■L ■ I ■ Class Book. _ GojpghtN . COPYRIGHT DEPOSrD IMMANUEL KANT'S Critique of Pure Reason En Commemoration of tfje Cmtntarg of ttg Jfrst publication TRANSLATED INTO ENGLISH BY F. MAX MULLER Nefo gork '^ j THE MACMTLLAN COMPANY LONDON: MACMILLAN & CO., Ltd. 1896 All rights reserved Copyright, 1896, By THE M.UMII.I.W < oMPANY. First edition printed 1881. Reprinted with alterations, 1896. XortoootJ 19rrss J. S. Cushing & Co. — Berwick & Smith Norwood Mass. U.S.A. DEDICATION Sir, To further, so far as in us lies, the growth of the sciences is to work in your Excellency's own interest, your own interest being intimately connected with them, not only through the exalted position of a patron of science, but through the far more intimate relation of a lover and enlightened judge. For that reason I avail myself of the only means within my power of proving my gratitude for the gracious confidence with which your Excellency honours me, as if I too could help toward your noble work. [Whoever delights in a speculative life finds with moderate wishes the approval of an enlightened and kind judge a powerful incentive to studies the results of which are great, but remote, and therefore entirely ignored by vulgar eyes.] To you, as such a judge, and to your kind attention I now sub- mit this book, placing all other concerns of my literary future under your special protection, and remaining with profound respect 1 Your Excellency's Most obedient Servant, IMMANUEL KANT. KONIGSBERG, March 29, 178 1. 1 The second paragraph is left out and the last sentence slightly altered in the Second Edition. TABLE OF CONTENTS PAGE Dedication xiii Table of Contents to First Edition xv Preface to First Edition xvii Introduction 1-12 I. The Idea of Transcendental Philosophy . . . 1 II. Division of Transcendental Philosophy . . . .10 I. The Elements of Transcendentalism . . . 15-39 First Part. Transcendental ^Esthetic 1 5-39 First Section. Of Space 18 Second Section. Of Time . . . . ' . 24 General Observations on Transcendental ^Esthetic . . 34 Second Part. Transcendental'Logic .... 40-51 Introduction. The Idea of a Transcendental Logic . . 40 I. Of Logic in General . . . . . .40 II. Of Transcendental Logic ...... 44 III. Of the Division of General Logic into Analytic and Dialectic 46 IV. Of the Division of Transcendental Logic into Tran- scendental Analytic and Dialectic .... 49 First Division. Transcendental Analytic . . . 52-237 Book I. Analytic of Concepts . .... 54-106 Chapter I. Method of Discovering all Pure Concepts of the Understanding . . . . . -55 Section 1. Of the Logical Use of the Understanding in General ........ 56 v vi Table of L 'out cms I'.V.I (Book I. Chapter I.) Section 2. Of the Logical Function of the Under- standing in Judgments 58 section 3. Of the Pure Concepts ol the Understand- ing, oi «'t the ( ategories 63 Chapter 11. Of tin- Deduction of the Pure Concepl the l mil rstanding ....... 70 Section 1. of the Principles of .t Transcendental Deduction in ( icncral ...... 70 Section -. Of the ,1 priori Grounds tor the Possibil- ity of K\|>< litnei j() 1. 01 the Synthesis «•• Apprehension in Intuition 82 thesis oi Reproduction in Imagination v Of the Synthesis ol Recognition in Concepts . 85 4. Preliminar) Explanation "t the Possibility of the Categories as Knowledge a priori ... 91 Section 3. of the Relation of the Understanding to 1 objects in General, and the Possibility of Know- ing them a priori ....... 94 Summary Representation of the Correctness, and of the Only Possibility of this Deduction of the Pure Concepts of the Understanding . . . .105 Book II. Analytic of Principles .... 107-237 Introduction. Of the Transcendental Faculty of Judg- ment in General . 108 Chapter I. Of the Schematism of the Pure Concepts of the Understanding 112 Chapter II. System of all Principles of the Pure Under- standing 121 Section 1. Of the Highest Principle of all Analytical Judgments 123 Section 2. Of the Highest Principle of all Synthetical Judgments 126 129 133 i 3 6 144 149 155 172 Table of Contents vii PAGE (Book II. Chapter II.) Section 3. Systematical Representation of all Syn- thetical Principles of the Pure Understanding 1. Axioms of Intuition 2. Anticipations of Perception .... 3. Analogies of Experience .... First Analogy. Principle of Permanence Second Analogy. Principle of Production Third Analogy. Principle of Community 4. The Postulates of Empirical Thought in General 178 Chapter III. On the Ground of Distinction of all Sub- jects into Phenomena and Noumena . . .192 Appendix. Of the Amphiboly of Reflective Concepts, owing to the Confusion of the Empirical with the Transcendental Use of the Understanding . .212 Second Division. Transcendental Dialectic . . . 238-564 Introduction 238 1. Of Transcendental Appearance (Illusion) . . ' . 238 2. Of Pure Reason as the seat of Transcendental Illu- sion 242 A. Of Reason in General . . . . . 242 B. Of the Logical Use of Reason .... 246 C. Of the Pure Use of Reason .... 247 Book I. Of the Concepts of Pure Reason . . 252-274 Section 1. Of Ideas in General 254 Section 2. Of Transcendental Ideas .... 261 Section 3. System of Transcendental Ideas . . 270 Book II. Of the Dialectical Conclusions of Pure Reason 275-564 Chapter I. Of the Paralogisms of Pure Reason . . 278 First Paralogism. Of Substantiality .... 284 Second Paralogism. Of Simplicity .... 286 Third Paralogism. Of Personality .... 294 Fourth Paralogism. Of Ideality 298 viii Table of Content* (Book II. Chapter I.) Consideration on the Whole o\ Pure Psychology, as affected bv these Paralogisms 308 328 330 339 344 352 362 37o Chapter 11. The Antinom) of Pure Reason . Section 1. System of Cosmological Ideas , Section 2. Antithetic oi Pure Reason First Conflict of the Transcendental Ideas Second Conflict ..... Third Conflict irth Conflict ..... Section v < )t the Interest of Reason in these Con- flicts 379 Section 4. Of the Transcendental Problems of Pure Reason, and the Absolute Necessity of their Solution ........ 389 ion 5. Sceptical Representation of the Cosmolog- ical Questions in the Four Transcendental Ideas . 396 Section 6. Transcendental Idealism as the Key to the Solution of Cosmological Dialectic . . . 400 Section 7. Critical Decision of the Cosmological Conflict of Reason with itself .... 405 Section 8. The Regulative Principle of Pure Reason with Regard to the Cosmological Ideas . -413 Section 9. Of the Empirical Use of the Regulative Principle of Reason with Regard to all Cosmolog- ical Ideas 419 I. Solution of the Cosmological Idea of the Total- ity of the Composition of Phenomena in an Universe 420 II. Solution of the Cosmological Idea of the Total- ity of the Division of a Whole given in Intu- ition 425 Tabic of Contents ix PAGE (Book II. Chapter II. Section 9.) Concluding Remarks on the Solution of the Transcendental-mathematical Ideas, and Pre- liminary Remark for the Solution of the Transcendental-dynamical Ideas . . . 428 III. Solution of the Cosmological Ideas with Regard to the Totality of the Derivation of Cosmical Events from their Causes .... 432 Possibility of a Causality through Freedom, in Har- mony with the Universal Law of Necessity . 436 Explanation of the Cosmological Idea of Freedom in Connection with the General Necessity of Nature . . . . . . . 439 IV. Solution of the Cosmological Idea of the Total- ity of the Dependence of Phenomena, with Regard to their Existence in General . . 452 Chapter III. The Ideal of Pure Reason . .-, 459 Section 1. Of the Ideal in General .... 459 Section 2. Of the Transcendental Ideal . . . 462 Section 3. Of the Arguments of Speculative Reason in Proof of the Existence of a Supreme Being . 471 Section 4. Of the Impossibility of an Ontological Proof of the Existence of God .... 477 Section 5. Of the Impossibility of a Cosmological Proof of the Existence of God .... 486 Discovery and Explanation of the Dialectical Illusion in all Transcendental Proofs of the Existence of a Necessary Being 495 Section 6. Of the Impossibility of the Physico-theo- logical Proof ....... 499 Section 7. Criticism of ail Theology based on Spec- ulative Principles of Reason ..... 508 x Table of ( ontents PAGE (Book II. Chapter III. Section 7.) Appendix to the Transcendental Dialectic. Of the Regulative Use of the Ideas of Pure Reason . 516 Of the Ultimate Aim of the Natural Dialectic of Human Reason 537 11. Method o] Transcendentalism .... 565-686 Chapter I. The Discipline of Pure Reason . . . 569 Section 1. The Discipline of Pure Reason in its Dog matical l Fse 572 Section 2. The Discipline of Pure Reason in its Polem ie.il I Fse ......... 593 The Impossibility of a Sceptical Satisfaction <>i Pun Reason in < onflicl with itseli ..... 608 tion 3. The Discipline ot Pun- Reason with Regard to Hypotheses . . . • • • • .617 Section 4. The Discipline of Pure Reason with Regard to its Proofs Chapter II. The Canon of Pure Reason . Section 1. Of the Ultimate Aim of the Pure Use of our Reason Section 2. Of the Ideal of the Summum Bonum as determining the Ultimate Aim of Pure Reason Section 3. Of Trowing. Knowing, and Believing . Chapter III. The Architectonic of Pure Reason Chapter IV. The History of Pure Reason Supplements 687-808 627 638 640 645 657 667 683 TO HIS EXCELLENCY THE ROYAL MINISTER OF STATE BARON VON ZEDLITZ TABLE OF CONTENTS TO THE FIRST EDITION 1 PAGES Introduction i (i) I. ELEMENTS OF TRANSCENDENTALISM. PART I. Transcendental /Esthetic . . . 17 (19) Section I. Of Space 20 (22) Section II. Of Time 27 (30) PART II. Transcendental Logic . . -44 (50) Division I. Transcendental Analytic in two books, with their chapters and sections . . . . 56 (64) Division II. Transcendental Dialectic in two books, with their chapters and sections .... 254 (293) II. METHOD OF TRANSCENDENTALISM. Chapter I. The Discipline of Pure Reason . . 607 (708) Chapter II. The Canon of Pure Reason . . 682 (795) Chapter III. The Architectonic of Pure Reason . 714 (832) Chapter IV. The History of Pure Reason . . 731 (852) 1 Instead of this simple Table of Contents, later editions have a much fuller one (Supplement III), which, as Rosenkranz observes, obscures rather than illustrates the articulation of the book. PREFACE 1 Our reason (Vernunft) has this peculiar fate that, with reference to one class of its knowledge, it is always troubled with questions which cannot be ignored, because they spring from the very nature of reason, and which cannot be answered, because they transcend the powers of human reason. Nor is human reason to be blamed for this. It begins with principles which, in the course of experience, it must follow, and which are sufficiently confirmed by experience. With these again, according to the necessities of its nature, it rises higher and higher to more remote conditions. But when it perceives that in this way its work remains for ever incomplete, because the questions never cease, it finds itself constrained to take refuge in principles which exceed every possible experimental application, and never- theless seem so unobjectionable that even ordinary com- mon sense agrees with them. Thus, however, reason becomes involved in darkness and contradictions, from which, no doubt, it may conclude that errors must be lurking somewhere, but without being able to discover them, because the principles which it follows transcend all the limits of experience and therefore withdraw them- 1 This preface is left out in later editions, and replaced by a new preface; see Supplement II (Vol. I, p. 364). xviii Preface selves from all experimental tests. It is the battle-field of these endless controversies which is called Metaphysic. There was a time when Metaphysic held a royal place among all the sciences, and, if the will were taken for the deed, the exceeding importance of her subject might well have secured to her that place of honour. At present it is the fashion to despise Metaphysic, and the poor matron, forlorn and forsaken, complains like Hecuba, Modo max- ima rcrum, tot generis natisque potens — )iu)ie trahor exul y inops (Ovid, Metam. xiii. 508). At first the rule of Metaphysic, under the dominion of the dogmatists, was despotic. But as the laws still bore the traces of an old barbarism, intestine wars and complete anarchy broke out, and the sceptics, a kind of nomads, despising all settled culture of the land, broke up from time to time all civil society. ' Fortunately their number was small, and they could not prevent the old settlers from returning to cultivate the ground afresh, though without any fixed plan or agreement. Not long ago one might have thought, indeed, that all these quarrels were to have been settled and the legitimacy of her claims decided once for all through a certain physiology of the human understanding, the work of the celebrated Locke. But, though the descent of that royal pretender, traced back as it had been to the lowest mob of common ex- perience, ought to have rendered her claims very sus- picious, yet, as that genealogy turned out to be in reality a false invention, the old queen (Metaphysic) continued to maintain her claims, everything fell back into the old rotten dogmatism, and the contempt from which metaphy- sical science was to have been rescued, remained the same as ever. At present, after everything has been tried, so Preface xix they say, and tried in vain, there reign in philosophy weariness and complete indifferentism, the mother of chaos and night in all sciences but, at the same time, the spring or, at least, the prelude of their near reform and of a new light, after an ill-applied study has rendered them dark, confused, and useless. It is in vain to assume a kind of artificial indifferentism in respect to enquiries the object of which cannot be in- different to human nature. Nay, those pretended indif- ferentists (however they may try to disguise themselves by changing scholastic terminology into popular language), if they think at all, fall back inevitably into those very metaphysical dogmas which they profess to despise. Nevertheless this indifferentism, showing itself in the very midst of the most flourishing state of all sciences, and affecting those very sciences the teachings of which, if they could be had, would be the last to be surrendered, is a phenomenon well worthy of our attention and considera- tion. It is clearly the result, not of the carelessness, but of the matured judgment 1 of our age, which will no longer rest satisfied with the mere appearance of know- 1 We often hear complaints against the shallowness of thought in our own time, and the decay of sound knowledge. But I do not see that sciences which rest on a solid foundation, such as mathematics, physics, etc., deserve this reproach in the least. On the contrary, they maintain their old reputa- tion of solidity, and with regard to physics, even surpass it. The same spirit would manifest itself in other branches of knowledge, if only their principles ^had first been properly determined. Till that is done, indifferentism and doubt, and ultimately severe criticism, are rather signs of honest thought. ' ' Our age is, in every sense of the word, the age of criticism, and everything must submit to it. Religion, on the strength of its sanctity, and law, on the strength of its majesty, try to withdraw themselves from it; but by so doing they arouse just suspicions, and cannot claim that sincere respect which reason pays to those only who have been able to stand its free and open examination. . XX Preface ledge. It is, at the same time, a powerful appeal to reason to undertake anew the most difficult of its duties, namely, self-knowledge, and to institute a court of appeal which should protect the just rights of reason, but dismiss all groundless claims, and should do this not by means of irresponsible decrees, but according to the eternal and unalterable laws of reason. This court of appeal is no other than the Critique of Pure Reason. I do not mean by this a criticism of books and systems, but of the faculty of reason in general, touching that whole class of knowledge which it may strive after, un- assisted by experience. This must decide the question of the possibility or impossibility of metaphysic in general, and the determination of its sources, its extent, and its limits — and all this according to fixed principles. This, the only way that was left, I have followed, and I flatter myself that I have thus removed all those errors which have hitherto brought reason, whenever it was unassisted by experience, into conflict with itself. I have not evaded its questions by pleading the insufficiency of human reason, but I have classified them according to principles, and, after showing the point where reason begins to misunderstand itself, solved them satisfactorily. It is true that the answer of those questions is not such as a dogma-enamoured curiosity might wish for, for such curi- osity could not have been satisfied except by juggling tricks in which I am no adept. But this was not the intention of the natural destiny of our reason, and it became the duty of philosophy to remove the deception which arose from a false interpretation, even though many a vaunted and cherished dream should vanish at the same time. In this work I have chiefly aimed at Preface xxi completeness, and I venture to maintain that there ought not to be one single metaphysical problem that has not been solved here, or to the solution of which the key at least has not been supplied. In fact Pure Reason is so perfect a unity that, if its principle should prove insuffi- cient to answer any one of the many questions started by its very nature, one might throw it away altogether, as insufficient to answer the other questions with perfect certainty. While I am saying this I fancy I observe in the face of my readers an expression of indignation, mixed with contempt, at pretensions apparently so self-glorious and extravagant ; and yet they are in reality far more moder- ate than those made by the writer of the commonest essay professing to prove the simple nature of the soul or the necessity of a first beginning of the world. For, while he pretends to extend human knowledge beyond the limits of all possible experience, I confess most humbly that this is entirely beyond my power. I mean only to treat of reason and its pure thinking, a knowledge of which is not very far to seek, considering that it is to be found within myself. Common logic gives an instance how all the simple acts of reason can be enumerated completely and systematically. Only between the common logic and my work there is this difference, that my question is, — what can we hope to achieve with reason, when all the material and assistance of experience is taken away ? So much with regard to the completeness in our laying hold of every single object, and the thoroughness in our laying hold of all objects, as the material of our critical en- quiries — a completeness and thoroughness determined, not by a casual idea, but by the nature of our knowledge itself. xxii Preface Besides this, certainty and clearness with regard to form are two essential demands that may very properly be addressed to an author who ventures on so slippery an undertaking. First, with regard to certainty, I have pronounced judg- ment against myself by saying that in this kind of enquiries it is in no way permissible to propound mere opinions, and that everything looking like a hypothesis is counterband, that must not be offered for sale at however low a price, but must, as soon as it has been discovered, be confiscated. For every kind of knowledge which professes to be cer- tain a priori, proclaims itself that it means to be taken for absolutely necessary. And this applies, therefore, still more to a definition of all pure knowledge a priori, which is to be the measure, and therefore also an example, of all apodictic philosophical certainty. Whether I have ful- filled what I have here undertaken to do, must be left to the judgment of the reader ; for it only behoves the author to propound his arguments, and not to determine before- hand the effect which they ought to produce on his judges. But, in order to prevent any unnecessary weakening of those arguments, he may be allowed to point out himself certain passages which, though they refer to collateral objects only, might occasion some mistrust, and thus to counteract in time the influence which the least hesitation of the reader in respect to these minor points might exer- cise with regard to the principal object. I know of no enquiries which are more important for determining that faculty which we call understanding (Verstand), and for fixing its rules and its limits, than those in the Second Chapter of my Transcendental Ana- lytic, under the title of ' Deduction of the Pure Concepts Preface xxiii of the Understanding.' They have given me the greatest but,- 1 hope, not altogether useless trouble. This enquiry, which rests on a deep foundation, has two sides. The one refers to the objects of the pure understanding, and is intended to show and explain the objective value of its concepts a priori. It is, therefore, of essential importance for my purposes. The other is intended to enquire into the pure understanding itself, its possibility, and the powers of knowledge on which it rests, therefore its sub- jective character ; a subject which, though important for my principal object, yet forms no essential part of it, be- cause my principal problem is and remains, What and how much may understanding (Verstand) and reason (Ver- nunft) know without all experience ? and not, How is the faculty of thought possible ? The latter would be an en- quiry into a cause of a given effect ; it would, therefore, be of the nature of an hypothesis (though, as I shall show elsewhere, this is not quite so) ; and it might seem as if I had here allowed myself to propound a mere opinion, leav- ing the reader free to hold another opinion also. I there- fore warn the reader, in case my subjective deduction should not produce that complete conviction which I ex- pect, that the objective deduction, in which I am here chiefly concerned, must still retain its full strength. For this, what has been said on pp. 82, 83 (92, 93) may possi- bly by itself be sufficient. Secondly, as to clearness, the reader has a right to demand not only what may be called logical or discursive clearness, which is based on concepts, but also what may be called aesthetic or intuitive clearness produced by intui- tions, i.e. by examples and concrete illustrations. With regard to the former I have made ample provision. That xxiv Preface arose from the very nature of my purpose, but it became at the same time the reason why I could not fully satisfy the latter, if not absolute, yet very just claim. Nearly through the whole of my work I have felt doubtful what to do. Examples and illustrations seemed always to be necessary, and therefore found their way into the first sketch ^)\ my work. But I soon perceived the magnitude of my task and the number of objects I should have to treat; and, when I saw that even in their driest scholastic form they would considerably swell my book, I did not consider it expedient to extend it still further through examples and illustrations required for popular purposes only. This work can never satisfy the popular taste, and the few who know, do not require that help which, though it is always welcome, yet might here have defeated its very purpose. The Abbe Terrasson * writes indeed that, if we measured the greatness of a book, not by the number of its pages, but by the time we require for mastering it, many a book might be said to be much shorter, if it were not so short. But, on the other hand, if we ask how a complicated, yet in principle coherent whole of specula- tive thought can best be rendered intelligible, we might be equally justified in saying that many a book would have been more intelligible, if it had not tried to be so very intelligible. For the helps to clearness, though they may be missed 2 with regard to details, often distract with re- gard to the whole. The reader does not arrive quickly enough at a survey of the whole, because the bright col- 1 Terrasson, Philosophic nach ihrem allgemeinen Einflusse auf alle Gegen- stande des Geistes und der Sitten, Berlin, 1762, p. 117. 2 Rosenkranz and others change fehlen into helfen, without necessity, I think. Preface xxv ours of illustrations hide and distort the articulation and concatenation of the whole system, which, after all, if we want to judge of its unity and sufficiency, are more im- portant than anything else. Surely it should be an attraction to the reader if he is asked to join his own efforts with those of the author in order to carry out a great and important work, according to the plan here proposed, in a complete and lasting man- ner. Metaphysic, according to the definitions here given, [s the only one of all sciences which, through a small but united effort, may count on such completeness in a short time, so that nothing will remain for posterity but to arrange everything according to its own views for didactic purposes, without being able to add anything to the sub- ject itself. For it is in reality nothing but an. inventory of all our possessions acquired through Pure Reason, systematically arranged. Nothing can escape us, -because whatever reason produces entirely out of itself, cannot hide itself, but is brought to light by reason itself, so soon as the common principle has been discovered. This abso- lute completeness is rendered not only possible, but neces- sary, through the perfect unity of this kind of knowledge, all derived from pure concepts, without any influence from experience, or from special intuitions leading to a definite kind of experience, that might serve to enlarge and in- crease it. Tecum Jiabita et noris quam, sit tibi curta stipel- lex (Persius, Sat. iv. 52). Such a system of pure (speculative) reason I hope myself to produce under the title of ' Metaphysic of Nature.' It will not be half so large, yet infinitely richer than this Critique of Pure Reason, which has, first of all, to discover its source, nay, the conditions of its possibility, xxvi Preface in fact, to clear and level a soil quite overgrown with weeds. Here I expect from my readers the patience and impartiality of a judge, there the goodwill and aid of a fellow-worker. For however completely all the principles of the system have been propounded in my Critique, the completeness of the whole system requires also that no derivative concepts should be omitted, such as cannot be found out by an estimate a priori, but have to be dis- covered step by step. There the synthesis of concepts has been exhausted, here it will be requisite to do the same for their analysis, a task which is easy and an amusement rather than a labour. I have only a few words to add with respect to the printing of my book. As the beginning had been delayed, I was not able to see a clean sheet of more than about half of it. I now find some misprints, though they do not spoil the sense, except on p. 379, line 4 from below, where specific should be used instead of sceptic. The antinomy of pure reason from p. 425 to p. 461 has been arranged in a tabular form, so that all that belongs to the thesis stands on the left, what belongs to the antithesis on the right side. I did this in order that thesis and antithesis might be more easily compared. INTRODUCTION [p-i] 1 I THE IDEA OF TRANSCENDENTAL PHILOSOPHY [Experience 1 is no doubt the first product of our un- derstanding, while employed in fashioning the raw material of our sensations. It is therefore our first instruction, and in its progress so rich in new lessons that the chain of all future generations will never be in want of new informa- tion that may be gathered on that field. Nevertheless, experience is by no means the only field to which our understanding can be confined. Experience tells us what is, but not that it must be necessarily as it is, and not otherwise. It therefore never gives us any really gen- eral truths, and our reason, which is particularly anxious for that class of knowledge, is roused by it rather than satisfied. General truths, which at the same time [p. 2] bear the character of an inward necessity, must be in- dependent of experience, — clear and certain by them- selves. They are therefore called knowledge a priori, while what is simply taken from experience is said to be, in ordinary parlance, known a posteriori or empiri- cally only. 1 The beginning of this Introduction down to ' But what is still more ex- traordinary,' is left out in the Second Edition. Instead of it Supplement IV. 2 Introduction Now it appears, and this is extremely curious, that even with our experiences different kinds of knowledge are mixed up, which must have their origin a priori, and which perhaps serve only to produce a certain connec- tion between our sensuous representations. For even if we remove from experience everything that belongs to the senses, there remain nevertheless certain original con- cepts, and certain judgments derived from them, which must have had their origin entirely a priori, and inde- pendent of all experience, because it is owing to them that we are able, or imagine we are able, to predicate more of the objects of our senses than can be learnt from mere experience, and that our propositions contain real generality and strict necessity, such as mere empirical knowledge can never supply:] But l what is still more extraordinary is this, that cer- tain kinds of knowledge leave the field of all pos- [p. 3] sible experience, and seem to enlarge the sphere of our judgments beyond the limits of experience by means of concepts to which experience can never supply any cor- responding objects. And it is in this very kind of knowledge which tran- scends the world of the senses, and where experience can neither guide nor correct us, that reason prosecutes its investigations, which by their importance we consider far more excellent and by their tendency far more ele- vated than anything the understanding can find in the sphere of phenomena. Nay, we risk rather anything, even at the peril of error, than that we should surrender 1 The Second Edition gives here a new heading: — III, Philosophy re- quires a science to determine the possibility, the principles, and the extent of all cognitions a priori. Introduction 3 such investigations, either on the ground of their uncer- tainty, or from any feeling of indifference or contempt. 1 Now it might seem natural that, after we have left the solid ground of experience, we should not at once proceed to erect an edifice with knowledge which we possess without knowing whence it came, and trust to principles the origin of which is unknown, without hav- ing made sure of the safety of the foundations by means of careful examination. It would seem natural, I say, that philosophers should first of all have asked the ques- tion how the mere understanding could arrive at all this knowledge a prio7'i, and what extent, what truth, and what value it could possess. If we take natural [p. 4] to mean what is just and reasonable, then indeed nothing could be more natural. But if we understand by natural what takes place ordinarily, then, on the contrary, nothing is more natural and more intelligible than that this exami- nation should have been neglected for so long a time. For one part of this knowledge, namely, the mathematical, has always been in possession of perfect trustworthiness ; and thus produces a favourable presumption with regard to other parts also, although these may be of a totally dif- ferent nature. Besides, once beyond the precincts of ex- perience, and we are certain that experience can never contradict us, while the charm of enlarging our know- ledge is so great that nothing will stop our progress until we encounter a clear contradiction. This can be 1 The Second Edition adds here : ' These inevitable problems of pure reason itself are, God, Freedom, and Immortality. The science which with all its apparatus is really intended for the solution of these problems, is called Metaphysic. Its procedure is at first dogmatic, i.e. unchecked by a previous examination of what reason can and cannot do, before it engages confidently in so arduous an undertaking.' 4 Introduction avoided if only we are cautious in our imaginations, which nevertheless remain what they are, imaginations only. How far we can advance independent of all ex- perience in a priori knowledge is shown by the brilliant example of mathematics. It is true they deal with objects and knowledge so far only as they can be represented in intuition. But this is easily overlooked, because that intuition itself may be given a priori, and be difficult to distinguish from a pure concept. Thus inspirited [p. 5] by a splendid proof of the power of reason, the desire of enlarging our know ledge sees no limits. The light dove, piercing in her easy Might the air and perceiving its resist- ance, imagines that flight would be easier still in empty space. It was thus that Plato left the world of sense, as opposing so many hindrances to our understanding, and ventured beyond on the wings of his ideas into the empty space of pure understanding. He did not perceive that he was making no progress by these endeavours, because he had no resistance as a fulcrum on which to rest or to apply his powers, in order to cause the understand- ing to advance. It is indeed a very common fate of human reason first of all to finish its speculative edifice as soon as possible, and then only to enquire whether the foundation be sure. Then all sorts of excuses are made in order to assure us as to its solidity, or to decline alto- gether such a late and dangerous enquiry. The reason why during the time of building we feel free from all anxiety and suspicion and believe in the apparent solidity of our foundation, is this: — A great, perhaps the greatest portion of what our reason finds to do consists in the analysis of our concepts of objects. This gives us a great deal of knowledge which, though it consists in no Introduction 5 more than in simplifications and explanations of [p. 6] what is comprehended in our concepts (though in a con- fused manner), is yet considered as equal, at least in form, to new knowledge. It only separates and arranges our concepts, it does not enlarge them in matter or con- tents. As by this process we gain a kind of real know- ledge a priori, which progresses safely and usefully, it happens that our reason, without being aware of it, ap- propriates under that pretence propositions of a totally different character, adding to given concepts new and strange ones a priori, without knowing whence they come, nay without even thinking of such a question. I shall therefore at the very outset treat of the distinction between these two kinds of knowledge. Of the Distmction between Analytical and Synthetical Judgments In all judgments in which there is a relation between subject and predicate (I speak of affirmative judgments only, the application to negative ones being easy), that relation can be of two kinds. Either the predicate B belongs to the subject A as something contained (though covertly) in the concept A ; or B lies outside the sphere of the concept A, though somehow connected with it. In the former case I call the judgment analytical, in the latter synthetical. Analytical judgments (affirmative) are therefore those in which the connection of the [p. 7] predicate with the subject is conceived through identity, while others in which that connection is conceived without identity, may be called synthetical. The former might be called illustrating, the latter expanding judgments, because in the former nothing is added by the predicate to the 6 Introduction concept of the subject, but the concept is only divided into its constituent concepts which were always conceived as existing within it, though confusedly ; while the latter add to the concept of the subject a predicate not conceived as existing within it, and not to be extracted from it by any process of mere analysis. If I say, for instance, All bodies arc extended, this is an analytical judgment. I need not go beyond the concept connected with the name of body, in order to find that extension is connected with it. I have only to analyse that concept and become conscious of the manifold elements always contained in it, in order to find that predicate. This is therefore an analytical judg- ment. But if I say, All bodies are heavy, the predicate is something quite different from what I think as the mere concept of body. The addition of such a predicate gives us a synthetical judgment. [It becomes clear from this, 1 [i. That our knowledge is in no way extended by analytical judgments, but that all they effect is [p. 8] to put the concepts which we possess into better order and render them more intelligible. 2. That in synthetical judgments I must have besides the concept of the subject something else (x) on which the understanding relies in order to know that a predicate, not contained in the concept, nevertheless belongs to it. In empirical judgments this causes no difficulty, because this x is here simply the complete experience of an object which I conceive by the concept A, that concept forming one part only of my experience. For though I do not in- clude the predicate of gravity in the general concept of 1 These two paragraphs to ' In synthetical judgments a priori, however,' are left out in the Second Edition, and replaced by Supplement V, Introduction 7 body, that concept nevertheless indicates the complete experience through one of its parts, so that I may add other parts also of the same experience, all belonging to that concept. I may first, by an analytical process, realise the concept of body through the predicates of extension, impermeability, form, etc., all of which are contained in it. Afterwards I expand my knowledge, and looking back to the experience from which my concept of body was ab- stracted, I find gravity always connected with the before- mentioned predicates. Experience therefore is the x which lies beyond the concept A, and on which rests the possibility of a synthesis of the predicate of gravity B with the concept A.] In synthetical judgments a priori, however, that [p. 9] help is entirely wanting. If I want to go beyond the con- cept A in order to find another concept B connected with it, where is there anything on which I may rest and through which a synthesis might become possible, con- sidering that I cannot have the advantage of looking about in the field of experience ? Take the proposition that all which happens has its cause. In the concept of something that happens I no doubt conceive of something existing preceded by time, and from this certain analytical judgments may be deduced. But the concept of cause is entirely outside that concept, and indicates something different from that which happens, and is by no means contained in that representation. How can I venture then to predicate of that which happens something totally different from it, and to represent the concept of cause, though not contained in it, as belonging to it, and belong- ing to it by necessity ? What is here the unknown x, on which the understanding may rest in order to find beyond 8 Introduction the concept A a foreign predicate B, which nevertheless is believed to be connected with it? It cannot be ex- perience, because the proposition that all which happens has its cause represents this second predicate as added to the subject not only with greater generality than experience can ever supply, but also with a character of necessity, and therefore purely a priori, and based on concepts. All our speculative knowledge a priori aims at and rests on such synthetical, i.e. expanding propositions, for [p. 10] the analytical are no doubt very important and necessary, yet only in order to arrive at that clearness of concepts which is requisite for a safe and wide synthesis, serving as a really new addition to what we possess already. [We 1 have here a certain mystery 2 before us, which must be cleared up before any advance into the unlimited field of a pure knowledge of the understanding can become safe and trustworthy. We must discover on the largest scale the ground of the possibility of synthetical judgments a priori ; we must understand the conditions which render every class of them possible, and endeavour not only to indicate in a sketchy outline, but to define in its fulness and practical completeness, the whole of that knowledge, which forms a class by itself, systematically arranged according to its original sources, its divisions, its extent and its limits. So much for the present with regard to the peculiar character of synthetical judgments.] It will now be seen how there can be a special [p. n] 1 This paragraph left out in the Second Edition, and replaced by Supple- ment VI. 2 If any of the ancients had ever thought of asking this question, this alone would have formed a powerful barrier against all systems of pure reason to the present day, and would have saved many vain attempts undertaken blindly and without a true knowledge of the subject in hand. Introduction 9 science serving as a critique of pure reason. [Every kind of knowledge is called pure, if not mixed with any- thing heterogeneous. But more particularly is that know- ledge called absolutely pure, which is not mixed up with any experience or sensation, and is therefore possible en- tirely a priori.] Reason is the faculty which supplies the principles of knowledge a priori. Pure reason therefore is that faculty which supplies the principles of knowing anything entirely a priori. An Organum of pure reason ought to comprehend all the principles by which pure knowledge a priori can be acquired and fully established. A complete application of such an Organum would give us a System of Pure Reason. But as that would be a difficult task, and as at present it is still doubtful whether and when such an expansion of our knowledge is here possible, we may look on a mere criticism of pure reason, its sources and limits, as a kind of preparation for a com- plete system of pure reason. It should be called a critique, not a doctrine, of pure reason. Its usefulness would be negative only, serving for a purging rather than for an expansion of our reason, and, what after all is a consid- erable gain, guarding reason against errors. I ca ll all knowledge transcendental which is occupied not so much with objects, as with our a priori concepts of objects. 1 A system of such concepts might be [p. 12] called Transcendental Philosophy. But for the present this is again too great an undertaking. We should have to treat therein completely both of analytical knowledge, and of synthetical knowledge a priori, which is more than we intend to do, being satisfied to carry on the analysis so 1 ' As with our manner of knowing objects, so far as this is meant to be possible a priori? Second Edition. 10 Introduction far only as is indispensably necessary in order to recognise in their whole extent the principles of synthesis a priori, which alone concern us. This investigation which should be called a transcendental critique, but not a systematic doctrine, is all we are occupied with at present. It is not meant to extend our knowledge, but only to rectify it, and to become the test of the value of all a priori knowledge. Such a critique therefore is a preparation for a New Organum, or, if that should not be possible, for a Canon at least, according to which hereafter a complete system of a philosophy of pure reason, whether it serve for an expansion or merely for a limitation of it, may be carried out, both analytically and synthetically. That such a system is possible, nay that it need not be so com- prehensive as to prevent the hope of its completion, may be gathered from the fact that it would have to deal, not with the nature of things, which is endless, but with the understanding which judges of the nature of [p. 13] things, and this again so far only as its knowledge a priori is concerned. Whatever the understanding pos- sesses a priori, as it has not to be looked for without, can hardly escape our notice, nor is there any reason to suppose that it will prove too extensive for a complete inventory, and for such a valuation as shall assign to it its true merits or demerits. 1 II DIVISION OF TRANSCENDENTAL PHILOSOPHY Transcendental Philosophy is with us an idea (of a science) only, for which the critique of pure reason should 1 Here follows Supplement VII in Second Edition. Introduction 1 1 trace, according to fixed principles, an architectonic plan, guaranteeing the completeness and certainty of all parts of which the building consists. (It is a system of all principles of pure reason.) 1 The reason why we do not call such a critique a transcendental philosophy in itself is simply this, that in order to be a complete system, it ought to contain likewise a complete analysis of the whole of human knowledge a priori. It is true that our critique must produce a complete list of all the fundamental con- cepts which constitute pure knowledge. But it need not give a detailed analysis of these concepts, nor a complete list of all derivative concepts. Such an analysis would be out of place, because it is not -beset with the [p. 14] doubts and difficulties which are inherent in synthesis, and which alone necessitate a critique of pure reason. Nor would it answer our purpose to take the responsi- bility of the completeness of such an analysis and deriva- tion. This completeness of analysis, however, and of derivation from such a priori concepts as we shall have to deal with presently, may easily be supplied, if only they have first been laid down as perfect principles of synthesis, and nothing is wanting to them in that respect. All that constitutes transcendental philosophy belongs to the critique of pure reason, nay it is the complete idea of transcendental philosophy, but not yet the whole of that philosophy itself, because it carries the analysis so far only as is requisite for a complete examination of synthetical knowledge a priori. The most important consideration in the arrangement of such a science is that no concepts should be admitted 1 Addition in the Second Edition. 1 2 Introduction which contain anything empirical, and that the a priori knowledge shall be perfectly pure. Therefore, although the highest principles of morality and their fundamental concepts are a priori knowledge, they do not [p. 15] belong to transcendental philosophy, because the con- cepts of pleasure and pain, desire, inclination, free-will, etc., which are all of empirical origin, must here be pre- supposed. Transcendental philosophy is the wisdom of pure speculative reason. Everything practical, so far as it contains motives, has reference to sentiments, and these belong to empirical sources of knowledge. If we wish to carry out a proper division of our science systematically, it must contain first a doctrine of the ele- ments, secondly, a doctrine of the method of pure reason. Each of these principal divisions will have its subdivisions, the grounds of which cannot however be explained here. So much only seems necessary for previous information, that there are two stems of human knowledge, which per- haps may spring from a common root, unknown to us, viz. sensibility and the understanding, objects being given by the former and thought by the latter. If our sensibility should contain a priori representations, constituting con- ditions under which alone objects can be given, it would belong to transcendental philosophy, and the doctrine of this transcendental sense-perception would neces- [p. 16] sarily form the first part of the doctrine of elements, be- cause the conditions under which alone objects of human knowledge can be given must precede those under which they are thought. CRITIQUE OF PURE REASON THE ELEMENTS OF TRANSCENDENTALISM THE ELEMENTS OF TRANSCENDENTALISM [p- 19] FIRST PART TRANSCENDENTAL .ESTHETIC Whatever the process and the means may be by which knowledge reaches its objects, there is one that reaches them directly, and forms the ultimate material of all thought, viz. intuition (Anschauung). This is pos- sible only when the object is given, and the object can be given only (to human beings at least) through a cer- tain affection of the mind (Gemiith). This faculty (receptivity) of receiving representations (Vorstellungen), according to the manner in which we are affected by objects, is called sensibility (Sinnlichkeit). Objects therefore are given to us through our sensi- bility. Sensibility alone supplies us with intuitions (An- schauungen). These intuitions become thought through the understanding (Verstand), and hence arise conceptions (Begriffe). All thought therefore must, directly or indi- rectly, go back to intuitions (Anschauungen), i.e. to our sensibility, because in no other way can objects be given to us. 15 1 6 Transcendental ALsthctic The effect produced by an object upon the faculty of representation (Vorstellungsfahigkeit), so far as we [p. 20] are affected by it, is called sensation (Empfindung). An intuition (Anschauung) of an object, by means of sensa- tion, is called empirical. The undefined object of such an empirical intuition is called phenomenon (Erscheinung). In a phenomenon I call that which corresponds to the sensation its matter; but that which causes the manifold matter of the phenomenon to be perceived as arranged in a certain order, I call its form. Now it is clear that it cannot be sensation again through which sensations arc arranged and placed in certain forms. The matter only of all phenomena is given us a posteriori ; but their form must be ready for them in the mind (Gemtith) a priori, and must therefore be capable of being considered as separate from all sen- sations. I call all representations in which there is nothing that belongs to sensation, pure (in a transcendental sense). The pure form therefore of all sensuous intuitions, that form in which the manifold elements of the phenomena are seen in a certain order, must be found in the mind a priori. And this pure form of sensibility may be called the pure intuition (Anschauung). Thus, if we deduct from the representation (Vorstel- lung) of a body what belongs to the thinking of the understanding, viz. substance, force, divisibility, etc., and likewise what belongs to sensation, viz. impermeability, hardness, colour, etc., there still remains some- [p. 21] thing of that empirical intuition (Anschauung), viz. exten- sion and form. These belong to pure intuition, which a priori, and even without a real object of the senses or of Transcendental ^Esthetic ly sensation, exists in the mind as a mere form of sensi- bility. The science of all the principles of sensibility a priori I call Transcendental ^Esthetic. 1 There must be such a science, forming the first part of the Elements of Transcendentalism, as opposed to that which treats of the principles of pure thought, and which should be called Transcendental Logic. In Transcendental ^Esthetic therefore we shall [p. 22] first isolate sensibility, by separating everything which the understanding adds by means of its concepts, so that nothing remains but empirical intuition (Anschauung). Secondly, we shall separate from this all that belongs to sensation (Empfindung), so that nothing remains but pure intuition (reine Anschauung) or the mere form of the phenomena, which is the only thing which sensibility a priori can supply. In the course of this investigation it will appear that there are, as principles of a priori know- ledge, two pure forms of sensuous intuition (Anschauung), namely, Space and Time. We now proceed to consider these more in detail. 1 The Germans are the only people who at present (i 781) use the word cesthetic for what others call criticism of taste. There is implied in that name a false hope, first conceived by the excellent analytical philosopher, Baum- garten, of bringing the critical judgment of the beautiful under rational prin- ciples, and to raise its rules to the rank of a science. But such endeavours are vain. For such rules or criteria are, according to their principal sources, empirical only, and can never serve as definite a priori rules for our judgment in matters of taste; on the contrary, our judgment is the real test of the truth of such rules. It would be advisable therefore to drop the name in that sense, and to apply it to a doctrine which is a real science, thus approaching more nearly to the language and meaning of the ancients with whom the division into aiad-qTa /ecu vorfrd was very famous (or to share that name in common with speculative philosophy, and thus to use aesthetic sometimes in a transcen- dental, sometimes in a psychological sense). C 1 8 Of Space First Section of the Transcendental ^Esthetic Of Space By means of our external sense, a property of our mind (Gemiith), we represent to ourselves objects as external or outside ourselves, and all of these in space. It is within space that their form, size, and relative position are fixed or can be fixed. The internal sense by means of which the mind perceives itself or its internal state, does not give an intuition (Anschauung) of the soul (Seele) itself, as an object, but it is nevertheless a fixed form under which alone an intuition of its interrial state is [p. 23] possible, so that whatever belongs to its internal determi- nations (Bestimmungen) must be represented in relations of time. Time cannot be perceived (angeschaut) externally, as little as space can be perceived as something within us. What then are space and time ? Are they real beings ? Or, if not that, are they determinations or relations of things, but such as would belong to them even if they were not perceived? Or lastly, are they determinations and relations which are inherent in the form of intuition only, and therefore in the subjective nature of our mind, without which such predicates as space and time would never be ascribed to anything? In order to understand this more clearly, let us first con- sider space. 1. Space is not an empirical concept which has been derived from external experience. For in order that cer- tain sensations should be referred to something outside myself, i.e. to something in a different part of space from that where I am ; again, in order that I may be able to Of Space 19 represent- them (vorstellen) as side by side, that is, not only as different, but as in different places, the representa- tion (Vorstellung) of space must already be there. There- fore the representation of space cannot be borrowed through experience from relations of external phenomena, but, on the contrary, this external experience becomes possible only by means of the representation of space. 2. Space is a necessary representation a priori, form- ing the very foundation of all external intuitions, [p. 24] It is impossible to imagine that there should be no space, though one might very well imagine that there should be space without objects to fill it. Space is therefore regarded as a condition of the possibility of phenomena, not as a determination produced by them ; it is a repre- sentation a priori which necessarily precedes all external phenomena. [3. On this necessity of an a priori representation of space rests the apodictic certainty of all geometrical prin- ciples, and the possibility of their construction a priori. For if the intuition of space were a concept gained a posteriori, borrowed from general external experience, the first principles of mathematical definition would be noth- ing but perceptions. They would be exposed to all the accidents of perception, and there being but one straight line between two points would not be a necessity, but only something taught in each case by experience. What- ever is derived from experience possesses a relative generality only, based on induction. We should there- fore not be able to say more than that, so far as hitherto observed, no space has yet been found having more than three dimensions.] 4. Space is not a discursive or so-called general [p. 25] 20 Of Space concept of the relations of things in general, but a pure intuition. For, first of all, we can imagine one space only, and if we speak of many spaces, we mean parts only of one and the same space. Nor can these parts be considered as antecedent to the one and all-embracing space and, as it were, its component parts out of which an aggregate is formed, but they can be thought of as existing within it only. Space is essentially one ; its multiplicity, and therefore the general concept of spaces in general, arises entirely from limitations. Hence it follows that, with respect to space, an intuition a priori, which is not empirical, must form the foundation of all conceptions of space. In the same manner all geomet- rical principles, e.g. 'that in every triangle two sides together are greater than the third,' are never to be derived from the general concepts of side and triangle, but from an intuition, and that a priori, with apodictic certainty. [5. Space is represented as an infinite quantity. Now a general concept of space, which is found in a foot as well as in an ell, could tell us nothing in respect to the quantity of the space. If there were not infinity in the progression of intuition, no concept of relations of space could ever contain a principle of infinity. 1 ] Conclusions from the Foregoing Concepts [p. 26] a. Space does not represent any quality of objects by themselves, or objects in their relation to one another; i.e. space does not represent any determination which is inherent in the objects themselves, and would remain, 1 No. 5 (No. 4) is differently worded in the Second Edition; see Supple- ment VIII. Of Space 21 even if all subjective conditions of intuition were removed. For no determinations of objects, whether belonging to them absolutely or in relation to others, can enter into our intuition before the actual existence of the objects them- selves, that is to say, they can never be intuitions a priori. b. Space is nothing but the form of all phenomena of the external senses; it is the subjective condition of our sensibility, without which no external intuition is possible for us. If then we consider that the receptivity of the subject, its capacity of being affected by objects, must necessarily precede all intuition of objects, we shall under- stand how the form of all phenomena may be given before all real perceptions, may be, in fact, a priori in the soul, and may, as a pure intuition, by which all objects must be determined, contain, prior to all experience, principles regulating their relations. It is therefore from the human standpoint only that we can speak of space, extended objects, etc. If we drop the subjective condition under which alone we can gain external intuition, that is, so far as we ourselves may be affected by objects, the representation of space means nothing. For this predicate is applied to objects only in so far as they appear to us, and are objects of our [p. 27] senses. The constant form of this receptivity, which we call sensibility, is a necessary condition of all relations in which objects, as without us, can be perceived ; and, when abstraction is made of these objects, what remains is that pure intuition which we call space. As the peculiar con- ditions of our sensibility cannot be looked upon as condi- tions of the possibility of the objects themselves, but only of their appearance as phenomena to us, we may say indeed that space comprehends all things which may 22 Of Space appear to us externally, but not all things by themselves, whether perceived by us or not, or by any subject what- soever. We cannot judge whether the intuitions of other thinking beings are subject to the same conditions which determine our intuition, and which for us are generally binding. If we add the limitation of a judgment to a subjective concept, the judgment gains absolute validity. The proposition 'all things are beside each other in space,' is valid only under the limitation that things are taken as objects of our sensuous intuition (Anschauung). If I add that limitation to the concept and say 'all things, as exter- nal phenomena, are beside each other in space,' the rule obtains universal and unlimited validity. Our discussions teach therefore the reality, i.e. the objective validity, of space with regard to all that can come to us exter- [p. 28] nally as an object, but likewise the ideality of space with regard to things, when they are considered in themselves by our reason, and independent of the nature of our senses. We maintain the empirical reality of space, so far as every possible external experience is concerned, but at the same time its transcendental ideality ; that is to say, we maintain that space is nothing, if we leave out of consideration the condition of a possible experience, and accept it as something on which things by themselves are in any way dependent. With the exception of space there is no other subjective representation (Vorstelluhg) referring to something exter- nal, that would be called a priori objective. [This J sub- jective condition of all external phenomena cannot there- fore be compared to any other. The taste of wine does 1 This passage to ' my object in what I have said ' is differently worded in the Second Edition; see Supplement IX. Of Space 23 not belong to the objective determinations of wine, con- sidered as an object, even as a phenomenal object, but to the peculiar nature of the sense belonging to the subject that tastes the wine. Colours are not qualities of a body, though inherent in its intuition, but they are likewise mod- ifications only of the sense of sight, as it is affected in dif- ferent ways by light. Space, on the contrary, as the very condition of external objects, is essential to their appear- ance or intuition. Taste and colour are by no means necessary conditions under which alone things [p. 29] can become to us objects of sensuous perception. They are connected with their appearance, as accidentally added effects only of our peculiar organisation. They are not therefore representations a priori, but are dependent on sensation (Empfindung), nay taste even on an affection (Gefiihl) of pleasure and pain, which is the result of a sensation. No one can have a priori, an idea (Vorstellung) either of colour or of taste, but space refers to the pure form of intuition only, and involves no kind of sensation, nothing empirical ; nay all kinds and determinations of space can and must be represented a priori, if concepts of forms and their relations are to arise. Through it alone is it possible that things should become external objects to us.] My object in what I have said just now is only to pre- vent people from imagining that they can elucidate the ideality of space by illustrations which are altogether insufficient, such as colour, taste, etc., which should never be considered as qualities of things, but as modifications of the subject, and which therefore may be different with different people. For in this case that which originally is itself a phenomenon only, as for instance, a rose, is taken 24 Of Time by the empirical understanding for a thing by itself, which nevertheless, with regard to colour, may appear [p. 30] different to every eye. The transcendental conception, on the contrary, of all phenomena in space, is a critical warn- ing that nothing which is seen in space is a thing by itself, nor space a form of things supposed to belong to them by themselves, but that objects by themselves are not known to us at all, and that what we call external objects are nothing but representations of our senses, the form of which is space, and the true correlative of which, that is the thing by itself, is not known, nor can be known by these representations, nor do we care to know anything about it in our daily experience. Second Section of the Transcendental vEsthetic Of Time I. Time is not an empirical concept deduced from any experience, for neither coexistence nor succession would enter into our perception, if the representation of time were not given a priori. Only when this representation a priori is given, can we imagine that certain things happen at the same time (simultaneously) or at different times (successively). [p. 31] II. Time is a necessary representation on which all intuitions depend. We cannot take away time from phenomena in general, though we can well take away phenomena out of time. Time therefore is given a priori. In time alone is reality, of phenomena possible. All 1 In the Second Edition the title is, Metaphysical exposition of the concept of time, with reference to par. 5, Transcendental exposition of the concept of time. Of Time 25 phenomena may vanish, but time itself (as the general condition of their possibility) cannot be done away with. III. On this a priori necessity depends also the possi- bility of apodictic principles of the relations of time, or of axioms of time in general. 'Time has one dimension only ; different times are not simultaneous, but successive, while different spaces are never successive, but simultaneous. Such principles cannot be derived from experience, because experience could not impart to them absolute universality nor apodictic certainty. We should only be able to say that common experience teaches us that it is so, but not that it must be so. These principles are valid as rules under which alone experience is possible ; they teach us before experience, not by means of experience. 1 IV. Time is not a discursive, or what is called a general concept, but a pure form of sensuous intuition. Different times are parts only of one and the same time. Repre- sentation, which can be produced by a single [p. 32] object only, is called an intuition. The proposition that different times cannot exist at the same time cannot be deduced from any general concept. Such a proposition is synthetical, and cannot be deduced from concepts only. It is contained immediately in the intuition and representa- tion of time. V. To say that time is infinite means no more than that every definite quantity of time is possible only by limita- tions of one time which forms the foundation of all times. The original representation of time must therefore be 1 I retain the reading of the First Edition, vor derselben, nicht durch dieselbe. Von denselben, the reading of later editions, is wrong; the emendation of Rosenkranz, vor denselben, nicht durch dieselben, unnecessary. The Second Edition has likewise vor derselben. 26 Of Time given as unlimited. But when the parts themselves and every quantity of an object can be represented as deter- mined by limitation only, the whole representation cannot be given by concepts (for in that case the partial repre- sentations come first), but it must be founded on immediate intuition. 1 Conclusions from the foregoing concepts a. Time is not something existing by itself, or inherent in things as an objective determination of them, something therefore that might remain when abstraction is made of all subjective conditions of intuition. For in the former case it would be something real, without being a real object. In the latter it could not, as a deter- [p. 33] mination or order inherent in things themselves, be antece- dent to things as their condition, and be known and per- ceived by means of synthetical propositions a priori. All this is perfectly possible if time is nothing but a subjec- tive condition under which alone 2 intuitions take place within us. For in that case this form of internal intui- tion can be represented prior to the objects themselves, that is, a priori. b. Time is nothing but the form of the internal sense, that is, of our intuition of ourselves, and of our internal state. Time cannot be a determination peculiar to exter- nal phenomena. It refers neither to their shape, nor their position, etc., it only determines the relation of rep- resentations in our internal state. And exactly because this internal intuition supplies no shape, we try to make good this deficiency by means of analogies, and represent 1 Here follows in the Second Edition, Supplement X. 2 Read allein instead of alle. Of Time 27 to ourselves the succession of time by a line progressing to infinity, in which the manifold constitutes a series of one dimension only; and we conclude from the properties of this line as to all the properties of time, with one excep- tion, i.e. that the parts of the former are simultaneous, those of the latter successive. From this it becomes clear also, that the representation of time is itself an intuition, because all its relations can be expressed by means of an external intuition. c. Time is the formal condition, a priori, of all phenom- ena whatsoever. Space, as the pure form of all [p. 34] external intuition, is a condition, a priori, of external phe- nomena only. But, as all representations, whether they have for their objects external things or not, belong by themselves, as determinations of the mind, to our inner state, and as this inner state falls under the formal con- ditions of internal intuition, and therefore of time, time is a condition, a priori, of all phenomena whatsoever, and is so directly as a condition of internal phenomena (of our mind) and thereby indirectly of external phenom- ena also. If I am able to say, a priori, that all external phenomena are in space, and are determined, a priori, according to the relations of space, I can, according to the principle of the internal sense, make the general assertion that all phenomena, that is, all objects of the senses, are in time, and stand necessarily in relations of time. If we drop our manner of looking at ourselves inter- nally, and of comprehending by means of that intuition all external intuitions also within our power of represen- tation, and thus take objects as they may be by them- selves, then time is nothing. Time has objective validity 28 Of Time with reference to phenomena only, because these are themselves things which we accept as objects of our senses; but time is no longer objective, if we [p. 35] remove the sensuous character of our intuitions, that is to say, that mode of representation which is peculiar to ourselves, and speak of things in general. Time is there- fore simply a subjective condition of our (human) intui- tion (which is always sensuous, that is so far as we are affected by objects), but by itself, apart from the subject, nothing. Nevertheless, with respect to all phenomena, that is, all things which can come within our experience, time is necessarily objective. We cannot say that all things are in time, because, if we speak of things in gen- eral, nothing is said about the manner of intuition, which is the real condition under which time enters into our rep- resentation of things. If therefore this condition is added to the concept, and if we say that all things as phenomena (as objects of sensuous intuition) are in time, then such a proposition has its full objective validity and a priori universality. What we insist on therefore is the empirical reality of time, that is, its objective validity, with reference to all objects which can ever come before our senses. And as our intuition must at all times be sensuous, no object can ever fall under our experience that does not come under the conditions of time. What we deny is, that time has any claim on absolute reality, so that, without [p. 36] taking into account the form of our sensuous condition, it should by itself be a condition or quality inherent in things ; for such qualities which belong to things by themselves can never be given to us through the senses. This is what constitutes the transcendental ideality of Of Time 29 time, so that, if we take no account of the subjective con- ditions of our sensuous intuitions, time is nothing, and can- not be added to the objects by themselves (without their relation to our intuition) whether as subsisting or inherent. This ideality of time, however, as well as that of space, should not be confounded with the deceptions of our sen- sations, because in their case we always suppose that the phenomenon to which such predicates belong has objective reality, which is not at all the case here, except so far as this objective reality is purely empirical, that is, so far as the object itself is looked upon as a mere phenomenon. On this subject see a previous note, in section i, on Space. Explanation Against this theory which claims empirical, but denies absolute and transcendental reality to time, even intelli- gent men have protested so unanimously, that I suppose that every reader who is unaccustomed to these consider- ations may naturally be of the same opinion. What they object to is this : Changes, they say, are real (this is proved by the change of our own representations, even [p. 37] if all external phenomena and their changes be denied). Changes, however, are possible in time only, and there- fore time must be something real. The answer is easy enough. I grant the whole argument. Time certainly is something real, namely, the real form of our internal intuition. Time therefore has subjective reality with regard to internal experience : that is, I really have the representation of time and of my determinations in it. Time therefore is to be considered as real, not so far as it is an object, but so far as it is the representation of myself as an object. If either I myself or any other being could 30 Of Time see me without this condition of sensibility, then these self-same determinations which we now represent to our- selves as changes, would give us a kind of knowledge in which the representation of time, and therefore of change also, would have no place. There remains therefore the empirical reality of time only, as the condition of all our experience, while absolute reality cannot, according to what has just been shown, be conceded to it. Time is nothing but the form of our own internal intuition. 1 Take away the peculiar condition of our sensibility, and the idea of time vanishes, because it is not inherent in the ob- jects, but in the subject only that perceives them. [p. 38] The reason why this objection is raised so unanimously, and even by those who have nothing very tangible to say against the doctrine of the ideality of space, is this. They could never hope to prove apodictically the absolute real- ity of space, because they are confronted by idealism, which has shown that the reality of external objects does not admit of strict proof, while the reality of the object of our internal perceptions (the perception of my own self and of my own status) is clear immediately through our consciousness. The former might be merely phenomenal, but the latter, according to their opinion, is undeniably something real. They did not see that both, without denying to them their reality as representations, belong nevertheless to the phenomenon only, which must always have two sides, the one when the object is considered by itself (without regard to the manner in which it is per- 1 I can say indeed that my representations follow one another, but this means no more than that we are conscious of them as in a temporal succes- sion, that is, according to the form of our own internal sense. Time, therefore, is nothing by itself, nor is it a determination inherent objectively in things. Of Time 31 ceived, its quality therefore remaining always problemati- cal), the other, when the form of the perception of the object is taken into consideration ; this form belonging not to the object in itself, but to the subject which per- ceives it, though nevertheless belonging really and neces- sarily to the object as a phenomenon. Time and space are therefore two sources of knowledge from which various a priori synthetical cognitions [p. 39] can be derived. Of this pure mathematics give a splendid example in the case of our cognitions of space and its vari- ous relations. As they are both pure forms of sensuous intuition, they render synthetical propositions a priori pos- sible. But these sources of knowledge a priori (being con- ditions of our sensibility only) fix their own limits, in that they can refer to objects only in so far as they are consid- ered as phenomena, but cannot represent things as they are by themselves. That is the only field in which they are valid ; beyond it they admit of no objective applica- tion. This ideality of space and time, however, leaves the truthfulness of our experience quite untouched, because we are equally sure of it, whether these forms are inher- ent in things by themselves, or by necessity in our intui- tion of them only. Those, on the contrary, who maintain the absolute reality of space and time, whether as subsist- ing or only as inherent, must come into conflict with the principles of experience itself. For if they admit space and time as subsisting (which is generally the view of mathematical students of nature) they have to admit two eternal infinite and self-subsisting nonentities (space and time), which exist without their being anything real, only in order to comprehend all that is real. If they take the second view (held by some metaphysical students [p. 40] 32 Of Time of nature), and look upon space and time as relations of phe- nomena, simultaneous or successive, abstracted from expe- rience, though represented confusedly in their abstracted form, they are obliged to deny to mathematical proposi- tions a priori their validity with regard to real things (for instance in space), or at all events their apodictic cer- tainty, which cannot take place a posteriori, while the a priori conceptions of space and time are, according to their opinion, creations of our imagination only. Their source, they hold, must really be looked for in experience, imagination framing out of the relations abstracted from experience something which contains the general charac- ter of these relations, but which cannot exist without the restrictions which nature has imposed on them. The former gain so much that they keep at least the sphere of phenomena free for mathematical propositions ; but, as soon as the understanding endeavours to transcend that sphere, they become bewildered by these very conditions. The latter have this advantage that they are not bewil- dered by the representations of space and time when they wish to form judgments of objects, not as phenom- ena, but only as considered by the understanding; but they can neither account for the possibility of mathemati- cal knowledge a priori (there being, according to them, no true and objectively valid intuition a priori), nor can they bring the laws of experience into true harmony with the a priori doctrines of mathematics. According to our theory of the true character of these original [p. 41] forms of sensibility, both difficulties vanish. Lastly, that transcendental aesthetic cannot contain more than these two elements, namely, space and time, becomes clear from the fact that all other concepts belong- Of Time 33 ing to the senses, even that of motion, which combines both, presuppose something empirical. Motion presup- poses the perception of something moving. In space, however, considered by itself, there is nothing that moves. Hence that which moves must be something which, as in space, can be given by experience only, therefore an empir- ical datum. On the same ground, transcendental aesthetic cannot count the concept of change among its a priori data, because time itself does not change, but only some- thing which is in time. For this, the perception of some- thing existing and of the succession of its determinations, in other words, experience, is required. GENERAL OBSERVATIONS ON TRANSCEN- DENTAL ^ESTHETIC In order to avoid all misapprehensions it will be neces- sary, first of all, to declare, as clearly as possible, what is our view with regard to the fundamental nature of [p. 42] sensuous knowledge. What we meant to say was this, that all our intuition is nothing but the representation of phenomena ; that things which we see are not by themselves what we see, nor their relations by themselves such as they appear to us, so that, if we drop our subject or the subjective form of our senses, all qualities, all relations of objects in space and time, nay space and time themselves, would vanish. They cannot, as phenomena, exist by themselves, but in us only. It remains completely unknown to us what objects may be by themselves and apart from the recep- tivity of our senses. We know nothing but our manner of perceiving them, that manner being peculiar to us, and not necessarily shared in by every being, though, no doubt, by every human being. This is what alone concerns us. Space and time are pure forms of our intuition, while sensation forms its matter. What we can know a priori — before all real intuition, are the forms of space and time, which are therefore called pure intuition, while sensation is that which causes our knowledge to be called a poste- riori knowledge, i.e. empirical intuition. Whatever our sensation may be, these forms are necessarily inherent 34 Transcendental Aisthetic 35 in it, while sensations themselves may be of the most different character. Even if we could impart the [p. 43] highest degree of clearness to our intuition, we should not come one step nearer to the nature of objects by themselves. We should know our mode of intuition, i.e. our sensibility, more completely, but always under the indefeasible conditions of space and time. What the objects are by themselves would never become known to us, even through the clearest knowledge of that which alone is given us, the phenomenon. It would vitiate the concept of sensibility and phenom- ena, and render our whole doctrine useless and empty, if we were to accept the view (of Leibniz and Wolf), that our whole sensibility is really but a confused representa- tion of things, simply containing what belongs to them by themselves, though smothered under an accumulation of signs (Merkmal) and partial concepts, which we do not consciously disentangle. The distinction between con- fused and well-ordered representation is logical only, and does not touch the contents of our knowledge. Thus the concept of Right, as employed by people of common sense, contains neither more nor less than the subtlest specula- tion can draw out of it, only that in the ordinary practical use of the word we are not always conscious of the mani- fold ideas contained in that thought. But no one would say therefore that the ordinary concept of Right was sensuous, containing a mere phenomenon ; for Right can never become a phenomenon, being a concept of [p. 44] the understanding, and representing a moral quality be- longing to actions by themselves. The representation of a Body, on the contrary, contains nothing in intuition that could belong to an object by itself, but is merely 36 Transcendental ^Esthetic the phenomenal appearance of something, and the man- ner in which we are affected by it. This receptivity of our knowledge is called sensibility. Even if we could see to the very bottom of a phenomenon, it would remain for ever altogether different from the knowledge of the thing by itself. This shows that the philosophy of Leibniz and Wolf has given a totally wrong direction to all investigations into the nature and origin of our knowledge, by repre- senting the difference between the sensible and the intel- ligible as logical only. That difference is in truth tran- scendental. It affects not the form only, as being more or less confused, but the origin and contents of our knowledge; so that by our sensibility we know the nat- ure of things by themselves not confusedly only, but not at all. If we drop our subjective condition, the object, as represented with its qualities bestowed on it by sensuous intuition, is nowhere to be found, and cannot possibly be found ; because its form, as phenomenal appearance, is determined by those very subjective conditions. It has been the custom to distinguish in phe- [p. 45] nomena that which is essentially inherent in their intuition and is recognised by every human being, from that which belongs to their intuition accidentally only, being valid not for sensibility in general, but only for a particular position and organisation of this or that sense. In that case the former kind of knowledge is said to represent the object by itself, the latter its appearance only. But that distinction is merely empirical. If, as generally hap- pens, people are satisfied with that distinction, without again, as they ought, treating the first empirical intuition as purely phenomenal also, in which nothing can be found Transcendental ^Esthetic 37 belonging to the thing by itself, our transcendental dis- tinction is lost, and we believe that we know things by themselves, though in the world. of sense, however far we may carry our investigation, we can never have anything before us but mere phenomena. To give an illustration. People might call the rainbow a mere phenomenal appear- ance during a sunny shower, but the rain itself the thing by itself. This would be quite right, physically speaking, and taking rain as something which, in our ordinary experience and under all possible relations to our senses, can be determined thus and thus only in our intuition. But if we take the empirical in general, and ask, [p. 46] without caring whether it is the same with every particu- lar observer, whether it represents a thing by itself (not the drops of rain, for these are already, as phenomena, empirical objects), then the question as to the relation between the representation and the object becomes tran- scendental, and not only the drops are mere phenomena, but even their round shape, nay even the space in which they fall, are nothing by themselves, but only modifica- tions or fundamental dispositions of our sensuous intuition, the transcendental object remaining unknown to us. The second important point in our transcendental aes- thetic is, that it should not only gain favour as a plausible hypothesis, but assume as certain and undoubted a charac- ter as can be demanded of any theory which is to serve as an organum. In order to make this certainty self- evident we shall select a case which will make its validity palpable. Let us suppose that space and time are in themselves objective, and conditions of the possibility of things by themselves. Now there is with' regard to both a large 38 Transcendental Aisthetic number of a priori apodictic and synthetical propositions, and particularly with regard to space, which for this rea- son we shall chiefly investigate here as an illustration. As the propositions of geometry are known synthetically a priori, and with apodictic certainty, I ask, whence do you take such propositions ? and what does the [p. 47] understanding rely on in order to arrive at such absolutely necessary and universally valid truths ? There is no other way but by concepts and intuitions, and both as given either a priori or a posteriori. The latter, namely em- pirical concepts, as well as the empirical intuition on which they are founded, cannot yield any synthetical propositions except such as are themselves also empirical only, that is, empirical propositions, which can never possess that necessity and absolute universality which are characteristic of all geometrical propositions. As to the other and only means of arriving at such knowledge through mere concepts or intuitions a priori, it must be clear that only analytical, but no synthetical knowledge can ever be derived from mere concepts. Take the proposition that two straight lines cannot enclose a space and cannot therefore form a figure, and try to deduce it from the concept of straight lines and the number two ; or take the proposition that with three straight lines it is possible to form a figure, and try to deduce that from those concepts. All your labour will be lost, and in the end you will be obliged to have recourse to intuition, as is always done in geometry. You then give yourselves an object in intuition. But of what kind is it? [p. 48] Is it a pure intuition a priori or an empirical one ? In the latter case, you. would never arrive at a universally valid, still less at an apodictic proposition, because ex- Transcendental ALsthetic 39 perience can never yield such. You must therefore take the object as given a priori in intuition, and found your synthetical proposition on that. If you did not possess in yourselves the power of a priori intuition, if that subjective condition were not at the same time, as to the form, the general condition a prioi-i under which alone the object of that (external) intuition becomes possible, if, in fact, the object (the triangle) were something by itself without any reference to you as the subject, how could you say that what exists necessarily in your subjective conditions of constructing a triangle, belongs of necessity to the triangle itself ? For you could not add something entirely new (the figure) to your concepts of three lines, something which should of necessity belong to the object, as that object is given before your knowledge of it, and not by it. If therefore space, and time also, were not pure forms of your intuition, which contains the a priori conditions under which alone things can become external objects to you, while, without that subjective condition, they are nothing, you could not predicate anything of external objects a priori and synthetically. It is there- fore beyond the reach of doubt, and not possible [p. 49] only or probable, that space and time, as the necessary conditions of all experience, external and internal, are purely subjective conditions of our intuition, and that, with reference to them, all things are phenomena only, and not things thus existing by themselves in such or such wise. Hence, so far as their form is concerned, much may be predicated of them a priori, but nothing whatever of the things by themselves on which these phenomena may be grounded. 1 1 Here follows in the Second Edition, Supplement XL THE ELEMENTS OE TRANSCENDENTALISM [p. 50] SECOND PART TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC INTRODUCTION THE IDEA OF A TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC I Of Logic in General Our knowledge springs from two fundamental sources of our soul ; the first receives representations (receptivity of impressions), the second is the power of knowing an object by these representations (spontaneity of concepts). By the first an object is given us, by the second the object is though^ in relation to that representation which is a mere determination of the soul. Intuition therefore and concepts constitute the elements of all our knowledge, so that neither concepts without an intuition correspond- ing to them, nor intuition without concepts can yield any real knowledge. Both are either pure or empirical. They are empirical when sensation, presupposing the actual presence of the 40 Transcendental Logic 41 object, is contained in it. They are pure when no sensa- tion is mixed up with the representation. The latter may be called the material of sensuous knowledge. Pure intui- tion therefore contains the form only by which [p. 51] something is seen, and pure conception the form only by which an object is thought. Pure intuitions and pure concepts only are possible a priori, empirical intuitions and empirical concepts a posteriori. We call sensibility the receptivity of our soul, or its power of receiving representations whenever it is in any wise affected, while the understanding, on the contrary, is with us the power of producing representa- tions, or the spontaneity of knowledge. We are so con- stituted that our intuition must always be sensuous, and consist of the mode in which we are affected by objects. What enables us to think the objects of our sensuous intuition is the understanding. Neither of these qualities or faculties is preferable to the other. Without sensibility objects would not be given to us, without understanding they would not be thought by us. Thoughts without con- tents are empty, intuitions without concepts are blind. Therefore it is equally necessary to make our concepts sensuous, i.e. to add to them their object in intuition, as to make our intuitions intelligible, i.e. to bring them under concepts. These two powers or faculties cannot ex- change their functions. The understanding cannot see, the senses cannot think. By their union only can know- ledge be produced. But this is no reason for confounding the share which belongs to each in the production of knowledge. On the contrary, they should al- [p. 52] ways be carefully separated and distinguished, and we have therefore divided the science of the rules of sen- 42 Transcendental Logic sibility in general, i.e. aesthetic, from the science of the rules of the understanding in general, i.e. logic. Logic again can be taken in hand for two objects, either as logic of the general or of a particular use of the understanding. The former contains all necessary rules of thought without which the understanding cannot be used at all. It treats of the understanding without any regard to the different objects to which it may be directed. Logic of the particular use of the understanding contains rules how to think correctly on certain classes of objects. The former may be called Elementary Logic, the latter the Organum of this or that science. The latter is generally taught in the schools as a preparation for certain sciences, though, according to the real progress of the human understanding, it is the latest achievement, which does not become possible till the science itself is really made, and requires only a few touches for its correction and completion. For it is clear that the objects themselves must be very well known before it is possible to give rules according to which a science of them may be established. General logic is either pure or applied. In the [p. 53] former no account is taken of any empirical conditions under which our understanding acts, i.e. of the influence of the senses, the play of imagination, the laws of mem- ory, the force of habit, the inclinations, and therefore the sources of prejudice also, nor of anything which supplies or seems to supply particular kinds of knowledge ; for all this applies to the understanding under certain circum- stances of its application only, and requires experience as a condition of knowledge. General but pure logic has to deal with principles a priori only, and is a canon of the understanding and of reason, though with reference to its Transcendental Logic 43 formal application only, irrespective of any contents, whether empirical or transcendental. General logic is called applied, if it refers to the rules of the use of our understanding under the subjective empirical conditions laid down in psychology. It therefore contains empirical principles, yet it is general, because referring to the use of the understanding, whatever its objects may be. It is neither a canon of the understanding in general nor an organum of any particular science, but simply a cathar- ticon of the ordinary understanding. In general logic, therefore, that part which is to con- stitute the science of pure reason must be entirely sepa- rated from that which forms applied, but for all [p. 54] that still general logic. The former alone is a real science, though short and dry, as a practical exposition of an elementary science of the understanding ougfyt to be. In this logicians should never lose sight of two rules : — 1. As general logic it takes no account of the contents of the knowledge of the understanding nor of the differ- ence of its objects. It treats of nothing but the mere form of thought. 2. As pure logic it has nothing to do with empirical principles, and borrows nothing from psychology (as some have imagined) ; psychology, therefore, has no influence whatever on the canon of the understanding. It proceeds by way of demonstration, and everything in it must be completely a priori. What I call applied logic (contrary to common usage according to which it contains certain exercises on the rules of pure logic) is a representation of the understand- ing and of the rules according to which it is necessarily 44 Transcendental Logic applied in concreto> i.e. under the accidental conditions of the subject, which may hinder or help its application, and are all given empirically only. It treats of attention, its impediments and their consequences, the sources of error, the states of doubt, hesitation, and conviction, etc., and general and pure logic stands to it in [p. 55] the same relation as pure ethics, which treat only of the necessary moral laws of a free will, to applied ethics, which consider these laws as under the influence of sen- timents, inclinations, and passions to which all human beings are more or less subject. This can never con- stitute a true and demonstrated science, because, like applied logic, it depends on empirical and psychological principles. II Of Transcendental Logic General logic, as we saw, takes no account of the con- tents of knowledge, i.e. of any relation between it and its objects, and considers the logical form only in the relation of cognitions to each other, that is, it treats of the form of thought in general. But as we found, when treating of Transcendental /Esthetic, that there are pure as well as empirical intuitions, it is possible that a similar distinction might appear between pure and empirical thinking. In this case we should have a logic in which the contents of knowledge are not entirely ignored, for such a logic which should contain the rules of pure thought only, would exclude only all knowledge of a merely empirical character. It would also treat of the origin of our know- ledge of objects, so far as that origin cannot be attributed Transcendental Logic 45 to the objects, while general logic is not at all [p. 56] concerned with the origin of our knowledge, but only con- siders representations (whether existing originally a priori in ourselves or empirically given to us), according to the laws followed by the understanding, when thinking and treating them in their relation to each other. It is con- fined therefore to the form imparted by the understanding to the representations, whatever may be their origin. And here I make a remark which should never be lost sight of, as it extends its influence on all that follows. Not every kind of knowledge a priori should be called transcendental (i.e. occupied with the possibility or the use of knowledge a priori), but that only by which we know that and how certain representations (intuitional or con- ceptual) can be used or are possible a priori only. Neither space nor any a priori geometrical determination of it is a transcendental representation ; but that knowledge only is rightly called transcendental which teaches us that these representations cannot be of empirical origin, and how they can yet refer a priori to objects of experience. The application of space to objects in general would likewise be transcendental, but, if restricted to objects of sense, it is empirical. The distinction between transcen- [p. 57] dental and empirical belongs therefore to the critique of knowledge, and does not affect the relation of that know- ledge to its objects. On the supposition therefore that there may be con- cepts, having an a priori reference to objects, not as pure or sensuous intuitions, but as acts of pure thought, being concepts in fact, but neither of empirical nor aesthetic origin, we form by anticipation an idea of a science of that knowledge which belongs to the pure understanding 46 Transcendental Logic and reason, and by which we may think objects entirely a prion. Such a science, which has to determine the origin, the extent, and the objective validity of such knowledge, might be called Transcendental Logic, having to deal with the laws of the understanding and reason in so far only as they refer a priori to objects, and not, as general logic, in so far as they refer promiscuously to the empirical as well as to the pure knowledge of reason. Ill Of the Division of General Logic into Analytic and Dialectic What is truth ? is an old and famous question by which people thought they could drive logicians into a corner, and either make them take refuge in a mere circle, 1 or make them confess their ignorance and conse- [p. 58 ] quently the vanity of their whole art. The nominal defi- nition of truth, that it is the agreement of the cognition with its object, is granted. What is wanted is to know a general and safe criterion of the truth of any and every kind of knowledge. It is a great and necessary proof of wisdom and sagac- ity to know what questions may be reasonably asked. For if a question is absurd in itself and calls for an answer where there is no answer, it does not only throw disgrace on the questioner, but often tempts an uncautious listener into absurd answers, thus presenting, as the ancients said, the spectacle of one person milking a he-goat, and of another holding the sieve. If truth consists in the agreement of knowledge with 1 The First Edition has Diallele, the Second, Dialexe. Transceiidental Logic 47 its object, that object must thereby be distinguished from other objects; for knowledge is untrue if it does not agree with its object, though it contains something which may be affirmed of other objects. A general criterium of truth ought really to be valid with regard to every kind of knowledge, whatever the objects may be. But it is clear, as no account is thus taken of the contents of knowledge (relation to its object), while truth concerns these very contents, that it is impossible and absurd to ask [p. 59] for a sign of the truth of the contents of that knowledge, and that therefore a sufficient and at the same time general mark of truth cannot possibly be found. As we have before called the contents of knowledge its material, it will be right to say that of the truth of the knowledge, so far as its material is concerned, no general mark can be demanded, because it would be self-contradictory. But, when we speak of knowledge with reference to its form only, without taking account of its contents, it is equally clear that logic, as it propounds the general and necessary rules of the understanding, must furnish in these rules criteria of truth. For whatever contradicts those rules is false, because the understanding would thus contradict the general rules of thought, that is, itself. These criteria, however, refer only to the form of truth or of thought in general. They are quite correct so far, but they are not sufficient. For although our knowledge may be in accordance with logical rule, that is, may not contradict itself, it is quite possible that it may be in contradiction with its object. Therefore the purely logical criterium of truth, namely, the agreement of knowledge with the general and formal laws of the understanding and reason, is no doubt a conditio sine 48 Transcendental Logic qua non, or a negative condition of all truth, [p. 60] Hut logic can go no further, and it has no test for dis- covering error with regard to the contents, and not the form, of a proposition. General logic resolves the whole formal action of the understanding and reason into its elements, and exhibits them as principles for all Logical criticism of our know- ledge. This part of logic may therefore be called Ana- lytic, and is at least a negative test of truth, because all knowledge must first be examined and estimated, so far as its form is concerned, according to these rules, before it is itself tested according to its contents, in order to see whether it contains positive truth with regard to its object. But as the mere form of knowledge, however much it may be in agreement with logical laws, is far from being sufficient to establish the material or objec- tive truth of our knowledge, no one can venture with logic alone to judge of objects, or to make any assertion, without having first collected, apart from logic, trust- worthy information, in order afterwards to attempt its application and connection in a coherent whole accord- ing to logical laws, or, still better, merely to test it by them. However, there is something so tempting in this specious art of giving to all our knowledge the form of the understanding, though being utterly ignorant [p. 61] as to the contents thereof, that general logic, which is meant to be a mere canon of criticism, has been employed as if it were an organum, for the real production of at least the semblance of objective assertions, or, more truly, has been misemployed for that purpose. This general logic, which assumes the semblance of an organum, is called Dialectic. Transcendental Logic 49 Different as are the significations in which the ancients used this name of a science or art, it is easy to gather from its actual employment that with them it was nothing but a logic of semblance. It was a sophistic art of giving to one's ignorance, nay, to one's intentional casuistry, the outward appearance of truth, by imitating the accurate method which logic always requires, and by using its topic as a cloak for every empty assertion. Now it may be taken as a sure and very useful warning that general logic, if treated as an organum, is always an illusive logic, that is, dialectical. For as logic teaches nothing with regard to the contents of knowledge, but lays down the formal conditions only of an agreement with the under- standing, which, so far as the objects are concerned, are totally indifferent, any attempt at using it as an organum in order to extend and enlarge our knowledge, at least in appearance, can end in nothing but mere talk, [p. 62] by asserting with a certain plausibility anything one likes, or, if one likes, denying it. Such instruction is quite beneath the dignity of philos- ophy. Therefore the title of Dialectic has rather been added to logic, as a critique of dialectical semblance ; and it is in that sense that we also use it. IV Of the Division of Transcendental Logic into Transcen- dental Analytic and Dialectic In transcendental logic we isolate the understanding, as before in transcendental aesthetic the sensibility, and fix our attention on that part of thought only which has its origin entirely in the understanding. The application of 50 Transcendental Logic this pure knowledge has for its condition that objects are given in intuition, to which it can be applied, for without intuition all our knowledge would be without objects, and it would therefore remain entirely empty. That part of transcendental logic therefore which teaches the elements of the pure knowledge of the understanding, and the prin- ciples without which no object can be thought, is transcen- dental Analytic, and at the same time a logic of truth. No knowledge can contradict it without losing at the same time all contents, that is, all relation to any [p. 63] object, and therefore all truth. But as it is very tempt- ing to use this pure knowledge of the understanding and its principles by themselves, and even beyond the limits of all experience, which alone can supply the material or the objects to which those pure concepts of the understanding can be applied, the understanding runs the risk of making, through mere sophisms, a material use of the purely for- mal principles of the pure understanding, and thus of judging indiscriminately of objects which are not given to us, nay, perhaps can never be given. As it is properly meant to be a mere canon for criticising the empirical use of the understanding, it is a real abuse if it is allowed as an organum of its general and unlimited application, by our venturing, with the pure understanding alone, to judge synthetically of objects in general, or to affirm and decide anything about them. In this case the employment of the pure understanding would become dialectical. The second part of transcendental logic must therefore form a critique of that dialectical semblance, and is called transcendental Dialectic, not as an art of producing dog- matically such semblance (an art but too popular with many metaphysical jugglers), but as a critique of the Transcendental Logic 51 understanding and reason with regard to their hyper- physical employment, in order thus to lay bare the false semblance of its groundless pretensions, and to [p. 64] reduce its claims to discovery and expansion, which was to be achieved by means of transcendental principles only, to a mere critique, serving as a protection of the pure understanding against all sophistical illusions. 5- Transcendental Logic TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC FIRST Division Transcendental Analytic Transcendental Analytic consists in the dissection of all our knowledge a priori into the elements which constitute the knowledge of the pure understanding. Four points are here essential : first, that the concepts should he pure and not empirical ; secondly, that they should not belong- to intuition and sensibility, but to thought and understand- in- ; thirdly, that the concepts should be elementary and carefully distinguished from derivative or composite con- cepts; fourthly, that our tables should be complete and that they should cover the whole held of the pure under- standing. This completeness of a science cannot be confidently accepted on the strength of a mere estimate, or by means of repeated experiments only ; what is required for it is an idea of the totality of the a priori knowledge of the under- standing, and a classification of the concepts based [p. 65] upon it; in fact, a systematic treatment. Pure under- standing must be distinguished, not merely from all that is empirical, but even from all sensibility. It constitutes therefore a unity independent in itself, self-sufficient, and not to be increased by any additions from without. The sum of its knowledge must constitute a system, compre- Transcendental Logic 53 hended and determined by one idea, and its completeness and articulation must form the test of the correctness and genuineness of its component parts. This part of transcendental logic consists of two books, the one containing the concepts, the other the principles of pure understanding. TRANSCENDENTAL ANALYTIC BOOK I ANALYTIC OF CONC1 PTS By Analytic of concepts I do not understand their analysis, or the ordinary process in philosophical dis- quisitions of dissecting any given concepts according to their contents, and thus rendering them more distinct; but a hitherto seldom attempted dissection of the faculty of the understanding itself, with the sole object of dis- covering the possibility of concepts a priori, by looking for them nowhere but in the understanding itself [p. 66] as their birthplace, and analysing the pure use of the understanding. This is the proper task of a transcen- dental philosophy, all the rest is mere logical treatment of concepts. We shall therefore follow up the pure con- cepts to their first germs and beginnings in the human understanding, in which they lie prepared, till at last, on the occasion of experience, they become developed, and are represented by the same understanding in their full purity, freed from all inherent empirical conditions. 54 Transcendental Analytic 55 ANALYTIC OF CONCEPTS CHAPTER I METHOD OF DISCOVERING ALL PURE CONCEPTS OF THE UNDERSTANDING When we watch any faculty of knowledge, different concepts, characteristic of that faculty, manifest them- selves according to different circumstances, which, as the observation has been carried on for a longer or shorter time, or with more or less accuracy, may be gathered up into a more or less complete collection. Where this collection will be complete, it is impossible to say beforehand, when we follow this almost mechan- ical process. Concepts thus discovered fortuitously only, possess neither order nor systematic unity, but [p. 67^ are paired in the end according to similarities, and, accord- ing to their contents, arranged as more or less complex in various series, which are nothing less than systematical, though to a certain extent put together methodically. Transcendental philosophy has the advantage, but also the duty of discovering its concepts according to a fixed principle. As they spring pure and unmixed from the understanding as an absolute unity, they must be connected with each other, according to one concept or idea. This connection supplies us at the same time with a rule, according to which the place of each pure concept of the understanding and the systematical com- 56 Transcendental Analytic pleteness of all of them can be determined a priori, in- stead of being dependent on arbitrary choice or chance. TRANSCENDENTA] METHOD OF THE DISCOVERY OF ALL PURE CONCEPTS OF THE UNDER- STANDING Section I Of the Logical Use of the Understanding in General We have before defined the understanding negatively only, as a non-sensuous faculty of knowledge. As with- out sensibility we cannot have any intuition, [p. 68] it is clear that the understanding is not a faculty of intui- tion. Besides intuition, however, there is no other kind oi knowledge except by means of concepts. The know- ledge therefore of every understanding, or at least of the human understanding, must be by means of concepts, not intuitive, but discursive. All intuitions, being sen- suous, depend oil affections, concepts on functions. By this function I mean the unity of the act of arranging different representations under one common representa- tion. Concepts are based therefore on the spontaneity of thought, sensuous intuitions on the receptivity of impressions. The only use which the understanding can make of these concepts is to form judgments by them. As no representation, except the intuitional, refers imme- diately to an object, no concept is ever referred to an object immediately, but to some other representation of it, whether it be an intuition, or itself a concept. A judg- ment is therefore a mediate knowledge of an object, or a representation of a representation of it. In every judg- ment we find a concept applying to many, and compre- Transcendental Analytic 57 hending among the many one single representation, which is referred immediately to the object. Thus in the judg- ment that all bodies are divisible, 1 the concept of divisible applies to various other concepts, but is here applied in particular to the concept of body, and this concept of body to certain phenomena of our experience, [p. 69] These objects therefore are represented mediately by the concept of divisibility. All judgments therefore are functions of unity among our representations, the know- ledge of an object being brought about, not by an imme- diate representation, but by a higher one, comprehending this and several others, so that many possible cognitions are collected into one. As all acts of the understanding can be reduced to judgments, the understanding may be defined as the faculty of judging. For we saw before that the understanding is the faculty of thinking, and thinking is knowledge by means of concepts, while con- cepts, as predicates of possible judgments, refer to some representation of an object yet undetermined. Thus the concept of body means something, for instance, metal, which can be known by that concept. It is only a con- cept, because it comprehends other representations, by means of which it can be referred to objects. It is there- fore the predicate of a possible judgment, such as, that every metal is a body. Thus the functions of the under- standing can be discovered in their completeness, if it is possible to represent the functions of unity in judgments. That this is possible will be seen in the following section. 1 Ver'dnderlich in the First Edition is rightly corrected into theilbar in later editions, though in the Second it is still veranderlich. 5S Transcendental Analytic METHOD OF THE DISCOVERY OF ALL PURE CON- CEPTS OF THE UNDERSTANDING [p. 70] Section II Of the Logical Function of the Understanding in Judgments If we leave out of consideration the contents of any judgment and fix our attention on the mere form of the understanding, we find that the function of thought in a judgment can be brought under four heads, each of them with three subdivisions. They may be represented in the following table : — Quantity of Judgments Universal. Particular. II Singular. Ill Quality Relation Affirmative. Categorical. Negative. Hypothetical Infinite. IV Modality Problematical. Assertory. Apodictic. Disjunctive. As this classification may seem to differ in some, though not very essential points, from the usual technicalities of logicians, the following reservations against any [p. 71] possible misunderstanding will not be out of place. 1. Logicians are quite right in saying that in using judgments in syllogisms, singular judgments may be Transcendental Analytic 59 treated like universal ones. For as they have no extent at all, the predicate cannot refer to part only of that which is contained in the concept of the subject, and be excluded from the rest. The predicate is valid therefore of that concept, without any exception, as if it were a general concept, having an extent to the whole of which the predicate applies. But if we compare a singular with a general judgment, looking only at the quantity of know- ledge conveyed by it, the singular judgment stands to the universal judgment as unity to infinity, and is therefore essentially different from it. It is therefore, when we consider a singular judgment (Judicium singnlare), not only according to its own validity, but according to the quantity of knowledge which it conveys, as compared with other kinds of knowledge, that we see how different it is from general judgments {judicia communici), and how well it deserves a separate place in a complete table of the varieties of thought in general, though not in a logic limited to the use of judgments in reference to each other. 2. In like manner infinite judgments must, in tran- scendental logic, be distinguished from affirmative ones, though in general logic they are properly classed to- gether, and do not constitute a separate part in [p. 72] the classification. General logic takes no account of the contents of the predicate (though it be negative), it only asks whether the predicate be affirmed or denied. Tran- scendental logic, on the contrary, considers a judgment according to the value also or the contents of a logical affirmation by means of a purely negative predicate, and asks how much is gained by that affirmation, with refer- ence to the sum total of knowledge. If I had said of the soul, that it is not mortal, I should, by means of a nega- 60 Transcendental Analytic tive judgment, have at least warded off an error. Now it is true that, so far as the logical form is concerned, I have really affirmed by saying that the soul is non-mortal, because I thus place the soul in the unlimited sphere of non-mortal beings. As the mortal forms one part of the whole sphere of possible beings, the non-mortal the other, I have said no more by my proposition than that the soul is one of the infinite number of things which remain, when I take away all that is mortal. But by this the infinite sphere of all that is possible becomes limited only in so far that all that is mortal is excluded from it, and that afterwards the soul is placed in the remaining part of its original extent. This part, however, even after its limitation, still remains infinite, and several more parts of it may be taken away without extending thereby in the least the concept of the soul, or affirmatively de- [p. 73] termining it. These judgments, therefore, though infi- nite in respect to their logical extent, are, with respect to their contents, limitative only, and cannot therefore be passed over in a transcendental table of all varieties of thought in judgments, it being quite possible that the function of the understanding exercised in them may become of great importance in the field of its pure a priori knowledge. 3. The following are all the relations of thought in judgments : — a. Relation of the predicate to the subject. b. Relation of the cause to its effect. c. Relation of subdivided knowledge, and of the col- lected members of the subdivision to each other. In the first class of judgments we consider two con- cepts, in the second two judgments, in the third several Transcendental Analytic 61 judgments in their relation to each other. The hypo- thetical proposition, if perfect justice exists, the obsti- nately wicked is punished, contains really the relation of two propositions, namely, there is a perfect justice, and the obstinately wicked is punished. Whether both these propositions are true remains unsettled. It is only the consequence which is laid down by this judgment. The disjunctive judgment contains the relation of two or more propositions to each other, but not as a conse- quence, but in the form of a logical opposition, the sphere of the one excluding the sphere of the other, and at the same time in the form of community, all the propositions together filling the whole sphere of the intended know- ledge. The disjunctive judgment contains there- [p. 74] fore a relation of the parts of the whole sphere of a given knowledge, in which the sphere of each part forms the complement of the sphere of the other, all being con- tained within the whole sphere of the subdivided know- ledge. We may say, for instance, the world exists either by blind chance, or by internal necessity, or by an exter- nal cause. Each of these sentences occupies a part of the sphere of all possible knowledge with regard to the existence of the world, while all together occupy the whole sphere. To take away the knowledge from one of these spheres is the same as to place it into one of the other spheres, and to place it in one sphere is the same as to take it away from the others. There exists therefore in disjunctive judgments a certain community of the differ- ent divisions of knowledge, so that they mutually exclude each other, and yet thereby determine in their totality the true knowledge, because, if taken together, they constitute the whole contents of one given knowledge. This is all 62 Transcendental Analytic I have to observe here for the sake of what is to follow hereafter. 4. The modality of judgments is a very peculiar func- tion, for it contributes nothing to the contents of a judg- ment (because, besides quantity, quality, and relation, there is nothing else that could constitute the contents of a judgment), but refers only to the nature of the copula in relation to thought in general. Problematical judg- ments are those in which affirmation or negation are taken as possible (optional) only, while in assertory judg- •m'ents affirmation or negation is taken as real (true), in apodictic as necessary. 1 Thus the two judg- [p. 75] ments, the relation of which constitutes the hypothetical judgment (antecedens ct consequens) and likewise the judgments the reciprocal relation of which forms the dis- junctive judgment (members of subdivision), are always problematical only. In the example given above, the proposition, there exists a perfect justice, is not made as an assertory, but .only as an optional judgment, which may be accepted or not, the consequence only being assertory. It is clear therefore that some of these judg- ments may be wrong, and may yet, if taken problemati- cally, contain the conditions of the knowledge of truth. Thus, in our disjunctive judgment, one of its component judgments, namely, the world exists by blind chance, has a problematical meaning only, on the supposition that some one might for one moment take such a view, but serves, at the same time, like the indication of a false road among all the roads that might be taken, to find out the true one. 1 As if in the first, thought were a function of the understanding, in the second, of the faculty of judgment, in the third, of reason; a remark which will receive its elucidation in the sequel. Transcendental Analytic 63 The problematical proposition is therefore that which ex- presses logical (not objective) possibility only, that is, a free choice of admitting such a proposition, and a purely optional admission of it into the understanding. The assertory proposition implies logical reality or truth. Thus, for instance, in a hypothetical syllogism the ante- cedcns in the major is problematical, in the [p. 76] minor assertory, showing that the proposition conforms to the understanding according to its laws. The apo- dictic proposition represents the assertory as determined by these very laws of the understanding, and therefore as asserting a priori, and thus expresses logical necessity. As in this way everything is arranged step by step in the understanding, inasmuch as we begin with judging prob- lematically, .then proceed to an assertory acceptation, and finally maintain our proposition as inseparably united with the understanding, that is as necessary and apodictic, we may be allowed to call these three functions of modality so many varieties or momenta of thought. METHOD OF THE DISCOVERY OF ALL PURE CON- CEPTS OF THE UNDERSTANDING Section III Of the Pure Concepts of the Understanding, or of the Categories General logic, as we have often said, takes no account of the contents of our knowledge, but expects that repre- sentations will come from elsewhere in order to be turned into concepts by an analytical process. Transcendental logic, on the contrary, has before it the manifold contents 64 Transcendental Analytic of sensibility a priori, supplied by transcendental [p. yy~\ aesthetic as the material for the concepts of the pure understanding, without which those concepts would be without any contents, therefore entirely empty. It is true that space and time contain what is manifold in the pure intuition a priori, but they belong also to the conditions of the receptivity of our mind under which alone it can receive representations of objects, and which therefore must affect the concepts of them also. The spontaneity of our thought requires that what is manifold in the pure intuition should first be in a certain way examined, received, and connected, in order to produce a knowledge of it. This act I call synthesis. In its most general sense, I understand by synthesis the act of arranging different representations together, and of comprehending what is manifold in them under one form of knowledge. Such a synthesis is pure, if the manifold is not given empirically, but a priori (as in time and space). Before we can proceed to an analysis of our representations, these must first be given, and, as far as their contents are concerned, no concepts can arise ana- lytically. Knowledge is first produced by the synthesis of what is manifold (whether given empirically or a priori). That knowledge may at first be crude and confused and in need of analysis, but it is synthesis which really collects the elements of knowledge, and unites them to a certain extent. It is therefore the first thing which we [p. 78^ have to consider, if we want to form an opinion on the first origin of our knowledge. We shall see hereafter that synthesis in general is the mere result of what I call the faculty of imagination, a blind but indispensable function of the soul, without Transcendental Analytic 65 which we should have no knowledge whatsoever, but of the existence of which we are scarcely conscious. But to reduce this synthesis to concepts is a function that belongs to the understanding, and by which the under- standing supplies us for the first time with knowledge properly so called. Pure synthesis in its most general meaning gives us the pure concept of the understanding. By this pure syn- thesis I mean that which rests on the foundation of what I call synthetical unity a priori. Thus our counting (as we best perceive when dealing with higher numbers) is a synthesis according to concepts, because resting on a common ground of unity, as for instance, the decade. The unity of the synthesis of the manifold becomes necessary under this concept. By means of analysis different representations are brought under one concept, a task treated of in general logic ; but how to bring, not the representations, but the pure synthesis of representations, under concepts, that is what transcendental logic means to teach. The first that must be given us a priori for the sake of knowledge of all objects, is the manifold in pure intuition. The second is, the synthesis of the manifold by means of [p. 79] imagination. But this does not yet produce true know- ledge. The concepts which impart unity to this pure synthesis and consist entirely in the representation of this necessary synthetical unity, add the third contribution towards the knowledge of an object, and rest on the understanding. The same function which imparts unity to various rep- resentations in one judgment imparts unity likewise to the mere synthesis of various representations in one intuition, V 66 Transce?idental Analytic which in a general way may be called the pure concept of the understanding. The same understanding, and by the same operations by which in concepts it achieves through analytical unity the logical form of a judgment, introduces also, through the synthetical unity of the mani- fold in intuition, a transcendental element into its repre- sentations. They are therefore called pure concepts of the understanding, and they refer a priori to objects, which would be quite impossible in general logic. In this manner there arise exactly so many pure con- cepts of the understanding which refer a priori to objects of intuition in general, as there were in our table logical functions in all possible judgments, because those func- tions completely exhaust the understanding, and compre- hend every one of its faculties. Borrowing a term of Aristotle, we shall call these concepts categories, [p. 80] our intention being originally the same as his, though widely diverging from it in its practical application. TABLE OF CATEGORIES Of Quantity Unity. Plurality. Totality. II Ill Of Quality Of Relation Reality. Of Inherence and Subsistence Negation. {substantia et accidens). Limitation. Of Causality and Dependence (cause and effect). Of Community (reciprocity be- tween the active and the passive). Trcuiscendental A?ia lytic 67 IV Of Modality Possibility. Impossibility. Existence. Non-existence. Necessity. Contingency. This then is a list of all original pure concepts of syn- thesis, which belong to the understanding a priori, and for which alone it is called pure understanding ; for it is by them alone that it can understand something in the manifold of intuition, that is, think an object in it. The classification is systematical, and founded on a common principle, namely, the faculty of judging (which is the same as the faculty of thinking). It is not the [p. 81] result of a search after pure concepts undertaken at hap- hazard, the completeness of which, as based on induc- tion only, could never be guaranteed. Nor could we otherwise understand why these concepts only, and no others, abide in the pure understanding. It was an enter- prise worthy of an acute thinker like Aristotle to try to discover these fundamental concepts ; but as he had no guiding principle he merely picked them up as they occurred to him, and at first gathered up ten of them, which he called categories or predicaments. Afterwards he thought he had discovered five more of them, which he added under the name of post-predicaments. But his table remained imperfect for all that, not to mention that we find in it some modes of pure sensibility (auando, nbi, situs, also prius, simul), also an empirical concept (motns), none of which can belong to this genealogical register of the understanding. Besides, there are some derivative concepts, counted among the fundamental concepts (actio, passio), while some of the latter are entirely wanting. 68 Transcendental Analytic With regard to these, it should be remarked that the categories, as the true fundamental concepts of the pure understanding, have also their pure derivative concepts. These could not be passed over in a complete system of transcendental philosophy, but in a merely critical [p. 82] essay the mention of the fact may suffice. I should like to be allowed to call these pure but deriva- tive concepts of the understanding the prcdicabilia, in opposition to the predicamenta of the pure understanding. If we are once in possession of the fundamental and primitive concepts, it is easy to add the derivative and secondary, and thus to give a complete image of the genealogical tree of the pure understanding. As at pres- ent I am concerned not with the completeness, but only with the principles of a system, I leave this supplemen- tary work for a future occasion. In order to carry it out, one need only consult any of the ontological manuals, and place, for instance, under the category of causality the/r^- dicabilia of force, of action, and of passion ; under the category of community the predicabilia of presence and resistance ; under the predicaments of modality the pre- dicabilia of origin, extinction, change, etc. If we asso- ciate the categories among themselves or with the modes of pure sensibility, they yield us a large number of de- rivative concepts a priori, which it would be useful and interesting to mark and, if possible, to bring to a certain completeness, though this is not essential for our present purpose. I intentionally omit here the definitions of these cate- gories, though I may be in possession of them. 1 In the 1 See, however, Karl's remarks on p. 210 (p. 241 of First Edition). Transcendental Analytic 69 sequel I shall dissect these concepts so far as is [p. 83] sufficient for the purpose of the method which I am pre- paring. In a complete system of pure reason they might be justly demanded, but at present they would only make us lose sight of the principal object of our investigation, by rousing doubts and objections which, without injury to our essential object, may well be relegated to another time. The little I have said ought to be sufficient to show clearly that a complete dictionary of these concepts with all requisite explanations is not only possible, but easy. The compartments exist ; they have only to be filled, and with a systematic topic like the present the proper place to which each concept belongs cannot easily be missed, nor compartments be passed over which are still empty. 1 1 Here follows in the Second Edition, Supplement XII. TRANSCENDENTAL ANALYTIC [ P . 8 4 ] CHAPTER II OF THE DEDUCTION OF THE PURE CONCEPTS OF THE UNDERSTANDING Section I Of the Principles of a Transcendental Deduction in General Jurists, when speaking of rights and claims, distin- guish in every lawsuit the question of right (quid juris) from the question of fact (quid facti), and in demanding proof of both they call the former, which is to show the right or, it may be, the claim, the deduction. We, not being jurists, make use of a number of empirical concepts, without opposition from anybody, and consider ourselves justified, without any deduction, in attaching to them a sense or imaginary meaning, because we can always appeal to experience to prove their objective real- ity. There exist however illegitimate concepts also, such as, for instance, chance, or fate, which through an almost general indulgence are allowed to be current, but are yet from time to time challenged by the question quid juris. In that case we are greatly embarrassed in looking for their deduction, there being no clear legal title, whether 70 Transcendental Analytic yi • from experience or from reason, on which their [p. 85] claim to employment could be clearly established. Among the many concepts, however, which enter into the complicated code of human knowledge, there are some which are destined for pure use a priori, indepen- dent of all experience, and such a claim requires at all times a deduction, 1 because proofs from experience would not be sufficient to establish the legitimacy of such a use, though it is necessary to know how much concepts can refer to objects which they do not find in experience. I call the explanation of the manner how such concepts can a priori refer to objects their transcendental deduc- tion, and distinguish it from the empirical deduction which shows the manner how a concept may be gained by experience and by reflection on experience ; this does not touch the legitimacy, but only the fact whence the possession of the concept arose. We have already become acquainted with two totally distinct classes of concepts, which nevertheless agree in this, that they both refer a priori to objects, namely, the concepts of space and time as forms of sensibility, and the categories as concepts of the understanding. It would be labour lost to attempt an empirical deduction of them, because their distinguishing characteristic is that they refer to objects without having borrowed any- thing from experience for their representation, [p. 86~] If therefore a deduction of them is necessary, it can only be transcendental. It is possible, however, with regard to these concepts, as with regard to all knowledge, to try to discover in 1 That is a transcendental deduction. j 2 Transcendental Analytic • experience, if not the principle of their possibility, yet the contingent causes of their production. And here we see that the impressions of the senses give the first impulse to the whole faculty of knowledge with respect to them, and thus produce experience which consists of two very heterogeneous elements, namely, matter for knowledge, derived from the senses, and a certain form according to which it is arranged, derived from the inter- nal source of pure intuition and pure thought, first brought into action by the former, and then producing concepts. Such an investigation of the first efforts of our faculty of knowledge, beginning with single perceptions and ris- ing to general concepts, is no doubt very useful, and we have to thank the famous Locke for having been the first to open the way to it. A deduction of the pure concepts a priori, however, is quite impossible in that way. It lies in a different direction, because, with refer- ence to their future use, which is to be entirely indepen- dent of experience, a very different certificate of birth will be required from that of mere descent from experi- ence. We may call this attempted physiological deriva- tion (which cannot properly be called deduction, [p. 87^ because it refers to a quaestio facti), the explanation of the possession of pure knowledge. It is clear therefore that of these pure concepts a priori a transcendental deduction only is possible, and that to attempt an empiri- cal deduction of them is mere waste of time, which no one would think of except those who have never under- stood the very peculiar nature of that kind of knowledge. But though it may be admitted that the only possible deduction of pure knowledge a priori must be transcen- dental, it has not yet been proved that such a deduction Transcendental Analytic 73 is absolutely necessary. We have before, by means of a transcendental deduction, followed up the concepts of space and time to their very sources, and explained and defined their objective validity a priori. Geometry, how- ever, moves along with a steady step, through every kind of knowledge a priori, without having to ask for a cer- tificate from philosophy as to the pure legitimate descent of its fundamental concept of space. But it should be remarked that in geometry this concept is used with reference to the outer world of sense only, of which space is the pure form of intuition, and where geometri- cal knowledge, being based on a priori intuition, possesses immediate evidence, the objects being given, so far as their form is concerned, through their very knowledge a priori in intuition. When we come, however, [p. 88] to the pure concepts .of the understanding, it becomes absolutely necessary to look for a transcendental, deduc- tion, not only for them, but for space also, because they, not being founded on experience, apply to objects gener- ally, without any of the conditions of sensibility ; and, speaking of objects, not through predicates of intuition and sensibility, but of pure thought a priori, are not able to produce in intuition a priori any object on which, previous to all experience, their synthesis was founded. These concepts of pure understanding, therefore, not only excite suspicion with regard to the objective validity and the limits of their own application, but render even the concept of space equivocal, because of an inclination to apply it beyond the conditions of sensuous intuition, which was the very reason that made a transcendental deduction of it, such as we gave before, necessary. Be- fore the reader has made a single step in the field of 74 Transcendental Analytic pure reason, he must be convinced of the inevitable necessity of such a transcendental deduction, otherwise he would walk on blindly and, after having strayed in every direction, he would only return to the same igno- rance from which he started. He must at the same time perceive the inevitable difficulty of such a deduction, so that he may not complain about obscurity where the object itself is obscure, or weary too soon with our re- moval of obstacles, the fact being that we have [p. 89] either to surrender altogether all claims to the know- ledge of pure reason — the most favourite field of all philosophers, because extending beyond the limits of all possible experience — or to bring this critical investigation to perfection. It was easy to show before, when treating of the con- cepts of space and time, how these, though being know- ledge a priori, refer necessarily to objects, and how they make a synthetical knowledge of them possible, which is independent of all experience. For, as no object can appear to us, that is, become an object of empirical intui- tion, except through such pure forms of sensibility, space and time are pure intuitions which contain a priori the con- ditions of the possibility of objects as phenomena, and the synthesis in these intuitions possesses objective validity. The categories of the understanding, on the contrary, are not conditions under which objects can be given in intuition, and it is quite possible therefore that objects should appear to us without any necessary reference to the functions of the understanding, thus showing that the understanding contains by no means any of their con- ditions a priori. There arises therefore here a difficulty, which we did not meet with in the field of sensibility, Transcendental Analytic 75 namely, how subjective conditions of thought can have objective validity, that is, become conditions of the possi- bility of the knowledge of objects. It cannot be [p. 90] denied that phenomena may be given in intuition without the functions of the understanding. For if we take, for instance, the concept of cause, which implies a peculiar kind of synthesis, consisting in placing according to a rule after something called A something totally different from it, B, we cannot say that it is a priori clear why phenomena should contain something of this kind. We cannot appeal for it to experience, because what has to be proved is the objective validity of this concept a priori. It would re- main therefore a pHori doubtful whether such a concept be not altogether empty, and without any corresponding object among phenomena. It is different with objects of sensuous intuition. They must conform to the formal conditions of sensibility existing a priori in the mind, because otherwise they could in no way be objects to us. But why besides this they should conform to the condi- tions which the understanding requires for the synthetical unity of thought, does not seem to follow quite so easily. For we could quite well imagine that phenomena might possibly be such that the understanding should not find them conforming to the conditions of its synthetical unity, and all might be in such confusion that nothing should appear in the succession of phenomena which could sup- ply a rule of synthesis, and correspond, for instance, to the concept of cause and effect, so that this concept would thus be quite empty, null, and meaningless. With all this phenomena would offer objects to our intuition, because intuition by itself does not require the functions [p. 91] of thought. y6 Transcendental Analytic It might be imagined that we could escape from the trouble of these investigations by saying that experience offers continually examples of such regularity of phe- nomena as to induce us to abstract from it the concept of cause, and it might be attempted to prove thereby the objective validity of such a concept. But it ought to be seen that in this way the concept of cause cannot possibly arise, and that such a concept ought either to be founded a priori in the understanding or be surrendered altogether as a mere hallucination. For this concept requires strictly that something, A, should be of such a nature that some- thing else, B, follows from it necessarily and according to an absolutely universal rule. Phenomena no doubt supply us with cases from which a rule becomes possible accord- ing to which something happens usually, but never so that the result should be necessary. There is a dignity in the synthesis of cause and effect which cannot be expressed empirically, for it implies that the effect is not only an accessory to the cause, but given by it and springing from it. Nor is the absolute universality of the rule a quality inherent in empirical rules, which by means of induction cannot receive any but a relative universality, that [p. 92] is, a more or less extended applicability. If we were to treat the pure concepts of the understanding as merely empirical products, we should completely change their character and their use. Transition to a Transcende7ital Deduction of tJie Categories Two ways only are possible in which synthetical repre- sentations and their objects can agree, can refer to each other with necessity, and so to say meet each other. Either it is the object alone that makes the representation Transcendental Analytic jj possible, or it is the representation alone that makes the object possible. In the former case their relation is em- pirical only, and the representation therefore never possible a priori. This applies to phenomena with reference to whatever in them belongs to sensation. In the latter case, though representation by itself (for we do not speak here of its 1 causality by means of the will) cannot produce its object so far as its existence is concerned, nevertheless the representation determines the object a priori, if through it alone it is possible to know anything as an object. To know a thing as an object is possible only under two conditions. First, there must be intuition by which the object is given us, though as a phenomenon only, secondly, there must be a concept by which [p. 93] an object is thought as corresponding to that intuition. From what we have said before it is clear that the first condition, namely, that under which alone objects can be seen, exists, so far as the form of intuition is concerned, in the soul a priori. All phenomena therefore must con- form to that formal condition of sensibility, because it is through it alone that they appear, that is, that they are given and empirically seen. Now the question arises whether there are not also antecedent concepts a priori, forming conditions under which alone something can be, if not seen, yet thought as an object in general ; for in that case all empirical know- ledge of objects would necessarily conform to such con- cepts, it being impossible that anything should become an object of experience without them. All experience con- tains, besides the intuition of the senses by which some- 1 Read deren instead of dessert. 78 Transcendental Analytic thing is given, a concept also of the object, which is given in intuition as a phenomenon. Such concepts of objects in general therefore must form conditions a priori of all knowledge produced by experience, and the objective validity of the categories, as being such concepts a priori, rests on this very fact that by them alone, so far as the form of thought is concerned, experience becomes possi- ble. If by them only it is possible to think any object of experience, it follows that they refer by necessity and a priori to all objects of experience. There is therefore a principle for the trans- [p. 94] cendental deduction of all concepts a priori which must guide the whole of our investigation, namely, that all must be recognized as conditions a priori of the possibility of experience, whether of intuition, which is found in it, or of thought. Concepts which supply the objective ground of the possibility of experience are for that very reason necessary. An analysis of the experience in which they are found would not be a deduction, but a mere illus- tration, because they would there have an accidental char- acter only. Nay, without their original relation to all possible experience in which objects of knowledge occur, their relation to any single object would be quite incom- prehensible. [There are three original sources, or call them faculties or powers of the soul, which contain the conditions of the possibility of all experience, and which themselves cannot be derived from any other faculty, namely, sense, imagina- tion, and apperception. On them is founded — 1. The synopsis of the manifold a priori through the senses. 2. The synthesis of this manifold through the imagination. Transcendental Analytic 79 3. The unity of that synthesis by means of original apperception. Besides their empirical use all these faculties have a transcendental use also, referring to the form only and possible a priori. With regard to the senses we have dis- cussed that transcendental use in the first part, [p. 95] and we shall now proceed to an investigation of the re- maining two, according to their true nature. 1 ] DEDUCTION OF THE PURE CONCEPTS OF THE UNDERSTANDING Section II Of the a priori Grounds for the Possibility of Experience [That a concept should be produced entirely a priori and yet refer to an object, though itself neither belonging to the sphere of possible experience, nor consisting of the elements of such an experience, is self-contradictory and impossible. It would have no contents, because no intui- tion corresponds to it, and intuitions by which objects are given to us constitute the whole field or the complete object of possible experience. An a priori concept there- fore not referring to experience would be the logical form only of a concept, but not the concept itself by which something is thought. If therefore there exist any pure concepts a priori, though they cannot contain anything empirical, they must nevertheless all be conditions a priori of a possible ex- perience, on which alone their objective reality depends. 1 The last paragraph is omitted in the Second Edition. There is instead a criticism of Locke and Hume, Supplement XIII. The Deduction of the Categories is much changed, as seen in Supplement XIV. 80 Transcendental Analytic If therefore we wish to know how pure concepts of the understanding are possible, we must try to find out what are the conditions a priori on which the possibility [p. 96] of experience depends, nay, on which it is founded, apart from all that is empirical in phenomena. A concept ex- pressing this formal and objective condition of experience with sufficient generality might properly be called a pure concept of the understanding. If we once have these pure concepts of the understanding, we may also imagine objects which are either impossible, or, if not impossible in themselves, yet can never be given in any experience. We have only in the connection of those concepts to leave out something which necessarily belongs to the conditions of a possible experience (concept of a spirit), or to extend pure concepts of the understanding beyond what can be reached by experience (concept of God). But trie ele- ments of all knowledge a priori, even of gratuitous and preposterous fancies, though not borrowed from experi- ence (for in that case they would not be knowledge a priori) must nevertheless contain the pure conditions a priori of a possible experience and its object, otherwise not only would nothing be thought by them, but they themselves, being without data, could never arise in our mind. Such concepts, then, which comprehend the pure think- ing a priori involved in every experience, are discovered in the categories, and it is really a sufficient deduction of them and a justification of their objective validity, if we succeed in proving that by them alone an object [p. 97] can be thought. But as in such a process of thinking more is at work than the faculty of thinking only, namely, the understanding, and as the understanding, as a faculty Transcendental Analytic 81 of knowledge which is meant to refer to objects, requires quite as much an explanation as to the possibility of such a reference, it is necessary for us to consider the subjective sources which form the foundation a priori for the possi- bility of experience, not according to their empirical, but according to their transcendental character. If every single representation stood by itself, as if isolated and separated from the others, nothing like what we call knowledge could ever arise, because knowledge forms a whole of representations connected and compared with each other. If therefore I ascribe to the senses a synopsis, because in their intuition they contain something manifold, there corresponds to it always a synthesis, and receptivity can make knowledge possible only when joined with spontaneity. This spontaneity, now, appears as a threefold synthesis which must necessarily take place in every kind of knowledge, namely, first, that of the apprehension of representations as modifications of the soul in intuition, secondly, of the reproduction of them in the imagination, and, thirdly, that of their recognition in concepts. This leads us to three subjective sources of knowledge which render possible the understanding, and through it all experience as an empirical product of the understanding. [p. 98] Preliminary Remark The deduction of the categories is beset with so many difficulties and obliges us to enter so deeply into the first grounds of the possibility of our knowledge in general, that I thought it more expedient, in order to avoid the lengthiness of a complete theory, and yet to omit nothing in so essential an investigation, to add the following four 82 Transcendental Analytic paragraphs with a view of preparing rather than instruct- ing the reader. After that only I shall in the third sec- tion proceed to a systematical discussion of these elements of the understanding. Till then the reader must not allow himself to be frightened by a certain amount of obscurity which at first is inevitable on a road never trodden before, but which, when we come to that section, will give way, I hope, to a complete comprehension. I Of the Synthesis of Apprehension in Intuition Whatever the origin of our representations may be, whether they be due to the influence of external things or to internal causes, whether they have arisen a priori or empirically as phenomena, as modifications of the mind they must always belong to the internal [p. 99] sense, and all our knowledge must therefore finally be subject to the formal condition of that internal sense, namely, time, in which they are all arranged, joined, and brought into certain relations to each other. This is a general remark which must never be forgotten in all that follows. Every representation contains something manifold, which could not be represented as such, unless the. mind distinguished the time in the succession of one impression after another ; for as contained in one moment, each representation can never be anything but absolute unity. In order to change this manifold into a unity of intuition (as, for instance, in the repre- sentation of space), it is necessary first to run through the manifold and then to hold it together. It is this Transcendental Analytic S3 act which I call the synthesis of apprehension, because it refers directly to intuition which no doubt offers some- thing manifold, but which, without a synthesis, can never make it such, as it is contained in one representation. This synthesis of apprehension must itself be carried out a priori also, that is, with reference to representations which are not empirical. For without it we should never be able to have the representations either of space or time a priori, because these cannot be produced except [p. 100] by a synthesis of the manifold which the senses offer in their original receptivity. It follows therefore that we have a pure synthesis of apprehension. II Of the Synthesis of Reproduction in Imagination It is no doubt nothing but an empirical law according to which representations which have often followed or accompanied one another, become associated in the end and so closely united that, even without the presence of the object, one of these representations will, according to an invariable law, produce a transition of the mind to the other. This law of reproduction, however, presupposes that the phenomena themselves are really subject to such a rule, and that there is in the variety of these representa- tions a sequence and concomitancy subject to certain rules ; for without this the faculty of empirical imagina- tion would never find anything to do that it is able to do, and remain therefore buried within our mind as a dead faculty, unknown to ourselves. If cinnabar were sometimes red and sometimes black, sometimes light and sometimes heavy, if a man could be changed now into 84 Transcendental Analytic this, now into another animal shape, if on the longest day the fields were sometimes covered with fruit, [p. 101] sometimes with ice and snow, the faculty of my empirical imagination would never be in a position, when represent- ing red colour, to think of heavy cinnabar. Nor, if a cer- tain name could be given sometimes to this, sometimes to that object, or if that the same object could sometimes be called by one, and sometimes by another name, with- out any rule to which representations are subject by them- selves, would it be possible that any empirical synthesis of reproduction should ever take place. There must therefore be something to make this repro- duction of phenomena possible by being itself the founda- tion a priori of a necessary synthetical unity of them. This becomes clear if we only remember that all phe- nomena are not things by themselves, but only the play of our representations, all of which are in the end deter- minations only of the internal sense. If therefore we could prove that even our purest intuitions a priori give us no knowledge, unless they contain such a combination of the manifold as to render a constant synthesis of repro- duction possible, it would follow that this synthesis of the imagination is, before all experience, founded on principles a priori, and that we must admit a pure transcendental synthesis of imagination which forms even the foundation of the possibility of all experience, such experience being impossible without the reproducibility of phe- [p. 102] nomena. Now, when I draw a line in thought, or if I think the time from one noon to another, or if I only represent to myself a certain number, it is clear that I must first necessarily apprehend one of these manifold representations after another. If I were to lose from my Transcendental Analytic 85 thoughts what precedes, whether the first parts of a line or the antecedent portions of time, or the numerical unities representing one after the other, and if, while I proceed to what follows, I were unable to reproduce what came before, there would never be a complete representation, and none of the before-mentioned thoughts, not even the first and purest representations of space and time, could ever arise within us. The synthesis of apprehension is therefore inseparably connected with the synthesis of reproduction, and as the former constitutes the transcendental ground of the possi- bility of all knowledge in general (not only of empirical, but also of pure a priori knowledge), it follows that a reproductive synthesis of imagination belongs to the tran- scendental acts of the soul. We may therefore call this faculty the transcendental faculty of imagination. in [ P . 103] Of the Synthesis of Recognition in Concepts Without our being conscious that what we are thinking now is the same as what we thought a moment before, all reproduction in the series of representations would be vain. Each representation would, in its present state, be a new one, and in no wise belonging to the act by which it was to be produced by degrees, and the manifold in it would never form a whole, because deprived of that unity which consciousness alone can impart to it. If in counting I for- get that the unities which now present themselves to my mind have been added gradually one to the other, I should not know the production of the quantity by the successive addition of one to one, nor should I know consequently 86 Transcendental Analytic the number, produced by the counting, this number being a concept consisting entirely in the consciousness of that unity of synthesis. The very word of concept (Begriff) could have sug- gested this remark, for it is the one consciousness which unites the manifold that has been perceived successively, and afterwards reproduced into one representation. This consciousness may often be very faint, and we may con- nect it with the effect only, and not with the act itself, i.e. with the production of a representation. But in [p. 104] spite of this, that consciousness, though deficient in pointed clearness, must always be there, and without it, concepts, and with them, knowledge of objects are perfectly impos- sible. And here we must needs arrive at a clear understanding of what we mean by an object of representations. We said before that phenomena are nothing but sensuous rep- resentations, which therefore by themselves must not be taken for objects outside our faculty of representation. What then do we mean if we speak of an object corre- sponding to, and therefore also different from our know- ledge ? It is easy to see that such an object can only be conceived as something in general —x\ because, beside our knowledge, we have absolutely nothing which we could put down as corresponding to that knowledge. Now we find that our conception of the relation of all knowledge to its object contains something of necessity, the object being looked upon as that which prevents our knowledge from being determined at haphazard, and causes it to be determined a priori in a certain way, be- cause, as they are all to refer to an object, they must necessarily, with regard to that object, agree with each Transcendental Analytic 87 other, that is to say, possess that unity which [p. 105] constitutes the concept of an object. It is clear also that, as we can only deal with the mani- fold in our representations, and as the x corresponding to them (the object), since it is to be something different from all our representations, is really nothing to us, it is clear, I say, that the unity, necessitated by the object, can- not be anything but the formal unity of our consciousness in the synthesis of the manifold in our representations. Then and then only do we say that we know an object, if we have produced synthetical unity in the manifold of intuition. Such unity is impossible, if the intuition could not be produced, according to a rule, by such a function of synthesis as makes the reproduction of the manifold a priori necessary, and a concept in which that manifold is united, possible. Thus we conceive a triangle as an object, if we are conscious of the combination of three straight lines, according to a rule, which renders such an intuition possible at all times. This unity of ride deter- mines the manifold and limits it to conditions which ren- der the unity of apperception possible, and the concept of that unity is really the representation of the object = .r, which I think, by means of the predicates of a triangle. No knowledge is possible without a concept, [p. 106] however obscure or imperfect it may be, and a concept is always, with regard to its form, something general, something that can serve as a rule. Thus the concept of body serves as a rule to our knowledge of external phe- nomena, according to the unity of the manifold which is thought by it. It can only be such a rule of intuitions because representing, in any given phenomena, the neces- sary reproduction of their manifold elements, or the syn- 88 Transcendental Analytic thetical unity in our consciousness of them. Thus the concept of body, whenever we perceive something outside us, necessitates the representation of extension, and, with it, those of impermeability, shape, etc. Necessity is always founded on transcendental condi- tions. There must be therefore a transcendental ground of the unity of our consciousness in the synthesis of the man- ifold of all our intuitions, and therefore also a transcendental ground of all concepts of objects in general, and therefore again of all objects of experience, without which it would be impossible to add to our intuitions the thought of an object, for the object is no more than that something of which the concept predicates such a necessity of synthesis. That original and transcendental condition is nothing else but what I call transcendental apperception, [p. 107] The consciousness of oneself, according to the determina- tions of our state, is, with all our internal perceptions, em- pirical only, and always transient. There can be no fixed or permanent self in that stream of internal phenomena. It is generally called the internal sense, or the empirical apperception. What is necessarily to be represented as numerically identical with itself, cannot be thought as such by means of empirical data only. It must be a con- dition which precedes all experience, and in fact renders it possible, for thus only could such a transcendental suppo- sition acquire validity. No knowledge can take place in us, no conjunction or unity of one kind of knowledge with another, without that unity of consciousness which precedes all data of intui- tion, and without reference to which no representation of objects is possible. This pure, original, and unchange- able consciousness I shall call transcendental apperception. Transcendental Analytic 89 That it deserves such a name may be seen from the fact that even the purest objective unity, namely, that of the concepts a priori (space and time), is possible only by a reference of all intuitions to it. The numerical unity of that apperception therefore forms the a priori condition of all concepts, as does the manifoldness of space and time of the intuitions of the senses. The same tran scendental unity of apperc ep- [p. 108] ^iion constitutes, in all possible phenomena which may come together in our experience, a connection of all these representations according to laws. For that unity of con- sciousness would be impossible, if the mind, in the know- ledge of the manifold, could not become conscious of the identity of function, by which it unites the manifold syn- thetically in one knowledge. Therefore the original and necessary consciousness of the identity of oneself is at the same time a consciousness of an equally necessary unity of the synthesis of all phenomena according to concepts, that is, according to rules, which render them not only necessarily reproducible, but assign also to their intuition an object, that is, a concept of something in which they are necessarily united. The mind could never conceive the identity of itself in the manifoldness of its representa- tions (and this a priori) if it did not clearly perceive the identity of its action, by which it subjects all synthesis of apprehension (which is empirical) to a transcendental unity, and thus renders its regular coherence a priori pos- sible. When we have clearly perceived this, we shall be able to determine more accurately our concept of an ob- ject in general. All representations have, as representa- tions, their object, and can themselves in turn become objects of other representations. The only objects which 9 and imagine that he thus added no inconsiderable extension to our knowledge of nature. No doubt, if I know a drop of water as a thing by itself in all its internal determinations, I cannot allow that one is different from the other, when their whole concepts are identical. But if the drop of water is a phenomenon in space, it has its place not only in the understanding (among concepts), but in the sensuous external intuition (in space), and in this case the physical place is quite indifferent with regard to the inner determinations of things, so that a place B can receive a thing which is perfectly similar or identical with another in place A, quite as well as if it were totally different from it in its internal determinations. Difference of place by itself and without any further conditions ren- ders the plurality and distinction of objects as phenomena not only possible, but also necessary. That so-called law of Leibniz therefore is no law of nature, but only an analytical rule, or a comparison of things by means of concepts only. Secondly. The principle that realities (as mere asser- tions) never logically contradict each other, is perfectly true with regard to the relation of concepts, but [p. 273] has no meaning whatever either as regards nature or as regards anything by itself (of which we can have no con- cept whatever). 1 The real opposition, as when A — B = o, takes place everywhere wherever one reality is united with another in the same subject and one annihilates the effect of the other. This is constantly brought before our eyes in nature by all impediments and reactions which, as depending on forces, must be called realitates phaenomena. 1 ' Whatever ' is omitted in the Second Edition. i Transcendental Ana lytic 223 General mechanics can even give us the empirical condi- tion of that opposition in an a priori rule, by attending to the opposition of directions ; a condition of which the tran- scendental concept of reality knows nothing. Although Leibniz himself did not announce this proposition with all the pomp of a new principle, he yet made use of it for new assertions, and his followers expressly inserted it in their system of the Leibniz-Wolfian philosophy. According to this principle all evils, for example, are nothing but the consequences of the limitations of created beings, that is, they are negations, because these can be the only opposites of reality (which is perfectly true in the mere concept of the thing in general, but not in things as phenomena). In like manner the followers of Leibniz consider it not only possible, but even natural, to unite all reality, without fearing any opposition, in one being ; because the only opposition they know is that [p. 274] of contradiction (by which the concept of a thing itself is annihilated), while they ignore that of reciprocal action and reaction, when one real cause destroys the effect of another, a process which we can only represent to our- selves when the conditions are given in sensibility. Thirdly. The Leibnizian monadology has really no other foundation than that Leibniz represented the difference of the internal and the external in relation to the understand- ing only. Substances must have something internal, which is free from all external relations, and therefore from com- position also. The simple, therefore, or uncompounded, is the foundation of the internal of things by themselves. This internal in the state of substances cannot consist in space, form, contact, or motion (all these determinations being external relations), and we cannot therefore ascribe 224 Transcendental Analytic to substances any other internal state but that which belongs to our own internal sense, namely, the state of representations. This is the history of the monads, which were to form the elements of the whole universe, and the energy of which consists in representations only, so that properly they can be active within themselves only. For this reason, his principle of a possible community of substances could only be a pre-established harmony, and not a physical influence. For, as every- [p. 275] thing is actively occupied internally only, that is, with its own representations, the state of representations in one substance could not be in active connection with that of another; but it became necessary to admit a third cause, exercising its influence on all substances, and making their states to correspond with each other, not indeed by oc- casional assistance rendered in each particular case (sys- tema assistentiae), but through the unity of the idea of a cause valid for all, and in which all together must receive their existence and permanence, and therefore also their reciprocal correspondence according to universal laws. Fourthly. Leibniz's celebrated doctrine of space and time, in which he intellectualised these forms of sensi- bility, arose entirely from the same delusion of transcen- dental reflection. If by means of the pure understanding alone I want to represent the external relations of things, I can do this only by means of the concept of their reciprocal action ; and if I want to connect one state with another state of the same thing, this is possible only in the order of cause and effect. Thus it happened that Leibniz conceived space as a certain order in the com- munity of substances, and time as the dynamical sequence of their states. That which space and time seem to pos^ Transcende7ital Analytic 225 sess as proper to themselves and independent [p. 276] of things, he ascribed to the confusion of these concepts, which made us mistake what is a mere form of dynamical relations for a peculiar and independent intuition, ante- cedent to things themselves. Thus space and time became with him the intelligible form of the connection of things (substances and their states) by themselves, and things were intelligible substances {snbstantiae noumena). Never- theless he tried to make these concepts valid for phe- nomena, because he would not concede to sensibility any independent kind of intuition, but ascribed all, even the empirical representation of objects, to the understanding, leaving to the senses nothing but the contemptible work of confusing and mutilating the representations of the understanding. But, even if we could predicate anything synthetically by means of the pure understanding of things by them- selves (which however is simply impossible), this could never be referred to phenomena, because these do not represent things by themselves. We should. therefore in such a case have to compare our concepts in a transcen- dental reflection under the conditions of sensibility only, and thus space and time would never be determinations of things by themselves, but of phenomena. What things may be by themselves we know not, nor need [p. 277] we care to know, because, after all, a thing can never come before me otherwise than as a phenomenon. The remaining reflective conceptions have to be treated in the same manner. Matter is substantia phenomenon. What may belong to it internally, I seek for in all parts of space occupied by it, and in all effects produced by it, all of which, however, can be phenomena of the external Q 226 Transcendental Analytic senses only. I have therefore nothing that is absolutely, but only what is relatively internal, and this consists itself of external relations. Nay, what according to the pure understanding should be the absolutely internal of matter is a mere phantom, for matter is never an object of the pure understanding, while the transcendental object which may be the ground of the phenomenon which we call matter, is a mere something of which we could not even understand what it is, though somebody should tell us. We cannot understand anything except what carries with it in intuition something corresponding to our words. If the complaint ' that we do not understand the internal of things,' means that we do not comprehend by means of the pure understanding what the things which appear to us may be of themselves, it seems totally unjust and unreasonable ; for it means that without senses we should be able to know and therefore to see things, that is, that we should possess a faculty of knowledge totally different from the human, not only in degree, but in kind [p. 278] and in intuition, in fact, that we should not be men, but beings of whom we ourselves could not say whether they are even possible, much less what they would be like. Observation and analysis of phenomena enter into the internal of nature, and no one can say how far this may go in time. Those transcendental questions, however, which go beyond nature, would nevertheless remain un- answerable, even if the whole of nature were revealed to us, for it is not given to us to observe even our own mind with any intuition but that of our internal sense. In it lies the mystery of the origin of our sensibility. Its relation to an object, and the transcendental ground of that unity, are no doubt far too deeply hidden for us, who can know Transcendental Analytic 227 even ourselves by means of the internal sense only, that is, as phenomena, and we shall never be able to use the same imperfect instrument of investigation in order to find any- thing but again and again phenomena, the non-sensuous, and non-phenomenal cause of which we are seeking in vain. What renders this criticism of the conclusions by means of the acts of mere reflection extremely useful is, that it shows clearly the nullity of all conclusions with regard to objects compared with each other in the understanding only, and that it confirms at the same time what [p. 279] we have so strongly insisted on, namely, that phenomena, though they cannot be comprehended as things by them- selves among the objects of the pure understanding, are nevertheless the only objects in which our knowledge can possess objective reality, i.e. where intuition corresponds to concepts. When we reflect logically only, we only compare in our understanding concepts among themselves, trying to find out whether both have exactly the same contents, whether they contradict themselves or not, whether something belongs to a concept, or is added to it, and which of the two may be given, while the other may be a mode only of thinking the given concept. But if I refer these concepts to an object in general (in a transcendental sense), with- out determining whether it be an object of sensuous or intellectual intuition, certain limitations appear at once, warning us not to go beyond the concept, and upsetting all empirical use of it, thus proving that a representation of an object, as of a thing in general, is not only insuffi- cient, but, if without sensuous determination, and indepen- dent of empirical conditions, self-contradictory. It is necessary therefore either to take no account at all of the 228 Transcendental Analytic object (as we do in logic) or, if not, then to think it under the conditions of sensuous intuition, because the intelligi- ble would require a quite peculiar intuition which we do not possess, and, without it, would be nothing to us, while on the other side phenomena also could never [p. 280] be things by themselves. For if I represent to myself things in general only, the difference of external relations cannot, it is true, constitute a difference of the things themselves, but rather presupposes it ; and, if the concept of one thing does not differ at all internally from that of another, I only have one and the same thing placed in different relations. Furthermore, by adding a mere affir- mation (reality) to another, the positive in it is indeed augmented, and nothing is taken away or removed, so that we see that the real in things can never be in contra- diction with itself, etc. ******** A certain misunderstanding of these reflective concepts has, as we showed, exercised so great an influence on the use of the understanding, as to mislead even one of the most acute philosophers to the adoption of a so-called system of intellectual knowledge, which undertakes to determine objects without the intervention of the senses. For this reason the exposition of the cause of the misunder- standing, which lies in the amphiboly of these concepts, as the origin of false principles, is of great utility in deter- mining and securing the true limits of the understanding. It is no doubt true, that what can be affirmed or denied of a concept in general, can also be affirmed or denied of any part of it {dictum de omni et nulld) ; but it [p. 281] would be wrong so to change this logical proposition as to make it say that whatever is not contained in a general Tra7iscendental Analytic 229 concept, is not contained either in the particular con- cepts comprehended under it ; for these are particular concepts for the very reason that they contain more than is conceived in the general concept. Nevertheless the whole intellectual system of Leibniz is built up on this fallacy, and with it falls necessarily to the ground, to- gether with all equivocation in the use of the understand- ing, that had its origin in it. Leibniz's principle of discernibility is really based on the supposition that, if a certain distinction is not to be found in the general concept of a thing, it could not be met with either in the things themselves, and that there- fore all things were perfectly the same (nnmero eadem), which are not distinguished from each other in their con- cept also, as to quality or quantity. And because in the mere concept of a thing, no account has been taken of many a necessary condition of its intuition, it has rashly been concluded that that which, in forming an abstraction, has been intentionally left out of account, did really not exist anywhere, and nothing has been allowed to a thing except what is contained in its concept. [p. 282] The concept of a cubic foot of space, wherever and how many times soever I may think it, is in itself perfectly the same. But two cubic feet are nevertheless distinguished in space, by their places alone (nnmero diversa), and these places are conditions of the intuition in which the object of our concept is given, and which, though they do not belong to the concept, belong nevertheless to the whole of sensibility. In a similar manner there is no contra- diction in the concept of a thing, unless something nega- tive has been connected with something affirmative ; and simply affirmative concepts, if joined together, cannot 230 Transcendental Analytic neutralise each other. But in sensuous intuition, where we have to deal with reality (for instance motion), there exist conditions (opposite directions) of which in the concept of motion in general no account was taken, and which render possible an opposition (not however a logical one), and from mere positives produce zero = o, so that it would be wrong to say that all reality must be in per- fect agreement, if there is no opposition between its con- cepts. 1 If we keep to concepts only, that which we call internal is the substratum of all relations or [p. 283] external determinations. If therefore I take no account of any of the conditions of intuition, and confine myself solely to the concept of a thing, then I may drop no doubt all external relations, and yet there must remain the con- cept of something which implies no relation, but internal determinations only. From this it might seem to follow that there exists in everything something (substance) which is absolutely internal, preceding all external determinations, nay, rendering them possible. It might likewise seem to follow that this substratum, as no longer containing any external relations, must be simple (for corporeal things are always relations only, at. least of their parts existing side by side) ; and as we know of no entirely internal deter- minations beyond those of our own internal sense, that substratum might be taken, not only as simple, but like- 1 If one wished to use here the usual subterfuge that realitates noumena, at least, cannot oppose each other, it would be necessary to produce an example of such pure and non-sensuous reality, to enable us to see whether it was something or nothing. No example, however, can be produced, except from experience, which never offers us anything but phenomena; so that this proposition means really nothing but that a concept, which contains affirma- tives only, contains no negative, a proposition which we at least have never doubted. Transcendental Analytic 231 wise (according to the analogy of our own internal sense) as determined by representations, so that all things would be really monads, or simple beings endowed with repre- sentations. All this would be perfectly true, unless some- thing more than the concept of a thing in gen- [p. 284] eral were required in order to give us objects of external intuition, although the pure concept need take no account of it. But we see, on the contrary, that a permanent phenomenon in space (impenetrable extension) may con- tain mere relations without anything that is absolutely internal, and yet be the first substratum of all external perception. It is true that if we think by concepts only, we cannot think something external without something internal, because conceptions of relations presuppose things given, and are impossible without them. But as in intuition something is contained which does not exist at all in the mere concept of a thing, and as it is this which supplies the substratum that could never be known by mere concepts, namely, a space which, with all that is contained in it, consists of purely formal, or real rela- tions also, I am not allowed to say, that, because nothing can be represented by mere concepts without something absolutely internal, there could not be in the real things themselves, comprehended under those concepts, and in their intuition, anything external, without a foundation of something absolutely internal. For, if we take no account of all conditions of intuition, then no doubt nothing re- mains in the mere concept but the internal in general, with its mutual relations, through which alone the exter- nal is possible. This necessity, however, which depends on abstraction alone, does not apply to things, if [p. 285] they are given in intuition with determinations expressive 232 Transcendental Analytic of mere relations, and without having for their foundation anything internal, for the simple reason that they are phenomena only, and not things in themselves. What- ever we may know of matter are nothing but relations (what we call internal determinations are but relatively internal) ; but there are among these relations some which are independent and permanent, and by which a certain object is given us. That I, when abstraction is made of these relations, have nothing more to think, does not do away with the concept of a thing, as a phenomenon, nor with the concept of an object in abstracto. It only shows the impossibility of such an object as could be determined by mere concepts, that is of a noumenon. It is no doubt startling to hear, that a thing should consist entirely of relations, but such a thing as we speak of is merely a phenomenon, and can never be thought by means of the categories only ; nay, it consists itself of the mere relation of something in general to our senses. In the same man- ner, it is impossible for us to represent the relations of things in abstracto as long as we deal with concepts only, in any other way than that one should be the cause of determinations in the other, this being the very concept of our understanding, with regard to relations. But as in this case we make abstraction of all intuition, a whole class of determinations, by which the manifold determines its place to each of its component parts, that is, the form of sensibility (space), disappears, though in truth [p. 286] it precedes all empirical casuality. If by purely intelligible objects we understand things which, without all schemata of sensibility, are thought by mere categories, such objects are simply impossible. It is our sensuous intuition by which objects are given to us that Transcendental Analytic 233 forms the condition of the objective application of all the concepts of our understanding, and without that intuition the categories have no relation whatever to any object. Nay, even if we admitted a kind of intuition different from the sensuous, our functions of thought would have no meaning with regard to it. If we only mean objects of a non-sensuous intuition, to which our categories do not apply, and of which we can have no knowledge whatever (either intuitional or conceptual), there is no reason why noumena, in this merely negative meaning, should not be admitted, because in this case we mean no more than this, that our intuition does not embrace all things, but objects of our senses only; that, consequently, its objective validity is limited, and space left for some other kind of intuition, and consequently for things as objects of it. But in that sense the concept of a noumenon is problematical, that is, the representation of a thing of which we can neither say that it is possible or that it is impossible, because we have no conception of any kind of intuition but that of our senses, or of any kind of concepts but of our categories, [p. 287] neither of them being applicable to any extra-sensuous object. We cannot therefore extend in a positive sense the field of the objects of our thought beyond the conditions of our sensibility, or admit, besides phenomena, objects of pure thought, that is, noumena, simply because they do not possess any positive meaning that could be pointed out. For it must be admitted that the categories by themselves are not sufficient for a knowledge of things, and that, with- out the data of sensibility, they would be nothing but subjective forms of unity of the understanding, and without an object. We do not say that thought is a mere product of the senses, and therefore limited by them, but it does 234 Transcendental Analytic not follow that therefore thought, without sensibility, has its own pure use, because it would really be without an object. Nor would it be right to call the noumenon such an object of the pure understanding, for the noumenon means the problematical concept of an object, intended for an intuition and understanding totally different from our own, and therefore themselves mere problems. The con- cept of the noumenon is not therefore the concept of an object, but only a problem, inseparable from the limitation of our sensibility, whether there may not be objects inde- pendent of its intuition. This is a question that [p. 288] can only be answered in an uncertain way, by saying that as sensuous intuition does not embrace all things without exception, there remains a place for other objects, that can- not therefore be absolutely denied, but cannot be asserted either as objects of our understanding, because there is no definite concept for them (our categories being unfit for that purpose). The understanding therefore limits the sensibility with- out enlarging thereby its own field, and by warning the latter that it can never apply to things by themselves, but to phenomena only, it forms the thought of an object by itself, but as transcendental only, which is the cause of phenomena, and therefore never itself a phenomenon : which cannot be thought as quantity, nor as reality, nor as substance (because these concepts require sensuous forms in which to determine an object), and of which therefore it must always remain unknown, whether it is to be found within us only, or also without us ; and whether, if sensi- bility were removed, it would vanish or remain. If we like to call this object noumenon, because the representation of it is not sensuous, we are at liberty to do so. But as we Transcendental Analytic 235 cannot apply to it any of the concepts of our understand- ing, such a representation remains to us empty, serving no purpose but that of indicating the limits of our sensuous knowledge, and leaving at the same time an [p. 289] empty space which we cannot fill either by possible expe- rience, or by the pure understanding. The critique of the pure understanding does not there- fore allow us to create a new sphere of objects beyond those which can come before it as phenomena, or to stray into intelligible worlds, or even into the concept of such. The mistake which leads to this in the most plausible manner, and which, though excusable, can never be justi- fied, consists in making the use of the understanding, con- trary to its very intention, transcendental, so that objects, that is, possible intuitions, are made to conform to con- cepts, not concepts to possible intuitions, on which alone their objective validity can rest. The cause of this is again, that apperception, and with it thought, precedes every possible determinate arrangement of represen- tations. We are thinking something in general, and determine it on one side sensuously, but distinguish at the same time the general object, represented in abstrac- tion, from this particular mode of sensuous intuition. Thus there remains to us a mode of determining the object by thought only, which, though it is a mere logical form without any contents, seems to us nevertheless a mode in which the object by itself exists (noumenon), with- out regard to the intuition which is restricted to our senses. [p. 290] Before leaving this transcendental Analytic, we have to add something which, though in itself of no particular 236 Transcendental Analytic importance, may yet seem to be requisite for the complete- ness of the system. The highest concept of which all transcendental philosophy generally begins, is the division into the possible and the impossible. But, as all division presupposes a divisible concept, a higher concept is re- quired, and this is the concept of an object in general, taken as problematical, it being left uncertain whether it be something or nothing. As the categories are the only concepts which apply to objects in general, the distinction whether an object is something or nothing must proceed according to the order and direction of the categories. I. Opposed to the concepts of all, many, and one, is the concept which annihilates everything, that is, none ; and thus the object of a concept, to which no intuition can be found to correspond, is = o, that is, a concept with- out an object, like the noumena, which cannot be counted as possibilities, though not as impossibilities either (ens nationis) ; or like certain fundamental forces, [p. 291] which have been newly invented, and have been con- ceived without contradiction, but at the same time with- out any example from experience, and must not therefore be counted among possibilities. II. Reality is something, negation is nothing ; that is, it is the concept of the absence of an object, as shadow or cold (nihil privativum). III. The mere form of intuition (without substance) is in itself no object, but the merely formal condition of it (as a phenomenon), as pure space and pure time (ens imaginarium), which, though they are something, as forms of intuition, are not themselves objects of intuition. IV. The object of a concept which contradicts itself, is nothing, because the concept is nothing; it is simply Transcendental Analytic 237 the impossible, as a figure composed of two straight lines {nihil negativnm). A table showing this division of the concept of nothing (the corresponding division of the concept of something- follows by itself) would have to be arranged as follows. Nothing, [p. 292] as I. Empty concept without an object. Ens rat'onis. II. Empty object of a III. Empty intuition without concept. an object. Nil privativum. Ens imaginarium IV. Empty object without a concept. Nihil negativam. We see that the ens rationis (No. 1) differs from the ens negativnm (No. 4), because the former cannot be counted among the possibilities, being the result of fancy, though not self-contradictory, while the latter is opposed to possibility, the concept annihilating itself. Both, however, are empty concepts. The nihil privati- vum (No. 2) and the ens imaginarium (No. 3) are, on the contrary, empty data for concepts. It would be impossible to represent to ourselves darkness, unless light had been given to the senses, or space, unless extended beings had been perceived. The negation, as well as the pure form of intuition are, without something real, no objects. TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC [ P . 293] Second Division Transcendental Dialectic INTRODUCTION 1. Of Transcendental Appearance (Illusion) We call Dialectic in general a logic of illusion (eine Logik des Scheins). This does not mean that it is a doctrine of probability (Wahrscheinlichkeit), for proba- bility is a kind of truth, known through insufficient causes, the knowledge of which is therefore deficient, but not deceitful, and cannot properly be separated from the analytical part of logic. Still less can phenomenon (Erscheinung) and illusion (Schein) be taken as identical. For truth or illusion is not to be found in the objects of intuition, but in the judgments upon them, so far as they are thought. It is therefore quite right to say, that the senses never err, not because they always judge rightly, but because they do not judge at all. Truth therefore and error, and consequently illusory appearance also, as the cause of error, exist in our judgments only, that is, in the relation of an object to our understanding. No error exists in our knowledge, if it completely agrees with the laws of our understanding, nor can there be [p. 294] an error in a representation of the senses/because they 238 Transcendental Dialectic 239 involve no judgment, and no power of nature can, of its own accord, deviate from its own laws. Therefore neither the understanding by itself (without the influence of another cause), nor the senses by themselves could ever err. The understanding could not err, because as long as it acts according to its own laws, the effect (the judg- ment) must necessarily agree with those laws, and the formal test of all truth consists in this agreement with the laws of the understanding. The senses cannot err, because there is in them no judgment at all, whether true or false. Now as we have no other sources of know- ledge but these two, it follows that error can only arise through the unperceived influence of the sensibility on the understanding, whereby it happens that subjective grounds of judgment are mixed up with the objective, and cause them to deviate from their destination; 1 just as a body in motion would, if left to itself, always follow a straight line in the same direction, which is changed however into a curvilinear motion, as soon as another force influences it at the same time in a different direc- tion. In order to distinguish the proper action [p. 295] of the understanding from that other force which is mixed up with it, it will be necessary to look on an erroneous judgment as the diagonal between two forces, which de- termine the judgment in two different directions, forming as it were an angle, and to dissolve that composite effect into the simple ones of the understanding and of the sen- sibility, which must be effected in pure judgments a priori 1 Sensibility, if subjected to the understanding as the object on which it exercises its function, is the source of real knowledge, but sensibility, if it in- fluences the action of the understanding itself and leads it on to a judgment, is the cause of error. 240 Transcendental Dialectic by transcendental reflection, whereby, as we tried to show, the right place is assigned to each representation in the faculty of knowledge corresponding to it, and the influence of either faculty upon such representation is determined. It is not at present our business to treat of empirical, for instance, optical appearance or illusion, which occurs in the empirical use of the otherwise correct rules of the understanding, and by which, owing to the influence of imagination, the faculty of judgment is misled. We have to deal here with nothing but the transcendental illusion, which touches principles never even intended to be applied to experience, which might give us a test of their correctness, — an illusion which, in spite of all the warnings of criticism, tempts us far beyond the em- pirical use of the categories, and deludes us with the mere dream of an extension of the pure understanding. All principles the application of which is entirely confined within the limits of possible experience, we [p. 296] shall call immanent ; those, on the contrary, which tend to transgress those limits, transcendent. I do not mean by this the transcendental use or abuse of the categories, which is a mere fault of the faculty of the judgment, not being as yet sufficiently subdued by criticism nor sufficiently attentive to the limits of the sphere within which alone the pure understanding has full play, but real principles which call upon us to break down all those barriers, and to claim a perfectly new territory, which nowhere recognises any demarcation at all. Here transcendental and transcendent do not mean the same thing. The principles of the pure understanding, which we explained before, are meant to be only of empirical, and not of transcendental application, that is, they cannot Transcendental Dialectic 241 transcend the limits of experience. A principle, on the contrary, which removes these landmarks, nay, insists on our transcending them, is called transcendent. If our critique succeeds in laying bare the illusion of those pre- tended principles, the other principles of a purely em- pirical use may, in opposition to the former, be called immanent. Logical illusion, which consists in a mere imitation of the forms of reason (the illusion of sophistic syllo- gisms), arises entirely from want of attention to logical rules. It disappears at once, when our attention [p. 297] is roused. Transcendental illusion, on the contrary, does not disappear, although it has been shown up, and its worthlessness rendered clear by means of transcendental criticism, as, for instance, the illusion inherent in the proposition that the world must have a beginning in time. The cause of this is that there exists in our reason (considered subjectively as a faculty of human knowledge) principles and maxims of its use, which have the appearance of objective principles, and lead us to mistake the subjective necessity of a certain connection of our concepts in favour of the understanding for an objective necessity in the determination of things by themselves. This illusion is as impossible to avoid as it is to prevent the sea from appearing to us higher at a distance than on the shore, because we see it by higher rays of light ; or to prevent the moon from ap- pearing, even to an astronomer, larger at its rising, although he is not deceived by that illusion. Transcendental Dialectic must, therefore, be content to lay bare the illusion of transcendental judgments and guarding against its deceptions — but it will never sue- j 242 Transcendental Dialectic ceed in removing the transcendental illusion (like the logical), and putting an end to it altogether, [p. 298] For we have here to deal with a natural and inevitable illusion, which itself rests on subjective principles, repre- senting them to us as objective, while logical Dialectic, in removing sophisms, has to deal merely with a mis- take in applying the principles, or with an artificial illu- sion produced by an imitation of them. There exists, therefore, a natural and inevitable Dialectic of pure rea- son, not one in which a mere bungler might get entangled from want of knowledge, or which a sophist might arti- ficially devise to confuse rational people, but one that is inherent in, and inseparable from human reason, and which, even after its illusion has been exposed, will never cease to fascinate our reason, and to precipitate it into momentary errors, such as require to be removed again and again. 2. Of Pure Reason, as the Seat of Transcendental Illusion A. Of Reason in General All our knowledge begins with the senses, proceeds thence to the understanding, and ends with reason. There is nothing higher than reason, for working up the material of intuition, and comprehending it under the highest unity of thought. As it here becomes [p. 299] necessary to give a definition of that highest faculty of knowledge, I begin to feel considerable misgivings. There is of reason, as there is of the understanding, a purely formal, that is logical use, in which no account is taken of the contents of knowledge ; but there is also a real use, in so far as reason itself contains the origin of cer- Transce?idental Dialectic 243, tain concepts and principles, which it has not borrowed either from the senses or from the understanding. The former faculty has been long defined by logicians as the faculty of mediate conclusions, in contradistinction to im- mediate ones {consequentiae immediatae) ; but this does not help us to understand the latter, which itself produces concepts. As this brings us face to face with the division of reason into a logical and a transcendental faculty, we must look for a higher concept for this source of know- ledge, to comprehend both concepts : though, according to the analogy of the concepts of the understanding, we may expect that the logical concept will give us the key to the transcendental, and that the table of the functions of the former will give us the genealogical outline of the con- cepts of reason. In the first part of our transcendental logic we defined the understanding as the faculty of rales, and we now distinguish reason from it, by calling it the facility of principles. [p. 300] The term principle is ambiguous, and signifies com- monly some kind of knowledge only that may be used as a principle, though in itself, and according to its origin, it is no principle at all. Every general proposition, even though it may have been derived from experience (by induction), may serve as a major in a syllogism of reason ; but it is not on that account a principle. Mathematical axioms, as, for instance, that between two points there can be only one straight line, constitute even general know- ledge a priori, and may therefore, with reference to the cases which can be brought under them, rightly be called principles. Nevertheless it would be wrong to say, that this property of a straight line, in general and by itself, 244 Transcendental Dialectic is known to us from principles, for it is known from pure intuition only. / I shall therefore call it knowledge from principles, whenever we know the particular in the general, by means of concepts. Thus every syllogism of reason is a form of deducing some kind of knowledge from a prin- ciple, because the major always contains a concept which enables us to know, according to a principle, everything that can be comprehended under the conditions of that concept. As every general knowledge may serve as a major in such a syllogism, and as the understanding supplies such general propositions a priori, these no doubt may, with reference to their possible use, be called principles. [p. 301] But, if we consider these principles of the pure under- standing in themselves, and according to their origin, we find that they are anything rather than knowledge from concepts. They would not even be possible a priori, unless we relied on pure intuition (in mathematics) or on conditions of a possible experience in general. That everything which happens has a cause, can by no means be concluded from the concept of that which happens ; on the contrary, that very principle shows in what man- ner alone we can form a definite empirical concept of that which happens. It is impossible therefore for the understanding to sup- ply us with synthetical knowledge from concepts, and it is really that kind of knowledge which I call principles abso- lutely ; while all general propositions may be called prin- ciples relatively. It is an old desideratum, which at some time, however distant, may be realised, that, instead of the endless Transcendental Dialectic 245 variety of civil laws, their principles might be discovered, for thus alone the secret might be found of what is called simplifying legislation. Such laws, however, are only limitations of our freedom under conditions by which it always agrees with itself ; they refer to something which is entirely our own work, and of which we ourselves can be the cause, by means of these concepts. But that objects in themselves, as for instance material nature, should be subject to principles, and be determined accord- [p. 302] ing to mere concepts, is something, if not impossible, at all events extremely contradictory. But be that as it may (for on this point we have still all investigations before us), so much at least is clear, that knowledge from princi- ples (by itself) is something totally different from mere knowledge of the understanding, which, in the form of a principle, may no doubt precede other knowledge, but which by itself (in so far as it is synthetical) is not based on mere thought, nor contains anything general, according to concepts. If the understanding is a faculty for producing unity among phenomena, according to rules, reason is the faculty for producing unity among the rules of the understanding, according to principles. Reason therefore never looks directly to experience, or to any object, but to the under- standing, in order to impart a priori through concepts to its manifold kinds of knowledge a unity that may be called the unity of reason, and is very different from the unity which can be produced by the understanding. This is a general definition of the faculty of reason, so far as it was possible to make it intelligible without the help of illustrations, which are to be given hereafter. 246 Transcendental Dialectic B. Of the Logical Use of Reason [p. 303] A distinction is commonly made between what is im- mediately known and what is only inferred. That in a figure bounded by three straight lines there are three angles, is known immediately, but that these angles to- gether are equal to two right angles, is only inferred. As we are constantly obliged to infer, we grow so accustomed to it, that in the end we no longer perceive this difference, and as in the case of the so-called deceptions of the senses, often mistake what we have only inferred for something perceived,,' mmediately. In every syllogism there is first a fundamental proposition ; secondly, another deduced from it ; and lastly, the conclusion (consequence), according to which the truth of the latter is indissolubly connected with the truth of the former. If the judgment or the conclusion is so clearly contained in the first that it can be inferred from it without the mediation or intervention of a third representation, the conclusion is called immediate (conse- quentia immediata) : though I should prefer to call it a conclusion of the understanding. But if, besides the fun- damental knowledge, another judgment is required to bring out the consequence, then the conclusion is called a conclusion of reason. In the proposition 'all men are mortal,' the following propositions are contained : some men are mortal ; or some mortals are men ; or nothing that is immortal is a man. These are therefore im- [p. 304] mediate inferences from the first. The proposition, on the contrary, all the learned are mortal, is not contained in the fundamental judgment, because the concept of learned does not occur in it, and can only be deduced from it by means of an intervening judgment. Transcendental Dialectic 247 In every syllogism I first think a rule (the major) by means of the understanding. I then bring some special knowledge under the condition of the rule (the minor) by means of the faculty of judgment, and I finally determine my knowledge through the predicate of the rule (con- clusio), that is, a priori, by means of reason. It is there- fore the relation represented by the major proposition, as the rule, between knowledge and its condition, that con- stitutes the different kinds of syllogism. Syllogisms are therefore threefold, like all judgments, differing from each other in the manner in which they express the relation of knowledge in the understanding, namely, categorical, hy- pothetical, and disjunctive. If, as often happens, the conclusion is put forward as a judgment, in order to see whether it does not follow from other judgments by which a perfectly different object is conceived, I try to find in the understanding the assertion of that conclusion, in order to see whether it does -not ex- ist in it, under certain conditions, according to a general rule. If I find such a condition, and if the object of the conclusion can be brought under the given [p. 305] condition, then that conclusion follows from the rule which is valid for other objects of k?iow ledge also. Thus we see that reason, in forming conclusions, tries to reduce the great variety of the knowledge of the understanding to the smallest number of principles (general conditions), and thereby to produce in it the highest unity. C. Of the Pure Use of Reason The question to which we have at present to give an answer, though a preliminary one only, is this, whether reason can be isolated and thus constitute by itself an 248 Transcendental Dialectic independent source of concepts and judgments, which spring from it alone, and through which it has reference to objects, or whether it is only a subordinate faculty for imparting a certain form to any given knowledge, namely, a logical form, a faculty whereby the cognitions of the understanding are arranged among themselves only, and lower rules placed under higher ones (the condition of the latter comprehending in its sphere the condition of the former) so far as all this can be done by their comparison. Variety of rules with unity of principles is a requirement of reason for the purpose of bringing the understanding into perfect agreement with itself, just as the understand- ing brings the variety of intuition under concepts, and thus imparts to intuition a connected form. Such a prin- ciple however prescribes no law to the objects [p. 306] themselves, nor does it contain the ground on which the possibility of knowing and determining objects depends. It is merely a subjective law of economy, applied to the stores of our understanding; having for its purpose, by means of a comparison of concepts, to reduce the general use of them to the smallest possible number, but without giving us a right to demand of the objects themselves such a uniformity as might conduce to the comfort and the extension of our understanding, or to ascribe to that maxim any objective validity. In one word, the question is, whether reason in itself, that is pure reason, contains synthetical principles and rules a priori, and what those principles are ? The merely formal and logical procedure of reason in syllogisms gives us sufficient hints as to the ground on which the transcendental principle of synthetical know- ledge, by means of pure reason, is likely to rest. Transcendental Dialectic 249 First, a syllogism, as a function of reason, does not refer to intuitions in order to bring them under rules (as the understanding does with its categories), but to con- cepts and judgments. Although pure reason refers in the end to objects, it has no immediate relation to them and their intuition, but only to the understanding and its judg- ments, these having a direct relation to the [p. 307] senses and their intuition, and determining their objects. Unity of reason is therefore never the unity of a possible experience, but essentially different from it, as the unity of the understanding. That everything which happens has a cause, is not a principle discovered or prescribed by reason, it only makes the unity of experience possible, and borrows nothing from reason, which without this relation to possible experience could never, from mere concepts, have prescribed such a synthetical unity. Secondly. Reason, in its logical employment, looks for the general condition of its judgment (the conclusion), and the syllogism produced by reason is itself nothing but a judgment by means of bringing its condition under a gen- eral rule (the major). But as this rule is again liable to the same experiment, reason having to seek, as long as possible, the condition of a condition (by means of a pro- syllogism), it is easy to see that it is the peculiar principle of reason (in its logical use) to find for every condi- tioned knowledge of the understanding the unconditioned, whereby the unity of that knowledge may be completed. This logical maxim, however, cannot become a principle of pure reason, unless we admit that, whenever the condi- tion is given, the whole series of conditions, subordinated to one another, a series, which consequently is [p. 308] itself unconditioned, is likewise given (that is, is contained in the object and its connection). 2^0 Transcendental Dialectic Such a principle of pure reason, however, is evidently synthetical; for analytically the conditioned refers no doubt to some condition, but not to the unconditioned. From this principle several other synthetical propositions also must arise of which the pure understanding knows nothing; because it has to deal with objects of a possible experience only, the knowledge and synthesis of which are always conditioned. The unconditioned, if it is really to be admitted, has to be especially considered with regard to all the determinations which distinguish it from whatever is conditioned, and will thus supply material for many a synthetical proposition a priori. The principles resulting from this highest principle of pure reason will however be transcendent, with regard to all phenomena ; that is to say, it will be impossible ever to make any adequate empirical use of such a principle. It will thus be completely different from all principles of the understanding, the use of which is entirely immanent and directed to the possibility of experience only. The task that is now before us in the transcendental Dialectic which has to be developed from sources deeply hidden in the human reason, is this : to discover the correctness or otherwise the falsehood of the principle that the series of conditions (in the synthesis of phenomena, or of objective thought in general) extends to the unconditioned, and what consequences result therefrom with regard to the empirical use of the understanding: — to rind [p. 309] out whether there is really such an objectively valid prin- ciple of reason, and not only, in place of it, a logical rule which requires us, by ascending to ever higher conditions, to approach their completeness, and thus to bring the highest unity of reason, which is possible to us, into our Transcendental Dialectic 251 knowledge : to find out, I say, whether, by some miscon- ception, a mere tendency of reason has not been mistaken for a transcendental principle of pure reason, postulating, without sufficient reflection, absolute completeness in the series of conditions in the objects themselves, and what kind of misconceptions and illusions may in that case have crept into the syllogisms of reason, the major proposition of which has been taken over from pure reason (being perhaps a petitio rather than a postulatum), and which ascend from experience to its conditions. We shall divide it into two parts, of which the first will treat of the tran- scendent concepts of pure reason, the second of transcendent and dialectical syllogisms. TRANSCENDENTAL DIALECTIC [p. 310] BOOK I OF THE CONCEPTS OF PURE REASON Whatever may be thought of the possibility of con- cepts of pure reason, it is certain that they are not simply obtained by reflection, but by inference. Concepts of the understanding exist a priori, before experience, and for the sake of it, but they contain nothing but the unity of reflec- tion applied to phenomena, so far as they are necessarily intended for a possible empirical consciousness. It is through them alone that knowledge and determination of an object become possible. They are the first to give material for conclusions, and they are not preceded by any concepts a priori of objects from which they could them- selves be deduced. Their objective reality however de- pends on this, that because they constitute the intellectual form of all experience, it is necessary that their application should always admit of being exhibited in experience. The very name, however, of a concept of reason gives a kind of intimation that it is not intended to be limited to experience, because it refers to a kind of knowledge of which every empirical knowledge is a part only (it may be, 252 Transcendental Dialectic 253 the whole of possible experience or of its empir- [p. 311] ical synthesis) : and to which all real experience belongs, though it can never fully attain to it. Concepts of reason serve for conceiving or comprehending ; concepts of the understanding for understanding (perceptions). If they contain the unconditioned, they refer to something to which all experience may belong, but which itself can never become an object of experience; — something to which reason in its conclusions from experience leads up, and by which it estimates and measures the degree of its own empirical use, but which never forms part of empirical synthesis. If such concepts possess, notwithstanding, objective validity, they may be called conceptus ratiocinati (concepts legitimately formed) ; if they have only been surreptitiously obtained, by a kind of illusory conclusion, they may be called conceptus ratiocinantes (sophistical concepts). But as this subject can only be fully treated in the chapter on the dialectical conclusions of pure rea- son, we shall say no more of it now, but shall only, as we gave the name of categories to the pure concepts of the understanding, give a new name to the concepts of pure reason, and call them transcendental ideas, a name that has now to be explained and justified. [p. 312] 254 Transcendental Dialectic TRANSCENDENTAL DIALECTIC BOOK I First Section Of Ideas in Gene?'al In spite of the great wealth of our languages, a thought- ful mind is often at a loss for an expression that should square exactly with its concept ; and for want of which he cannot make himself altogether intelligible, either to others or to himself. To coin new words is to arrogate to oneself legislative power in matters of language, a proceed- ing which seldom succeeds, so that, before taking so des- perate a step, it is always advisable to look about, in dead and learned languages, whether they do not contain such a concept and its adequate expression. Even if it should happen that the original meaning of the word had become somewhat uncertain, through carelessness on the part of its authors, it is better nevertheless to determine and fix the meaning which principally belonged to it (even if it should remain doubtful whether it was originally used exactly in that meaning), than to spoil our labour by becoming unintelligible. Whenever therefore there exists one single word only for a certain concept, which, in its received meaning, exactly covers that concept, and when it is of [p. 313] great consequence to keep that concept distinct from other related concepts, we ought not to be lavish in using it nor Transcendental Dialectic 255 employ it, for the sake of variety only, as a synonyme in the place of others, but carefully preserve its own pecul- iar meaning, as otherwise it may easily happen that the expression ceases to attract special attention, and loses itself in a crowd of other words of very different import, so that the thought, which that expression alone could have preserved, is lost with it. From the way in which Plato uses the term idea, it is easy to see that he meant by it something which not only was never borrowed from the senses, but which even far transcends the concepts of the understanding, with which Aristotle occupied himself, there being nothing in experi- ence corresponding to the ideas. With him the ideas are archetypes of things themselves, not only, like the cate- gories, keys to possible experiences. According to his opinion they flowed out from the highest reason, which however exists no longer in its original state, but has to recall, with difficulty, the old but now very obscure ideas, which it does by means of reminiscence, commonly called philosophy. I shall not enter here on any literary discus- sions in order to determine the exact meaning which the sublime philosopher himself connected with that expres- sion. I shall only remark, that it is by no [p. 314] means unusual, in ordinary conversations, as well as in written works, that by carefully comparing the thoughts uttered by an author on his own subject, we succeed in understanding him better than he understood himself, because he did not sufficiently define his concept, and thus not only spoke, but sometimes even thought, in opposition to his own intentions. Plato knew very well that our faculty of knowledge was filled with a much higher craving than merely to 256 Transcendental Dialectic spell out phenomena according to a synthetical unity, and thus to read and understand them as experience. He knew that our reason, if left to itself, tries to soar up to knowledge to which no object that experience may give can ever correspond ; but which nevertheless is real, and by no means a mere cobweb of the brain. Plato discovered his ideas principally in what is prac- tical, 1 that is, in what depends on freedom, which again belongs to a class of knowledge which is a [p. 315] peculiar product of reason. He who would derive the concept of virtue from experience, and would change what at best could only serve as an example or an im- perfect illustration, into a type and a source of know- ledge (as many have really done), would indeed transform virtue into an equivocal phantom, changing according to times and circumstances, and utterly useless to serve as a rule. Everybody can surely perceive that, when a person is held up to us as a model of virtue, we have always in our own mind the true original with which we compare this so-called model, and estimate it accord- ingly. The true original is the idea of virtue, in regard to which all possible objects of experience may serve as examples (proofs of the practicability, in a certain degree, of that which is required by the concept of reason), but never as archetypes. That no man can ever act up to 1 It is true, however, that he extended his concept of ideas to speculative knowledge also, if only it was pure, and given entirely a priori. He extended it even to mathematics, although they can have their object nowhere but in possible experience. In this I cannot follow him, nor in the mystical deduc- tion of his ideas, and in the exaggerations which led him, as it were, to hypos- tasise them, although the high-flown language which he used, when treating of this subject, may well admit of a milder interpretation, and one more in accordance with the nature of things. Transcendental Dialectic 257 the pure idea of virtue does not in the least prove the chimerical nature of that concept ; for every judgment as to the moral worth or unworth of actions is possi- ble by means of that idea only, which forms, therefore, the necessary foundation for every approach to moral perfection, however far the impediments inherent in human nature, to the extent of which it is difficult to determine, may keep us removed from it. The Platonic Republic has been supposed to [p. 316] be a striking example of purely imaginary perfection. It has become a byword, as something that could exist in the brain of an idle thinker only, and Brucker thinks it ridiculous that Plato could have said that no prince could ever govern well, unless he participated in the ideas. We should do better, however, to follow up this thought and endeavour (where that excellent philosopher leaves us without his guidance) to place it in a clearer light by our own efforts, rather than to throw it aside as useless, under the miserable and very dangerous pretext of its impracticability. A constitution founded on the greatest possible human freedom, according to laws which enable the freedom of each individual to exist by the side of the freedom of others (without any regard to the highest possible human happiness, because that must necessarily follow by itself), is, to say the least, a necessary idea, on which not only the first plan of a constitution or a state, but all laws must be based, it being by no means necessary to take account from the beginning of existing impediments, which may owe their origin not so much to human nature itself as to the actual neglect of true ideas in legislation. For nothing can be more mischievous and more unworthy a philoso- 258 Transcendental Dialectic pher than the vulgar appeal to what is called adverse experience, which possibly might never have existed, if at the proper time institutions had been framed accord- ing to those ideas, and not according to crude [p. 317] concepts, which, because they were derived from ex- perience only, have marred all good intentions. The more legislation and government are in harmony with that idea, the rarer, no doubt, punishments would become; and it is therefore quite rational to say (as Plato did), that in a perfect state no punishments would be neces- sary. And though this can never be realised, yetv the idea is quite correct which sets up this maximum as an archetype, in order thus to bring our legislative constitu- tions nearer and nearer to the greatest possible perfection. Which may be the highest degree where human nature must stop, and how wide the chasm may be between the idea and its realisation, no one can or ought to deter- mine, because it is this very freedom that may be able to transcend any limits hitherto assigned to it. It is not only, however, where human reason asserts its free causality and ideas become operative agents (with regard to actions and their objects), that is to say, in the sphere of ethics, but also in nature itself, that Plato rightly discovered clear proofs of its origin from ideas. A plant, an animal, the regular plan of the cosmos (most likely therefore the whole order of nature), show clearly that they are possible according to ideas only; [p. 318] and that though no single creature, under the singular conditions of its existence, can fully correspond with the idea of what is mo'st perfect of its kind (as little as any individual man with the idea of humanity, which, for all that, he carries in his mind as the archetype of all his Transcendental Dialectic 259 actions), those ideas are nevertheless determined through- out in the highest understanding each by itself as un- changeable, and are in fact the original causes of things, although it can only be said of the whole of them, con- nected together in the universe, that it is perfectly adequate to the idea. If we make allowance for the exaggerated expression, the effort of the philosopher to ascend from the mere observing and copying of the physical side of nature to an architectonic system of it, teleologically, that is according to ideas, deserves re- spect and imitation, while with regard to the principles of morality, legislation, and religion, where it is the ideas themselves that make experience of the good possible, though they can never be fully realised in experience, such efforts are of very eminent merit, which those only fail to recognise who attempt to judge it accord- ing to empirical rules, the very validity of which, as principles, was meant to be denied by Plato. With re- gard to nature, it is experience no doubt which supplies us with rules, and is the foundation of all truth : with regard to moral laws, on the contrary, experience is, alas ! but the source of illusion ; and it is altogether reprehen- sible to derive or limit the laws of what we [p. 319] ought to do according to our experience of what has been done. Instead of considering these subjects, the full develop- ment of which constitutes in reality the peculiar character and dignity of philosophy, we have to occupy ourselves at present with a task less brilliant, though not less use- ful, of building and strengthening the foundation of that majestic edifice of morality, which at present is under- mined by all sorts of mole-tracks, the work of our reason, 260 Transcendental Dialectic which thus vainly, but always with the same confidence, is searching for buried treasures. It is our duty at pres- ent to acquire an accurate knowledge of the transcenden- tal use of the pure reason, its principles and ideas, in order to be able to determine and estimate correctly their influence and value. But before I leave this preliminary introduction, I beg those who really care for philosophy (which means more than is commonly supposed), if they are convinced by what I have said and shall still have to say, to take the term idea, in its original meaning, under their special protection, so that it should no longer be lost among other expressions, by which all sorts of representa- tions are loosely designated, to the great detriment of philosophy. There is no lack of names adequate to express every kind of representation, without our having to encroach on the property of others. I shall [p. 320] give a graduated list of them. The whole class may be called representation {irpraescntatio). Under it stands con- scious representation, perception (pereeptio). A perception referring to the subject only, as a modification of his state, is se?isation (sensatio), while an objective sensation is called knowledge, cognition (cognitio). Cognition is either intuition or concept (intnitus vel conceptus). The former refers immediately to an object and is singular, the latter refers to it mediately, that is, by means of a characteristic mark that can be shared by several things in common. A concept is either empirical or pure, and the pure concept, so far as it has its origin in the understanding only (not in the pure image of sensibility) is called notion (notio). A concept formed of notions and transcending all possible experience is an idea, or a concept of reason. To any one who has once accustomed himself to these distinctions, it II Transcendental Dialectic 261 must be extremely irksome to hear the representation of red colour called an idea, though it could not even be rightly called a notion (a concept of the understanding). TRANSCENDENTAL DIALECTIC [p- 321] BOOK I Second Section Of Transce7idental Ideas We had an instance in our transcendental Analytic, how the mere logical form of our knowledge could con- tain the origin of pure concepts a priori, which represent objects antecedently to all experience, or rather indicate a synthetical unity by which alone an empirical knowledge of objects becomes possible. The form of judgments (changed into a concept of the synthesis of intuitions) gave us the categories that guide and determine the use of the understanding in every experience. We may ex- pect, therefore, that the form of the syllogisms, if referred to the synthetical unity of intuitions, according to the manner of the categories, will contain the origin of cer- tain concepts a priori, to be called concepts of pure reason, or transcendental ideas, which ought to determine the use of the understanding within the whole realm of experience, according to principles. The function of reason in its syllogisms consists in the universality of cognition, according to concepts, and the syllogism itself is in reality a judgment, deter- [p. 322] mined a priori in the whole extent of its condition. The 262 Transcendental Dialectic proposition ' Caius is mortal,' might be taken from experi- ence, by means of the understanding only. But what we want is a concept, containing the condition under which the predicate (assertion in general) of that judgment is given (here the concept of man), and after I have arranged it under this condition, taken in its whole extent (all men are mortal), I proceed to determine accordingly the know- ledge of my object (Caius is mortal). What we are doing therefore in the conclusion of a syl- logism is to restrict the predicate to a certain object, after we have used it first in the major, in its whole extent, under a certain condition. This completeness of its ex- tent, in reference to such a condition, is called universality (universalitas) ; and to this corresponds, in the synthesis of intuitions, the totality (universitas) of conditions. The transcendental concept of reason is, therefore, nothing but the concept of the totality of the conditions of any- thing given as conditioned. As therefore the uncondi- tioned alone renders a totality of conditions possible, and as conversely the totality of conditions must always be unconditioned, it follows that a pure concept of reason in general may be explained as a concept of the uncondi- tioned, so far as it contains a basis for the synthesis of the conditioned. As many kinds of relations as there are, which [p. 323] the understanding represents to itself by means of the categories, so many pure concepts of the reason we shall find, that is, first, the unco?iditioned of the categorical syn- thesis in a subject ; secondly, the unconditioned of the hypothetical synthesis of the members of a series ; thirdly, the unconditioned of the disjunctive synthesis of the parts of a system. Transcendc7ital Dialectic 263 There are exactly as many kinds of -syllogisms, each of which tries to advance by means of pro-syllogisms to the unconditioned : the first to the subject, which itself is no longer a predicate ; the second to the presupposition, which presupposes nothing else ; and the third to an aggregate of the members of a division, which requires nothing else, in order to render the division of the concept complete. Hence the pure concepts of reason implying totality in the synthesis of the conditions are necessary, at least as problems, in order to carry the unity of the understanding to the unconditioned, if that is possible, and they are founded in the nature of human reason, even though these transcendental concepts may be without any proper application in concreto, and thus have no utility beyond bringing the understanding into a direction where its application, being extended as far as possible, is brought throughout in harmony with itself. Whilst speaking here of the totality of condi- [p. 324] tions, and of the unconditioned, as the common title of all the concepts of reason, we again meet with a term which we cannot do without, but which, by long abuse, has become so equivocal that we cannot employ it with safety. The term absolute is one of those few words which, in their original meaning, were fitted to a concept, which afterwards could not be exactly fitted with any other word of the same language, and the loss of which, or what is the same, the loose employment of which, entails the loss of the concept itself, and that of a concept with which reason is constantly occupied, and cannot dis- pense with without real damage to all transcendental in- vestigations. At present the term absolute is frequently used simply in order to indicate that something applies 264 Transcendental Dialectic to an object, considered in itself, and thus as it were inter- nally. In this way absolutely possible would mean that something is possible in itself (interne), which in reality is the least that could be said of it. It is sometimes used also to indicate that something is valid in all respects (without limitation), as people speak of absolute sovereignty. In this way absolutely possible would mean that which is possible in all respects, and this is again the utmost that could be said of the possibility of a thing. It is true that these two significations [p. 325] sometimes coincide, because something that is internally impossible is impossible also in every respect, and there- fore absolutely impossible. But in most cases they are far apart, and I am by no means justified in concluding that, because something is possible in itself, it is possible also in every respect, that is, absolutely possible. Nay, with regard to absolute necessity, I shall be able to show hereafter that it by no means always depends on internal necessity, and that the two cannot therefore be considered synonymous. No doubt, if the opposite of a thing is in- trinsically impossible, that opposite is also impossible in every respect, and the thing itself therefore absolutely necessary. But I cannot conclude conversely, that the opposite of what is absolutely necessary is internally impossible, or that the absolute necessity of things is the same as an internal necessity. For in certain cases that internal necessity is an entirely empty expression, with which we cannot connect the least concept, while that of the necessity of a thing in every respect (with regard to all that is possible) implies very peculiar deter- minations. As therefore the loss of a concept which has acted a great part in speculative philosophy can never Transcendental^ Dialectic 265 be indifferent to philosophers, I hope they will also take some interest in the definition and careful preservation of the term with which that concept is connected. I shall therefore use the term absolute in this [p. 326] enlarged meaning only, in opposition to that which is valid relatively and in particular respects only, the latter being restricted to conditions, the former free from any restrictions whatsoever. It is then the absolute totality in the synthesis of conditions at which the transcendental concept of reason aims, nor does it rest satisfied till it has reached that which is unconditioned absolutely and in every respect. Pure reason leaves everything to the understanding, which has primarily to do with the objects of intuition, or rather their synthesis in imagination. It is only the absolute totality in the use of the concepts of the understanding, which reason reserves for itself, while trying to carry the synthetical unity, which is realised in the category, to the absolutely unconditioned. We might therefore call the latter the unity of the phenomena in reason, the former, which is expressed by the category, the unity in the understanding. Hence reason is only con- cerned with the use of the understanding, not so far as it contains the basis of possible experience (for the abso- lute totality of conditions is not a concept that can be used in experience, because no experience is uncondi- tioned), but in order to impart to it a direction towards a certain unity of which the understanding knows nothing, and which is meant to comprehend all acts of the under- standing, with regard to any object, into an [p. 327] absolute whole. On this account' the objective use of the pure concepts of reason must always be transcendent: 266 Transcendental Dialectic while that of the pure concepts of the understanding must always be immanent, being by its very nature restricted to possible experience. By idea I understand the necessary concept of reason, to which the senses can supply no corresponding object. The concepts of reason, therefore, of which we have been speaking, are transcendental ideas. They are concepts of pure reason, so far as they regard all empirical knowledge as determined by an absolute totality of conditions. They are not mere fancies, but supplied to us by the very nature of reason, and referring by necessity to the whole use of the understanding. They are, lastly, transcendent, as overstepping the limits of all experience which can never supply an object adequate to the transcendental idea. If we speak of an idea, we say a great deal with respect to the object (as the object of the pure understanding) but very little with respect to the subject, that is, with respect to its reality under empirical conditions, because an idea, being the concept of a maximum, can never be adequately given in concrete As the latter is really the whole aim in the merely speculative use of reason, and as [p. 328] the mere approaching a concept, which in reality can never be reached, is the same as if the concept were missed altogether, people, when speaking of such a con- cept, are wont to say, it is an idea only. Thus one might say, that the absolute whole of all phenomena is an idea only, for as we can never form a representation of such a whole, it remains a problem without a solution. In the practical use of the understanding, on the contrary, where we are only concerned with practice, according to rules, the idea of practical reason can always be realised in con- creto, although partially only ; nay, it is the indispensable Transcendental Dialectic 267 condition of all practical use of reason. The practical realisation of the idea is here always limited and deficient, but these limits cannot be denned, and it always remains under the influence of a concept, implying absolute com- pleteness and perfection. The practical idea is therefore in this case truly fruitful, and, with regard to practical conduct, indispensable and necessary. In it pure reason becomes a cause and active power, capable of realising what is contained in its concept. Hence we cannot say of wisdom, as if contemptuously, that it is an idea only, but for the very reason that it contains the idea of the necessary unity of all possible aims, it must determine all practical acts, as an original and, at least, limitative condition. Although we must say that all transcendental [p. 329] concepts of reason are ideas only, they are not therefore to be considered as superfluous and useless. For although we cannot by them determine any object, they may never- theless, even unobserved, supply the understanding with a canon or rule of its extended and consistent use, by which, though no object can be better known than it is accord- ing to its concepts, yet the understanding may be better guided onwards in its knowledge, not to mention that they may possibly render practicable a transition from physical to practical concepts, and thus impart to moral ideas a certain strength and connection with the specu- lative knowledge of reason. On all this more light will be thrown in the sequel. For our present purposes we are obliged to set aside a consideration of these practical ideas, and to treat of reason in its speculative, or rather, in a still more limited sense, its purely transcendental use. Here we must fol- 268 Traftscendental Dialectic low the same road which we took before in the deduction of the categories ; that is, we must consider the logical form of all knowledge of reason, and see whether, per- haps, by this logical form, reason may become a source of concepts also, which enable us to regard objects in themselves, as determined synthetically a priori in rela- tion to one or other of the functions of reason. Reason, if considered as a faculty of a certain [p. 330] logical form of knowledge, is the faculty of concluding, that is, of judging mediately, by bringing the condition of a possible under the condition of a given judgment. The given judgment is the general rule {major). Bring- ing the condition of another possible judgment under the condition of the rule, which may be called subsumption, is the minor, and the actual judgment, which contains the assertion of the rule in the subsumed case, is the conclu- sion. We know that the rule asserts something as gen- eral under a certain condition. The condition of the rule is then found to exist in a given case. Then that which, under that condition, was asserted as generally valid, has to be considered as valid in that given case also, which complies with that condition. It is easy to see therefore that reason arrives at knowledge by acts of the under- standing, which constitute a series of conditions. If I arrive at the proposition that all bodies are changeable, only by starting from a more remote knowledge (which does not yet contain the concept of body, but a condition of such a concept only), namely, that all which is com- posite is changeable ; and then proceed to something less remotely known, and depending on the former, namely, that bodies are composite ; and, lastly, only advance to a third proposition, connecting the more remote knowledge Transcendental Dialectic 269 (changeable) with the given case, and conclude that bodies therefore are changeable, we see that we have [p. 331] passed through a series of conditions (premisses) before we arrived at knowledge (conclusion). Every series, the exponent of which (whether of a categorical or hypothet- ical judgment) is given, can be continued, so that this procedure of reason leads to ratiocinatio polysyllogistica, a series of conclusions which, either on the side of the conditions {per prosy llogismos) or of the conditioned {per episy llogismos), may be continued indefinitely. It is soon perceived, however, that the chain or series of prosyllogisms, that is, of knowledge deduced on the side of reasons or conditions of a given knowledge, in other words, the ascending series of syllogisms, must stand in a very different relation to the faculty of reason from that of the descending series, that is, of the progress of reason on the side of the conditioned, by means of episyl- logisms. For, as in the former case the knowledge em- bodied in the conclusion is given as conditioned only, it is impossible to arrive at it by means of reason in any other way except under the supposition at least that all the members of the series on the side of the conditions are given (totality in the series of premisses), because it is under that supposition only that the contemplated judg- ment a priori is possible ; while on the side of the condi- tioned, or of the inferences, we can only think [p. 332] of a growing series, not of one presupposed as complete or given, that is, of a potential progression only. Hence, when our knowledge is considered as conditioned, reason is constrained to look upon the series of conditions in the ascending line as complete, and given in their totality. But if the same knowledge is looked upon at the same 270 Transcendental Dialectic time as a condition of other kinds of knowledge, which constitute among themselves a series of inferences in a descending line, it is indifferent to reason how far that progression may go a parte posteriori, or whether a total- ity of the series is possible at all, because such a series is not required for the conclusion in hand, which is suffi- ciently determined and secured on grounds a parte priori. Whether the series of premisses on the side of the con- ditions have a something that stands first as the highest condition, or whether it be without limits a parte priori, it must at all events contain a totality of conditions, even though we should never succeed in comprehending it ; and the whole series must be unconditionally true, if the conditioned, which is considered as a consequence result- ing from it, is to be accepted as true. This is a demand of reason which pronounces its knowledge as determined a priori and as necessary, either in itself, and in that case it requires no reasons, or, if derivative, as a member of a series of reasons, which itself is unconditionally true. TRANSCENDENTAL DIALECTIC [P- 333] BOOK I Third Section System of Transcendental Ideas We are not at present concerned with logical Dialectic, which takes no account of the contents of knowledge, and has only to lay bare the illusions in the form of syllogisms, Transcendental Dialectic 271 but with transcendental Dialectic, which is supposed to contain entirely a priori the origin of certain kinds of knowledge, arising from pure reason, and of certain de- duced concepts, the object of which can never be given empirically, and which therefore lie entirely outside the domain of the pure understanding. We gathered from the natural relation which must exist between the tran- scendental and the logical use of our knowledge, in syllogisms as well as in judgments, "that there must be three kinds of dialectic syllogisms, and no more, corre- sponding to the three kinds of conclusion by which reason may from principles arrive at knowledge, and that in all of these it is the object of reason to ascend from the condi- tioned synthesis, to which the understanding is always restricted, to an unconditioned synthesis, which the under- standing can never reach. The relations which all our representations share in common are, 1st, relation to the subject; 2ndly, the rela- tion to objects, either as phenomena, or as ob- [p. 334] jects of thought in general. If we connect this subdivi- sion with the former division, we see that the relation of the representations of which we can form a concept or an idea can only be threefold: 1st, the relation to the sub- ject ; 2ndly, the relation to the manifold of the phenom- enal object ; 3rdly, the relation to all things in general. All pure concepts in general aim at a synthetical unity of representations, while concepts of pure reason (tran- scendental ideas) aim at unconditioned synthetical unity of all conditions. All transcendental ideas therefore can be arranged in three classes : the first containing the absolute (unconditioned) unity of the thinking subject ; the seco7id the absolute unity of the series of conditions of 2J2 Tra nscendental Dialectic phenomena ; the third the absolute unity of the conditio?i of all objects of thought in general. The thinking subject is the object-matter of psychology, the system of all phenomena (the world) the object-matter of cosmology, and the being which contains the highest condition of the possibility of all that can be thought (the Being of all beings), the object-matter of theology. Thus it is pure reason which supplies the idea of a transcen- dental science of the soul (psychologia ratioualis), of a tran- scendental science of the world (cosmologia rationalis), and, lastly, of a transcendental science of God (theologia transcendentalis) . Even the mere plan of any [p. 335] one of these three sciences does not come from the under- standing, even if connected with the highest logical use of reason, that is, with all possible conclusions, leading from one of its objects (phenomenon) to all others, and on to the most remote parts of any possible empirical synthesis, — but is altogether a pure and genuine product or rather problem of pure reason. What kinds of pure concepts of reason arc comprehended under these three titles of all transcendental ideas will be fully explained in the following chapter. They follow the thread of the categories, for pure reason never refers direct to objects, but to the concepts of objects framed by the understanding. Nor can it be rendered clear, except hereafter in a detailed explanation, how first, reason simply by the synthetical use of the same function which it employs for categorical syllogisms is necessarily led on to the concept of the absolute unity of the thinking sub- ject ; secondly, how the logical procedure in hypothetical syllogisms leads to the idea of something absolutely uncon- ditioned, in a series of given conditions, and how, thirdly, Transcende7ital Dialectic 273 the mere form of the disjunctive syllogism produces necessarily the highest concept of reason, that of a Being of all beings ; a thought which, at first sight, seems extremely paradoxical. [p. 336] No objective deduction, like that given of the categories, is possible with regard to these transcendental ideas ; they are ideas only, and for that very reason they have no relation to any object corresponding to them in experi- ence. What we could undertake to give was a subjective deduction 1 of them from the nature of reason, and this has been given in the present chapter. We can easily perceive that pure reason has no other aim but the absolute totality of synthesis on the side of conditions (whether of inherence, dependence, or concur- rence), and that it has nothing to do with the absolute completeness on the part of the conditioned. It is the former only which is required for presupposing the whole series of conditions, and thus presenting it a priori to the understanding. If once we have a given condition, com- plete and unconditioned itself, no concept of reason is required to continue the series, because the understanding takes by itself every step downward from the condition to the conditioned. The transcendental ideas therefore serve only for ascending in the series of conditions till they reach the unconditioned, that is, the principles. With regard to descending to the conditioned, there is no doubt a widely extended logical use which our reason [p. 337] may make of the rules of the understanding, but no tran- scendental one ; and if we form an idea of the absolute totality of such a synthesis (by progresses), as, for 1 Instead of Anleitung read Ableitung. 274 Transcendental Dialectic instance, of the whole series of all future changes in the world, this is only a thought (ens rationis) that may be thought if we like, but is not presupposed as necessary by reason. For the possibility of the conditioned, the totality of its conditions only, but not of its consequences, is pre- supposed. Such a concept therefore is not one of the transcendental ideas, with which alone we have to deal. Finally, we can perceive, that there is among the tran- scendental ideas themselves a certain connection and unity by which pure reason brings all its knowledge into one system. There is in the progression from our know- ledge of ourselves (the soul) to a knowledge of the world, and through it to a knowledge of the Supreme Being, something so natural that it looks like the logical progres- sion of reason from premisses to a conclusion. 1 Whether there exists here a real though hidden relationship, such as we saw before between the logical and transcendental use of reason, is also one of the questions the answer to which can only be given in the progress of these investi- gations. For the present we have achieved what we wished to achieve, by removing the transcen- [p. 338] dental concepts of reason, which in the systems of other philosophers are generally mixed up with other concepts, "without being distinguished even from the concepts of the understanding, out of so equivocal a position ; by being able to determine their origin and thereby at the same time their number, which can never be exceeded, and by thus bringing them into a systematic connection, marking out and enclosing thereby a separate field for pure reason. 1 See Supplement XXVI. TRANSCENDENTAL DIALECTIC BOOK II OF THE DIALECTICAL CONCLUSIONS OF PURE REASON One may say that the object of a purely transcendental idea is something of which we have no concept, although the idea is produced with necessity according to the origi- nal laws of reason. Nor is it possible indeed to form of an object that should be adequate to the demands of reason, a concept of the understanding, that is, a concept which could be shown in any possible experience, and rendered intuitive. It would be better, however, and less [p. 339] liable to misunderstandings, to say that we can have no knowledge of an object corresponding to an idea, but a problematic concept only. The transcendental (subjective) reality, at least of pure concepts of reason, depends on our being led to such ideas by a necessary syllogism of reason. There will be syllo- gisms therefore which have no empirical premisses, and by means of which we conclude from something which we know to something else of which we have no concept, and to which, constrained by an inevitable illusion, we never- theless attribute objective reality. As regards their result, 275 276 Transcendental Dialectic such syllogisms are rather to be called sophistical than rational, although, as regards their origin, they may claim the latter name, because they are not purely fictitious or accidental, but products of the very nature of reason. They are sophistications, not of men, but of pure reason itself, from which even the wisest of men cannot escape. All he can do is, with great effort, to guard against error, though never able to rid himself completely of an illusion which constantly torments and mocks him. Of these dialectical syllogisms of reason there are there- fore three classes only, that is as many as the ideas to which their conclusions lead. In the syllogism [p. 340] of \hz first class, I conclude from the transcendental con- cept of the subject, which contains nothing manifold, the absolute* unity of the subject itself, of which however I have no concept in this regard. This dialectical syllogism I shall call the transcendental paralogism. The second class of the so-called sophistical syllogisms aims at the transcendental concept of an absolute totality in the series of conditions to any given phenomenon ; and I conclude from the fact that my concept of the uncon- ditioned synthetical unity of the series is always self- contradictory on one side, the correctness of the opposite unity, of which nevertheless I have no concept either. The state of reason in this class of dialectical syllogisms, I shall call the antinomy of pure reason. Lastly, according to the third class of sophistical syl- logisms, I conclude from the totality of conditions, under which objects in general, so far as they can be given to me, must be thought, the absolute synthetical unity of all con- ditions of the possibility of things in general ; that is to say, I conclude from things which I do not know accord- Transceiidcntal Dialectic 277 ing to their mere transcendental 1 concept, a Being of all beings, which I know still less through a transcendental concept, and of the unconditioned necessity of which I can form no concept whatever. This dialectical syllogism of reason I shall call the ideal of pure reason. 1 Transcendent is a misprint. TRANSCENDENTAL DIALECTIC [p. 341] BOOK II CHAPTER I OF THE PARALOGISMS OF PURE REASON The logical paralogism consists in the formal faulti- ness of a conclusion, without any reference to its con- tents. But a transcendental paralogism arises from a transcendental cause, which drives us to a formally false conclusion. Such a paralogism, therefore, depends most likely on the very nature of human reason, and produces an illusion which is inevitable, though not insoluble. We now come to a concept which was not inserted in our general list of transcendental concepts, and yet must be reckoned with them, without however changing that table in the least, or proving it to be deficient. This is the concept, or, if the term is preferred, the judgment, / think. It is easily seen, however, that this concept is the vehicle of all concepts in general, therefore of transcen- dental concepts also, being always comprehended among them, and being itself transcendental also, though with- out any claim to a special title, inasmuch as it serves only to introduce all thought, as belonging to conscious- 278 i Transcendefital Dialectic 279 ness. However free that concept may be from all that is empirical (impressions of the senses), it serves [p. 342] nevertheless to distinguish two objects within the nature of our faculty of representation. /, as thinking, am an object of the internal sense, and am called soul. That which is an object of the external senses is called body. The term /, as a thinking being, signifies the object of psychology, which may be called the rational science of the soul, supposing that we want to know nothing about the soul except what, independent of all experience (which determines the I more especially and in concrete), can be deduced from the concept of I, so far as it is present in every act of thought. Now the rational science 'of the soul is really such an undertaking ; for if the smallest empirical element of my thought or any particular perception of my internal state were mixed up with the sources from which that science derives its materials, it would be an empirical, ,and no longer a purely rational science of the soul. There is therefore a pretended science, founded on the single propo- sition of / think, and the soundness or unsoundness of which may well be examined in this place, according to the principles of transcendental philosophy. It should not be objected that even in that proposition, which ex- presses the perception of oneself, I have an internal experience, and that therefore the rational science of the soul, which is founded on it, can never be quite [p. 343] pure, but rests, to a certain extent, on an empirical prin- ciple. For this inner perception is nothing more than the mere apperception, / think, without which even all transcendental concepts would be impossible, in which we really say, I think the substance, I- think the cause, 280 Transcendental Dialectic etc. This internal experience in general and its pos- sibility, or perception in general and its relation to other perceptions, there being no special distinction or em- pirical determination of it, cannot be regarded as em- pirical knowledge, but must be regarded as knowledge of the empirical in general, and falls therefore under the investigation of the possibility of all experience, which investigation is certainly transcendental. The smallest object of perception (even pleasure and pain), if added to the general representation of self-consciousness, would at once change rational into empirical psychology. I think is, therefore, the only text of rational psychology, out of which it must evolve all its wisdom. It is easily seen that this thought, if it is to be applied to any object (my self), cannot contain any but transcendental predi- cates, because the smallest empirical predicate would spoil the rational purity of the science, and its indepen- dence of all experience. We shall therefore follow the thread of the [p. 344] categories, with this difference, however, that as here the first thing which is given is a thing, the I, a thinking being, we must begin with the category of substance, by which a thing in itself is represented, and then proceed backwards, though without changing the respective order of the categories, as given before in our table. The topic of the rational science of the soul, from which has to be derived whatever else that science may contain, is therefore the following.. Transcendental Dialectic 281 I The Soul is substance. II III As regards its quality, simple. As regards the different times in which it exists, numerically identical, that is unity (not plurality) . IV It is in relation to possible objects in space. 1 All concepts of pure psychology arise from [p. 345] these elements, simply by way of combination, and with- out the admixture of any other principle. This sub- stance, taken simply as the object of the internal sense, gives us the concept of immateriality ; and as simple substance, that of incorruptibility ; its identity, as that of an intellectual substance, gives us personality ; and all these three together, spirituality ; its relation to objects in space gives us the concept of commercium (intercourse) with bodies ; the pure psychology thus rep- resenting the thinking substance as the principle of life in matter, that is, as soul (anima), and as the ground of animality ; which again, as restricted by spirituality, gives us the concept of immortality. To these concepts refer four paralogisms of a transcen- 1 The reader, who may not guess at once the psychological purport of these transcendental and abstract terms, or understand why the latter attribute of the soul belongs to the category of existence, will find their full explanation and justification in the sequel. Moreover, I have to apologise for the many Latin expressions which, contrary to good taste, have crept in instead of their native equivalents, not only here, but throughout the whole of the work. My only excuse is, that I thought it better to sacrifice something of the elegance of language, rather than to throw any impediments in the way of real students, by the use of inaccurate and obscure expressions. 282 Transcendental Dialectic dental psychology, which is falsely supposed to be a science of pure reason, concerning the nature of our thinking being. We can, however, use as the foundation of such a science nothing but the single, and in itself per- fectly empty, representation of the /, of which [p. 346] we cannot even say that it is a concept, but merely a consciousness that accompanies all concepts. By this /, or he, or it (the thing), which thinks, nothing is repre- sented beyond a transcendental subject of thoughts = x, which is known only through the thoughts that are its predicates, and of which, apart from them, we can never have the slightest concept, so that we are really turning round it in a perpetual circle, having already to use its representation, before we can form any judgment about it. And this inconvenience is really inevitable, because con- sciousness in itself is not so much a representation, dis- tinguishing a particular object, but really a form of repre- sentation in general, in so far as it is to be called knowledge, of which alone I can say that I think some- thing by it. It must seem strange, however, from the very begin- ning, that the condition under which I think, and which therefore is a property of my own subject only, should be valid at the same time for everything which thinks, and that, depending on a proposition which seems to be em- pirical, we should venture to found the apodictical and general judgment, namely, that everything which thinks is such as the voice of my own consciousness declares it to be within me. The reason of it is, that we are con- strained to attribute a priori to things all the qualities which form the conditions, under which alone [p. 347] we are able to think them. Now it is impossible for me Transcendental Dialectic 283 to form the smallest representation of a thinking being by any external experience, but I can do it through self-con- sciousness only. Such objects therefore are nothing but a transference of my own consciousness to other things, which thus, and thus only, can be represented as thinking beings. The proposition / think is used in this case, how- ever, as problematical only ; not so far as it may contain the perception of an existence (the Cartesian, cogito, ergo sum), but with regard to its mere possibility, in order to see what properties may be deduced from such a simple proposition with regard to its subject, whether such sub- ject exists or not. If our knowledge of thinking beings in general, so far as it is derived from pure reason, were founded on more than the cogito, and if we made use at the same time of observations on the play of our thoughts and the natural laws of the thinking self, derived from them, we should have before us an empirical psychology, which would form a kind of physiology of the internal sense, and perhaps ex- plain its manifestations, but would never help us to under- stand such properties as do not fall under any possible experience (as, for instance, simplicity), or to teach apodic- tically anything touching the nature of thinking beings in general. It would not therefore be a rational psychology. As the proposition / think (taken problemati- [p. 348] cally) contains the form of every possible judgment of the understanding, and accompanies all categories as their vehicle, it must be clear that the conclusions to be drawn from if can only contain a transcendental use of the understanding, which declines all admixture of experience, and of the achievements of which, after what has been said before, we cannot form any very favourable anticipations. 284 Transcendental Dialectic We shall therefore follow it, with a critical eye, through all the predicaments of pure psychology. 1 I The First Paralogism of Substantiality That the representation of which is the absolute subject of our judgments, and cannot be used therefore as the determination of any other thing, is the substance. I, as a thinking being, am the absolute subject of all my possible judgments, and this representation of myself can never be used as the predicate of any other thing. Therefore I, as a thinking being (Soul), am Substance. Criticism of the First Paralogism of Pure' 2 ' Psychology We showed in the analytical portion of transcendental logic, that pure categories, and among them that of sub- stance, have in themselves no objective meaning, unless they rest on some intuition, and are applied to [p. 349] the manifold of such intuitions as functions of synthetical unity. Without this they are merely functions of a judg- ment without contents. I may say of everything, that it is a substance, so far as I distinguish it from what are mere predicates and determinations. Now in all our think- ing the I is the subject, in which thoughts are inherent as determinations only ; nor can that I ever be used as a determination of any other thing. Thus everybody is con- strained to look upon himself as the substance, and on thinking as the accidents only of his being, and determi- nations of his state. 1 All that follows from here to the beginning of the second chapter, is left out in the Second Edition, and replaced by Supplement XXVII. 2 Afterwards transcendental instead of pure. Transcendental Dialectic 285 But what use are we to make of such a concept of a substance ? That I, as a thinking being, continue for my- self, and naturally neither arise nor: perish, is no legitimate deduction from it ; and yet this conclusion would be the only advantage that could be gained from the concept of the substantiality of my own thinking subject, and, but for that, I could do very well without it. So far from being able to deduce these properties from the pure category of substance, we have on the contrary to observe the permanency of an object in our experience and then lay hold of this permanency, if we wish to apply to it the empirically useful concept of substance. In this case, however, we had no experience to lay hold of, but have only formed a deduction from the concept [p. 350] of the relation which all thinking has to the I, as the com- mon subject to which it belongs. Nor should we, what- ever we did, succeed by any certain observation in proving such permanency. For though the I exists in all thoughts, not the slightest intuition is connected with that repre- sentation, by which it might be distinguished from other objects of intuition. We may very well perceive there- fore that this representation appears again and again in every act of thought, but not that it is a constant and per- manent intuition, in which thoughts, as being changeable, come and go. Hence it follows that in the first syllogism of transcen- dental psychology reason imposes upon us an apparent knowledge only, by representing the constant logical sub- ject of thought as the knowledge of the real subject in which that knowledge inheres. Of that subject, however, we have not and cannot have the slightest knowledge, because consciousness is that which alone changes repre- 286 Transcendental Dialectic sentations into thoughts, and in which therefore, as the transcendental subject, all our perceptions must be. found. Beside this logical meaning of the I, we have no know- ledge of the subject in itself, which forms the substratum and foundation of it and of all our thoughts. In spite of this, the proposition that the soul is a substance may well be allowed to stand, if only we see that this concept can- not help us on in the least or teach us any of the ordinary conclusions of rationalising psychology, as, for [p. 351] instance, the everlasting continuance of the soul amid all changes and even in death, and that it therefore signifies a substance in idea only, and not in reality. The Second Paralogism of Simplicity Everything, the action of which can never be consid- ered as the concurrence of several acting things, is simple. Now the Soul, or the thinking I, is such a thing : — Therefore, etc. Criticism of the Second Paralogism of Transcendental Psychology This is the strong (yet not invulnerable) syllogism among all dialectical syllogisms of pure psychology, not a mere sophism contrived by a dogmatist in order to impart a certain plausibility to his assertions, but a syllogism which seems able to stand the sharpest examination and the gravest doubts of the philosopher. It is this : — Every composite substance is an aggregate of many substances, and the action of something composite, or that which is inherent in it as such, is an aggregate of many actions or accidents distributed among many sub- Transcendental Dialectic 287 stances. An effect due to the concurrence of many acting substances is no doubt possible, if that effect is [p. 352] external only (as, for instance, the motion of a body is the combined motion of all its parts). The case is different however with thoughts, if considered as accidents belong- ing to a thinking being within. For suppose it is the composite which thinks, then every part of it would contain a part of the thought, and all together only the whole of it. This however is self-contradictory. For as representations, distributed among different beings (like the single words of a verse), never make a whole thought (a verse), it is impossible that a thought should be inher- ent in something composite, as such. Thought therefore is possible only in a substance which is not an aggregate of many, and therefore absolutely simple. 1 What is called the nervns probandi in this argument lies in the proposition that, in order to constitute a thought, the many representations must be comprehended under the absolute unity of the thinking subject. Nobody how- ever can prove this proposition from concepts. For how would he undertake to do it? The proposition [p. 353] that a thought can only be the effect of the absolute unity of a thinking being, cannot be considered as analytical. For the unity of thought, consisting of many representa- tions, is collective, and may, so far as mere concepts are concerned, refer to the collective unity of all co-operating substances (as the movement of a body is the compound movement of all its parts) quite as well as to the absolute unity of the subject. According to the rule of identity 1 It would be very easy to give to this argument the ordinary scholastic dress. But for my purposes it is sufficient to have clearly exhibited, even in a popular form, the ground on which it rests. 288 Transcendental Dialectic it would be impossible therefore to establish the necessity of the presupposition of a simple substance, the thought being composite. That, on the other hand, such a propo- sition might be established synthetically and entirely a priori from mere concepts, no one will venture to affirm who has once understood the grounds on which the possi- bility of synthetical propositions a priori rests, as explained by us before. It is likewise impossible, however, to derive this neces- sary unity of the subject, as the condition of the possi- bility of the unity of every thought, from experience. For experience never supplies any necessity of thought, much less the concept of absolute unity. Whence then do we take that proposition on which the whole psycho- logical syllogism of reason rests? It is manifest that if we wish to represent to ourselves a thinking being, we must put ourselves in its place, and supplant as it were the object which has to be considered by our own subject (which never happens in any [p. 354] other kind of investigation). The reason why we postu- late for every thought absolute unity of the subject is because otherwise we could not say of it, I think (the manifold in one representation). For although the whole of a thought may be divided and distributed under many subjects, the subjective I can never thus be divided and distributed, and it is this I which we presuppose in every thought. As in the former paralogism therefore, so here also, the formal proposition of apperception, I think, remains the sole ground on which rational psychology ventures to undertake the extension of its knowledge. That proposi- tion, however, is no experience, but only the form of Transcendental Dialectic- 289 apperception inherent in, and antecedent to, every expe- rience, that is a purely subjective conditioii, having refer- ence to a possible experience only, but by no means the condition of the possibility of the knowledge of objects, and by no means necessary to the concept of a thinking being in general ; although it must be admitted that we cannot represent to ourselves another intelligent being without putting ourselves in its place with that formula of our consciousness. Nor is it true that the simplicity of my self (as a soul) is really deduced from the proposition, I think, for it is already involved in every thought itself. The proposition / am simple must be considered as the imme- [p. 355] diate expression of apperception, and the so-called syllo- gism of Cartesius, cogito, ergo sum, is in reality tautological, because cogito (sum cogitans) predicates reality immediately. / am simple means no more than that this representation of I does not contain the smallest trace of manifoldness, but is absolute (although merely logical) unity. Thus we see that the famous psychological argument is founded merely on the indivisible unity of a representa- tion, which only determines the verb with reference to a person ; and it is clear that the subject of inherence is designated transcendentally only by the I, which accom- panies the thought, without our perceiving the smallest quality of it, in fact, without our knowing anything about it. It signifies a something in general (a transcendental subject) the representation of which must no doubt be simple, because nothing is determined in it, and nothing- can be represented more simple than by the concept of a mere something. The simplicity however of the repre- sentation of a subject is not therefore a knowledge of the u 290 Transcendental Dialectic simplicity of the subject, because no account whatever is taken of its qualities when it is designated by the entirely empty expression I, an expression that can be applied to every thinking subject. So much is certain therefore that though I [p. 356] always represent by the I an absolute, but only logical, unity of the subject (simplicity), I never know thereby the real simplicity of my subject. We saw that the propo- sition, I am a substance, signified nothing but the mere category of which I must not make any use (empirically) in concreto. In the same manner, I may well say, I am a simple substance, that is, a substance the representation of which contains no synthesis of the manifold ; but that concept, or that proposition also, teaches us nothing at all with reference to myself, as an object of experience, because the concept of substance itself is used as a func- tion of synthesis only, without any intuition to rest on, and therefore without any object, valid with reference to the condition of our knowledge only, but not with refer- ence to any object of it. We shall test the usefulness of this proposition by an experiment. Everybody must admit that the assertion of the simple nature of the soul can only be of any value in so far as it enables me to distinguish the soul from all matter, and thus to except it from that decay to which matter is at all times subject. It is for that use that our proposition is really intended, and it is therefore often expressed by, the soul is not corporeal. If then I can show that, [p. 357] although we allow to this cardinal proposition of rational psychology (as a mere judgment of reason from pure categories) all objective validity (everything that thinks is simple substance), we cannot make the least use of it, Transcendental Dialectic 291 in order to establish the homogeneousness or non-homo- geneousness of soul and matter, this will be the same as if I had relegated this supposed psychological truth to the field of mere ideas, without any real or objective use. We have irrefutably proved in the transcendental ^Es- thetic that bodies are mere phenomena of our external sense, not things by themselves. We are justified there- fore in saying that our thinking subject is not a body, i.e. that, because it is represented by us as an object of the internal sense, it is, so far as it thinks, no object of our external senses, and no phenomenon in space. This means the same as that among external phenomena we can never have thinking beings as such, or ever see their thoughts, their consciousness, their desires, etc., exter- nally. All this belongs to the internal sense. This argu- ment seems indeed so natural and popular that even the commonest understanding has always been led [p. 358] to it, the distinction between souls and bodies being of very early date. But although extension, impermeability, cohesion, and motion, in fact everything that the external senses can give us, cannot be thoughts, feeling, inclination, and de- termination, or contain anything like them, being never objects of external intuition, it might be possible, never- theless, that that something which forms the foundation of external phenomena, and which so affects our sense as to produce in it the representations of space, matter, form, etc., if considered as a noumenon (or better as a transcendental object) might be, at the same time, the subject of thinking, although by the manner in which it affects our external sense it produces in us no intui- tions of representations, will, etc., but only of space and 2Q2 Transcendental Dialectic its determinations. This something, however, is not ex- tended, not impermeable, not composite, because such predicates concern sensibility only and its intuition, when- ever we are affected by these (to us otherwise unknown) objects. These expressions, however, do not give us any information what kind of object it is, but only that, if considered by itself, without reference to the external senses, it has no right to these predicates, peculiar to external appearance. The predicates of the internal sense, on the contrary, such as representation, think- [p. 359] ing, etc., are by no means contradictory to it, so that really, even if we admit the simplicity of its nature, the human soul is by no means sufficiently distinguished from matter, so far as its substratum is concerned, if (as it ought to be) matter is considered as a phenomenon only. If matter were a thing by itself, it would, as a com- posite being, be totally different from the soul, as a simple being. But what we call matter is an external phenome- non only, the substratum of which cannot possibly be known by any possible predicates. I can therefore very well suppose that that substratum is simple, although in the manner in which it affects our senses it produces in us the intuition of something extended, and therefore composite, so that the substance which, with reference to our external sense, possesses extension, might very well by itself possess thoughts which can be represented consciously by its own internal sense. In such wise the same thing which in one respect is called corporeal, would in another respect be at the same time a thinking being, of which though we cannot see its thoughts, we can yet see the signs of them phenomenally. Thus the expres- sion that souls only (as a particular class of substances) Transcendental Dialectic 293 think, would have to be dropt, and we should return to the common expression that men think, that is, [p. 360] that the same thing which, as an external phenomenon, is extended, is internally, by itself, a subject, not composite, but simple and intelligent. But without indulging in such hypotheses, we may make this general remark, that if I understand by soul a being by itself, the very question would be absurd, whether the soul be homogeneous or not with matter which is not a thing by itself, but only a class of repre- sentations within us ; for so much at all events must be clear, that a thing by itself is of a different nature from the determinations which constitute its state only. If, on the contrary, we compare the thinking I, not with matter, but with that object of the intellect that forms the foundation of the external phenomena which we call mat- ter, then it follows, as we know nothing whatever of the matter, that we have no right to say that the soul by itself is different from it in any respect. The simple consciousness is not therefore a knowledge of the simple nature of our subject, so that we might thus distinguish the soul from matter, as a composite being. If therefore, in the only case where that concept might be useful, namely, in comparing myself with objects of external experience, it is impossible to determine the peculiar and distinguishing characteristics of its nature, what is the use, if we pretend to know that the [p. 361] thinking I, or the soul (a name for the transcendental object of the internal sense), is simple ? Such a propo- sition admits of no application to any real object, and can- not therefore enlarge our knowledge in the least. Thus collapses the whole of rational psychology, with 2Q4 Transcendental Dialectic its fundamental support, and neither here nor elsewhere can we hope by means of mere concepts (still less through the mere subjective form of all our concepts, that is, through our consciousness) and without referring these concepts to a possible experience, to extend our know- ledge, particularly as even the fundamental concept of a simple nature is such that it can never be met with in experience, so that no chance remains of arriving at it as a concept of objective validity. The Third Paralogism of Personality Whatever is conscious of the numerical identity of its own self at different times, is in so far a person. Now the Soul, etc. Therefore the Soul is a person. Criticism of the Third Paralogism of Transcendental Psychology Whenever I want to know by experience the numerical identity of an external object, I shall have to [p. 362] attend to what is permanent in that phenomenon to which, as the subject, everything else refers as determination, and observe the identity of the former during the time that the latter is changing. I myself, however, am an object of the internal sense, and all time is but the form of the internal sense. I therefore refer each and all of my suc- cessive determinations to the numerically identical self; and this in all time, that is, in the form of the inner intui- tion of myself. From this point of view, the personality of the soul should not even be considered as inferred, but Transcendental Dialectic 295 as an entirely identical proposition of self-consciousness in time, and that is indeed the reason why it is valid a priori. For it really says no more than this : that dur- ing the whole time, while I am conscious of myself, I am conscious of that time as belonging to the unity of my- self ; and it comes to the same thing whether I say that this whole time is within me as an individual unity, or that I with numerical identity am present in all that time. In my own consciousness, therefore, the identity of person is inevitably present. But if I consider myself from the point of view of another person (as an object of his external intuition), then that external observer con- siders me, first of all, in time, for in the apperception time is really represented in me only. Though he admits, therefore, the I, which at all times accompanies all rep- resentations in my consciousness, and with [p. 363] entire identity, he will not yet infer from it the objective permanence of myself. For as in that case the time in which the observer places me is not the time of my own, but of his sensibility, it follows that the identity which is connected with my consciousness is not therefore con- nected with his, that is, with the external intuition of my subject. The identity of my consciousness at different times is therefore a formal condition only of my thoughts and their coherence, and proves in no way the numerical identity of my subject, in which, in spite of the logical identity of the I, such a change may have passed as to make it impossible to retain its identity, though we may still attribute to it the same name of I, which in every other state, and even in the change of the subject, might yet retain the thought 296 Transcendental Dialectic of the preceding and hand it over to the subsequent subject. 1 Although the teaching of some old schools [p. 364] that everything is in a flux, and nothing in the world permanent, cannot be admitted, if we admit substances, yet it must not be supposed that it can be refuted by the unity of self-consciousness. For we ourselves cannot judge from our own consciousness whether, as souls, we are perma- nent or not, because we reckon as belonging to our own identical self that only of which we are conscious, and therefore are constrained to admit that, during the whole time of which we are conscious, we are one and the same. From the point of view of a stranger, however, such a judgment would not be valid, because, perceiving in the soul no permanent phenomena, except the representation of the I, which accompanies and connects them all, we cannot determine whether that I (being a mere thought) be not in the same state of flux as the other thoughts which are chained together by the I. [p. 3 6 5] It is curious, however, that the personality and what is presupposed by it, namely, the permanence and sub- stantiality of the soul, has now to be proved first. For 1 An elastic ball, which impinges on another in a straight line, communi- cates to it its whole motion, and therefore (if we only consider the places in space) its whole state. If then, in analogy with such bodies, we admit sub- stances of which the one communicates- to the other representations with consciousness, we could imagine a whole series of them, in which the first communicates its state and its consciousness to the second, the second its own state with that of the first substance to a third, and this again all the states of the former, together with its own, and a consciousness of them, to another. That last substance would be conscious of all the states of the previously changed substances, as of its own, because all of them had been transferred to it with the consciousness of them; but for all that it would not have been the same person in all those states. Transcendental Dialectic 297 if we could presuppose these, there would follow, if not the permanence of consciousness, yet the possibility of a permanent consciousness in one and the same subject, and this is sufficient to establish personality which does not cease at once, because its effect is interrupted at the time. This permanence, however, is by no means given us before the numerical identity of ourself, which we infer from identical apperception, but is itself inferred from it, so that, according to rule, the concept of substance, which alone is empirically useful, would have to follow first upon it. But as the identity of person follows by no means from the identity of the I, in the consciousness of all time in which I perceive myself, it follows that we could not have founded upon it the substantiality of the soul. Like the concept of substance and of the simple, how- ever, the concept' of personality also may remain, so long as it is used as transcendental only, that is, as a concept of the unity of the subject which is otherwise unknown to us, but in the determinations of which there is an uninter- rupted connection by apperception. In this sense such a concept is necessary for practical purposes and sufficient, but we can never pride ourselves on it as helping to ex- pand our knowledge of our self by means of [p. 366] pure reason, which only deceives us if we imagine that we can concluse an uninterrupted continuance of the subject from the mere concept of the identical self. That concept is only constantly turning round itself in a circle, and does not help us as with respect to any question which aims at synthetical knowledge. What matter may be as a thing by itself (a transcendental object) is entirely unknown to us ; though we may observe its permanence as a phenome- non, since it is represented as something external. When 298 Transcendental Dialectic however I wish to observe the mere I during the change of all representations, I have no other correlative for my comparisons but again the I itself, with the general condi- tions of my consciousness. I cannot therefore give any but tautological answers to all questions, because I put my concept and its unity in the place of the qualities that belong to me as an object, and thus really take for granted what was wished to be known. The Fourth Paralogism of Ideality {with Regard to Exter- nal Relations) That, the existence of which can only be inferred as a cause of given perceptions, has a doubtful existence only:— [p. 367] All external phenomena are such that their existence cannot be perceived immediately, but that we can only infer them as the cause of given perceptions : — Therefore the existence of all objects of the external senses is doubtful. This uncertainty I call the ideality of external phenomena, and the doctrine of that ideality is called idealism ; in comparison with which the other doc- trine, which maintains a possible certainty of the objects of the external senses, is called dualism. Criticism of the Fourth Paralogism of Transcendental Psychology We shall first have to examine the premisses. We are perfectly justified in maintaining that that only which is within ourselves can be perceived immediately, and that my own existence only can be the object of a mere percep- tion. The existence of a real object therefore outside me Transcetidental Dialectic 299 (taking this word in its intellectual meaning) can never be given directly in perception, but can only be added in thought to the perception, which is a modification of the internal sense, and thus inferred as its external cause. Hence Cartesius was quite right in limiting all perception, in the narrowest sense, to the proposition, I (as a thinking being) am. For it must be clear that, as what [p. 368] is without is not within me, I cannot find it in my apper- ception ; nor hence in any perception which is in reality a determination of apperception only. In the true sense of the word, therefore, I can never perceive external things, but only from my own internal perception infer their existence, taking the perception as an effect of which something external must be the proxi- mate cause. An inference, however, from a given effect to a definite cause is always uncertain, because the effect may be due to more than one cause. Therefore in refer- ring a perception to its cause, it always remains ,doubtful whether that cause be internal or external ; whether in fact all so-called external perceptions are not a mere play of our external sense, or point to real external objects as their cause. At all events the existence of the latter is infer- ential only, and liable to all the dangers of inferences, while the object of the internal sense (I myself with all my representations) is perceived immediately, and its existence cannot be questioned. It must not be supposed, therefore, that an idealist is he who denies the existence of external objects of the senses ; all he does is to deny that it is known by immedi- ate perception, and to infer that we can never [p. 369] become perfectly certain of their reality by any experience whatsoever. 300 Transcendental Dialectic Before I expose the deceptive illusion of our paralogism, let me remark that we must necessarily distinguish two kinds of idealism, the transcendental and the empirical. Transcendental idealism teaches that all phenomena are representations only, not things by themselves, and that space and time therefore are only sensuous forms of our intuition, not determinations given independently by them- selves or conditions of objects, as things by themselves. Opposed to this transcendental idealism, is a transcendental realism, which considers space and time as something in itself (independent of our sensibility). Thus the tran- scendental realist represents all external phenomena (admitting their reality) as things by themselves, existing independently of us and our sensibility, and therefore existing outside us also, if regarded according to pure con- cepts of the understanding. It is this transcendental realist who afterwards acts the empirical idealist, and who, after wrongly supposing that the objects of the senses, if they are to be external, must have an existence by them- selves, and without our senses, yet from this point of view considers all our sensuous representations insufficient to render certain the reality of their objects. The transcendental idealist, on the contrary, [p. 370] may well be an empirical realist, or, as he is called, a dualist ; that is, he may admit the existence of matter, without taking a step beyond mere self-consciousness, or admitting more than the certainty of representations within me, that is the cogito, ergo sum. For as he con- siders matter, and even its internal possibility, as a phe- nomenon only, which, if separated from our sensibility, is nothing, matter with him is only a class of representa- tions (intuition) which are called external, not as if they Transcendental Dialectic 301 referred to objects external by themselves, but because they refer perceptions to space, in which everything is outside everything else, while space itself is inside us. We have declared ourselves from the very beginning in favour of this transcendental idealism. In our system, therefore, we need not hesitate to admit the existence of matter on the testimony of mere self-consciousness, and to consider it as established by it (sc. the testimony), in the same manner as the existence of myself, as a thinking being. I am conscious of my representations, and hence they exist as well as I myself, who has these representa- tions. External objects, however (bodies), are phenomena only, therefore nothing but a class of my representations, the objects of which are something by means of these repre- sentations only, and apart from them nothing, [p. 371] External things, therefore, exist by the same right as I myself, both on the immediate testimony of my self-con- sciousness, with this difference only, that the representa- tion of myself, as a thinking subject, is referred to the internal sense only, while the representations which in- dicate extended beings are referred to the external sense also. With reference to the reality of external objects, I need as little trust to inference, as with reference to the reality of the object of my internal sense (my thoughts), both being nothing but representations, the immediate perception (consciousness) of which is at the same time a sufficient proof of their reality. The transcendental idealist is, therefore, an empirical realist, and allows to matter, as a phenomenon, a reality which need not be inferred, but may be immediately per- ceived. The transcendental realism, on the contrary, is necessarily left in doubt, and obliged to give way to 3