THE PSYCHOLOGY OF THE KAISER MORTON PRINCE Class.. :' 1 : Book ~Yl Copyright N?. COPYRIGHT DEPOSIT. THE KAISER TAKEN UNAWARES. THE PSYCHOLOGY OF THE KAISER A Study of His Sentiments and His Obsession BY MORTON PRINCE BOSTON: RICHARD G. BADGER TORONTO: THE COPP CLARK CO., LIMITED LONDON: T. FISHER UNWIN 1915 Copyright, 19 15, by Morton Prince All Rights Reserved Urterwood wui Underwood The Gorham Press, Boston, U. S. A. AUG -7 1915 ©CI.A410016 SYNOPSIS I. The Kaiser's Antipathy. II. The Kaiser's Prerogatives. III. The Kaiser's Divine Right De- lusion. IV. The German Autocracy and the Army. V. The Kaiser's Sentiments. VI. The Kaiser's Self-Regarding Sentiment. VII. Aims of the German Democracy. VIII. The Real Cause of the Kaiser's Antipathy. IX. The Kaiser's Antipathy an Ob- session and a Defense Reac- tion. The Moral THE PSYCHOLOGY OF THE KAISER THE PSYCHOLOGY OF THE KAISER i THE KAISER'S ANTIPATHY |"N the consciousness of the Kaiser there ■*■ is nothing that is more dominant than his increasing and virulent antipathy to a great body of citizens constituting no less than one-third of his empire — the Social Democrats. We have all read of the Kaiser's hatred of the party known as the Social Demo- cratic Party. We have read the epithets which he has constantly hurled at them, and of his antipathy to their creeds. "Traitors," "a plague that must be ex- terminated," "a horde of men unworthy 7 8 The Psychology of the Kaiser to bear the name of Germans," "foes to the country and empire," "people with- out a country and enemies of religion," he has called them. To a delegation of striking miners he said: For me every Social Democrat is synony- mous with an enemy of the empire and of his country. If, therefore, I believe that there are any Socialist tendencies in the move- ment [the strike of 100,000 men], stirring up to unlawful resistance, I shall act with merciless rigor and bring to bear all the power at my disposal — which is great. Again : The doctrines of the Social Democrats are not only opposed to the commandments of God and Christian morality but are also al- together unpractical, being equally injurious to the individuals and the whole community. The Psychology of the Kaiser 9 So violent is the hatred of the Kaiser toward this party that he even has thought it might come to suppressing it by the army. He said to the young soldiers at Potsdam: For you there is only one foe, and that is my foe. In view of our present Socialist troubles, it may come to this, that I command you to shoot down your own relatives, brothers, and even parents, in the streets, which God forbid; but then you must obey my orders without a murmur. Why so much feeling? Why such re- current outbursts of anger and hatred against a political party which in num- bers is twice as large as any other single party in the empire, a party which in 191 2 cast 4,250,000 votes * and which was * The total vote cast was 12,207,000. The number of Social Democrats elected was not fairly proportionate to the voting strength of the party owing to the pecu- io The Psychology of the Kaiser represented in the German Parliament in 1912 by no members, the representatives liar election laws existing in the different states of Ger- many. Hence ballot reform was the principal imme- diate issue of the party before the war. In Prussia, for example, there is what is called the "three-class system." The voters are divided into three classes ac- cording to the amount of taxes paid, the total taxes being divided into three equal parts. "Then, starting with the highest taxpayers, those voters whose taxes total the first third of taxes paid constitute the first class of electors. They are the wealthiest men and nat- urally are smallest in numbers. "The second class is made up of those electors who pay taxes equal to the second division. Their number is a little larger. The third class is made up of all the rest of the voters. "Each class elects the same number of deputies to the Reichstag. Obviously the respectable middle class com- posed of that element in Continental politics known as the bourgeoisie throws its vote with that of the aris- tocracy against the people at large. In one careful analysis of this system the ratio in the division was roughly as follows : one voter in the first class ; thirty-two voters in the second class; three hundred and fifty voters in the third class. "Now the exclusive gentleman in the first class elected just as many members of the Reichstag as did the 350 workingmen in the third class, or the thirty-two well-to- do business men in the second class." ("The Kaiser," edited by Asa Don Dickenson, p. 105.) The Psychology of the Kaiser II of over 21,000,000 people, nearly one- third of the population? S. P. Orth ("Socialism and Democracy in Europe") gives various instances of the inequality which appears in the cities. "In Berlin in one precinct one man paid one-third of the taxes and consequently possessed one-third of the legislative influence in that precinct. In another precinct the president of a large bank paid one-third of the taxes, and two of his associates paid another third. These three men named the member of the Diet from that precinct." In Saxony the electorate is divided into four classes according to their income. The members of each class have respectively 1, 2, 3, and 4 votes. Consequently, in 1909 18,491 voters of the fourth class, having 4 votes each, cast 73,964 votes, while 32,567 voters of the first class cast only 32,567 votes. Corresponding inequalities of representation neces- sarily followed. One result of the election laws is that the cities where the Social Democrats preponderate have very small rep- resentation, while the rural districts where the conser- vatives (Junkers) are a majority have a dispropor- tionately large representation. Thus Greater Berlin with 850,000 voters, where the Social Democrats are in a vast majority, was represented in the Reichstag by only eight members while the same number of voters in the small rural districts were represented by forty-eight mem- bers. Again: The city of Berlin in 1910 with a popu- lation of 2,000,000 was governed by 33,062 persons, owing to the three-class system of voting. 12 The Psychology of the Kaiser These are strong words of the Kaiser's I have quoted. They are not mere invec- tives uttered during the heat of a politi- cal campaign. They are not to be classed with those emotional castigations with which political stump-speech orators, working themselves up to a state of pas- sionate indignation, flay their adversaries, and which are promptly forgotten as soon as the campaign is ended — albeit the Kaiser is essentially a stump-speech ora- tor. We have all learned not to take seri- ously the ephemeral indignation of the political orator. But the Kaiser's denun- ciation of the Social Democrats is the expression of an antipathy which is fixed, It may also be pointed out that the 4,250,000 votes cast by the Social Democrats in 1912 do not represent the whole opposition to the autocracy, inasmuch as cer- tain liberal groups, the progressives and the people's party cast together 1,506,000 votes. The Psychology of the Kaiser 13 deep-rooted, persistent, and is a part of his personality, for it has manifested it- self in the form of recurrent attacks of anger and hatred ever since he came to the throne, twenty-seven years ago. It is like unto an obsessing idea, common enough, which, fixed deep down in the mind, rises in consciousness whenever its object presents itself. Fixed antipathies are always, for the psychologist, objects of interesting study, but for others, even in an Emperor, they are little more than matters of intellectual curiosity unless the antipathy is one of practical political import, one that affects the policies of Government and the course of history. If the antipathy of the Kaiser were only of that trivial kind common to many people, which is manifested as a dread of snakes, or of death, or other banal ob- 14 The Psychology of the Kaiser ject, its study would be of little practical interest excepting for its victim, Wil- liam II. himself, although the revelation of its origin and meaning would give an insight into one component, however un- important, of an exalted personality. The periodical recurrence of the an- tipathy and the psychological reactions to which it gave rise would probably affect the happiness of no one but himself and the unhappy members of his family who would have to bear the brunt of it. No one is interested in other people's symp- toms. But it is different when such a recur- ring antipathy is of a political nature. Then by a study of the underlying causes of this obsessing idea we not only can ob- tain an insight into important components of the personality of a great historical character, but we should expect to find The Psychology of the Kaiser 15 the true motives which have determined those policies of Government and the course of history which have been the direct result of the antipathy. The Kaiser's hatred of the Social Democrats has had momentous practical consequences. It is safe to say that it has been more than any other single fac- tor the motive which has determined him to maintain, against the progressive spirit of modern civilization, the present auto- cratic system of government, to resist all liberal attempts to change the Constitu- tion so as to give responsible representa- tive government to the people and to de- fend what he claims as his prerogatives. It has determined other tyrannous meas- ures which have suppressed freedom of speech and the press and banefully op- pressed the liberty of the German people. I refer to the law of lese-majeste. 16 The Psychology of the Kaiser This law, a return to the feudalism of the Middle Ages, is the means the Kaiser employs to punish those who talk back. He may insult his subjects, call them all manner of names, misrepresent their prin- ciples, their purposes and ideals, excite animosity against them "as enemies to the country and religion," but if they answer back they are met by the law of lese- majeste, and this law is enforced, as every one knows, with merciless severity to sup- press political opponents. Against the Democrats the law has been used as a weapon of suppression, though without success. Under this law statistics showed that up to 1898, during only the first decade of William II. 's reign, more than 1,000 years of imprison- ment had been inflicted upon offenders. A recent responsible writer asserts that up to 1 9 14 the sentences had reached The Psychology of the Kaiser IJ 30,000 years, but I do not know upon what authority these figures are based. It is not surprising that editors of So- cial Democratic newspapers, many po- litical leaders of the party, and writers for the Democratic press have been among those who have served terms in prison for lese-majeste, or offense against the press law. There have been times when scarcely a week passed without three or four trials. But against the Social Democratic mem- bers of the Reichstag when making use of their prerogatives as elected representa- tives of the people, this law has not been sufficient to satisfy the Kaiser's animosity. So on one occasion when they refused to rise and cheer him, in response to a de- mand, the Kaiser had introduced, through his Chancellor, a bill to permit the crim- inal prosecution of these delegates. To 1 8 The Psychology of the Kaiser its credit, be it said, the majority refused to permit this encroachment upon its rights. It is safe to say that such a criminal law as lese-majeste and its abuse for po- litical purposes in England would cost the King his crown. To this antipathy of the Kaiser may also be traced in large part responsibility for the consolidation of the autocratic and military party in Germany. For, by suppressing the political power of the only militant party that has opposed this autocracy, the Kaiser has been enabled to solidify his power and intrench him- self with his army as the dominating po- litical force which has determined the foreign policies of the empire. It is safe to say that if the democracy had been in power, or if the constitutional system of government had been such that The Psychology of the Kaiser 19 the Social Democratic Party, in and out of the Reichstag, could have made its in- fluence felt, the foreign and military poli- cies and methods of the Government would have been far different and there would have been no war. Germanism and Pan-Germanism would not have threatened the world.* * Surprise has been expressed that the Social Demo- crats, in view of their avowed principles and their plat- form, did not in the beginning throw their influence against the war, but are patriotically supporting the government. In other words, that there is a United Fatherland. There is no question that the Social Demo- crats were bitterly opposed to this war and yet they cast their 111 votes in the Reichstag unanimously in favor of the war budget, but it was after war had been declared by the Upper House and the Emperor. This seems on the face of the facts a complete re- versal of the Party policy and yet it is easily under- stood. The Social Democrats, though opposed to militarism and war, are first and all the time patriots. They have always declared that if the Fatherland were at- tacked they would rally to its defense, and all the world knows that the German people as a whole have been made to believe that the Fatherland was attacked. In 1907 Bebel, then leader of the Party, declared in 20 The Psychology of the Kaiser More than this, it is impossible, I be- lieve, for any one to study the internal a debate in the Reichstag that if the Fatherland were attacked even he, in his old age, would "shoulder a mus- ket" in its defense. And in the next Party Convention he declared: "I said, if the Fatherland really must be defended, then we will defend it. Because it is our Father- land. It is the land in which we live, whose lan- guage we speak, whose culture we possess. Because we wish to make this, our Fatherland, more beauti- ful and more complete than any other land on earth. We defend it, therefore, not for you but against you." Likewise Von Vollmar later said in the Bavarian Diet: "If the necessity should arise for the protection of the realm against foreign invasion, thtn it will become evident that the Social Democrats love their Fatherland no less than do their neighbors; that they will as gladly and heroically offer themselves, to its defense. On the other hand, if the foolish notion should ever arise to use the army for the sup- port of a warring class prerogative, for the defense of indefeasible demands, and for the crushing of those just ambitions which are the product of our times, and a necessary concomitant of our economic and political development, — then we are of the firm con- viction that the day will come when the army will remember that it sprang from the people, and that its own interests are those of the masses." The Psychology of the Kaiser 21 politics of Germany without arriving at the firm conviction that the elimination As S. P. Orth, from whose work I take these quota- tions, says, "This makes their position very clear." When war was declared the position which the Social Democrats were obliged to take was also clear. It was not a question of opposing the war. As Patrick Henry declared, in his famous speech at the beginning of our own Revolution, "Gentlemen may cry 'Peace! Peace!' But there is no Peace. The war has actually begun." And so with the Social Democrats, it was only a ques- tion of voting supplies. The Social Democrats dis- claimed all responsibility for the war. As Deputy Haase said in the Reichstag in explanation of the vote of his colleagues : "The responsibility for this calamity falls upon those who are responsible for the imperial policies that led to it. We absolutely decline all responsi- bility. The Social Democrats fought this policy with all their might. At this moment, however, the question before us is not war, or no war. The war is here. The question now is one of defence of the country. Our nation and the future of its liberty are jeopardized by a possible victory of Russian despotism, the hands of which are stained with blood of the best of its own nation. Against this danger it is our duty to secure the culture and in- dependence of our land." And the Vorwaerts, the official organ of the Social Democrats, on July 30th, just before the declaration of war, announced: 22 The Psychology of the Kaiser of German militarism, for which the war is being waged, and therefore the hope "We are opposed to militarism, and we reaffirm our opposition to monarchism, to which we have al- ways been opposed, and always will be. We have been compelled from the first to lead a bitter strug- gle against the temperamental wearer of the crown. We recognize, however, and we have stated it re- peatedly, that William II. has proved himself to be a sincere friend of peace among the nations, particularly in later years. . . . But even the strongest character is not entirely free from influ- ence, and we regret to say that proofs are accumu- lating in abundance that the clique of war shouters have been at work again to influence the govern- ment in favor of the devastation of the whole of Europe. . . . "In England it is the general opinion that the German Kaiser in his capacity as the ally and ad- viser of Austria was the arbiter in this trouble and had it in his power to let peace or war fall from the folds of his royal robes. And England is right. As conditions are, William II. has the decision in his hands." It will thus be seen that although the Social Demo- crats feel that the Kaiser and the military party are to blame for the war, they also necessarily feel that as patriots they must support the Fatherland as would be the case with any party in any country. But it also follows that if the Democracy had been in control of the government of Germany there would have been no war. The Psychology of the Kaiser 23 of permanent world's peace, must rest upon the German Democratic Party. From this viewpoint, the study of the Kaiser's antipathy for the Social Demo- crats offers a most fruitful psychological study. Why, then, I repeat, so much feeling when the Kaiser thinks of the Social Democratic Party? Why such hatred of it? Why such anger? Why such a per- sonal attitude? To explain it on the ground of differ- ences in political principles, as a politi- cal antipathy intensely expressed in terms of an intense emotional personality, is a superficial and inadequate psychological explanation, although it is commonly satisfying as a political explanation. The two are not synonymous. The reasons for this distinction will appear as we pro- ceed. 24 The Psychology of the Kaiser If the party represented only a small band of criminal agitators, of militant anarchists, let us say, who sought by as- sassination and terrorism to destroy the existing Government, such an attitude of mind would be easily comprehensible and would need no analysis. But the So- cial Democratic Party in 1888, on the accession of William II., on the basis of one voter in every five of the population, represented less than 4,000,000 subjects, and in 19 12 over 21,000,000, a third of the total population.* It is, therefore, * The steady growth of the Social Democratic Party has been phenomenal and is of importance in the bearing it has upon the future. In 1871 the party cast only 124,000 votes and from that time to 1912 there has been an almost continuous increase, as may be seen from the following table: 1871 124,000 1874 352,000 1877 493,000 1878 437,000 1881 312,000 1884 550,000 The Psychology of the Kaiser 25 representative of a large part of the pub- lic opinion of the empire, and, above all, of the working classes. Indeed, it is the largest political party in the empire. Criminal agitation is, therefore, out of the question. In other countries political feeling in times of crises often runs high, and at times statesmen, rulers, leaders of politi- cal parties generally, have strong political bias and feel intensely hostile to their po- litical opponents ; but they do not regard them as foes of their country, and God, and religion, to be crushed by every force in the power of the Government; and they rarely carry their hostility, and anger, 1887 763,000 1890 1,427,000 1893 1,787,000 1898 2,107,000 1903 3,011,000 1907 3,259,000 1912 4,250,000 26 The Psychology of the Kaiser and hatred into social and industrial life, as has been the case with the German Emperor. Furthermore, the persistency of the Emperor's antipathy is remarkable. It is like an obsession. He has retained, un- diminished, his hatred of the Social Democrats from his accession to the out- break of the war, and has never ceased to angrily stigmatize them with such emo- tional epithets as I have cited. Now it is probable, owing to a psycho- logical law, that when strong emotion, out of all apparent proportion to the cause, is excited by some object, that ob- ject has struck some sentiment, a "com- plex" of ideas and emotions deeply rooted in the personality, but not squarely ad- mitted and faced by consciousness. Ex- amples of this we see every day. A strong protectionist inveighs with The Psychology of the Kaiser 27 intense anger against the principle of free trade and the political party that advo- cates this principle in its platform. The reason he consciously gives is the eco- nomic disadvantage which, he appre- hends, will result to the country at large. But though this may be the reason, or rather one reason for his political opin- ion, it is not the real reason for his emo- tion — his anger and his invectives. These are due to the fact that the free- trade doctrine strikes a chord within him which resonates with selfish fear for his own business interests, and the reaction of this chord is anger. In other words, to use a homely phrase, while apparently speaking from the viewpoint of political principles, he is really "talking out of his pocket." But he does not squarely face and perhaps is only half conscious or en- tirely unconscious of this fact. This 28 The Psychology of the Kaiser selfish viewpoint is his "unconscious at- titude of mind." Now, is the Kaiser's antipathy to the Social Democrats merely the expression of an academic disbelief in Marxian principles of Socialism and a disbelief in the practicability of such principles if applied by the State to political govern- ment? Or are these only ostensible rea- sons for his antipathy? If the latter, a study of the Kaiser's mind ought to re- veal deep-rooted sentiments of another kind which will explain his emotional reaction. But in that case, for a complete explanation, we must inquire what there is that is peculiar in the political tenets of the Social Democracy that touches these sentiments and excites the reaction. In other words, it is a question of the Why. These questions rise above a banal cu- The Psychology of the Kaiser 29 riosity to inquire into a peculiar personal dislike of an Emperor, however that might be justified by the exalted world- position which he occupies. They are important in that, if pursued, they may lead to a deeper understanding of his personality, and they may unfold both his viewpoint of government as exempli- fied by the German system and the an- tagonistic viewpoint of the German De- mocracy, which for many years has been striving against the power of the Em- peror to force its ideals and aspirations upon the autocracy that rules Ger- many. All these questions are involved in the psychology of the personality of the Kaiser. The political questions are in- volved, for no personality can be under- stood apart from its environment to which it reacts, and which is largely re- 30 The Psychology of the Kaiser sponsible for the formation of "senti- ments." The sentiments are of prime and fun- damental importance in the formation of a personality. I use the term "senti- ments" in a restricted psychological sense and not in accordance with popular usage. I shall have occasion later to ex- plain how sentiments are formed after we have become acquainted with some of the Kaiser's mental attitudes. Meanwhile I would simply explain in justification of this inquiry, that charac- ter depends upon the psycho-physiologi- cal organization of ideas, derived in the broadest sense from life's experiences, with the innate primitive instinctive dis- positions to behave or react to given situ- ations (i. e., to react to the environ- ment). Thus, on the one hand, sentiments are The Psychology of the Kaiser 31 formed which characterize our attitude toward life, including therein our per- sonal, social, political, and industrial re- lations to the world about us ; and, on the other, the inborn natural instincts of man are harnessed, controlled, and repressed, or cultivated and given free rein. Upon the development of sentiments, therefore, not only the behavior of the individual depends, but the whole social organiza- tion. Of course, in a brief article of this kind we shall be obliged to limit our- selves to a few of the sentiments involved in the questions placed before us and therefore to a very limited study of the Kaiser's personality. II THE KAISER'S PREROGATIVES ET us go back to the year 1888, -■— ' when the Kaiser came to the throne. In his very first speech to the Prussian Diet he proclaimed with noticeable em- phasis that he was "firmly resolved to maintain intact and guard from all en- croachment the chartered prerogatives of the Crown." (The Kaiser, edited by Asa Don Dickenson, page 113.) It was noticed that he laid marked stress on these words, so that it was publicly com- mented upon by those who heard him. This intention to defend his prerogatives the Kaiser has consistently maintained ever since, and more than once has pro- claimed. What are the "prerogatives" 32 The Psychology of the Kaiser 33 about which the Kaiser took the very first opportunity to warn Germany and about which he has been so tenacious? They can be briefly stated. In the first place, we must know it is the Kaiser's prerogative not to be respon- sible to the people or to Parliament, but only to himself. He does not derive his power from either, but he reigns by his own right. This is his prerogative. Fur- thermore, he not only reigns, but it is his prerogative to govern. The King of England reigns, but, as has so often been said, he does not govern. In England the responsibility for governing rest? en- tirely with the Ministry, which in prin- ciple is only a select committee of Par- liament. It is the English Parliament, therefore, and practically the elected House of Commons that governs. In the second place it is the Kaiser's 34 The Psychology of the Kaiser prerogative to appoint a Chancellor to help him govern. He has no Cabinet, nor Board of Advisors. The Chancellor is responsible only to the Emperor. Par- liament may be entirely opposed to him, but in such case he does not necessarily resign, as would the British Prime Min- ister, nor is it the customary usage. He may not have been a member of Parlia- ment when appointed. The Kaiser alone may dismiss him, as he dismissed Bis- marck. The Emperor may disregard him and his advice, if he likes ; so that in prac- tice he may be his own Chancellor, as it is commonly said in Germany he has been ever since Bismarck's dismissal and as Bismarck foretold would be the case. A third prerogative is to appoint the Ministers, the heads of the great depart- ments — Navy, Foreign Affairs, Colonies, &c, who are under the Chancellor. The Psychology of the Kaiser 35 Thus all executive power resides in the Kaiser. Parliament has none. We may say it is the Kaiser's prerogative to be the administration. A fourth prerogative is to be Com- mander in Chief of the Army and to have absolute authority over the forces of the army both in peace and in war. (Art. 63 of the Constitution.) It is his pre- rogative to "determine the numerical strength, the organization, and the di- visional contingents of the imperial army"; also to appoint all superior of- ficers. (Art. 64.) That the Kaiser re- gards this as one of his most cherished prerogatives the world well knows. A fifth and exceedingly powerful pre- rogative is to appoint and control the seventeen members of the upper house — the Bundesrath, or Federal Council — the most powerful upper house in the world. 36 The Psychology of the Kaiser The Kaiser thus has the votes — only fourteen being required — to defeat any amendment to the Constitution, and in practice he has always controlled a ma- jority of the Council, which has been the creature of the Kaiser throughout its history. With the consent of the Council he can declare war, but, as the Council is a lady of easy consent, this limitation need not bear hardly and the wooing need be but short and light. A sixth prerogative is to initiate all legislation, although indirectly, through his controlled Federal Council, of which the Chancellor is President. The lower house, the Reichstag, elected by the peo- ple, cannot initiate legislation, so well did Bismarck fix the Constitution for the ben- efit of Prussia and the Kaiser. All measures must originate in the up- per house, which can also veto them The Psychology of the Kaiser 37 when amended in the Reichstag, and can dissolve the latter (with the Kaiser's con- sent) if it doesn't like its ways. (Think of the House of Lords dissolving the Commons!) The Kaiser has thus very- great power in controlling legislation. (With almost innumerable parties, none of which has a majority, in the House, log-rolling under an astute Chancellor has been raised to a fine art that would make an American State Legislature blush like a neophyte.) The Reichstag, however, can refuse to vote supplies and to pass measures fa- vored by the Kaiser. The elected repre- sentatives of the people can thus talk, resolve and criticise, and refuse to follow the Kaiser and thus create a public opinion which he may or may not dare to oppose, but they can do little more. Ill THE KAISER'S DIVINE RIGHT DELUSION T? INALLY, the Kaiser claims that his -*- prerogative to govern is derived from God, granted by the Almighty to his house, the house of Hohenzollern. This is far from being meant as a figure of speech or mere rhetoric, or an allegori- cal expression of religious responsibility for duties to be performed. It is a deep, all-abiding belief and principle of ac- tion. It is difficult for us Americans of the twentieth century fully to grasp this be- lief in a present-day man of boasted cul- ture, from whom we expect common sense. We may laugh at it, but in its 38 The Psychology of the Kaiser 39 practical consequences it is no laughing matter. It is fundamental to the Kai- ser's viewpoint and to an understanding of his attitude toward his subjects and the world. Another sovereign derives his right to reign, if not to govern, from the Constitution of his country, which means in the last analysis by contract with his people. But the German Emperor refuses to acknowledge any responsibility to the people, or any dependence upon the peo- ple, or the Constitution, or contract, for his right to govern. He derives this right directly from God. Whatever rights and powers the people possess descend from the Kaiser, who grants them through the Constitution; the rights and powers of the Kaiser do not ascend from the people, as in a democracy. The concentration of irresponsible 4-0 The Psychology of the Kaiser hereditary power in one man and those appointed by him is plainly an autoc- racy. "The Divine right of Kings to rule" is a doctrine dating back to the Middle Ages, and is by Americans naively supposed to have ended nearly a century ago with the dissolution of the "Holy Alliance," whose designs upon South America gave rise to our Monroe Doctrine in 1823. This doctrine of Divine right, then, is one of the prerogatives, if not in his mind the great prerogative, which the Kaiser announced he was resolved to de- fend. And it does not belong to the pres- ent Kaiser alone, but was possessed, as he claims, by his long line of ancestors of the House of Hohenzollern, and will descend to his successors of this house. It is the prerogative of his house. Thus he announced : The Psychology of the Kaiser 41 It is the tradition of our house that we, the Hohenzollerns, regard ourselves as appoint- ed by God to govern and to lead the people whom it is given us to rule, for their well- being and the advancement of their material and intellectual interests. And again: I look upon the people and nation handed on to me as a responsibility conferred upon me by God: and that it is, as is written in the Bible, my duty to increase this heritage, for which one day I shall be called upon to give an account; those who try to interfere with my task I shall crush. And again: I regard my whole position as given to me direct from heaven, and that I have been called by the Highest to do His work, by One to Whom I must one day render an account. 42 The Psychology of the Kaiser This claim as German Emperor, or as King of Prussia, has been announced again and again by the Kaiser, and his words have been quoted by the press, by magazine writers and pamphleteers and bookmakers unto weariness of the reader. The prerogatives we have briefly sum- marized are imperial, but be it noted they are double-headed in that — mutatis mutandis — they also belong to William II. as King of Prussia so far as the con- stitutional relations of the kingdom to the empire make them applicable. The odd notion of Divine right the Kaiser picked up from his grandfather, William I., who, when he was crowned King of Prussia at Konigsberg, to show he was above the Constitution which his predecessor had granted the people, raised with his own hands the crown from the altar, "set it on his own head, The Psychology of the Kaiser 43 and announced in a loud voice, 'I receive this crown from God's hand and from none other.' " And, referring to this historical inci- dent, the present Kaiser, William II., in a speech, now historic, at the same place, said: And here my grandfather, again, by his own right, set the Prussian crown upon his head, once more distinctly emphasizing the fact that it was accorded him by the will of God alone, and not by Parliament or by any assemblage of the people or by popular vote, and that he thus looked upon himself as the chosen instrument of Heaven, and as such performed his duties as regent and sovereign. From a psychological point of view, it does not matter — any more than it sig- nified anything to the Kaiser and his grandfather— that, as a matter of fact, 44 The Psychology of the Kaiser the first ruling Hohenzollern of Bran- denburg, Elector Frederick I., acquired his title to the Electorate by taking from King Sigismund of Hungary, in 141 1, a mortgage on the province (the nucleus of modern Prussia) as security for a loan to that hard-up potentate of about one hundred thousand gulden. A little later he foreclosed the mortgage and took title — a rather poor title at that, as there was already a mortgage on the property which it was convenient for Sigismund to repu- diate. Perhaps royal second mortgages — like marriages — are made in Heaven, and thus they become "Divine Rights." * What does psychologically matter is that the present Kaiser has persuaded himself, forgetting all about this business transaction, that his early Hohenzollern *In 1701 Elector Frederick III. took the title of (first) King of Prussia as Frederick I. The Psychology of the Kaiser 45 Shylock (in foreclosing the mortgage) "felt within himself the call to journey to this land" of Brandenburg — plainly a Divine call — and "was convinced that the task [of governing] was given him from above." (Kaiser's speech, Feb. 3, 1899.) What counts psychologically is that the Kaiser believes that a Divine right to rule is his prerogative. How, in this age, a man who has shown such marked ability in certain directions can be such a fool — I mean psychologically, of course — as to persuade himself to believe such stuff, is another story that would make an interesting psychological study in itself, and in the last analysis could probably be traced to subconscious wishes which have produced this con- scious delusion, just as such subconscious processes determine the delusions of in- sane people. 46 The Psychology of the Kaiser Our conscious thoughts are much more determined by subconscious processes, of which we are unaware, than we realize. One great popular delusion is that our minds are more exact logical instruments than they really are, and we stand in awe of the minds of great men, thinking that because they are superior in certain direc- tions, therefore they are superior in all other directions of their activities where they claim superiority; whereas, as a mat- ter of fact, a man may be eminently supe- rior in certain fields of mental activity and psychologically a perfect fool-thinker and fool-performer in other fields. Helmholtz said of the eye that it was such an imperfect optical instrument that if an instrument maker should send him an optical instrument so badly made he would refuse to accept it and return it forthwith. He might have said the The Psychology of the Kaiser 47 same thing of the human mind. It is a very imperfect instrument of thought. All we can say of it is, that though a poor thing, it is the best we can get. The deeper insight we get into the mechanism of the human mind, the poorer thing it appears as an instrument of precision. This Divine Right delusion is psy- chologically interesting in that it very closely resembles and behaves like the delusions characteristic of the mental dis- ease paranoia. This is not to say — indeed it would be absurd to say as some have said — that the Kaiser is afflicted with paranoia. But it is true that in normal people we find the prototypes of mental processes observed in abnormal mental conditions. The essential characteristic of paranoia is a systematized delusion: that is, some belief into which all sorts of facts of the environment are interwoven and 48 The Psychology of the Kaiser through which such events, casual actions of other people and their motives are in- terpreted. Thus, an insane person may imagine he is the object of persecution and then proceed to interpret any kind of act of others, really unrelated to himself, through this belief, imagining that it is directed towards the end of persecuting him. Or a paranoiac may imagine that he is the divine emissary of God and then interpret one hundred and one everyday events of life as divine messages to him- self. In normal people we see the prototype of such a delusion in the form of a mildly fixed idea which leads a person to wrongly interpret other people's motives and acts. You may say, if you like, that he believes such and such a thing because he wishes to, or because of some firmly fixed belief through which he interprets The Psychology of the Kaiser 49 it. The difference between the normal and abnormal person is that the former can, if he desires and the truth is properly presented, change his belief; the abnor- mal person cannot. It would be an extravagance to say that the Kaiser's delusion is anything more than a normal fixed idea which he could change if he wished to. But this fixed idea is so strong, so deeply rooted in his personality, and so directly the ex- pression of a cherished and cultivated wish, conscious or subconscious, that it dominates his interpretation of facts which to an ordinary person flatly contra- dict it. It leads him to entirely ignore both palpable facts, such as the purchase with cold cash, by his ancestor, of the throne, or more exactly, electorate of Brandenburg, and universally accepted understandings of the relation of God to 50 The Psychology of the Kaiser the worldly affairs of men — so universally accepted that they have passed into the common-sense of mankind. We may say, paraphrasing the words of a subconscious personality known as "Sally" in a case of multiple personality describing the at- titude of mind of one of her other selves: "There are so many things he cannot or will not see. He holds to certain beliefs and ideas with unwearying patience. It makes no difference that the facts are all against him. He still ignores the facts, still idealizes himself and his preroga- tives." The Kaiser's fixed idea is, according to psychological laws, determined by wishes — his wish to be sole and autocratic ruler of Prussia and the Empire, his wish to be the sole arbiter and director of the imperial destinies, his wish, "considering himself the instrument of the Lord, with- The Psychology of the Kaiser 51 out heeding the views and opinions" and will of his subjects to "go his way"; his wish to decide everything, like a patri- arch for the people, and to treat them like children; his wish to be looked up to as the supreme power — all these desires de- termine in him the belief that he is the "anointed of the Lord," a ruler by Divine authority. For only by such authority could he logically find justification for the assumption of such powers and the fulfillment of his desires. In other words, through the acceptance of the Divine Right Delusion he finds a means for the fulfillment of his wishes. And curiously enough, but still according to psycholog- ical laws, this fixed idea with its powerful instinct of self-assertion has awakened in his junker and militaristic supporters sentiments of self-abasement through which they yield submissively to this as- 52 The Psychology of the Kaiser sumed prerogative of the Kaiser and adopt an attitude of Divinity Worship. Thus we have a politico-religious cult in which the Kaiser is the Godhead. And thus we have wishes conscious and sub- conscious, but working subconsciously, making a fool — psychologically speaking — of the Kaiser. The most curious part of this whole Di- vine Right business is that in Germany, with all its "Kultur," there has been scarcely one single voice among all the people of Germany publicly to deny this claim, excepting the voice of the Social Democracy; or if there has, it has been like a voice crying in the wilderness — or perhaps from behind prison bars, where such rashness brought the prisoner, con- demned under the feudal law of lese-ma- jeste. We shall presently see what the German democracy thinks about it. IV THE GERMAN AUTOCRACY AND THE ARMY THE practical upshot of this whole German system of government, in which imperial prerogatives and an im- potent opera bouffe Reichstag are essen- tial ingredients, is that the Kaiser with his Chancellor and the Ministers of the several departments (Foreign Affairs, Navy, Post Office, &c), a bureaucracy responsible only to the Kaiser, constitute an autocracy independent of Parliament and the voters. Consequently the Gov- ernment is intended to be and is for the State, by the State, not of the people, by the people. The Kaiser's point of view as to his 53 54 The Psychology of the Kaiser own place in the State is shown by some of his sayings : "There is only one master in this country — I am he and I will not tolerate another." "There is no law but my law; there is no will but my will," he told his soldiers, and, "The King's will is the highest law," he wrote in the Golden Book of Munich. And so, as a German Professor, Lud- wig Gurlitt, has said: He regards his people, the masses, as chil- dren not yet of age, and thinks the Govern- ment competent to prescribe the course of their social and cultural development — a pro- found and fatal mistake ... a mediaeval idea ! Autocracy makes for efficiency, but it also makes for the suppression of the as- pirations of the people and self-govern- ment. But if the Kaiser, the bureau- The Psychology of the Kaiser 55 cracy, and an emasculated Parliament were the whole system of government, au- tocracy would be incomplete. The sys- tem would crumble away as by an earth- quake when democracy became success- ful at the polls. The system, therefore, must be sup- ported by power of some kind. Without power behind the throne, or behind any government, autocratic, monarchical, or republican, that government would fall at the first shock of internal conflict. In a real republic that power is the will of the people — commonly called public opinion. But we have seen that the Ger- man system does not rest upon public opinion. Upon what, then? William II., indeed, as the "instrument of the Lord," has flaunted his own defiance of public sentiment. Five years ago he said: 56 The Psychology of the Kaiser Considering myself as the instrument of the Lord, and without heeding the views and opinions of the day, I go my way. Behind the German autocracy is the army, under the absolute control of the Kaiser. Upon the army the Kaiser de- pends for the security of his rule. The army is the power behind the throne. As one writer remarks: "The army is the foundation of the social structure of the empire. " The Kaiser, on one occasion, declared: With grave anxiety I placed the crown upon my head. Everywhere I met doubt, and the whole world misjudged me. But one had confidence in me; but one believed in me — that was the army. And relying upon the army, and trusting in God, I began my reign, knowing well that the army is the The Psychology of the Kaiser 57 main tower of strength for my country, the main pillar supporting the Prussian throne, to which God in His wisdom had called me. He said in 1891 : The soldier and the army, not parliamen- tary majorities and decisions, have welded together the German Empire. My confi- dence is in the army — as my grandfather said at Coblenz : "These are the gentlemen on whom I can rely." And again, asserting his belief in mili- tary force as the means upon which the empire must rely to accomplish its ends at home and abroad, he quoted the say- ing of Frederick William I. : If one wishes to decide something in this world, it is not the pen alone that will do it if unsupported by the power of the sword. 58 The Psychology of the Kaiser In his first official act as Emperor, (June 15, 1888,) he declared: The absolutely inviolable dependence upon the war lord (Kriegsherr) is, in the army, the inheritance which descends from father to son, from generation to generation. . . . So we are bound together, I and the army. Thus we are born for one another, and thus we will hold together in an indissoluble bond, in peace or storm, as God wills. This close connection between the army and the Prussian Kings, as Profes- sor Gauss points out, is a tradition which William II. has sedulously maintained, just as we have seen he has maintained the traditions of a Divine right to rule. THE KAISER'S SENTIMENTS WITH the meaning of all these pre- rogatives in mind, let us look a bit more closely into the psychology of the Kaiser. In doing so let us bear in mind that in the doctrine of Divine right we see developed in the Kaiser a strong sentiment of the most personal kind, of birthright, of self-interest. And, be- sides this, in all the other prerogatives which the Kaiser has so defiantly re- solved to defend against all encroach- ments, we also have sentiments of self- interest — sentiments of possession, of rights pertaining to self. All these sentiments are bound up with 59 60 The Psychology of the Kaiser a consciousness of his own personality (a "self-regarding" sentiment), with his ego. And there is a great deal of ego, of consciousness of his ego, in his personality. Perhaps his enemies would say, as was said of the great orang-utan, Bimi, in Kipling's tale — Bimi, who also wished to crush his enemies in furious outbursts of jealous rage — "there is too much ego in his cosmos." Now, as a matter of psychology, "senti- ments," as I have already said, are of tre- mendous importance as factors in per- sonality and as forces which determine attitudes of mind, reactions of the per- sonality to the environment and conduct. Upon the formation of "sentiments" the character of a person and his social behavior fundamentally depend. And by the formation of sentiments in the course of the individual's mental development The Psychology of the Kaiser 61 the primitive innate instincts of human nature are harnessed and brought under control and their impulses given proper direction. Thus these primitive impulses are repressed or cultivated according to the ideals of society. Otherwise, driven by the impulses of our innate instincts, we should all run amuck through society. We must understand, then, a little more precisely what, psychologically and technically speaking, a sentiment is. I am not using the word in the popular sense. Without going into the psychol- ogy deeply, we may say that a sentiment is an idea of something, as its object, or- ganized or associated with one or more instinctive emotions which give the idea impulsive force. In the personality of every human being — and the same is true of animals — there are a number of emotional instincts. 62 The Psychology of the Kaiser These instincts are characterized by a particular emotion which each possesses, and may be named indifferently, for our present purposes, either after the emotion itself or after the biological aim which the instinct serves. Every person, for instance, possesses a pugnacity instinct of which the emotion is anger. Other such instincts are fear, parental feeling, disgust, curiosity, self- assertion, self-abasement, reproduction, and so on. All such instincts have a bio- logical function in that they serve either to protect, like anger and fear, the indi- vidual (and the species) from danger against its enemies and prevent its ex- tinction, or, like the parental and repro- ductive instincts, serve to perpetuate the species, or like the curiosity instinct, to acquire knowledge and learn by experi- ence, and so on. Emotion, as the very The Psychology of the Kaiser 63 word itself indicates, moves us — i. e., it is a force that impels toward some end and the emotion of each instinct carries it to fulfillment. When an emotion — i. e., instinct — has been excited by some object, whether it be a material thing, like a snake, or an- other person, or something mental — an idea of a material object, or a thought as of a possible danger to the individual, or of a political principle — the emotion may become so associated with and bound to the object that whenever the object is presented in consciousness the emotion is excited. This particularly happens when the emotion has been frequently excited by the same object. Thus a person may acquire a fear of snakes, or thunderstorms, or hatred of a person. Two or more emotional instincts may be organized in this way 64 The Psychology of the Kaiser into a system about a given idea as their object. Now, when an idea always excites one or more emotions, so that the idea is al- ways accompanied by the same emotional reaction, the whole is called a sentiment. Thus we have the sentiment of love of a mother for her child, of hatred of a tyrant, of disgust for a vicious person, of pride of self, and so on. Practically, psychological analysis shows that the organization of a senti- ment is more complicated than such a simple arrangement would make it, and that the sentiment is deeply and widely rooted in a number of ramifying, pre- vious mental experiences and innate emo- tions. This is expressed by popular lan- guage when we say a given sentiment is deeply rooted in a person's personality. The emotions serve to give their ideas The Psychology of the Kaiser 65 great intensity and driving force for ac- tion. It is held by some psychologists that a sentiment always includes innately organ- ized systems of several emotions so that a different emotion is necessarily excited according to the situation in which the object presents itself. Thus a hated per- son will awaken in us joy, or sorrow, or anger, or fear, according to whether he suffers injury, or escapes destruction, or prospers, or is likely to get the better of us. In accordance with this view a senti- ment is an organized system of emotions centred about an idea of an object. The mechanism, as I have stated it, however, is sufficiently accurate for our purpose. With these general principles in mind, one has only to read the Kaiser's speeches to recognize that his ideas of himself and 66 The Psychology of the Kaiser of his prerogatives, which he jealously defends, are organized with instinctive emotions of great intensity — emotions be- longing to greed of possession, and pride, and self-assertion, (or self-display,) and pugnacity, and vengeful emotion, and jealousy. These ideas are therefore sen- timents deeply fixed and organized in his personality, and given great driving force by their emotions, which tend to carry them to activity and fruition. Hence it is that the Kaiser's sentiments of himself and his prerogatives exhibit great intensity of feeling and determine his conduct to assert his rights and to ex- ercise and enjoy them by being his own Chancellor and ruling the army and em- pire, and, if need be, to defend them most vigorously. VI THE KAISER'S SELF-REGARDING SENTI- MENT T3 UT we must leave these traits of the ■*-J Kaiser's personality for the imme- diate issue of our study. One sentiment, however, ought to be considered more intimately if certain of his most notori- ous peculiarities are to be understood. I refer to what has been called the "self- regarding" sentiment. Every person possesses such a senti- ment, although it varies according to the ingredients that enter into it. Professor William McDougall, one of the most eminent of contemporary psychologists, has analyzed this sentiment, and at- 67 68 The Psychology of the Kaiser tributes it to the biological instincts of self-assertion and self-abasement com- pounded in varying proportions with the idea of self. (These instincts are com- mon to animals as well as men and have a biological end.) We thus get different types of self. When the first instinct of self-asser- tion — also called self-display — with its emotion of positive self-feeling is the chief instinct, then we have a type in which pride is the main characteristic of the idea of self. When the second in- stinct (with the emotion of negative self- feeling) is happily blended in the senti- ment, we have a type of self-respect. To illustrate the former type, Pro- fessor McDougall (Social Psychology) draws the character of an imaginary Prince in whom the first instinct is the dominating one. It is interesting to see The Psychology of the Kaiser 69 how perfectly his picture represents the Kaiser: Imagine the son of a powerful and foolish Prince to be endowed with great capacities and to have in great strength the instinct of self-display with its emotion of positive self- feeling. Suppose that he is never checked, or corrected, or criticised, but is allowed to lord it over all his fellow-creatures without restraint. The self-regarding sentiment of such a child would almost necessarily take the form of an unshakable pride, a pride constantly gratified by the attitudes of defer- ence, gratitude, and admiration of his social environment; the only dispositions that would become organized in this sentiment of pride would be those of positive self-feeling or elation and of anger (for his anger would be invariably excited when any one failed to assume toward him the attitude of subjection or deference). 70 The Psychology of the Kaiser His self-consciousness might be intense and very prominent, but it would remain poor in content; for he could make little progress in self-knowledge; he would have little occa- sion to hear, or to be interested in, the judg- ments of others upon himself; and he would seldom be led to reflect upon his own char- acter and conduct. The only influences that could moralize a man so endowed and so brought up would be either religious teach- ing, which might give him the sense of a power greater than himself to whom he was accountable, or a very strong natural en- dowment of the tender emotion and its al- truistic impulse, or a conjunction of these two influences. A man in whom the self-regarding senti- ment had assumed this form would be in- capable of being humbled — his pride could only be mortified; that is to say, any display of his own shortcomings or any demonstra- tion of the superiority of another to himself The Psychology of the Kaiser 71 could cause a painful check to his positive self-feeling and a consequent anger, but could give rise neither to shame nor to humilia- tion, nor to any affective state, such as ad- miration, gratitude, or reverence, in which negative self-feeling plays a part. And he would be indifferent to moral praise or blame; for the disposition of negative self- feeling would have no place in his self- regarding sentiment; and negative self-feel- ing, which renders us observant of the atti- tude of others toward ourselves and recep- tive toward their opinions, is one of the es- sential conditions of the influence of praise and blame upon us. The inordinate cultivation in the Kaiser of the self-regarding sentiment with the unalloyed instinct of self-dis- play also explains, psychologically, the manifestations of certain traits which have amazed the world. I mean his 72 The Psychology of the Kaiser colossal vanity as manifested by his fond- ness for dressing himself up in all sorts of uniforms and constantly changing his costumes — on occasions as often as five or six times in a single day, and even dur- ing the course of a Court reception — his fondness for having himself photo- graphed or painted, or his portrait made as busts, lithographs, medals, and bas-re- liefs, always posing in heroic attitudes for the purpose. It is interesting to compare the snap- shots of the Kaiser with the posed pho- tographs (there are thousands of photo- graphs of him), and not only as himself, but in the heroic character of a Roman Emperor mounted on a charger, and again in imitation of the Emperor Char- lemagne. It explains his self-assumption to be an artist — a painter, a musician, a composer, The Psychology of the Kaiser 73 an architect, an art critic, a preacher, and Heaven knows what else. It also gives a psychological explanation of his inability to stand personal criticism, and for his vain obtuseness in not being able to un- derstand how any one should not look upon him excepting with reverent awe. One of the authors of "The Kaiser" cites the following two incidents. One of his subjects had been sentenced to prison for hinting something disre- spectful about his sovereign: William was genuinely amazed that such an unnatural crime could ever have been com- mitted. He u read and reread the papers in the case with the closest attention"; and finally said to the waiting official : "It would seem that this man hitherto has not been a criminal — son of respectable parents, himself in a respectable walk of life, with a good 74 The Psychology of the Kaiser education. And yet — how do you explain this — this insult to the Anointed of the Lord? Strange! Strange!" On another occasion: After reading a speech of the Socialist leader Bebel, containing some animadver- sion upon himself, he turned to the officer in attendance with clouded brow and flash- ing eye, and remarked in a voice trembling with passion : u And all this to me ! To me ! What is the country coming to?" This self-regarding sentiment is also at the bottom of that dominating trait — love of power — which has led him to aspire to world power and to believe that with his army and with a stronger navy, toward the upbuilding of which he has directed untiringly his energies, he could conquer the world. It even led him to think of conquering the United States, for The Psychology of the Kaiser 75 when we were engaged in war with Spain he declared, as I have authority for say- ing, "If I had had a larger fleet I would have taken Uncle Sam by the scruff of the neck!' * * In a letter to the author, July 7, 1898, Joseph Cham- berlain, then Colonial Secretary of Great Britain, wrote: "Of course you will win, and will be able to dictate terms to Spain. The Continental Powers will not inter- fere because England will not join them. I am certain that if opinion here had been different to what it is, you would have had to face a European coalition. "A fortnight ago (do not quote me as the authority) the German Emperor said to a friend of mine, 'If I had had a larger fleet I would have taken Uncle Sam by the scruff of the neck' — and this represents the view of the older monarchies who begin to desire a Monroe Doc- trine for Europe. But, in view of the attitude of this country, they dare not move. "You are therefore free to work out your destiny." I have now been fully authorized to publish this letter. There is much other corroborative evidence, which is undoubtedly accessible, of this attempt to form a Euro- pean coalition against the United States and of its being blocked by England. (See letter of Mr. G. Creigh- ton Webb, in the New York Times, June 2, 1915.) In this connection the following statement in my possession giving a conversation between another member of the English Cabinet and the late Mr. F. W. Holls, formerly Judge of the First Hague Tribunal (and my informant's 76 The Psychology of the Kaiser That this saying of the Kaiser's meant more than a mere momentary ebullition of petulant feeling or a thoughtless boast becomes manifest when we bear in mind that it was made towards the end of June, 1898, after the arrival of Vice- Admiral von Diedrich and his fleet at Manila on June 12. It is significant that von Diedrich, when asked by Dewey why so large a German naval force — five ships, a more powerful force than that of the American fleet — was present, replied, "I am here by order of the Kaiser, sir," guardian), at least is of corroborative value. This Cabi- net officer (mentioned by name) said to Mr. Holls that during the Spanish-American war, the Continental Pow- ers had a plan to secure England's assent to interven- tion. One of the London ambassadors was appointed to sound him on the proposition, he being then Acting- Prime Minister. On being asked if intervention would meet with the views of Her Majesty's government, he said: "Intervention had indeed been considered, but — that the only form it could possibly take would be to place the fleet of Great Britain at the disposal of the President of the United States!" The Psychology of the Kaiser 77 and the same explanation has been given since. We know now that there was an attempt made to form a coalition of Con- tinental monarchies against the United States to intervene in the war in favor of Spain, but that it was blocked by Eng- land who, there is evidence to show, threatened to place her navy on the side of this country. Consequently Germany and the other Powers dared not move. As it was we came to the brink of war in July through the action of von Diedrich in in- terfering, after the battle of Manila, May 1, with the blockade by Dewey.* * It has come to light that events went so far that a German ship, it has been reported, cleared for action and Dewey, in the famous choleric interview (July 10) with the German Admiral's representative, Flag-Lieuten- ant v. Hintzer, threatened war if Germany wanted it. This part of the interview was thus reported to Mr. John Barrett by "one of the officers of the Olympia who heard the conversation": "If the German Government" (said Dewey) "has decided to make war on the United States, or has any intention of making war, and has so 78 The Psychology of the Kaiser The remark of the Kaiser that he "would have taken Uncle Sam by the scruff of the neck" must be taken in con- nection with all the events of the time and particularly with the attempt to form a European coalition against the United States which probably would have been successful had it not been for the action of England. And so this same self-regarding senti- ment, distorted and unbalanced, in co- operation with other sentiments, led him in 191 4 to have contempt for the other Powers and to believe that he had a strong enough army to terrify Russia and her ally, France, into submission, and so he gave Austria authority to take Servia "by the scruff of the neck" ; to feel, in case informed your Admiral, it is his duty to let me know. . . . But whether he intends to fight or not I am ready." (Admiral George Dewey, by John Barrett: 1899: p. 115). The Psychology of the Kaiser 79 the gleam of the "shining armour" and the clang of the rattling sabre did not suffice, that he had a strong enough army to take Russia "by the scruff of the neck," and so he declared war against that coun- try; to feel that he had a strong enough army to take France "by the scruff of the neck," and so he declared war against France; to feel that he had a strong enough army to take Belgium "by the scruff of the neck," and so he invaded that country with his army; and it led him more than twenty years ago to believe that some day he would have a strong enough navy to take England "by the scruff of the neck," and so he builded and builded his navy and drank to "Der Tag." Of course the Kaiser's hypertrophied and one-sided self-regarding sentiment was not the sole psychological factor in 80 The Psychology of the Kaiser determining his attitude of mind towards the United States and the other Powers. There were many factors, but it was one; and it accounts for his notorious con- tempt for other nations and at that time, particularly, for the United States. There were also sentiments of World- power and Empire, of German Kultur and War- Worship; a desire to have a "place in the sun," to possess colonies and, in particular, the Philippines and those of England and France; and to extend the German Empire to the iEgean Sea on the south and the North Sea on the north. The self-regarding sentiment, obvi- ously, has played also a large part in the Divine Right Delusion, ia cooperation with the wishes we have considered, form- ing a large ego-centric complex. Such, and other manifestations of the Kaiser's self-regarding sentiment, due to The Psychology of the Kaiser 81 the impulsive force of its highly devel- oped instinct of self-display, (self-asser- tion,) would make this element of his personality an interesting psychological study by itself. I merely wish now to point out that it is the extreme type of this sentiment that is responsible for many of his extravagances of speech and action, and that it plays a part, as we shall see, in his reactions to democracy. VII AIMS OF THE GERMAN DEMOCRACY NOW let us return to the Kaiser's hatred of democracy. This also is a sentiment organized with several emo- tional instincts, &c, which we need not bother about here. That he has a hatred of democracy is obvious. But why? To know that he has a hatred is not enough. We want it explained, to know why. It is not a sufficient explanation to say that he disbelieves in the princi- ples of democracy. That would not be sufficient to account for the develop- ment of the sentiment of hatred and for the reaction of anger which democracy 82 The Psychology of the Kaiser 83 excites. What created the hatred? For so much emotion there must be a deeper- lying cause — some hidden sentiment which, we may suspect, conflicts with the sentiments of his cherished prerogatives and his self-regarding sentiment. We want to know the Why. With this object let us consider the object of the hatred — the aims of the party of democ- racy, one of the great political forces in Prussia and the empire; one with which, as we have seen, the Emperor has been passionately in conflict since his acces- sion to the throne. We cannot under- stand the psychological reaction of the Emperor without understanding the aims and the potential power of this political force. For this purpose I shall have to ask the reader to bear for a moment with a slight digression, keeping in mind what has been said about the Kaiser's 84 The Psychology of the Kaiser sentiments until we return to our main theme. What does the Social Democratic Party stand for and in what respect are its aims antagonistic to the Emperor's prerogatives and the German system of government? The party is widely re- garded in the United States, I am con- strained to believe, as the party of so- cialism. But this idea needs consider- able modification. Indeed, so much so that the party would, if its aims were un- derstood, receive the moral support of Americans. Socialism has an ominous sound to American ears. The word has a stigma for many and is calculated to repel. At one time in its early history Marxian Socialism, formulated by Marx himself as "the social ownership of the means of production and distribution," was the The Psychology of the Kaiser 85 dominating aim of the German Socialist Party. But times have changed. The aims of the party have undergone various meta- morphoses as the result of conflicts of factions within, fusions and political evo- lution. Since the Kaiser came to the throne in 1888 a revolution has taken place in the aims, methods, tactics, and programs of the party. In accordance with this change, in 1890, the name was changed to the Social Democratic Party. Socialism has been relegated to the background and democracy has become the paramount aim and issue. In other words, the principles of the socialist, Marx, have given place to those of the brilliant democratic leader, Las- salle. Both men are dead, but democracy survives. As one authority (S. P. Orth) 86 The Psychology of the Kaiser puts it, "Marx is a tradition, democracy is an issue." Today one hears very little of Marx and a great deal of "legislation" based on democratic principles: The last election [19 12], with its brilliant victory for Social Democracy, was not won on the general issues of the Erfurter pro- gram, but on the particular issue of the ar- rogance of the bureaucracy and ballot re- form. Marxian propagandism has been sloughed off. But even if the Demo- cratic Party still stood for socialism as its paramount aim this fact would not necessarily make it antagonistic to the Emperor's prerogatives or the German system of government. The State might become engaged in all sorts of individ- ual enterprises without the fundamental The Psychology of the Kaiser 87 structure of Government becoming al- tered. As a matter of fact, Germany is today the most socialized nation in the world. We will not stop to inquire into the origin of this State Socialism. It does not matter for our purposes that these State socialistic measures were offered as a "bribe," to use Bismarck's term, to the Social Democrats to cease agitation against the government, and that the Em- peror long ago dropped this policy when he found that the Social Democrats would not be bribed. They would have none of these measures. They wanted political rights, political freedom of thought and speech, and the right to man- age their own government just as we do ours in the United States. The German State owns railroad, canal and river transportation, telegraph 88 The Psychology of the Kaiser and telephone systems, harbors and a par- cel post. It conducts banks, insurance, savings banks, and pawnshops. It ad- ministers sick and accident insurance and old-age pensions. The municipalities own public utilities of all kinds, theatres, markets, and warehouses. The State, or municipality, obviously might go further and administer iron, coal, and manufacturing enterprises; it might undertake all sorts of socialistic functions without altering one whit the prerogatives of the Crown, or of Par- liament, or of the relations of the Gov- ernment to the people. Governmental autocracy would still exist and very likely would administer these industrial enterprises with the same satisfying ef- ficiency with which it administers every- thing else it has taken hold of. The intense anger and hatred with The Psychology of the Kaiser 89 which the Emperor reacts to the Social Democrats cannot, therefore, be ex- plained by the principles of socialism per se, although he may disbelieve in ex- treme Marxian socialism. Even if these were still the aim of the party, there must be some other explanation that a Social Democrat should be stigmatized as an enemy of the empire, of religion and God, to be shot down by the army if his party became too strong. Let us examine then the demands as given in the latest program (1912) of the Social Democrats and some of the legislation for which they have fought. The demands are given in fourteen ar- ticles. Number one demands equal opportu- nities for all, special privileges to none — good American doctrine. Number two relates to reform of the ballot laws and 90 The Psychology of the Kaiser has been the main immediate issue. "Universal, direct, equal, secret ballot" is demanded — also American doctrine. Owing to the present inequality of the ballot the Democrats have been badly handicapped in that they cannot elect their proportionate number of repre- sentatives. Number three relates to the existing system of government. A true Parlia- mentary Government is demanded, and a Ministry, like that of England, responsi- ble to Parliament, instead of the present autocratic system by which the Ministry is responsible only to the Emperor. Also, it is demanded that "the power to declare war or maintain peace" be given to the lower house (Reichstag). Consent of the Reichstag to all State appropriations (as with the House of Commons and the American Congress). The Psychology of the Kaiser 91 Numbers four and five relate respec- tively to the organization of the army and reform of administrative justice, abolish- ing class privilege at law, &c. Number six demands the "right to combine, meet, and organize." Number seven relates to the establishment of a national Depart- ment of Labor, factory inspection, and a legalized universal eight-hour day, &c. Number eight relates to reform of the industrial insurance laws, and lowering the age of old-age pensions from 70 to 65, &c. Number nine: complete religious free- dom. Separation of Church and State. No support of any kind for religious pur- poses from public funds — good Ameri- can doctrine again. Number ten de- mands universal free schools. Number eleven relates to reform of taxation de- manding abolition of indirect taxes and 92 The Psychology of the Kaiser taxes on necessities of life and reduction of tariff on those schedules which encour- age trusts. Number twelve supports "measures that tend to develop commerce and trade." Number thirteen: "A graduated income, property and inheritance tax" in order to dampen "the ardor of the rich for a constantly increasing army and navy." Number fourteen: "Internal im- provements and colonization"; but the "cessation of foreign colonization now done for the purpose of exploiting for- eign peoples for the sake of gain." The first thing that will strike the reader is the absence of anything essen- tially socialistic in the principles formu- lated in this program. They are rather what we in this country would call "Re- publican," "Progressive," and "Demo- cratic." They are not nearly as social- The Psychology of the Kaiser 93 istic as many of the functions now under- taken by the German State. With the exception of those articles that relate ex- clusively to German conditions (such as numbers four and eight) and the aboli- tion of indirect taxation, they express good American doctrine and are, for the most part, axiomatic in this country. No American and no Englishman would see anything in them to get ex- cited about, although he might hold a different opinion about the expediency of one or the other demand. Undoubted- ly the spirit of German democracy goes further than the program, especially in particular parts of Germany; neverthe- less this program formulates the demands of the national party. Between the American Republic and German democracy there is, or should be, a bond of common sympathy, the bond of 94 The Psychology of the Kaiser common political ideals and common purpose — the love of political and reli- gious liberty, freedom of thought, free- dom of speech, and freedom of the press without fear of imprisonment or punish- ment under "lese-majeste" or any power of the State; the emancipation of man- kind from the tyranny of autocracy; the "right to life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness" according to the dictates of the individual conscience; the rule of the people and not of an autocracy, the sub- ordination of the State to the will of the people — and to this end government based not upon an army, but upon public opinion as expressed by the votes of the people. When these ideals and purposes of the German democracy are realized in the United States, American public opinion will have the strongest ties of sympathy The Psychology of the Kaiser 95 with the great masses of Germany, strug- gling for these ends against an intrenched "State." Between German democracy and American public sentiment there can be no conflict. It is only with the autocratic classes that there can be antagonism, but the autocratic classes mean the State as an artificially created entity isolated from and distinct from the masses of the peo- ple. Why, then, does the Emperor almost alone, even among Germans, react to the ideals of democracy with such pas- sion, such anger, and such hatred? On psychological grounds we can anticipate that such emotion must be for personal reasons and because they strike some in- tense emotional sentiment. We find the key to the puzzle when we come to examine Articles 3 and 4. Num- 96 The Psychology of the Kaiser ber three has been the paramount issue of the democracy — it is its foundation stone. Number two, the reform of the ballot, while the main political issue of the day, is only a means to this end. The fundamental issue is (1) a true Parliamentary Government, with parlia- mentary power in conformity with mod- ern democratic ideas, such as obtains in England; and (2) the abolition of a Chancellor and Ministry appointed by the Kaiser and responsible only to the Kaiser and the substitution of a Govern- ment responsible to Parliament. Thus the Government and the army would be responsible to the people and rest upon public opinion. This democratic principle seems to our ideas not only harmless enough, but a matter of course and only the expression of the age we live in. But to the Kai- The Psychology of the Kaiser 97 ser it means a personal cataclysm. It means the abolition of the greatest of the Kaiser's prerogatives; it means the denial of the Divine right of Kings; it means the downfall of the House of Hohenzol- lern, in that it means the reduction of the prerogatives of the house to reigning without governing. He could be no longer his own Chan- cellor, as he is recognized generally to be today in fact. His wings would be clipped. He would be shorn of auto- cratic power. He could no longer dic- tate policies of government. The will of the people would rule. What would be the use of a "Divine right" to sit as a social ornament upon a throne and watch the people rule? Furthermore, his "self-regarding sen- timent," characterized by the instinct of self-assertion and the emotion of pride, 98 The Psychology of the Kaiser would receive an unbearable rebuff. He would no longer be the central figure in Europe, overlording all other rulers by his personality, his autocratic power, and his prerogatives. The conflict between the Kaiser and the democracy thus be- comes a personal conflict on his part. VIII THE REAL CAUSE OF THE KAISER'S ANTIPATHY /FATHERING together the facts ^-* which we have collated, we have found in the Kaiser intensely strong senti- ments of his prerogatives, an almost ab- normal self-regarding sentiment, and a powerful, steadily growing political party acting in antagonism to those sen- timents and threatening in case of suc- cess to rob him of his prerogatives. Now, with these facts in mind, let us analyze the antecedent contents of the Kaiser's mind a little more intimately. If he has been a thinking being at all, we know, in view of the political and his- 99 ioo The Psychology of the Kaiser torical facts we have studied — any asser- tion to the contrary would meet with in- credulous skepticism — there have been thoughts, however fleeting, of what would happen to himself and his house if the democratic reforms should prevail; thoughts of being robbed of his preroga- tives, robbed of his power to rule the Kingdom of Prussia, to rule the Imperial Bundesrat by his power as King of Prussia, to rule the Reichstag through the Bundesrat; thoughts of being robbed of the prerogatives to be his own Chan- cellor, to appoint his own Ministry, to control the army, to be independent of Parliament and public opinion and the public will — in short, robbed of being an autocratic ruler of the Kingdom of Prus- sia and the German Empire by Divine right. And there has been a full realization The Psychology of the Kaiser 101 of the increasing power of democracy, steadily growing in numbers, and rising, swelling, year by year, like a great ir- resistible tidal wave, threatening sooner or later to carry all before it and over- whelm the system of autocracy. And against this growing avalanche of bal- lots of the democracy he sees no defense for himself save the army, and so he calls upon his soldiers to be prepared to "shoot down your own relatives, brothers, and even parents in the streets," when he shall give the word of command. Such thoughts and such realizations of future danger could not but excite the biological defensive instinct of fear. And this instinct, being associated with its ob- ject, the idea of democracy, forms a sen- timent, the fear of democracy. This sen- timent is further associated with or crys- tallized about other egoistic sentiments of 102 The Psychology of the Kaiser self and his House and his prerogatives. Hence it may be described as a fear of democracy because of the danger to him- self and his House of Hohenzollern, a fear of being deprived by the hands of the democracy of his prerogative to be an autocrat. It is a fear of democracy, not for Germany but for himself. He fears for his own life, so to speak, for, if you rob him of his prerogatives, do you not take away that which to him is his life? This does not mean that he is aware of this very personal egoistic or egocen- tric fear-sentiment. He undoubtedly would not admit it to others, nor is it likely that he could, even if he would, admit it to himself, because it has not been squarely faced, but has been thrust aside, repressed by the pride of his self- regarding sentiment and not allowed to The Psychology of the Kaiser 103 come to the full light of consciousness. Though not recognized by himself, it is there all the same, repressed into the sub- conscious, or, if you prefer, in the back- ground of the mind (which, after all, is a part of the subconscious). Repressed into the subconscious, it is there necessarily intimately systematized with, and has deep roots in, the many associated antecedent thoughts that, as we have seen, gave rise to it. So long as these so-called psycho-genetic thoughts are there unmodified — conserved also, like a phonographic record, in the sub- conscious — he could not get rid of his fixed fear of the democracy if he would. In this light his famous declaration of his prerogative, "I am the Supreme War Lord," receives deeper meaning when at the same time we remember he is the head of that autocracy that wields the 104 The Psychology of the Kaiser power. We can see into the background of his mind. He sees the danger, we see the fear. We see, too, in the background of his mind a realization of a growing democracy, and we find there upon what methods he relies if the German democ- racy should win at the polls and change the Constitution. To oppose the will of the people he has the army. And we see into his inner consciousness when he prepared (as already quoted) the minds of his young soldiers for "the day." IX THE KAISER'S ANTIPATHY AN OBSESSION AND A DEFENSE REACTION NOW let us go one step further. Al- though this egocentric sentiment of fear for himself and his dynasty is re- pressed into the subconscious, it is not for that reason inert and incapable of affect- ing his conscious processes. On the con- trary, as we are forced to believe from the result of psychological investigations into such conditions of personality, it de- termines many of his conscious processes of thought, of his political principles and his activities against his most dangerous political enemy. In the first place, it induces a defense 105 106 The Psychology of the Kaiser reaction of an intensely emotional char- acter which aims to direct his activities in a direction that will protect him against the dangers of democracy. This defense reaction is anger and the sentiment of hatred. It should be explained that psychologi- cal analysis of the emotions goes to show that the sentiment of hatred is made up of several emotions associated with its object, of at least fear and anger and vengeful emotions, which last also in- cludes anger besides that most conspicu- ous trait of the Kaiser — the self-regard- ing sentiment. The way the defense reaction comes into play is this: The instinctive emo- tions and their sentiments are awakened and recur from time to time whenever the subconscious egoistic sentiment or any of its associated psychogenetic The Psychology of the Kaiser 107 thoughts — those of his possible fall from power — is touched. The sentiments of fear he will not admit to himself, and they are repressed as such; but the fear- emotion appears in consciousness dis- guised as hatred, of which it is a compo- nent. Anger against and hatred of democracy he is prepared to admit. They are fully faced and rise into the full light of consciousness, although their real underlying cause is hidden. Such an intensely fixed emotional idea, (hatred,) recurring whenever its object is presented to consciousness, is, in prin- ciple, an obsession, although it may not be so beyond control as to be pathologi- cal. But, as in the Kaiser's case, it may be only the apparent obsession, i. e., a defense reaction to the real obsession hid- den in the subconscious. The Kaiser s real obsession is a subconscious phobia, a 108 The Psychology of the Kaiser fear of democracy for himself and his House. It is interesting to notice in this con- nection how the national hatred of one nation for another is recognized by pop- ular language as a phobia or fear. We speak of an Anglo-phobia, of a Russo- phobia, to describe the hatred of, let us say, Germany for England and Russia. Though the nation would not admit being afraid, nevertheless, by the very term employed, it is popularly recog- nized that the hatred is really though un- consciously the expression of a fear. In the case of the Kaiser's phobia of democracy, the impulsive forces of the biological instincts of pugnacity, (anger) , fear, self-assertion, &c, provide the en- ergy of the fighting spirit and carry to fruition his political ideas aimed at re- pressing the Social Democrats. This is The Psychology of the Kaiser 109 exemplified by the Kaiser's exhortations, threats, and epithets hurled in his speeches at these alone of his political en- emies, and by the laws enacted and the use of the lese-majeste to suppress them. By suppressing the Social Democracy he is defended from his peril. Hence, as I have said, anger and hatred is a defense reaction. There are other ways in which the Kaiser's subconscious phobia uncon- sciously determines his mental behavior — by this I mean his modes or reasoning, his political principles and activities. As is well recognized not only by psycholo- gists but by popular notions, such a re- pressed, unadmitted sentiment becomes a motivating force, a subconscious motive that directs our conscious reasonings. Thus the Kaiser rationalizes, as psy- chologists say, his political objections to no The Psychology of the Kaiser democracy — that is, unwilling to admit his real objections, he finds and formu- lates logical reasons why democracy is wrong and why his own opinions are right, really believing in them, perhaps, as God-given. Saving the introduction of the Deity, this is nothing more than what every one does who is unconscious- ly influenced by subconscious motives of which he is unaware. When we say that a person is uncon- sciously influenced by this or that, un- consciously governed by a prejudice or sentiment like jealousy or fear or am- bition or what not, we mean that he is governed by a motive which is subcon- scious, which he will not admit to him- self, and of which he is therefore un- aware. It determines his thoughts just as the hidden works of a clock determine the movements of the hands and chimes. THE MORAL WHAT is the moral of all this? Surely the insight into the Kai- ser's mind which a study of his senti- ments and his phobia has given us reveals something more important than the mere personality of an exalted personage — ex- alted in the eyes of the world. It gives us an insight into the political forces which are wrestling within the German Empire for those ideals for which hu- manity has been striving through all the ages. It reveals the forces which for years have been striving with might and main to suppress these ideals. And it re- veals the forces upon which the world must depend to overthrow Germanism. in H2 The Psychology of the Kaiser The Kaiser and his House of Hohen- zollern and all that they stand for have become Civilization's World-Problem. If the Powers of Europe want lasting peace through the overthrow of autoc- racy and militarism, i. e., Germanism, the obsession of the Kaiser points the way — look to the democracy of Germany! Deacidified using the Bookkeeper process. Neutralizing agent: Magnesium Oxide Treatment Date: .... 20Q1 PreservationTechnologies A WORLD LEADER IN PAPER PRESERVATION 111 Thomson Park Drive Cranberry Township, PA 16066 (724)779-2111 ";; LIBRARY OF CONGRESS 007 803 838 A