily prove that they are very clear;
firstly, by a reference to the manner in which I found
them, namely, by rejecting all propositions that were in
the least doubtful, for it is certain that such as could
not be rejected by this test when they were attentively
considered, are the most evident and clear which the
human mind can know. Thus by considering that he
who strives to doubt of all is unable nevertheless to
doubt that he is while he doubts, and that what reasons
thus, in not being able to doubt of itself and doubting
nevertheless of everything else, is not that which we
call our body, but what we name our mind or thought,
I have taken the existence of this thought for the first
principle, from which I very clearly deduced the fol-
lowing truths, namely, that there is a God who is the
author of all that is in the world, and who, being the
source of all truth, cannot have created our understand-
ing of such a nature as to be deceived in the judgments
it forms of the things of which it possesses a very clear
and distinct perception. Those are all the principles of
which I avail myself touching immaterial or metaphys-
ical objects, from which I most clearly deduce these
other principles of physical or corporeal things,
namely, that there are bodies extended in length,
breadth, and depth, which are of diverse figures and are
moved in a variety of ways. Such are in sum the
principles from which I deduce all other truths. The
second circumstance that proves the clearness of these
principles is, that they have been known in all ages, and
even received as true and indubitable by all men, with
the exception only of the existence of God, which has
been doubted by some, because they attributed too
n6 LETTER OF THE AUTHOR.
much to the perceptions of the senses, and God can
neither be seen nor touched.
But, though all the truths which I class among my
principles were known at all times, and by all men,
nevertheless, there has been no one up to the pres-
ent, who, so far as I know, has adopted them as prin-
ciples of philosophy : in other words, as such that we
can deduce from them the knowledge of whatever else
is in the world. It accordingly now remains for me
to prove that they are such ; and it appears to me that I
cannot better establish this than by the test of experi-
ence : in other words, by inviting readers to peruse the
following work. For, though I have not treated in it
of all matters — that being impossible — I think I have
so explained all of which I had occasion to treat, that
they who read it attentively will have ground for the
persuasion that it is unnecessary to seek for any other
principles than those I have given, in order to arrive at
the most exalted knowledge of which the mind of man
is capable ; especially if, after the perusal of my writ-
ings, they take the trouble to consider how many di-
verse questions are therein discussed and explained,
and, referring to the writings of others, they see how
little probability there is in the reasons that are ad-
duced in explanation of the same questions by princi-
ples different from mine. And that they may the more
easily undertake this, I might have said that those im-
bued with my doctrines have much less difficulty in
comprehending the writings of others, and estimating
their true value, than those who have not been so im-
bued ; and this is precisely the opposite of what I before
said of such as commenced with the ancient philosophy,
LETTER OF THE AUTHOR. 117
namely, that the more they have studied it the less fit
are they for rightly apprehending the truth.
I should also have added a word of advice regarding
the manner of reading this work, which is, that I
should wish the reader at first to go over the whole of
it, as he would a romance, without greatly straining
his attention, or tarrying at the difficulties he may per-
haps meet with in it, with the view simply of knowing
in general the matters of which I treat ; and that after-
wards, if they seem to him to merit a more careful ex-
amination, and he feel a desire to know their causes, he
may read it a second time, in order to observe the con-
nection of my reasonings ; but that he must not then
give it up in despair, although he may not everywhere
sufficiently discover the connection of the proof, or un-
derstand all the reasonings — it being only necessary to
mark with a pen the places where the difficulties occur,
and continue to read without interruption to the end;
then, if he does not grudge to take up the book a third
time, I am confident he will find in a fresh perusal the
solution of most of the difficulties he will have marked
before ; and that, if any still remain, their solution will
in the end be found in another reading.
I have observed, on examining the natural constitu-
tions of different minds, that there are hardly any so
dull or slow of understanding as to be incapable of ap-
prehending good opinions, or even of acquiring all the
highest sciences, if they be but conducted along the
right road. And this can also be proved by reason ;
for, as the principles are clear, and as nothing ought to
be deduced from them, unless most manifest inferences,
no one is so devoid of intelligence as to be unable to
comprehend the conclusions that flow from them.
n8 LETTER OF THE AUTHOR.
But, besides the entanglement of prejudices, from
which no one is entirely exempt, although it is they
who have been the most ardent students of the false
sciences that receive the greatest detriment from
them, it happens very generally that people of ordin-
ary capacity neglect to study from a conviction that
they want ability, and that others, who are more ardent,
press on too rapidly : whence it comes to pass that they
frequently admit principles far from evident, and draw
doubtful inferences from them. For this reason, I
should wish to assure those who are too distrustful of
their own ability that there is nothing in my writings
which they may not entirely understand, if they only
take the trouble to examine them ; and I should wish,
at the same time, to warn those of an opposite tendency
that even the most superior minds will have need of
much time and attention to remark all I designed to
embrace therein.
After this, that I might lead men to understand the
real design I had in publishing them, I should have
wished here to explain the order which it seems to me
one ought to follow with the view of instructing him-
self. In the first place, a man who has merely the vul-
gar and imperfect knowledge which can be acquired
by the four means above explained, ought, before all
else, to endeavour to form for himself a code of morals
sufficient to regulate the actions of his life, as well for
the reason that this does not admit of delay as because
it ought to be our first care to live well. In the next
place, he ought to study Logic, not that of the schools,
for it is only, properly speaking, a dialectic which teaches
the mode of expounding to others what we already
know, or even of speaking much, without judgment, of
LETTER OF THE AUTHOR. 119
what we do not know, by which means it corrupts
rather than increases good sense — but the logic which
teaches the right conduct of the reason with the view
of discovering the truths of which we are ignorant ;
and, because it greatly depends on usage, it is desirable
he should exercise himself for a length of time in prac-
tising its rules on easy and simple questions, as those
of the mathematics. Then, when he has acquired some
skill in discovering the truth in these questions, he
should commence to apply himself in earnest to true
philosophy, of which the first part is Metaphysics, con-
taining the principles of knowledge, among which is
the explication of the principal attributes of God, of the
immateriality of the soul, and of all the clear and sim-
ple notions that are in us ; the second is Physics, in
which, after finding the true principles of material
things, we examine, in general, how the whole universe
has been framed ; in the next place, we consider, in par-
ticular, the nature of the earth, and of all the bodies
that are most generally found upon it, as air, water,
fire, the loadstone and other minerals. In the next
place, it is necessary also to examine singly the nature of
plants, of animals/ and above all of man, in order that
we may thereafter be able to discover the other sciences
that are useful to us. Thus, all Philosophy is like a
tree, of which Metaphysics is the root, Physics the
trunk, and all the other sciences the branches that grow
out of this trunk, which are reduced to three principal,
namely, Medicine, Mechanics, and Ethics. By the
science of Morals, I understand the highest and most
perfect which, presupposing an entire knowledge of the
other sciences, is the last degree of wisdom.
But as it is not from the roots or the trunks of trees
120 LETTER OF THE AUTHOR.
that we gather the fruit, but only from the extremities
of their branches, so the principal utility of philosophy
depends on the separate uses of its parts, which we can
only learn last of all. But, though I am ignorant of al-
most all these, the zeal I have always felt in endeavour-
ing to be of service to the public, was the reason why
I published, some ten or twelve years ago, certain Es-
says on the doctrines I thought I had acquired. The
first part of these Essays was a "Discourse on the
Method of rightly conducting the Reason, and seeking
Truth in the Sciences," in which I gave a summary of
the principal rules of logic, and also of an imperfect
ethic, which a person may follow provisionally so long
as he does not know any better. The other parts were
three treatises : the first of Dioptrics, the second of Me-
teors, and the third of Geometry. In the Dioptrics, I
designed to show that we might proceed far enough in
philosophy as to arrive, by its means, at the knowledge
of the arts that are useful to life, because the invention
of the telescope, of which I there gave an explanation,
is one of the most difficult that has ever been made. In
the treatise of Meteors, I desired to exhibit the differ-
ence that subsists between the philosophy I cultivate
and that taught in the schools, in which the same mat-
ters are usually discussed. In fine, in the Geometry,
I professed to demonstrate that I had discovered many
things that were before unknown, and thus afford
ground for believing that we may still discover many
others, with the view of thus stimulating all to the in-
vestigation of truth. Since that period, anticipating
the difficulty which many would experience in appre-
hending the foundations of the Metaphysics, I endeav-
oured to explain the chief points of them in a book of
LETTER OF THE AUTHOR. 121
Meditations, which is not in itself large, but the size of
which has been increased, and the matter greatly illus-
trated, by the Objections which several very learned
persons sent to me on occasion of it, and by the Re-
plies which I made to them. At length, after it ap-
peared to me that those preceding treatises had suffi-
ciently prepared the minds of my readers for the
Principles of Philosophy, I also published it ; and I
have divided this work into four parts, the first of
which contains the principles of human knowledge, and
which may be called the First Philosophy, or Meta-
physics. That this part, accordingly, may be properly
understood, it will be necessary to read beforehand the
book of Meditations I wrote on the same subject. The
other three parts contain all that is most general in
Physics, namely, the explication of the first laws or
principles of nature, and the way in which the heavens,
the fixed stars, the planets, comets, and generally the
whole universe, were composed ; in the next place, the
explication, in particular, of the nature of this earth,
the air, water, fire, the magnet, which are the bodies
we most commonly find everywhere around it, and of
all the qualities we observe in these bodies, as light,
heat, gravity, and the like. In this way, it seems to
me, I have commenced the orderly explanation of the
whole of philosophy, without omitting any of the mat-
ters that ought to precede the last which I discussed.
But to bring this undertaking to its conclusion, I
ought hereafter to explain, in the same manner, the na-
ture of the other more particular bodies that are on the
earth, namely, minerals, plants, animals, and especially
man ; finally, to treat thereafter with accuracy of Medi-
cine, Ethics, and Mechanics. I should require to do
122 LETTER OF THE AUTHOR.
this in order to give to the world a complete body of
philosophy ; and I do not yet feel myself so old, — I do
not so much distrust my strength, nor do I find myself
so far removed from the knowledge of what remains,
as that I should not dare to undertake to complete this
design, provided I were in a position to make all the
experiments which I should require for the basis and
verification of my reasonings. But seeing that would
demand a great expenditure, to which the resources
of a private individual like myself would not be
adequate, unless aided by the public, and as I have no
ground to expect this aid, I believe that I ought for the
future to content myself with studying for my own in-
struction, and posterity will excuse me* if I fail hereaf-
ter to labour for them.
Meanwhile, that it may be seen wherein I think I
have already promoted the general good, I will here
mention the fruits that may be gathered from my Prin-
ciples. The first is the satisfaction which the mind
will experience on finding in the work many truths be-
fore unknown ; for although frequently truth does not
so greatly affect our imagination as falsity and fiction,
because it seems less wonderful and is more simple, yet
the gratification it affords is always more durable and
solid. The second fruit is, that in studying these prin-
ciples we will become accustomed by degrees to judge
better of all the things we come in contact with, and
thus be made wiser, in which respect the effect will be
quite the opposite of the common philosophy, for we
may easily remark in those we call pedants that it ren-
ders them less capable of rightly exercising their rea-
son than they would have been if they had never known
it. The third is, that the truths which they contain,
LETTER OF THE AUTHOR. 123
being highly clear and certain, will take away all
ground of dispute, and thus dispose men's minds to
gentleness and concord ; whereas the contrary is the ef-
fect of the controversies of the schools, which, as they
insensibly render those who are exercised in them more
wrangling and opinionative, are perhaps the prime
cause of the heresies and dissensions that now harass
the world. The last and chief fruit of these Principles
is, that one will be able, by cultivating them, to dis-
cover many truths I myself have not unfolded, and
thus passing by degrees from one to another, to
acquire in course of time a perfect knowledge of
the whole of philosophy, and to rise to the highest
degree of wisdom. For just as all the arts, though in
their beginnings they are rude and imperfect, are yet
gradually perfected by practice, from their containing
at first something true, and whose effect experience
evinces ; so in philosophy, when we have true principles,
we cannot fail by following them to meet sometimes
with other truths ; and we could not better prove the
falsity of those of Aristotle, than by saying that men
made no progress in knowledge by their means during
the many ages they prosecuted them.
I well know that there are some men so precipitate
and accustomed to use so little circumspection in what
they do, that, even with the most solid foundations,
they could not rear a firm superstructure ; and as it is
usually those who are the readiest to make books, they
would in a short time mar all that I have done, and in-
troduce uncertainty and doubt into my manner of phil-
osophizing, from which I have carefully endeavoured
to banish them, if people were to receive their writings
as mine, or as representing my opinions. I had, not
124 LETTER OF THE AUTHOR.
long ago, some experience of this in one of those who
were believed desirous of following me the most
closely,* and one too of whom I had somewhere said
that I had such confidence in his genius as to believe
that he adhered to no opinions which I should not be
ready to avow as mine ; for he last year published a
book entitled "Fundamenta Physicse," in which, al-
though he seems to have written nothing on the sub-
ject of Physics and Medicine which he did not take
from my writings, as well from those I have published
as from another still imperfect on the nature of ani-
mals, which fell into his hands ; nevertheless, because
he has copied them badly, and changed the order, and
denied certain metaphysical truths upon which all
Physics ought to be based, I am obliged wholly to dis-
avow his work, and here to request readers not to at-
tribute to me any opinion unless they find it expressly
stated in my own writings, and to receive no opinion as
true, whether in my writings or elsewhere, unless they
see that it is very clearly deduced from true principles.
I well know, likewise, that many ages may elapse ere
all the truths deducible from these principles are
evolved out of them, as well because the greater num-
ber of such as remain to be discovered depend on cer-
tain particular experiments that never occur by chance,
but which require to be investigated with care and ex-
pense by men of the highest intelligence, as because it
will hardly happen that the same persons who have the
sagacity to make a right use of them, will possess also
the means of making them, and also because the ma-
jority of the best minds have formed so low an estimate
* Regius; see La Vie de M. Descartes, réduite en abrégé
(Baillet). Liv. vii., chap. vii. — T.
LETTER OF THE AUTHOR. 125
of philosophy in general, from the imperfections they
have remarked in the kind in vogue up to the present
time, that they cannot apply themselves to the search
after truth.
But, in conclusion, if the difference discernible be-
tween the principles in question and those of every
other system, and the great array of truths deducible
from them, lead them to discern the importance of con-
tinuing the search after these truths, and to observe the
degree of wisdom, the perfection and felicity of life, to
which they are fitted to conduct us, I venture to believe
that there will not be found one who is not ready to la-
bour hard in so profitable a study, or at least to favour
and aid with all his might those who shall devote them-
selves to it with success.
The height of my wishes is, that posterity may some-
time behold the happy issue of it, etc.
TO THE MOST SERENE PRINCESS,
ELIZABETH,
ELDEST DAUGHTER OF FREDERICK, KING OF BOHEMIA,
COUNT PALATINE, AND ELECTOR OF THE
SACRED ROMAN EMPIRE.
Madam, — The greatest advantage I have derived from
the writings which I have already published, has arisen
from my having, through means of them, become
known to your Highness, and thus been privileged to
hold occasional converse with one in whom so many
rare and estimable qualities are united, as to lead me
to believe I should do service to the public by proposing
them as an example to posterity. It would ill become
me to flatter, or to give expression to anything of
which I had no certain knowledge, especially in the
first pages of a work in which I aim at laying down the
principles of truth. And the generous modesty that is
conspicuous in all your actions, assures me that the
frank and simple judgment of a man who only writes
what he believes will be more agreeable to you than the
ornate laudations of those who have studied the art of
compliment. For this reason, I will give insertion to
nothing in this letter for which I have not the certainty
both of experience and reason ; and in the exordium, as
in the rest of the work, I will write only as becomes
a philosopher. There is a vast difference between real
and apparent virtues ; and there is also a great discrep-
ancy between those real virtues that proceed from an
126
DEDICATION. 127
accurate knowledge of the truth, and such as are accom-
panied with ignorance or error. The virtues I call appar-
ent are only, properly speaking, vices, which, as they are
less frequent than the vices that are opposed to them,
and are farther removed from them than the inter-
mediate virtues, are usually held in higher esteem than
those virtues. Thus, because those who fear dangers
too much are more numerous than they who fear them
too little, temerity is frequently opposed to the vice of
timidity, and taken for a virtue, and is commonly more
highly esteemed than true fortitude. Thus, also, the
prodigal are in ordinary more praised than the liberal ;
and none more easily acquire a great reputation for
piety than the superstitious and hypocritical. With re-
gard to true virtues, these do not all proceed from true
knowledge, for there are some that likewise spring
from defect or error ; thus, simplicity is frequently the
source of goodness, fear of devotion, and despair of
courage. The virtues that are thus accompanied with
some imperfections differ from each other, and have
received diverse appellations. But those pure and per-
fect virtues that arise from the knowledge of good
alone are all of the same nature, and may be comprised
under the single term wisdom. For, whoever owns the
firm and constant resolution of always using his reason
as well as lies in his power, and in all his actions of do-
ing what he judges to be best, is truly wise, as far
as his nature permits ; and by this alone he is just,
courageous, temperate, and possesses all the other vir-
tues, but so well balanced as that none of them appears
more prominent than another : and for this reason, al-
though they are much more perfect than the virtues
that blaze forth through the mixture of some defect,
128 DEDICATION.
yet, because the crowd thus observes them less, they
are not usually extolled so highly. Besides, of the two
things that are requisite for the wisdom thus described,
namely, the perception of the understanding and the
disposition of the will, it is only that which lies in the
will which all men can possess equally, inasmuch as the
understanding of some is inferior to that of others.
But although those who have only an inferior under-
standing may be as perfectly wise as their nature per-
mits, and may render themselves highly acceptable to
God by their virtue, provided they preserve always a
firm and constant resolution to do all that they shall
judge to be right, and to omit nothing that may lead
them to the knowledge of the duties of which they are
ignorant; nevertheless, those who preserve a constant
resolution of performing the right, and are especially
careful in instructing themselves, and who possess also
a highly perspicacious intellect, arrive doubtless at a
higher degree of wisdom than others ; and I see that
these three particulars are found in great perfection in
your Highness. P'or, in the first place, your desire of
self-instruction is manifest, from the circumstance that
neither the amusements of the court, nor the accus-
tomed mode of educating ladies, which ordinarily
condemns them to ignorance, have been sufficient to
prevent you from studying with much care all that
is best in the arts and sciences ; and the incomparable
perspicacity of your intellect is evinced by this, that
you penetrated the secrets of the sciences and acquired
an accurate knowledge of them in a very short period.
But of the vigour of your intellect I have a still
stronger proof, and one peculiar to myself, N in that I
have never yet met any one who understood so gener-
DEDICATION. 129
ally and so well as yourself all that is contained in my
writings. For there are several, even among men of
the highest intellect and learning, who find them very
obscure. And I remark, in almost all those who are
versant in Metaphysics, that they are wholly dis-
inclined from Geometry ; and, on the other hand, that
the cultivators of Geometry have no ability for the in-
vestigations of the First Philosophy : insomuch that I
can ^av with truth I know but^one mind, and th at is
your own, to which both studies are alike congenial,
and which I therefore, with propriety, designate in-
comparable. But what most of all enhances my ad-
miration is, that so accurate and varied an acquaintance
with the whole circle of the sciences is not found in
some aged doctor who has employed many years in
contemplation, but in a Princess still young, and whose
countenance and years would more fitly represent one
of the Graces than a Muse or the sage Minerva. In
conclusion, I not only remark in your Highness all that
is requisite on the part of the mind to perfect and sub-
lime wisdom, but also all that can be required on the
part of the will or the manners, in which benignity and
gentleness are so conjoined with majesty that, though
fortune has attacked you with continued injustice, it
has failed either to irritate or crush you. And this
constrains me to such veneration that I not only think
this work due to you, since it treats of philosophy
which is the study of wisdom, but likewise feel not
more zeal for my reputation as a philosopher than
pleasure in subscribing myself, —
Of your most Serene Highness,
The most devoted servant,
DESCARTES.
THE PRINCIPLES OF PHILOSOPHY,
PART I.
OF THE PRINCIPLES OF HUMAN KNOWLEDGE.
I. Th^ax jii orcjer to s^ek ^ tr u th . Jt is ne cesjp.rvjQt^gJn
the course of our life, to doubt as far as possible, of all
As we were at one time children, and as we formed
various judgments regarding the objects presented to
our senses, when as yet we had not the entire use of
our reason, numerous prejudices stand in the way of
our arriving at the knowledge of truth ; and of these it
seems impossible for us to rid ourselves, unless we un-
dertake, once in our lifetime, to doubt of all those
things in which we may discover even the smallest sus-
picion of uncertainty.
II. That we ought also to consider as false all that
is doubtful.
Moreover, it will be useful likewise to esteem as false
the things of which we shall be able to doubt, that we
may with greater clearness discover what possesses
most certainty and is the easiest to know.
III. That we ought not meanwhile-tn make use of
doubt in the conduct of life.
In the meantime, it is to be observed that we are to
avail ourselves of this general doubt only while en-
gaged in the contemplation of truth. For, as far as
concerns the conduct of life, we are very frequently
130
PART I. 131
obliged to follow opinions merely probable, or even
sometimes, though of two courses of action we may
not perceive more probability in the one than in the
other, to choose one or other, seeing the opportunity of
acting would not unfrequently pass away before we
could free ourselves from our doubts.
IV. Why we may doubt^ of ^ensibjf ^'hingp..
Accordingly, since we now only design to apply our-
selves to the investigation of truth, we will doubt, first,
whether of all the things that have ever fallen under
our senses, or which we have ever imagined, any one
really exist ; in the first place, because we know by ex-
perience that the senses sometimes err, and it would be
imprudent to trust too much to what has even once de-
ceived us ; secondly, because in dreams we perpetually
seem to perceive or imagine innumerable objects which
have no existence. And to one who has thus resolved
upon a general doubt, there appear no marks by which
he can with certainty distinguish sleep from the waking
state.
V. Why—we may also doubt of mat hematic al dem-^
onstrat iqnfi .
We will also doubt of the other things we have before
held as most certain, even of the demonstrations of
mathematics, and of their principles which we have
hitherto deemed selfrevident ; in the first place, because
we have sometimes seen men fall into error in such
matters, and admit as absolutely certain and self evi-
dent what to us appeared false, but chiefly because we
have learnt that God who created us is all-powerful ;
for we do not yet know whether perhaps it was his will
to create us so that we are always deceived, even in the
things we think we know best : since this does not ap-
132 THE PRINCIPLES OF PHILOSOPHY.
pear more impossible than our being occasionally de-
ceived, which, however, as observation teaches us, is
the case. And if we suppose that an all-powerful God
is not the author of our being, and that we exist of our-
selves or by some other means, still, the less powerful
we suppose our author to be, the greater reason will we
have for believing that we are not so perfect .as that we
may not be continually deceived.
VI. That we possess a free-will, by which we can
withhold our assent from what is doubtful, and thu§
avoid error. „
But meanwhile, whoever in the end may be the au-
thor of our being, and however powerful and deceitful
he may be, we are nevertheless conscious of a freedom,
by which we can refrain from admitting to a place in
our belief aught that is not manifestly certain and un-
doubted, and thus guard against ever being deceived.
VII. That we cannot doubt of our existence while
we doubt, and that this is the first knowledge we ac-
quire when we philosophize in order.
While we thus reject all of which we can entertain
the smallest doubt, and even imagine that, it is false,
we easily indeed suppose that there is neither God, nor
sky, nor bodies, and that we ourselves even have
neither hands nor feet, nor, finally, a body ; but we can-
not in the same way suppose that we are not while we
doubt of the truth of these things ; for there is a re-
pugnance in conceiving that what thinks does not exist
at the very time when it thinks. Accordingly, the
knowledge, / think, therefore I am, is the first and
most certain that occurs to one who philosophizes
orderly.
VIII. That we hence discover the distinction be-
PART I. 133
tween the mind and the body, or between a thinking
and corporeal thing.
And this is the best mode of discovering the nature
of the mind, and its distinctness from the body: for
examining what we are, while supposing, as we now
do, that there is nothing really existing apart from our
thought, we clearly perceive that neither extension, nor
figure, nor local motion,* nor anything similar that can
be attributed to body, pertains to our nature, and noth-
ing save thought alone ; and, consequently, that the
notion we have of our mind precedes that of any cor-
poreal thing, and is more certain, seeing we still doubt
whether there is any body in existence, while we al-
ready perceive that we think.
IX. What thought (cogitatio) is.
By the word thought, I understand all that which so
takes place in us that we of ourselves are immediately
conscious of it ; and, accordingly, not only to under-
stand (intelligere, entendre), to will (velle), to im-
agine (imaginari) , but even to perceive (sentir e, sen-
tir), are here the same as to think (cogitare, penser).
For if I say, I see, or, I walk, therefore I am ; and if I
understand by vision or walking the act of my eyes or
of my limbs, which is the work of the body, the con-
clusion is not absolutely certain, because, as is often
the case in dreams, I may think that I see or walk, al-
though I do not open my eyes or move from my place,
and even, perhaps, although I have no body: but, if I
mean the sensation itself, or consciousness of seeing or
walking, the knowledge is manifestly certain, because
* Instead of "local motion," the French has "existence in
any place."
134 THE PRINCIPLES OF PHILOSOPHY.
it is then referred to the mind, which alone perceives
or is conscious that it sees or walks.*
X. That the notions which are simplest and self-
evident, are obscured by logical définitions ; and that
such are not to be reckoned among the cognitions ac-
quired by study, [but as born with us] .
I do not here explain several other terms which I
have used, or design to use in the sequel, because their
meaning seems to me sufficiently self-evident. And I
frequently remarked that philosophers erred in at-
tempting to explain, by logical definitions, such truths
as are most simple and self-evident ; for they thus only
rendered them more obscure. And when I said that
the proposition, I think, therefore I am, is of all others
the first and most certain which occurs to one philoso-
phizing orderly, I did not therefore deny that it was
necessary to know what thought, existence, and certi-
tude are, and the truth that, in order to think it is nec-
essary to be, and the like ; but, because these are the
most simple notions, and such as of themselves afford
the knowledge of nothing existing, I did not judge it
proper there to enumerate them.
XL How we can know our mind more clearly than
our body.
But now that it may be discerned how the knowl-
edge we have of the mind not only precedes, and has
greater certainty, but is even clearer, than that we
have of the body, it must be remarked, as a matter
that is highly manifest by the natural light, that to
nothing no affections or qualities belong; and, accord-
ingly, that where we observe certain affections, there
* In the French, "which alone has the power of perceiving,
or of being conscious in any other way whatever."
PART I. 135
a thing or substance to which these pertain, is neces-
sarily found. The same light also shows us that we
know a thing or substance more clearly in proportion
as we discover in it a greater number of qualities.
Now, it is manifest that we remark a greater number
of qualities in our mind than in any other thing; for
there is no occasion on which we know anything what-
ever when we are not at the same time led with much
greater certainty to the knowledge of our own mind.
For example, if I judge that there is an earth because
I touch or see it, on the same ground, and with still
greater reason, I must be persuaded that my mind
exists ; for it may be, perhaps, that I think I touch the
earth while there is one in existence ; but it is not pos-
sible that I should so judge, and my mind which thus
judges not exist ; and the same holds good of whatever
object is presented to our mind.
XII. How it happens that every one does not come
equally to know this.
Those who have not philosophized in order have had
other opinions on this subject, because they never dis-
tinguished with sufficient care the mind from the body.
For, although they had no difficulty in believing that
they themselves existed, and that they had a higher
assurance of this than of any other thing, nevertheless,
as they did not observe that by themselves, they ought
here to understand their minds alone [when the ques-
tion related to metaphysical certainty] ; and since, on
the contrary, they rather meant their bodies which
they saw with their eyes, touched with their hands,
and to which they erroneously attributed the faculty
of perception, they were prevented from distinctly ap-
prehending the nature of the mind.
136 THE PRINCIPLES OF PHILOSOPHY.
XIII. In what sense the knowledge of other things
depends upon the knowledge of God.
But when the mind, which thus knows itself but is
still in doubt as to all other things, looks around on
all sides, with a view to the farther extension of its
knowledge, it first of all discovers within itself the
ideas of many things ; and while it simply contem-
plates them, and neither affirms nor denies that there
is anything beyond itself corresponding to them, it is
in no danger of erring. The mind also discovers cer-
tain common notions out of which it frames various
demonstrations that carry conviction to such a degree
as to render doubt of their truth impossible, so long as
we give attention to them. For example, the mind
has within itself ideas of numbers and figures, and it
has likewise among its common notions the principle
that if equals be added to equals the wholes will be
equal, and the like ; from which it is easy to demon-
strate that the three angles of a triangle are equal to
two right angles, etc. Now, so long as we attend to
the premises from which this conclusion and others
similar to it were deduced, we feel assured of their
truth; but, as the mind cannot always think of these
with attention, when it has the remembrance of a con-
clusion without recollecting the order of its deduction,
and is uncertain whether the author of its being has
created it of a nature that is liable to be deceived, even
in what appears most evident, it perceives that there is
just ground to distrust the truth of such conclusions,
and that it cannot possess any certain knowledge until
it has discovered its author.
XIV. That we may validly infer the existence of
PART I. 137
God from necessary existence being comprised in the
concept we have of him.
When the mind afterwards reviews the different
ideas that are in it, it discovers what is by far the chief
among them — that of a Being omniscient, all-power-
ful, and absolutely perfect ; and it observes that in this
idea there is contained not only possible and contin-
gent existence, as in the ideas of all other things which
it clearly perceives, but existence absolutely necessary
and eternal. And just as because, for example, the
equality of its three angles to two right angles is neces-
sarily comprised in the idea of a triangle, the mind is
firmly persuaded that the three angles of a triangle
are equal to two right angles ; so, from its perceiving
necessary and eternal existence to be comprised in the
idea which it has of an all-perfect Being, it ought
manifestly to conclude that this all-perfect Being
exists.
XV. That necessary existence is not in the same
way comprised in the notions which we have of other
things, but merely contingent existence.
The mind will be still more certain of the truth of
this conclusion, if it consider that it has no idea of any
other thing in which it can discover that necessary ex-
istence is contained ; for, from this circumstance alone,
it will discern that the idea of an all-perfect Being has
not been framed by itself, and that it does not repre-
sent a chimera, but a true and immutable nature, which
must exist since it can only be conceived as necessarily
existing.
XVI. That prejudices hinder many from clearly
knowing the necessity of the existence of God.
Our mind would have no difficulty in assenting to
138 THE PRINCIPLES OF PHILOSOPHY.
this truth, if it were, first of all, wholly free from pre-
judices; but as we have been accustomed to distin-
guish, in all other things, essence from existence, and
to imagine at will many ideas of things which neither
are nor have been, it easily happens, when we do not
steadily fix our thoughts on the contemplation of the
all-perfect Being, that a doubt arises as to whether the
idea we have of him is not one of those which we
frame at pleasure, or at least of that class to whose
essence existence does not pertain.
XVII. That the greater objective (representative)
perfection there is in our idea of a thing, the greater
also must be the perfection of its cause.
When we further reflect on the various ideas that'
are in us, it is easy to perceive that there is not much
difference among them, when we consider them sim-
ply as certain modes of thinking, but that they are
widely different, considered in reference to the objects
they represent ; and that their causes must be so much
the more perfect according to the degree of objective
perfection contained in them.* For there is no differ-
ence between this and the case of a person who has the
idea of a machine, in the construction of which great
skill is displayed, in which circumstances we have a
right to inquire how he came by this idea, whether, for
example, he somewhere saw such a machine con-
structed by another, or whether he was so accurately
taught the mechanical sciences, or is endowed with
such force of genius, that he was able of himself to in-
vent it, without having elsewhere seen anything like
it ; for all the ingenuity which is contained in the idea
* "as what they represent of their object has more perfection."
— French.
PART I. 139
objectively only, or as it were in a picture, must exist
at least in its first and chief cause, whatever that may
be, not only objectively or representatively, but in
truth formally or eminently.
XVIII. That the existence of God may be again
inferred from the above.
Thus, because we discover in our minds the idea of
God, or of an all-perfect Being, we have a right to in-
quire into the source whence we derive it ; and we will
discover that the perfections it represents are so im-
mense as to render it quite certain that we could only
derive it from an all-perfect Being; that is, from a
God really existing. For it is not only manifest by
the natural light that nothing cannot be the cause of
anything whatever, and that the more perfect cannot
arise from the less perfect, so as to be thereby pro-
duced as by its efficient and total cause, but also that
it is impossible we can have the idea or representation
of anything whatever, unless there be somewhere,
either in us or out of us, an original which comprises,
in reality, all the perfections that are thus represented
to us ; but, as we do not in any way find in ourselves
those absolute perfections of which we have the idea,
we must conclude that they exist in some nature dif-
ferent from ours, that is, in God, or at least that they
were once in him ; and it most manifestly follows [from
their infinity] that they are still there.
XIX. That, although we may not comprehend the
nature of God, there is yet nothing which we know so
clearly as his perfections.
This will appear sufficiently certain and manifest to
those who have been accustomed to contemplate the
idea of God, and to turn their thoughts to his infinite
140 THE PRINCIPLES OF PHILOSOPHY.
perfections ; for, although we may not comprehend
them, because it is of the nature of the infinite not to
be comprehended by what is finite, we nevertheless
conceive them more clearly and distinctly than mate-
rial objects, for this reason, that, being simple, and un-
obscured by limits,* they occupy our mind more fully.
XX. That we are not the cause of ourselves, but
that this is God, and consequently that there is a God.
But, because every one has not observed this, and
because, when we have an idea of any machine in
which great skill is displayed, we usually know with
sufficient accuracy the manner in which we obtained
it, and as we cannot even recollect when the idea we
have of a God was communicated to us by him, seeing
it was always in our minds, it is still necessary that we
should continue our review, and make inquiry after
our author, possessing, as we do, the idea of the in-
finite perfections of a God : for it is in the highest de-
gree evident by the natural light, that that which knows
something more perfect than itself, is not the source
of its own being, since it would thus have given to it-
self all the perfections which it knows ; and that, con-
sequently, it could draw its origin from no other being
than from him who possesses in himself all those per-
fections, that is, from God.
XXI. That the duration alone of our life is suffi-
cient to demonstrate the existence of God.
* After limits, "what of them we do conceive is much less
confused. There is, besides, no speculation more calculated
to aid in perfecting our understanding, and which is more
important than this, inasmuch as the consideration of an ob-
ject that has no limits to its perfections fills us with satisfac-
tion and assurance." — French.
PART I. 141
The truth of this demonstration will clearly appear,
provided we consider the nature of time, or the dura-
tion of things ; for this is of such a kind that its parts
are not mutually dependent, and never co-existent ;
and, accordingly, from the fact that we now are, it
does not necessarily follow that we shall be a moment
afterwards, unless some cause, viz., that which first
produced us, shall, as it were, continually reproduce
us, that is, conserve us. For we easily understand
that there is no power in us by which we can conserve
ourselves, and that the being who has so much power
as to conserve us out of himself, must also by so much
the greater reason conserve himself, or rather stand
in need of being conserved by no one whatever, and, in
fine, be God.
XXII. That in knowing the existence of God, in
the manner here explained, we likewise know all his
attributes, as far as they can be known by the natural
light alone.
There is the great advantage in proving the exist-
ence of God in this way, viz., by his idea, that we at
the same time know what he is, as far as the weakness
of our nature allows; for, reflecting on the idea we
have of him which is born with us, we perceive that he
is eternal, omniscient, omnipotent, the source of all
goodness and truth, creator of all things, and that, in
fine, he has in himself all that in which we can clearly
discover any infinite perfection or good that is not
limited by any imperfection.
XXIII. That God is not corporeal, and does not
perceive by means of senses as we do, or will the evil
of sin.
For there are indeed many things in the world that
142 THE PRINCIPLES OF PHILOSOPHY.
are to a certain extent imperfect or limited, though
possessing also some perfection; and it is accordingly
impossible that any such can be in God. Thus, look-
ing to corporeal nature,* since divisibility is included
in local extension, and this indicates imperfection, it is
certain that God is not body. And although in men it
is to some degree a perfection to be capable of perceiv-
ing by means of the senses, nevertheless since in every
sense there is passivityf which indicates dependency,
we must conclude that God is in no manner possessed
of senses, and that he only understands and wills, not,
'however, like us, by acts in any way distinct, but al-
ways by an act that is one, identical, and the simplest
possible, understands,wills, and operates all, that is, all
things that in reality exist; for he does not will the
evil of sin, seeing this is but the negation of being.
XXIV. That in passing from the knowledge of
God to the knowledge of the creatures, it is necessary
to remember that our understanding is finite, and the
power of God infinite.
But as we know that God alone is the true cause of
all that is or can be, we will doubtless follow the best
way of philosophizing, if, from the knowledge we
have of God himself, we pass to the explication of the
things which he has created, and essay to deduce it
from the notions that are naturally in our minds, for
we will thus obtain the most perfect science, that is,
the knowledge of effects through their causes. But
* In the French, "since extension constitutes the nature of
body."
t In the French, "because our perceptions arise from im-
pressions made upon us from another source," i. e., than our-
selves.
PART I. 143
that we may be able to make this attempt with suf-
ficient security from error, we must use the precaution
to bear in mind as much as possible that God, who is
the author of things, is infinite, while we are wholly
finite.
XXV. That we must believe all that God has re-
vealed, although it may surpass the reach of our
faculties.
Thus, if perhaps God reveal to us or others, matters
concerning himself which surpass the natural powers
of our mind, such as the mysteries of the incarnation
and of the trinity, we will not refuse to believe them,
although we may not clearly understand them; nor
will we be in any way surprised to find in the immens-
ity of his nature, or even in what he has created, many
things that exceed our comprehension.
XXVI. That it is not needful to enter into dis-
putes* regarding the infinite, but merely to hold all that
in which we can find no limits as indefinite, such as the
extension of the world, the divisibility of the parts of
matter, the number of the stars, etc.
We will thus never embarrass ourselves by disputes
about the infinite, seeing it would be absurd for us who
are finite to undertake to determine anything regarding
it, and thus as it were to limit it by endeavouring to
comprehend it. We will accordingly give ourselves
no concern to reply to those who demand whether the
half of an infinite line is also infinite, and whether an
infinite number is even or odd, and the like, because
it is only such as imagine their minds to be infinite who
seem bound to entertain questions of this sort. And,
for our part, looking to all those things in which in cer-
* "to essay to comprehend the infinite." — French.
144 THE PRINCIPLES OF PHILOSOPHY.
tain senses, we discover no limits, we will not, there-
fore, affirm that they are infinite, but will regard them
simply as indefinite. Thus, because we cannot imagine
extension so great that we cannot still conceive greater,
we will say that the magnitude of possible things is
indefinite, and because a body cannot be divided into
parts so small that each of these may not be conceived
as again divided into others still smaller, let us regard
quantity as divisible into parts whose number is in-
definite ; and as we cannot imagine so many stars that
it would seem impossible for God to create more, let
us suppose that their number is indefinite, and so in
other instances.
XXVII. What difference there is between the in-
definite and the infinite.
And we will call those things indefinite rather than
infinite, with the view of reserving to God alone the
appellation of infinite ; in the first place, because not
only do we discover in him alone no limits on any side,
but also because we positively conceive that he admits
of none ; and in the second place, because we do not in
the same way positively conceive that other things are
in every part unlimited, but merely negatively admit
that their limits, if they have any, cannot be discovered
by us.
XXVIII. That we must examine, not the final, but
the efficient, causes of created things.
Likewise, finally, we will not seek reasons of natural
things from the end which God or nature proposed to
himself in their creation (i. e., final causes),* for we
* " We will not stop to consider the ends which God pro-
posed to himself in the creation of the world, and we will en-
tirely reject from our philosophy the search of final causes." —
French.
PART I. 145
ought not to presume so far as to think that we are
sharers in the counsels of Deity, but, considering him
as the efficient cause of all things, let us endeavour to
discover by the natural light* which he has planted in
us, applied to those of his attributes of which he has
been willing we should have some knowledge, what
must be concluded regarding those effects we perceive
by our senses ; bearing in mind, however, what has been
already said, that we must only confide in this natural
light so long as nothing contrary to its dictates is re-
vealed by God himself.f
XXIX. That God is not the cause of our errors.
The first attribute of God which here falls to be
considered, is that he is absolutely veracious and the
source of all light, so that it is plainly repugnant for
him to deceive us, or to be properly and positively the
cause of the errors to which we are consciously sub-
ject ; for although the address to deceive seems to be
some mark of subtlety of mind among men, yet with-
out doubt the will to deceive only proceeds from malice
or from fear and weakness, and consequently cannot
be attributed to God.
XXX. That consequently all which we clearly per-
ceive is true, and that we are thus delivered from the
doubts above proposed.
Whence it follows, that the light of nature, or
faculty of knowledge given us by God, can never com-
pass any object which is not true, in as far as it attains
to a knowledge of it, that is, in as far as the object is
clearly and distinctly apprehended. For God would
* " Faculty of reasoning." — French.
t The last clause, beginning "bearing in mind," is omitted
in the French.
146 THE PRINCIPLES OF PHILOSOPHY.
have merited the appellation of a deceiver if he had
given us this faculty perverted, and such as might lead
us to take falsity for truth [when we used it aright].
Thus the highest doubt is removed, which arose from
our ignorance on the point as to whether perhaps our
nature was such that we might be deceived even in
those things that appear to us the most evident. The
same principle ought also to be of avail against all the
other grounds of doubting that have been already
enumerated. For mathematical truths ought now to
be above suspicion, since these are of the clearest.
And if we perceive anything by our senses, whether
while awake or asleep, we will easily discover the truth
provided we separate what there is of clear and dis-
tinct in the knowledge from what is obscure and con-
fused. There is no need that I should here say more
on this subject, since it has already received ample
treatment in the metaphysical Meditations; and what
follows will serve to explain it still more accurately.
XXXI. That our errors are, in respect of God,
merely negations, but, in respect of ourselves, priva-
tions.
But as it happens that we frequently fall into error,
although God is no deceiver, if we desire to inquire
into the origin and cause of our errors, with a view to
guard against them, it is necessary to observe that they
depend less on our understanding than on our will,
and that they have no need of the actual concourse of
God, in order to their production; so that, when con-
sidered in reference to God, they are merely negations,
but in reference to ourselves, privations.
XXXII. That there are only two modes of think-
PART I. 147
ing in us, viz., the perception of the understanding and
the action of the will.
For all the modes of thinking of which we are con-
scious may be referred to two general classes, the one
of which is the perception or operation of the under-
standing, and the other the volition or operation of the
will. Thus, to perceive by the senses (sentire), to
imagine, and to conceive things purely intelligible, 8
are only different modes of perceiving (percipiendi) ;
but to desire, to be averse from, to affirm, to deny, to
doubt, are different modes of willing.
XXXIII. That we never err unless when we judge
of something which we do not sufficiently apprehend.
When we apprehend anything we are in no danger
of error, if we refrain from judging of it in any way;
and even when we have formed a judgment regarding
it, we would never fall into error, provided we gave
our assent only to what we clearly and distinctly per-
ceived ; but the reason why we are usually deceived, is
that we judge without possessing an exact knowledge
of that of which we judge.
XXXIV. That the will as well as the understand-
ing is required for judging.
I admit that the understanding is necessary for
judging, there being no room to suppose that we can
judge of that which we in no way apprehend; but the
will also is required in order to our assenting to what
we have in any degree perceived. It is not necessary,
however, at least to form any judgment whatever, that
we have an entire and perfect apprehension of a thing ;
for we may assent to many things of which we have
only a very obscure and confused knowledge.
XXXV. That the will is of greater extension than
148 THE PRINCIPLES OF PHILOSOPHY.
the understanding, and is thus the source of our
errors.
Further, the perception of the intellect extends only
to the few things that are presented to it, and is always
very limited : the will, on the other hand, may, in a cer-
tain sense, be said to be infinite, because we observe
nothing that can be the object of the will of any other,
even of the unlimited will of God, to which ours can-
not also extend, so that we easily carry it beyond the
objects we clearly perceive ; and when we do this, it is
not wonderful that we happen to be deceived.
XXXVI. That our errors cannot be imputed to
God.
But although God has not given us an omniscient
understanding, he is not on this account to be con-
sidered in any wise the author of our errors, for it is
of the nature of created intellect to be finite, and of
finite intellect not to embrace all things.
XXXVII. That the chief perfection of man is his
being able to act freely or by will, and that it is this
which renders him worthy of praise or blame.
That the will should be the more extensive is in har-
mony with its nature ; and it is a high perfection in
man to be able to act by means of it, that is, freely.;
and thus in a peculiar way to be the master of his own
actions, and merit praise or blame. For self-acting
machines are not commended because they perform
with exactness all the movements for which they were
adapted, seeing their motions are carried on neces-
sarily ; but the maker of them is praised on account of
the exactness with which they were framed, because he
did not act of necessity, but freely ; and, on the same
principle, we must attribute to ourselves something
PART I. 149
more on this account, that when we embrace truth, we
do so not of necessity, but freely.
XXXVIII. That error is a defect in our mode of
acting, not in our nature ; and that the faults of their
subjects may be frequently attributed to other masters,
but never to God.
It is true, that as often as we err, there is some de-
fect in our mode of action or in the use of our liberty,
but not in our nature, because this is always the same,
whether our judgments be true or false. And al-
though God could have given to us such perspicacity
of intellect that we should never have erred, we have,
notwithstanding, no right to demand this of him ; for,
although with us he who was able to prevent evil and
did not is held guilty of it, God is not in the same way
to be reckoned responsible for our errors because he
had the power to prevent them, inasmuch as the do-
minion which some men possess over others has been
instituted for the purpose of enabling them to hinder
those under them from doing evil, whereas the do-
minion which God exercises over the universe is per-
fectly absolute and free. For this reason we ought to
thank him for the goods he has given us, and not com-
plain that he has not blessed us with all which we know
it was in his power to impart.
XXXIX. That the liberty of our will is self-evi-
dent.
Finally, it is so manifest that we possess a free will,
capable of giving or withholding its assent, that this
truth must be reckoned among the first and most com-
mon notions which are born with us. This, indeed,
has already very clearly appeared, for when essaying
to doubt of all things, we went so far as to suppose
150 THE PRINCIPLES OF PHILOSOPHY.
even that he who created us employed his limitless
power in deceiving us in every way, we were conscious
nevertheless of being free to abstain from believing
what was not in every respect certain and undoubted.
But that of which we are unable to doubt at such a time
is as self-evident and clear as any thing we can ever
know^
XL. That it is likewise certain that God has fore-
ordained all things.
But because what we have already discovered of
God, gives us the assurance that his power is so im-
mense that we would sin in thinking ourselves capable
of ever doing anything which he had not ordained be-
forehand, we should soon be embarrassed in great
difficulties if we undertook to harmonise the pré-or-
dination of God with the freedom of our will, and en-
deavoured to comprehend both truths at once.
XLI. How the freedom of our will may be recon-
ciled with the Divine pre-ordination.
But, in place of this, we will be free from these em-
barrassments if we recollect that our mind is limited,
while the power of God, by which he not only knew
from all eternity what is or can be, but also willed and
pre-ordained it, is infinite. It thus happens that we
possess sufficient intelligence to know clearly and dis-
tinctly that this power is in God, but not enough to
comprehend how he leaves the free actions of men in-
determinate ; and, on the other hand, we have such con-
sciousness of the liberty and indifference which exists
in ourselves, that there is nothing we more clearly or
perfectly comprehend: [so that the omnipotence of
God ought not to keep us from believing it]. For it
would be absurd to doubt of that of which we are fully
PART I. 151
conscious, and which we experience as existing in our-
selves, because we do not comprehend another matter
which, from its very nature, we know to be incompre-
hensible.
XLII. How, although we never will to err, it is
nevertheless by our will that we do err.
But now since we know that all our errors depend
upon our will, and as no one wishes to deceive himself,
it may seem wonderful that there is any error in our
judgments at all. It is necessary to remark, however,
that there is a great difference between willing to be
deceived, and willing to yield assent to opinions in
which it happens that error is found. For though
there is no one who expressly wishes to fall into error,
we will yet hardly find any one who is not ready to as-
sent to things in which, unknown to himself, error
lurks ; and it even frequently happens that it is the de-
sire itself of following after truth that leads those not
fully aware of the order in which it ought to be sought
for, to pass judgment on matters of which they have
no adequate knowledge, and thus to fall into error.
XLIII. That we shall never err if we give our as-
sent only to what we clearly and distinctly perceive.
But it is certain we will never admit falsity for
truth, so long as we judge only of that which we
clearly and distinctly perceive; because, as God is no
deceiver, the faculty of knowledge which he has given
us cannot be fallacious, nor, for the same reason, the
faculty of will, when we do not extend it beyond the
objects we clearly know. And even although this
truth could not be established by reasoning, the minds
of all have been so impressed by nature as spontan-
152 THE PRINCIPLES OF PHILOSOPHY.
eously to assent to whatever is clearly perceived, and
to experience an impossibility to doubt of its truth.
XLIV. That we uniformly judge improperly when
we assent to what we do not clearly perceive, although
our judgment may chance to be true ; and that it is
frequently our memory which deceives us by leading
us to believe that certain things were formerly suffi-
ciently understood by us.
It is likewise certain that, when we approve of any
reason which we do not apprehend, we are either de-
ceived, or, if we stumble on the truth, it is only by
chance, and thus we can never possess the assurance
that we are not in error. I confess it seldom happens
that we judge of a thing when we have observed we
do not apprehend it, because it is a dictate of the
natural light never to judge of what we do not know.
But we most frequently err in this, that we presume
upon a past knowledge of much to which we give our
assent, as to something treasured up in the memory,
and perfectly known to us ; whereas, in truth, we have
no such knowledge.
XLV. What constitutes clear and distinct percep-
tion.
There are indeed a great many persons who, through
their whole lifetime, never perceive anything in a way
necessary for judging of it properly; for the knowl-
edge upon which we can establish a certain and in-
dubitable judgment must be not only clear, but also
distinct. I call that clear which is present and mani-
fest to the mind giving attention to it, just as we are
said clearly to see objects when, being present to the
eye looking on, they stimulate it with sufficient force,
PART I. 153
and it is disposed to regard them; but the distinct is
that which is so precise and different from all other ob-
jects as to comprehend in itself only what is clear.*
XLVI. It is shown, from the example of pain, that
a perception may be clear without being distinct, but
that it cannot be distinct unless it is clear.
For example, when any one feels intense pain, the
knowledge which he has of this pain is very clear, but
it is not always distinct; for men usually confound it
with the obscure judgment they form regarding its
nature, and think that there is in the suffering part
something similar to the sensation of pain of which
they are' alone conscious. And thus perception may
be clear without being distinct, but it can never be dis-
tinct without likewise being clear.
XLVII. That, to correct the prejudices of our early
years, we must consider what is clear in each of our
simplet notions.
And, indeed, in our early years, the mind was so im-
mersed in the body, that, although it perceived many
things with sufficient clearness, it yet knew nothing
distinctly; and since even at that time we exercised
our judgment in many matters, numerous prejudices
were thus contracted, which, by the majority, are never
afterwards laid aside. But that we may now be in a
position to get rid of these, I will here briefly enum-
erate all the simple notions of which our thoughts are
composed, and distinguish in each what is clear from
what is obscure, or fitted to lead into error.
XLVIII. That all the objects of our knowledge are
* "what appears manifestly to him who considers it as he
ought." — French.
t "first." — French.
154 THE PRINCIPLES OF PHILOSOPHY.
to be regarded either (i) as things or the affections
of things: or (2) as eternal truths; with the enumera-
tion of things.
Whatever objects fall under our knowledge we con-
sider either as things or the affections of things,* or as
eternal truths possessing no existence beyond our
thought. Of the first class the most general are sub-
stance, duration, order, number, and perhaps also some
others, which notions apply to all the kinds of things.
I do not, however, recognise more than two highest
kinds (summa genera) of things; the first of intellec-
tual things, or such as have the power of thinking, in-
cluding mind or thinking substance and its properties ;
the second, of material things, embracing extended
substance, or body and its properties. Perception,
volition, and all modes as well of knowing as of will-
ing, are related to thinking substance ; on the other
hand, to extended substance we refer magnitude, or ex-
tension in length, breadth, and depth, figure, motion,
situation, divisibility of parts themselves, and the like.
There are, however, besides these, certain things of
which we have an internal experience that ought not
to be referred either to the mind of itself, or to the body
alone, but to the close and intimate union between
them, as will hereafter be shown in its place. Of this
class are the appetites of hunger and thirst, etc., and
also the emotions or passions of the mind which are
not exclusively mental affections, as the emotions of
anger, joy, sadness, love, etc. ; and, finally, all the sen-
* Things and the affections of things are (in the French)
equivalent to "what has some (1. e. a real) existence," as op-
posed to the class of "eternal truths," which have merely an
ideal existence.
PART I. 155
sations, as of pain, titillation, light and colours, sounds,
smells, tastes, heat, hardness, and the other tactile
qualities.
XLIX. That the eternal truths cannot be thus
enumerated, but that this is not necessary.
What I have already enumerated we are to regard
as things, or the qualities or modes of things. We
now come to speak of eternal truths. When we ap-
prehend that it is impossible a thing can arise from
nothing, this proposition, ex nihilo nihil fit, is not con-
sidered as somewhat existing, or as the mode of a
thing, but as an eternal truth having its seat in our
mind, and is called a common notion or axiom. Of
this class are the following : — It is impossible the same
thing can at once be and not be; what is done cannot
be undone ; he who thinks must exist while he thinks ;
and innumerable others, the whole of which it is in-
deed difficult to enumerate, but this is not necessary,
since, if blinded by no prejudices, we cannot fail to
know them when the occasion of thinking them occurs.
L. That these truths are clearly perceived, but not
equally by all men, on account of prejudices.
And, indeed, with regard to these common notions,
it is not to be doubted that they can be clearly and dis-
tinctly known, for otherwise they would not merit this
appellation : as, in truth, some of them are not, with re-
spect to all men, equally deserving of the name, because
they are not equally admitted by all : not, however,
from this reason, as I think, that the faculty of knowl-
edge of one man extends farther than that of another,
but rather because these common notions are opposed
to the prejudices of some, who, on this account, are not
able readily to embrace them, even although others,
156 THE PRINCIPLES OF PHILOSOPHY.
who are free from those prejudices, apprehend them
with the greatest clearness.
LI. What substance is, and that the term is not ap-
plicable to God and the creatures in the same sense.
But with regard to what we consider as things or
the modes of things, it is worth while to examine each
of them by itself. By substance we can conceive noth-
ing else than a thing which exists in such a way as to
stand in need of nothing beyond itself in order to its
existence. And, in truth, there can be conceived but
one substance which is absolutely independent, and that
is God. We perceive that all other things can exist
only by help of the concourse of God. And, accord-
ingly, the term substance does not apply to God and
the creatures univocally, to adopt a term familiar in
the schools ; that is, no signification of this word can
be distinctly understood which is common to God and
them.
LII. That the term is applicable univocally to the
mind and the body, and how substance itself is known.
Created substances, however, whether corporeal or
thinking, may be conceived under this common con-
cept ; for these are things which, in order to their exist-
ence, stand in need of nothing but the concourse of
God. But yet substance cannot be first discovered
merely from its being a thing which exists independ-
ently, for existence by itself is not observed by us.
We easily, however, discover substance itself from any
attribute of it, by this common notion, that of nothing
there are no attributes, properties, or qualities: for,
from perceiving that some attribute is present, we infer
that some existing thing or substance to which it may
be attributed is also of necessity present.
PART I. 157
LUI. That of every substance there is one princi-
pal attribute, as thinking of the mind, extension of the
body.
But, although any attribute is sufficient to lead us to
the knowledge of substance, there is, however, one
principal property of every substance, which constitutes
its nature or essence, and upon which all the others de-
pend. Thus, extension in length, breadth, and depth,
constitutes the nature of corporeal substance; and
thought the nature of thinking substance. For every
other thing that can be attributed to body, presupposes
extension, and is only some mode of an extended
thing ; as all the properties we discover in the mind are
only diverse modes of thinking. Thus, for example,
we cannot conceive figure unless in something ex-
tended, nor motion unless in extended space, nor imagi-
nation, sensation, or will, unless in a thinking thing.
But, on the other hand, we can conceive extension
without figure or motion, and thought without imagi-
nation or sensation, and so of the others ; as is clear to
any one who attends to these matters.
LIV. How we may have clear and distinct notions
of the substance which thinks, of that which is cor-
poreal, and of God.
And thus we may easily have two clear and distinct
notions or ideas, the one of created substance, which
thinks, the other of corporeal substance, provided we
carefully distinguish all the attributes of thought from
those of extension. We may also have a clear and
distinct idea of an uncreated and independent thinking
substance, that is, of God, provided we do not suppose
that this idea adequately represents to us all that is in
God, and do not mix up with it anything fictitious, but
158 THE PRINCIPLES OF PHILOSOPHY.
attend simply to the characters that are comprised in
the notion we have of him, and which we clearly know
to belong to the nature of an absolutely perfect Being.
For no one can deny that there is in us such an idea of
God, without groundlessly supposing that there is no
knowledge of God at all in the human mind.
LV. How duration, order, and number may be also
distinctly conceived.
We will also have most distinct conceptions of dura-
tion, order, and number, if, in place of mixing up with
our notions of them that which properly belongs to the
concept of substance, we merely think that the duration
of a thing is a mode under which we conceive this
thing, in so far as it continues to exist; and, in like
manner, that order and number are not in reality dif-
ferent from things disposed in order and numbered,
but only modes under which we diversely consider
these things.
LVI. What are modes, qualities, attributes.
And, indeed, we here understand by modes the same
with what we elsewhere designate attributes or quali-
ties. But when we consider substance as affected or
varied by them, we use the term modes ; when from
this variation it may be denominated of such a kind,
we adopt the term qualities [to designate the different
modes which cause it to be so named] ; and, finally,
when we simply regard these modes as in the substance,
we call them attributes. Accordingly, since God must
be conceived as superior to change, it is not proper to
say that there are modes or qualities in him, but sim-
ply attributes ; and even in created things that which is
found in them always in the same mode, as existence
PART I. 159
and duration in the thing which exists and endures,
ought to be called attribute and not mode or quality.
LVII. That some attributes exist in the things to
which they are attributed, and others only in our
thought ; and what duration and time are.
Of these attributes or modes there are some which
exist in the things themselves, and others that have
only an existence in our thought ; thus, for example,
time, which we distinguish from duration taken in its
generality, and call the measure of motion, is only a
certain mode under which we think duration itself, for
we do not indeed conceive the duration of things that
are moved to be different from the duration of things
that are not moved : as is evident from this, that if two
bodies are in motion for an hour, the one moving
quickly and the other slowly, we do not reckon more
time in the one than in the other, although there may
be much more motion in the one of the bodies than in
the other. But that we may comprehend the duration
of all things under a common measure, we compare
their duration with that of the greatest and most regu-
lar motions that give rise to years and days, and which
we call time ; hence what is so designated is nothing
superadded to duration, taken in its generality, but a
mode of thinking.
LVIII. That number and all universals are only
modes of thought.
In the same way number, when it is not considered
as in created things, but merely in the abstract or in
general, is only a mode of thinking; and the same is
true of all those general ideas we call universals.
LIX. How universals are formed ; and what are the
i6o THE PRINCIPLES OF PHILOSOPHY.
five common, viz., genus, species, difference, property,
and accident.
Universals arise merely from our making use of one
and the same idea in thinking of all individual objects
between which there subsists a certain likeness ; and
when we comprehend all the objects represented by
this idea under one name, this term likewise becomes
universal. For example, when we see two stones, and
do not regard their nature farther than to remark that
there are two of them, we form the idea of a certain
number, which we call the binary ; and when we after-
wards see two birds or two trees, and merely take no-
tice of them so far as to observe that there are two of
them, we again take up the same idea as before, which
is, accordingly, universal ; and we likewise give to this
number the same universal appellation of binary. In
the same way, when we consider a figure of three sides,
we form a certain idea, which we call the idea of a
triangle, and we afterwards make use of it as the uni-
versal to represent to our mind all other figures of three
sides. But when we remark more particularly that of
figures of three sides, some have a right angle and
others not, we form the universal idea of a right-an-
gled triangle, which being related to the preceding as
more general, may be called species ; and the right an-
gle the universal difference by which right-angled
triangles are distinguished from all others ; and farther,
because the square of the side which sustains the right
angle is equal to the squares of the other two sides, and
because this property belongs only to this species of
triangles, we may call it the universal property of the
species. Finally, if we suppose that of these triangles
some are moved and others not, this will be their uni-
PART I. 161
versai accident ; and, accordingly, we commonly reckon
five universals, viz., genus, species, difference, prop-
erty, accident.
LX. Of distinctions ; and first of the real.
But number in things themselves arises from the
distinction there is between them: and distinction is
threefold, viz., real, modal, and of reason. The real
properly subsists between two or more substances ; and
it is sufficient to assure us that two substances are
really mutually distinct, if only we are able clearly and
distinctly to conceive the one of them without the other.
For the knowledge we have of God renders it certain
that he can effect all that of which we have a distinct
idea: wherefore, since we have now, for example, the
idea of an extended and corporeal substance, though
we as yet do not know with certainty whether any sucK
thing is really existent, nevertheless, merely because
we have the idea of it, we may be assured that such
may exist ; and, if it really exists, that every part which
we can determine by thought must be really distinct
from the other parts of the same substance. In the
same way, since every one is conscious that he thinks,
and that he in thought can exclude from himself every
other substance, whether thinking or extended, it is
certain that each of us thus considered is really dis-
tinct from every other thinking and corporeal sub-
stance. And although we suppose that God united a
body to a soul so closely that it was impossible to form
a more intimate union, and thus made a composite
whole, the two substances would remain really distinct,
notwithstanding this union ; for with whatever tie God
connected them, he was not able to rid himself of the
power he possessed of separating them, or of conserv-
i62 THE PRINCIPLES OF PHILOSOPHY.
ing the one apart from the other, and the things which
God can separate or conserve separately are really dis-
tinct.
LXI. Oi the modal distinction.
There are two kinds of modal distinctions, viz., that
between the mode properly so-called and the substance
of which it is a mode, and that between two modes of
the same substance. Of the former we have an exam-
ple in this, that we can clearly apprehend substance
apart from the mode which we say differs from it;
while, on the other hand, we cannot conceive this mode
without conceiving the substance itself. There is, for
example, a modal distinction between figure or motion
and corporeal substance in which both exist; there is
a similar distinction between affirmation or recollection
and the mind. Of the latter kind we have an illustra-
tion in our ability to recognise the one of. two modes
apart from the other, as figure apart from motion, and
motion apart from figure ; though we cannot think of
either the one or the other without thinking of the
common substance in which they adhere. If, for ex-
ample, a stone is moved, and is withal square, we can,
indeed, conceive its square figure without its motion,
and reciprocally its motion without its square figure ;
but we can conceive neither this motion nor this figure
apart from the substance of the stone. As for the dis-
tinction according to which the mode of one substance
is different from another substance, or from the mode
of another substance, as the motion of one body is dif-
ferent from another body or from the mind, or as mo-
tion is different from doubt, it seems to me that it
should be called real rather than modal, because these
modes cannot be clearly conceived apart from the
PART I. 163
really distinct substances of which they are the modes.
LXII. Of the distinction of reason (logical dis-
tinction).
Finally, the distinction of reason is that between a
substance and some one of its attributes, without which
it is impossible, however, we can have a distinct con-
ception of the substance itself; or between two such
attributes of a common substance, the one of which we
essay to think without the other. This distinction is
manifest from our inability to form a clear and dis-
tinct idea of such substance, if we separate from it
such attribute ; or to have a clear perception of the one
of two such attributes if we separate it from the other.
For example, because any substance which ceases to
endure ceases also to exist, duration is not distinct
from substance except in thought (ratione) ; and in
general all the modes of thinking which we consider
as in objects differ only in thought, as well from the
objects of which they are thought as from each other
in a common object.* It occurs, indeed, to me that I
have elsewhere classed this kind of distinction with the
modal (viz., towards the end of the Reply to the First
Objections to the Meditations on the First Philoso-
phy) ; but there it was only necessary to treat of these
distinctions generally, and it was sufficient for my pur-
pose at that time simply to distinguish both of them
from the real.
LXIII. How thought and extension may be dis-
* "and generally all the attributes that lead us to entertain
different thoughts of the same thing, such as, for example,
the extension of body and its property of divisibility, do not
differ from the body which is to us the object of them, or from
each other, unless as we sometimes confusedly think the one
without thinking the other. — French.
IÔ4 THE PRINCIPLES OF PHILOSOPHY.
tinctly known, as constituting, the one the nature of
mind, the other that of body.
Thought and extension may be regarded as consti-
tuting the natures of intelligent and corporeal sub-
stance ; and then they must not be otherwise conceived
than as the thinking and extended substances them-
selves, that is, as mind and body, which in this way are
conceived with the greatest clearness and distinctness.
Moreover, we more easily conceive extended or think-
ing substance than substance by itself, or with the
omission of its thinking or extension. For there is
some difficulty in abstracting the notion of substance
from the notions of thinking and extension, which, in
truth, are only diverse in thought itself ~(l e., logically
different) ; and a concept is not more distinct because
it comprehends fewer properties, but because we ac-
curately distinguish what is comprehended in it from
all other notions.
LXIV. How these may likewise be distinctly con-
ceived as modes of substance.
Thought and extension may be also considered as
modes of substance ; in as far, namely, as the same
mind may have many different thoughts, and the same
body, with its size unchanged, may be extended in sev-
eral diverse ways, at one time more in length and less
in breadth or depth, and at another time more in
breadth and less in length ; and then they are modally
distinguished from substance, and can be conceived not
less clearly and distinctly, provided they be not re-
garded as substances or things separated from others,
but simply as modes of things. For by regarding
them as in the substances of which they are the modes,
we distinguish them from these substances, and take
PART I. 165
them for what in truth they are : whereas, on the other
hand, if we wish to consider them apart from the sub-
stances in which they are, we should by this itself re-
gard them as self -subsisting things, and thus confound
the ideas of mode and substance.
LXV. How we may likewise know their modes.
In the same way we will best apprehend the diverse
modes of thought, as intellection, imagination, recol-
lection, volition, etc., and also the diverse modes of ex-
tension, or those that belong to extension, as all figures,
the situation of parts and their motions, provided we
consider them simply as modes of the things in which
they are ; and motion as far as it is concerned, pro-
vided we think merely of locomotion, without seeking
to know the force that produces it, and which never-
theless I will essay to explain in its own place.
LXVI. How our sensations, affections, and appe-
tites may be clearly known, although we are frequently
wrong in our judgments regarding them.
There remain our sensations, affections, and appe-
tites, of which we may also have a clear knowledge, if
we take care to comprehend in the judgments we form
of them only that which is precisely contained in our
perception of them, and of which we are immediately
conscious. There is, however, great difficulty in ob-
serving this, at least in respect of sensations ; because
we have all, without exception, from our youth judged
that all the things we perceived by our senses had an
existence beyond our thought, and that they were en-
tirely similar to the sensations, that is, perceptions, we
had of them. Thus when, for example, we saw a cer-
tain colour, we thought we saw something occupying
a place out of us, and which was entirely similar to
i66 THE PRINCIPLES OF PHILOSOPHY.
that idea of colour we were then conscious of; and
from the habit of judging in this way, we seemed to
see this so clearly and distinctly that we esteemed it
(i, e., the externality of the colour) certain and in-
dubitable.
LXVII. That we are frequently deceived in our
judgments regarding pain itself.
The same prejudice has place in all our other sensa-
tions, even in those of titillation and pain. For though
we are not in the habit of believing that there exist out
of us objects that resemble titillation and pain, we do
not nevertheless consider these sensations as in the
mind alone, or in our perception, but as in the hand,
or foot, or some other part of our body. There is no
reason, however, to constrain us to believe that the
pain, for example, which we feel, as it were, in the
foot is something out of the mind existing in the foot,
or that the light which we see, as it were, in the sun.
exists in the sun as it is in us. Both these beliefs are
prejudices of our early years, as will clearly appear in
the sequel.
LXVIII. How in these things what we clearly con-
ceive is to be distinguished from that in which we may
be deceived.
But that we may distinguish what is clear in our sen-
sations from what is obscure, we ought most carefully
to observe that we possess a clear and distinct knowl-
edge of pain, colour, and other things of this sort,
when we consider them simply as sensations or
thoughts; but that, when they are judged to be certain
things subsisting beyond our mind, we are wholly una-
ble to form any conception of them. Indeed, when
■any one tells us that he sees colour in a body or feels
PART I. 167
pain in one of his limbs, this is exactly the same as if
he said that he there saw or felt something of the na-
ture of which he was entirely ignorant, or that he did
not know what he saw or felt. For although, when
less attentively examining his thoughts, a person may
easily persuade himself that he has some knowledge of
it, since he supposes that there is something resem-
bling that sensation of colour or of pain of which he is
conscious ; yet, if he reflects on what the sensation of
colour or pain represents to him as existing in a
coloured body or in a wounded member, he will find
that of such he has absolutely no knowledge.
LXIX. That magnitude, figure, etc., are known far
differently from colour, pain, etc.
What we have said above will be more manifest,
especially if we consider that size in the body perceived,
figure, motion (at least local, for philosophers by
fancying other kinds of motion have rendered its na-
ture less intelligible to themselves), the situation of
parts, duration, number, and those other properties
which, as we have already said, we clearly perceive in
all bodies, are known by us in a way altogether differ-
ent from that in which we know what colour is in the
same body, or pain, smell, taste, or any other of those
properties which I have said above must be referred to
the senses. For although when we see a body we are
not less assured of its existence from its appearing
figured than from its appearing coloured,* we yet
know with far greater clearness its property of figure
than its colour.
LXX. That we may judge of sensible things in two
* " by the colour we perceive on occasion of it." — French.
168 THE PRINCIPLES OF PHILOSOPHY.
ways, by the one of which we avoid error, by the other
fall into it.
It is thus manifest that to say we perceive colours in
objects is in reality equivalent to saying we perceive
something in objects and are yet ignorant of what it is,
except as that which determines in us a certain highly
vivid and clear sensation, which we call the sensation
of colours. There is, however, very great diversity in
the manner of judging: for so long as we simply judge
that there is an unknown something in objects (that is,
in things such as they are, from which the sensation
reached us), so far are we from falling into error that,
on the contrary, we thus rather provide against it, for
we are less apt to judge rashly of a thing which we
observe we do not know. But when we think we per-
ceive colours in objects, although we are in reality ig-
norant of what we then denominate colour, and are
unable to conceive any resemblance between the col-
our we suppose to be in objects, and that of which we
are conscious in sensation, yet because we do not ob-
serve this, or becausethere are in objects several prop-
erties, as size, figure, number, etc., which, as we clearly
know, exist, or may exist in them as they are perceived
by our senses or conceived by our understanding, we
easily glide into the error of holding that what is called
colour in objects is something entirely resembling the
colour we perceive, and thereafter of supposing that
we have a clear perception of what is in no way per-
ceived by us.
LXXI. That the chief cause of our errors is to be
found in the prejudices of our childhood.
And here we may notice the first and chief cause of
our errors. In early life the mind was so closely
PART I. 169
bound to the body that it attended to nothing beyond
the thoughts by which it perceived the objects that
made impression on the body : nor as yet did it refer
these thoughts to anything existing beyond itself, but
simply felt pain when the body was hurt, or pleasure
when anything beneficial to the body occurred, or if
the body was so highly affected that it was neither
greatly benefited nor hurt, the mind experienced the
sensations we call tastes, smells, sounds, heat, cold,
light, colours, and the like, which in truth are repre-
sentative of nothing existing out of our mind, and
which vary according to the diversities of the parts
and modes in which the body is affected.* The mind
at the same time also perceived magnitudes, figures,
motions, and the like, which were not presented to it
as sensations but as things or the modes of things ex-
isting, or at least capable of existing out of thought,
although it did not yet observe this difference between
these two kinds of perceptions. And afterwards when
the machine of the body, which has been so fabricated
by nature that it can of its own inherent power move
itself in various ways, by turning itself at random on
every side, followed after what was useful and avoided
what was detrimental ; the mind, which was closely
connected with it, reflecting on the objects it pursued
or avoided, remarked, for the first time, that they ex-
isted out of itself, and not only attributed to them
magnitudes, figures, motions, and the like, which it
apprehended either as things or as the modes of things,
* "which vary according to the diversities of the move-
ments that pass from all parts of our body to the part of the
brain to which it (the mind) is closely joined and united." —
French.
170 THE PRINCIPLES OF PHILOSOPHY.
but, in addition, attributed to them tastes, odours, and
the other ideas of that sort, the sensations of which
were caused by itself ;* and as it only considered other
objects in so far as they were useful to the body, in
which it was immersed, it judged that there was
greater or less reality in each object, according as the
impressions it caused on the body were more or less
powerful. Hence arose the belief that there was more
substance or body in rocks and metals than in air or
water, because the mind perceived in them more hard-
ness and weight. Moreover, the air was thought to
be merely nothing so long as we experienced no agi-
tation of it by the wind, or did not feel it hot or cold.
And because the stars gave hardly more light than the
slender flames of candles, we supposed that each star
was but of this size. Again, since the mind did not
observe that the earth moved on its axis, or that its
superficies was curved like that of a globe, it was on
that account more ready to judge the earth immovable
and its surface flat. And our mind has been imbued
from our infancy with a thousand other prejudices of
the same sort which afterwards in our youth we for-
got we had accepted without sufficient examination,
and admitted as possessed of the highest truth and
clearness, as if they had been known by means of our
senses, or implanted in us by nature.
LXXII. That the second cause of our errors is that
we cannot forget these prejudices.
And although now in our mature years, when the
mind, being no longer wholly subject to the body, is
not in the habit of referring all things to it, but also
* "which it perceived on occasion of them" (•£ e., of exter-
nal objects). — French.
PART I. 171
seeks to discover the truth of things considered in
themselves, we observe the falsehood of a great many
of the judgments we had before formed; yet we ex-
perience a difficulty in expunging them from our mem-
ory, and, so long as they remain there, they give rise
to various errors. Thus, for example, since from our
earliest years we imagined the stars to be of very small
size, we find it highly difficult to rid ourselves of this
imagination, although assured by plain astronomical
reasons that they are of the greatest, — so prevailing is
the power of preconceived opinion.
LXXIII. The third cause is, that we become fa-
tigued by attending to those objects which are not
present to the senses ; and that we are thus accustomed
to judge of these not from present perception but from
pre-conceived opinion.
Besides, our mind cannot attend to any object with-
out at length experiencing some pain and fatigue ; and
of all objects it has the greatest difficulty in attending
to those which are present neither to the senses nor
to the imagination: whether for the reason that this
is natural to it from its union with the body, or be-
cause in our early years, being occupied merely with
perceptions and imaginations, it has become more fa-
miliar with, and acquired greater facility in thinking
in those modes than in any other. Hence it also hap-
pens that many are unable to conceive any substance
except what is imaginable and corporeal, and even sen-
sible. For they are ignorant of the circumstance, that
those objects alone are imaginable which consist in ex-
tension, motion, and figure, while there are many oth-
ers besides these that are intelligible; and they per-
suade themselves that nothing can subsist but body,
172 THE PRINCIPLES OF PHILOSOPHY.
and, finally, that there is no body which is not sensible.
And since in truth we perceive no object such as it is
by sense alone [but only by our reason exercised upon
sensible objects], as will hereafter be clearly shown,
it thus happens that the majority during life perceive
nothing unless in a confused way.
LXXIV. The fourth source of our errors is, that we
attach our thoughts to words which do not express
them with accuracy.
Finally, since for the use of speech we attach all our
conceptions to words by which to express them, and
commit to memory our thoughts in connection with
these terms, and as we afterwards find it more easy
to recall the words than the things signified by them,
we can scarcely conceive anything with such distinct-
ness as to separate entirely what we conceive from the
words that were selected to express it. On this ac-
count the majority attend to words rather than to
things ; and thus very frequently assent to terms with-
out attaching to them any meaning, either because
they think they once understood them, or imagine they
received them from others by whom they were cor-
rectly understood. This, however, is not the place to
treat of this matter in detail, seeing the nature of the
human body has not yet been expounded, nor the ex-
istence even of body established ; enough, neverthe-
less, appears to have been said to enable one to distin-
guish such of our conceptions as are clear and distinct
from those that are obscure and confused.
LXXV. Summary of what must be observed in or-
der to philosophize correctly.
Wherefore if we would philosophize in earnest, and
give ourselves to the search after all the truths we are
PART I. 173
capable of knowing, we must, in the first place, lay
aside our prejudices ; in other words, we must take
care scrupulously to withhold our assent from the
opinions we have formerly admitted, until upon new
examination we discover that they are true. We
must, in the next place, make an orderly review of the
notions we have in our minds, and hold as true all and
only those which we will clearly and distinctly appre-
hend. In this way we will observe, first of all, that
we exist in so far as it is our nature to think, and at
the same time that there is a God upon whom we de-
pend; and after considering his attributes we will be
able to investigate the truth of all other things, since
God is the cause of them. Besides the notions we
have of God and of our mind, we will likewise find that
we possess the knowledge of many propositions which
are eternally true, as, for example, that nothing can-
not be the cause of anything, etc. We will farther
discover in our minds the knowledge of a corporeal
or extended nature that may be moved, divided, etc.,
and also of certain sensations that affect us, as of pain,
colours, tastes, etc., although we do not yet know the
cause of our being so affected; and, comparing what
we have now learne'd, by examining those things in
their order, with our former confused knowledge of
them, we will acquire the habit of forming clear and
distinct conceptions of all the objects we are capable
of knowing. In these few precepts seem to me to be
comprised the most general and important principles
of human knowledge.
LXXVI. That we ought to prefer the Divine au-
thority to our perception ;* but that, apart from things
* " reasonings." — French.
174 THE PRINCIPLES OF PHILOSOPHY.
revealed, we ought to assent to nothing that we do not
clearly apprehend.
Above all, we must impress on our memory the in-
fallible rule, that what God has revealed is incompar-
ably more certain than anything else ; and that we
ought to submit our belief to the Divine authority
rather than to our own judgment, even although per-
haps the light of reason should, with the greatest clear-
ness and evidence, appear to suggest to us something
contrary to what is revealed. But in things regarding
which there is no revelation, it is by no means con-
sistent with the character of a philosopher to accept
as true what he has not ascertained to be such, and
to trusf more to the senses, in other words, to the in-
considerate judgments of childhood than to the dic-
tates of mature reason.
PART IL
OF THE PRINCIPLES OF MATERIAL THINGS.
I. The grounds on which the existence of material
things may be known with certainty.
Although we are all sufficiently persuaded of the ex-
istence of material things, yet, since this was before
called in question by us, and since we reckoned the per-
suasion of their existence as among the prejudices of
our childhood, it is now necessary for us to investigate
the grounds on which this truth may be known with
certainty. In the first place, then, it cannot be doubted
that every perception we have comes to us from some
object different from our mind; for it is not in our
power to cause ourselves to experience one perception
rather than another, the perception being entirely de-
pendent on the object which affects our senses. It
may, indeed, be matter of inquiry whether that object
be God, or something different from God ; but because
we perceive, or rather, stimulated by sense, clearly and
distinctly apprehend, certain matter extended in length,
breadth, and thickness, the various parts of which have
different figures and motions, and give rise to the sen-
sation we have of colours, smells, pain, etc., God would,
without question, deserve to be regarded as a deceiver,
if he directly and of himself presented to our mind the
idea of this extended matter, or merely caused it to
be presented to us by some object which possessed
neither extension, figure, nor motion. For we clearly
175
176 THE PRINCIPLES OF PHILOSOPHY.
conceive this matter as entirely distinct from God, and
from ourselves, or our mind ; and appear even clearly
to discern that the idea of it is formed in us on occasion
of objects existing out of our minds, to which it is
in every respect similar. But since God cannot de-
ceive us, for this is repugnant to his nature, as has
been already remarked, we must unhesitatingly con-
clude that there exists a certain object extended in
length, breadth, and thickness, and possessing all those
properties which we clearly apprehend to belong to
what is extended. And this extended substance is
what we call body or matter.
II. How we likewise know that the human body is
closely connected with the mind.
We ought also to conclude that a certain body is
more closely united to our mind than any other, be-
cause we clearly observe that pain and other sensations
affect us without our foreseeing them ; and these, the
mind is conscious, do not arise from itself alone, nor
pertain to it, in so far as it is a thing which thinks,but
only in so far as it is united to another thing extended
and movable, which is called the human body. But
this is not the place to treat in detail of this matter.
III. That the perceptions of the senses do not teach
us what is in reality in things, but what is beneficial or
hurtful to the composite whole of mind and body.
It will be sufficient to remark that the perceptions
of the senses are merely to be referred to this intimate
union of the human body and mind, and that they usu-
ally make us aware of what, in external objects, may
be useful or adverse to this union, but do not present
to us these objects as they are in themselves, unless
occasionally and by accident. For, after this obser-
PART II. 177
vation, we will without difficulty lay aside the preju-
dices of the senses, and will have recourse to our
understanding alone on this question by reflecting
carefully on the ideas implanted in it by nature.
IV. That the nature of body consists not in weight
hardness, colour and the like, but in extension alone.
In this way we will discern that the nature of mat-
ter or body, considered in general, does not consist in
its being hard, or ponderous, or coloured, or that
which affects our senses in any other way, but simply
in its being a substance extended in length, breadth,
and depth. For with respect to hardness, we know
nothing of it by sense farther than that the parts of
hard bodies resist the motion of our hands on coming
into contact with them ; but if every, time our hands
moved towards any part, all the bodies in that place
receded as quickly as our hands approached, we
should never feel hardness ; and yet we have no rea-
son to believe that bodies which might thus recede
would on this account lose that which makes them
bodies. The nature of body does not, therefore, con-
sist in hardness. In the same way, it may be
shown that weight, colour, and all the other qualities
of this sort, which are perceived in corporeal matter,
may be taken from it, itself meanwhile remaining en-
tire : it thus follows that the nature of body depends
on none of these.
V. That the truth regarding the nature of body is
obscured by the opinions respecting rarefaction and
a vacuum with which we are pre-occupied.
There still remain two causes to prevent its being
fully admitted that the true nature of body consists in
extension alone. The first is the prevalent opinion,
178 THE PRINCIPLES OF PHILOSOPHY.
that most bodies admit of being so rarefied and con-
densed that, when rarefied, they have greater exten-
sion than when condensed; and some even have sub-
tilized to such a degree as to make a distinction be-
tween the substance of body and its quantity, and be-
tween quantity itself and extension. The second cause
is this, that where we conceive only extension in
length, breadth, and depth, we are not in the habit of
saying that body is there, but only space and further
void space, which the generality believe to be a mere
negation.
VI. In what way rarefaction takes place.
But with regard to rarefaction and condensation,
whoever gives his attention to his own thoughts, and
admits nothing of which he is not clearly conscious,
will not suppose that there is anything in those proc-
esses further than a change of figure in the body rare-
fied or condensed : so that, in other words, rare bodies
are those between the parts of which there are num-
erous distances filled with other bodies; and dense
bodies, on the other hand, those whose parts approach-
ing each other, either diminish these distances or take
them wholly away, in the latter of which cases the
body is rendered absolutely dense. The body, how-
ever, when condensed, has not, therefore, less exten-
sion than when the parts embrace a greater space,
owing to their removal from each other, and their dis-
persion into branches. For we ought not to attribute
to it the extension of the pores or distances which its
parts do not occupy when it is rarefied, but to the
other bodies that fill these interstices; just as when
we see a sponge full of water or any other liquid, we
do not suppose that each part of the sponge has on
PART IL 179
this account greater extension than when compressed
and dry, but only that its pores are wider, and there-
fore that the body is diffused over a larger space.
VII. That rarefaction cannot be intelligibly ex-
plained unless in the way here proposed.
And indeed I am unable to discover the force of the
reasons which have induced some to say that rarefac-
tion is the result of the augmentation of the quantity
of body, rather than to explain it on the principle ex-
emplified in the case of a sponge. For although when
air or water is rarefied we do not see any of the pores
that are rendered large, or the new body that is added
to occupy them, it is yet less agreeable to reason to
suppose something that is unintelligible for the pur-
pose of giving a verbal and merely apparent explana-
tion of the rarefaction of bodies, than to conclude, be-
cause of theit rarefaction, that there are pores or dis-
tances between the parts which are increased in size,
and filled with some new body. Nor ought we to re-
frain from assenting to this explanation, because we
perceive this new body by none of our senses, for
there is no reason which obliges us to believe that we
should perceive by our senses all the bodies in exist-
ence. And we see that it is very easy to explain rare-
faction in this manner, but impossible in any other;
for, in fine, there would be, as appears to me, a mani-
fest contradiction in supposing that any body was in-
creased by a quantity or extension which it had not
before, without the addition to it of a new extended
substance, in other words, of another body, because
it is impossible to conceive any addition of extension
or quantity to a thing without supposing the addition
i8o THE PRINCIPLES OF PHILOSOPHY.
of a substance having quantity or extension, as will
more clearly appear from what follows.
VIII. That quantity and number differ only in
thought (ratione) from that which has quantity and
is numbered.
For quantity differs from extended substance, and
number from what is numbered, not in reality but
merely in our thought; so that, for example, w é e may
consider the whole nature of a corporeal substance
which is comprised in a space of ten feet, although we
do not attend to this measure of ten feet, for the ob-
vious reason that the thing conceived is of the same
nature in any part of that space as in the whole ; and,
on the other hand, we can conceive the number ten,
as also a continuous quantity of ten feet, without
thinking of this determinate substance, because the
concept of the number ten is manifestly the same
whether we consider a number of ten feet or ten of any-
thing else ; and we can conceive a continuous quantity
of ten feet without thinking of this or that determin-
ate substance, although we cannot conceive it without
some extended substance of which it is the quantity.
It is in reality, however, impossible that any, even the
least part, of such quantity or extension, can be taken
away, without the retrenchment at the same time of
as much of the substance, nor, on the other hand, can
we lessen the substance, without at the same time tak-
ing as much from the quantity or extension.
IX. That corporeal substance, when distinguished
from its quantity, is confusedly conceived as some-
thing incorporeal.
Although perhaps some express themselves other-
wise on this matter, I am nevertheless convinced that
PART IL 181
they do not think differently from what I have now
said: for when they distinguish (corporeal) substance
from extension or quantity, they either mean nothing
by the word (corporeal) substance, or they form in
their minds merely a confused idea of incorporeal sub-
stance, which they falsely attribute to corporeal, and
leave to extension the true idea of this corporeal sub-
stance ; which extension they call an accident, but with
such impropriety as to make it easy to discover that
their words are not in harmony with their thoughts.
X. Wliat space or internal place is.
Space or internal place, and the corporeal substance
which is comprised in it, are not different in reality,
but merely in the mode in which they are wont to be
conceived by us. For, in truth, the same extension
in length, breadth, and depth, which constitutes space,
constitutes body ; and the difference between them lies
only in this, that in body we consider extension as
particular, and conceive it to change with the body ;
whereas in space we attribute to extension a generic
unity, so that after taking from a certain space the
body which occupied it, we do not suppose that we
have at the same time removed the extension of the
space, because it appears to us that the same extension
remains there so long as it is of the same magnitude
and figure, and preserves the same situation in respect
to certain bodies around it, by means of which we
determine this space.
XI. How space is not in reality different from cor-
poreal substance.
And indeed it will be easy to discern that it is the
same extension which constitutes the nature of body
as of space, and that these two things are mutually di-
i8a THE PRINCIPLES OF PHILOSOPHY.
verse only as the nature of the genus and species dif-
fers from that of the individual, provided we reflect
on the idea we have of any body, taking a stone for
example, and reject all that is not essential to the na-
ture of body. In the first place, then, hardness may
be rejected, because if the stone were liquefied or re-
duced to powder, it would no longer possess hard-
ness, and yet would not cease to be a body; colour
also may be thrown out of account, because we have
frequently seen stones so transparent as to have no
colour ; again, we may reject weight, because we have
the case of fire, which, though very light, is still a
body; and, finally, we may reject cold, heat, and all
the other qualities of this sort, either because they
are not considered as in the stone, or because, with
the change of these qualities, the stone is not supposed
to have lost the nature of body. After this examina-
tion we will find that nothing remains in the idea of
body, except that it is something extended in length,
breadth, and depth; and this something is comprised
in our idea of space, not only of that which is full of
body, but even of what is called void space.
XII. How space differs from body in our mode of
conceiving it.
There is, however, some difference between them
in the mode of conception; for if we remove a stone
from the space or place in which it was, we conceive
that its extension also is taken away, because we
regard this as particular, and inseparable from the
stone itself: but meanwhile we suppose that the same
extension of place in which this stone was remains,
although the place of the stone be occupied by wood,
water, air, or by any other body, or be even supposed
PART IL 183
vacant, because we now consider extension in general,
and think that the same is common to stones, wood,
water, air, and other bodies, and even to a vacuum
itself, if there is any such thing, provided it be of the
same magnitude and figure as before, and preserve
the same situation among the external bodies which
determine this space.
XIII. What external place is.
The reason of which is, that the words place and
space signify nothing really different from body which
is said to be in place, but merely designate its magni-
tude, figure, and situation among other bodies. For
it is necessary, in order to determine this situation,
to regard certain other bodies which we consider as
immovable; and, according as we look to different
bodies, we may see that the same thing at the same
time does and does not change place. For example,
when a vessel is being carried out to sea, a person sit-
ting at the stern may be said to remain always in one
place, if we look to the parts of the vessel, since with
respect to these he preserves the same situation; and
on the other hand, if regard be had to the neighbour-
ing shores, the same person will seem to be perpetually
changing place, seeing he is constantly receding from
one shore and approaching another. And besides, if
we suppose that the earth moves, and that it makes
precisely as much way from west to east as the vessel
from east to west, we will again say that the person
at the stern does not change his place, because this
place will be determined by certain immovable points
which we imagine to be in the heavens. But if at
length we are persuaded that there are no points really
immovable in the universe, as will hereafter be shown
i84 THE PRINCIPLES OF PHILOSOPHY.
to be probable, we will thence conclude that nothing
has a permanent place unless in so far as it is fixed
by our thought.
XIV. Wherein place and space differ.
The terms place and space, however, differ in sig-
nification, because place more expressly designates
situation than magnitude or figure, while, on the other
hand, we think of the latter when we speak of space.
For we frequently say that a thing succeeds to the
place of another, although it be not exactly of the
same magnitude or figure; but we do not therefore
admit that it occupies the same space as the other ;
and when the situation is changed we say that the
place also is changed, although there are the same
magnitude and figure as before : so that when we say
that a thing is in a particular place, we mean merely
that it is situated in a determinate way in respect of
certain other objects ; and when we add that it occu-
pies such a space or place, we understand besides that
it is of such determinate magnitude and figure as ex-
actly to fill this space.
XV. How external place is rightly taken for the
superficies of the surrounding body.
And thus we never indeed distinguish space from
extension in length, breadth, and depth ; we sometimes,
however, consider place as in the thing placed, and at
other times as out of it. Internal place indeed differs
in no way from space ; but external place may be taken
for the superficies that immediately surrounds the thing
placed. It ought to be remarked that by superficies
we do not here understand any part of the surround-
ing body, but only the boundary between the surround-
ing and surrounded bodies, which is nothing more than
PART II. 185
a mode ; or at least that we speak of superficies in gen-
eral which is no part of one body rather than another,
but is always considered the same, provided it retain
the same magnitude and figure. For although the
whole surrounding body with its superficies were
changed, it would not be supposed that the body which
was surrounded by it had therefore changed its place,
if it meanwhile preserved the same situation with re-
spect to the other bodies that are regarded as immov-
able. Thus, if we suppose that a boat is carried in
one direction by the current of a stream, and impelled
by the wind in the opposite with an equal force, so
that its situation with respect to the banks is not
changed, we will readily admit that it remains in the
same place, although the whole superficies which sur-
rounds it is incessantly changing.
XVI. That a vacuum or space in which there is
absolutely no body is repugnant to reason.
With regard to a vacuum, in the philosophical sense
of the term, that is, a space in which there is no sub-
stance, it is evident that such does not exist, seeing
the extension of space or internal place is not differ-
ent from that of body. For since from this alone, that
a body has extension in length, breadth, and depth,
we have reason to conclude that it is a substance, it
being absolutely contradictory that nothing should
possess extension, we ought to form a similar infer-
ence regarding the space which is supposed void, viz.,
that since there is extension in it there is necessarily
also substance.
XVII. That a vacuum in the ordinary use of the
term does not exclude all body.
And, in truth, by the term vacuum in its common
i86 THE PRINCIPLES OF PHILOSOPHY.
use, we do not mean a place or space in which there
is absolutely nothing, but only a place in which there
is none of those things we presume ought to be there.
Thus, because a pitcher is made to hold water, it is
said to be empty when it is merely filled with air; or
if there are no fish in a fish-pond, we say there is
nothing in it, although it be full of water ; thus a ves-
sel is said to be empty, when, in place of the merchan-
dise which it was designed to carry, it is loaded with
sand only, to enable it to resist the violence of the
wind; and, finally, it is in the same sense that we say
space is void when it contains nothing sensible, al-
though it contain created and self -subsisting matter;
for we are not in the habit of considering the bodies
near us, unless in so far as they cause in our organs
of sense, impressions strong enough to enable us to
perceive them. And if, in place of keeping in mind
what ought to be understood by these terms a vacuum
and nothing, we afterwards suppose that in the space
we called a vacuum, there is not only no sensible ob-
ject, but no object at all, we will fall into the same
error as if, because a pitcher in which there is noth-
ing but air, is, in common speech, said to be empty,
we were therefore to judge that the air contained in
it is not a substance {res subsistens).
XVIII. How the prejudice of an absolute vacuum
is to be corrected.
We have almost all fallen into this error from the
earliest age, for, observing that there is no necessary
connection between a vessel and the body it contains,
we thought that God at least could take from a vessel
the body which occupied it, without it being necessary
that any other should be put in the place of the one
PART IL 187
removed. But that we may be able now to correct
this false opinion, it is necessary to remark that there
is in truth no connection between the vessel and the
particular body which it contains, but that there is an
absolutely necessary connection between the concave
figure of the vessel and the extension considered gen-
erally which must be comprised in this cavity ; so that
it is not more contradictory to conceive a mountain
without a valley than such a cavity without the ex-
tension it contains, or this extension apart from an
extended substance, for, as we have often said, of
nothing there can be no extension. And accordingly,
if it be asked what would happen were God to remove
from a vessel all the body contained in it, without per-
mitting another body to occupy its place, the answer
must be that the sides of the vessel would thus come
into proximity with each other. For two bodies must
touch each other when there is nothing between them,
and it is manifestly contradictory for two bodies to
be apart, in other words, that there should be a dis-
tance between them, and this distance yet be nothing;
for all distance is a mode of extension, and cannot
therefore exist without an extended substance.
XIX. That this confirms what was said of rarefac-
tion.
After we have thus remarked that the nature of cor-
poreal substance consists only in its being an extended
thing, and that its extension is not different from that
which we attribute to space, however empty, it is easy
to discover the impossibility of any one of its parts in
any way whatsoever occupying more space at one time
than at another, and thus of being otherwise rarefied
than in the way explained above ; and it is easy to per-
i88 THE PRINCIPLES OF PHILOSOPHY.
ceive also that there cannot be more matter or body in
a vessel when it is filled with lead or gold, or any other
body however heavy and hard, than when it but con-
tains air and is supposed to be empty : for the quan-
tity of the parts of which a body is composed does not
depend on their weight or hardness, but only on the
extension, which is always equal in the same vase.
XX. That from this the non-existence of atoms
may likewise be demonstrated.
We likewise discover that there cannot exist any
atoms or parts of matter that are of their own nature
indivisible. For however small we suppose these parts
to be, yet because they are necessarily extended, we
are always able in thought to divide any one of them
into two or more smaller parts, and may accordingly
admit their divisibility. For there is nothing we can
divide in thought which we do not thereby recognize
to be divisible; and, therefore, were we to judge it in-
divisible our judgment would not be in harmony with
the knowledge we have of the thing ; and although we
should even suppose that God had reduced any particle
of matter to a smallness so extreme that it did not
admit of being further divided, it would nevertheless
be improperly styled indivisible, for though God had
rendered the particle so small that it was not in the
power of any creature to divide it, he could not how-
ever deprive himself of the ability to do so, since it is
absolutely impossible for him to lessen his own om-
nipotence, as was before observed. Wherefore, abso-
lutely speaking, the smallest extended particle is al-
ways divisible, since it is such of its very nature.
XXI. It is thus also demonstrated that the exten-
sion of the world is indefinite.
PART II. 189
We further discover that this world or the whole
(universitas) of corporeal substance, is extended with-
out limit, for wherever we fix a limit, we still not only
imagine beyond it spaces indefinitely extended, but
perceive these to be truly imaginable, in other words,
to be in reality such as we imagine them ; so that they
contain in them corporeal substance indefinitely ex-
tended, for, as has been already shown at length, the
idea of extension which we conceive in any space what-
ever is plainly identical with the idea of corporeal sub-
stance.
XXII. It also follows that the matter of the heavens
and earth is the same, and that there cannot be a plur-
ality of worlds.
And it may also be easily inferred from all this that
the earth and heavens are made of the same matter;
and that even although there were an infinity of
worlds, they would all be composed of this matter ;
from which it follows that a plurality of worlds is im-
possible, because we clearly conceive that the matter
whose nature consists only in its being an extended
substance, already wholly occupies all the imaginable
spaces where these other worlds could alone be, and we
cannot find in ourselves the idea of any other matter.
XXIII. That all the variety of matter, or the di-
versity of its forms, depends on motion.
There is therefore but one kind of matter in the
whole universe, and this we know only by its being ex-
tended. All the properties we distinctly perceive to
belong to it are reducible to its capacity of being di-
vided and moved according to its parts; and accord-
ingly it is capable of all those affections which we per-
ceive can arise from the motion of its parts. For the
190 THE PRINCIPLES OF PHILOSOPHY.
partition of matter in thought makes no change in it ;
but all variation of it, or diversity of form, depends on
motion. The philosophers even seem universally to
have observed this, for they said that nature was the
principle of motion and rest, and by nature they under-
stood that by which all corporeal things become such
as they are found in experience.
XXIV. What motion is, taking the term in its
common use.
But motion (viz., local, for I can conceive no other
kind of motion, and therefore I do not think we ought
to suppose there is any other in nature), in the ordi-
nary sense of the term, is nothing more than the action
by which a body passes from one place to another.
And just as we have remarked above that the same
thing may be said to change and not to change place
at the same time, so also we may say that the same
thing is at the same time moved and not moved. Thus,
for example, a person seated in a vessel which is set-
ting sail, thinks he is in motion if he look to the shore
that he has left, and consider it as fixed ; but not if he
regard the ship itself, among the parts of which he
preserves always the same situation. Moreover, be-
cause we are accustomed to suppose that there is no
motion without action, and that in rest there is the
cessation of action, the person thus seated is more
properly said to be at rest than in motion, seeing he is
not conscious of being in action.
XXV. What motion is properly so called.
But if, instead of occupying ourselves with that
which has no foundation, unless in ordinary usage, we
desire to know what ought to be understood by mo-
tion according to the truth of the thing, we may say,
PART IL 191
in order to give it a determinate nature, that it is the
transporting of one part of matter or of one body from
the vicinity of those bodies that are in immediate con-
tact with it, or which we regard as at rest, 9 to the
vicinity of other bodies. By a body as a part of mat-
ter, I understand all that which is transferred together,
although it be perhaps composed of several parts,
which in themselves have other motions; and I say
that it is the transporting and not the force or action
which transports, with the view of showing that mo-
tion is always in the movable thing, not in that which
moves ; for it seems to me that we are not accustomed
to distinguish these two things with sufficient accur-
acy. Farther, I understand that it is a mode of the
movable thing, and not a substance, just as figure is
a property of the thing figured, and repose of that
which is at rest.
PART III.
OF THE VISIBLE WORLD.
I. That we cannot think too highly of the works of
God.
Having now ascertained certain principles of mate-
rial things, which were sought, not by the prejudices
of the senses, but by the light of reason, and which
thus possess so great evidence that we cannot doubt of
their truth, it remains for us to consider whether from
these alone we can deduce the explication of all the
phenomena of nature. We will commence with those
phenomena that are of the greatest generality, and
upon which the others depend, as, for example, with
the general structure of this whole visible world. But
in order to our philosophizing aright regarding this,
two things are first of all to be observed. The first is,
that we should ever bear in mind the infinity of the
power and goodness of God, that we may not fear fall-
ing into error by imagining his works to be too great,
beautiful, and perfect, but that we may, on the con-
trary, take care lest, by supposing limits to them of
which we have no certain knowledge, we appear to
think less highly than we ought of the power of God.
II. That we ought to beware lest, in our presump-
tion, we imagine that the ends which God proposed to
himself in the creation of the world are understood by
us.
The second is, that we should beware of presuming
192
PART III. 193
too highly of ourselves, as it seems we should do if we
supposed certain limits to the world, without being as-
sured of their existence either by natural reasons or by
divine revelation, as if the power of our thought ex-
tended beyond what God has in reality made ; but like-
wise still more if we persuaded ourselves that all
things were created by God for us only, or if we
merely supposed that we could comprehend by the
power of our intellect the ends which God proposed to
himself in creating the universe.
III. In what sense it may be said that all things
were created for the sake of man.
For although, as far as regards morals, it may be a
pious thought to believe that God made all things for
us, seeing we may thus be incited to greater gratitude
and love toward him ; and although it is even in some
sense true, because there is no created thing of which
we cannot make some use, if it be only that of exercis-
ing our mind in considering it, and honouring God on
account of it, it is yet by no means probable that all
things were created for us in this way that God had no
other end in their creation ; and this supposition would
be plainly ridiculous and inept in physical reasoning,
for we do not doubt but that many things exist, or
formerly existed and have now ceased to be, which
were never seen or known by man, and were never of
use to him.
PART IV.
OF THE EARTH.
CLXXXVIII. Of what is to be borrowed from
disquisitions on animals and man to advance the
knowledge of material objects.
I should a'dd nothing farther to this the Fourth Part
of the Principles of Philosophy, did I purpose carry-
ing out my original design of writing a Fifth and
Sixth Part, the one treating of things possessed of
life, that is, animals and plants, and the other of man.
But because I have not yet acquired sufficient knowl-
edge of all the matters of which I should desire to
treat in these two last parts, and do not know whether
I shall ever have sufficient leisure to finish them, I will
here subjoin a few things regarding the objects of our
senses, that I may not, for the sake of the latter, delay
too long the publication of the former parts, or of what
may be desiderated in them, which I might have re-
served for explanation in those others: for I have
hitherto described this earth, and generally the whole
visible world, as if it were merely a machine in which
there was nothing at all to consider except the figures
and motions of its parts, whereas our senses present to
us many other things, for example colours, smells,
sounds, and the like, of which, if I did not speak at all,
it would be thought I had omitted the explication of
the majority of the objects that are in nature.
194
PART IV. 195
CLXXXIX. What perception (sensus) is, and how
we perceive.
We must know, therefore, that although the human
soul is united to the whole body, it has, nevertheless,
its principal seat in the brain, where alone it not only
understands and imagines, but also perceives ; and this
by the medium of the nerves, which are extended like
threads from the brain to all the other members, with
which they are so connected that we can hardly touch
any one of them without moving the extremities of
some of the nerves spread over it; and this motion
passes to the other extremities of those nerves which
are collected in the brain round the seat of the soul,*
as I have already explained with sufficient minuteness
in the fourth chapter of the Dioptrics. But the move-
ments which are thus excited in the brain by the nerves
variously affect the soul or mind, which is intimately
conjoined with the brain, according to the diversity of
the motions themselves. And the diverse affections of
the mind or thoughts that immediately arise from these
motions, are called perceptions of the senses (sensuum
perceptiones), or, as we commonly speak, sensations
(sensus) .
CXC. Of the distinction of the senses ; and, first, of
the internal, that is, of the affections of the mind
(passions), and the natural appetites.
The varieties of these sensations depend, firstly, on
the diversity of the nerves themselves, and, secondly,
of the movements that are made in each nerve. We
have not, however, as many different senses as there
are nerves. We can distinguish but seven principal
* " common sense." — French.
iç6 THE PRINCIPLES OF PHILOSOPHY.
classes of nerves, of which two belong to the internal,
and the other five to the external senses. The nerves
which extend to the stomach, the oesophagus, the
fauces, and the other internal parts that are subservient
to our natural wants, constitute one of our internal
senses. This is called the natural appetite (appetitus
naturalis). The other internal sense, which embraces
all the emotions (commotiones) of the mind or pas-
sions, and affections, as joy, sadness, love, hate, and
the like, depends upon the nerves which extend to the
heart and the parts about the heart, and are exceed-
ingly small ; for, by way of example, when the blood
happens to be pure and well tempered, so that it di-
lates in the heart more readily and strongly than usual,
this so enlarges and moves the small nerves scattered
around the orifices, that there is thence a correspond-
ing movement in the brain, which affects the mind'
with a certain natural feeling of joy; and as often as
these same nerves are moved in the same way, al-
though this is by other causes, they excite in our mind
the same feeling (sensus, sentiment). Thus, the im-
agination of the enjoyment of a good does not contain
in itself the feeling of joy, but it causes the animal
spirits to pass from the brain to the muscles in which
these nerves are inserted ; and thus dilating the orifices
ôf the heart, it also causes these small nerves to move
in the way appointed by nature to afford the sensation
of joy. Thus, when we receive news, the mind first
of all judges of it, and if the news be good, it rejoices
with that intellectual joy (gaudium intellectuale)
which is independent of any emotion (commotio) of
the body, and which the Stoics did not deny to their
wise man [although they supposed him exempt from
PART IV. 197
all passion]. But as soon as this joy passes from the
understanding to the imagination, the spirits flow from
the brain to the muscles that are about the heart, and
there excite the motion of the small nerves, by means
of which another motion is caused in the brain, which
affects the mind with the sensation of animal joy
(laetitia animalis). On the same principle, when the
blood is so thick that it flows but sparingly into the
ventricles of the heart, and is not there sufficiently di-
lated, it excites in the same nerves a motion quite dif-
ferent from the preceding, which, communicated to the
brain, gives to the mind the sensation of sadness, al-
though the mind itself is perhaps ignorant of the cause
of its sadness. And all the other causes which move
these nerves in the same way may also give to the
mind the same sensation. But the other movements
of the same nerves produce other effects, as the feel-
ings of love, hate, fear, anger, etc., as far as they are
merely affections or passions of the mind; in other
words, as far as they are confused thoughts which the
mind has not from itself alone, but from its being
closely joined to the body, from which it receives im-
pressions ; for there is the widest difference between
these passions and the distinct thoughts which we have
of what ought to be loved, or chosen, or shunned, etc.,
[although these are often enough found together].
The natural appetites, as hunger, thirst, and the others,
are likewise sensations excited in the mind by means
of the nerves of the stomach, fauces, and other parts,
and are entirely different from the will which we have
to eat, drink, [and to do all that which we think proper
for the conservation of our body] ; but, because this
198 THE PRINCIPLES OF PHILOSOPHY.
will or appetition almost always accompanies them,
they are therefore named appetites.
CXCI. Of the external senses ; and first of touch.
We commonly reckon the external senses five in
number, because there are as many different kinds of
objects which move the nerves and their organs, and
an equal number of kinds of confused thoughts ex-
cited in the soul by these emotions. In the first place,
the nerves terminating in the skin of the whole body
can be touched through this medium by any terrene
objects whatever, and moved by these wholes, in one
way by their hardness, in another by their gravity, in
a third by their heat, in a fourth by their humidity,
etc. — and in as many diverse modes as they are either
moved or hindered from their ordinary motion, to that
extent are diverse sensations excited in the mind, from
which a corresponding number of tactile qualities de-
rive their appellations. Besides this, when these
nerves are moved a little more powerfully than usual,
but not nevertheless to the degree by which our body
is in any way hurt, there thus arises a sensation of titil-
lation, which is naturally agreeable to the mind, be-
cause it testifies to it of the powers of the body with
which it is joined, [in that the latter can suffer the ac-
tion causing this titillation, without being hurt]. But
if this action be strong enough to hurt our body in any
way, this gives to our mind the sensation of pain.
And we thus see why corporeal pleasure and pain, al-
though sensations of quite an opposite character, arise
nevertheless from causes nearly alike.
CXCII. Of taste.
In the second place, the other nerves scattered over
the tongue and the parts in its vicinity are diversely
PART IV. 199
moved by the particles of the same bodies, separated
from each other and floating in the saliva in the
mouth, and thus cause sensations of diverse tastes ac-
cording to the diversity of figure in these particles.*
CXCIII. Of smell.
Thirdly, two nerves also or appendages of the brain,
for they do not go beyond the limits of the skull, are
moved by the particles of terrestrial bodies, separated
and flying in the air, not indeed by all particles indif-
ferently, but by those only that are sufficiently subtle
and penetrating to enter the pores of the bone we call
the spongy, when drawn into the nostrils, and thus to
reach the nerves. From the different motions of these
particles arise the sensations of the different smells.
CXCIV. Of hearing.
Fourthly, there are two nerves within the ears, so
attached to three small bones that are mutually sus-
taining, and the first of which rests on the small mem-
brane that covers the cavity we call the tympanum of
the ear, that all the diverse vibrations which the sur-
rounding air communicates to this membrane are
transmitted to the mind by these nerves, and these vi-
brations give rise, according to their diversity, to the
sensations of the different sounds.
CXCV. Of sight.
Finally, the extremities of the optic nerves, compos-
ing the coat in the eyes called the retina, are not moved
by the air nor by any terrestrial object, but only by the
globules of the second element, 10 whence we have the
sense of light and colours : as I have already at suffi-
* In the French this section begins, "Taste, after touch the
grossest of the senses," etc.
200 THE PRINCIPLES OF PHILOSOPHY.
cient length explained in the Dioptrics and treatise of
Meteors.*
CXCVI. That the soul perceives only in so far as it
is in the brain.
It is clearly established, however, that the soul does
not perceive in so far as it is in each member of the
body, but only in so far as it is in the brain, where
the nerves by their movements convey to it the diverse
actions of the external objects that touch the parts
of the body in which they are inserted. For, in the
first place, there are various maladies, which, though
they affect the brain alone, yet bring disorder upon,
or deprive us altogether of the use of, our senses, just
as sleep, which affects the brain only, and yet takes
from us daily during a great part of our time the fac-
ulty of perception, which afterwards in our waking
state is restored to us. The second proof is, that
though there be no disease in the brain, [or in the
members in which the organs of the external senses
are], it is nevertheless sufficient to take away sensa-
tion from the part of the body where the nerves ter-
minate, if only the movement of one of the nerves that
extend from the brain to these members be obstructed
in any part of the distance that is between the two.
And the last proof is, that we sometimes feel pain as
if in certain of our members, the cause of which, how-
ever, is not in these members where it is felt, but some-
where nearer the brain, through which the nerves pass
that give to the mind the sensation of it. I could es-
tablish this fact by innumerable experiments; I will
* In the French this section begins, "Finally, sight is the
most subtle of all the senses," etc.
PART IV. 201
here, however, merely refer to one of them. A girl
suffering from a bad ulcer in the hand, had her eyes
bandaged whenever the surgeon came to visit her, not
being able to bear the sight of the dressing of the
sore; and, the gangrene having spread, after the ex-
piry of a few days the arm was amputated from the
elbow [without the girl's knowledge] ; linen cloths tied
one above the other were substituted in place of the
part amputated, so that she remained for some time
without knowing that the operation had been per-
formed, and meanwhile she complained of feeling va-
rious pains, sometimes in one finger of the hand that
was cut off, and sometimes in another. The only ex-
planation of this is, that the nerves which before
stretched downwards from the brain to the hand, and
then terminated in the arm close to the elbow, were
there moved in the same way as they required to be
moved before in the hand for the purpose of impressing
on the mind residing in the brain the sensation of pain
in this or that finger. [And this clearly shows that
the pain of the hand is not felt by the mind in so far
as it is in the hand, but in so far as it is in the brain.]
CXCVII. That the nature of the mind is such that
from the motion alone of body the various sensations
can be excited in it.
In the next place, it can be proved that our mind
is of such a nature that the motions of the body alone
are sufficient to excite in it all sorts of thoughts, with-
out it being necessary that these should in any way re-
semble the motions which give rise to them, and es-
pecially that these motions can excite in it those con-
fused thoughts called sensations (sensus, sensationes) .
For we see that words, whether uttered by the voice or
202 THE PRINCIPLES OF PHILOSOPHY.
merely written, excite in our minds all kinds of
thoughts and emotions. On the same paper, with the
same pen and ink, by merely moving the point of the
pen over the paper in a particular way, we can trace
letters that will raise in the minds of our readers the
thoughts of combats, tempests, or the furies, and the
passions of indignation and sorrow ; in place of which,
if the pen be moved in another way hardly different
from the former, this slight change will cause thoughts
widely different from the above, such as those of re-
pose, peace, pleasantness, and the quite opposite pas-
sions of love and joy. Some one will perhaps object
that writing and speech do not immediately excite in
the mind any passions, or imaginations of things dif-
ferent from the letters and sounds, but afford simply
the knowledge of these, on occasion of which the mind,
understanding the signification of the words, after-
wards excites in itself the imaginations and passions
that correspond to the words. But what will be said
of the sensations of pain and titillation? The motion
merely of a sword cutting a part of our skin causes
pain, [but does not on that account make us aware of
the motion or figure of the sword] . And it is certain
that this sensation of pain is not less different from the
motion that causes it, or from that of the part of our
body which the sword cuts, than are the sensations we
have of colour, sound, odour, or taste. On this ground
we may conclude that our mind is of such a nature that
the motions alone of certain bodies can also easily ex-
cite in it all the other sensations, as the motion of a
sword excites in it the sensation of pain.
CXCVIII. That by our senses we know nothing of
PART IV. 203
external objects beyond their figure [or situation],
magnitude, and motion.
Besides, we observe no such difference between the
nerves as to lead us to judge that one set of them con-
vey to the brain from the organs of the external senses
anything different from another, or that anything at
all reaches the brain besides the local motion of the
nerves themselves. And we see that local motion alone
causes in us not only the sensation of titillation and of
pain, but also of light and sounds. For if we receive
a blow on the eye of sufficient force to cause the vibra-
tion of the stroke to reach the retina, we see numerous
sparks of fire, which, nevertheless, are not out of our
eye ; and when we stop our ear with our finger, we hear
a humming sound, the cause of which can only pro-
ceed from the agitation of the air that is shut up within
it. Finally, we frequently observe that heat [hardness,
weight], and the other sensible qualities, as far as they
are in objects, and also the forms of those bodies that
are purely material, as, for example, the forms of fire,
are produced in them by the motion of certain other
bodies, and that these in their turn likewise produce
other motions in other bodies. And we can easily con-
ceive how the motion of one body may be caused by
that of another, and diversified by the size, figure, and
situation of its parts, but we are wholly unable to con-
ceive how these same things (viz., size, figure, and
motion), can produce something else of a nature en-
tirely different from themselves, as, for example, those
substantial forms and real qualities which many philos-
ophers suppose to be in bodies ; nor likewise can we
conceive how these qualities or forms possess force to
cause motions in other bodies. But since we know,
204 THE PRINCIPLES OF PHILOSOPHY.
from the nature of our soul, that the diverse motions
of body are sufficient to produce in it all the sensations
which it has, and since we learn from experience that
several of its sensations are in reality caused by such
motions, while we do not discover that anything be-
sides these motions ever passes from the organs of the
external senses to the brain, we have reason to conclude
that we in no way likewise apprehend that in external
objects, which we call light, colour, smell, taste, sound,
heat or cold, and the other tactile qualities, or that
which we call their substantial forms, unless as the va-
rious dispositions of these objects which have the
power of moving our nerves in various ways.*
CXCIX. That there is no phenomenon of nature
whose explanation has been omitted in this treatise.
And thus it may be gathered, from an enumeration
that is easily made, that there is no phenomenon of na-
ture whose explanation has been omitted in this
treatise; for beyond what is perceived by the senses,
there is nothing that can be considered a phenomenon
of nature. But leaving out of account motion, magni-
tude, figure, [and the situation of the parts of each
body], which I have explained as they exist in body,
we perceive nothing out of us by our senses except
light, colours, smells, tastes, sounds, and the tactile
qualities ; and these I have recently shown to be noth-
ing more, at least so far as they are known to us, than
certain dispositions of the objects, consisting in magni-
tude, figure, and motion.
CC. That this treatise contains no principles which
* " the diverse figures, situations, magnitudes, and motions
of their parts." — French.
PART IV. 305
are not universally received; and that this philosophy
is not new, but of all others the most ancient and com-
mon.
But I am desirous also that it should be observed
that, though I have here endeavoured to give an ex-
planation of the whole nature of material things, I
have nevertheless made use of no principle which was
not received and approved by Aristotle, and by the
other philosophers of all ages ; so that this philosophy,
so far from being new, is of all others the most ancient
and common : for I have in truth merely considered
the figure, motion, and magnitude of bodies, and
examined what must follow from their mutual con-
course on the principles of mechanics, which are con-
firmed by certain and daily experience. But no one
ever doubted that bodies are moved, and that they are
of various sizes and figures, according to the diversity
of which their motions also vary, and that from mutual
collision those somewhat greater than others are di-
vided into many smaller, and thus change figure. We
have experience of the truth of this, not merely by a
single sense, but by several, as touch, sight, and hear-
ing: we also distinctly imagine and understand it.
This cannot be said of any of the other things that fall
under our senses, as colours, sounds, and the like ; for
each of these affects but one of our senses, and merely
impresses upon our imagination a confused image of
itself, affording our understanding no distinct knowl-
edge of what it is.
CCI. That sensible bodies are composed of insensi-
ble particles.
But I allow many particles in each body that are
perceived by none of our senses, and this will not per-
206 THE PRINCIPLES OF PHILOSOPHY.
haps be approved of by those who take the senses for
the measure of the knowable. [We greatly wrong
human reason, however, as appears to me, if we sup-
pose that it does not go beyond the eye-sight] ; for no
one can doubt that there are bodies so small as not to
be perceptible by any of our senses, provided he only
consider what is each moment added to those bodies
that are being increased little by little, and what is
taken from those that are diminished in the same way.
A tree increases daily, and it is impossible to conceive
how it becomes greater than it was before, unless we at
the same time conceive that some body is added to it.
But who ever observed by the senses those small bodies
that are in one day added to a tree while growing?
Among the philosophers at least, those who hold that
quantity is indefinitely divisible, ought to admit that in
the division the parts may become so small as to be
wholly imperceptible. And indeed it ought not to be
a matter of surprise, that we are unable to perceive
very minute bodies ; for the nerves that must be moved
by objects to cause perception are not themselves very
minute, but are like small cords, being composed of a
quantity of smaller fibres, and thus the most minute
bodies are not capable of moving them. Nor do I think
that any one who makes use of his reason will deny
that we philosophize with much greater truth when
we judge of what takes place in those small bodies
which are imperceptible from their minuteness only,
after the analogy of what we see occurring in those we
do perceive, [and in this way explain all that is in na-
ture, as I have essayed to do in this treatise], than
when we give an explanation of the same things by in-
venting I know not what novelties, that have no rela-
PART IV, 207
tion to the things we actually perceive, [as first matter,
substantial forms, and all that grand array of qualities
which many are in the habit of supposing, each of
which is more difficult to comprehend than all that is
professed to be explained by means of them].
CCII. That the philosophy of Democritus is not
less different from ours than from the common.*
But it may be said that Democritus also supposed
certain corpuscles that were of various figures, sizes,
and motions, from the heaping together and mutual
concourse of which all sensible bodies arose; and,
nevertheless, his mode of philosophizing is commonly
rejected by all. To this I reply that the philosophy of
Democritus was never rejected by any one, because he
allowed the existence of bodies smaller than those we
perceive, and attributed to them diverse sizes, figures,
and motions, for no one can doubt that there are in
reality such, as we have already shown ; but it was re-
jected, in the first place, because he supposed that these
corpuscles were indivisible, on which ground I also re-
ject it; in the second place, because he imagined
there was a vacuum about them, which I show to be im-
possible ; thirdly, because he attributed gravity to these
bodies, of which I deny the existence in any body, in
so far as a body is considered by itself, because it is a
quality that depends on the relations of situation and
motion which several bodies bear to each other; and,
finally, because he has not explained in particular how
all things arose from the concourse of corpuscles alone,
or, if he gave this explanation with regard to a few of
them, his whole reasoning was far from being coherent,
* " that of Aristotle or the others." — French.
208 THE PRINCIPLES OF PHILOSOPHY.
[or such as would warrant us in extending the same
explanation to the whole of nature]. This, at least, is
the verdict we must give regarding his philosophy, if
we may judge of his opinions from what has been
handed down to us in writing. I leave it to others to
determine whether the philosophy I profess possesses
a valid coherency, [and whether on its principles we
can make the requisite number of deductions ; and, in-
asmuch as the consideration of figure, magnitude, and
motion has been admitted by Aristotle and by all the
others, as well as by Democritus, and since I reject all
that the latter has supposed, with this single exception,
while I reject generally all that has been supposed by
the others, it is plain that this mode of philosophizing
has no more affinity with that of Democritus than of
any other particular sect].
CCIII. How we may arrive at the knowledge of the
figures, [magnitudes], and motions of the insensible
particles of bodies.
But, since I assign determinate figures, magnitudes,
and motions to the insensible particles of bodies, as if
I had seen them, whereas I admit that they do not fall
under the senses, some one will perhaps demand how I
have come by my knowledge of them. [To this I re-
ply, that I first considered in general all the clear and
distinct notions of material things that are to be found
in our understanding, and that, finding no others ex-
cept those of figures, magnitudes, and motions, and of
the rules according to which these three things can be
diversified by each other, which rules are the principles
of geometry and mechanics, I judged that all the
knowledge man can have of nature must of necessity
be drawn from this source; because all the other no-
PART IV. 209
tions we have of sensible things, as confused and ob-
scure, can be of no avail in affording us the knowl-
edge of anything out of ourselves, but must serve
rather to impede it] . Thereupon, taking as my ground
of inference the simplest and best known of the princi-
ples that have been implanted in our minds by nature,
I considered the chief differences that could possibly
subsist between the magnitudes, and figures, and situa-
tions of bodies insensible on account of their smallness
alone, and what sensible effects could be produced by
their various modes of coming into contact ; and after-
wards, when I found like effects in the bodies that we
perceive by our senses, I judged that they could have
been thus produced, especially since no other mode of
explaining them could be devised. And in this matter
the example of several bodies made by art was of great
service to me : for I recognize no difference between
these and natural bodies beyond this, that the effects of
machines depend for the most part on the agency of
certain instruments, which, as they must bear some
proportion to the hands of those who make them, are
always so large that their figures and motions can be
seen; in place of which, the effects of natural bodies
almost always depend upon certain organs so minute
as to escape our senses. And it is certain that all the
rules of mechanics belong also to physics, of which it
is a part or species, [so that all that is artificial is withal
natural] : for it is not less natural for a clock, made of
the requisite number of wheels, to mark the hours, than
for a tree, which has sprung from this or that seed, to
produce the fruit peculiar to it. Accordingly, just as
those who are familiar with automata, when they are
2io THE PRINCIPLES OF PHILOSOPHY.
informed of the use of a machine, and see some of its
parts, easily infer from these the way in which the
others, that are not seen by them, are made; so from
considering the sensible effects and parts of natural
bodies, I have essayed to determine the character of
their causes and insensible parts.
CCIV. That, touching the things which our senses
do not perceive, it is sufficient to explain how they can
be, [and that this is all that Aristotle has essayed].
But here some one will perhaps reply, that although
I have supposed causes which could produce all natural
objects, we ought not on this account to conclude that
they were produced by these causes; for, just as the
same artisan can make two clocks, which, though they
both equally well indicate the time, and are not differ-
ent in outward appearance, have nevertheless nothing
resembling in the composition of their wheels ; so
doubtless the Supreme Maker of things has an infinity
of diverse means at his disposal, by each of which he
could have made all the things of this world to appear
as we see them, without it being possible for the human
mind to know which of all these means he chose to em-
ploy. I most freely concede this ; and I believe that I
have done all that was required, if the causes I have as-
signed are such that their effects accurately correspond
to all the phenomena of nature, without determining
whether it is by these or by others that they are ac-
tually produced. And it will be sufficient for the use
of life to know the causes thus imagined, for medicine,
mechanics, and in general all the arts to which the
knowledge of physics is of service, have for their end
only those effects that are sensible, and that are accord-
PART IV. 2ii
ingly to be reckoned among the phenomena of nature.*
And lest it should be supposed that Aristotle did, or
professed to do, anything more than this, it ought to be
remembered that he himself expressly says, at the com-
mencement of the seventh chapter of the first book of
the Meteorologies, that, with regard to things which
are not manifest to the senses, he thinks to adduce
sufficient reasons and demonstrations of them, if he
only shows that they may be such as he explains
them.f
CCV. That nevertheless there is a moral certainty
that all the things of this world are such as has been
here shown they may be.
But nevertheless, that I may not wrong the truth
by supposing it less certain than it is, I will here dis-
tinguish two kinds of certitude. The first is called
moral, that is, a certainty sufficient for the conduct of
life, though, if we look to the absolute power of God,
what is morally certain may be false. [Thus, those
who never visited Rome do not doubt that it is a city
of Italy, though it might be that all from whom they
got their information were deceived]. Again, if any
one, wishing to decipher a letter written in Latin char-
acters that are not placed in regular order, bethinks
* " have for their end only to apply certain sensible bodies
to each other in such a way that, in the course of natural
causes, certain sensible effects may be produced ; and we will
be able to accomplish this quite as well by considering the
series of certain causes thus imagined, although false, as if
they were the true, since this series is supposed similar as far
as regards sensible effects." — French.
\ 'Enel ôè irspî tûv àfavûv tt) aladrjaei vofii^ofiev licavûç àKoôeôsïxdai
Kara rbv Myov, èàv elç to âvvarov àvayâywjuev, è/c re tûv vvv