%'W-\S V---V V^v iO" * ,- V * (3. 5) • *P a"* *j6P\M%kx"* o>- 4/ 4 O \P Tj . » - .0 *-> ' • . • .** r^ <» - • * ^b a* • *a < 'bV > -^ ^ >j W •'* ♦' Digitized by the Internet Archive in 2011 with funding from The Library of Congress http://www.archive.org/details/outlineofsirwillOOmurr LIMITS OF RELIGIOUS THOUGHT EXAMINED. Lectures, delivered in the Oxford University Pulpit, on the " Bampton Foundation." By Kev. H. Lon- gueville Mansel. With Copious Notes translated for the American edition. 12mo, cloth, 1.50. " This is incomparably the ablest contribution to the cause of sound learning and treasures of exact thought, which has recently been added to the common stock. In clear and simple terms, with strong sense and abundant learning, positions are laid down which will affect the science of thinking for a long future, and which administer a strong and wholesome corrective tc the flippant materialism of lie times." — Congregationalist. HISTORICAL EVIDENCES OF THE TRUTH OF THE SCRIPTURE Rec- ords, stated anew, with Special reference to the Doubts and Discoveries of Modern times. Lectures delivered in the Oxford University Pulpit, on the Bampton Foundation. By Geo. Rawlinson, M.A. With the Copious Notes translated for the American edition. 12mo, cloth, 1.75 " Theconsumate learning, judgment, and general ability displayed by Mr. Rawlinson in his edition »f Herodotus are exhibited in this work also." — North American Review. 11 In its special application of secular history to the illustration of the sacred record ; it possesses an Interest and value for Biblical students, which can hardly be expressed in words. We Bee not how any man of candor can read this volume and retain a doubt as to the authenticity of the historical books of the Old Testament." — N. Y. Independent. PROGRESS OF DOCTRINE IN THE NEW TESTAMENT; Lectures on the Bampton Foundation. By Thomas Dehany Bernard, Exeter College. 12mo, cloth, 1.50. "A book of remarkablo ability aud interest. No production within the present century has appeared more fresh in matter, original In style, or of more permanent value to the cause of truth, than this." bis can l^rtas. LIFE OF CHRIST HISTORICALLY CONSIDERED. The Hulsean Lectures with Notes Critical, Historical, and Explanatory. By C. J. Ellicott, B.D. Royal 12mo, cloth, 1.75 " Prof. Ellicott has shown himself to be a true scholar. He is doubtless among the very first of all English speaking scholars of the present generation." — New Englander. " Every page seems to be the result of deep thoug'jt and careful investigation." — Evang. Review. " This is no common book. It is evidently the production of a master mind." — United Presbyterian. INTRODUCTION TO THE STUDY OF THE GOSPELS. With Historical and Explanatory notes. By Brooke Foss Westcott, Trinity College, Cam- bridge. With an Introduction by Prof. H. B. Hackett, D.D. Royal 12mo, cloth, 2.00. '-The work is a striking combination of originality with erudition, its argument Is masterlv."- Philadelphii Lutheran. OUTLINE OF SIE WILLIAM HAMILTON'S PHILOSOPHY. OUTLINE SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON'S PHILOSOPHY. A TEXT-BOOK FOR STUDENTS. BY THE REV. J. CLARK MURRAY, PROFESSOR OF MENTAL AND MORAL PHILOSOPHY, QUEEN'S UNIVERSITY, CANADA. * ©BEttfj an Entroljucti0n, BY THE REV. JAMES McCOSH, LL.D, PRESIDENT OF PRINCETON COLLEGE, NEW JERSEY. BOSTON: GOULD .A. N D LINCOLN, 69 WASHINGTON STREET. NEW YORK: SHELDON AND COMPANY. CINCINNATI : G. S. BLANCHAliD & CO. TOENOTO, ONT. : ADAM, STEVENSON & CO. 18 70. Entered according to Act of Congress, in the year 1870, by GOULD AND LINCOLN, In the office of the Librarian of Congress, at Washington. Rockwell & CrjURcniLL, Printers, Boston. &o tfje fHcmorg O F SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON, THIS ESSAY IN THE EXPOSITION OF HIS PHILOSOPHY Is Inscribed BY A GBATEFUL PUPIL. 'On Earth there is nothing great but Man: In Man there is nothing great but Mind." PREFACE. °X«c The primary object of this work is to provide a convenient text-book in philosophy. The labors of Sir William Hamilton as a professor formed generally the most powerful influence in the philosophical education of those who came within their reach ; and a similar influence has extended into wider circles through his writings. It seemed to me, therefore, that his philosophy might still be made a valuable instrument of philosophical culture. The chief difficulty, in the way of this lay in the selection of one of his works, suitable for use as a text-book. A very slight acquaintance with these is sufficient to show that none of them by itself presents a complete view of his philosophical opinions in systematic order. 1 The Lectures on Metaphysics, 1 For many readers it may not be unnecessary to enumerate the works of Sir William Hamilton. (1.) His edition of lieicVs Works (1846) contains, besides many valuable footnotes, a number of supplementary dissertations on various philosophical subjects. Only a few of the intended dissertations were ever completed; but since his death his editors have published the fragmentary materials he had collected for the dissertations which had been left unfinished. (2.) The articles which he had contributed to the Edinburgh Review were col- lected into one volume, with numerous additions, under the title of Discussions in Philosophy and Literature, Education and University Reform (1852). (3.) The lectures, which he had been in the habit of delivering to his classes, were published posthumously; the Lectures on Metaphysics, in 1859; the Lectures on Logic, in 1860. IX X PREFACE. which contain the fullest account of his philosophy, and from which, therefore, the largest extracts have been drawn for the present work, besides being devoted mainly to one subdivision of his system, fail to give his matured views, or the matured expression of his views, on some subjects, while the discussion of many points is overladen with a mass of extraneous matter, which is generally confusing to the beginner and unnecessary for the comprehension of Hamilton's own system. I have, therefore, thought it advisable to attempt the systematic ex- hibition of his philosophical opinions without regard to the order or the mode of treatment which he has followed in any of his writings. In doing so, however, it was necessary to adopt some order ; and it seemed to me that I had no right to adopt any other than that which the philosopher has himself suggested in his distribution of the philosophical sciences, 1 though he has nowhere been able to carry it out. This distribution may possess comparatively little merit, and has certainly exerted no influence in directing the course of speculative thought in Europe or America, such as has flowed from Hegel's or from Comte's classification of the sciences ; but the system of Hamilton would be inadequately represented by following any other course than that which I have adopted. With regard to the liberties which I have taken in the composition of this Outline, I may remark, in the first place, that it has frequently been necessary to transfer passages from their original contexts, and that, in doing so, I have introduced them into their new contexts by such connecting particles and phrases as seemed most appropriate. I have l See Lectures on Metaphysics, VII. PREFACE. XI also frequently left out of a passage a feAv words which were not essential to its meaning, especially when they appeared to be intended rather for an audience than for readers. Such slight liberties I have not considered it necessary to indicate. Occasionally, moreover, where Hamilton's editors intimate that he has adopted the language of another writer for the expression of his views, I have not preserved the marks of quotation, as these might have been confusing to a student. In one or two instances, however, I have ventured on an independent or abridged statement of Hamilton's doctrine ; but such passages have been uniformly pointed out in the footnotes. It may also be added that I am responsible for the tabular classifications at pages 83 and 88, as well as for some slight alterations of expression in the others. With these ex- planations it may be said that the text is wholly Hamilton's. As an exposition of Hamilton's Philosophy, the Outline con- tains some imperfections which were unavoidable. Even in the language these may at times be traced : for, while the volume is in the form of a text-book for private study, the largest portion of it is extracted from lectures which were intended to be delivered to a class ; and though I have endeavored to leave out all the most obtrusive expressions of direct address, it was impossible to destroy the general form of phraseology. Some passages, moreover, undoubtedly suffer from being used as an exposition of a doctrine in a different connection and in a different point of view from that in which they were originally written. I believe, however, that no liberty which I have taken in the composition of the book has originated a single misrepresentation of Hamilton's opinions, while the whole volume offers a fair representation of his complete XII PREFACE. philosophical system. At the same time I do not take the responsibility of recommending that my book should be ac- cepted as a final authority in any important question concerning Hamilton's doctrine, without referring to the works of the philosopher himself. I have, therefore, uniformly subjoined, within parentheses, a distinct reference to the place in his works from which each passage of the Outline is extracted; and, to prevent mistake, I may observe that each reference embraces the whole passage between it and the previous reference. I am not without hope, therefore, that, while the Outline may serve the purpose for which it is primarily designed, it may also be of some use to those who desire an acquaintance with Sir "William Hamilton's system of philosophy, and have found the state of his writings a formidable obstacle in their way. I have only to add that the work is merely expository, and that, therefore, while I have avoided any criticism of Hamilton's doctrines, I do not always undertake the responsibility of their defence. I believe, however, that the teaching of philosophy must still, at least, be conducted by helping the student to master the varying points of view from which the different representative systems look out on the field of speculation. For this reason, I trust that a slight service has been rendered to the cause of philosophical education by presenting, with a completeness which has never before been attempted, the system of Sir William Hamilton. J. CLARK MURRAY. Queen's College, Ont., October, 1870. CONTENTS. PAOB Introductory Note, by Dr. James McCosh . .' . . xxiii INTRODUCTION. § 1. The General Nature of Philosophy ...... 19 (A) Nominal Definition of Philosophy 19 (B) Real Definition of Philosophy 20 I. Historical or Empirical Knowledge . . . .21 II. Philosophical or Scientific Knowledge ... 22 Philosophy, strictly so called, is the Science of Mind . 24 § 2. Classification of the Philosophical Sciences ..... 25 Tabular View of tho Classification 27 FIRST DIVISION OF PHILOSOPHY. PHENOMENAL PSYCHOLOGY. INTRODUCTION TO PHENOMENAL PSYCHOLOGY. CHAPTER I. DEFINITION OF THE SCIENCE, AND EXPLANATION OF TERMS IN THE DEFINITION. Phenomenal Psychology defined 31 Terms of tho definition explained 31 * XIII XIV CONTENTS. (A) Terms expressing the Manifestations of Mind . . .32 (B) Terms expressing the Unknown Basis of Mental Manifesta- tions 34 CHAPTER II. CONSCIOUSNESS IN GENERAL. § 1. Consciousness: Its General Nature ....... 37 § 2. Consciousness: Its Special Conditions ...... 40 (A) Undisputed Conditions : — I. It is an actual knowledge. II. It is an immediate knowledge. III. It supposes dis- crimination. IV. It involves judgment. V. It implies memory .......... 40 (B) Disputed, whether consciousness is & particular faculty, or the universal condition, of intelligence . . . .42 I. It cannot be discriminated from the other faculties . 43 II. It is cognizant of their objects, as well as of their operations 45 § 3. Consciousness : Its Evidence and Authority ..... 46 (A) It is the principal source from which all knowledge of mental phenomena must be obtained. — Phrenology ... 47 (B) Authority of its Testimony. — Two points of view, under which its deliverances may be considered . . . .48 Rules for applying its Testimony . . ■ . . . .53 §4. Consciousness: Classification of its Phenomena . . . .53 I. Knowledges; II. Feelings; III. Conations . . 54 Criticism of Objections to the Classification: I. That the three classes are not co-ordinate; II. That there can be only two fundamental powers of mind 56 CONTENTS. XV FIRST PART OF PHENOMENAL PSYCHOLOGY. PHENOMENOLOGY OF THE COGNITIONS. INTRODUCTION. CLASSIFICATION OF THE COGNITIVE FACULTIES. What is meant by a mental power ........ 61 Distribution of the Faculties of Knowledge 63 Tabular View of the Distribution 66 CHAPTER I. THE PRESENTATIVE FACULTY. § 1. External Perception ......... 67 (A) Distinction between Sensation and Perception ... 68 Law : Sensation and Perception are always in the inverse ratio of each jther 69 Illustration of the Law: I. From a comparison of the dif- ferent senses ; II. From comparing different impressions of the same sense, as different (1) in degree, (2) in kind 69 (B) Distinction in the Qualities of Matter 73 The qualities as contemplated from the point of view of Sense and from that of the Understanding ... 74 I. Deduction of the Primary Qualities .... 75 II. Induction of the Secundo-Primary Qualities ... 78 III. Induction of the Secondary Qualities .... 81 Tabular Classification of the Qualities of Matter ... 83 The Object in Perception is either a primary quality or the quasi-primary phasis of a secundo-primary ... 84 In Perception, therefore, two facts are always given, that I am, and that something different from me exists . . 86 Theories of Perception, which arise from the acceptance or non-acceptance of these facts in their integrity . . 87 XVI CONTENTS. Tabular Classification of these theories .... 88 §2. Self- Consciousness . . . . . . . . . ^ 90 Self-consciousness contrasted with Perception . . . .90 The fundamental forms of Self-Consciousness are Time and Self, as those of Perception are Time and Space. Two difficulties removed 91 CHAPTER II. THE CONSERVATIVE FACULTY. The relation of the Conservative Faculty to the Presentative on the one hand, and to the Reproductive and Representative on the other . 94 § 1. The fact of Retention ......... 96 That Cognitions, in the interval between acquisition and repro- duction, continue to subsist in the mind, though out of con- sciousness, is proved I. From External Perception, by (1} the Sense of Sight, (2) the Sense of Hearing, (3) the other Senses . . . .96 II. From the Association of Ideas 99 III. From our Acquired Habits and Dexterities. Three theories to account for these 100 1. That of Hartley and Reid criticised . . .101 2. That of Stewart criticised 102 3. Hamilton's own theory explained . . . . 103 § 2. Explanation of Retention ........ 104 Retention is explained by the self-activity of the mind, the real difficulty being, not how a mental activity endures, but how it ever vanishes 105 Inferences. 1. That Retention extends to all the mental phenomena . . 107 2. That to explain Retention, physiological hypotheses are un- necessary. Dependence of memory on the state of the brain 107 CONTENTS. XVII CHAPTER III. THE REPRODUCTIVE FACULTY. Reproduction governed by Laws 110 Distinction between the primary and the secondary Laws of Reproduction 111 § 1. Primary Laws of Reproduction 112 (A) General. I. Law of Possible Reproduction .112 II. Laws of Actual Reproduction 112 1. Law of Repetition . . . . . . .114 2. Law of Redintegration 114 (B) Special. I. Law of Similars 115 II. Law of Contrast 116 III. Law of Coadjacency 117 § 2. Secondary Laws of Reproduction ....... 117 ' General Law of Preference acts 117 (A) By relation to the thought suggesting, giving . . . 118 I. Law of Immediacy 118 II. Law of Homogeneity .118 (B) By relation to the mind, giving the Law of Facility. What thoughts are more easily suggested 118 § 3. Distinction of Suggestion and Reminiscence . . . . .120 Reminiscence explained 120 CHAPTER IV. THE REPRESENTATIVE FACULTY. This faculty is determined to represent by (1) the Reproductive Faculty, (2) the Faculty of Comparison. Imagination Productive Imagination is therefore Representation plus Comparison Representation is not limited to sensible objects Dreaming, Somnambulism, Reverie The Organs of Imagination the same as those of Sense . 126 127 128 128 131 XVIH CONTENTS. CHAPTER V. THE ELABORATIVB FACULTY. § 1. Primary Acts of Comparison ....... 134 1. Affirmation of Existence 134 2. Discrimination of the Ego and the Non-ego .... 134 3. Judgment of Agreement or Dissimilarity .... 135 4. Recognition of Substance . . . . . . .135 5. Recognition of Cause 135 § 2. Classification . . . . . • . . . .136 (A) Collective Notions 136 (B) Abstraction, poetical and scientific . . . . .138 (C) Generalization; General Notions; Their Extension and Com- ' prehension 140 What is the object of Consciousness, when we employ a gen- eral term ? Antagonistic doctrines of the Nominalists and the Conceptualists 142 Conceptualism originates in ambiguity of terms . . 144 Theories on the question of the Primum Cognitum . . 145 1. That terms are first expressive of individual objects . 145 2. That they first expross classes ..... 146 3. That they first express neither the precisely general nor the determinately particular, but the vague and con- fused. (Hamilton's theory) 147 § 3. Judgment . 150 § 4. Reasoning ........... 153 I. Deductive Reasoning, 1. In Comprehension; 2. In Extension . 153 II. Inductive Reasoning, 1. In Comprehension; 2. In Extension 158 Reasoning, which is synthetic in Extension, is analytic in Comprehension. Confused application of the terms Analysis and Synthesis 160 CONTENTS. XIX CHAPTER VI. THE REGULATIVE FACULTY. This faculty is the source of necessary or a priori cognitions . . . 162 Criteria of such cognitions: 1. Incomprehensibility; 2. Simplicity; 3. Necessity and Universality; 4. Certainty .... 164 The conditions of positive thought are: 1. Non-contradiction, and 2. Relativity 165 § 1. Non-contradiction involves the three laws of : 1. Identity; 2. Con- tradiction; 3. Excluded Middle 166 § 2. Relativity implies that we can know neither the unconditionally limited (the Absolute) nor the unconditionally unlimited (tho Infinite), but only the limited, and the conditionally limited. This condition is brought to bear under two relations : . . . 167 (A) The Relation of Knowledge ....... 169 (B) The Relations of Existence, which are either I. Intrinsic, of Substance and Quality, or . . . 169 II. Extrinsic, comprehending Time, Space, and Degree . 170 Tabular view of the Conditions of Thought 174 APPENDIX TO CHAPTER VI. LAW OF THE CONDITIONED IN ITS APPLICATION TO THE PRIN- CIPLE OF CAUSALITY. Statement and Illustration of the principle 173 Theories to explain the principle explained and criticised . . . 177 Tabular view of these theories 180 SECOND PART OF PHENOMENAL PSYCHOLOGY. PHENOMENOLOGY OF THE FEELINGS. INTRODUCTION. Relation of the Feelings to the Cognitions on the one hand, and the Conations on the other 193 XX CONTENTS. CHAPTER I. ABSTRACT THEORY OF PLEASURE AND PAIN. Definition of Pleasure and Pain 198 Their different kinds : 1. Positive and Negative Pleasure and Pain ; 2. Pain of Restraint and that of Over-exertion .... 199 CHAPTER II. THE ABSTRACT THEORY APPLIED TO THE CONCRETE PHENOMENA. § 1. The Feelings as 'Causes . . . 200 As Causes the feelings are divided into the pleasurable and the painful 200 I. The apparent contradictions to the theory in actual life are really confirmations 200 II. The theory is confirmed by the affections called painful : (1) Grief; (2) Fear; (3) Pity; (4) Enjoyment of tragedies 202 Four general causes which affect the intensity of our Feelings : I. Novelty; II. Contrast; III. Harmony or Discord between coexistent activities; IV. Association 203 § 2. The Feelings as Effects . . ... . . . 20G As effects of the different energies of life, the feelings may be classified in accordance with the different classes of energies. (A) The Sensations, or feelings which accompany the exercise of bodily powers, are divided into (I.) those of Sensus Fixus, and (II.) those of Se?isus Vagus 206 (B) The Sentiments, or feelings which accompany the exercise of the higher mental powers, comprehend I. The contemplative, the concomitants of our cognitive powers, which are divided into (1) those of the sub- sidiary faculties; (a) Self-consciousness and (b) Im- agination, and (2) those of the elaborative faculty, CONTENTS. XXI (a) by itself, (b) in conjunction with imagination. The last include : i. the Beautiful; ii. the Sublime; iii. the Picturesque ....... 208 II. The practical, the concomitants of our conative powers, comprehending those that relate to (1) self-preserva- tion, (2) enjoyment of existence, (3) preservation of the species, (4) our tendency to perfection, (5) the moral law 219 THIRD PART OF PHENOMENAL PSYCHOLOGY. PHENOMENOLOGY OF THE CONATIONS. Terms to express these phenomena 225 They are divided into (A) Desires, blind and fatal tendencies to action .... 226 (B) Volitions, free tendencies to action. The freedom of will is proved (1) directly, (2) indirectly, though it is incon- ceivable (1) because of the Law of the Conditioned, (2) because motiveless volition is morally unaccountable. But the inconceivability does not invalidate the fact, (1) be- cause the causal judgment is merely a mental impotence, (2) because fatalism is equally inconceivable . . . 226 SECOND DIVISION OF PHILOSOPHY. NOMOLOGICAL PSYCHOLOGY. (A) Homology of the Cognitions 231 (B) Homology of the Feelings 232 (C) Nomology of the Conative Powers 233 XXII CONTENTS. THIRD DIVISION OF PHILOSOPHY. INFERENTIAL PSYCHOLOGY. CHAPTER I. EXISTENCE IN GENERAL. The axiom, that we have no knowledge of existence itself, but merely of its phenomena, explained in reference to I. Matter, and II. Mind 237 This axiom is divided into two : I. That the properties of existence are not necessarily of the same number as our faculties of apprehending them . . . 240 II. That the properties known are not necessarily known in their native purity . . . . . . . . .242 Certain inferences, however, regarding existence itself may be necessi- tated by its phenomena 244 CHAPTER II. EXISTENCE OF GOD AND IMMORTALITY OF THE SOUL. The notion of a God implies not only Omnipotence, but Intelligence and Virtue ; and Virtue involves Freedom 247 The proof of God's existence, therefore, requires the proof of two prop- ositions : I. That the universe is the creation of a free original intelligence 250 II. That the universe is governed not merely by physical, but by moral, laws 252 Value of mental science to theology 253 Evil influences of the exclusive study of physical science . . . 254 Consequences which would result from referring everything to the mechanism of nature 256 INTRODUCTORY NOTE. — »o»io« — Sir William Hamilton was the greatest metaphysician of his age, and his metaphysics will be studied by thinking minds in all coming ages. But his system was not drawn out in a compendious form by himself. In order to find it, students have to search a number of treatises in the shape of reviews, dissertations, class-lectures, notes, and notes upon notes. The stablished metaphysician delights in all this as an exhibition of the working of Hamilton's pene- trating intellect, and because of the value of the seeds which, in the exuberance of his learning, he scatters in his progress. But as he often moves with great rapidity, and turns off at sharp angles into collateral discussions, the younger student is apt to be left behind and to become per- plexed, and he longs to have some guide who may furnish him with a clear and combined view of the philosophy as a whole. This felt want has been supplied in Professor Murray's " Outline of Hamilton's Philosophy." I have carefully read the work in proof, and I am able to say that it furnishes an admirable summary, — clear, cor- XXIV INTRODUCTORY NOTE. rect, and readily intelligible, of the leading doctrines and connections of Hamilton's Philosophy. The account is ren- dered mainly in Hamilton's own language, by one who un- derstands his philosophy, and who has the higher merit of entering thoroughly into the spirit of his great teacher. I have observed that in points in regard to which there have been disputes as to Hamilton's meaning, Professor Murray seems to me to give the proper version. Those who are led by this brief exposition to take a gen- eral view, as from a height to which Professor Murray has conducted them, of the country spread out before them, will be allured, when he has left them, to enter upon a more par- ticular exploration for themselves, when they will find in- numerable scattered ore which could not have a place in a mere Outline. The testimony now given will not be esteemed of less value because it comes from one who feels that Hamilton has often followed Kant's Critical Method too implicitly, and who dissents from his doctrines of Causality, of the Relativity of Knowledge, and of the negative nature of our Idea of the Infinite. JAMES McCOSH. Princeton, New Jersey, U. S., Oct. 1, 1870. INTRODUCTION. THE GENERAL NATURE AND DIVISIONS OF PHILOSOPHY. § 1. THE GENERAL NATURE OF PHILOSOPHY. In commencing a course of philosophical discipline, it is important to obtain, at least, a general notion of what philosophy is. In order to this, there are two questions to be answered : (A) What is the mean- ing of the name? and (£) What is the meaning of the thing? (A) Nominal Definition of Philosophy. Philoso- phy is a term of Greek origin, — it is a compound of of wh i c h the sciences gy, embracing I are (1 .) Ethics and (2.) \ • Politics. (C) Results, of which the science is Inferential Psychology. FIRST DIVISION OF PHILOSOPHY. PHENOMENAL PSYCHOLOGY. INTRODUCTION TO PHENOMENAL PYSCHOLOGY. CHAPTER I. DEFINITION OF THE SCIENCE AND EXPLANATION OF TERMS IN THE DEFINITION. Phenomenal Psychology — Psychology, strictly so denominated — is the science conversant about the 'phenomena or modifications or states of the Mind or Conscious Subject or Soul or Spirit or Self or Ego. In this definition I have purposely accumulated a variety of expressions, in order that I might have the earliest opportunity of making you accurately ac- quainted with their meaning. Before, therefore, proceeding further, I shall pause a moment in expla- nation of the terms in which this definition is ex- pressed. The term Psychology itself is a Greek compound, its elements being 4'°z^ signifying soul or mind, and Myos, signifying discourse or doctrine. Psychology is, therefore, the discourse or doctrine treating of the human mind. The above definition of psychology contains two correlative sets of terms, — the one designating the phenomena of knowing, willing, feeling, desiring, etc., 31 32 AN OUTLINE OF in which the mind becomes known ; the other des- ignating the mind, considered as the unknown sub- stance to which these phenomena belong. Of the former class are the words phenomenon, mode, modifi- cation, state; and to these may be added the analogous terms quality, property, attribute, accident. Of the latter class are subject, mind, soul, spirit, self, ego. (A) Terms expressing the Manifestations of the Mind. I. Phenomenon is the Greek word for that which appears, and may therefore be translated by appearance. There is, however, a distinction to be noticed. (1.) In the first place, the employment of a Greek term shows that it is used in a strict and philosophical applica- tion. (2.) In the second place, the term appearance is used to denote not only that which reveals itself to our observation, as existent, but also that which only seems to be, in contrast to that which truly is. There is thus not merely a certain vagueness in the word, but it even involves a kind of contradiction to the sense in which it is used when employed for phenome- non. In consequence of this, the term phenomenon has been naturalized in our language as a philosoph- ical substitute for the term appearance. The terms phenomenon and appearance are employed in reference to a substance, as known; the remaining terms, in reference to a substance, as existing. II. A mode is the manner of the existence of any- thing. Take, for example, a piece of wax. The wax may be round, or square, or of any other definite fig- ure ; it may also be solid or fluid. Its existence in any of these modes is not essential ; it may change sir william Hamilton's philosophy. 33 from one to the other without any substantial altera- tion. As the mode cannot exist without a substance, we can accord to it only a secondary or precarious existence in relation to the substance, to which we ac- cord the privilege of existing by itself, per se existere; but though the substance be not restricted to any par- ticular mode of existence, we must not suppose that it can exist, or at least be conceived by us to exist, in none. All modes are, therefore, variable states; and though some mode is necessary for the existence of a thing, any individual mode is accidental. III. Modification is properly the bringing a thino- into a certain mode of existence ; but it is very com^ monly employed for the mode of existence itself. IV. State is a term nearly synonymous with mode, but of a meaning more extensive, as not exclusively limited to the mutable and contingent. Y- Quality is, likewise, a word of a wider signifi- cation, for there are essential and accidental qualities. (1.) The essential qualities of a thing are those apti- tudes, those manners of existence and action, which it cannot lose without ceasing to be. For example, in man, the faculties of sense and intelligence ; in body, the di- mensions of length, breadth, and thickness ; in God, the attributes of eternity, omniscience, omnipotence, etc. (2.) By accidental qualities are meant those apti- tudes and manners of existence and action which sub- stances have at one time and not at another, or which they have always, but may lose without ceasing to be. (a) For example, of the transitory class are the whiteness of a wall, the health which we enjoy, the fineness of the weather, etc. (b) Of the permanent 34 AN OUTLINE OF class are the gravity of bodies, the periodical move- ment of the planets, etc. VI. Attribute is a word properly convertible with quality, for every quality is an attribute, and every attribute is a quality ; but in our language, custom has introduced a certain distinction in their application. Attribute is considered as a word of loftier signifi- cance, and is, therefore, conventionally limited to qual- ities of a higher application. Thus, for example, it would be felt as indecorous to speak of the qualities of God, and as ridiculous to talk of the attributes of matter. VII. Property is correctly a synonym for peculiar quality ; but it is frequently used as coextensive with quality in general. VIII. Accident, on the contrary, is an abbreviated expression for accidental or contingent quality. (B) Terms expressing the unknown Basis of mental Phenomena. I. The word mind is of a more limited application than the term soul. In the Greek Philosophy the term 4>u%yj, soul, comprehends, besides the sensitive and rational principle in man, the principle of organic life both in the animal and vegetable kingdoms. Since Descartes limited psychology to the domain of consciousness, the term mind has been rigidly em- ployed for the self-knowing principle alone. Mind, therefore, is to be understood as the subject of the various internal phenomena of which we are con- scious. II. The term subject (subjectum, ^itdaraatq,' dnoxefaevov) is used to denote the unknown basis which lies sin william Hamilton's philosophy. 35 under the phenomena of which we become aware, whether in our external or internal experience. But the philosophers of mind have, in a manner, usurped and appropriated this expression to themselves. Ac- cordingly in their hands the phrases, conscious or thinking subject, and subject simply, mean precisely the same thing ; and custom has prevailed so far that, in psychological discussions, the subject is a term now currently employed throughout Europe for the mind or thinking principle. The utility of this expression is founded on two circumstances. The first is that it affords an adjective ; the second, that the terms sub- ject and subjective have opposing relatives in the terms object and objective, so that the two pairs of words to- gether enable us to designate the primary and most important analysis and antithesis of philosophy in a more precise and emphatic manner than can be done by any other technical expressions. Subject, we have seen, is a term for that in which the phenomena, re- vealed to our observation, inhere, — what the school- men have designated the materia in qua. Limited to the mental phenomena, subject, therefore, denotes the mind itself; and subjective, that which belongs to, or proceeds from, the thinking subject. Object, on the other hand, is a term for that about which the know- ing subject is conversant, — what the schoolmen have styled the materia circa quam ; while objective means that which belongs to, or proceeds from, the object known ; and thus denotes what is real in opposition to what is ideal, — what exists in nature in contrast to what exists merely in the thought of the individual. III. The terms self and ego we shall take together, as 36 AN OUTLINE OF HAMILTON'S PHILOSOPHY. they are absolutely convertible. The self, the I, is recognized in every act of intelligence, as the sub- ject to which that act belongs. It is I that perceive, I that imagine, I that remember, I that attend, I that compare, I that feel, I that desire, I that will, I that am conscious. The I, indeed, is only manifested in one or other of these special modes ; but it is mani- fested in them all ; they are all only the phenomena of the I, and, therefore, the science conversant about the phenomena of mind is, most simply and unam- biguously, said to be conversant about the phenom- ena of the I or Ego. This expression, as that which, in many relations, best marks and discrimi- nates the conscious mind, has now become familiar in every country, with the exception of our own. Why it has not been naturalized with us is not unap- parent. In English the I could not be tolerated ; because, in sound, it would not be distinguished from the word significant of the organ of sight. We must, therefore, either renounce the term, or resort to the Latin Ego; and this is perhaps no disadvan- tage, for, as the word is only employed in a strictly philosophical relation, it is better that this should be distinctly marked, by its being used in that relation alone. The term self is more allowable ; yet still the expressions Ego and Non-Ego are felt to be less awk- ward than those of Self and Not-Self. (Lectures on Metaphysics, VIII. and IX.) CHAPTER II. CONSCIOUSNESS IN GENERAL. In taking a comprehensive survey of the mental phenomena, these are all seen to comprise one essen- tial element, or to be possible only under one necessary condition. This element or condition is consciousness, or the knowledge that I, — that the Ego exists, in some determinate state. In this knowledge they appear or are realized as phenomena, and with this knowledge they likewise disappear, or have no longer a phenomenal existence ; so that con- sciousness may be compared to an internal light, by means of which, and which alone, what passes in the mind is rendered visible. It follows, therefore, that consciousness must form the first object of our con- sideration. § 1. consciousness: its general nature. Nothing has contributed more to spread obscurity over a very transparent matter than the attempts of philosophers to define consciousness. Consciousness cannot be defined ; we may be ourselves fully aware what consciousness is, but we cannot, without confu- sion, convey to others a definition of what we our- selves clearly apprehend. The reason is plain. 37 38 AN OUTLINE OF Consciousness lies at the root of all knowledge. Consciousness is itself the one highest source of all comprehensibility and illustration ; how, then, can we find aught else by which consciousness may be illustrated or comprehended? To accomplish this, it would be necessary to have a second consciousness, through which we might be conscious of the mode in which the first consciousness was possible. In short, the notion of consciousness is so elementary, that it cannot possibly be resolved into others more simple. It cannot, therefore, be brought under any genus, — any more general conception; and, consequently, it cannot be defined. But though consciousness cannot be logically defined, it may, however, be philosophi- cally analyzed. This analysis is effected by observing and holding fast the phenomena or facts of conscious- ness, comparing these, and, from this comparison, evolving the universal conditions under which alone an act of consciousness is possible. But before proceeding to show you in detail Avhat the act of consciousness comprises, it may be proper, in the first place, to recall to you, in general, what kind of act the word is employed to denote. I know, I feel, I desire, etc. What is it that is neces- sarily involved in all these ? It requires only to be stated to be admitted, that when I know, I must know that I know, — when I feel, I must know that I feel, — when I desire, I must know that I desire. The knowledge, the feeling, the desire, are possible only under the condition of being known, and being known by me. For if I did not know that I knew, I would not know ; if I did not know that I felt, I SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON* S PHILOSOPHY. 39 would not feel ; if I did not know that I desired, I would not desire. Now, this knowledge, which I, the subject, have of these modifications of my being, and through which knowledge alone these modifica- tions are possible, is what we call consciousness. The expressions I know that I knoio; I know that I /eel; I know that I desire ; are thus translated by, I am conscious that I know ; I am conscious that I feel; I am conscious that I desire. Consciousness is thus, on the one hand, the recognition by the mind or ego of its acts and affections; — in other words, the self-affirmation that certain modifications are known by me, and that these modifications are mine. But, on the other hand, consciousness is not to be viewed as anything different from these modifications themselves, but is, in fact, the general condition of their existence, or of their existence within the sphere of intelligence. Though the simplest act of mind, consciousness thus expresses a relation subsist- ing between two terms. These terms are, on the one hand, an I or Self, as the subject of a certain modi- fication ; and, on the other hand, some modifi- cation, state, quality, affection, or operation belong- ing to the subject. Consciousness, thus, in its simplicity, necessarily involves three things, — (1.) a recognizing or knowing subject; (2.) a recognized or known modification ; and (3.) a recognition or knowl- edge by the subject of the modification. We may, therefore, lay it down as the most general characteristic of consciousness, that it is the recogni- tion by the thinking subject of its own acts or affec- tions. 40 AN OUTLINE OF § 2. CONSCIOUSNESS .' ITS SPECIAL CONDITIONS. In this, the most general characteristic of con- sciousness, all philosophers are agreed. The more arduous task remains of determining its special con- ditions. Of these, likewise, some are almost too palpable to admit of controversy. (A) Before proceeding to those in regard to which there is any doubt or difficulty, it will be proper, in the first place, to state and to dispose of such deter- minations as are too palpable to be called in question. Of these admitted limitations, I. The first is, that consciousness is an actual and not a potential knowledge. Thus a man is said to know, that is, is able to know, that 7 -f- 9 are — 16, though that equation be not, at the moment, the object of thought ; but we cannot say that he is con- scious of this truth unless while it is actually present to his mind. II. The second limitation is, that consciousness is an immediate, not a mediate knowledge. We are said, for example, to know a past occurrence when we represent it to the mind in an act of memory. We know the mental representation, and this we do im- mediately and in itself, and are also said to know the past occurrence, as mediately knowing it through the mental modification which represents it. Now, we are conscious of the representation as immediately known ; but we cannot be said to be conscious of the thing represented, which, if known, is only known through its representation. sir william Hamilton's philosophy. 41 III. The third condition of consciousness, which may be held as universally admitted, is, that it sup- poses a contrast, — a discrimination; for we can be conscious only inasmuch as we are conscious of some- thing ; and we are conscious of something only inas- much as Ave are conscious of .what that something is, — that is, distinguish it from what it is not. This discrimination is of different kinds and degrees. (1.) In the first place, there is the contrast between the two grand opposites, self and not-self, — ego and non-ego, — mind and matter. We are conscious of self only in and by its contradistinction from not-self; and are conscious of not-self only in and by its contradistinction from self. (2.) In the second place, there is the discrimination of the states or modifications of the internal subject or self from each other. We are conscious of one mental state only ns we contradistinguish it from another ; where two, three, or more such states are confounded, we are conscious of them as one ; and were we to note no difference in our mental modifica- tions, we might be said to be absolutely unconscious. (3.) In the third place, there is the distinction between the parts and qualities of the outer world. We are conscious of an external object only as we are conscious of it as distinct from others ; where several distinguishable objects are confounded, we are conscious of them as one ; where no object is dis- criminated, we are not conscious of any. 1 IV. The fourth condition of consciousness, which 1 See this subject treated more fully under Phenomenology of the Cognitions, Chap. V., § 1. 42 AN OUTLINE OF may be assumed as very generally acknowledged, is, that it involves judgment. 1 A judgment is the men- tal act by which one thing is affirmed or denied of another. This fourth condition is in truth only a necessary consequence of the third, — for it is im- possible to discriminate without judging, discrimi- nation or contradistinction being, in fact, only the denying one thing of another. V. The fifth undeniable condition of consciousness is memory. This condition also is a corollary of the third. For without memory our mental states could not be held fast, compared, distinguished from each other, and referred to self. Without memory, each indivisible, each infinitesimal, moment in the mental succession would stand isolated from each other, — would constitute, in fact, a separate existence. The notion of the ego, or self, arises from the recognized permanence and identity of the thinking subject in contrast to the recognized succession and variety of its modifications. But this recognition is possible only through memory. The notion of self is, therefore, the result of memory. But the notion of self is in- volved in consciousness, so consequently is memory. (Led. on Metaph., XL Compare Reid's Works, pp. 932-7.) (.B) We are now about to enter on a more disputed territory. Aristotle, Descartes, Locke, and philoso- phers in general, have regarded consciousness, not as a particular faculty, but as the universal condition of intelligence. Reid, on the contrary, following, prob- ably, Hutcheson, and followed by Stewart, Royer- 1 See note on preceding page. sm william Hamilton's philosophy. 43 Collard, and others, has classed consciousness as a co- ordinate faculty with the other intellectual powers ; distinguished from them, not as the species from the individual, bitt as the individual from the individual. And as the particular faculties have each their peculiar object, so the peculiar object of consciousness is the operations of the other faculties themselves, to the ex- clusion of the objects about which these operations are conversant. This analysis we regard as false. 1 For it is impos- sible, in the first place, to discriminate consciousness from all the other cognitive faculties, or to discrimi- nate any one of these from consciousness ; and, in the second, to conceive a faculty cognizant of the various mental operations, without being also cognizant of their several objects. I. We know, and We know that we know: — these propositions, logically distinct, are really identical ; each implies the other. We know (i. e., feel, per- ceive, imagine, remember, etc.) only as we know that we thus know ; and we know that we know, only as we know in some particular manner (i. e. , feel, perceive, etc.). So true is the scholastic brocard : " Non senti- mus nisi sentiamus nos sentire; non sentimus nos sen- tire nisi sentiamus." The attempt to analyze the 1 This is described by Hamilton as " the first contested position," which he intends to maintain, with regard to consciousness (Led. on Metaph., p. 143, Am. ed.); but it leads him into a long digression (Ibid., pp. 1*3-182), at the close of which there is no mention of any other contested positions. Did this digression cause him to forget his apparent intention to continue the subject from which he started? His editors give no indication that they have observed this omission. — J. C. M. 44 AN OUTLINE OF cognition I know, and the cognition / know that I know, into the separate energies of distinct faculties, is therefore vain. But this is the analysis of Reid. Consciousness, which the formula I know that I know adequately expresses, he views as a power specifically distinct from the various cognitive faculties compre- hended under the formula / know, precisely as these faculties are severally contradistinguished from each other. But here the parallel does not hold. I can feel without perceiving ; I can perceive without imag- ining ; I can imagine without remembering ; I can remember without judging (in the emphatic significa- tion) ; I can judge without willing. One of these acts does not immediately suppose the other. Though modes merely of the same indivisible subject, they are modes in relation to each other, really distinct, and ad- mit, therefore, of psychological discrimination. But can I feel without being conscious that I feel ? — can I remember without being conscious that I remember ? or, can I be conscious without being conscious that I perceive, or imagine, or reason, — that I energize, in short, in some determinate mode, which Eeid would view as the act of a faculty specifically different from consciousness ? That this is impossible Reid himself admits. But if, on the one hand, consciousness be only realized under specific modes, and cannot there- fore exist apart from the several faculties in cumulo; and if, on the other, these faculties can all and each only be exerted under the condition of consciousness ; consciousness, consequently, is not one of the special modes into which our mental activity may be resolved, but the fundamental form, — the generic condition of sir william Hamilton's philosophy. 45 them all. Every intelligent act is thus a modified consciousness ; and consciousness a comprehensive term for the complement of our cognitive energies. II. But the vice of Reid's analysis is further mani- fested in his arbitrary limitation of the sphere of con- sciousness ; proposing to it the various intellectual operations, but excluding their objects. "I am con- scious," he says, "of perception, but not of the object I perceive ; I am conscious of memory, but not of the object I remember." The reduction of consciousness to a particular fac- ulty entailed this limitation.-. For, once admitting consciousness to be cognizant of objects as of operations, Reid could not, without absurdity, degrade it to the level of a special power. For thus, in the^rs^ place, consciousness, coextensive with all our cognitive fac- ulties, would yet be made co-ordinate with each; and in the second, two faculties would be supposed to be simultaneously exercised about the same object, to the same extent. But the alternative which Reid has chosen is, at least, equally untenable. The assertion that we can be conscious of an act of knowledge without being conscious of its object, is virtually suicidal. A men- tal operation is only what it is by relation to its ob- ject; the object at once determining its existence, and specifying the character of its existence. But if a relation cannot be comprehended in one of its terms, so we cannot be conscious of an operation without being conscious of the object to which it exists only as correlative. For example, We are conscious of a perception, says Reid, but are not conscious of its 46 AN OUTLINE OF object. Yet how can we be conscious of a perception, that is, how can we know that a perception exists, — that it is a perception, and not another mental state, — and that it is the perception of a rose, and of noth- ing but a rose ; unless this consciousness involve a knowledge (or consciousness) of the object which at once determines the existence of an act, specifies its kind, and distinguishes its individuality? An- nihilate the object, you annihilate the operation ; an- nihilate the consciousness of the object, you annihilate the consciousness of the operation. In the greater number indeed of our cognitive energies, the two terms of the relation of knowledge exist only as iden- tical ; the object admitting only of a logical discrimi- nation from the subject. I imagine a Hippogryph. The Hippogryph is at once the object of the act and the act itself. Abstract the one, the other has no ex- istence ; deny me the consciousness of the Hippo- gryph, you deny me the consciousness of the imagina- tion ; I am conscious of zero ; I am not conscious at all. (Discussions, pp. 47-49. Compare Led. on Metaph., XII.) § 3. CONSCIOUSNESS : ITS EVIDENCE AND AUTHORITY. I now proceed to consider consciousness as the source from whence we must derive every fact in the Philosophy of Mind. And in prosecution of this purpose I shall, in the first place, endeavor to show you that it really is the principal, if not the only, source from which all knowledge of the mental phenomena must be obtained ; and, in the second SIB WILLIAM HAMILTON* 'S PHILOSOPHY. 47 place, I shall consider the character of its evidence, and what, under different relations, are the degrees of its authority. (A) As consciousness has been shown to be the condition of all the mental phenomena, it is mainly, if not solely, to consciousness, that we must resort for an acquaintance with these phenomena. Accord- ing to the doctrine of phrenology, indeed, an ac- quaintance with the various mental powers may be obtained by observation of the various parts of the brain, which that science maintains that it has dis- covered to be their several organs. But though the mind, in its lower energies and affections, is imme- diately dependent on the conditions of the nervous system, and, in general, .the development of the brain in different species of animals is correspondent to their intelligence, still it is impossible to connect the mind or its faculties with particular parts of the nervous system. For I have proved, by the most extensive induction, that the alleged physiological facts on which phrenology professes to be based, such as its assertion of the correspondence between the development of the cerebellum and the function which it ascribes to it, are often not only unfounded, but the very reverse of the truth. 1 1 In the above paragraph I have endeavored to embody the teach- ing of Sir William Hamilton on the subject of which it treats. His editors have relegated this portion of his lectures, so far as it seemed worthy of preservation, to an appendix (Led. on Metaph., Appendix II.), where it may be consulted. I have thought it unnecessary to go into detail, both because the position of phrenology has changed since Hamilton's time, and because it is unnecessary to digress into the question concerning the function of the various organs in the 48 AN OUTLINE OF (B) We proceed to consider, in the next place, the authority, the certainty, of this instrument. Now, it is at once evident, that philosophy, as it affirms its own possibility, must affirm the veracity of consciousness ; for, as philosophy is only a scientific development of the facts which consciousness reveals , it follows, that philosophy, in denying or doubting the testimony of consciousness, would deny or doubt its own existence. (Lect. on Metaph.,lLV.) How, then, do the facts of consciousness certify us of their own veracity? To this the only possible answer is, that as elements of our mental constitution, as the essential conditions of our knowledge, they must by us be accepted as true. To suppose their falsehood, is to suppose thai we are created capable of intelligence, in order to be made the victims of delusion ; that God is a deceiver, and the root of our nature a lie. But such a supposition, if gratuitous, is manifestly illegitimate. For, on the contrary, the data of our original consciousness must, it is evident, in the first instance, be presumed true. It is only if proved false, that their authority can, in consequence of that proof, be, in the second instance, disal- lowed. Here, however, at the outset, it is proper to take a distinction, the neglect of which has been produc- tive of considerable error and confusion. It is the distinction between the data or deliverances of con- sciousness considered simply in themselves, as appre- encephalon, in order to vindicate, not only the value, but the neces- sity, of reflection in the study of mind. — J. C. M. sir william Hamilton's philosophy. 49 hended facts or actual manifestations, and those deliverances considered as testimonies to the truth of facts beyond their own phenomenal reality. I. Viewed under the former limitation, they are above all scepticism. For as doubt is itself only a manifestation of consciousness, it is impossible to doubt that, when consciousness manifests, it does manifest, without, in thus doubting, doubting that we actually doubt; that is, without the doubt con- tradicting and therefore annihilating itself. Hence it is that the facts of consciousness, as mere phenom- ena, are by the unanimous confession of all sceptics and idealists, ancient and modern, placed high above the reach of question. II. Viewed under the latter limitation, the deliver- ances of consciousness do not thus peremptorily repel even the possibility of doubt. I am conscious, for example, in an act of sensible perception, (1.) of myself, the subject knowing; and, (2.) of something given as different from myself, the object known. To take the second term of this relation : that I am conscious in this act of an object given, as a non-ego, — that is, as not a modification of my mind, — of this, as a phenomenon, doubt is impossible. For, as has been seen, we cannot doubt the actuality of a fact of consciousness without doubting, that is subverting, our doubt itself. To this extent, therefore, all scep- ticism is precluded. But though it cannot but be admitted that the object of which we are conscious in this cognition is given, not as a mode of -self, but as a mode of something different from self, it is, how- ever, possible for us to suppose, without our supposi- 4 50 AN OUTLINE OF tion, at least, being felo-de-se, that, though given as a non-ego, this object may, in reality, he only a repre- sentation of a non-ego, in and by the ego. Let this, therefore, be maintained ; let the fact of the testimony be admitted, but the truth of the testimony, to aught beyond its own ideal existence, be doubted or denied. How in this case are we to proceed ? It is evident that the doubt does not in this, as in the former case, refute itself. It is not suicidal by self-contradiction. The Idealist, therefore, in denying the existence of an external world, as more than a subjective phenom- enon of the internal, does not advance a doctrine ab initio null, as a scepticism would be which denied the phenomena of the internal world itself. It is, therefore, manifest that we may throw wholly out of account the phenomena of consciousness, con- sidered merely in themselves ; seeing that scepticism in regard to them, under this limitation, is confess- edly impossible ; and that it is only requisite to vin- dicate the truth of these phenomena, viewed as attestations of more than their own existence, seeing that they are not, in this respect, placed beyond the possibility of doubt. When, for example, consciousness assures us that, in perception, we are immediately cognizant of an ex- ternal and extended non-ego ; or that, in remembrance, through the imagination, of which we are immediately cognizant, we obtain a mediate knowledge of a real past ; how shall we repel the doubt, — in the former case, that what is given as the extended reality itself is not merely a representation of matter by mind ; in the latter, that what is given as a mediate knowledge of sir william Hamilton's philosophy. 51 the past, is not a mere phantasm, containing an illu- sive reference to an unreal past? We can do this only in one way. The legitimacy of such gratuitous doubt necessarily supposes that the deliverance of consciousness is not to be presumed true. If, there- fore, it can be shown, on the one hand, that the de- liverances of consciousness must philosophically be accepted, until their certain or probable falsehood has been positively evinced ; and if, on the other hand, it cannot be shown that any attempt to discredit the veracity of consciousness has ever yet succeeded ; it follows that, as philosophy now stands, the testimony of consciousness must be viewed as high above sus- picion, and its declarations entitled to demand prompt and unconditional assent. I. In the first place, as has been said, it cannot but be acknowledged that the veracity of consciousness must, at least iu the first instance, be conceded. " Neganti incumbit probatio." Nature is not gratui- tously to be assumed to work, not only in vain, but in counteraction of herself ; our faculty of knowledge is not without a ground to be supposed an instrument of illusion ; man, unless the melancholy fact be proved, is not to be held organized for the attainment, and actuated by the love of truth, only to become the dupe and victim of a perfidious creator. II. But, in the second place, though the veracity of the primary convictions of consciousness must, in the outset, be admitted, it still remains competent to lead a proof that they are undeserving of credit. But how is this to be done ? As the ultimate grounds of knowledge, these convictions cannot be redargued 52 " AN OUTLINE OF from any higher knowledge ; and as original beliefs, they are paramount in certainty to every derivative assurance. But they are many ; they are, in author- ity, co-ordinate ; and their testimony is clear and precise. It is therefore competent for us to view them in correlation; to compare their declarations, and to consider whether they contradict,- and, by contradict- ing, invalidate each other. This mutual contradiction is possible in two ways. (1.) It may be that the primary data themselves are directly or immediately contradictory of each other ; (2.) It may be that they are mediately or indirectly contradictory, inasmuch as the consequences to which they necessarily lead, and for the truth or falsehood of which they are therefore responsible, are mutually repugnant. By evincing either of these, the veracity of consciousness will be disproved ; for in either case consciousness is shown to be inconsistent with itself, and consequently incon- sistent with the unity of truth. But by no other process of demonstration is this possible. (Meid's Works, pp. 743-5.) Before we are entitled to accuse consciousness of being a false witness, we are bound, first of all, to see whether there be any rules by which, in employing the testimony of consciousness, we must be governed ; and whether philosophers have evolved their systems out of consciousness in obedience to these rules. For if there be rules under which alone the evidence of consciousness can be fairly and fully given, and, consequently, under which alone consciousness can serve as an infallible standard of certainty and truth, and if philosophers have despised or neglected these, sir jvilliam Hamilton's philosophy. 53 then must we remove the reproach from the instru- ment, and affix it to those blundering workmen who have not known how to handle and apply it. Now, in attempting a scientific deduction of the philosophy of mind from the facts of consciousness, there are, in all, if I generalize correctly, three laws which afford the exclusive conditions of psychological legitimacy. I. The Law of Parcimony : That we admit nothing which is not either an original datum of consciousness or the legitimate consequence of such a datum. II. The Law of Integrity: That we embrace all the original data of consciousness and all their legiti- mate consequences. III. The Law of Harmony : That we exhibit each of these in its individual integrity, neither distorted nor mutilated, and in its relative placje, whether of pre-eminence or subordination. (Lect. on Metaph., XV., and ReicVs Works, p. 747.) § 4. consciousness : CLASSIFICATION of its phe- nomena. On taking a survey of the mental modifications or phenomena of which we are conscious, these are seen to divide themselves into three great classes. (1.) In the first place, there are the phenomena of Knowledge ; (2.) In the second place, there are the phenomena of Feeling, or the phenomena of pleasure and pain ; and (3.) In the third place, there are the phenomena of Conation, or of will and desire. Let me illustrate this by an example. I see a picture. Now, first of all, I am conscious of perceiving a certain com- 54 AN OUTLINE OF plement of colors and figures ; I recognize what the ob- ject is. This is the phenomenon of Cognition or Knowl- edge. But this is not the only phenomenon of which I may be here conscious. I may experience certain affections in the contemplation of this object. If the picture be a masterpiece, the gratification will be un- alloyed ; but if it be an unequal production, I shall be conscious, perhaps of enjoyment, but of enjoyment alloyed with dissatisfaction. This is the phenomenon of Feeling, or of Pleasure and Pain. But these two phenomena do not yet exhaust all of which I may be conscious on the occasion. I may desire to see the picture long, — to see it often, — to make it my own, and, perhaps, I may will, resolve, or determine so to do. This is the complex phenomenon of Will and Desire. The characters by which these three classes are reciprocally discriminated, are the following : — I. In the phenomena of cognition, consciousness distinguishes an object known from the subject know- ing. This object may be of two kinds : it may either be the quality of something different from the ego ; or it may be a modification of the ego or subject itself. In the former case, the object, which may be called for the sake of discrimination the object-object, is given as something different from the percipient subject. In the latter case, the object, which may be called the subject-object, is given as really identical with the conscious ego ; but still consciousness distinguishes it, as an accident, from the ego. As the subject of that accident, it projects, as it were, this subjective phenomenon from itself, — views it at a distance, — in a word, objectifies it. This discrimination of sir wizliam Hamilton's philosophy. 55 self from self — this objectification — is the quality which constitutes the essential peculiarity of cog- nition. II. In the phenomena of feeling, on the contrary, consciousness does not place the mental modification or state beyond itself; it does not contemplate it apart, — as separate from itself, — but is, as it were, fused into one. The peculiarity of feeling, there- fore, is that there is nothing but what is subjectively subjective ; there is no object different from self, — no objectification of any mode of self. We are, indeed, able to constitute our states of pain and pleasure into objects of reflection ; but in so far as they are objects of reflection, they are not feelings, but only reflex cognitions of feelings. III. In the phenomena of conation, there is, as in those of cognition, an object, and this object is also an object of knowledge. Will and desire are only possible through knowledge, — " Ignoti nulla cupido." But though both cooniition and conation bear relation to an object, they are discriminated by the difference of this relation itself. In cognition, there exists no want ; and the object, whether objective or subject- ive, is not sought for, nor avoided ; whereas in cona- tion there is a want, and a tendency supposed, which results in an endeavor, either to obtain the object, when the cognitive faculties represent it as fitted to afford the fruition of the want ; or to ward off the object, if these faculties represent it as calculated to frustrate the tendency of its accomplishment. (Led. on Metaph., XLII.) 56 AN OUTLINE OF To the above classification of the mental phenom- ena objections have been taken. I. It has been objected, that the three classes are co-ordinate. It is evident that every mental phenom- enon is either an act of knowledge, or only possible through an act of knowledge, for consciousness is a knowledge, and, on this principle, many philoso- phers, as Descartes, Leibnitz, Spinoza, Wolf, Plat- ner, and others, have been led to regard the faculty of cognition as the fundamental power of mind, from which all others are derivative. To this the answer is easy. These philosophers did not observe that, although pleasure and pain, although desire and volition, are only as they are known to be ; yet, in these modifications, a quality, a phenomenon of mind, absolutely new, has been superadded, which was never involved in, and could, therefore, never have been evolved out of, the mere faculty of knowl- edge. The faculty of knowledge is certainly the first in order, inasmuch as it is the conditio sine qua non of the others ; and we are able to conceive a being possessed of the power of recognizing existence, and yet wholly void of all feeling of pain and pleasure, and of all powers of desire and volition. On the other hand, we are wholly unable to conceive a being possessed of feeling and desire, and, at the same time, without a knowledge of any object upon which his affections may be employed, and without a con- sciousness of these affections themselves. We can farther conceive a being possessed of knowledge and feeling alone, — a being endowed with a power of recognizing objects, of enjoying the exer- sir jvilliam Hamilton's philosophy. 57 cise, and of grieving at the restraint of his activity, — and yet devoid of voluntary agency — of that conation which is possessed by man. To such a being would belong feelings of pain and pleasure, but neither desire nor will, properly so called. On the other hand, however, we cannot possibly conceive the existence of a voluntary activity independently of all feeling ; for voluntary conation is a faculty which can only be determined to energy through a pain or pleasure, — through an estimate of the rela- tive worth of objects. In distinguishing the cognitions, feelings, and cona- tions, it is not, therefore, to be supposed that these phenomena are possible independently of each other. In our philosophical systems, they may stand sepa- rated from each other in books and chapters ; in nature, they are ever interwoven. In every, the simplest, modification of mind, knowledge, feeling, and desire or will, go to constitute the mental state ; and it is only by a scientific abstraction that we are able to analyze the state into elements, which are never really existent but in mutual combination. These elements are found, indeed, in very various pro- portions in different states ; sometimes one prepon- derates, sometimes another ; but there is no state in which they are not all coexistent. (Led. on Metap7i., XI.) II. A second objection is urged by Krug, a distin- guished champion of the Kantian system, who goes so far as to maintain, not only that what have ob- tained the name of feelings constitute no distincf class of mental functions, but that the very supposition is 58 AN OUTLINE OF HAMILTON'S PHILOSOPHY. absurd, and even impossible. The power of cogni- tion and the power of conation, he holds, are in pro- priety to be regarded as two different fundamental powers, only because the operation of our mind ex- hibits a twofold direction of its whole activity, — one inwards, another outwards ; in consequence of which we are constrained to distinguish, on the one hand, an immanent ideal or theoretical, and, on the other, a transeunt real or practical, activity. Hence it is argued that, if we interpolate a third species of ac- tivity, its direction must be either immanent or transeunt, or both, or neither ^of these ; but on the first three suppositions there are still only two kinds of mental activity, and on the fourth there is merely an additional activity, in no direction, which is no activity at all. In answer to this it may be said, (1.) That, in place of two forms of mental activity, we may competently suppose three, ineunt, immanent, and transeunt. (2.) That directions are properly ascribed only to the movements of external things. (Abridged from Lecture XLI. of the Led. on Metaph.) The order of these phenomena is determined by their relative consecution. Feeling and appetency suppose knowledge. The cognitive faculties, there- fore, stand first. But as will, and desire, and aver- sion suppose a knowledge of the pleasurable and painful, the feelings will stand second as intermediate between the other two. (Led. on Metaph., XL) The phenomena of knowledge come, therefore, first under consideration, and philosophy is principally and primarily the Science of Knowledge. (Reid's Works, p. 808, note.) FIRST PART OF PHENOMENAL PSYCHOLOGY. PHENOMENOLOGY OF TEE COGNITIONS. FIRST PART OF PHENOMENAL PSYCHOLOGY. PHENOMENOLOGY OF THE COGNITIONS. INTRODUCTION. CLASSIFICATION OF THE COGNITIVE FACULTIES. I now proceed to the particular investigation of the first class of the mental phenomena, and shall com- mence by delineating to you the distribution of the cognitive faculties which I shall adopt, — a distribution different from any other with which I am acquainted. But I would first premise an observation in regard to psychological powers. As to mental powers, you are not to suppose them entities really distinguishable from the thinking prin- ciple, or really different from each other. Mental powers are not like bodily organs. It is the same simple substance which exerts every energy of every faculty, however various, and which is affected in every mode of every capacity, however opposite. It is a fact, too notorious to be denied, that the mind is capable of different modifications ; that is, can exert different actions, and can be affected by different pas- sions. But these actions and passions are not all dis- 61 62 AN OUTLINE OF similar ; every action and passion is not different from every other. On the contrary, they are like, and they are unlike. Those, therefore, that are like, we group or assort together in thought, and bestow on them a common name ; nor are these groups or assortments manifold, — they are, in fact, few and simple. Again, every action is an effect ; every action and passion a modification. But every effect supposes a cause ; every modification supposes a subject. When we say that the mind exerts an energy, we virtually say that the mind is the cause of the energy ; when we say that the mind acts or suffers, we say, in other words, that the mind is the subject of a modification. But the modifications, that is, the actions and passions, of the mind, as we stated, all fall into a few resembling groups, which we designate by a peculiar name ; and as the mind is the common cause and subject of all these, we are surely entitled to say, in general, that the mind has the faculty of exerting such and such a class of energies, or has the capacity of being modified by such and such an order of affections. On this doc- trine, a faculty is nothing more than a general term for the causality the mind has of originating a certain class of energies ; a capacity, only a general term for the susceptibility the mind has of being affected by a particular class of emotions. From what I have now said, you will be better pre- pared for what I am about to state in regard to the classification of the first great order of mental phe- nomena, and the distribution of the faculties of knowl- edge founded thereon. I formerly told you that the mental phenomena are never presented to us sepa- sm William Hamilton's philosophy. 63 rately ; they are always in conjunction, and it is only by an ideal analysis and abstraction that, for the pur- poses of science, they can be discriminated and con- sidered apart. The problem, proposed in such an analysis, is to find the primary threads which, in their composition, form the complex tissue of thought. In what ought to be accomplished by such an analysis, all philosophers are agreed, however different may have been the result of their attempts. I shall not state and criticise the various classifications pro- pounded of the cognitive faculties. I shall only de- lineate the distribution of the faculties of knowledge which I have adopted, and endeavor to afford you some general insight into its principles. I again repeat that consciousness constitutes, or is coextensive with, all our faculties of knowledge, — these faculties being only special modifications under which consciousness is manifested. It being, there- fore, understood that consciousness is not a special faculty of knowledge, but the general faculty out of which the special faculties of knowledge are evolved, I proceed to this evolution. I. In the first place, as we are endowed with a fac- ulty of Cognition, or Consciousness in general, and since it cannot be maintained that we have always possessed the knowledge which we now possess, it will be admitted that we must have a faculty of ac- quiring knowledge. But this acquisition of knowl- edge can only be accomplished by the immediate presentation of a new object to consciousness ; in other words, by the reception of a new object within the sphere of our cognition. We have thus a faculty 64 AN OUTLINE OF which may be called the Acquisitive, or the Presenta- tive, or the Receptive. Now, new or adventitious knowledge may be either of things external or of things internal. If the ob- ject of knowledge be external, the faculty receptive or presentative of the qualities of such object will be a consciousness of the non-ego. This has obtained the name of External Perception, or of Perception sim- ply. If, on the other hand, the object be internal, the faculty receptive or presentative of the qualities of such subject-object, will be a consciousness of the ego. This faculty obtains the name of Internal or Reflex Perception, or of Self -consciousness. By the foreign psychologists this faculty is termed also the Internal Sense. II. In the second place, inasmuch as we are capa- ble of knowledge, we must be endowed not only with a faculty of acquiring, but with a faculty of retaining or conserving it when acquired. We have thus, as a second necessary faculty, one that may be called the Conservative or Retentive. This is Memory, strictly so denominated. III. But, in the third place, if we are capable of knowledge, it is not enough that we possess a faculty of acquiring, and a faculty of retaining it in the mind, but out of consciousness ; we must further be endowed with a faculty of recalling it out of unconsciousness into consciousness ; in short, a reproductive power. This Reproductive faculty is governed by the laws which regulate the succession of our thoughts, — the laws, as they are called, of Mental Association. If these laws are allowed to operate without the inter- sip william Hamilton's philosophy. 65 veution of the will, this faculty maybe called Sugges- tion, or Spontaneous Suggestion; — whereas, if applied under the influence of the will, it will properly obtain the name of Reminiscence, or Recollection. By repro- duction, it should be observed, that I strictly mean the process of recovering the absent thought from un- consciousness, and not its representation in conscious- ness. IV. In the fourth place, as capable of knowledge, we must not only be endowed with a presentative, a conservative, and a reproductive faculty ; there is re- quired for their consummation a faculty of represent- ing in consciousness, and of keeping before the mind the knowledge presented, retained, and reproduced. We have thus a Representative faculty ; and this ob- tains the name of Imagination or Phantasy. V. In the fifth place, all the faculties we have con- sidered are only subsidiary. They acquire, preserve, call out, and hold up, the materials, for the use of a higher faculty which operates upon these materials, and which we may call the Elaborative or Discursive faculty. This faculty has only one operation, — it only compares. It may startle you to hear that the high- est function of mind is nothing higher than compari- son ; but, in the end, I am confident of convincing you of the paradox. VI. But, in the sixth and last place, the mind is not altogether indebted to experience for the whole appa- ratus of its knowledge. What we know by experi- ence, without experience we should not have known ; and as all our experience is contingent, all the knowl- edge derived from experience is contingent also. But 66 AN OUTLINE OF HAMILTON'' 8 PHILOSOPHY. there are cognitions in the mind which are not con- tingent, — which are necessary, — which we cannot but think, — which thought supposes as its fundamen- tal condition. These cognitions, therefore, are not mere generalizations from experience. But if not de- rived from experience, they must be native to the mind. These native cognitions are the laws by which the mind is governed in its operations, and which af- ford the conditions of its capacity of knowledge. These necessary laws, or primary conditions of intel- ligence, are phenomena of a similar character; and we must, therefore, generalize or collect them into a class ; and on the power possessed by the mind of manifesting these phenomena we may bestow the name of the Regulative faculty. (Lect. on Metwph., XX.) The following is a tabular view of the distribution of the Special Faculties of Knowledge. C 1. External — Perception. I. Presentative < C 2. Internal — Self-Consciousness. II. Conservative — Memory. C 1. Without will — Suggestion. [SJ J III. Reproductive < c 2. With will — Reminiscence. t> IV. Representative — Imagination or Phantasy. V. Elaborative — Comparison, or the Faculty of Relations. VI. Regulative — Reason or Common Sense. PHENOMENOLOGY OF THE COGNITIONS. CHAPTER I. THE PRESENTATIVE FACULTY. This faculty is subdivided into External Perception and Internal Perception, or Self-cousciousuess. I commence with the former of these. § 1. EXTERNAL PERCEPTION. External or Sensitive Perception, or Perception sim- ply, 1 is that act of consciousness whereby we appre- hend in our body, (1.) certain special affections, whereof, as an animated organism, it is contingently susceptible ; and (2.) those general relations of exten- sion, under which, as a material organism, it necessa- rily exists. Of these perceptions the former is sen- sation proper ; the latter, 'perception proper, (field's Works, pp. 876-7.) This distinction it is necessary to explain, as well as a correlative distinction in the qualities of matter ; and we shall thus be the better 'For a sketch of the various meanings of the word Perception, see Reid's Works, p. 876, note. — J. C. M. 07 68 AN OUTLINE OF prepared for understanding the true theory of percep- tion. (A) Sensation and Perception. Before pro- ceeding to state the great law which regulates the mutual relation of these phenomena, it is proper to say a few words illustrative of the nature of the phe- nomena themselves. Perception is a special kind of knowledge ; sensation a special kind of feeling ; and Knowledge and Feeling, it will be remembered, are two out of the three great classes, into which we divided the phenomena of mind. Now, as Perception is only a special mode of Knowledge, and Sensation only a spe- cial mode of Feeling, so the contrast of Perception and Sensation is only the special manifestation of a con- trast, which universally divides the generic phenom- ena themselves. It ought, therefore, in the first place, to have been noticed, that the generic phenom- ena of Knowledge and Feeling are always found coexistent, and yet always distinct ; and the oppo- sition of Perception and Sensation should have been stated as an obtrusive, but still only a particular, ex- ample of the general law. But not only is the dis- tinction of Perception and Sensation not generalized by our psychologists ; it is not concisely and precisely stated. A Cognition is objective, that is, our con- sciousness is then relative to something different from the present state of the mind itself; a Feeling, on the contrary, is subjective, that is, our consciousness is exclusively limited to the pleasure or pain experi- enced by the thinking subject. Cognition and feeling are always coexistent. The purest act of knowledge is always colored by some feeling of pleasure or pain ; SIR 1PTLLIAM HAMILTON 3 S PHILOSOPHY. 69 for no energy is absolutely indifferent, and the gross- est feeling exists only as it is known in consciousness. This being the case of cognition and feeling in general, the same is true of perception and sensation in par- ticular. Perception proper is the consciousness, through the senses, of the qualities of an object known as different from self; Sensation proper is the consciousness of the subjective affection of pleasure or pain, which accompanies that act of knowledge. Perception is thus the objective element in the com- plex state, — the element of Cognition; Sensation is the subjective element, — the element of Feeling. The most remarkable defect, however, in the pres- ent doctrine upon this point, is the ignorance of our psychologists in regard to the law by which the phe- nomena of cognition and feeling, — of perception and sensation, — are governed, in their reciprocal relation. This law is simple and universal ; and, once enounced, its proof is found in every mental manifestation. It is this : Knowledge and Feeling, — Perception and Sensation, — though always coexistent, are always in the inverse ratio of each other. That these two ele- ments are always found in coexistence, as it is an old and a notorious truth, it is not requisite for me to prove. But that these elements are always found to coexist in an inverse proportion, — in support of this universal fact, it will be requisite to adduce proof and illustration. In doing this I shall, however, confine myself to the relation of Perception and Sensation. I. The first proof I shall take from a comparison of the several senses; and it will be found that, pre- 70 AN OUTLINE OF cisely as a sense has more of the one element, it has less of the other. Laying Touch aside for the moment, as this requires a special explanation, the other four senses divide themselves into two classes, according as Perception or Sensation predominates. The two in which the former element prevails, are Sight and Hearing ; the two in which the latter, are Taste and Smell. 1. Taking the first two, it will be at once admitted that (a) /Sight at the same instant presents to us a greater number and a greater variety of objects and qualities than any other of the senses. In this sense, therefore, Perception is at its maximum. But Sensation is here at its minimum ; for in the eye we experience less organic pleasure or pain from the impressions of its appro- priate objects (colors), than we do in any other sense. (b) Next to Sight, Hearing affords us, in the shortest interval, the greatest variety and multitude of cognitions ; and as sight divides space almost to infinity, through color, so hearing does the same to time, through sound. Hearing is, however, much less extensive in its sphere of Knowledge or Percep- tion than sight ; but in the same proportion is its capacity of Feeling or Sensation more intensive. We have greater pleasure and greater pain from single sounds than from single colors ; and, in like man- ner, concords and discords, in the one sense, affect us more agreeably or disagreeably, than any modifications of light in the other. 2. In Taste and Smell the degree of Sensation, sir William Hamilton's philosophy. 71 that is, of pleasure or pain, is great in proportion as the perception, that is, the information they afford, is small. 3. In regard to Touch, without entering on dis- puted questions, it is sufficient to know, that in those parts of the body where sensation predominates, per- ception is feeble ; and in those where perception is lively, sensation is obtuse. In the finger-points tactile perception is at its height ; but there is hardly any other part of the body in which sensation is not more acute. Touch, therefore, if viewed as a single sense, belongs to both classes, — the objective and the subjective. But it is more correct to regard it as a plurality of senses, in which case touch, properly so called, having a principal organ in the finger- points, will belong to the class in which perception proper predominates. II. The analogy, which we have thus seen to hold good in the several senses in relation to each other, prevails likewise among the several impressions of the same sense. Impressions in the same sense differ both (1.) in degree and (2.) in quality or kind. 1. Taking their difference in degree, and supposing that the degree of the impression determines the degree of the sensation, it cannot certainly be said, that the minimum of Sensation infers the maximum of Perception ; for Perception always supposes a cer- tain quantum of Sensation : but this is undeniable, that, above a certain limit, Perception declines, in proportion as Sensation rises. Thus, in the sense of sight, if the impression be strong we are dazzled, blinded, and consciousness is limited to the pain or 72 AN OUTLINE OF pleasure of the Sensation, in the intensity of which Perception has been lost. 2. Take now the difference, in kind, of impres- sions in the same sense. Of the senses, take again that of Sight. Sight, as will hereafter be shown, is cognizant of color, and of figure. But though figure is known only through color, a very imperfect cognizance of color is necessary, as is shown in the case (and it is not a rare one) of those individuals who have not the faculty of discriminating colors. These persons, who probably perceive only a certain difference of light and shade, have as clear and distinct a cog- nizance of figure, as others who enjoy the sense of sight in absolute perfection. This being understood, you will observe, that, in the vision of color, there is more of Sensation; in that of figure, more of Per- ception. Color affords our faculties of knowledge a far smaller number of differences and relations than figure ; but, at the same time, yields our capacity of feeling a far more sensual enjoyment. But if the pleasure we derive from color be more gross and vivid, that from figure is more refined and permanent. It is a law of our nature, that the more intense a pleasure, the shorter is its duration. The pleasures of sense are grosser and more intense than those of intellect ; but, while the former alternate speedily with disgust, with the latter we are never satiated. The same analogy holds among the senses themselves. Those in which Sensation predominates, in which pleasure is most intense, soon pall upon, us ; whereas those in which Perception predominates, and which hold more immediately of intelligence, afford us a less SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON'S PHILOSOPHY. 73 exclusive but a more enduring gratification. How soon are we cloyed with the pleasures of the palate, com- pared with those of the eye ; and, among the objects of the former, the meats that please the most are soonest objects of disgust. This is too notorious in regard to taste to stand in need of proof. But it is no less certain in the case of vision. In painting, there is a pleasure derived from a vivid and harmo- nious coloring, and a pleasure from the drawing and grouping of the figures. The two pleasures are dis- tinct, and even, to a certain extent, incompatible. For if we attempt to combine them, the grosser and more obtrusive gratification, which we find in the col- oring, distracts us from the more refined and intellect- ual enjoyment we derive from the relation of figure ; while, at the same time, the disgust we soon expe- rience from the one tends to render us insensible to the other. {Led. on Ifetaph, XXIV. 1 ) (B) Distinction in the Qualities of Matter. The qualities of body I divide into three classes. Adopting and adapting, as far as possible, the previ- ous nomenclature, 2 the first of these I would denomi- nate the class of Primary, or Objective, Qualities ; the second, the class of Secundo-Primary, or Subjectivo- Objective, Qualities ; the third, the class of Secondary, or Subjective, Qualities. The general point of view from which the Qualities of Matter are here considered is not the Physical, but 1 See also Reid's Works, Note D *. This note contains a history of the recognition of the distinction between sensation and perception. 2 For a historj' of this distinction, consult Reid's Works, note D. -J. C. M. 74 AN OUTLINE OF the Psychological. But, under this, the ground of principle on which these qualities are divided and des- ignated is, again, twofold. There are, in fact, within the psychological, two special points of view; (1.) that of Sense, and (2.) that of Understanding. 1. The point of view chronologically prior, or first to us, is that of Sense. The principle of division is here the different circumstances under which the qual- ities are originally and immediately apprehended. On this ground, as apprehensions or immediate cognitions through Sense, the Primary are distinguished as ob- jective, not subjective, as percepts proper, not sensa- tions proper ; the Secundo-primary, as objective and subjective, as percepts proper and sensations proper; the Secondary, as subjective, not objective, cognitions, as sensations proper, not percepts proper. 2. The other point of view, chronologically poste- rior, but first in nature, is that of Understanding. The principle of division is here the different charac- ter under which the qualities, already apprehended, are conceived or construed to the mind in thought. On this ground, the Primary, being thought as essen- tial to the notion of Body, are distinguished from the Secundo-primary and Secondary, as accidental; while the Primary and Secundo-primary, being thought as manifest or conceivable in their own nature, are distin- guished from the Secondary, as in their own nature oc- cult and inconceivable. For the notion of Matter hav- ing been once acquired, by reference to that notion, the Primary Qualities are recognized as its a priori or necessary constituents ; and we clearly conceive how they must exist in bodies in knowing what they are sir jvilliam Hamilton's philosophy. 75 objectively in themselves ; the Secundo-primary Qual- ities, again, are -recognized as a posteriori or contin- gent modifications of the Primary, and we clearly con- ceive how they do exist in bodies in knowing what they are objectively in their conditions ; finally, the Secondary Qualities are recognized as a posteriori or contingent accidents of matter, but we obscurely sur- mise how they may exist in bodies only as knowing what they are subjectively in their effects. It is thus apparent that the Primary Qualities may be deduced a priori, the bare notion of matter being given ; they being, in fact, only evolutions of the con- ditions which that notion necessarily implies ; whereas the Secundo-primary and Secondary must be induced a posteriori ; both being attributes contingently super- added to the naked notion of matter. The Primary Qualities thus fall more under the point of view of Understanding, the Secundo-primary and Secondary more under the point of view of Sense. I. Deduction of the Primary Qualities. — Space or extension is a necessary form of thought. We cannot think it as non-existent ; we cannot but think it as existent. But we are not so necessitated to imagine the reality of aught occupying space ; for while unable to conceive as null the space in which the material universe exists, the material universe itself we can, without difficulty, annihilate in thought. All that ex- ists in, all that occupies, space, becomes, therefore, known to us by experience ; we acquire, we con- struct, its notion. The notion of space is thus native, or a priori; the notion of what space contains, ad- 76 AN OUTLINE OF ventitious, or a posteriori. Of this latter class is that of Body or Matter. Now, we ask, what are the necessary or essential, in contrast to the contingent or accidental, properties of Body, as apprehended and conceived by us? The answer to this question affords the class of Primary, as contradistinguished from the two classes of Secun- do-primary and Secondary Qualities. It will be admitted that we are able to conceive body only as that which (1.) occupies space, and (2.) is contained in space. But these catholic conditions of body, though really simple, are logically complex. We may view them in different aspects or relations. 1. The property of filling space (Solidity in its unexclusive signification, Solidity Simple) implies two correlative conditions : {a) the necessity of tri- nal extension, in length, breadth, and thickness (Solid- ity Geometrical) ; (b) the corresponding impossibility of being reduced from what is to what is not thus ex- tended (Solidity Physical, Impenetrability.) (a) Out of the absolute attribute of trinal exten- sion may be again explicated three attributes under the form of necessary relations : (i.) Number or Di- visibility ; (ii.) Size, Bulk, or Magnitude; (iii.) Shape or Figure. i. Body necessarily exists, and is necessarily known, either as one body or as many bodies. Num- ber, i.e., the alternative attribution of unity or plu- ralty, is thus, in a first respect, a primary attribute of matter. But, again, every single body is also, in different points of view, at the same time one and many. Considered as a whole, it is, and is appre- SIR )V1LLIAM HAMILTON'S PHILOSOPHY. 77 bended as actually one ; considered as an extended whole, it is, and is conceived, potentially many. Body being thus necessarily known, if not as already divided, still as always capable of division, Divisibil- ity or Number is thus likewise, in a second respect, a primary attribute of matter. ii. Body (invito majus, this or that body) is not infinitely extended. Each body must, therefore, have a certain finite extension, which, by comparison with that of other bodies, must be less or greater or equal ; in other words, it must by relation have a certain Size, Bulk, or Magnitude; and this again, as esti- mated both (a) by the quantity of space occupied aud (/$) by the quantity of matter occupying, affords likewise the relative attributes of Dense and Rare. iii. Finally, bodies, as not infinitely extended, have consequently their extension bounded. But bounded extension is necessarily of a certain Shape or Figure. (b) The negative notion, the impossibility of con- ceiving the compression of body from an extended to an unextended, its elimination from space, affords the positive notion of an insuperable power in body of resisting such compression or elimination. This force, which, as absolute, is a conception of the un- derstanding, not an apprehension through sense, has received no precise or unambiguous name. We might call it Ultimate or Absolute Incompressibility . 2. The other most general attribute of matter, that of being contained in space, in like manner affords, by explication, an absolute and a relative attribute : (a) the Mobility, that is, the possible motion, and conse- 78 AN OUTLINE OF quently the possible rest, of a body ; and (5) the Situation, Position, Ubication, that is, the local cor- relation of bodies in space. For (a) Space being conceived as infinite (or rather being inconceivable as not infinite) , and the place oc- cupied by body as finite, body in general, and of course each body in particular, is conceived capable either of remaining in the place it now holds, or of being translated from that to any then unoccupied part of space. And (b) As every part of space, i.e., every potential place, holds a certain position relative to every other, so, consequently, must bodies, in so far as they are all contained in space, and as each occupies at one time one determinate space. II. Induction of the Secundo- Primary Qualities. These qualities are modifications, but contingent mod- ifications, of the primary. They suppose the pri- mary ; the primary do not suppose them. They have all relation to space, and motion in space ; and are all contained under the category of Resistance or Pressure. For they are all only various forms of a relative or superable resistance to displacement, which, we learn by experience, bodies oppose to other bodies, and, among these, to our organism moving through space, — a resistance similar in kind (and therefore clearly conceived) to that absolute or in- superable resistance, which we are compelled, inde- pendently of experience, to think that every part of matter would oppose to any attempt to deprive it of its space, by compressing it into an inextended. In so far, therefore, as they suppose the Primary, sib william Hamilton's philosophy. 79 which are necessary, while they themselves are only accidental, they exhibit, on the one side, what may be called a quasi-primary quality ; and, in this re- spect they are to be recognized as percepts, not sen- sations, as objective affections of things, and not as subjective affections of us. But, on the other side, this objective element is always found accompanied by a Secondary quality or sensorial passion. The Secundo-primary qualities have thus always two phases, both immediately apprehended. On their primary or objective phasis, they manifest themselves as degrees of resistance opposed to our locomotive en- ergy ; on their secondary or subjective phasis, as modes of resistance or pressure affecting our sentient organism. Thus standing between, and, in a certain sort, made up of, the two classes of Primary and Sec- ondary qualities, to neither of which, however, can they be reduced ; this their partly common, partly peculiar nature, vindicates to them the dignity of a class apart from both the others, and this under the appropriate appellation of the Secundo-primary Qual- ities. They admit of a classification from two different points of view. They may be (1.) physically, they may be (2.) psychologically, distributed. 1. Considered physically, or in an objective rela- tion, they are to be reduced to classes corresponding to the different sources in external nature from which the resistance or pressure springs. And these sources are, in all, three : (a) that of Go-attraction ; (b) that of Repulsion; (c) that of Inertia. (a) Of the resistance of Co-attraction there may 80 AN" OUTLINE OF be distinguished, on the same objective principle, two subaltern genera: (i.) that of Gravity, or the co-at- traction of the particles of body in general; and (ii.) that of Cohesion, or the co-attraction of the particles of" this and that body in particular. i. The resistance of Gravity or Weight, according to its degree (which, again, is in proportion to the Bulk and Density of ponderable matter), affords, under if, the relative qualities of Heavy and Light (absolute and specific) . ii. The resistance of Cohesion (using that term in its most unexclusive universality) contains many spe- cies and counter-species. Without proposing an ex- haustive, or accurately subordinated, list, of these there may be enumerated (a) the Hard and Soft; (/?) the Firm (Fixed, Stable, Concrete, Solid,) and Fluid (Liquid) , the Fluid being again subdivided into the Thick and Thin ; (r)the Viscid and Friable ; with (5) the Tough and Brittle (Ruptile and Irruptile) ; (e) the Rigid and Flexible; (o-) the Fissile and Injissile; (£) the Ductile and Inductile (Extensible and Inextensi- ble) ; (yj) the Retractile and Irretractile (Elastic and Inelastic) ; (0) (combined with Figure) the Rough and Smooth; (c) the Slippery and Tenacious. (5) The resistance from Repulsion is divided into the counter-qualities of (i.) the (relatively) Compress- ible and Incompressible (ii.) the Resilient and Irre- silient (Elastic and Inelastic) . (c) The resistance from Inertia (combined with Bulk and Cohesion) comprises the counter-qualities of the (relatively) Movable and Immovable. There are thus at least fifteen pairs of counterat- SIP WILLIAM HAMILTON'S PHILOSOPHY. 81 tributes which we may refer to the secundo-primary qualities of body ; — all obtained by the division and subdivision of the resisting forces of matter, consid- ered in an objective or physical point of view. 2. Considered psychologically, or in a subjective relation, they are to be discriminated, under the genus of the Relatively resisting, (a) according to the de- gree in which the resisting force might counteract our locomotive faculty or muscular force, and (6) accord- ing to the mode in which it might affect our capacity of feeling or sentient organism. Of these species, the former would contain under it the gradations of the quasi-primary quality, the latter the varieties of the secondary quality — these constituting the two ele- ments of which, in combination, every secundo-pri- mary quality is made up. III. Induction of the Secondary Qualities. — The secondary, as manifested to us, are not, in propriety, qualities of body at all. As apprehended, they are only subjective affections, and belong only to bodies in so far as these are supposed furnished with the pow- ers capable of specifically determining the various parts of our nervous apparatus to the peculiar action, or rather passion, of which they are susceptible ; which determined action or passion is the quality of which alone we are immediately cognizant, the external con- cause of that internal effect remaining to perception altogether unknown. Thus, the secondary qualities (and the same is to be said, mutatis mutandis, of the secundo-primary) are, considered subjectively, and considered objectively, affections or qualities of things diametrically opposed in nature, — of the organic and 6 82 AN OUTLINE OF inorganic, of the sentient and insentient, of mind and matter ; and though, as mutually correlative, and their several pairs rarely obtaining in common language more than a single name, they cannot well be con- sidered, except in conjunction, under the same cate- gory or general class : still their essential contrast of character must be ever carefully borne in mind. And in speaking of these qualities, as we are here chiefly concerned with them on their subjective side, I re- quest it may be observed, that I shall employ the ex- pression Secondary qualities to denote those phenome- nal affections determined in our sentient organism by the agency of external bodies, and not, unless when otherwise stated, the occult powers themselves from which that agency proceeds. Of the secondary qualities, in this relation, there are various kinds ; the variety principally depending on the differences of the different parts of our nervous apparatus. Such are the proper sensibles, the idio- pathic affections of our several organs of sense, as Color, Sound, Flavor, Savor, and Tactual Sensation ; such are the feelings from Heat, Electricity, Galvanism, etc. ; nor need it be added, such are the muscular and cutaneous sensations which accompany the perception of the secundo-primary qualities. Such, though less directly the result of foreign causes, are Titillation, Sneezing, Horripilation, Shuddering, the feeling of what is called Setting-the-teeth-on-edge, etc., etc.; such, in fine, are all the various sensations of bodily pleasure and pain determined by the action of external stimuli. (jReid's Works, Note D.) From the above account of the distinction between sir william Hamilton's philosophy. 83 - »» d £ * 2 3 »S -o -2 55 a. 55 e ft? g I »! 3 O • s a •S i ^ -3 -a ,d d a in -« |t a •-5 "Si "S 'P. -3 > •3 o o ID s § § O -2 C) Oh « 60 fc .2 ft S a Ed O 2 S « sin william Hamilton's philosophy. 89 (i.) If the veracity of consciousness be allowed to the equipoise of the object and subject in the act, but rejected as to the reality of their antithesis, the system of Absolute Identity emerges, which reduces both mind and matter to phenomenal modifications of the same common substance. (ii.) and (iii.) If the testimony of consciousness be refused to the co-originality and reciprocal indepen- dence of the subject and object, two schemes are de- termined, according as the one or the other of the terms is placed as the original and genetic. Is the object educed from the subject, Idealism; is the sub- ject educed from the object, Materialism, is the result. These systems are all conclusions from an original interpretation of the fact of consciousness in per- ception, carried intrepidly forth to its legitimate issue. But there is one scheme, which, violating the integrity of this fact, and, with the complete idealist, regarding the object of consciousness in perception as only a modification of the percipient subject, or, at least, a phenomenon numerically different from the object it represents, — endeavors, however, to stop short of the negation of an external world, the reality of which, and the knowledge of whose reality, it seeks by various hypotheses to establish and explain. This scheme, — which we would term Cosmothetic Idealism, Hypothetical Realism, or Hypothetical Dualism, — although the most inconsequent of all systems, has been embraced, under various forms, by the immense majority of philosophers. (Reid's Works, pp. 748-9. ) J 1 See also Discussions, pp. 55-6 ; and Led. on Metaph. (XVI.) Keid's Works, Note C, contain a more elaborate classification of the 90 AN OUTLINE OF § 2. SELF-CONSCIOUSNESS. This faculty will not occupy us long, as the princi- pal questions regarding its nature and operation have been already considered, in treating of Consciousness in general. I formerly showed that it is impossible to distin- guish Perception, or the other Special Faculties, from Consciousness, — in other words, to reduce Conscious- ness itself to a special faculty. I stated, however, that though it be incompetent to establish a faculty for the immediate knowledge of the external world, and a faculty for the immediate knowledge of the in- ternal, as two ultimate powers, exclusive of each other, and not merely subordinate forms of a higher immediate knowledge, under which they are compre- hended or carried up into one, — I stated, I say, that though the immediate knowledges of matter and of mind are still only modifications of Consciousness, yet that their discrimination, as subaltern faculties, is both allowable and convenient. The sphere and character of this faculty of acquisi- tion will be best illustrated by contrasting it with the other. Perception is the power by which we are made aware of the phenomena of the external world ; Self-consciousness, the power by which we apprehend the phenomena of the internal. The objects of the various theories of perception. In the Led. on MetapJi. (Lect. XXV.) will be found a vindication of Natural Realism; and in the following lecture, a polemic against Hypothetical Eealism. — J. C. M. SIB WILLIAM HAMILTON'S PHILOSOPHY. 91 former are all presented to us in space and time ; space and time are thus the two conditions, — the two fundamental forms of external perception. The objects of the latter are all apprehended by us in time and in self; time and self are thus the two conditions, — the two fundamental forms, — of Internal Perception or Self-consciousness. Time is thus a form or condi- tion common to both faculties ; while space is a form peculiar to the one, self a form peculiar to the other. What I mean by the form or condition of a faculty, is that frame, that setting (if I may so speak), out of which no object can be known. Thus, we only know, through Self-consciousness, the phenomena of the Internal world, as modifications of the indivisible Ego or conscious unit ; we only know, through per- ception, the phenomena of the External world, under space, or as modifications of the extended and divisible Non-ego or known plurality. Two difficulties, how- ever, may here be suggested : — 1. It may be asked, if self, or Ego, be the form of Self-consciousness, why is the not-self, the Non-ego, not in like maimer called the form of Perception ? To this I reply, that the not-self is only a negation, and, though it discriminates the objects of the external cog- nition from those of the internal, it does not afford to the former any positive bond of union among them- selves. This, on the contrary, is supplied to them by the form of Space, out of which they can neither be perceived, nor imagined by the mind. Space, there- fore, as the positive condition under which the Non- ego is necessarily known and imagined, and through 92 ■ AN OUTLINE OF which it receives its unity in Consciousness, is'properly said to afford the condition, or form, of External Per- ception. 2. But a more important question may be started. If Space, if extension, be a necessary form of thought, this, it may be argued, proves that the mind itself is extended. The reasoning here proceeds upon the assumption that the qualities of the subject know- ing must be similar to the qualities of the object known. This, as I have already stated, is a mere philosophical crotchet, — an assumption without a shadow even of probability in its favor. That the mind has the power of perceiving extended objects is no ground for holding that it is itself extended. Still less can it be maintained, that because it has ideally a native or necessary conception of Space, it must really occupy Space. Nothing can be more ab- surd. On this doctrine, to exist as extended is sup- posed necessary in order to think extension. But if this analogy hold» good, the sphere of ideal Space, which the mind can imagine, ought to be limited to the sphere of real Space which the mind actually fills. This is not, however, the case ; for though the mind be not absolutely unlimited in its power of conceiving Space, still the compass of thought may be viewed as infinite in this respect, as contrasted with the petty point of extension, which the advocates of the doc- trine in question allow it to occupy in its corporeal domicile. The faculty of Self-consciousness affords us a knowl- edge of the phenomena of our minds. It is the source of Internal experience. You will, therefore, observe, sin william Hamilton's philosophy. 93 that, like External Perception, it only furnishes us with facts ; and that the use we make of these facts — that is, what we find in them, what we deduce from them — belongs to a different process of intelli- gence. Self-consciousness affords the materials equally to all systems of philosophy ; all equally admit it, and all elaborate the materials which this faculty supplies, according to their fashion. (Led. on Metaph., XXIX.) PHENOMENOLOGY OF THE COGNITIONS. CHAPTER II. THE CONSERVATIVE FACULTY. MEMORY PROPER. Through the powers of External and Internal Per- ception, we are enabled to acquire information, — experience ; but this acquisition is not of itself inde- pendent and complete ; it supposes that we are also able to retain knowledge acquired, for we cannot be said to get what we are unable to keep. The faculty of Acquisition is, therefore, only realized through an- other faculty, — the faculty of Retention or Conserva- tion. Here we have another example of what I have already frequently had occasion to suggest to your observation; we have two faculties, two elementary phenomena, evidently distinct, and yet each depend- ing on the other for its realization. Without a power of Acquisition, a power of Conservation could not be exerted ; and, without the latter, the former would be frustrated, for we should lose as fast as we acquired. But as the faculty of Acquisition would be useless without the faculty of Retention, so the faculty of Re- tention would be useless without the faculties of Re- 94 AN OUTLINE OF HAMILTON'S PHILOSOPHY. 95 production and Representation. That the mind retained, beyond the sphere of consciousness, a treas- ury of knowledge would be of no avail, did it not possess the power of bringing out, and of displaying, — in other words, of reproducing, and representing, — this knowledge in consciousness. But because the faculty of Conservation would be fruitless without the ulterior faculties of Reproduction and Representation, we are not to confound these faculties, or to view the act of mind, which is their joint result, as a simple and elementary phenomenon. Though mutually de- pendent on each other, the faculties of Conservation, Reproduction, and Representation are governed by dif- ferent laws, and, in different individuals, are found greatly varying in their comparative vigor. The in- timate connection of these three faculties, or elemen- tary activities, is the cause, however, why they have not been distinguished in the analysis of philosophers ; and why their distinction is not precisely marked in ordinary language. In ordinary language, we have, indeed , words which , without excluding the other fac- ulties, denote one of these more emphatically. Thus, in the term Memory, the Conservative Faculty, the phenomenon of Retention is the central notion, with which, however, those of Reproduction and Represen- tation are associated. In the term Recollection, again, the phenomenon of Reproduction is the principal no- tion, accompanied, however, by those of Retention and Representation, as its subordinates. By Memory or Retention, you will see, is only meant the condition of Reproduction ; and it is, there- fore, evident that it is only by an extension of the 96 AN OUTLINE OF term that it can be called a faculty, that is, an active power. It is more a passive resistance than an energy, and ought, therefore, perhaps to receive rather the appellation of a capacity. But the nature of this ca- pacity or faculty we must now proceed to consider. (Led. on Metaph., XXX.) § 1. THE FACT OF RETENTION. In the first place, then, I presume that the fact of Retention is admitted. "We are conscious of certain cognitions as acquired, and we are conscious of these cognitions as resuscitated. That, in the interval, when out of consciousness, these cognitions do con- tinue to subsist in the mind, is certainly an hypothe- sis, because whatever is out of consciousness can only be assumed ; but it is an hypothesis which we are not only warranted, but necessitated, by the phenomena, to establish. For, besides the phenomena of Reten- tion, there are many which it is impossible to explain by any other hypothesis ; and I shall here adduce the evidence which appears to me not merely to warrant, but to necessitate the conclusion, that the sphere of our conscious modifications is only a small circle in the centre of a far wider sphere of action and passion, of which we are only conscious through its effects. I. External Perception. Let us take our first ex- ample from Perception, and in that faculty let us commence with 1. The sense of Sight. Now, you either already know, or can be at once informed, what it is that has sir william Hamilton's philosophy. 97 obtained the name of Minimum Visibile. You are of course aware, in general, that vision is the result of the rays of light reflected from the surface of objects to the eye ; a greater number of rays is reflected from a larger surface ; if the superficial extent of an object, and, consequently, the number of rays which it re- flects, be diminished beyond a certain limit, the ob- ject becomes invisible ; and the Minimum Visibile is the smallest expanse which can be seen, — which can consciously affect us, — which we can be conscious of seeiug. This being understood, it is plain that, if we divide this Minimum Visibile into two parts, neither half can, by itself, be an object of vision, or visual consciousness. They are, severally and apart, to consciousness as zero. But it is evident that each half must, hy itself, have produced in us a certain modification, real though unperceived ; for as the per- ceived whole is nothing but the union of the unper- ceived halves, so the Perception — the perceived affection itself of which we are conscious — is only the sum of two modifications, each of which severally eludes our consciousness. When we look at a distant forest, we perceive a certain expanse of green. Of this, as an affection of our organism, we are clearly and distinctly conscious. Now, the expanse, of which we are conscious, is evidently made up of parts of which we are not conscious. No leaf, perhaps no tree, may be separately visible. But the greenness of the forest is made up of the greenness of the leaves ; that is, the total impression of which we are conscious is made up of an infinitude of small im- pressions of which we are not conscious. 7 98 AN OUTLINE OF 2. Sense of Hearing. — Take another example, from the sense of hearing. In this sense, there is, in like manner, a Minimum Audibile, that is, a sound the least which can come into perception and conscious- ness. But this Minimum Audibile is made up of parts which severally affect *the sense, but of which affec- tions, separately, we are not conscious, though of their joint result we are. We must, therefore, here likewise admit the reality of modifications beyond the sphere of consciousness. To take a special example. When we hear the distant murmur of the sea, — what are the constituents of the total perception of which we are conscious? This murmur is a sum made up of parts, and the sum would be as zero if the parts did not count as something. The noise of the sea is the complement of the noise of its several waves ; — tzovtL XXX.) PHENOMENOLOGY OF THE COGNITIONS. CHAPTER III. THE REPRODUCTIVE FACULTY. I now pass to the next faculty in order, — the fac- ulty which I have called the Reproductive. I am not satisfied with this name ; for it does not precisely, of itself, mark what I wish to be expressed, — namely, the process by which what is lying dormant in mem- ory is awakened, as contradistinguished from the rep- resentation in consciousness of it as awakened. Perhaps the Resuscitative Faculty would have been better ; and the term Reproduction might have been employed to comprehend the whole process, made up of the correlative acts of Retention, Resuscitation, and Representation. Be this, however, as it may, I shall at present continue to employ the term in the limited meaning I have already assigned. Every one is conscious of a ceaseless succession or train of thoughts, one thought suggesting another, which again is the cause of exciting a third, and so on. But if thoughts and feelings and conations (for you must observe, that the train is not limited to the phe- 110 AN OUTLINE OF HAMILTON'S PHILOSOPHY. Ill noinena of cognition only) do notarise of themselves, but only in causal connection with preceding and sub- sequent modifications of mind, it remains to be asked and answered, — Do the links of this chain follow each other under any other condition than that of sim- ple connection? — in other words, may any thought, feeling, or desire be connected ivith any other? Or is the succession regulated by other and special laws, ac- cording to which certain kinds of modification exclu- sively precede, and exclusively follow, each other? The slightest observation of the phenomenon shows that the latter alternative is the, case ; and on this all philosophers are agreed. Nor do philosophers differ in regard to what kind of thoughts are associated to- gether. They differ almost exclusively in regard to the subordinate question, of how these thoughts ought to be classified, and carried up into system. This, therefore, is the question to which I shall address myself. (Led. on Metaph., XXXT.) The relations, on the ground of which one thought suggests another, give us what may be called the primary laws of Reproduction; but when several thoughts are all capable of being suggested by another, as all equally related by the primary laws, what de- termines which of these thoughts shall actually be suggested ? The principles that determine this may be named secondary laws of Reproduction. 1 1 In this paragraph 1" have attempted an explicit definition of the distinction, as drawn by Hamilton, between the primary and the sec- ondary laws of reproduction. — J. C. M. 112 AN OUTLINE OF § 1. PRIMARY LAWS OF REPRODUCTION. There are three subjective unities, wholes, or identi- ties , each of which affords a ground of chronological succession, and reciprocal suggestion, to the several thoughts which they comprehend in one. In other words, Reproduction has three sources. These are (1.) The unity of thoughts, differing in time and mod- ification, in a co-identity of Subject; (2.) The unity of thoughts, differing in time, in a co-identity of Mod- ification; (3.) The unity of thoughts, differing in modification, in a co-identity of Time. The three unities thus characterized constitute three (A) General Laws op Reproduction. I. Law of Possible Reproduction. Of these unities the first affords a common principle of the pos- sibility of association, or mutual suggestion for all our mental movements, however different in their charac- ter as modifications, however remote in the times of their occurrence ; for all, even the most heterogene- ous and most distant, are reproducible, co-suggestible, or associable, as, and only as, phenomena of the same unity of consciousness, — affections of the same indi- visible Ego. There thus emerges the Law of Asso- ciability or Possible Co-Suggestion : All thoughts of the same mental subject are associable, or capable of suggesting one another. II. Laws op Actual Reproduction. But the unity of subject, the fundamental condition of the as- sociability of thought in general, affords no reason sin william Hamilton's philosophy. 113 why this particular thought should, de facto, recall or suggest that. We require, therefore, besides a law of possible, a law or laws of actual Reproduction. Two such are afforded iu the tivo other unities, — those of Modification and of Time. And now let us, for the sake of subsequent refer- ence, pause a moment to state the following symbolic illustration : — ABC A' A" Here the same letter, repeated in perpendicular or- der, is intended to denote the same mental mode, brought into consciousness, represented, at different times. Here the different letters, in horizontal order, are supposed to designate the partial thoughts inte- grant of a total mental state, and therefore coexistent or immediately consequent, at the moment of its actual realization. This being understood, we proceed : — Of these two unities that of modification affords the ground, why, for example, an object determining a mental modification of a certain complement and char- acter to-day, this presentation tends to call up the representation of the same modification determined by that object yesterday. Or suppose, as in our sym- bols, the three A's to typify the same thought, deter- mined at three different times, be the determining movement of a presentation or a representation. On the second occasion, A' will suggest the representation of A. This it will not be denied that it can do ; for, 114 AN OUTLINE OF on the possibility hereof depends the- possibility of simple remembrance. The total thought, after this suggestion, will be A' -(- A ; and on the third occa- sion, A" may suggest A' and A ; both on this princi- ple, and on that other which we are immediately to consider, of co-identity in time. We have thus, as a first general law of actual Reproduction, Suggestion, or Association : — 1. The Law or Repetition or of Direct Re- membrance : Thoughts, co-identical in modification, but differing in time, tend to suggest each other. The unity of time affords the ground why thoughts, different in their character as mental modes, but hav- ing once been proximately coexistent (including under coexistence immediate consecution) as the parts of some total thought, — and a totality of thought is determined even by a unity of time, — do, when recalled into consciousness, tend immediately to .suggest each other, as co-constituents of that former whole, and mediately, that whole itself. Thus let (A, B, C, D, E, F) be supposed a complement of such concomitant thoughts. If A be recalled into consciousness, A will tend to reawaken B, B fy) re- awaken C, and so on, until the whole formerly co- existent series has been reinstated, or the mind di- verted by some stronger movement on some other train. We have thus, as a second general law of ac- tual Reproduction, Suggestion, or Association, — 2. The Law of Redintegration, of Indirect Remembeance, or of Reminiscence : Thoughts, once co-identical in time, are, however different as men- sir william Hamilton's philosophy. 115 tal modes, again suggestive of each other, and that in the mutual order which they originally held. Philosophers, in generalizing the phenomena of re- production, have, if the exception of Aristotle be ad- mitted, of these two, exclusively regarded the law of Redintegration. That of Repetition was, however, equally worthy of their consideration . For the exci- tation of the same by the same, differing in time, is not less marvellous than the excitation of the differ- ent by the different, identical in time. It was a prin- ciple, too, equally indispensable to explain the phe- nomena. For the attempts to reduce these to the law of Redintegration alone will not stand the test of criticism ; since the reproduction of thought by thought, as disjoined in time, cannot be referred to the reproduction of thought by thought, as conjoined in time. Accordingly we shall find, in coming to de- tail, that some phenomena are saved by the law of Repetition alone, while others require a combination of the two laws of Repetition and Redintegration. Such combinations of these two laws constitute the (B) Special Laws of Repkoduction. The laws under this head are, — I. The Law of Similaes : Things, — thoughts, resembling each other (be the resemblance simple or an- alogical) , are mutually suggestive. From Aristotle downwards, all who have written on Suggestion, whether intentional or spontaneous, have recognized the association of similar objects. But whilst all have thus fairly acknowledged the ef- fect, none, I think (if Aristotle be not a singular excejDtion) , have speculated aright as to the cause. 116 AN OUTLINE OF Iii general, Similarity has been lightly assumed, lightly laid down, as one of the ultimate principles of associations. Nothing, however, can be clearer than that resembling objects, — resembling mental modifi- cations, — being, to us, in their resembling points, identical, they must, on the principle of Repetition, call up each other. This, of course, refers principally to suggestion for the first time. Subsequently, Redinte- gration co-operates with Repetition ; for now the re- sembling parts have formed together parts of the same mental whole, and are, moreover, associated both as similar and as contrasted. II. The Law of Contkast : Things, — thoughts, contrasted with each other (be the contrast one of con- trariety or of contradiction) , are mutually suggestive. 1. All contrast is of things Contained under a com- mon notion. Qualities are contrasted only as they are similar. A good horse and a bad syllogism have no contrast. Virtue and vice agree as moral attri- butes ; great and little agree as quantities, and as ex- traordinary deflections from ordinary quantity. Even existence and non-existence are not opposed as differ- ent genera, but only as species of existence, — posi- tive existence and negative existence. Conspecies thus (as wolf and dog) may be associated either as similars or as contraries, — similars as opposed to ani- mals of other genera, — contraries as opposed to each other. Contraries are thus united under a higher no- tion. 2. Affirmation of any quality involves the negation of its contradictory, — the affirmation of goodness is virtually the negation of badness ; and many terms sir william Hamilton's philosophy. 117 for the contradictory qualities are only negations and affirmations, — just, unjust, — finite, infinite, — par- tial, impartial. Hence logical contradictory opposi- tion is even a stronger association than logical con- trariety, because only between two. 3. Contrast is a relation, — the knowledge of con- traries is one. 4. Consciousness is only of the distinguishable ; and therefore contrast most clearly distinguished must heighten consciousness. III. The Law of Co-adjacency : Things, — thoughts, related to each other as Cause and Effect, Whole and Parts, Substance and Attribute, Sign and Signified, are mutually suggestive. § 2. SECONDARY LAWS OF REPRODUCTION. In obedience to the primary laws, movements sug- gest and are suggested in proportion to the strictness of the dependency between that prior and this poste- rior.. But such general relation between two thoughts — and on which are founded the two Abstract or Primary laws of Repetition and Redintegration — is frequently crossed, is frequently superseded, by an- other, and that a particular relation, which determines the suggestion of a movement not warranted by any dependence on its antecedent. To complete the laws of reproduction we must therefore recognize, as a Secondary or Concrete principle, what may be styled (under protest, for it is hardly deserving of the title Law), The Law of Preference: Thoughts are suggested, not merely by force of the general subjective 118 AN OUTLINE OF relation subsisting between themselves; they are als'o suggested in proportion to the relation of interest (from whatever source) in which these stand to the individual mind. This general law of Preference yields, as its modes, the special secondary laws ; for, under the laws of possibility, one thought being associated with a plural- ity, and each of that plurality being therefore suggest- ible, it suggests one in preference to another according to two laws: (1.) By relation to itself, the thought most strictly associated with itself; (2.) By relation to mind, the thought most easily suggestible. That there must be two laws, is shown, because two associ- ated thoughts do not suggest each other with equal force. B may be very strongly associated with A, but A very slightly associated with B. This is two- fold ; (1.) in order of time, (2.) in order of interest. (A) Under the first head, that of suggestion by re- lation to the thought suggesting, may be stated the fol- lowing special laws : — I. The Law op Immediacy : Of two thoughts, if the one be immediately, the other mediately, connected with a third, the first will be suggested by the third in preference to the secoyid. - II. The Law of Homogeneity : A thought ivill suggest another of the same order in preference to one of a different order. Thus a smell will suggest a smell, a sight a sight, an imagination an imagination, in preference to a thought of a different class. (B) Under the second head, that of suggestion by relation to the mind, may be stated, as a special law, sin william Hamilton's philosophy. 119 The Law of Facility : A thought easier to suggest will be roused in preference to a more difficult one. The easier are I. Those more clearly, strongly impressed than the reverse. Such are ideas more undistractedly, atten- tively received; in youth, in the morning; assisted by novelty, wonder, passion, etc. Hence, also, sights are more easily suggested than smells, imaginations than thoughts, etc. II. Those more recent, than older (cceteris par- ibus} . III. Those more frequently repeated (caiteris par- ibus) . IV. Those which stand more isolated from foreign and thwarting thoughts. V. Those which are more connected with homoge- neous and assisting thoughts. VI. Those more interesting to (1.) natural cogni- tive powers, talents ; (2.) acquired habits of cognition, studies ; (3.) temporary line of occupation. VII. Those more in harmony with affective dispo- sitions, (1.) natural, (2.) habitual, (3.) temporary. 1 (Beid's Works, Note D***.) 1 It is due to Sir William Hamilton to bear in mind, that bis the- ory of the laws of reproduction seems never to have been worked into a form perfectly satisfactory to himself. Nearly all that relates to the secondary laws, as well as to the special primary laws, is left in an unfinished state. The exposition in reference to these points, which I have given, is taken, with a few alterations and additions of expression, from the fragments obtained by Mr. Mansel among Sir William's papers. — J. C. M. 120 AN OUTLINE OF § 3. DISTINCTION OF SUGGESTION AND REMINISCENCE. The faculty of Reproduction may be considered as operating either spontaneously, without any interfer- ence of the will, or as modified in its action by the in- tervention of volition. In the one case, as in the other, the Reproductive Faculty acts in subservience to its own laws. In the former case, one thought is allowed to suggest another, according to the greater general connection subsisting between them ; in the latter, the act of volition, by concentrating attention upon a certain determinate class of associating circum- stances, bestows on these circumstances an extraordi- nary vivacity, and, consequently, enables them to ob- tain the preponderance, and exclusively to determine the succession of the intellectual train. The former of these cases, where the Reproductive Faculty is left wholly to itself, may not improperly be called Spon- taneous Suggestion, or Suggestion simply ; the latter ought to obtain the name of Reminiscence or Recol- lection. To form a correct notion of the phenomena of Rem- iniscence, it is requisite that we consider under what conditions it is determined to exertion. In the first place, it is to be noted that, at every crisis of our ex- istence, momentary circumstances are the causes which awaken our activity, and set our recollection at work to supply the necessaries of thought. In the second place, it is as constituting a want (and by want, I mean the result either of an act of desire or of voli- tion) , that the determining circumstance tends prin- SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON'' S PHILOSOPHY. 121 cipally to awaken the thoughts with which it is asso- ciated. This being the case, we should expect that each circumstance which constitutes a want should suggest, likewise, the notion of an object, or objects, proper to satisfy it ; and this is what actually hap- pens. It is, however, further to be observed, that it is not enough that the want suggests the idea of the object ; for if that idea were alone, it would remain without effect, since it could not guide me in the pro- cedure I should follow. It is necessary, at the same time, that to the idea of this object there shoidd be associated the notion of the relation of this object to the want, of the place where I may find it, of the means by which I may procure it, and turn it to ac- count, etc. For instance, I wish to make a quota- tion : this want awakens in me the idea of the author in whom the passage is to be found, which I am de- sirous of citing ; but this idea would be fruitless, un- less there were conjoined, at the same time, the representation of the volume, of the place where I may obtain it, of the means I must employ, etc. Hence I infer, in the first place, that a want does not awaken an idea of its object alone, but that it awakens it accompanied with a number, more or less considerable, of accessory notions, which form, as it were, its train or attendance. This train may vary according to the nature of the want which suggests the notion of an object ; but the train can never fall wholly off, and it becomes more indissolubly attached to the object, in proportion as it has been more fre- quently called up in attendance. I infer, in the second place, that this accompani- 122 AN OUTLINE OF ment of accessory notions, simultaneously suggested with the principal idea, is far from being as vividly and distinctly represented in consciousness as that idea itself; and when these accessories have once been completely blended with the habits of the mind, and its reproductive agency, they at length finally dis- appear, becoming fused, as it were, in the conscious- ness of the idea to which they are attached. Thus, if we appreciate correctly the phenomena of Reproduction or Reminiscence, we shall recognize, as an incontestable fact, that our thoughts suggest each other, not one by one successively, as the order to which language is astricted might lead us to infer ; but that the complement of circumstances, under which we at every moment exist, awakens simultaneously a great number of thoughts ; these it calls into the presence of the mind, either to place them at our dis- posal, if we find it requisite to employ them, or to make them co-operate in our deliberations, by giving them, according to their nature and our habits, an influence, more or less active, on our judgments and consequent acts. It is also to be observed, that, in this great crowd of thoughts always present to the mind, there is only a small number of which we are distinctly conscious ; and that, in this small number, we ought to distinguish those which, being clothed in language oral or men- tal, become the objects of a more fixed attention; those which hold a closer relation to circumstances more impressive than others ; or which receive a pre- dominant character by the more vigorous attention we bestow on them. As to the others, although not the SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON 's PHILOSOPHY. 123 objects of clear consciousness, they are nevertheless present to the mind, there to perform a very impor- tant part as motive principles of determination ; and the influence which they exert in this capacity is even the more powerful in proportion as it is less apparent, being more disguised by habit. (Led. on 3Ietaj)h., XXXII.) PHENOMENOLOGY OE THE COGNITIONS. CHAPTEE IV. THE REPRESENTATIVE FACULTY. By the faculty of Representation, as I formerly men- tioned, I mean strictly the power the mind has of holding up vividly before itself the thoughts which, by the act of Eeproduction, it has recalled into con- sciousness. Though the processes of Representation and Reproduction cannot exist independently of each other, they are nevertheless not more to be confounded into one than those of Reproduction and Conservation. They are, indeed, discriminated by differences suffi- ciently decisive. Reproduction, as we have seen, op- erates, in part at least, out of consciousness. Repre- sentation, on the contrary, is only realized as it is realized in consciousness ; the degree or vivacity of the Representation being always in proportion to the degree or vivacity of our consciousness of its reality. Nor are the energies of Representation and Reproduction always exerted by the same individual in equal inten- sity, any more than the energies of Reproduction and Retention. Some minds are distinguished for a higher 124 AN OUTLINE OF HAMILTON'S PHILOSOPHY. 125 power of manifesting one of these phenomena ; others, for manifesting another ; and as it is not always the person who forgets nothing who can most promptly recall what he retains, so neither is it always the per- son who recollects most easily and correctly who can exhibit what he remembers in the most vivid colors. It is to be recollected, however, that Retention, Re- production, and Representation, though not in differ- ent persons of the same relative vigor, are, however, in the same individuals, all strong or weak in refer- ence to the same classes of objects. For example, if a man's memory be more peculiarly retentive of words, his verbal reminiscence and imagination will, in like manner, be more particularly energetic. In common language, it is not of course to be ex- pected that there should be found terms to express the result of an analysis which had not even been per- formed by philosophers ; and, accordingly, the term Imagination, or Phantasy, which denotes most nearly the Representative process, does this, how- ever, not without an admixture of other processes, which it is of consequence for scientific precision that we should consider apart. In the view I take of the fundamental processes, the act of Representation is merely the energy of the mind in holding up to its own contemplation what it is determined to represent. I distinguish, as essen- tially different, the Representation and the determi- nation to represent. I exclude from the Faculty of Representation all power of preference among the ob- jects it holds up to view. This is the function of faculties wholly different from that of Representation, 126 AN OUTLINE OF which, though active in representing, is wholly pas- sive as to what it represents. What, then, it maybe asked, are the powers by which the Representative Faculty is determined to represent, and to represent this particular object, or this particular complement of objects, and not any other? These are two. 1. The first of these is the Reproductive Faculty. This faculty is the great immediate source from which the Representative receives both the materials and the determination to represent ; and the laws by which the Reproductive Faculty is governed govern also the Representative. Accordingly, if there were no other laws in the arrangement and combination of thought than those of association, the Representative Faculty would be determined in its manifestations, and in the character of its manifestations, by the Reproductive Faculty alone ; and, on this supposition, Representa- tion could no more be distinguished from Reproduc- tion than Reproduction from Association. 2. But there is another elementary process which we have not yet considered : Comparison, or the Faculty of Relations , to which the representative act is likewise subject, and which plays a conspicuous part in determining in what combinations objects are rep- resented. By the process of Comparison, the complex objects, called up by the Reproductive Faculty, un- dergo various operations. They are separated into parts ; they are analyzed into elements ; and these parts and elements are again compounded in every various fashion. In all this the Representative Fac- ulty co-operates. It, first of all, exhibits the phe- nomena so called up by the laws of ordinary associa- sir William Hamilton's philosophy. 127 lion. In this it acts as handmaid to the Reproductive Faculty. It then exhibits the phenomena as variously elaborated by the analysis and synthesis of the Com- parative Faculty, to which, in like manner, it performs the part of a subsidiary. 1 This being understood, you will easily perceive that the Imagination of common language — the Productive Imagination of philosophers — is nothing but the Representative process, plus the process to which I would give the name of the Comparative. In this compound operation, it is true that the Represen- tative act is the most conspicuous, perhaps the most essential, element. For, in the^rs^ place, it is a con- dition of the possibility of the act of comparison, that the material on which it operates (that is, the objects reproduced in their natural connections) should be held up to its observation in a clear light, in order that it may take note of their various circumstances of relation ; and, in the second, that the result of its own elaboration, that is, the new arrangements which it proposes, should be realized in a vivid act of Rep- resentation. Thus it is, that, in the view both of the vulgar and of philosophers, the more obtrusive, though really the more subordinate, element in this compound process has been elevated into the princi- pal constituent ; whereas, the act of Comparison — the act of separation and reconstruction — has been re- garded as identical with the act of Representation. Thus Imagination, in the common acceptation of the term, is not a simple but a compound faculty, — a faculty, however, in which Representation forms the principal constituent. If, therefore, we were. obliged 128 AN OUTLINE OF to find a common word for every elementary process of our analysis, Imagination would be the term which, with the least violence to its meaning, could be ac- commodated to express the Kepresentative Faculty. By Imagination, thus limited, you are not to sup- pose that the faculty of representing mere objects of sense alone is meant. On the contrary, a vigorous power of Kepresentation is as indispensable a condi- tion of success in the abstract sciences as in the poet- ical and plastic arts ; and it may, accordingly, be reasonably doubted whether Aristotle or Homer were possessed of the more powerful Imagination. The term Imagination, however, is less generally applied to the representations of the Comparative Faculty considered in the abstract than to the representations of sensible objects concretely modified by comparison. The two kinds of imagination are, in fact, not fre- quently combined. Accordingly, using the term in this its ordinary extent, that is, in its limitation to objects of sense, it is finely said by Mr. Hume : "Nothing is more dangerous to reason than the flights of imagination, and nothing has been the occasion of more mistakes among philosophers. Men of bright fancies may, in this respect, be compared to those angels whom the Scriptures represent as covering their eyes with their wings." Dreaming, Somnambulism, Eeverie, are so many effects of imagination determined by association, — at least, states of mind in which these have a decisive in- fluence. 1. Dreaming. If an impression on the sense often commences a dream, it is by imagination and sugges- sir william Hamilton's philosophy. 129 tion that it is developed and accomplished. Dreams have frequently a degree of vivacity which enables them to compete with the reality ; and if the events which they represent to us were in accordance with the circumstances of time and place in which we stand, it would be almost impossible to distinguish a vivid dream from a sensible perception. " If," says Pascal,, " we dreamt every night the same thing, it would per- haps affect us as powerfully as the objects which we perceive every day. And if an artisan were certain of dreaming every night for twelve hours that he was a king, I am convinced that he would be almost as happy as a king who dreamt for twelve hours that he was an artisan It is only because dreams are different and inconsistent, that we can say, when we awake, that we have dreamt; for life is a dream a little less inconstant." The influence of dreams upon our character is not without its interest. A particular tendency may be strengthened in, a man solely by the repeated action of dreams. Dreams do not, however, as is commonly supposed, afford any appreciable indication of the character of individuals. It is not always the subjects that occupy us most when awake that form the mat- ter of our dreams ; and it is curious that the persons the dearest to us are precisely those about whom we dream most rarely. 2. Somnambulism is a phenomenon still more as- tonishing. In this singular state, a person performs a regular series of rational actions, and those fre- quently of the most difficult and delicate nature, and, what is still more marvellous, with a talent to which 9 130 AN OUTLINE OF he could make no pretension when awake. His mem- ory and reminiscence supply him with recollections of words and things which perhaps were never at his disposal in the ordinary state ; he speaks more fluently a more refined language ; and, if we are to credit what the evidence on which it rests hardly allows us to disbelieve, he has not only per- ceptions through other channels than the common or- gans of sense, but the sphere of his cognitions is am- plified to an extent far beyond the limits to which sensible perception is confined. This subject is one of the most perplexing in the whole compass of phi- losophy ; for, on the one hand, the phenomena are so marvellous that they cannot be believed, and yet, on the other, they are of so unambiguous and palpable a character, and the witnesses to their reality are so numerous, so intelligent, and so high above every suspicion of deceit, that it is equally impossible to deny credit to what is attested by such ample and un- exceptionable evidence. 3. Reverie. The third state, that of Reverie, or castle-building, is a kind of wakiug dream, and does not differ from dreaming, except by the consciousness which accompanies it. In this state, the mind aban- dons itself without a choice of subject, without control over the mental train, to the involuntary associa- tions of imagination. It is thus occupied without being properly active ; it is active, at least, without effort. Young persons, women, the old, the unem- ployed, and the idle, are all disposed to reverie. There is a pleasure attached to its illusions, which renders it as seductive as it is dangerous. The mind, sir william Hamilton's philosophy. 131 by indulgence in this dissipation, becomes enervated ; it acquires the habit of a pleasing idleness, loses its activity, and at length even the power and the desire of action. Organs of Imagination. I shall terminate the consideration of Imagination Proper by a speculation concerning the organ which it employs in the repre- sentations of sensible objects. The organ which it thus employs seems to be no other than the organs themselves of Sense, on which the original impressions were made, and through which they were originally perceived. Experience has shown that Imagination depends on no one part of the cerebral apparatus ex- clusively. There is no portion of the brain which has not been destroyed by mollification, or induration, or external lesion, without the general faculty of Repre- sentation being injured. But experience equally proves that the intracranial portion of any external organ of sense cannot be destroyed without a certain partial abolition of the Imagination Proper. For ex- ample, there are many cases recorded by medical ob- servers, of persons losing their sight, who have also lost the faculty of representing the images of visible objects. They no longer call up such objects by remi- niscence ; they no longer dream of them. Now, in these cases, it is found that not merely the external instrument. of sight — the eye — has been disorgan- ized, but that the disorganization has extended to those parts of the brain which constitute the internal instrument of this sense, that is, the optic nerves and thalami. If the latter — the real organ of vision — remain sound, the eye alone being destroyed, the im- 132 AN OUTLINE OF HAMILTON' S PHILOSOPHY. agination of colors and forms remains as vigorous as when vision was entire. Similar cases are recorded in regard to the deaf. These facts, added to the ob- servation of the internal phenomena which take place during our acts of representation, make it, I think, more than probable that there are as many organs of Imagination as there are organs of Sense. Thus I have a distinct consciousness, that, in the internal representation of visible objects, the same organs are at work which operate in the External Perception of these ; and the same holds good in an imagination of the objects of Hearing, Touch, Taste, and Smell. But not only sensible perceptions, voluntary mo- tions, likewise, are imitated in and by the imagination. I. can, in imagination, represent the action of speech, the play of the muscles- of the countenance, the move- ment of the limbs ; and when I do this, I feel clearly that I awaken a kind of tension in the same nerves through which, by an act of will, I can determine an overt and voluntary motion of the muscles ; nay, when the play of imagination is very lively, this ex- ternal movement is actually determined. Thus we frequently see the countenances of persons, under the influence of imagination, undergo various changes ; they gesticulate with their hands, they talk to them- selves, and all this is in consequence only of the im- agined activity going out into real activity. I should, therefore, be disposed to conclude, that, as in Percep- tion, the living organs of sense are from without de- termined to energy, so, in Imagination, they are de- termined to a similar energy by an influence from within. (Lect. on Metaph., XXXIII.) PHENOMENOLOGY OF THE COGNITIONS. CHAPTER V THE ELABORATIVE FACULTY. The faculties Avith which we have been hitherto engaged may be regarded as subsidiary to that which we are now about to consider. This, to which I gave the name of the Elaborative Faculty, the Faculty of Relations, or Comparison, constitutes what is properly denominated Thought, and corresponds to what the Greek philosophers understood by dtdvota, the Latin by Discursus. It supposes always at least two terms, and its act results in a judgment, that is, an affirma- tion or negation of one of these terms of the other. In opposition to the views hitherto promulgated in regard to Comparison, I will show that this facuhy is at work in every, the simplest, act of mind ; and that from the primary affirmation of existence in an origi- nal act of consciousness to the judgment contained in the conclusion of an act of reasoning, every operation is only an evolution of the same elemental process, — that there is a difference in the complexity, none in the nature of the act. What I have, therefore, to 133 134 AN OUTLINE OF prove is, in the first place, that Comparison is sup- posed in every, the simplest, act of knowledge ; in the second, that our factitiously simple, our factitiously complex, our abstract, and our generalized notions are all merely so many products of Comparison ; in the third, that Judgment, and, in the fourth, that Reasoning, is identical with Comparison. § 1. PRIMARY ACTS OF COMPARISON. 1. The first or most elementary act of Comparison, or of that mental process in which the relation of two terms is recognized and affirmed, is the judgment vir- tually pronounced, in an act of Perception, of the Non-ego, or, in an act of Self-consciousness, of the Ego. This is the primary affirmation of existence. The notion of existence is one native to the mind . It is the primary condition of thought. The first act of experience awoke it, and the first act of consciousness was a subsumption of that of which we were conscious under this notion ; in other words, the first act of consciousness was an affirmation of the existence of something. The first or simplest act of Comparison is thus the discrimination of existence from non-ex- istence ; and the first or simplest judgment is the affirmation of existence, in other words, the denial of non-existence. 2. But the something of which we are conscious, and of which we predicate existence, in the primary judgment, is twofold, — the Ego and the Non-ego. We are conscious of both, and affirm existence of both. But we do more ; we do not merely affirm the SIR 1VILLIAM HAMILTON' S PHILOSOPHY. 135 existence of each out of relation to the other, but, in affirming their existence, we affirm their existence in duality, in difference, in mutual contrast; that is, we not only affirm the Ego to exist, but deny it existing as the Non-ego ; we not only affirm the Non-ego to exist, but deny it existing as the Ego. The second act of Comparison is thus the discrimination of the Ego and the Non-ego ; and the second judgment is the affirmation that each is not the other. 3. The third gradation in the act of Comparison is in the recognition of the multiplicity of the coexistent or successive phenomena, presented either to Percep- tion or Self-consciousness, and the judgment in regard to their resemblance or dissimilarity. 4. The fourth is the Comparison of the phenomena with the native notion of Substance, and the judgment is the grouping of these phenomena into different bun- dles, as the attributes of different subjects. In the external world this relation constitutes the distinction of things ; in the internal, the distinction of pow- ers. 5. The fifth act of Comparison is the collation of successive phenomena under the native notion of Caus- alit}^, and the affirmation or negation of their mutual relation as cause and effect. § 2. CLASSIFICATION. So for, the process of Comparison is determined merely by objective conditions ; hitherto, it has fol- lowed only in the footsteps of nature. In those, again, we are now to consider, the procedure is, in a 136 AN OUTLINE OF certain sort, artificial, and determined by the necessi- ties of the thinking subject itself. The mind is finite in its powers of comprehension ; the objects, on the contrary, which are presented to it, are, in proportion to its limited capacities, infinite in number. How, then, is this disproportion to be equalized? How can the infinity of nature be brought down to the finitude of man? This is done by means of Classification. Objects, though infinite in number, are not infinite in variety ; they are all, in a certain sort, repetitions of the same common qualities, and the mind, though lost in the multitude of individuals, can easily grasp the classes into which their resembling attributes enable us to assort them. This whole process of Classifica- tion is a mere act of Comparison, as the following de- duction will show. (A) Collective Notions. In the first place, this may be shown in regard to the formation of complex notions, with which, as the simplest species of classi- fication, we may commence. By Complex or Collec- tive notions I mean merely the notion of a class formed by the repetition of the same constituent notion. Such are the notions of an army, a forest, a town, a number. These are the names of classes, formed by the repetition of the notion of a soldier, of a tree, of a house, of a unit. You are not to confound, as has sometimes been done, the notion of an army, a for- est, a town, a number, with the notions of army , forest, town, and number; the former, as I have said, are complex or collective, the latter are general or univer- sal notions. It is evident that a collective notion is the result of sin iriLLiAJi Hamilton's philosophy. 137 comparison. The repetition of the same constituent notion supposes that these notions were compared, their identity or absolute similarity affirmed. In the whole process of classification the mind is in a great measure dependent upon language for its suc- cess ; and in this, the simplest of the acts of Classifica- tion, it may be proper to show how language affords to mind the assistance it requires. Our complex no- tions being formed by the repetition of the same notion, it is evident that the difficulty we can experience in forming an adequate conception of a class of identical constituents will be determined by the difficulty we have in conceiving a multitude. The comprehension of the mind is limited ; it can embrace at once but a small number of objects. It would thus seem that an obstacle is raised to the extension of our complex ideas at the very outset of our combinations. How, then, does the mind proceed? When, by a first combina- tion, we have obtained a complement of notions as complex as the mind can embrace, we give this com- plement a name. This being done, we regard the as- semblage of units thus bound up under a collective name as itself a unit, and proceed, by a second combi- nation, to accumulate these into a new complement of the same extent. To this new complement we give another name ; and then again proceed to perform, on this more complex unit, the same operation we had performed on the first ; and so we may go on rising from complement to complement to an indefinite ex- tent. Thus, a merchant, having received a large un- known sum of money in crowns, counts out the pieces by fives, and having done this till he has reached 138 AN OUTLINE OF twenty, he lays them together in a heap ; around these he assembles similar piles of coin, till they amount, let us say, to twenty ; and he then puts the whole four hundred into a bag. In this manner he proceeds, until he fills a number of bags, and placing the whole in his coffers, he will have a complex or collective notion of the quantity of crowns which he has received. It is on this principle that arithmetic proceeds ; tens, hundreds, thousands, myriads, hun- dreds of thousands, millions, etc., are all so many factitious units, which enable us to form notions, vague indeed, of what otherwise we could have obtained no conception at all. So much for complex or collective notions, formed without decomposition, — a process which I now go on to consider. (B) Abstraction. Our thought, that is, the sum total of the Perceptions and Representations which occupy us at any given moment, is always, as I have frequently observed, compound. The composite ob- jects of thoughts may be decomposed in two ways, and for the sake of two different interests. 1. In the first place, we may decompose in order that we may recombine, influenced by the mere pleas- ure which this plastic operation affords us. This is poetical analysis and synthesis. On this process it is needless to dwell. It is evidently the work of com- parison. For example, the minotaur, or chimsera, or centaur, or gryphon (hippogryph) , or any other poetical combination of different animals, could only have been effected by an act in which the representa- tions of these animals were compared, and in which certain parts of one were affirmed compatible with sir william Hamilton's philosophy. 139 certain parts of another. How, again, is the imagina- tion of all ideal beauty or perfection formed '? Simply by comparing the various beauties or excellences of which we have had actual experience, and thus being enabled to pronounce in regard to their common and essential quality. 2. In the second place, we may decompose in the interest of science ; and as the poetical composition was principally accomplished by a separation of in- tegral parts, so this is principally accomplished by an abstraction of constituent qualities. On this process it is necessary to be more particular. Suppose an unknown body is presented to my senses, and that it is capable of affecting each of these in a certain manner. As furnished with five different organs, each of which serves to introduce a certain class of perceptions and representations into the mind, we naturally distribute all sensible objects into five species of qualities. The abstraction of the senses is thus an operation the most natural ; it is even impos- sible for us not to perform it. Let us now see whether abstraction by the mind be more arduous than that of the senses. We have formerly found that the comprehension of the mind is extremely limited : it can only take cog- nizance of one object at a time, if that be known with full intensity ; and it can accord a simultaneous at- tention to a very small plurality of objects, and even that imperfectly. Thus it is that attention fixed on one object is tantamount to a withdrawal, to an ab- straction, of consciousness from every other. The ab- straction of the intellect is thus as natural as that of 140 AN OUTLINE OF the senses ; it is even imposed by the very constitu- tion of our minds. But is Abstraction, or rather, is exclusive attention the work of Comparison ? This is evident. The ap- plication of attention to a particular object, or quality of an object, supposes a choice or preference, and this again supposes Comparison and Judgment. But this may be made more manifest from a view of the act of generalization, on which we are about to en- ter. (C) Generalization. The notion of the figure of the desk before me is an abstract idea, — an idea that makes part of the total notion of that body, and on which I have concentrated my attention, in order to consider it exclusively. This idea is abstract, but it is at the same time individual ; it represents the fig- ure of this particular desk, and not the figure of any other body. But had we only individual abstract no- tions, what would be our knowledge? We should be cognizant only of qualities viewed apart from their subjects (and of separate phenomena there exists none in nature) ; and as these qualities are also separate from each other, we should have no knowledge of their mutual relations. We should also be over- whelmed with their number. It is necessary, therefore, that we should form Ab- stract General notions. This is done when, comparing a number of objects, we seize on their resemblances ; when we conceutrate our attention on these points of similarity, thus abstracting the mind from a consid- eration of their differences ; and when we give a name to our notion of that circumstance in which they all sin wiLLTAM Hamilton's philosophy. 141 agree. The General Notion is thus one which makes us know a quality, property, power, action, relation ; in short, any point of view uucler which we recog- nize a plurality of objects as a unity. It makes us aware of a quality, a point of view, common to many things. It is a notion of resemblance ; hence the reason why general names or terms, the signs of gen- eral notions, have been called terms of resemblance {termini similitadinis) . In this process of Generali- zation we do not stop short at a first Generalization. By a first Generalization we have obtained a num- ber of classes of resembling individuals. But these classes we can compare together, observe their simi- larities, abstract from their dhTerences, and bestow on their common circumstance a common name. On these second classes we can again perform the same operation, and thus ascending the scale of general no- tions, throwing out of view always a greater number of differences, and seizing always on fewer similarities in the formation of our classes, we arrive at length at the limit of our ascent in the notion of being or ex- istence. Thus placed on the summit of the scale of classes, we descend by a process the reverse of that by which we have ascended ; we divide and subdivide the classes, by introducing always more and more characters, and laying always fewer differences aside ; the notions become more and more composite, until we at length arrive at the individual. I may here notice that there is a twofold kind of quantity to be considered in notions. It is evident that in proportion as the class is high it will, in the first place, contain under it a greater number of classes, 142 AN OUTLINE OF and, in the second, will include the smallest com- plement of attributes. Thus being or existence con- tains under it every class ; and yet, when we say that a thing exists, we say the very least of it that is pos- sible. On the other hand, an individual, though it contain nothing but itself, involves the largest amount of predication. For example, when I say, This is Richard, I not only affirm of the subject every class from existence down to man, but likewise a number of circumstances proper to Richard as an individual. Now, the former of these quantities, the external, is called the Extension of a notion ; the latter, the in- ternal quantity, is called its Comprehension or Inten- sion. They are in the inverse ratio of each other : the greater the Extension, the less the Comprehen- sion ; the greater the Comprehension, the less the Ex- tension. Having given you this necessary information in re- gard to the nature of Generalization, I proceed to con- sider one of the most simple, and, at the same time, one of the most perplexed, problems in philosophy, — in regard to the object of consciousness, when we em- ploy a general term. In the explanation of the pro- cess of Generalization, all philosophers are at one ; the only differences that arise among them relate to the point, whether we can form an adequate idea of that which is denoted by an abstract, or abstract and general term. Throwing out of account the ancient doctrine of Realism, which is curious only in an historical point of view, there are two opinions which still divide phi- losophers. Some maintain that every act and every sir william Hamilton's philosophy. 143 object of mind is necessarily singular, and that the name is that alone which can pretend to generality. Others, again, hold that the mind is capable of forming notions, representations, correspondent in universality to the classes contained under, or expressed by, the gen- eral term. The former is the doctrine of Nominalism ; the latter, the doctrine of Conceptualism. The Nominalists maintain that every notion, con- sidered in itself, is singular, but becomes, as it were, general, through the intention of the mind to make it represent every resembling notion, or notion of the same class. Take, for example, the term man. Here we can call up no notion, no idea, corresponding to the universality of the class or term. This is mani- festly impossible. For as man involves contradictory attributes, and as contradictions cannot coexist in one representation, an idea or notion adequate to man can- not be realized in thought. The class man includes individuals, male and female, white and black and copper-colored, tall and short, fat and thin, straight and crooked, whole and mutilated, etc., etc. ; and the notion of the class must, therefore, at once represent all and none of these. It is, therefore, evident, though the absurdity was maintained by Locke, that we can- not accomplish this ; and, this being impossible, we cannot represent to ourselves the class man by any equivalent notion or idea. All that we can do is to call up some individual image, and consider it as rep- resenting, though inadequately representing, the gen- erality. This we easily do, for as we can call into imagination any individual, so we can make that indi- vidual image stand for any or for every other which 144 AN OUTLINE OF it resembles in those essential points which constitute the identity of the class. This opinion, which, after Hobbes, has been maintained, among others, by Berkeley, Hume, Adam Smith, Campbell, and Stew- art, appears to me not only true, but self-evident. A general notion is nothing but the abstract notion of a circumstance in which a number of individual ob- jects are found to agree, that is, to resemble each other. Now, resemblance, being a relation, cannot be represented in Imagination. 1 The two terms, the two relative objects, can be severally imaged in the sensible phantasy, but not the relation itself. This is the object of the Comparative Faculty, or of Intelli- gence Proper. To objects so different as the images of sense and the unpicturable notions of intelligence, different names ought to be given; and, accordingly, this has been clone wherever a philosophical nomen- clature of the slightest pretensions to perfection has been formed. In the German language, which is now the richest in metaphysical expressions of any living tongue, the two kinds of objects are carefully distin- guished. In our language, on the contrary, the terms- idea, conception, notion, are used almost as convertible for either ; and the vagueness and confusion which is thus produced, even within the narrow sphere of spec- ulation to which the want of the distinction also con- fines us, can be best appreciated by those who are 1 It must be observed that the term Imagination is here used for the representation of sensible objects alone. See above, p. 128. — J. C. M. sin william Hamilton's philosophy. 145 conversant with the philosophy of the different coun- tries. 1 In connection with general terms, another curious question has likewise divided philosophers. It is this : Does Language originate in General Appellatives or by Proper Names? Did mankind, in the formation of language, and do children, in their first application of it, commence with the one kind of words or with the other? The determination of this question — the question of the Primum Cognitum, as it was called in the Schools — is not involved in the question of Nominalism. On this question two opposite theo- ries have been advanced. 1. Many illustrious philosophers have maintained that all terms, as at first employed, are expressive of individual objects, and that these only subsequently ob- tain a general acceptation. This opinion I find main- tained by Vives, Locke, Rousseau, Condillac, Adam Smith, Steinbart, Tittel, Brown, and others. "There is nothing," says Locke, "more evident than that the ideas of the persons children converse with (to in- stance in them alone) are like the persons themselves, only particular. The ideas of the nurse and the mother are well framed in their minds ; and, like pic- tures of them there, represent only those individuals. The ..names they first gave to them are confined to these individuals ; and the names of nurse and mamma, the child uses, determine themselves to those persons. 1 In the Lect. on Metaph. (Lect. XXXV.) will be found an elabo- rate critique of the doctrine of Conceptualism, in the form in which it was maintained by Dr. Thomas Brown. — J. C. M. 10 146 AN OUTLINE OF Afterwards, when time ahd a larger acquaintance have made them observe that there are a great many other things in the world that in some common agreements of shape and several other qualities resemble their father and mother, and those persons they have been used to, they frame an idea which they find those many particulars do partake in ; and to that they give, with others, the name man, for example. And thus they come to have a general name and a general idea." l 2. On the other hand, an opposite doctrine is main- tained by many profound philosophers. " General terms," says Leibnitz, "serve not only for the perfec- tion of languages, but are even necessary for their es- sential constitution. For if by particulars be under- stood things individual, it would be impossible to speak, if there were only proper names, and no appel- latives, that is to say, if there were only names for things individual, since, at every moment, we are met by new ones, when we treat of persons, of accidents, and especially of actions, which are those that we de- scribe the most ; but if by particulars be meant the lowest species (species infimce) , besides that it is fre- quently very difficult to determine them, it is manifest that these are already universals, founded on similarity. Now, as the only difference of species and genera lies in a similarity of greater or less extent, it is natural to note every kind of similarity or agreement, and consequently to employ general terms of every de- gree ; nay, the most general being less complex with 1 Locke's Essay on the Human Understanding, III., 3, 7. SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON 3 S PHILOSOPHY. 147 regard to the essences which they comprehend, al- though more extensive in relation to the things indi- vidual to which they apply, are frequently the easiest to form, and arc the most useful. It is likewise seen that children, and those who know but little of the language which they attempt to speak, or little of the subject on which they would employ it, make use of general terms, as thing, plant, animal, instead of us- ing proper names, of which they are destitute. And it is certain that all proper or individual names have been originally appellative or general." l 3. But I have now to state a third opinion, inter- mediate between these, which conciliates both, and seems, moreover, to carry a superior probability in its statement. This opinion maintains, that, as our knowledge proceeds from the confused to the distinct, so, in the mouths of children, language at first ex- presses neither the precisely general nor the determi- nately particular, but the vague and confused; and that, out of this, the universal is elaborated by gen- erification, the particular and singular by specifica- tion and individualization. Though our capacity of attention be very limited in regard to the number of objects on which a faculty can be simultaneously directed, yet these objects may be large or small. We may make, for example, a single object of attention either of a whole man, or of his face, or of his eye, or of the pupil of his eye, or of a speck upon the pupil. To each of these objects there can only be a certain amount of attentive per- 1 Nouveaux Essais, Lib. III., cap. 1. 148 AN OUTLINE OF ception applied, and we can concentrate it all on any- one. In proportion as the object is larger and more complex, our attention can of course be less applied to any part of it, and, consequently, our knowledge of it in detail will be vaguer and more imperfect. But having first acquired a comprehensive knowledge of it as a whole, we can descend to its several parts, con- sider these both in themselves, and in relation to each other, and to the whole of which they are constituents, and thus attain to a complete and articulate knowledge of the object. We decompose, and then we recom- pose. But in this we always proceed first by decomposi- tion or analysis. All analysis indeed supposes a fore- gone composition or synthesis, because we cannot decompose what is not already composite. But in our acquisition of knowledge, the objects are pre- sented to us compounded ; and they obtain a unity only in the unity of our consciousness. The unity of con- sciousness is, as it were, the frame in which objects are seen. I say, then, that the first procedure of mind in the elaboration of its knowledge is always analytical. It descends from the whole to the parts, — from the vague to the definite. Definitude, that is, a knowledge of minute differences, is not, as the op- posite theory supposes., the first, but the last, term of our cognitions. Between two sheep an ordinary spec- tator can probably apprehend no difference, and if they were twice presented to him, he would be unable to discriminate the one from the other. But a shep- herd can distinguish every individual sheep ; and why? Because he has descended from the vague sir william Hamilton's philosophy. 149 knowledge which we all have of sheep, — from the vague knowledge which makes every sheep, as it were, only a repetition of the same undifferenced unit, — to a definite knowledge of qualities by which each is con- trasted from its neighbor. Now, in this example, we apprehend the sheep by marks not less individual than those by which the shepherd discriminates them ; but the whole of each sheep being made an object, the marks by which we know it are the same in each and all, and cannot, therefore, afford the principle by which we can discriminate them from each other. Now this is what appears to me to take place with children. They first know the things and persons presented to them as wholes. But wholes of the same kind, if we do not descend to their parts, afford us no mark by which we can discriminate the one from the other. Children, thus, originally perceiving similar objects — persons, for example — only as wholes, do at first hardly distinguish them. They apprehend first the more obtrusive marks that separate species from species, and, in consequence of the notorious con- trast of dress, men from women ; but they do not as yet recognize the finer traits that discriminate indi- vidual from individual. But, though thus apprehend- ing individuals only by what we now call their specific or their generic qualities, it is not to be supposed that children know them by any abstract general attributes ; that is, by attributes formed by com- parison and attention. On the other hand, because their knowledge is not general, it is not to be sup- posed to be particular or individual, if by particular be meant a separation of species from species, and by 150 AN OUTLINE OF individual, the separation of individual from indi- vidual ; for children are at first apt to confound in- dividuals together, not only in name, but in reality. What I have now said is, I think, sufficient in regard to the nature of Generalization. It is notoriously a mere act of Comparison. We compare objects ; we find them similar in certain respects, that is, in certain respects they affect us in the same manner ; we con- sider the qualities in them, that thus affect us in the same manner, as the same ; and to this common qual- ity we give a name ; and as we can predicate this name of all and each of the resembling objects, it con- stitutes them into a class. Aristotle has truly said that general names are only abbreviated definitions, and definitions, you know, are judgments. For ex- ample, animal is only a compendious expression for organized and animated body ; man, only a summary of rational animal, etc. § 3. JUDGMENT. In the processes of judgment and reasoning, the act of Comparison is a judgment of something more than a mere affirmation of the existence of a phenomenon, — something more than a mere discrimination of one phenomenon from another; and, accordingly, while it has happened that the intervention of judgment in every, even the simplest, act of primary cognition, as monotonous and rapid, has been overlooked, the name has been exclusively limited to the more varied and elaborate comparison of one notion with another, and the enouncement of their agreement or disagreement. sin william Hamilton's philosophy. 151 It is in the discharge of this, its more obtrusive func- tion, that we are now about to consider the Elabora- tive Faculty. I have already noticed that our knowledge does not commence with the individual and the most particular objects of knowledge, — that we do not rise in any regular progress • from the less to the more general, first considering the qualities which characterize indi- viduals, then those which belong to species and gen- era, in regular ascent. On the contrary, our knowl- edge commences with the vague and confused. Out of this the general and the individual are both equally evolved. In consequence of this genealogy of our knowledge we usually commence by bestowing a name upon a whole object or congeries of objects, of which, however, we possess only a partial and indefinite con- ception. In the sequel, this vague notion becomes somewhat more determinate ; the partial idea which we had becomes enlarged by new accessions ; by de- grees our conception waxes fuller, -find represents a greater number of attributes. With this conception, thus amplified and improved, we compare the last no- tion which has been acquired ; that is to say, we com- pare a part with its whole, or with the other parts of this whole, and, finding that it is harmonious, — that it dovetails and naturally assorts with other parts, —we acquiesce in this union ; and this we denominate an act of judgment. I have the conception of a triangle, and this concep- tion is composed in my mind of several others. Among these partial notions, I select that of two sides greater than the third, and this notion, which I had at 152 AN OUTLINE OF first, as it were, taken apart, I reunite with the others from which it had been separated, saying the triangle contains always two sides, which together are greater than the third. Every time we judge, we compare a total concep- tion with a partial, and we recognize that the latter really constitutes a part of the former. One of these conceptions has received the name of subject; the other, that of attribute or predicate. The verb which connects these two parts is called the copula. The quadrangle is a double triangle; nine is an odd num- ber; body is divisible. Here quadrangle, nine, body, are subjects ; a double triangle, an odd number, divis- ible, are predicates. The whole mental judgment, formed by the subject, predicate, and copula, is called, when enounced in words, proposition. In discourse, the parts of a proposition are not al- ways found placed in logical order ; but to discover and discriminate them, it is only requisite to ask, What is the thing of which something else is affirmed or denied? The answer to this question will point out the subject; and we shall find the predicate if we inquiry, What is affirmed or denied of the matter of which we speak? In fine, when we judge, we must have, in the first place, at least two notions ; in the second place, we compare these; in the third, we recognize that one contains or excludes the other ; and, in the fourth, we acquiesce in this recognition. sm wizliam Hamilton's philosophy. 153 § 4. REASONING. Simple Comparison or Judgment is conversant with two notions, the one of which is contained in the other. But it often happens that one notion is con- tained in another not immediately, but mediately, and we may be able to recognize the relation of these to each other only through a third, which, as it imme- diately contains the one, is immediately contained in the other. Take the notions A, B, C, — A contains B ; B contains C ; A therefore also contains C. But as, ex hypothesi, we do not at once and directly know C as contained in A, we cannot immediately compare them together and judge of their relation. We there- fore perform a double or complex process of compari- son ; we compare B with A, and C with B, and then C with A through B. We say, B is a part of A ; C is a part of B ; therefore C is a part of A. This double act of comparison has obtained the name of Reasoning; the term Judgment being left to express the simple act of comparison, or rather its result. Reasoning is either from the whole to its parts ; or from all the parts, discretively, to the whole they con- stitute, collectively. The former of these is Deduc- tive, the latter is Inductive, Reasoning. The state- ment you will find, in all logical books, of reasonings from certain parts to the whole, or from certain parts to certain parts, is erroneous. I shall first speak of the reasoning from the whole to its parts, — or of I. Deductive Reasoning. It is self-evident, that whatever is the part of a part is a part of the whole . 154 AN OUTLINE OF This one axiom is the foundation of all reasoning from the whole to the parts. There are, however, two kinds of whole and parts ; and these constitute two varieties, or rather two phases, of deductive reasoning. This distinction, which is of the most important kind, has nevertheless been wholly overlooked by philosophers, in consequence of which the utmost perplexity and confusion have been introduced into the science. I have formerly stated that a proposition consists of two terms, — the subject and the predicate. Now, in different relations we may regard the subject as the whole and the predicate as its part, or the predicate as the whole and the subject as its part. Let us take the proposition, milk is white. Now, here we may either consider the predicate white as one of a number of attributes, the whole complement of which constitutes the subject milk. In this point of view, the predicate is a part of the subject. Or, again, we may consider the predicate white as the name of a class of objects, of which the subject is one. In this point of view, the subject is a part of the predicate. You will remember the distinction, which I for- merty stated , of the twofold quantity of notions or terms . The Extension of a notion or term corresponds to the greater number of subjects contained under a predi- cate ; the Intension, or Comprehension, of a notion or term, to the greater number of predicates contained in a subject. These quantities or wholes are always in the inverse ratio of each other. Nov/, it is sino-u- lar that logicians should have taken this distinction between notions, and yet not have thought of applying SIR 1FILLIAM HAMILTON'S PHILOSOPHY. 155 it to reasoning. But so it is ; and this is not the only oversight they have committed in the application of the very primary principles of their science. The great distinction we have established between the subject and predicate considered severally, as, in different re- lations, whole and as part, constitutes the primary and principal division of Syllogisms, both Deductive and Inductive ; and its introduction wipes off a complex mass of rules and qualifications, which the want of it rendered necessary. I can, of course, at present, only explain in general the nature of this distinction ; its details belong to the science of the Laws of Thought, or Logic, of which we are not here to treat. 1. Deductive Reasoning in Comprehension. I shall first consider the process of that Deductive Inference in which the subject is viewed as the whole, the pred- icate as the part. In this reasoning, the whole is deter- mined by the Comprehension, and is, again, either a Physical or Essential whole, or an Integral or Mathe- matical whole, (a) A Physical or Essential whole is that which consists of not really separable parts, of or pertaining to its substance. Thus, man is made up of two substantial parts, — a mind and a body ; and each of these has again various qualities, which, though separable only by mental abstraction, are considered as so many parts of an essential whole. Thus the at- tributes of respiration, of digestion, of locomotion, of color, are so many parts of the whole notion we have of the human body ; cognition, feeling, desire, virtue, vice, etc., so many parts of the whole notion we have of the human mind ; and all these together, so many 156 AN OUTLINE OF parts of the whole notion we have of man. (b) A Mathematical or Integral or Quantitative whole is that which has part out of part, and which therefore can be really partitioned. The Integral, or, as it ought to be called, Integrate whole (totum integratum) is composed of integrant parts (partes integrantes) , which are either homogeneous or heterogeneous. An example of the former is given in the division of a square into two triangles ; of the latter, in the divis- ion of the animal body into head, trunk, extremities, etc. This being understood, let us consider how we pro- ceed when we reason from the relation between a com- prehensive whole and its parts. Here it is evident that all the parts of the predicate must also be parts of the subject; in other terms, all that belongs to the predicate must also belong to the subject. In the words of the scholastic adage, Nota notoe est nota rei ipsius; Predicatum predicati est predicatum sub- jecti. An example of this reasoning : — Europe contains England ; England contains Middlesex ; Therefore, Europe contains Middlesex. In other words, England is an integrant part of Eu- rope ; Middlesex is an integrant part of Europe. This is an example from a mathematical whole and parts. Again : — Socrates is just (that is, Socrates contains justice as a quality) ; Justice is a virtue (that is, justice contains virtue as a constituent part) ; Therefore, Socrates is virtuous. sir willtam Hamilton's philosophy. 157 In other words, justice is an attribute or essential part of Socrates ; virtue is an attribute or essential part of justice ; therefore, virtue is an attribute or essential part of Socrates. This is an example from a physical or essential whole and parts. 2. Deductive Reasoning in Extension. I proceed, in the second place, to the other kind of Deductive Reasoning, — that in which the subject is the part, the predicate is the whole. This reasoning proceeds under that species of whole which has been called the Logical, or Potential, or Universal. This whole is determined by the Extension of a notion ; the genera having species, and the species individuals, as their parts. The parts of a logical or universal whole are called the subject parts. From what you know of the process of generaliza- tion, you are aware that general terms are expressive of attributes which may be predicated of many differ- ent objects ; and inasmuch as these objects resemble each other in the common attribute, they are consid- ered by us as constituting a class. Thus, when I say that a horse is a quadruped ; Bucephalus is a horse ; therefore, Bucephalus is a quadruped; — I virtually say, — horse, the subject, is a part of the predicate quadruped; Bucephalus, the subject, is part of the predicate horse; therefore, Bucephalus, the subject, is part of the predicate quadruped. In the reasoning under this whole you will observe that the same word, as it is whole or part, changes from predicate to sub- ject ; horse, when viewed as a part of quadruped, be- ing the subject of the proposition ; whereas, when 158 AN OUTLINE OF viewed as a whole containing Bucephalus, it becomes the predicate. II. Inductive Reasoning is founded on the princi- ple, that what is true of every constituent part belongs, or does not belong, to the constituted whole. Induction, like Deduction, may be divided into two kinds, ac- cording as the whole and parts, about which it is con- versant, are Comprehensive or Extensive. 1. Thus, in the former: — Gold is a metal, yellow, ductile, fusible in aqua regia, of a certain specific gravity, and so on ; These qualities constitute this body (are all its parts) ; Therefore, this body is gold. 2. In the latter: — Ox, horse, dog, etc., are animals, that is, are con- tained under the class animal ; Ox, horse, dog, etc., constitute (are all the con- stituents of) the class quadruped ; Therefore, quadruped is contained under animal. Both in the Deductive and Inductive processes the inference must be of an absolute necessity, in so far as the mental illation is concerned ; that is, every consequent proposition must be evolved out of every antecedent proposition with intuitive evidence. I do not mean, by this, that the antecedent should be nec- essarily true, or that the consequent be really con- tained in it ; it is sufficient that the antecedent be assumed as true, and that the consequent be, in con- formity to the laws of thought, evolved out of it as its part or its equation. This last is called Logical or Formal or Subjective truth ; and an inference may be sin william Hamilton's philosophy. 159 subjectively or formally true, which is objectively or really false. The account given of Induction in all works of Logic is utterly erroneous. Sometimes we find this inference described as a precarious, not a necessary, reasoning. It is called an illation from some to all. But here the some, as it neither contains nor consti- tutes the all, determines no necessary movement, and a conclusion drawn under these circumstances is log- ically vicious. Others again describe the Inductive process thus : — What belongs to some objects of a class belongs to the whole class ; This property belongs to some objects of the class ; Therefore, it belongs to the whole class. This account of Induction, which is the one vou will find in all the English works on Logic, is not an inductive reasoning at all. It is, logically considered, a deductive syllogism ; and, logically considered, a syllogism radically vicious. It is logically vicious to say, that, because some individuals of a class have certain common qualities apart from that property which constitutes the class itself, therefore the whole individuals of the class should partake in these quali- ties. For this there is no logical reason, — no neces- sity of thought. The probability of this inference, and it is only probable, is founded on the observation of the analogy of nature, and, therefore, not upon the laws of thought by which alone reasoning, considered as a logical process, is exclusively governed. To be- come a formally legitimate induction, the objective probability must be clothed with a subjective neces- 160 AN OUTLINE OF sity, and the some must be translated into the a?? which it is supposed to represent. In the deductive syllogism we proceed by analysis, that is, by decomposing a whole into its parts ; but as the two wholes with which reasoning is conversant are in the inverse ratio of each other, so our analysis in the one will correspond to our synthesis in the other. For example, when I divide a whole of exten- sion into its parts, — when I divide a genus into the species, a species into the individuals it contains, — I do so by adding new differences, and thus go on ac- cumulating in the parts a complement of qualities which did not belong to the wholes. This, therefore, which, in point of extension, is an analysis, is, in point of comprehension, a synthesis. In like manner, when I decompose a whole of comprehension, that is, decompose a complex predicate into its constit- uent attributes, I obtain by this process a simpler and more general quality, and thus this, which, in re- lation to a comprehensive whole, is an analysis, is, in relation to an extensive whole, a synthesis. As the deductive inference is Analytic, the inductive is Syn- thetic. But as induction, equally as deduction, is conversant with both wholes, so the synthesis of in- duction on the comprehensive whole is a reversed process to its synthesis on the extensive whole. You will therefore be aware, that the terms analysis and synthesis, when used without qualification, may be- employed at cross purposes, to denote operations precisely the converse of each other. And so it has happened. Analysis, in the mouth of one set of phi- losophers, means precisely what synthesis denotes in Silt WILLIAM HAMILTON' S PHILOSOPHY. 161 the mouth of another ; nay, what is even still more frequent, these words are perpetually converted with each other by the same philosopher. I may notice, what has rarely, if ever, been remarked, that synthe- sis, in the writings of the Greek logicians, is equivalent to the analysis of modern philosophers ; the former, regarding the extensive whole as the priucipal, applied analysis, xa T ' ^<>%rjv, to its division ; the latter, viewing the comprehensive whole as the principal, in general limit analysis to its decomposition. This, however, has been overlooked, and a confusion the most inex- tricable prevails in regard to the use of these words, if the thread of the labyrinth is not obtained. (Led. on Metaph., XXXIV.-XXXVII.) 11 PHENOMENOLOGY OF THE COGNITIONS. CHAPTER VI. THE EEGULATIVE FACULTY. I now enter upon the last of the Cognitive Faculties, — the faculty which I denominated the Regulative. Here the term faculty ', you will observe, is employed in a somewhat peculiar signification, for it is employed not to denote the proximate cause of any definite en- ergy, but the power the mind has of being the native source of certain necessary or a priori cognitions ; which cognitions, as they are the conditions, the forms, under which our knowledge in general is possible, constitute so many fundamental laws of intellectual nature. It is in this sense that I call the power which the mind possesses of modifying the knowledge it re- ceives, in conformity to its proper nature, its Regula- tive Faculty. The Regulative Faculty is, however, in fact, nothing more than the complement of such laws ; it is the locus principiorum. It thus corre- sponds to what was known in the Greek philosophy under the name of vovt;, when that term was rigor- ously used. To this faculty has been latterly applied 162 AN OUTLINE OF HAMILTON'S PHILOSOPHY. 163 the name Reason; but this term is so vague and am- biguous, that it is almost unfitted to convey any defi- nite meaning. The term Common Sense has likewise been applied to designate the place of principles. This word is also ambiguous. In the first place, it was the expression used in the Aristotelic philosophy to denote the Central or Common Sensory, in which the differ- ent external senses met and were united. In the sec- ond place, it was employed to signify a sound under- standing applied to vulgar objects, in contrast to a scientific or speculative intelligence; and it is in this signification that it has been taken by those who have derided the principle on which the philosophy, which has been distinctively denominated the Scottish, pro- fesses to be established. This is not, however, the mean- ing which has always, or even principally, been at- tached to it ; and an incomparably stronger case might be made out in defence of this expression than has been done by Reid, or even by Mr. Stewart. It is, in fact, a term of high antiquity and very general accep- tation. Were it allowed in metaphysical philosophy, as in physical, to discriminate scientific differences by scientific terms, I would employ the word noetic, as derived from voDc, to express all those cognitions that originate in the mind itself; dianoetic to denote the operations of the Discursive, Elaborative, or Com- parative Faculty. 1 (Led. onMetaph., XXXVIII.) 1 For an account of the various names by which the principles of Common Sense have been designated, see Betel's Works, Note A. This note is an elaborate dissertation on the Philosophy of Common Sense, and deserves study in this connection. — J. C. M. 164 AN OUTLINE OF The essential notes or characters, by which we are enabled to distinguish our original from our derivative cognitions, may be reduced to four : — 1. Their Incomprehensibility. When we are able to comprehend how or why a thing is, the belief of the existence of that thing is not a primary datum of consciousness, but a subsumption under the cognition or belief which affords its reason. 2. Their Simplicity. If a cognition or belief be made up of, and can be explicated into, a plurality of cognitions or beliefs, it is manifest that, as compound, it cannot be original. 3. Their Necessity and Absolute Universality. These may be regarded as coincident. For when a belief is necessary, it is, eo ipso, universal ; and that a belief is universal is a certain index that it must be necessary. To prove the necessity, the universality must, however, be absolute ; for a relative univer- sality indicates no more than custom and education, howbeit the subjects themselves may deem that they follow the dictates of nature. 4. Their Comparative Evidence and Certainty. This, along with the third, is well stated by Aristotle : "What appears to all, that we affirm to be; and he who rejects this belief will assuredly advance nothing better deserving of credence." (Reid's Works, pp. 754-5.) Though it be now generally acknowledged, by the profoundest thinkers, that it is impossible to analyze all our knowledge into the produce of experience, ex- ternal or internal, and that a certain complement of cognitions must be allowed as having their origin in sir william Hamilton's philosophy. 165 the nature of the thinking principle itself; they are not at one in regard to those which ought to be rec- ognized as ultimate and elemental, and those which ought to be regarded as modifications or combinations of these. The reduction of our native cognitions to system is therefore a problem which still remains to be solved. These cognitions are founded on the nec- essary conditions of thought ; and we have now to see that philosophers have failed to enumerate all those conditions. {Led. on Metaph., XXXVIII.) Now, the conditions of all positive thought are two : (1.) Non-contradiction; (2.) Relativity. If either of these conditions be violated, thought (employing that term as comprehending all our cognitive energies) is not positive, — it is only negative; for thought is positive only when existence, objective or subjective, is predi- cated of an object. If the condition of Non-contra- diction be not fulfilled, there emerges The really im- possible, — Nihil purum; if that of Relativity be not purified, there results The Impossible to Thought, — Nihil cogitabile. It might be supposed that negative thinking, being a negation of thought, is in propriety a negation therefore, absolutely, of all mental activity. But this would be erroneous. In fact, as Aristotle observes, every negation involves an affirmation, and we cannot think or predicate non-existence except by reference to existence . Thus even negative thought is realized only under the condition of Relativity and positive thinking. For example, we try to think, — to predicate existence in some way, — but find ourselves unable. We then predicate incogitability ; and if we 166 AN OUTLINE OF do not always predicate, as an equivalent, (objective) non-existence, we shall never err. It is only, then, when both of these conditions are fulfilled, that we think — Something. § 1. THE CONDITION OF NON-CON TH A DICTION. This condition is insuperable. We think it not only as a law of thought, but as a law of things ; and while we suppose its violation to determine an abso- lute impossibility, we suppose its fulfilment to afford only the Not-impossible. Thought is, under this con- dition, merely explicative or analytic; and the condi- tion itself is brought to bear under three phases, constituting three laws : (1 . ) the law of Identity ; (2.) the law of Contradiction (more properly Non- contradiction) ; (3.) the law of Excluded Middle (between two contradictories) - 1 The science of these is Logic; and as the laws are only explicative, Logic is only formal. Though necessary to state the condition of Non-con- tradiction, there is no dispute about its effect, no dan- ger of its violation. When, therefore, I speak of the Conditioned, the term is used in special reference to Eelativity. By existence Conditioned is meant em- phatically existence relative, — existence thought under relation. Relation may thus be understood to contain all the categories and forms of positive thought. (Discussions, pp. 602-3.) 1 Eor a full discussion of these laws see Led. on Log., V. and VI. ; and Appendix IV. — J. C. M. sir william Hamilton's philosophy. 167 § 2. THE CONDITION OF RELATIVITY. By this condition it is implied that the mind can conceive, and can consequently know, only the limited, and the conditionally limited. The unconditionally un- limited, or the Infinite, the unconditionally limited, or the Absolute, cannot positively be construed to the mind ; they can be conceived only by a thinking away from, or abstraction of, those very conditions under which thought itself is realized: consequently the notion of the Unconditioned is only negative, — negative of the conceivable itself. For example : — I. On the one hand, we can positively conceive neither (1.) an absolute whole, that is, a whole so great that we cannot also conceive it as a relative part of a still greater whole, nor (2.) an absolute part, that is, a part so small that we cannot also conceive it as a relative whole, divisible into smaller parts. II. On the other hand, we cannot positively repre- sent or realize or construe to the mind (as here Un- derstanding and Imagination coincide), (1.) an in- finite whole, for this could only be done by the infinite synthesis in thought of finite wholes, which would re- quire an infinite time for its accomplishment ; nor (2.) , for the same reason, can we follow out in thought an infinite divisibility of parts. The result is the same whether we apply the pro- cess to limitation in space, in time, or in degree. The unconditional negation and the unconditional affirma- tion of limitation — in other words, the Infinite and the Absolute, properly so called — are thus equally 168 AN OUTLINE OF inconceivable to us. The conditionally limited (which we may briefly call the Conditioned) is thus the only possible object of knowledge and of positive thought ; thought necessarily supposes condition. For as the eagle cannot outsoar the atmosphere in which he floats, and by which alone he is supported ; so the mind can- not transcend that sphere of limitation within and through which exclusively the possibility of thought is realized. The Conditioned is the mean between two extremes, — two inconditionates, exclusive of each other, neither of which can be conceived as possible, but of which, on the principles of contradiction and excluded middle, one must be admitted as necessary. Our faculties are thus shown to be weak, but not deceitful. The mind is not represented as conceiving two propositions, subversive of each other, as equally possible ; but only as unable to understand, as possible, either of two extremes, one of which, however, on the ground of their mutual repugnance, it is compelled to recog- nize as true. We are thus taught the salutary lesson, that the capacity of thought is not to be constituted into the measure of existence ; and are warned from recognizing the domain of our knowledge as necessa- rily coextensive with the horizon of our faith. And, by a wonderful revelation, we are thus, in the very consciousness of our inability to conceive aught above the relative and finite, inspired with a belief in the existence of something unconditioned beyond the sphere of all reprehensible reality. (Discussions, pp. 13-15.) The condition of Eelativity is therefore not insuper- sir jvilliam Hamilton's philosophy. 169 able. We should think it not as a law of things, but merely as a law of thought. Thinking, under this condition, is ampliative or synthetic. Its science, Metaphysic, using that term in a comprehensive mean- ing, is therefore material, in the sense of non-formal. The relations under which this condition is brought to bear are either necessary and original, or contin- gent and derivative. The latter are such as One and Other, End and Mean, Whole and Part, etc., etc. Relations like these, which we frequently employ in the actual applications of our cognitive energies, ad- mit of classification from different points of view ; but to attempt their arrangement at all, far less on any exclusive principle, would here be manifestly out of place. In so far, then, as it is necessary, the condi- tion of Relativity is brought to bear under two prin- cipal relations ; the one springing from the subject of knowledge (the relation of Knowledge) , the other from the object of knowledge (the relations of Existence). (A) The Relation of Knowledge is that which arises from the reciprocal dependence of the subject and object of thought. Whatever comes into con- sciousness is thought by us either as belonging to the mental self exclusively (subjectivo-subjective) , or as belonging to the not-self exclusively (objectivo-objec- tive) , or as belonging partly to both (subjectivo-objec- tive). (B) The Relations of Existence are either in- trinsic or extrinsic. I. The intrinsic, which may also be called the qual- itative, relation is that of Substance and Quality (quality being variously styled form, accident, prop- 170 AN OUTLINE OF erty, mode, affection, phenomenon, appearance, attri- bute, predicate, denomination, etc.). Substance and Quality are manifestly only thought as mutual rela- tives. 1. We cannot think a quality existing absolutely, in or of itself; we are constrained to think it as inhering in some basis, substratum, hypostasis, subject, or sub- stance. 2. But this substance cannot be conceived by us, except negatively, that is, as the unapparent, — the inconceivable correlative of certain appearing quali- ties. If we attempt to think it positively, we can think it only by transforming it into a quality or bun- dle of qualities, which, again, we are compelled to re- fer to an unknown substance, now necessarily supposed for their incogitable basis. Everything in fact may be conceived as the quality or as the substance of something else. But absolute substance and absolute quality, — these are both in- conceivable, as more than negations of the conceiv- able. II. The extrinsic relation of existence may be called quantitative, and is threefold, as constituted by three species of quantity, — Time, Space, and Degree. i. Time, Protension, or Protensive quantity, called likewise Duration, is a necessary condition of thought. It may be considered both (1.) in itself, and (2.) in the things which it contains. 1. In itself, — (a) Time is positively inconceivable, firstly, either, (a) on the one hand, as absolute, that is, absolutely commencing or absolutely terminating, or (/3) on the sin ivilliam Hamilton's philosophy. 171 other hand, as infinite or eternal, whether ab ante or a post; it is no less inconceivable, secondly, if we at- tempt (a) to fix an absolute minimum or (/5) to fol- low out an infinite division. (b) Time is positively conceivable, if conceived, firstly, as an indefinite past, present, or future, or, sec- ondly, as an indeterminate mean between the two unthinkable extremes of an absolute least and an infi- nite divisibility ; for thus it is relative. 2. Things in Time are either, firstly, coinclusive, wheu, (a) if of the same time they are, pro tanto, iden- tical apparently and in thought, (b) if of different times (as causes and effect, causce et causatum), they appear as different but are thought identical; or, secondly, they are coexclusive, when they are mutually either prior and posterior or contemporaneous. The impossi- bility of thinking as non-existent in time (either past or future) aught which we have conceived as existent, affords the principle of Causality, etc. 1 ii. Space, Extension, or Extensive quantity is, in like manner, a necessary condition of thought, and may also be considered both (1.) in itself and (2.) in the things which it contaius. 1. In itself, — (a) Space is positively inconceivable, firstly, as a whole, either (a) infinitely unbounded or (/5) absolutely bounded ; secondly, as a part, either (a) infinitely divisible or (/?) absolutely indivisible. (6) Space is positively conceivable as a mean be- 1 See this principle developed in the Appendix to this Chapter. — J. C. M. 172 AN OUTLINE OF tween these extremes, that is, either as an indefinite whole or as an indefinite part ; for thus it is rela- tive. 2. The things in Space maybe considered, firstly, in relation to Space itself, when the extension occu- pied by a thing is called its place, and a thiug chang- ing its place gives the relation of motion. Considered, secondly, in relation to each other, they are either (a) inclusive, thus originating the relation of containing and contained, or (6) coexclusive, thus determining the relation of position or situation, — of here and there ( Ubication) . On Space are dependent what are called the Primary Qualities of body, strictly so de- nominated, and Space combined with Degree affords, of body, the Secundo-primary Qualities. Our inabil- ity to conceive an absolute elimination from space of aught which we have conceived to occupy space, gives the law of what I have called Ultimate Incom- pressibility , etc. 1 iii. Degree, Intension, or Intensive quantity is not, like Time and Space, an absolute condition of thought. It may therefore be thought as null, or as existing only potentially. But thinking it to be, we must think it as a quantity ; and, as a quantity, it is posi- tively both inconceivable and conceivable. 1. In itself, — («) Degree is positively inconceivable, (a) abso- lutely, either as least or as greatest, (/5) infinitely, either in increase or diminution ; but (b) It is positively conceivable, in so far as it is 1 See above, Chap. I., § 1. (B). — J. C. M. sip wilham Hamilton's philosophy. 173 conceived as relative, — as indefinitely high or higher, as indefinitely low or lower. 2. The things thought under Degree, (a) if of the same intension, are correlatively uniform ; (6) if of a different degree, are correlatively higher or lower. Degree is developed into the Secondary Qualities of body, and, combined with Space, into the Secundo- primary. 1 (Discussions, pp. 602-8. Compare Led. on Metaph., XXXVIII.) (On the next page is given a tabular view of the above conditions of thought.) APPENDIX TO CHAPTEE VI. LAW OF THE CONDITIONED IN ITS APPLICATION TO THE PRINCIPLE OF CAUSALITY. To manifest the utility of introducing the principle of the Conditioned into our metaphysical speculations, I shall (always in outline) give one only, but that a signal illustration of its importance. Of all questions in the history of philosoph} r , that concerning the origin of our judgment of Cause and Effect is perhaps the most celebrated ; but, strange to say, there is not, so far as I am aware, to be found a comprehensive view of the various theories proposed in explanation, — not to say, among these, any satis- factory explanation of the phenomenon itself. The phenomenon is this : When aware of a new appearance, we are unable to conceive that therein 1 See the preceding note. — J. C. M. 174 AN OVTLINE OF H pq < M to M a H PR O 02 to o ^ -J * "2 •r-> fl .£ H O © * o 8 o J 5 sir william Hamilton'' s philosophy. 175 has originated any new existence, and are therefore constrained to think that what now appears to us under a new form, had previously an existence under others — others conceivable by us or not. These others (for they are always plural) are called its cause; and a cause, or more properly causes, we cannot but suppose ; for a cause is simply everything without which the effect would not result, and all such concurring, the effect cannot but result. We are utterly unable to realize in thought the possibility of the complement of existence being either increased or diminished. We are unable, on the one hand, to conceive nothing becoming something, or, on the other, something be- coming nothing. When God is said to create out of nothing, we construe this to thought by supposing that he evolves existence out of nothing but himself ; and in like manner we conceive annihilation only by conceiving the Creator to withdraw his creation, by withdrawing his creative energy from actuality into power. " Nil posse creaTi De Nihilo, neque quod genitu 'st ad Nil revocari; " " Gigni De Nihilo Nihil, in Nihilum Nil posse reverti." These lines of Lucretius and Persius enounce a phys- ical axiom of antiquity, which, when interpreted by the doctrine of the Conditioned, is itself at once re- 1 called into harmony with revealed truth, and, express- ing in its purest form the conditions of human thought, expresses also implicitly the whole intellectual phe- nomenon of causality. There is thus conceived an absolute tautology be- 176 AN OUTLINE OF tween the effect and its causes. We think the causes to contain all that is contained in the effect ; the ef- fect to contain nothing which was not contained in the causes. Take an example. A neutral salt is an effect of the conjunction of an acid and an alkali. Here we do not, and here we cannot, conceive that, in ef- fect, any new existence has been added, nor can we conceive that any has been taken away. But another example : Gunpowder is the effect of a mixture of sulphur, charcoal, and nitre ; and these three sub- stances are again the effect of simpler constituents, and these constituents again of simpler elements, either known or conceived to exist. Now, in all this series of compositions, we cannot conceive that aught begins' to exist. The gunpowder, the last compound, we are compelled to think, contains precisely the same quan- tum of existence that its ultimate elements contained prior to their combination. Well; we explode the powder. Can we conceive that existence has been diminished by the annihilation of a single element previously in being, or increased by the addition of a single element which was not heretofore in nature ? " Omnia mutant ur ; nihil interit," is what we think, what we must think. This, then, is the mental phe- nomenon of causality, — that we necessarily deny in thought that the object, which appears to begin to be, really so begins ; and that we necessarily identify its present with its past existence. Here it is not requi- site that we should know under what form, under what combinations, this existence was previously realized; in other words, it is not requisite that we should know what are the particular causes of the par- sip iyilliam Hamilton's philosophy. Ill ticular effect. The discovery of the connection of determinate causes and determinate effects is merely contingent and individual, — merely the datum of experience ; but the principle that every event should have its causes is necessary and universal, and is im- posed on us as a condition of our human intelligence itself. This necessity of so thinking is the only phe- nomenon to be explained. The opinions in regard to the nature and origin of the principle of causality fall into two great catego- ries. The first category (A) comprehends those theories which consider this principle as Empirical, or a posteriori, that is, as derived from experience; the other (B) comprehends those which view it as Pure, or a priori, that is, as a condition of intelligence itself. These two primary genera are, however, severally subdivided into various subordinate classes. The former category (A) , under which this princi- ple is regarded as the result of experience, contains two classes, inasmuch as the causal judgment may be sup- posed founded either (I.) on an Original, or (II.) on a Derivative, cognition. Each of these again is divided into two, according as the principle is sup- posed to have an objective, or a subjective, origin. In the former case, that is, where the cognition is sup- posed to be original and underived, it is Objective, or rather Objectivo-Objective ; when held to consist in an immediate perception of the power or efficacy of causes in the external and internal ivorlds (1.) ; and Subjective, or rather Objectivo-Subjective, when viewed as given in a self-consciousness alone of the power or efficacy of our own volitions (2.). In the 12 178 AN OUTLINE OF latter case, that is, where the cognition is supposed to be derivative ; if objective, it is viewed as a product of Induction and Generalization (3.) ; if subjective, of Association and Custom (4.). In like manner, the latter category (B), under which the causal principle is considered not as a re- sult, but as a condition, of experience, is variously divided and subdivided. In the first place, the opin- ions under this category fall into two classes, inasmuch as some regard the causal judgment (I.) as an Ulti- mate or Primary law of mind, while others regard it (II.) as a Secondary or Derived. Those who hold the former doctrine, in viewing it as a simple original principle, hold likewise that it is a positive act, — an affirmative datum of intelligence. This class is finally subdivided into two opinions. For some hold that the causal judgment, as necessary, is given in what they call " the principle of Causality," that is, the principle which declares that everything which begins to be must have its cause (5.) ; while at least one philosopher, without explicitly denying that the causal judgment is necessary, would identify it with the principle of our "Expectation of the Constancy of Nature" (6.). Those who hold that it can be analyzed into a higher principle, also hold that it is not of a positive, but of a negative, character. These, however, are divided into two classes. By some it has been maintained, that the principle of Causality can be resolved into the principle of Contradiction (7.), which, as I formerly stated, ought in propriety to be called the principle of Non-Contradiction. On the other hand, it may be (though it never has been) argued, that the judgment sir william Hamilton's philosophy. 179 of Causality can be analyzed into what I called the principle of the Conditioned, — the principle of relativ- ity (8.). To one or the other of these eight heads all the doctrines that have been actually maintained in regard to the origin of the principle in question, may be referred ; and the classification is the better worthy of your attention, as in no work will you find any attempt at even an^ enumeration of the various theories, actual and possible, on this subject. (The table on the next page affords a general conspectus of these theories.) An adequate discussion of these several heads, and a special consideration of the differences of the indi- vidual opinions which they comprehend, would far exceed our limits. I shall, therefore, confine myself to a few observations on the value of these eight doc- trines in general, without descending to the particular modifications under which they have been maintained by particular philosophers. (A) Theories which derive the Causal Judg- ment from Experience. Of these, I. The first two, — (1.) that which asserts that we have a perception of causal agency as we have a percep- tion of external objects; and (2.) that which maintains that we are self-conscious of efficiency, — have been always held in combination, though the second has been frequently held by philosophers who have aban- doned the first as untenable. Considering them to- gether, that is, as forming the opinion that we directly and immediately apprehend the efficiency of causes, both external and internal, — this opinion is refuted by two objections. The first is, that we have no such 180 AN OUTLINE OF r=l » » a "3 o a Pm "3 e O •* H Ci sT ■ 5 a ,a SI >> H a .a 5> d "c3 S3 .a s o 0Q O 05 r-H c^ eo ^n" \ / ■ ' v a, (4 '3 .0 '■3 w Pm 3 o o rt o J3 o ja £ H o ;d C3 a o "S 2 o o "3 >H 73 o # £* o £ O 0) a 'S a a fc "3 & "£* 3 c3 > 0> hi Ph M a eg tJO c9 J3 .2 3 .2 a a '3 o to O IS? 3 o o O „o o H o 3 ca o o CC! P^ la fl Sin WILLIAM HAMILTON'S PHILOSOPHY. 181 apprehension ; the second, that if we had, this being merely empirical, merely conversant with indi- vidual instances, could never account for the quality of necessity and universality which accompanies the judgment of causality. (a) First objection, (1.) as against the first theory. In regard to the first of these objections, it is now universally admitted, that we have no perception of the connection of cause and effect in the external world. For example ; when one billiard-ball is seen to strike another, we perceive only that the impulse of the one is followed by the motion of the other, but have no perception of any force or efficiency in the first, by which it is connected with the second, in the rela- tion of causality. Hume was the philosopher who decided the opiuion of the world on this point. He was not, however, the first who stated the fact, or even the reasoner who stated it most clearly. I could adduce a whole army of philosophers previous to Hume who had announced and illustrated the fact. First objection, (2.) as against the second theory. There are many philosophers who surrender the exter- nal perception, and maintain our internal conscious- ness, of causation or power. This opinion was, in one chapter of his Essay, advanced by Locke, and, at a very recent date, it has been amplified and enforced with distinguished ability by the late M. Maine de Biran, one of the acutest metaphysicians of France. On this doctrine, the notion of cause is not given to us by the observations of external phenomena, which, as considered only by the senses, manifest no causal efficiency, and appear to us only as successive ; it is 182 AN OUTLINE OF given to us within, in reflection, in the consciousness of our operations and of the power which exerts them, — namely, the will. I make an effort to move my arm, and I move it. When we analyze attentively the phenomenon of effort, which M. de Biran considers as the type of the phenomena of volition, the follow- ing are the results : 1°, The consciousness of an act of will ; 2°, The consciousness of a motion pro- duced ; 3°, A relation of the motion to the volition. And what is this relation ? Not a simple relation of succession. The will is not for us a pure act without efficiency, — it is a productive energy ; so that, in a volition, there is given to us the notion of cause ; and this notion we subsequently project out from our in- ternal activities, into the changes of the external world. This reasoning, in so far as regards the mere empir- ical fact of our consciousness of causality, in the rela- tion of our will as moving, and of our limbs as moved, is refuted by the consideration, that between the overt fact of corporeal movement of which we are cognizant, and the internal act of mental determination of which we are also cognizant, there intervenes a numerous series of intermediate agencies of which we have no knowledge; and, consequently, that we can have no consciousness of any causal connection between the extreme links of this chain, — the volition to move and the limb moving, as this hypothesis asserts. No one is immediately conscious, for example, of moving his arm through his volition. Previously to this ulti- mate movement, muscles, nerves, a multitude of solid and fluid parts, must be set in motion by the will ; sin william Hamilton's philosophy. 183 but of this motion we know, from consciousness, abso- lutely nothing. A person struck with paralysis is conscious of no inability in his limb to fulfil the de- terminations of his will ; and it is only after having willed, and finding that his limbs do not obey his vo- lition, that he learns by his experience, that the exter- nal movement does not follow the internal act. But as the paralytic learns after the volition that his limbs do not obey his mind ; so it is only after volition that the man in health learns that his limbs do obey the mandates of his will. (6) The Second Objection, mentioned above, is fatal to the theory which would found the judgment of causality on any empirical cognition, whether of the phenomena of mind or of the phenomena of mat- ter. Admitting that causation were cognizable, and that perception and self-consciousness were competent to its apprehension, still, as these faculties could only take note of individual causations, we should be wholly unable, out of such empirical acts, to evolve the quality of necessity and universality, by which this notion is distinguished. Admitting that we had really observed the agency of any number of causes, still this would not explain to us how we are unable to think a manifestation of existence without thinking it as an effect. Our internal experience, especially in the relation of our volitions to their effects, may be useful in giving us a clearer notion of causality ; but it is altogether incompetent to account for what in it there is of the quality of necessity. II. As the first and second opinions have been usually associated, so also have the third and fourth ; 184 AN OUTLINE OF that is, the doctrine that our notion of causality is the offspring of the objective principle of Induction or Gen- eralization, and the doctrine that it is the offspring of the subjective principle of Association or Custom. 3. In regard to the former, it is plain that the ob- servation that certain phenomena are found to succeed certain other phenomena, and the generalization con- sequent thereon, that these are reciprocally causes and effects, could never of itself have engendered, not only the strong, but the irresistible belief, that every event must have its cause. Each of these observa- tions is contingent ; and any number of observed con- tingencies will never impose upon us the feeling of necessity, — of our inability to think the opposite. Nay, more, this theory evolves the absolute notion of causality out of the observation of a certain number of uniform consecutions among phenomena ; that is, it would collect that all must be, because some are. But we find no difficulty whatever in conceiving the reverse of all or any of the consecutions w T e have ob- served ; and yet the general notion of causality, which, ex hypothesi, is their result, we cannot possibly think as possibly unreal. We have always seen a stone fall to the ground when thrown into the air; but we find no difficulty in representing to ourselves the possibility of one or all stones gravitating from the earth ; only we cannot conceive the possibility of this, or any other event, happening without a cause. 4. Nor does the latter afford a better solution. The necessity of so thinking cannot be derived from a custom of so thinking. Allow the force of custom to sir william Hamilton's philosophy. 185 be great as may be, still it is always limited to the customary ; and the customary has nothing whatever in it of the necessary. But we have here to account not for a strong, but for an absolutely irresistible belief. On this theory, also, the causal judgment, when asso- ciation is recent, should be weak, and should only gradually acquire its full force in proportion as cus- tom becomes inveterate. But do we find that the causal judgment is weaker in the young, stronger in the old? There is no difference. In either case, there is no less and no more ; the necessity in both is absolute. (B) Theories which maintain the Causal Judg- ment to be a Deliverance of Intelligence. Of the four opinions comprised under this category, I. The first two agree in holding that the causal judgment may be identified with a primary intellec- tual principle. 5. Of these, the first (the fifth in general) main- tains that this principle is necessary, making its rejec- tion in thought impossible. To this are to be referred the relative theories of Descartes, Leibnitz, Karnes, Eeid, Kant, Fichte, Bouterweck, Jacobi, Stewart, Cousin, and the majority of modern philosophers. Now, without descending into details, it is manifest in general, that against the assumption of a special principle, which this doctrine makes, there exists a primary presumption of philosophy. This is the Law of Parcimony, which forbids, without necessity, the multiplication of entities, powers, principles, or causes; above all, the postulation of an unknown force where a known impotence can account for the 186 AN OUTLINE OF phenomenon. We are, therefore, entitled to apply Occam's razor to this theory of causality, unless it be proved impossible to explain the causal judgment at a cheaper rate, by deriving it from a higher, and that a negative, origin. On a doctrine like the present is thrown the onus of vindicating its necessity, by show- ing that, unless a special and positive principle be assumed, there exists no competent mode to save the phenomena. It can only, therefore, be admitted pro- visorily ; and it falls of course, if the phenomenon it would explain can be explained on less onerous condi- tions. Leaving, therefore, this theory, which cer- tainly does account for the phenomenon, to fall or stand, according as either of the two last opinions be, or be not, found sufficient, I go on to that preceding these. 6. Dr. Brown has promulgated a doctrine of Caus- ality, which may be numbered as the sixth ; though perhaps it is hardly deserving of distinct enumeration. He actually identifies the causal judgment, which to us is necessary, with the principle by which we are merely inclined to believe in the uniformity of nature's operations. But apart from all subordinate objec- tions, it is sufficient to say that the phenomenon to be explained is the necessity of thinking, — the absolute impossibility of not thinking, — a cause ; whilst all that the latter pretends to is, to incline us to expect that like antecedents will be followed by like conse- quents. This necessity to suppose a cause for every phenomenon, *Dr. Brown, if he does not expressly deny, keeps cautiously out of view, virtually, in fact, sir wilham Hamilton's philosophy. 187 eliminating all that requires explanation in the prob- lem. II. The two remaining theories agree with the fifth and sixth in regarding the causal judgment as of a pri- ori origin, but differ from them in viewing it as deriv- ative and secondary. Of these two theories, 7. The first attempts to establish the principle of Causality upon the principle of Contradiction. Listen to the pretended demonstration : Whatever is produced without a cause, is produced by nothing, in other words, has nothing for its cause. But nothing can no more be a cause than it can be something. The same intuition, which makes us aware that nothing is not something, shows us that everything must have a real cause of its existence. To this it is sufficient to say, that the existence of causes being the point in ques- tion, the existence of causes must not be taken for granted in the very reasoning which attempts to prove their reality. In excluding causes, we exclude all causes ; and consequently exclude " nothing " con- sidered as a cause ; it is not, therefore, allowable, contrary to that exclusion, to suppose "nothing" as a cause, and then from the absurdity of that supposition to infer the absurdity of the exclusion itself. If every- thing must have a cause, it follows that, upon the ex- clusion of other causes, we must accept of nothing as a cause. But it is the very point at issue, whether everything must have a cause or not ; and, therefore, it violates the first principles of reasoning to take this qusesitum itself as granted. This opinion is now uni- versally abandoned. 8. The eighth and last opinion is that which re- 188 AN OUTLINE OF gards the judgment of causality as derived; and derives it not from a power, but from an impotence, of mind ; in a word, from the principle of the Con- ditioned. I do not think it possible, without a de- tailed exposition of the various categories of thought, to make you fully understand the grounds and bear- ings of this opinion. In attempting to explain, you must, therefore, allow me to take for granted certain laws of thought, to which I have only been able inci- dentally to allude. Those, however, which I postu- late, are such as are now generally admitted by all philosophers who allow the mind itself to be a source of cognitions ; and the only one which has not been recognized by them, but which, as I endeavored briefly to prove, must likewise be taken into account, is the Law of the Conditioned, that the conceivable has always two opposite extremes, and that the extremes are equally inconceivable. Philosophers, who allow a native principle to the mind at all, allow that Existence is such a principle. I shall, therefore, take for granted Existence as the highest category or condition of thought. All that we perceive or imagine as different from us, we per- ceive or imagine as objectively existent. All that we are conscious of as an act or modification of self, we are conscious of only as subjectively existent. All thought, therefore, implies the thought of existence. As a second category or subjective condition of thought, I postulate that of Time. This likewise cannot be denied me. It is the necessary condition of every conscious act ; thought is only realized to us as in succession, and succession is only conceived by sir william Hamilton's philosophy. 189 us under the concept of time. Existence and Exist- ence in Time is thus an elementary form of our intel- ligence. But we do not conceive existence in time absolutely or infinitely, — we conceive it only as con- ditioned in time; and Existence Conditioned in Time expresses, at once and in relation, the three categories of thought which afford us in combination the princi- ple of Causality. This requires some explanation. When we perceive or imagine an object, we per- ceive or imagine it (1.) As existent, and (2.) As in Time; Existence and Time being categories of all thought. But what is meant by saying, I perceive, or imagine, or, in general, think an object only as I perceive, or imagine, or, in general, think it to exist? Simply this : that, as thinking it, I cannot but think it to exist, in other words, that I cannot annihilate it in thought. I may think away from it, I may turn to other things, and I can thus exclude it from my consciousness; but, actually thinking it, I cannot think it as non-existent, for as it is thought, so it is thought existeut. But a thing is thought to exist, only as it is thought to exist in time. Time is present, past, and future. We cannot think an object of thought as non-existent depresenti. But can we think that quantum of exist- ence of which an object, real or ideal, is the comple- ment, as non-existent, either in time past, or in time future? Make the experiment. Try to think the ob- ject of your thought as non-existent in the moment before the present. You cannot. Try it in the mo- ment before that. You cannot. Nor can you annihi- late it by carrying it back to any moment, however 190 AN OUTLINE OF HAMILTON^ PHILOSOPRY. distant in the past. You may conceive the parts of which this complement of existence is composed, as separated ; if a material object, you can think it as shivered to atoms, sublimated into ether; but not one iota of existence can you conceive as annihilated, which subsequently you thought to exist. In like manner, try the future, — try to conceive the prospec- tive annihilation of any present object, of any atom of any present object. You cannot. All this may be possible, but of it we cannot think the possibility. But if you can thus conceive neither the absolute com- mencement nor the absolute termination of anything that is once thought to exist, try, on the other hand, if you can conceive the opposite alternative of infinite non-commencement, or of infinite non-termination. To this you are equally impotent. This is the cate- gory of the Conditioned as applied to the category of Existence under the category of Time. But in this application is the principle of Causality not given ? Why, what is the law of Causality ? Sim- ply this, — that, when an object is presented phenom- enally as commencing, we cannot but suppose that the complement of existence, which it now con- tains, has previously been; in other words, that all that we at present come to know as an effect must previously have existed in its causes ; though what these causes are, we may perhaps be altogether un- able even to surmise. (Led. on Metaph., XXXIX., and Discussions, pp. 609-622. Compare also Led. on Metaph., XL.) SECOND PART OF PHENOMENAL PSYCHOLOGY. PHENOMENOLOGY OF THE FEELINGS. SECOND PART OF PHENOMENAL PSYCHOLOGY. PHENOMENOLOGY OF THE FEELINGS. INTRODUCTION. In entering on the second great class of mental phenomena, there is a preliminary question to be dis- posed of: What is the position of the Feelings by reference to the two other classes ; and, in particular, should the consideration of the Feelings precede or follow that of the Conations ? To resolve this problem let us take an example. A person is fond of cards. In a company, where he beholds a game in progress, there arises a desire to join in it. Now, the desire is here manifestly kin- dled by the pleasure which the person had and has in the play. The feeling thus connects the cognition of the play with the desire to joiu in it ; it forms the bridge, and contains the motive, by which we are roused from mere knowledge to appetency, — to co- nation, by reference to which we move ourselves so as to attain the end in view. Thus we find, in actual life, the Feelings interme- diate between the Cognitions and the Conations. And 13 193 194 AN OUTLINE OF HAMILTON'S PHILOSOPHY. this relative position of the several powers is neces- sary : without the previous cognition, there could be neither feeling nor conation ; and without the previ- ous feeling there could be no conation. For if the mere cognition of a thing were sufficient to rouse co- nation, then it is evident (1.) that all objects, known in the same manner and in the same degree, would become equally the objects of desire and will ; while (2.) all persons would desire an object equally, as long as their cognition of the object remained the same. Our conclusion, therefore, is, that as in our actual existence the feelings find their place after the cogni- tions and before the conations, so in the science of mind the theory of the feelings ought to follow that of our faculties of knowledge, and to precede that of our faculties of will and desire. PHENOMENOLOGY OF THE FEELINGS. CHAPTER I. ABSTRACT THEORY OF PLEASURE AND PAIN. I proceed to deliver the theory of pleasure and pain. I. Man exists only as he lives ; as an intelligent and sensible being, he consciously lives, but this only as he consciously energizes. Human existence is only a more general expression for human life, and human life only a more general expression for the sum of energies in which that life is realized, and through which it is manifested in consciousness. Observation. The term energy is here used to com- prehend all the mixed states of action and passion of which we are conscious. II. Human existence, human life, human energy, is not unlimited, but on the contrary determined to a certain number of modes, through which alone it can possibly be exerted. These different modes of action are called, in different relations, powers, faculties, ca- pacities, dispositions, habits. HI. Man, as he consciously exists, is the subject of pleasure and pain ; and these of various kinds ; 195 196 A N OUTLINE OF but as man consciously exists in and through the exertion of certain determinate powers, so it is only through the exertion of these powers that he becomes the subject of pleasure and pain ; each power being in itself at once the faculty of a specific energy, and a capacity of an appropriate pleasure or pain, as the concomitant of that energy. IV. The energy of each power of conscious exist- ence having, as its reflex or concomitant, an appro- priate pleasure or pain, and no pleasure or pain being competent to man, except as the concomitant of some determinate energy of life, the all-important question arises : What is the general law under which these counter-phenomena appear in all their special mani- festations ? V. The answer to this question is : the more perfect, the more pleasurable, the energy ; the more imperfect, the more painful. VI. The perfection of an energy is twofold : (1.) subjective, by relation to the power of which it is the exertion; (2.) objective, by relation to the object about which it is conversant. VII. (1.) By relation to its power, an energy is perfect, when it is tantamount (a) to the full, and (b) not to more than the full, complement of free and spontaneous energy which the power is capable of exerting ; an energy is imperfect, either (a) when the power is restrained from putting forth the whole amount of energy it would otherwise tend to do, or (5) when it is stimulated to put forth a larger amount than that to which it is spontaneously disposed. The amount of energy in the case of a single power sir jvilliam Hamilton's philosophy. 197 is of two kinds, (a) intensive, (b) protensive. A per- fect energy is, therefore, that which is evolved by a power, both in the degree and for the continuance to which it is competent without straining ; an imperfect energy, that which is evolved by a power in a lower or in a higher degree, for a shorter or for a longer con- tinuance than, if left to itself, it would freely ex- ert. When we look to complex states in which & plurality of powers may be simultaneously called into action, we have, besides (a) the intensive and (5) protensive quantities of energy, (c) a third kind, to wit, the ex- tensive quantity. A state is said to contain a greater amount of extensive energy, in proportion as it forms the complement of a greater number of simultaneously co-operating powers. This complement, it is evident, may be conceived as made up either of energies all intensively and protensively perfect and pleasurable ; or of energies all intensively and protensively imper- fect and painful ; or of energies partly perfect, partly imperfect ; and this in every combination afforded by the various perfections and imperfections of the inten- sive and protensive quantities. It may be here noticed that the intensive and the two other quantities stand always in an inverse ratio to each other; that is, the higher the degree of any en- ergy, the shorter is its continuance, and, during its continuance, the more completely does it constitute the whole mental state. VIII. (2.) By relation to the object about which it is conversant (and by object is here denoted every objective cause by which a power is determined to 198 AN OUTLINE OF activity) , an energy is perfect, when this object is of such a character as to afford to its power the condition requisite to let it spring to full spontaneous activity ; imperfect, when the object is of such a character as either (a) to stimulate the power to a degree or to a continuance of activity beyond its maximum of free exertion ; or (b) to thwart it in its tendency towards this its natural limit. An object is consequently pleasurable or painful, inasmuch as it determines a power to perfect or to imperfect energy. But an object, or plurality of objects simultaneously presented, may determine a plurality of powers into co-activity. The complex state, which thus arises, is pleasurable in proportion as its constitutive energies are severally more perfect ; painful in proportion as these are more imperfect : and in proportion as an object, or a complement of objects, occasions the av- erage perfection or the average imperfection of the complex state, is it, in like manner, pleasurable or painful. IX. In conformity to this doctrine, pleasure and pain may be thus defined : Pleasure is a reflex of the spontaneous and unimpeded exertion of a power, of whose energy we are conscious; Pain, a reflex of the overstrained or repressed exertion of such a power. Observations. I. In illustration of these definitions it may be observed that, 1. Pleasure is defined to be the reflex of perfect energy, and not to be either energy or the perfection of energy itself; and why? (a) It is not simply de- fined an energy, because some energies are not pleas- urable, being either painful or indifferent, (b) It is SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON' S PHILOSOPHY. 199 not simply defined the perfection of an energy, be- cause we can easily separate in thought the perfection of an act from any feeling of pleasure in its perform- ance. The same holds true, mutatis mutandis, of the definition of pain, as a reflex of imperfect energy. 2. The term spontaneous refers to the subjective, the term unimpeded to the objective, perfection. 3. There are powers in man, the activities of which lie beyond the sphere of consciousness ; l but it is of the very essence of pleasure and pain to be felt, and there is no feeling out of consciousness. II. It is also to be observed that, on this doctrine, there are different kinds of pleasure and pain. 1. In the first place, these are twofold, inasmuch as each is either positive and absolute or negative and rel- ative. («) The mere negation of pain does, by re- lation to pain, constitute a state of pleasure. Thus the removal of toothache replaces us in a state which, though one really of indifference, is, by contrast to our previous agony, felt as pleasurable. This is neg- ative or relative pleasure, (b) Positive or absolute pleasure, on the contrary, is all that pleasure which we feel above a state of indifference, and which is therefore prized as a good in itself, and not simply as the removal of an evil. On the same principle pain is also divided. 2. But, in the second place, there is a subdivision of positive pain into (a) that which accompanies a repression of the spontaneous energy of a power, and (b) that which is conjoined with its effort when stim- ulated to over-activity. {Led. on Metaph., XLII.) 1 See Phenomenology of the Cognitions, Chap. II., § 1. PHENOMENOLOGY OF THE FEELINGS. CHAPTER II. THE ABSTRACT THEORY APPLIED TO THE CONCRETE PHENOMENA : CLASSIFICATION OF THE FEELINGS. We may consider the feelings either as causes or as effects. (1.) As causes, they are viewed in relation to their product, — pleasure, or pain. (2.) As effects, they are viewed as themselves products of the action of our different constitutive functions. § 1. THE FEELINGS AS CAUSES. In this point of view, the feelings are distributed simply into the pleasurable and the painful; and it remains, on the theory I have proposed, to explain in general the causes of these opposite affections, without descending to their special kinds. I. The theory meets with no contradiction from the facts of actual life ; for the contradictions, which at first sight these seem to offer, prove, when examined, to be real confirmations. Thus it might be thought that the aversion from exercise, — the love of idle- ness, — in a word, the dolce far niente, — is a proof 200 AN OUTLINE OF HAMILTON'S PHILOSOPHY. 201 that the inactivity, rather than the exertion, of our powers is the condition of our pleasurable feelings. This objection, from a natural proneness to inertion in man, is superficial. Is the far niente — is that doing nothing, in which so many find so sincere a gratification — in reality a negation of activity, and not in truth itself an activity intense and varied? To do nothing, in this sense, is simply to do nothing irk- some, especially to do no outward work. But is the mind internally, the while, unoccupied and inert? This, on the contrary, may be vividly alive, — may be intently engaged in the spontaneous play of imagina- tion ; and so far, therefore, in this case, from pleasure being the concomitant of inactivity, the activity is at once vigorous and unimpeded, and such accordingly as, on our theory, would be accompanied by a high degree of pleasure. Ennui is the state on which we find nothing to exercise our powers ; but ennui is a state of pain. II. A strong confirmation of the theory is derived from the phenomena presented by those affections which we emphatically denominate the painful. 1. Take, for example, the affection of grief, — the sorrow we feel in the loss of a beloved object. Is this affection unaccompanied with pleasure? So far is this from being the case, that the pleasure so greatly predominates over the pain as to produce a mixed emotion, which is far more pleasurable than any other of which the wounded heart is susceptible. 2. In like manner, fear is not simply painful. It is a natural disposition, has a tendency to act; and there is consequently, along with its essential pain, a 202 AN OUTLINE OF certain pleasure as the reflex of its energy. This is finely expressed by Akensicle : — " Hence, finally, by night The village matron round the blazing hearth Suspends the infant audience with her tales, Breathing astonishment ! of witching rhymes And evil spirits of the death-bed call Of him who robbed the widow and devoured The orphan's portion ; of unquiet souls Risen from the grave to ease the heavy guilt Of deeds in life concealed ; of shapes that walk At dead of night and clank their chains, and wave The torch of hell around the murderer's bed. At every solemn pause the crowd recoil, Gazing each other speechless, and congealed With shivering sighs, till, eager for the event, Around the beldame all erect they hang, Each trembling heart with grateful terrors quelled." 3. Pity, also, which, being a sympathetic passion, implies a participation in sorrow, is yet confessedly agreeable. The poet even accords to the energy of this benevolent affection a preference over the enjoy- ments of an exclusive selfishness : — " The broadest mirth unfeeling folly wears Is not so sweet as virtue's very tears." 4. On the same principle is to be explained the en- joyment which men have in spectacles of suffering, — in the combats of animals and men, in executions, in tragedies, etc. ; a disposition which not un frequently becomes an irresistible habit, not only for individuals, but also for nations. The excitation of energetic emotions, painful in themselves, is also pleasura- ble. sir william Hamilton's philosophy. 203 " We may here notice four general causes which con- tribute to raise or to lower the intensity of our ener- gies, and consequently to determine the correspond- ing degree of pleasure or pain. I. JSfovelty. The principle on which novelty determines a higher energy is twofold ; and of these the one may be called the subjective, the other the objective. 1. In a subjective relation, the new is pleasurable, inasmuch as this supposes that the mind is determined to a mode of action, either from inactivity or from another state of energy, (a) In the former case, en- ergy, the condition of pleasure, is caused ; (b) in the latter, a change of energy is afforded, which is also pleasurable ; for powers energize less vigorously in proportion to the continuance of the same exertion, and, consequently, a new activity being determined, this replaces a strained or expiring exercise, that is, it replaces a painful, indifferent, or unpleasurable feel- ing by one of comparatively vivid enjoyment. 2. In an objective relation, a novel object is please ing, because it affords a gratification to our desire of knowledge. The old is already known, and therefore no longer occupies the cognitive faculties ; whereas the new, as new, is still unknown, and rouses to en- ergy the powers by which it is to be brought within the system of our knowledge. II. Contrast operates in two ways ; for it has the effect of enhancing both the real or absolute, and the apparent or relative, intensity of a feeling. (1.) As an instance of the former, the unkindness of a person, from whom we expect kindness, rouses to a far higher 204 AN OUTLINE OF pitch the emotions consequent on injury. (2.) As an instance of the latter, the pleasure of eating appears proportionally great when it is immediately con- nected and contrasted with the removal of the pangs of hunger. III. The relation of harmony or discord, in which one coexistent activity stands to another. At differ- ent times we exist in different complex states of feeling, and these states are made up of a number of constituent thoughts and affections. At one time — say during a sacred solemnity — we are in a very different frame of mind from what we are in at an- other, — say during the representation of a comedy. Now, then, in such a state of mind, if anything occurs to awaken to activity a power previously occupied, or to occupy a power, previously in energy, in a differ- ent manner, this new mode of activity is either of the same general character and tendency with the other constituent elements of the complex state, or it is not. (1.) In the former case, .the new energy chimes in with the old ; each operates without impediment from the other, and the general harmony of feeling is not violated; (2.) in the latter case, the new energy jars with the old, and each severally counteracts and im- pedes the other. Thus, in the sacred solemnity, and when our minds are brought to a state of serious con- templation, everything that operates in unison with that state — say a pious discourse or a strain of sol- emn music — will have a greater effect. But suppose that, instead of the pious discourse, or the strain of solemn music, we are treated to a merry tune or a witty address ; these, though at another season they sin wjlliam Hamilton's rniLosorar. 205 might afford us considerable pleasure, would, under the circumstances, cause only pain. IV. Association. It is evident, in the first place, that one object, considered simply and in itself, will be more pleasing than another, in proportion as it, of its proper nature, determines the exertion of a greater amount of free energy. But, in the second place, the amount of free energy, which an object may itself elicit, is small, when compared with the amount that may be elicited by its train of associated representa- tions. Thus it is evident, that the object, which in itself would otherwise be pleasing, may, through the accident of association, be the occasion of pain ; and on the contrary, that an object, naturally indiffer- ent or even painful, may, by the same contingency, be productive of pleasure. This principle accounts for a great many of our intellectual pleasures and pains ; but it is far from accounting for everything. In fact, it supposes, as its condition, that there are pains and pleasures not founded on association. Association is a principle of pleasure and pain, only as it is a principle of energy of one character or another ; and the attempts that have been made to resolve all our mental pleasures and pains into association are guilty of a twofold vice. For (1.) they convert a partial into an exclusive law; and (2.) they elevate a subordinate into a supreme principle. (Lect. on Metaph., XLIV.) The influence of association, by which Mr. Alison and Lord Jeffrey , among others, have attempted to explain the whole phenomena of our intellectual pleasures, was more properly, I think, appreciated by 206 AN OUTLINE OF Hutcheson. "We shall see hereafter," he says, and Aristotle said the same thing, " that associations of ideas make objects pleasant and delightful, which are not naturally apt to give any such pleasures ; • and the same way, the casual conjunction of ideas may give a disgust where there is nothing disagreeable in the form itself. And this is the occasion of many fantas- tic aversions to figures of some animals and to some other forms. Thus swine, serpents of all kinds, and some insects really beautiful enough, are beheld with aversion by many people, who have got some acci- dental ideas associated with them. And for distastes of this kind no other account can be given." § 2. THE FEELINGS AS EFFECTS. Since all feeling is the state in which we are con- scious of some of the energies or processes of life, as these energies or processes differ, so will the correla- tive feelings : in a word, there will be as many differ- ent feelings as there are distinct modes of mental activity. Now, the feelings, which accompany the exertion of the bodily powers, whether cognitive or appetent, will constitute a distinct class, to which we may with great propriety give the name of Sensations ; whereas, on the feelings, which accompany the ener- gies of all our higher powers of mind, we may, with equal propriety, bestow the name of Sentiments. (A) The Sensations may be divided into two classes: (1.) those included under what has been called Sensus Fixus, comprehending the five deter- minate senses of touch, taste, smell, hearing, sight; (2.) SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON* S PHILOSOPHY. 207 those included under what has beeu called Sensus Vagus, comprehending such sensations as those of heat and cold, of muscular tension and lassitude, of hunger and thirst, etc. I. Sensus Fixus. In regard to the determinate senses, each of these organs has its specific action, and its appropriate pleasure or pain. This pleasure and pain, which is that alone belonging to the action of the living organ, and which therefore may be styled organic, we must distinguish from that higher feeling, which perhaps results from the exercise of imagina- tion and intellect upon the phenomena delivered by the senses. Thus, I would call organic the pleasure we feel in the perception of green or blue, and the pain we feel in the perception of a dazzling white ; but I would be perhaps disposed to refer to some other power than the external sense the enjoj^ment we experience in the harmony of colors, and certainly that which we find in the proportions of figure. When it is required of us to explain, particularly and in detail, why the rose, for example, produces this sensation of smell, assafcetida that other, and so forth, and to say in what peculiar action does the per- fect or pleasurable, and the imperfect or painful, ac- tivity of an organ consist, we must at once profess our ignorance. All that we can say is, that, on the general analogy of our being, when the impression of an object on a sense is in harmony with its amount of power, and thus allows it the condition of springing to full spontaneous energy, the result is pleasure ; whereas, when the impression is out of harmony with 208 AN OUTLINE OF the amount of power, and thus either represses it or stimulates it to over-activity, the result is pain. II. Sensus Vagus. The same explanation must be applied to the sensations which belong to this sense, but in regard to these it is not necessary to say any- thing in detail. (B) The Sentiments may be divided into (1.) the contemplative, the concomitants of our cognitive pow- ers, and (2.) the practical, .the concomitants of our powers of conation. I. The contemplative sentiments are again distribu- ted into (1.) those of the subsidiary faculties, and (2.) those of the elaborative faculty. 1. The feelings, accompanying the subsidiary fac- ulties, may be subdivided into (a) those of self-con- sciousness, and (b) those of imagination, compre- hending under imagination the relative faculty of reproduction. (a) Sentiments attending Self -consciousness. By self-consciousness we become aware that we live. Now, we are conscious of our life only as we are con- scious of our activity, and we are conscious of activity only as we are conscious of a change of state ; for all activity is the going out of one state into another. Now, if there be nothing which presents to our facul- ties the objects on which they may exert their activity ; in other words, if there be no cause whereby our act- ual state may be made to pass into another, there results a peculiar irksome feeling of a want of excite- ment, which we denominate tedium or ennui. An inability to thought is a security against this feeling, and therefore tedium is far less felt by the uncultivated SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON 3 's PHILOSOPHY. 209 thau by the educated. The more varied the objects presented to our thought, the more varied and viva- cious our activity, the iuteuser will be our conscious- ness of living, and the more rapidly will the time appear to fly. Hence we explain why we call our easy occupations pastimes, and why play is so engag- ing when it is at all deep. Games of hazard de- termine a continual change, : — now we hope, now we fear; while in games of skill, we experience also the pleasure which arises from the activity of the under- standing in carrying through our own, and frustrating the plan of our antagonist. All that relieves tedium, by affording a change and an easy exercise for our thoughts, causes pleasure. The best cure of tedium is some occupation which, by concentrating our attention on external objects, shall divert it from a retortion on ourselves. All occupa- tion is either labor or play ; labor when there is some end ulterior to the activity, play when the activity is for its own sake alone. In both, however, there must be ever and anon a change of object, or both will soon grow tiresome. Labor is thus the best preventive of tedium, for it has an external motive which holds us steadfast to the work ; while, after the completion of our task, the feeling of repose, as the change from the feeling of a constrained to that of a spontaneous state, affords a vivid and peculiar pleasure. Labor must alternate with repose, or we shall never know what is the true enjoyment of life. Thus it appears that a uniform continuity in our in- ternal states is painful, and that pleasure is the result of their commutation. It is, however, to be observed, 14 210 AN OUTLINE OF that the change of our perceptions and thoughts, to be pleasing, must not be too rapid; for as the intervals, when too long, produce the feeling of tedium, so, when too short, they cause that of giddiness or vertigo. The too rapid passing, for example, of visible objects or of tones before the senses, of images before the phantasy, of thoughts before the understanding, occa- sions the disagreeable feeling of confusion or stupe- faction, which, in individuals of very sensitive temperament, results in nausea or sickness. (6) Sentiments attending Imagination. Whatever in general facilitates the play of imagination, is felt as pleasing ; whatever renders it more difficult is felt as displeasing. We are pleased with the portrait of a person whose face we know, if like, because it en- ables us to recall the features into consciousness easily and freely ; and we are displeased with it, if unlike, because it not only does not assist, but thwarts us in our endeavor to recall them ; while, after this has been accomplished, we are still further pained by the disharmony we experience between the portrait on the canvas and the representation in our own imagina- tion. A short and characteristic description of things which we have seen pleases us, because, without exacting a protracted effort of attention, and through a few striking traits, it enables the imagination to place the objects vividly before it. On the same prin- ciple, whatever facilitates the reproduction of the ob- jects which have been consigned to memory is pleasurable ; as, for example, resemblances, contrasts, other associations with the passing thought, metre, rhyme, symmetry, appropriate designations, etc. To SIK WILLIAM HAMILTON'S PHILOSOPHY. 211 realize an act of imagination it is necessary that we comprehend the manifold as a single whole : an ob- ject, therefore, which does not allow itself without difficulty to be thus represented in unity, occasions pain ; whereas an object, which can easily be recalled to system, is the cause of pleasure. The former is the case when the object is too large or too complex to be perceived at once, when the parts are not promi- nent enough to be distinctly impressed on the memory. Order and symmetry, again, facilitate the acts of re- production and representation, and consequently afford us a proportional gratification. But, on the other hand, as pleasure is in proportion to the amount of free energy, an object which gives no impediment to the comprehensive energy of imagination may not be pleasurable, if it be so simple as not to afford to this faculty a sufficient exercise. Hence it is, that not variety alone, and not unity alone, but variety com- bined with unity, is that quality in objects, which we emphatically denominate beautiful. 2. Under the head of the feelings which are asso- ciated with the elaborative faculty or the understand- ing, it will be proper to consider, in the first place, those which arise from the operations of the under- standing by itself, and afterwards those which accom- pany the joint exercise of the understanding and the imagination. (a) Sentiments attending the exercise of the Under- standing by itself. The function of the understanding may in general be said to bestow, on the cognitions which it elaborates, the greatest possible compass, the greatest possible clearness and distinctness, the great- 212 AN OUTLINE OF est possible certainty and systematic order ; and inas- much as we approximate to the accomplishment of these ends, we experience pleasure ; inasmuch as we meet with hindrances in our attempts, we experience pain. Obscurity and confusion in our cognitions we feel as disagreeable, whereas their clearness and dis- tinctness afford us sincere gratification. We are pained by a hazy and perplexed discourse, but rejoice in one perspicuous and profound. Hence the pleasure we experience in having the cognitions we possessed, but darkling and confused, explicated into life and order ; and, on this account, there is hardly a more pleasing object than a tabular conspectus of any com- plex whole. We are soothed by the solution of a riddle ; and the wit which, like a flash of lightning, discovers similarities between objects which seemed contradictory, affords a still intenser enjoyment. The multitude — the multifarious character — of the objects presented to our observation stands in signal contrast with the very limited capacity of the human intellect. This disproportion constrains us to classify. Now, the process of classification is per- formed by that function of the understanding which apprehends resemblances. In this detection of the similarities between different objects an energy of the understanding is fully and freely exerted ; and hence results a pleasure. But as in general notions the knowledge of individual existences loses in precision and completeness, we again endeavor to find out dif- ferences in the things which stand under a notion, to the end that we may be able to specify and individual- ize them. This counter-process is performed by that sir William Hamilton's philosophy. 213 function of the understanding which apprehends dis- similarities between resembling objects, and in the full and free exertion of this energy there is a feeling of pleasure. The intellect further tends to reduce the piecemeal and fragmentary cognitions it possesses to a systematic whole ; in other words, to elevate them into Science. Hence the pleasure we derive from all that enables us with ease and rapidity to survey the relation of com- plex parts as constituting the members of one organic whole. The intellect, from the necessity it has of thinking eyerything as the result of some higher reason, is thus determined to attempt the deduction of every object of cognition from a simple principle. When, therefore, we succeed or seem to succeed in the discovery of such a principle, we feel a pleasure ; as ^e feel a pain when the intellect is frustrated in this endeavor. To the feelings of pleasure which are afforded by the unimpeded energies of the understanding belongs, likewise, the gratification we find in the apprehension of adaptation of means to ends. Human intelligence is naturally determined to propose to itself an end ; and, in the consideration of objects, it thus naturally thinks them under this relation. If, therefore, we con- sider an object in reference to an end, and if this ob- ject be recognized to fulfil the conditions which this relation implies, the act of thought, in which this is accomplished, is an unimpeded and consequently pleasurable energy ; whereas the act of cognizing that these conditions are wanting, and the object therefore 214 AN OUTLINE OF ill adapted to its end, is a thwarted, and therefore a painful, energy of thought. (b) Sentiments attending the Understanding and the Imagination in conjunction. The feelings of satis- faction which result from the plastic imagination, that is, the phantasy and the understanding conjointly, are principally those of beauty and sublimity ; and the judgments which pronounce an object to be sublime, beautiful, etc., are called, by a metaphorical expres- sion, Judgments of Taste. They have also been called ^Esthetical Judgments ; but both terms are unsatis- factory. In the following observations it is almost needless to observe that I can make no attempt at more than a simple indication of the origin- of the pleasure we derive from the contemplation of those objects, which, from the character of the feelings they determine, are called beautiful, sublime, picturesque, etc. i. The Beautiful has been divided into the free or absolute, and the dependent or relative. In the former case it is not necessary to have a notion of what the ob- ject oughtto be before we pronounce it beautiful, ornot ; in the latter case such a previous notion is required. We judge, for example, a flower to be beautiful, though unaware of its destination, and that it contains a complex apparatus of organs all admirably adapted to the propagation of the plant. When we are made cognizant of this, we obtain, indeed, an additional gratification, but one wholly different from that which we experience in the contemplation of the flower itself, apart from all consideration of its adaptations. This distinction appears to me unsound. What has sir willtam Hamilton's philosophy. 215 been distinguished as dependent or relative beauty is nothing more than a beautified utility or a utilized beauty. Be this, however, as it may, our pleasure in both cases arises from a free and full play being allowed to our cognitive faculties. (a) In the case of free beauty, — beauty, strictly so called, — both the imagination and the understand- ing find occupation ; and the pleasure we experience from such an object is in proportion as it affords to these faculties the opportunity of exerting fully and freely their respective energies. Now, it is the prin- cipal function of the understanding, out of the multi- farious presented to it, to form a whole. Its entire activity is, in fact, a tendency towards unity; and it is only satisfied when this object is so constituted as to afford the opportunity of an easy and perfect per- formance of this its function. The object is then judged to be beautiful or pleasing. This enables us to explain the differences of different individuals in the apprehension of the beautiful. If an understand- ing, by natural constitution, by cultivation and exer- cise, be vigorous enough to think up rapidly into a whole what is presented in complexity, the individual has an enjoyment, and he regards the object as beau- tiful ; whereas if an intellect perform this function slowly and with effort, if it succeed in accomplishing the end at all, the individual can feel no pleasure (if he does not experience pain), and the object must to him appear as one destitute of beauty, if not positively ugly. Hence it is that children, boors, in a word persons of a weak or uncultivated mind, may find the 216 AN OUTLINE OF parts of a building beautiful, while unable to compre- hend the beauty of it as a whole. (/?) In the case of relative or dependent beauty we must distinguish the pleasure we receive into two,, combined indeed, but not identical. The one of these pleasures is that from the beauty which the object contains, and the principle of which we have been just considering. The other of these pleasures is that which we showed was attached to a perfect energy of the understanding in thinking an object under the notion of conformity as a mean adapted to an end. The result, then, of what has now been said is, that a thing beautiful is one whose form occupies the imagi- nation and understanding in a free and full, and con- sequently in an agreeable, activity. ii. The feeling of pleasure in the sublime is essen- tially different from our feeling of pleasure in the beautiful. The beautiful affords a feeling of un- mingled pleasure in the full and unimpeded activity of our cognitive powers ; whereas our feeling of sub- limity is a mingled one of pleasure and of pain, — of pleasure in the consciousness of strong energy, of pain in the consciousness that this energy is in vain. But as the amount of pleasure in the sublime is greater than the amount of pain, it follows that the free energy it elicits must be greater than the free energy it repels. The beautiful has reference to the form of an object, and the facility with which it is comprehended. For beauty, magnitude is thus an impediment. Sub- limity, on the contrary, requires magnitude as its condition ; and the formless is not unfrequently sub- sir william Hamilton's philosophy. 217 lime. That we are at once attracted and repelled by sublimity, arises from the circumstance that the object, which we call sublime, is proportioned to one of our faculties, and disproportioned to another; but as the degree of pleasure transcends the degree of pain, the power whose energy is promoted must be superior to that power whose energy is repressed. The sublime may be divided, according to the three quantities, into the sublime of extension, the sublime of protension, and the sublime of intension; or, what comes to the same thing, the sublime of space, the sublime of time, and the sublime of power. In the two former the cognitive, in the last the conative, powers come into play. («) An object is extensively or protensively sub- lime when it comprises so great a multitude of parts that the imagination sinks under the attempt to rep- resent it in an image, and the understanding to measure it by other quantities. Baffled in the attempt to reduce the object within the limits of the faculties by which it must be comprehended, the mind at once desists from the ineffectual effort, and conceives the object not by a positive, but by a negative, notion ; it conceives it as inconceivable, and falls back into repose, which is felt as pleasing by contrast to the continuance of a forced and impeded energy. Exam- ples of the sublime — of this sudden effort, and of this instantaneous desisting from the attempt — are manifested in the extensive sublime of Space, and in the protensive sublime of Eternity. (,3) An object is intensively sublime when it in- volves such a degree of force or power that the imag- 218 AN OUTLINE OF ination cannot at once represent, and the understand- ing cannot at once bring under measure, the quantum of this force ; and when, from the nature of the object, the inability of the mind is at once made apparent, so that it does not proceed in the ineffectual effort, but at once calls back its energies from the attempt. It is thus manifest that the feeling of the sublime will be one of mingled pain and pleasure ; pleasure, from the vigorous exertion and the instantaneous repose ; pain, from the consciousness of limited and frustrated activity. This mixed feeling in the con- templation of the sublime object is finely expressed by Lucretius when he says : — "Me quaedam divina voluptas Percipit atque horror." iii. The Picturesque, however opposite to the sub- lime, seems, in my opinion, to stand to the beautiful in a somewhat similar relation. An object is posi- tively ugly, when it is of such a form that the imagi- nation and the understanding cannot help attempting to think it up into unity, and yet their energies fail in the endeavor, or accomplish it only imperfectly after time and toil. The cause of this continuance of effort is, that the object does not present such an appearance of incongruous variety as at once to com- pel the mind to desist from the attempt of reducing it to unity ; but, on the contrary, leads it on to attempt what it is yet unable to perform, — its reduction to a whole. But variety — variety even apart from unity — is pleasing ; and if the mind be made content to sir william Hamilton's philosophy. 219 expatiate freely and easily in this variety, without at- tempting painfully to reduce it to unity, it will derive no inconsiderable pleasure from this exertion of its powers. Now, a picturesque object is precisely of such a character. It is so determinately varied and so abrupt in its variety ; it presents so complete a ne- gation of all rounded contour, and so regular an irreg- ularity of broken lines and angles ; that every attempt at reducing it to an harmonious whole is at once found to be impossible. The mind, therefore, which must forego the energy of representing and thinking the object as a unity, surrenders itself at once to the energies which deal with it only in detail. II. The practical feelings are divisible into five classes, as they relate to (1.) our self-preservation, (2.) the enjoyment of our existence, (3.) the preser- vation of the species, (4.) our tendency towards de- velopment and perfection, (5.) the moral law. 1 . The feelings of self-preservation are those of hun- ger and thirst, loathing, sorrow, bodily pain, repose, fear at danger, anxiety, shuddering, alarm, composure, security, and the nameless feeling at the representa- tion of death. Several of these feelings are corpo- real, and may be considered, with equal propriety, as modifications of the vague sense. 2. The feelings relating to the enjoyment of existence arise from the fact that man is determined not only to exist, but to exist well ; he is therefore determined also to desire whatever tends to render life agreeable, and to eschew whatever tends to render it disagree- able. All, therefore, that appears to contribute to the former, causes in him the feeling of joy ; whereas 220 AN OUTLINE OF all that seems to threaten the latter excites in him the repressed feelings of fear, anxiety, sorrow, etc., which we have already mentioned. 3. Man is determined not only to preserve him- self, but to preserve the species to which he belongs, and with this tendency various feelings are associated . To this head belong the feelings of sexual love and parental affection. But the human affections are not limited to family connections. " Man," says Aristotle, "is the sweetest thing to man." We have thus a ten- dency to social intercourse, ancf society is at once the necessary condition of our happiness and of our per- fection. In conformity with his tendency to social existence man is endowed with a sympathetic feeling ; that is, he rejoices with those that rejoice, and grieves with those that grieve. Compassion or pity is the name given to the latter modification of sympathy; the former is without a definite name. Besides sym- pathetic sorrow and sympathetic joy, there are a variety of feelings which have reference to our exist- ence in a social relation. Of these there is that con- nected with vanity, or the wish to please others from the desire of being respected by them ; with shame, or the fear and sorrow at incurring their disrespect ; with pride, or the overweening sentiment of our own worth. To the same class we may refer the feelings connected with indignation, resentment, anger, scorn, etc. 4. There is in man implanted a desire of develop- ing his powers, — a tendency towards perfection. In virtue of this, the consciousness of all comparative inability causes pain ; the consciousness of all com- SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON 's PHILOSOPHY. 221 parative power causes pleasure. To this class belong the feelings which accompany emulation, — the desire of rising superior to others ; and envy, — the desire of reducing others beneath ourselves. 5. We are conscious that there is in man a moral law, which unconditionally commands the fulfilment of its behests. Inasmuch as moral intelligence uncon- ditionally commands us to perform what we are con- scious to be our duty, there is attributed to man an absolute worth. The feeling, which the manifesta- tion of this worth excites, is called respect. With the consciousness of the lofty nature of our moral tenden- cies, and our ability to fulfil what the law of duty prescribes, there is couuected the feeling of self- respect; whereas, from a consciousness of the contrast between what we ought to do and what we actually perform, there arises the feeling of self-abasement. The sentiment of respect for the law of duty is the moral feeling, which has by some been improperly denominated the moral sense; for through this feeling we do not take cognizance whether anything be morally good or morally evil, but when by our intel- ligence we recognize aught to be of such a character, there is herewith associated a feeling of pain or pleasure, which is nothing more than our state in ref- erence to the fulfilment or violation of the law. Man, as conscious of his liberty to act and of the law by which his actions ought to be regulated, recognizes his personal accountability, and calls himself before the internal tribunal which we denominate conscience. Here he is either acquitted or condemned. The ac- 222 AN OUTLINE OF HAMILTON'S PHILOSOPHY. quittal is connected with a peculiar feeling of pleasur- able exultation, as the condemnation is with a peculiar feeliug of painful humiliation, — remorse. {Led. on Metaph., XLV. and XLVI.) THIRD PART OF PHENOMENAL PSYCHOLOGY. PHENOMENOLOGY OF THE CONATIONS. THIRD PART OF PHENOMENAL PSYCHOLOGY. PHENOMENOLOGY OF THE CONATIONS. Under the third class of mental phenomena are comprehended both the phenomenon of desire and the phenomenon of volition. In English unfortunately we have no term capable of adequately expressing what is common both to volition and desire, that is, the ?iisns or conatus, — the tendency towards the reali- zation of their end. Were we to say the phenomena of tendency, the phrase would be vague ; and the same is true of the phenomena of doing. Again, the term phenomena of appetency is objectionable, because (to say nothing of the unfamiliarity of the expression) appetency, though perhaps etymologically unexcep- tionable, has, both in Latin and English, a meaning almost synonymous with desire. Like the Latin appetentia, the Greek vps^t<; is equally ill-balanced ; for, though used by philosophers to comprehend both will and desire, it more familiarly suggests the latter, and we need not, therefore, be solicitous, with Mr. Harris and Lord Monboddo, to naturalize in Euglish the term orectic. Again, the phrase phenomena of activity would be even worse ; every possible objection 15 ' 225 226 AN OUTLINE OF can be made to the term active powers, by which the philosophers of this country have designated the orec- tic faculties of the Aristotelians. For you will ob- serve that all faculties are equally active ; and it is not the overt performance, but the tendency towards i it, for which we are in quest of an expression. The term Conative is employed by Cuclworth, and I shall adopt the word conations as the most appropriate expression for this class of phenomena. (Lect. on Metaph., XL) The conations, as tendencies to action, are divisible into classes, as such tendencies are either blind and fatal, or deliberate and free. The former are desires, the latter, volitions. (A) Desires may be subdivided according to their objects, for they relate either (1.) to Self-preserva- tion, or (2.) to the Enjoyment of Existence, or (3.) to the Preservation of the Species, or (4.) to our Tendency towards Development and Perfection, or (5.) to the Moral Law. 1 (Lect. on Metaph., XLYI.) II. Will is a free cause, a cause which is not also an effect, a power of absolute origination. (Discus- sions, p. 623.) It is proved to be so, 1. Directly, by an immediate testimony of con- sciousness to the fact (Lect. on Metaph., II. ; ReioVs Works, p. 624, note, and pp. 616-7, notes) ; while 1 It may be observed that this is the classification of the - desires given above (Phenomenology of the Feelings, Chap. II., § 2, (B) II.) ; and it is the only classification attempted by Sir William Ham- ilton. It ought not, however, to be forgotten that it is suggested, not in an independent treatment of the desires, but in a description of the feelings which the desires originate. — J. C. M. SIB WILLIAM HAMILTON' S PHILOSOPHY. 227 2. Indirectly also it is implied in our conscious- ness, at once of an uncompromising law of duty, and of our beinsr the accountable authors of our actions. (Led. on Metaph., II. ; Discussions, pp. 623-4.) The fact of a free volition is indeed positively in- conceivable, and that for two reasons : — 1. The Law of the Conditioned in Time, under the form of the Law of Causality, renders impossible the conception of an absolute commencement. 2. On the one hand, the determination of the will by motives can be conceived only as a necessitation which would render moral accountability impossible. On the other hand, were we to admit as true what we cannot think as possible, still the doctrine of a motive- less volition would be only casualism ; and the free acts of an indifferent, are, morally and rationally, as worthless as the pre-ordered passions of a determined will. How, therefore, moral liberty is possible in man or in God must remain, under the present limitation of our faculties, wholly incomprehensible ; but the fact of liberty caunot be redargued on the ground of its incomprehensibility. For, 1. The judgment of causality, which renders free will inconceivable, has been proved not to depend on a 'power of the mind, imposing, as necessary in thought, what is necessary in the universe of existence. This judgment is a mere mental impotence, — an impotence to conceive either of two contradictories ; and as the one or the other of contradictories must be true, whilst both cannot, there is no ground for inferring a fact to be impossible merely from our inability to conceive its 228 AN OUTLINE OF HAMILTON'S PHILOSOPHY. possibility. At the same time, if the causal judgment be not an express affirmation of mind, but only an incapacity of thinking the opposite, it follows that such a negative judgment cannot counterbalance the express affirmative, the unconditional testimony, of consciousness, that we are, though we know not how, the true and responsible authors of our actions, not merely the worthless links in an adamantine series of causes and effects. 2. But not only may the fact of our moral liberty be shown to be possible, though inconceivable ; the very objection of incomprehensibility, by which the fatalist had thought to triumph over the libertarian, may be retorted against himself. The scheme of freedom is not more inconceivable than the scheme of necessity. For whilst fatalism is a recoil from the more obtrusive inconceivability of an absolute commencement, on the fact of which commencement the doctrine of liberty proceeds ; the fatalist over- looks the equal, but less obtrusive, inconceivability of an infinite non-commencement, on the assertion of which non-commencement his own doctrine of neces- sity must ultimately rest. As equally unthinkable, the two counter, the two one-sided, schemes are thus theoretically balanced. But practically our conscious- ness of the moral law, which, without a moral liberty in man, would be a mendacious imperative, gives a decisive preponderance to the doctrine of freedom over the doctrine of fate. We are free in act, if we are accountable for our actions. [Discussions, pp. 623-5.) SECOND DIVISION OF PHILOSOPHY. NOMOLOGICAL PSYCHOLOGY. NOMOLOGICAL PSYCHOLOGY. Nomological Psychology, or the Nomology of Mind, is that science which investigates, not contin- gent appearances, but the necessary and universal facts, that is, the laws, by which our faculties are governed, to the end that we may obtain a criterion by which to judge or to explain their procedures and manifestations. Now, there will be as many depart- ments of Nomological Psychology as there are classes of mental phenomena ; for as each class proposes a different end, and, in the accomplishment of that end, is regulated by peculiar laws, each must consequently have a different science conversant about these laws, that is, a different Nomology. (A) First Part of Nomological Psychology: Nomology of the Cognitions. There is no one, no Nomological, science of the Cognitive faculties, in general ; though we have some older treatises which, though partial in their subject, afford a name not un- suitable for a nomology of the cognitions, — namely, Gnoseologia or Gnostologia. There is no indepen- dent science of the laws of Perception ; if there were, it might be called ^Esthetic, which, however, as we shall see, would be ambiguous. Mnemonic, or the 231 232 AN OUTLINE OF science of the laws of Memory, has been elaborated at least in numerous treatises ; but the name Anam- nestic, the art of Recollection or Reminiscence, might be equally well applied to it. The laws of the Repre- sentative faculty, — that is, the laws of Association, — have not yet been elevated into a separate ISTomolog- ical science. Neither have the conditions of the Reg- ulative or Legislative faculty, the faculty itself of Laws, been fully analyzed, far less reduced to system ; though we have several deservedly forgotten treatises, of an older date, under the inviting name of Zoolo- gies. The only one of the cognitive faculties, whose laws constitute the object-matter of a separate science, is the Elaborative. This Nomology has obtained the name of Logic 1 among other appellations, but not from Aristotle. The best name would have been Dianoetic. Logic is the science of the laws of thought in relation to the end which our cognitive faculties propose, — i. e., the True. To this head might be referred Grammar, — Universal Grammar, Philosophical Grammar, or the science conversant with the laws of Language, as the instrument of thought. (B) Second Part of Nomological Psychology : Nomology of the Feelings. The Nomology of our Feelings, or the science of the laws which govern our capacities of enjoyment, in relation to the end which they propose, — *. e., the Pleasurable, — has ob- tained no precise name in our language. It has been 1 Sir William Hamilton has a separate course of lectures on Logic, which, however, could not, even in the most abridged form, be em- bodied in the present work. — J. C. M. SIX WILLIAM HAMILTON'' S PHILOSOPHY. 233 called the Philosophy of Taste, and, on the Continent especially, it has been denominated ^Esthetic. Neither name is unobjectionable. The first is vague, meta- phorical, and even delusive. In regard to the second, you are aware that aU&n