I In ■1 ' /$? Book_ _.S-l£*_ INTRODUCTION STUDY OF PHILOSOPHY BY J. H. W. STUCKENBERG, D.D. NEW YORK A. C. ARMSTRONG AND SON 3 & 5 West 18 th Street, near 5 th Avenue 1902 Sfr1> \ Copyright, 1SS6, By A. C. ARMSTRONG & SON, Presswork by John Wilson and Son, University Press. PREFACE. The title indicates the specific aim of this volume. It is not an encyclopaedia ; nor is it intended as an introduction to any particular philosophical system, or to the history of the various systems, but to the study of philosophy itself. The book was not written for philosophers, but for students and others who desire to prepare themselves for philosophic pursuits. While especially adapted to beginners in philosophy, maturer students will find it helpful as a review. It may serve to concentrate and crystallize the thoughts which have been confused and bewildered by the perplexing prob- lems of philosophy, and by the antagonistic views in the different systems, and thus may prepare the thinker for a new and more vigorous start in philosophic re- search. The urgent need of such a work is the apology for its existence, — a need evident to all who under- stand the inherent difficulties of philosophy, the con- flicting notions respecting its nature, aim, divisions, and method, and the numerous mistakes of students, and their failure to secure the best results from philosophic inquiries. iii iv PREFACE. The specific aim has not merely determined the gen- eral character of the volume, but also its particular parts, so as to limit the contents strictly to the scope of an introductory work. No labor has been spared to present, in the clearest manner, such thoughts as are regarded most essential for the beginner. The reader who knows the difference between floundering in a subject, and thinking through it, is in no danger of mistaking obscurity as synonymous with philosophical profundity. But even an elementary work in philos- ophy is obliged to discuss subjects which require pro- found study, and furnish food for the deepest thought. Particularly is this the case with those great problems which have enlisted the best energies of thinkers ever since the birth of philosophy. The student who has the acumen and thoroughness which adapt him to phil- osophical investigations will appreciate the importance of grappling early with themes which most severely test his intellectual powers. While intent on securing all possible help to put him into the right attitude to philosophy, he will value all aids only as means for becoming independent of foreign help. Philosophy is not taught, but thought; and even an introductory work presupposes that the student will do more for himself than others can do for him. Particularly in philosophy is it true, that what one gets depends on what he brings. The best introduction to philosophy is not so much an accumulation of materials of thought, as the develop- PBEFACE. V ment and proper direction of the energy of thought. While the following chapters aim to give a clear state- ment of problems, and hints for their solution, it is evi- dent that their full discussion must be left to philosophy itself. Where mere statements are all that the philoso- pher requires, the beginner may need the processes themselves which lead to the results attained by ma- ture thinkers ; and here such processes are frequently given, so that, by means of the genetic method, the student may learn that only by thinking through a thought can it be appropriated. At the end of each chapter, hints are found under the head of Reflections, intended partly as a review, but mainly as suggestions for independent inquiry and for mental discipline. Aside from the nature of the subject, the character of the volume has been determined by the author's own experience of the difficulties of philosophical studies, and by extensive observations, in America and Ger- many, of the perplexities and mistakes of students of philosophy. Particularly have these observations been valuable in Berlin, where students congregate from all parts of the world. A careful consideration of the need of beginners has led to the treatment of certain subjects with greater fulness than required in ordinary philo- sophical works ; while other topics have been only men- tioned or briefly discussed, their full consideration being left to a period of greater maturity. A clear view of philosophy itself and its divisions, a definite statement of the problems involved, and specific directions for VI PREFACE. thorough and successful study, have been the constant aim. While the views of philosophers in past ages may be learned from their books, or from the history of phi- losophy, the student generally finds it exceedingly diffi- cult to form a comprehensive view of present tendencies in philosophic thought, — tendencies which are the more important because he is continually, though perhaps unconsciously, subject to their influence. Frequent reference is made to the present status of philosophy, in order that the student may learn what special de- mands the age makes on the philosophic thinker, and against what dangers he must guard. Wisdom does not lose itself in random thinking, but it selects timely and useful subjects, which the historic development justi- fies and the age makes urgent, and which are capable of richest development and most fruitful application. Much valuable help has been derived from the numer- ous volumes consulted ; but as none of them has exactly the same aim as this volume, they could not determine the general plan and particular method of the book. It is hoped that the student will find in the work that independence respecting prevalent systems which the book itself is intended to promote. So far as justice required, special mention has been made of the authors used. The student will be grateful for the views of emi- nent philosophers on the most important problems ; and he who makes reading subordinate to thinking will not regret the opportunities for reflection furnished by the interruptions occasioned by footnotes. The longer PREFACE. vii notes are thrown into the Appendix, and to these the numbers in the text refer. In discussing the relation of philosophy to science, it would have been easy to treat the subject wholly from the philosophical standpoint. But this relation has become so important, that both sides should be heard; and for this reason the views of scientists, as well as those of philosophers, are presented: hence numerous references are made, both in the text and in the Appendix, to leaders in science. In addition to the works referred to in the text, a list of books is given at the end of the first chapters, on the subjects therein discussed. This list may be valu- able as an introduction to the literature on philosophy, particularly to the philosophical journals. Besides a knowledge of current philosophical tendencies, these journals furnish valuable aid to the student for the selection of works on the general subject, and on the various departments of philosophy. J. H. W. STUCKENBERG. Berlin, Dec. 21, 1887. CONTENTS. CHAPTER PAGE Introduction < • . 1 I. Definition of Philosophy 11 II. Relation of Philosophy to Religion 57 III. Philosophy and Natural Science 93 IV. Philosophy and Empirical Psychology .... 129 V. Division of Philosophy 159 VI. Theory of Knowledge (Noetics) 175 VII. Metaphysics 242 VIII. Esthetics 268 IX. Ethics 310 X. The Spirit and the Method in the Study of Philosophy 345 APPENDIX 399 INDEX 421 ix INTRODUCTION. If philosophy is the object of our search, the ques- tion respecting the means for its attainment is funda- mental. But not less important is an inquiry into the state of the person who is to engage in this search, and to use these means. The apprehension of the subject, and the application of the means, depend on the stu- dent's intellectual grasp and energy, his previous train- ing and mental possessions. Since these vary so greatly, their peculiarities in each individual case cannot be taken into account here : only what must be required of all can be indicated. Although we are obliged to leave the matter mainly to himself, the greatest emphasis must be placed on the state of the beginner in the study of philosophy. Thrown upon his own resources more than in any other pursuit, a fault in himself or in his attitude toward philosophy may prove fatal to success. Not only must philosophy in the abstract, and what the student is in himself, be considered. The develop- ment attained by philosophy and the general condition of thought, particularly in his immediate surroundings, are also important factors in determining his course. Even mature philosophers cannot ignore the current tendencies of their age ; still less can this be done by beginners. The earnest student of philosophy, an inquirer into deepest thought, is supposed to be exempt 2 INTRODUCTION. from ordinary errors and prejudices respecting the nature and value of his pursuit. The severe labor re- quired of the philosophic thinker is evidence that the best truth may lie farthest below the surface, and cannot be received as a direct impression through the senses, or as an inspiration. Other views calculated to embarrass him may, however, be worthy of serious attention, — views infecting the air we breathe, and unconsciously becoming a part of our very being and intellectual life. In every age opposite tendencies prevail, animated by different spirits, pursuing methods which are in conflict, and terminating in results which cannot be harmonized. Frequently these antagonistic movements are extremes which beget and develop one another. When the error in an extreme is discovered, the mind is apt to reject even the truth with which it is associated, and to adopt one-sidedly the truth which was ignored or denied ; but truth out of right relations, or developed in undue pro- portion to other truths, is itself an error. It requires rare breadth, depth, and impartiality, to discern, appro- priate, and properly relate all that is true in a system, while rejecting all that is erroneous. Amid the numerous currents of our agitated age, there are two fundamental tendencies which are radically antagonistic. On the one hand, we discover the maxim which confines thought to external objects, as the only source of valid and valuable knowledge. Observation and experiment are pronounced the only means of com- municating with the real, and the mind is solely esteemed as the agent which unites the materials thus gathered, and which draws from them such laws as give the intel- lect a comprehensive view of the facts, and enable it in some measure to foretell coming natural events. Nature being regarded as the chief object of investigation, INTRODUCTION. 3 empiricism, aided by mathematics, domineers thought. The mind is treated as the passive tool of the sense, subject to its laws, run in its grooves, and limited by its authority. The human interests receiving supreme attention are those most closely connected with nature, and with the animal creation at large. As the facts of the natural world are made the germs of science, so the facts of human history become the seeds of ethics, sociology, and politics. A deep distrust of mind is fre- quently revealed by minds controlled by this tendency, and vigorous efforts are made to suppress aspiration be- yond the limits of natural law. Much formerly regarded as real, or at least as a mental representation of reality, is now mercilessly assigned to poetry and fiction, while the sense is endowed with an intuitive knoAvledge of things as they are. To thought preferring the limits of its own law to those of empirical realism, the region of mythology is generously donated. Cherished ideals are treated as pleasant and perhaps harmless illusions ; faith is regarded as effete ; and theology and meta- physics are interpreted as aberrations of mind on its way to positivism, the Ultima Thule of reliable thought. This tendency is not, however, confined to positivists. Sacrificing depth to breadth, it is a widely diffused spirit with various manifestations, agreeing in its negations rather than in its positions. Thus experience may be lauded as the sole guide, and yet the results obtained may differ greatly. The theoretic rejection of faith does not prevent assumptions which reveal astounding credu- lity. Theology can be rejected as worthless, and then, to meet the cravings of the mind, something termed natural religion can be invented, or a cultus of reason, genius, or humanity can be instituted. If a practical rest can be found in a theoretical void, agnosticism may be 4 INTRODUCTION. pronounced final. Facts may be regarded as most valuable in their naked, unconnected reality, while a system of them is viewed as suspicious because too mental. Above all else, that is esteemed as having worth which can be weighed and measured, and ex- pressed in mathematical formulas. Numerous evidences of this spirit are found in life and literature. Socialism boldly proclaims that science has abolished the spiritual world and the ideals, and that consequently the most illiterate, by placing himself on the conclusions of science, will be consistent with it if he limits his desires and pursuits to the immediate inter- ests of this life. Selfishness and passion have much to do with determining these interests. Unless some altru- istic notions can be communicated to him, he is freed from the dominion of all authority outside of himself, that of blind force or the penal laws of society alone excepted. With the dominion of empiricism, new methods of education are also to be introduced. Men- tal science is treated as vague and unreliable, because it does not submit to tape-lines and scales. Even history is depreciated, because it does not square itself to the rules of mathematics. Humanity has so meandering a course, that it can be studied to best advantage in the severer scientific regularity of brutes. The classics are objectionable, because by promoting ideals they disturb the mind's possession of the reals. Not indeed all who cherish this spirit go to these extremes ; but one need only be familiar with the press of the day, to learn that potent factors in society tend to destroy the ethical and spiritual basis, to interpret what is termed mental by the mechanical, to deprive the soul of confidence in its peculiarities and deepest inter- ests, and to involve it in that pessimism which has INTRODUCTION. 5 become so marked a feature of the most sensitive and most cultured among those controlled by this spirit. So general and so dominant is this spirit, that all who eagerly enter the domain of science, to become masters of its principles, are likely to come under its influence. In proportion to the zeal with which an object is pur- sued, does it abstract the attention from other objects. Not in enthusiasm for a specialty is there danger for the mind, but in affirmations respecting the reality or char- acter of the territory lying outside of that specialty, and not even entered by the intellect. It is a common human failing to make the knowledge obtained in one sphere of thought the light to illumine the darkness of every other sphere. Not unfrequently has nature been interpreted by the knowledge obtained of mind; and, in our day, the reverse is common. The correctness of the claims made by this spirit will be considered later ; here we want only to contrast it with another tendency. In science itself there are numerous illustrations that the best scientists are not exclusive. Not a few of them admit that science is neither the measure of reality nor the limit of the intel- lect. Tyndall, Huxley, Haeckel, Helmholtz, Du Bois- Reymond, and many others, prove by their works that science is but the basis for thought in its progress to broader generalizations and higher flights. There are even scientists who compensate for the absence of fancy in their themes, by liberally supplying it themselves. But it is outside of the domain of science that a spirit, the opposite of that described, is most manifest. All religion proves that the mind is unwilling to be confined to the dogmatism of empiricism. But also in other departments thought rebels against the prescribed limits, strives to free itself from the trammels of gross objects, 6 INTRODUCTION. revels in poetry and fiction, and thus proves that it wants to supplement the known realities of nature with creations of its own, in order that it may obtain satis- faction. The age which seeks to curb thought has not a few who hail even Emerson's poetry as philosophy, failing to discriminate between the rational and imagin- ative elements in his works. Plato has been subject to the same treatment in all ages. And it looks as if in realistic America an era of Hegelistic idealism were about to be inaugurated, — an idealism farthest removed from the dominion of facts, and blending the subtlest fiction with the profoundest reason. Look where we will in the most practical and most scientific lands, thought proves by a fact, by its own energy, that it cannot be buried under a mass of sensations. It is not necessary to prove to the student of phi- losophy, that there are aspirations which a cramped knowledge cannot satisfy. Nor is it worth while further to pursue this spirit in its efforts to move in a sphere which transcends the phenomena of nature. One need but understand himself, in order to know that the real of the senses is not the limit of the real of reason. Never has the intellect been limited to the former, ex- cept by a theory not fully understood by its advocates. Looking at these opposite tendencies, both equally marked in our day, what is their lesson ? What posi- tion respecting them shall we take? Empiricism is liable to err in limiting thought to sensations, while speculation is in danger of ignoring the data of the senses. The one treats as final what is but a beginning ; the other treats as the beginning what still requires a solid basis. The mind cannot be content with the facts of nature bound together in a rigid system of laws, while all reality beyond the visible and the tactual is INTRODUCTION. 7 denied. Nor can we build solid structures on creations of the fancy. The mind conscious of itself demands a certainty that is absolute, and at the same time the pur- suit of thought to its utmost limits. This means the union of what is good and reliable in both tendencies, without the adoption of their extremes. It means actualism and realism, whether found in the highest or lowest domains of thought. The intellect can only be true to itself while moving in a freedom whose sole law is the neces- sity of reason. The above result justifies the demand for philosophy. Numerous other reflections lead to philosophy and illus- trate its scope. 1. The concrete is endless. The mind cannot remem- ber all individual objects ; if it did, they would only prove a useless burden. But every step it takes from the concrete toward the abstract, from percepts to concepts, and from concepts to principles, decreases the number but increases the comprehensiveness of the objects before the mind. There is a strong innate tendency to unite under as few heads as possible all the objects of knowledge. However far separated at the start, as they increase in depth, the thoughts converge and tend to union in the ultimate principles. 2. Besides this tendency to seek the fundamental thought which lies in many or all other thoughts, the mind also wants to find the various relations of concepts. It seeks so to unite fragmentary thoughts as to form a system. Not content with the spontaneous association of thoughts, it aims to discover their hidden relations, so that it may construct an intellectual cosmos in which nothing is isolated. 3. Numerous objects appear before consciousness, and then vanish to return no more. In this way a fleeting 8 INTRODUCTION. world is presented, and because continually vanishing it fails to satisfy. Does the mind exist merely for the sake of these ever-changing impressions, or has it a value of its own ? It is hard to believe that the universe has no other meaning than to furnish passing phenomena. As the same underlying consciousness abides amid the changes of its objects, so the mind seeks the eternal substance behind the vanishing forms. It inquires into the ultimate real ; asks whether its nature changes, or whether in what we term phenomena there is seen only the effect of changing the relations of the real. Can we conceive of the substance as unchangeable, and yet as the source of all changes ? 4. Our opinions vary. We make mistakes, and cor- rect them. Much once held as established beyond all question is now pronounced false. Its experiences may lead the mind to question its ability to discover the truth. The differences of opinion, the conflicts between systems, and the numerous disputes on the most signifi- cant and most trivial subjects, shake its confidence in the ordinary thinking. As the intellect becomes critical, it distinguishes between subjective views (opinions) of truth, and the truth itself. Are there criteria which furnish an absolute test of systems and an invariable standard of truth ? 5. The greatest interests are attacked. The exist- ence of spirit is questioned; the freedom and immor- tality of the soul are denied ; reason is eliminated from the universe, and blind force is thought to banish design ; God being dethroned, atoms are made omnipotent. Is there still a reliable basis for religion ? Or is faith an empty vision, and hope a dream ? What are the objects of supreme worth ? 6. Much that appears I condemn, and much that I INTRODUCTION. 9 think desirable does not exist. How to destroy the one and promote the other, thus becomes an important problem. In one domain of values, taste rules; in another, conscience. What is their authority? How can they be satisfied ? 7. As soon as the intellect penetrates beyond the surface of ordinary thought, numerous perplexing prob- lems appear. The effort to solve them leads deeper and deeper, and reveals a world formerly hid. Far away from the phenomenal, the mind is thrown wholly on its own resources, and depends on the penetrative energy of its thoughts. How can it discover the laws of reason and move safely in the realm of pure thinking ? These hints give an idea of some of the ways which lead to philosophic thought, and also indicate the sphere in which the discussions of this book move. The logi- cal arrangement of the chapters is seen at a glance. First the Nature of philosophy is considered ; then its Relation to adjacent subjects ; its general Divisions are then given, and these are followed by an explanation of each division ; and last of all the Spirit and Method in the study of philosophy are discussed. INTRODUCTION TO THE STUDY OF PHILOSOPHY. CHAPTER I. DEFINITION OF PHILOSOPHY. Intellect is energy, great equally in discovering as in solving problems. The leading systems of thought have revealed difficulties before unseen, and exposed fallacies in reasoning before supposed to be perfect. The works of Plato and Aristotle, of Hume, Kant, and Hegel, teem with problems ; and some supposed solu- tions given by them are found to contain greater prob- lems than they themselves knew. Difficulties multiply as we go deeper ; and whoever discovers a new unsolved question proves that he has thought more correctly or more profoundly than his predecessors. The discovery of such problems, where the ordinary thinking sees none, is the first step toward philosophical thought; and the determination of their exact nature is a condi- tion for all successful attempts at solution. The diffi- culty which arrests thought tests the mind's quality, and tends to develop its capacity. Resistance makes the intellect conscious of itself, and arouses its greatest energy. The supposed limits of the understanding, for instance, provoke to almost superhuman efforts to transcend them. Unless the tension is too great, it will 11 12 INTRODUCTION TO STUDY OF PHILOSOPHY. develop the utmost strength. The spontaneous flow of thought which we do not master, and are scarcely con- scious of, may become so habitual as to unfit the mind for riveted attention to profound themes, and for the control of its own processes ; while problems requir- ing penetrative thought, and long, absorbing investiga- tion, are of inestimable value for intellectual discipline, even if their study ends in no solutions. Only with severe labor can we rise from a life lost amid sensations, to a steady contemplation of concepts. These are at first taken for what they seem to be, just like the im- pressions through the senses ; only after severe training to the task can the mind fathom their meaning, discover their problems, discern their relations, and learn what they imply, but do not explicitly state. This life in the concepts, if deep and consistent, moves among the problems which have enlisted the best energies of the first thinkers for thousands of years, and have given birth to philosophy. All who use this term intelligently recognize it as designating a sphere which lies far beyond the range of ordinary thinking, though numerous avenues lead from the one to the other. The profoundest efforts to solve the mysteries of thought and being have usually been regarded as characteristic of philosophers. The first and final causes, and the great concepts lying between them, are the realm of philosophy ; but such statements are too general to convey any tangible meaning. It is a popular conviction, that the object of philo- sophical contemplation lies beyond ordinary scholarship, as well as beyond the search of the masses ; and hence but few in any age, even when scholarship was not unusual, have been honored with the illustrious name DEFINITION OF PHILOSOPHY. 13 of philosophers. But the reverence accorded to them has been based on vague notions of the excellence of their pursuit, rather than on a clear conception of its exact nature. The recognition that depth characterizes philosophy has not served to dispel the mysteries con- nected with the term. The popular mind associates with it wisdom and reason, — peculiar endowments and a peculiar sphere of inquiry ; but however eminent and solitary the position thus assigned to philosophy, its real character has been but little understood by the popular mind. All this becomes self-evident so soon as we appreciate the truth, that we understand only what we intellectually elaborate or work out for our- selves. The use of the term on the part of scholars is scarcely less vague than in the popular mind. The proof is found in works of scientists and philosophers, and in general literature. The thoughtful reader is conse- quently constrained to ask, What constitutes philoso- phy? An inquiry into the mysteries of being? The objects which philosophers contemplate ? The method of inquiry ? The results attained by the investigation ? Whoever seriously reflects on the word will apprehend the difficulty of determining its exact sense. With the prevailing vagueness in its use, what wonder if those beginning the study of philosophy are puzzled by the nature, aim, relations, and limits of the subject? In many problems an exhaustive study is the condi- tion of clear conception ; still it is evident that at the very outset the exact place of a discipline in the whole system of knowledge should be determined in order to insure its successful investigation. Perhaps even this can be done only after long inquiry ; in that case no effort should be spared in the beginning to determine 14 INTRODUCTION TO STUDY OF PHILOSOPHY. the subject proximately and as clearly as possible. The limitation given a subject by the definition is essential to concentration and perspicuity of thought. We must find a subject, must separate it from its attachments, and possess it intellectually, before we can apply to it predi- cates or use it effectively. The rational and successful pursuit of a study, therefore, necessarily depends largely on a clear conception of its nature. Only when an object is in some measure known, can the way to it be found; only then can it be recognized when discovered; only then can its importance be appreciated, and direc- tions for its pursuit be valuable. With no definite end in view, the most diligent study is in danger of losing itself in distractions, in fruitless searchings, and idle wanderings. Definitions are a mental necessity. In every defini- tion, two things are to be distinguished; namely, an object defined, and the mind giving the definition. When two persons define the same word differently, the reason is found in the knowledge, the needs, the preferences, the prejudices, and perhaps the whims, of the persons. An object may be viewed in two lights. We can ask what it is in itself, or we can content our- selves with the impression it makes on our minds or what it is to us. In the latter case we consider only what the object seems to be, or how it strikes us. We do not go beyond this to inquire whether our impres- sion is correct, but we take it as final. Superficial as this is, it is the common way of viewing objects. An inquisitive energy is required to lead the mind from the naive to the critical standpoint, which demands an investigation of the impression itself in order to deter- mine its truth or falsity. So long as uncriticised impres- sions or mere opinions are taken for real knowledge, we DEFINITION OF PHILOSOPHY. 15 must expect definitions to be personal and arbitrary, with a flavor of the defining subject rather than the characteristics of the object defined. A sharp distinction between the mind as subject and the object before it, and a discernment of the difference between what seems to be and what is, are the best evi- dences that the mind has passed from its spontaneous to the critical and philosophical stage. By abstracting (separating) the object from the subject, and by concen- trating the attention on it, the mind seeks the (not a) definition. It is an epoch in the history of intellect, when it begins to make objective truth the standard of subjective value. We must not imagine that definitions alone change while the objects remain the same. A word may be variously defined ; but then the same word stands for as many different objects as there are definitions. Both Hegel and J. S. Mill wrote on logic, but they did not discuss the same subject. We speak of the philosophy of Plato and of Comte, but the latter rejected from phil- osophical inquiry what in Plato's system is the essence. And, as the same word may stand for different things, so different words may stand for the same object. There is thus much that is accidental and arbitrary in the use of words ; and where clearness and exactness are sought, it is of the first importance to come to an agreement on the sense in which words are to be taken. Aside from these general considerations, there is spe- cial need of determining the meaning of philosophy. It would be difficult to find another word of the same prominence which has been subject to as many changes and to such a variety of definitions. At different times it has been made to include all that is possible and real on earth, in heaven, and in imagination. It is no wonder, 16 INTRODUCTION TO STUDY OF PHILOSOPHY. therefore, that teachers of philosophy and authors of philosophical works find it extremely difficult to define the term, and be consistent in its use. This is espe- cially true of the historians of philosophy, who are perplexed to know what to admit and what to exclude of the materials regarded in the various ages as philo- sophical. While some standards limit these to rational speculation, others embrace science and a large part of general literature. When we consider the heterogeneity of objects designated by the term at present, we must first define " system of philosophy," when used, if it is to convey any definite meaning. Indeed, in the same university, philosophical systems may be taught which really exclude each other. It is evident that this indefiniteness must interfere both with the study and the progress of philosophy. The stream flowing through history for thousands of years has at last separated into so many rivulets that it is in danger of losing itself in the sand. Philoso- phers, therefore, recognize the necessity of coming to an understanding on the use of the term, so that they may concentrate their efforts, and also understand one another. Consequently, in philosophical journals and books, the definition of philosophy is one of the subjects most frequently discussed. So long as those regarded as philosophers cannot agree as to the object which engrosses their attention, it is not surprising that phi- losophy itself is regarded with suspicion, and treated by many as unworthy of serious inquiry. Not a few earnest thinkers are inquiring whether philosophy stands for any thing definite and valuable ; whether it is pos- sible as a distinct department of thought. If it is an independent subject worthy of profound consideration, why do not philosophers limit the word and their inves- DEFINITION OF PHILOSOPHY. 17 tigations to that subject? Some have become suspi- cious that under cover of that attractive name men have sought for something which is unattainable. May it not be that the progress of knowledge shows that philosophers have been dreaming, and that, being awake now, they are searching in vain for the reality in their dreams ? Some are ready to put philosophy on a level with astrology and alchemy ; they accordingly assign its place to the past wanderings of the human mind in its progress toward knowledge. This confusion discourages the beginner, and makes the study difficult. The vague use of the term also encourages looseness in thinking, and deceives the stu- dent into the belief that he has attained something real and precious, when he has nothing but a word that is almost meaningless, and includes the most heterogene- ous materials. Of the many who study what is called philosophy, not a few at the end of their collegiate course cannot define the word. It may even happen that those who have studied the elements of psychology or logic imagine that they have mastered philosophy ! We might yield to the temptation either to drop the term altogether, or to leave it in its present indefinite-' ness, with no particular object and no peculiar sphere T were it not for the treasures of the past which it holds, and for the conviction that it stands for something too precious to lose. Subjects are often difficult in propor- tion to their intrinsic value, and the terms used vaguely to designate them may only indicate the eagerness of the mind to grasp the subjects themselves. There is no other word to take the place of " philosophy ; " but the concept for which it stands is so difficult, because it lies beyond the usual objects of contemplation, and this naturally contributes to the present confusion. 18 INTRODUCTION TO STUDY OF PHILOSOPHY. But no one who forms and appreciates the concept will begrudge the labor it costs. The student with patient thoroughness in the beginning may discover a light which shall illumine his course till the end. PRINCIPLES WHICH DETERMINE THE DEFINITION. In a definition we aim at a full and clear apprehen- sion of an object. This is only possible by so limiting that object as to be readily distinguishable from others, especially from those most closely related. Brevity being essential to clearness in definitions, we cannot give a full description of an object by defining it ; the characteristic marks by which it can at once be recog- nized will meet all requirements. In order that an object may be known, its own peculiarities, as well as its relation to other objects, must be indicated. The most essential elements are the determination of the class or genus to which the object belongs, and its peculiarities in that genus (the genus proximum and the differentia specified). Where a subject is complicated, it is more easy to determine what the general requirements of a defini- tion are than to fix the principles according to which it is to be found. With all the learned and laborious efforts to define philosophy, these principles have not been sufficiently considered. We cannot expect agree- ment respecting the definition, unless it is understood with what conditions it must comply. Our first inquiry must therefore be: What rules should be followed in defining philosophy ? Owing to the variety of objects at one time or another included under this name, there may be a strong temptation to let preference or prejudice or a mere whim decide to which the term shall be applied. DEFINITION OF PHILOSOPHY. 19 Every arbitrary, merely subjective definition, must, however, be rejected. Whatever its authority to the mind giving it, objective value it cannot claim. We are not seeking any one's opinion, but philosophy itself, — an aim according to which the reader is expected to accept or reject all presented in this chapter. For the same reason we cannot let any existing sys- tem determine the sense of the word, unless the system itself has been proved the true philosophy. It is com- mon to adopt a system taught at a university, and then make it the test of other systems. Those pursuing this method should remember that there is a difference between philosophy and philosophical systems. Every system is apt to have some peculiar views respecting philosophy ; and it is to be regretted if the beginner accepts these, and lets them determine the whole course of his inquiries, instead of waiting until the mind can compare and critically test the various systems, and can either form its own or adopt one rationally. The philo- sophic mind can wait. Not a few define the term according to what they think philosophy can and ought to accomplish, thus lim- iting it to what they regard as most important or within the reach of the mind. This, however, makes the sub- jective state the principle of the definition, while the historic use of the term is ignored. If this rule is adopted, there may be as many definitions as definers. Besides, it has by no means been determined what the limits of the knowable are ; this, in fact, is one of the most important problems of philosophy, and it would be unreasonable to close the investigation by making any one's opinion on the subject the last appeal. Useful as the etymology may be in determining the original sense of a word, it does not necessarily indicate 20 INTRODUCTION TO STUDY OF PHILOSOPHY. its meaning afterwards. Words are but symbols of thought, and their meaning is liable to change with the concepts for which they stand. It sometimes happens that in the course of time the sense of a word changes to the very opposite of the original. The development of a subject is also a development of the corresponding term, which grows with it in definiteness and richness. Yet the etymology may be useful, the original meaning of a word being in many cases like the seed which determines the future growth. As all development is according to law, each stage of progress depending on the preceding growth, the etymology is important in giving the root of the meaning, the concept of those Avho first used the term, and the nature of the subject then designated by it. While, therefore, we do not expect the etymology to give the use of the term " phi- losophy " in the different ages and the various systems, it will, nevertheless, be valuable in determining impor- tant elements in the historic use of the word. The history of the term is far more important than its etymology. It gives the notions attached to the word by the leading philosophers and in the prominent systems. Even if the historical use has varied greatly, there is in all probability something common, some leading thought which underlies the various senses, at least in the principal systems. If this common element can be found, it will give the central thought of philos- ophy in all ages, or that which makes an historical sys- tem philosophical. Those who ignore this historical use of the term must regard the standard histories of phi- losophy misnomers, and must sever the word arbitrarily from its past associations. The history of philosophy is a summary of the thinking of all philosophers, even the greatest of whom constitutes only a small part of the DEFINITION OF PHILOSOPHY. 21 whole course of philosophical development. If, then, we prefer the whole to its parts, we must place the his- toric use of the term higher than the conception of any philosopher, unless that conception is either a legitimate product of the historical development, or else proves that development to be fundamentally wrong. Useful as the historical development is in determining the sense of the term, it has unfortunately terminated in no generally accepted definition. We cannot there- fore appeal to the present use of the word to determine its sense, nor is any system so prominent as to make any particular meaning generally prevalent. Still the con- sciousness of the age, especially of its best thinkers, must be taken into account. A careful study of the subject will show that the con- fusion is largely verbal. Philosophy really has a sphere of its own, clearly defined, and very important ; and no other subject can either take its place or make it un- necessary. Its separate existence and continued study are thereby justified. It will be found that there is a sense which gives the essence of the etymology, as well as of the historic use of the term ; which contains what is common to the great systems ; which marks an impor- tant and distinct department of thought; and which also gives the idea on which the present intelligent use of the word is based. We shall now, under the guidance of these principles, proceed to determine the meaning of the term. ETYMOLOGY AND HISTORY OF THE WORD. The etymology * primarily indicates a certain spirit and tendency, namely the love of wisdom, and the striv- ing to become wise. So long as wisdom was a pursuit * <£iAos ail(I cro^c'a, 22 INTRODUCTION TO STUDY OF PHILOSOPHY. and not an attainment, its exact nature could not be determined. The sphere of inquiry and the goal reached were to each seeker the measure for his appre- hension of the desired object. Thus wisdom as the chief excellence of man might be differently appre- hended according to the views, preferences, and results of the inquirers. It might be viewed as the summit of speculation in any particular department, or as the cul- mination of all theoretical inquiry ; or it could be taken as the practical guide of life or as skill for attaining par- ticular ends, — a skill in which the highest theory and best practice are united. It was not unusual to ascribe wisdom to persons who excelled in an art or learning. Pythagoras is said to have been the first who employed " philosophy " to designate a particular subject ; and it is claimed, that he called himself a philosopher rather than wise,* because he thought God alone wise, while man is merely a friend of wisdom, and strives to attain it.f This sentiment, however, corresponds most fully with the spirit of Socrates, and many think it should be at- tributed to him rather than to Pythagoras. Plato also repeatedly states that wisdom belongs only to God, but that it becomes man to be a friend or lover of wisdom. In the historical use of the word, we behold a reflec- tion of the various views of philosophy itself in the course of its development. We must, however, distin- guish between the popular and the technical use of the term. In the former, some phase of philosophy is usually * <.A6os rather than 6<;. t On the use of the term among the Greeks, I have found of special value " Philosophic," hy R. Haym, in Ersch und Gruber's Encyklopaedie ; Paulsen, " Ueber das Verhaltniss der Philosophic zur Wissenschaft," in Vierteljahrsschrift fur loissenschaftliche Philosophie, 1877, first number; and Ueberweg's Grundriss der Geschichte der Philosophie, Einleitung. DEFINITION OF PHILOSOPHY. 23 seized, or a general characteristic designated ; but it is of little service in determining the technical sense. While originally the word indicated merely a mental attitude toward wisdom, and the striving to which that led, it was soon used also to designate the result of this striving.* For a long time, however, the word was used vaguely. Thus Herodotus employs it to designate the desire for learning, while Thucydides uses it in the sense of striving after intellectual culture. Among others, sophists and rhetoricians were called philosophers, and the contents of their instruction were designated phi- losophy. Isocrates, for instance, uses the term for rheto- ric. Even in the Socratic school the sense of the word was by no means fixed. Plato employs it for study, for learning, for love of learning; but the knowledge to which he especially applies it is that sought for its own sake and not for practical application. Thus he speaks of himself as a philosopher, in distinction from the sophist, who makes a trade of imparting instruction, and from the politician, who seeks knowledge for practi- cal ends. Like Plato, his pupil Aristotle also uses the word in various senses. Besides this general use of the term, we, however, find that Plato and Aristotle also employ it in a techni- cal sense. Thus Plato, as already intimated, uses it to designate the purely theoretical activity of the mind, aside from any practical application of the results attained. While the artist seeks skill, and the rhetori- cian and politician eloquence, in order to influence popular assemblies, the philosopher seeks truth, simply * The word larropia has heen subject to a simliar development as (fKAoo-otfua. Both originally designated merely a subjective state or atti- tude, and afterwards the results attained, namely histories and philoso- phies. The same is true of many other terms. 24 INTRODUCTION TO STUDY OF PHILOSOPHY. because it is the truth. The philosopher also differs from the historian, who merely describes events. Plato wants to get behind phenomena, and seeks to attain an intellectual apprehension of existence ; and he holds that " a philosopher is one who sees the essence of things, the true things, the ideas." * Not satisfied with the tran- sient and the particular, Plato sought the eternal and the universal ; instead of what seems to be, he aimed to get at reality itself. From the world of sense he with- drew to the world of ideas, the archetypes of all exist- ence, the contemplation of which he regarded as the true philosophy. The term, however, is not confined to this contemplation or to any mental attitude, but is also applied to the knowledge or system which is the result. But as a system philosophy was not distinguished from mathematics and physics; and in one instance Plato speaks of geometry as included in philosophy. The verb " to philosophize " is used by Aristotle in the sense of inquiring or searching after knowledge or truth, and he pronounces philosophy the science of truth. It is thus a general term for learning, especially for deeper knowledge. Like his teacher, Aristotle did not separate science from philosophy.! He, however, makes a distinction in favor of what he calls the " first philosophy," afterwards designated metaphysics. But in philosophy he also includes physics, mathematics, ethics, and politics. In its widest sense Aristotle, in * Paulsen. t ia is at times used by him as synonymous with o-otfu'a, and also with eTn conditions which apply equally to all content.* It is not definite enough to say that logic is the science of "the necessary laws of thought." For, if the laws sought are necessary, how can we do other- wise than think according to them ? If necessary, they must operate whether we know them or not. Yet, properly understood, it is correct to say that logic treats of the necessary laws of thought. Thought is not lawless or arbitrary ; it is a rigid, per- fect system, of which mathematics is but an illustration ; it is an organism, in which part fits into part, and part follows part, with perfect regularity and consistency. As in the solution of a mathematical problem a single mistake vitiates the entire process which follows, and makes the result false, so it is with all our mental pro- cesses ; one mistake vitiates the whole. It is common to say that logic aims to prevent these mistakes by giv- ing the laws of correct thinking, and the criteria by which all thought must be tested. This will do if we understand what is meant by correct thinking ; it evi- dently means the proper sequence of thought. All real thinking is correct ; if there are mistakes, it is because there is a lack of thought. He who says 2+2=5, does * Pure or formal logic thus differs from applied logic, which treats of the laws of thought in relation to the material or content of thought. Pure logic gives formal truth, applied gives material truth; the former shows under what conditions thought harmonizes with itself, the latter gives the laws which show the relation of thought to its content. By- limiting logic to the laws of thought, we also distinguish it from Hegel's view according to which the principles of thought are also those of being. 226 INTRODUCTION TO STUDY OF PHILOSOPHY. not think 2+2, but 2+3. So he who says : Most men die a natural death, therefore Socrates died a natural death, does not think at all. Errors, then, do not spring from thinking, but from the failure to think ; it is by thinking that we discover errors, which are the product of thoughtlessness somewhere. If thinking can err, where is the corrective of thinking? We often use words instead of thoughts, and thus make mistakes ; but by thinking through a subject, and by putting thoughts into the words, we correct the errors. Logic, then, simply gives the laws of all thought, and these it learns from thought itself ; it gives the laws according to which men must think in order to get the truth, but these are at the same time the laws which all men follow who really think. Viewed in this light, logic gives the deepest philos- ophy of the mind. In its thought, the intellect mani- fests itself, and in the laws of thought we have the laws of the intellect. Those who see in pure logic only rules for attaining a knowledge of other objects — not of the mind itself — do not know what a revelation they miss. Thus in the study of what is called formal logic, real knowledge is gained, namely of the mind. In consider- ing the forms of thought, these forms themselves are the material of knowledge. Logic deals with concepts, and with them exclusively. With language it deals only so far as it embodies thought; and with things it deals only through their concepts. 23 Language is viewed in logic purely as a symbol of thought. The basis of all reasoning must be absolutely reliable and universally applicable, namely axioms. The pri- mary law is that of identity, or rather equality (being in reality two laws), namely that A equals A. Its THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE. 227 converse is the law of contradiction. A is not equal to non-A. From the law of equality we also get that of excluded middle: Every thing equals either A or non-A. These three laws contain the principles of all com- parison ; namely, that a thing is like or unlike the standard, a third supposition being excluded. All processes of syllogistic reasoning are comparisons or determinations of likeness and unlikeness. Abstraction also depends on the same laws : it is comparison for the sake of discovering and abstracting what is common to different objects. B, C, D, differ ; but B = a, b, c, d ; C = a, e, f, g ; D = a, A, t, Jc ; that is, they all agree in that they have a. We can express the thought thus : B does not equal A except in so far as it is the same as A. It is this A, or this element of sameness or equality, which we want to find in abstrac- tion. In this way the marks of things, which consti- tute them classes, or arrange them under the same concepts, are found. When we search for what is com- mon to things, we call the process abstraction ; when we search for what is common to events, we call the process induction.* Deduction is the reverse, and may be viewed as a concretion of the abstract. For science, as well as philosophy, logic is fundamen- tal, and has been regarded so since the days of Aristotle.f It is so essential because it disciplines the mind for every department of thought, and gives the normative laws of all thinking. Within the last fifty years great efforts have been made, both in Germany and England, to develop logic beyond the bare skeleton which came * Taine, History of English Literature, on Stuart Mill, says, " Ail the methods of induction, therefore, are methods of abstraction." t Cicero calls it Ars omnium artium maxima. 228 INTRODUCTION TO STUDY OF PHILOSOPHY. down through the middle ages from Aristotle.* But the much already done shows how much yet remains to be done. Since logic is usually treated more fully in our insti- tutions of learning than any other department of phi- losophy, it is not necessary to enter into details here. It is, however, important to note that the correct sequence of thought is by no means a guaranty that truth will be the result. Only on the right basis, or with truth as the starting-point, will correct thinking end in truth. And it will generally be found, that, when men disagree, their logic is less at variance than the premises from which their reasoning starts. Before entering upon an argument, the disputants should first determine whether each does not start with a postulate different from that of the other. The assumptions are often of far greater significance than the proofs. In the tendency to specialism, there is a twofold dan- ger ; namely, of choosing a basis for reasoning without a sufficiently broad induction, and of applying the re- sults of our reasoning to spheres that really lie outside of this application. In the one case our argument is too narrow, in the other too broad. In determining the basis from which reasoning starts, all that really per- tains to it should be taken into account. By putting into that basis more than belongs to it, we get results that are not warranted. Thus some draw from their notion of a substance inferences of the greatest impor- tance without ever considering what the substance really * In Germany numerous works on logic have appeared. Hegel gave a new impulse to the study by his work on the subject. AmoDg the more recent books are those of Ulrici, Lotze, Ueberweg, Sigwart, Wundt, Schuppe, Bergmann. In England Whately revived an interest in logic; and works on that subject have been published by Hamilton, Mansel, Mill, De Morgan, Whewell, Boole, Venn, Jevons, and others. THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE. 229 is, and not aware that what they infer from the sub- stance is only that with which their own imagination has endowed it. Hence the object of reasoning should first of all be thoroughly mastered. Then the conclu- sions should be rigorously confined to the objects to which they have been found actually to apply. Rea- soning that pertains to quantity does not explain quality. What applies to material processes has significance only for all that is known to be material. Physiological demonstrations can determine psychological questions only if it has been proved that physiology is psychology, or that they have a sphere in common. Just because it has become so customary to determine what is true in one sphere by what has been established in another, the student should train his mind severely to limit his conclusions to the objects and spheres for which they have been established. Three rules, then, are essential for the attainment of logical truth : master the object of thought so as to know its content ; reason correctly respecting that which is known of the subject; limit the conclusion to that respecting which it has been established. 3. COMPLETION OF KNOWLEDGE. Not merely truth, but truth in greatest perfection, is the aim of intellect. That restless impulse to know, which the Germans call Wissensdrang, or Wissenstrieb, may be the inspiration of but few ; among these, how- ever, are all philosophic thinkers. Nothing short of the deepest thought in the most perfectly developed stage and in the best form can satisfy the aspiring mind. Hints on the development of knowledge itself (not merely of an individual's attainments) are found in 230 INTRODUCTION TO STUDY OF PHILOSOPHY. works on logic, psychology, and pedagogics; but the subject is usually treated in a fragmentary manner. Its importance justifies separate treatment, in order to secure for it more thorough and more systematic dis- cussion. The philosopher and educator find that it teems with weighty problems; and the student, who wants to become a thinker as well as a learner, and who desires to increase knowledge as well as to master what is already known, will seek principles so to guide him in his researches as to develop the best results from the thoughts already attained. The very idea of developing something new from what is known, implies that the new is somehow con- nected with the old, or lies in it as in embryo. The present rests on the past, and the future lies in the present, and there are threads which lead from the one to the other. So when we speak of the completion of knowledge, we want to find the threads which lead from the known to the unknown. Thought is a seed with a certain degree of development at a particular time ; and future progress consists in the development of what is still undeveloped in the seed, or but imper- fectly developed in the plant. The completion of thought, therefore, implies abso- lute dependence on the seed, but independence of the development already attained, in the sense of not being limited by it. Independent, original thought, guided by the energy in the living seed, is the condition for passing to what is new and yet old ; for developing, as Hegel would say, the energy of the flower into the fruit which it virtually contains. For the increase of knowledge in any department it is, therefore, essential to learn what stage of develop- ment has been attained, otherwise there is danger of THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE. 231 wasting time in searching for what is already found. A true philosophy does not undervalue history, but assigns to it the proper place in intellectual training. Historical study may not develop intellectual strength as greatly as philosophy and science ; but only when one has learned what others have done in his specialty can he understand what yet remains to be done, or work successfully to do what is still needed. In the historical knowledge, seized by a philosophical mind, there may be important hints and impulses for new development. New problems may be suggested, the failures of other thinkers will serve as warnings against wrong methods, and all that has already been accom- plished should be the starting-point for accomplishing what is yet to be done. Even if it gives only this starting-point, the historical knowledge is valuable, since it may save from tedious wanderings over beaten tracks. The methods of others may be fit for a help or guide, but not for a tether. The student must avoid ruts ; and with a safe compass, he must not fear to launch out into the deep. A pupil may find a teacher's method invaluable for disciplinary purposes ; but he cannot hope to add any thing new to the stock of knowledge by only repeating experiments performed much better by some one else. The young mathema- tician might learn much by repeating Newton's elab- orate and intricate calculations, but he would not be likely to add any thing to mathematical science by the process. There is scarcely any danger that philosophy will repeat the mistake of under-estimating observation and experiment ; but, from what has been said, it is evident that there is danger of expecting from these themselves what can be wrested from them only by the energy of 232 INTRODUCTION TO STUDY OF PHILOSOPHY. thought. Whatever may transpire outside of the mind, and however necessary for knowledge it may be, intel- lectual progress depends on the amount of thought put into the results of observation and experiment. While this is true in science, the need of great mental energy in regions not so immediately connected with observa- tion is still more apparent. As no one can master or develop all subjects, the student, after securing a liberal education, is obliged to limit himself; he must choose something as a specialty if he wants to become an authority in any thing. The choice of the proper subject for special study is of the first importance, and is by no means wholly determined by the profession or general calling chosen. In order that the choice may be rational, the student must not merely take into account his ability, circumstances, and opportunities, but also the importance and fruitfulness of the subject. Inquiries may be of subordinate value and not worth the time spent on them, or they may be resultless because the subject itself is fruitless. Espe- cially in philosophy, on which so much effort has been spent in fruitless inquiries, is it important to select for profound study important and fruitful problems. Usually the progress of knowledge is regarded as a growth in the comprehension of the causes of things. Science is largely an inquiry into immediate causes, as philosophy is an inquiry into ultimate principles, which must include the first and final causes. All deeper thought seeks the explanation of what occurs, by deter- mining its origin (the genetic method). Here it is not necessary to emphasize the investigation of causes, since its importance is generally admitted ; it will be more helpful to take up neglected elements. Frequently causes lie wholly beyond our reach, or an THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE. 233 inquiry into cause may be irrelevant. Thus, to inquire into the cause of being is the same as inquiring into the being which existed before being. But in dealing with objects there are numerous other problems than those which pertain to cause, — problems which are concerned with a full understanding of the thing itself. We can ask what it is, how it compares with other objects, where it is, and what it can do ; that is, instead of inquiring how a thing became what it is, we concentrate our investigations on the nature of the thing itself. In philosophical inquiries we deal with ideas and concepts, which are remote from concrete objects. The region of pure thinking is peculiarly difficult, thought itself being the sole guide and corrective of thought. Unless here the mind is fully master of its concepts, it is liable to take the flights of fancy for the process of reason. Instead of taking the psychological standpoint, and merely observing the movement of objects in the mind, philosophy checks this movement in order to enter the objects themselves, to think them exhaustively, so as to leave nothing in them or pertaining to them obscure. We thus pass, as it were, from physics to chemistry ; from mere relations and conditions and movements, to the nature of objects. Take, for in- stance, the notion of substance. In common parlance the word is used as if perfectly understood, but critical reflection shows that there are depths in it which the mind has not fathomed. We thus operate with the word as a mere symbol, while the thought itself is lost. The meaning of the term " substance " should be probed until no further inquiries respecting it are possible, or until the limit of thought has been reached. The more comprehensive and abstract a term, the greater the temptation to use it vaguely ; and this vagueness neces- 234 INTRODUCTION TO STUDY OF PHILOSOPHY. sarily extends to all objects included under the term. Common among such vague terms are " being," " cause," "matter," "spirit," "consciousness," "person." The pronoun " I " is a rich subject for reflection. Does it include all that is meant by soul or spirit ? Does it in- clude the body ? Is it the representative of the whole man, or only of the conscious self ? If it stands for the personality, what is the exact meaning of that personal- ity ? Does the " I " stand for a substance, or is it only an aggregate of the various states of consciousness? By thus taking up subjects, and giving to itself a full account of them, the mind soon discovers that it is in the habit of operating familiarly with concepts which are full of mystery ; that it is prone to inquire into the causes of things before understanding the things them- selves; that it takes symbols for things and concepts; and that in many, perhaps by far the most, of our men- tal operations, we are only half awake. It is only by deep and persistent reflection that we become sufficiently conscious of ourselves to see that our intellectual life is largely a dream, — a dream in which we dream that we are awake. In being aroused to full consciousness, the mind makes real progress, attaining a state which will influence all its future operations. The result is not merely a clearing of the understanding, but also a de- velopment of our- knowledge. Even if no new objects are discovered, the old ones are made more distinct, and whatever is in them is unfolded. But this very process may also lead to something else ; namely, to the discov- ery of germs rich in the promise of new developments. This method of taking a subject and holding it stead- ily before the mind to let the light of the intellect illu- mine every part of it, is wholly different from what is called discursive thought. We do not proceed from THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE. 235 one thing to another, but abide by one subject. Our thought moves, but around and through and in the same object. Subject and predicate are not taken apart and viewed separately, as sometimes seems to be the case ; but the subject is seen in its predicates, so that the mind, in considering them, consciously abides by the subject. It does not enter on a process of syllogis- tic reasoning to infer something else from the subject. It indeed wants to make new discoveries, but those which are to be found in the subject itself, not outside of it. In comparison with the discursive, we can call this the penetrative and exhaustive method of thought. Let A be the object of this penetrative energy of thought. Instead of making A simply a link in a chain, so that I pass from it to B, thence to C, etc., I make A the focus on which all possible light is steadily concentrated. I want to know just what A is and con- tains. I may already know that it contains the predi- cates a, b, c, d, but these do not exhaust it. There is an unknown x which I want to discover, and for that reason I confine all my investigations to A. If I proceed from the known to the unknown, it is from the known to the unknown in the subject itself. In this process thought, however, does not confine itself permanently to one point. Hegel's dialectic process has at least demonstrated this: that to think any subject exhaus- tively, necessarily leads beyond the subject to something else. Individual thoughts may, like islands of the sea, not be connected superficially, but at their base. This penetrative method, a characteristic of all philo- sophical thinking, is so much insisted on here because its neglect is so common, and its attainment so difficult. Our modern life, with its endless distractions, and its absorption by details, with much reading and little 236 INTRODUCTION TO STUDY OF PHILOSOPHY. thinking, tends to make thoughts the waves which play on the surface, while the deep remains unfathomed. Thus the habit is formed of using subjects and predi- cates without thoroughly understanding them. That men, even scholars, constantly use concepts which they cannot define, is one of the worst and most common vices of modern thought. In order to pass from the subject itself to something else, we must distinguish between what it contains, and what the mind infers from it. The oil painting before me is nothing but canvas with certain colors. Analyze the picture as I will, I find nothing but these. But how much more than these the mind infers from the picture ! It was painted, it did not grow ; it is the product of an artist ; he had a definite end in view, embodied in the picture his ideal, and had skill in execution. And these conclusions are just as reliable as the fact that the painting consists of canvas and colors. But every inference I draw respecting the artist depends on a correct apprehension of the picture. If it is a chromo, or a copy, or a poor picture, I make serious blunders in my inferences by reasoning on the supposition that it is a Raphael. The same is true of all objects : they contain some- thing, but may suggest more ; and what they suggest depends on what' they contain. After exhausting the real contents, we proceed to what is implied by them. I want to learn from an object what it is, and what it can teach me respecting other objects and the whole universe. If what I infer from an object is really implied by it (is really a necessity of thinking), then it is as reliable knowledge as any other. In this way, and not merely from observation, we get new subjects for reflection. Why we draw these inferences, is one THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE. 237 of the important problems of philosophy ; how to draw them correctly, is a question for logic. Because some- thing is, therefore we infer that something else must be. This is, and therefore that must be, really involve all that can be known. And the development of knowl- edge requires the mastering of the concepts of what is known to be, and then the following to their utmost limits the inferences legitimately drawn therefrom. From this it is evident that real objects of knowledge are not merely obtained through the senses, and by watching our inner operations, but that they may also be learned from correct inferences. In science this has been proved by inferring the existence of objects, and then afterwards confirming the inference by direct dis- covery of the objects. Besides this exhaustive method in treating separate concepts, progress may also be expected by connecting thoughts, and thus forming new combinations, and making these combinations the source of new infer- ences. New combinations of thoughts are new discov- eries, and may furnish new germs for future progress. Is not all inference in reality but a relating process? Analysis and synthesis, induction and deduction, are but processes by means of which implied relations are made explicit. All thinking is but explication of an implication. If knowledge is to be completed, it is evidently not enough that separate concepts be mastered, that several of them be combined, and that the implied be made explicit by means of inferences. Disconnected thoughts, lying around loose in fragments, do not constitute knowledge in an exalted sense any more than stones scattered about constitute a building. In order to be completed, knowledge must be put into a systematic 238 INTRODUCTION TO STUDY OF PHILOSOPHY. form. It is only in a system that a thought occupies its proper place in relation to other thoughts, and attains the highest perfection of which it is capable. In order that there may be system, a subject must be clearly denned, so as to determine its relation to the subjects immediately above and below it. After its place in the universe of knowledge has been determined by the definition and necessary explanations, the sub- ject must be separated into parts, according to the logical principles of division ; that is, the divisions must include the whole subject, but in such a way that they do not include one another.* Various methods of division are possible ; and the one adopted must be determined by the nature of the subject, the stage of development attained, and the aims of the author. The divisions may be chronological or geographical; they may be determined by external marks, or by internal characteristics. The last is the most perfect, since it arranges knowledge according to its inherent relations and real connections. In every case the same principle of division should be followed throughout. If, for instance, a subject were to be divided partly historically, partly geographically, partly according to its inherent character, there would be confusion in- stead of system, overlapping instead of division. Under the main ones come the subdivisions, which must also follow the same principles. A subject can be divided and subdivided almost endlessly. The ana- lytic process may be carried to such an extent that the result is a lifeless skeleton. The scholasticism of the middle ages was fond of nice and curious distinctions, which became a kind of mania; but by this process alone, however valuable for the study of a subject, * See the chapter on the Division of Philosophy. THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE. 239 living systems, intellectual organisms, are not produced. All separation is for the sake of forming the parts into an articulated union, and every true system is a syn- thesis of correlated parts. As nothing exists except in relations, we cannot think a thing correctly if we conceive it in isolation. There is no individual except as part of the whole ; really and fully to comprehend a thing means, as we have seen, that the universe, of which it is a part, must be comprehended. But the synthetic work is usually far more difficult than the analytic. Many can take apart a watch, who cannot put it together again ; and yet the pieces are valuable only because they form the watch. The dissection of the dead body is so important because it enables to understand the living body as an organism. And in mind as well as body we do not want pieces of a ruin, but a perfect system. It is an imperfect view of a system, to regard it as a mere form which does not affect the truth itself. As the arm is something very different on the body from what it is when severed, so a thought is not the same when seen by itself as when viewed in its proper con- nections and relations. In the system, thought is given in its completeness or totality, with all its interlacings. All questions pertaining to relation, cause, and pur- pose, have relevancy only to thought in an articulated system. The idea of system presupposes the connection of thought so as to form a unity. But how can this unity be established or rather discovered? By finding the principles involved in a subject we get that wherein all pertaining to it is united. A system consists in the arrangement of all a subject involves under its princi- ples according to their organic relations. Some idea is 240 INTRODUCTION TO STUDY OF PHILOSOPHY. the animating spirit of every true system, giving it life and determining the various organs of the system. From this it is evident that system is not merely of aesthetic value, nor merely an expedient for remember- ing and using and communicating knowledge: it is necessary for the completion of thought itself. The mind demands it. Much supposed to be well under- stood is found to be in a crude state as soon as an effort is made to put it into its proper place and articulations in a system. Then it is found that a truth unsystema- tized is only half truth ; it is completed truth when its exact relation to other truth is determined. Thus the very effort to systematize thought leads to its deeper study and more perfect development. But it also makes the mind conscious of its limitations. All our systems are imperfect. Many of our thoughts, espe- cially the highest, we cannot yet put into a system. Even the effort to harmonize them is baffled. In their isolation we do not see that they are in conflict, but it becomes evident so soon as we attempt to articulate them. Most painfully do we become conscious of limi- tation in our efforts to complete all knowledge in unity under its ultimate principles. This is the ideal of philosophy in its search for those final explanations which are the conditions of all systems. Only when completed can the theory of knowledge determine abso- lutely the limits of human thought. REFLECTIONS. Define Knowledge. Its Origin. Its external and in- ternal factors. Relation to Imagination, Opinion, Faith. Subjective views and objective Knowledge. Not Certainty, but its grounds are the Criteria of Knowledge. Reasons for believing in an external THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE. 241 world. Kant's Ding an sieh. The unconscious basis of conscious operations. Logic. Formal and applied. Logic as a revelation of the nature of Mind. What is meant by Norms of Thought ? Can real Thinking err ? Laws of Thought discovered by Logic, as mental Pro- cesses by Psychology. What is abstract thought ? Does reasoning lead to the discovery of objects of existence ? Explain Causation. Hume's view. Basis of universal and necessary Truth. Law of Identity, and Law of Equality. Doctrine of Innate Ideas. Views of Leib- nitz and Kant on the subject. Relation of Thought to Objects. Harmony of Idealism and Realism. Can we identify the Laws of Thought and Being (Hegel) ? Place of the Theory of Knowledge in Philosophy. Brilliant and penetrative Thought. Exhausting a Sub- ject, and discursive Thinking. What is System ? How formed ? Its effect on Thought. Conditions for devel- oping and increasing Knowledge. Limits of Thought. Their relation to the Limits of the Real. Significance of the Theory of Knowledge for the times. Is Reason- ing more than comparison ? Basis of Reasoning. Kant's analytic and synthetic Judgments. On what grounds do we infer the unknown from the known ? 242 INTRODUCTION TO STUDY OF PHILOSOPHY. CHAPTER VII. METAPHYSICS. By generalizing the various objects of profitable thought, we can comprehend all of them under the real, the possible, and the desirable. The first includes all that actually is, the last embraces the ideals to be sought, and the second gives the sphere in which their realiza- tion may be expected. As the severe method of philos- ophy eliminates from its inquiries whatever is fanciful, it finds in the three groups all that can claim its atten- tion. The realm of thought itself consists largely in the determination of what is possible. Many of the problems of the real can be answered only in terms of logical possibility by our intellects. The third division, the desirable, does not directly concern the theory of knowledge, which deals primarily with what the intel- lect regards as necessary or possible ; but in that divis- ion are included aesthetics and ethics, which deal with ideals and their realization. The problem of the first division leads us into the darkest and most difficult region of thought, namely metaphysics. This much-abused term represents the highest aim of philosophy, and the ultimate limit of intellectual aspira- tion. The word itself originated in the title given by one of his pupils to certain works of Aristotle. These treated of the ultimate principles of being in general, and constituted what Aristotle himself called " Wis- METAPHYSICS. 243 dom," or "First Philosophy," or "Theology." The fourteen books under the title of " Metaphysics " were placed after his works on Physics; and this circum- stance is generally supposed to have determined the title, its sense being that these books should follow those on Physics. It may, however, be that the title was intended to indicate the nature of the contents, namely such as lie beyond physics.* It is only of secondary importance what the original import of the words of which " metaphysics " is com- pounded may have been, or what sense was attached to the compound itself by him who first used it to desig- nate a particular subject. Aristotle himself did not designate any part of his philosophy by this term, nor is it certain that all the books placed under this title are by him. The general contents of these books may, however, be a valuable aid in understanding the original meaning of the term ; but what his pupils or successors called metaphysics, can no more be a law for the sense of the term at present, than "physics," as employed by the ancients, can determine its use by scientists now. But the aim of Aristotle in his First Philosophy indicates the aim of metaphysic in all ages, being the thread running through all metaphysical systems. In this First Philosophy, Aristotle aimed to discover the general principles of being, in distinction from the special sciences, which are devoted to particular depart- ments of being. f He sought to explain what lies * Ta iieTa ra