;Mi?ja^iiK{ -r 'c^ p ^.. ^ % ^^ ^-. * ■. s ^ ^0 .0 ^ H ■' ^d^ ->* G^ "bo^ x^-^ ■^>. " c^ '^ xO<^ // O M <^ >■ -*^\\\V j^ ■ 1 .0 M THE MINOK WORKS OF GEORGE GROTE. LONDON : PRINTED BY WILLTA3I CLOWES AND SONS, STAMFOUD STREET AXD CHARINO CROSS. jL^.^neu'.'z ^s/:y?i,^u?v"izy^lds7>' ■^i.I&p. THE MINOR WORKS OF GEORGE GROTE. >\ WITH CRITICAL REMARKS ON HIS INTELLECTUAL CHARACTER, WRITINGS, AND SPEECHES, By ALEXANDER BAIN. ^ 1876, Wash LONDON: JOHN MURRAY, ALBEMARLE STREET. 1873. The right of Translation is reserved. NOTICE TO BINDER. K>« Frontispiece, juvenile Portrait of Mr. Grote, from a miniature painted from life by Ross, at Badgemore, Oxon. PREFACE, In the present volume are brought together the most important of Mr. Grote's minor writings. The sub- jects are very varied ; in all of them the composition is highly wrought ; and the scholarly and philoso- phical essays are for the most part treated in a popular manner. The earliest work of the author given at full is the ' Essentials of Parliamentary Reform.' It came out at the commencement of his public and parliamentary career, and sets forth in a systematic shape his theory of Representative Grovernment. Since the date of its publication this country has passed through forty years of unexampled political excitement and dis- cussion ; nevertheless, from the thoroughness of the author's grasp of political principles, the freshness and vigour of his illustration, and, not least, the high moral tone pervading the whole, the work is neither antiquated nor commonplace. In particular, his mode of supporting the doctrine that makes property the basis of the franchise, so far from being hackneyed by repetition, has lain unused on occasions when it might have been employed with effect. The short paper on Hobbes is a notice of the first VI PREFACE. • and second volumes of Sir William Molesworth's luxiirions and complete edition of Hobbes's writings. An interesting account of the circumstances that led Molesworth to undertake the edition, at a consider- able outlay, is given by Mrs. Grote ('Life,' p. 128). The notice is exceedingly characteristic of its author, and reproduces some of his most deep-seated con- victions, and most frequent topics of conversation. The article on Grecian Legends, published in 1843, was preparatory to the first part of the 'History of Greece,' which deals with Legendary Greece ; going over the ground of the sixteenth and seventeenth chapters of the work. It is not bereft of its interest by the more expanded handling in those chapters. One of the examples given of a myth created in our own times, has been reckoned a felicitous contribution to the author's general theory. The article on Boeckh's ' Metrology,' published in 1844, in the Classical Miisewn^ is a careful and elaborate estimate of the evidence remaining to us respecting Ancient Measures, Weights, and Money. The interest of the discussion is not confined to the scholar. By means of the usages relative to the standards of measure, weight, and money coinage, the general reader will obtain glimpses of ancient life, while ample proofs are afibrded of the Eastern origin of this part of Greek and Eoman civilisation. The ' Presidential Address to the City of London Scientific Institution ' and the ' Address on deliver- PEEFACE. Vll ing the prizes at University College/ are deliberately composed, and express the speaker's sentiments as to the aims of young men preparing themselves for the work of life. The pursuit of knowledge, both as a means, and for its own sake^ is strongly put forward in combination with a high ideal of self-reliance and patriotic citizenship. The Review of Sir Greorge Lewis's work, on the • Credibility of Early Roman History,' is both an interesting summary of the work, and a close criti- cism of its positions. Concurring with the author in his standard of historical evidence, and in his re- probation of the long-prevalent looseness of historical statements, Mr. Grrote points out instances where he thinks Lewis's scepticism is carried too far. The reader will be gratified to see the agreements and the differences of these two great authorities, as to the historical value of the earliest Roman records. The article (originally published as a pamphlet) on Plato's Doctrine respecting the Rotation of the Earth, is throughout polemical, and on that ground alone shows the author to advantage. The point in dispute is — Whether Plato- maintained the Rotation of the Earth about its axis, in opposition to the then received view of its being stationary. To have anti- cipated the greatest of astronomical discoveries would have been immensely to his honour. The question apparently involves the meaning of a Greek word ; but it really turns upon a very different considera- tion, namely, whether Plato could hold two doctrines viii PREFACE. inconsistent with each other — the revolution of the starry sphere and the revokition of the earth. Plato, in a fanciful manner of his own, maintained both doctrines, and did not feel the inconsistency; and, Mr. Grote, so far from being shocked or astonished at the circumstance as his opponents appear to be, characteristically regards it as a very frequent situation of the human mind. The discussion brings out some curious specimens of ancient modes of thinking. The ' Review of John Stuart Mill's Examination of Sir William Hamilton's Philosophy ' is a studied pro- duction, and takes a wide scope. It is prefaced by a warm eulogium on the elder Mill, which has a permanent biographical value. Before entering upon the Examination of Hamilton, Mr. Grote surveys the other works of its author — the ' Logic,' the ' Political Economy,' and the 'Liberty'; and avows his own obligations more particularly to the ' Logic' The review of the work on Hamilton lucidly discusses the chief topic in debate, and is distinguished among other points for pronouncing a more favourable opinion upon Hamilton on the whole than that expressed by Mill as the result of his critical examination. The Papers on Philosophy are printed from the author's MSS. The principal topic handled in them is the great question of Metaphysics — the Perception of the External World, on which Mr. Grote had long and intently meditated, but without having published his conclusions. There is also a criticism written PREFACE. IX shortly before his death on some parts of M. Taine's work, ' De 1' Intelligence/ chiefly with reference to another favourite subject — the primary truths of science. The Introduction contains abstracts of the Essay on Mackintosh, the Eeview of ' Mitford's Greece,' and the Speeches in Parliament — the six Ballot Speeches being given by themselves — followed by a critical survey of the ' History of Grreece,' the 'Plato,' and the 'Aristotle'; and ends with a notice of Mr. Grote's later public career, particularly in his connection with the University of London. A. B. London, October, 1873. TABLE OF CONTENTS. Jl REFACK .• .. •• .. ., .. CRITICAL ESTIMATE OF CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. Chap. I. Writings from 1820 to 1830 II. Speeches ox the Ballot III. Miscellaneous Speeches IV. History of Greece V. Work on Plato YI. Work on Aristotle YII. Later Public Life . . PAGE V [1] [19j [38] [66] [104] [120] [159] ESSENTIALS OF PARLIAMENTARY REFORM .. .. 1 NOTICE OF SIR WILLIAM MOLESWORTH'S EDITION OF THE WORKS OF HOBBES 57 GRECIAN LEGENDS AND EARLY HISTORY .. .. 73 REVIEW OF BOECKH ON ANCIENT WEIGHTS, COINS, AND MEASURES 135 PRESIDENTIAL ADDRESS, IN COMMEMORATION OF THE TWENTY - FIRST ANNIVERSARY OF THE LONDON SCIENTIFIC INSTITUTION 175 ADDRESS ON DELIVERING THE PRIZES AT UNIVER- SITY COLLEGE 195 REVIEW OF SIR G. C. LEWIS ON THE CREDIBILITY OF EARLY ROMAN HISTORY 205 xii CONTENTS. PAGE PLATO'S DOCTRINE EESPECTING THE ROTATION OF THE EARTH, AND ARISTOTLE'S COMMENT UPON THAT DOCTRINE 237 REVIEW OF JOHN STUART MILL ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON 277 PAPERS ON PHILOSOPHY 331 THE INTELLECTUAL CHARACTER AND WRITINGS OP GEOBGE GEOTE. -K>^ CHAPTEE I. WRITINGS FROM 1820 TO 1830. Mr. Grote's literary career may be said to have commenced with a pamphlet on Parliamentary Eeform, which, as has been atated in his biography, he composed by the bedside of his wife, in 1821. This first essay in the field of political science was prompted by an impatience of the plausible fallacies put forth by a writer in the ' Edinburgh Eeview/ No. LXI., in an article afterwards ascribed on good groimds to Sir James Mackintosh. In that article, Mackintosh is strongly in favour of Eeform, and throughout displays much liberality of tone. He is, however, especially averse to Universal Suffrage and to the Ballot ; and propounds a scheme for representing classes equally, altliough the numbers composing the classes might be very unequal. Grote's reply is scathing. We detect in his theory of politics, now for the first time promulgated, strong marks of Mill's famous article on Government ; we see also that he had already matured his conviction as to the ballot. There is, moreover, in the article, a highly sustained Ehetoiic, h [2] CHAEACTER AND WRITINGS. which may well have been nourished by Burke's Speeches, but was probably his own ideal of effective composition, the result of continued intimacy with the best literary pro- ductions ancient and modern. His subsequent style plainly shows that he considered this first attempt as too figurative. In the ballot speeches his style was much less rhetorical, and more effective. The present pamphlet also contains many sentences obscurely worded ; while his later style was remarkably clear. At the outset of the pamphlet, he regards the ^ Edinburgh Review ' as evincing a rooted hostility to any effective Par- liamentary Reform, and accounts for this by its connexion with the great aristocratical Whig party. Section I. is entitled ' General Principles of the Reformers.' It begins by applying to political science Bacon's exposure of the low condition of the sciences generally, the test being their fruits or practical workings. Bacon's remedy, namely, to sift and verify fundamental principles, if applied to political philo- sophy, would consist in enquiring what experience teaches concerning the laws of human action. Now, the amplest observation attests that the conduct of every individual will be determined by his interest. This is true not merely of individual, but also of conjoined action. If a hundred individuals possess the privilege of passing and executing the laws for a large country, they will to a certainty appro- priate the wealth and services of the inhabitants just as far as they are permitted. A governing company, therefore, must be constructed on such a scale that the majority of its members shall profit as little as possible by misgovernment. For that end, there are two requisites : First, the numbers must be considerable, so that the share of each individual may be low. Secondly, the relative situation of the members must be so arranged, that if they combine for sinister pur- poses, the benefits of misrule may be distributed equally. The first precaution would be nugatory without the second ; had there been a slave suffrage at Athens, the masters would still have been the sole gainers ; the slaves would have had WRITINGS FROM 1820 TO 1830. [3] « no share. Again, as any large number is unfit for the exer- cise of deliberative power, the ruling company must be divided into two classes — periodical electors, and elected legislators ; an enlarged numerical qualification can belong only to electors. But this enlargement is nugatory, unless the suffrage of each person is emancipated from control : which is possible only by a system of secret delivery. Moreover, as a Legislative share in the privileges of government is more valuable than an Elective share, this difference must be reduced hj frequency of election. How do these principles apply to the British Constitution ? If the slightest credit is due to the incessant and flaming proclamations of the Whigs, the majority of the ruling com- pany, as at present constituted, draw a decided benefit from misgovernment. In 1793, Earl Grey presented to Parlia- ment a petition in which it was asserted, and evidence ten- dered in proof, that a majority of the Commons was returned by seventy-one peers and ninety-one commoners. This is a sufficient explanation of the abuses denounced by the Whigs. What is the remedy ? The advocates of Eeform, in demanding an extended number of electors, do not urge the absolute necessity of making the suffrage universal : they do, however, maintain secret suffrage to be a vital requisite. Section 11. is ' Modes of Attack employed by the Enemies of Parliamentary Reform.' The just mode of attack is to pro- pose alternative means for attaining the end. One means proposed is the scheme of a disinterested ministry, in other words, a Whig ministry. The Whigs, it is pretended, will reject tlie benefits of misgovernment, and be content with their share, in common with the rest of the people, of a cheap system. But now, he asks, Upon what do these splendid pretensions rest ? On nothing but the speeches and promises of the Whigs them- selves. The track of lofty and flattering promise has long been known as conducting to power, and many are the knaves that walk therein. Yet farther, wlien we liear that there h 2 [4] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. are citizens who may be securely entrusted with the licence of inflicting evil, of course, for such persons, crime can have no attractions, and laws are needless and inoperative. Does then our penal code except the Whigs from its sanctions ? Not only so, but such men ought to be above the ordinary self-interested motives of payment for services. Do then the salaries of the Administration of 1806 remain untouched in the Exchequer ? If not, this alone places them on the level of ordinary life. It is not meant by such remarks to make any special censure upon the Whigs. But were they to claim an immunity from all penal laws whatsoever, the boon w^ould be trifling as compared with the pretensions to power. If there were no law to deter them from crime, voluntary associations would arise and probably restrain their licence ; while no exemption from private law could lay at their feet a spoil so secure and alluring, and, at the same time, so compatible with an untarnished fame as the posts that they aspire to. The next mode of argument for evading Keform is to set up the check of public opinion. Conceding, in the first instance, that public opinion is successful in defeating extravagance on the part of the administration, would it give a decided interest in good government ? It is at best a check, and not a spur. However efficacious pronounced opinion might be in keeping off new taxes, it would inspire no zeal for reduction of present burdens. The motive is a powerful one, but will it never be misled or disunited by official pretence or stratagem ? A government can easily alarm people into unnecessary wars, and so provide for a useless squad of dependents. The popular sentiment would probably become highly distempered by the poisonous matter that an interested body could infuse. The con- cession, however, now made in favour of the influence of public opinion is too much. The machinery of the social system, in the construction of laws, attests the impotence of the bridle of opinion. Unless the penal code can be turned into a useless scroll, it follows that from no one crime are WETTINGS FBOM 1820 TO 1830. [5] we sufficiently guaranteed by the avenging murmurs and by the uplifted arm of the public. Far less would public opinion maintain a vigilant censorship on an evil-intentioned government. As a preventive of private enormities — a rape or a murder — public opinion acts with the greatest advan- tage: no corrupt associations distort our sentiments, no expectations of profit from connivance can dull the horror of the act ; the sympathy is kindled by the concentration of the suffering ; the act itself is distinct and conspicuous ; the character of the deed is flagrant ; the criminal is a marked man ; and, finally, public opinion has an ally in the injured party or those connected with him. Now, mark the deduc- tions to be made from all these counts, when the same check is intended to subdue the sinister interest of a government. Experience attests our indulgence and even admiration of robbery and murder when on a grand scale ; our feelings are averted from the injustice and desolation of a war to par- take in the triumph of the general, and extol the terrific power that has done the work. The majesty of power that veils from our eyes its flagrant enormities completely white- washes the more insignificant minutiae of oppression ; not to speak of the hopes of place and profit to individuals. The extortion of a politic government, may impose but a trifling privation on each member of the community ; the evil may be enormous in the sum, but it appeals rather to cool reflec- tion than to our excited sensibilities. Again, the acts are of a kind very difficult to detect > how can public opinion keep steadily in view the nice boundary between necessary and unnecessary taxation ? Farther, the body to be acted on is numerous, and forms the most opulent, powerful and best instructed class in the community. Their mutual interest creates a train of peculiar feeling, and a perverted standard of conduct, rendering them insensible to reproach, at least until it swells to the loudest pitch. Mere languid dis- approbation is insufficient ; the feeling must be kindled into animosity and menace, and England stimulated into a [6] OHAEACTER AND WRITINGS. clamorous eJBferyescence, from the Thames to the Tay. During this time, the partisans of the government intersect the popular sentiment in all directions ; perplex and disturb its unison, counterwork its ejffect on the timid and the in- different, by impeaching the designs of its adversaries, and by setting up, on their own side, a still louder cry of impiety and rebellion. If reduced to yield, they find means by adroit concessions to retain part of their ground : and as opinion cannot long keep its lofty pitch, if the government can hold on for a limited period, the threats of the public will quickly subside. Even, if the public opinion should thwart any pernicious measures, it inflicts no punishment, and impresses no motive for the future. Again, as abuses seldom press signally on one individual, or on a small knot of persons, they do not draw forth a leader ; so that public opinion is left to organise itself in desultory detachments. To all which we must add, that as laws are made because an injured person would inflict excessive punishment on his enemy, an incensed people triumphing in a successful insur- rection cannot be expected to impose a stricter rein on their resentment. The impotence of the check is proved by the amplest testimony, seeing that it is the one check that springs up everywhere. Yet when we unrol the great mass of mankind, how striking and* irresistible are the proofs of its incompetency ! That it is an insufficient check upon the present governing class in England, we are informed by the most satisfactory evidence. The Whig members of Par- liament expatiate upon the defiance of the popular senti- ments by the Ministry ; and the Ministers, while confessing that the many are against them, declare that the sound, the rational part of the community, those alone hnown to the Constitution are in their favour. Others maintain that the people are too ignorant to detect misgovernment. The remedy is — let them see only the good ; present to men of ability no hope of reward from misrule. The author now considers the Reviewer's plan for a WRITINGS FROM 1820 TO 1830. [7] Representation of Classes. The proposal is to examine the variety of local and professional interests composing the general interest, and to give to each of these suitable repre- sentatives. In order to consider the effect of this plan, the author takes a simple case : let a community consist of three classes — lawyers, landholders, merchants — each returning a member to make a governing body. What will be the course of this triumvirate ? Each deputy is devoted to his class, but he can do nothing singly ; but if he combine with another, the concurrence of the third is of no importance, and his interest is disregarded. That equal protection to all classes, which the theory supposes, is in practice unattain- able. The interests of no class can be protected unless they can return a majority of the governing body. All that one class can do is to combine with other classes, merging what interest it has in opposition to these, and standing up only for what the united classes have 4n common; and if a majority is formed, that common interest will be secured. The ancient Eoman class-system was in the Eeviewer's model ; and the two wealthiest of the six classes were able to outvote all the rest, while these included an overwhelming majority of the people. The second half of the pamphlet takes account of the Eeviewer's Objections to a thorough Parliamentary Eeform. And first, his objections to Universal Suffrage. The Eeviewer supposes Ireland to be an independent state, with four-fifths of the population Catholics, and a government elected by universal suffrage ; where, in that case, would the Protestants be ? The author retorts, where would they be on the class system ? As the whole island is composed of Protestants and Catholics, under every possible system one or other sect must have the majority, and must dominate the other. The Eeviewer seems fully aware that universal suffrage would entail a neglect of the interests of the few ; he omits to remark that the return of a majority by the few would produce the same inattention to the interests of the many. When the rivalry in the state is merely as to the [8] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. possession of good things, there will be a partial renunciation of interest, so as to appease the discordance ; but an un- conquerable antipathy like that between Protestants and Catholics, blacks and whites, is irremediable. In the case between the many and the few, it may be undeniably proved that a majority chosen by the many will pursue the interest that the many have in common with the few. This position the author explains at length. The most interesting and original part of the argument is where he deals with the common allegation that the many would not respect projyerty. He points out the insidious attempt to restrict this word to the large proprietors. Strictly speaking, the poorest labourer has property, for which he needs the full protection of the law ; and the laws for protecting large properties must equally protect the small. Mr. Grote, as we shall see, on subsequent occasions reverts to this fallacy. (See on this point, p. 53 et seq,) A considerable portion of the pamphlet is occupied with the Reviewer's attack on the Ballot. The line of attack is rather strange. The Eeviewer thinks it a fallacy that the value of popular elections depends on the exercise of a deliberate judgment by the electors ; the real value is in diffusing public spirit. The author deals with this in his most vigorous style, shewing that it essentially consists in assigning to the general public the very worst part that they can play — the part of mobs. It is the result of the existing state of things, that the bulk of the community have inter- fered in national affairs by a display of physical force ; and reasoners have thereby been led to consider collective agency as an essential requisite of their political life. But the display of physical force should no more enter into politics than into mutual protection against lawlessness. The Eeviewer still farther urges the loss of excitement and heat through secret voting, — the Kfelessness and want of motive to go to the poll ; the virtues of the community do not arise from secret meditation, and do not flourish in solitude. The replies are sufficiently telling ; and although WRITINGS FROM 1820 TO 1830. [9] the author's illustration, every time he touches this question is fresh and racy, I shall defer the specimens of his handling until I come to the speeches in Parliament. The vigour of the pamphlet furnished a new weapon to the friends of Eeform. The 'Examiner' styled it "a very able and a very seasonable pamphlet/' and regarded the defence of the Ballot as the most comprehensive and useful part of the work ; adding that " Eeformers have paid too little attention to this excellent plan for curbing the sinister and immoral exercise of bribery and intimidation on the part of the great." We may see that Mr. Grote's studies in politics, theoretical and practical, were now well advanced. He had thoroughly imbibed the method and views of James Mill, which he developed by resources peculiar to himself. On the 25th of April, 1822, Lord John Eussell moved in the House of Commons, " That the present state of the repre- sentation of the people in Parliament requires the most serious consideration of this House." A long debate ensued, in which Mr. Canning delivered an elaborate oration. The motion was rejected by 269 to 164. Mr. Canning s speech drew out from Mr. Grote a letter published in the ^ Morning Chronicle,' full of his usual argu- mentative power and vigour of language. We need not reproduce it in full, but one or two extracts will be useful in showing the author's intensity of feeling on Eeform. The introduction is to this effect : — " That Mr. Canning's eloquence should prove triumphant in an assembly, so large a portion of which is ' self-elected ' (to use the unanswered and unanswerable phrase of Lord John Eussell), can excite no surprise whatever. His task is indeed an easy one on the floor of St. Stephen's. Would he but condescend to essay his powers on the other side of the [10] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. question, Avould he persuade gentlemen to surrender close, privileged, and hereditary seats, accompanied with a lucrative expenditure of 22,000,000?. per annum, and as much or as little to do as they please ; and to descend into the character of industrious, economical, and responsible legislators — this indeed would be an aim worthy of the rhetorician. And I much question whether even Mr. Canning's eloquence, if exerted on this side, would produce quite so many cheers, and such frequent laughter, as it seems to do at present. " To appreciate duly the extent of this gentleman's oratory, let us remove it from the circle of sympathising and con- fidential critics among whom it was delivered, and measure its effect upon the larger public without. \Yill his speech impel their minds in the proportion of 269 to 164, as it has already won the House of Commons? Let us review its contents briefly, with reference to that public for whose benefit the debate is imagined to have taken place." The essence of the speech, he states, as consisting of three arguments. The first is " Reformers do not agree in their proposals : Ergo, there ought to be no reform." The second is ^^ A Reform in the Parliament would depress and extinguish the Crown." The writer remarks — " This is an unqualified avowal, that monarchical govern- ment is highly injurious to the people. For such a decla- ration, I or any one else, anybody except Mr. Canning or Mr. F. Robinson, would be prosecuted. ' Any Legislature,' says the former, ' really elected by the people, responsible to them, and therefore promoting solely and exclusively the public good, would abrogate the Royal Prerogative. The latter, therefore, is irreconcileably at variance with the public happiness and interests.' Such is the view entertained by Mr. Canning, and by the Parliament who second Mr. Can- ning, of the genuine value of Monarchical Government. A more severe condemnation of the Throne cannot be pro- nounced, than this assertion, that an assembly aiming at the public happiness would never retain it." " Next comes an argument cogent indeed, but not easily WRITINGS FROM 1820 TO 1830. [11] referable to any known rules of logic : — 'The present con- stitution is the one under which Mr. Canning was born, and which therefore ought on no account to be changed.' When an infant of celebrity is born, we are commonly flattered with the hopes of some striking improvement which he is to accomplish — a reproduction of the golden age or of the Saturnian system of government. But Mr. Canning's god- fathers and godmother appear to have vowed in his name, that the world should be bound fast exactly in the position which it held when that gentleman first saw the light." Canning's fourth argument — " that it is not a good thing that the House of Commons should be so constituted as to coincide with the sentiments of the people " — is dealt with as we should expect. The concluding paragraph is — " Having thus anatomised the chief part of Mr. Canning's speech, I may venture to predict that it will not divide the nation in the proportion of 269 to 164. But this will be only a fresh demonstration of that general incapacity of the British race, which Mr. Canning so pointedly notices — from the melancholy effects of which we are providentially extricated by possessing a Legislature wise by blood and by inheritance." Among some essays, preserved in MSS. of the date 1822, there is a short paper wherein Mr. Crete refutes the alleged hostility of the bulk of the people to property, as inferred from occasional popular injustices. He meets the charge by several arguments. In the first place, he remarks, while so much stress is laid on the individual rich man whom the people have despoiled, no notice is taken of the many rich whom they have left untouched. Secondly, in order to predict the behaviour of any man or body of men, we must consider what their permanent interest points to. Thirdly, if it were admitted "that because the people have com- mitted occasional violations of property, therefore the people are hostile to property," the same might be equally aflSrmed of every other form of government. We ought to compute [12] CHARACTER AND WHITINGS. the instances of spoliation, under governments responsible to the people, and those under governments of one, or a few, in order to decide the question with perfect accuracy. But as this proceeding is impracticable, there remains one other method, namely, to apply the maxim " that every man will pursue his own interest," under which it will appear that the bulk of the people have a most essential interest in strengthening the motives to the accumulation of capital, because upon that depends the demand for labour. It is the very poorest that have the strongest interest in pro- moting accumulation. On the other hand, a monarch or an aristocracy, or both allied, have an interest directly at variance with the public hai3piness. They have an interest in plundering and degrading the community to the deepest extent, and in forcing the subjects to toil in their behalf ; this being the mode by which they will reap the largest harvest of wealth and power. Lastly, an attack of the people upon the property of an individual rich man no more proves that the people are hostile to the laws of property, than their attack upon his life would prove that they were inimical to the laws protecting life. In both instances, they may be misled to make a particular exception, but this does not prove them insensible to the value of the laws of property and life, or to the importance of adhering to them on other occasions. In the 'Westminster Eeview,' for April, 1826, appeared the celebrated article on Mitford's ' History of Greece.' It already evinces both the extent of his minute research and the decision of his views on Grecian politics. Whilst his democratic sympathies were engendered by the studies pur- sued in preparation for the History, his controversial faculty was aroused by the misstatements of this widely-read His- torian ; Mitford being at this period in possession of the educational field, as well in the universities as in family circles. WRITINGS FROM 1820 TO 1830. [13] The introduction to the article is a clear and condensed statement of the chain of cause and effect in the evolution of the Grecian mind. First of all was the subdivision of the Grecian population into a great number of distinct city-com- munities. The smallness of these communities brought the whole of the members into intimate fellowship and personal communication of views upon the public situation. In such a state of things, a hereditary chief, or mere head of a clan, could not hold his ground ; and the collective govern- ment of the state superseded personal government. The executive function was much better administered, being under the eye of the whole community. Moreover, every- thing in the condition of the Greeks favoured publicity of life, and interest in affairs. The desire of applause acquired extraordinary ascendency : and in this motive lay the sti- mulus to individual excellence in whatever accomplishments the public held in esteem. The extinction of the hereditary chiefs threw open the supreme power of the state to rivalry and competition ; and, when the circumstances excluded the agency of mere force, the grand and foremost engine was the power of persuasion, particularly as applied to assembled multitudes. The materials of persuasive address consisted of all manner of facts, analogies, and reasonings, bearing on the eligibility of any public measures ; involving a strong in- terest in contemporaneous critical history, the first specimen of which we owe to Thucvdides. When these various mental acquisitions were sought as means of ascendency, esteem was conferred on the man that could teach them. Numerous instructors arose, in Ehetoric chiefly and avowedly, but indi- rectly in all the branches of knowledge then existing ; and the success of those instructors in money and in fame was very great. But the teaching of the persuasive art led the way to the philosophy of the mind ; and it was amidst the intellectual excitement of ancient Greece that this master- science had its beginning. The field for the observation of human beings was no less ample than interesting : the variety of laws and institutions, the number of social experi- [14] CHAEACTEE AND WRITINGS. ments so to speak, the contentions of parties, tlie criticism of public men^ the diversities of individual excellence, in oratory, in poetry, in war, in legislation, stimulated critical enquiry into the causes of success. Superior men arose, with the aptitude for system and science ; by these the special experiences were converted into general rules ; and there thus gradually emerged the sciences of rhetoric, politics, etliics, and logic. Another influence was derived from the relio:ious festivals and gatherings. To these we apply the inadequate word games; the real term was contests (a'y(ove<;). The appetite for glory was greatly fostered at snch gatherings ; while the chief attention was given to gymnastic exercises ; but the garland was also bestowed for music and poetry. " Considerinsf the Grecian institutions as having: brouo-ht into operation these incentives to individual excellence, they will appear without a parallel in the history of humanity ; and judging by the same standard, too, it is abundantly certain that democracies were by far the best amon^; all the Grecian governments ; nor will it be too much to affirm, that had it not been for democracy, and that approximation to democracy which a numerous and open aristocracy pre- sents, this wonderful precocity of intellectnal development among the Greeks wonld have been impracticable, and that people would have been now forgotten amidst so many others who have marched only with the average pace of human improvement. Publicity and constant discussion of all matters relating to the general interest — accessibility of the public esteem, which could not be thoroughly monopolised by any predominant few — intense demand for those great political qualities which are fitted to command the respect alid assent of the general community — encouragement to eloquence, and to all those acquirements which eloquence presupposes, as well as to that system of instruction and mental philo- sophy which follows in its train — all these characteristics were to be found in the democracies more completely than in any other Grecian governments, and these, as we have above WEITINaS FROM 1820 TO 1830. [15] shown, were the great stimulating causes of Grecian eminence. Where a state was under the close government of one or of a few, circumstances were highly unfavourable to the develop- ment of individual superiority; the ruling powers not only held out no encouragement to it, but even interfered to sup- press and banish it by force as a rival to their own monopoly." It was never Mr. Grote's custom to advance positions of this nature without supporting them by facts: and his ex- posure of Mitford gives him an opportunity of unfolding his resources. I shall select only one point, because of its paramount interest, and because it is one of Grote's charac- teristic points of political doctrine. After giving a series of facts to set forth the atrocities of ancient oligarchy, he adds a testimony of tremendous and indisputable force. This is the oath (apparently the sena- torial oath) cited by Aristotle as formally sworn among some of the ancient oligarchies, containing these words — ''I will he evil-minded toicards the people, and will hring upon them hy my counsel ichatever mischief I can'' The philosopher's own remark is not less significant : his suggestion to the oligarchs being — '' Let them misgovern if they choose ; but let them at least employ some decent pretences to delude the people into a belief of the contrary." But for our ex- perience of the irresistible effect of the habit of submission among men, we might wonder that any government thus afi'ected towards its subjects could be suffered to exist a single month. Yet the subversion of the oligarchies almost always arose, not so much from popular resistance as from dissensions among the leading men themselves ; there being always room for aspiring nobles to acquire popularity by appearing to act as protectors of the oppressed many. Thus were formed two aristocratic parties — denominated by Mitford the party of the poor, and the party of the rich ; appellations employed both by Plato and by Aristotle, but yet involving an important mistake. The party called the " party of the poor," ought to be called the community minus the rich. Rich and not-rich are the proper terms for bisecting the [16] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. commimity. The classification into rich and poor is a fal- lacy, the source of many most erroneous political reasonings. Thus, according to Aristotle, Oligarchy has a place when the wealthy few possess the government, and employ their power for their own ends, not for the public good ; Demo- cracy is when the poor many, possessing the powers of government, use these powers for their own interest, not the public interest. The pliilosopher seems to imagine that if the wealthy as a class possess no distinct privileges, the government is necessarily in the hands of the poor, and that the poor have an interest contrary to the public interest. Now the word " poor " is here used in a double sense : it signifies at one time the whole community excepting the rich; and at another time the destitute poor. Only in this last sense can the poor ever be said to have an interest distinct from the public interest ; the whole community ex- cluding the rich has obviously the same interest as the whole communitv includino; the rich. As not more than one man in a hundred can be called rich, ninety-nine hundredths of the community are poor ; and the interest of ninety-nine hundredths of the community must always be the same as the interest of the whole communitv. There can be little doubt that the persistent denunciations of Grecian democracy, of which Mitford's book is a notable sample, were kept up for the sake of their application to modern instances; and Mr. Grote, by his vindication of Athens, has powerfully counterworked one of the machina- tions for retarding the growth of popular government in the present day. He is, however, fully alive to the weaknesses and defects of the old democracies, just as he is sensible of many defects in the popular constitutions of oiu^ own time ; but, *• taking these defects at the utmost, and comparing the Grecian democracies with any other form of government, either existing in ancient times, or projected by the ancient philosophers, we have no hesitation in pronouncing them decidedly and unquestionably superior. That the securities they provided for good government were lamentably de- WEiriNGS FROM 1820 TO 1830. [17] ficient, we fully admit; but tlie oligarchies and inonarcliies afforded no securities at all." The complaint made against these democracies, by Xenophon and Aristotle, was not that they missed their own end, but that they aimed at, and to a certain degree attained, the happiness of all the free citizens, minus the rich, to the prejudice of the separate interests of the rich. His replies to Mitford's other charges, — that the popular assemblies were fickle in their decisions ; that the democra- cies were unstable and torn with dissensions ; that, in them rich men were unduly taxed (as by the liturgies at Athens) ; that unjust accusations were preyalent ; that re-diyision of the lands was a fayourite measure of democracy, — are oyer- whelming from the array of counter facts to every one. The latter half of the article is occupied with exposing the gross peryersions in Mitford's narratiye of transactions. This we need not exemplify ; for although the calumnies against democracy baye a permanent yitality/the historical blunders of such writers as Mitford are dead and decomposed. It is not often that the mild temper of Mr. Grote permitted of sarcasm, so we may quote this sentence from the criticism of Mitford's inaccuracies respecting the early proceedings of Philip of Macedon : — " Ancient writers haye left us lament- ably in the dark respecting many most important parts of ancient history; but we ought not to be seyere upon them for their want of minuteness in describing plans which were never concerted, and treaties which were never entered into." The article concludes thus : — " It is sufiiciently obvious that the historian who can thus deviate from his authorities in recounting specific facts, is still less to be relied upon for accuracy in any general views, where the result arising from a comparison of seyeral different authorities, not separately assignable, is to be laid before the reader. If partiality can discolour the former, it will prevent any approximation to truth in the latter. And should Grecian history ever be re-written with care and fidelity, we venture to predict that c [18] CHAEACTER AND WRITINGS. Mr. Mitford's reputation, for these as well as for other de- sirable qualities, will be prodigiously lowered. That it should have remained so long exalted, is a striking proof how much more apparent than real is the attention paid to Greek literature in this country ; and how much that atten- tion, where it is sincere and real, is confined to the techni- calities of the language, or the intricacies of its metres, instead of being employed to unfold the mechanism of society, and to bring to view the numerous illustrations Avhich Grecian phenomena afford, of the principles of human nature. It is not surprising, indeed, that the general views of Mr. Mitford should be eminently agreeable to the reigning interests in England ; nor that instructors devoted to those interests should carefully discourage all those mental quali- ties which might enable their pupils to look into evidence for themselves, and to deduce just inferences from the Greek authors who are put into their hands. But though such instructors cannot be prevented from teaching superficially, they may at least be deprived of the credit of teaching otherwise than superficially; and few works would more effectually conduce to this end than a good history of Greece."* * It ought to be mentioned, in recording the literary labours of Mr. Grote during this decade, that he bestowed much time upon some MSS. of Jeremy Bentham's, which the venerable sage en- treated his young disciple to put into a readable form. The pile of materials being carefully digested and arranged by George Grote, he produced in 1822 a small octavo volume, with the following title : "• Analysis of the Influence of Natural Religion on the Temporal Happiness of Mankind, by Philip Beauchamp." The MS. was handed to Mr. Place, who employed Eichard Carlile to print the tract ; the reason being that Carlile was lying in Dorchester gaol, and thus safe from farther prosecution. At that period the London booksellers were afraid of having anything to do with writings wherein Eehgion was in question. The original papers, in Bentham's handwriting, became the property of Mrs. George Grote under the Author's will, and are still extant, as well as the letter to G. Grote which accompanied the packet. SPEECHES ON THE BALLOT. [19] CHAPTEK II. SPEECHES ON THE BALLOT. On the 25th of April, 1833, Mr. Grote made his first motion in favour of the BaHot. At the outset of his speech he quotes Lord John Eussell's expression in originally proposing the Reform Bill: — "So constituting this House, as that it should enjoy, and com- mand, and deserve, the confidence of the people." He calls on the House now to review the mode of taking votes upon the same simple, precise, and momentous principle. The Reform Bill has given a numerous and intelligent commu- nity, say a million of voters. What would have been said if there had been a clause in the bill dividing that constituency into two classes — one class free, the other subject voters ? What if the bill had numbered all the tenants on a great man's esta?te, and all occupiers of houses under him, as so many lip-voters, necessary, indeed, as mechanical instru- ments for transmitting his will to the hustings, but legally incapable of expressing any determination but his ? But it is not by law alone that the freedom of voting is subverted ; natural causes may work the same thing. One half of the present constituency are unable to call their votes their own. No doubt there are some splendid examples of political virlue — men who give an honest vote and incur the con- sequent hazard ; but the larger number stifle the voice of conscience, and give way before an overruling destiny. The public mischief thus arising is that the House does not command the confidence of the people ; the elective system is a failure and a nullity ; for the only characteristic dis- tinguishing it from a vain mummery is the genuine suffrage of each qualified voter. The private mischiefs are the solemn falsehoods at the poll, the sense of self-abasement at being c 2 [20] CHARACTEE AND "WRITINGS. / the mstrni^gj^i^ ^f another's \Yill, the political apathy and recklessr^gg^ the thousand angry feelings everywhere accom- panyipg priyate terrorism. Xow, \\hateYer be the sources ^* /Ais evil, the condition of its agency is publicity of votes, -^-iie Ballot may not put an end to all persecution for political sentimentSj but it will put an end to compulsory and insincere voting. In France, during the last ten years, the Ballot proved the single guarantee against an overwhelming govern- ment ascendency. Under the Ballot individual bribery could have no place ; collective bribery would be hazardous and difficult. But for one vote perverted by bribery, twenty are perverted by in- timidation. He next deals with the objections to secrecy, as tending to mendacity and promise-breaking. Now it is true that a tenant voting by Ballot onay thus break his promise, but why should you suppose that he ^vill do so ? There is only one answer ; the promise has been given contrary to his genuine and conscientious feeling. Preferring A in his conscience, the elector has beencon strained to promise that he will vote for B ; such a promise involves the inecessity of lying one way or the other ; either to his country, if he keeps the promise, or to his superior, if he breaks it. But what falsehood can be worse than a dishonest vote at the poll ? If a juror who gives a dishonest verdict, or a witness who de- poses an untruth, sins in poisoning the fountains of justice, the electoral trust-breaker sins scarcely less in poisoning the fountains of legislation. The opponents of the Ballot talk as if the only falsehood a voter can tell is the breaking faith with one who has extorted from him a dishonest promise. There is another and greater wrong, the breaking faith with the public. What this House should recognise is the superior obligation of the public trust to the private pledge. The promise is bad enough; the act would be far worse. All that can be said against the Ballot is, that it enables these compulsory and immoral promises to be violated with impu- nity ; thus getting rid of the more noxious of the two lies. SPEECHES ON THE BALLOT. [21] But this is not the fair way of looking at the effect of the secret vote. The compulsory and dishonest promises, whence the lyiug proceeds, will seldom be exacted. To tie a man down to a hateful pledge, when you cannot ascertain whether he keeps it, is a fruitless affront ; tending to rouse the galling ideas of coercion, without attaining a real hold over the conduct. Even now, is there no promise-breaking under the open vote? Does it not eternally happen that a dependent is compelled by his superior to break a promise already voluntarily made to another ? Speaking in a whisper is not synonymous with lying; much less is speaking aloud synonymous with openness of heart and truth-telling. There are cases where secrecy conduces to fraud ; there are cases where it is the only sure road to truth. When a witness deposes to facts, it is essential that his testimony should be public ; but when you wish a man's private unbiassed judgment, you will be nearer your end by making his communication strictly con- fidential. This last is the situation of an elector at the poll. He then proceeds to another favourite objection. The elective franchise, it is said, is a trust ; every elector is responsible for the way that he exercises it ; publicity is a necessary consequence, for the sake of the non-electors. He admits that there would be great weight in the argument, if the objector could show that open voting was either a benefit or a security to the non-electors. He thinks he can prove that the reverse is the fact. He assumes that the electoral trust means this, namely, that an elector shall deliver his genuine and conscientious opinion at the poll, whether it agrees or disagrees with that of other people. Now this can be obtained only by his own free will ; no extremity of force can wring it from him. The open vote cannot convert a single voter from dishonesty to honesty ; but it makes thousands of honest voters dishonest against their inclinations. Every voter becomes controllable by one or a [22J CHAEACTER AND WEITINGS. few private masters, who exercise over his comfort a para- mount influence. Under the mask of responsibility to the public, you fasten round his neck the base and dismal chain of private dependence. Moreover, is it really contended that non-voters are competent to exercise control or super- vision over the voters ? The onlv reason for setting: them aside as non- voters, is their presumed incapacity of judging on political subjects. When the non-electors do intermeddle it is as ardent partisans, and in a manner purely mis- chievous. Dictation by a private individual, the vultus instantis iyranni, and dictation by an assembled crowd, the civium ardor prava jvheniium, end in the same deplorable result — spurious and insincere voting. If the voters are sufficiently numerous, and well-dis- tributed, so as to have collectively the same interests as the community, they can have no wish except to choose honestly ; and this is the only ground on which the recent extension of the constituency can be vindicated. If respon- sibility had to be relied upon, as the guarantee for honest voting, any extension of the constituency would have been absurd and injurious ; a small constituency is far more pointedly responsible than a numerous one ; every step in enlarging the electoral body, is a step in diminution of the responsibility of each individual elector. Nay, upon this principle, the single-headed constituency of Old Sarum would have been the best in the whole kingdom. Another argument is that the influence of rich men over voters is a very salutary thing, and that the Ballot is mis- chievous as tending to abridge it. " How much influence over voters ought a rich man to have ? As much as he can purchase ? No, certainly — for even the present law forbids all idea of his purchasing any influence. Not as much as he can purchase, but as much as he deserves, and as much as unconstrained freemen are willing to pay him. Amongst unconstrained freemen, the man of recognised superiority will be sure to acquire spon- taneous esteem and deference ; these are his just deserts?, SPEECHES ON THE BALLOT. [23] and they come to him unbidden and unbespoken. But. they will come to him multiplied tenfold, if along with such intrinsic excellencies, he possesses the extrinsic recom- mendations of birth and fortune — if he be recommended to the attention of his neighbours by the conspicuous blazon of established opulence and station — and if he be thus fur- nished with the means of giving ample range and effect to an enlightened beneficence. This is the meed which awaits men of birth and station, if they do but employ their faculties industriously and to the proper ends. Poorer men may, doubtless, attain it also ; but with them the ascent is toilsome, the obstructions numerous, and the success at best uncertain : to the rich man the path is certain and easy — the wiUing public meet him half way, and joyfully hail the gradual opening of his virtues. He is the man to whom they delight to pay homage ; and their idolatrous fancy forestalls and exaggerates his real merits. " This, Sir, is, in my opinion, the legitimate influence of wealth and station; to ser^e as the passport, the ally, and the handmaid, of superior worth and talent. This influence is as gentle and kindly as it is lasting and infallible ; it is self-created and self-preserving ; and it is, morever, twice blest, for it blesses as well the few who exercise it, as the many over whom it is exercised." But it is the curse and misery of our species that the great and wealthy choose to govern by mere dint of wealth and station, unallied with those beneficent ingredients. Wealth, in any hands, carries with it the power of befriend- ing one man, and injuring another ; it can extort the votes that the possessor has not virtue enough to earn. This is the illegitimate influence of wealth and station— when it supersedes and disenthrones the diviner qualities of the man and the hero. Under open voting, the influence of wealth is alike in every hand ; nay, the worse a man is, the more effectively he will employ the bad weapons. The Ballot decomposes the mixture of good and evil, with the exactness of a chemical agent. The man that employs wealth and [24] CHAEACTER AND WRITINGS. station as they ought to be employed will not lose a particle of influence; his standard is planted in the interior of men's bosoms ; his ascendency is as sure and as operative in the dark as in the light. And what would be the harm, if that coarser and baser influence, which cannot subsist witiiout coercive force, were suppressed and extirpated altogether? The question was started by Berkeley, " Whether an un- educated gentry are not the greatest of all natural evils ?" The counter part of the proposition is no less true — That a gentry well-educated and of enlarged sympathies, are among the foremost of national blessings. The most effectual way of preserving that blessing will be to render the vote of an elector inaccessible to all coercion, and attainable only by such as have gained his genuine esteem. This is tlie only prize that can stimulate the listlessness, or soften the natural pride, of one whose wealth places him above the equal communion of his fellow-men; and by rendering the sufi*rage secret, you lock this precious prize in a casket, which can neither be stolen by fraud, nor ravished by tyranny ; you reserve it in the inmost sanctuary, as a free- will offering to ascertained merit, and as a stimulus to all noble aspirations. In the peroration, he says : — '' If ever there was a case in which the address to your reason was vehemently and powerfully seconded by the appeal to your feelings, that case is the emancipation of honest voters — the making peace between a man's duty and his worldly cares — the rescue of political morality from the snares which now beset it, and from the storms which now lay it prostrate. You are called upon to protect the rights, and to defend the integrity, of the electoral conscience ; to shield the innocent from perse- cution at the hands of the guilty ; to guard the common- wealth against innumerable breaches of trust, committed by the reluctant hands of well-meaning citizens. You are called upon to bridle the tyranny of those who violate, by the same blow, their duty to their neighbour and their duty to their country. You are called upon to encourage the SPEECHES ON THE BALLOT. [25] formation of an electoral conscience in those bosoms where it has as yet had no existence ; and to cure that recklessness and immorality with which unprincipled voters now prosti- tute their franchise, in order to conciliate custom or pro- motion. Above all, you are called upon to make this House, what it professes and purports to be, a real emanation from the pure and freespoken choice of the electors ; an assembly of men commanding the genuine esteem and confidence of the people, and consisting of persons, the fittest which the nation affords, for executing the true end and aim of government. When all these vast interests, collective and individual, are at stake in this one measure, am I not justified in demanding from you not merely a cold and passive attention, but an earnest sympathy and solicitude ? " The motion was vigorously supported, in a short speech, by Dr. Lushington. Mr. Cobbett replied to the objections founded on the American use of the Ballot. Daniel O'Connell made a short and telling speech, which brought up Sir Eobert Peel, who dwelt upon the apathy and dead languor that w^ould take place if canvassing were put an end to ; the impossibility of preserving secrecy ; the evil of making the House more democratic than it is. It was merely absurd to say that a man with ten thousand a year should not have more influence over the Legislature of the country than a man of ten pounds a year. He thought universal suffrage more plausible than vote by Ballot. There were arguments in favour of extending the franchise to women, to which it was no easy matter to find any logical answer : other and more important duties were intrusted to women ; women were allowed to hold property, to vote on many occasions in virtue of that property — nay, a woman might inherit the Throne, and perform all the functions of the first office of the State. The electoral system had not had a fair trial ; and members would be better employed in reading the report of the Poor- Law Commissioners, and considering some remedies for the evils there depicted. [26] CHAKACTER AND WRITINGS. The vote was — Ayes, 106 ; Noes, 211 ; Pairs, 26. The second occasion of bringing on the motion was on the 3rd of June, 1835. He had the advantage of being able to appeal to the recent election as furnishing abundant instances of gross intimidation, and by the help of these, and by vary- ing his illustrations, he contrived to impart a degree of freshness that was not apparent in any of the speeches in reply. He began by assuming that in conferring upon any man the title and functions of an elector, you really intend to invest him with a substantive and independent character. The contrary would imply, that Parliament, while pretending to bestow a vote upon him, designs, in fact, to bestow under- hand a second vote upon somebody else. If the law intends to play this trick with voters, the sooner it is proclaimed the better. The secret voter may give a wrong judgment, but at all events his vote is his own determination. Publicity of the suffrage enables intermeddlers from without to work on the hopes and fears of individual electors. Eeferring to the recent election, he observed that the newspapers of every party abounded with complaints of undue influence ; so familiar was it, that it seemed the ordinary course of nature in the electioneering world. Sometimes a landlord generally notified to his tenants that he did not mean to interfere with their votes ; but this edict of manumission would appear both preposterous and insulting, if the pre- existing dependence had not been felt. The voters seem to be considered as lawful prize and prey, milium ac tuiye ^ecus, belonging of right to that party which can drag them with the greatest violence. It is but too evident that the efforts of the imperative classes of society to subjugate the will of the humbler voters are nowise likely to be suspended or relaxed for the future. He next criticised a bill brought in by the member for Shaftesbury (Mr. Poulter), for making intimidation penal, and concluded with a reply to the stock of objections to the Ballot (its being un-English ; causing SPEECHES ON THE BALLOT. [27] promises to be broken ; witbdrawing responsibility from the voter ; reducing the influence of the wealthy.) ' Lord Howick insisted that the machinery of the Ballot was impracticable. Lord John Russell saw no hope of improvement, except in the better dispositions of the men of property themselves. Lord Stanley was at much pains to show that the G-rey cabinet when they carried the Reform Bill, had come under a pledge to go no farther. Sir Robert Peel spoke at some length, but with no originality. Division, 146 for, to 319 against. The following year (1836) on the 23rd of June, instead of a motion declaratory of the principle of the Ballot, Mr. Grote brought in a bill containing the provisions and machinery for secret voting. It would be superfluous, he remarks, to insist upon what all constitutional writers admit, that the primary condition of representative government is the eflScient operation of the elective principle. It is therefore no waste of time to con- sider the question of freedom or purity of election. What are the facts at present? So notorious are the evils and abuses that they are come to be treated as light and familiar. In introducing the Reform Act, Lord Grey proclaimed that nomination of members of Parliament should cease to exist. It is time to fulfil this beneficent pledge. The reality and prevalence of election abuses can now be made to rest on the testimony of Committees of the House, which have brought out a body of dark and infamous details, showing the springs and working of what we extol and sanctify under the name of representation. AU parties make loud complaints of intimidation. Much is made, in the Irish elections, of intimi- dation by the people and the priests, but still more frequent is the dictation of landlords and agents, and of the rich in general. Irish abuses are only English abuses on a gigantic scale. The clergy of the Church of England have not been behindhand in their zeal at the critical moment of an election ; the Vice-Chancellor of the University of Cambridge dis- [28] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. missed his gardener for refusing to vote for the present member for that town. But the nation in its collective majesty has a paramount title to the free and independent' suffrage of each separate elector. It is time for the House to interpose a remedy when the distempers of our electoral system have been proclaimed by its own authority. Have gentlemen made up their minds to see this leprosy cleave to us and to our posterity for ever? The remedy is secret voting. It trenches on no existing rights. Voting by Ballot is unfettered and unbiassed voting ; when Cicero, in speaking of the Ballot at Rome, calls it Tahellse, vindex tacitse libertatis — the upholder of silent liberty — he says what is emphatically true. He next goes on to reply to objections. It is said, that however an elector may vote, people will guess or suspect how he has voted. Why so ? Because his sentiments are known, and he has no motive to depart from them. There is an eternal and indissoluble alliance between secrecy and freedom. Gentlemen make intimidation by the mob an object of abhorrence ; they may abolish it by a measure that protects from all modes of intimidation at once. The much- extolled responsibility of the elector is either a phantom or a mask for the precise mischief of intimidation. The pub- licity of the votes of members of Parliament rests on three distinct grounds, all absent in the case of the electors. The smallness of their number gives them an interest of their own, apart from, and often hostile to, the community; the same smallness enables the public to watch their conduct ; lastly, the speciality and continuity of their functions also enable the public to judge wliether they discharge their duties. But, on the other hand, how idle to talk of the responsibility of seven or eight hundred thousand persons. Lord John Eussell had said the Ballot would remove the electors from good and improving influences. But what are the good influences that can operate upon a man apart from his own conscience and conviction? The good in- fluences will really be expanded and fostered* The SPEECHES ON THE BALLOT. [29] specific agency of the Ballot is against intimidation; its effect is not so conclusive, but will still be powerful against bribery. There may be a corrupt agreement in a small constituency ; but this proves only that small constituencies are faulty. Surely it is a noble object to watch over and cherish the honest and untainted portion of the constituency. As to the breaking of promises, the first purpose of a repre- sentation is to collect the real sense of the qualified voters ; the duty towards a private party is a secondary object. Yet the Ballot does not command any man to break his promise ; it merely enjoins him to perform the act of voting without a witness. Promise-breaking in this situation is the proof that the voter has been constrained. To tell the intimidator — because you have compelled a voter to promise against his will, therefore you have acquired a good title to compel him to vote, — is to guarantee the last stage of tyranny out of respect to the first. Then as to the influence of property, there is onlv one influence that will be withdrawn — the power of rewarding or. punishing electors according to their vote. Does the House recognise in any one citizen of this community — a peer or commoner, titled or untitled — a legi- timate authority to reward or punish electors for their votes ? Leader seconded the motion in a speech of some length, and Charles Villiers spoke with his wonted ability in the course of the debate. None of the Whig or Tory leaders spoke. The House divided — Ayes 88 ; Noes 139. On the 8th of March, 1837, the motion was next brought forward, also in the shape of a bill ; but the speech abstained from the explanation of the machinery in detail. I select a few of the points. It is not enough to say that secret voting disengages you altogether from the disorderly tumult and vexatious obstruc- tion inseparable from the pronouncing of a candidate's name at the hustings, and from the continuous proclamation of the varying state of the poll. The main purpose is to procure [30] CHAEACTER AND WRITINGS. free, sincere, and independent voting. This ought to secure for it the consent of all parties ; for how can any man repu- diate the principle of general freedom of votes, without assuming to himself a despotism little less monstrous than the ancient inquisition in matters of religion ? Free agency is the very soul of voting. Such is the English constitution in theory at least. Listen to Blackstone, and you will be beo:uiled into the belief that everv man's vote is his own vote ; descend into the committee-room, and you will find that the canvassers of election rack their ingenuity to dis- cover, not modes of persuasion, but modes either of com- pulsion or of seduction. It was acknowledged by the present Prime Minister only last year, that the great evil of the day is that every one thinks he has a right to employ his influence over another. In an article in the ' Edinburgh Eeview ' against the Ballot (written by Lord Brougham), tlie extent of intimidation at elections is described in language which it is impossible to surpass. On this point the reports of the committees of this House afford materials enough for the most insatiable appe- tite. Wherever any man possesses the means of inflicting injury on another, or withholding benefits, the power is used for electioneering purposes. As to exclusive dealing, the Tory organs are preaching it openly as a matter of political obligation. For all this, no one else has suggested any remedy. The Ballot will be an act of emancipation for all dependent voters. Some gentlemen tell us that while averse to theoretical or organic reforms, they burn with zeal for the removal of all proved abuses. Let them peruse the report of the Intimidation Committee, and they will find a harvest of proved abuses, rank, and pining for the sickle. Whence is it that election abuses in all their grossness and variety, at least three parts out of four, take their origin ? It is from the struggles of extraneous tyranny to grasp the vote of the voter. Now the surest mode of warfare against crime is to disappoint the criminal of his exj)ected booty. Instead of secrecy being dishonourable, it is used in every private SPEECHES ON THE BALLOT. [31] association, and its introduction is only treading in the beaten path of sound and practical legislation. Objectors, putting aside freedom of election as a light and worthless consi- deration, reproach the Ballot with multiplying false promises and false declarations. What then? Is there to be no privacy anywhere because falsehoods may be made and remain undiscovered ? The secrecy of the post opens a door to falsehood ; yet if there be any act of despotism that excites peculiar abhorrence it is the breaking the seal of private letters. Persecutors of every class may well be angry with the Ballot; it enables the voter to do his duty without baring his bosom to the assault of private malice. The victims of religious oppression in all ages, have carried on their worship secretly, and no historian has ever dared to revile them. Is it an unpardonable sin, under the pressure of penalties, to combine outward conformity with secret dis- sent ? Secrecy is the refuge of the weak against the strong. Publicity enables the political prosecutor to combine with the hundred arms of Briareus, the hundred eyes of Argus. If the Ballot makes hypocrites, open voting makes hypocrites, at least as many in number and much more in kind. Under the Ballot influence will be futile : when the process of intimidation is forbidden to be consummated, it will not be begun. Then, as to bribery. A voter accustomed to take bribes will feel that his market is struck from under him when he is directed to vote in secrecy. In ensuring ignorance of the poll, it prevents the candidate from knowing how many votes he must buy to secure his majority. Next, as to the argument from responsibility. You cannot make the elector responsible for voting ill ; for where is the standard ? Among Tories, to vote ill is to vote for a Whig or a Eadical, and conversely. As to the multitude that have no votes, why are they excluded ? What arguments should we hear in reply to a motion for universal suffrage ? But if these men are to coerce the voters, admit then at once they are the superior party of the two. If the non-electors acted generally on the invitation given to them, we should have universal suffrage [32] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. practically, but brought about by the most violent and un- warrantable means. The unrepresented classes have nothing to lose and much to gain, from placiog every qualified voter in circumstances for an honest and conscientious use of his franchise ; it concerns them that the poorer voters should not be subservient to the richer; that the franchise should be kept at least as wide as at present. At one time the Ballot is assailed because it will extinguish the influence of wealth ; at another time because it will extino:uish the influence of disfranchised poverty. If you insist that the elector shall be responsible to the people at large, you are bound to pro- tect him against the tyranny of the great man in his neigh- bourhood. Coercion and counter-coercion are assumed to be the essential and tutelary forces which keep the electors in their proper orbit. It often happens that the pressure from two opposing quarters is so violent that the elector knows not which he ought to obey. The concludino; sentences are : — " I feel that in advocatinsr the Ballot, I am upholding nothing less than the sacred right of free judgment and free utterance in political matters. I am treading in the steps of those illustrious men who have rescued the individual conscience from its trammels, and vindicated its liberty and inviolability in matters of religion. I am striving to baffle the guilty efforts of that spirit of persecution which still harasses the political world, and still defiles the sincerity and solemnity of the elective franchise. If, Sir, you can break the sword of the persecutor, and assure freedom of election, without the aid of the Ballot, proceed to the task without delay, for never was there a case of more pressing necessity. But when it is notorious that this can- not be done, and when the alternative of the Ballot is ready within your reach, I beseech you to consider whether you can, with a safe conscience, license and perpetuate the count- less mischiefs of an unprotected suff*rage." The debate was short, and the opposition was somewhat milder in tone than in former years. The House divided — Ayes, 155 ; Noes, 267 ; Pairs, 5. SPEECHES ON THE BALLOT. [33] The motion was renewed in the recently elected Parlia- ment of 1838 (16th of February) ; and the mover availed himself of the experience at the elections. If it were proposed to cut down the present number of seven hundred thousand qualified electors to four hundred thousand, the attempt would be resisted alike by those who desired to adhere to the present franchise, and those who desired to enlarge it. Yet open voting is a practical dis- franchisement to hundreds and thousands of electors. Many decline to exercise the franchise at all : and with regard to those who do vote, what is the difference between taking away the vote and taking away the voter's liberty of voting as he inwardly prefers ? There is little difference of opinion as to the main purposes of a representative government ; it is to get a House of Commons possessing the confidence of the people ; for this we go through the harassing and costly business of a general election. Does the practical working conform to this ? The evidence shows that the existing system is not a representative system. Many votes are given, of all shades of party, that express the genuine senti- ments of the electors ; with respect to a large proportion, the reverse is the truth. The innumerable discourses of candidates on the hustings during the late election, the daily criminations and recriminations of all the newspapers — Whig, Tory, and Radical — all certify the virulence of the evil. He quoted a number of individual testimonies — Lord Palmerston at Tiverton, the Whig and Tory versions of the election in the West Riding of Yorkshire, and others. The number of ejectments, notices to quit, changes of dealing and dismissals of employment, if it could be collected, would be large and remarkable ; and as one punishment inflicted corresponds to a thousand persons deterred, these acts are but a small proportion of the cases of undue interference. In many cases, the franchise is hated as a burden. An election sheds a disastrous twilight over all the relations of social life, — tyranny, ruin for conscientious behaviour, success of unprincipled compliance, suspension of inter- d [34] CHARACTEB AND WRITINGS. course, factitious riot and disorder. If no protection be allowed, the franchise must fall into the same degeneracy and disgrace as the old system before 1831. Lord John Russell had expressed his strong sense of the " terrible position " of the landlords, and rather than that it should continue, he would adopt the Ballot. Since then, there have been two general elections, and the terrible position is un- affected. If the supporters of the Reform Act wish to reap the good they have sown, they must adopt the inexpugnable safeguard of the secret vote. As knowledge is power, absence of knowledge is absence of power. It is in vain to reason with the intimidator, to cajole him, to cry shame upon him, to hold out legal penalties. Intimidation is too gentlemanlike and fashionable to be subdued by such leaden weapons. It is the inmate of courts and manor-houses : the cherished companion of lordly bosoms : all the pride of wealth and rank, and all the fierceness of political bigotry conspire to uphold it; the clergyman who discourses elo- quently in the pulpit on charity and forgiveness of enemies, neither enjoins nor manifests any such dispositions during a contested election ; even ladies of high fashion are not ashamed to direct W'ith their own delicate hands, the instant discontinuance of a tradesman who has dared to vote for the shocking Radical. Under the Ballot those who now dictate votes by means of servile and selfish fears must resort to other methods of guidance : if they disdain to substitute persuasion for control, they will be left, as they ought to be, to impotent and unavailing complaints. Some persons maintain, that secret voting will be inoperative unless canvassing is also prohibited. The word '^ canvassing " is equivocal ; it includes something that is harmless and even indispensable, and much that is revolting and odious. Under the Ballot, you would have a committee and a canvass ; to consult the prevailing sentiment, to communicate informa- tion, to rectify mistakes, and to convince, as well as might be, such as are adverse. Beyond these limits begins the odious part of the practice. In no scene on the face of the SPEECHES ON THE BALLOT. [35] earth are the harassing and ungenerous arts of enforcing constrained compliance more skilfully practised than at an English election. Then as to violation of promises. What is the behaviour of a country gentleman when the Tory canvassers tell him that Farmer So-and So, his tenant, has promised his vote to the Eadical candidate ? To hear the arguments against the Ballot, one would think an election by open voting was a school of probity and veracity. Instead of that, the promise of a dependent voter is respected just so far as it coincides with the will and dictates of his superior. The promises now broken are precisely the best class of promises. The elector is under a paramount obligation, from which no act of his own can discharge him, to give his vote according to his own conscientious preference. A promise to vote contrary to his own judgment, is a premedi- tated breach of solemn public duty. If there be in human affairs an unlawful covenant, that is one of the deepest dye ; wrong in the man who gives the pledge, wrong in the highest degree, and altogether without excuse or extenuation, in the man who extorts it. The responsibility of the elector is an abuse of terms. It is seduction and intimidation under another name. The debate that followed was well sustained. The motion was seconded by Mr. Ward, in an effective speech. Mr. James referred to a time some years ago, w^hen he presented a petition in favour of the Ballot, which was received with shouts of laughter. Lytton Bulwer spoke in favour of the motion. Lord John Eussell replied at some length. It was on this occasion that Sir Eobert Peel made his principal speech on the subject ; merely the old topics more elabo- rately worded. He treated the position of the elector and of the member of Parliament as the same ; he declared that the best institutions had their abuses; the abuses in elections were greatly exaggerated ; secret voting is at variance with the institutions, usages, and feelings of the people, and witli free discussion ; then, there will be no secrecy with the Ballot ; on the day of election, the doubtful voter will be d 2 [36] CHAEACTER AND WRITINGS. asked to stay away; the voter will as a rule keep his promise, or else blab to his wife or somebody, who will tell the agent ; there may be great political outbursts, when the public are so unreasonably prejudiced, that they need enlio:htened control : the Ballot has not worked well in other countries, nor did it in Kome; it will have to be followed by universal suffrage. The Division stood— Ayes, 200 ; Noes, 317. The sixth and last time the motion was made, was on the 18th of June, 1839. The speech introducing it was less than a column of the newspaper report. Apologising for iteration, he said his historical experience had taught him that it was not the introduction of novel arguments which political truth depended upon for its success, but in having the proper arguments frequently brought forward and con- sidered. It was not fruitfulness of invention that enabled the advocates of Catholic emancipation to carry their point : the novelty of every argument had been exhausted long before the final triumph. Even though they meant the Eeform Act to be final, did they mean also to embalm its deformities ? As the evils were fully admitted, why did not some one propose a remedy different from the Ballot ? He could not understand the objection of its being too demo- cratic a measure, unless the objectors held that democratical opinions prevailed amongst the majority of the electors throughout the country, and that the Ballot would enable them to vote more freely in favour of theii' opinions. The measure was indispensable to any state of the franchise — household, educational, or universal. He did not envy the feelings of any gentleman, who, after having witnessed a contested election, did not feel for the hardships to which many persons were exposed, and who did not wish that some measure of protection should be extended to them. The undue interference with the exercise of the suffrage was not consistent with the perfect freedom of the country ; the Ballot was the only antidote against the taint which SPEECHES ON THE BALLOT. [37] poisoned the life-blood of the representative system. It might be rejected, but it would not be rejected long. The debate was enlivened by the brilliancy of Macaulay in support of the motion. He began with a long apology for open questions, as the Ballot was now made in the cabinet. He admitted that the Ballot would take from the voter some good, while it destroyed many bad motives. There was a time when he hoped that the evil of intimida- tion would yield to the force of public opinion and the progress of intelligence ; he had, however, been compelled to relinquish that view. The evil had increased within the last seven years — within the last three years ; and he attributed the increase in some measure to the Eeform Bill. In saying so, he was only charging the Eeform Bill with what accom- panied every measure of improvement ; the Eeformation in the Church, and the Eevolution both gave rise to new evils. The Eeform Bill had extended the suffrage to thousands who were open to intimidation ; and better be elected for Old Sarum than owe a seat to fear-extorted votes. All tyranny was bad, but the worst kind of tyranny was that which used the machinery of freedom. Intimidation was corruption in its worst and most loathsome form — it was corruption stripped of every blandishment and grace — of every savour- ing of hospitable bounty and good humour. He was opposed to the reconstruction of the Eeform Bill, but to make that Bill effectual they should not allow nomination to remain in an altered and more odious form. Lord John Eussell made a laboured reply to Macaulay, and was himself severely handled by Shell. Sir James Graham went into the vexed historical question, often brought up in the Ballot debates, as to what was the understanding of the original framers of the Eeform Bill on the subject of the Ballot. Sir Eobert Peel in a short speech lectured the cabinet on their doctrine of open questions. On a division, the Ayes were 216 ; Noes, 333. [38] CHAEACTEK AND WRITINGS. CHAPTEE III. MISCELLANEOUS SPEECHES. 1833. Mr. Grote's maiden speech was delivered on the 22nd of February, in support of a motion to refer to the committee then sitting on Municipal Corporations, a petition from the Merchant Tailors' Company of the City of London. It had been denied that the City Companies were corporations in the same sense as the municipal corporations. Mr. Grote contended that as they were not companies in the commercial sense of the term, and as they passed regulations for par- ticular trades, they exercised powers belonging properly to a municipal corporation. More important was the occasion of his next speech, five days later, in opposition to the Irish Coercion Bill. In spite of his respect for the quarter whence the measure came, he could not approve of it. It contained some wise and tutelary provisions ; but as a whole it would not answer its end. He could not speak of it but as a most revolting measure. He had listened patiently to the catalogue of enormities detailed by the noble lord (Mthorp). This was nothing new to him ; the Irish had ever been a lawless people, a fact not sufficiently dwelt upon. They (the legislature) should strengthen the hands of justice under the existing tribunals.' The proposed courts-martial would not be impartial courts; and their mistakes would be on the side, not of mercy, but of severity. These courts-martial were held responsible only to higher courts-martial, which was no guarantee, for the condemnation of one military man by another would be prevented by the esprit cle corps among officers. He objected to the Bill on two distinct grounds. The first was subjecting Ireland to MISCELLANEOUS SPEECHES. [39] tlie goyernment of military tribunals ; the next was the pro- hibition of public meetings, and the right to petition. " He was sure that they had not arrived yet at the period when the relations bet\yeen the governors and the governed in that country were so pure, and so free from suspicion, as to enable the people to dispense with all the bulwarks of the constitu- tion." There were abundance of grievances yet to redress in that country of long standing, and it would be wise as well as delicate in the Government to pause before they shut the door against all the public complaints from the people of Ireland. On the following day he presented a petition from a num- ber of persons called Separatists, who sought to be exempted, like the Quakers, from taking oaths. (This was afterwards done by Act 3 & 4 Will. IV., c. 82.) On the 7th of March he presented a petition from i^orwich, stating that the return of Lord Stormont and Sir James Scarlett had been effected by means of bribery and cor- ruption, and praying that a Parliamentary Commission might be sent down, fully and fairly to enquire into and expose the system. He supported the prayer of the petition ; but the Solicitor-General objected to it as irregular. On the 13th he presented a petition from Marylebone against the Irish Coercion Bill, and gave his cordial support to the prayer of the petition. On the 31st of May, he spoke on Lord Althorp's resolutions for a renewal of the Bank Charter. He concurred generally in the resolutions ; but, on the 1st of July, in the debate on the second resolution, which made the promissory notes of the Bank of England a legal tender (although always payable in gold at the Bank itself, or any of its branches), he avowed an entire change of opinion, on the ground that in the poor districts there would not be an adequate supply of specie ; there would, in fact, be a commission charged for gold over what would be demanded for notes. The clause would also hinder small depositors — men who had their thirty or forty pounds — from carrying gold to the country bank. He had a [40] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. farther distrust of the measure from its being adopted and praised by gentlemen who held certain opinions on the ques- tion of the currency, sincerely enough, he had no doubt, but in his view injurious if adopted. Lord Althorp followed, and declared that he had himself been much influenced by Mr. Grote's former opinions, given in evidence before the Committee on the Bank Charter, and could not concur in his new views. Mr. Clav thouo;ht that the manly and noble conduct of the honourable member for London, in thus frankly avowing what he now considered to be an error of opinion, was above all praise ; and, instead of de- tracting from his character for talent and judgment, would only increase his deservedly high reputation. On Lord Althorp's fourth resolution, fixing the allowance to the Bank of England for managing the public debt, Mr. Clay moved an amend- ment in favour of reduction. Mr. Grote spoke in favour of another amendment for postponing the resolution, and making further investigation before fixing the allowance, which he did not think too great. On the 19th of June, on the resumption of a debate on the claims of English subjects on the Danish Government, he presented a petition from claimants in the City of London ; and contended that the case was one of great injustice. On the 21st, in Committee on the Church Temporalities (Ireland) Bill, on clause 147 (application of monies arising from sale of perpetuities) being read, Mr. Secretary Stanley proposed the omission of the clause. A very excited debate followed. O'Connell indulged in his bitterest taunts. Dr. Lushington said he had never heard a discussion in which the decency of parliamentary language, or the courtesy of public life had been so much departed from. The question in dispute was the alienation of Church property to secular purposes. The clause involved this alienation in a small degree. At the same time the Government got out of the difficulty by maintaining that the funds alluded to were not Church property. Still, the clause was now surrendered. Mr. Grote spoke shortly, but with more than his accustomed MISCELLANEOUS SPEECHES. [41] point and terseness. He did entertain an objection to the Bill in the first instance, because it "did not, in his opinion, go the length that people expected it would go towards rectifying that great ecclesiastical enornnity of Europe — the Irish Church." Still, knowing the difficulties the ministers would have to contend with in getting it passed, he felt ♦ anxious to support it ; but when he found that, defective as it was, it was to be robbed of one of its chiefest members, he felt bound to oppose the withdrawal of the clause. The supposition was that the withdrawal had a view to what might happen in the Lords ; but what worse could the Lords do than send the Bill back, and then they might consider the omission of the clause. His advice to ministers was, instead of offering a few crumbs of reform to the people, and afterwards endeavouring to pare down even those few, to give such measures as they might think just and necessary, with- out any reference to what might be the conduct of another assembly. Lord John Eussell " confessed he turned with gratification from the frothy declamation which had so lavishly been bestowed on the subject, to the calm, and as usual, rational arguments which had been addressed to the House by the honourable member for London." The gist of his speech was to avoid a contest with the Lords until there was a ques- tion of still greater importance to contend for ; " he was of opinion that this country could not stand a revolution once a-year." On the 2nd of July he presented a petition from the merchants of London, trading with Oporto, complaining of the losses undergone by them in the struggle existing for the last ten months in Portugal. On the 30th Mr. Eoebuck moved that the House would, with the smallest delay possible, consider the means of establishing a system of national education. Mr. Grote seconded the motion, in the belief that two things were per- fectly true ; the first, that the present system of education was defective: the other, that the defects could not be [42] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. remedied without the assistance of Government. He referred in terms of great commendation to Cousin's book on ' Educa- tion in France.' On the 7th of August, on the third reading of the Customs' Duties Bill, after commenting on the enormous duty on cur- rants — 44s. 4id, per cwt. — he moved its reduction to 28s. ; the motion was defeated by a small majority. On the 9th, on a clause in the Renewal of the Bank Charter, continuing the renewal for ten years, he urged that seven years would be a sufficiently long period. On the 10th he recommended that the variations in the Bank circulation should be published weekly in the Gazette. 1834. The opening days of this session were troubled with tlie discussion of a charge made against Mr. Sheil, that while voting against the Irish Coercion Bill of last session, he had privately expressed himself to the effect, that Ministers ought to press the Bill, and that it is impossible to live in Ireland without it. An extraordinary personal altercation took place between Lord Althorp and Mr. Sheil ; and they were both ordered into the custody of the Serjeant-at-arms until they gave assurances that they would take no steps outside the House. Mr. O'Connell moved the appointment of a Com- mittee of Privileges to investigate the charge, which was carried by a large majority. Mr. Grote was made chairman of the committee. On the 12th of Februarv he rose in the House to move, by request of the committee, that Mr. O'Connell's name be now added to the committee ; he having, in his motion, declined to name himself. After some stick- ling, the motion was agreed to. On the 14th Mr. Grote brought up the report of the committee, which was a com- plete vindication of Mr. Sheil's character. On the 20th of February he presented a petition from the parishioners of AUhallows, Lombard Street, disapproving of .MISCELLANEOUS SPEECHES. [43] the conduct of the Dean and Chapter of Canterbury, in pre- ferring to the incumbency of the parish a non-resident ; and took the opportunity of making some remarks on the neces- sity of an early measure of Church Reform. In a speech palliating the appointment, Sir E. Inglis acknowledged the calm and temperate manner in which Mr. Grote had discussed what persons, not of his temper and discretion, would have made an occasion to provoke other sentiments than he had roused. On the 18th of March he took part in a debate on the Tea Duties. On the 14th of April, in Committee of Supply, he objected strongly to the amount of the vote for the Consular Depart- ment, and also to the discrepancies of the salaries. The fol- lowing day, on a vote of £20,000 for education, he was of opinion that the Government ought to extend the vote. On the 30th he opposed the second reading of Sir A. Agnew's Bill for the Observance of tlie Sabbath. He con- sidered it nothing more or less than a sentence of imprison- ment upon the working classes of society upon the Sabbath. " Eeligion to be effective must be spontaneous and sincere." On the 9th of May, Lord Althorp moved the second reading of the Poor Laws Amendment Bill. Mr. Grote was an active supporter of the measure in all its stages. In the debate on the second reading, he spoke with intense fervour on the necessity of the change. He had perused with de- liberate attention all the Reports of the Commission of Inquiry. Even the vast and abusive expenditure under the present law was as dust in the balance compared with the evil effect on the character and comfort of the labouring classes. He was aware of the great jealousy expressed at the powers to be vested in the Commissioners; but the question was, did the urgency of the case require them? His concluding sentences are : — " Entertaining a strong and decided opinion on this subject, I have done my best to persuade the House to read this Bill a second time. I know that I have done this at no small risk of favour and popu- [44] CHARACTEE AND WRITINGS. larity to myself ; for I understand that a petition was this day presented from my own constituents, directed strongly against the passing of this Bill. Sir, it is not without the deepest regret and concern that I find myself opposed to constituents to whom I am attached by every tie, and to whom I owe the honourable station which I now occupy. But so strong is my conviction of the absolute necessity of some large remedial measure as an antidote to the over- whelming evil of pauperism — so firm is my belief of the necessity of some central supervising agency to secure the fulfilment of any salutary provisions which the legislature may prescribe — so strong is my conviction on these cardinal points, that if it were to cost me the certain sacrifice of my seat, I should feel bound to tell mv constituents that I dis- sented from them, and that I would do my best to promote the attainment of this necessary, and, in the main, valuable remedy. In doing so, I should feel with pain that I had decided contrary to the opinion of my constituents ; but I should also feel, that I had decided in unison with the best interests of my country." In Committee, he spoke frequently on the details. He opposed the concession of the Government to limit the appointment of the Commissioners to five years. On the bastardy clauses he complained that Lord Althorp was making concessions to the public feeling rather than to reason or argument. On the 27th of May, Mr. Ward brought forward his motion for reducing the revenues of the Irish Church. Mr. G-rote was to second the motion. Those who sought to identify the two Churches of England and Ireland would degrade the one church without elevating the other. There was only one case in Europe where the temporalities of the established church went, not to a majority, but to a small minority of the people, and that w^as Ireland. In France, under the bigoted reign of Charles X., the cost of religious worship to the State was less than one shilling a head; in Ireland it was one pound ten shillings a head. Some contended MISCELLANEOUS SPEECHES. [45] that the State had no right to touch the property of the Irish Church, or to apply it to other than religious purposes. This might be maintained by a Koman-Catholic, but every Protestant must be aware that in the progress of the Ee- formation church property had been diverted to other pur- poses. If the legislature attempted to continue the Irish Church in its present magnitude, the legislature would share in its . unpopularity ; it was considered a grievance upheld only by the irresistible influence of English connexion. When the advocates of the repeal of the Union put forward the evils of the Irish Church establishment, no man replied. Although this speech was composed and appears in Hansard, it was not delivered (see " Life," p. 90.) On the 8th of July, he supported Mr. Ward's motion for taking authentic lists of the divisions of the House. The motion was carried ; and from that time commenced the recording of the names of those that vote in the divisions. On the 25th, on the Order of the Day for the House to resolve itself into a Committee of Ways and Means, Mr. Goulburn made an attack upon the Government for increas- ing offices, by Commissions and otherwise, and particularly instanced an office held by Macaulay. Mr. Orote defended the expenditure upon Commissions of Inquiry, but \Aith regard to the salary given to Mr. Macaulay, with all his admiration for that excellent and most gifted individual, he could not but consider it extravagant. 1835. Sir Eobert Peel was now in office, and the opening of the Session was marked by an animated debate. In the Commons an Amendment on the Address was moved by Lord Morpeth, strongly expressing the desirableness of prosecuting measures of reform, and condemning the recent dissolution of Parlia- ment. Mr. Pemberton replied to the very vigorous attack of Lord Morpeth. Mr. Ewart spolce for the amendment. [46] CHAEACTER AND WRITINGS. Mr. Eichards made an apology for ministers, on" tlie ground that the late Government itself was not giving satisfaction to reformers ; among other illustrations, he quoted their recep- tion of the Ballot. Mr. Grote then rose. He said his reform principles conducted him to very different conclusions from the member who had just sat down. As a reformer, he could not consent to look for a ministry in the ranks of the party ever the most hostile to reform. If his present vote would have the effect of displacing the present Government, that would be an additional reason for giving it. Lord Grey's adminis- tration had been slow in making reforms, but that could not be said of Lord Melbourne's, seeing it had not been allowed that fair trial for which the advocates of the present Govern- ment were so clamorous. Great public excitement bad been created, which could be allayed only by the assurance, con- tained in the Amendment, that the cause of reform was not to suffer. The Royal Speech, if it had come from a ministry he confided in, would not have given him satisfaction, but coming from a ministry in which he had no confidence at all, was still more objectionable. Its defects would have justified a still stronger amendment. He could not forget their acts previous to 1830. The Government of Lord Grey was the first that had openly approved of and acted on the principles of Eeform ; it did not come up to his wishes; but however slow, it would never stand still. The mover of the address had spoken of a morbid desire for change; what he found was an ardent wish for improving our institutions. Whoever asserted that there was anything incompatible with law and government was guilty of a calumny upon the body of the people. Reformers had been taunted with want of unanimity, but they had quite enough of sense and reflection to pursue the stream of Reform peaceably and calmly, without even allowing the impediments that they might meet with to force them out of their channel, or to make them fret and foam with vexation. He thought the defence of the ministry by a reference to the King's prerogative, would soon lead the prerogative itself to be questioned. MISCELLANEOUS SPEECHES. [47] The Amendment was carried bv 309 to 302. On the 10th of March, in a debate on the Malt Duties, Sir James Graham had made allusion to a change of mi- nistry, and said '' they had been told of, or rather threatened with, a Grote and Warburton Administration." Mr. Grote rose in consequence. He said a friend " had been pleased to connect his name with a possible ministry: he, however, regretted such a fancy had ever been started, inasmuch as such a situation was as much above his ambition, as it would be foreign to his taste, his pursuits, and his interests." More- over, on the present question, he dissented from the very persons that were to be coupled with him in the supposed ministry. He objected to the repeal of the Malt Duties, and considered Sir Robert Peel's arguments to be unanswer- able, and rejoiced that he had dispersed so many of the agricultural fallacies so often put forth in the House. The following night, Sir George Grey moved for a Com- mittee to enquire into the most effectual method to put a stop to bribery at elections. Mr. Grote expressed himself willing to go into the Committee with the fullest disposition to consider any remedy that might be proposed, apart from the Ballot, and trusted that if they were unsuccessful, they would follow the example of the member for Edinburgh, and get over their former scruples and objections to the Ballot. The Committee was appointed. On the 18th, Sir John Campbell moved the second reading of the Imprisonment for Debt Bill. The Bill abolished im- prisonment, except in the cases of fraud. Mr. Grote said the Bill was recommended both by policy and by humanity: and he was more convinced of this by the speech (hostile) of the President of the Board of Trade than by any other reasoning on the subject. He was better pleased that his views should be sustained by the failure of his opponent's arguments, than by the success of his own. On the 27th of May, Mr. Shaw presented several petitions expressing, in somewhat violent language, alarm and dismay at the proposed measure respecting the Irish Church. [48] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. Various members commented upon the language of the petitions. Mr. Grote would make only one observation on the subject. Much had often been said as to the ferocious language of the Radicals and the working classes : but no petition coming from these ever abounded in such calumnious assertions, and imputation of the w^orst motives as the petition dow coming from the Conservatives of South Lanca- shire, and likewise the petition from Durham. It was right that the same character should be applied to violent lan- guage, whether it came from the ultra-Pious or the ultra- Radical. On the 15th of June, the Municipal Corporation Bill was unanimously read a second time. Mr. Grote, commenting upon a speech of Lord Stanley's, objected to the large number of councillors allowed by the Bill ; and advocated the removability of charitable trustees, and also of the recorder. He also protested against a proposal for retaining the franchise of the freemen. Both on this occasion, and afterwards in Committee, he opposed the qualification of a three years' occupancy. On the 26th of June, he presented a petition from Great Yarmouth, praying for the Ballot, in consequence of the drunkenness, riot and corruption at the last election there. He should have wished the petition referred to a Select Committee, but he was personally overcharged with Com- mittee business, and could not attend to it. On the 1st of July, in Committee on the Municipal Corporation Bill, on clause 23, providing that one-third of the Town Councils should go out of office annually, an amendment was moved by Mr. Charles Buller, to the effect that the whole be elected annually. Mr. Grote supported the principle of annual election, and from the experience of the City of London, refuted the objection that it would cause a continual influx of new and inexperienced men. The same evening he moved, in a short speech, the introduction of the Ballot at Municipal Elections ; but did not press the motion to a vote. MISCELLANEOUS SPEECHES. [49] On the 31st of August, there came on for consideration the Lords' Amendments to the Municipal Corporations Bill. Considerable public excitement had been aroused by these amendments. Lord John Russell stated what points the Government would, and what they would not, surrender. Sir Eobert Peel followed and assisted in compromising the differences. Mr. Hume objected to the amount of the con- cessions. Mr. Grote still more emphatically. Whatever he might think of the proceedings of the House of Lords in other respects, he was bound to acknowledge that they had resolutely adhered to their independent character; and it would not be amiss if the Commons would do the same. It would ill become the dignity of that House — the assembled representatives of the people of Eogland — to yield important principles merely for the purpose of conciliating the other House of Parliament. When the people of England were fully and justly represented in that House, there ought to be no other power in the State which should be able to stand against them. He complained that Lord John Russell, in one or two of his concessions, had gone the length of vindi- cating the Lords' amendments on their merits. He would rather wait for a better Bill than barter away the best principles of the measure for the purpose of getting the immediate consent of the other House. Both on that occasion and next night, he objected strongly to the test of pecuniary qualification, which Lord John Russell agreed to retain with a modification suggested by Sir Robert Peel. He had come down to the House with the full intention of dividing upon this question, but had been induced, in consequence of the observations he had heard, to alter his purpose. Still he was anxious to give his reasons, namely, his repugnance to the principle of qualification, and his sense that the concession was too great. He thought the tone of the present debate was calculated to have no other effect than to give the Lords a power of legislating over this House, and to make the country believe that this House would not stand by any great principle which it had en- e [50] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. deavoured to establish. He could not see what the country had gained by the Reform Bill, which had in a great degree put an end to the system of filling the House with nomi- nees of the Lords, if the other House was to exercise its power in another way, by enabling minorities of the Commons to triumph over decided majorities of the repre- sentatives of the people. 1836. On the 20th of April, a keen discussion arose as to members of the House voting on Private Bills wherein they had a pecuniary interest. Mr. Grote agreed in the prin- ciple, but did not see how it could be fully carried out. The inference that he would draw was that Committees of that House were not fit tribunals for deciding private business. The same night, in presenting a petition from sixty merchants of the City of London, complaining of the ill efiects, on our commerce with Turkey, of the overbearing interference of Eussia, — he deprecated any course that would involve this country in a war with Russia. It had of late become the custom to use very unmeasured language as to the aggressions of Russia, respecting which, whatever opinion he might entertain as a private individual, he considered unwise and impolitic when expressed in the House. On the 22nd, a motion was made to inculpate Mr. O'Connell for his share in making a corrupt bargain at the Carlow election, notwithstanding that a Select Committee had sat upon the transaction and given in a Report in an opposite sense. It was a purely party move. Mr. Grote stood upon the decision of the Committee, as being cool and impartial, whereas the present motion had the character of political hostility to O'Connell. It was somewhat remark- able that hon. gentlemen opposite, who were now so anxious to preserve the parity of election, had taken a very different course last year when the York and Great Yarmouth cases MISCELLANEOUS SPEECHES. [51] were under discussion. The House on that occasion was content with pronouncing a slight censure on the parties implicated ; but if the hon. members on that (the Ministerial) side of the House had insisted on dragging those men up again, would it not have been denounced as an act of the grossest partiality, emanating from a low spiteful feeling of personal hostility ? On the 29th, he presented a petition for the equalisation of the duty on East and West India sugars ; and thought that they were called by every reason of justice, fairness and policy to abolish the discriminating duty in favour of the West Indies. On the 9th of June, the House had to consider the Lords' Amendments to the Municipal Corporations (Ireland) Bill ; the debate lasting two nights. Lord John Eussell, on the part of the Government, took a more decided tone on this occasion than in the case of the English bill ; but yet pro- posed certain concessions. Mr. Grote spoke as usual shortly, but with increased emphasis on the hostile attitude of the Lords. He would have preferred that the Lords' Amend- ments should have been at once rejected, unless they had found any one that they could in their consciences approve. If ever there was a Bill, on which the House should look to its own dignity, it was the one now before them, for it had been dealt with by the other House in a manner in which no Bill had ever before been treated. The representatives of the people might have been spared the pain of making con- cessions to those who had declined, he might almost say exultingly declined, to make anything like concessions to them. He did not wish to speak lightly of a collision between the two Houses of Parliament ; but let the collision come when it might, it never would arise on a more noble or a more natural object than the present. The fact that they must meet with the same spirit of opposition from their Lordships on all important measures, rendered him less solicitous than he might otherwise have been for the settle- ment of the difference between the two Houses on this e2 [52] CHAEACTER AND WRITINGS, particular subject. When he 'saw the House of Commons perpetually considering upon all measures of reform, not how much they ought in justice to give, but how much the Lords would be disposed to grant, he thought that the time was come when they ought to inform their constituents of that melancholy truth, and let them decide whether they would be governed on the principles avowed by the House of Lords, or on those acted on by the House of Commons. On the 16th of July, in Committee on the Stamp Duties Bill, he strongly trusted the time would soon arrive when the Chancellor of the Exchequer would propose the abolition of the penny duty, and thereby remove every obstacle to the diffusion of knowledge throughout the country. On the 25th the Established Churcli Bill was read a third time. In the debate 3Ir. Grote protested against the allow- ances to the bishops. The very lowest salary granted by the bill he held sufficient for the Archbishop of Canterbury, instead of 15,000Z. a year as proposed. Why, was it possible to conceive any set of duties which could be more easily or tranquilly performed, or which were more exempt from all those difficulties that required labour, assiduity and talent to surmount them, than those allotted to the Archbishop of Canterbury? It was impossible not to draw a comparison between those incomes and the miserable stipends of the working clergy. It was said lOOZ. or 150?. a year was enough for a curate, yet the Archbishop of Canterbury was not in anywise the superior of the humbler individuals so remu- nerated. 1837. In April this year came up the Canada Eesolutions, on which Mr. Grote spoke repeatedly in opposition to the Government. His first and longest speech was on the 21st, in answer to Sir Eobert Peel's criticism of ]\Ii\ Eoebuck's proposal that the Upper House of Assembly should be merely advisers to the 2:overnor and not a co-ordinate branch of the MISCELLANEOUS SPEECHES. [53] legislature. He considered that the exercise of a veto upon the popular assembly by such a council as was proposed was infinitely more obnoxious than the veto of the governor, who had the prestige of a representative of the power and majesty of the king. On the bringing up of the Report of the Reso- lutions on the 28th, he declared his continued regret at the decision of the House regarding them. On the 10th of May he supported a bill for abolishing the qualification arising out of the payment of rates and taxes, required by the Reform Act for borough, but not for county voters. On the 22nd, in Committee on the Bill for abolishing the Punishment of Death in the Burning or Destroying Build- ings and Ships, he urged that if the punishment of death was to be retained, it would be better that it should be inflicted in private, as public executions were never attended with beneficial results. The death of the king having led to a dissolution of Par- liament on the 17th of Julv, the Houses reassembled on the 15th of November. On the 20th was moved the address to the Queen's Speech. On that night, and on the following, Lord John Russell gave answers to the complaints made by the advanced liberals, that the Government was backward in measures of further reform. Mr. Grote gave the noble lord credit for his candour, but could not award him any higher commendation. He complained that the noble lord had regarded the Ballot as inseparable from the two other ques- tions of extension of the suffrage and repeal of the Septennial Act. He was favourable to the two last measures, but would bring forward the Ballot on its own independent merits. If such arguments as were now used by the noble lord had been allowed to prevail on a former occasion, the Reform Bill itself would never have passed. He felt deeply sorry for the declarations just made by the noble lord; they would pro- duce a greater and much more painful sensation than the Duke of Wellington's celebrated declaration against the Reform Bill. [54] CHAEACTER AND WRITINGS. On the 4tli of December, on going into Committee upon the Municipal Officers' Declaration Bill, framed for the relief of Quakers and Moravians, Mr. Grote moved that the bill be extended to all classes of Her Majesty's subjects. The extension was meant for the Jews. The amendment was lost by a majority of 16. On the 13th of December, in a speech of great delicacy and tact, he took exception to a proposal for granting an addition of 8000?. a year to the income of the Duchess of Kent. He was one of those who took the strongest view of the duty of economising the public money. He often, there- fore, felt bound to resist the claims made on the public purse by those in the middle station, and in that more humble than it. He could not take that course with satisfaction to his own feelings and conscience, unless he was prepared to exercise the same scrutinising investigation into the claims of those who filled an exalted station. On the 15th the Civil List had to be voted. Mr. Hume moved the reduction of the vote to Her Majesty (385,000Z.) by 50,000Z. Mr. Grrote would most willingly support every- thino* that could add not only to the comfort and elegance, but also to the dignity and splendour of the Sovereign ; yet he was of opinion that the best friends to the respectability of the Crown were those who were most anxious that it should not appear in the light of an odious and unnecessary burden on the shoulders of the people. On the 19th he made a motion to remove from the Civil List the sum allotted to pensions. He argued against those pensions in a speech of some length. His objections were that no adequate pubKc advantage accrued from the fund ; that it involved a double and conflicting reference to the reward of merit and the relief of distress ; that in this last application it was in contradiction to the strict principle involved in the Poor Law Amendment Act ; and that it was a means of patronage to the Government of the day. On the 22nd, a debate was brought in by Mr. Leader on the affairs of Canada, now in a state of rebellion. Mr. Grote MISCELLANEOUS SPEECHES. [55] traced the present calamities to last year's resolutions: he would not have these resolutions on his conscience for any- thing that could be offered him. He regretted to find the confidence prevailing on both sides of the House, that the expression of a strong opinion from a large majority in the British Parliament, was alone necessary to put down at once all idea of resistance in the minds of the people of Canada. Many had said that there was no analogy between the present state of Canada and that of the provinces of the United States in 1774. He contended that the grievances in both cases were the same, the principal being the right of the British Government to take the people's money. He had listened with surprise to the member for Newark (Mr. Gladstone) when he said it was not a mere speculative grievance, or grievance of principle, but a series of pro- tracted oppressions, which had led the United States of America to shake off the yoke of Britain. That statement was entirely inaccurate. The British Legislature had assumed over Canada, as it had done over the United States, a right of control, which however the noble lord (Lord John Eussell) might regard it, he was sure would have been considered by the Lord Eussell of former days, and by Algernon Sydney, as equal to a sentence of slavery. 1838. Canada was the first subject of this session. On the 16th of January, Lord John Eussell moved an Address to the Queen, expressing regret at the Canadian re- bellion, and assuring Her Majesty " that while this House is ever ready to afford relief to real grievances, we are fully determined to support the efforts of Her Majesty for the sup- pression of revolt and the restoration of tranquillity." Mr. Grote used very strong language in disapproving of the Government for the absence of all conciliating measures, while bent upon the employment of force to suppress the [56] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. rebellion. He imfavourably criticised the whole policy of the Home Government in the treatment of the colony. He could see no benefit from severity and coercion, whilst it must produce the great evil of continuing in the minds of the inhabitants a feeling of despair that justice would be done to their country. Next day, he presented and supported a petition from Mr. Eoebuck, praying that he might be heard at the bar in the defence of the House of Assembly of Lower Canada, and in opposition to the measure of '^ impolicy and injustice " which Government meant to introduce with regard to that country. The petition was ordered to be printed. On the 22nd, he formally proposed " that John Arthur Eoebuck, Esq., be heard at the bar of the House, as the agent of the Assembly of Lower Canada, against the Canada Bill, on the second reading- thereof." As the Bill meant to sus- pend the constitution of the colony, which was, in fact, a suspension of the House of Assembly, it was a matter of justice to give the agent of that body an opportunity of de- fending the body at the bar of the House. Mr. Gladstone followed, and while agreeing that it would be most desirable to hear Mr. Roebuck, protested against recognising him as '' the agent of the House of Assembly." After speeches by Lord John Russell, Lord Stanley, and others, on the technical form of the proposal, the House de- cided in favour of hearing Roebuck. Accordingly, on the Order of the Day for the second reading of the Lower Canada Government Bill, he advanced to the bar, and addressed the House. On his retiring, the debate commenced on a motion that the House go into committee on the Bill. On the second night of the debate (23rd of January) Mr. Grote spoke. He concurred in the propriety of sending out Lord Durham as Governor of Canada ; and he could also express his satisfaction at the announcement of the intention of the Government to exercise clemency towards those who had been engaged in the late revolt. He complained, however, that the chances of Lord Durham's success were very much MISCELLANEOUS SPEECHES, [57] spoiled by the suspension of the Assembly. He had before expressed an opinion, which was not very favourably received in the House, but which he, nevertheless, sincerely enter- tained, that a separation between the colony and the mother- country was the most desirable thing that could happen, both for the mother-country and for the colony. Already there was the commencement of a feeling of sympathy be- tween the Canadas and the people of the United States. If they would have colonial possessions such as Canada, they had this difficult problem to solve — they had to maintain the supremacy of this country, and at the same time to give satisfaction to the Canadian people. It was usual to make severe remarks on the speeches of what is called the Radical party in the House (of Commons), and to speak contemptu- ously of the smallness of their numbers, although he was rather surprised, if the Radical party were really so small and contemptible, that honourable members should find so much in their speeches worthy of comment; but he must say, that of the speeches in the House that were likely to alienate tbe feelings of the colonists, it was not those that spoke for thejn, but those that spoke against them, which w^ere more likely to produce such a result. On the 29th, there was a debate on the third reading of the Canada Bill. Mr. Grote spoke with the same emphasis as before. He saw in the Bill no remedy proposed for any of the evils that now constituted the grievances of the Canadians, while he saw in it one great grievance added to those already existing, of which, even those that had hitherto abstained from taking part in these matters must feel the burden. The representation of the people in Canada would now be a name and a shadow. In answer to the allegation that the consti- tution had become unworkable, he blamed the Executive Government for not using its prerogative in the appointment of members such as would be acceptable to the majority of the people. They might foresee the difficulties of suspending an existing constitution, when they heard the proposition of a supporter of the Government to saddle the colony with an [58] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. Established Church. The same reasons that led him to wish to improve the representative institutions in this country, which imperfectly and unfaithfully represented the people, induced him to be strenuous in preserving the Canadian Assembly, which really did represent the people. He doubted and mistrusted the power of the Government to restore the Assembly, and he did not feel confident that they wished it; the more so, when he observed that the Govern- ment had to conciliate Sir Robert Peel, and to obtain his support, in whatever new constitution might be given to Canada. On the 25th of April Mr. Serjeant Talfourd moved the second reading of his Copyright Bill, which was to extend the term of copyright to sixty years. Mr. Grote opposed the measure as replete with mischief to the public, doubtful in its pecuniary results as to the authors themselves, and calcu- lated to rob those authors of what, he was persuaded, they set a greater value upon than any pecuniary gain — a wide and enduring circle of literary and intrinsic admiration. On the 19th of July, on a proposition of Lord John Eussell for an additional advance of money to the relief of the owners of compositions for tithes in Ireland, he offered his strenuous resistance, confessing, however, that after the sur- render of the appropriation clause, he had ceased to take any interest in the Tithe Bill. At the same time, when he found that a large sum of money was to be paid out of the pockets of the people of England, he was bound to declare that no proposition had ever been submitted to the House since he became a member to which he felt a more unqualified oppo- sition. Lord John Eussell replied in the usual strain, that the Government could not, in their circumstances, with the hostility they encountered both in the Commons and in the Lords, do more than they had done. On the 26th, the Irish Tithe Bill was read a third time. The debate was stormy. Mr. Grote excelled himself in the energy of his denunciation of the measure. The Bill would only raise increased odium to the existing constitution of MISCELLANEOUS SPEECHES. [59] the Irish Church. Now he had been as unreserved as any man in the expression of his abhorrence of the monstrous principle, and the equally monstrous effects of that esta- blishment, but he would not for that reason support a Bill which he conscientiously objected to. If any settlement of the Irish Church question were proposed, founded on just principles, and likely to be final, he would not object to a grant for closing a wound that had so long been bleeding. On the 15th of August, on the Order of the Day for the third reading of the Canada Government Declaratory and Indemnity Bill, he declared his satisfaction at being one of the inconsiderable minority that had opposed the Act for the temporary government of Lower Canada, out of which had arisen the necessity for this Bill. He could not recon- cile the Bill with the encomiums passed by its supporters on Lord Durham; if the noble lord deserved those en- comiums, that Bill was not necessary ; and if he had been guilty of illegal acts, the encomiums could not be right. 1839. Parliament was opened on the 5th of February, but Mr. Grote's name does not appear in the debates, till the 5th of March. On that day he supports Mr. Milner Gibson, in urging Lord Palmerston to counteract the Eussian influence that had been brought to bear on Sweden against making Slito a free port. On the 12th of March, Mr. Villiers brought on a motion on the Corn Laws, which led to a five nights' debate. On the second night, Mr. Grote supported the motion in a speech occupying ten pages of Hansard. His characteristics as a debater — the mastery and handling of facts, the argu- mentative vigour and point, the telling retort of the allega- tions on the other side — are fully displayed on this occasion. But in a subject so completely thrashed out, it is not advisable to occupy space with an analysis of the speech. [60] CHAEACTEE AND WETTINGS. On tlie IQth, there was a debate, introduced by Lord Sandon, on the French blockade of the Mexican ports. Mr. Grote took part, and after unfavourably criticising the French proceeding, he found fault with Lord Palmerston for the tardiness of his interference. On the 21st, Mr. Hume made a motion in favour of House- hold Suffrage, and prefaced it by an elaborate speech. Lord John Eussell followed Mr. Hume, and was followed by Mr. Grote. The noble lord, he said, had dwelt very much on the mischiefs of the future changes, and the danger of un- settling the principles of the Reform Act ; and he must say that the noble lord had borro^ved manv of his observations from the speeches made by the opponents of his own Bill in 1831 and 1832. He did not think the noble lord w^ould carry the public with him by simply telling them that they had got the Eeform Bill, and must be content to take it for better or for worse. He could not consent to treat the Eeform Act as a kind of canon of Scripture, which was to have notluDg added and nothing taken away. He saw no valid reason for withholding the elective suffrage from any man, unless it could be proved, or a strong presumption could be raised, that he was unfit to exercise it ; that was the view of representative government in every nation that possessed one. The householders under £10 were men labouring assiduously every day, discharging faithfully all the obligations of private life, having the greatest possible interest in the inviolability of the laws that ensured the stability of property and secured the earnings of industry. Instead of having the interest imputed to them by the noble lord of defrauding the public creditor, the Avorking classes would lend no approbation or acceptance to a measure so injurious to themselves. On the 15th of April, in consequence of Lord Eoden's motion carried in the House of Lords to appoint a Select Committee to enquire into the state of Ireland, Lord John Eussell, in a very long speech, asked the House to express approval of the Irish administration of the Government. MISCELLANEOUS SPEECHES. [61] On the third night of the debate that followed, Mr. Grote spoke shortly. He said that if the question now at issue were simply the conduct of the Irish executive under the Marquis of Normanby, he should have no hesitation in giving his vote in favour of the resolution. He must, however, guard himself against being supposed to go beyond the letter of the resolution, or to express confidence in Lord Melbourne's Government generally. The Irish executive administration is in truth almost the only remnant of Liberalism which now distinguishes ministers from the gentlemen opposite ; and for this reason it has been most abundantly attacked. What is the doctrine of finality so often preached from the Treasury bench, but the Con- servative principle announced in all its plenitude and in all its vigour ? For the first time in modern English history, we have neither a Liberal Ministry nor a Libera] Oppo- sition. On the 3rd of May, Lord John Kussell moved that the House go into Committee on the Jamaica Bill, by which it was proposed to suspend for a time the Legislative Assembly. Mr. Grote, as might have been expected, strongly opposed the Bill, both on the score of justice and on the score of wisdom. The smallness of the ministerial majority (5), led to the resignation of Ministers, and to Sir Eobert Peel's attempt to form a Government, which was frustrated by the Queen's refusing to part with her ladies of the bedchamber. On the 8th of July, Mr. Hume moved for a Committee on the whole history and constitution of the Bank of England. Mr. Grote approved of an enquiry, but con- sidered it too wide in its scope to be undertaken at so late a period of the session. 1840. During this session, Mr. Grote spoke but seldom. On the 1st of April, he took part in the three days' debate [62] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. on the Corn Laws, raised on a motion by Mr. Charles Villiers. On the 15th of May, in the debate on the Budget, he urged the removal of the stamp duty on policies of marine iDsurance. The only other speech was with reference to a motion by Lord Althorp (10th of March) for a Committee to enquire into the effects produced by the note-issuing banking esta- blishments. Mr. Grote was favourable to the appointment of the Committee, and mentioned the points that he thought it should take up, and also those that he thought it should avoid. 1841. In the debate on the Address, on the 26th of January, Mr. Grote made a noted speech on the Syrian question. He could not forget that we have been exerting our force against persons with whom we have not the slenderest grounds of quarrel : neither Mehemet Ali nor his supporters, nor any other person in Syria, has done the least injury to English men or to English interests : nay, we have been gainers by the government of the Pasha in Syria. We are told the expedition was undertaken for maintaining the integrity of the Ottoman empire, under a treaty of July, 1839. Setting aside the French opposition to the treaty, and our dangers arising therefrom, he disputed the wisdom of the guarantee. He asked whether we have fully viewed the extent of the consequences of this guarantee. It was often said that we should interfere in Turkey, to prevent Eussia from inter- fering. If the only method of excluding the Emperor Nicholas from Constantinople is to keep constantly ahead of him in devoted offers to the Sultan, our chance is but slender. The real security is the direct terror of our arms. But as to our Syrian expedition, Eussia is herself the grand projector of the enterprise. We are consulting the very MISCELLANEOUS SPEECHES. [63] party whom we suspect of entertaining thievish designs as to the best means of locking up and preserving our treasure. We have been hurried to the verge of an European war. The rupture between England and France is a signal calamity for both. The initial cause of so fatal a change — the tropical point from which the sun of peace began to avert his cheering rays from the latitude of Europe, is to be found in the treaty of last July, and in our Syrian expe- dition which followed it. The Foreign Secretary has cured, or professes to have cured, a distemper in the extremities of the Continent ; but the medicine has driven the distemper into the heart and vitals. If the noble lord has accom- plished a new settlement of the Ottoman empire, he has at the same time forcibly abrogated a pre-existing settlement, to which he himself had assented. That we should under- take to maintain the integrity of the Ottoman empire, both against foreign invaders and against itself and its own internal causes of disruption, he must record his deliberate protest, as well as against our recent embodiment of the principle in the Syrian expedition. If, in respect to our internal affairs, we are destined to obtain no farther progress; if the cold shadows of finality have at length closed in around us, and intercepted all visions of a brighter future ; if the glowing hopes once associated with a Reform Ministry and the reformed Parliament have perished like an exploded bubble, — at least in regard to our foreign affairs, let us preserve from shipwreck that which is the first of all blessings and necessities ; that which was bequeathed to us by the ante-Reform Ministry and the unreformed Parliament — I mean peace and accord with the leading nations of Europe, but especially with our nearest and greatest neigh- bour, France. On the 15th of March, he strongly supported a motion by Lord John Russell, for a loan to the colony of South Australia, to rescue it from pressing financial difficulties. He had been one of the original supporters of the plan for forming the colony, and although he had no pecuniary in- [64] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. terest in it, lie considered, in opposition to many members, that the colony had not been a failure. In the discussions connected with the Poor Law Amend- ment Bill, Mr. Grote took an active part. He uniformly defended the principles of the Bill, and supported its most stringent provisions ; in Committee he suggested a number of amendments. In replying to Mr. Duncombe's attacks on the Commissioners, he remarked, that he had supported the Bill of 1834, in opposition to his own constituency ; but he had now the satisfaction of knowins: that in the Citv of London the law was favourably regarded by the great body of the ratepayers. On the 25th of March (and again on the 22nd of April) he brought forward a series of resolutions relative to New South Wales. The resolutions were grounded on the com- plaint that our Government had thrown upon the colony the whole burden of the gaols and police, rendered necessary for the convicts sent out from this country, and had appropri- ated for that purpose the money arising from the land and emigration fund. He proposed that the charge should be in some way apportioned between the colony and the mother- country. A considerable debate ensued, but the motion was negatived by 54 to 10. His final effort in Parliament was in the great Sugar Duties debate on the 11th of May of this year. He put forth all his argumentative power on this occasion. At the commencement he descanted on Free Trade generally, and forcibly urged the mischiefs of protection in corn ; the alter- nate hot and cold fits of the corn-trade must be regarded by every one as a serious evil. Applying himself to the Sugar question, he took up the protectionist's favourite argument from the encouragement of slavery, and turned it over on every side. His own abhorrence of slavery is expressed in terms of unmistakeable sincerity ; while he exposes all the subterfuges of protection in claiming to discourage the slave- labour of Brazil and Cuba. As regards our home population, he did not wish to draw pictures of distress, or to move the MISCELLANEOUS SPEECHES. [65] feelings of the House by describing the circumstances of those whose condition is the least comfortable. He never thought that a just or deliberate judgment upon any contro- verted question could be promoted by such a mode of treat- ing it. It was enough for his argument to state the plain matter of fact, that there are millions of persons in these realms to whom the difference in the price of sugar is most sensibly felt in their morning and evening meals. / [66] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. CHAPTEK IV. ' THE HISTORY OF GREECE.' The actual composition of tlie * History of Greece '— such as it appeared in a published form in 1846 — was commenced in 1842. The preparation for the work may be shortly summed up thus : — First, in the reading, re-reading, and cogitation of the original sources and authorities, together with the study of the commentators, critics, and interpreters of the facts. For many years had he pondered the authors of classical Greece ; his interest not being limited to historical narrative, but extending to the literature for its own sake, and still more to the philosophy for its owm sake. His desire from the beginning was to realise not merely the events, but also the manners, habits, modes of life, and institutions, private as well as public. On all these matters he had already composed methodical and, as far as possible, exhaustive sketches. He had also systematically gone through a wide course of reading of the manners, habits, customs, institutions, and peculiarities of all other recorded nations, especially at the earlier stages of civilization. In his commonplace books and references he had a very great collection of such facts, and the ' History ' itself is strewn with illustrative allusions from that source. Of late years, still greater attention has been paid to this region of historical wealth ; and the available material has been considerably augmented; while novel inferences have been drawn from the experience thus brouo'ht to view. Mr. Grote possessed that essential quality of a historian — THE HISTORY OF GREECE. [67] the historical or narrative interest. In school days he devoured novels ; in later life the place of these was taken by histories and biographies relating to every nation and time. He felt and avowed the still more peculiar interest in the process of growth or evolution, whether in political insti- tutions, in literature, or in philosophy and science. The historical taste was thus with him a very wide and mixed susceptibility, and his narrative compositions became corre- spondingly varied in their interest. His earnest devotion to mental science, in all depart- ments — psychology, ethics, metaphysics, and logic — had no small share in the characteristic excellencies of liis historical compositions. Very few metaphysicians have become historians on the great scale ; the most conspicuous examples are Hume and James Mill. To these authors has always been attributed, among other merits, a peculiar subtlety in the dissection of motives and the exhibition of character. Metaphysical superiority is the cause (or, at all events, the evidence) of one great quality of the historian — the analytic aptitude or faculty. Science and analysis are nearly convertible terms. The chain of cause and effect in phenomena or events is enveloped and en- tangled in a mass of irrelevant or unconcerned accompani- ments. The scientific explanation of a fact is the separating of the essential from the casual antecedents ; an effort very severe and uncongenial to the untutored mind, being an- tagonistic to our habits and to many of our strongest feelings, which are mainly gratified by tacts in the lump or the undissected concrete. There is a favourite rhetorical comparison of history to the course of a noble river; the poet exhibits the river in the scenic grandeur of its totality ; bat if we wish to explain scientifically its different aspects — the volume of its waters, the speed of its current, its sedi- ment, its saline constituents, and its temperature — we must perform an operation repugnant to the natural mind; we must resolve the imposing aggregate into the abstractions of magnitude, gravity, force, solubility, and make a like /2 [68] CHARAOTEH AND WRITINGS. analysis of the rocks and soil in its bed and on its banks. This analysis is not indeed the consummation of scientific discovery, but it is the indispensable preparation ; the deeper, the correcter the analysis, the greater the chances of a profound and just explanation of the phenomena. The philosophical historian of the French Revolution has to disentano^le, in the antecedent history and condition of France, the productive from the unproductive circumstances — performing a conjoint operation of analysis and proof, for which, apart from other qualifications, few historians have had the requisite scientific steadiness. Moreover, the final terms of a historical analysis are facts and laws of the human mind ; in these, therefore, all historical explanation must centre ; and he that adds, to the ample experience of an observing man of the world, the precise handling of the psychologist, must be, of all others, the best fitted for the highest part of the historian's duties. Had Mr. Grote written only the * History,' a lengthened discourse might have been required to show that he was in no mean degree an accomplished and original psychologist and logician. The proofs might have been conclusively drawn from the ^ History,' but they would have been mostly inferential and indirect. In regard to psychology, or the science of mind strictly viewed, we could point to his studies on the influence of the feeliQo:s in matters of truth and false- hood, which studies gave the master-key to the legendary or mythical ingredients of the Grecian story. The corruption of the intellect by the emotions and passions was one of his earliest and most strongly iterated themes. Under logic proper we should naturally have to advert to his theory and standard of evidence, which was up to the severest demands of historical accuracy. This high standard, however, had various determining motives. He notices, in the preface, the growing strictness of historians in their exaction of evidence, and quotes individual instances. Special to himself was a severe regard to truth, as opposed alike to the false and to the vague. There can be nothing THE HISTORY OF GREECE. [69] deserving of the name of trutli without preciseness in the use of leading terms, and this condition is never lost sight of in Grote's writings. His early logical training bore this fruit; and at a later period he entered with avidity into the principles and methods of inductive evidence as ela- borated in the ' Logic ' of John Stuart Mill. His career as an English politician and member of Par- liament, during a great democratic struggle, was necessarily of the greatest value for understanding the free governments of antiquity. This has often been remarked upon as a point in his favour when compared with the erudite German professors, who had never *' learned from personal experience the nature of a popular deliberative body." Such experience, however, would have availed but little, had it been unaccom- panied with intense popular sympathies. The democracies of Greece had commended themselves to his ardent feeling:s for human improvement ; they were not always what he could have wished, though greatly in advance of anything that the world had seen before them, and of the greater number of the polities that came after them. Athens — the eye of Greece, Mother of arts and eloquence — Was the democracy by pre-eminence, the object of his special interest and aflection. He found (he used to say) many admirers of Athens, but no one possessed with a strong philo-Athenian sentiment. He avowed himself, at the outset of his work, as the historian of Grecian freedom ; the plan, as stated in his own words, was to " exhaust the free life of collective Hellas." For the ancient world and ancient modes of thinking, in some of their contrasts with the modern, he had a strong predilection ; and hence he turned Grecian studies to their proper end of correcting the one-sidedness of our prevailing notions and usages. This he esteemed the great recom- mendation of classical culture, and the motive for its being retained in general education. More especially did he [70] CHAEACTEK AND WRITINGS. regard tlie ancient ethics as an essential supplement of our modern views ; but, unfortunately^ we are precluded from knowing, except in a general way, to what extent and on what points. A rapid survey of the leading features of the ' History ' will enable us to note its characteristic merits, as settled by the judgment of competent critics, while alluding at the same time to the points whereon opinions are still divergent. As to the general effect, perhaps the most emphatic testimony was given by Mr. Mill, in these words : — " Though the statement has the air of an exaggeration, yet, after much study of Mr. Grote's book, we do not hesitate to assert, that there is hardly a fact of importance in Grecian history which was perfectly understood before his re-examination of it." The opening of the ^ History ' is marked by the peculiar mode of dealing with legendary Greece. The author had already published an article giving his views as to the origin of the Legends ; that paper is reprinted in the present volume, as containing illustrations not wholly superseded by the fuller handling in the first volume of the ' History.' I summarise his later positions, nearly in his own w^ords : — Having regard to the standard of evidence recognised for modern events, '^ I begin the real history of Greece with the first recorded Olympiad, or 776 B.C. To such as are accus- tomed to the habits once universal, and still .not uncommon, in investigating the ancient world, I may appear to be striking off one thousand years from the scroll of history ; but to those whose canon of evidence is derived from Mr. Hallam, M. Sismondi, or any other historian of modern events, I am well assured that I shall appear lax and credulous rather than exigent or sceptical. For the truth is, that historical records, properly so called, do not begin until long after this date ; nor will any man, who candidly considers the extreme paucity of attested facts for the cen- turies after 776 B.C., be astonished to learn that the state of Greece" for seven or more centuries, previous "cannot be described upon anything like decent evidence." THE HISTORY OF GREECE. [71] "The times which I thus set apart from the region of history are discernible only through a different atmosphere — that of epic poetry and legend. To confound together these disparate matters is, in my judgment, essentially un- philosophical. I describe the earlier times by themselves, as conceived by the faith and feeling of the first Greeks, and known only through their legends, without presuming to measure how much or how little of historical matter these legends may contain. If the reader blame me for not assist- ing him to determine this — if he ask me why I do not undraw the curtain and disclose the picture, I reply in the words of the painter Zeuxis, when the same question was addressed to him on exhibiting his master-piece of imitative art — ' The curtain is the picture.' What we now read as poetry and legend was once accredited history, and the only genuine history which the first Greeks could conceive or relish of their past time; the curtain conceals nothing behind, and cannot by any ingenuity be withdrawn. I undertake only to show it as it stands, not to efface, still less to re-paint, it. " Three-fourths of the two volumes now presented to the public are destined to elucidate this age of historical faith, as distinguished from the later age of historical reason : to exhibit its basis in the human mind — an omnipresent reli- gious and personal interpretation of nature ; to illustrate it by comparison with the like mental habit in early modern Europe ; to show its immense abundance and variety of narrative matter, with little care for consistency between one story and another : lastly, to set forth the causes which over- grew and partially supplanted the old epical sentiment and introduced, in the room of the literal faith, a variety of compromises and interpretations." The author's peculiarity lay in illustrating the origination of tradition, whether with or without foundation of fact, in the emotional tendencies of the mind. By no one had this mental operation been hitherto made fully apparent ; since his exposition, it has become a received doctrine of human [72] CHAKACTER AND WRITINGS. nature. '^ The influence of imagination an 1 feeling is not confined simply to the process of retouching, transferring, or magnifying narratives originally founded on fact ; it will often create now narratives of its own, without any such preliminary basis." Whenever any body of sentiment is widely prevalent, all incidents in conformity with that senti- ment are eagerly believed. If real incidents are not at hand, their place will be supplied by impressive fictions ; the perfect harmony of such fictions with the general feeling stands in place of testimony ; and to question them is to incur obloquy. In the innumerable religious legends — deriving their origin not from facts misreported, but from pious feelings pervading the society — not merely the inci- dents, but often even the personages, are unreal ; the gene- rating sentiment being conspicuously discernible, and pro- viding its ow^n matter as well as its own form. We have now the word " Myth " or mythus, to express not a mere fiction, falsification, or untruth, but a narrative shaped to suit a strong sentiment or feeling, and believed in solely through the influence of that feeling. In accordance with this view, the Historian occupies his first volume with detailing the chief legendary tales and narratives of Greece, first as regards the gods, and next as regards heroes and men : following a systematic order so as to connect each locality with its own legends. The two con- cluding chapters are devoted to the discussion of the Grecian myths. The one chapter takes them up as understood, felt, and interpreted by the Greeks themselves, and traces the altered state of the Grecian mind respecting them, from the unflinching credence of the early Greeks to the altera- tion of view following the influence of extended commerce and the development of physical science, together with the advanced ethical standard of later times. The subject is illustrated by the author's usual thoroughness and exhaustive learning, and the chapter, when read for the first time, is one to leave an indelible impression. The concluding chapter is "The Grecian Mythical View Compared with that of THE HISTORY OF GREECE. [73] Modern Europe." The author here pursues the illustration through the Middle Ages, adverting to the Legends of the Saints, the Eomances of Chivalry, the Teutonic and Scan- dinavian Epic, and our early English history. Taken in their proper character, the Grecian myths con- stitute an important chapter in the history of the Grecian mind, and of the human race. The faith of the Greeks in their historical narratives is as much subjective and peculiar as their faith in their religion ; the two are intimately con- joined, and cannot be separated without violence. Gods, heroes and men, religion and patriotism, matters divine, heroic, and human — were all woven together into one indivi- sible web, in which the threads of truth and reality, whatever they might originally have been, were not intended to be, and were not in fact, distinguishable. To realise to himself, and to bring before the reader, the religious feelings of the Greek mind at its different stages was regarded by Mr. Grote as an indispensable portion of his duty as a historian. He never loses an opportunity for this end ; and his success has been admitted. The work has been done once for all. On one point, however, subsequent inquirers have not coincided with him. He maintained, with emphasis, that we could not go back beyond the legends as they stand. "The legendary age had its antecedent causes and deter- mining conditions, but of these we know nothing, and we are compelled to assume it as a primary fact for the pur- pose of following out its subsequent changes. To conceive absolute beginning or origin is beyond the reach of our faculties ; we can neither apprehend nor verify anything beyond progress, or development, or decay — change from one set of circumstances to another, operated by some defi- nite combination of physical or moral laws. In the case of the Greeks, the legendary age, as the earliest in any way known to us, must be taken as the initial state from which this series of changes commences." This view is remark- ably characteristic of the author's thorough appreciation of. [74] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. and acquiescence in, the limitation of the human faculties. In resignation to the inevitable, at all points, he had effec- tually schooled himself; and the triumph of his discipline is best seen in matters of knowledire. The despair of ascending beyond the recorded legends has not been shared by all inquirers. Comparative philology has been invoked to show the connection between the Greek leo^ends and the Hindu mvtholoo:v; the names and functions of the deities have been found to be strikinelv allied. Again, the very incidents of legendary narrative are shown in various instances to be of wide-spread occurrence over different countries, pointing to some remote common orio'in. 3Ioreover, the attempt had often been made to assign a speculative origin to the polytheistic creed, in accordance with known laws and tendencies of the human mind. Comte's three stages have become familiar to the public mind, and were well known to Mr. Grote. An interestins: statement of the theoretical development of religious belief up to the point of the Grecian legends was given in Mr. Mill's review of the first and second volumes of the * History.' Since then, minute attention to the records of primitive societies has greatly advanced these speculations. Within the last few Years the writin2:s of Sir John Lubbock, Tvlor, and M'Lennau have thrown new light upon the stages antecedent to the Greeks. Had these works appeared before Mr. Grote wrote the early chapters, he would have studied them most carefully, and have extracted from them whatever satisfied his judg- ment as bearing on the anterior stages of religious belief. He was, however, slow to admit the sufficiency of the evi- dence for such theories : and at the time when he wrote there was nothing that he could rely upon for carrying him back bevond the stag:e of the leo;ends. One great advantage has been gained from his taking up this position, namely, perfect impartiality in representing the facts as they are actually recoi'ded. It is true that, even THE HISTORY OF GREECE. [75] when he had a theory to support, he was scrupulous to a degree in his statement of facts : yet, our satisfaction is here unalloyed by the possibility of suspicion. Consequently, the comparative mythologists and speculators can accept his rendering of Grecian facts as authentic data, of equal value with the original records; while his empirical generalities meet tlie other theorisers half way. I cannot help referring to one singular and undesigned coincidence between one of his generalities and a theory derived from a totally different region of facts. He remarks in the worship of the Greeks a concurrence of three things in the objects of worship, whether gods, demi-gods, or heroes — the tribal name, the deity worshipped, and the fact of descent : all this is conjoined in the " eponymos " of each tribe. The Herakleids, besides bearing the name, deified Herakles, and called themselves his descendants. Now Mr. M'Lennan has generalised the same coinci- dence under the name " totemism," derived from the word " totem," among the American Indians, absurdly rendered " medicine " by the early travellers. He shows that the " totem," which may be various in kind, but draws largely from the lower animals, is the tribal name, the ancestor, and the object of worship: and '• totemism," in the shape of animal worship more particularly, is traced by him as a phenomenon of wide-spread occurrence, and comprising a very large department of the religious worship of early nations. In the twentieth chapter of his work, Mr. Grote endea- vours to derive from the Homeric poems an account of the state of society in legendary Greece. The attempt had been often made ; still, in the author's treatment there is considerable freshness and many new suggestions. The triple political institution — hasileus (king), -houle (senate), agora (assembly) — he minutely examines, as the precursor of the democracies of later Greece. One of the favourite extracts of the reviewers is that passage where he traces to the infancy of the nation *' the employment of public [76] CHARACTEK AND WRITINGS. speaking as the standing engine of government and the proximate cause of obedience." He also takes great pains to illustrate the character of the moral sentiment in the ages depicted by Homer. The keynote is struck thus : — " There is no sense of obligation, then, existing between man and man, as such, and very little between each man and the community of which lie is a member ; such sentiments are neither operative in the real world nor present to the imaginations of the poets." Personal feelings either towards the gods, the king, or some near and known individual fill the whole of a man's bosom. While copiously illustrating, by citations from the his- tories of early society, the features and peculiarities of the Homeric Greeks, he still refrains from speculating on the anterior stages; and the remark already made, as to his voraciousness of rendering, is equally applicable here. In this department, too, much has been done to elucidate the condition of primitive man, but hitherto the researches have not suflSced to assign a situation immediately preceding that given in the Homeric poems. In a chapter on the internal structure of the Hiad and Odyssey, he maintains that, while the Odyssey possesses a unity throughout, the Hiad bears traces of the combination of two separate poems, one an Achilleid, having for its subject the wrath of Achilles, the other (Books 2-7 and 10) an addition converting the Achilleid into an Iliad. The evidence is drawn from the internal structure of the poem, a kind of evidence that he himself always held to be ex- tremely precarious. He accordingly treated his view as having merely a probability superior to any other. No part of the history, however, was more frequently dissented from by critics ; but though he perused all the hostile criticisms, he saw no sufficient reason for giving up his case. The entire compass of the Homeric field has been more recently surveyed by Mr. Gladstone, in an exceedingly care- ful and elaborate disquisition, entitled ' Studies on Homer and the Homeric Age.' He devotes one volume to the THE HISTOKY OF GREECE. [77] ethnology of the Greek races ; another to the religion and morals of the Homeric age ; in a third, he inquires into the polities, or political constitutions, compares the T^^ojans and Greeks, discusses the geography of the Odyssey, and expatiates on the artistic merits of Homer. On various points he comes into collision with Mr. Grote. He takes very high ground as to the historical value of Homer, main- taining that in regard to the religion, history, ethnology, polity, and life at large, his poems stand far above any later traditions; that of all the ages that have passed since Homer, not one has produced a more acute, accurate, and comprehensive observer ; and that he alone was imbued from head to foot with the spirit and the associations of the heroic time. He thinks that a great error has been committed in not distinguishing Homer by a broad line from all the other sources of legendary narrative — namely, Hesiod, the trage- dians and the minor Greek poets, the scattered notices of the historians, the antiquarian writers near the Christian era, and the scholiasts. He considers that Mr. Grote's treatment of the legends has countenanced this error, and he opens up for consideration the question whether the personality of Agamemnon and Achilles has no better root in history than that of Pelasgus, of Prometheus, or of Hellen ; and whether all these are no more than equal in credit to Ceres, Bacchus, or Apollo. While Mr. Grote regards as hopeless any inquiry into the ante-Hellenic Pelasgians, Mr. Gladstone undertakes to show, from Homer, that two distinct races appear on the stage, a superior and an inferior; the superior were the Hellenes, represented by the Greeks, the besiegers of Troy; the inferior, the Pelasgi, represented by the Trojans. The Hellenes culminated in Attica, the Pelasgians in Arcadia. The two races had distinctive aptitudes, and the Greek mind in its highest development combined the two. Mr. Gladstone's account of the religion consists in a minute examination of all the deities introduced by Homer. Starting from the idea that the Homeric theology is a cor- [78] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. ruption or defacement of the primitive Scriptural traditions, lie shows by what downward steps the true and pure idea of God became transformed into the imperfect deities of Homer. He distinguishes what he considers the traditive from the inventive element of the theogony. In passing from the theology to the morals, he replies with some warmth to Mr. Grote's remark that the Greek terms for good and evil {a: of a vote. Amono- other indica- tions he refers to the cheers of the people as a proof of their power ; for in every tolerably-regulated assembly the giving of applause distinguishes the body itself from mere strangers or spectators ; it being a truth common to every age that such applause constitutes a share in the business and con- tributes to the decision. Mr. Gladstone combats at length Mr. Grote's theory of THE HISTORY OF GREECE. [79] the double structure of the Iliad, resenting especially the suggestion of the possibility of double authorship. His reasonings are very subtle, and many of them are of a kind that might not be generally convincing ; yet the discussion is highly stimulating, opening up varied aspects of the poem and starting new problems. Legendary Greece together with the Homeric poems occupy the first volume of the ' History ' and nearly one half of the second. The author now changes the designation to — " Part II. — Historical Greece " — under which all his subsequent chapters are numbered. Not content with indicating his sense of the broad distinction between the legendary and the historical times by this very emphatic mode of shaping the titles, he performs the somewhat violent operation of transposing the Geography of Greece from its natural place at the outset of the work to the be^inuino' of Part II. He was aware of the awkwardness of the arrangement, and admitted that the legends, in common with the his- torical facts, were sus(;eptible of elucidation from the geo- graphy, but did not consider the artifice too much for marking the chasm between the legendary and the historical domain. The geographical sketch is careful and highly interesting ; it might have been advantageously enlarged ; the bearings of the geographical facts on the character, institutions, and history of the Greeks are by no means exhausted. An often-quoted passage, on the effect of the configuration of the Grecian territory on the political system and the intellec- tual development, is remarkable for tlie author's caution in not crediting physical influences with more than their legitimate worth. For explaining the many-sided superiority of Greece to the rest of the world, we must postulate, in the first instance, an inherent superiority of race. The scattered branches of the human family being, from what- ever causes, most unequally, as well as most variously, gifted in their natural organisation, some one people must be at the top. A favourable surrounding converts the small [80] CHARACTER AI^ID WRITINGS. primitive inequality into a divergence of careers so great as to seem wholly incompatible with a common origin. I quote the following summary from Mr. Mill : — " In the six concluding chapters of the second volume Mr. Grote comprises the sum of what is known respecting the early condition of those Grrecian states which have pro- perly no history prior to the Persian invasion, and brings down the history of tlie Peloponnesian Greeks to the age of Croesus and Pisistratus. The fragmentary nature of the information, and the conscientious integrity of the author, who scruples to supply the deficiency of certified facts by theory and conjecture, render these chapters, with one ex- ception, somewhat meagre. The exception is the chapter treating of the legislation of Lycurgus, the earliest Grecian event of first-rate historical importance." The chapter on the '^ Laws and Discipline of Lycurgus at Sparta" has a twofold interest. The main subject is the origin and character of that extraordinary system of public discipline which forms the point of departure of the action of Sparta in the vicissitudes of the Grecian story. The one-sided Spartan culture, with its astonishing results, was a favourite subject with the Greek philosophers ; and it will descend through all time as a unique manifestation of humanity. Mr. Grote has applied his analysing power to the phenomenon, and we can scarcely hope ever to extract from the materials a more thorough account than he has given us. The other point in the chapter is the examination of the evidence for one important item in the alleged reforms of Lycurgus — the equal division of the lands. Intrinsi- cally this is not incredible, considering what Lycurgus really effected; but being unmentioned by all the authors that were alive while the institutions of Sparta were still in force, and appearing for the first time in Plutarch, the evidence for it must be held as defective. After exhaus-' tively reviewing all the earlier authorities, Mr. Grote comes to inquire how the allegation could have sprung up in the age of Plutarch ; and here he is rewarded by a most feli- THE HISTORY OF GREECE. [81] citous application of his theory of the generation of the mythus. To all previous historians such a statement as Plutarch's seemed necessarily to contain some truth : to him the origin suggested itself apart from any vestige whatso- ever of underlying fact. It was fiction from first to last— '' the expression of some large idea and sentiment, so powerful in its action on men's minds at a given time as to induce them to make a place for it among the realities of the past." A situation actually occurred in the times of Agis III. (about 250 B.C.) when men's imaginations were heated to the proper pitch for fabricating a legend. The missing link is thus supplied, and the Lycurgian division of the lands of Sparta has taken its place among mythical creations. The second instalment of the * History ' — volumes three and four— appeared in 18i7. Two more volumes followed in 1849. The critique in the Edinburgh Review on these four volumes was by Sir George Cornewall Lewis. The third volume opens with a chapter entitled, " The Age of the Grecian Despots," one of the author's best con- tributions to political philosophy, as well as to Grecian history. It records the gradual change from the primitive political constitution of Homer — King, Council, and Assembly — to the advent of Democracy. The early stages are obscure. The Homeric king, strong in his divine right and personal ascendency, appears to have been superseded by his council, as an oligarchy, who acted in a body for legislative purposes, while one of their number, by rotation or otherwise, headed the executive. It was out of these oligarchies that there came forth, between 650 and 500 B.C., the class of rulers termed Despots, who got possession of the supreme power in various ways, but exercised it without check or control, and often with such tyrannous excesses that their name became odious in Greece. While in some states, as Sparta, the ancient hereditary king was maintained, his authority being withdrawn and himself superseded, except as a vene- rable relic, by more modern creations, in the greater part of Greece the kingship disappeared. 9 [82] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. This whole chapter is full of interesting political reflec- tions as to the historical chans^es in the institution of monarchy. The remarks on the British Constitution as it would have appeared to Aristotle, are highly suggestive and curious. Two chapters are devoted to the early history of Athens ; the first recounting its political constitution and history (so far as ascertainable) before Solon ; the second embracing the legislation of Solon. On this last subject the author bestows especial attention. The reforms of Solon were called forth by great internal dissension, produced by the misery of the poorer population. This misery seemed to have been greatly owing to the workings of the law of debtor and creditor, to which Solon applied the relief of the sponge, with a palliation to the creditor by debasing the money standard. Mr. Grote is in his element in the exposition and vindi- cation of these strong measures, and gives us a valuable episode on the prejudices entertained in antiquity against lending money at interest. Eeviewing at length the various chancres made by Solon, he corrects the confusion that afterwards prevailed between these and the institutions of subsequent legislators. Solon, indeed, laid the foundations of Athenian democracy ; yet his institutions were not demo- cratical, but oligarchical. The concluding eulogy on the legislator himself is highly illustrative of the author's own type of human nobleness. '' He (Solon) represents the best tendencies of his age, combined with much that is per- sonally excellent ; the thirst for enlaro^ed knowledsfe and observation, not less potent in old age than in youth ; the conception of regularised popular institutions, departing sensibly from the type and spirit of the governments around him, and calculated to found a new character in the Athenian people ; a genuine and reflecting sympathy with the mass of the poor, anxious not merely to rescue them from the oppressions of the rich, but also to create in them habits of self-relying industry ; lastly, during his temporary possession of a power altogether arbitrary, not merely an THE HISTORY OF GREECE. [83] absence of all selfish ambition, but a rare discretion in seizing the mean between conflicting exigencies." Before the death of Solon occurred the usurpation of the despot Pisistratus, which Solon vainly but courageously- resisted. The narrative of his reign is interrupted for many- chapters by a survey of the Asiatic G-reeks (Ionic, ^iEolic, and Dorian) and the natives of Asia Minor, with whom the Greeks became connected. A chapter is devoted to the Lydians, Modes, Cimmerians, Scythians ; one to the Phoe- nicians, one to the Egyptians, one to the growth of Carthage. The author exhausts all available sources in rendering complete his account of these various nations, not merely for their intrinsic historical interest, but for their influence on the Greek mind and history ; this being very notable in the case of Egypt. Then comes Grecian colonisation in the westward direction^ — Italv, Sicilv, and Gaul: the Sicilian settlements being more peculiarly mo- mentous in the succeeding events, while celebrity attached to some of the cities of the Italian Greeks. In his review. Sir G. C. Lewis remarks that " Greek colonisation is dis- cussed with remarkable success." Other chapters take up the Akarnanians, Epirots, Illyrians, Macedonians, Paeonians, Thracians, and Greek colonies in Thrace. The survey is completed by a chapter on Kyrene, Barka, and Hesperides. A short but interesting chapter (xxviii.) deals with the Pan-Hellenic Festivals — Olympic, Pythian, Nemean, and Isthmian ; investigating their origin, character, and effect on the Greek mind. These are severally brought before the reader in their most striking and picturesque details. The Lyric Poetry is next passed in review; from which, singularly enough, there is an insensible transition to the constellation of Wise Men (usually called Seven), the begin- ners of Greek Philosophy. In continuation of these is the commencement of Greek prose. The same chapter em- braces the rise of Grecian art. A chapter on the Government of Peisistratus and his sons at Athens contains the episode of Harmodius and Aristogeiton, 9 2 [84] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. on which the author's commentaries are fresh and interest- ing, and contain an additional application of his law of the o:rowth of le2:end. The expulsion of the Peisistratus family is the signal for the next sfreat advance in democracy, under Cleisthenes. Mr. Grote has the merit of clearing up this great revolutioD, and of teaching its unspeakable importance to the future of Athens. Amono- the institutions ascribed to Cleisthenes i& the ostracism, ^yhich is for the first time rationally ex- plained as a great constitutional sedative, at a period when the State could not afibrd the presence of restless intriguers. It was a mild substitute for impeachment; and Sir George Lewis thinks that had it existed in England, in the time of Charles I., it mi^rht have o:ot rid of Strafford and Laud without the necessity of sendino; them to the block. The historian's concludiuo; reflections on the reforms of Cleisthenes stir the heart like the sound of a trumpet. Never weary of the them^ of human liberty, he re-toiiches it on each occasion with fresh and irlowinir colours. Wliat Herodotus puts in the front rank of the advantages of democracy — " its most splendid name and promise " — is no mere rhetoric, but a real power, the source of all the ex- ploits that have conferred immortal renown on the Athenian name. Four chapters contain the events preparatory to the gTcat Persian strus^ele, and brins: it down to Marathon, " the narrative of which cannot be read, for the himdredth time, without deep emotion." The rise of the Persian empire, under its founder Cyrus : the succession of Cambvses and of Darius ; the Ionic revolt and its supjDression by Darius ; the invasion of the mainland of Greece, with a special view to be avenged on Athens ; the encounter at Marathon — all belong to the purely narrative work of the historian. After an interruption, to be noticed presently, he continues, in five chapters more, the invasion of Xerxes, which led to the immortal conflicts at Tiiermopyl^, Artemisium, Salamis, Platsea, and Mycale. " Marathon and, for the most part, THE HISTOEY OF GREECE. [85] Salamis and Mycale are the work of Athens ; Thermopylse, and to a great extent Platsea, of Sparta. By the courage, intelligence, and moral superiority in contending against overwhelming numbers which the Greeks exhibited at this great crisis, they have earned the imperishable gratitude of all civilised nations." (G. C Lewis.) We ought not to pass the chapter on Marathon without some reference to the concluding portion, which is occupied in dealing with the charges made against the Athenians for their ill-treatment of Miltiades after his great services. The vindication is in Mr. Grote's very best manner. Extenuating nothing, he shows that the conduct of Miltiades that led to his punishment was reprehensible in the extreme, that his past services were fairly taken into account, in the only admissible way, to wit, in mitigation of the penalty. It was from no fickleness in the people that they turned against him ; they had been most lavish in their gratitude after the great victory, and their change of mind was due to an adequate cause. It was a weakness in the Greeks to be too much carried away by their impulses of gratitude for dis- tinguished services. With this fitted in, often to fatal re- sults, another weakness (perhaps having the same root in the mind) which Mr. Grote deploringly signalises. '^ There is no feature," he says, " that more largely pervades the impres- sible Grecian character than a liability to be intoxicated and demoralised by success ; there was no fault from which so few eminent Greeks were free ; there was hardly any danger against which it was at once so necessary and so difficult for the Grecian governments to take security, especially the democracies, where the manifestations of enthusiasm were always the loudest." In a chapter (xxxvii.) introduced during the panic of the Persians after the defeat of Marathon, he takes occasion to notice the great Ionic philosopher, Thales, and his suc- cessors ; and recounts at full the views, character, and political position of Pythagoras in the colony of Italian Greeks at Croton, in Italy. This is the author's first contribution to [86] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. the rise and progress of Greek philosophy, which he included in his original plan of the ' History of Greece.' Tlie conclusion of the Persian repulse is followed by a chapter on Sicily, whose history is resumed with the brazen- bull despot, Phalaris of Agrigentum, and continued through a series of despots in the different cities, to the establishment of popular governments throughout the island. Eeturning to Athens, the historian enters on a new phase of his undertaking — the growth of the Athenian empire, as a consequence of the Persian war. I shall here again borrow, unfortunately for the last time, the summary expressions of Sir George Lewis : — " The imperial rule of Athens was, as Mr. Grote has shown, exercised, on the whole, with moderation. There were no very unusual obligations imposed on the subject state; and so long as it was quiet, and submitted patiently to its condition of dependence, it had little to com- plain ot But the loss of independence was a bitter privation to the Greek freeman, and hence the dominion of Athens rested ultimately on force or fear. Her own orators and statesmen accordingly always represent her as standing in the same relation to her dependent cities as a despot to his individual subjects; and openly proclaim the necessity of using towards them the terrible maxims of Greek despotism. Hence, revolt was summarily punished, as in the memorable case of Mitylene ; while, on the other hand, the proceedings of Brasidas, in Thrace, show that much persuasion and cajolery, backed by the presence of a Lacedemonian army, might be necessary in order to induce an Athenian dependent city to throw off its allegiance." "The history of these subject-allies of Athens — of the transition from a voluntary hegemony or headship, to a com- pulsive imperial rule — has never been so well written, or half so well explained, as by Mr. Grote." One of the model chapters of the 'History' is (chapter xlvi.) the account of the changes in the Athenian constitution under Pericles ; the final development of the democracy, as it stood during all the remainder of Athenian freedom. The THE HISTORY OF GREECE. [87] central fact of the change was the instituting of the Dikas- teries, whereby the judicial power was finally separated from the executive. Mr. Grote reviews in an exhaustive way the momentous bearings of this change, and shows that every feature in the new system had a significance entirely over- looked in the usual rough-and-ready criticism of Athenian institutions under the guidance of the comic poets. He makes the happiest use of our modern trial by jury in the elucidation of these Athenian courts, and strikingly remarks, especially w^ith reference to the large number of the dikasts (several hundreds in one court), that there was at that time no other conceivable mode of bringing to justice rich and powerful criminals. The mighty drama — the Peloponnesian War — occupies nearly three volumes of the original issue (vi., vii., viii.) The story is related with all the author's narrative power; his sympathies are deeply engaged throughout the memorable vicissitudes of those twenty-nine years. The splendid bursts and temporary triumphs of the doomed heroine irradiate the deepening gloom. In the course of this war, Mr. Grote has introduced many of his novel points of view, as regards both characters and incidents. As might be supposed, his estimate of Pericles is lofty, it is also in the details peculiarly his own. " Pericles," he remarks, "is not to be treated as the author of the Athenian character; he found it with its very marked positive characteristics and susceptibilities, among which those that he chiefly brought out and improved were the best." He repressed the lust of conquest and regularised the democratic movement; and, most of all, did he favour the pacific and intellectual development — rhetoric, poetry, arts, philosophical research, and recreative variety. Agri- culture, trade, the means of defence, were all enormously advanced during his time; and he is identified with the clothing of Athens in her imperial mantle of architectural decoration. His love of philosophy, and his studies under the philosopher Anaxagoras, are carefully quoted in his favour. [88] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. Of the cliaracters that have to be drawn in the narrative of the struggle, the most trenchant, and yet irresistibly just, is the sketch of Nikias, the principal cause of the ruin of Athens. The contrast between Pericles and Nikias could have come from no other hand. The mistaken confidence in a man of even mediocrity, fi'om the lustre of his religious professions and practice, and the extreme decorum of his private life, coupled with pecuniary liberality and incor- ruptibility, shows the Athenian public to be not so far removed from human nature in our own time. Sydney Smith's picture of Perceval is a historical parallel. Cleon, the leather-seller, is extricated from the hands of both Aristophanes and Thucydides. Oar historian's warm admiration for the greatest historical authority of the ancient world does not prevent him from discerning the occasions when bias crept into his narrative, and one of these is the picture of Cleon. The leather-seller had his faults, and expiated with his life the weakness of his judgment in mili- tary affairs. He had the qualities that in all countries of free debate go to make a great opposition speaker ; but the charges of Thucydides, amplified by Aristophanes, are treated by Mr. Grote as inconsistent Nvith themselves and contrary to evidence. Moreover, there were critical moments when Cleon, in Mr. Grote's opinion, did eminent public service. Alcibiades necessarily occupied a large share of attention during these trying events. He contributed more than any other man to plunge the Athenians into the disastrous expe- dition to Syracuse ; and more than any man, after Nicias, to turn that adventure into ruin, and the consequences of it into still greater ruin. Yet, he w^as never once defeated either by land or by sea ; in new situations he was never wanting. On the w^hole we shall find few men in whom eminent capacities for action and command are so thoroughly marred by an assemblage of bad moral qualities as in Alcibiades, In a remarkable eulogy on the Spartan Callicratidas, Mr. Grote does honour to an enemy of Athens, on the high grounds of his moral superiority to his age and nation, as THE HISTORY OF GKEECE. [89] shown in declaring that, so long as he was in command, not a single free Greek should be reduced to slavery if he could prevent it. The grandeur and sublimity of this proceeding was without a parallel in Grecian history. But Mr. Grote is careful to guard his admiration, for the allies would make the reasonable remark — " If ^ve should come to be Conon's prisoners, he will not treat us in this manner." " Recijprocity is essential to moral observances, public or private, and doubt- less Callicratidas felt a w^ell-grounded confidence, that two or three auspicious examples would sensibly modify the future practice on both sides. But some one must begin by setting such examples, and the man who does begin, having a posi- tion that gives reasonable chance' that others will folloiv, is a hero." One of the most extraordinary incidents in Athenian history was the mutilation of the Hermse, or half-statues of the god Hermes, which stood in vast numbers in all parts of Athens. One night all these statues were mutilated and defaced by unknown hands. The profanation excited a ferment of feeling, which historians have usually treated as exaggerated and absurd. Mr. Grote corrects this notion, by his juster appreciation of the religious sentiments of the Greeks. He had given notice, in the preface to his first volume, that this incident would be a testing case of a historian's "entering into the way in which the Greeks con- nected their stability and security with the domiciliation of the gods in the soil ; " and his own handling has amply com- plied with the test. Equally happy and convincing is the explanation given of one of the melancholy acts of the Athenian public, the con- demnation of the ten generals after the battle of Arginusse, a victory to Athens deplorable from the loss of Callicratidas. Mr. Grote reviews the case in all its particulars, as if he w^ere the judge in a supreme court of appeal. He shows that the accusation against the generals was proceeding in due form, and might have been decided with perfect justice, but for the occurrence of a grand family solemnity of the Ionic race, [90] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. the Apaturia (our Christmas in an intensified form), during which the empty places made in the family circles by the recent battle, led to excited reflection on the culpable neglect of the generals to perform the obsequies to the slain. The trial was resumed under this excitement. The formali- ties provided by the constitution for securing a fair trial were violently set aside (Socrates alone of the presiding officials daring to withstand the current), and the generals were condemned. "It was an act of violent injustice and illegality, deeply dishonouring the men that passed it and the Athenian character generally." It was long and bitterly repented. Much as the subject had been discussed, Mr. Grote was the first to perceive in the incidents of an Athenian Christmas, an adequate explanation of the vindictive pro- ceeding. Another remarkable event in the war is the setting up of the oligarchy of tlie Four Hundred. This is the subject of a thrillins: narrative, and also furnishes additional illustra- tions of the Athenian democracy ; and, not least, of the extra- ordinary respect for constitutional forms, which was the rvle, while the fatality just mentioned was the exception, in the best times of Athens. The naval fight at -^gospotami ended the twenty-nine years' combat between Athens and Sparta. Athens was ruined. The Spartan conqueror is master of the city, de- stroys its material defences, sets up the oligarchy known as the Thirtv Tvrants, whose wholesale executions did not suffice to uphold it. The democracy is again restored. With deep satisfaction the historian depicts their lenity towards the usurpers — both the Four Hundred and the Thirty — as contrasted with the cruelties thev had suffered at the hands of the oligarchs. The respect to the rights of property was an equally honourable distinction of the democratic rule. Our author leads us to the end of the restless career of Alcibiades, and then indulges in a pause, which, however, is only to enter on a campaign in another field. Chapter Ixvii. is entitled, " The Drama, Rhetoric and Dialectic, THE HISTORY OF GREECE. [91] the Sophists:'' the real interest of the chapter being con- centrated in the last head. A most offensive odour had been imparted to these men; and the grounds of it are now challenged for the first time. The charges are gone over point for point, and confronted with a broadside of destructive facts, for ever silencing the calumniators of the unfortunate Sophists. The present chapter is generally con- sidered to have done the work : but, we shall not see the last, nor the most curious part of the case, till we come to the " Aristotle." The succeeding chapter is equally exciting in its origi- nality — the account of Socrates. The author found here a vent to discharge his very strongest impulses — the love of free inquiry, the reprobation of the tyranny of sentiment in the human mind, the delight in the self-acting judgment of the individual ; and he followed out the opening with his usual energy. In the story of Socrates he does justice to the sublimity and the pathos of the circumstances attending the trial, and measures out strict justice to the Athenian people, who were on their trial no less than Socrates. But his greatest interest centred in the Socratic cross- questioning, an unparalleled phenomenon in the history of thought. I well remember his conversation in the heat of composing this chapter ; his astonishment at the invention of such a weapon, and his belief that if it could be resumed in any shape, it might still have an extraordinary potency in quickening independent thought. These two chapters on the Sophists and Socrates closed the eighth volume. A critic in the Times gave utterance to the opinion that the work was now virtually closed ; as if the remaining narrative could furnish no equal displays of the author's originality, or impart no new surprise. There might be a momentary plausibility in the supposition ; yet the subsequent volumes did not confirm the critic's judg- ment. The ninth volume opened with three long chapters on the famous expedition of the Ten Thousand Greeks. The [92] CHAT^ACTER AND WRITINGS. author carefully recounts every turn of this memorable expe- dition, which did not effect its purpose, but yet taught the contemporary world the impotence of the Persian land force, while possessing an undying interest as a display of Athenian qualities and accomplishments. It "exemplifies the dis- cipline, the endurance, the power of self-action and adapta- tion, the susceptibility of influence from sjpeecli and discussion ^ the combination of the reflecting obedience of citizens with the mechanical regularity of soldiers, which confer such immortal distinction on the Hellenic character." Now it was the Athenian democracy, and its allied institutions, of which not the least important was the schooling of the rhetors and sophists, which raised men able to sway the minds of others by speech, and educated the mass of citizens to listen to reasons and follow prudential guidance. This fact was never shown to better advantage than in the difficulties of that remarkable expedition, and in the way that they were met and overcome by the oratory of Xenophon ; the persuasive- ness of which essentially consisted in a series of appeals to the self-regarding forethought of the audience. The Spartans were undoubtedly great on the field; yet the salvation of the Oyreian force was chiefly due to qualities that were not Spartan but Athenian. The author avows his strong engrossment and interest in the proceedings of these mercenaries. In a private letter at the time, to Sir George Lewis, he describes himself as at work on the ' Anabasis,' and " finds the day too short." The Lacedemonian empire, in its brief tenure of power, falls next to be described. Greece now saw the merits of the Athenian supremacy in a new light. The Spartan tyranny was too hot to last, and it soon met with a crushing reverse, under the Thebans and Epaminondas. The recital of this great Nemesis is a cheering and brilliant ray after the deep gloom of Syracuse and u3Egospotanii. In regard to the illustrious Theban, Mr. Grote cannot add to, or take from, the admiration of all succeeding times ; but his por- traiture, as usual, contains fresh and characteristic touches. THE HISTORY OF GREECE. [93] As in the case of Solon and Pericles, we are told that Epaminondas, in addition to all the education of an accom- plished Theban citizen, sought with eagerness the conversa- tion of the philosophers -within his reach, and came under the influence of two that had been companions of Socrates. In this way, he both enlarged his intellectual grasp and, like Pericles, emancipated himself from that superstitious dread of signs and omens that had enslaved so many Grecian commanders. His eloquence was effective even against the best Athenian opponents. The combination of such great capacity with a modest and unambitious disposition was a rare exception to the prevailing forwardness and self-esteem of Greeks generally. Nor was he less remarkable for the gentleness of his political antipathies, the repugnance to harsh treatment of conquered enemies, and the refusal to mingle in intestine bloodshed. The prowess of Epaminondas left the Spartans helpless, and enabled Athens to regain a certain measure of her old ascendency. Nineteen chapters, occupying the bulk of two volumes, are devoted to the bringing about of this mighty result. But the historian, in a few significant sentences, strikes the delighted reader with a cold shudder of appre- hension and foreboding. The recovery of the Chersonese by Athens, which was the moment of her maximum of return- ing greatness, almost exactly coincided with the revolt among her principal allies, named the Social War, and with the accession of Philip of Macedon. *^ At the opening of my ninth volume, after the surrender of Athens, Greece was under the Spartan empire. Its nume- rous independent city-communities were more completely regimented under one chief than they had ever been before, Athens and Thebes being both numbered among the fol- lowers of Sparta. " But the conflicts recounted in these volumes (during an interval of forty-four years — 404-3 B.C. to 360-59 B.C.) have wrought the melancholy change of leaving Greece more disunited, and more destitute of presiding Hellenic [94] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. authority, than she had been at any time since the Persian invasion. Thebes, Sparta, and Athens had all been engaged in weakening each other ; in which, unhappily, each has been more successful than in strengthening herself. The maritime power of Athens is now indeed considerable, and may be called very great, if compared with the state of degradation to which she had been brought in 403 B.C. But it will presently be seen how unsubstantial is the foundation of her authority, and how fearfully she has fallen off from that imperial feeling and energy which ennobled her ancestors under the advice of Pericles. " It is under these circumstances, so untoward for defence, that the aggressor from Macedonia arises." The historian now turns to Sicilv, unmentioned since the Syracusan catastrophe. The first of the Sicilian chapters brings the Carthaginians on the stage, and recounts the fall of the Gelonian dynasty and the rise of the elder Dionysius. Another chapter is devoted to this noted personage, whose career is a model of the "Despot's progress." A third chapter completes his terrible reign of thirty-eight years. All the power of Carthage was arrayed against him, but he had an effective ally in the pestilence. At the moment of his death, Dionysius boasted of having left his dominion " fastened by chains of adamant, " sustained by a large body of mercenaries, well trained and well paid, by impregnable fortifications in the islet of Ortygia, by four hundred ships of war, by immense magazines of arms and military stores, and by established intimidation over the minds of the Syracusans. He was succeeded by his elder son Dionysius the younger ; but a far higher part in the government was taken by Dion, brother-in-law of the elder Dionysius. An entirely new and unique interest attaches to the joint careers of these two men. The philosopher Plato had gained an ascendency over the mind of Dion, and was pressed by him to take a part in re-organising the government of Syracuse. Three different visits did the philosopher pay to Syracuse, one abrupt and unsatisfactory, in the time of the elder •THE HISTORY OP GREECE. [95] despot ; a second and third, with better omens, in the time of the youDger. On this intimacy between Plato and Dion Mr. Grote dwells at some length, regretting the impracticable temper and views of the philosopher, as throwing away the chance of an interesting experiment in , politics. The two masters — king and minister — became alienated ; Dion is banished, lives at Athens, his property being first allowed him and then withheld. He collects a small armament, invades and raises Sicily against the despot ; plays a really noble part for a time, and shows intellectual and moral qualities worthy of the pupil of a lofty philosophy. He gains the day, is master of Syracuse, but collapses into ignominious blundering, instead of achieving an illustrious name as the liberator of Sicily. Accordingly, the work has to be done over again. A man of higher mould, one of the upper ten of Grecian commanders, is sent from Corinth to the Syracusans in their distress. This is Timoleon, whose home life at Corinth was already remarkable for the act of killing his own brother who had made himself despot. Mr. Grote does not fail to turn this preliminary incident to the edification of us moderns, in whom he remarks the sentiment of family covers a larger proportion of the field of morality,. as compared with obligations towards country, than it did in ancient times. The hazardous enterprise succeeds through Timoleon's bravery, his skilful plans, his quickness of movement, coupled with extraordinary good fortune. He speedily gains posses- sion of Syracuse. He could have easily and even plausibly become despot ; instead of which he determines at once to pull down the nest of all the previous despotisms — the strong- hold of Ortygia. Very soon he has to meet a vast Cartha- ginian armament, which he utterly defeats with inferior numbers. He clears Sicily of enemies and despots. Finally, he lays down his power at Syracuse, spending his life in retirement, and acting only as an adviser in emergencies. Epaminondas had been his model, and, if he could not be said to improve upon that original, he varied the noble type. [96] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. HaviDg done due honour to the Sicilian hero, the history now reverts to Athens. The dreary tale of ineffectual re- sistance to the onward tread of the Macedonian conquerors is still relieved by flashes of heroism and genius. After all that Athens had suffered, and after the dis- union among the Grecian states, the new hazards from a great military neighbour like Philip of Macedon were serious indeed. The spirit of Athens was yet equal to ordinary efforts, and there came forward one man who, as an orator, political leader, and diplomatist, has had no superior, if he ever had an equal. But the ability of Demos- thenes at home was unsupported by any corresponding generalship in the field. The presence now of Epaminondas in Greece might have nipped Macedonian conquest in the bud. The Athenian general Iphicrates had displayed powers equal to the occasion, but, owing to a personal quarrel in the beginning of the Social War, he and Timotheus, another general of ability, were lost to Athens. The agency of corruption was extensively employed by Philip: he could always gain partisans in every popular assembly in Greece — one of the unavoidable weaknesses of popular government. The Athenians were cursed with a new incubus, different from Nikias, but not less fatal — the incorruptible and plain-spoken Phokion. Mr. Grote takes the measure of Phokion's deserts, and credits him with a large share of the ruined fortunes of his country. Athens became at last demoralised as regarded one of her capital virtues : her citizens had contracted a growing reluctance to personal military service. Many adventurers were now to be bought, like the Ten Thousand Greeks, and to these mercenaries unavoidable operations were mainly entrusted ; but they also involved expense. " The energy of the Periklean Athenian of 431 B.C. had been crushed in the disasters closing the Peloponnesian war, and had never again revived. The Demosthenic Athenian of 360 B.C. had, as it were, grown old. Pugnacity, Pan-Hellenic championship, and the love of enterprise, had died within him. He was a quiet, home- THE HISTORY OF GREECE. [97] keeping, refined citizen, attached to the democratic constitu- tion, and executing with cheerful pride his ordinary city- duties under it ; but immersed in industrial or professional pursuits, in domestic comforts, in the impressive manifesta- tions of the public religion, in the atmosphere of discussion and thought, intellectual as well as political. To renounce all this for foreign and continued military service, he con- sidered as a hardship not to be endured, except under the pressure of danger near ^nd immediate." It was the glory of Demosthenes to struggle all his life against this declen- sion of public spirit, and to be able to whip it up to occa- . sional efforts ; it was the merit of Phocion to pander to it and indulge it, to furnish it with justification and excuse, when wrought upon by his younger rival. The disastrous and disgraceful betrayal of the Phokians in 346 B.C., one of the bad turning-points in the contest with Philip, and the silence of Demosthenes at the opportune moment, are severely commented on, and yet too well ac- counted for, by our historian. I cite this, as one of many instances, with a view to show how far he was from glossing the real weaknesses of the Athenian democracy, and also to prepare the way for a closing remark as to his handling of Athens throughout. I attribute to the thoroughly scientific and logical cast of Grote's mind, in conjunction with his wide knowledge of political facts, the novelty and the soundness of his views as to the governments of Greece, whether democratical or otherwise. There were many floating allegations as to the workings of these governments, some of them sober although inadequate, others wholly uncertified by evidence and biassed by partisanship. By careful scrutiny of the au- thorities, he ascertained, so far as possible, what was true and what was false; how far the aspersions of the democracies and the praise of despots and oligarchs was well founded. This was a matter of historical evidence. But, as I remarked at the outset, there followed a second and more difficult operation— a truly scientific, analytic, and logical procedure h [98] CHAEACTER AND WRITINGS. —to assign the proper causes of effects that were proved to have taken place. Here a historian is constantly misled, in the same manner as the everyday politician, by mere co- incidences, which he is tempted to pronounce cause and effect. While many persons professing to be educated are disposed to resolve all the peculiar differences between American and English habits into the difference in the form of government of the two countries, it will seem very natural to attribute all the faults and misfortunes of Athens to her democracy alone. It is the province of a scientific or logical discipline to raise the student above this level, and teach him by what arts mere coincidences can be eliminated and genuine causation established. The Baconian method of varying the circumstances, improved upon in the experi- mental philosophy of the last two centuries, has to be applied to historical events, and has to be accommodated to the peculiarities of the case. When people say democracy did so and so, oligarchy so and so, the logician asks, among other things, has the alleged effect of democracy been always present in democracies, and always absent from the other forms of government? This is not conclusive of the point, but it is enough to dissipate a host of silly assertions. Then again, in political cause and effect, there must always be shown some natural tendency, growing out of the laws of the human mind, in an alleged cause to produce the alleged consequences ; this is to follow out what is called the deductive method in logic. Half of the twelfth and concluding volume is occupied with the conquests of Alexander the Great, first in Greece, and next in Asia. " Apart from the transcendent merits of Alexander as a soldier and a general, some authors give him credit for grand and beneficent views on the subject of imperial government, and for intentions highly favourable to the improvement of mankind." Mr. Grote &ees " no ground for adopting this opinion. As far as we can venture to anticipate what would have been Alexander's future, we see nothing in prospect except years of ever-repeated THE HISTOEY OF GKEECE. [99J aggression and conquest, not to be concluded until he had traversed and subjugated all the inhabited globe. The ac- quisition of universal dominion was the master passion of his soul." He could have consolidated nothing. His best administrative device was the imitation of the Persian satrapies, with Macedonians as his instruments. He was neither Macedonian nor Greek in sentiment. The sub- stitute for nationality of feeling was an exorbitant self- estimation inflamed by success into the belief of divine parentage, which entitled him to treat all mankind as subjects under the common sceptre to be wielded by himself. Hel- lenic in genius, he was Oriental in purpose. At the close of the narrative of Alexander's career, the reader will find a careful estimate of the civilising influence of Greece upon Asia, following on Alexander's conquests, through the immediate agency of his successors. Hellenism, properly so called, never passed over into Asia. All that did pass was a faint and partial resemblance of it, carrying the superficial marks of the original. A great number of indi- vidual Greeks found employment in the service, military and civil, of the Greco-Asiatic kings. Important social and political consequences turned upon the diffusion of the lan- guage, but the Hellenised Asiatic was still a foreigner, with Grecian speech, exterior varnish, and superficial manifes- tations. The world, as a whole, was a loser by the dis- appearance of the genuine article and the substitution of this spurious product. After the narrative of Alexander's exploits, two chapters close the account of Grecian affairs at home. Stirring pas- sages bestrew these chapters, and the author's characteristic handling crops out on notable occasions : not the least re- markable, perhaps, is the scene of Phocion's condemnation. But the end draws near. Demosthenes is sacrificed. Athens passes under an oligarchy ; she is a political nullity. The countrymen of Aristeides and Pericles have fallen into degrading servility and suppliant king-worship. "An his- torian accustomed to the Grecian world as described by h 2 / [100] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. Herodotus, Thucydides, and Xenophon, feels that the life has departed from his subject, and, with sadness and humiliation, brings his narrative to a close." A chapter on the Sicilian and Italian Greeks ends the eventful narrative. The style of the '^History' has had a full share of criticism. Great merits have been conceded to it, while certain defects have been taken notice of. The author's character admits of being illustrated by the peculiarities of his language. Endowed with a great verbal memory, passing his life in the company and conversation of cultivated and refined society, well-read in English literature, he could not but attain a full command of the best English diction. His taste and resources were still farther improved by his familiarity with the choice literature of five other languages, Greek, Latin, French, German, Italian. He keenly appre- ciated the helleS'Iettres ; they constituted part of his pleasures all through life. It does not seem that he imitated, in his early compo- sitions, any one model. He contracted his own ideal of effective composition, which was, first of all, to be thoroughly intelligible ; next, to be forcible and pointed ; and, lastly, to be ele2:ant and refined. He had a few mannerisms, but no affectation. His vocabularv inclined to an excess of classical words, by which he gained superior precision and occasional terse- ness. He coined a good many words from Latin and Greek, such as autonomy, hegemony, gens, phratry, dikastery, hop- lite, demus, most of which are admitted as necessities, while several have been deemed superfluous. His compounds with '^ self " are characteristically numerous : self-agency^ self-sufficing, self-acting, self-judging, &c. Of the figures of Ehetoric, he freely indulged in similes and metaphors, of which he had a good command. His only other figurative device was the manipulation of abstract nouns and adjectives for brevity : — as " a standing protest against forward affirmation," " dilatory tactics," ^^ mature divine efficiency," " the negative vein." The bolder figures THE HISTORY OF GEEECE. [101] — epigram, hyperbole, interrogation, climax, are scarcely ever used. He has one notable epigram for the myth — *'a past that never was present." Antithesis, or pointed balance, so abundant in Macaulay, is entirely wanting. His sentences are generally simple and intelligible in arrangement; sometimes periodic, but more commonly loose. They are tolerably, but not studiously, various in plan ; and long and short are freely intermingled. Their flow is easy and unaffected. Of the expository qualities of style, precision and per- spicuity took precedence. Extreme simplicity, or the being intelligible to the lowest capacity through the employment of homely and familiar phrases, was not aimed at. As regards the emotional qualities, he could, on occasions, command strength and pathos alike, and both impart their charm to the * History.' Humour he never sought to attain. His touches of high poetic elegance, if not numerous, are sometimes exquisite in quality. The chief complaint against the style generally is that it is not continuously artistic ; and this must be ad- mitted. The ' remark is also made that, in the distribution of the materials, the author allows the discussions, au- thorities, and quotations, to hang like a weight on the narrative ; that he has both repetitions and dislocations. To all which the reply is, that his mind was occupied, in the first instance, with other objects than the making of a work of art : — the getting at truth by laboriously sifting in- sufficient materials, the elucidation of political principles, the inculcation of ethical and political lessons. There is a limit to the capacity of the greatest mind. Had he bestowed an additional quarter of a year on every volume, with an eye to the form and language solely, he might have improved the * History' as a composition; but it is doubtful whether this would have been the most useful occupation of his time. It was not his habit to re-write his works ; he did so readily, if he discovered anything defective in the matter or in the general arrangement ; but as regarded mere expression, he ii [102] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. was satisfied with the revision of the manuscript and the careful correcting of the proofs. The greatest virtue of a writer undoubtedly is 'to rise to the occasion, and this can fearlessly be predicated of Mr. Grote. In October 1847 appeared the Letters on Switzerland, printed first in the Spectator and afterwards in a small 8vo. volume. In August of that year Mr. Grote made an excursion to Swit- zerland, in order to observe, close at hand, the nearest modem analogue of the Grecian republics. His visit coincided ^^ith the crisis of the Swiss revolution. I quote from the Preface his own account of the purpose of the visit : — " The inhabitants of the twenty-two cantons of Switzer- land are interesting on every ground to the general intelli- gent public of Europe. But to one whose studies lie in the contemplation and interpretation of historical phenomena, they are especially instructive — partly from the many speci- alities and differences of race, language, religion, civilization, wealth, habits, &c., which distinguish one part .of the popula- tion from another, comprising, between the Ehine and the Alps, a miniature of all Europe, and exhibiting the fifteenth century in immediate juxtaposition with the nineteenth — partly from the free and unrepressed action of the people, which brings out such distinctive attributes in full relief and contrast. To myself in particular they present an addi- tional ground of interest from a certain political analogy (nowhere else to be found in Europe) with those who pro- minently occupy my thoughts, and on whose history I am still engaged — the ancient Greeks. " In listening not only to the debates in the Diet, but also to the violent expressions of opposite sentiment manifested throughout the country during the present summer, I felt a strong impulse to understand how such dispositions had arisen ; to construe the present in its just aspect as a sequel to the past: and to comprehend that past itself in con- LETTEES ON SWITZERLAND. [103] junction with the feelings whicli properly belong to it, not under the influence of feelings belonging to the present. The actual condition, and reasonable promise, of Swiss federal politics were different an 1841 and 1844, and have become again materially different in 1847. We have to study each period partly in itself, partly with reference to that which preceded it, and out of which it grew^ " A man must have little experience of historical pheno- mena to suppose that in any violent political contention all the right is likely to lie on one side and all the wrong on the other. I have not disguised my conviction that both the Swiss parties have committed wrong ; nor is my statement likely to give satisfaction to either of them : to show the pro- lific power of wrong deeds in generating their like, is, in my judgment one of the most important lessons of history." The Letters may be fairly regarded as a masterly unravel- ling of Swiss politics, in which the author traces the chain of events from the first inflammatory incident — the election of Dr. Strauss to a chair in the University of Zurich — and shows that the moving power throughout was the aggressive action of the Eoman Catholic Church. The work will remain as an interesting chapter on Swiss history, and as one of the many narratives illustrating the disturbance of civil politics by the cry of '' Eeligion in danger." The writer holds the scales with the hand of Justice herself, showing at what points both parties overstepped the bounds of political morality. His dread of foreign intervention, and his strong condemnation and distrust of M. Guizot, are very expressive of his way of looking at foreign politics. The familiar spectacle of the great Powers overbearing the small was to him a source of unmitigated repugnance. [104] CHAEACTER AND WRITINGS. CHAPTER V. WORK ON PLATO. In May 1865, nine years after the completion of the ^His- tory of Greece/ appeared ' Plato and the other Companions of Socrates.' The Preface puts the reader at once into possession of the author's leading aims and peculiarities. His point of de- parture, in rendering an account of the Platonic Philosophy, is Socrates himself. Connected with him is the large inter- mixture of the negative vein in Plato's ^Dialogues/ which the author for the first time brings into the foreground. The setting forth of the negative side of all doctrines — the argu- ments against as well as the aro^uments for — he considers as not merely a distinction of these two philosophers, but as an essential of philosophy itself. Discussion, polemic, dis- sent, are the marks whereby the habits of the philosopher are distinguished from the unreasoned acquiescence of the mul- titude in the traditional and prevalent beliefs. It was, more- over, a trait of Socrates, maintained in one half of the Platonic Dialogues, to terminate a discussion in a purely negative result, to unsettle without settling. It was a farther following up of the same peculiarity in Plato to start different, and even opposing, views in his different com- positions, and to leave behind him inconsistencies never reconciled. The perception of these inconsistencies has led critics either to force them into harmony by subtle con- siderations, or to make a choice among the Dialogues, accept- ing some as the real Platonic comjwsitions and rejecting the others as spurious. Mr. Grote, on the contrary, recognises such inconsistencies as facts, and as very interesting facts, of WORK OX PLATO. [105] the pliilosophical character of his author. Once more, the career of Plato shows two stages, the first marked by the confessed ignorance and philosophical negative of Socrates ; the last, with the peremptory, dictatorial, affirmative of Lycurgus. The Preface closes with the following reflections : — " The philosophy of the fourth century B.C. is peculiarly valuable and interesting, not merely from its intrinsic speculative worth — from the originality and grandeur of its two principal heroes — from its coincidence with the full display of dramatic, rhetorical, artistic genius — but also from a fourth reason not unimportant — because it is purely Hellenic ; preceding the development of Alexandria and the amalgamation of Oriental views of thought with the inspirations of the Academy or the Lyceum. The Orontes and the Jordan had not yet begun to flow westward and to impart their own colour to the waters of Attica and Latium. Not merely the real world, but also the ideal world, present to the minds of Plato and Aristotle, were purely Hellenic. Even during the cen- tury immediately following, this had ceased to be fully true in respect to the philosophers of Athens ; and it became less and less true with each succeeding century. New foreign centres of rhetoric and literature — Asiatic and Alexandrian Hellenism — were fostered into importance by regal encourage- ment. Plato and Aristotle are thus the special representatives of genuine Hellenic philosophy. The remarkable intellectual ascendency acquired by them in their own day, and main- tained over succeeding centuries, was one main reason why the Hellenic vein was enabled so long to maintain itself, though in impoverished condition, against adverse influences from the East, ever increasing in force. Plato and Aristotle outlasted all their Pagan successors — successors at once less purely Hellenic and less highly gifted. And when Saint Jerome, near 750 years after the decease of Plato, com- memorated with triumph the victory of unlettered Chris- tians over the accomplishments and genius of Paganism, he illustrated the magnitude of the victory by singling out [106] ^tHARACTER AND WRITINGS. Plato and Aristotle as the representatives of vanquished philosophy." It has been a very common remark that Mr. Grote, from his peculiar turn of mind and his doctrinal views, was not the most qualified person to comment upon Plato, while he would be quite in his element with Aristotle. The remark is somewhat infelicitous and misplaced; the semblance of foundation for it being both insignificant and unreal. The interest and admiration felt by him for the Platonic writings as a whole could not be surpassed by anyone, although he differed from manv as to the nature of Plato's merits. Far from being unpoetical in his own tastes, he was all his life a lover of poetry ; he could have said with Plato, " I myself might have become a tragic poet." He relished the dramatic beauties of the ^ Dialogues,' and emulated in his own style the happy illustrative similes of his author. But the rack could not have extorted from him the admission that poetry is truth, that emotion is evidence. For imagination working in its own sphere, and also as lending itself to the elucidation and adornment of the results of the scientific reason, he had the greatest respect ; for imagination taking the place of reason he had no respect, whether in Plato, in Aristotle, or in any other man. The work begins with an exhaustive review of early Greek Philosophy, from Thales to Democritus. A second chapter contains an interesting commentary on the position and points of view of these primitive thinkers, and prepares the way for the next stage of Grecian thought, by the remark that com- mon to them all was the absence of Dialectic, or systematic negative criticism. The inventor of dialectic, we are told by Aristotle, was Zeno ; and his extant philosophy and method are described by Mr. Grote with a detail corresponding to his sense of the momentous nature of the innovation. The opening of the negative vein imparts from this time forward a new character to Grecian philosophy — a character never present in the most advanced Oriental speculation. The positive and negative forces, emanating from different WORK ON PLATO. [107] aptitudes of the human mind, are, henceforth, both of them actively developed, and in strenuous antithesis to each other. It is not enough to propound a theory in obscure, oracular metaphors and half-intelligible aphorisms, like Heracleitus, or in verse, more or less impressive, like Parmenides or Empedocles. Every theory must be sustained by proofs-, guarded against objections, defended against imputations of inconsistency, compared with other rival theories. From this quarter we have to approach both Socrates and Plato. The life of Plato is next reviewed. In making the most of the scanty notices preserved, Mr. Grote is careful to place before the reader the political surrounding of the period from his nineteenth to his twenty-fifth year (409-403), a period of extraordinary disaster for Athens, and involving, among other things, the severest strain upon all able-bodied citizens for military service. Philosophical study must have been very much restricted ; moreover, as Plato entertained at first a political ambition, he would not think of philosophy until he failed in that object. His studious life, when it began, had no marked interruption but the episode of his Sicilian visits. He was the founder of the earliest establish- ment for philosophical teaching — a building with grounds, lecture-room, and library. This was the Academy. In chapter iv. the author considers the Platonic Canon. Both ancients and moderns were at one as to the real works of Plato, down to the end of the last century. During the present century, the genuineness of many of the alleged works has been called in question: in consequence of which, Mr. Grote examines at length the external evidence for the received canon, which evidence he regards as peculiarly strong, being far above what we possess for the works of Demosthenes, Euripides, Aristophanes, Isocrates, or Lysias. The great point in the argument is the perpetuation of the Academy, Avith its library, up to the date of the foundation of the Alexandrine Collection, which collection would acquire a well-guaranteed set of the genuine Platonic writings j while our present canon rests on the authority of that collection and its librarians. [108] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. In a separate chapter, Mr. Grote considers the grounds of the recent objections to the time-honoured canon. The new turn was given by Schleiermacher, who began by assum- ing as fundamental postulates — first, a systematic unity of scheme and purpose, running through all the Dialogues ; secondly, an intentional order, with a view to this scheme. Upon these two assumptions he classifies the Dialogues, rejecting some that do not fall within the scheme. He is followed by other critics, who, without agreeing altogether in his assumptions, are yet more sweeping in their rejections. Against all these critics Mr. Grote produces reasons that seem irresistible. The different theories laid down respecting the general and systematic purposes of Plato, he regards as uncertified and gratuitous ; the " internal reasons " are only another phrase for expressing each critic's opinion respecting Plato as a philosopher and a writer. *' Considering that Plato's period of philosophical composi- tion extended over fifty years, and that the circumstances of his life are most imperfectly known to us, it is surely hazardous to limit the range of his varieties on the faith of a critical repugnance, not merely subjective and fallible, but withal entirely of modern growth : to assume, as basis of reasoning, the admiration raised by a few of the first dia- logues — and then to argue that no composition inferior to this admired type, or unlike to it in doctrine or handling, can possibly be the work of Plato. ' The Minos, Theages, Epistolae, Epinomis, &c, are unworthy of Plato : nothing so inferior in excellence can have been composed by him. No dialogue can be admitted as genuine which contradicts another dialogue, or which advocates any low or incorrect or un-Platonic doctrine. No dialogue can pass which is adverse to the general purpose of Plato as an improver of morality and a teacher of the doctrine of Ideas.' On such grounds as these we are called upon to reject various dialogues ; and there is nothing upon which, generally speaking, so much stress is laid as upon inferior excellence. For my part, I cannot recognise any of them as sufficient grounds of excep- WOEK ON PLATO. [109] tion. I have no difficulty in belieying not merely that Plato (like Aristophanes) produced many successive novelties — ^ not at all similar one to the other, and all clever' — but also that among these novelties there were inferior dialogues as well as superior : that in different dialogues he worked out different, even contradictory, points of view — and among them some which critics declare to be low and objectionable ; that we have among his works unfinished fragments and abandoned sketches, published without order, and perhaps only after his death." Mr. Jowett's remarks on this perplexed theme are as follows : — " I cannot agree with Mr. Grote in admitting as genuine all the writings commonly attributed to Plato in antiquity^ any more than with Schaarschmidt and some other German critics, who reject nearly half of them On the other hand, Mr. Grote trusts mainly to the Alexandrian canon. But I hardly think that we are justified in attributing much weiofht to the authority of the Alexandrian librarians in an age when there was no regular publication of books and every temptation to forge them, and in which the writings of a school were naturally attributed to the founder of the school. And even without intentional fraud there was an inclination to believe rather than to inquire. Would Mr. Grote accept as genuine all the writings which he finds in the lists of learned ancients attributed to Hippocrates, to Xenophon, to Aristotle? The Alexandrian canon of the Platonic writings is deprived of credit by the admission of the ' Epistles,' which are not only unworthy of Plato, but in several places plagiarised from him and flagrantly at vari- ance with historical fact." To the query of Mr. Jowett, '^ Would Mr. Grote accept as genuine all the writings attributed to Hippocrates," &c., an answer was given in anticipation, grounded on the special preservation of the Platonic writings in the library of the Academy, no similar advantage belonging to the other writers. Mr. Jowett rejects, not without hesitation, Lesser Hippias, [110] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. First Alcibiades, and Menexenus. He considers it right, however, to give them a place in his work. He is thus sub- stantially at one with Mr. Grote on the Dialogues, but not on the Epistles, whose genuineness is supported by Mr. Grote, both in the ' History ' and in the * Plato,' by arguments of no small cogency, which we should like to see Mr. Jowett answer in detail. Bentley, the crusher of spurious Epistles, allowed the Epistles of Plato: his extraordinary learning did not enable him to detect in them " flagrant violations of historical fact." Subsequent scholars, while denying their genuineness, allow them to be the work of early and well-informed authors. The seventh epistle especially is, by Boeckh, considered genuine, and by Ueberweg, the work of a well-informed contemporary. Cicero, Plutarch, Aristeides, etc., all attest facts on the authority of these Epistles. The chief objections to them by critics generally are founded on their being unworthy of Plato. Mr. Grote does not think himself competent to determine a priori what the style of Plato's letters may have been ; he has no difficulty in believing that Plato may have expressed himself with as much mysticism and obscurity as we now read in the second and seventh epistles : he is not surprised at the allusions to details which critics who look upon him altogether as a spiritual person, disallow as mean and unwortliy. It is curiously remarked by Ueberweg that Mr. Grote's '^ accepting as genuine all the dialogues accredited by Thra- syllus has caused him to lose sight of tJie essential unity present in Plato^s thought and u'orJcs, and to admit in its stead a midtifariousness abounding in change and contradiction,^^ The real fact is, Mr. Grote is not blinded by his acceptance of the canon of Thrasyllus. He sees no possibility of gaining the " unity " by any number of rejections ; he has followed the upholders of unity through all their clashing experiments, and found only confusion and contradiction. The regaining of unity and consistency in Plato's WTitings, by rejecting a sufficient number of dialogues, involves an entirely new theory of the tactics of a forger of writings, WOEK ON PLATO. [Ill] namely, that he should contradict all the leading doctrines of the author imitated. Now, although it is one of the usual marks of a spurious writing to contain inconsistencies unfelt by the writer, but detected by well-informed critics, it is surely not the practice of any forger to make such open and vital contradictions as those existing between the sup- posed spurious and the real dialogues of Plato, How should a forger of epistles of Paul expect to succeed by maintaining a series of doctrines in marked opposition to all the charac- teristic views of the apostle ? There is but one conceivable situation suitable to this policy : namely, where there was a wish to gain the w^eight of a great name to certain views special to the forger, and where all external circumstances were so far favourable to the reception of the forgery as to outweigh the internal discordance. In chapter vi., entitled "Platonic Compositions Generally," Mr. Grote gives his views as to the method of Plato. Although on isolated points others have agreed with him, yet the general strain of the criticisms on Plato's plan and purpose has the character of novelty. The first impression produced by the Platonic writings is their exceeding variety; no one epithet can describe them all. Some critics in an- tiquity described Plato as essentially a searcher or inquirer, and as never reaching any certain result. This is going too far ; he is sceptical in some dialogues, dogmatical in others. Again, Aristotle characterised his style of writing as some- thing between poetry and prose, and declared that the doctrine of Ideas obtained all its plausibility from metaphors. This is also true to a certain extent ; many of the dialogues possess a degree of poetic exuberance condemned as exces- sive by contemporary and subsequent critics, who had before them, for comparison, the most finished compositions of Greece. Moreover, the power of his dramatic situations would have carried away the prizes at the Dionysiac festivals, if he had followed the drama as a profession. But these poetic attributes are not found in all the Dialogues. Plato was sceptic, dogmatist, religious mystic, and inquisitor. [112] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. mathematician, philosopher, poet (erotic as well as sati- rical), rhetor, artist, all in one — or at least, all in turn, — throughout the fifty years of his philosophical life. So much appears in his published Dialogues. But he was a lecturer besides, and of his lectures we have no record, ex- cepting only a tantalizing observation of Aristotle. The only occasions where he lays aside the pen of " Imaginary Conversations " and speaks in his own person, are in the much repudiated EjDistles, from which Mr. Grote brings before us some singular views as to the mode of communi- cating knowledge. He peculiarly disclaims written com- positions, and regards oral communications and debate, coupled with intense meditation apart, as the only effective mode of intellectual illumiDation. Also his standard of mastery of any subject was that the learner shall be able to endure from others, and himself apply to others, a Socratic elenchus, or cross-examination as to all the difficulties. In classifying the Dialogues, our author starts from one of the divisions given by Thrasyllus — the two-fold division of Dialogues of Search and Dialogues of Exposition, setting aside the Apolo^T of Socrates and the Menexenus as com- positions apart. Deviating from Thrasyllus in the detailed enumeration, he gives nineteen Dialogues of Search and fourteen of Exposition. The most elaborate example of Search is Thesetetus. Among Expository dialogues, Timaeus is a marked example, being devoid of all negative criticism. Many are not purely of either character. Mr. Grote's strong point, as is already apparent, lies in his rendering of the Search Dialogues. This is a species of com- position now rare and strange : modern readers do not understand what is meant by publishing an inquiry without any result — a story without an end. To settle a question and finish with it — to get rid of the debate, as if it were a troublesome temporary necessity — is not what Plato desires ; the torpedo shock of conscious ignorance is what he, after Socrates, aims at imparting. He tells us himself that he is a searcher, and has not made up his own mind ; WORK OX PLATO. [113] critics generally will not believe him ; Mr. Grote does. Most historians of ancient philosophy fail to realise, because themselves disliking, the process of mere negation. They would tolerate it in small doses, and as an aid to affir- mation; requiring that, when you deprive a man of one affirmative solution, you must be prepared at once with another. ^^ Le Koi est Mort ; Vive le Eoi ! " the dogmatic throne must never be empty. The claims of the objector must be satisfied before the affirmer can be held solvent. For the mere evoking of literary charm, Plato was attached to the polemic form. He feels a strong interest in the pro- cess of enquiry, in the debate jper se ; and he presumes the like interest in his readers. He has no wish to shorten the process; he claims it as the privilege of philosophical dis- cussion that the speakers are not tied to time by the Klepsydra. And he really succeeded in inspiring readers with something of his own interest in the dialectical process. The charm imparted by him to the process of philosophising is one main cause of the preservation of his writings from the terrible shipwreck that has overtaken so much of the abun- dant contemporary literature. But the most important consideration, in Mr. Grote's view, still remains. It is the special ground assigned by Socrates for his negative procedure, namely, that chronic and deep- seated malady of the human mind, the false persuasion of knowledge. To this state Socrates applied his Elenchus, making people explain what they meant by Justice, Tem- perance, Courage, Law, and other familiar terms. The answers elicited were simple expressions of the ordinary prevalent belief in matters wherein each community pos- sesses established dogmas, laws, customs, sentiments, fashions, points of view belonging to itself; many of them diametri- cally opposed to what is accepted in other communities. There can be no philosophy unless these consecrated opinions are to be freely canvassed and disturbed. Philosophy is thus the proclaimed enemy of orthodoxy ; the philosopher, by the i [114] CHAKACTER AND WRITINGS. law of his being, is a dissenter. Accordingly the indictment against Socrates ran thus : '^ Socrates commits crime, inas- much as he does not believe in the gods in whom the city believes, but introduces new religious beliefs." Nomos (Law and Custom) King of All (to borrow the phrase cited by Herodotus from Pindar) exercises plenary power, spiritual as well as temporal, over individual minds; moulding the emotions as well as the intellect according to the local type ; determining everyone's sentiments, belief, and predispositions to believe ; fashioning thought, speech, and points of view, no less than action ; yet reigning under the appearance of habitual self-suggested tendency. Never before did King Nomos meet with such an adversary as Socrates. In these very decided views as to the Platonic position in the Dialogues of Search, Mr. Grote has as yet very little following. Mr. Jowett, alluding to the Gorgias, one of the Dialogues emphasised by our author as putting forward the right of dissent or private judgment, regards this mode of stating the question as really opposed both to the spirit of Plato and of ancient philosophy generally ; so far from advocating toleration or free thought, Plato (in the LaWs) has laid him- self open to the charge of intolerance ; no speculations had as yet arisen respecting the liberty of prophesying. Now, it must be distinctly allowed that Mr. Grote, being himself an ardent apostle of free enquiry, is naturally pre- disposed to find allies among the greatest of mankind. He may, therefore, somewhat overstrain tlie amount of support lent to individual freedom by Socrates and Plato. Yet his case is far stronger than Mr. Jowett would lead us to suppose. As regards Socrates, it is seemingly irresistible. In Plato it does not rest on the Gorgias alone. There, indeed, does Mr. Grote find the remarkable expression put into the mouth of Socrates: "You, Polus, bring against me the authority of the multitude, as well as of the most eminent citizens, all upholding your view. But I, one man standing here alone, do not agree with you." In the Pha^don, also, Socrates is made to give a dying testimony to the freedom of debate : WOEK ON PLATO. [115] *^ If I appear to you to affirm anything truly, attend to me ; l)ut, if not, oppose me with all your powers of reasoning." A very emphatic passage to the same effect occurs in the Politicus, the chief spokesmen being made to complain of the interdict maintained against adverse criticism of the legal and consecrated doctrines. Mr. Grote admits the change that had come over Plato when he wrote the Laws. Instead of adducing it, however, to neutralise the animated protests in favour of liberty in the Gorgias and the Phsedon, so as to show that Plato, taken as a whole, was indifferent in the matter, he deplores it as the most repulsive feature of Plato's senility. After all, Mr. Jowett cannot be far off from Mr. Grote's views, when he allows himself to represent Plato " as assert- ing the duty of the one wise and true man to dissent from the folly and falsehood of the many." Occasions necessarily arise for adverting to Plato's treat- ment of the Sophists, on which modern historians of philo- sophy have bettered the instruction. The author repeats, that the charges made against the Sophists (as well as the Megarics), namely corrupting youth, perverting truth and morality, by making the worse appear the better reason, subverting established beliefs, — were all urged against Plato himself by his contemporaries, and indeed against all the philosophers indiscriminately. They are outbursts of feeling natural to the practical, orthodox citizen, who represents the common sense of the time and place ; declaring his anti- pathy to those speculative, freethinking innovations of theory, which challenge the prescriptive maxims of traditional cus- tom by a theoretical standard. In point of fact, the persons commonly called Sophists did far less violence to the orthodox sentiments than either Socrates or Plato. Indeed Plato's dislike to the Sophists was part and parcel of his dislike to the general multitude of Athenians. In the Re- public, he says emphatically, that the Sophists teach nothing but the opinions of the multitude, and call these wisdom. Mr. Jowett so far agrees with Mr. Grote tliat the Sophists i 2 [116] CHARACTER AXD WRITINGS. did not, as so generally alleged, corrupt the youth ; the Athenian youth were no more corrupted in the time of Demosthenes than in the time of Pericles. He puts the question, however, — -'^ Would an Athenian, as Mr. Grote supposes, in the fifth century before Christ:, have included Socrates and Plato, as well as Gorgias and Protagoras, under the speciiic class of Sophists ? " and answers ** No." '* The man of genius, the great original thinker, the disinterested seeker after truth, the master of repartee whom no one ever defeated in an argument, was separated, even in the mind of the vulgar Athenian, by an ' interval which no geometry can express,' from the balancer of sentences, the interpreter and reciter of the poets, the divider of the meanings of words, the teacher of rhetoric, the professor of morals and manners." Kow, there was one marked peculiarity of the Sophists : they received regular pay; Socrates and Plato merely accepted presents. But in the eyes of both Socrates and Plato, teaching for pay was exceedingly discreditable ; we are not told to what length the Athenian public shared in this anti- pathy. As to any of the other points mentioned, it is exceed- ingly difficult to discover why the vulgar Athenian should set up Socrates and Plato as immeasurably superior to the general body of teachers, called Sophists. Mr. Grote thinks highly of the Athenians, but he utterly refuses to accredit them with a fine sense of what distinguished the true philo- sopher from the eloquent repeater of commonplace. It is in the present work that Mr. Grote has found oppor- tunities of unfolding a number of his own philosophical views. He has indicated his tenets in some of the highest questions of Psychology, Logic, Ethics, and Metaphysics. I shall here briefly sketch his leading positions as a philosophical tliinker. In adhering to experience as the sole fountain of legi- timate belief, and to utility, as the sole criterion of what is morally right, he was thorough-going and consistent. He disclaimed the criterion of Intuition or Instinct in botli spheres ; and, incidentally in commenting on Plato and on WOEK OjST PLATO. [117] Aristotle, has argued with no little force in favour of his own side. He embraced with eagerness several of the most important aspects of the gi-eat law or doctrine of Eelativity, respecting which many sagacious glimpses appear in ancient philosophy. Mr. Jowett speaks too lightly of the import of this doctrine, when he calls it a truism of the present time. No doubt it is well enough recognised in a few familiar appli- cations such as pleasures and pains, fine art, and some aspects of knowledge ; but I doubt if in its lull compass, any great number of persons w^ould either understand it or tolerate all its legitimate consequences. Yet it is one of those cardinal doctrines that must be true universallv, or not at all. It is in the exposition of Aristotle's Categories that the author takes note of Eelativity as the essential fact of all Knowdedge or Cognition. Every fact or quality exists only with reference to some other fact or quality, as its correla- tive or opposite — light, dark : cold, hot ; up, down ; wise, foolish. This is the most fundamental of all the aspects of the doctrine. A more restricted but exceedingly momentous aspect is largely dwelt on by Mr. Grote ; the correlation of subject and object in perception; the mutual implication of the per- cipient mind with the thing perceived — the percipiens and the jpercejptum. His mode of handling this antithesis in connec- tion with the Berkeleian idealism is most fully shown in one of the essays in the present volume (p. 332). The mode of Eelativity most forcibly stated in the ' Plato,' is the relativity of truth or belief to the affirming or believing subject. This is dwelt upon in the commentary on The^- TETUS, as the most probable rendering of the Protagorean dictum — homo mensura, "man is a measure to himself." As he understands the doctrine, Mr. Grote is thoroughly at one with Protagoras, although the view was impugned by both Plato and Aristotle. He attributes no small import- ance to the doctrine ; it being, in his opinion, the philoso- phical formula of the right of private judgment, as opposed to the assumed infallibility of some one man or body of men. [118] CHAEACTEE AND WETTINGS. ^ In this grand chef-d'oeuvre of Plato, Mr. Grote's philo- sophical handling everywhere appears to full advantage, and the student will find a rewarding exercise in comparing him with the other commentators on the dialogue. His opposition to the a jpriori philosophy is stated in the discussion on the meanings of Cause, in the Phsedon. Following Hume and Brown, he understands '*by causes nothing more than phenomenal antecedents constant and unconditional, ascertainable by experience and induction." In connexion with the Protagoras, the Gorgias, and the Eepublic he sets forth certain ethical points of view that he lays great stress upon. In Protagoras, Plato affirms the doctrine that good and evil are identical with pleasurable and painful, and that virtue is an affair of measurement and computation. Mr. Grote, in like manner, holds that there is no intelligible standard of reference for application of the terms good and evil, except the tendency to produce happi- ness or misery ; if this standard be rejected, ethical debate ceases to be a matter of rational discussion, and becomes only an enunciation of the different sentiments, authoritative and self-justifying, that are prevalent in each community. An important qualification, however, has been omitted by Plato. His measurement omits to take account of man as a member of society, and to value the pleasures and pains of others. This is one of the defects of Plato's ethical theory. In Gorgias he takes a totally different view of virtue — the preservation of a high tone of mental health. Vice he treats as a kind of disease, and the eradication of this taint or disease is what the virtuous man must aim at. Mr. Grote tries to give a meaning to what lies under this high- flown metaphor ; remarking how our being is divided between the transient impressions made upon us, and a certain permanent element, namely, the established cha- racter, habits, dispositions, intellectual requirements — the accumulated mental capital of the past life. This permanent element must be kept in good condition ; we must not for the sake of present and transitory pleasure impair the WORK ON PLATO. [119] * general stock of pleasurable accumulations. Still, the per- manent itself derives all its substance and value from the regard to pleasures and the avoidance of pains. In the first book of the Republic, which is occupied with a stirring polemic on the nature of justice, Plato, in oppo- sition to the received opinions of mankind, declares that justice is a good thing in itself, without regard to the consequences. This is the first statement of the doctrine, afterwards insisted on by the Stoics, and repeated in modern ethics, that virtue is all-sufiScient to the happiness of the virtuous agent, whatever be his fate in other respects. As a counter thesis, Mr. Grote strikingly illustrates the essential reciprocity of virtuous conduct — one of the many phases of the Law of Eelativity. Plato has endeavoured to accredit a fiction misrepresenting the constant phenomena and standing conditions of social life. Among these conditions, reciprocity of services is fundamental. Each individual has both duties and rights : each is required to be just to others : others are required to be just to him. The rights and obligations of any one towards the rest are inseparably correlated ; without this the terms " right " and '^ obligation " are void of meaning. In Plato we have the first faint indications of what is now called Teleology, or a science of Ends, as distinct from the sciences of the Order of Nature. Aristotle was more explicit ; he being the first to shape the practical sciences of ethics, politics, and rhetoric, into whose definition there entered a statement of the End. Mr. Grote, at an early period of his studies, worked out this conception of the practical sciences, and I believe instigated Mr. Mill to compose that striking chapter, added to the second edition of his Logic, entitled ' The Logic of Practice.' [120] CHARACTER A^B WRITINGS. CHAPTEE VI. WORK ON ARISTOTLE. Mr. Grote began the ' Aristotle ' in liis seventy-first year. His preparatory studies had been ample, including a life-long acquaintance with most of the Aristotelian treatises. All his accumulated knowledge on ancient Greece as a whole, and his persistent devotion to philosopliy in its modern as well as its ancient phases, could be now brought to bear on his concluding and most laborious task. That his unremitted exertions for six years at an ad- vanced age should terminate in a fragment only, is matter of lasting regret, but not of astonishment. The difficulties of the subject are great; and his mode of dealing with it, combining lucid interpretation with critical comparison, could cost nothing less than a protracted effort. Ten years of his prime would have scarcely sufSced to complete the projected survey of Aristotle and his contemporaries, as a parallel to Plato. ^ The two volumes that have been published are mainly occupied with the logical treatises of the great philosopher. Prefixed to the account of these are two chapters — one on the life of Aristotle, the other on the Canon. The extant notices of Aristotle's career are very un- satisfactory. The facts are few, and many of them doubtful from conflicting testimonies. The biographer's task is chiefly made up of the sifting of authorities, and the comparing of the statements with the history of the time as otherwise known. The opening paragraph deserves to be quoted, as a bird's- W©RK ON ARISTOTLE. [121] eye view of the situation of philosophy in the Aristotelian age : — " In my preceding work, ^ Plato and the Other Companions of Sokrates/ I described a band of philosophers differing much from each other, but all emanating from Sokrates as common intellectual progenitor ; all manifesting themselves wholly or principally in the composition of dialogues ; and all living in an atmosphere of Hellenic freedom, as yet untroubled by any overruling imperial ascendency from without. From that band, among whom Plato is facile jprincejoSy I now proceed to another, among whom the like pre-eminence belongs to Aristotle. This second band knew the Sokratic stimulus only as a historical tradition ; they gradually passed, first from the Sokratic or Platonic dialogue — dramatic, colloquial, cross-examining — to the Aristotelian dialogue, semi-dramatic, rhetorical, counter-expository; and next to formal theorising, ingenious solution and divination of special problems, historical criticism and abundant collec- tions of detailed facts : moreover, they were witnesses of the extinction of freedom in Hellas, and of the rise of the Mace- donian kingdom out of comparative nullity to the highest pinnacle of supremacy and mastership. Under the suc- cessors of Alexander, this extraneous supremacy, inter- meddling and dictatorial, not only overruled the political movements of the Greeks, but also influenced powerfully the position and working of their philosophers ; and would have become at once equally intermeddling even earlier, under Alexander himself, had not his whole time and personal energy been absorbed by insatiable thirst for Eastern con- quests, ending with an untimely death." Among the most interesting aspects of the philosopher's life are those opened up by Mr. Grote, through the con- temporary history. While attending the school of Plato, he contracted intimacy with a fellow-pupil, Hermeias, a man of great ability and energy, who became despot of two little towns in Asia Minor, Atarneus and Assos (opposite the island of Lesbos). In consequence of a hurt when a child, [122] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. lie was known to be a eunu'cli, and had become the slave of the prior despot of Atarneus. On Plato's death, Aristotle left Athens and accepted an invitation to reside with Hermeias, during which residence he married Pythias, the despot's niece. The happy intimacy^ was put an end to by the treachery of the Persian general in command of the neighbouring region, who decoyed Hermeias into his grasp and sent him up to the Persian king, by whom he was put to death. Aristotle's deep grief is permanently recorded in a § hymn or paean composed to the memory of his friend. The Persians took possession of the towns of Hermeias, and Aristotle went to Mitylene. His next recorded movement is to the Macedonian court, as tutor to the youthful Alexander; an appointment partly owing (we may suppose) to his father's having been Philip's court physician, and partly to his own already acquired reputation for philosophy. His residence at Pella, the Macedonian capital, and his instruc- tions to Alexander, continued, with occasional interruptions, till Alexander's accession to the throne in 336 B.C. In the year following, which saw the completion of the preparations for invading Persia, he went to Athens, and opened a new school of philosophy, as a rival to the Academy, still kept up by the successors to Plato ; in that school he spent the remaining thirteen years of his life. Apart from his philo- sophic teaching and pursuits, he had by no means an easy time. He was under Macedonian patronage ; he was still consulted by Alexander, and maintained a constant corre- spondence with Antipater, Alexander's deputy or viceroy in the government of Macedonia and its dependencies. He was thus in a position of antagonism to the sentiments of the majority of the Athenian public. " It will thus appear, that though all the preserved writings of Aristotle are imbued with a thoroughly inde- pendent spirit of theorising contemplation and lettered industry, uncorrupted by any servility or political bias — yet his position during the twelve years between 335-323 B.C. inevitably presented him to the Athenians as the Mace- WORK ON ARISTOTLE. [123] donising philosopher, parallel with Phokion as the Macedon- ising politician, and in pointed antithesis to Xenokrates at the Academy, who was attached to the deraocratical consti- tution, and refused kingly presents. Besides that enmity which he was sure to incur, as an acute and self-thinking philosopher, from theology and the other anti-philosophical veins in the minds of ordinary men, Aristotle thus became the object of unfriendly sentiment from many Athenian patriots, who considered the school of Plato generally as hostile to popular liberty, and who had before them examp^p s of individual Platonists, ruling their respective cities with a sceptre forcibly usurped." The death of Alexander at Babylon, in June 323 B.C., came upon the world with a shock : and gave hopes of deliverance to enslaved Greece. There was an anti-Mace- donian rising at Athens ; Phocion and the other Macedonian leaders went for safety to Antipater ; and Aristotle's enemies thought the moment opportune for an onslaught on him. Following the Socratic precedent, the chief priest of the Eleusinian temple entered against him an indictment for impiety. The grounds of the indictment were peculiar; consisting mainly of the Hymn to Hermeias, and the in- scription on a statue to Hermeias at Delphi. To this was added the citation of certain heretical doctrines from his published writings, of which the chief seems to have been a declaration against the efficacy of prayers and sacri- fices. On this curious indictment Mr. Grote remarks that the hymn or paean in honour of Hermeias would be more offensive to the feelings of an ordinary Athenian than any philosophical dogma extracted from the cautious prose com- positions of Aristotle. Such hymns had been previously composed in honour of individual Greeks by Pindar and others; the same lofty and exaggerated comparison to deities had been indulged in: yet the searching eye of the historian of Greece discloses a difference. Hermeias was a compound of three enormities — a eunuch, a slave, and a despot. He was not a despot pure and simple, but a [124] CHARACTEE AND WRITINGS. eunuch-despot beginning from a slave; while there wa^ no redeeming public exploit that would have softened the harshness of the combination. A groundwork of political antipathy, overlaid by such a charge, gave Aristotle small chance at that moment; he bowed to the storm, which he knew could not last, retired from Athens, and would have soon returned, but for his death. A sentence of his com- posed defence is preserved, wherein he rebuts the charge of deifying Hermeias (ranking him in the ode with Herakles, aij^d others) by alleging tliat he had notoriously erected a tomb, and performed funeral ceremonies to him as a mortal. Mr. Grote remarks, that this did not meet tlie case: the Athenians would not have felt the logical inconsistency of the two proceedings ; what they felt was the worthlessness of Hermeias, to whom he rendered these great honours, whether as divinity or as human being. The solemn measure and character of a paean was disgraced by being applied to so vile a person. Mr. Grote has farther supplied illustrative comments on the position of Aristotle with reference to the rival schools, namely, of Isocrates and of Plato ; and gives what evidence remains of his feelings towards his rivals, on which bitter reflections were common. The second chapter is entitled the ^Aristotelian Canon.' The problem of what are Aristotle's genuine writings has far greater complication than attends the Platonic canon ; and Mr. Grote exhausts his learning and acumen in the attempt to unravel it. We shall not follow him in this research, but shall advert only to his concluding dissertation on the exact meanino; of the renowned distinction between Esoteric and Exoteric doctrine. The basis of explanation of these words, as occurring in Aristotle's own writings, is exceedingly narrow. The word ^ Exoteric ' occurs in eight passages of the extant works (taking in the Eudemian Ethics, which is disputed by some critics) ; seven of these are indecisive ; but reasoning from the eighth, Mr. Grote thinks that the word means dialectical delate as contrasted with demonstration] a funda- WOEK ON AEISTOTLE. [125] mental distinction with Aristotle. This is very different from the common acceptation of the two contrasting terms — exo- teric and esoteric. According to Mr. Grote, the ' esoteric ' is the essence of science or philosophy itself, in its deductive, demonstrative, or syllogistic march ; the ^ exoteric ' is some- thinof Ivino; outside of this, extrinsic, but vet a valuable province in itself, the province of the probable, the disput- able, where there is no proper demonstration, but a series of arguments pro and eon. The Organon or Methodised Eatiocination of Aristotle, fell under corresponding heads, the one (Demonstrative) represented by the Analytica, the other (Dialectic) by the Topica. Of the prodigious total of works composed by Aristotle, the larger number have perished. There still remain about forty treatises, of authenticity not open io any reasonable suspicion, attesting the grandeur of his intelligence, in respect of speculative force, positive and negative, system- atizing patience, comprehensive curiosity as to matters of fact, and diversified applications of detail. In the order of study most generally agreed upon, the first place is given to the collection of treatises called the Organon, six in number : — The Categories ; De Interpretatione or De Enun- ciatione ; Analytica Priora; Analytica Posteriora ; Topica ; De Sophisticis Elenchis. The last, although a short treatise, is very important ; it forms naturally a part of the Topica ; so that, in fact, there are five distinct treatises : each having a well-marked subject. Mr. Grote's greatest originality as an expositor appears in his account of the first treatise — Categoric, the Cate- gories. It corresponds to the logical department of Terms, although the best known logicians have discarded Aristotle's treatment, and have usually given in some detached chapter a List of the Categories without connecting explanation, often accompanied with an insinuation that the subject does not belong to Logic. Nevertheless, the nature of Terms, and their various distinctions, have their beginning in the book of the Categories. Aristotle was the first to distinguish [126] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. terms as Equivocal and TJnivocdly and to regard predication or the proposition as made up of terms. The Ten Categories or Predicaments are a comprehensive classification of all things that enter into a proposition, either as Subject or as Predicate. They are : — ^' 1. Essence 01 Substance ; such as, man, horse. 2. How mucli ov Quan- tity ; such as, two cubits long, three cubits long. 3. ]Miat manner of ov Quality ; such as, Avhite, erudite. 4. Ad aliquid — To something or Relation ; such as, double, half, greater. I| 5. J\niere ; such as, in the market-place, in the Lykeium. 6. When ; such as, yesterday, last year. 7. In what posture ; such as, he stands up, he is sitting down. 8. To have ; such as, to be shod, to be armed. 9. Activity ; such as, he is cutting, he is burning. 10. Passivity ; such as, he is being cut, he is being bAi'ned." '' In this enumeration, Aristotle takes his departure, not from any results of prior research, but from common speech; and from the dialectic, frequent in his time, which debated about matters of common life and talk, about received and current opinions. We may presume him to have studied and compared a variety of current propositions, so as to discover the different relations in which subjects and predicates did stand or could stand to each other ; also the various ques- tions which might be put respecting any given subject, with the answers suitable to be returned. " The chief stress of Aristotle's exposition rests upon the first four categories — Substance, Quantity, Quality, Relation; as to the six last — Wliere, Wlien, Posture. Having, Activity ^ Passivity, he says little upon any of them ; upon some nothino; at all. The cardinal explanation of the whole scheme turns upon the First Category — Substance or Essence. From the prevailing signification of this term, as the most extreme and attenuated of all abstractions, we are unprepared for the meaning given to it by Aristotle, namely, the Concrete Individual. The First Ens or First Essence — that which is Ens in the fullest sense — is the individual concrete person or WORK ON ARISTOTLE. [127] thing in nature ; Sokrates, Bukephalus, this man, that horse, that oak-tree, &c. This First E^is is indispensable as Sub- ject or Substratum for all the other Categories, and even for predication generally. It is a subject only ; it never appears as a predicate of anything else. Haying defined in this fashion substance or First Essence, by which he placed himself in diametrical opposition to Plato's Ideas, Aristotle states what he means by a Second Essence, namely the species that a thing belongs to ; Sokrates First Essence; man or animal — Species or Second Essence. Here in reality, he is goiug on another tack, mixing up with the categories a different set of distinctions; these terms, however, — First and Second Essences, are of vital moment in the Aristotelian philosophy. The proper antithesis to Substance is seen in the remaining nine Categories — Quantity, Quality, &c, which are predicates for clothing the First Essence, or Individual. An individual man, horse, building, possesses Quantity in various ways ; also Quality as white, living, costly. Aristotle discusses and classifies the modes of Quantity, as shown in the mathematical sciences, and in the adjectives of degree little, much, &c. He then proceeds to Relation, and gets out of his depth, not seeing that relation instead of being a property co-ordinate with Quantity, Quality, and the rest, is at the foundation of tlie whole, as Mr. Grote amply shows. The ancient philoso- phers had far-seeing glimpses into the principle of Eelativity, but usually broke down at some point or other, and landed themselves in confusion and even contradiction ; and the present attempt of Aristotle is a signal example. In seekino: a clue to what was in the mind of Aristotle when he drew up this very imperfect classification of things entering into either the Subject or the Predicate of propo- sitions, Mr. Grrote points out the last as the most suggestive. Every one is astonished, after surveying the sweeping generalities — Quantity, Quality, and Relation, to come down to Posture (sitting, lying), Having (possessing shoes or arms) ; for while the higher, and grander attributes, include every- [128] CHAKACTER AND WRITINGS. thing in their sweep, the last can apply only to some human being or animal. We infer from this that Aristotle had in his mind chiefly some individual man, and put all the dif- ferent questions that could be answered respecting that individual. The caprice in choosing the number Ten, was the remains in Aristotle's mind of the fascination for particular numbers, which so largely affected the Pythagoreans, and after them, Plato. The number might easily have been extended, or it might have been contracted, as it was by the Stoics, wha recognised only Four : while Plotinus and Galen each made out Five. ^^ He was, as far as we can see, original in taking as the point of departure for his theory, the individual man, horse, or other perceivable object ; in laying down this Concrete Particular with all its outfit of details, as the type of Ens proper, complete and primary ; and in arranging into classes the various secondary modes of Ens according to their different relations to the primary type and the mode in w^hich they contributed to make up its completeness. He thus stood opposed to the Pythagoreans and Platonists, who took their departure from the Universal, as the type of full and true Entity ; while he also dissented from Demokritus> who recognised no true Eiis except the underlying, imper- ceptible, eternal atoms and vacuum. Moreover, Aristotle seems to have been the first to draw up a logical analysis of Entity in its widest sense, as distinguished from that meta- physical analysis which we read in his other works ; the two not being contradictory, but distinct and leading to different purposes. Both in the one and in the other, his principal controversy seems to have been with the Platonists, who dis- regarded both individual objects and accidental attributes ; dwelling upon Universals, Genera, and Species, as the only real Entia capable of being known." The second treatise of the Organon is called De Inter- pret a tione, the doctrine of the Proposition. This, with the %VOEK ON ARISTOTLE. [129] * Analytica Priora/ is the source of the theory of Propo- sitions in modern Logic. Denial or negative affirmation was in a very confused state in the philosophies prior to Aristotle ; and although his terminology is not in all respects fully developed, he made the great step of distinguishing the Quantity of Propositions — as Universal or Particular, from which followed the two modes of denial, Contrary and Con- tradictory. The Maxim or Law of Contradiction was a part of this theory, which Mr. Grote attributes exclusively to Aristotle, in opposition to Sir W. Hamilton's attempt to trace it up to Plato. A considerable portion of the treatise is devoted to the so-called Modal Propositions — the Possible and the Neces- sary — and rings all the changes growing out of their oppo- sites. Much dissension has taken place among logicians as to these modals. Mr. Grote shows that they have a place in Logic, but have not been satisfactorily dealt with by Aristotle, being a very serious clog in his handling, both of the proposition and the syllogism. Next follows the Analytica Prioka containing the theory of the syllogism. This great artificial construction is claimed by Aristotle, as exclusively his own, and there is no reason to contest his claim. He had no model to proceed upon except geometry, which had already in his time been cast into its present form, although not with Euclid's system. By examining a vast number of examples of reasoning or arguments, he had detected the uniform presence of two primary propositions, related to each other, and to the proposition to be proved, in certain definite ways. He provided technical language for expressing the consti- tuent propositions and terms, and found out nearly all the modes of relationship of the premises that would give true conclusions. He prepared the way for the mutual resolution of argumentative forms (called reduction) by laying down the laws of the Conversion of Propositions, although his attempts to prove these laws are a manifest failure. He h [130] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. characterised Figure by the position of the Middle Term, and worked out by trial all the valid moods in the Three Figures (the Fourth was a later addition). He was the first to employ alphabetical letters to abbreviate the state- ment of prepositional forms, having seen something of the same sort in geometry. He set great store upon the supe- riority of the First Figure, as the only one wherein we can prove the Universal Affirmative, — the great aim of scientific research. His exposition is not always- satisfactory, and is greatly encumbered by the introduction of Modal Pro- positions. He exemplifies the dialectical applications of the syllogism, still farther carried out in the treatise called Topica : and handles various forms of fallacy. Mr. Grote is always careful to remark Aristotle's admission that the jprincij^ia or premises of demonstration are furnished by experience and induction, each separate science con- tributing its own quota ; astronomical observation and expe- rience furnishing the basis of astronomical laws, and so on. This was one of his marked points of opposition to Plato. Nevertheless, he was very far from steady in his hold of induction. In the second book of ' Analytica Priora,' occurs his attempt to give induction the form of syllogism, which Mr. Grote fully shows to be utterly fallacious, although renewed by most formal logicians down to Whately. It was the distinguishing glory of John Stuart Mill to show the relation of Induction to Deduction, and Mr. Grote zealously adopted his explanation. Aristotle, as Mr. Grote points out, was not wedded exclusively to the deductive formalities. In his numerous treatises on other subjects, scarcely any allusion is made to the syllogism, nor to its rules as laid down in the * Analytica.' He held that the deductive process was only the last half of the process of inference, and presupposed a foregone induction. It was the deductive portion that he himself analysed, and if any one had performed a similar analysis of the other half, we may fairly believe that he would have welcomed it, as filling up a gap in the complete theory of reasoning. WOKK ON ARISTOTLE. [131] Various leading points of Aristotelian doctrine, occurring in the ^ Analytica Priora,' are elucidated in Mr. Grote's com- mentary. The antithesis of notior nobis, and notior naturd, is strongly insisted on in many of Aristotle's writings. Here it is expounded by the contrast between example or induction, and deduction. The distinction is intelligible enough, but the phraseology is somewhat strained and figurative, and is not employed in modern philosophy. The ^ Analytica Priora ' is intended to give the complete theory of the syllogism, or deductive reasoning. There are two great applications of the syllogism — demonstration and dialectic — processes fundamentally contrasted by Aristotle. To the first, demonstration, he devotes a treatise called * Analytica Posteriora;' to the second a still larger treatise, the ' Topica.' The Posterior Analytics — ostensibly devoted to demon- strative or scientific truth, and the processes implicated in demonstration — is somewhat miscellaneous in its character ; it contains a good deal of foreign matter, although all of interest in the Aristotelian philosophy. Mr. Grote takes pains, at the outset of his commentary on this treatise, to illustrate the distinction between science and dialectic. Science or demonstration meant with Aristotle, as with us, the region of knowledge laid out by special inquirers after careful examination ; it is confined to a small number of subjects ; it has recognised jprincipia, or first principles to start from ; these principles are universally and essentially true, and admitted by all ; they are obtained from the induc- tion of particulars. On the other hand, dialectic is common sense or opinion, the knowledge of general society ; it extends to all manner of subjects; its principles are the received opinions of the community, or the dicta of individuals of more or less weight ; these are at best but probable. Both departments agree in coming under the scope of the syllogism. It was a feature of Aristotle's business-like sagacity or h2 [132] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. practical good sense, always to be aware of the comparatiye degree of certainty attainable in different subjects. There were two extremes — the exact sciences of demonstration, and the utterly loose and undigested opinions of the multitude upon complicated and difficult topics; between these two extremes lay a middle region, represented by his various miscellaneous treatises on topics theoretical and practical. For demonstration he takes the best illustrative type, Geometry. The learner of a demonstrative science must possess certain jprsecognitay in the shape of definitions and axioms, on which the teacher is to proceed. But then arises the Platonic paradox : learning is an impossible act ; for either you know a thing already, or you don't know it ; if you don't know it, how can you go in search of a thing that you are wholly ignorant of? Aristotle shows the way out of this puzzle by distinguishing between imperfect and perfect knowledge. He then deals with a different class of objectors, persons that failed to see the cardinal property of demon- stration ; one set maintaining the possibility of demonstrating backward ad infinitum; the other contending for the legi- timacy of reasoning in a circle. Again, in demonstration, the principles must be necessary or essential, and not concomitant or accidental (this is not the case.) He next contends, very properly, that the principia should be of the very highest universality, not inferior or derivative principles, which of course are them- selves demonstrable. Further, in demonstration, the con- clusion must follow necessarily from the premises. Again, the premises must be appropriate to the matter in hand. Moreover, the process of demonstration, although requiring universal propositions, neither requires nor countenances the Platonic theory of ideas — universal substances beyond and apart from particulars. Once more, the grand fundamental maxim of contradiction, appealed to in demonstrating by reducUo ad alsurdum, is not enunciated in any special science, but is a point of contact or communion of all the sciences ; it belongs to the First Philosophy, and is not to be made the WORK ON ARISTOTLE. [133] subject of scrutiny by the geometer or other specialist as such. In dialectical disputation, the questions and answers should always be kept within the limits of the science ; hence it is futile to discuss geometry with persons that are not geometers. Mr. Grote follows this treatise through its numerous wind- ings and repetitions, and succeeds in making plain the author's drift, even when he is crude and inconsistent. There is some confusion of thought in applying the syllo- gistic designation, the middle term, to intermediate links in physical cause and effect, and the celebrated four causes are brought in to explain the meanings of knowdedge. Generally speaking Aristotle has a good grasp of the main conditions of demonstration : he is less steady, but still very knowing, in the niceties of definition. From our present logical point of view we can see distinctly what he is aiming at, and where he misses : and the interest of the work consists in tracing the struggles of an original mind. The concluding chapter of the treatise discusses the mental origin of the jprincipia of demonstration themselves. Mr. Grote gives a careful rendering of Aristotle's view of tliis disputed problem, showing that he cannot be ranked with intuitionists, inasmuch as he held these first principles to be acquired ; still he regarded the inductive process as cul- minating in the infallible Nous, or theorising intelligence. The TopiCA is a very remarkable treatise. It is the working out of an artificial scheme for conducting dialectical debates, in which Aristotle exhausts all the resources of his logical subtleties. In this, as in the syllogism itself, he claims entire originality. He found teachers of contentious dialogue, as well as of rhetoric, but they knew nothing of the theory of their art; he compares them to a teacher of shoe-making that should merely show his pupils ready- made shoes. Long and elaborate as this treatise is, Mr. Grote follows it through all the details, and leaves a very fresh and vivid [134] CHAEACTEB AND WHITINGS. impression of Aristotle's genius for flue distinctions and technical abstractions. The first book is preparatory. It repeats the contrast between demonstration and dialectic, showing in particular the foundation of dialectic in common opinions instead of scientific principles. But not content with drawing the real distinction between the demonstrative and the dialectical syllogism, Aristotle makes a farther distinction between dialectic and eristic, on which Mr. Grote remarks that he is here carried away by his fixed determination to damage the Sophists — a purpose manifested at intervals throughout the treatise, and involving him in frequent inconsistencies. The Aristotelian name for the first principles in dialectic debate is endoxa, meaning opinions more or less authoritative, being fortified by a certain amount of prevailing belief or acceptance, and therefore possessing a certain presump- tion in their favour. These endoxa are opposed to adoxa, propositions wanting in authority, of which the extreme variety is named paradoxa, which have the predominant authority of opinion against them. We have naturalised this last class in our word paradox ; we ought also to have endox and adox, the endox especially is necessary to the un- derstanding of the present treatise. '' The essential feature of the endoxon is, that it has acquired a certain amount of recognition among the mass of opinions and beliefs floating and carrying authority at the actual time and place. When Josephus distinguished himself as a disputant in the schools of Jerusalem on points of law and custom, his arguments must have been chiefly borrowed from the endoxa or preva- lent opinions of the time and place ; but these must have differed widely from the endoxa found and argued upon by the contemporaries of Aristotle at Athens. '^It is within the wide field of floating opinions that dialectical debate and rhetorical pleading are carried on. Dialectic supposes a questioner or assailant, and a respon- dent or defendant. The respondent selects and proclaims a problem or thesis, which he undertakes to maintain; the WOKK ON AKISTOTLE. [135] assailant puts to him successive questions, with the view of obtaining concessions which may serve as premisses for a counter-syllogism, of which the conclusion is contradictory or contrary to the thesis itself, or to some other antecedent premiss which the respondent has already conceded. It is the business of the respondent to avoid making any answers which may serve as premisses for such a counter-syllogism. If he succeeds in this, so as not to become implicated in any contradiction with himself, he has baffled his assailant, and gained the victory. There are, however, certain rules and conditions, binding on both parties, under which the debate must be carried on. It is the purpose of the Topica to in- dicate these rules ; and, in accordance therewith, to advise both parties as to the effective conduct of their respective cases — as to the best thrusts and the best mode of parrying. The assailant is supplied with a classified catalogue of ma- terials for questions, and with indications of the weak points which he is to look out for in any new subject which may turn up for debate. He is further instructed how to shape, marshal, and disguise his questions, in such a way that the respondent may least be able to foresee their ultimate bearing. The respondent, on his side, is told what he ought to look forward to and guard against. Such is the scope of the present treatise; the entire process being considered in the large and comprehensive spirit customary with Aristotle, and distributed according to the Aristotelian terminology and classification." The debate is valuable, first, as a stimulating mental ex- ercise ; next, as facilitating our intercourse with the multi- tude, whose opinions we should know and be able to modify ; lastly, in the scrutiny of the principles of science proper. The first head is substantially the Platonic view of the Dia- logues of Search. The second is characteristic of Aristotle, who was careful to collect the current opinions of the multi- tude on all matters. He is also careful to lay out the class of problems suitable for debate ; they must neither be what all persons believe. [136] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. nor what no one believes ; there must be doubts and diflS- culties, and yet the premisses needed for their solution must not be far-fetched or recondite. The plan of the treatise follows that fourfold division of propositions, known as the predicables, which, in later times, were enumerated as five. Looking to the nature of a pro- position, as made up of two things — subject and predicate, the ordinary case should be that the subject means one thing, the predicate another ; '* generalship needs long ex- perience ; " " generalship " means one property, " needs long experience " means another ; and the coupling of the two is a piece of information or communicated knowledge. Now the proposition appears in its full character, when the two meanings are wholly unconnected by nature, so that we should never by considering one arrive at the other ; of such kind are propositions as to the original locality of minerals, plants, or animals ; for by looking at a mineral specimen we have no means of telling where it came from. To this extreme dis- connection of subject and predicate Aristotle gave the name concomitant predication ; it represents the proposition in its highest reality as imparting knowledge. Another case is where subject and predicate are distinct in meaning, but yet so far involved in one another, that by a full study of the subject, one might discover or discern the predicate. Such are the propositions as to geometrical figures. In a triangle the sum of two sides is greater than the third. Now a triangle means a three-sided figure, and that is all ; the fact that the combined length of two sides exceeds the third side is a distinct fact, but yet it is impli- cated in, or grows out of, the essential nature of the triangle, the three-sided property. For this new mode of predication Aristotle invented a term translated jprojprium or property ; and the distinction reflects honour on his subtlety. Con- comitant and property are thus the two modes of real predi- cation. But this is not all. People are very often ignorant of the meaning of the subject itself, or if not wholly ignorant? they may be imperfectly cognizant of its exact and fuU WORK ON ARISTOTLE. [137] meaning. Hence many propositions are framed, not to unite a subject and a predicate as distinct facts, but to declare the meaning of a subject : " a triangle is a three-sided figure," ^' generalship is the art of commanding of an army " — are propositions of this nature. Here is an entirely new mode of predication, it has the form and not the reality of a pro- position. Some other name must be found for this third situation ; we call it now definition, verbal predication, essen- tial predication. This threefold distinction in the forms of predication is most important ; it was made by Aristotle, and constitutes the predicables. But for the third mode he used two desig- nations — definition and genus ; the later logicians perplexed the matter still more by using three heads, genus^ species, difference ; their reason, probably, being that definition was explained by Aristotle as _p6r genus et dijfferentiam — stating first the genus of a thing and next its specific difference. It is obvious to us now that the verification of these three modes of predication proceeds by quite different routes. In the totally disconnected propositions — those of circumstance or accident, the proof (in the last resort) must be observa- tion of fact ; in the propria, observation may be brought in, but is not essential ; a skilful inference from the meaning of the subject evolves the predicate. In the third kind, we have not to deal with truth or falsehood, but with conformity between particulars and a general statement. Aristotle was very far from discerning fully the exact nature or conditions of each of these three modes of predi- cation ; yet he had marvellously shrewd glimpses of their respective characteristics. Farther : each of the predicables must fall under one or other of his Ten Categories, which gives enlarged scope for multiplying distinctions. Occasionally Aristotle makes this reference to some of the categories, but to no good purpose ; the categories themselves are too roughly laid out for any pregnant application. Aristotle's acuteness discovered another circumstance in [138] CHAEACTER AND WRITINQS. connection with the debating of true and false, namely, that the question often turned upon an identity ; whereupon, as usual, he takes to dividing the modes or kinds of identity — identity (1) numero, (2) specie, (3) genere. This also survived in the schools as he gave it. Finally : " What helps are available to give to the dialec- tician a ready and abundant command of syllogisms ? Four distinct helps may be named : (1) he must make a large col- lection of propositions ; (2) he must study and discrimiuate the different senses in which the terms of these propositions are used ; (3) he must detect and note differences ; (4) he must investigate resemblances." This is bravely sketched ; but the filling up disappoints us. The first and second helps are fairly discussed ; the two last — to our present apprehension, the most vital and funda- mental facts of knowledge — are merely made the groimd of some remarks upon classification and induction. Aristotle saw that induction, syllogism, and definition, were all pro- cesses of resemblance ; and he brought under the same head, as an endoxon, that what happens in any one of a string of similar cases, will happen in the rest. The meaning of toj^os (which gives the title Tojoica), in Latin locus, is a place where may be found arguments or modes of arguing, suited to each purpose or occasion — sedes argumentoTum, A short exemplification of xlristotle's copious detail of Loci, will show his meaning. Beginning with those theses where the predicate of the proposition to be impugned is Concomitant or Accident — the real proposition in the strictest sense — he enumerates no less than thirty-seven distinct loci, or argumentative points of view regarding it. Most of them suggest modes of assailing the thesis ; but there are also occasional intimations to the respondent in the debate, how he may best guard himself. Of the thirty-seven Mr. Grote recounts twenty-two, remarking, that " there are some items repetitions of each other, or at least not easily distinguishable " — a serious derogation from Aristotle's logical acuteness. WOEK ON ARISTOTLE. [139] The first locus is highly to the purpose. The supposition and pretension is that the proposition is one of Concomi- tance. Let the assailant, therefore, look and see whether in point of fact it does not fall under some of the other predicables ; whether the predicate may not be of the genus, essence, or definition of the subject itself; the very common mistake of confounding a real with a verbal pro- position. If the proposition, White is a colour, be given as a Concomitant, it can be impugned and shown to be an affirmation of the genus of the subject, for " white " is a species under the genus "colour." By showing this, an opponent may gain a dialectical victory. The second locus goes to the truth or falsehood of a uni- versal proposition, affirmative or negative, and declares the real basis or proof of a universal, namely, the truth of the particulars. This is of course the foundation of all inductive proof. Out of this arises at once the policy of an assailant or objector — review the particulars, and if any of them is untrue, the proposition is broken down. Or, instead of reviewing the ultimate particulars which might be endless or impossible — take them in genera and species, or sub- propositions; inasmuch as the higher generalities are fre- quently an aggregate of inferior, having a smaller compass ; " all bodies gravitate " (highest universal) : solids gravitate, liquids gravitate, airs gravitate (sub-propositions). Aristotle's own example is a favourite doctrine of his, belonging to the Eelativity of Knowledge. — The cognition of opposites is one ; and he divides Opposites into the several species, Belata, and Correlata, Contraries, Contradictories, and opposites re- specting Habitus and Privatio. Instead of dealing with this locus as merely one out of thirty- seven, Aristotle should have made it the head and front of the whole dialectic of Concomitant Affirmation. The proof or disproof of a universal, by examination of particulars, is the alpha and omega of science, proof, or certainty in knowledge. His third locus is also fundamental, but it should have been first — to define the terms used both in the subject and [140] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. in the predicate. Not a step should be taken with any proposition till its terms are defined. Moreover, definition is a branch of logic by itself, and in the sequel, Aristotle has a vast number of loci bearing upon definition, this being one of his predicables or divisions, so that he need not have introduced the process, except by reference, among the loci of concomitance. A fourth locus^ both for assailant and for respondent, is to discriminate the cases where the authority of the multitude is conclusive from those where it is not ; a rather trying operation, although exceedingly to the purpose. This should have been done once or for all by philosophers like Aristotle himself ; there should have been provided a set of canons of authority, to be applied by the disputants whom the present treatise addresses. Aristotle gives more than one suggestion as to cases where the terms of a universal thesis have a double or triple sense. This should come under definition ; for the carrying out of the process of defining discloses double meanings and equivo- cation. When there is an equivocation, a wary disputant can make use of it against an unwary opponent. Consent is obtained to the proposition under one meaning of a term, and then extorted for the other meaning. The refutation of a universal, by quoting contradictory particulars, unavoidably comes up again and again, and ought to have been consecutive and systematic. Thus, if a predicate is a generic quality, as in "the soul is moved J^ some of the specific modes must be applicable — some known variety of motion, as increase, destruction, generation, &c. If none of the recognised modes of motion apply to the soul, then the thesis is refuted. A very pertinent locus is, look to the antecedents and consequents of the thesis — what things it assumes, and what will follow from it; if any of these can be disproved, the thesis fails. This is repeated, without material difference, in a subsequent locus, A locus belonging to the tactics or management of a WOEK ON ABISTOTLE. [141] debate (called by Aristotle a sophistical procedure) is to transfer the debate to some point where we happen to be more at home. It may be advantageous in attacking the thesis, to construe the terms in their strict etymological sense, rather than according to usage. This is merely a repetition of the loci bearing upon equivocation or double meanings of words. The predicate may belong to its subject either necessarily or usually, or by pure hazard. Here Aristotle forgets the nature of concomitance, which is to exclude necessary con- nexions ; or else he repeats his first locus. The thesis may have predicate and subject exactly syno- nymous, so that the same thing will be affirmed as an accident of itself. G-rows also out of attention to the mean- ing of the terms, or definition. A number of loci bear upon the nature of opposita, ac- cording to Aristotle's classification of them, which he handled dexterously, and for the most part soundly. Very properly, he has a locus for reasoning by analogy, although imperfectly appreciating the nature and limitations of the process. He had also a considerable mastery of the argument from concomitant variations, or the proof from more or less ; out of which he extracts a highly serviceable locus. xin argument described by Aristotle as ex adjuncto, is something like what we now call the method of difference. " If the subject, prior to adjunction of the attribute, be not white or good, and if the adjunction of the attribute makes it white or good, then you may argue that the adjunct itself must be white or good." The foregoing selection contains the leading points of the second book of the ^ Topica,' perhaps the most remarkable book of the ten, when we consider that it sets forth, in a crude condition, the principal canons of inductive logic. These statements cannot be called germs, for they never germinated; inductive logic was developed from other sources ; they are rather crumbs and crudities, examples [142] CHAEACTER AND WHITINGS. of the numerous great truths that Aristotle touched in his speculative course. The third book carries out the same predicable, viz., accident or concomitant, to the practical department of good or evil, expetenda and fugienda ; the question being, of two or more distinct subjects which is the better or more desir- able. This is really an abuse of the forms of logic, which Aristotle is guilty of in the Ethics also, to suppose that they could be applied with any advantage to determining good and evil. There are doubtless certain formal maxims and criteria that may be laid down in this department, but the logical technicalities, accident, proprium, genus, species, are much better away from all that class of discussions. That such topics should be frequent in the dialectical debating at Athens was inevitable. They came closest home to every bosom. And as Aristotle himself was intensely practical, and the author of the best treatises in antiquity on ethics and on politics, he could bring his sagacity to bear upon the modes of comparing different ends of pursuit. Accordingly he here casts into the form of loci for debate a number of his views and theories. For example : — " Of two good subjects compared, that is better and more desirable which is the more lasting, or which is preferred by the wise and good man, or by the professional artist in his own craft, or by right law, or by the multitude, all or most of them. That is absolutely or simply better and more desirable, which is declared to be such by the better cognition ; that is better to any individual which is better by his own cognition." A thing is more desirable when good on its own account than when good by accident. What is good to all and at all times is better than what is good only for a special occasion or individual ; to be in good health is better than to be cut for the stone. What is good by nature, as justice, is better than what is good by artifice or acquisition, as the just individual, whose character must have been acquired. G-ood in the primary and more exalted elements of any subject, is more desirable than good belonging to the derivative, secondary. WOEK ON AEISTOTLE. [143] ■* and less exalted ;. health, which resides in the fundamental constituents of the body (wet, dry, hot, cold) is better than strength or beauty, residing in the hues and muscles. An end is superior to the means. These are a few out of a prolix enumeration of loci for good and evil ; they are given in the common forms of ethical disquisition, but in the latter portion of the book the language of formal logic is made to apply to this class of questions. For example. He supposes the thesis to be propounded to be a particular proposition. In that case we can apply the logical rule that the universal proves the particular, affirmative or negative. So the loci from opposites can be applied to particulars of the present class. It is a locus of contraries, if all pleasure is good, then all pain is evil ; hence if some pleasure is good, some pain is evil. Again, there is an argument, a fortiori, thus: if some capacity is a less good than science, while yet some capacity is good, then some science is good. A debater may propound a thesis with the assumption that, if true or false in any one case, it shall be accepted as true or false universally (if the human soul is immortal, all other souls are immortal). This is evidently to extend the particular into an universal, and the respondent must try to prove the negative in some particular case. These and other cases where the forms of logic are applied, might have been introduced into the previous book. The criteria special to a practical question are not brought for- ward at all : the propositions are treated purely in the logical aspect. The fourth book of the Topica is occupied with the pre- dicable " genus." It is really an excursus upon the relations of genus and species, of which Aristotle had an adequate mastery. Simple as the relationship is, it might be very readily blundered, especially in abstruse instances, so that many debates would arise upon the referring of a species to its proper genus. Suppose A is declared to be genus of B ; if now there be any members of B that cannot come under genus A, then B is not species of A, that is, A is not genus [144] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. of B. Again, the species has all the attributes of the genus and something more ; if, then, an alleged species has not all the generic qualities, it is not a species of that genus. Farther, the same species cannot be in two distinct genera, unless either one of the two be subordinate to the other, or both are comprehended under some common higher genus [not always then]. Thus the thesis may declare that justice is science ; now justice is in the distinct genus " virtue " ; but as both science and virtue can be referred to one and the same higher genus, the thesis '' justice is science " is not open to refutation. As usual, he makes this predicate run the gauntlet of his contraries, but does not clearly extricate the situations that he creates. He supposes cases where the species has some contrary, but the genus has not, and vice versa ; sickness in general (he says) has for its contrary health in general, but particular species of sickness, as fever, gout, &c., have no contrary. In all this- part, he goes astray from defective views of contrariety and correlation. Altogether, his handling of genus is historically curious, but uninstructive to the modern reader. The fifth book, devoted to '^ proprium " as a predicable, is not satisfactory. It was a great stroke of subtlety to chalk out this predicable, but his hold of it is very loose. His re- finements and distinctions violate the true nature of the pro- prium, and he admits irrelevant matter without knowing it. He distinguishes a proprium semper from a proprium occa- sional ; it is the proprium semper of a god to be immortal ; it is the proprium sometimes of a man to be walking in the market place. Now while it is a nice point to determine whether immortality be the essence (definition) of a god or the proprium ; the modern logician would regard " walking in the market place " as accident or concomitant of a man, although the power or capability of walking would be regarded as proprium. Among things of doubtful relevance is the prescription that the proprium should be better known than the subject whereof it is predicated ; the suitable place WORK ON ARISTOTLE. [145] for this remark is under definition, where also it is given. There is farther a locus or caution against equivocal terms, which applies alike to every mode of predication. A pro- prium may be impeached, in debate, if it belongs to other subjects equally with the one that you attach it to. Perhaps the correctest observation respecting the proprium, as expressly defined by himself is this: — To set out the pro- prium well, the predicate ought to reciprocate and ought to be co-extensive with the subject, but it ought not to affirm the essence thereof, as '' man is an animal by nature gentle," where the predicate is co-extensive with the subject and yet does not declare the essence. The loci regarding proprium are numerous and prolix, and the repetitions and inconsistencies have incurred strictures from the commentators. He does not fail to ring the changes in his opposita ; he introduces his locus of more and less, and brings in the still more abstruse distinctions of his philosophy, as his favourite esse and fieri. The sixth book, the predicable of " definition," is a grand effort of logical manipulation. The author shows his usual minuteness of distinction, and copiousness of enumeration, with the same faults of confusion and irrelevance. Mr. Grote follows him through thirty-six different loci bearing on the matter or substance of definition, while there are others bearing on the expression. From a few examples, the reader can ima- gine the general drift of the book as rendered by Mr. Grote. In debates respecting definition, the attack or defence may turn upon one or other of five points ; — the alleged definition may not apply to the subject at all ; a genus may have been given (defining being per genus et differentiam) but not the ricrht genus ; the definition may include extraneous matter ; it may not declare the essence ; it may be good in substance but badly expressed or set out. The three first points belong to the previous books, the two remaining are the subject-matter of the present book. Of these two, one relates to the substance of definition, the other to the form or expres- sion. The last is taken first. ^ I [146] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. Bad expression may appear in two ways; there may be indistinctness ; and there may be redundancy. Indisiinctness may arise from equivocal terms ; from the misuse of meta- phors ; from employing terms that are far-fetched or little known (exemplified from Plato) ; from not making clear the contrary of the defining quality ; lastly, when the defining marks are insufficient to make known the thing meant (a criterion which Aristotle's own definitions often lamentably fail to satisfy). Bedundancy arises if the terms include other things besides the object defined (this error is not well described by "redundancy"); and if the same attribute be predicated twice over. Much more numerous, as well as more interesting, are the loci bearing on the substance of the definition. As in the other predicables, Aristotle puts his best foot foremost ; his first loci generally touch the fundamental conceptions of the subject. He starts with the sweeping requirement that the matter of the definition must be jprius and notius as com- pared with the definiend. One of his favourite distinctions is between things more known absolutely, or hy nature, and things more known to us ; by nature, the point is better known than the line, the line than the surface, the surface than the solid ; to us, the solid is best known ; we begin by conceiving the concrete solid ; and afterwards attain to the abstractions — surface, line, point. Too plainly, a definer may commit many sins against such an abstruse require- ment as this ; and hence the scope for an acute opponent fitted out from the Aristotelian armoury. A second locus impugns a definition that does not mention the genus ; a third is aimed at insufficiency of enumeration — there being three or four facts, and only one mentioned. The genus may be properly given, while there are faults in giving the differenti96. A definition may be exclusively negative, e. g,, a line is length without breadth. If the subject be relative, so must the differentiae. If the subject admits of More and Less, the definition must say so. When a relatum has to be defined, the true correlate must be given. As usual, all WORK ON ARISTOTLE. [147] modes of opposition furnish loci. The terms of a definition must not conjoin incompatible facts ; white has been defined, colour mingled with fire ; now colour is incorporeal, and cannot be mingled with fire which is corporeal. It is a mistake to define a subject by what is its highest excellence, a rhetor is one that omits nothing that can be plausibly said for a cause. You may not be able to attack a definition as a whole, but may successfully impugn some of its parts. More- over, you may take an adroit advantage of obscurity or intelligibility, by clearing it up so as to suit your own purpose. The seventh book continues the theses on definition, and enters upon the important collateral question of identity or sameness, already discriminated by Aristotle with sameness numero, and sameness sjpecie or genere. His close observation of the field of logical proof could not but disclose to him this property, just as he obtained an insight into the fact of relativity ; but he necessarily failed to put both facts into their position as the fundamentals of all cognition' The predicables are now finished, and the eighth book brings us back to the kind of general considerations advanced in the first. What is the order of procedure most suitable; first, for the questioner or assailant ; next, for the respondent or defender ? This order is different for the dialectician and for the man of science or philosopher. Aristotle classifies the different purposes of the debate, and claims originality in so doing, as well as in prescribing rules for each kind sepa- rately. He administers counsel to both partners in the conduct of the debate ; he indicates the mode of approaching it by preparatory questions ; these fall under the four heads — induction of particulars, maintaining the dignity of the dis- course, concealment, and the imparting of clearness. What he has to say about induction has already been noted; of dignity he says little ; the arts of concealment are detailed at great length, and include deception of manner as well as masking of operations; for clearness he prescribes the use of familiar examples taken from well-known poets like Homer. I 2 [148] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. He instructs the respondent separately, and \Yitli considerable minuteness, although, in point of fact, the equipment for both partners must be very much the same. Towards the close of the book the dialectic shades off into the syllogistic logic, with which it is more or less implicated, the logical fallacies being also dialectical fallacies. In the present book he treats of petitio principii, and petitio contrariorum as occurring in dialectic. His concluding remarks consist of sound advice for exercise and practice in debate. The ninth and last book of the ^Topica' illustrates the remark just made as to the interlacing of logic and dialectic. So thoroughly has this been regarded as a logical treatise, that it has been adopted as a constituent part of the syllo- gistic or scholastic logic, and is the classical dissertation on fallacies slavishly retained in its minutest details to our own time. None of the other books of the ' Topica ' have found a place in our modern education ; the scheme of the predicables has been borrowed from it, but without Aristotle's copious elucidations and applications of them. Although Mr. Grote's analysis of the Sophistici elenchi will be found to contain fresh points of view, even to those that have studied the ' Fallacies' in ' Whately ' or any other work on the scholastic model, we shall do no more than call atten- tion to the chapter as concluding the author's vindication of the Sophists. It never occurred to any one before Mr. G-rote to remark on the extraordinary liberty taken by Aristotle with the so- called Sophists, when he used their name to designate the entire body of fallacies, or intellectual errors and weaknesses, which it was the object of a logical discipline to provide against and correct. "Fallacy," he said, ^^ thy name is Sophist." If there had been one special mode of error in- dulged in by the Sophists as a class, or in any way identified with their vocation, as when philosophers are styled theo- retical, or when politicians are said to take low views of human nature, there might have been a show of propriety in calling such error by their name. The disparaging word WOEK ON AKISTOTLE. [149 "empiric" was first given by Hippocrates to the medical men of his own time, because they did not combine general views or theories with their practice. But to gather together every known species of error, to compile a treatise professedly exhaustive of the violations of sound reasoning, and to name the whole after the Sophists, as if they alone were guilty of such transgressions, and the rest of the world were infallible, was a proceeding equally strange and reprehensible. Aristotle adopted Plato's dislike of the Sophists. One might perhaps suppose that they had better reasons for thinking badly of the class than Mr. Grote has for dissenting from their concurrent view on such a matter. But the in- consistencies of both philosophers in maintaining their ill opinion of these men are enough to rouse suspicion. The Sophist, according to Aristotle, is one who makes money by a show of wisdom without the reality. The ostensible purpose of the present treatise, judging from its title, is to expose the bad arts and unsound arguments of this personage ; the actual contents of the treatise must be regarded as, for the time, an admirable classification of lomcal fallacies, executed at no small cost of time and labour. The Sophistical Elenchus or refutation, being a delusive semblance imposing on ordinary men, cannot be understood without the theory of Elenchus in general ; and this theory cannot be understood without the entire theory of the syllo- gism, of which the Elenchus is one variety. We must know the conditions of a good and valid syllogism before we can study tlie tests of a valid elenchus, which last must be known as a preparation for the pseudo-elenchus — the sophistical, invalid, or sham — refutation. There are four species of debate : (1) didactic, (2) dialectic, (3) peirastic, (4) eristic or sophistic. Between the two first, Mr. Grote remarks, there is a real antithesis, much dwelt upon by Aristotle ; but the peirastic and the eristic are mere aspects or varieties of dialectic. Dialectic is essentially gymnastic and peirastic ; gymnastic in reference to the two [150] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. debaters, and peirastic in reference to the arguments and doctrines made use of. Victory is the aim of the disputants in every case, but the arts employed may be honest and creditable, exemplifying the worthy debate. If, however, the assailing champion, bent upon victory at all cost, has re- course to dishonest interrogative tricks, or the defensive champion to perverse and obstructive negations, beyond the prescribed boundary, the debate is called by Aristotle eristic or contentious, from the undue predominance of the con- troversial spirit and purpose; also soj)histic^ from the fact that there existed (as he asserts) a class or profession of persons called Sophists, who regularly studied and practised these culpable mancBuvres, first with a view to rtsputation, and ultimately with a view to pecuniary profit, being pre- tenders to knowledge and wisdom without any justifying reality. It must be apparent that no man, not even Aristotle him- self, could consistently carry out this distinction. In the first place, it is altogether irrelevant to the scope of logic, which considers the value of arguments and not their purpose. In the next place, the line between the worthy and the unworthy disputant is impossible to draw. Mr. Grote's concluding observations on Aristotle's false position in this whole matter are irresistible and yet mild : — " I think it a mistake on the part of Aristotle to treat the fallacies incidental to the human intellect as if they were mere traps laid by Sophists and litigants ; and as if they would never show themselves, assuming dialectical debate to be conducted entirely with a view to its legitimate pur- poses of testing a thesis and following out argumentative consequences. It is true that, if there are infirmities inci- dental to the human intellect, a dishonest disputant will be likely to take advantage of them. So far it may be well to note his presence. But the dishonest disputant does not originate these infirmities ; he finds them already existing, and manifested undesignedly not merely in dialectical debate, but even in ordinary discourse. It is the business of those . WORK ON ARISTOTLE. [151] who theorize on the intellectual processes to specify and discriminate the fallacies as liabilities to intellectual error among mankind in general, honest or dishonest, with a view to precaution against their recurrence, or correction, if they do occur ; not to present them as inventions of a class of pro- fessional cheats, or as tares sown by the enemy in a field where the natural growth could be nothing but pure wheat. " In point of fact the actual classification of fallacies given by Aristotle is far sounder than his announcement would lead us to expect. Though he entitles them sophistical refuta- tions, describing them as intentionally cultivated and exclu- sively practised by professional Sophists for gain, or by unprincipled litigants for victory, yet he recognises them as often very difficult of detection, and as an essential portion of the theory of dialectic generally. The various general heads under which he distributes them are each characterised by intellectual or logical marks." The Topica completes the Organon or logical treatises of Aristotle. It was Mr. G-rote's intention to add here a chapter of his own on the modern logic as compared with the Aristotelian ; but the time already consumed upon a single department of his author warned him that he must proceed to other subjects. Next to the Organon came the Meta- THYSics. Of this department he takes a very enlarged view. To attain supreme and commanding generalities has been the aim of great thinkers in all ages. The first Greek philosophers were distinguished by their search after some all-embracing unity ; they thought to comprehend the Universe under a single idea. In Aristotle's time the plurality of the sciences was recognised ; the mathematical, the physical, and the biological departments were separately sketched, while the mental department was seen to be dis- tinct and unique. Nevertheless, it was felt by Aristotle that there must still be a central or master science, some common ground w^here all the departments come together, as one in [152] CHARACTEE AND WEITINGS. the many. By the search after such a science the philosopher was distinguished from the specialist. For the construction of this first philosophy, as he called it, Aristotle laid hold of the logical maxim called the prin- ciple of contradiction, and took much pains to expound it, and to vindicate it against some of his predecessors who seemed to deny it. He took a very just view of the nature of this maxim ; he regarded it as common to all reasoning, in every department, and as in itself indemonstrable. In addition to the purely logical law of contradiction, he em- braced, as suitable for his first philosophy, his four causes, the distinction between potential and actual, and the abstrac- tions form, matter, and privation, which play a great part in his philosophy. The treatises termed (by an accident) Metaphysica are occupied with the numerous discussions raised upon these points, and with criticisms upon the views of the preceding philosophers respecting them. Since, however, the Physica, although nominally the special department treating of the physical phenomena of the universe — motion, force, &c., is really expounded in the strain of the Metaphysica, Mr. Grote couples the two, and entitles his account of them ' Physica and Metaphysica'. Unfortunately he has executed only one chapter of this design, which, however, taken along with a free translation of the six leading books of the Metaphysica, will convey to the reader a very distinct view of the Aristo- telian handling of the highest abstractions of philosophy. These treatises are the classical authority for the opinions of the early Greek philosophers, and in that view alone must always be resorted to by the student of the history of phi- losophy, and Mr. Grote has done much to satisfy the desire of the English reader for this information. . Mr. Grote had formerly prepared an account of the very difficult treatise on the Soul (De Axima). Although not so full as he might have made it, had he come upon the subject in regular course, and with time and strength at his com- WORK ON ARISTOTLE. [153] Tna.nd, it embraces all the leading and difficult points of Aristotle's Psychology. While working on this treatise, he repeatedly stated that he had gained new insight into the fundamental positions of the Aristotelian philosophy. More particularly he was led to see that one pervading conception of Aristotle's mind was the notion of the Celestial Body — a mixture of science and emotion — which was to him both a philosophy and a theology. His vital distinction of Form and Matter was invoked to express the relation of Soul and Body. The Soul was ^' Form " ; and the grand region of Form, in the Universe, is the Celestial Body — the vast, deep, circular, perceivable mass circumscribing the Kosmos, and en- closing, in and around its centre, Earth with the three other elements (Water, Air, Fire), tenanted by substances gene- rated and perishable. This celestial body is the abode of Divinity, including many divine beings who take part in its eternal rotations — the Sun, Moon, Stars, and other gods. Every Soul (there being a hierarchy of souls from the Plant upwards), every Form that animates tlie matter of a living being, derives from this celestial region its vitalising influence. This doctrine of the divine body, as the source of Soul, is not stated in the ' De Anima,' but imported from other treatises, to supply gaps in the information ; and the appli- cation is a novelty. It is carried out still farther into the vexed question of Aristotle's opinions as to the highest human soul — the Nous, or thinking principle, divided into two functions, receptive {Intellectus Pattens) and constructive or theorising (Intellectus Agens). Of the two, the last — Intellectus Agens — is the more venerable ; it is pure intel- lectual energy, unmixed, unimpressible from without, and separable from all animal body. It is more especially iden- tified with the celestial substance, and is eternal and im- mortal. But this immortality is not conferred on individuals, or on the theorising Nous as it exists in Socrates, Plato, or any other man : the individualities of these men perish with the body. Such is Mr. Crete's rendering of Aristotle's [154] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. obscure indications on this subject. Other interpreters sup- Ij pose that the doctrine of a personal or individual immortality can be inferred from certain passages. Sir A. Grant pnts stress upon the remark, — '' It is uncertain whether the soul be not the actuality of the body in the same way as the sailor is the actuality of his hoat,'' from which the inference might be, although it is not drawn by Aristotle, that the sailor could, at the end of his voyage, step out of his boat. Of one thing we may be tolerably confident, that Aristotle would not pro- nounce a decided opinion against so venerated a doctrine as our continued existence after death ; although he makes very little of it as a motive, in the Ethics. There are included in the work, several polemical dis- cussions as to Aristotle's doctrines respecting TJniversals and the mental origin of First Principles. The paper on TJniversals brings out the contrast of Plato and Aristotle on TJniversals, shown chiefly from the Categories, wherein the Platonic ideas are met by the Aristotelian doctrine of Substance, in the First Category, as being constituted by a particular or concrete individual, of which the universals were predicable. The '^ Hoc Aliquid " is the only complete '^ Ens '' or substance, and the Universal exists along with it, as a predicate, but is nothing in itself apart. As reo^ards the mental origin of our knowledo:e of First O c? O Principles, or Axioms, this is the question debated in modern times under the designation Intuitions as opposed to Ex- perience. The supporters of intuitive or innate ideas, or common sense, have often claimed Aristotle as on their side, and Sir W. Hamilton in particular, has produced an array of thirteen citations to that effect. Mr. Grote ex- amines all these citations, and shows that in only one of them does Aristotle appear as the champion of authoritative common sense. The other twelve citations, he maintains either to have no bearing upon the point, or to indicate the very reverse ; and he charges Hamilton in regard to many of them, with mistaking or misrepresenting Aristotle's meaning. WORK ON AlUSTOTLE. [155] 111 a separate dissertation, he gathers together the state- ments of Aristotle respecting first, the authority of common sense ; and secondly, the origin, in the mind, of the axioms or princijpia of science. The result arrived at on the first head, is that common sense is an inferior authority, as com- pared with science. The second head involves a difficult psychological enquiry, that Aristotle was very imperfectly qualified to resolve. He evidently inclines to the inductive origin of first principles. In the Analytica, he states that axioms are derived by induction, from particulars of sense, and are apprehended or approved by the Nous or intellect ; which leaves an undecided margin between the two origins — a posteriori and a priori : and it is not possible to extract a definite settlement of the question from his conflicting modes of representation. It has been made a complaint against Mr. Grote, and is the principal objection taken against his work, that while rebutting Hamilton's appropriation of Aristotle to the modern sect of intuitionists, he is himself guilty of the like offence in forcing his author to speak in the language of the a pos- teriori school, to which he was attached. I think the charge misapprehends Mr. Grote's w^ay of looking at the great philo- sophers of the past. It was certainly agreeable to find Plato or Aristotle holding his own favourite opinions (more espe- cially on ethical subjects) ; but he studied and admired their writings altogether irrespective of this consideration. More- over, he would not have been flattered by their adhesion to his views, in the absence of valid reasons ; his idea of philo- sophy was emphatically Ferrier's "reasoned truth." He never looked to Aristotle to confirm his own opinions ; and would not have considered himself a gainer by forcing a coincidence of view out of precarious and vacillating state- ments. At the same time, seeing that authority is one of the strongholds of the belief in innate ideas (being homogeneous with tlie doctrine itself), he considered it worth his while to show that Aristotle could not be fairly enrolled among the •• testimonies " for that creed. 1 56] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. In Mr. Grote's exposition of the Aristotelian doctrines there is nothino: more characteristic than the stress he lavs upon Substance as equivalent to the Individual Concrete, basing on the opposition in which the first of the Categories is. made to stand to all the rest. Objection has been taken to this interpretation on the ground that the treatise Cate- gorise is of doubtful authenticity, if not certainly spurious. The answer is twofold. In the first place, Mr. Grote did by no means overlook the question of the authenticity of the Categorise, as is clear from his note in Vol. i. p. 80, where he says that he is not convinced by the arguments that have been urged against the treatise. And, secondly, the same note claims that in any case the treatise should be considered, because the doctrine of the Categories is indisputably Aris- totelian. As touching the nature of Substance this is so true that from others of the works never suspected, there is no difficulty in establishing the identification with the Individual Concrete, or at least in arguing as strongly as Mr. Grote argues for it. Complaint has also been made by the critics that the dis- cussion on the Canon in Chap. ii. is inadequate to the sub- ject, all questions as to the received works being waved aside with the general remark that about forty treatises remain of authenticity not open to any reasonable suspicion. The objection is in so far w^ell founded that there is room for much remark both as to the genuineness of some of the printed w^orks and as to the form and exact constitution of others. Mr. Grote, however, in p. 59 gives it plainly to be understood that at the particular places he meant to discuss such matters, adding that he should not be able to fall back, as for Plato, upon a single authoritative catalogue of the works. Besides, it remains uncertain whether he did not intend to devote a part of the treatise of three chapters left in the MS. between his second chapter and the chapter on the Categorise to farther consideration of the Canon in general. With the opinion that he certainly had of the authenticity of the chief works, he might well be anxious, at his time of WOEK ON AEISTOTLE. [157] life, to postpone external discussions till he liad worked out his exposition of the works themselves. The frequently-expressed regret that Mr. Grote had not undertaken the Politics and the Ethics is natural and just. With respect to the Politics, it was not merely that he had been long conversant with both the theory and the practice of politics, and without bias except towards the interests of the people as a whole : there was a Still deeper reason for the regret. Aristotle's leaning as a theorist in politics must have been qualified by his own position in Athens, the greatest of existing democracies. He was "semi-Macedo- nian in his sympathies. He had no attachment to Hellas as an organised system, autonomous, self-acting, with an Hellenic city as president." He had no love for the democratical constitution as such, and probably contem- plated with satisfaction its approaching extinction. Yet our present knowledge assures us that but for the demo- cratical system of Greece, philosopliy would never have reached the point that it did in his person ; no despotism would have been so tolerant of philosophers as was the Athenian people. Now the Politics of Aristotle w^as written under circum- stances rendering it scarcely possible to do justice to demo- cracy. He professes to be an impartial critic of all political systems, and probably is so to a very considerable degree ; but he wants to be carefully tracked by some one thoroughly conversant (as far as a modern can be) with the w orkings of the Greek governments. No man has yet appeared so com- petent for this task as Mr. Grote ; with the utmost respect and tenderness towards Aristotle himself, he combined an exact view of his political situation, and all the attainable knowledge of the political facts of Grecian history. He had occasion to challenge Aristotle's estimate of Nikias, as com- pletely belied by the facts before us. And there might have been still more to say on his political theories — his search after the phantom of a golden mean in political constitutions that could always be a tyrant's plea against the popular prin- [158] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. ciple, whicli alone had been identified (as Mr. Grote believed) with the superiority of Greece, and whose extinction by Aristotle's patrons had permanently depressed the condition of the world, both politically and intellectually. As regards the Ethics, there can be no doubt that Mr. Grote's handling of Aristotle's doctrines would have been unique. Those doctrines he regarded as not only a great advance upon Socrates and Plato, but as in various respects superior to some of our modern conceptions. His leanings as an ethical theorist are shown in the ^ Plato,' both with reference to Plato himself and in the delineation of the Cyrenaics and Cynics ; while the present work contains brief though expressive notices of Epicurus and the Stoics. But the work of Aristotle, so minute in its detail of points re- specting virtues, conduct, and happiness, would have afforded numerous openings for fresh remarks on the questions that come home to every one. Many have asked why he might not have postponed, or contracted, the Logic, so as to secure the Politics and the Ethics. To reply that he followed a natural order of the works would not be the whole explanation. The fact must be told, that, while he had no small interest in ethics and politics, he had a fascination for logic and metaphysics. He was one — " That unto logic hadde long y-go." LATEE PUBLIC LIFE. [159] CHAPTER VII. LATER PUBLIC LIFE. Mr. Geote was one of the original founders of the London University, afterwards called University College, and was an active member of Council from the commencement, in 1827, up to the year 1831. He entered with zeal into the scheme, as proposing to impart an education that should be at once extensive and unsectarian. He again joined the Council in 1849, and from that time till his death took a leading part in the administration of the College. In 1860 he became Treasurer ; and on the death of Lord Brougham, in 1868, he was elected President. His was one of seven names added by the Crown, on the 19th of March, 1850, to the Senate of the University of London, the others being Lords Monteagle and Overstone, Sir James Graham, Thomas B. Macaulay, Sir George Corne- wall Lewis, and Henry Hallam. From the date of his ap- pointment he gave unremitting attention to the business of the Senate, entering into every question that arose, and taking a lead in the most critical decisions of the University during the twenty-one years of his connexion with it. The first subject of great importance that came up after Mr, Grote's appointment was the admission of the Graduates to a position in the government of the University. On the 26th of February, 1850, there was laid before the Senate a declaration and statement, signed by 361 Graduates, desiring that the Graduates might be admitted into the corporate body. This was the commencement of a protracted agitation and struggle, terminated, in 1858, by the issue of a new Charter, [160] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. conceding what had been fought for. Mr. Grote cordially supported the claims of the Graduates. His aid in this cause was warmly acknowledged in a resolution of the Annual Committee of Convocation passed shortly after his death. On the 1st of February, 1851, a memorial was presented to ih.e Senate, signed by eleven persons (including Sir Row- land Hill and his three brothers, and Mr. William Ellis), in favour of throwing open the degrees of the University to all classes, irrespective of the manner or place of their education. On the 5th of April was presented another petition to the same effect, more numerously signed. No notice appears to have been taken of these applications. On the 19th of November, 1856, the Senate admitted the London Working Men's College amoDg the affiliated colleges of the University. Mr. Grote opposed this step, on the ground that so long as the Uni- versity required attendance on classes, a line should be drawn between those who could give up their whole time to study and those that spent their day in industrial avocations. He had been hitherto favourable to the combining of certified class instruction with examinations as requisites to the de- grees. The admission of the Working Men's College (carried chiefly by members of Senate opposed to the restricting of the degrees to students in the affiliated colleges) shook his faith in the value of the class certificates. About the same time it became known to the Senate that certificates were granted by some of the affiliated colleges on mere nominal studentship. This completed the conviction in Mr. Grote's mind that the degrees should be thrown open, and granted on the exclu.-ive test of examinations. Accordingly, when the subject came up in connexion with the Draft Charter, by w^hich the Graduates were to be admitted, he supported the insertion of a clause for abrogating the original constitution as to affiliated colleges ; which clause was carried in the Senate by a large majority. Many remonstrances followed *this decision, especially from the affiliated colleges. The Senate entrusted to Mr. Grote and Mr. Warburton the drawing up a report on these remonstrances, which was presented to LATER PUBLIC LIFE. [161] the Senate on the 22nd of July, 1857. This report was Mr. Grote's composition, and contains an exhaustive discussion of the arguments of the remonstrants. On the 8th of July, 1857, while the Draft Charter was under discussion, a memorial was laid before the Senate, signed by twenty-four men of science, Fellows of the Eoyal Society, suggesting the institution of degrees and honours for proficiency in mathematical and physical science. On the 14th of April, 1858, the Senate appointed a Committee to consider the propriety of establishing degrees in science ; of this Committee Mr. Grote was a member, along with the Chancellor, Mr. Warburton, Sir James Clark, Dr. Arnott, Mr. Faraday, Mr. Brande, Mr. Walker, and Mr. Hopkins. The Committee held a series of meetings, and examined the memorialists individually as to their views and wishes, and afterwards drew up a report in favour of the principle of degrees in science. Being reappointed by the Senate to prepare a definite scheme, the Committee agreed that there should be a Bachelor's Degree, which should rest on a broad and comprehensive basis of scientific acquirement, and a Doctor's Degree for eminence in special branches. A draft- scheme for the several Degrees was, at the Committee's request, prepared by Dr. Arnott. It was very much o wing- to Mr. Grote's advocacy that the Moral Sciences were re- tained in the programme, several members of the Committee being disposed to limit the subject of examination to the Physical and Natural-History Sciences. On the 7th of July, the Senate, with one dissentient voice, adopted the report. The degrees were instituted accordingly. The other uni- versities are slowly entering upon a similar course. On the 27th of February, 1862, he* succeeded Sir John Lefevre as Vice-Chancellor. It was a singular testimony to the largeness of his views, that Mr. Grote's life-long classical studies and associations left him free to appreciate fully the great importance of science in education. In point of fact, however, he combined with his own erudite pursuits an intense avidity for the phy- m [162] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. sical sciences, along with the metaphysical, and.they formed a considerable portion of his reading to the last. He uni- formly resisted all proposals to limit the study of logic and moral philosophy, or to lower its position in the degrees where it had obtained a place ; and, generally, he was an advocate for the breadth of culture maintained in the Matri- culation and Degree Examinations, as contrasted with the restricted number of subjects required for the Oxford and Cambridge degrees. Another subject that he lost no opportunity of pressing was the Education of Women. The Senate had been advised that, under the terms of the original charter of the University, women were inadmissible to the examiuations, and when Miss Elizabeth Garrett, in 1862, applied to be admitted as a candidate for matriculation, the application was refused by a majority of seven to six. At a subsequent meeting of the senate a memorial was presented from Mr. Newson Garrett and others, in favour of procuring such an alteration of the charter as would extend to women the privileges of the University. This memorial was taken into consideration on the 7 th of May, and Mr. Grote moved : — '^ That the senate will endeavour, as far as their powers reach, to obtain a modification of the charter, rendering female students admissible to the degrees and honours of the University of London, on the same conditions of examination as male students, but not rendering them admissible to become Members of Convocation." • The motion was lost by the casting vote of the Chancellor. Mr. Crete's speech on the occasion, as preserved in his own handwriting, wa§ to the following effect : — " I am glad that the senate, by the vote which they have passed at an earlier period of this meeting, have agreed to maintain the matriculation examination as it now stands, with its full curriculum and requirements. In my concep- tion the first duty of the senate is to keep up a high standard of liberal education, and make their certificates and degrees LATER PUBLIC LIFE. [163] attainable only by a large and comprehensive range of study. Subject to this primary condition, their second duty is to throw open their examinations to all who have gone through the prescribed studies, and who are prepared to give proof of their having done so with diligence and efficacy. " My present motion is consequent upon Mr. Garrett's letter, which stands on the minutes of this day, wherein he intimates that his daughter. Miss Elizabeth Garrett, has gone through the studies which give her a prospect of passing the matriculation examination of the University of London, and his hope that the technical legal objection, which now excludes her as well as other women from the examination, may be removed by a modification of the charter. The senate will recollect that the application of Miss Garrett came before us at a former meeting, and that doubts were then entertained by various persons whether the legal inter- pretation of our charter did exclude women from our exami- nations. Since then all doubt has been terminated by the opinion of the Attorney-General (taken, not by us, but by those who desire to obtain admission). He pronounces that such is the legal interpretation, and that females are at present inadmissible. '' Though I accept this as the unquestionable legal inter- pretation, I think that Mr. Garrett is perfectlj^ right in calling it technical. It is altogether at variance with the spirit of the charter, as expressed in the large words of the second clause : 'Her Majesty deems it to be the duty of her royal office, for the advancement of re^gion and morality and the promotion of useful knowledge, to hold forth to all classes and denominations of her faithful subjects, without any distinction whatsoever, an encouragement for pursuing a regular and liberal course of education.' After reading these words, I say, which express the most unequivocal totality, and forbid the introduciug of any distinction whatsoever, no one would imagine that the first step would be to take a distinction so important and so far reaching, that it strikes off one half of Her Majesty's faithful subjects, and those, too, [164] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. all the members of her own sex. The motion which I am now about to make is in full conformity with the spirit and with the ordinary meaning of those most comprehensive phrases. It goes only to make the legal interpretation of the charter harmonise with its spirit. "It is known to every one, however occasionally over- looked, that the cultivators of literature and science, though the majority of them are men, include also in their ranks a minority of women. Among this minority of women, some have rendered essential service to science and to all who seek for scientific instruction. The great French astronomer Laplace acquired imperishable renown by the profound and original researches of his ' Mecanique Celeste ' ; but an English lady, Mrs. Somerville, rendered a service, though inferior, not less real, by doing what few men were com- petent to do, by adapting that work to English readers in her book called the 'Mechanism of the Heavens' ; and she rendered a still greater service by her better-known works — ' The Connection of the Physical Sciences,' and ' Physical G-eography' — to which works a large circle of readers, males as well as females, have been greatly indebted for instruction. The fact thus stands upon record, and is undeniable, that there exists a female minority who cultivate literature and science, atid that some of the members of that minority have entitled themselves to take rank along with the most eminent men, even in the most abstruse and diflScult branches of science. '^ Such being the case, I maintain that when an university is constituted, as ours is, for the express purpose of en- couraging a high measure of scientific and literary studies, the plainest principles of justice require that we should take the literary and scientific world as it is and deal equally with both sexes ; that we should acknowledge the female minority as well as the male majority: and that, after having deter- mined proper conditions of examination, we should admit* individuals of the sex of Mrs. Somerville to be examined, as well as individuals of the sex of Laplace. The onus jprobandi LATER PUBLIC LIFE. [165] lies on those who contend that the female minority should be excluded from our examinations, and none but members of our own sex admitted, and a masculine type, and that to admit women to the studies suitable for men would be con- founding a distinction important to uphold. Gentlemen who hold this opinion have undoubtedly a full right to judge for themselves on the type of female education, and I am quite aware that a very respectable portion of the community judge as they do about it. But I dissent from them : I hold the opposite opinion ; and another portion of the community, equally respectable, hold the opinion along with me. I believe that the studies included in our curriculum are improving and beneficial in their effect upon the minds of women, where women are disposed and able to appropriate them, as well as upon the minds of men. Now those females who hold the same views as I do on feminine education, and their fathers or guardians, are powerfully interested in the admission of women to our examinations ; but those who adopt the same opinion as Lord Overstone have really no interest in the question at all. Whether the University is open or closed to women, these females will pursue their own educational march in a different direction, without being affected by our regulations. They have a full right to do this ; but they have no right to make their own opinions upon female education binding on all, whether assentient or dissentient ; they have no locus standi entitling them to insist on closing the doors of our University against all those other females who approve and desire to pursue the studies which it prescribes. "I make no pretensions to exalt my own opinion on female education, and that of those who agree with me, as a type of orthodoxy, but neither can I admit the right of any other person to stigmatise it as heresy. " Mr. Garrett says to us : — ^ My daughter is devoting her- self to those studies which your charter declares to be laudable and to deserve encouragement ; she has qualified herself by diligent application to fulfil the requirements of [166] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. your matriculation curriculum. I ask you to allow her pro- ficiency to be tested at your examinations, and to give her a certificate if she can answer the questions satisfactorily ; she, as well as myself, considers that the certificate will be an honour and credit to her, and an advantage to her future plans of life.' Now to this request on the part of Mr. and Miss Garrett the senate are called upon to reply : — ' We cannot admit Miss Garrett to be examined. We consider our studies as laudable and deserving encouragement only for men ; we consider them not laudable, and we intend to discountenance them, in women. We cannot grant any academical honours and advantages which will tend to encourage what is a bad and wrong type of education for women.' " This is the answer which the senate are called upon to make in declining to admit Miss Garrett, and I maintain that it is an answer which the senate is not warranted in returning. The senate, in making such an answer, and in enforcing an exclusion justified by it, would be usurping a right of determining by authority a point which Mr. Garrett and his daughter have full discretion to determine for them- selves. " I contend that every female (assisted in the cases of those in statu ]^u])illari by parent or guardian) has a right to choose for herself among the various types of education, which of them will best suit her own aptitudes, tastes, or plans of life. The choice will of course be different under different circumstances. One w^oman may prefer a highly ornamental education, exuberant in accomplishments ; an- other may study the full perfection of domestic management and housewivery ; a third may take to modern languages ; a fourth may address herself to science and the severe depart- ments of literature : and, lastly, others may blend all these different matters in every conceivable proportion. All these varieties will co-exist ; I lay down no uniform rule, nor do I imagine that any one rule can be laid down. My argument is that the choice between them all lies with the female LATER PUBLIC LIFE. [167] herself; and that if, among the various types, she prefers that which coincides with our curriculum, we ought to be the last persons to discountenance or discredit her for doing so. It is enough for me to show that our type is one among many admissible types of feminine education ; one which any woman may choose, if she feels in herself a vocation for it, and a capacity of going through the study and application which it involves. '^ If gentlemen will look at the question fairly and impar- tially, I think they will see that the objections in detail against admitting females to our examinations are not less untenable than the objections on principle. Our University would come to consist of graduates and matriculated students, in majority male, in minority female. How it can be less respectable in any one's eyes from this conjunction of female names with male names in our printed calendar, I am at a loss to understand. In my eyes it would be more respect- able, because I should feel that we had done our best to recompense and to encourage intellectual power, combined with steady application, wheresoever and in whomsoever it was to be found. The only case in which I see the possibility of inconvenience from a minority of females is in the mem- bership of Convocation. That case I expressly except in the words of my motion. The functions of Convocation are con- ducted by public meeting and public debate. I see no advantage to women in assigning to them a share in those debates, nor do I anticipate that they would themselves wish it. The great recompense and privilege to them is that which they will share with male graduates — authentic record of their proficiency, upon proof given of diligent and success- ful study. " It is well known to all that, as matters now stand, a large proportion of the business of teaching in this country is per- formed by women : moreover, no small proportion of current and periodical literature is also furnished by women. Who- ever goes to the great reading-room at the British Museum, as I do very frequently, will see there every day of the week [168] CHAEACTER AND WRITINGS. a considerable number of females among the various readers who avail themselves of the privilege of visiting that large stock of books. He will farther see these females in the reading- room engaged not simply in reading, but in writing : employed with manuscript and copy-book, and surrounded by books of reference, which plainly indicate that they are occupied with some literary work. Now, seeing that this literary work and this teaching work is at present actually performed by females, it will undoubtedly be better performed by instructed females than by the uninstructed. To open for females, as our examinations would do, a test for distinguishing the most instructed from the least instructed, would be a benefit alike to them and to the public. To the superior and the best qualified teachers, who look to that profession as their means of living and their ground of personal importance, we should be rendering one of the most valuable services which could be rendered. We should enable them to distinguish them- selves, by an honourable and unequivocal characteristic, from the number of other women who, as it is but too well known, undertake the duty of teaching without any intellectual preparation for it, often simply through pecuniary misfor- tunes in their families, which throw upon them the unex- pected necessity of living by their own exertions. Our certificate would afford to them an improved chance of obtaining that preference which they deserve for a profes- sional appointment in their own line ; and we should furnish to those, with whom the appointment is vested, the best evidence of intellectual fitness which can guide their choice. " The conviction has spread much, and is spreading more, among both sexes, that women must be taught much more than they have been, to earn for themselves and by their own efforts an honourable and independent living. There is a larger proportion of women now than formerly who are dissatisfied with a life of mere dependence, without any active purposes or prospects. To throw open to them the- field of professional competition more largely than is now done appears to me most desirable as well as most equitable ; LATER PUBLIC LIFE. [169J but it is an essential preliminary to success in any line that habits of steady, accurate application should be formed at an early period of life. Wherever a female has that genuine aspiration to attain an independent and self-maintaining position, which in my judgement is a virtue alike in both sexes, the prospect of access to our examinations and certi- ficates will tend to stimulate that diligent and serious application in early life which is now wanting, because it goes untested and unrewarded. Complaints of the general inaccuracy of women's minds are sufiSciently frequent to have reached every one. Let those women who are superior to this very frequent infirmity, and who are prepared to prove them- selves superior, have the opportunity of doing so by admis- sion to our examinations. " An objection will probably be taken against me from the other side. It may be said that if females were admitted, few would come, and scarcely any one would pass, because our examinations are too severe. I might reply by saying, that, assuming none to come, we should stand only as we are now, with the advantage of having abolished a harsh and unfair exclusion. The fact, if it be a fact, is no valid objec- tion against my proposition. I am prepared to admit that at first very few females will come. It cannot be otherwise : for our examinations cannot be approached by persons of either sex without careful and special preparation. But I do not believe that this will last long. How many will come, no one can know until the experiment is tried. We are sure that the females will always be a minority as compared to the numbers of our sex. Bnt they will be a distinguished and valuable minority who have proved their worth, their superiority, and their title to confidence by diligent applica- tion, and by the fact of having attained, under disadvantages of education, an amount of proficiency which even persons of our sex, with far greater advantages, have to work hard for. "I will now submit my motion as it stands here to the decision of the senate. Our present exclusion, on the simple ground of sex, appears to me unfair and objectionable, n [170] CHARACTER AND WRITINGS. and I trust that the senate will weigh attentively and dis- passionately the strong reasons which exist for abolishing it." On the death of Henry Hallam, in 1859, Mr. Grote became a Trustee of the British Museum, and, as in the case of University College and the University of London, he gave unfailing attendance on the meetings of the trustees, and sat on the most laborious committees. In 1864 he was also elected a trustee of the Hunterian Museum. Mr. Grote's published writings, coupled with the record of his life and work, reveal the lineaments of a great character, the intellectual and the moral ingredients supporting each other. In his public career, and in his wide literary research, a clear, powerful, and originating intellect was guided by the purest aims and the most scrupulous arts. With scholarly resources of language, his rhetoric is the servant of trutli. At all points merging his own self-importance, he takes account of all opposing considerations, and does justice to every rival. The reverse of sanguine as to human progress, he yet laboured for every good cause that satisfied his mind, — science, education, and the self-acting judgment of the individual. Differing in many points from the prevailing opinions of the time, he avoided giving needless offence, and co-operated with men of all shades of doctrine, political and religious. In the depths of his character there was a fund of sympathy, generosity, and self-denial rarely equalled among men ; on the exterior, his courtesy, affability, and delicate consideration of the feelings of others were indelibly impressed upon every beholder; yet this amiability of demeanour was never used to mislead, and in no case relaxed his determination for what he thought right. Punctual and exact in his engagements, he inspired a degree of confidence and respect which acted most beneficially on all the institu- tions and trusts that he took a share in administering ; and his loss to them was a positive calamity. ESSENTIALS OP PAKLIAMENTARY REFORM. 1831. B PREFACE. The extraordinary advance of the public mind, on the subject of Parliamentary Reform, within the last two or three years, is such as the most careless observer cannot overlook or dispute. Even the warmest friends of the ex- isting system of representation are among the first to confess and to lament this ominous change ; and those who recorded their disapprobation of the system, at a time when its deformities were less acknowledged, may congratulate themselves that their efforts, aided by recent events, have not been thrown away. To any one who examines the signs of the times, there will appear a remarkable analogy between the present period and that which in France preceded the first French Eevo- lution. The supreme power — the source of all the painful restraints and burdens imposed upon society — has lost its hold on our moral feelings, and is becoming worn out and discredited. From ancient habit, and from the imperious necessity of one known standard of action, men still pay their taxes and obey the commands of the Legislature ; and thev have done so from the Revolution of 1688 to the last few years, without ever seriously asking themselves what title that Legislature possessed to their confidence. The mere name of Parliament has sufficed to strike them with awe : a body of English gentlemen, variable under certain conditions, and bearing the same denomination as those assemblies which fought the battles of the people against the Stuart princes, has always been and still is sitting at Westminster ; and the mass of the people, as it commonly B 2 4 ESSENTIALS happens, have been slow to perceive that the relations of that assembly towards them are the very reverse of what they were in the seventeenth century. A partial community of interest between the House of Commons and the people, prior to 1688, was created, not by the mode of their election, but by common fear of the Crown : and so soon as the alliance — equally profitable to both parties — between the House of Commons and the Crown, was organized, the divorce of the former from the people was an immediate and inevi- table result. But no glaring evidence of such a divorce appeared on the face of affairs : on the contrary, the atten- tion of intelligent observers was called more to the im- provement in the administration of the Crown, than to the deterioration in the character of the House. Nor can we wonder at the general inattention to this latter fact, when we recollect that the formalities of election remained un- altered : — that tlie great and wealthy, and all the talented dependents on greatness and wealth, had the strongest in- terest in upholding the degenerated assembly, and in con- tinuing to cry up the blessings of securities against the Crown, when the Crown, as a separate enemy, had ceased to be formidable ; and farther, that the English Government during the last century was really both good and free, in comparison with even the best of those on the Continent. During the last forty years two circumstances have been simultaneously operating to sharpen the insight of the English people into the real character of their Constitution — diffusion of knowledge, and increase of burdens. The number of those who read and talk politics has been pro- digiously multiplied : newspapers, though their circulation is studiously restricted by a pernicious tax, are now num- bered among the aliments of life by the population of every considerable town ; and an extensive class of independent thinkers, unconnected with the leading strugglers for power, and refusing to be regimented either as Whig or Tory, has grown up all around. While political knowledge and feel- ings were monopolised by a small knot of gentlemen, the OF PAKLIAMENTARY REFOEM. 5 whole of their narrow circle, whatever might be their dis- sensions amongst themselves, had a separate and exclusive interest as against the whole community, and their debates were shaped accordingly. But the circle has now been so enlarged, as no longer to have any interest at variance with the whole community; and the tone of political dis- cussion, instead of being purely personal and factious, has consisted, to a great degree, of principle and philosophy, making their way by slow degrees against established cor- ruptions and ancient prejudice. Whoever has watched the proceedings in Parliament during the last ten years, on the subjects of Law Eeform and Commercial Eeform, must have seen ample evidence of this truth. But, even if the intelligence of the English people had continued unexcited and stationary, it is scarcely possible that such taxation as ours could have been permanently endured without impairing their good will towards the Go- vernment which imposed it. The amount of money drawn from the nation and expended by the English Government, since the year 1793, is something which defies all power of conjecture, and which we can scarcely believe even when the Parliamentary returns are summed up before our eyes. No conqueror ever wrung from vanquished and despised aliens so severe a tribute as the English Aristocracy have extorted from their subjects and fellow-countrymen. During the war, men paid without murmuring, on the assurance that such exorbitant demands would only be temporary, and that peace would bring with it relief and abundance : during the first years of peace, promises of retrenchment in progress ope- rated to appease their discontent ; but when year after year passes, and the amount of taxation is still found most weighty and distressing, the sufferers become painfully dis- appointed and clamorous. Even the most patient and reve- rential men begin to inquire into the system which bears upon them so heavily, and to look with an invidious eye on the receivers of the public money. They judge of the tree by its fruits : their painful sense of the effects is trans- Q, ESSENTIALS ferred to the cause. They listen with attention to criticisms on the Constitution, and a new light beams within them, when the character, the interest, and the working, of the House of Commons, as at present constructed, are made evi* dent. Nothing short of impenetrable stupidity could make the English people continue to trust a House to which they owe such immoderate burdens, and from which they have at length ceased to expect relief. These two causes taken together — diffusion of knowledge, and unrelenting taxation — sufficiently explain the growing dis- credit of that system which passed current with the thinking men of the last century. Taken as it now stands in public opinion, the English Government seems approaching to the condition of the old despotism of France, prior to the Eevo- lution of 1789. Its anomalies, its abuses, its want of system and coherence throughout, its immoral and corruptive effects upon the whole community — are becoming too palpable and revolting to make it suffice as an engine of taxation. The men of wit and eloquence, like Mr. Canning, who undertook to deck out all these hideous deformities — arcem facere ex cloaca — have passed away, and few new orators venture to risk their reputation on the same dangerous ground. We may even congratulate ourselves on possessing a Ministry whose disapprobation of the existing system has been un- equivocally proclaimed. At such a juncture, therefore, there is every reason to expect that the perilous consequences of keeping up the disgraced machinery will be duly appreci- ated, and that some attempts to amend it will no longer be postponed. But whether such attempts will be sincere or deceptive — judicious or mistaken — comprehensive or superficial — is a point by no means equally certain. It is nevertheless of incalculable consequence. For, if the real defects of the existing representation are not accurately conceived — if the general principles, from whence alone these defects arise, are not laid bare and kept in mind — we run much risk of having some new delusion palmed upon us, equally objectionable OF PARLIAMENTARY REFORM. T in substance with the present, whereby misgovernment may be rendered, for another half century, decorous and endurable. The workings of the sinister interest may be reproduced under another name, and with a slight variation in the external forms, unless the public are taught to recognise and detect the seeds of evil in an untried scheme, before its bitter fruits shall have been actually tasted. There is much reason to fear that the amendments con- templated by the Whig Ministry will be of this insufficient description — that they will apply themselves rather to clear away the obnoxious symptoms of a rotten system, than to redress the real source of mischief. The various speeches of Whig Eeformers within the last ten years, and the doc- trines broached in the great Party Eeview, display so errro- neous a conception of the real vices of our representative system, and so decided an aversion to the only effectual remedies, that gentlemen of that school can scarcely be expected to recommend any such Eeforni as will really im- part a new heart and spirit to the Sovereign Council. It will be something, indeed, to obtain even a partial Keform ; and when we reflect on the opposition which the Borough- holders are likely to offer, a Ministry may deserve our thanks for accomplishing something widely removed from perfection. But it is of the last importance that the public should accept such a Reform only for what it is worth — that they should not mistake it for the whole improvement requisite — and that they should continue to withhold their confidence from the Parliament until it be so elected as to afford them full and adequate securities for good govern- ment. It is to assist in guarding against this error that the present pamphlet is composed. Assuming that some Eeform is admitted to be necessary, I am anxious to place in relief the leading features which are essential to its efficacy — to expose those mis-statements of its real end, and those sophisms as to the means, wliereby half might be passed upon us for the whole, or changes of name and form for 8 ESSENTIALS, ETC. h, newly acquired securities — and to signalize, especially, some of the fallacies which I think most likely to mislead a Whig Ministry. In the year 1821, I published a pamphlet entitled 'Statement of the Question of Parliamentary Eeform,' in refutation of an article in No. 61 of the ' Edin- burgh Eeyiew.' That article, ostensibly a review of Mr. Bentham's work on Eadical Eeform, contained an elaborate exposition of the Ee viewer's ideas on the subject of Parlia- mentary Eeform, and an earnest and deliberate recom- mendation of the theory of representation by classes, as the best security for a good Parliament. Some of the remarks which I then offered, in reply to that Eeviewer, appear to me suitable to the present juncture, and I shall embody the substance of them in the following pages. ESSENTIALS OP PARLIAMENTAKY REFORM. When a people first awake to a strong feeling of discontent against Institutions of long standing, their indignation will seldom be directed in due proportion against all the ob- jectionable parts. Accident brings to their view some one of the many ramifications of evil in a glaring manner, and at an opportune moment : while others, no less mischievous in themselves, either are not obtruded so indecently on the public, or find it otherwise occupied, and thus escape notice. This disproportionate and partial perception not only has the efiect of retarding the proper outcry against unobserved abuses, but tends farther to keep out of view those great principles which connect one abuse with another, and which form the common source of all of them. Where the evil is thus imperfectly conceived, the remedies, demanded are likely to be equally incomplete and superficial. Something of this sort is discernible in the clamours raised against the Eepresentative System, Men fasten upon some special incongruity or abomination, as if the removal of it were the grand object to be efi*ected by a Keform. Manchester, Leeds, and Birmingham, are great cities, important enough to have their interests protected by Eepresentatives of their own : Old Sarum, Gatton, and Weobly are insignificant hamlets, yet their interests are 10 ESSENTIALS better protected than those of the three greatest manufac- turing cities in England. As long as the argument for Reform is thus put, its opponents meet it satisfactorily, by showing that, if the suffrage were transferred from the three hamlets to the three cities above-mentioned, all things else remaining unchanged, the residents in the latter would be neither better nor worse protected than they are at present. In like manner some persons exclaim against the open bribery at the Liverpool election, or against the severity of the Duke of Newcastle in expelling his tenants at Newark, and are anxious that such transactions should be prevented in future. But here, too, it is easy to reply, that little would be gained by tying men down to bribe in secret, and with some degree of coyness and ceremony. Nor is it without reason that the Duke of Newcastle complains of having been held up as a single and unique tyrant, while other landlords are accomplishing the same end with greater certainty and good fortune. Such abuses are indeed indefensible ; but they ought to be attacked, not as vicious excrescences on a system sound in the main, but as symptoms, rather gross and magnified, of widespread internal corruption. The system of representa- tion should be surveyed, conceived, and criticised, as a whole : the purposes which it ought to answer should be compared with its actual workings ; and it should be ac- counted a blessing or an injury according as the one of these coincides wdth or departs from the other. No Eeform can be treated as complete which does not render the Eepre-' sentative Body on the whole an efficient and trustworthy instrument of gpod government. That which the people require at the hands of their Government is, protection for their persons, their earnings, and their inheritances : good, accessible, cheap, and speedy justice, for settling private disputes, and for bringing offenders to punishment : together with an adequate public force, for ensuring execution of the laws, and for keeping off external enemies. No less sacred is the duty, though OF PARLIAMENTARY REFORM. 11 reserved for unborn statesmen to fulfil, of ensuring to the poorer classes universally tke largest attainable amount of instruction ; I would add, of protecting them against indigence, were I not persuaded that well directed instruc- tion would implant in them the habit of regulating their own numbers, and thus of maintaining wages, by their own prudence, at the proper level. To pay for all these services, adequate taxes — not insignificant in amount, even under the best management — ^must, of course, be levied. All this may be summed up in a few comprehensive words : but, in reality, it comprises an unceasing series of laborious acts and painful supervision, sufficient to weary the zeal and fret the temper of benevolence itself: it calls for complete devotion of time, on the part of some of the ablest heads in the community : nor has the man ever yet existed, who could continue engaged in such employments without wishing to leave them half-performed. The nature of the case forbids that free competition, which ensures steady perseverance in the most repulsive private pro- fessions : for every public servant is necessarily a temporary monopolist. On the other hand, if there be this temptation to elude the obligations incident to office, there is a motive yet more unconquerable to multiply demands for taxes : to create pretences for palliating unlimited expenditure; and to acquire ascendency, or gratify liberality, at the expense of the public purse. To counteract, as much as may be, such overwhelming temptations, a feeling of anxious responsibility must be kept up in the minds of Government functionaries; and the romancers of the last age, complimenting the House of Commons at the expense of King, Peers, and subordinates, were pleased to assign that House as the body through whom responsibility was to be ensured. Not that Members of Parliament were supposed to be endued with any inborn virtue greater than that of gentlemen in office whom it was their business to watch : but their aptitude was affirmed to be derived from their being elected periodically by the 12 ESSENTIALS people. Election by tlie people, real or supposed, was the ultimate source of security. The framers of this seducing picture, misled by common parlance and tradition, overlooked the fact that elections by the people were a pure fiction : that the persons who elected formed only a fraction of the people ; and that to this electoral fraction, in the last resort, all the security was to be traced. According as the majority of the electors had interests identified with or opposed to the * people, would be the security for good government arising from election. If the former, then security would be real and efficacious : if the latter, then not only would there be no real security to the people, but the pretended security would be a source of great separate evil, inasmuch as the House of Commons would be under the same temptations to neglect and abuse their trust as the functionaries whom they were assumed to control. To take precautions against King, Peers, and Public Officers in general, is sufficiently difficult : but if the House of Commons and the electors be also interested in mis-government, the very idea and possibility of precaution becomes extinct; and the phalanx against the people is multiplied, strengthened, and rendered more irresistible than it could be by any other contrivance imaginable. If the electors form only a small fraction of the people, they and the persons whom they choose must inevitably have a greater interest in conniving at misgovernment and sharing in its benefits, than in the obnoxious task which a rigid duty towards the people would impose upon them. A small fraction, set apart and vested with power, may at particular emergencies act in behalf of the people against some common enemy : as the old French Parliaments occa- sionally resisted the enormities of the court ; but their uniform tendency, here and elsewhere, now and in ancient times, has been directly opposite. It is fruitless to search for any peculiar set of men, exempted by peculiar virtue, or by station in society, from this predominant disposition. Individuals, superior to these and even to greater temp- OF PARLIAMENTARY REFORM. V6 tations, may doubtless be accidentally found : but if our earth were blest with any such celestial breed, elections and electors would be superfluous altogether. Government officers might on that supposition be trusted to perform their duties without any control, or a King and Peers to control them without any Commons. It really implies an insult both to King and to Peers to suppose that they can derive any accession of virtue from Commons chosen by a narrow electoral fraction, and thus under the same mis- leading influences as themselves. Whoever is of this opinion, must imagine the King and the Peers to be worse than ordinary men : a supposition which the true theories of Government do not by any means countenance. The great question, therefore, with regard to the electoral body, will always be, are they few or many ? Do they form a large or a small proportion of the people ? If many in name and appearance, are they all so protected that each elector counts for a separate and independent unit ? Unless such questions can be satisfactorily answered, the whole process of election will certainly be useless, and, probably, worse than useless ; productive by its own working of much separate and peculiar evil. How they are to be answered in England, Lord Grey in vain warned the country by his memorable Petition of 1793. The truth then proclaimed, is now better known and less disputed. Less than 200 families, partly Peers, partly Com- moners, return the majority of the Lower House. Of the remaining minority, a large proportion owe their return to money or local influence — to electors who vote from hope of gain or from fear of loss : and the handful which remains, chosen by a few electoral bodies under very peculiar cir- cumstances, serve only to show what the House might be if the whole system were amended. When this wonderful paucity of the real, determining, electors is thus made out to us, we see at once that the Constitution is now and long has been only an oligarchy governing under certain forms and ceremonies. So long as 14 ESSENTIALS it retains this character, do improvement is to be hoped for. So long as the House of Commons is chosen by a small fraction of the community, the commimity will derive from its existence no security which they would not have enjoyed equally well without it, from King and Peers only. Paucity of the real electors is the grand, the specific evil: multi- plication of the real electors, until they cease to have a separate interest from the community, must be the vital, the effectual remedy. Nothing short of this can regenerate the body chosen. It is useless to substitute one small body in place of another, under pretence of picking out rich or enlightened individuals : it is useless to render the small body a trifle larger, until they become paiici, instead of jyauciores or paucissimi : it is equally useless to prescribe new forms, or to invent new fictions, by way of giving respect- ability to their proceedings. Let other circumstances be as they may, if the electors remain a narrow minority, elections w^ill be in the last result just what they are now : and the tree, deriving nutriment from the same pernicious soil — radice in Tariara tendens — wdll still continue to bear its bitter and poisonous fruits. Among those doctrines, which divert the public eye from the real vices of our representation, there is none more current or more easily received than that of founding the Eepresentative System on property — of making i:iroperty the hasis of the elective franchise. The sense put upon these words, indeed, is neither imiform nor well-defined: but all the fluctuations in their meaning appear reducible to two leading distinctions, which I propose successively to examine. Some persons, when they aflSrm that property is the only suitable basis for representation, seem to intend that every man should be vested with an elective power proportioned to his fortune — that the weight of each in determining the members to be chosen should be measured by the amoimt of property which he possesses. Because (they maintain), the richer a man is, the greater the stake which he has in the OF PARLIAMENTARY REFORM. 15 conntry— the greater his interest in the preseTvation and augmentation of its wealth and power. If this principle were openly followed out, without equivocation or disguise, we should see the votes of men graduated and valued : there would be voters of one star, two stars, three stars, and so on, as there are in the lists of East India Proprietors: and perhaps Sir Eichard Arkwright, and Mr. Alexander Baring, by virtue of the countless stars which would stand opposite to their names, might be deemed qualified to return a member between them. But the reasoning, on which any such preference to great proprietors is founded, is altogether untenable and fallacious. Not only is it untrue that they have a greater interest than small proprietors, or non-proprietors, in good government, but it may be clearly shown that they have much less. Among all the obligations which a good government ought to discharge towards a body of citizens, there is none of which the omission will not be far more painfully felt by the small than by the great proprietor. Suppose the course of justice to be dilatory, expensive, or corrupt. By all these circumstances the small proprietor is ruinously aggrieved: the course of his industry is interrupted or cut off: that constant aggregation of petty savings, without which he cannot leave his family in the condition occupied by himself, is rendered impossible ; and if he escapes loss or fraud in his own person, he is sure to be called on to rescue less fortunate friends or kinsmen. The great proprietor, on the other hand, is far less exposed to injury from such sources : he is embarrassed by no daily calling : his wealth attracts around him a host of private dependants, who conspire to protect him against the world without, and enable him almost to dispense with the shield of law : while he acquires a power, frightful indeed to society, but profitable to himself, of dealing out unredressed outrage to others. The state of society throughout Europe during the middle ages amply attests that which is here stated : and if the administration of our law v/ere to recede from what it is now to what it was 16 ESSENTIALS ^^h three or four centuries ago, the blow to the middling and the poor would be inconceivably severe, while the great proprietors would gain in one way as much as they lost in the other. Take, again, the economy of the public revenue. It is the small, not the great, proprietor, whose interest in this desirable object is most powerful. For though the latter pays a larger positive sum in the shape of taxes, yet any given proportion of a large income subtracts much less from the enjoyments of the possessor than the same proportion of a small one: and, what is more important still, whenever excessive taxes are raised, it is the great proprietor who stands the best chance of determining the parties to be benefited by them. High taxation is to the rest of the community pure, uncompensated, sacrifice: to the great proprietor it is sacrifice on the one side, with the prospect of patronage on the other. In no case is he injured by this description of misgovernment so much as the small pro- prietor : frequently, he proves a considerable gainer by it. But if the great proprietor is less interested than the small in the performance of the obvious duties of government, still more is this true with regard to the remote and exalted obligations. What member of the community has so little to gain by diffusing instruction among the poor, as a very rich man ? He sees and hears less of them than any one else : and as he is always able to pay for the services of the choice few among them, his comfort is scarcely at all affected by the good or bad character of the mass. With respect, again, to the moral effect of the government — to its influence, so prodigious either to good or to evil on the minds and character of the citizens. Is the great proprietor more interested than others in so constructing all its machinery as to encourage probity, industry, and self-denial, and to discountenance fraud, rapacity, and improvidence ? In this, as in the other cases, he will be found to have little or no interest in that salutary moral teaching which would be the first of all blessings to every other man in the community. OF PARLIAMENTABY EEFORM. 17 To him the prevalence of such habits would be a loss of consequence, of ascendancy, of admiration. His position commands him to cherish far more unworthy and immoral dispositions among the community : to spread abroad that overweening and prostrate veneration of wealth, which not only softens all scruples as to the mode of acquisition, but effaces true dignity of character, and renders men the pliant instruments of any one who can help them on in life : to plant in every one's bosom a passion for that show and osten- tation, which none indeed can successfully exhibit except the rich themselves, but which every one may pant after and affect, until he loses both the relish for simple and accessible enjoyments, and the feeling of sympathy and brotherhood with men of inferior style. How lamentably such defects eat up the happiness and taint the springs of beneficence among the middling and the poor, is abundantly manifest : how they have been fostered in England under the baneful ascendency of wealth in large masses, is matter of remark to all who compare it with the Continent. It is then demonstrable, that the great proprietors are the precise persons in the nation to whom good government in all its branches is the least essential. And, if so, what pre- tence remains for arming them with any peculiar influence in the choice of members of Parliament? Loose language, assisted by rooted habits of deference and idolatry, have cast a dense cloud in men's minds over this important subject. Our terminology rudely bisects the community into rich and poor — men of property and men of no property : and hence an association grows up in our thoughts between men of property and the institution of property. The deep respect, which deservedly belongs and has always been paid to that inestimable institution, is transferred mechanically to those who are surnamed after it : they come to be considered as its guardian angels and natural protectors : while such as refuse submission to them are vilified as if destitute of the jnst feelings towards property. But the truth is, that these men of property have no other interest in the institution of c 18 ESSENTIALS property than that which they possess in common with the mass of smaller proprietors, whom we so vaguely huddle together as men of no property. To become an instrument of benefit to his country, a great proprietor ought to act, not upon that narrow interest which connects him with other great proprietors, but upon that more extended interest which binds him to all proprietors whatever. He must con- descend to confound himself with their ranks, to join in the prosecution of objects by which he benefits only in common with them, and to catch a portion of the modesty, the assiduous habits, and the demand for unbought sympathy appertaining to their station. In place of that curse of English society — small proprietors apeing the imperfections of the great — true benevolence would teach the great pro- prietors to imbibe the virtues of the small. But never will they do this so long as a peculiar and privileged interference in elections is reserved for them : so long as peculiar elec- toral rights fence them off conspicuously from the remain- ing: commuriitv, and thus both entice and enable them to conspire for their separate interest ; and so long as un- principled expectants are tempted to look to them for promotion, apart from the approving voice of public opinion. But if there be no ground for privileging great proprietors on pretence of superior interest in good government, as little reason is there for doing so on the score of superior know- ledge and intelligence. Admittiag it for the present to be true, that without such aids as can only be procured by persons possessing a certain moderate income, such as 100?. per annum, no one can acquire sufficient instruction to per- form the functions of elector — admittino: that moderate in- come affords a just presumption of capacity as compared with very low income — yet to rate the understandings of men throughout the whole scale in proportion to their wealth, would be a measurement altogether perverse and un- warrantable. Superior income is not only an inaccurate test in individual cases, but it affords no ground for guessing at the capacities of men, even as a general rule. A man of OF PARLIAMENT AKY REFOBM. 19 lOOL or 200?. a-year, who lives in a considerable city, enjoys opportunities for mental improvement, not perhaps equalling those which richer men might command, but far exceeding those which the majority of them ever turn to account. Individuals who will labour to instruct themselves are in- deed rare in this class : but they are also rare amongst the classes who possess lOOOZ., 2000Z., or 5000Z. per annum ; and the ordinary literature and periodicals form the stock read- ing of the one as well as of the other. In comparing men of middling incomes, from 100/. per annum upwards, there is no presumption of superior capacity on either side : but when we reach the very high figures in the scale, it will be found that not only is there no presumption in favour of mental eminence, but there is a probability not easy to be rebutted against it. The position and circumstances of a very rich man cut off all motive to mental labour : he is caressed and deified by his circle without any of those toils whereby others purchase an attentive hearing ; and the purple, the fine linen, and the sumptuous fare every day, of Dives, are impediments to solid improvement, hardly less fatal than the sores and wretchedness of Lazarus. I trust that I have now shown that neither on the ground of special interest in favour of good government nor on that of presumed mental superiority, are the great proprietors entitled to privilege or ascendency in the representative system. Protection they will of course receive, in common with all other proprietors : but if they seek pre-eminence, they must be content to earn it by evidences of superior worth and ability. Equalize their political position as much as you will, the prejudices of mankind are sure to turn the scale more or less in their favour : their private munificence confounds itself with and enhances their public services ; and the eyes of the unambitious many eagerly look for merit where they are predisposed to pay deference. That property should be the basis of representation, then, in such sense as to award greater elective influence to the large proprietor than to the small, is a proposition altogether c 2 20 ESSENTIALS inadmissible. No sacrifice, indeed, can be too great to pro- tect property; but as this institution is of incalculable benefit to the whole mass of smaller proprietors, a legislature chosen by all of them together, great and small alike, is as sure to protect property, as to guard personal safety. And the great proprietors will be no less certain of enjoying security in common with the rest, than of being debarred from all undue usurpations beyond ; for the same insti- tutions which shut them out from the latter, guarantee to them the former. There is another sense in which some persons propose to make property the hasis of representation. They are of opinion that no one who does not enjoy an income of a certain given amount, ought to exercise any political rights : to all above that minimum, they would award equal, not graduated, elective power ; all below it they would dis- franchise without exception. Some indeed are more in- dulgent, others more rigorous in determining the point of actual exclusion : but the principle of exclusion is the same with all. The reasonings sometimes advanced on behalf of this opinion appear to imply that no person below the appointed minimum has any interest in preserving property : that property is an institution beneficial indeed to a fortunate minority, but injurious and oppressive to the remaining multitude ; and that if the interest of the latter w^ere con- sulted, not only existing possessions would be divided but the institution itself would be swept away. This theory of pro- perty, fatal as it would prove to the continuance of the insti- tution, except in the most degraded state of the human intelligence, is not unfrequently resorted to by aristocratical advocates, when they wish to alarm the middling classes into uncomplaining submission. It is fortunate that a just comprehension of the interests of all holds out brighter prospects. So far from being injured by the institution of property, the multitude have a deep and lasting interest in its continuance. No set of men, OF PAELIAMENTARY EEFOEM. 21 whether all poor, or all rich, or some poor and some rich, can possibly live together in society without some rules to define what shall be enjoyed by one and w^hat by another. One man, by virtue of these rules, may acquire a greater amount of enjoyment than another, but the fixity and ob- servance of the rules is as much necessary to the continuous sequence of smaller acquisitions as to the safe enjoyment of the greater. One man, in like manner, may turn the air and the sun to greater account than another ; but these beneficent influences are alike indispensable to all. Here and there a being maybe discovered so destitute and un- happy as to be inaccessible to any additional suffering : to have no enjoyment open to him, except that which he can find unappropriated, or that which he can snatch by force : to be, in other words, in the position to which all man- kind would be reduced, if no laws of property were known or respected. But such cases are rare exceptions to the ordinary lot of the many, who derive a steady subsistence from the uninterrupted exercise of their industry. Scanty as this subsistence too frequently is, it would be intercepted altogether if the safety of property became a matter even of reasonable doubt : for it arises from the outlay of capitalists, made only under assured prospect of return, and ready to be withheld the moment future acquisitions can no longer be reckoned on. Deprived of all means of recruiting his little fund, the poor labourer passes from assured subsistence into absolute and irremediable starvation. The disfranchisement of the body of the poor, then, cannot for a moment be sustained on the pretence that they have no interest in the maintenance of property. They have at least as great an interest in its stability as the rich : for even a temporary suspension of its laws would deprive them of existence, while the rich might stand some feeble chance of defending and reserving to themselves their pre-existing hoard. But are the poor wise enough to recognise and act upon this interest ? Many reasoners contend that they are not ; 22 ESSENTIALS and hence, in general, the reluctance to bestow on them political rights : though there are not wanting persons who, inconsistently enough, protest against universal suffrage, both on one ground and on the other ; insisting on the one hand that the body of the poor have a real interest hostile to property, and reproaching the poor on the other for their brutish ignorance in not yenerating so sacred and beneficent an institution. The ignorance of the body of the people is a ground for their disfranchisement far more plausible than the former, because, to a certain extent, the fact is undeniable. No one can dispute that they ought to be, and might be, much more carefully educated than they are at present. Yet I feel w^ell persuaded that their ignorance, comparatively to other classes, has been greatly over-stated, and in parti- cular that no evidence can be adduced of unfriendly feel- ings, in the generality of them, towards the institution of property. Is there any error or prejudice now current among the poorer classes, to which a parallel cannot be produced among the richer ? If they are taunted with their hostility to machinery, may they not recriminate on the landlords by pointing to the Usury Laws and to the Corn Laws ? If their misapprehension of the principle of population is cited as an evidence of stupidity, how will the squires and parsons, and the parochial chiefs in general, stand exonerated from the like imputation ? To me it appears that the poorer classes in general have an understanding sufficiently just, docile, and unprejudiced, to elect, and to submit to, the same legislators whom the middling classes themselves, if they voted apart and voted secretly, would single out. But assuming the contrary to be the fact, as so many sincere reformers believe and lament — admitting that the poor are at the present moment un- prepared for the elective franchise — expedients may yet be found for allaying the apprehensions of the middling classes, without either degrading the lower by perpetual exclusion, OF PAELTAMENTARY EEFOEM. 23 or neglecting to provide for the duties of Groyernment towards them. Reasoning on this admission, we should of course acquiesce, under a certain modification, in the principle that property should at present form the basis of representation, — not under the belief that men of property had any superior interest in good government, but because, under the exist- ing difficulties in obtaining, and carelessness in diffusing, knowledge, few persons below a certain amount of income could be presumed to have yet acquired mental aptitude for the elective function. It cannot with any pretence of reason be maintained, that a man of lOOZ. annual income has not enjoyed full facilities for instructing himself up to the requisite pitch. A pecuniary qualification, there- fore, if fixed at lOOZ. annual income, would embrace no one, as far as could be reasonably presumed, unworthy of the trust. It has been stated that a qualification of 100?. annual income would comprehend a million of electors : but if the conjecture were not confirmed by actual returns, I should think it requisite to lower the qualification until that number was attained. No number of voters falling much short of a million, could possibly put out of sight and out of apprehension that first of all evils, a separate interest from the community; and in order to purchase such a certainty, it would be well worth w^hile to submit to such slight depression in the scale of instruction as might be incurred by introducing persons of an income the next degree below lOOZ. per annum. Nor could any reasonable alarmist anticipate either hostility to property, or general unsoundness of view^s, from the richest million in the country. They might as soon be imagined to surrender England to a foreign enemy, or to plant in it the seeds of an epidemic disease, as to invade or unsettle the sanctity of property. A representative system including one million of voters, pfoperly distributed and protected, would be that "almost 24 ESSENTIALS all " in Parliamentary Eeform which a distinguished orator* unworthily predicated of the proposal to admit members from three or four great towns. It would purify the Groyernment, thoroughly, at once and for ever, of that deep and inveterate oligarchical taint which now infects it in every branch. The Old Man of the Sea would be shaken from our backs, never more to resume his gripe. The interest and well-being of the middling classes would become the predominant object of solicitude, and would be followed out with earnest and single-hearted perse- verance. Economy in the state expenditure; unremitting advance towards perfection in the law and in the adminis- tration of justice ; entire abstinence from ambitious or un- necessary wars : all these great results would be ensured by such a legislature as completely as the most ardent patriot could desire. iNor would it fail to operate a wholesome change in the public sentiment, and to root out or mitigate many of our wide-spread national vices. It would suppress that avidity for patronage which now renders so many fathers of families petitioners at the doors of the neigh-- bouring great : it would lower the value of the rich man's nod, and teach men to earn advance in the world, not by clinging to his skirts, but by their own industry and their own frugality ; and it would eradicate the proneness to local jobbing which the imperfect constitution of parishes and corporate bodies so fatally implants and so abundantly remunerates. Legislators so chosen must be men of first- rate intelligence, whose discussions would rectify and elevate the tone of political reasoning throughout the whole country — men in whom the accident of birth and connection would be eclipsed by the splendour of their personal qualities - — identified in heart and spirit with the happiness of the middling classes — and no less qualified, by laborious com- pletion of their own mental training, to serve as an exam]3le and an incentive to aspiring youth. * H. Brougham, 1830. OF PARLIAMENTARY REFORM. 25 A constituency of one million of voters would infallibly bring about these signal and beneficent results, without the slightest loss or peril to any one, except to those who are receiving undue gains or exercising a malignant influence. The very idea of peril to the middling classes is unreason- able and absurd : they w^ould themselves form the con- stituent body, and the acquisition to them in every w^ay would be incalculable. Nor would it prove injurious to the tranquil man, who enjoys his affluence apart, without seeking to club with the oligarchical confederacy. Such a person has really no interest distinct from that of the middling class; he suffers at present under their grievances, and would partake in their benefits under an improved system. To wealthy individuals of superior ability and benevolence, it would be highly gratifying and consolatory : since it would cut off the perennial source of those abuses against which they have been vainly striving in detail. There needs but one addition to render such an electoral system every thing which the widest philanthropy could aim at. A provision should be annexed to it, gradually lowering the qualification at the end of certain fixed periods, so as to introduce successively fresh voters, and after a certain period to render the suffrage nearly co-extensive with the community. The interval might be employed in improving and extending education, so as to remove the only valid ground which is now supposed to command the disfranchise- ment of the poor.* This very deficiency in the poor, on which the necessity of their present exclusion is founded, demonstrates the vast importance of impressing on the Government peculiar mo- tives to enlighten them. What portrait shall we draw of a government, under which four-fifths of the male adults are so degraded in understanding, as to be incapable of formino- any opinion on the laws to which their obedience is exacted, * I owe the suggestion of this gradual enlargement of the franchise to an excellent weekly journal — the Examiner. 26 ESSENTIALS and to be destitute, therefore, of that rational attachment towards them which assists and seconds so materially the operations of justice ? If their stupidity be really so de- plorable, as to leave them ignorant whether they owe grati- tude or execration to their laws and their legislators, it is impossible to make exertions too speedy or too strenuous to amend it. Under a government faithful and energetic in the performance of all its duties, such mental darkness would be rapidly dispelled, and the reason for continued dis- franchisement would disappear along with it. But inasmuch as among all the duties of Government, those which it owes to the poor are the most liable to be neglected, the deter- mination of periods for gradually extending to them the suffrage would serve as a spur to quicken inactivity, and as an admonition to prevent forgetfulness. And it is but too possible, that a body of representatives, perfect and admir- able for the middling classes, might be less keenly alive to the importance of elevating the condition and assuring the independence of the laborious many. If they seriously con- templated perpetual disfranchisement — if they considered the many, not as minors requiring farther tuition, but as half-witted by nature and smitten with inherent incapacity — they would be slow in communicating to them acquire- ments not deemed available to any ultimate end, and only sharpening the sense of an humiliating exclusion. A constituency of a million of voters, however, even taken apart and without any such gradual enlargement, would effect a change so great and desirable, that I should deeply regret to abate the demand for it by thus showing that it w^ould not accomplish every thing. The poor, though not permitted to vote, would partake in its benefits : not merely by the diminution of taxes, and by such amendments in the law as would open to them the avenues of justice, but also by the improved character of the wealthy and middling class, and by the more frequent prevalence of sober and useful virtues in the place of ostentatious frivolity. If it be once determined that the . constituency shall in- OF PARLIAMENTARY REFORM. 27 elude a million of voters, it is better to select tliem by an uniform income qualification than by any other. No just excuse can be given for preference on such an occasion, except presumed mental superiority : and though the infer- ence derived from income is by no means free from objection, I know not any better which can be obtained. If the aggregate of voters were smaller, certain professions and occupations might be resorted to, as affording adequate evidence of mental capacity : but it will be found that the richest million will embrace all those whose occupation or profession could have been thus singled out as presumptive testimony. The endless varieties of qualification in different English boroughs appear more like an olio of anomalous customs, than like the methodical workings of a reasonable Legis- lature. But the principle of uniform qualification has been impugned, and that of multiform qualification maintained, by some reasoners of note, who have insisted on the propriety of rendering the representative system a representation of classes, not of individuals. That theory I shall now examine. In combating the principle of strengthening the great proprietors at elections, I have supposed it to be acted upon openly and avowedly, by allotting a number of votes to each man proportioned to the amount of his property. Such a regulation, however, is repugnant to the general habits of English elections. Immense as the iufluence of great proprietors is at present, it is still exercised under a thin disguise, which enables men to quibble about its amount, and sometimes, when it suits their purpose, even to contest its reality. The conditions under which it is exer- cised, unhappily, aggravate its inherent mischief: for while they nowise serve to restrain or purify the oligarchical influence, they render its modus operandi such as to keep the minds of the people venal, open to intrigue in all shapes, athirst for irregular patronage, and insensible to any public 28 ESSENTIALS principle. But English thinkers have become familiar with this practice of attaining by stealth ends obnoxious to avow : and those who, in their plans of reform, leave the olig- archical preponderance still unabated, usually seek for some new contrivance to screen its working, and to mystify its real character. What is called the class system of repre- sentation, advocated in the ^Edinburgh Eeview,' as well as in other places, is a contrivance of this description. The plan of the class system is to divide the citizens into various classes ; each consisting of individuals bound together by some interest common to them all, but separate from the rest of the citizens. Thus we are to have one class of merchants, and another of landholders : and each of these is to elect representatives, intended to watch specially over the interests of their several classes, and to see that those interests are adequately protected in parliament. Each repre- sentative is supposed peculiarly cognizant of the interests of his own class, and under special obligation to promote and prefer them. No uniform qualification for voters (we are told), either founded on property or on any other prin- ciple, could ensure the election of members either acquainted with the interests of these various classes, or animated with competent zeal to watch over them. The interests of the class of merchants will not be protected unless that class elects representatives : the same with the class of landholders, and with the rest. Whoever would see this theory explained and vindicated at length, should consult the article on Keform in No. 61 of the ^ Edinburgh Eeview.' Let us consider the simplest particular case which can be imagined to answer the conditions of the theory. Suppose three classes, landholders, merchants, and lawyers, each returning one member, or each an equal number of members, to form a governing body. Each member comes exclusively devoted to the service of his own class : but as no measure can be adopted without a majority, two out of the trium- virate must combine : and that combination can only take place by mutual concessions on the part of the tw^o allies, OF PAELIAMENTAHY KEFORM. 29 eacli consenting to drop such part of his respective class interest as may interfere with the class interest of the other. Those two out of the three will combine whose alliance can be accomplished with the smallest sacrifice of their respective class interests. But when two out of the three have com- bined, the concurrence of the third becomes a matter of no importance. His interest, therefore, and the interest of his class, is completely disregarded. The two allies, who, as a majority, are in possession of the governing power, would be unfaithful deputies of their respective classes, were they to concede anything in favour of a colleague with whose co- operation tliey can dispense. How then is the end answered of affording protection to each of the separate class interests ? It is so far from being attained, that each and every one of them remains unpro- tected. The moment that the members begin discussion, it must become apparent that each class interest excludes the rest : and that to ensure protection to one of them is to deny it to the others. Either the assembly has a majority of its members returned by one particular class, or it has not. If the former, then the dominant class interest is indeed sedulously provided for, but all the classes in the minority are neglected and trampled upon. If the latter, then it is not the separate interest of any class whatever which is pro- tected, but the common interest of those two or more classes who combine to form a majority; all the classes in the minority being neglected as in the previous case. Perhaps the partisans of this system may reply, that they never imagine a deputy to seek protection for his class in- terest at the expense of other classes, but only so far as the interest of other classes can be made to coincide with it. But on this supposition the cardinal principle of the system is infringed, and the deputy ceases at once to be a class deputy. He does no more for the class by whom he is re- turned than for the other classes by whom he is not returned. He becomes, what he ought assuredly under every good system to be, a deputy devoted to the service of the country ; 30 ESSENTIALS for the interest which all classes have in common is the interest of the country. The fundamental error of the class system consists in a wrong conception of what constitutes the interest of the country. " We must divide the people into classes (observes the Edinburgh Ee viewer) and examine the variety of heal and professional interests of which the general interest is com- ])osed.'" Now the general interest, far from being composed of various local and professional interests, is not only distinct from, but exclusive of, every one of them. The interest of an individual by himself apart — the interest of the same man jointly with any given fraction of his fellow-citizens — and his interest jointly with the whole body of his fellow-citizens — all these are distinct objects, abhorrent and irreconcileable in general, coinciding occasionally by mere accident. To promote the joint interest of any given class, you do not set about first to promote the separate interest of one member of it, then the separate interest of another member, and so on. You neglect all these, to fix your eyes on an inde- pendent end, the joint interest of all the members of the class one with another. Just so it is with that grand aggre- gate of classes, the community. The general interest is not to be attained by pursuing first the separate interest of one class, then the separate interest of another, but must be studied as an object apart from all these. Individuals com- pose the class, but the interest of the class is not the sum total of the separate interests of all its members : classes compose the community, but the interest of the community is not the sum total of the separate interests of all its classes. And a governing body which would promote the universal interest, must discard all inclination to the separate interest of anv class whatever. What would be the result of the class representation, as its partisans apply their principles, it is not difficult to trace. The great body of the community — the multitude — are con- sidered to be one class, and are as such empowered to return certain representatives. The remaining minority are then ! OF PAKLIAMENTAEY EEFORM. 31 subdivided into a great number of different classes, each of which is to elect members of its own and for its own benefit. From this nice subdivision many of the electing classes be- come of course numerically small. And is it not manifest that these numerically small classes will combine to form a majority in the assembly ? and that the classes not included in the majority — the multitude among the number — will receive no more protection than if their deputies had never been elected ? The oligarchical Proteus thus reappears, in another of his ever-varying shapes: and the result of the system may be described in the words used by Livy (i. 43) when he is explaining the Koman class system ascribed to Servius Tullius — '' Gradus facti, ut neque exclusus quisquam suffragio videretur, et vis omnis penes primores civitatis esset." Votes are given to the people, not as a security for good government, but as a sop to delude and quiet them : the real power remains, where it would be if they had no votes, vested in the few of rank and property. It may be urged, indeed, that this result arises, not from the inherent principles of the class system, but from a vicious distribution of the people into disproportionate classes : that if the separate classes framed were more equal, and each numerically large, no majority in the assembly could com- bine without including a number so large as to coincide in interest with the whole community. Such an arrangement is indeed conceivable : but if, in the last result, the deputies are neither able nor inclined to follow out any other interest than that of the community, what is gained by the pecu- liarity of the system — that of calling the electors together in classes — and what would be lost by abandoning it ? Would not the same result be equally assured if the same number of electors voted in sections not coinciding with each man's class or profession, and not suggesting the idea of any distinct principle of union among themselves ? Not merely would the result be equally assured : it would be far more infallible and far more complete. The general interest will be most certain of receiving paramount and 32 ^^^^^K ESSENTIALS undeyiating attention, Avhen it stands forth prominently and conspicuously as the single purpose of delegation — when it enters into every man's feelings of duty — and when it is least traversed and overlaid by other objects of pursuit. All these essential requisites are frustrated by summoning the electors to vote in groups, each animated by a peculiar interest dis- tinct from the community. Each class, convoked apart, will dwell upon and magnify its own separate interests, which it will treat as at least co-ordinate in importance with the general interest ; the minds of individuals will be engrossed by the feelings of their rights and obligations as fellow- classmen ; and the sentiment of a common interest with the whole nation will be to a great degree obliterated. A member thus elected will carrv to Parliament the sentiments of his constituents respecting the treatment which their class ought to receive : the interest of the class will be his first duty, that of the country his second : at any rate, the two conflicting obligations will divide his soul, and drive him to perpetual trimming and evasion. No sincere or single- hearted patriot can be seen in the assembly. Instead of an union of wise and incorruptible legislators, agreeing in one common end, and only differing as to the means of pro- motino' it — Parliament would become an arena for rival con- spirators or opposing counsel, each engaged in serving a separate client ; each seeking to twist a grant or to qualify a restriction, in his own peculiar sense ; and no two con- curring in devotion to the same ultimate objects. Such would be the tendency of a representative system, under which each member should be chosen by a peculiar class, and should be recognised as the special guardian of the interest of his class. The more strono:lv and intimatelv the members of each choosing body are knit together, the more perniciously would this anti-social taint infect the legislative assembly. I grant indeed that vestiges of it may still remain — that it will not be entirely extirpated — under the best electoral svstem conceivable. For as each member must be chosen OF PARLIAMENTARY REFORM. 33 by a particular body of electors, and those too voting in one neighbourhood, their own separate interest may occasionally pervert their ju-^gment, and lead them to elect with little reference to their obligations as citizens of the community. But under good electoral arrangements this cannot happen often, nor in many places* at once; and the more its mis- cliievous tendency is denounced, the less likely it will be to occur at all. Instead of trying to guard against such a tendency, and only submitting to it where precautions prove ineffectual, the class system actually recognises it as a sound and bene- ficial principle of action, and is built upon it as upon a corner-stone. Independent of all other objections, the mon- strous immorality of the system cannot be too earnestly exposed. It treads out and extinguishes every spark of a o^eneral interest: it disavows all idea of the rio-hts and obli- gations attached to citizenship : and those feelings which bind us to our community, the source of so many exalted virtues, become obsolete and unknown. In place of an united and harmonious nation, what does the system present to us ? A mere congeries of unfriendly confederacies, each combating for its own separate ends : the strong classes combining to prey upon the weak, and grasping at the Legislature as an engine of usurpation : the weak submitting from inability to resist, and hating a Legislature from whence they derive no protection : the members of each class deeming the others legitimate plunder, and treating them in effect as aliens under the cheat of a common country. All these conse- quences are infallible, if ParKament is to be corrupted into a congress of class deputies, instead of an assembly of citizen legislators. A salutary Eeform ought to proceed on principles the very reverse of the class system. Far from encouraging the exercise of the elective franchise by local bodies and corpora- tions, every such union ought to be studiously disseverefl, so that an electoral section which returns one member mav seldom or never consist of individuals already united by any partial D 34 ESSENTIALS tie. It is the individual judgment of each voter which is required : a certain number of voters must concur to return the same candidate, in order to answer the purpose of attest- ing his competence ; but it is neither necessary nor desirable that all of them should vote in the same place. By proper distribution of the electoral bodies and places of voting, each elector might vote with little personal inconvenience, and disengaged from any corporate bias. In speaking thus respecting local and partial associations, I would by no means be understood to dispute their great utility when limited to their proper sphere. For local purposes, they are excellent and indispensable : and their organization ought to be revised and purified with much greater solicitude than has ever been hitherto manifested. In England the old institutions have liogered on from gene- ration to generation untouched by the hand of philosophy : salutary in their first commencement, they have not only outlived their period of utility, but have passed into instru- ments of jobbing and abuse. The history of a corporation is the history of the English Parliament. The rise and pro- gress of these bodies in the twelfth and thirteenth centuries forms an epoch in the history of society : without them the blessings of security would have been unknown ; and the European countries might still have been groaning under the tyranny of local barons, contentious indeed as against each other, but animated with a common spirit of insolence and rapacity towards the people. Against such enemies, every individual in the nascent town had a joint interest : and very imperfect corporate institutions sufficed, while the idea of danger to all from the same quarter was predominant and overpowering. But when the enemy without ceased to be formidable, the leading men in a town found themselves possessed of established ascendency over their fellow towns- men, which it was tempting to convert to their own account. The once useful corporation gradually degenerated into a field of disunion and intrigue : freemen remaining distin- guished by an indefensible line, and by still more indefensible OF PARLIAMENTAEY EEFORM. 35 privileges, from non-freemen ; and a select junto mal-admi- nistering over them all. The subject of good municipal institutions and assemblies, which is now attracting so much attention in France, deserves no less serious consideration in England : but however these bodies may be constituted, whether well or ill, it will still be essential to exclude their interference as much as possible in elections for the general legislature. The use and abuse of corporate bodies, and the pernicious tendency of the class system in general, is a topic deserving of the deeper attenfion, as the existing English representa- tive system is in effect a class government, of which the landholders form the preponderating partners. Hence such plans of Reform, as retain the class system unchanged, and profess merely to vary and remodel its component parts, come recommended by the imposing assertion, that the principle on which they proceed has already been tried, and is familiar to the Constitution. It has, indeed, been abundantly tried, and its baneful workings are easy to be detected ; not merely in the details of misgovernment, but also in the perverted tone of the current politics. What more common than to hear the country described as composed of so many " interests " — some more or less great and valuable than others — the landed interest and the manufacturing interest — the East Indian and the West Indian interest — the Ship interest, and the Wool interest! Some persons even speak as if they imagined that Parliament met for no other purpose than to watch over these great interests; each of which is constantly complaining that it does not receive adequate protection, and that " rival interests " return so many members to Parliament as to stifle its just claims. Such pretensions involve the fundamental fallacy of the class system. Landlords or manufacturers have sacred claims on the Legislature in common with the general body of citizens, but they acquire no new and peculiar claims by the fact of their sharing in the same occupation or in the same descrip- D 2 36 ESSENTIALS tion of revenue. Protection to themselves, as individuals, is their indisputable right : protection to their " interest " as a separate interest, is a privilege over their fellow citizens — a monstrous injustice and usurpation. Because a hundred or a thousand men choose to band together, to give them- selves a common name, and to talk of themselves as an interest,!^ the Legislature to make separate terms with them, and to grant them concessions at the expense of the modest citizen, who seeks only a citizen's share in the benefits of good government ? Yet such concessions, teeming as they do with evil, are in the ordinary spirit and track of the English Parliament. Its constitution, tainted with the inherent vice of the class system, has caused it to be pulled hither and thither by the great rival " interests : " it has been a theatre for their selfish struggles among themselves, as well as for their common encroachments on the body of the people, who, as they bear not the name and the banners of any particular "interest," have been treated as if they needed no " protection " at all. No man can have atten- tively studied the English Government without learning, that the path of advancement and honour has been mono- polized by these potent fraternities, and that the character of a private citizen was of little account. Hence the fatal temptation, so prevalent wherever w^e look, to join some one of them in intriguing for privilege or undue gain, and to renounce all sense of obligation towards the people as a body. Even virtuous men, who would shudder at injustices for their own individual benefit, become perverted with the class-morality, and act agreeably to the memorable declara- tion of Lord Grey, when he set his order against and above his country. I abstain from touching, as I might well do, on the en- couragement which such a state of the representation affords to the most mischievous tenets of the mercantile svstem. Though not chargeable with having given birth to them, it has assuredly retarded their extirpation. The body of con- sumers — the general public, — who are interested in low OF PARLIAMENTARY REFORM. 37 and steady prices, especially of necessaries — constitute no " interest/' and are never seen in battle array. It is in vain that political economy advocates their cause against the sellers, not only forward in associating and loud in complaint, but favoured by the erroneous disposition of ordinary men to sympathise only with a special and recognised class. Having established the necessity of a total number of voters, so great as not to be capable of having a separate interest from the country, and of taking their votes, not in classes, but as individuals, I come to the important question of open or secret voting. There is every possible reason for taking the votes by Ballot : not one single reason, so far as I can discern, for taking them openly. This question has been so admirably handled in the ' Westminster Review ' of last July, that I might be satisfied with referring to the demonstration there given : but it is impossible to pass over a subject of such incalculable moment without a few addi- tional words to elucidate and enforce it. Without ballot, the most extensive provisions of Eeform in other respects would be nullified : for the creation of new open votes would be only an empty multiplication of names, leaving the band of real choosers scarcely larger than it was before. Under secret suffrage, every man who has a vote is a real chooser : he votes from genuine, intrinsic, preference, well or ill founded, for his candidate. His vote can neither oblige nor offend : it is an act purely public, and counts as a separate grain of evidence to attest the competency of the person whom he supports. Under open voting, the reverse is true in all points. The number of nominal voters does not afford any test of the number of real choosers : out of a thousand voters there may not be fifty who have any genuine preference for their candidate, or any sincere per- suasion of his fitness for the trust. Provided only he be exempt from notorious disgrace or indisputable imbecility, the grades of superiority above that low minimum are never 38 ESSENTIALS scrutinised. And the election of a candidate, even by a considerable number of open votes, far from furnishing presumption of his competency, proves only that he has either many dependents, or an unusual number of influ- ential private friends, who are willing to make his cause their own. If reasons were needed against open voting, the disgusting details of an English election would abundantly supply them. The candidate convenes an active committee of pri- vate friends, who look over the list of voters, and set about to consider by what weapons or baits each of them is assail- able. Some of them are known to be openly venal : others are dependent tenants on the estate of Lord A. or Mr. B. : a third class are tradesmen, and supply the families of Lord C. and Mr. D. : of the remainder, several are comfortable in their incomes, but are fond of shooting, and prize highly the permission of going upon a neighbouring manor, or are* anx- iously seeking intimacy with some families wealthier than themselves. To track out all these ramifications of each voter's peculiar interest — to penetrate the hidden sources of his hopes and fears — and to hook his vote through the me- dium of one or the other — is the business of an election com- mittee. It is futile to prohibit any part of their proceedings, while the means and the motive to practise them are left open : and however the number of open voters may be mul- tiplied, it will only become more troublesome, but by no means less practicable, to govern the majority of them by pri- vate hopes and fears. At certain grand periods of excitement numerous voters may break loose, and give open utterance to their faith with the exalted constancy of martyrs ; in ordinary times, they are tame and sequacious, and a thou- sand of them are marshalled with hardly less facility than a hundred. In spite of the crooked manceuvres so universal in elec- tioneering, there are persons who dwell much on the empty and fallacious distinction between dependent and independent voters. A poor voter, they affirm, is by his station depen- OF PAKLIAMENTARY EEFOEM. 39 dent, and this is urged as one reason for withholding votes from the poor : while a person of greater affluence is spoken of as if his position afforded security for his independence. But the test here assumed, for measuring dependence and in- dependence, is equivocal to a high degree. That man is the most dependent who is liable to suffer the greatest and most irreparable evil at the hands of some one or some few others ; and many who enjoy a most eligible position are, for that very reason, exposed to far more alarming liability of evil than simple poverty ever entails. A poor artisan or labourer may be displaced, but the number of equally good situations open to him is so considerable, that he may speedily hope to repair his loss. But the higher and better paid officers have more to lose by dismissal, while the number of such places is so limited as to afford them little chance of an equivalent elsewhere. It seems evident, therefore, that shop- men, clerks, and highly paid functionaries of every de- scription, being greater sufferers by arbitrary displacement, are really more dependent than artisans or servants, and consequently that poverty is no measure of the degree of dependence. But it is superfluous to verify the graduation of the scale, if we can satisfy ourselves that he who is called thoroughly independent is exposed to powerful private influence, more than sufficient to pervert any open vote. I would fain ask whose position is so fortunate as to enable him to deny this ? Look at the tradesman who is making 500Z. or lOOOZ. per annum, and the manufacturer or merchant who is making 2000Z. or 3000Z. Each of them acquires his income out of fractions, some large, some small, arising from connections profitable in various degrees ; and the best of these connections think themselves fully entitled to ask for his vote, whenever they take interest in an election. If the request be refused merely on public grounds, displeasure and provocation are infallible: and the refuser incurs the chance of pecuniary loss, of seeing himself supplanted by rivals, and of being stigmatised as ungrateful. How is this 40 ESSENTIALS consistent with the pretended independence of his position ? Even the man whose income is already treasured up, finds many individuals around him whom it is exquisitely pleasing to oblige and highly distressing to offend, though their political views may be such as he entirely disapproves. Is it not true, then, that the man most independent by position and circumstances is yet so fettered and so vulnerable, as to lay him under temptations far too strong for average political integrity ? So long as voting is open, therefore, the votes of the middling and of the affluent will be determined, in the majority of cases, by some one of the innumerable varieties of private influence : nor is the Ballot less essential to purify their votes than to liberate those of the poor. I duly ap- preciate the beneficial effects of the private sympathies, and of that readiness to oblige and to requite, without which life would be a desert : but if the business of voting is to be subservient to a public end, it ought to be abstracted alto- gether from the sphere of their interference. Is it at all less detrimental to the main purpose of voting — the advance- ment of the wisest and best men in the community into the Legislative Assembly — that I should vote to please a friend, to return an obligation, or to conciliate a customer, than that I should sell my vote for ten pounds, or for a place in the Excise? It is melancholy to confess that on this im- portant topic the morality both of rich and poor has yet to be formed, nor can we hope ever to see it formed except by means of the Ballot. Most men consider their vote merely as a means of rendering service to a friend ; and dispose of it exactly on the same principles as they would bestow any other favour. How abominable would be the course of justice, if they forgot their trust as jurors in the same cool and systematic manner : if one man thought himself au- thorized to solicit, and another to grant, a verdict in favour of plaintiff or defendant ! Yet the function of voter is no less a public trust than that of juror : nor would the mischief of corrupt juries, prodigious as it is, surpass that of corrupt OF PARLIAMENTARY REFORM. 41 voting. It is fruitless to admonish men on the pernicious tendency of what is daily before their eyes, so long as the misleading influence is left in full vigour and application : but if the door be once shut against such influence, there is nothing to prevent voting from being assimilated to other public trusts, and from becoming really conducive to its peculiar and all-important purpose* * The duty of a voter to the public has been banished, not only out of fact and society, but also out of political reasonings and conceptions. Hence the extraordinary difference in the public senti- ment between the promise made by a voter to support a particular candidate, and the promise made by a juror to deliver a particular verdict. To be known to have made such a promise as juror, would suffice to brand a man with infamy. But assuming that he has been guilty enough to make it, and that he repents prior to the verdict, will it not be generally considered that he commits less evil by breaking his promise than by consummating an injustice? The indignation of mankind is directed, not against the violation of such a promise, but against the making it and the asking it. Were voting considered as a public trust, the like feeling would prevail with respect to a voter. But it is considered as a matter purely private and optional ; so that all which the public exacts of a voter is that he shall keep a promise when he has once made it ; and strenuous opposition has been raised to the Ballot, on the ground that it would permit him to violate his promise without detection. Objectors on this ground forget that no promise, interfering with the due execution of a public trust, can be innocently made ; and that with respect to culpable promises, the desirable object is to prevent them from being ever asked or ever made, not to ensure their strict observance after they are made — to preserve men from ever entangling themselves in that trying position, wherein they can only choose between violating a promise or forfeiting a trust. Now it is obvious that electors are much less likely to be called upon to promise when they vote secretly, than when they vote openly : and where few promises are asked, few promises can be broken : so that the fact which the objection assumes, that pro- mises will be habitually broken, is really untrue ; while the end is also attained, of removing one great temptation to an undue species of promise. 42 ESSENTIALS I had the opportunity of being present, a little before the French elections of June, 1830, at a private preliminary meeting of French electors in one of the arrondissements not far from Paris. About thirty electors met, to estimate the chances and to concert measures for the success of their candidate in the approaching contest. They called over the electoral list, and each person present pronounced respecting those whom he knew or those who lived near him, whether they were likely to be supporters or opponents. For such as were not thoroughly known, attempts were made to guess at their political sentiments or at their private partialities. But never was the slightest hint started of winning over a questionable voter by solicitation and intrigue, or of ap- proaching his bosom by those invisible bye-paths which an English electioneerer so skilfully explores. Such artifices appear to have been considered in France too degrading for any one except the agents of Charles X., who did indeed employ them as much as was practicable, and who of course spared no pains to nullify and elude the Ballot. Among the several objections urged against the Ballot, there is one which not only admits, but is even founded upon, the marvellous debasement produced by the English system of open voting. Some persons allege that under secret voting scarcely any elector would go to the poll : that when his vote could neither gratify a friend nor repay a benefactor, he could not be induced by a " cold sense of duty" to undertake the inconsiderable labour of going occasionally to a neighbouring voting place. So low is their estimate of the strength of the public affections amongst a commimity whom yet they describe as pre-eminently virtuous, and under a Government which they extol as little short of perfection ! To me such eulogies either on the people or on the Government seem little better than a childish self-adulation : yet I never could have supposed an average Englishman so dead to all public feeling, as to think a good member too dearly purchased at the cost of a short walk or ride — (for the labour of voting need be no OF PARLIAMENTARY REFORM. 43 greater) — once every year, or every two or three years. Assuming the fact, however, to be true, the expediency of a secret suffrage Is not impeached by it. Though few votes be actually given, yet as every vote denotes a genuine preference and esteem, some rational ground is really ac- quired for believing the person chosen to be a superior man : whereas a hundred times the number of privately-determined votes proves literally nothing in favour of his competency as a Legislator. Better take the evidence of ten sincere truth-tellers, than that of a thousand suborned witnesses, who speak without caring whether what they attest is true or false. Others object that the Ballot will be found in practice not to produce secrecy, inasmuch as a man may tell and will tell how he has voted. They omit to indicate at the same time the test whereby they mean to determine whether he speaks truth or falsehood. Of what value is a man's statement, when he may violate truth without any chance of detection, and when he has a direct interest in repelling tyrannical inquisition by justifiable deceit ? His vote may perhaps be guessed : but that is not enough ; it must be actually and positively known, before a patron can make his displeasure or his satisfaction contingent on the direction of it. And, indeed, the virulent opposition of the vote-commanders to the Ballot, plainly demonstrates how little faith they them- selves repose in this miserable quibble. There are others who exclaim loudly against the mischiefs of secrecy, and against the lying and hypocrisy of the Ballot, forgetting that they are themselves habitually employing it in their clubs, and that they can therefore scarcely be treated as serious when they brand it with such contumelious epithets elsewhere. Secrecy is good or bad according as it conduces to a good or a bad end : and in the case of voting, it may be proved to be essential to the most beneficent of all ends. And as a vote given by Ballot quickly comes to be ranged among matters unbecoming to pry into — ^just as no man ever thinks himself entitled to ask about the tenor 44 ESSENTIALS of his friend's will, or the amount of his property — so there really would be neither lying nor hypocrisy, except where a shameful intrusion had been employed to wring from the voter his secret, and where the lie was a pardonable shelter against the greater evil of oppression. " In order that all men (observes Dr. Johnson)* may be taught to speak the truth, it is necessary that all likewise should I'earn to hear it." When gentleness, sympathy, and tolerance of dissent shall have become habits of action in the superior, evasion and concealment in the inferior will disappear of themselves. But until the former has thrown away his spear, it is monstrous to call upon the latter to perform his duty without a shield. But there is one argument against the Ballot which I never hear advanced without indignation. It is to be with- held because it would cut down the influence of the great proprietors. Wheresoever we turn in Reform, these tre- mendous giants are posted to bar our progress — " Apparent dirae facies, inimicaque Trojae Numina magna Deum." It is indeed true that the Ballot would materially abridge their influence : and any reform which did not effect that end would be hollow and delusive. Far from denying or disguising such a result, the advocates of the Ballot avow and exult in it. And they ask at the same time what peril would ensue if the influence of the great proprietors were so far cut down as to be proportioned to their individual wisdom and merit, not to the size of their rent-rolls ? In order that this class, against whom mankind have never yet provided adequate safeguards — insolent bullies and ravish ers in the Grecian States; cruel ejectors of neigh- bouring poor proprietors in the Roman Republic ; sticklers for the Fist-right,t in the middle ages, against the growing * Bamhler, No. 96. t I take the liberty of translating literally the significant German compound Faust-rechL OF PARLIAMENTARY REFORM. 45 ideas of law and order in the cities ; spoilers of the church property, for their own benefit, in the sixteenth century; auxiliaries of Charles Stuart against English liberty in the seventeenth ; authors, in the eighteenth and nineteenth, of the devouring war and the Corn Laws ; in an age of crime, the most high-handed criminals; in an enlightened time, the most obstinate foes of improvement. In order that this class may outbid friendless merit and ride down con- scientious opposition, are we to dupe the people with the spurious forms instead of the essence and virtue of an electoral security ? To cheat them with the outward and visible sign, while we rob them of the inward and spiritual grace ? To invest them with an important public trust, designing beforehand that they should barter it away each to his patron-aristocrat, and thus to efface in their minds, by Legislative authority, the idea of obligation to the com- munity ? The influence of these elevated beings must indeed be as the dew from Heaven, if it be worth purchasing at the cost of all the evils of a simulated suffrage. If they must have more votes than one — for the influence which they claim means nothing else — let them become three-star, four-star, or twenty-star men, leaving to the humbler citizen his one poor vote secret and free. It will be bad enough to exalt them thus into a privileged few : they may spare us the bitterness of making them, besides, extorters and corrupters of other men's votes. The importance of the Ballot, on every ground, as well in its direct and immediate as in its remote and in- direct effects, appears to me vast and overwhelming. But it cannot, undoubtedly, be rendered efficacious, if the number of voters who concur to return a single member is permitted to be small. In that case, an opulent man might bribe them in the mass, covenanting to pay to each a certain sum after his election. But if the number be large, it will become too expensive thus to pay all in order to purchase a majority. In my opinion, no section or district which returns a member ought ever to consist of less than 2000 46 ESSENTIALS voters : every section ought to include an equal or nearly an equal number ; and if the necessity of obtaining a certain aggregate of returns out of a certain aggregate of voters permitted, it would be an improvement to make the number of voters in each electoral section even greater than 2000. Every increase in the number of secret votes, whereby a candidate is chosen, furnishes increased presumption of his superior qualifications. In this point of view, the number of members in the House of Commons becomes an important subject of •dis- cussion, because the smaller its total, the greater the number of voters who can be allotted to each separate returning body. The present House would be foimd far too numerous for the dispatch of business, if all the members were con- stant at their posts. The real working persons in it are notoriously a very small proportion : two hundred members constitute a large, three hundred a very large, attendance ; and questions which draw together a greater number than three hundred are rare and unusual indeed. Three hundred really assiduous members appear to me amply sufficient to prosecute the business of legislation : and the surplus above that number, if any there were, would be found rather to impede than to forward the ends for which they are assembled. To lessen the total number of members, too, as much as can be done without delaying the public busi- ness, is advantageous in other ways : it renders the post itself more conspicuous and honourable : it fastens public attention more steadily upon each member's parliamentary conduct ; and it will of course be easier to find three hun- dred highly qualified persons in the country than five hundred, so as to avoid the necessity of resorting to a lower scale of intellect. If the aggregate of voters were a million, and the members returned to Parliament 300, no returning body need include less than 3300 voters : if the members of OF PARLIAMENTARY REFORM. 47 Parliament were 500 in number, each returning body might then have 2000 voters allotted to it. A body of 2000 electors, voting secretly, and voting so as to occasion no expense, could not be tampered with by the most expert electioneerer. The member whom a majority of these return, must be a person of some public reputation ; a person believed to possess talent and worth, not merely equal, but much superior, to the average of his fellow-citizens. In looking over the manifold enormities of our present system of representation, it will generally be found that any one defect, if left uncorrected, suffices to neutralize the remedies applied to the rest. If voters are habitually called upon to vote at a distance, one of two consequences will ensue : either they will not vote at all, or they will find means to shift upon some one else the expense of their journey. In the first case, the benefit of their judgment is lost : in the second, solicitation, intrigue, and preponderance of the half-qualffied rich man, are revived and rendered available. It is essential to any good system of voting, that an elector should vote at or near the place of his habitual residence. Any parish, any fraction of a parish, or any cluster of parishes, which comprised 200 voters, might have a separate polling-place, with proper apparatus : ten such being combined to form one returning body. Less than 200 (or such a proportion of them as chose to come) ought not to make use of the same ballotting-box : with a number smaller than this, secrecy could not be effectually guaran- teed. All the votes might thus be taken on the same day, with little inconvenience to any one, and hardly any neces- sary expense. The existing distinction into Town and County Elections, without any reference to the number of voters contained in each county or in each town, appears to me indefensible and injurious in every way. The grand circumstance to be con- sidered in the electoral sub- divisions is the number of voters 48 ESSENTIALS included in each returning body, so as to ensure that no Member enters the House of Commons who has not ob- tained a certain minimum of votes, and so as to equah'ze, besides, the value of each man's vote, or the elective force vested in each voter. For, if one man votes in a returning body of 200, and another in a returning body of 2000, — the vote of the first is worth ten times as much as the vote of the second: and comparing the elective force assigned to each, or the total effect which each is allowed to produce upon the representative body, the result is, as if the first man had ten votes and the second only one. It is obvious that such inequality, if pushed to a certain extent, would of itself be enough to corrupt a system of representation in- volving all the other requisite conditions ; nor can any reason be given why even a small inequality should be allowed. When the voters are polled in small fractions, at different places, and all on the same day, the enormous evils attending populous elections as now transacted would altogether dis- appear. The saturnalia of our present elections are enough to shock any reasonable man, and to alienate him, not only from the external show of popular control, but even from the people themselves. The riot, drunkenness, and fighting in the streets, form an appropriate parallel and accompaniment to the low manoeuvres of electioneering leaders behind the scenes. Yet there are those who contend that these dis- graceful and noxious tumults are essential to the existence of public spirit, and that they serve to nurture both the sublime emotions and the sense of mutual right and duty which con- nect a man with his fellow^-citizens. To me they appear no less inconsistent with genuine patriotism than with private decency. A great public question is discredited and rolled in the dirt by being converted into the war-w^hoop of a hired mob, in whom the fiction of a public concern serves only to supersede the restraints of private life, without substituting any better feeling than that of devotion to their temporary employer. The band of sicarii organised by Clodius against OF PARLIAMENTARY REFORM. 49 his enemies at Eome could not be more destitute of attach- ment to the public welfare. Indeed, the whole transaction is more akin to a pugilistic contest or a horse race, than to a selection between two opponents, each professing to be qualified for the grandest function which society has to fill up. The resemblance would be complete in almost all points, if the backers of pugilists were to carry into the ring banners inscribed with some popular question or high sounding abstract word : — Dutch Sam and the Kevolution of 1688 ! Neal and Purity of Election ! When the knuckles and wind of Dutch Sam had achieved a triumph, his friends would retire, confirmed in their attachment to the Ee volution of 1688, and exulting in the idea that the victory just gained would do much to imprint its benefits on the public mind. There are some few cases of exception, even as matters are at present, where the population really take a sincere interest in the event of the election. But the evil of fixing one single place of voting, and of congregating men in large numbers about it, is still very great, though of a difierent character. Inflamed by one common sentiment, the crowd cannot be restrained from venting, either by words or by action, their antipathy against opposite voters, who are abused or pelted, so as to drive away the timid, and to furnish a pretence to the indolent for remaining at home. Such bursts of wrath, where no effective and tranquil system of control has as yet been organised on behalf of the people, may perhaps be pardonable against a flagitious statesman : against a private citizen, they are altogether vicious and inexcusable, and they fatally counteract the salutary lesson, so hardly learnt by any one, of tolerance towards disin- terested dissent. Nor does an election, so taken, exhibit a fair result of the judgment of all the voters nominally appealed to. Every evil incidental to elections would be done away with, and the efficacy of the system as a means to good government greatly strengthened, if voters polled secretly, in small bodies, and in different places at the same time. E 50 ESSENTIALS One more addition remains to be made to the essentials of Parliamentary Reform : — increased frequency of election. A peaceful citizen, accustomed to elections as they are now, may well feel repugnant to such invasions of his comfort at shorter periods ; but when it has been shown that voting may be so conducted as to molest no man's tranquillity, a most injurious prepossession will be dispelled, on this truly important part of the field. Election for seven years certain has almost the same effect as election for life. So faintly is the imagination affected by a contingency seven years removed, that if a man can be trusted to do well for that long period, he might also be trusted to do well, though chosen for life. What would be said of the prudence of any one, who, having selected a particular attorney or physician, should enter into a contract binding himself to resort to no other for the same space of seven years? Would he not be universally considered to have taken the most effectual measure for making them remiss and indifferent ? On the other hand we find, in the actual course of affairs, that although a man may change his lawyer or physician any day, he very rarely does change : because these practi- tioners, knowing that if they do not give satisfaction, they will immediately lose business, take care to be attentive and zealous in their duty. I think it may be stated, as a general fact, that when a trust is revocable at pleasure, the person entrusted acts so as not to deserve displacement, and in general is not displaced. This is precisely what we desire to see happen with respect to Members of Parliament : and the mode of ensuring it will be, as in other cases, by conferring on them their trust for very short fixed periods. One year, in my opinion, would be quite sufficient, and better than any longer period : two years would be tolerable ; three years seriously objectionable on account of its length ; and any period longer than ihxep years not to be entertained for a moment. Many persons are alarmed at the idea of annual elections, OF PARLIAMENTARY REFORM. 51 as if they imported actual cHange of members every year. This would, indeed, be a very formidable evil, — an evil only less than that of retaining dishonest or incompetent members. I feel -persuaded that their real operation would fce. directly the reverse: that a naember would retain his seat longer under annual elections than under any other, because the security for his good conduct would be so much more com- plete. The ideas of accountability and obligation, and the necessity of maintaining a high reputation with the public, could never be absent from his mind : the shortness of the period would leave him little hope of making up the negli- gence of one month by increased diligence during the re- mainder; and as he would indulge a reasonable hope of re-election, if he only avoided occasioning painful disappoint- ment to his constituents, the motives to zeal and good con- duct would be really at their maximum. If a man possesses the confidence of an electoral body in 1831, and is under such paramount and continuous motives to do his very best, can he be supposed likely to lose it in 1832, except by some most rare and unusual occurrence ? On the other hand, if the certain duration of his trust be lengthened, the motives to the best possible discharge of it are proportionally en- feebled, and he is more likely to do or to omit something whereby he would deserve to forfeit, and would really forfeit, the confidence of his constituents. It is only under the shorter duration that the desirable result will be ensured, of members being continued, simply because they deserve to be continued, in possession of their trust. Some persons apprehend that annual elections would make a member too attentive to the approaching end of his trust, and that they would subjugate the independence of his private judgment too much to the voters by whom he was to be re-chosen or displaced. But it is to be recollected that a voting section constituted as I have supposed — ^voting by ballot, in small divisions, and without any separate local tie — would be nothing more than a fraction of the general public, and that, consequently, the same behaviour which E 2 52 ESSENTIALS sustained his reputation with the general public, would also sustain it with his own peculiar voters. The only prejudices, therefore, to which he will be called upon to bend, are those of the general public. To these every man must bend, more or less: and the only person who can hope to combat them effectually and foeneficially? will be he who has established a high reputation on other grounds for wisdom and virtue. The motive to establish and sustain such a reputation will be highest in the bosom of the member chosen for a year, whose authority will therefore will be the greater when he stands up against any special prejudice. Nor do I imagine that he would be backward in such an opposition, so far as prudence will permit. For if he timidly chimes in with the prejudice, and if some bolder rival takes out of his hands the task of enlightening the public, comparative discredit is sure to await him. The path of evasion will be found hardly less dangerous, and far less elevating and satisfactory, than that of sincerity. Perhaps it may be contended, that according to the principles on which I have reasoned, annual elections would not be sufficiently frequent, and that monthly elections ought to be regarded as still better. To this I reply, first, that monthly elections would be a vast additional trouble to voters, without any adequate benefit. Secondly, that there are reasons which make a year preferable for this purpose to any shorter period. For it is desirable that the voters, when they exercise their privilege of re-choosing a member, should fix their eyes on his general reputation for worth and ability, more than on his conduct with reference to any particular question. This general estimate is the resulting impression, formed by surveying and laying to heart succes- sively a series of his acts and speeches, assisted by the criticisms which each of them may provoke from the organs of public discussion. The seat of the member ought, there- fore, to be assured for a period sufficiently long to include a certain number of various acts and speeches, so as to serve as a basis for that general estimate on which the voters ought OF PARLIAMENTARY REFORM. 63 to proceed, and so as to prevent their judgment from being unduly absorbed by any one particular question. A year, in my opinion, is long enough to answer this condition per- fectly, and short enough to keep alive the most earnest sense of obligation in the bosom of the member. Though I regard a year as the best period, and any period longer than two years as seriously objectionable, yet I am far from denying that even triennial parliaments would be a prodigious improvement, in comparison with septennial, which are, as I have before observed, scarcely less pernicious than nominations for life. . Tho conditions, then, of an effectual Parliamentary Eeform, without alarming the middling classes by multiplying very poor voters in their present state of intelligence, are the following : — 1. An aggregate of voters not less than one million, formed of all persons enjoying the largest income. It has been stated that a pecuniary qualification of £100 annual income would embrace one million of voters: whether this be the fact or not, can only be verified by actual returns : but I think the qualification ought to be so adjusted as to be sure of embracing such an aggregate. 2. This aggregate of one million distributed into electoral divisions of equal or nearly equal numbers, coinciding as little as possible with separate class interests, or local inte- rests, and each voting for one member. 3. Electors to vote bv ballot : in small bodies and at separate polling places, yet so that no body smaller than 200 shall be assigned to the same ballotting-box. Each election to be concluded in one day. 4. Parliaments on no consideration longer than triennial ; better far, if biennial : better still, if annual. By these provisions alone, an enormous and incalculable gain would be assured : but, to render them quite complete, they ought to be accompanied with a farther provision for 54 ... ESSENTIALS 'i. u gradually lowering the suffrage at the end of some fixed period, say five years, so as to introduce successively new voters at the end of every five years, and to render the suffrage at the end of twenty or twenty-five years, nearly co-extensive with the community. The interval would be more than sufficient so to educate and prepare the minds of the poorer voters, as to obviate all ground for alarm on the part of the richer. It is but too certain, however, that we shall not at the present moment acquire even our million of voters with the requisite accompanying precautions : so that it becomes a matter important to determine, since all of the first four provisions cannot be obtained, which of them can be least injuriously postponed, and which of them ought to be most strenuously insisted on. Whatever else may be postponed, let no man for a moment think of laying aside the Ballot. This is the vast and grand amendment, in the absence of which every other concession would be unavailing and nugatory. Without secret voting there cannot be public-minded voting : and without public- minded voting, men worthy to be legislators can neither be singled out nor preferred — scarcely even created. Under a numerous and equally distributed open suffrage, it is possible that the mutes and idlers in the present House might be replaced by active and stirring gentlemen, and that what Mr. Tennyson calls " the inert physical mass " of the House mio'ht thus be lio-htened. But the voters, thouo-h increased in number, would still persist in their rooted habit of voting from desire to oblige, from fear to offend, or from personal sympathy or kindness of one description or another: the election committee and the canvass would still be the grand instruments of success ; and the most promising candidate would be he who, steering his political course midway between truth and falsehood, so as to offend no one, could create the most favourable impression by seducing manners, by overflowing politeness, and by officious attentions. It is not from such a school that the men are to be drawn, OF PARLIAMENT AKY REFORM. 55 under whose guardianship we may lay down our heads in peace, and to whose mandates or exactions we should cheerfully submit, under the conviction that they emanated from tried wisdom and benevolence. It is only when the vote, secured by secrecy, stands upon grounds quite distinct from the ordinary track of private affections and sympathies, that the elector will look out for that assemblage of public qualities which the magnitude of the trust really calls for. Then only will such qualities be sought, and then only will they be found. To gain the Ballot, it w^ould be amply worth while to make concessions as to the number of voters, if we were compelled to take our choice between the two. Though I could not place full confidence in an aggregate of voters much smaller than a million, I should greatly prefer 500,000 voters, qualified by superiority of income, along with the Ballot, to 2,000,000 of voters without it. If the House of Commons were reduced in number to 300, an aggregate of 500,000 voters would allow of 1660 voters for each electoral division. A suffrage, narrowed even to this nearly oligar- chical limit, but accompanied by the Ballot and by triennial parliaments, w^ould afford a great and salutary opening to superior minds and to men of public reputation, and a com- fortable foretaste of better things to come. NOTICE OF SIR WILLIAM MOLESWOETH'S EDITION OF THE WORKS OF HOBBES. {The 'Spectator' Newspaper, 1830.) \j¥a. h TiBy > ill ot .i^._- ■fe, ^ _ ^J> ■-. ^ \^ ^ _." -. -. f- 11 gi jl " ** ax NOTICE T (^R OF SIR WILLIAM MOLESWOETH'S edition: 1 Tk ,-. K Iifsd to OF THR WORKS OF HOBBES. ;: tt -i^- > *^<-£^e.7]fjir] or sometimes kXtjScov in the Homeric sense, which means a dictum, accidentally significant to the hearer of something which the speaker did not intend or think of, and therefore ominous. (Odyss. xviii. 117, xx. 100.) But we cannot admit that he is right in distinguishing "Oo-o-a from 6eov 6/x<^7) (II. XX. 129 ; Odyss. iii. 215), nor can we agree with him in thinking that ""Oo-o-a means " the general talk of men, the clamour of a multitude, as distinguished from the statement of some known individual." ^Oo-o-a in Homer is the voice proceeding from Zeus, heard only by some special person or persons for whom it is destined : the verb 6Wo/xat seems to denote the impression made upon the internal man by this divine agent, without any present or material cause, wherein sight is not clearly distinguished from hearing (Odyss. i. 115 ; xx. 81): a parallel to " I hear a voice thou canst not hear, That says I must not stay : I sec a form thou canst not see, That beckons me away." a 2 84 GRECIAN LEGENDS homely and infantine English, it lias been whispered by a little bird. But we may be pretty well assured that few of the audience will raise questions about authority ; the story From hence the word ocro-o/xat passes to signify any vague, in- distinct presentiment. The ^7;/x77 of Hesiod (0pp. et D. 761) is different, and really bears the meaning which Buttman assigns to the Homeric "Oacra — ^jjijirj 8' ovTL^ Tva^irav aTroXXvrai rjvr tva ttoXXol AaoL cf)rjiJiit,ov(Ti' 6e6s vv Tts ccrrl koi avrrj. Here the heavenly origin is struck off : the vox poi:)uli is exalted into the vox Dei. ^schines, in a very curious j)assage too long to be here cited, rather reverts to the old idea of <^rjixri (cent. Timarch. c. 27). And in the account which Herodotus gives of the battle of Mycale, we have the Homeric "Ocrcra, the messenger of Zeus, decidedly reproduced. The battle of Mycale on the coast of Asia Minor, and that of Platpea in Bceotia, were fought on the same day : the former in the afternoon — the latter in the morning. Previous to the onset at Mycale, the Greeks were in much appre- hension respecting their countrymen in Bceotia, who were exj)osed to the very superior force under Mardonius. But just as the Mycalean Greeks were preparing to attack, " there flew into the whole camp a voice, and a herakVs staff appeared lying on the beach : and the voice went through them to this effect, that the Greeks in Boeotia were then conquering the army of Mardonius. Many indeed are the evidences by which divine phenomena manifest themselves ; since on this occasion, the defeats of Mycale and Plat^a happening on the same day, the voice came over to the Greeks in Asia so as to inspire new courage into their army." — Herod, ix. 100 : Igvo-l hi crcfn cfyr]}xrj re icreTrraro is to crrparoTreSov TTCLV — (prj/xT} TolcTL F^XXyjcnv icraTrLKero. H]/ Se appcuSLr] cr vento falsely deified. See Grimm, Deutsche Mythologie, art. ' Helden/ cap. xi., and the curious citations in that instructive article. One from Albericus we transcribe (p. 201) : " In hac generatione decima ab incarnjatione Domini (i. e, before) regnasse invenitur quidam Mercurius in Gottlandia insula : a quo Mercuric, quo Wodan dictus est, descendit genealogia Anglorum ot multorum aliorum," &c. This is to the full as authentic as Mr. Clinton's Phoronetis, I 2 116 GRECIAN LEGENDS grayidae" — were ready to pour forth, and still more ready- to welcome, impressive legends calculated to satisfy any earnest feeling which animated them. Finally, we added^ that transporting ourselves back to Greece in the seventh and eighth centuries before the Christian era, when recorded matter of fact was unknown, we should find the empire of mythus all but omnipotent, and the necessity of requiring some positive evidence as a condition of belief, neither recognised nor thought of, even among the superior minds of the community; plausible fiction in exclusive vogue, authenticated truth not yet risen above the horizon. The countless divine le^fends eno:endered durins; these C (D CD ealry ages by the religious feelings of the Greeks, both attest and elucidate what has been here advanced. Such tales are found possessing the firmest hold on the public mind and belief, yet confessedly without any foundation in fact ; emanating originally from the poets or other productive minds of the community, but adapted by them to the state of feeling which they shared in common with the rest, and requiring no stronger certificate to procure for them both a cordial welcome, and a sincere belief. A-UToStSaKTOS 8 €t/Xt, ^€0$ §€ jJLOi kv (j>p€^9 — Eurip. Electr., 435 ; see also the Fragment of Pindar ap. Plutarch. Terrestria et Aquatilia Animal, c. 36, p. 984. c.) We have here, then, a perfect mythus,but tacked on to an historical fact and an historical person — a mythico- historical incident. Now it appears to us that the mistake so commonly made, in regard to the Grecian early legends, consists in dealing with the Trojan war and the x\jgonautic expedition, in the same way as we deal with this story of Arion — in seeking a basis of fact for the two former, as we successfully do for the latter. There is this essential difference between the two. In regard to the Trojan war and the Argonautic expedition, the legend stands alone, professing only to refer to an un- defined past time: there is no collateral evidence of any kind to corroborate either its incidents or the realitv of its personal characters. But in the case of Arion, we know the existence, the celebrity, and the date of the poet, upon evidence quite independent of the legend, just as we know the existence of Lord Byron: if we affirm that the legend has an historical basis, we do not ground our affirmation on the single certificate of the legend itself. When any similar independent evidence can be produced to certify the main fact of an expedition of confederated Greece against Troy in 1183 B.C., or the outfit of a commonplace vessel, Argo, from Jolcos to Colchis in the preceding generation, we shall then readily yield our assent : until this is done, it is unreasonable to call for any such historical assent. A certain number of the plays of Shakspeare have an historical basis. How do we know this ? Xot upon the testimony of Shakspeare himself, or of these particular plays themselves, but upon positive testimony, independent both of the one and the other. Any play for which you cannot, by some independent evidence, demonstrate an historical basis, passes ipso fado as non-historical. Apply the same test to the early Grecian poems, and we exact no more. And this brings us back to the principle which we laid down some time ago, that the onu^ prohandi always lies upon. AND EARLY HI8T0EY. 123 the historian, and the simple absence of evidence is sufficient to put him out of court. Obvious as such a position will seem, it places us at issue with an inquirer no less eminent than Mr. Fynes Clinton. In speaking of the personages of the old Grecian poems, belonging to a supposed date anterior to all recorded chrono- logy, and long before all positive history, Mr. Clinton says (Introduction, p. vi.) :— " We may acknowledge as real persons all those whom there is no reason for rejecting. The presumption is in favour of the early tradition, if no argument can he brought to overthrow it. The persons may be considered real, when the description of them is consistent with the state of the country at that time : when no national prejudice or vanity could be concerned in inventing them : when the tradition is consistent and general : when rival or hostile tribes concur in the leading facts : when the acts ascribed (divested of their poetical ornament) enter into the political system of the age, or form the basis of other transactions which fall within known historical times." Such are Mr. Clinton's rules for appreciating historical evidence : we think them every way inadmissible. First, — Mr. Clinton practically annuls the obligation of positive proof, as incumbent on the historian ; for the obli- gation comes to nothing, if he can satisfy it by producing simply '^ an early tradition," and then calling upon his opponents for arguments to overthrow it. Admit this posi- tion, and Brute, the Trojan, may still remain at the apex of English history. According to Mr. Clinton's rule, the assertions of the early tradition, in respect to times long anterior to positive history, will be admitted upon easier terms than the assertion of a contemporary witness in regard to his own times. For as you know nothing at all of the remote past, you cannot produce any evidence to contradict events alleged to have then taken place. Mr. Clinton not only lightens his own shoulders of all the burden of proving, but casts upon those of his adversary a burden of disproving, altogether intolerable and unheard of. 124 GRECIAN LEGENDS Secondly, — the word tradition is not merely vague, but thoroughly misleading : it acts upon the mind by means of an assumption, which being tacitly implied and not openly expressed, escapes direct confutation. The plain meaning of the word is, a narrative handed down from generation to generation ; and fiction may be handed down in this way quite as well as fact, as we see by the Grecian religious legends. But the assumption whereby this word is made to carry evidentiary force, is that the narrative originally arose contemporaneously with, and was derived from, the incident which it professes to recount. As soon as this assumption is clearly stated, we perceive it to be often untrue, always gratuitous. The birth and parentage of tradition is essen- tially unsearchable — " caput inter nubila condit " — you hear the voice, but cannot tell from whence it proceeds. Thirdly, — No greater privilege can be required in favour of a known and good contemporary witness, than that which Mr. Clinton here claims for mere impersonal hearsay. If you put into the box a veracious witness who has had means of knowing the facts to which he deposes, we are bound either to believe him, or to overthrow his testimony by argument or counter-testimony. In placing '^ early tradition '^ on this very same footing, Mr. Clinton effaces all the gra- duating lines by which the value of positive evidence is to be determined. Fourthlv, — Mr. Clinton overlooks the verv existence of jplausihie fiction, and its generic difference from historical matter of fact. Plausible fiction will satisfy all the con- ditions which he lays down, to determine what persons are "real" in the old legends, just as well as authenticated truth ; the plausibility of the fiction consists in its satisfying such conditions. One of the tests, indeed, furnished by Mr. Clinton is to be excepted — " Persons are to be considered as real, when no national prejudice or vanity could be concerned in inventing them." But, in the first place,, we are far too little acquainted with the range of sentiment prevalent among the early Greeks to allow of our applying this nega- AND EARLY HISTOEY. 125 tive test in practice: and in the second place, we again repeat, that the burden of proof rests with those who claim for a narrative or for a person the prlyilege of being in- scribed on the tablet of history ; not upon those who treat it as uncertified, and for that reason as presumptively fictitious. It is by no means onr purpose to maintain that there is no historical matter in the ancient Grecian leo:ends. ximono-st the varied and interesting agglomerate which they compose, we doubt not that there are frao-ments of historical matter of fact imbedded : and we shall rejoice much when any one will furnish some assured criterion bv which to verify them and detach them from the rest. How unsuccessful have been the attempts hitherto made to accomplish such dis- crimination, we desire no better proof than this recent work on Chronology by Mr. Clinton, wherein he professes to compute the number of generations occupied by Grecian legendary personages anterior to the first Olympiad — to strike out such as are fictitious, and to retain only those which are real. To seek a fixed chronological arrangement in this ante- mundane chaos, appears to us much the same as if any one were to take the flat round plate, constituting the surface of the earth as conceived by Homer, — with the deep and gentle river Oceanus flowing round it and returning into itself, — and distribute it into regular parallels of latitude, one passing through the island of Calypso, and another through the territory of the Cyclopes. And when we follow Mr. Clinton throuo'h the details of his scheme, we remark a curious alternation of cautious doubt with extreme licence of positive assertion ; enough of doubt is admitted to invalidate the whole series, vet numerous statements are made which imply that no such doubts ought to Lave application. Thus Mr. Clinton tells us (p. 123) '' that the Olympiad of Corcebus, B.C. 776, is the first date in Grecian chronology which can be fixed upon authentic evidence " — and that "in proceeding iipivard, this date is our highest point." The 126 GRECIAN LEGENDS chronology for the anterior period he professes to reckon downwards, starting from Phoroneus, 977 years before the first Olympiad. But, let us ask, where is the value, and what is the credibility, of chronology, reckoned downwards? All chronological reckonings in the past must first be made upwards : you start from the present, and you then reckon upwards to some fixed point in the past, from w^hich you may make a fresh start in either direction. If, for example, we are to reckon downwards from Phoroneus, we must first have performed the reckoning upwards from the present time to Phoroneus : if we are compelled, from want of " authentic evidence," to suspend our upward reckoning at the vear B.C. 776, as Mr. Clinton allows, then anv reckonins: downwards to the year B.C. 776, from some undetermined point in anterior time such as the supposed epoch of Pho- roneus, must be completely illusory. Having informed us — most correctly, as we think — that there is no authentic chronolog:v hig:her than B.C. 776, Mr. Clinton misfht have spared himself the trouble of tracing imaginary chrono- logical parallels for the earlier time. Again, Mr. Clinton for the most part treats as fictitious the general class of eponymous persons — those whose names coincide with, and are produced as having given origin to, the name of a tribe, a city, a demus, a mountain, a river, a spring, &c. This class is very numerous throughout the legendary genealogies, and would appear to be still more so if we were better acquainted with the nomenclature of places and communities throughout Greece. Thus Hellen, Caucon, Pelasgus, and others, are, in Mr. Clinton's opinion, fictitious persons ; such names and genealogies are not to be understood in their literal meaning, but as symbolical of certain circumstances in the historv of the tribe--" the genealogical expression may be false (he tells us, p. 3), but the connexion which it describes is real." This, in our judgment, is a just remark, and points at the true value of the legendary genealogies : but we must observe, in the first place, that Mr. Clinton flinches from the application of AND EARLY HISTORY. 127 his own principle when he recognizes as real persons, Cad- mus, Danaus, Hyllus, and others, the eponymous heroes of the Cadmeians, the Danaans, and the Doric tribe Hylleis, just as Kruse (Hellas, vol. i., cap. v., sec. i., p. 414) dis- tinguishes between Hellen and Pelasgus, affirming the former to be real, and the latter fabulous : and, in the second place, that whoever adopts such a view, subverts altogether the general authority of the genealogies, con- sidered as attesting personal and chronological reality. For w^hen it is conceded that so large a proportion of the story, told by the same witnesses, and depending upon the same authority, is fiction, we cannot with any reason be called upon to admit the remainder as so much authentic history. The genealogical tables of Mr. Clinton, conformably to this method of partial, scepticism inlaid with general faith, present a singular medley of mythical and real personages ; a real father preceding a mythical son; or a real son fol- lowing a mythical father ; or real personality intermarrying with mythical, under the name either of husband or wife. It appears to us quite as easy, and w^e will add, not less philosophical, to credit the heroic genealogies entire, than to accept the mangled limbs of them as they appear in Mr. Clinton's pages, distinguished by common and italic type. Mr. Clinton contends vehemently for the humanity and historical personality of Hercules ; and we understand why he is so easy of faith upon this point, seeing that the genealogy of the Spartan kings, upon which the compu- tations of Eratosthenes as to the date of the Trojan war w^ere founded, assumes an unbroken series of real persons from Leonidas or Cleombrotus up to Hercules. Tf Mr. Clinton can bring himself to believe that Hercules was an historical man, we cannot understand why he should have any scruple in adopting the entire theory of Euemerus, and in humanising not only all the Pagan heroes but all the Pagan gods : for there is not a single personage to be found amongst them, who, from the mother's womb to the funeral pile, is more pointedly distinguished from ordinary humanity than 128 GEECIAN LEGENDS Hercules. We read with amazement the reasoning by which Mr. Clinton professes to demonstrate that Hercules was a real man who lived so many hundred years before the Christian era. If we had not already prolonged this article too much, we would analyse them and exhibit their futility : upon grounds equally good we would engage to degrade and humanise all the divine tenants of Olympus. Nothing can be more thoroughly un-Hellenic than to believe in Hercules as a man. If we had been born in Greece in the fifth century before the Christian era, we should have imbibed a faith which would have led us to carry offerings to his Herakleion ; w^e should have invoked his aid during peril, and should have listened with veneration to the epic poems which commemorated his marvellous exploits, his journeys, and his sufferings. Perhaps we might have believed, with Pindar and the Sicyonians (Pindar, Nem. iii. 21 — Pausan. ii., 10, 1), that he combined in mysterious unity the attri- butes of a Hero and a God : or we might have adopted the conviction of Herodotus, that there were two different beings named Hercules : the one a God, the other a Hero (Herod, ii. 44). But to conceive Hercules as a real ordinary his- torical man, begotten by some father of our own con- temptible stature and infirmities, and no nearer to the Gods than ourselves, is a tenet which we must have regarded as impious and inadmissible. In reverence for this ancient faith — now extinct, but once so fruitful in productions of lasting beauty — w^e ought at least to suffer its magnificent and essentially superhuman creations to set, like the tropical sun, with unabated splen- dour, without passing through the '^ pale gradation " and inglorious commonplace of physical humanity. One other observation we will cite from Mr. Clinton. ^^ It is necessary (he says, p. 3), for the right understanding of antiquity, that the opinions of the Greeks concerning their own origin should be set before us, even if these are erroneous opinions ; and that their story should be told as they have told it themselves." AND EARLY HISTORY. 129 This is just and important : and, if Mr. Clinton had laid the remark to heart, he would have spared the heroic personality of Hercules, instead of dealing with it upon the same principle as the Homeric scholiast applies to the im- mortal horses Xanthus and Balius. It is not indeed too much to say, that if he had laid this remark to heart, he would have re-written his whole early chronology. For he constantly abandons the views of the G-reeks, without any scruple ; he admits distinctions between real and fictitious persons, such as they would never have dreamt of ; he casts away, as fictions, personages more frequently thought of, and more reverentially believed in, than the rest, viz., the eponymous heroes of cities, tribes, and demi. No bribe would have induced us to read aloud Mr. Clinton's work in the presence of Herodotus. We agree, then, with Mr. Clinton, that the antiquities of the Greeks should be told as they themselves have told them. And the very first condition lor accomplishing this object is, that w^e should rightly appreciate the creative and unrecording age, of inspired bards and believing listeners, in which the early legends originally sprimg up — as dis- tinguished from the after-growth of positive and historical criticism, to which they were no way adapted, and by which they were disintegrated and recast into a seeming chrono- logical sequence ; above all, that we should place ourselves at the point of view of Grecian religious faith. The antiquities of every Grecian state are merged in and identified with its religion : without it they become utterly incomprehensible. At the opening of the Grecian world, Gods and Heroes, beings super-human and extra- human, occupy the canvas : realities in the eye of faith — fictions in that of modern criticism ; but in no case human realities, nor fit subjects for history and chronology. The ancients did indeed introduce a sort of chronology even among their Gods and Heroes, for it was noway offensive to their belief to speak of a God being born, or of one God being more ancient than another. But when we once keep in view the light in which the K 130 GKECIAN LEGENDS ancients regarded these initial personages in their history, it will appear preposterous to expect an adherence to human scale or measurement, either in their exploits, their suc- cessions, or their duration. " Datur hsec venia (says Livy), antiquitati, ut miscendo humana divinis, primordia urbium augustiora faciat." Livy here tells us that the history of the past is to be accommodated, by a proper mixture of things human and divine, to the sentiments, in the minds of the present, of what is august and holy. In other words, it is to be mythus^ which the sentiment of the present can both abundantly supply and profoundly appreciate ; not positive matter of fact, which is insufiScient for the purpose as well as inaccessible to the view. Hekataeus, of Miletus, the historian, boasted of a pedigree, for himself and his gens or phratry, commencing with a God and descending through fifteen successive links to himself (Herod, ii. 143). In like manner the gens to which Thucy- dides, the historian, belonged, was traced up to -^acus the son of Zeus (Marcellin. Vit. Thuc. init.) : these may serve as a specimen of similar genealogies which every noble family in the Grecian cities could boast of and commemorate in its gentile sacrifices. According to the ancient point of view, the God at the top was quite as firmly believed to be a reality as any of the members of the series, and was far more deeply cherished than the rest : nay, the principal value of the whole genealogy was derived from the circumstance, that it connected the living members with the God whom they worshipped as their progenitor as well as their pro- tector. According to the modern point of view, the God at least is struck off as a fiction, and the genealogy thus becomes essentially acephalous. We have a continuous pedigree, of which the last member is indisputably real, the first member as indisputably fictitious. At some point or other between the two, the line separating fiction from truth must be drawn : but we know not where to find that point, and Mr. Clinton's rules, which were intended to solve this problem, are altogether insufficient and illusory. Whether AND EAELY HISTORY. 131 the undetermined point is to be taken a little higher or a little lower in the series, let this be recollected — that to us who reject the Grecian religious faith, the earlier pheno? mena and the earlier persons of Grecian history are pure fable, not exaggerations or mis-reports of matter of fact.* Agreeing then as we do with Mr. Clinton in the opinion that all authentic evidence of Grecian chronology — all chronological reckoning upwards — ceases with B. c. 776 ; we are compelled to treat the period earlier than B.C. 776, more in accordance with this fundamental supposition than he has treated it himself. We regard it as an — " Illimitable ocean, without bound. Without dimension, where length, breadth, and height, And time and space, are lost" — the empire of mythus or legend, purely and simply ; jich in plausible incidents adapted to the sentiment and accredited * As an illustration of the inseparable connexion between early genealogies and religious belief, we cite an analogous fact respecting the Anglo-Saxon genealogies, from Grimm, 'Deutsche MytJiologie,'' Anhang, pp. 1-11, art. "xlngel Sachsische Stammtafeln." "In the fifth and sixth centuries," he says, " the Anglo-Saxons at their transit into Britain brought with them out of Germany the tale of the descent of their noblest families. All of them carry themselves back to Woden ; but they sometimes ascend even higher, and enu- merate a series of gods or deified heroes as ancestors of Woden. After their conversion to Christianity, the attempt was made to connect the family stem of these gods and heroes with the Hebraic tradition of the first human family — to bring their heathen fore- fathers into harmony with the Noah and Adam of Scripture." (Anhang, p. 11.) Here we see that the change of religion brought about an entire change of the earlier genealogies. Grimm thinks that similar genealogies were received among the other Teutonic tribes — the Frisians, Westphalians, Franks, &c. He treats them as quite worthless in respect to chronological matter of fact. " These catalogues of names," he says, " possess not the smallest chronological value for the oldest times : they first become historical with the lines of the Anglo-Saxon kings. But this detracts nothing from the importance of the legend." K 2 132 GRECIAN LEGENDS by the reliofion of the auditors, but neither entitled to the authority, nor amenable to the laws, of historical reality. The scenes which it presents may be looked at, either with the eye of pious faith, as they were by the original recipients, or with that of aesthetic and poetical faith, by those who are unbelievers in the Homeric Pasranism. But in either case they must be contemplated from a given and distant point of view, which the spectator is not at liberty to alter : like the beautiful feminine image which fascinates the gaze of Faust whilst in the witch's cell, they vanish into untrace- able mist, the moment he approaches either to touch or to scrutinise. That there is more or less of matter of fact among these ancient legends, we do not at all doubt. But if it be there, it is there by accident, because it happened to fall in with the purpose of the mythopoeic narrator, who will take fact, as he takes fiction, when it is suggested by the impulse in his own mind, or germane to the sentiment of his hearers. To discriminate the fact from the fiction, is a problem which we ourselves know not how to solve, in the absence of some positive evidence independent of the legend itself. We shall gratefully listen, if any one wall teach us : but sure wo are that some road must be discovered very far removed from that hitherto trodden by historical critics. For w^e cannot too strongly protest against the process of picking out pre- tended matter of fact, by simply decomposing the legend and eliminating all which is high-coloured, or impressive, or miraculous; it condemns us to all the tameness and insi- pidity of prose, but we remain as far as ever from the cer- tainty and solid nourishment of truth. For the period after B.C. 776, we conceive that a different manner of dealing with evidence becomes both necessary and admissible. We then come to tread a beaten chronological track, and to deal with assured historical personages: our positive information, though scanty, is yet sufficient to afford us holding ground when we try to discriminate matter of fact either from exaggeration or from fiction. Mythus has AND EARLY HISTORY. 133 ceased to be predominant, but it still continues to spring up as an element of itself out of its own soil of emotion and sentiment ; attached, indeed, to positive facts, yet in many cases clearly distinguishable from inaccuracy or mis-report of facts. We tried to illustrate this point by the legend of Arion quoted from Herodotus. The German poet Schiller, in his beautiful ode, ^Die Goetter Griechenlands,' describes the physical world as it was conceived in antiquity, replete with personifications, and animated in all its localities by unseen beings who mingled their sympathies and interests with the chequered lot of short-lived man. And he presents, as a repulsive contrast, the physical world as it is now studied and understood — a lifeless and impersonal aggregate, slavishly obedient to rules of which it has no consciousness, and destitute of all sympathy with the men who suffer or profit by it. Estimated by a poetical standard, the loss has been serious indeed: but it has been far more than compensated by the acquisition of lasting and substantial benefits. We have obtained in exchange an ascertained, methodical, and constantly increas- ing body of authentic truth : and we have obtained it, let ns remark, not by transforming and refining the imperfect ancient physics themselves, but by following cautiously the track, and respecting the limits, of positive evidence. There were, however, in antiquity, as we have already stated, a body of allegorising philosophers, who could neither accept literally the interesting personifications of the old world, nor strike out for themselves a means of reaching the assured results of the new. These men extracted from the ancient mythi a string of pretended physical sequences, resolving the embraces of Zeus and Here into the descent of the pure ether from on high upon the lower strata of the atmosphere, and dissipating all the charm of the original conception under pretence of banishing exaggeration and poetical orna- ment. The allegorised physics of Heraclides and Porphyry form a suitable counterpart to the historicised legend. There is music in the high-pitched voice and irregular 134 GRECIAN LEGENDS, ETC. rhythm of childhood, and there is soraething better than music in the grave tone and discriminating emphasis of the mature man. But between the two lies an awkward interval, of intolerable harshness and dissonance — the broken voice of the youth just bursting into puberty : and this seems to us the only fit accent for the reading of the historical war of Troy, as it is sketched by Thucydides and Mr. Payne Knight, and as it is detailed by Dictys the Cretan. ON ANCIENT WEIGHTS, COINS, AND MEASURES. (^Classical Museum, 1844.) ON ANCIENT WEIGHTS, COINS, AND MEASURES M. BoECKH has so long been celebrated in the philological world for profound erudition — for method, as well as in- genuity, in the combination of scattered facts, and for the quality, somewhat rare among eminent scholars, of sobriety in the field of conjecture — that no preface is necessary when I proceed to offer a few remarks upon one of his recent and most elaborate productions * The Metrologie is a work not unworthy of its distinguished author. The dispersed fragments of evidence, respecting the weights, measures, and monetary systems of the ancient world — one of the most perplexing subjects in the whole range of philology, — are patiently collected, and perspi- cuously discussed : and the thirty chapters, of which the book consists, are so closely packed with matter, as to for- bid the possibility of any condensed abstract of the entire contents. The views of M. Boeckh are, in several respects, original, differing even from opinions stated by himself in former publications : he has, moreover, imparted to the subject a new interest, by considering the metrological systems of the various countries in antiquity in continual comparison with each other, so as to elicit valuable proofs of * Metrologisclte Untersuclmngen uher Gewichte^ Munfzilsse, und Masse dcs Alterthums in ihrem Zusainmenliange, Von August. Boeckh. Berlin, 1838. 1 vol, 8vo. 138 EEYIEW OF BOECKH 0:N ANCIENT WEIGHTS, early comtDunion and transition of ideas between them. His book embraces the weights and measures prevalent throughout all the countries known to us in the ancient world, — Babylon, Syria, Phenicia, Judaea, Egypt, Sicily, Italy, and Eome: and the comparative metrology of these nations is presented to us in a way analogous to the Ver- ffleichende Qrammatih of Bopp, in regard to the extensive family of the Indo-Germanic languages ; it exhibits the diffusion of institutions, originating in the very ancient civilization of Babylon, to the neighbouring countries whose period of settled ordinances and commerce was more recent. Though this transition must have taken place anterior to recorded history, and, therefore, in a manner which we cannot now fathom, yet the reality of the fact is sufficiently proved by its lasting and ascertained results. In cases where the weights and measures of two different nations are found to be in a precise and definite ratio one to the other — either exactly equal, or exact multiples and parts of each other — we may fairly presume, either that the one has borrowed from the other, or that each has borrowed from some com- mon source {MetroL c. ii. § 3). Where the ratio is in- accurate, or simply approximative, it is to be treated as accidental and undesigned. I request particular attention to this distinction between a precise ratio, and a ratio merely approximative, which M. Boeckh lays down very clearly, and which he justly announces as the cardinal principle of his metrological reasonings. To a great extent, he has succeeded in exhibiting an analogy, both interesting and hitherto unknown, between the metrical and statical systems of the various countries to which his work relates. But I must at the same time add, that there are several of his conclusions which appear to me very imperfectly supported, and some even which are not to be reconciled with the evidence. In a subject so obscure and perplexed from beginning to end, this is by no means wonderful. In investigating the subject of the ancient weights and ' COINS, AND MEASURES. 139 measures, in so far as they afford evidence of communion or analogous proceeding between the different nations of anti- quity, the great point to be attended to is the normal system as it was fixed by law, abstracting from those imperfections which attended the execution of it in detail. All mechanical processes in antiquity were carried on far more loosely and inaccurately than they are at present : pieces of money, as well as weights and measures, were both less durable and less exact, in spite of the solicitude of the ancient governments. We know by the evidence of inscriptions, with respect to Athens, that normal weights and measures were preserved under custody of a public officer in the chapel of the Hero Stephane- phorus; that copies of these were made and distributed for private use ; and that strict watch was directed to be kept for the purpose of excluding fraudulent or incorrect weights and measures in the shops and market.* The case was similar at Rome, and seemingly also at Jerusalem (Metrol. c. ii. § 3). In this manner the theoretical perfection of the standard was maintained in the minds of the people as it was when originally adopted, in spite of imperfect execution in practice. M. Boeckh enters upon his subject, in the third chapter of the work, by an investigation of the Eoman liquid measure, quadrantal or amphora, in its relation to the Roman pound weight. According to the Silian plebiscite, as reported by Festus, the legal definition of a quadrantal was, a vessel con- taining eighty pounds weight of wine or water : the congius being one-eighth part of it, and containing ten pounds weight of the same. By this regulation the dimensions of the vessels containing liquids were made dependent, not upon cubical measurement, but upon weight, like the imperial gallon in England. Now the Attic liquid measure called %o{)9, was the exact equivalent of the Eoman congius ; and the Attic fjL€Tp7]Tr}^, the largest unity of liquid measures at Athens, contained twelve %oe9, and was equivalent to one Boeckh, Corpus InscripL Grcecar. No. 123-150. 140 EEYIEW OF BOECKH ON ANCIENT WEIGHTS, and a half amphoraa, or quadrantalia. Such a definite ratio does undoubtedly indicate either some common original from which both'systems must have been deduced, or an imitation of one of them by the other. M. Boeckh seeks to deduce both one and the other from the East, where it will be pre- sently shewn that the Chaldaeans at Babylon had adopted in very early times a system of determining their cubic measures by ultimate reference to a given weight. " If," (he says, iii. 4. p. 26) " we regard this relation of the weights and measures, based upon a given weight of water, which is the keystone of the Eoman system, and if we carry the application of this water-weight backwards to the chief measures of the ancient world, we shall find a connection really and truly organic between the systems of the different people of antiquity, and we shall arrive at last at the funda- mental unity of weight and measure in the Babylonian system ; so that this supposition is found to be verified in all its consequences and details. To give some prelimi- nary intimation of this, I shall shew that the Grecian (or more accurately, the ^ginaean) and the Eoman pound are in the ratio 10:9; the ^^ginasan pound is half the ^ginsean mina ; but the cubical measures stood normally in the ratio of the weights ; and therefore the Grecian cubic foot was to the Eoman as 10 : 9 ; and as the Eoman cubic foot weighs eighty pounds of rain-water, so also the Grecian cubic foot weighs eighty Grecian or j3Egina3an pounds, equal to forty ^ginaean minse. The unity of weight (in Greece) however is, not forty minae, but sixty minae, or a talent. In the original institutions of the people of antiquity every thing has its reason, and we find scarcely any thing purely arbitrary : nevertheless, this unity of weight, the talent, does not coincide with the unity of measure — neither with the cubic foot, nor with any other specific cubical denomination. But the coincidence reveals itself at once, as soon as we discover that the Babylonian cubic foot, standing as it does in the ratio of 3 : 2 to the Grecian cubic foot, weighs sixty ^ginsean minae (=60 Babylonian minae = 1 Babylonian talent) of raiii-water." COINS, AND MEASURES. 141 M. Boeckh here promises more than his volume will be found to realise. He does, indeed, satisfactorily shew that the Babylonian talent w^as identical with, and was the original prototype of, the ^ginsean talent, and that the standard and scale of weight was strikingly and curiously similar in Asia, in Egypt, and in Greece. But he has not, I think, made out the like with regard to the Grecian measures, either of length or capacity, and his proof of the ratio of 3 : 2 between the Babylonian and the Grecian foot will be found altogether defective. Nor has he produced adequate evidence to demonstrate, either the ratio of 10 : 9 between the Grecian or-Sjginsean pound and the Roman pound, or that of 1 :'2 between the ^ginsean pound and the ^Egi- naean mina ; the ratio between the Grecian cubic foot and the Roman cubic foot, too, as also that between the Grecian cubic foot and any given Grecian weight, is, as he proposes it, inadmissible. In fact, there is no such thing (properly speaking) as an ^ginsean pound weight ; nor is there any fixed normal relation between Grecian weight and Grecian measures, either of length or of capacity, though there is a fixed normal relation between Babylonian weight and Babylonian measures, as also between Roman weight and Roman measures. The Greek scale of weight consisted of the talent, the mina, the drachma, and the obolus : the talent consisting of 60 minae — the mina of 100 drachmae — the drachma of 6 obols. The scale of weight in Sicily and Italy was essen- tially and originally different, having for its unit the pound — always divided into twelve ounces, except in central Italy, north of the Apennines, where it contained only ten ounces. These denominations were universal throughout Sicily and Italy, though the pound, in one part of Italy and another, was not the same absolute weight, any more than the talent in Greece. M. Boeckh, as well as all other writers on the subject, recognises this radical distinction between the Hel- lenic population on the one hand, and the earliest inha- bitants, both of Italy and Sicily, on the other, in respect, 142 REVIEW OF BOECKH ON ANCIENT WEIGHTS, both to the denomination and divisions, of the statical and monetary scale. And I may here remark, that the suppo- sition of identity of Pelasgian race between the original population of Epirus, and that of the south-eastern regions of Italy, announced with confidence by Niebuhr, and adopted by K. 0. Miiller, becomes open to doubt from our finding no mention of pound weight or ounce weights among the Epirots. The Corinthian colonies on the coast of Epirus — Leukas, Anaktorium, and Ambrakia, as w^ell as the island of Korkyra — pursued a system of coinage purely Hellenic, consisting of talents, minse, and drachmae. But the Co- rinthian colony of Syrakuse, as well as every other Hellenic establishment, either in Sicily or Italy, adopted a mixed system, in which talents, minae, and drachmae, were blended together with pounds and ounces, not according to any one uniform principle, but varying from town to town both in Italy and Sicily. The statical denominations prevalent among the Italian and Sicilian Greeks, arising as they do out of a compound of two systems originally distinct, present questions full of perplexity, and such as can hardly be solved with our existing stock of information. The words talent, drachma, and obolus, are genuine Greek, and of Grecian origin : the first of the three even occurs in Homer, though in a sense quite different from that which it subsequently bore in Greece; denoting, seemingly, a definite, but small, weight,* But the systematic graduation * Aristotle had said (ScJioL Ven, ad Iliad, xxiii. 269) that the talent in Homer was a weight altogether undefined. M. Boeekh agrees with him (Metrol, iv. 1. p. 33). But surely this opinion cannot be reconciled with the assertion that " Odysseus weighed out ten talents of gold " {Biad xix. 247 : 'Kpvaov Se o-rrjcras 'OSixrei^s Se/ca TvavTa rdXavTo) ; or even with the specification of a definite number of talents of gold — ten talents, two talents, &c. (Odyss, iv. 526, and other passages cited in Damm's Lexicon), The word rdXavTov originally means a scale, as is well known, and is often so used by Homer, , In the Iliad and Odyssey, as well as in the Hesiodic Works and COINS, AND MEASUEES. 143 of weights in Greece seems of a date later than the Odyssey ; and the word mna, or mina, which forms the central point of the scale, has no root in the Greek language. It is of Chaldaic origin, and has also been discovered by Cham- poUion among the ancient hieroglyphic writing of Egypt (Metrol, iv. 2. p. 39). The etymology of this word points to the quarter from whence the Greeks received their scale of weight: and it will be found that there is suflScient analogy between the scales adopted in Greece, Judaea, Phe- nicia, and Egypt, to warrant a belief that all of them were derived from one common origin — the Chaldaic priesthood at Babylon. We are told by Herodotus, that the Greeks adopted from the Babylonians the sun-dial, the gnomon, and the division of the day into twelve hours: and M. Boeckh, in one of the most learned sections of the Metrologie (iv. 4), has traced the diffusion of the worship of Mylitta, or Aphrodite Urania, original in Assyria, through the inter- mediation of the Phenicians, to Greece, Asia Minor, and Sicily. In the fifth chapter of his work, M. Boeckh investigates the value of the Babylonian talent-weight as compared with the Grecian. Herodotus, in his enumeration of the tribute- money paid by the various regions subject to the kings of Days, reference occurs to the chief measures of length and of area ; opyvia, 7rYJ)(y<;, 7roi)s, (nnOafjirj, Swpov, irXidpov, yvrj ; but no precise or definite measure of capacity is noticed in them ; fiirpov and d/x,^6- c^opcijs are of unknown bulk. But the scale of dry measure is at least as old as the Hesiodic poem called The Catalogue of Women, as we may ascertain by the occurrence of the word /xeSt/^T/os, which only belongs to the language as a technical denomination of measure. See the story of Mopsus and Kalchas, Hesiod op. Strah. xiv. p. 921 ; Fragm, ed. Gaisf. xiv. M-vpLOL elacv aptOfJiov' arap fxirpov ye fxiSifJivos* The word piihiixvo^ seems to belong to the same family as fxirpov, metior, which is said to be traceable to a Sanskrit root. (Curtius, Dg Nominum Grcecorum Formatione, Linguarum Gognatarum Batione hahitd, p. 48. Berlin, 1842.) 144 REVIEW OF BOECKH ON ANCIENT WEIGHTS, Persia, states that the greater number of them \yere directed to pay in silver, a given number of Babylonian talents ; while the Indians were required to pay in gold, a certain number of Euboic talents : and he then adds that the Babylonian talent was equivalent to 70 Euboic minsB (Herod, iii. 89). The total sums however, as Herodotus states them, do not precisely coincide with the items of his estimate ; but there is a confusion either in the calculations of the historian, or in the text, which cannot be rectified by the aid of our present MSS., and we are only enabled to see that the estimate of 70 Euboic minae is lower than the real value of the Babylonian talent. Two other statements are found, of the value of the latter : Pollux gives it at 70 Attic talents, JElian at 72 Attic talents. That the number 72 is more exact than 70, is a reasonable presumption : but if we attach to Attic talents the value of the Attic money talent as established by Solon, the three statements of Herodotus, Pollux, and ^lian, will become ab- solutely irreconcileable : for the Euboic talent was a weight decidedly and considerably larger than the Solonian Attic talent. But the three statements come into complete har- mony when we interpret the Attic talents, as stated by Pollux and -3Elian, to mean " great Attic talents," as they are called by Dardanus the ancient Metrologue ; that is, Attic talents as they stood before the reduction of Solon. It is ascer- tained not merely by the evidence of Dardanus, but by the still more incontrovertible testimony of a published Athenian inscription, that the '' great Athenian talent and mina " con- tinued in exclusive use at Athens, as weights, for several cen- turies after Solon — that the debasement introduced by that legislator applied only to the coins, drachmae, obols and their multiples, together with the mina and talent considered as pecuniary denominations apart from actual weight. The Attic mina and talent underwent, by the enactment of Solon, a change similar to that of the English pound during suc- cessive centuries. Our pound originally contained a full pound weight of standard silver, and its signification both as ' COINS, AND MEASURES. ' 145 money and as weight was identical; but in process of time the standard was lowered, and its pecuniary meaning was greatly changed, while its meaning as weight remained un- altered. We know by the evidence of the inscription above alluded to, that the mina as weight — the commercial mina, as it was formally denominated — was required to weigli 138 Solonian standard drachmae : and it will be shewn pre- sently that its exact weight had originally been 138f of such drachmae. Construed in this verv rational and admissible sense, the three accounts of Herodotus, Pollux, and -3Elian, respecting the value of the Babylonian talent will be found concurrent. It is divided according to the common scale, viz. 60 minae, and 6000 drachmae of its own : and it is equivalent to 72 Euboic minse each weighing 138| Solonian standard drachmae. In other words, it is equivalent to 10,000 of these Solonian drachmae ; the precise value of the ^^ginaean talent, ac- cording to the express announcement of Pollux, being in the ■proportion of 5 : 3 to the Solonian standard. Calculating by this proportion, the standard weight of a Babylonian or ^ginaean drachma (the 6000th part of a Babylonian or ^ginaean talent) ought to be 112.295 English grains Troy. We are hardly entitled to expect any remaining actual coins to be of full standard weight, since almost every state in antiquity coined below its own standard, even when the standard continued legally unchanged ; and we must allow besides for loss arising from wear and tear. But it is re- markable that the Persian silver darics, now in the British Museum, adjusted as they doubtless were to the Babylonian scale by which the silver tribute was measured, do exhibit a weight of 224 English grains troy, or a little above — nearly the exact weight which they ought to have as Babylonian or ^ginaean didrachms. In the sixth chapter of his work, M. Boeckh enters into an elaborate examination of the Hebraic, Phenician, and Syrian system of weight and money : and he establishes on probable grounds, that the scale followed in these countries L 14:6 REVIEW OF BOECKH ON ANCIENT WEIGHTS, even from very early times, agreed with and was borrowed from the Babylonian.. The Hebraic talent had 60 minae, and 3000 holy shekels or didrachms : of the latter, the best and heaviest specimens now remaining approach so very near to the normal weight of the Babylonian or ^ginaean didrachma, that we may confidently reckon them as having been originally the same (c. vi. § 3). It appears however, that the subordinate divisions of the Hebraic scale were not coincident with those of the ^giuaean, which portioned the drachma into 6 obols : the Hebraic holv shekel or didrachm was divided into 20 gera, and the common shekel or drachma (the half of the holy shekel) into 10 gera : thus rendering a gera the equivalent of an Attic obolus (vi. 3 and vi. 5). M. Boeckh gives, in c. vi. § 7, the weight of a number of different coins, some of various Syrian kings, others of the Phenician cities. The heaviest and least worn amon2:st them come so near to the normal wei^'ht of the ^srinaean didrachm as to authorise the conclusion that they were intended to conform to it : and there are several conformable coins, belonging to the Sicilian city of Panormus, which raise an inference that the same standard of weight and money had passed from Tyre to its colony Carthage. That both the Euboic talent with its subdivisions, and the Babylonian talent with its subdivisions, were in use through- out the Persian empire, is proved by the fact that the tributes to government were required to be paid in them. I may remark however, that it is very doubtful whether the Persian tribute was paid in coined money. Herodotus tells us, that it was the practice of the great king's officers to melt the silver and gold which they received in payment of tribute, and to pour it into large earthenware jars : as soon as the metal cooled, the jars were broken : portions were then detached from the mass when there was occasion to make disbursements. * We know farther from the same his- * Herod, iii. 96. Tovtov t6v (f>6pov Brjcravpit^^i 6 fSacnXevs rpoiria TOtwSc. 'Es TTiOovs K£pafjiLVovs TT^fas KaTcy^cet' TrXTycras dk to dyyo<;, Trepiaipiu tov Kepajxov cTrcav Se SerjOy ^pr)fxdT(Jiv^ /cara/coTrret toctovto ocTov a^ iKaarOTe hajrai. i COINS, AND MEASURES. 147 torian, that the gold and silver in the treasury of Kroesus was principally, if not entirely uncoined.* There could be no advantage in receiving coin when it was destined to be melted : moreover, the coins, which the great king might receive at one extremity of his large empire^ would be un- suitable for payments at the other extremity, or even at the centre. The object of the requisition was a given weight of fine metal; weighed according ta the Euboic, or smaller talent, for the gold ; according to the Babylonian, or larger talent, for the silver. I shall have occasion to revert to this point, which I do not find noticed by M. Boeckh, when I come to speak of the conventions between Antiochus and the Romans. Both the Babylonian and the Euboic scale of weight passed from Asia, probably through the medium of Phenicians, into Greece : the former being adopted principally in Pelopon- nesus and the Dorian states, in Boeotia, Pholxis, Thessaly, Makedonia, and Krete. M. Boeckh adds Achaia to the list : but the passage of Hesychius, on which he relies, is obscure and unsatisfactory .t The conventions between Athens, Argos, Elis, and Mantineia, in the Peloponnesian war, respecting the pay of troops, were stipulated in iEginsean drachmae and trioboli ; and the reckoning of the assembled Amphik- tyonic council was carried on in ^ginaean staters or di- drachms.J There may possibly have been other scales in some Grecian cities not coinciding either with the ^ginaean, the Euboic, or the Attic : but we have no distinct infor- mation concerning any such. The coins now remaining, of those Grecian states which followed the ^ginaean standard, * Herod, vi. 125. •j* Hesych. Trax^ty SpaxfJf^rj- to SiSpaxj^ov 'A^atot. When the Achaean confederacy first established itself extensively in Peloponnesus, the cities composing it were bound by a special resolution to use the same weights and measures and coins. Polyb. ii. 37. f Thukyd. v. 47 ; also Xenoph. Eellen, v. 2, 21. Boeckh, Corp. Inscrip. Grcecarum, No. 1688. L 2 148 REVIEW OF BOECKH ON ANCIENT WEIGHTS, do not exhibit a full proportion of 5 : 3 between the iEginaean and the Attic drachma ; their actual weight falls decidedly below it. On the ground of this inferior weight, Mr. Hussey, in his instructive Treatise on the Ancient Weights and Measures, disputes the correctness of Pollux, in giving the proportion of 5 : 3, a statement hitherto universally admitted, and which M. Boeckh successfully vindicates. That states which pro- fessed to follow the jiEginsean scale, should nevertheless coin a degraded money, is by no means astonishing, nor does the fact furnish any reason for questioning the proportions an- nounced to us as normally belonging to the scale. Of the various Grreek states which professed to follow the same standard, some coined better money, others worse, according to circumstances : the general tendency amongst them, as it has been in modern no less than in ancient times, was to lower continuallv the value of their coins, and never ao:ain to raise it. The Athenian mint maintained the integrity of its coinage, from Solon downward, longer than the rest ; but we may perfectly well admit — as it is stated by K. 0. MuUer, no less than by Mr. Hussey, that the ^ginaean didrachm, as it was actually coined in Peloponnesus during the Pelopon- nesian war, had become so lowered as only to be worth 1^ Attic didrachm — without discarding the belief, that the JEginaean scale, as first introduced and applied, placed these two coins in the ratio of 5 : 3. M. Boeckh produces positive evidence that such w^as actually the fact, from the still remaining coins of Melos and Byzantium ; both of them Dorian settlements, and oue a colony of Spaita. Very an- cient coins are found of both these cities, exhibiting the full weight of the jSEginaean standard, with a deduction alto- gether insignificant ; and there is every reason to conclude that these states must have derived their scale of. coinage from their mother cities in Greece Proper, maintaining it faithfully in practice even after the latter had silently re- ceded from it. The coins of the Makedonian kings, anterior to Alexander the Great — those of the Bisaltse and those of the Chalkideans in Thrake — exhibit in like manner very COINS, AND MEASUEES. 149 nearly the full ^ginsean standard weight. Either these are to be taken as examples of the genuine, undegraded ^ginaean standard, and as authenticating the proportion which Pollux gives us, of 5 : 3 between that standard and the Solonian Attic: or else they must be taken as instances of some other monetary scale heavier than the ^ginsean ; w^hich is unsupported by any evidence, and contrary to all pro- babilitv. Respecting the Euboic talent, the opinion which M. Boeckh now maintains, that it is identical with the ante- Solonian Attic talent, is supported by the approximative weight of many actual coins, as well as by strong indirect evidence ; the adoption of it introducing a high degree of symmetry into the systems of Grecian coinage. In his FuUic Economy of Athens, our author had treated the Euboic talent as closely approximating to the Attic talent introduced by Solon, but he has since seen reason to alter his judgment. We know the value of the Solonian Attic talent, as well as the extent of depreciation which Solon introduced : we know^, therefore, that the talent, as it stood before his de- preciation, was considerably less than the ^ginsean talent. Apart from the Solonian Attic, the -zEginsean and the Euboic are the only scales of which w^e find any mention throughout Greece Proper, in the earlier periods of Grecian history : the scale prevalent at Athens w^as not the ^ginsean ; and there is presumption, both negative and positive, that the Euboic, which derived its name from the Ionic cities of Euboea, and which we know to have lasted for many centuries after- wards in the Ionic city of Priene* in Asia Minor, was also adopted in tlie metropolis of the Ionic race, just as the chief seat of the iEginsean scale was among the cities of Dorian race. * Boeckh, Corp, Inscript. Groecar, No. 2906. Dioskurides pro- mises, to each of the persons going through their training in the gymnasium, an Euboic mina of beef : j^o^iov Kpeuys fjuvav Ev/SolktJv. I do not perceive that M. Boeckh has referred to this in his Metrologie, 150 EEYIEW OF BOECKH OX ANCIENT WEIGHTS, Admitting the Euboic talent to have been that which ex- isted at Athens down to the legislation of Solon, it stood to the ^ginsean talent in the ratio of 5 : 6, and to the Solonian talent in the ratio of 25 : 18 : the drachma belonging to it being of the Aveight of 93.5 English grains. And this weight is, to a considerable degree, borne out by the re- maining coins of various cities in Euboea, as well as by those of the Chalkidic cities of Ehegium in Italy, and Naxos in Sicily {Metrol yiii. 3, 4). In the ninth chapter of the Metrologie, M. Boeckh inves- tigates the proceeding of Solon in respect to the Athenian moneys, and establishes upon grounds, very sufficient and satisfactory, the extent of depreciation which he introduced. He supposes, with much probability, that the precise point to which Solon carried his depreciation was determined by the definite and simple ratio which he desired to establish with the ^ginaean talent. At that early time, in all pro- bability, the latter was really adhered to in practice by the PelojDonnesian and other states around, which it ceased to be afterwards. The ratio of the ^ginsean to the Euboic or ante-Solonian talent was as 6 : 5 ; to the Attic talent established by Solon, as 5 : 3. The ratio of the Euboic to the Attic talent was as 25 : 18. The Attic monetary standard as established by Solon was the lowest then known in Greece, but it was at the same time faithfully adhered to by the Athenian mint, to a degree at that time very unusual. Partly from the general tendency to substitute a low standard in place of a high one, partly from the ascendency subsequently acquired by Athens, the Attic standard became extensively diffused throughout Greece as well as Sicily and Asia Minor. M. Boeckh seems to be of opinion, that the Solonian Attic talent was originally co-existent in Asia along with the ^^ginsean and Euboic talent : but for this there seems little evidence. Eespecting the Egyptian scale of weight and money, of which M. Boeckh treats in his tenth chapter, there is no COINS, AND MEASUEES. 151 information anterior to the time of the Ptolemies ; no coins have been found of an earlier date, nor does it appear that any earlier Egyptian coins were ever struck. The coins of the Ptolemies now remaining conform very nearly to the ^ginaean or Babylonian scale of weight : they are prin- cipally tetradrachms and didrachms adapted to the weight of the jEginsean talent : and the reason why they were so was, in all probability, that the first Ptolemy adopted that scale of weight which he found already current in Egypt. For the tendency throughout Greece during the preceding century had been to discontinue the ^ginaean scale in coinage, and to adopt the Attic ; and Alexander the Great had recently introduced this change into the Matedonian coinage. There is therefore a strong presumption that the scale of weight current in Egypt in the earlier times was the Babylonian or ^ginaean. Gradually this standard became degraded in practice and abandoned, in Egypt as well as elsewhere : the name drachma at the time when that country passed from its native kings to the formal dominion of the Komans, was given to a coin equivalent only to the Roman denarius and the Attic drachma of the same period : but the time and manner in which this change was brought about, cannot be clearly made out. Such is the extensive and interesting analogy which M. Boeckh has established between the units and scale of weight, and the monetary scales founded upon them, throughout the various portions of the Hellenic and Oriental world : and such is the relation, which he has been the first to set forth clearly, between the three principal monetary scales prevalent in Greece — the ^ginsean, the Euboic, and the Attic. Of the copious collection of particular facts, and the luminous reasonings by which his conclusions are sustained, I cannot, in the present short paper, pretend to give any adequate idea. I now pass to other points on which he has not been equally successful. He lays it down (Metrol, ix. 2. p. 122) as a ratio both certain and precise, that the Eoman pound was f of the 152 REVIEW OF BOECKH ON ANCIENT WEIGHTS, Attic mina of 100 Solonian standard drachmae : and this ratio he cites frequently in the course of his work, appealing to it as a means of establishing numerous ulterior con- clusions. But the proof upon which it rests is neither adequate nor convincing. First, he refers to the stipulation in the treaty between the Eomans and the Asiatic king, Antiochus. During the first negociations carried on by the Eomans with that defeated prince, they required that he should pay them 15,000 Euboic talents, by stated instal- ments (Polyb. xxi. 14) : but in the second negociations, or linal and amended treaty, the conditions stood as follows — ^Apyvplov Se Sorco A.vtlo^o^ ^Attlkov Vcofxaioi^ apicrrov ToXavra 12,000, ev ereau 12, hihov^ Ka6^ eKaarov eVo? 'X^iKia* /jL7] eXarrov Se eX/cerco to rakavrov Xcrpcbv 'Pco/jial/ccop 80. (Polyb. xxii. 2(5). Antiochus engages to pay to the Eomans 12,000 talents of the finest Attic silver, each talent to weigh not less than 80 Eonian pounds. Because Attic silver is here specified, M. Boeckh contends that no other can be meant than Attic talents : but this is an unfounded infer- ence, as we may see by examining the treaty concluded a short time before, between the Eomans and iEtolians, wherein the latter thus covenant— Aorwcraz^ Se AlrcoXol apyvplov 1X7] 'y^€Lpovo<; ^Attlkov, irapa^prjfjia fiev rakavra FiV^oLKa 200 TM arpaTTjya) too ev rfj 'EXXaSr dvrl rplrou jjbepov^ Tov apyvplov ')(^pvaLov, eav ^ovXcovrai, StSoz/T€9, tmv BeKa /jLvcov apyvplov, j(^pualov /xvav SldovT€<;. (Polyb. xxii. 15). Here we find an engagement to pay 200 Euboic talents of fau' Attic silver : thus evincing that the mention of '' the lest Attic silver," in the treaty with Antiochus, neither implies any reference to Attic talents, nor sustains the inference which M. Boeckh builds upon it, viz., the normal ratio 60 : 80 between the Eoman pound and the Solonian Attic talent.* * Livy, in reciting the treaty between the Eomans and Antiochus, gives the sum— " Argenti probi 12,000 Attica talenta— talentum ne minus pondo octoginta Romanis ponderibus pendat " (xxxviii. 38). COINS, AND MEASUKES. 153 To me there appears something anomalous in defining a recognised Grecian metallic standard by a given weight in Roman pounds : and, accordingly, we find in the other treaties that vvhen the Euboic standard is specified, no mention is made of Roman pounds, nor of any foreign weight. The fact, that in this final treaty with Antiochus, all specification of a Grecian standard is omitted, and a standard composed of Roman pounds substituted in its place, seems to me to indicate that the talent, so defined, was a mere denomination of weight, chosen for the occasion - — ^not identified with any known Grecian system, though approximating to the Attic talent. It is to be remembered, that what the Romans wanted, was, not Grecian coins, but Grecian silver of a given weight and fineness : this is shown by the stress laid upon the quality of the silver — "fair Attic silver " — " the hest Attic silver T When, in their first nego- ciations, they required Antiochus to pay 15,000 Euboic talents, or, when they demanded from Carthage 10,000 Euboic talents (Polyb. xy. 7), they could not have meant to insist upon receiving that enormous sum in didrachms and tetradrachms of the Euboic scale : such coins, if brought to Rome, must be melted and re- coined before they could be made available. The essential object with them, was to define the weight of silver to be paid to them, and a definition by Roman pounds would be most easily acted upon by Roman commissioners. The word talent was re- ceived in many different senses, in Sicily, Italy, and Greece : a special meaning was put upon it for this particular oc- casion : just as, in any payment required to be made from But this, I conceive, is not to be attended to, when we have before us the far higher authority as well as the much more specific state- ment of Polybius. When Livy recites the former treaty with the u^tolians, he describes the sum to be paid simply as Euhoica talenta, without any regard to the additional words of Polybius, apyvpiov /jltj Xctpovos 'Arrt/cov ; which words, nevertheless, are essential to the comprehension of the mode and form in which the payment was to be made (xxxviii, 9). 154 EEVIEW OF BOECKH ON ANCIENT WEIGHTS, England to America, an arbitrary rate of exchange, not widely removed from the ordinary rate, might be determined beforehand between the pound sterling and the dollar. The only other testimony adduced by M. Boeckh, of the alleged exact ratio of the Eoman pound and the Attic Solonian mina (3 : 4), is contained in a sentence of the Metrologiis of the Benedictine Andlekta; in the interpreta- tion of which he assumes as certain, what is at best doubtful, that ^ArTLKa^; Spa^/xa?, in the language of so very late a writer, means standard Solonian drachmae. But even if we grant this assumption, the evidentiary force of the passage will still remain very disputable. For there are several statements in the other metrological writers (see Galen, Dioskorides and Kleopatra, as printed in Stephens's Thesaurus, besides Priscian cle Ponderihus, v. 33), distinctly contra- dicting it, and announcing other proportions; and M. Boeckh has shewn no reason wliy they should all be set aside, and the authority of the Benedictine Analehta ex- clusively trusted. It is true that there is much contradiction and discrepancy in their various statements of the ratio between mina, drachma, libra, and uncia (Metrol. p. 116- 120) ; but the reasonable inference, even from this irrecon- cileable confusion, is, that the two scales of weight were in the beginning radically distinct, having no point of actual contact, and no exact or normal ratio between them. If, as M. Boeckh supposes, there had been a normal and original correspondence between the two scales, in the proportion of 60 minae, or 1 Solonian talent to 80 Eoman pounds, would not this fact have been intimated by Pliny or by Celsus ? Both of these authors treat the Attic drachma as the equi- valent of the denarius, 84 to the Eoman pound : they con- sider the Attic mina as 100 : 84, in reference to the Eoman pound. Now this was nothing more than an approximative ratio first derived from the comparison of the degraded coinage of both states ; and if M. Boeckh's supposition be correct, it must have superseded the ancient, precise normal ratio of 100 : 75, which must have been as well known as COINS, AND MEASUKES. 155 the ratio of the Attic x^^^ ^^^ fierpTJTTj^; to the Roman congius and amphora. The silence of Pliny and Celsus is to me a strong reason for believing that no such exact propor- tion between the Attic mina and the Roman pound originally existed. And this contradictory evidence, positive as well as negative, of which M. Boeckh takes little notice, appears to me to outweigh the unsupported testimony of the Bene- dictine Metrologiis. Wurm in his treatise {Be Ponderum, Nummorum, &g. Rationibus ap, Bomanos et Qrsecos : Stuttgard, 1821) adopts the same view as M. Boeckh in regard to the treaty between the Romans and Antiochus: he considers it certain that exact xlttic talents and nothing else, must be meant : and he says, " Sequitur in his presse Livius Polybium : " which is not correct, since in the very cardinal point of the ques- tion, in the specification of '^ Attica talenta," JLivy departs from Polybius. Wurm also agrees with M. Boeckh in setting aside the dissentient testimonies of the later metrological writers. But the general scope of Wurm's book is not the same with that of M. Boeckh : the former professes only to exhibit the actual relative weight, as nearly as it can be found, of Attic talents, and Roman pounds : and for this pur- pose we have evidence enough in the coins, without any appeal to the treaty above mentioned. The number of Attic coins still remaining is quite sufficient to enable us to determine approximatively, with sufficient accuracy for practical pur- poses, the standard weight of the Solonian drachma: the result of very numerous particular trials brings it to 67.37 grains Troy, according to M. Boeckh : to 66.6, according to Mr. Hussey. One Attic talent, or 6000 of these drachmae, is nearly equal in weight to 80 Roman pounds : and there- fore the ratio of 3 : 4 between the Roman pound and the Attic mina, if stated simply as a tolerably near approach to the truth, is one which I am by no means disposed to question. But this is not sufficient for M. Boeckh's argument, which requires a rigid distinction between precise ratios and ap- 156 KEYIEW OF BOECKH ON ANCIENT WEIGHTS, proximative ratios. For the latter, as he himself justly lays it doAvn, are to be regarded as merely accidental and unde- signed : while the former carry with them evidence of sys- tematic and intentional harmony between the two scales compared — of original relationship either in the way of fili- ation or in that of fraternity. M. Boeckh is thus compelled to maintain a position much more difficult than that of Wurm : he undertakes to demonstrate that the ratio of 3 : 4 between the Eoman pound and the Attic mina is mathe- matically exact, being involved in the normal schemes of the two systems ; and he dwells upon it as a capital point of original and intentional contact between. them. It is in this light that he considers it, in very many passages of his book, when he treats it as a matter proved, and appeals to it confidently as a ground for farther inferences : it is in this light that I consider it also, when I maintain that he has produced no sufficient evidence to entitle him to do so. To point out an instance of his employment of this very problematical ratio as an ascertained premise in ulterior reasoning, we need only pass to the 17th chapter, in which he proposes to establish " the deduction of the Eoman cubic foot and foot of length, from the ^ginsean weight and the Grecian cubic measure, and the intentional ratio of the Roman foot to the Grecian foot, as the cube root of 9 to the cube root of 10 ; ^^9 : ^10 " (p. 284). He first seeks to prove that ''the Grecian (or more properly speaking, the ^ginsean) pound is to the Eoman pound as 10 : 9:" next, that the Grecian cubic foot is to the Roman cubic foot in the same ratio — 10 : 9 ; and his argument proceeds as follows (p. 285) : *^ It is a matter of fact that the Eoman pound is to the half of the -^o-insean mina as 9 : 10 ; for it (viz. the Eoman pound) is to the Attic mina as 3:4; and the Attic mina is to the ^ginsean mina as 3:5, consequently the Eoman pound is to the ^ginaean mina as 9 : 20, or to the half of the ^ginsean mina as 9 : 10. But this half ^ginaean mina was a pound, as will be shewn hereafter : it is therefore COllSrS, AND MEASURES. 157 demonstrated, that the ^gineean and the Eoman pound were in the ratio of 10 : 9. It remains still to demonstrate, that the Olympic cubic foot, and the Eoman quadrantal, stood in the same relation ; but this cannot be done with equal strictness." Unable to offer a strict proof of this ratio of 10 : 9 between the Grecian cubic foot and the Eoman quad- rantal, M. Boeckh gives some general considerations in the way of indirect evidence, and he here again puts in the front rank the Drecise ratio between the Grecian and Eoman A. pound which he supposes himself to have just before demon- strated. *' We acknowledge a complete coincidence of the Grecian and Eoman pound in the ratio of 10 : 9, which implies that the latter was originally adapted to the standard of the former" (p. 286). Here we see that he is dealing not with simple approximations, leaving a certain amount of practical error, but with exact coincidences, involved in the normal schemes of the two systems, and shewing that the framers of the one have adjusted their arrangements with a view to the other. And the whole of his proof of systematic analogy between the Eoman and Grecian scales of weight, rests upon the admission of an exact ratio of 3 : 4 between the Eoman pound and the Solonian mina ; which I have already shewn to be uncertain and unattested. Another point which M. Boeckh includes as established, in the demonstration which I have cited just above, is, that the j^ginaean mina contained two iEginaean litrso or pounds. When we turn to the chapters in which he assigns his evi- dence for this, it will appear very inconclusive (xix. 1. p. 303 ; xxiv. 2. p. 343). The j^Eginaean scale of weight consisted of talents, minae, drachmae, and oboli : it had no pounds nor ounces. When the Greek colonies settled in Sicily, they found a copper currency among the Sikel population, and an independent scale of weight consisting of pounds and ounces, with which their own became blended. The result is highly perplexing, and in many points not intelligible, for want of evidence : but we know, and M. Boeckh has very clearly shewn in opposition to the opinion of Bentley and 158 REVIEW OF BOECKH ON ANCIENT WEIGHTS, others, that the Sicilian talent contained 120 litrae in money value, and therefore that one Sicilian mina contained two litrae in money value. We know also from x\ristotle that the Sicilian litra was equal in value to an ^ginaean obolus of silver, which was therefore in Sicily called a silver litra. But it is nowhere shewn that the Sicilian talent containing 120 litrae in value was of the weight of an ^ginaean talent : nor that the tveight called a litra in Sicily was -rro'tli part of the iveight called a Sicilian talent ; much less, of an ^gi- naean talent. At the time when the identitv of meanino^ between litra and obolus first took its rise, the litra con- tained a quantity of copper such as could be purchased in the market for an ^ginaean obolus : that this quantity of copper was in weight precisely the -ri-o^l^ P^^^ ^f ^^ jiEgi- naean talent weight, is certainly not very probable, and not to be admitted without some j)ositive proof. And M. Boeckh himself appears only to contend that the ratio was some- thing originally not very far from the truth (see xxiv. 2 p. 343) ; so that it is altogether impossible to rely upon it as evidence of original and intrinsic relationship between the Eoman and the ^ginaean pound, even if we consider the expression ^giiidean i^ound as admissible. I now come to the ratio which M. Boeckh alleo-es to have subsisted between the Olympic cubic foot, and the Roman cubic foot or quadrantal — as 10 : 9. Of this he has himself stated (see the passage already cited from p. 285) that he is unable to offer sufficient direct proof : and the general con- siderations into which he enters (pp. 286, 287) will not be found to compensate for the absence of such proof. Yet he introduces in other places this unproved ratio for the purpose of establishing ulterior conclusions : for example in p. 277 (xv. 2) he says : '' The Attic metretes contains 72 Roman sextarii : but the Greek cubic foot is, as will be hereafter shewn, y of the Roman quadrantal, which contains 48 sextarii : the Greek cubic foot is therefore 53-^ sextarii, and the Attic metretes f ^ of the Greek cubic foot." Here are two new conclusions, the authority of which rests entirely COINS, AND MEASURES, 159 * upon the admission of the ratio of 10 : 9 between the Greek cubic foot and the Eoman quadrantal, which M. Boeckh believes himself to have proved, but has not proved : and again these two new conclusions — the equality of the Greek cubic foot to 534- Eoman sextarii, and the ratio of the same to the Attic metretes, as 20 : 27 — appear in other parts of his volume as if they too were matters ascertained (see xiii. 7. p. 242 ; xiv. 3. p. 263 ; xvL 2. p. 282). In researches such as these of M. Boeckh, unless the fundamental posi- tions are placed beyond all doubt, the subsequent deductions become illusory, and are but too well calculated to illustrate the impressive warning, which he has himself delivered in his preface, against fine-spun metrological hypotheses. The well-known correspondence between the Attic mea- sures of capacity, both liquid and dry, and the Eoman measures of capacity — both as to positive quantities and scale of division — is a fact very striking and remarkable. Now the Eoman measures of capacity exhibit an exact pro- portion with the Eoman weights : an amphora or quadrantal weighing precisely 80 Eoman pounds, and a congius (the parallel both in quantity and denomination of the Attic %ou9) weighing precisely 10 pounds. This correspondence, a fact certain but hitherto unexplained, M. Boeckh wishes to trace to a supposed original correspondence of the scale of weio-ht, transmitted from Babvlon first to Greece and then to Eome : the cubical unit being in all the three cases (he asserts) determined by a given weight of rain-water (see pp. 286, 287). I have already said that his deduction of the j^ginaean scale of weight from the Babylonian appears to me sufficiently sustained, and the light which he has thereby thrown upon the statical systems, both of Greece and the East, is new and valuable. But in extending the same deduction to Eome — in tracing the acknowledged cor- respondence of Eoman and Attic cubical measures to a pri- mitive correspondence of Eoman and Attic weights, — he has, in my judgment, altogether failed. I am the more anxious to point this out, because his copious erudition may perhaps 160 REVIEW OF BOECKH ON ANCIENT WEIGHTS, enable him either to strengtlien his proof, or to discover some better mode of explanation : and I am very siKe that there is no man in Europe more capable of solvinn^ a problem at once so difficult and so interesting to philological enquirers. I pass over M. Boeckh's remarks on the relation of the Gnrecian and Eoman foot of length: his eleventh chapter contains ample particulars as to the actual length both of one and the other, but his attempt to connect them in theory, as if the Eoman foot had been originally adapted to the Grecian in the ratio of 2-i : 25, is an hypothesis resting upon unsupported analogies (compare xi. 8. p. 199 ; and xvii. 2, 3, 4. pp. 288-292). I come to the positions which he lays down, respecting the relation of Grecian weights and measures one with another : wherein I discover much which appears to me erroneous and illusory. It has been alreadv mentioned that there exists in the Eoman system, a precise, determinate connection between the weights and the cubic measures : the amphora or quad- rantal weighing by legal standard 80 pounds ; and the congius ( = Attic x^^^) ^^'^ighing 10 pounds. ISTow^ M. Boeckli thinks tliat he can establish the like precise and determinate connection between the Grecian weights and Grecian cubic measures. The Eoman amphora contains 48 sextarii, the Attic metretes 72 sextarii : the former weio-hs 80 Eoman pounds, therefore the latter weighs 120 Eoman pounds : but the Eomcm pound is | of the Attic mina : therefore the Attic metretes weighs 90 Attic minae or 1-J- Attic talent : or in other words, the Solonian talent is equal to a weight of water § of the Attic metretes (xv. 2. p. 278). Such is ]M. Boeckh's proof of the exact and determinate connection between the Grecian weights and Grecian cubic measures. And here again we see that the w^hole cogency of the proof depends upon the admission, that the Eoman pound is f of the Solonian mina : and that the ratio between them is rigorous, numerical, aud essentially belonging to the two systems ; not simply approximative. In such pre- COINS, AND MEASURES. 161 liminary admissions no inquirer can acquiesce, as I have already endeavoured to shew, until ampler evidence is pro- duced than that which is contained in the Metrologie. Nor is this the only defective point in the book respecting the Grecian cubic measures. It is a recognised fact, that in the Solonian Attic scale the monetary talent, mina, and drachma, are each f of the respective denominations in the -ZEginsean scale : M. Boeckh has attempted to shew that the same ratio prevails between the cubic measures of the two scales ; that the Solonian Attic metretes and medimnus are each 4 of the j$]ginaean. The evidence in support of this position is really so feeble that I cannot explain to myself how it should have appeared to him satisfactory. First (Metrol, XV. 1. p. 275), he cites a passage from Lucian, which proves only, at the very most, that the ^ginsean medimnus was larger than other measures of the same denomina- tion; if indeed it proves anything to the point, of which reasonable doubt may be entertained (Lucian, Timon, c. 57). Next, he quotes a passage out of the Etymologihon Magnum, V, Alyivaca, 'EXeyero Se ra /JueyaXa, Alytvata, dirb rov vo /Ji [a /iiaTO<;' koI yap to Klyivalov raXavJOV TrXelov rjSvparo Tov 'Attlkov; sl citation which not only does not assist M. Boeckh's conclusion, but operates powerfully to contradict it ; and so sensible is he of this, that he permits himself to discredit his own witness, by annexing as a criticism of his own — " Since the jEginaean money was more notorious than the jiEginaean measures, the incorrect limitation is added, airo TOV vo/jLi(T/jiaTo<;, &c." Accepting the statement of the witness, I must reject M. Boeckh's unfounded semi-negation of it. Thirdly, he produces in juxtaposition two distinct testimonies with regard to the contributions to the public meals at Sparta. Plutarch says, that every partaker of these public meals contributed monthly a medimnus of barley-meal, eight choes of wine, five minae of cheese, and two and a half minee of figs (Plutarch. Lykurg. 12). But Diksearchus (aj;. Athen, iv. p. 141) states that each person contributed to these same meals near upon one Attic me- M 162 EEVIEW OF BOECKH ON ANCIENT WEIGHTS, dimnus and a half, and some eleven or twelve choes of wine, besides a certain weight of cheese and figs : moreover, for the purchase of condiment, about ten ^ginaean oboli (aXcf^LToov fiev o)^ rpla fjuaXLcrra rj/jLL/jieSL/jiva ^Attlkol, oIlvov Se %oa9 evZeKCL nva fj ScoSeKa, &c.). Now, before we can combine these two passages, to draw any inference from them as to the relative value of ^ginaean and Attic measures, we must adopt several assumptions, each of which is liable to more or less of doubt. First, we must assume that Plutarch and Diksearchus both speak of the same period, and had in their minds the same actual quantities of meal and wine. Secondly, that Plutarch meant an Mginaean medimnus, and ^giuBean choes ; for he says no such thing. Thirdly, that Diksearchus speaks of a monthly contribution, and not of any different period : for he specifies no time, whereas, Plutarch specifies a month. And fourthly, that Dikaearchus had heard of and intended to designate some known and definite quantity ; for his words, in their obvious meaning, imply that he did not himself accurately know, or that no precise weight was even fixed by law. And when we have taken all these matters for granted, what is the inference wdiich the two passages combined present ? Some- thing quite foreign to M. Boeckh's purpose ; I will state it in his own words : — '' Dikaearchus therefore (he says Theo- phrastus, by an oversight) estimated the Lakonian measure as something less than IJ of the Attic. This doubtless coincides in some measure with that value of the jiEginsean talent which Hussey had elicited from the coins, something above 1^ of the Attic : but that was merely a value of coins which no longer corresponded with their original standard ; and I have sufficiently proved that the ^Eginsean talent, as weight, stood to the Attic in the ratio of 5 : 3. Even without any closer historical testimony, there is an internal pro- hdbility that the j^Eginsean and the Solonian Attic measures stood to each other in the same ratio as the two scales of weights, namely, as 5:3; possibly the Spartan measure, even if it conformed to that proportion, might be viewed COINS, AND MEASURES. 163 roundly as about half as much again as the Attic, and by mistake it might then he treated as something less than half as much again, instead of something more than half as much again." — This is all the positive evidence produced. Surely, so distinguished a critic as M. Boeckh cannot think that the definite ratio of 5 : 3, between ^ginsean and Attic measures, can be admitted upon evidence such as this ; passages not only amplified by so many gratuitous postulates, but even distorted from their true and plain meaning. The misfortune is, that he goes on to treat the ratio here spoken of as a matter perfectly ascertained, and to deduce ulterior consequences from it. i But M. Boeckh farther contends, that independent of positive testimony, there is '' an internal jprobdbility that the ^ginsean cubic measures stood to the Solonian Attic in the same ratio as the two scales of weight, namely, as 5 : 3." Admitting for a moment this very questionable position — that identity of ratio between the measures and weights of the two systems is a fact to be presumed, and not to be proved — it amounts to a decisive negation of the ratio of 5 : 3, for which M. Boeckh is contending. When he says that *'he has sufficiently proved the -^gineean talent as weight to have been in the ratio of 5 : 3 to the Attic/' he cannot have had present to his memory the earlier parts of his own book : for he has distinctly shewn the reverse. He has shewn, and the inscription to which he appeals places the fact beyond a doubt, that Solon, while he altered the value of the talent as money, so as to establish a ratio of 3 : 5 with the ^ginsean talent, left the talent as weight un- changed ; or, to use the words of our author himself, p. 115 (ix. 1), "the ante-Solonian mina had disappeared in the money-weight, but still continued in use as commercial weight " (down to the period at least to which the inscrip- tion refers). A mina of money, or 100 drachmae of silver, came by the depreciation of Solon to weigh ^ of an j^ginsean mina : but a mina weight of tin, iron, or any other com- modity, remained as it was before, not f of an ^ginaean m2 164 REVIEW OF BOECKH ON ANCIENT WEIGHTS, raina, but -^ of it. Conseqnentlv, the appeal which M. Boeckh makes to the original ratio of tlie ^ginaean and Attic weights, distinctly contradicts his position — that the Attic cubic measures were in the ratio of 3 : 5 to the ^ginaean. In order to maintain the doctrine here alluded to, M. Boeckh is driven to the inadmissible hypothesis that Solon, when he created the ratio of 3 : 5 between the Attic money- talent and the ^o:inaean talent, altered at the same time the Attic metretes and medimnus, so as to introduce the same ratio to the corresponding ^ginaean denominations. "When Solon," (he says) " diminished the Attic money-weight to f of the ^ginaean, he at the same time enlarged the measures, as we are told by Plutarch on the authority of Androtion. This enlargement once appeared to me a doubt- ful point : but if the Attic measure had been before purely accidental and local, wWiout any correspondence with the weight, it may, doubtless, have been smaller than the new Solonian measure : at anv rate, we learn from this statement that Solon established a new metrical scale." (ix. 2. p. 276). Here M. Boeckh overthrows the fundamental assumption on which his previous argument had rested. He had before told us that we might safely presume the Attic and ^ginaean measures to be in the same ratio as the respective weights : now he intimates, that the primitive Attic measures may have been '' purely local and accidental, without any corre- spondence with the weights." The argument derived from internal probability, on which he before dwelt, is here for- mally discarded ; and we are left, not only without any positive testimony, but without any rational ground for presuming a ijviori, that the Attic medimnus and metretes were to the ^ginaean in the ratio of 3 : 5. I believe that the statement of Androtion, as quoted by Plutarch (Solon, c. 15), has no reference to the medimnus | and metretes, and that we cannot even deduce from it the va2:ue inference last intimated bv M. Boeckh — ^viz., that Solon made some new arransrement of the measures. The j COINS, AND MEASURES. 165 words of Plutarch are — kol ttjv afxa tovtg) yevo/jbh-qv rcov T€ fjuerpcov eirav^rjaLv koX tov vo filer /juaro^; e? tl/jLt^v; (so it stands in Eeiske's edition: Coray leaves out e?). ''E/caroz; yap iTTOLTjcre hpayjioiv ttjv fivdv, irporepov €^BofJi7]KovTa rptcov ovaav. Now I think that the words, tSov fierpcov eirav^rfcnvj apply simply to the statement which immediately follows — to the increase of the mina as a monetary meastire, from 73 drachmao to 100 ; of course too, the increase of the talent in the same proportion. I agree with the remark made by M. Boeckh, p. 114, that this is an incorrect way of describing the real monetary change introduced by Solon, inasmuch as the mina before that change, as well as after it, was divided into 100 drachmae, and not into 73 : the differ- ence consisting in the diminished size and weight of the drachmae. But still it is the mode of description adopted by Androtion : and we may fairly suppose that the words "increase of the measures,'^ refer to nothing beyond the increased number of drachmae, which every mina and every talent were now made to contain, as particularised in the succeeding sentence. Moreover, it will appear that the strongest considerations of " internal probability " — something very little short of an internal certainty, conduct us to the conclusion that Solon left the Attic measures generally undisturbed — the reverse of that which M. Boeckh lays down. For we know positively that Solon did not meddle with the weights : he created a double meaning for the words mina and talent: he intro- duced the anomaly, that the mina — which had hitherto meant a known weight of silver, iron, tin, or any other merchandise — received a special and exceptional sense when applied to silver coin. However men may, in time, become accustomed to this, the first moment of divorce between the scale of weight and that of money, must present to them a perplexing anomaly and repugnance : and there could be but one motive for Solon to permit it. All interference with customary weights and measures is well known to produce so much vexation and discontent, that even the most 166 REVIEW OF BOEOKH ON ANCIENT WEIGHTS, popular and powerful goyernmeiits experience prodigious difficulty in carrying it into effect. For the express purpose of affording relief to debtors, Solon degraded the monetary standard : but the anomaly, which his new arrangement introduced, is an evident proof of his reluctance to disturb the general system of weights. And it affords a proof, no less evident, that he would not choose such a moment for re-arranging the liquid and dry measures. For the frag- ments preserved of his poems, impressively attest his painful sense of the difficulties and dangers against which he had to contend, in the midst of angry mutiny on the part of the degraded and enslaved poor, and murmuring acquiescence on the part of the rich, in whom all political power had hitherto been vested. To add, to the many prevalent ele- ments of discontent, a new one of his own creating, would be, least of all, consistent with the cautious and com- promising spirit, which is conspicuous throughout all his enactments. These arguments, I think, will suffice to shew that the position laid down by M. Boeckh, in regard to the ratio between Attic measures and ^ginaean measures, is not only unsupported, but incorrect. We have no ground whatever for believing that the Attic metretes or medimnus was f of the ^ginsean. We do not at all know what w^as the ratio betw^een the two ; if indeed it be certain that they were not the same. . Along with this position, we are compelled to dismiss all the series of imaginary ratios comprised in the following sentences of the Metrologie (xvi. 1. p. 281). " If it be true that the Olympic cubic foot is ^ of the Eoman quadrantal (N,B. this is altogether unproved), it then contains 53} Eoman sextarii, since the quadrantal contains 48 sextarii. But the ^ginaean metretes contains 120 sextarii (N.B. this is incorrect, depending only on the supposed ratio of the Mgm^diR metretes to the Attic) : therefore its ratio to the Olympic cubic foot is as 120 : 53^ = 9 : 4 — or it is 2^ Olympic cubic feet. But the cubic foot COINS, AND MEASURES. 167 has 64 cubic palms: if then the ^ginaean metretes was divided like the Attic, as it unquestionably was, into 144 kotylse, the ^ginsean kotyle contained exactly one cubic palm, because 4 : 9 : : 64 : 144. This beautiful coincidence resulted necessarily from the fact, that the Olympic cubic foot stood to the great Babylonian cubic foot as 2:3, and that the -3]gin8ean metretes contained 1 J Babylonian cubic feet." I sincerely wish that this coincidence had been sustained by such evidence as to render its trustworthiness com- mensurate with its beauty. In the last sentence quoted from M. Boeckh, an alleged ratio is noticed between the Olympic cubic foot and. the great Babylonian cubic foot, as 2 : 3 — a subject to the in- yestigation of which he deyotes the twelfth chapter of his volume. And here again I am compelled to lament the feebleness of the positive testimony, in the midst of a series of suppositions and possibilities, all of which end only in an approximative result : whereas the author pro- fesses to detect determinate numerical ratios, and to deduce from them evidence of original correspondence and derivative adjustment between the two systems. He cites distinct passages from Hero and Didymus, which attest an exact ratio (as 5 : 6) of the Eoman foot, to the Philetserian foot employed by the kings of Pergamus in Asia Minor, as well as to the Ptolemaic foot in Egypt : and this Philetserian foot is probably the same with the royal Persian or Babylonian foot, employed under the Persian empire. But the ratio alleged of >§/2 : ^3 between the Grecian foot and the Babylonian foot rests only upon two passages; of the sufficiency of which the reader shall judge. Herodotus gives the height and thickness of the walls of Babylon in royal cubits : he then adds — 'O Se /SaatXTjtof; irriyv<^ rev /jberpiov earl 7r7^;^eo9 /jue^oov rpiat Sa/crvXiotat (i. 178). Again, the Scholiast on Lucian's Kataplus, evidently copy- ing from Herodotus, comments (c. 16) upon the expression of Lucian, oXw ttiJ^^l ^aa-LkiKWy as follows — 'O r^ap /Saac- 168 REVIEW OF BOECKH ON ANCIENT WEIGHTS, \lko<^ 7r>7%i;9 e^et virep rov IBlcotlkov koX kolvov rpel^ SaKTv\ov<;. Upon which M. Boeckh remarks, p. 214: "By the expression fiirpio^ Trfj^v^, as Ideler and others have already observed, owtliing can he meant except the well- known common cubit of the GreeJcs, of IJ Olympic feet:" and he adds that Ideler's view is in this respect confirmed by the Scholiast on Lucian (Metrol. xii. 2. p. 214). Wurm (de Fonderibus, § 56) adopts the same construction of the passage : but in spite of the concurrence of so many able expositors, I venture to contend that they all put upon Herodotus a meaning which his words do not bear. Hero- dotus contrasts the royal cubit with the moderate or ordi- nary cubit : he is speaking purely and simply of Babylonian measures ; he intimates nothing whatever respecting the identitv of the ordinary Babvlonian cubit with the Grecian cubit. M. Boeckh has shewn verv instructivelv, in the 13th and 14th chapters of the Metrologie^ that there were in Assyria, in Palestine, and in Egypt, two distinct scales of length — a royal cubit or sacred cubit, and a common cubit : the former longer by a definite quantity than the latter, and em- ployed principally for solemn or public purposes. Now it is plain, when Herodotus calls the royal cubit " longer by three finger-breadths or daktyls than the moderate ciibit^' that the direct comparison is between two distinct Babylonian measures. On what ground are we to presume an implied identity between the smaller Babylonian measure and a Grecian measiu-e of the same denomination ? I say, designedly, identity, or precise eqiiality : the point which M. Boeckh's argument requires him to make out. For if nothing more be meant than approximative equality, this is a matter which I willingly concede. It is to be recol- lected that the cubit and the foot, having a natural standard, cannot differ very much from each other in any two countries^ though they will always differ to a certain extent, unless we suppose an intentional derivation or adjustment. Any English traveller visiting France durin^• the last century, COINS, AND MEASURES. 169 and describing the length of a room or a building, would probably mention the number of feet as reported to him, without noticing the minute difference between the French foot and the English foot. But if he found that the French government, in measuring farms for the assessment of the land-tax, employed a special foot measure, called the royal foot, three inches longer than the ordinary foot of France, he would be struck with this fact, and w^ould insert in his journal — '' The royal foot is three inches longer than the ordinary foot." But he w^ould not mean thereby to assert, nor would any reader be authorised to infer, that the ordinary foot of France was equal to the ordinary foot of England. Just such is the declaration of Herodotus. All that we can legitimately deduce from it, is, that the "moderate cubit " of Babylon differed from the Grecian cubit no more than the ordinary cubit of one nation might naturally differ from the ordinary cubit of another. Nor is it indeed certain that there was one common cubit in Greece : meaning always a measure adapted to one precise standard. That the Samians had a cubit of their own, we know from Herodotus (ii. 168), who says that the Egyptian cubit was equal to the Samian. M. Boeckh admits that the Samian cubit was completely different from the common Grecian cubit (xiii. 2. p. 221) : of course therefore the Samian foot measure must have differed in the same proportion : a fact not easy to be reconciled with the state- ment of M. Boeckh in another place (xvi. 1. p. 281) " that no other Grecian foot than the Olympic foot, or the foot of the Olympic stadium, existed." What evidence is there to prove that the Olympic standard of the foot-measure was adopted by all the countless autonomous communities of Greece ? Why are we to regard Samos as the solitary case of exception? Long measures differ in this respect from cubic measures or weights — they have a natural standard : but the unit of weight or of capacity must be determined by the special dictum of law. An autonomous community, 170 REVIEW OF BOECKH ON ANCIENT WEIGHTS, on first establishing a scale of weight, being under the neces- sity of naaking some arbitrary selection, might naturally borrow the Euboic or the ^ginaean scale, prevalent amongst its neighbours : but many distinct standards of the foot- measure, all proceeding from the natural standard of the human foot, but each minutely differing from the rest, might co-exist in Greece without any serious inconvenience. We are not to presume here any precise identity, or universal adoption of one common standard, imless we can prove the fact by some positive evidence. Until the abundant erudition of M. Boeckh can supply such evidence, I must contend that he is not entitled to treat the Olympic foot as an universally adopted Grecian foot : still less is he entitled to consider Herodotus as having alluded to this Olympic foot, and the cubit founded upon it, when he said that " the Babylonian cubit was three daktyls longer than the moderate cubit." Unfortunately, these two unauthorized assumptions lie at the bottom of all the elabo- rate calculations in the Metrologie respecting the Grecian and Babylonian long measures — calculations leading after all only to an approximative result, which M. Boeckh is obliged to excuse by appealing to the inaccurate mechanical proceedings of the ancients. Such mechanical inaccuracy I freely admit ; and if sufficient positive testimony were produced, of intentional correspondence between two distinct metrical systems in the ancient world, I should not reject the testimony on the ground that details of the proceeding' had not precisely conformed to the attested designs of the framers. But here we are without positive testimony : we are called upon to infer intentional adaptation, or relation- ship between two systems, merely from harmony in the results ; and for such an inference nothing short of exact harmony — no approximative analogies — will suffice. More especially is this true with respect to the foot and the cubit : measures which always have been and always will be nearly equal, even in countries the most widely separated. The most remarkable circumstance which characterizes COINS, AND MEASUEES. 171 the long measures as well as the weights, of Greece, Asia, and Egypt, is the prevalence of the same scale of division — the cubit, the foot, the span, the palm, and the dactyl. Thoroughout all the wide extent of territory here spoken of, this same scale of division prevailed, pointedly distinguished from the imcial or duodecimal division of the foot which we find in Italy and Sicily. That so precise a conformity in the metrical scale argues one common origin, and that Greece was in this respect a borrower from the East, I see no reason to doubt. But that the actual standard of the lengths measured was identical and derivative, I cannot believe until I see it proved. M. Boeckh nevertheless permits himself to assert positively — " As the Grecian long measure has been already shewn to have existed in the earliest times in Egypt, which had a community of system with the Chalda^ans, the derivation of the Grecian measure either from the East or from Egypt no longer admits of a doubt " (xvi. 1. p. 281). I trust that the complete conviction which this sentence breathes will induce M. Boeckh to re-examine and improve the very precarious evidence on which alone it now reposes. As I have felt myself compelled to call in question many references upon which M. Boeckh seems implicitly to rely, I will notice one case in which he seems to me to impugn without reason the testimony of one of his own best autho- rities. In treating of the royal or Philetserian foot, applied in the measurements of Asia Minor under the kings of Per- gamus, he cites a passage from Hero, in which the ratio of the Philetserian foot to the Eoman foot is given as 6 : 5 — given in plain language and with precise fractions {MetroL xii. 2 ; p. 215). But M. Boeckh finds that this ratio does not exactly comport with that which he imagines himself to have discovered as the original determining ratio of the Babylonian foot to the Grecian foot, viz. ^3 ^2. Accord- ingly, he denies the rigid accuracy of the valuation given by Hero : he says — ^* Assuredly the estimate of the Philetserian foot in reference to the Koman foot as G : 5, is not precise, 172 KEYIEW OF BOECKH ON ANCIENT WEIGHTS, because it is certain that neither of them was determined with any view to the other" (p. 218). Now there is not throuo'hout the whole of M. Boeckh's metrolooical investi- gatioDS, a more direct, precise, or unimpeached testimony than tliis of Hero, which he treats as merely approximative : and that too because it does not coincide with a long tissue of calculations of his own, based upon assumptions as yet unsupported. If a statement such as this of Hero is not to be trusted, the class of researches to which the Metrologie is devoted will become utterly impracticable : for no better evidence can be procured. The last four chapters of M. Boeckh's volume are devoted to an account of the various pound weights and scales of weight throughout Italy; of the perplexing variations in the Eoman silver and copper money ; and of the monetary estimates in the census of Servius TuUius. They are chapters highly instructive : in respect to the Roman silver money, the clearest and most complete that I know. He rejects and refutes the opinion of Mebuhr, that the debasement of the Roman standard was caused or accompanied by an extra- ordinary rise in the value of copper, so that the diminished coins possessed as great a purchasing power as the full-sized coins had possessed before. Whether the value of the metal copper underwent any serious or continued reduction in refer- ence to silver, may be a matter of reasonable doubt : certain it is, that no such adventitious cause need be invoked to account for the degradation of the standard. Such a pro- ceeding has been so nearly universal with governments both ancient and modern, that the contrary may be looked upon as a remarkable exception. The limits to which this article has already extended will not permit me to furnish any detailed remarks upon M. Boeckh's account of the Itahan and Roman scales of \veight and money. I will only mention, that since the publication of the Metrologie, another work of singular importance on the same subject has appeared in Italy, by the learned fathers Marchi and Tessieri : ' L'^es grave del Museo Kirche- COINS, AND MEASURES. 173 riano, ovvero le Monete primitive de' Popoli dell' Italia Media ordinate e descritte. Eoma 1839/ The collection of the Kircherian Museum at Eome, unrivalled in the number and completeness of its specimens of the ancient Italian ses grave, and enriched by many recent discoveries, has here, for the first time, been explained and reduced to order, and connected with the inferences legitimately deducible from it. Two of these inferences I will briefly glance at, inasmuch as they bear directly upon the positions maintained in M. Boeckh's Metrologie ; in one case, in the way of confirmation, in the other, of contradiction. M. Boeckh advances two positions ; first, that the duo- decimal division of the pound prevailed all over Italy ; next, that the absolute weight called by the name of a found was not the same throughout that country — heavier in some parts, lighter in others. The second of these two positions has been placed beyond a doubt by the new facts set forth in the work of the two learned fathers. They have produced ancient cast copper- money of the Latins and Volscians, which belong to an as, or pound weighing 13 Eoman ounces, and coins of Hadria in Picenum, which indicate an as, reaching even to 16 Roman ounces. The ancient Etruscan pound, as far as we can judge by the coins published and authenticated, appears to have been the lightest in Italy. But, on the other hand, the opinion of M. Boeckh, that the duodecimal division of the pound was universal through- out Italy, has been shewn to be erroneous. Amongst the people of middle Italy, north of the Apennines, a decimal division of the pound prevailed, distinguishing them from the people south of the same chain, who employed the duode- cimal scale. Of the numerous coins belonging to the people south of the Apennines, not a single quincunx, or coin of five ounces, has yet been discovered : the complete series runs from the semis or six ounces downwards, omitting the quin- cunx — triens, quadrans, sextans, and uncia. On the other 174 REVIEW OF BOECKH ON ANCIENT WEIGHTS, ETC. hand, for the coins north of the Apennines, comprising those of seven different townships, no semis has ever been found ; the highest denomination below the as is the quincunx, below which the other coins appear just as in the duodecimal series. There is no way of explaining this veiy marked and uniform contrast, except by admitting a decimal division of the pound north of the Apennines* In Sicily, where the coalescence of the Grecian and Italian systems produced a complication almost inextricable, a silver quincunx as well as a semis appears to have prevailed : at least we find in the fragments of Epicharmus mention both of TrevrcoyKcov and rj/jLlXtrpov (Pollux, ix. 82). This double scale of weight, prevalent in different regions of Italy, is a remarkable phenomenon ; only recently verified, and as yet unexplained. * See the valuable dissertation of Dr. Lepsius, Ueher die Ver- hreitiing des Italisclien Milnzsystems von Etrurien aus, p. 74. (Leipzig, 1842.) PRESIDENTIAL ADDRESS, m COMMEMORATION OF THE TWENTY-FIRST ANNIVERSARY OF THE LONDON SCIENTIFIC INSTITUTION. {In the London Tavern, 1st June, 1846.) PRESIDENTIAL ADDRESS, IN COMMEMORATION OF THE TWENTY-FIRST ANNIVERSARY OF THE LONDON SCIENTIFIC INSTITUTION. The usual loyal toasts haying been drunk, the Chairman then said : — I now have to propose to you, gentlemen, the toast which forms the immediate subject of our present meeting. It will need no eloquence to recommend it to your cordial reception ; nevertheless, I should be doing little justice, either to my own feelings or to yours, if I did not preface the introduction of it with a few words of allusion to the past as well as to present circumstances. I propose to you the toast, " Prosperity to the City of London Literary and Scientific Institution." Twenty-one years have now elapsed, gentlemen, since this Institution was first projected and brought into existence, intended for the special use and benefit of persons engaged in professional and commercial pursuits. Twenty-one years forms a large fraction of every man's life ; a space of time in which much may be achieved, and much ought to be achieved, by individuals as well as by communities ; a space long enough to take measure of the practical benefits and eflSciency of any association, and to judge how far it may boast of good fruit in the past, or carry the promise of still better fruit for the future. I am happy in the knowledge that the twenty-one years of collective life which this Institution has enjoyed, have more than justified the largest expectations of its original projectors. I am still more happy in the conviction that, while a fair allowance is to be made for N 178 PRESIDENTIAL ADDEESS, human infirmity of temper, and while occasional mistakes in dealing with untried contingencies have been inevitable, there has been throughout the management of our Institution nothing in the nature of extravagance, or destructive party spirit, or delusive conceptions of its legitimate scope and pur- poses — much less any reproach of graver character — to sully the honourable recollections of our earliest and most difficult period. In the month of June, 1825, at the time when our first meeting for the establishment of the Institution took place, I believe that no Institution of this precise character, and in- tended for the same description of persons, yet existed in the United Kino'dom. AYe had, indeed, before us the encourao-ins: example of the Mechanics' Institution, then recently brought into working, and producing, as now, admirable results ; and Dr. Birkbeck, the founder of that Institution, to whose inde- fatigable and creative genius the cause of popular instruction owes more than to any man that ever lived, was still in the full vio'our of his career, to show how much could be done by sino'le-hearted enero-y and talent in brino-ius: toaether isolated individuals for the common purpose of improvement. But there existed no analogous scheme for the large and important class by whom our city is chiefly occupied ; and it was to fill up in part this gap that the present Institution was projected. I know, indeed, and I rejoice to know, that there are now several Institutions analogous to our own ; some in other parts of London — some in the other great towns of this country. I am sure that every gentleman who hears me will wish them success and prosperity. I pretend not to raise invidious comparisons between those societies and our own ; I hope, in all good and useful results, they will fully rival us, and that they will leave to us nothing but that w^hich is indisputably our due — the honour of historical precedence — the honour of having been the first to originate a Literary Institution for commercial and professional persons. To an audience like you, gentlemen — and I would fain hope, 1 LONDON SCIENTIFIC INSTITUTION. 179 to any intelligent audience of the present day — arguments to demonstrate the value of institutions such as ours would be trite and superfluous. But such was not the case when this Institution first began. In 1825 the idea was novel, and the scheme untried ; it required a degree of openness and libera- lity of mind, then by no means common, to appreciate its usefulness ; it required a certain degree of penetration, and, I will add, a certain measure of that valuable attribute called a hopeful temperament, to believe that, if useful, it was also practicable. There were many who doubted whether, when the banner of instruction and improvement was unfurled, there would be found any considerable body of volunteers from the commercial and professional classes to flock to it : there were still more who doubted whether those volunteers who came would stay to uphold it, would accept a systematic organization, or would furnish out of their own number a body of managers willing and able to undertake laborious functions of detail. A new member, who now for the first time visits our prennses in Aldersgate Street, sees at once that his subscription purchases for him something substantive, tangible, full of interest and convenience, to say the least of it ; but in June, 1825, all these conveniences were yet only in promise, and it might reasonably be held uncertain whether a sufficient number of members would have faith in that promise being realized, to induce them to come forward with subscriptions, at that time necessarily confided to the employment of gentlemen not personally known. To those among the friends and gentlemen around me who have present to their minds (as I have present to mine) the debates and calculations of the spring of 1825, when we were engaged in ushering this Institution into existence, it will be well known that we had a thousand uncertainties of this character to contend w^ith. They will recollect how much we owe to the high public character, and the forward and generous zeal of my late lamented friend, Mr. John Smith, the first president of our nascent Institution — a gentleman whose name cannot N 2 180 PRESIDENTIAL ADDEESS, be mentioned without esteem and honour, and who stood always among the foremost in the promotion of public in- struction. Besides Mr. John Smith, the new Institution was fortunate enouoh to find other liberal and hio'h-minded commercial men to support and encourage its early efforts : what was better than any supporters, it obtained earnest, discreet, and laborious committee-men among its own mem- bers, several of whom I am happy to see at this table, who undertook the troublesome and unrewarded task of oyer- coming all the difficulties of its first organization, and accom- plished that task with skill and success. Moreover — a point no less essential than good committee-men — the Institution was also fortunate enough to find an exemplary secretary, Mr. Stacy, whose last twenty-one years have been devoted to the service of the Institution with a diligence as unwearied as it has been well-directed, and whose remarkable talent, both for business and for conciliaticm, was of the most special necessity during the first years of difficulty with which the Institution had to struggle. Through these valuable and meritorious agencies our Institution w^as enabled to take an honourable start even from the first, to work itself gradually into efficient operation, even when it had everything to create and provide, and to realize fully that which its sponsors had promised and vowed when the name was first bestowed. I glance, briefly, gentlemen, at these topics, connected with the infancy of our Institution, not less in the way of congratulation as to the past than in that of contrast and encouragement as to the present. It was then in its season of probation; it had to win its way to confidence, and to establish a character with the commercial and pro- fessional public. It has now earned that confidence, and needs no testimonial of character, except its own past con- duct. Our course has been one of progressive increase, with interruption only rare and occasional. Distributing our past life of twenty-one years into three periods of seven •years each, our average number of members was, during the first of these periods, 728; during the second, 903; LONDON SCIENTIFIC INSTITUTION. 181 during the third, 974; and we now number a total of 1073 members. We possess a library, for reference and circulation, of between 9000 and 10,000 volumes; we have spacious and convenient premises, enlarged and remodelled — I might almost say rebuilt — by ourselves, though, in spite of the most careful economy, at a very heavy cost ; we can show a Museum with various scientific accompaniments and instructive specimens, and a sufficient number of class-rooms for those classes which are formed among the members to prosecute some continuous branch of study. We can boast, also, an excellent and com- modious lecture-room, built by ourselves, and paid for by our own money. This lecture-room was opened in 1829, in the fifth year of our existence, by an inaugural address, which the present Lord Chief Justice of England, then Mr. Common-Sergeant Denman, did us the honour to deliver. The room holds, with perfect convenience, between 500 and 600 persons, and when first opened was amply sufficient for all our wants ; but the increase in our numbers has now rendered it inadequate to its purpose, and the just complaint of our members respecting the insufficiency of room and comfort on evenings of cro\^ded attendance, is one of the most pressing difficulties with which our Insti- tution has now to contend, and which I hope it will be soon in a position to remove. Independent of the lecture- room, the large outlay upon our premises generally has of course driven us to contract a considerable debt ; and the interest upon this debt, as well as the setting apart of instalments for its gradual liquidation, constrains us to the painful necessity of circumscribing both our usefulness to the members and our furtherance to science and literature. But, gentlemen, this necessity, painful as it is, is not beyond our means. Our Institution, though a debtor, is not an embarrassed debtor: that which it has promised it has performed faithfully, and is competent as well as willing still to perform. I dwell upon this fact with emphasis, and I should deeply regret if it were not true to the 182 PEESIDENTIAL ADDRESS, letter. It is not for us, who rest altogether upon the support of a commercial and professional public, to set the example of disregarding that which, among such a public especially, is as the staff and guardian of life — pecuniary good faith and probity. No, gentlemen; if our Institution invokes, as it does invoke, an augmentation of funds, we do not come forward as suppliant insolvents, to solicit relief or extrication from past imprudences or present embarrass- ments ; we ta]^e higher ground. We come forward as stewards in the cause of literature and science in this city, feeling that we have established a fair and honourable claim to the confidence of all who have that holy cause at heart. We come prepared to show that our Institution, as it stands, both is now, and has been throughout its twenty-one years' life, good and useful ; and we ground upon that fact a wish to acquire means of extending our use- fulness yet further. We know that we have done far more than could reasonably have been expected, or than any one actually did expect, in 1825 ; and that, assuming only the same degree of generous zeal for literature and science which prevailed then, the man who desires to deepen their roots and promote their development in the city of London will find no better hands to aid him than our Institution. Feeling a pride, gentlemen, in what we have done for these objects during the past, we are in no w^ay ashamed of saying that we desire to be armed with still ampler and more unfet- tered powers of serving the same purposes during the future. Gentlemen, the twenty-one years' biography of our Insti- tution stands permanently on record in the two thick manu- script volumes in the hands of our secretary, containing the minutes of forty-two regular half-yearly meetings of the members of the Institution, and of various special general meetings held by public notice. I need not remind you that, at each of these half-yearly meetings, it is both the duty and the practice of the managing committee to present a report on the general and financial condition of the Institution ; so that the series of those reports forms a continuous narrative, LONDON SCIENTIFIC INSTITUTION. 183 not less instructive than authentic. At several of those meetings I had myself the honour to preside : and I can per- sonally testify to the good feeling and propriety with which they were conducted, to the due admixture of a free spirit of criticism with a reasonable confidence in the board of management, and with cheerful acquiescence in the con- cluding vote of the majority. I have recently refreshed my memory, and renewed my acquaintance with these forty- two half-yearly reports, and with the facts set forth in them from time to time by the committee ; and I find in them ample evidences of an intellectual movement at once well sustained and well directed. I find in them, besides, proofs of an assiduous cultivation of those arts and tastes which, if they lie apart from the intellect properly so called, are yet of a character most in harmony with the intellectual man, and tend to awaken and develop the imaginative impulses of our nature. First, I trace with satisfaction the gradual growth of the library of the Institution from its first modest poverty in 1825 — not more than 89 volumes — to its present comparative abundance, of more than 9000 volumes. I content myself with calling this comparative abundance, for I trust that it is destined to still further increase, and still wider usefulness. Nor is it only the catalogue of the library which has become more bulky, or the shelves which have become fuller ; there is ample proof that the members make good use of the library, and desire to read the books as well as to possess them. There is ample proof of this, even for those to whom the fact is not familiar by personal experience, in the difficulty which the committee have had in so framing their library regulations as to satisfy the impatience of members for procuring books to read. From the library I pass to the lectures, many paid, some gratuitous ; and when I go through the list of these various lectures, I find that there is scarcely any subject — scientific, literary, philosophical, economical, historical, or connected with poetry and the arts — which has not been presented, more or less extensivelv, to the minds of the members of ourlnsti- 184 PRESIDENTIAL ADDRESS, tution. The list would be far too long to read, and it is of course diversified so as to meet great varieties of taste and tendencies on the part of different members : there may be some subjects too dry, others too frivolous, according to the judgment of the person criticising ; but I, for my part, should be sorry to see any of them left out. The Institution only lives and thrives by the alliance of these diversities of pursuit ; the co-operation of both is indispensable to the gratification of every one singly. Of these numerous lectures — whether on astronomy and geography, on the productions and attri- butes of distant countries, on experimental chemistry, physics, or physiology, on mental philosophy and political economy, on history, the drama, poetry, or painting — of all these lec- tures, the least impressive will not have been without its echo and response in the minds of those who heard it, while the richest and most emphatic will have proved eminently stir- ring and suggestive. And, gentlemen, the number of these lectures which have been gratuitous is a fact highly deserving of notice on the part of those who are interested in the pros- perity of the Institution, just as it well merits the continued expressions of thanks which have been passed at every half- yearly meeting. It proves the valuable influence of such institutions as ours in calling forth disinterested exertions on the part of instructed men ; and it is the more gratifying, inasmuch as several of these lecturers have themselves been members of the Institution. But, gentlemen, the lectures, thoug'h beneficial and indis- pensable, are not the department of our Institution which I look at with the greatest interest. The classes for special and continuous instruction on particular subjects, formed among the members themselves, under the auspices of the managing committee, are, in my mind, a circumstance yet more impres- sive and encouraging. In the lecture-room, let the talents of the lecturer be what they may, the minds of the hearers are more passive than active : they hear and they feel, they receive wholesome nutriment, a part of which will doubtless remain with them ; but they are, after all, only recipients — LONDON SCIENTIFIC INSTITUTION. 185 recipients of an impulse which comes upon them from without, and is to a great degree transient. It is otherwise with the classes meeting continuously for special, perseveriiig, and laborious instruction: whether assisted and superin- tended, as many of them have been, by a paid master, pro- vided by the committee, or formed without that assistance, where the committee have not been able, with a due regard to the finances of the Institution, to grant assistance, by the members themselves on the principle of mutual instruc- tion. It is in these class-rooms, gentlemen, that you see our Institution in active and living function. The library and the lecture-room do, indeed, furnish the previous helps; but it is in these class-rooms that you see the nutriment assimilate, the blood circulate, the muscle move. It is here that you witness that most gratifying phenomenon — the adult man again putting himself to school ; undergoing that self-imposed labour and training which, with reference to individuals, has in all ages been the great cause of eminence to those whom the world has ennobled, but which, with reference to more numerous bodies, stands as the imposing distinction of our nineteenth century. For the French and Latin languages, I observe that classes have been constantly going on and well attended, with little interrup- tion. For tbe German, less constantly, yet still frequently. For the Italian and Spanish, also frequently. Nor have languages alone formed the subjects of this class study. I notice also other pursuits, usually less popular, which have been approached with the same persevering and earnest devotion of time and trouble. I observe records of classes on natural and experimental physics, on mathematics, on political economy, on logic, on phrenology, and various other subjects ; which I state, gentlemen, not at all with a view of pretending to set forth a list of all that has been done, but only as specimens of what I may call the intel- lectual vitality of our Institution, calculated to make our tendencies and purposes better understood. There is, how- ever, one class which I cannot omit specially to notice, be- 186 ; PEESIDENTIAL ADDRESS, cause it both is now, and has long been, well sustained and popular ; and because it is, in my judgment, eminently use- ful, as exercising a powerful stimulus to activity on the minds of the members, I mean the class for historical and philological discussion. Standing, as the Institution does, apart from all party political excitement and controYersial religion, and deeply interested as it is in maintaining in- ternal harmony among its members, the discussion class lias been kept free from the two great perils which might have impaired its usefulness. The questions, announced before- hand, have been found to provoke a serious preliminary study, and to cultivate among the members both the faculties of thought and expression, in a manner very different from that empty fluency about nothing, which the habits of a mere debating society too often generate. The listening members have been disposed to enforce, and the speakers to observe, a degree of good feeling, as well as an intelligent handling of the subject, which renders this class a valuable instrument of improvement. And here again we meet with a new pro- vocative to that mental labour on the value of which I have so much insisted. I shall not forget to notice, also, the music and drawing classes, conducted by members of the Institution ; partly be- cause the former especially is found to be one of the most attractive and popular classes within its walls ; partly because those musical exercises which Milton did not disdain to com- prehend in his lofty sketch of the curriculum of a gentle- man's education, may well be numbered among the allure- ments of our premises in Aldersgate Street, once the actual site of that illustrious man's house and abode. They form a necessary part of that character of universality to which the Institution aspires, and which it must maintain undiminished, if it would be at once self-supporting and permanent. Com- plexity and variety of pursuit is essential to its usefulness not less than to its stability ; it must be competent to meet the demands both of the intellect and the imagination in their principal branches ; it must represent, if I may so LONDON SCIENTIFIC INSTITUTION. 187 speak, a little mental world, wherein all the manifold work- ings of the vast mental world without, are seen in abridg- ment and in miniature. Much credit is due to its managers for having steadily kept in view this comprehensive mission, neither disdaining the light and recreative subjects, nor shrinking from the dry and serious ; the fuller audiences of the former both sustain, and are sustained by, the more select and laborious students who devote themselves to the latter. I am happy further to know that the advantages of the lectures and of the library are open to ladies, and that this privilege is actually employed to a consider- able extent, producing unmixed benefit. For, certainly, literary and intellectual culture is not less advantageous to one sex than to the other ; and our Institution ought to be the last to sanction that narrow view which would deprive our female relatives of access to the means of improvement, while we are labouring hard to disseminate them among our- selves. Now, gentlemen, it is the essential principle of our Institu- tion to be voluntary and self-supporting. We have no other permanent fund of reliance than the subscriptions of our members ; and if ever the time shall come when they shall deem the advantages of the Institution an insufficient equivalent for what they are called upon to pay, we shall not survive, nor shall we deserve to survive, any longer. I am one of those who number self-reliance among the car- dinal virtues of the human bosom, second in rank only to honesty and integrity ; and it is one of the circumstances of which I feel proud in the history of this Institution, that it has been self-relying and self-supporting. Its members have proved this, as by their other conduct, so also by raising the large sum of money required for the repair and enlargement of their premises, through loans derived chiefly from individuals of their own number. But, gentle- men, the man that helps himself is the man that best de- serves the help of others ; and I will not scruple to maintain 188 PRESIDENTIAL ADDRESS, that this Institution renders a service to the commercial and professional public of London, which entitles it to call for such help, even from those who may not feel induced to join it as members. I believe it to have a powerful claim on the approbation, countenance, and aid of the merchants and bankers generally of this great city. To say nothing of that disinterested sympathy which ought to prevail, and which doubtless in most cases will prevail, between the principal of an establishment and the younger men who serve as his auxiliaries, I do not hesitate to affirm that he has a positive interest in upholding their morality, in enlarging their intelligence, in opening the most favourable avenues (as far as he can do so without obtrusive interference) for the employment and direction of their leisure hours. Speaking as one, the best years of whose life have been passed as prin- cipal of a banking house, I contend, emphatically, that mer- chants and bankers will obey the call of interest, as well as the call of duty, in seconding the voluntary effi^rts of our members, and in strengthening the self-acquired position w^hich our Institution now occupies. Though useful for men of all ages, its beneficial influence will, of course, be found most efficient in regard to younger men — to that age when the character is ductile and the tastes undetermined — when much depends, for good or evil, on the associates with whom a youth may be thrown into connection. In those early, and, to a certain extent, doubtful years, the admission of a young man into our Institution, whether you look at it as keeping him out of the reach of expense, as guaranteeing him against dissipated company, or as opening to him the largest measure of elevating and refined pursuits which in his position is attainable, — in all these points of view, I say, the admission to our Institution will prove to him at once tutelary and attractive. He has his bread to get, doubtless; his industrious habits must not be impaired. Certainly, if I supposed for a moment that our Institution would impair them, I should not be here to uphold it. I should consider that any other service which LONDON SCIENTIFIC INSTITUTION. • 189 the Institution miglit do him would be a poor compensa- tion for the loss of his independent industry. But, gentle- men, the young man who enters our Institution, having his bread to get, finds every other member of it in the same situation as himself; every member of it is also com- mercial and professional, having his leisure to bestow upon the Institution, but having no free time besides. It is not among a body of men such as this that any sentiment un- favourable to industry — any sentiment tending to excuse negligence or distraction of mind — can ever for a moment have a chance of succeeding. Well, gentlemen, I shall grant most fully, that with a commercial and professional public, habits of steady industry are the first thing needful ; but I shall contend, with equal strenuousness, that they are not the only thing needful. There are, in the life of every commercial and professional man, hours of leisure, as well as hours of work — I wish, in- deed, from the bottom of my heart, that the circumstances were such as to enable him to command still longer hours of leisure — but that which he now enjoys is enough to make a considerable difference, according as it is well or ill bestowed. Now, gentlemen, there are many innocent and agreeable ways of passing leisure; and I am the last person to obtrude the literary, the scientific, the recreative pursuits of our In- stitution upon any unwilling partaker. If a young man has tastes of another kind, I wish him happy in his own way. But I do say, that if he chance to have a taste for literary or scientific pursuits, or for mental recreations, it is of very great moment that the taste should not be stifled for want of nourishment, nor die out from the mere impossibility of gratification. Suppose him to come from that valuable and economical place of education now flourishing among us — the City of London School — or from any other good school elsewhere, and to pass from thence into a counting-house ; he will doubtless have treasured up a certain stock of acquired knowledge, and will perhaps have brought away a treasure hardly less valuable —the wish to acquire more knowledge. 190 • PEESIDENTIAL ADDRESS, This is the exact case with many a young man when he first enters upon the threshold of his commercial career ; for the fatal supposition, that what has been learnt at school has been learnt only to be thrown aside or buried like the talent in a napkin, is a mistake, committed, indeed, by too many persons in every rank of life, but not committed by all. I do not hesitate to affirm, gentlemen, that to a young man with these dispositions our Institution holds out the most effective support, and the most propitious allurement, which his situa- tion admits. It brings into play those principles of sociability which are so predominant in the youthful character, and which, if they do not find good objects to fasten upon, are but too likely to be seduced towards frivolities, perhaps even towards what is positively bad — it brings into play, I say, those principles of sociability, and allies them with pursuits at once improving to the intellect and elevating to the ima- gination. Gentlemen, this is a great and a noble end — to blend the extension of human sociability with the improve- ment of human intellect, and with the expansion of our imaginative pleasures ; to bring men together, not merely as partakers of the same meat and drink, not merely as part- ners in the same scheme of commercial gain, but also as fellow-proprietors of the same rational nature, and as mutual agents each in the improvement of others. Under one form or another, this is one of the capital problems of modern society, and our Institution may well be proud of helping to accomplish it. Humble, indeed, our efforts are, and on a small scale, as compared with what we can all wish and con- ceive : but even the undistino-uished soldier in the ranks derives some dignity from the consciousness of a grand cause upheld in part by his arm. A young man of the commercial or professional class, who enlists in our regiment, finds himself in a companionship calculated to develop all the improving tendencies of his nature, and, I venture boldly to assert, not calculated to develop any others ; certainly none for which himself, or his relatives, might have reason to feel after-repentance. He LONDON SCIENTIFIC INSTITUTION. 191 finds encouragement and sympathy in keeping alive the acquisitions of his school period, or in extending the same habits to new subjects of study ; the dead volumes on the library shelves, and the living voice in the lecture-room, are alike calculated to enlarge the range of his ideas ; whatever be his vein of taste, or line of study, he will enjoy greater facilities for prosecuting it than would be open to him in any other quarter. He will learn to respect and value the in- tellectual tendencies of others, even though they happen to be different from his own, and to regard human improve- ment as one great whole, towards which many different streams converge. If his mind be strung no higher than the pitch of passive curiosity, it will, at least, find an apt and abundant nutriment, often invigorating, always pleasing and harmless: if it be more self-working and inquisitive, there will be ample materials of thought, and definite objects of acquisition, placed within his reach, together with a little community quite sufficiently extensive to sustain within him the wholesome fire of emulation. In those years which pre- cede the age when he will think it prudent to take upon him the charo^e of a familv, our Institution offers to him a harbour for his leisure hours, a diversion from his daily toil, and a stimulus for all the seeds of intellectual life that are dormant within him. It holds out opportunities such as Daniel Defoe, or other men of genius, who knew the city of London in its earlier and grosser days, must have sighed for in vain in their own solitary parlours. And, gentlemen, let me again say it, he will find every- thing in our Institution arranged with a view to the prior and imperious exigencies of a life of industry. We look to the commercial and professional classes, and we look to none besides : we offer them mental occupation for their leisure hours only, with the full knowledge, and with the sincere regret, that they have no room for more. We know both the moderate means, and the moderate leisure, of those for whom we work ; we shall seek to engraft upon their habits of business as much of literature and science as the case admits, 192 PRESIDENTIAL ADDRESS, but we shall not encourage them to convert the accessory occupation into the principal. Upon the individual industry, prudence, and success of our members, each in his own sepa- rate walk of life, depends, not merely the prosperity, but even the continued existence, of the collective Institution. We have this important truth present to our minds as intimately as if it were engraven on the walls of our building ; and could we by possibility forget it, we should find it thrust upon our attention by the manner in which occasional depressions, in the general state of London commerce, operate in diminish- ing the number of om' members. The unfavourable state of commerce in London, during the years between 1841 and 1844, caused a temporary falling-off in our numbers, which, for a moment, disturbed the calculation of our managers. From this I rejoice to say that we have now completely re- covered ; but we have not forgotten its past occurrence, and it serves as a salutary admonition to prudence and watchful- ness. Gentlemen, — T shall again remind you that this is our twenty-first birthday. Our season of youth is over, and we now pass into the period of maturity. We have taken rank, and are identified with the mind and intelligence of this great city ; be it ours to act in a manner worthy of our age and our calling. To those — whether they be many or few, I know not — who may still hold the ungenial preju- dice that there is an inherent incompatibility between a day of industry in the counting-house, and an evening of study in the lecture-room, the class-room, or the library — we must continue to present the best of all refutations, in the lives and behaviour of our members. To those, on the other hand, whose sentiments are more generous and exalted, who esteem an enlightened population a greater glory than splendid edifices, and immeasurable capital, and who account it an honour to London to interweave the threads of literature and science with the staple of a commercial and professional life ; to these minds, we offer ourselves with confidence as auxiliaries and instruments, prepared to justify our claim LONDON SCIENTIFIC INSTITUTION. 193 upon their fraternal sympathy. There always have been minds of this enlarged and kindly stamp : witness, among other things, the great amount of property bequeathed for educational purposes ; of which bequests some, indeed, have been ill-considered and capricious ; but many too have been dictated by the purest and most earnest solicitude for the diffusion of human knowledge. It is but too well known how many of these bequests have become misemployed or useless by negligence or fraud on the part of trustees ; how many of them too, even where the original purpose has been faithfully adhered to, have turned to nullity or mischief, because that purpose itself is no longer in harmony with the exigencies of a modern age. Let it be our task to prove to minds such as these, and to all who really have at heart the diffusion of literature and science in the City of London, that they can in no way better assist this inestimable object than by employing our ministration, and by seconding the voluntary efforts of our members. That which is given or bequeathed to us can neither lie useless nor become un- employed, for our financial proceedings are both well known and diligently watched by the members ; our purposes are of endless necessity, and can never grow obsolete, while a due flexibility as to the means of accomplishing them is insepar- able from our management. To-morrow, as well as to-day— in the times of our descendants as in our own — the life of the commercial and professional man will consist of a day of labour and an evening of leisure, which may be well or ill appropriated ; to-morrow, as well as to-day, the sociability of his nature may be enlisted in favour of the better employ- ment instead of the worse — in favour of mental progress and elevating recreations, and against both seductions and lassi- tude ; provided there be a brotherhood ready organized, com- manding as well as deserving his confidence, with whom he can mingle and fraternise. This organization, gentlemen, it is our pride to have created ; we shall bequeath it to our successors, together with an unfinished but noble task, which will never cease to require the exertions of an enlightened o 194 PEESIDENTIAL ADDRESS. benevolence, and never cease to bless them with the requiting consciousness of well doing. That which we have begun will be matured and perfected by others ; and our Institu- tion, destined for enduring mental wants, fed by the energies of a concentrated population, and sustained by the silent stream of human improvement, will pass from w^ell-spent youth to vigorous manhood, without being fated to reach the age of superannuation or decrepitude. [This Institution, on which Mr. Grote had lavished his support, in every form, during twenty years, declined in its prosperity from this date, owing to the altered habits of the class for whose benefit it had existed. The introduction of the ^'Omnibus," or cheap conveyance system, induced the young men engaged in business in the city to lodge in the suburbs, and the purposes of the London Scientific Institution ceased to offer the same inducements to become members.] ' ADDRESS ON DELIVERING THE PRIZES AT UNIVERSITY COLLEGE. (ls< July, 1846.) o 2 ADDRESS ON DELIVEEING THE PEIZES AT UNIYEESITY COLLEGE. Ladies and Gentlemen, — I should depart from tlie pre- cedents of former years, and I should do little justice either to your feelings or to my own, if I permitted this meeting to separate without saying a few words on the business which has just been auspiciously concluded. In regard to myself personally, I feel that the Council of University College have done me great honour by inviting me to preside at a ceremony so interesting in its character, and so beneficial in its tendencies. To be the instrument of placing in the hands of those students most distinguished for their ability and diligence that meed of honour which they have so fairly won, is a duty which no man can perform unmoved, and which the first men among us for position and intellect might well be proud to perform. In the success of University College I have always felt a sincere and lively interest, having taken a part, though a humble part, in its first foundation, and having had my name honoured by being commemorated with the foundation stone as a member of its earliest Council, I rejoice to find, from the Eeport read by Professor De Morgan, that the hold which the College had in former years acquired on the public mind, as a good and efficient place of instruction, has been fully sustained, that the number of pupils has increased, and that their conduct has been so creditable and exemplary. There was, indeed, one portion of the Eeport which occa- 198 DELIVERY OF THE PEIZES sioned me the deepest regret — I mean that portion which announced the retirement of Professor Long from the Chair of Latin, a gentleman whose extensive erudition, dis- criminating criticism, and remarkable power of illustrating ancient literature and history, are so well known and so highly appreciated by every classical scholar amongst us. If it should appear to the more zealous friends of the College that its students are not so numerous as might have been expected from the number of affluent families in and near the metropolis, to whose children it offers • facilities for an elevated range of education such as they never before possessed, we must consider, on the other hand, that the College at its first formation had to encounter much un- candid hostihty, which has only of late become discredited and forgotten ; that it had nothing but the force of truth and its own intrinsic merit to rely upon, without any extraneous support from powerful and organised parties, either in Church or State. According to the temper and character of our population, the greatest amount of real merit will not dispense with this accessory advantage, of being known as an establishment fixed and settled — not dating from yesterday, but having a past to look back upon, traditional or historical. But this season of disadvantage and hostility is now overpast; the College has outlived the stigma of novelty, as well as the more unjust stigma of irreligion. It has now taken its rank as one of the great and permanent institutions of the metro- polis, and may fairly calculate on that steady increase, which real good management, distinguished teachers, and educa- tional efficiency, when they find a clear stage and no preju- dice, are sure to bring about. It can already appeal to the ' Calendar of the University of London,' and to the award of scholarships and other prizes by the senate of that body, as an evidence of the proficiency of its students and the success of its professors ; and the proportion of prizes, obtained by its students from the award of the Universitv of London, will be tound not merely to satisfy, but greatly to surpass, all AT UNIVERSITY COLLEGE. 199 reasonable expectation. It will confide in the same results, and will require only the same fair and impartial trial, to ensure its future increase and extension. You, Gentlemen, the successful students whom the Ex- aminers have this day pronounced worthy to receive from my hands prizes and certificates of honour, you will require no words of mine to enhance the well-earned gratification which now fills your bosom. Your triumph has been one honestly achieved, which all will envy you, but which none can either impeach or disparage. Any man who reads over the ques- tions of the different professors in the examination papers, will see at once that the test of proficiency applied is not merely strict, but exceedingly trying and severe ; that the student who has answered such queries even fairly and tolerably, has profited much by the lessons of his professor ; but that he, whose answers merit a prize or a certificate of honour, has displayed that rare mastery of his subject, and that happy combination of laborious study beforehand with spontaneous and productive association at the moment of trial, which mark the rich and well-endowed mind, and give the amplest promise of future success and improvement. It will enhance in your view. Gentlemen, the value of your prizes, that your parents and near relatives will feel hardly less of satisfaction than yourselves, and that you are thus enabled to commence the task of discharging that debt of gratitude which parental affection has been so long imposing upon you. You will exult, and you have good reason to exult, in that which has just been achieved; but let the achievement of this day serve but as a prelude and an in- centive to yet further progress, and yet larger acquisitions, beyond. Let the prize which you now hold demonstrate to you the efficacy of steady, single-minded, well-directed application ; but let it at the same time prove to you that without a continuance of that application, no fresh rewards will await you. The triumphs of the youth are most valuable, as they presage and assist the future eminence of the adult man ; but in the one competition as well as in the other, it is 200 DELIVERY OF THE PRIZES the same sterling quality of mind, the same devotion and concentration of purpose, the same docility to good teaching and to a good system, which wins the race. ^ut it is not to those students alone, into whose hands I have had the gratification of delivering prizes and certificates of honour — it is not to them alone that I would address my observations. There are other students present whom per- sonally I am not permitted to know, but whose efforts have been less fortunate in the competition just terminated. To them, I fear, the acclamations which have welcomed the prizemen of this day will speak only of disappointed attempt ; yet I venture to remind them, that the augmies for the future are not merely consoling, but full of hope and promise. Though the prize can be only for one, and special notice only for a few, yet all those competitors who have diligently and seriously put forth their best efforts, may be well assured that every particle of that diligence will reap its due fruit and reward. They have dug the field carefully, without obtaining the pot of golden treasure there concealed ; but still, the field has been dug, and has been placed in condition to throw up a rich futm^e haiTest ; and in the fulness of time that harvest will be reaped. It is on this common ground that all the assiduous and earnest competitors for the prize, the defeated as well as the successful, may meet, with equal pride and confidence. In the great field of mental improve- ment there is room for all, without monopoly or exclusive possession to any one ; all, without exception, have advanced themselves to a higher grade of knowledge and capacity, and have qualified themselves for greater achievements and for ruder labom-s in future years. I have abeady remarked, that in estimating the difficulties with which the student has had to grapple, and the degree of proficiency which has been rewarded by the prize of this day, we are not confined simply to the declaration of the Examiner ; we have before us also the list of questions which have been propounded for answer, and we are thus as it were introduced into the class-room, so as to measure the range of AT UNIYEESITY COLLEGE. 201 instruction embraced by the Professor. I venture to assert that no man can read those papers without feeling satisfied that a competent answer, given on the spot, to such queries, involves no common amount of intellectual resources and requirements. And when we go through the long series of these various lists, as they stand here printed in the suc- cessive pages of the little volume annually set forth by the College, we are presented with an aggregate idea, both encouraging and impressive, of the wide mental field which its entire course covers. To suffice for the intellectual neces- sities of the present day, theoretical as well as practical, enlarged and diversified as they now are, is no easy task. In former centuries, when the great universities now existing in Europe were founded, the range of science and literature open to be studied was very narrow ; but now, each separate branch has been widened, and several new branches have been put forth ; the mathematical and physical sciences have come to comprise an immeasurable heap of theorems and general facts, such as could not have been imagined even in the time of Lord Bacon : the true requirements of scientific method, the process of logic and induction, and the pheno- mena of psychology generally, have been revived and analysed anew by minds trained in these positive investiga- tions; the languages and literature of the ancient world, though not more extensive in respect of original documents than they were a century ago, have yet been examined by more piercing eyes, and have been found to suggest in- ferences which reproduce Kome and Athens under new points of view; comparative grammar and philology have brought languages, ancient and modern, distant and near, under one common analytical survey. Moreover, in addition to that which constitutes the stock of the scientific and literary man, there are the ministers of applied science, the practical chemist and the civil engineer, who have acquired, in the present industrial development of society, an import- ance such as those professions never before enjoyed; and though last mentioned, not least in importance, the school- 202 DELIVERY OF THE PEIZES master of the present day has come to have his dignified mission correctly appreciated. Here are large intellectual exigencies, belonging to our age, and tending even to yet farther increase and expansion for the future. It has been the honourable aim of University College to adapt itself to that large measure of pure science and literature, as well as to that combination of science with practice, which the forward minds of our generation have marked out — to make provision for the legal and medical student, as well as for the classical and mathematical — to furnish appropriate aid and training to the schoolmaster, the civil engineer, and the practical chemist. The scheme includes classes w^hich had not before been made the subjects of special professorship ; and the largest, as well as the cheapest, range of instruction accessible in London, has thus been opened to the willing student, embracing both theory and practice. If, in providing so comprehensive a scheme of education, the administrators of the College have pre- sumed upon a wider extension of demand than is yet found to exist among the opulent and middling community of London — if they have anticipated intellectual appetites which have not as yet spread beyond chosen minds, and if some of their classes are therefore for the present scantily attended — I shall not affect to extenuate what they have done as an error or an imprudence. I shall rather glory in it as redounding to their honour, that they have set up an elevated standard of educational requirement, and that they have endeavoured to attract others to the eminence thus selected. While supplying to the full all the recognised subjects of instruction, they have tried to guide and to enlarge the public sentiment on this important matter, instead of contracting their own views so as to court only the maximum of immediate resort. I hope, and I believe, that they will succeed in diffusing among the public of London larger ideas on the proper measure of a citizen's education — in correcting that mistaken impatience with which parents, often under no pressure of necessity, abridge AT UNIYEESITY COLLEGE. 203 those years requisite for their son's complete education, and hurry him into professional life a half-educated man : above all, I hope they will succeed in extending and deepening that love of knowledge, without which every man, let his station or prosperity in life be what they may, remains essentially mutilated in one of the most essential features of the human character. To bind men together by this com- mon love of knowledge, the primitive meaning of the word jpMlosojphy — a tie more ample and comprehensive than either political or theological party, to concentrate in the same establishment an array of distinguished teachers, with wide diversities of intellectual aptitude, yet organised and acting in concert towards the grand purpose of an all-sided educa- tion, to eliminate at the same time those seeds of discord which cause what is meant for mankind, to ba given up to sect or party, — this has been the animating scheme of University College, in which every exalted and patriotic mind will wish to it the fullest success. Upon you, Gentlemen, the students of the College, whom I now see around me, that success will mainly depend — upon every one of you more or less — but most of all upon those meritorious and conspicuous students to whom I have this day had the pleasure of delivering prizes and certificates of honour, as well as those for whom the like distinctions may be in reserve on future occasions similar to the present. It is from your conduct and character that the place in which you have received your education will be judged ; and among the tutelary motives which will be required, to guard you through the various trials of life, this consideration will doubtless have its fair and prominent place. I trust that the maxims which you have imbibed in University College — the distinguished men from whom you have received instruction, and the companions with whom you have re- ceived it — perhaps also the scene of this day and the few, but deep-felt, words which you now hear from this chair — may form recollections of no mean force in assisting all your best and most virtuous resolutions. That you will be 204 DELIYEEY OF THE PRIZES, &c. estimable and honourable citizens, I shall not permit myself for a moment to doubt ; but I am farther sanguine enough to hope, not less for your own sakes than for that of the College in which you have been educated, that you will also be something more. The knowledge which your residence in University College has implanted in you, the literary and scientific associations which are now grouped in your minds, the habits of reading and application of which you have shown such conspicuous proof, are not mere artificial enforce- ments applied to your youth, destined to be thrown aside when you take up the active duties of a profession ; they are to be preserved and cultivated side by side with those duties, as the recreation, the treasure, the interior mental life, of the professional man. The man of regulated habits will suffice for both exigencies ; he will indeed account pecimiary independence and self-reliance to be an obligation not less imperative than pecuniary integrity, but the largest con- struction of this oblio:ation will still leave him leisure enough to preserve him from the misfortune — I had almost said, the disgrace — of an unlettered life — that unlettered life which has been characterised by more than one eminent man, as a life no better than death, " Yita sine Uteris mors est." I trust that the studies and intellectual associations of your College period will pass by unbroken tradition into youi' mature life, enlarged and improved, but never relin- quished; and while you thus procure for yourselves per- sonally a dignified existence and a source of perennial satis- faction, you will at the same time repay the care and labours of your teachers, you will confer an honour on University College, and vou will second in the most effective manner the noble purposes of its Founders, to raise the level, as well as to enlarge the spread of public education. REVIEW OF SIR G. C. LEWIS ON THE CREDIBILITY OF EARLY ROMAN HISTORY. {Edinlmrgh Beview^ 1856.) REVIEW OF SIR G. C. LEWIS OX THE CREDIBILITY OF EARLY ROMAN HISTORY.* Among the wide circle of historical readers, there are few who follow with satisfaction, and some who even repudiate with impatience, investigations into the evidence on which the narrative before them rests. Such investigations they regard as the special duty of the author. They desire only to know the results, set forth in a luminous and attractive manner, with suitable reflections. If they are perusing an animated narrative — adjusted to their notions of probability in respect to the succession of events, and accommodated to their ethical and sesthetical sentiments in its appreciation of characters and situations — they willingly hail the matter as so much added to their previous knowledge. A moderate show of references suffices to make them presume that the author has collated the necessary evidence and elicited from it a true or credible history. No such presumption indeed will arise, if he contradicts their notions of probability, or adopts canons of ethical and sesthetical appreciation depart- ing from theirs — if he describes sequences to them unex- pected, or introduces supernatural forces on occasions which they deem inappropriate — if he disparages persons and insti- tutions admirable in their eyes. The shock to their feelings * Inquiry into the Credibility of the Early Boman History. By Sir George Cornewall Lewis, Bart. 2 vols. 8vo. 1855. 208 REVIEW OF SIR G. C. LEWIS will then certainly raise doubts, and may perhaps provoke to examination of the original authorities. But except under such a stimulus, the idea of mistrusting the sufficiency of the author's proofs is one which neither suggests itself spon- taneously to them, nor finds ready admission when suggested by others. The degree to which an historian can count upon easy faith, depends upon the pre-established harmony of sentiment between him and his readers, enforced by his own powers of style and exposition. Both the appreciating sentiments, and the received mea- sure of internal credibility, vary materially from age to age, and from nation to nation : but subject to this condition, the description above given applies to historical readers gene- rally. For the large majority of them, indeed, the fact cannot be otherwise. They have no time — to pass over other disqualifications — even for hearing all the distinct matters of proof; much less for weighing and comparing them, for hunting out what may have been overlooked^ or for studying the process of combination and elimination which the his- torian's task requires from him. Such labour must be per- formed by one or a few for the benefit of many. And the security which the many possess for its being faithfully per- formed, arises not so much from their own demand, as from the emulation and competition of historical students them- selves. The probability of eventual animadversion, from a few censors themselves conversant with the original sources, is a motive almost indispensable to keep the historian up to the proper pitch, throughout his long and often irksome preparations. By such censorship the comparison of his narrative with the sum total of attainable evidence becomes forced upon general readers, little disposed of themselves to originate the question. The analytical or dissecting process of criticism serves as a valuable control on the synthetical and constructive effort of the historian ; who, however con- scientious, is under temptation to aim too exclusively at those charms of pictorial execution without which large popularity is hardly attainable. ON EARLY ROMAN HISTORY. 209 Of this analytical process, the work of Sir George Lewis, now before us, affords an admirable specimen. It exhibits a complete and intelligent mastery of the original authorities, a full knowledge of what has been done by former critics, with an equitable spirit of appreciation towards them, and a familiarity with historical research, modern as well as ancient. It is full of copious illustration from the kindred subject of Grecian antiquity. While rich in premises, it is sparing in conclusions, and strictly exigent as to sufficiency of proof — the work of one who, though seeking earnestly for truth, is not ashamed to confess that he cannot find it, and to rest in such acknowledgment of ignorance, where there is no evidence, at once literal and cogent, to enforce some positive affirmation. We recognise in Sir George Lewis the precise antithesis of that vehement impulse of divination, confident alike both in belief and in disbelief, which so often carried away the vigorous intellect of Niebuhr. If indeed there be any single purpose, prominent and peculiar, in a work of so much breadth and learning as this ' Enquiry,' it is to protest against the Niebuhrian licence of substitution and reconstruction. The book is not, and does not profess to be, a history of Eome ; but we are mistaken if it does not tend to influence materially the composition of future Eoman histories. Like the critical philosophy of Kant, as con- trasted with the antecedent dogmatic philosophy of Leibnitz and Wolf, it is a magazine of arms on the negative side of the question. The historian will find brought before him, more fully than in any previous work, the problems with which he has to grapple, the means of solving them, and the amount of success hitherto attained by employing those means ; lastly, the contradictions and inconsistencies which the original authorities, scanty as they are, present in abundance. Sir George Lewis reviews the Eoman history from its earliest times down to the fall of the Eepublic, about forty vears before the Christian era. Upon the subsequent events durin^ the Empire, he does not touch. Counting upwards r 210 REVIEW OF SIR G. C. LEWIS from the fall of the Eepiiblic to the received date of the capture of Troy and the migration of JEneas, there was a space of about 1140 years. Through this long antiquity Augustus and his contemporaries looked up to jiEneas and the exiles from Troy, mythical ancestors of the Julian and other p:reat Eoman families. The series of years is here distributed into several periods, vrith the evidences, primary or secondary, discordant or harmonious, indicated and appre- ciated. In writing a history of Eome, the historian must neces- sarily begin from the beginning; and the difficulty is, in this as well as in other inquiries, to find a beginning. He must grope his way for some time nearly in the dark, until at length he emerges into twilight, and into a slowly im- proving daylight. In the process of criticism this order is reversed. Sir George Lewis takes his point of departure from the latest period. Proceeding backward from the fell of the Kepublic to the invasion of Italy by Pyrrhus in 281 B.C., he exhibits a full catalogue of the historical pro- ductions of the Eoman world during: the last two centuries before the Christian era. The catalogue is a very respectable one ; and though nearly all the works are lost, we have notices remaining which inform us of their general contents and style of execution. Julius Caesar and Sallust, comparatively recent as they are, must be named as the oldest Eoman writers from whom any entire historical compositions remain. Livy was born B.C. 59, and died at the age of seventy-six. His history extended from the earliest times of Eome to the death of Drusus, nine years before the Christian era. Between him and Cato the Censor (the earliest Eoman historian who composed in his own language, about 150 B.C.) the following historians are known to us by name and by a few fragments : — Calpurnius Piso Frugi, Cassius Hemina, Caius Fannius, L. Attius, Caius Sempronius Tuditanus, Lucius Coelius Antipater, Cnaeus Gel- lius, Sextus Gellius, Aulus Gellius, Clodius Licinus, Publius Sempronius Asellio, Marcus iEmilius Scaurus, Publius Eu- ON EARLY ROMAN HISTORY. 211 tilius Eufus, Quintus Lutatius Catulus, Caius Licinius Macer Quintus Claudius Quadrigarius, Quintus Valerius Antias, Lucius Otacilius Pilitus, Lucius Cornelius Sylla, Lucius Cor- nelius Sisenna, Quintus ^lius Tubero, &c. Besides these and other historians in the Latin language, there were several Romans, some of illustrious position, who composed historical works in Greek. Among them there were the two earliest of all Roman historians — Quintus Fabius Pictor and Lucius Cincius Alimentus, both of them in high public position and active service throughout the Second Punic War. Cincius was even taken prisoner by Hannibal, from whom he learnt various facts afterwards reported in his history. Ennius (b.c. 239-169) and Nsevius, a generation older, though poets, are also historical witnesses. Ennius, the first composer of hexameter verses in Latin, wrote a sort of metrical chronicle, called ' Annales,' of the affairs of Rome from Romulus and Remus down to his own time. Nsevius wrote a similar chronicle of the First Punic War (in which he had himself served), employing the native Latin metre, Saturnian verse. Passing to Greeks : the life of Polybius is comprised be- tween B.C. 210-120, and his forty books of universal history (of which only five remain entire) included the period from B.C. 220 down to B.C. 146, the date of the capture of Carthage and Corinth, which events Polybius witnessed. Sosilus and Silenus, contemporary with and companions of Hannibal, wrote histories of the Second Punic War. Philinus of Agri- gentum described the First Punic War, with which he was contemporary, in a spirit blamed by Polybius as unfair towards the Romans. Lastly, both Hieronymus of Cardia and Timaeus of Tauromenium, contemporaries of Pyrrhus, described his war against the Romans. Indeed Pyrrhus him- self seems to have composed memoirs of his own operations. These are the earliest portions of Roman affairs, described by historians either actually or nearly contemporaneous. Besides these histories, there existed in the last two cen- P 2 212 EEYIEW OF SIR G. C. LEWIS turies of the Eepublic, many orations spoken on various public occasions by magistrates and senators, and preserved as well as edited by the speakers themselves. Among the orations, the oldest was that of Appius the Blind, who being conducted in his old age into the Senate when the question of peace or war with Pyrrhus was under discussion, deter- mined his countrymen to reject the propositions of peace (B.C. 280). In the time of Cicero, a large collection of these miscellaneous public harangues existed. He had read no less than a hundred and fiftv from the elder Cato alone, and he indicates Cornelius Cethegus (who died in b. c. 196, shortly after the Second Punic War) as the earliest Eoman distinguished for eloquence. It is to this later period of the Eepublic that Sir George Lewis devotes his first two chapters — among the most in- structive in the work. He sets before us the reallv historical ao:e of Eome — the assemblas^e of all the authoi^ from whom we derive (mediately or immediately) our knowledge of Eoman events ; and he appreciates, as far as is practicable under the loss of their works, their scope, manner, and point of view. The following summary deserves attention both in itself and as furnishing a standard of comparison for the evidences of the earlier age of Eome : — " If we trace the Roman history back from the dictatorship of Julius C^sar, we find that its events were fully recorded by intel- ligent, trustworthy, and well-informed contemporary writers, up to the beginning of the GfiUic war of 225 B.C. Up to that period, the majority of these historians were native Eomans, though some of them, and particularly those of the earlier time, T\Tote in Greek. For the period of thirty-nine years between the beginning of the fii'st Punic War and the Gallic War (264-225, B.C.) there were no native historians who were personal witnesses of the events of the day : but they lived with the generation who were actors in them, and were able to obtain their information from sources of unques- tionable authenticity. The First Punic. War was narrated by one Greek at least who lived during its progress ; and probably other Sicilians at ^^ time wrote its historv. ON EAELY KOMAN HISTORY. 213 " It is true that the native historians of Eome from Fabius Pictor down to Claudius Quadrigarius and Valerius Antias, did not hold a high rank as artists ; that their manner was in general dry, stiff, and jejune ; that they were deficient in philosophical spirit ; and that their historical style resembled rather that of a mediaeval chronicle, or of such writers as Holinshed or Stow, than the work of Thucydides, which they might have imitated ; or the works of Sallust, Livy, and Tacitus, which their own literature afterwards produced. Cicero will not even allow them the name of historians. So inferior were they to the Greek writers iij that line of com- position, that he regards them as mere annalists or memoir- writers — as mere mechanical registrars of facts, without any claim to the higher merits of the historian. According to the Koman standard of history (he says), the only requisite is, that the writer should tell the truth : the style of his composition is immaterial. They studied only to express their meaning in the smallest num- ber of words consistent with being understood. Their model was, the official annals of the year, kept by the Pontifex Maximus. Cicero himself wished to produce a history which should equal those of the Greek writers ; as Virgil attempted to rival Homer, and Horace the Greek lyric poets. He looks upon history chiefly as a work of art, and as a composition fitted for an orator." (Vol. i. p. 40.) After noticing criticisms from Sallust, Velleius Paterculus, and Dionysius of Halicarnassus, coinciding in spirit with those of Cicero, Sir George Lew^is proceeds : — " But though the series of historical writers who have been enumerated, from Fabius and Cincius down to Sylla and Macer, were not distinguished for any literary or philosophical excellence — though they were not artists in history — yet they were trust- worthy witnesses respecting the events of their own time. They were most of them men conversant with public affairs both civil and military — who had filled high offices and sat in the senate — who had in some cases been actors in the events which they nar- rated — and who by their social position, had access to good information and enlightened opinions respecting the political events of their time." (Vol. i. p. 43.) The loss, almost total, of these later historians — combined with the preservation of so many details respecting the early 214 EEYIEW OF SIR G. C. LEWIS Eoman history in the extant books of Livy and Dionysius — fostesr an involuntary illusion in the reader's mind, that the earlier periods were both better known and more inter- esting to the Eomans themselves, than the later. This is a mistake pointed out by Sir George Lewis : — " They (Fabius, Cincius, and the other historians) were concise in the early periods, and full in the times of which they had per- sonal experience. Their main purpose was to write recent and contemporary history. Even Livy, whom, on account of the acci- dental preservation of the earlier books and loss of the later books, of his history, we are accustomed to regard as an antiquarian com- piler, was in truth regarded in quite a different light, when his entire work was extant. The principal object of Livy was to relate the events of the period immediately preceding his own life, and partly contemporary with it. The books of his history beginning with 103, and extending to 142, being nearly a third part of the entire work, were coincident with his own lifetime. He himself, in his preface, supposes his readers to be more solicitous to read the history of the civil wars, than to dwell on the early period." (Vol. i. p. U.) The superior interest felt by Livy and others in the events of the later Eepublic is not difficult to explain. Those events surpassed prodigiously, in magnitude and in awe-striking accompaniments, the wars and internal disputes of Rome in her earlier days of comparative feebleness, — " Vincere cum Yeios posse, laboris erat." It is these antecedent events, recorded in the first ' Decad ' of Livy*, which form the special subject of Sir George Lewis's * Enquiry into the Credibility of the Early Roman History.' We have approached them, as he has done, by an upward march through the later events ; because we con- * The first Decad of Livy ends with the Consulship of Fabius Maximus Gurges and Junius Brutus Scasva, in B.C. 292. His eleventh book (now lost) brought the third Samnite War to a conclusion. His twelfth book (also lost) described the beginning of the war of Pyrrhus against the Eomans (b.c. 280). ON EARLY ROMAN HISTORY. 215 sider it an important feature in his method, to pass from the more known to the less known, and to appreciate the reporting historians before he begins to weigh and measure the evidences open to their inspection. We find in Livy and other writers a history of Eome for 472 years earlier than Pyrrhus ; from B. c. 753, the period assigned for the foundation of the city. This narrative which we read, — or something like it, though with many differences of detail, — was received during the literary ages of Eome, and appealed to as matter of popular belief by poets and orators. Now the question is. what authorities had Fabius and Cincius, the earliest Eoman historians (who flourished during the Second Punic War), and those who came after them, for composing the history of five centuries anterior to themselves ? Sir George Lewis sets forth the various hypotheses which have been advanced as answers to this question. He exa- mines with much care (Vol. i. 155, seg^.), the real compre- hension and evidentiary value of what were called the Pontifical Annals — ' Annales Maximi,' — kept by the Chief Pontiff from an early period down to the Pontificate of P. Mucins in B.C. 121. The pontiff caused various notable incidents to be inscribed on a whitened board and publicly posted up. What these incidents were, we are very imper- fectly informed ; but as far as we can make out, they were events susceptible of a religious interpretation, which called upon the pontiff to prescribe some expiatory ceremony for appeasing the wrath of the gods, — events such as dearth, pestilence, earthquakes, eclipses, prodigies of various kinds.* Livy, who occasionally mentions incidents of this character, is likely to have derived them, directly or indirectly, from the Pontifical Annals. The prodigies, such as divine voices, * A fragment of Cato says (ap. Aul. Gell. ii. 28), " Non lubet scribere, quod in tabula apud Pontificem Maximum est, quotiens annona cara est, quotiens lunae aut solis lumini caligo aut quid obstiterit," &c. 216 KEVIEW OF SIR G. C. LEWIS speaking oxen, rain of blood or of flesh, &c., are more dis- tinctly traceable to contemporary record than any other events in the early Koman history. That these pontifical annals were meagre, and destitute of all information on public matters, there is every reason to believe. At what precise date they commenced, and even whether there was matter registered in every successive year, we are ignorant. But it seems certain that there can have been no continuous preservation of them for the time anterior to the capture of Eome by the Gauls (b.c. 390). These pontifical tablets were all that early Eome possessed in the nature of annals prior to Fabius Pictor and Cincius. Sir George Lewis justly censures the laxity with which Niebuhr, Arnold, and other historians, appeal to certain invi- sible witnesses, called The Old Annals, The Ancient Annalists^ some Old Annalist, &c., as authorities for facts between B.C. 500-300 (see numerous examples cited, vol. i. p. 93, seq,). Nothino; can be more misleadino- than this lani>;uao:e. There existed no such annals (except the pontifical tablets) of an earlier date than B.C. 210. And when Livy says, as we sometimes find, *^ Invenio in quibusdam annalibus," &c., he must mean authors of this date, or later. To him these authors were ancient, very ancient — at the distance of 150 years. Nay, we even find Cicero a generation earlier than Livy, speaking of Cato as extremely ancient {loerveterem).* But the vague allusions of Niebuhr and Arnold suggest to readers the erroneous belief that there were Eoman annalists, contemporary with the seige of Veii or the Decemvirate, from whom Livy's statements, or a modified version of them at least, are borrowed. Though there existed no continuous history or annals during the first two centuries of the Eepublic, yet there were undoubtedly throughout all that period detached me- morials : contemporary registrations of notable isolated facts * Cicero, Brutus, 15. 61. " Earn nos ut perveterem habemus," &c. (i.e. Cato). ON EAKLY ROMAN HISTORY. 217 — treaties with foreign states — laws (such as the Twelve Tables) — decrees of the senate — inscriptions on brazen plates, or on linen cloth — commemoration of the magistracies of particular men, and even partial lists of their succession — precedents kept by the scribes or secretaries who carried on the routine of business in the magisterial offices of the consuls, censors, and praetors. The earliest known inscription, commemorating any public event — the treaty between Rome and Carthage, seen by Polybius — dated very shortly after the expulsion of the kings. Even the earliest times of the Republic were thus not destitute of documents ; but none such can be traced during the regal period. Sir George Lewis, in his fifth chapter, reviews and estimates these sources of Roman history. They were (to cite his words in another place, vol. ii. p. 361.) " detached notices and fragments of evi- dence, but not a continuous narrative ; they were not the work of an historian, and thev did not of themselves form a history of the period : there was a substratum of notation, but not an authentic narrative of events." This '' substratum of notation " can be traced distinctly to the earliest times of the Republic ; but no history was erected upon it by any Roman until Fabius Pictor, three centuries afterwards. Nevertheless, the history of Rome, as we read it in Dionysius and Livy (both of them much later than Fabius), contains, not merely a string of naked facts, such as might be noted on brazen plates, or on whitened boards, but also abundance of incidents related with minute details, animated descriptions, precise relation of the words and thoughts of the principal actors. It was in the same copious and circumstantial manner that Fabius and suc- ceeding annalists recounted the family tragedies of the Roman kings, as well as many of the wars and internal political contests which marked the first two centuries of the Republic. From whence then did Fabius and his suc- cessors obtain the knowledge of these details, so long anterior to their own time? Not certainly from the "substratum of notation : " which, even if it had been systematic and con- 218 EEYIEW OF SIR G. C. LEWIS tinuous, instead of being merely disjointed and occasional, could have supplied nothing beyond bare and brief facts. We must here look for sources of information distinct from contemporary brass, wood, or linen. To find a source for these detailed incidents, many of them highly poetical and interesting, Niebuhr contended for the existence of early ballad-poems, or epic lays, anterior to Nseyius and Ennius. Dr. Arnold and Mr. Macaulay have adopted the same hypothesis : and the beautiful * Lays of Ancient Rome,' composed by the latter, will imprint it on the recollection of every En2:lish reader. Sir Geor^-e Lewis examines the point at considerable length (Vol. i. pp. 212-38). Niebuhr distributes large portions of the Eoman history, from Eomulus down to the Gallic conflagration, into various epic lays ; which, however, he supposes to have been composed long after the events to which they referred, chiefly about B.C. 320-300 ; and to have been once extremely popular, though they were discredited and lost after Ennius had introduced Greek metres, and after the Latin poetry became assimilated to the Greek. That ballads were sung among the early Romans, we may readily presume. The fact is common to almost all coun- tries. But that there existed poems of considerable bulk, embodying a large proportion of that which we now read as Livy's prose, is by no means to be presumed without proof ; though, if the fact could be proved, it would be an interest- ing accession to our knowledge. Now no such poems were known to the Romans of the historical ag:e. It is true that the incidents themselves are often of a cast highly romantic and poetical ; and upon this ground chiefly the inference is founded, that they must have been derived from poems. But such inference is shown by Sir George Lewis to be un- warranted. Licidents of a romantic character may be real, and are accepted as such if properly attested. The career of Alexander the Great is as full of romance as that of Coriolanus : the suicide of Cleopatra is intrinsically not less poetical than that of Lucretia ; while that of the Emperor ON EARLY ROMAN HISTORY. 219 Otho is more sublime and impressive than either. Moreover, the early Eoman history, though partly poetical in its incidents, is in still larger measure wholly unpoetical : the ballad-theory, even if admitted, accounts for the smaller portion only ; not for the larger, nor yet for the mixture of the two. Lastly, Niebuhr supposes that the incidents of these ballad-poems were generally fictitious : but if this be granted, the hypothesis of poems becomes unnecessary : the origin of fictitious stories may be suflBciently explained by oral tradition alone, without any poems, written or un- written : — " There is nothing in the fictitious part of the early Eoman history which may not be accounted for, by supposing that it con- sists of legends floating in the popular memory, composed of elements partly real but chiefly unreal, and moulded into a con- nected form as they passed from mouth to mouth ; the picturesque, interesting, or touching incidents being selected, and the whole grouped and coloui*ed by the free pencil of tradition. Even these legends would be improved and polished by the successive histo- rians through whose hands they passed, after they had been once reduced to writing. Such an origin would account for their poetical features without supposing them derived from a metrical original — from a poem in the proper sense of the word." (Vol. i. p. 221.) " The theory of Niebuhr is unsupported by evidence sufficient to prove its truth; and, even if it were proved, would afford little or no assistance towards solving the most difficult and important problem of this history. That there were poems of some sort composed in the Latin language, before the time of Livius, Naevius, and Ennius, cannot be doubted : the prohibition of defa- matory verses, in the laws of the Twelve Tables, is an undoubted proof of the practice of the poetic art among the Eomans in the year b.c. 450. But all positive evidence and all arguments from analogy and probability conspire to prove, that the Latin language at this time was in a rude, uncultivated state, unsuited to poetical treatment ; that the old native Saturnian metre, which Horace stigmatises as imfit for the contact of civilised life, was rough, inharmonious, and scarcely distinguishable from prose ; and that the early Komans, however poetical may have been the ideas in which they conceived their ancient annals and the exploits of their forefathers, were principally occupied with military pursuits, and 220 EEYIEW OF SIR G. C. LEWIS bestowed little thouglit on poetry or tlie fine arts " (Vol. i. p. 235.) Niebuhr's ' Theory of Epic Lays/ therefore, cannot be accepted as the source of any considerable portion of the details of early Roman history. For these details no source can be assigned except oral statements and traditions ; many of them, doubtless, current in the great families, respecting their distinguished ancestors (^vhose waxen images were preserved, and carried in funeral processions), and first embodied in a written continuous history by Fabius and his successors. Upon " the substratum of notation " was thus at length erected a fabric of history. " There was a eontinuons list of magistrates, more or less com- plete and authentic, ascending to the commencement of the consular government ; from the burning of the city, there was a series of meagre official annals, kept by the chiqf pontiff; many ancient treaties and texts of laws, including the Twelve Tables, were pre- served, together with notes of ancient usages and rules of customary law, civil and religious, recorded in the books of the pontiffs and some of the civil magistrates ; and these documentary sources of history, which furnished merely the dry skeleton of a narrative, were clothed with flesh and muscle by the addition of various stories handed down from preceding times by oral tradition. Some assistance may have been derived from popular songs, and still more from family memoirs ; but there is nothing to make it pro- bable that private families began to record the deeds of their dis- tinguished members before any chronicler had arisen for the events which interested the commonwealth as a whole." (Vol. i. p. 243.) "We think that this is a correct statement of the means of information possessed by the Eoman annalists of B.C. 210, and later, when they undertook to draw up a history of Eome, beginning with B.C. 753, and even earlier ; 472 years before the war with Pyrrhus, and 540 years before their own times. It is to be remarked that the ^^ notation " ascends only to the commencement of the Eepublic ; but the details are carried 244 years higher, throughout the kingly period, and even more. The whole of the kingly period is an ON EAKLY KOMAN HISTORY. 221 assemblage of oral details, uncontrolled by any ascertainable notation. Having laid down these principles as to the sources of early Eoman history, Sir George Lewis illustrates them by analysing the received narrative, from the earliest times to the landing of Pyrrhus in Italy. He distributes it into six portions : — 1. The primitive history and ethnology of Italy. 2. The settlement of .^neas in Italy. 3. The Alban king- dom and the foundation of Rome. 4. The period of the seven kings of Rome. 5. The period from the expulsion of the kings to the capture of the city by the Gauls. 6. The period from the capture of the city by the Gauls to the war with Pyrrhus. " These six periods (observes Sir G. Lewis, p. 266) it will be convenient to investigate separately ; as their historical character, and the proportion in which fact and fiction are mixed, differ considerably." The distinction here drawn, as to proportions of fact and fiction, appears to us true only respecting the last three of the six periods, — hardly true respecting the first three. It is to the two last periods, comprising together the early history of the Republic, that we must devote all the remarks which our space will allow : but we cannot pass over the four first without stating generally, that Sir G. Lewis has conse- crated to them two chapters of abundant erudition with an excellent running commentary. In perusing the multifarious discrepancies, the fanciful adventures, and the licence of de- tailed assertion, which these chapters set forth, we see what Fabius, Cinciiis, Cato, &c., with their full religious and pa- triotic faith, were content to accept as their national history. We can take measure of their critical judgment and canon of credibility. There was, however, a considerable difi*erence in this point between Fabius and Cato on the one hand, and writers a century or a century and a half later (such as Cicero, Atticus, Varro, Livy, &c.) on the other. The latter not only censure the chronological ignorance of their pre- decessors {e.g. the description of Numa as a disciple of Pytha- 222 REVIEW OF SIR G. C. LEWIS goras), but also seek to rationalise (much to the displeasure of Dionysius of Halicarnassus), the miraculous stories and divine interventions — such as the suckling of Eomulus and Eemus by a she-wolf, and the interviews of Kuma with the nymph Egeria (Vol. i. pp. 402-48).* In Chapter xii., occupying about the first half of Sir George Lewis's second volume, the Koman history is analysed, from the expulsion of the kings to the burning of the city : an in- terval of about 120 years (b.c. 510-390). Its earliest portion includes the wars carried on by the nascent Eepublic against the Tarquinian exiles ; who were aided, first by the Etruscan Porsena, next by the Latins mustered in arms at Eegillus, and there totally defeated. These incidents are given with many details, often highly picturesque and interesting. They are supposed by Niebuhr to have formed the subject of one of the epic lays : but even if this were granted, we must suppose something like them to have floated probably in the form of oral narrative or legend. Yet Pliny had seen a treaty between Porsena and the Eomans, whereby the * It appears that Yarro and his immediate j^redecessors and contemporaries were the first to bring into historical notice many memorials then existing of Eoman registered antiquity which had been unknown to, or overlooked by, preceding annalists, such as Fabius and Cato. The " substratum of notation," composed as it was of unconnected fragments, became thus more fully explored and better understood in b.c. 50, than it had been a century before, in B.C.- 150. Hence arise in part the discrepancies recited by Livy and Dionysius. The writers of the Yarronian age differed from their predecessors because they had consulted new matters of evidence. This comparison of the age of Yarro with that of Fabius is much insisted on in a recent work of learning and research pub- lished last year at Basle, L. 0. Brocker, Untersuchungen uber die Glnuhwurdigkeit der alt-BdmiscJien Gescliiclite. Brocker notes espe- cially that the Yarronians treated the Eegal period more briefly, and the Eepublican period far more copiously, than Fabius and Cato, the new matters of evidence relating apparently to the Eepublic only. See the second of Brocker's Ahhandhngen, pp. 41-82. ON EABLY ROMAN HISTORY. 223 latter became bound to the humiliating condition of not using iron for any other purposes than those of agriculture. This treaty cannot be reconciled with the accounts which we read of the wars between the Eomans and Porsena. The oral details and the " notation " are here at variance. While setting forth the ancient statements respecting these wars, with his usual fulness of reference, Sir George Lewis touches on the first nomination of a dictator at Rome. That Titus Lartius was the first dictator, and that he was appointed during one of the years not long preceding the battle of Regillus, is affirmed both by Livy and by Dionysius. As to the precise year they do not agree : nor does Liyy give many antecedent particulars — not knowing which to prefer among the dissentient accounts before him. Diony- sius, however, — to whom, as a Greek, the dictatorial office seemed probably more striking and peculiar than it did to Livy, — works up one of these narratives at great length : — " Dionysius g^Ves the detailed account of the dictatorship, and of the appointment of the first dictator, as if it was as well ascer- tained as the history of the creation of the first presidency of the India Board, and the appointment of the first president, under the administration of Mr. Pitt. He knows not only the causes which led to the creation of the office, but also the various stages of the proceedings, the debates in the senate, the speeches of the senators, the motives of their policy, the mutual feelings of delicacy, and all the other material circumstances of the transaction. "The long and detailed account of the creation of the office of dictator appears to belong to a class of fictions, of which we meet with many examples in the early Eoman history, and which we may call institutional legends. The whole narrative of Dionysius is plainly a political drama, invented to explain the very peculiar institution of the Eoman dictatorship : the officer being supreme and absolute, although for a limited time ; the senate being judges of the necessity of the appointment, and the appointment being made by one of the consuls." (Vol. ii. pp. 27-46.) Among the Eoman " institutional legends " — which, let it be observed, even if Niebuhr's epic lays existed, can hardly have been embodied in them, and can be referred to no other 224 REVIEW OF SIR G. C. LEWIS source than oral narrative — one of the most curious is, the first secession of the Plebs, and the first appointment of tri- bunes of the people (b. c. 492 ), about seven years after the earliest dictator. The recital is set forth and examined by- Sir George Lewis pp. 62-88. It is given in minute detail and with long harangues intermixed, by Dionysius. Livy tells the story more briefly. Cicero and other authors touch on it incidentally. The Roman annalists, in recounting the circumstances of this event (more than 250 years prior to the earliest of them ) can have had no other authority than oral in- formants. In analysing the narrative, Sir George Lewis farther seeks to show that the internal discrepancies and inconsistencies are so serious as to exclude the possibility of any better authority. Now we cannot think that this latter part of his case is fully made out. It seems to us that he overrates the magnitude of the discrepancies ; that they, are neither inexplicable, nor greater than might well have occurred between witnesses all contemporaneous. It is true that Dionysius and Livy differ as to the nature of the treaty which the senate were obliged to conclude with the exasperated plebeians, after the latter had seceded to the Mons Sacer. " According to Dionysius, the main subject of the negotiation was a Seisachtheia, for the relief of the plebeian debtors. When this measure had been conceded, the institution of the tribunes was suggested by Lucius Junius Brutus, as an additional guarantee ; and this after-thought was made the subject of a separate nego- tiation. Livy is entirely silent as to any arrangement about a remission of debts, and describes the compact as limited to the institution of tribunes. Cicero agrees with Livy, and considers the tribunate as the sole result of the first secession."^ (Vol. ii. p. 77.) We admit that Liyy says nothing about a remission of debts. But we contend that this is an omission on his part : that his own narrative implies virtually the fact of such remission having been granterl, so as to be hardly consistent ON EAELY ROMAN HISTORY. 225 with itself, unless upon that hypothesis. He had told us explicitly that the cause which drove the plebeians to the desperate measure of secession,* was, the cruel suffering in- flicted upon the great multitude of them by debt, and by the law which made the insolvent debtor the slave of his creditor: that the liberal patricians had been doing their utmost, though in vain, to procure for them relief from such suffering : and that the very last act which precipitated the secession was, the abdication of the popular dictator (Valerius) in disgust, because he could not prevail on the senate to grant any relief. Assuming this state of things, how can it be believed that the plebeians, when they became masters of the situation and forced the senate to offer terms, demanded no redress of this severe and present grievance ; and that they were satisfied with the prospective benefit to be derived from appointing two tribunes, about whom before not a word had been said ? To confirm our view — that Livy's own account requires us to assume a remission of debts as having been granted — we may add, that after having dwelt so much upon the pressure of debt before the secession, he says nothing more about it after the secession : the grievance disappears for a long series of years. Turning to Dionysius, we find that his account is con- sistent, complete, and natural. The plebeians had seceded on account of debt : the first concession whereby the intimi- dated senate try to pacify them is a promise of relief from debt : and with this the plebeians are so overjoyed that they are not disposed of themselves to demand more. But their long-sighted leader, L. Junius, reminds them that their only guarantee for the observance of the promise is, that they should have tribunes of their own appointment, and with powers adequate to their protection. The tribunes are thus (to use the phrase of Sir George Lewis) " an afterthought ; " they are not a substitute for debt-relief, but a guarantee for its accomplishment. * Livy, vol. ii. pp. 23, 27, 31. — " Totam plebem sere alieno demersam esse," &c. Q 226 REVIEW OF SIR G. C. LEWIS In regard to the passage of Cicero, we agree rather with the interpretation of Niebuhr than with that of Sir George Lewis. We think that Cicero (like Liyy) says what implies that a remission of debts must have been granted.* And it appears to us that an historian who finds himself in the presence of three such accounts as those of Dionysius, Livy, and Cicero, is warranted in supplying out of the first that fact which, though not expressly mentioned by the other two, is required to make each of them consistent with himself. Sir George Lewis pursues his minute analysis of the con- tradictions and incoherences which pervade the immediately succeeding period of Eoman history — the story of Coriola- nas — that of Spurius Cassius, the proposer of the first agra- rian law — the expedition and death of the three hundred Fabii, &c. All these are details which must have been de- rived by the annalist from oral communication. Yet in the midst of them the " substratum of notation " occasionally crops * The passage of Cicero is in the Fragment Be Bej)uhlicd, ii. 33, 34. Cicero states, as explicitly as Dionysius and Livy, that the cause which brought about the suffering and secession of the plebeians, was the pressure of their private debts. The senate (he adds) might have applied a measure of relief to this grievance of debt, but they let slip the oj)portumty of doing so. Accordingly, they were constrained at last to submit to a concession much more formidable to their own power — the creation of the tribunate. " Quo tiun consilio pr^etermisso, causa populo nata est, duobus tri- bunis plebis per seditionem creatis, ut potentia senatus atque auctoritas minueretur." If the Senate were forced ultimately to make a more serious concession, this proves that the mutinous debtors had acquired increased strength. How then is it credible that they should become willing to bear the pressure of debt, which they had mutinied in order to escape ? The tribunate in itself could not mitigate this grievance. Cicero means (in om* judgment) that the Senate, having refused to grant a measm^e of debt-relief in time, when it would have given satisfaction, were forced, when the discontent ripened into irresistible mutiny, to grant, not only this debt-relief, but something much greater besides. ON EAELY ROMAN. HISTORY. 227 out, thus (B.C. 462), we have : — " Many of the notices are of a character which seem to betoken contemporaneous regis- tration, such for instance, as the consecration of the temple of Dins Fidius on the nones of June, on the Quirinal hill, by the Consul Spurius Posthumius, in the year 466 B.C." (Vol. ii. p. 162) — and the punishment of two Vestal Virgins, Opimia and Orbinia (Vol. ii. pp. 141, 152, 183), who were buried alive for unchastity. This punishment was probably registered in the Pontifical Annals, since it had a salutary effect, as we learn from Livy and Dionysius, in appeasing the anger of the Gods, recently manifested in alarming- prodigies. To the Decemviral Government an elaborate section is devoted (Vol. ii. pp. 161, 252). These Decemvirs were named, after eleven years of plebeian importunity, to prepare written laws for rendering the administration of the Consuls both determinate in its principles and equal in its operation on patricians as well as plebeians. They composed the Twelve Tables — the earliest authentic monument of Eoman law. The history of the Decemvirate — given in detail by Livy, and in still greater detail by Dionysius — is " the institutional legend " respecting the origin, promulgation, and authors of these memorable and much admired tables. We agree with Sir George Lewis that this narrative must have been first put together by annalists long posterior, mainly from oral report; and that its credibility must be estimated accordingly. But we cannot think that the proof of this point is strengthened by his analysis of the texture of the narrative, nor that the internal difficulties and discrepan- cies are so grave as he represents. That which he conceives as a tissue of improbabilities is so far from appearing in the same light to Dionysius, that the latter (x. 1) expressly takes credit for furnishing on this occasion a philosophical and in- structive recital. The character and proceedings of the chief Decemvir Appius do not appear to us unnatural, nor do we feel the embarrassments started by Sir George Lewis. Why did Appius (it is asked) resign his place in the decemvirate Q 2 228 REVIEW OF SIR G. C. LEWIS after the first year, and thus expose himself to the chance of not being re-elected ? (Vol. ii. p. 229.) We may surely answer — Because those who had been his colleagues during the meritorious proceedings of the first year, would not have been suitable for the atrocities of the second. Then by what force were Appius and his second colleagues enabled to tyrannise with temporary impunity ? " We hear (says Sir George Lewis) of no instruments of their power, except a/ew clubs or associations of young patricians, who are paid for their services by confiscated property." These ivere the instruments of the decemviral tyranny ; and they appear to us, as they appeared to Dionysius and Livy, sufficient for the purpose. These historians do not recognise the attenuating numerical adjective, a few : Dionysius even mentions (x. 60) bands of poor and reckless satellites enlisted by the decem- virs, in addition to the patrician youth. Moreover Livy expressly states that the only sufferers by the decemviral tyranny were the plebeians ; that among the patrician order, the younger men, who formed the real force, were gainers in every way ; and that even the elder or senatorial patricians, who disliked the decemvirs, disliked the suffering plebeians as much or more, were pleased to see them humbled, and even aggravated their humiliation by insult.* With such antipathy and mistrust between the two orders, and with such an amount of positive support from the more power- ful of the two, the Decemvirs possessed ample means of maintaining their tyranny during eighteen months, not to say longer. * Livy, iii. 36, 37. " Aliquamdiu sequatus inter omnes terror fuit ; paulatim totus verier e inplebem coepiL Ahstinehatur a Patribus : in huiniliores libidinose crudeliterque consulebatur ; hominum, non causarnm, toti erant : ut apud quos gratia vim sequi haberet." " Primores Patrum odisse Decemviros, odisse plebem ; nee probare, quae fierent ; et credere, baud indignis accidere. Avide ruendo in libertatem lapses juvare nolle : cumulare quoque injurias, ut tsedio praBsentium eonsules duo tandem et status pristinus rerum in desiderium venirent." ON EARLY ROMAN HISTORY. 229 Again " We might have expected " (says Sir George Lewis, p. 238), "judging by the other atrocities ascribed to Appius, that he would have caused Virginia to be seized without the formalities of a public trial, and that he would have im- prisoned or killed her relatives and protectors." It might have been safer for him if he had done so. But Dionysius describes it as the ordinary practice of the Decemvirs in their tyranny, to suborn accusers and pronounce iniquitous judgments : when this had been done in a long series of cases without resistance, Appius did not sufficiently calculate the chances of resistance in a new case. Nor can we wonder that he did not anticipate the tragical event of a father publicly stabbing his own daughter in the forum. These and other embarrassments which a critical inquirer brings to view in the Decemviral history, are all very proper for notice. But we think that they are by no means inca- pable of solution : that the author himself, if he had been writing a work of history instead of criticism, would easily have found solutions : and that they are no greater than an historian, who has the advantage of contemporary authorities, must often be prepared to solve. Though poorly furnished as to external attestation, the story in its internal texture appears to us more plausible and coherent than his book exhibits it. During the sixty years between the fall of the Decemvirs and the Gallic capture, the internal history of Eome be- tokens a forward movement on the part of the plebeians. The demand made by the latter for equal admissibility to the consulship, is refused by the patricians ; who are, however, obliged to make the concession of substituting, in place of consuls, new magistrates entitled military tribunes (with powers nearly approaching to those of the consuls), among whom plebeians were eligible. These consular tribunes, with many alternating years of patrician consulship, con- tinued for seventy-seven years, when the Licinian laws re-established the consulship, with the peremptory en- 230 REVIEW OF SIR G. C. LEWIS actment that one of the two consuls must be a plebeian. Respecting the historical character of this period, our author observes, — '' After the year B.C. 367, we hear no more of consular tribunes, and the office disappears from the Fasti. With the exception of the account of the first election of consular tribunes, the history of this magistracy during the seventy-seven years of its existence is consistent, coherent, and intelligible ; and the historical nar- rative supports and explains the lists of names in the tables of magistrates. So far, therefore, as the internal evidence goes, it confirms the authenticity of the traditionary accounts of the period in question." (Vol. ii. p. 396.) Here we have " the substratum of notation " and the traditionary details in a state of admitted harmony. Sir George Lewis pursues his analysis of the history through the 110 years between the Gallic capture and the landing of Pyrrhus. Though he still detects many contradictions and inconsistencies, they do not appear to him so glaring as those of the former period. As to the foreign wars with the Gauls, indeed, there are discrepancies impossible to reconcile between Polybius and Livy ; as to those with the Latins and Samnites, there are no such grave contradictions, though much is obscure and uncertain. Among the internal affairs of Rome, we commend to particular attention what is said about the Agrarian Laws, which are handled in a manner extremely perspicuous and instructive. (Vol. ii. p. 137, 183, 384.) Some proofs are also adduced (which might probably be multiplied) of the continuance of the contemporary regis- tration for various isolated facts. (Vol. ii. p. 483-6.) On the whole, the facts and narratives indicate that we are approaching towards that clearer sunlight of history which begins to prevail for the times after Pyrrhus. Having performed this dissection of the evidences, with many most profitable comments upon Niebuhr, Arnold, and other previous expositors, Sir George Lewis adds a con- cluding chapter, summing up the general results of his inquiry, and illustrating his reasonings by comparisons with ON EARLY ROMAN HISTORY. 231 Grecian history. We have no space to dwell upon these pertinent and well-chosen analogies, and can only advert to the general conclusion. Eemarking that as the different schools of historical criticism agree in considering attestation by contemporary witnesses as the essential condition for justifying belief in an alleged fact, he thus proceeds : — " The maiQ difference between the divergent schools is as to the extent to which contemporary attestation may be presumed without direct and positive proof. Both assume the same mode of proving an historical fact : but the former refuse to infer the proof from the existence of an oral tradition ; the latter consider that inference legitimate. The former deny that the existence of a popular belief with respect to the past, derived from oral reports, raises a pre- sumption that the events narrated were at the time of their sup- posed occurrence observed by credible witnesses, and by them handed down to posterity. The latter, on the other hand, hold that the existence of such a popular belief (combined perhaps with some accessory circumstances) authorises the conclusion that the current story was derived from credible contemporary witnesses, and has descended from them in a substantially unfalsified state." .... " The difference between the opposite opinions on this subject is therefore a difference of degree rather than of principle. Nobody asserts that all history must be taken directly from the reports of percipient witnesses. No historian applies the strict rule of judi- cial evidence, that all hearsay reports are to be discarded. In treating of the period which precedes contemporary history, all persons admit traditionary, secondary, or hearsay evidence, up to a certain point. The question is, where that point ought to be fixed?" (Vol. ii. p. 490.) After a few words (p. 494) upon the " difficulties which beset the application of rules of evidence to the semi-historical or crepuscular period, — a period of which some knowledge has been preserved, though by imperfect means, and in a dete- riorated state," — the last result is thus given : — " All the historical lajbour bestowed upon the early centuries of Eome will, in general, be wasted. The history of this period, viewed as a series of picturesque narratives, will be read to the greatest advantage in the original writers, and will be deteriorated by reproduction in a modern dress. If we regard a historical 232 EEVIEW OF SIR G. C. LEWIS painting merely as a work of art, the accounts of the ancients can only suffer from being retouched by the pencil of the modern restorer. On the other hand, all attempts to reduce them to a purely historical form, by conjectural omissions, additions, alterations, and transpositions, must be nugatory." " Those who are disposed to labour in the field of Eoman history will find a worthier reward for their toils, if they employ them- selves upon the time subsequent to the Italian expedition of Pyrrhus." ....** In this history, much must remain incomplete, uncertain, and unknown : but the great outlines are as firmly marked as in a modern history, composed with brighter lights and from ampler materials : and the historical inquirer will meet with a richer return for his labours, than if he bewildered himself with vain attempts to distinguish between fact and fiction, in the accounts of the foundation of Eome, the constitution of Servius, the expulsion of Tarquin, the war with Porsena, the creation of the dictatorship and tribunate, the decemviral legislation, the siege of Veii and the capture of Kome by the Gauls ; or even the Licinian rogations, and the Samnite Wars." (Vol. ii. p. 556.) We subscribe to these conclusions fully, so far as regards Eoman history under the kings and prior to the Eepublic. As to the period of the Eepublic, we cannot adopt them without some qualification. Sir George Lewis fairly states the question : It being admitted, that there is a certain point antecedent to the beginning of contemporary history, up to which point historical research is legitimate and rea- sonable — where is this terminus to be fixed in regard to Eome ? He would fix it at the landing of Pyrrhus in Italy, But we submit that this is within the actual limits of con- temporary Grecian authorship, and, in a certains ense, even of Eoman authorship — through the speech of Appius in the Senate, which was preserved to later times. This terminus is therefore too low to correspond with the principles laid down. The Licinian laws can hardly be thrown into the category of the unsearchable — along with the foundation of Eome. In fixing the upward terminus, we perceive no index so ap- propriate as the beginning of contemporary notation ; which is, in truth, contemporary history in fragment and rudiment. ON EARLY ROMAN HISTORY. 233 Wherever matters of fact and of public import were recorded, even though detached and without coherence, historical re- search becomes admissible. Now in Eome, " the substratum of notation " can be traced up to the commencement of the Eepublic, but not higher. No similar notation belongs to the regal period : at least, if any such existed, it never crops out, but is irrevocably sub- merged and undiscernible. Accordingly, the suitable upward terminus for historical research is, in our view, the commence- ment of the Eepublic. We consider the kingly period as lying above the limit of historical research, and as " a series of picturesque narratives" in which no matter of fact had ever any recorded existence apart from fiction. Comparing Eoman with Grecian history, we regard (conformably to Sir George Lewis's view) all that precedes the Eoman Eepublic as corresponding to heroic or legendary Greece ; we consider the first two centuries of the Republic as corresponding to Greece between the first recorded Olympiad (776 B.C.) and the year 500 B.C. To the first of the two, the microscope of the historian is inapplicable. Eespecting the second, we cannot say the same ; for there are, or were, some recorded realities which an attentive contemplation may hope to magnify and bring into fuller day-light, both in themselves and in the consequences deducible from them. This is the only line of demarcation which we see any theoretical reason for drawing. Whether the researches into the history of the early Eepublic will turn out very fruitful, or will yield much of new certainty and new probability, is a different question. We are not sanguine in hoping that they will: but neither are we sanguine respecting those investigations, recommended by Sir George Lewis as pre- ferable, into the later history of the Eoman Eepublic ; where there w^as once much contemporary information, now entirely lost, and represented by little except the Epitomes of Livy. What we expect from farther study of the early Eepublic, is, not so much a corrected version of the facts of detail, as better and clearer views of the institutional practice and 234 REVIEW OF SIR G. C. LEWIS development, gathered by combination, inference, and cau- tious hypothesis, from a variety of distinct sources. Books on Roman antiquities (especially the excellent work of Becker and Marquardt) already teach us much respecting the magistracies and constitutional growth of the Republic : but we acquire no knowledge (beyond the literal statements as they stand) respecting the period of the Kings. And though there is much fanciful conjecture in Niebuhr, it is indisputable that many portions of Roman republican anti- quity (the Agrarian Laws especially) are far better under- stood than they were before his writings. Discountenancing as Sir George Lewis does all historical inquiry into Roman history anterior to Pyrrhus, it is natural that he should pronounce, as to that period, "All attempts to reduce the accounts of the ancients to an historical form by conjectural omissions, additions, alterations, and transpositions, must be nugatory." This is perfectly true respecting the period of the Kings, but we are not prepared to pronounce the like peremptory verdict (must) about the first two centuries of the Republic. The former (as we have above remarked) contains none of the genuine materials of history ; the latter contains some, in greater or less propor- tion. Li our view, wherever the genuine materials of history exist, all the processes above indicated are frequently indis- pensable, to bring out of them either continuous narrative or determinate results. It is by going through such elaboration that history is distinguished from a mere collection of depo- sitions. The manner in which Sir George Lewis sets forth the discrepancies between Livy and Dionysius, and the tone of his criticisms on Niebuhi', tend to suggest two impressions, which we are by no means sure that he would sanction, but from which we certainly dissent. 1. That discrepancies, as many and as great, are not to be foimd between contem- porary witnesses. 2. That the Niebuhrian spirit of hypo- thesis and recombination is illegitimate in principle, — not simply objectionable from abusive excess in Niebuhr's hands. ON EARLY ROMAN HISTORY. 235 Now we think that contemporary witnesses often form a multitude with every variety of dissonance and contradic- tion :* and that if, out of such perplexities, an historian is to construct a narrative setting forth the true or the probable, he cannot proceed without a large latitude of preference and hypothesis. Even with the most unexceptionable historians — with Gibbon or Mr. Hallam — the narrative supplied to the reader is a result put together in their own minds, founded upon an attentive study of all the evidences, yet not without many inferences, comparisons, and eliminations of their own. Neither of these authors could have performed his task, if " conjectural omission, addition, alteration, and transposition," had been forbidden. We know that these liberties are liable to much abuse, and that they have been abused by Niebuhr. * As a parallel to the discrepancies between Livy and Dionysius, we transcribe the following account of the original authorities respecting the wars in La Vendee, from the beginning of 1793 downwards. We have here contemporary witnesses, under the full publicity of modern times, described by M. Michelet, eminent both as an historian and as a laborious examiner of original archives. (Histotre de la Revolution Frangaise, vol. vii. p. 78.) " Le livre le plus instructif sur Thistoire de la Vendee ( j'allais dire, le seul) est celui de Savary, pere du membre de I'Academie des Sciences : Guerres des Vendeens, par un officier, 1824. Dans les autres, il y a peu a prendre. Ce sont des romans, qui ne soutiennent pas I'examen : les noms, les dates, les faits, presque tout y est inexact, faux, impudemment surcharge de fictions. Je le sais maintenant a mes depens, apres avoir perdu des annees dans la critique inutile de ces deplorables livres. Savary donne les vraies dates, et un nombre immense de pieces : les notes de Cauclaux, de Kleber, d'Oppenheim, y ajoutent un prix inestimable." We know the work of Savary, and can certify that it fully merits the encomiums bestowed upon it by M. Michelet. But to compose such a work, requires a combination of ability, diligence, and oppor- tunity, such as are rarely brought together in the same person. How many periods are there of human affairs, in which there are contemporary authors approximating to the dark side of Michelet's picture, without any such witness to control them as Savary ! 236 REVIEW OF SIR G. C. LEWIS, ETC. But in commending a salutary vigilance of criticism on this eminent man, in so many instances of his arbitrary dealing with evidence, we must at the same time guard against what appears to us an opposite extreme. We cannot dis- allow the constructive imagination of the historian, nor lighten his responsibility by tying him down to a literal sequence. While claiming for historians this freedom of judgment, in their laborious task of eliciting probability out of con- flicting statements and analogies, we should be glad if it could always be exercised subject to such a censorship as that of Sir George Lewis. No man interested either in ancient history or in the general theory of historical study, can read his book without profit ; but none will profit by it so much as those who, adopting his conclusions only in part, account the first two centuries of the Eoman Eepublic a subject still open to historical research and philosophical explanation. PLATO'S DOCTEINE RESPECTING THE ROTATION OF THE EARTH, AND ARISTOTLE'S COMMENT UPON THAT DOCTRINE. 1860. Examination of tJie three following Questions : — 1. Whether the Doctrine of the Ea^rth's Eotation is affirmed OR IMPLIED IX the PlATONIC TiM.EUS ? 2. If AFFIRMED OR EMPLIED, FN" WHAT SENSE ? 3. What is the Cosmical Function which Plato assigns to the Earth in the Tim.eus? PLATO-ON THE EARTH'S ROTATION- The following paper was originally intended as an explana- tory note on the Platonic Timeeus, in the work which I am now preparing on Plato and Aristotle. Interpreting, differ- ently from others, the much debated passage in which Plato describes the cosmical function of the Earth, I found it indispensable to give my reasons for this new view. But I soon discovered that those reasons could not be comprised within the limits of a note. Accordingly I here publish them in a separate Dissertation. The manner in which the Earth's rotation was conceived, illustrates the scientific cha- racter of the Platonic and Aristotelian age, as contrasted with the subsequent development and improvement of astro- nomy. In Plato, Timseus, p. 40 B, we read the following words — Trjv Se Tpo(f>bv fxev f)jbL€Tepav, elXKofievrjv Se irepl top Sea iravro^ TToXov rerafievov (j^vKaKa /cat Brjficovpyov vvkt6<; re kol ri/j,€pa<^ i/ii7]'^av7](TaTo, Trpcorrjv kol Trpeo-^vrdrTjv 6eo)v, ocrot eWo? ou- pdvov yeyovaac, I give the text as it stands in Stallbaum's edition. The obscurity of this passage is amply attested by the numerous differences of opinion to which it has given rise, both in ancient and in modern times. Various contempo- raries of Plato (€1/^06— Aristot. De Coelo, II. 13, p. 293 b. 30) understood it as asserting or implying the rotatory movement of the earth in the centre of the Kosmos, and adhered to this doctrine as their own. Aristotle himself alludes to these 240 PLATCyS DOCTRINE contemporaries without naming them, and adopts their in- terpretation of the passage ; but dissents from the doctrine, and proceeds to impugn it by arguments. Cicero mentions (Academic. II. 39) that there were persons who believed Plato to have indicated the same doctrine obscurely, in his Timaeus : this passage must undoubtedly be meant. Plu- tarch devotes a critical chapter to the enquiry, what was Plato's real doctrine as to the cosmical function of the earth — its movement or rest (Quaestion. Platonic. VIL 3, p. 1006). There exists a treatise, in Doric dialect, entitled Tcfiaico 7(0 Ao/cpco Hepl '^u^a? Koct/jlco koX cf>vaLo<;, — which is usually published along with the works of Plato. This treatise was supposed in ancient times to be a genuine production of the Lokrian Timaeus, whom Plato introduces as his spokesman in the dialogue so called. As such, it was considered to be of much authority in settling questions of interpretation as to the Platonic Timaeus. But modem critics hold, I believe unanimously, that it is the work of some later Pythagorean or Platonist, excerpted or copied from the Platonic Timaeus. This treatise represents the earth as being in the centre and at rest. But its language, besides being dark and meta- phorical, departs widely from the phraseology of the Platonic Timaeus: especially in this — that it makes no mention of the cosmical axis, nor of the word IXXofxevrjv or elXovfievrjv. Alexander of Aphrodisias (as we learn from Simplikius ad Aristot. De Coelo, fol. 126) followed the construction of Plato given by Aristotle. " It was improbable (he said) that Ari- stotle could be ignorant either what the word signified, or what was Plato's purpose " (aWa tcS 'ApiaroTeXet, (prjalv^ ovTco XiyovTL tWeaOai, ov/c evXoyov avriXeyeiv' a)9 aXrj- 6w jcip ovT€ T779 Xe^eco9 to o-rj/juaLvojubevov 66/^09 rjv dyvoelv avTov, 0VT6 TOP TlXdTcovo<; gkottov. This passage is not given in the Scholia of Brandis). Alexander therefore construed lXXo/jL€V7]v as meaning or implying rotatory movement, though in so doing he perverted (so Simplikius says) the true meaning to make it consonant with his own suppo- sitions. ON THE ROTATION OF THE EARTH. 241 Proklus maintains that Aristotle has interpreted the pas- sage erroneously, — that iKKofievriv is equivalent to <7<^t7- jofiivrjp or ^vve')(piJb'€vr}v — and that Plato intends by it to affirm the earth as at rest in the centre of the Kosmos (ad Timaeum, Book iv., p. 681 ed. Schneider). Simplikius himself is greatly perplexed, and scarcely ventures to give a positive opinion of his own. On the whole, he inclines to believe that IWojbiivrjv might possibly be understood, by superficial readers, so as to signify rotation, though such is not its proper and natural sense : that some Piatonists did so mis- understand it : and that Aristotle accepted their sense for the sake of the argument, without intending himself to coun- tenance it (ad Aristot. De Coelo, p. 126). Both Proklus and Simplikius, we must recollect, believed in the genuineness of the Doric treatise ascribed to Timaeus Locrus. Eeasoning upon this basis, they of course saw, that if Aristotle had correctly interpreted Plato, Plato himself must have interpreted incorrectly the doctrine of Timaeus. They had to ascribe wrong construction either to Plato or to Aristotle : and they could not bear to ascribe it to Plato. Alkinous, in his Eisagoge (c. 15) gives the same interpre- tation as Proklus. But it is remarkable that in his para- phrase of the Platonic words, he calls the earth r}iJL€pa<;^v\a^ Kol vvkt6<; : omitting the significant epithet STj/jnovpyof;. In regard to modern comments upon the same disputed point, I need only mention (besides those of M. Cousin, in the notes upon his translation of the ' Timaeus,' and of Martin in his ' Etudes sur le Timee ') the elaborate discussion which it has received in the two recent Dissertations ' Ueber die kosmischen Systeme der Griechen,' by Gruppe and Boeckh. Gruppe has endeavoured, upon the evidence of this passage, supported by other collateral proofs, to show that Plato, towards the close of his life, arrived at a belief, first, in the rotation of the earth round its own axis, next, at the double movement of the earth, both rotation and translation, round the sun as a centre (that is, the heliocentric or Copernican system) : that Plato was the first to make this discovery, but R 242 PLATO'S DOCTRINE that he was compelled to announce it in terms intentionally equivocal and obscure, for fear of offending the religious sentiments of his contemporaries (^ Die kosmischen Systeme der Griechen,' by O. F. Gruppe, Berlin. 1851). To tbis dis- sertation ]\L Boeekh — the oldest as well as the ablest of all living philologists — has composed an elaborate reply, with his usual fulness of illustrative matter and sobriety of infer- ence. Opinions previously delivered by him (in his early treatises on the Platonic and Pythagorean philosophy) had been called in question by Gruppe : he has now re-' asserted them and defended them at length, maintaining that Plato always held the earth to be stationary and the sidereal sphere rotatory ; and answering or extenuating the arguments which point to an opposite conclusion (' Unter- suchungen iiber das kosmische System des Platon/ by August Boeekh, Berlin, 1852). Gruppe has failed in his purpose of proving that Plato adopted either of the two above-mentioned doctrines — either the rotation of the earth round its own axis, or the trans- lation of the earth round the sun as a centre. On both these points I concur with Boeekh in the negative view. But though I go along with his reply as to its negative results, I cannot think it satisfactory in its positive aspect as an exposition of the doctrine proclaimed in the Platonic Timseus : nor can I admit that the main argument of M. Boeckh's treatise is sufficient to support the inference which he rests upon it. Moreover, he appears to me to set aside or explain away too lightly the authority of Aristotle. I agree with Alexander of Aphrodisias and with Gruppe who follows him, in pronouncing Aristotle to be a good witness, when he declares what were the doctrines proclaimed in the Pla- tonic TimsBus ; though I think that Gruppe has not accu- rately interpreted either Timseus or Aristotle. The capital argument of Boeekh is as follows : '^ The Pla- tonic Timaeus affirms, in express and unequivocal terms, the rotation of the outer celestial sphere (the sidereal sphere or ^.planes) in twenty-four hours, as bringing about and deter- ON THE ROTATION OF THE EARTH. 243 mining the succession of day and night. Whoever believes this cannot at the same time believe that the earth revolves round its own axis in twenty-four hours, and that the suc- cession of day and night is determined thereby. The one of these two afiirmations excludes the other; and, as the first of the two is proclaimed, beyond all possibility of doubt, in the Platonic Timseus, so we may be sure that the second of the two cannot be proclaimed in that same discourse. If any passage therein seems to countenance it, we must look for some other mode of interpreting the passage." This is the main argument of M. Boeckh, and also of Messrs. Cousin and Martin. The latter protests against the idea of imputing to Plato "un melange monstrueux de deux systemes incompatibles " (' Etudes sur le Timee,' vol. ii. p. 86-88). As applied to any person educated in the modern astro- nomy, the argument is irresistible. But is it equally irre- sistible when applied to Plato and to Plato's time ? I think not. The incompatibility which appears so glaring at pre- sent, did not suggest itself to him or to his contemporaries. To prove this we have only to look at the reasoning of Aristotle, who (in the treatise De Coelo, ii. 13-14, p. 293. b. 30, 296. a. 25) notices and controverts the doctrine of the rotation of the earth, with express reference to the followers of the Platonic Timaeus, and who (if we follow the view of Martin) imputes this doctrine with wilful falsehood to Plato, for the purpose of contemptuously refuting it, "pour se donner le plaisir de la refuter avec dedain." Granting the view of M. Boeckh (still more that of Martin) to be correct, we should find Aristotle arguing thus : — " Plato affirms the diurnal rotation of the earth round the centre of the cosmical axis. This is both incredible, and incompatible with his own distinct affirmation that the sidereal sphere revolves in twenty-four hours. It is a glaring inconsistency that the same author should affirm both the one and the other." Such would have been Aristotle's reasoning, on the hypo- thesis which I am considering ; but when we turn to his R 2 244 PLATO'S DOCTRINE treatise we find that he does not employ this argument at all. He contests the alleged rotation of the earth upon totally different arguments — chiefly on the ground that rotatory motion is not natural to the earth, that the kind of motion natural to the earth is rectilineal, towards the centre ; and he adds various corollaries flowing from this doctrine which I shall not now consider. At tlie close of his refutation, he states in general terms that the celestial ap- pearances, as observed by scientific men, coincided with his doctrine. Hence we may plainly see that Aristotle probably did not see the incompatibility, supposed to be so glaring, upon which M. Boeckh's argument is founded. To say the least, even if he saw it, he did not consider it as glaring and decisive. He would have put it in the foreground of his refutation, if he had detected the gross contradiction upon which M. Boeckh insists. Bnt xlristotle does not stand alone in this dulness of vision. Amono; the various com- mentators, ancient and modern, who follow him, discussing the question now before us, not one takes notice of M. Boeckh's argument. He himself certifies to us this fact, claiming the argument as his own, and expressing his asto- nishment that all the previous critics had passed it over, though employing other reasons much weaker to prove the same point. We read in IM. Boeckh's second ' Commentatio de Platonico Systemate Coelestium Globorum et de Vera Indole Astronomiae Philolaicae,' Heidelberg, 1810, p. 9, the following words : — " Non moveri tellurem, Proclus et Simplicius ostendunt ex Phaedone. Parum flrmum tamen argumentum est ex Phaedone ductum ad interpretandum Timaei locum : nee melius alteram, quod Locrus Timaeus, quern Plato sequi putabatur, terram stare affirmat : quia, ut nuper explicuimus, non Plato ex Locro, sed personatus Locrus ex Platone, sua compilavit. At omnium firmissimum et certissimum argu- mentum ex ipso nostro dialogo sumptum, adhuc, quod jure mirerey nemo rejperit Etenim, quum, paulo supra, orbem ON THE ROTATION OF THE EARTH. 245 stellarum fixarum, quern Graeci arrKavrj appeUant, dextrorsum ferri quotidiano motu Plato statuebat, non poterat uUum terrae motum admittere ; quia, qui hunc admittit, iUum non toller e non potest.'^ (This passage appears again cited by M. Boeckh himself in his more recent dissertation ^ Unter- suchungen iiber das kosmische System des Platon/ p. 11). The writers named (p. 7) as having discussed the question, omit- ting or disregarding this most cogent argument, are names extending from Aristotle down to Euhnken and Ideler. It is honourable to the penetration of M. Boeckh that he should have pointed out, what so many previous critics had overlooked, that these two opinions are scientifically incom- patible. He wonders, and there may be good ground for wondering, how it happened that none of these previous writers were aware of the incompatibility. But the fact that it did not occur to them, is not the less certain, and is of the greatest moment in reference to the question now under debate ; for we are not now inquiring what is or is not scientifically true or consistent, but what were the opinions of Plato. M. Boeckh has called our attention to the fact, that these two opinions are incompatible ; but can we safely assume that Plato must have perceived such incompati- bility between them ? Surely not. The Pythagoreans of his day did not perceive it; their cosmical system included both the revolution of the earth and the revolution of the sidereal sphere round the central fire, ten revolving bodies in all (Aristotel. Metaphysic. i. 35, p. 96 a. 10. De Ccelo, ii. 13, p. 293 b. 21). They were not aware that the revolutions of the one annulled those of the other as to effect, and that their system must involve the two contradictory articles, or " melange monstrueux/' of which Martin speaks so disdain- fully. Nay, more, their opponent, Aristotle, while producing other arguments against them, never points out the contra- diction. Since it did not occur to them, we can have no greater difficulty in believing that neither did it occur to Plato. Indeed, the wonder would rather be if Plato had seen an astronomical incompatibility which escaped the 246 PLATO'S DOCTRINE notice both of Aristotle and of many subsequent writers who wrote at a time when astronomical theories had been developed and compared with greater fulness. Even Ideler, a good astroDomer as well as a good scholar, though he must surely have known that Plato asserted the rotation of the sidereal sphere (for no man can read the ' Timeeus ' without knowing it), ascribed to him also the other doctrine inconsistent with it, not noticing such inconsistency until M. Boeckh pointed it out. It appears to me, therefore, that M. Boeckh has not satis- factorily made good his point — " Plato cannot have believed in the diurnal rotation of the earth, because he unquestion- ably believed in the rotation of the sidereal sphere as causing the succession of night and day." For, though the two doctrines really are incompatible, yet the critics ante- cedent to M. Boeckh took no notice of such incompatibility. We cannot presume that Plato saw what Aristotle and other authors, many even writing under a more highly developed astronomy, did not see. We ought rather, I think, to pre- sume the contrary, unless Plato's words distinctly attest that he did see farther than his successors. Now let us examine what Plato's words do attest : — ^rjv Se Tpo(j)ov jJLev TjixeTepav eiWo/jbevrjv (al. etXo/Jievrjv, IWo/jievrjv) 8e irepl rov Sia iravTo^ iroiKov reTajuLevov (pvXa/ca kol Brj/jLLovpyov vvKTo^ re KoX rjiJbepa<^ i/Ji7]')(^avi](7aT0, TTpdorrjV kol 7rp€a/3vTdT7]v deodv, oaoi eWo9 ovpdvov yey ovacn, I explain these words as follows : — In the passage immediately preceding, Plato had described the uniform and unchanging rotation of the outer sidereal sphere, or Circle of The Same, and the erratic movements of the sun, moon, and planets, in the interior Circles of the Diverse. He now explains the situation and functions of the earth. Beino; the first and most venerable of the intra- kosmic deities, the earth has the most important place in the interior of the kosmos — the centre. It is packed, fastened, or rolled, close round the axis which traverses the entire kosmos ; and its function is to watch over and bring about ON THE ROTATION OF THE EARTH. 247 the succession of night and day. Flato conceives the hosmic axis itself as a solid cylinder revolving or turning round, and causing thereby the revolution of the circumference or the sidereal sphere. The outer circumference of the kosmos not only revolves round its axis, but obeys a rotatory impulse emanating from its axis, like the spinning of a teetotum or the turning of a spindle. Plato in the Republic illustrates the cosmical axis by comparison with a spindle turned by Necessity, and describes it as causing by its own rotation the rotation of all the heavenly bodies (Republ. x. p. 616, c. 617 A), e/c Se tS)v aKpcov Terafxevov ^Kvwyicr]^ drpaKToVy S/' ov Trdcraf; e7narpe(^ecr6ai ra^ 7r6pL(f)opa<; .... KVKKeladai he Sr] arpe^ofxevov rov drpaKTOv oKov /xev rrjv avrrjv ^opdv .... arpe^eaOaL he avrov ev TOiopCi)Vf Trepl yjv rj ^opeta tCjv oXcoi/, Trcpi 7]V at avaKVKXy(T€L<;, av€)(ov(Tav rov oXov ovpavov, rjv KaV ArXavra Sia tovto irpocTUpiqKacTiV, o)S arp^TTTOV Kol arpvTOV ivipyeiav k^ovcrav, /cat p^^vroi koI to rerapevov ivSeLKwrai TirrjViov et^at rrfv pcav raiJTrjV 8i;i/a/xti/, T7]V 0o^ V€p6v T€ Kot rapa^coSe?, eTreipwras avOpixiTrrjiCDV TrprjyfjLOLTCov irept ; also iii. 40. 1 See Eurip. Hipp, 6-96-140. The language of the attendant, after his affectionate remonstrance to Hippolytus had been disre- garded, supplicating Aphrodite to pardon the recalcitrancy of that virtuous hut obstinate youth, is characteristic and touching (114-120). ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF SIR W. HAMILTON. 303 logical bearing on the controversy between liim and Mr. Mansel, we are obliged to confess that in this point of view it has little objective relevancy. The problem was, how to reconcile the actual evil and suffering in the universe (which is recited as a fact by Mr. Mansel, though in terms con- veying a most inadequate idea of its real magnitude) with the goodness of God. Mr. Mill repudiates the explanatory hypothesis tendered by Mr. Mansel as a solution, but without suggesting any better hypothesis of his own. For ourselves, we are far from endorsing Mr. Mansel's solution as satis- factory ; yet we can hardly be surprised if he considers it less unsatisfactory than no solution at all. And vfhen we reflect how frequently and familiarly predicates applicable to man are applied to the Supreme Being, when they can- not possibly be understood about Him in the same sense, we see no ground for treating the proceeding as disingenuous, which Mr. Mill is disposed to do. Indeed, it cannot easily be avoided: and Mr. Mill himself furnishes us with some examples in the present volume. At page 491, he says : — " It would be difficult to find a stronger argument in favour of Theism, than that the eye must have been made by one who sees, and the ear by one who hears." In the words here employed, seeing and hearing are pre- dicated of God. Now when we predicate of men, that they see or hear^ we affirm facts of extreme complexity, especially in the case of seeing ; facts partly physical, partly mental, involving multifarious movements and agencies of nerves, muscles, and other parts of the organism, together with direct sensational impressions, and mental reconstruction of the past, in- separably associated therewith ; all which, so far as they are known, are perspicuously enumerated in the work of Pro- fessor Bain* on the ' Senses and the Intellect.' Ao:ain, Mr. * See especially his chapter ii. 'On the Sensations of Sight,' pp. 222, 241-217, in the second edition of this work. 304 REVIEW OF JOHN STUAET MILL Mill speaks (in p. 102 and elsewhere) of " the yerar*ity o f God." When we say of our neighbour that he is a yeracious man, we ascribe to him a habit of speaking the truth ; that is, of employing his physical apparatus of speech, and his mental power of recalling and recombining words lodged in the memory, for the purpose of asserting no other propo- sitions except such as declare facts which he knows, or beliefs which he really entertains. But how either seeing, or hearing, or veracity, in these senses, can be predicated of God, we are at a loss to understand. And if they are to be predicated of God in a different sense, this admits the same license as Mr. Mansel contends for in respect to Goodness, when he feels that undeniable facts preclude him from predicating that epithet univocally respecting God and respecting man.* On the whole, it seems to us, that though Mr. Mill will consent to worship only a God of perfect goodness, he has thrown no new light on the grave problem — frankly stated, though imperfectly solved, by Mr. Mansel — how such a conception of God is to be reconciled with the extent of evil and suffering actually pervading human life and animal life throughout the earth. V^^e are compelled to say, respecting Mr. Mill's treatment of this subject — what we should not say respecting his treatment of any other — that he has left an old perplexing problem not less perplexing than he found it. Reverting, not unwillingly, from theology to philosophy, we now pass on to Mr. ^lill's ninth chapter (p. 128 seq.), of the Interpretation of Consciousness. There is assuredly no lesson more requiring to be taught than the proper mode of * Descartes says, in his Principia PhilosopMcB, i. 51 : " Et quidem substantia quse nulla plane re indigeat, unica tantum potest in- telligi — nempe Deus. Alias vero omnes, non nisi ope concursus Dei existere posse perspieimus. Atque ideo nomen substantiaB non convenit Deo et illis univoce, ut dici solet in scholis ; hoc est, nulla ejus nominis significatio potest distinete intelligi, quae Deo et crea- turis sit communis." ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF SIR W. HAMILTON. 305 conducting such interpretation ; for the number of different modes in which Consciousness has been interpreted is astonishing. Mr. Mill begins by citing from Sir W. Hamil- ton's lectures a passage of some length, upon which he bestows considerable praise, regarding it as — " One of the proofs that, whatever may be the positive value of his (Sir W. Hamilton's) achievements in metaphysics, he had a greater capacity for the subject than many metaphysicians of high reputation ; and particularly than his two distinguished predecessors in the same school of thought — ' Eeid and Stewart.' " — p. 131. This is one of the greatest compliments to Sir W. Hamilton that the book contains, and as such we are glad to cite it. On the subject of Consciousness, Mr. Mill has cited from Sir W. Hamilton other good observations besides the one last alluded to ; but, unfortunately, these are often neutral- ised by opposite or inconsistent opinions also cited from other parts of his works. The number of such inconsisten- cies produced is indeed one remarkable feature in Sir W. Hamilton's philosophical character. He seems to follow out energetically (as Plato in his various dialogues) the vein of thought pervading his mind at each particular moment, without troubling himself to look back upon his own prior speculations. Even compared with the best views of Sir W. Hamilton, however, Mr. Mill's mode of handling the subject of Consciousness exhibits signal improvement. To some of his observations we shall call particular attention. All philosophers agree that what Consciousness testifies is to be believed ; but they differ much on the question — To what points Consciousness does testify? and even on the still deeper question — How shall we proceed to ascertain what are these attested points ? What is the proper method of studying or interrogating Consciousness ? Upon this, Mr. Mill remarks (pp. 145-147) : — " Here emerges the distinction between two different methods of studying the problems of metaphysics ; forming the radical dif- X 306 REVIEW OF JOHN STUAET MILL ference between the two great schools into which metaphysicians are divided. One of these I shall call, for distinction, the intro- spective method ; the other, the i^sycliologicaL M. Cousin observes that Locke went wrong from the beginning, by j)lacing before him- self, as the question to be first resolved, the origin of our ideas. This (he says) was commencing at the wrong end. The proper course would have been to begin by determining what the ideas now are ; to ascertain what it is that Consciousness now tells us ; postponing till afterwards the attempt to frame a theory concerning the origin of any of the mental phenomena. " I accept the question as M. Cousin states it ; and I contend that no attempt to determine what are the direct revelations of Consciousness can be successful, or entitled to any regard, unless preceded by what M. Cousin says ought only to follow it — an enquiry into the origin of our acquired ideas. For we have it not in our power to ascertain, by any direct process, what Conscious- ness told us at the time when its revelations were in their pristine purity. It only offers itself to our inspection as it exists now, when those original revelations are overlaid and buried under a mountainous heap of acquired notions and perceptions. " It seems to M. Cousin, that if we examine, with care and minuteness, our present states of Consciousness, distinguishing and defining every ingredient which we find to enter into them — every element that we seem to recognise as real, and cannot by merely concentrating our attention upon it analyse into anything simpler — we reach the ultimate and primary truths, which are the sources of all our knowledge, and which cannot be denied or doubted with- out denying or doubting the evidence of Consciousness itself — that is, the only evidence that there is for anything. I maintain this to be a misconception of the conditions imposed on enquirers by the difficulties of psychological investigation. To begin the enquiry at the point where M. Cousin takes it up is, in fact, to beg the question. For he must be aware, if not of the fact, at least of the belief of his opponents, that the laws of the mind — the laws of Association, according to one class of thinkers, the Categories of the Understanding according to another — are capable of creating, out of those data of Consciousness which are uncontested, purely mental conceptions, which become so identified in thought with all our states of Consciousness, that ice seem, and cannot hut seem, to receive tliem hy direct intuition. For example, the belief in Matter, in the opinion of these thinkers is, or at least may be, thus produced : — ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF SIK W. HAMILTON. 307 *' ' The proof that any of the alleged Universal Beliefs, or Prin- ciples of Common Sense, are affirmations of Consciousness, supposes^ two things : that the beliefs exist, and that they cannot possibly have been acquired. The first is, in most cases, undisputed ; but the second is a subject of enquiry which often taxes the utmost resources of psychologists. Locke was therefore right in believing that ' the origin of our ideas ' is the main stress of the problem of mental science, and the subject which must be first considered in forming the theory of the Mind.' " This citation from Mr. MilFs book is already almost too long, yet we could have wished to prolong it still more, from the importance of some of the succeeding paragraphs. It presents, in clear discrimination and contrast, two opposite points of view according to which the phenomena of mind are regarded by different philosophers, and the method of studying them determined: tke introspective method, adopted by M. Cousin and others — the psychological or analytical method, pursued by Locke and by many other eminent men since Locke — "the known and approved method of physical science, adapted to the necessities of psychology " — (p. 148.) There are passages of Sir W. Hamilton's writings in which he appears to feel that the introspective method alone is insufficient for the interpretation of Consciousness, and that the analytical method must be employed to reinforce it. But on this as on other points, he is not always consistent with himself. For in laying down the principle upon which the primary truths of Consciousness, the original data of intelligence, are to be ascertained and distinguished from generalizations out of experience and custom, he declares that the one single and certain mark is Necessity; they must be beliefs which we are under the necessity of believing — of which we cannot get rid by any mental effort. He decides this, of course, for himself, by the introspective method alone. He (with M. Cousin and other philosophers who take the same view) does not apply the analytical method to enquire whether his necessity of belief may not be a purely acquired necessity, and nowise congenital. It X 2 308 EEVIEW OF JOHN STUAET MILL. is, indeed, remarkable tliat these pliilosopliers do not even seek to apply the introspective method as far as that method will really go. They are satisfied with introspection of their own present minds, without obtaining results of the like process, as ajDj^lied to other minds, in different times and places. They declare various beliefs to be necessary to the human mind universallv, merelv because such is the actual fact with their own minds and with those immediately around them ; sometimes even in defiance of proof that there are (or have been) persons not sharing such beliefs, and occasionally even believing the contrary ; therefore, when even the introspective method really disallows their affirmative instead of sustainins: it. This is, in truth, an abuse of the introspective method ; yet, even if that method were employed in its fullest extent — if the same incapability of believing otherwise could Jbe shown as common to all mankind — it mio-ht still be onlv the effect of a strono^ asso- ciation. The analytical method must still be called in to ascertain whether we are forced to suppose such incapability to be an original fact of consciousness, or whether it may not have been generated in the mind by circumstances, under the natural working of the laws of association. It is certain that these laws not only may, but must, give birth to artificial inconceivabilities in the mind ; and that some of these may be equal in strength to such, if any, as are natural. " The History of Science," says Mr. Mill, following out the same train of reasoning which we read in the third book of his System of Logic, " teems with inconceivabilities which Lave been conquered ; and with supposed necessary truths, which have fii'st ceased to be thought necessary, then to be thought true, and have finally come to be deemed impossible." — p. 150. jifter various observations, chieflv exhibitino' the rashness of many censures bestowed by Sir W. Hamilton on Brown, Mr. Mill gives us three valuable chapters (xi., xii., xiii.), wherein he analyses the Belief in an External World, the Belief in Mind as a separate Substance or Xoumenon, and ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF SIR W. HAMILTON. 309 the Primary Qualities of Matter. To each of these topics he applies what he calls the jpsijclwlogical method, as con- trasted with the simply introspective method of Sir W. Hamilton (the Ego and Non-Ego affirmed to be given together in the primary deliverance of Consciousness) and so many other philosophers. He proves that these beliefs are noway intuitive, but acquired products ; and that the known laws of Association are sufficient to explain how they are acquired ; especially the Law of Inseparable Associa- tion, together with that of Obliviscence — a very useful, dis- criminating phrase, which we first find employed in this volume (p. 259 et passim). He defines Matter to be a ^permanent possibilitij of Sensation ; he maintains that this is really all which (apart from philosophical theories) mankind in general mean by it ; he shows that mere possibilities of sensation not only may, but must, according to the known Laws of Association, come to present " to our artificialized Consciousness " a character of objectivity — (pp. 198, 199). The correlating subject, though present in fact and indis- pensable, is eliminated out of conscious notice, according to the Law of Obliviscence. These chapters will well rej ay the most careful perusal. We can only find room for one passage (pp. 214, 215) : — " Throughout the whole of our sensitive life, except its first beginnings, we unquestionably refer our sensations to a me and a not-me. As soon as I have formed, on the one hand, the notion of Permanent Possibilities of Sensation, and on the other, of that con- tinued series of feelings which I call my life — both these notions are, by an irresistible association, recalled by every sensation I have. They represent two things, with both of which the sensation of the moment, be it what it may, stands in relation ; and I cannot be conscious of the sensation without being conscious of it, as related to these two things. They Lave accordingly received relative names, expressive of the double relation in question. The thread of con- sciousness which I apprehend the relation as a part of, is called the Subject ; the group of Permanent Possibilities of Sensation to which I refer it, and which is partially realised and actualised in it, is called the Object of the sensation. The sensation itself ought to 310 REVIEW OF JOHN STUART MILL have a correlative name, or rather ought to have two such names — one denoting the sensation as opposed to its Subject, the other de- noting it as opposed to its Object ; but it is a remarkable fact that this necessity has not been felt, and that the need of a correlative name to every relative one has been considered to be satisfied by the terms Object and Subject themselves. It is true that these two are related to one another, but only through the sensation. We have no conception of either Subject or Object, either Mind or Matter, except as something to which we refer our sensations, and whatever other feelings we are conscious of. The very existence of them both, so far as cognisable by us, consists only in the relation they respectively bear to our states of feeling. Their relation to each other is only the relation between those two relations. The immediate correlatives are, not the pair. Object, Subject, but the two pairs, Object, Sensation objectively considered — Subject, Sensation subjec- tively considered. The reason why this is overlooked might easily be shewn, and would fui*nish a good illustration of that important part of the Laws of Association, w^hich may be termed the Laws of Obliviscence.' ' This chapter, on the Primary Qualities of Matter, con- troverts the opinion of Sir W. Hamilton, that extension, as consisting of coexistent partes extra partes, is immediately and necessarily apprehended by our consciousness. It cites, as well as confirms, the copions proof given by Professor Bain (in his work on the Senses and the Intellect) that our conception of extension is derived from our muscular sensi- bility : that our sensation of muscular motion unimpeded constitutes our notion of empty space, as our sensation of muscidar motion impeded constitutes that of filled space: that our conception of extension, as an aggregate of co- existent parts, arises from the sense of sight, which com- prehends a great number of parts in a succession so raipd as to be confounded with simultaneity ; and which not only becomes the symbol of muscular and tactile succession, but even acquires such ascendency as to supersede both of them in our consciousness. Confirmation is here given to this important doctrine, not merely by observations from Mr. Mill himself, but also from the very curious narrative, dis- covered and produced by Sir W. Hamilton, out of a work ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF SIR W. HAMILTON. 311 of the German philosopher, Plainer. Plainer instiluted a careful examination of a man born blind, and ascertained that this man did not conceive extension as an aggregate of simultaneous parts, but as a series of sensations experienced or to be experienced in succession — (pp. 232, 233). Tlie case reported from Plainer both corroborates the theory of Professor Bain, and receives its proper interpretation from that theory ; while it is altogether adverse to the doctrine of Sir W. Hamilton — as is also another case, which he cites from Maine de Biran: — " It gives a very favourable idea of Sir W. Hamilton's sincerity and devotion to truth," remarks Mr. Mill, p. 247, '' that he should have drawn from obscurity, and made generally known, two cases so unfavourable to his own opinions." We think this remark perfectly just ; and we would point out besides, in appreciating Sir W. Hamilton's merits, that his appetite for facts was useful to philosophy, as well as his appetite for speculation. But the person whose usefulness to philosophy we prefer to bring into the foreground, is Plainer himself. He spent three weeks in patient examination of this blind man, and the tenor of his report proves that his sagacity in interpreting facts was equal to his patience in collecting them. The rarity of all such careful and pre- meditated observation of the facts of mind, appears to us one main reason why (what Mr. Mill calls) the psychological theory finds so little acceptance ; and why those who main- tain that what now seems a mental integer was once a mul- tiplicity of separate mental fragments, can describe the ante- cedent steps of the change only as a latens jorocessus, which the reader never fully understands, and often will not admit. Every man's mind is gradually built up from infancy to maturity ; the process is always going on before our eyes, yet the stages of it — especially the earliest stages, the most pregnant with instruction — are never studied and put on record by observers trained in inductive logic knowing beforehand what they ought to look for as the sine qua non 312 KEYIEW OF JOHN STUART MILL for proving or disproving any proposed theory. Such cases as that cited by Platner — cases of one marked congenital defect of sense, enabling us to apply the Method of Difference — are always within reach ; but few Platners are found to scrutinise and record them. Historians of science describe to us the laborious and multiplied observations, and the elaborate precautions for ensuring accuracy of observation, which recent chemical and physical enquirers have found indispensable for the establishing of their results. We cannot, therefore, be surprised that mental philosophers, dealing with facts even more obscure, and careless about enlarging, varying, authenticating their records of particular facts, should have had little success in establishing any results at all. But if even those, who adopt the psychological theory, have been remiss in the observation of particular mental facts, those who deny the theory have been far more than remiss ; they have been blind to obvious facts contradicting the principles which they lay down. Mr. Mill, in chap, xiv., deals with this denial, common to Mr. Mansel with Sir W. Hamilton. That philosophers so eminent as both of them should declare confidently — " what I cannot but think, must be a priori^ or original to thought ; it cannot be engendered by experience upon custom " (p. 264) — appears to us as extraordinary as it does to Mr. Mill. Though no one ever surpassed Sir W. Hamilton in large acquaintance with the actual diversities of human belief, and human incapacities of believing — yet he never seems to have thought of bringing this acquaintance into account, when he assured the students in his lecture-room that custom, experience, indissoluble asso- ciation, were altogether insufficient to engender a felt neces- sity of believing. Such forgetfulness of w^ell-known mental facts cannot be reproached to the advocates of the psycho- logical theory. In chap. XV., Mr. Mill examines Sir W. Hamilton's doctrine on unconscious mental modifications. He points out the confused manner in w^hich Sir W. Hamilton has conceived ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF SIR W. HAMILTON. 313 mental latency, as well as the inconclusive character of the reasoning whereby he refutes the following doctrine of Dugald Stewart — That in the most rapid trains of associa- tion, each separate item must have been successively present to consciousness, though for a time too short to leave any memory. Sir W. Hamilton thinks that the separate items mh,y pass, and often do pass, unconsciously ; which opinion Mr. Mill also, though not approving his reasons, is inclined to adopt, *' I am myself inclined (p. 285) to admit unconscious mental modifications, in the only sense in which I can attach any very distinct meaning to them, namely, unconscious modifications of the nerves. It may well be believed that the apparently suppressed links in a chain of association, those which Sir W. Hamilton con- siders as latent, really are so : that they are not even momentarily felt, the chain of causation being continued only physically — by one organic state of the nerves succeeding another so rapidly that the state of mental consciousness appropriate to each is not produced." Mr. Mill gives various illustrations in support of this doctrine. He at the same time calls attention to a valuable lecture of Sir W. Hamilton's, the thirty-second lecture on Metaphysics ; especially to the instructive citation from Cardaillac contained therein, noting the important fact, which descriptions of the Law of Association often keep out of sight — that the suggestive agency of Association is carried on, not by single antecedents raising up single consequents, but by a mass of antecedents raising up simultaneously a mass of consequents, among which attention is very unequally distributed. We shall say little upon Mr. Mill's remarks on Sir W. Hamilton's Theory of Causation — (chap. xvi.). This theory appears to Mr. Mill absurd ; while the theory of Mr. Mill (continued from Hume, Brown, and James Mill) on the same subject appears to Sir W. Hamilton insufficient and unsatis- factory — " professing to explain the phenomenon of causality, but previously to explanation, evacuating the phenomenon 314 REVIEW OF JOHN STUART MILL of all that desiderates explanation" — (p. 295). For our- selves, we embrace the theory of Mr. Mill : * yet we are aware that the remark just cited from Sir W. Hamilton re- presents the dissatisfaction entertained towards it by many objectors. The unscientific and antiscientific yearnings pre- valent among mankind lead them to put questions which no sound theory of Causation will answer ; and they are ready to visit and trust any oracle which professes to deliver a confident affirmative solution of such ques- tions. Among all the terms employed by metaphysicians, * At the same time we cannot go along with Mr. Mill in the following affirmation (p. 201) : — " This natural probability is converted into certainty when we take into consideration that universal law of our experience which is termed the Law of Causation, and which makes us unable to conceive the beginning of anything ivithout an antecedent condition or cause, ^' Such " inability to conceive " appears to us not in correspondence with facts. First, it cannot be properly either affirmed or denied, until agreement is obtained what the word cause means. If three persons, A, B, and C, agree in affirming it — A adopting the meaning of Aristotle, B that of Sir William Hamilton, and that of Mr. Mill — the agreement is purely verbal ; or rather, all three concur in having a mental exigency pressing for satisfaction, but differ as to the hypothesis which satisfies it. Next, if we reason upon Mr. Mill's theory as to Cause, certainly those who deny his theory can have no difficulty in conceiving events without any cause (in that sense) ; nor have those who adopt his theory any greater difficulty. These last believe that there are, throughout, constant and uniform conditions on which the occur- rence of every event depends ; but they can perfectly conceive events as occurring without any such uniform sequence. In truth, the belief in such causation, as pervading all nature, is an acquired result of scientific training. The greater part of mankind believe that some events occur in regular, others in irregular, succession. Moreover, a full half of the metaphysical world espouse the doctrine of free-will, and consider that all volitions occur without any cause at all. ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF Sill W. HAMILTON. 315 none is used in a greater variety of meanings than the term Cause. In Mr. Mill's next chapter (xvi.), he comments on Sir W. Hamilton's doctrine of Concepts or General Notions. There are portions of this chapter with which we agree less than with most other parts of the volume ; especially with his marked hostility to the term Concept, and the reasons given for it ; which reasons appear to us not very consistent with what he has himself said in the ' System of Logic/ Book IV. ch. ii. § 1-3. The term Concept has no necessary con- nexion with the theory called Conceptualism. It is equally available to designate the idea called up by a general name, as understood either by Mr. Bailey or by James Mill. We think it useful as an equivalent to the German word Begriff, wiiich sense Sir W. Hamilton has in view when he introduces it, though he does not always adhere to his profession. And when Mr. Mill says (p. 331) — " I consider it nothing less than a misfortune, that the words Concept, General Notion, or any other phrase to express the sup- posed mental modification corresponding to a general name, should ever have been invented," we dissent from his opinion. To talk of 'Hhe Concept of an individual," however, as Mr. Mansel does (pp. 338, 339), is improper and inconsistent with the purpose for which the name is given. We are more fully in harmony with Mr. Mill in his tw^o next chapters (xviii. et seq.) on Judgment and Eeasoning ; which are among the best chapters in the volume. He there combats and overthrows the theory of Reasoning laid down by Sir W. Hamilton ; but we doubt the propriety of his calling this ''the Conceptualist theory" (pp. 367, 368): since it has nothing to do with Conceptualism, in the special sense of antithesis to Realism and Nominalism, — but is, in fact, the theory of the Syllogism as given in the Analytics of Aristotle, and generally admitted since. Not merely Conceptualists, but (to use Mr Mill's own language, p. 366) 316 REVIEW OF JOHN STUART MILL " nearly all the writers on logic, taught a theory of the science too small and narrow to contain their o^vn facts." Such, indeed, was the theory constantly taught until the publication of Mr. Mill's ' System of Logic ; ' the first two books of which corrected it, by arguments which are re- inforced and amplified in these two chapters on Judgment and Reasoning, as well as in the two chapters next following — chaps. XX. and xxi. — (" Is Logic the Science of the Forms of Thought— On the Fundamental Laws of Thought"). The contrast which is there presented, in many different ways, between the limited theory of logic taught by Sir W. Hamilton and Mr. Mansel, and the enlarged theory of Mr. Mill, is instructive in a high degree. We consider Mr. Mill as the real preserver of all that is valuable in Formal Logic from the unfortunate consequences of an erroneous estimate, brought upon it through the exaggerated preten- sions of logicians. When Sir W. Hamilton contrasts it pointedly with physical science (of which he talks with a sort of supercilious condescension, in one of the worst passages of his writings, p. 401) — when all its apparent fruits were produced in the shape of ingenious but barren verbal techni- calities — what hope could be entertained that Formal Logic could hold its ground in the estimation of the recent gene- ration of scientific men ? Mr. Mill has divested it of that assumed demonstrative authority which Bacon called " re- gere res per syllogismum," but he has at the same time given to it a firm root amidst the generalities of objective science. He has shown that in the great problem of Evidence or Proof, the Laws of Formal Logic, though bearing only on one part of the entire procedure, yet bear upon one essen- tial part, proper to be studied separately : and that the maintenance of consistency between our affirmations (which is the only special province of Formal Logic) has great importance and value as a part of the process necessary for ascertaining and vindicating their truth, or exposing their character when false or uncertified — but no importance and value except as a part of that larger exigency. ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF SIR W. HAMILTON. 317 While Mr. Mill was amending the Syllogistic theory so as to ensure for Formal Logic its legitimate place among the essentials of scientific procedure, Sir W. Hamilton was at the same time enlarging it on its technical side, in two modes which are highly esteemed both by himself and by others : 1. The recognition of two kinds of Syllogisms ; one in Extension, the other in Comprehension ; 2. The doctrine of the Quantification of the Predicate. Both these novelties are here criticised by Mr. Mill in chapter xxii., which we recommend the reader to peruse conjointly with Lectures 15 and 16 of Sir W. Hamilton on Logic. Now whereas the main objection, by which the study of the syllogistic logic has been weighed down and discredited in modern times, is this, that it encumbers the memory with formal distinctions, having no useful application to the real process and purposes of reasoning — the procedure of Sir W. Hamilton might almost lead us to imagine that he himself was trying to aggravate that objection to the uttermost. He introduces a variety of new canons (classifying Syllogisms as Extensive and Intensive, by a distinction founded on the double quantity of notions, in Extension and in Compre- hension) which he intimates that all former logicians have neglected — while it plainly appears, even on his own show- ing, that the difference between syllogisms, in respect to these two sorts of quantity, is of no practical value; and that " we can always change a categorical syllogism of the one quantity into a categorical syllogism of the other by reversing the order of the two premises, and by reversing the meaning of the copula " (Lect. xvi. p. 296) ; nay, that every syllogism is already a syllogism in both quantities (Mill, p. 431). Against these useless ceremonial reforms of Sir W. Hamilton, we may set the truly philosophical explanation here given by Mr. Mill of the meaning of propositions. " All judgments (he says, p. 423), except where both the terms are proper names, are really judgments in Comprehension ; thougli it is customary, and the natural tendency of the mind, to express most of them in terms of Extension. In other words, we never Q 18 REVIEW OF JOHX STUAKT MILL really predicate anything but attributes ; though, in the usage of language, we commonly predicate them by means of words which are names of concrete objects, because (p. 426) we have no other convenient and compact mode of speaking. Most attributes, and nearly all large bundles of attributes, have no names of their own. We can only name them by a circumlocution. We are accustomed to speak of attributes, not by names given to themselves, but by means of the names which they give to the objects they are attributes of." " All our ordinary judgments (p. 428) are in Comprehension only ; Extension not being thought of. But we may, if we please, make the Extension of our general terms an express object of thought. When I judge that all oxen ruminate, I have nothing in my thoughts but the attributes and their co-existence. But when by reflection I perceive what the proposition implies, I remark that other things may ruminate besides oxen, and that the unknown multitude of things which ruminate form a mass, with which the unknown multitude of things having the attributes of oxen is either identical or is wholly comprised in it. Which of these two is the truth I may not know, and if I did, took no notice of it when I assented to the proposition, all oxen ruminate ; but I perceive, on consideration, that one or other of them must be true. Though I had not this in my mind when I affirmed that all oxen ruminate, I can have it now ; I can make the concrete objects denoted by each of the two names an object of thought, as a collective though inde- finite aggregate ; in other words, I can make the Extension of the names (or notions) an object of direct consciousness. When I do this, I perceive that this operation introduces no new fact, but is only a difterent mode of contemplating the very fact which I had previously expressed by the words, all oxen ruminate. The fact is the same, but the mode of contemplating it is different. There is thus in all Propositions a judgment concerning attributes (called by Sir W. Hamilton a Judgment in Comprehension) wliich we make as a matter of course ; and a possible judgment in or concerning Extension, which we may make, and which will be true if the former is true." From the lucid explanation here cited (and from a follow- ing paragraph too long to transcribe, p. 433), we see that there is no real distinction between Judgments in Compre- hension and Judgments in Extension ; that the appearance of distinction between them arises from the customary mode ON THE PFIILOSOPHY OF SIR W. HAMILTON. 319 of enunciation, which custom is here accounted for ; that the addition to the theory of the Syllogism, for which Sir W. Hamilton takes credit, is .alike troublesome and unprofitable. The like may also be said about his other innovation, the Quantification of the Predicate. Still more extensive are the changes (as stated by himself) wdiich this innovation would introduce in the canons of Syllogism. Indeed, when we read his language (Appendix to ' Lectures on Logic,' pp. 291-297) censuring generally the prior logicians from Aristotle downw^ards, and contending that " more than half the value of logic had been lost " by their manner of handling it — we may appreciate the magnitude of the reform which he believed himself to be introducing-. The laro^er the reform, the more it behoved him to be sure of the ground on which he was proceeding. But on this point we remark a serious deficiency. After laying down, with appropriate empliasis, the valuable logical postulate, to state explicitly what is thought implicitly, on which, Sir W. Hamilton says, " Logic ever insists, but which logicians have never fairly obeyed — it follows that logically we ought to take into account the quantity, always understood in thought , but usually, and for manifest reasons, elided in expression, not only of the suhject^ but also of the predicate of a judgment." — Discussions on PJiilos., p. 614. Here Sir W. Hamilton assumes that the quantity of the predicate is always understood in thought; and the same assumption is often repeated, in the Appendix to his ' Lec- tures on Logic,' p. 291 and elsewhere, as it was alike obvious and incontestable. Now it is precisely on this point that issue is here taken with Sir W. Hamilton. Mr. Mill denies altogether (p. 437) that the quantity of the predicate is always understood or present in thought, and appeals to every reader's consciousness for an answer :— " Does he, when he judges that all oxen ruminate, advert even in the minutest degree to the question, whether there is anything else that ruminates ? Is this consideration at all in his thoughts, any 320 REVIEW OF JOHN STUART MILL more tlian any other consideration foreign to tlie immediate subject ? One person may know that there are other ruminating animals, another may think that there are none, a third may be without any opinion on the subject ; but if they all know what is meant by ruminating, they all, when they judge that every ox ruminates, mean precisely the same thing. The mental process they go through, as far as tliat one judgment is concerned, is precisely identical ; though some of them may go on farther, and add other judgments to it." The last sentence cited from Mr. Mill indicates the vice of Sir W. Hamilton's proceeding in quantifying the predicate, and explains why it was that logicians before him declined to do so. Sir W. Hamilton, in this proceeding, insists on stating explicitly, not merely all that is thought implicitly, but a o^reat deal more : * addino; to it somethinsr else, wdiich * Among the various authorities (upon this question of quanti- fying the j)redicate) collected by Sir W. Hamilton in the valuable Appendix to his Lectures on Logic, we find one (p. 311) which takes the same ground of objection as Mr. Mill, in these words : — ' The cause why the quantitative note is not usually joined with the predicate, is, that there would thus be two qucesita at once ; to w^it, whether the predicate were affirmed of the subject, and whether it were denied of everything beside. For when we say, all man is all rational, we judge that all man is rational, and judge like\^ise that rational is denied of everything hut man. But these are, in reality, two different qucesita ; and therefore it has become usual to state them, not in one, but in two several propositions. And this is self-evident, seeing that a qucesitum, in itself, asks only, — Does or does not this inhere in that 9 and not, Does or does not this inhere in that, and at the same time inhere in nothing elsef^ The author of this just and sagacious remark — much sm*passing what the other writers quoted in the Appendix say — was a Jew who died at Perpignan in or near 1370, named Levi Ben Gerson or Gersonides. An interesting account of this man, eminent as a writer and thinker in his age, will be found in a biogi'aphy by Dr. Joel, published at Breslau in 1862, Levi Ben Gerson als Beli- gions philosoph. He distinguished himself as a ^Titer on theology, philosophy, and astronomy ; he was one of the successors to the free ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF SIR W. HAMILTON. 321 mayy indeed, be thought conjointly, but which more fre- quently is not thought at all. He requires us to pack two distinct judgments into one and the same proposition: he interpolates the meaning of the Propositio Conversa sim- jpliciter into the form of the Propositio Oonvertenda (when an universal Affirmative), and then claims it as a great advantage, that the proposition thus interpolated admits of being converted siinpliciter, and not merely jper accidens, Mr. Mill is, nevertheless, of opinion (pp. 439-443) that though "the quantified syllogism is not a true expression of what is in thought, yet writing the predicate with a quan- tification may be sometimes a real help to the Art of Logic." We see little advantage in providing a new complicated ' form, for the purpose of expressing in one proposition what naturally throws itself into two, and may easily be expressed in two. If a man is prepared to give us information on one Qusesitum, why should he be constrained to use a mode of speech which forces on his attention at the same time a second and distinct Quaesitum — so that he must either give us information about the two at once, or confess himself ignorant respecting the second ? The two next chapters of Mr. Mill, noticing some other minor peculiarities (all of them unfortunate, and one, p. 447, really unaccountable) of Sir W. Hamilton's Formal Logic ; and some Fallacious Modes of Thought countenanced by Sir W. Hamilton (chs. xxiii., xxiv. — pp. 446, 478), we are com- pelled to pass over. We must find space, however, for a few words on the Freedom of the Will (ch. xxv.), which (in Mr. Mill's language, pp. 488-549), " w^as so fundamental with Sir W. Hamilton, that it may be regarded as the central idea of his system — ^the determining cause of most of his philosophical opinions." Prior to Sir W. Hamilton, we find speculative vein of Maimonides, and one of the continuators of the Arabic Aristotelian philosophy. He both commented on and com- bated the doctrines of Averroes. Dr. Joel thinks that he died earlier than 1370. Y 322 EEVIEW OF JOHN STUART MILL some writers who maintain the doctrine of Free-will, others who maintain that of Necessity: each supporting their re- spective conclusions by reasons which they deem suflScient. Sir W. Hamilton declares that both the one doctrine and the other are inconceivable and incomprehensible ; yet that, by the law of Excluded Middle, one or other of them must be true: and he decides in favour of Free-will, of which he believes himself to be distinctly conscious ; moreover, Free- Avill is essential (he thinks) to moral responsibility, of which also he feels himself conscious. He confesses himself, however? unable to explain the possibility of Free-will ; but he main- tains that the same may be said about Necessity also. " The cliampions of both the two opposite doctrines are at once resistless in attack, and impotent in defence " — (Hamilton's ' Footnotes on Keid,' p. 602). Mr. Mansel also asserts, even more confidently than Sir W. Hamilton, that we are directly conscious of Free-will — (p. 503). Sir W. Hamilton has himself given some of the best aro'uments ao:ainst the doctrine of Free-will, in refutation of Reid : aro-uments, some of which are here cited bv Mr. Mill with praise which they well deserve — (pp. 497, 498). But ]\Ir. Mill's own reasoning on the same side is of a still higher order, enlarging the grounds previously urged in the last book of his ^System of Logic' He protests against the term Necessity ; and discards the idea of Necessity, if it be understood to imply anything more than invariability of antecedence and consequence. If it mean tliat, experience proves thus much about antecedents in the world of mind, as in the world of matter: if it mean more, experience does not prove more, either in the world of matter or in the world of mind : nor have w^e any grounds for affirming it in either — (p. 501). If it were true, therefore, that conscious- ness attested Free-will, we should find the testimony of consciousness opposed to a full proof from experience and induction. But does consciousness really attest what is called Free-will ? Mr. Mill analyses the case, and declares in the negative. ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF SIR W. HAMILTON. 323 " To be conscious of Free-will, must mean to be conscious, before I bave decided, tbat I am able to decide either way ; exception may be taken in limine to tbe use of the word conscious^ ness in such an application. Consciousness teUs me what I do or feel. But what I am able to do, is not a subject of consciousness. Consciousness is not prophetic ; we are conscious of what is, not of what will or can be. We never know that we are able to do a thing, except from having done it, or something similar to it. Having acted, we know, as far as that experience reaches, how we are able to act; and this knowledge, when it has become familiar, is often confounded with, and called by, the name of consciousness. But it does not derive any increase of authority from being misnamed : its truth is not supreme over, but depends upon, experience. If our so-called consciousness is not borne out by experience, it is a delusion. It has no title to credence, but as an interpretation of experience ; and if it is a false interpretation it must give way." —pp. 503, 504. After this salutary and much-needed warning against the confusion between consciousness as an infallible authority, and belief upon experience, of which we are conscious as a belief — Mr. Mill proceeds to sift the alleged self-evident connexion between Free-will and Accountability. He shows, not merely that there is no connexion, but that there is a positive repugnance between the two. By Free-will is meant that a volition is not determined by motives, but is a spon- taneous mental fact, neither having a cause, nor admitting of being predicted. Now, the very reason for giving notice that we intend to punish certain acts, and for inflicting punishment if the acts be committed, is, that we trust in the efficacy of the threat and the punishment as deterring motives. If the volition of agents be not influenced by motives, the whole machinery of law becomes unavailing, and punishment a purposeless infliction of pain. In fact, itr is on that very ground that the madman is exempted from punishment ; his volition being presumed to be not capable of being acted upon by the deterring motive of legal sanction. The free agent, thus understood, is one who can neither feel himself accountable, nor be rendered account- Y 2 324 EEVIEW OF JOHN STUAET MILL able, to or by others. It is only the necessary agent (the person whose volitions are determined by motives, and, in case of conflict, by the strongest desire or the strongest apprehension) that can be held really accountable, or can feel himself to be so. " The true doctrine of the Causation of human actions," says Mr. Mill, p. 516, *' maintains, in opposition both to pure and to modified Fatalism, that not only our conduct, but our character is in part amenable to our will : that we can, by employing the proper means, improve our character : and that if our character is such that, while it remains what it is, it necessitates us to do wrong — it will be just to apply motives which will necessitate us to strive for its improvement. We shall not indeed do so unless we desire our improvement, and desire it more than we dislike the means which must be employed for the purpose." It thus appears that of the two propositions, 1, volitions are necessary, or depend on causes ; 2, volitions are free, or •do not depend on causes — neither the one nor the other is inconceivable or incomprehensible, as Sir W. Hamilton sup- posed them to be. That the first is true, and the second false, we learn by experience, and by that alone ; just as we learn the like in regard to the phenomena of the material world. Indeed, the fact that human volitions are both pre- dictable and modifiable, quite as much as all those physical phenomena that depend upon a complication of causes — which is only a corollary from what has just been said — is so universally recognised and acted upon by all men, that there would probably be little difference of opinion about this question, if the antithesis were not obscured and mystified by the familiar, but equivocal, phrases of Free-will and Necessity. Passing over chapter xxvii., in which Mr. Mill refutes Sir W. Hamilton's opinion that the study of mathematics is worthless, or nearly so, as an intellectual discipline — we shall now call attention to the concluding remarks which sum up the results of the volume. After saying that he " differs from almost everything in Sir W. Hamilton's philosophy, on which ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF SIR W. HAMILTON. 325 he particularly valued himself, or which is specially his own," Mr. Mill describes Sir W. Hamiliton's general merits as follows : — " They chiefly consist in his clear and distinct mode of bringing before the reader many of the fundamental questions of meta- physics : some good specimens of psychological analysis on a small scale : and the many detached logical and psychological truths which he has separately seized, and which are scattered through his writings, mostly applied to resolve some special difficulty, and again lost sight of. I can hardly point to anything he has done towards helping the more thorough understanding of the greater mental phenomena, unless it be his theory of Attention (including Abstraction), which seems to me the most perfect we have; but the subject, though a highly important, is comparatively a simple one." — p. 547. Agreeing in this general view of Sir W. Hamilton's merits, we should be disposed to describe them in language stronger and more emphatic as to degree, than that which has just been cited. But what is stated in the pages immediately following (pp. 550, 551) — That Sir W. Hamilton's doctrines appear to be usually taken up under the stimulus of some special dispute and often afterwards forgotten ; That he did not think out subjects until they were thoroughly mastered, or until consistency was attained between the different views which the author took from different points of observation ; That, accordingly, his philosophy seems made up of scraps from several conflicting metaphysical systems — All this is literally and amply borne out by the many inconsistencies and contradictions which Mr. Mill has brought to view in the preceding chapters. It would appear that the controversial disposition was powerful with Sir W. Hamilton, and that a present impulse of that sort (as has been said respecting Bayle, Burke, and others) not only served to provoke new intellec- tual combinations in his mind, but also exercised a Lethaean influence in causing obliviscence of the old. But we can hardly follow Mr. Mill in ascribing the defect to " excessive absorption of time and energy by the study of old writers " 326 EEVIEW OF JOHN STUART MILL (p. 551). If this study did no other good, it at least kept the memory in exercise. Now, what surprises us most in Sir W. Hamilton's inconsistencies, is the amount of self- forgetfulness which they imply. While the laborious erudition of Sir W. Hamilton cannot be fairly regarded as having produced any of his intellectual defects, it undoubtedly stamped upon him his special title of excellence as a philosopher. This is fully recognised by Mr. Mill ; though he treats it as belonging not so much to a philosopher as to an historian of philosophy. He concludes (pp. 552—554) :— " It is much to be regretted that Sir W. Hamilton did not write the history of philosophy, instead of choosing, as the dii'ect object of his intellectual exertions, philosophy itself. He possessed a knowledge of the materials such as no one, probably for many generations, will take the trouble of acquiring again. Inde- pendently of the great interest and value attaching to a knowledge of the historical development of speculation, there is much in the old writers on philosophy, even those of the middle ages, really worth preserving for its scientific value. But this should be ex- tracted, and rendered into the phraseology of modern thought, by persons as familiar with that as with the ancient, and possessing a command of its language : a combination never yet so perfectly realised as in Sir W. Hamilton. This, which no one but himself could have done, he has left undone, and has given us instead a con- tribution to mental philosophy, which has been more than equalled by many not superior to him in powers, and wholly destitute of erudition. Of all persons in modern times entitled to the name of philosophers, the two, probably, whose reading on the subject was the scantiest, in proportion to their intellectual capacity, were Archbishop Whately and Dr. Brown. Accordingly they are the only two of whom Sir W. Hamilton, though acknowledging their abilities, speaks with some tinge of superciliousness. It cannot be denied that both Dr. Brown and Whately would have thought and written better than they did, if they had been better read in the writings of previous thinkers ; but I am not afraid that pos- terity will contradict me when I say, that either of them has done far greater service to the world in the origination and diffusion of important thought than Sir W. Hamilton with all his learning ; ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF SIR W. HAMILTON. 327 because, though indolent readers, they were both of them active and fertile thinkers. " It is not that Sir W. Hamilton's erudition is not frequently of real use to him on particular questions of philosophy. It does him one valuable service : it enables him to know all the various opinions which can be held on the questions he discusses, and to conceive and express them clearly, leaving none of them out. This it does, though even this not always ; but it does little else, even of what might be expected from erudition when enlightened by philosophy. He knew, with extraordinary accuracy, the on of each philosopher's opinions, but gave himself little trouble about the Slotu With one exception, I find no remark bearing upon that point in any part of his writings. I imagine he would have been much at a loss if he had been required to draw up a philosophical estimate of the mind of any great thinker. He never seems to look at any opinion of a philosopher in connection with the same philosopher's other opinions. Accordingly he is weak as to the mutual relations of philosophical doctrines. One of the most striking examples of this inability is in the case of Leibnitz," &c. Here we find in a few sentences the conclusion which Mr. Mill conceives to be established by his book. We shall state how far we are able to concur with it. He has brought the matter to a direct issue, by weighing Sir W. Hamilton in the balance against two other actual contemporaries ; instead of comparing him with some unrealised ideal found only in the fancy of critics and reviewers. Comparing Sir W. Hamilton with Dr. Brown, we cordially subscribe to the opinion of Mr. Mill. We think that Dr. Brown has *' done far greater service to the world than Sir W. Hamilton, in the origination and diffusion of important thought." To speak only of two chief subjects in the field of important thought — Causality and the Freedom of the Will — we not only adopt the conclusions of Dr. Brown, but we admire both his acuteness and his originality in vindi- cating and illustrating the first of the two, while we dissent entirely from the views of Sir W. Hamilton. This alone would be sufficient to make us approve the superiority assigned by Mr. Mill to Dr. Brown. We discover no com- pensating item to be placed to the credit of Sir W. Hamilton : 328 REVIEW OF JOHN STUART MILL for the great doctrine of the Eelativity of Knowledge, which is our chief point of philosophical brotherhood with him, was maintained by Brown also. But in regard to Dr. Whately, our judgment is altogether different. We cannot consent to admit him as a superior, or even as an equal, to Sir W. Hamilton, " in the origination and diffusion of important thought.'^ He did much service by reviving an inclination and respect for Logic, and by clear- ing up a part of the technical obscurity which surrounded it : but we look upon him as an acute and liberal-minded English theologian, enlarging usefully, though timidly, the intellectual prison in which many orthodox minds are con- fined — rather than as a fit aspirant to the cosmopolitan honours of philosophy. " An active and fertile thinker," Mr. Mill calls Whately; and such he undoubtedly was. But such also we consider Sir W. Hamilton to have been, in a degree at least equal. If the sentence which we have quoted above be intended to deny the predicate, ** active and fertile thinker," of Sir W. Hamilton, we cannot acqui- esce in it. His intellect appears to us thoroughly active and fertile, even when we dissent from his reasonings — nay> even in the midst of his inconsistencies, when a new growth of opinions is unexpectedly pushed up, on ground which we supposed to be already pre-occupied by another both older and different. And we find this same judgment implied in the discriminating remarks upon his philoso- phical procedure made by Mr. Mill himself — (pp. 271, 272). For example, respecting Causality and the Freedom of the Will, we detect no want of activity and fertility, though marked evidence of other defects — especially the uncondi- tional surrender of a powerful mind to certain privileged inspirations, worshipped as '' necessities of thought." While thus declaring how far we concur in the parallel here drawn of Sir W. Hamilton with Brown and Whately, we must at the same time add that the comparison is. taken under circumstances unduly favourable to these two last. There has been no exposure of their errors and incon- ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF SIR W. HAMILTON. 329 sistencies, equal in penetration and completeness to the ernsliing volume which Mr. Mill has devoted to Sir W. Hamilton. To make the odds fair, he ought to furnish a similar systematic examination to Brown and Whately ; enabling us to read their works (as we now do those of Sir W. Hamilton) with the advantage of his unrivalled micro- scope, which detects the minutest breach or incoherence in the tissue of reasoning, and of his large command of philo- sophical premisses, w^hich brings into full notice what the author had overlooked. Thus alone could the competition between the three be rendered perfectly fair. We regret, as Mr. Mill does, that Sir W. Hamilton did not undertake the composition of a history of philosophy. Nevertheless we must confess that we should hardly feel such regret, if we could see evidence to warrant Mr. Mill's judgment (p. 554) that Sir W. Hamilton was 'indifferent to the Slotl of a man's opinions, and that he was incompetent to draw up an estimate of the opinions of any great thinker," &c. Such incompetence, if proved to be frequent and con- siderable, would deprive an author of all chance of success in writing a history of philosophy. But the study of Sir W. Hamilton's works does not prove it to us, though Mr. Mill has convicted him of an erroneous estimate of Leibnitz. We say frequent and considerable, because no historian of philosophy is exempt from the defect more or less ; or rather (to pass out of the self-confidence of the Absolute into the modesty of the Relative) we seldom find any historian whose estimate of great philosophical thinkers does not often differ from our own. Hence we are glad when ample and original extracts are produced, enabling us to test the historian, and judge for ourselves — a practice which Sir W. Hamilton would have required no stimulus to enforce upon him. There ought, indeed, to be various histories of philosophy, com- posed from different points of view ; for the ablest historian cannot get clear of a certain exclusiveness belonging to himself. But so far as we can conjecture what Sir W. Hamilton ivoiild or could have done, we think that a history 330 EEVIEW OF JOHN STUART MILL. of philosophy composed by him would have surpassed any work of the kind in our language. We trust that Sir W. Hamilton's works will long continue to be read, along with Mr. Mill's examination of them ; and we should be glad if the works of other philosophers could be read along with a comment of equal acuteness and impartiality. Any point of view which could command the adherence of such a mind as Sir W. Hamilton's, deserves to be fully considered. Moreover, the living force of philosophy, as directress of human intelligence, depends upon keeping up in each of her devotees a full mastery of many divergent and opposite veins of reasoning — a knowledge, negative and afSrmative, of the full case of opponents as well as of his own. It is to Philosophy alone that our allegiance is sworn, and while we concur mostly with Mr. Mill's opinions, we number both him and Sir W. Hamilton as a noble pair of brethren, serving alike in her train. Amicus Hamilton ; magis amicus Mill; arnica ante omnes Philosojjhia, PAPERS ON PHILOSOPHY. (From the Author's MSS.) PAPERS ON PHILOSOPHY. Under the date 1822, Mrs. Grote has preserved a fasciculus of very interesting essays on Metaphysics, Mr. Grote's earliest productions in that walk. They prove both the extent of his reading, and the subtlety and the depth of his own reflections. The longest and best essay is entitled '' Object and Extent of Metaphysics." It not only raises the most difficult questions in the philosophy of mind, but shows that he had already made up his mind, and taken his side, on the con- troversies that divide the schools. Five vears before, he represented himself as half-convinced by Berkeley ; he is now a Berkleian, and something more. He comes at once to the point — What is the meaning of ^External body'? and answers it according to Berkeley, although with a more advanced psychology. He expands in his own way the Berkleian motto — esse est percijoi — and does not shirk any of the difficulties. The following extracts are a specimen : — When the word Carlton-house is pronounced, a certain set of visible and tangible sensations is re-kindled in my mind — that is, I fancy myself again seeing or touching Carlton- house. When the word is pronounced, I myself supply un- consciously the act of seeing or touching, by virtue of which such a sound excites the idea habitually associated with it. And when I sav, '^ Carlton-house exists " — the full and accurate description of my state of mind is, '' I fancy that 334 papi;rs on philosophy. I see Carlton-house — I rememher to have lately seen it — or I now see it, &cr But it will doubtless be asked, " Does not Carlton-house exist when I am not thinking of it? Would it not exist though I were annihilated ?" This question, if strictly analysed, will appear to be an utter sophism — involving conditions which preclude the possibility of replying to it either in the affirmative or negative. How can I frame any kind of affirmation or denial on a subject, on which I am interdicted from employ- ing my thoughts ? I am forbidden to think upon Carlton- house — yet I am desired, notwithstanding, to say whether it exists or not. I am to suppose my mind and powers of judging annihilated — yet I am required to deliver a judg- ment on a subject placed before me. Now surely when these self-contradicting conditions are exposed, this question, which is usually the experimentum crucis of the Materialist, shrinks into an unmeaning puzzle. In order to reply to a question regarding Carlton-house, it is obvious that I must employ my thoughts about it. My decision, therefore, whether affirmative or negative, implies uniformly two things — first, that my mind is in action, i.e., not annihilated, secondly, that it is employed upon that particular subject and upon nothing else. In other words, any conceivable answer which I may return must imply two conditions the direct reverse of that which the question demands. If indeed I am asked, " whether Carlton-house cannot exist exce]^t when I am looMng at it,^^ I readily answer, that it may exist just as much when I do not see it, as when I do. But when I say this, the whole amount of my affirmation is, that I remember distinctly to have seen it, and expect fully that I may see it again — and that without at present looking upon it. The states of mind which I call remembrance and expectation may doubtless occur separately from what is usually termed perception, and may kindle a lively belief in the existence of the thing so remembered and expected. EXTEENAL PEECEPTION. 335 But this feeling of remembrance, expectation, and belief, is precisely as strong in the case of other sensations, when constant, as it is in those of sight and touch. My remem- brance and belief that the noise of a cataract, which I have visited formerly, now exists, is just as strong as my remem- brance and belief that the water or the rocks exist. I have as full a conviction that I may again hear the one, as that I may again see the other. Should it be asked, whether there is any noise when I am not near to hear it, I should answer, that there unquestionably was. It matters not whether I actually hear it or not. I remember to have heard it and expect to hear it again. There is not a shade of difference in my feelings with regard to the sound, and with regard to the rocks. I have already remarked that partly from their perma- nence, partly from their urgency, the visual and tactile sensations come to exercise prodigious ascendency over our minds. All our other states of mind are viewed with refer- ence to these others, as antecedents or concomitants or consequents, and the visual and tactile sensations thus appropriate and enslave all the rest. But these two pre- dominant classes of sensations acquire, as I have endeavoured to explain, a seeming independence of our mental modifi- cations, and appear to have an existence distinct from and without our minds. Hence, since a powerful interest con- tinually impels us to consider all our sensations with refer- ence to the visual and tactile, and since these appear to exist distinct from the mind — we contract an habitual desire of tracing our states of mind up to something distinct from and independent of ourselves. We search about for an external something to which we may attribute any mental affection of which we are conscious ; and when the latter has once been fastened and domiciliated with any external something, the process of the mind appears to be performed, its dissatisfaction is appeased, and it is set at rest. The early growth of this tendency is of infinite and melan- 336 PAPERS ON PHILOSOPHY. choly importance. It thrusts itself upon us upon all occa- sions, as an operation of primary necessity ; it perverts our views of what is desirable or practicable to know, and distorts altogether the application of the power of thought ; and it casts so deep a mist over all the proceedings of the understanding, as no subsequent reflexion can entirely dissipate. When a state of mind occurs w^hich is not fami- liar to us, and which we desire to explain, we are drawn away from that path of observation and comparison which alone can conduct us to a solid result ; we do not think of comparing the different trains of which it forms a member, in order to separate its casual from its constant companions. We instantly look for an external something on which we may hitch it, and if none such presents itself, we slide easily into the process of creation, and fasten that which is to be accounted for upon some fictitious and imaginary entity. Of these numberless mistakes the source is to be sought iu that early habit which bestows upon the visual and tactile sensations so complete an ascendency over the mind, and which leads us to father all our other mental modifications upon them alone. I cannot depart from this topic without offering a few remarks on the controversy between Berkeley and Eeid, with regard to which much misconception appears to have arisen. The merits of the latter have been blazoned forth, and his refutation paraded far and wide as victorious and irresistible, by his disciple and expositor, Mr. Stewart, whereas the treatise of the former has been left an orphan (to use a beautiful expression of Plato) and defenceless, and seems to have met with few who could comprehend its bearings, or disengage the truth w^hich its author so suc- cessfully struck out, from the errors which particular pre- judices led him to array by its side. Few treatises ever stood more in need of such a commentator ; for the mixture which it presents is indeed singular. It is remarkable, that both Berkeley and Keid (as each has left upon record) were EXTERNAL PERCEPTION. 337 led into their different and contradictory trains of thought by the very same motive — an aversion to Atheism, and a zeal for the maintenance of religious belief. To place religion on a firm and unassailable foundation, the Bishop thought it requisite to refute the supposition that there was any unthinking substance existing without the perceiving mind, and to prove that only spiritual or thinking substances could be thus independently existent. While, in pursuance of these views, he adheres to the former track, his reasonings are strikingly ingenious and original. He insists forcibly on the impossibility of seeing anything unseen, hearing anything unheard, conceiving anything un- conceived, &c., which is what is meant by affirming that the objects of sight, of touch, of conception, or of any other mental feeling whatever, exist independent of the mind. I shall not dwell any longer upon this part of his writings, because I have endeavoured to enforce the same line of argument in various parts of these Essays, and because perhaps the very best statement of the doctrine, which Berkeley*s book affords, is a passage already cited. But when, in furtherance of his original plan, the Bishop sought to evade the application of these reasonings to the case of Spirit, it is melancholy to observe the confusion which beo:ins to overcloud his mind, and the unreal dis- tinctions which appear to satisfy his once piercing and irresistible scrutiny. "A spirit (said he) cannot be known by way of idea ; it is a simple, undivided, active Being, per- cipient of ideas, but not itself perceived, like an Idea. We know a Spirit immediately by way of notion. Now though it is impossible that an Idea, whose esse is pereipi, should exist without being perceived ; yet it is not impossible that a Spirit, whose esse is joercipere, should exist without being perceived." Such was the distinction by which Berkeley strove to shelter Spirit from the arguments by which he had attacked matter. A very cursory inspection will discover its in- sufficiency. For either the word Spirit means nothing, or • z 338 PAPERS ON PHILOSOPHY. else it means something conceived, believed, imagined, sup- posed, &c., call the state of mind what you will. To say, that my ideas may be perceived by another percipient, is merely to say, that I may conceive, or believe, or know, or suppose, &c., that they are perceived by another percipient. Another percipient is, in other words, something known or conceived as perceiving. And it is impossible that anything known or conceived can have an existence independent of the knowing or conceiving mind. At any rate, it makes no difference whether the thino* known be thinkino; or un- thinking. If the independent existence of the latter is impossible, that of the former is equally so ; if that of the former be possible, so is that of the latter. Now as this line of distinction could not be maintained, it was obvious that Berkelev's doctrine was self-contradictorv. The question was, which half of it should destroy the other. Viewing the controversy simply as it stood between Eeid and Berkeley, it must be owned that the inconsistency, which so glaringly pervades the doctrine of the latter, placed his adversary upon a ground of attack singularly advan- tageous. The admissions, in which the Bishop had so liberally indulged towards Spirit, were perfectly sufficient to vindicate the existence of Matter, if they conld be shewn to apply equally to it — that is, if the distinction which Berkelev had drawn between the two could be removed. But this distinction consisted in the hypothesis, that we knew matter by way of ideas, or of an intervening something immediately perceived by the mind — while we knew sjDirit immediately, or without any such intervention. This was the ideal theorv, and Dr. Eeid directed the whole force of his reasonings against it. " We are admitted (said he) to know Spirit immediately ; what reason is there for supposing that we know Matter in anv other way ? Whv should not our apprehension of the one be as direct and immediate as that of the other? Can any evidence be adduced of the intervention of an idea, in the case of material substance ?" EXTEKNAL PEECEPTION. 339 It was perfectly true that no such evidence could be adduced. And as far as regards Berkeley, or any one who coincides with Berkeley's admissions concerning Spirit, I think the arguments of Eeid are decisive and invincible. But his advantage over the Bishop merely arose from his consistency in vindicating two errors, which must stand or fall together ; while his adversary, in dismissing one, clung with increased vehemence and pertinacity to the other. By the removal, therefore, of the ideal theory, it must be allowed that the repugnance and self-contradiction of Berkeley's system was demonstrated, and the controversy decided in favour of Eeid. Not so the controversy about the independent existence of material substance. The real value of Berkeley's argu- ments on the negative side of this question is not at all impaired, because they happened in his mind to be closely knit together with certain errors, which rendered it in- consistent in him to maintain them. And the actual force of these arguments is so far from depending on the ideal theory (on the destruction of which Mr. Stewart rests the celebrity of Eeid), that they must, if received, exclude and nullify that theory altogether. For the ideal theory is nothing but a supposition framed to explain the mode in which we perceive external objects. Now if there exist no objects independent of the mind, the ideal theory becomes altogether useless and unmeaning, inasmuch as the difficulty, which it was destined to explain, is terminated. When I affirm that I am conscious of nothing but my own states of mind or mental modifications — whether called sensations, conceptions, acts of belief, or by any other name, this general statement of fact is certainly no theory at all ; but least of all is it the ideal theory, which is of a nature and purpose altogether inconsistent with this statement of fact. The truth is, that if the ideal theory is an unsupported hypo- thesis, so also is the supposition of external independent objects. If the ideas, of which I am conscious, are really nothing, distinct from and independent of the. conscious z 2 340 PAPERS ON PHILOSOPHY. mind — then neither are the external objects, which I per- ceive, anything distinct from and independent of the perceiving mind. To say that there may exist objects without my mind, distinct from its perceptions ; but that there cannot possibly exist any objects within my mind, distinct from its consciousness, is an assumption destitute of all evidence, and virtually predetermining the very question in disj)ute, by introducing the expressions, icitliout and within the mind ; a phraseology altogetlier unmeaning, if the hypothesis of external objects be rejected. [In 1860, there occurred an interesting correspondence on the same subject, which is here reproduced in full. The ostensible start was from the conchiding chapter of Pro- fessor Bain's work, ^The Emotions and the Will,' where a criticism was made on Ferrier's * Institutes,' from the point of view of the Relativity of all Knowledge ; the Subject-and- Object Eelativity being only one example, although posses- sing an altogether exceptional importance. In point of fact, however, Mr. Grote had of his own motion been meditating intently on the correlation of the Subject and Object in per- ception, and took this opportunity to put down his thoughts in writing.] SUBJECT AND OBJECT. There are portions of your section on this subject which do not quite satisfy me. I coincide more fully with your treatment of the same matter (or the branch of the same matter which relates to the material world), in your first volume [^ The Senses and the Intellect '], pp. 366-376. The relativeness of Subject to Object, as I conceive it, stands singly and by itself, apart from all relativeness between two or more diverse objects of cognition. Whether cognition be only possible under the assumption of a known contrast between two different objects, as you imagine — or SUBJECT AND OBJECT. 341 whether it be also possible with only one object, not con- sciously contrasted with any foil, as I incline to believe — in either case the cognizant subject is the same, equally present and incorporated in the fact of cognition. An act of cog- nition has no meaning without a cognizing subject and a cognitum object : the former always the same, the latter variable : both being opposite points of view (or poles) ol the same indivisible fact of mind. If, in addition to this, it be true that there must be two distinct objects, known in antithesis to each other by the cognizant subject, let the position be proved : but it seems to me distinct from, and independent of, the position above laid down respecting subject and object. The two positions ought to be affirmed and reasoned upon apart from each other : not thrown together under one general head. You say truly (vol. i. p. 376) that to speak of a cognitum apart from a cognoscens is " self-contradiction :" but it is surely no self-contradiction (whether exact or not) to say that we can know red without green, or light without darkness. You seem to consider the antithesis of subject and object, as coinciding with that of ideal and real — mind and matter — internal and external. I cannot but think that subject and object is more general and fundamental than this. The dis- tinction Subject — Object belongs to the ideal world, as well as to the sensational. John Mill says in his ^ Logic ' (Book i. c. iii. p. 55) — " Even imaginary objects, which are said to exist only in our ideas, are to be distinguished from our ideas of them. The hobgoblin which never existed is not the same thing with my idea of a hobgoblin. They are all, not thoughts, but objects of thought, though all the objects are alike non- existent." Plato's archetypal Ideas were Objects, though neither material nor extended. The act of Conception, as well as the act of Perception, is in itself indivisible : but both the one and the other may be looked at either in the subjective or in the objective point of view. The Subject is that which either one or the other has in common with all the other acts of our mind or 342 PAPEES ON PHILOSOPHY, Gonsciousness — the indeterminate Ego, The Object is that which either one or the other has either peculiar to itself, or common only to a select fraction of our acts of consciousness: it is the varying Ego, or the principle of variation and specialisation in Ego. We cannot properly speak of it as iVbii-Ego: it involves, not a negation, but a simple modifi- cation and determination, of the Subject. The antithesis of Ego and Non-Ego, which some writers adopt, involves an illusion : the real antithesis is between Eg^o determinate and Ego indeterminate: the determinate Ego being the com- plete mental fact, from which the indeterminate Ego is the highest abstraction. There seem to be various sources of confusion in reference to this antithesis of Subject — Object. 1. Our own bodies. I apprehend that the earliest con- ception of Subject, that which prevails in unreflecting minds, is the distinction between each man's body and matter external to his body. He considers his body to be Subject — that is, Mmself, What is external to his body is Object, or not himself. This distinction gets early and powerful hold upon the mind. But it is evidently an objective distraction, between two different objects : for each man's body is object to himself as Subject : it is seen and felt, and the boundary between it and what is beyond it can be traced by sensation and movement. The body partakes of the nature both of Subject and Object. Considered as object, the distinction between our body and matter extraneous to our body, is not only clear and marked but highly important : it is the most familiar and indispensable of all distinctions. Whait is ex- traneous to our own body, is extraneous to ourselves as Subject : for the Subject is identical with the body, or at least co-extensive with it. What is really an antithesis between two objects, is converted into antithesis or divorce between object and subject. 2. The second source of confusion is, that w^e look back upon our own ^ast sensations, perceptions, and mental acts generally. When I recollect or conceive an object which I SUBJECT AND OBJECT. 343 saw or touched an hour ago, I know that I am not now seeing or touching it. My jpercipient Subject forms no part of the recollection: and it appears as if that which I recollect or conceive was Object pure and simple, without a Subject. But there is here an illusion : because my Subject, though not interfering as percipient, interferes as reminiscent or eoncipient, and forms an equally essential part of the real fact. To our memory, or conception, is present only the objective point of view of the past sensation; but the memory or conception itself forms the subjective to correlate with it. 3. A third source of confusion relates to the distinction between myself and other subjects. I believe that other subjects are often affected in the same manner as I am — often not so. But in making this comparison, it is plain that I regard my own subject as an object. Other persons can be only objects to me : and when I compare myself to them, I become an ohject to myself : that is my past sensa- tions and mental acts pass under my review, or become objects to my reminiscent or reflecting subject. I, the Subject, am in this way, as it were, counted twice over: once as reflecting, once again as object reflected upon ; and it is in the latter capacity alone that I am compared with other subjects. The distinction, or resemblance, which I note between my sensations and those of other men, is in reality an objective distinction, noted by myself as com- jparing subject between myself and others as compared objects. But the fact that I am the comparing subject passes un- noticed and out of sight : all that is usually noticed is, the two compared objects, myself and others. It is forgotten that this comparison cannot be made without myself as subject to make it. The subject, as such, is overlooked : it cannot come into separate consciousness : it can only be understood by comparing together some or all of our past mental acts and attending to that which they all have in common. But in this process, my past self becomes an Object, to my present self as Subject: my 344 PAPERS ON PHILOSOPHY. present self being of necessity implied, but not consciously present. James Mill (' Analysis', vol. i. pp. 244, 245, 249) adverts to this distinction between ;past self and p^eseiit self. He seems liowever to think that present selfcsiJi come into separate consciousness as well as past self. If he means this, I cannot agree with him. I think that self only comes into conscious- ness as an ohject — 2^^^^ ^^ future self: as subject, or present self it is implied, but never revealed or discernible. The distinction between past self or object, and present seK, or subject, enables us to criticise Ferrier's position, that "every cognition must involve a cognition of self." If he had said, that " every cognition must involve self as the cognizant," I think he would have been perfectly correct. The self, present self or subject, is constant and indispensable as the cognoscens, but cannot become the cognitum. The 2)resent self forms one constant and unalterable pole of the indivisible act of cognition. Our past self on the contrary, belongs to the other or objective pole. But -even in this sense of the objective self, Ferrier's position is not exact. It is not true that every cognition must involve a cognition of self. In many cognitions, the objective self is not at all included. I know many things, which I do not at all recol- lect to have seen, or heard, or discovered, or reasoned out, by my past or objective self. Of some cognitions, this past self makes a part ; but not of all. But the present self belono;s to all. The distinction between these two sorts of cognitions is important to bear in mind, because it contributes materially to generate the illusion of an Objective Absolute. Because many of my cognitions include no reference to a (past or objective) self, and are in this respect distinguishable from those which do include such reference — it is imamned that the first class are wholly divorced from self ; that they are complete and independent absolutes. It is forgotten that the present or subjective self is implicated alike in both the two classes. SUBJECT AND OBJECT. 345 In explaining this abstruse point of psychological theory, the first great problem is, to find means of bringing the forgotten present or suhjective self into notice. It cannot be known by direct and immediate consciousness, in reference to any present sensation or cognition. It can only be known by inference from the sum total of our past mental states, and by appeal to the fact of cognition as the radical or primordial element from which psychology takes its start. Instead of pretending to explain this primordial fact by the hypothesis of an Absolute Object acting upon an Absolute Subject to generate cognition, we have to take the cognition itself as an indivisible act capable of being looked at from two sides — either from the side common to all cognitions, or from that which varies from time to time in each particular case. The second problem is, while rescuing the subjective self from oblivion, to bring it into notice as not isolated but always incorporated with some particular object, with which it is fused in one and the same mental act. Every mental act or condition — be it sensation, perception, conception, emotion, volition, belief, intuition, ratiocination — includes the subject determined by its object, and may be looked at from one or from the other point of view\ If I speak of an Object of perception, of belief, of intuition, of ratiocination — I myself am present, in the mental state which dictates the speech, as percipient, credent, intuent, ratiocinant : the Object is relative to me, in one or other of these capacities ; and I am relative to that as to other objects. The Noumena require a Nous to apprehend them, and reciprocally the Nous requires Noumena to enable it to come into act: so also the Percepta and Percipiens mutually imply each other, and are two modes of looking at the same real fact. The distinction between the Keal and the Ideal is doubt- less very important to be maintained : but it does not turn upon the distinction between Object and Subject. It turns on the distinction between Sentient Subject and Concipient or Cogitant Subject, or (which is equivalent) between 346 PAPERS OX PHILOSOPHY. Objectum Sensum and Objectum Cogitatum or Conception — between the act of Sensation and the act of Ideation. Sub- ject and Object are each common to both : but in the one class, I am sentient subject, in the other class, cogitant subject: in the one class the object is an object of per- ception, in the other an object of conception or an Ens Eationis. I am myself the true and fundamental subject of all my propositions : every proposition announces by impli- cation — I feel, I think, J believe, and so and so. There are many propositions in Avhich this is not directly included in the formal enunciation : but it is not the less really under- stood in all, without exception. In explaining the nature of propositions, this ineffaceable subjective basis ought to be formally and emphatically laid down. In practice men lose sight of it, because of its universality : but these forgotten but constcint elements are the very matters which the analysing philosopher should take the most pains to bring clearly into view. [The foregoing was transmitted to Professor Terrier, who made to it the reply published in his Eemains, vol. 1. The interest of that reply will be greatly enhanced by its being read in connection with Mr. Grote's paper.] " The point at issue between Mr. G. and me is this : — He holds that the ])resent self is never the object, or any part of the object, of our consciousness. I venture to hold the ^' opposite opinion, and have given expression to it in my " opening proposition, in which it is maintained that the self " and the not-self are always apprehended simiiltaneoiisly, '^ although I admit that the self is usually no prominent or " explicit portion of the cognition. " In Mr, G.'s paper there is a certain ambiguity (as I dare- " say there are plenty on my side of the question), something " at least about which I am in doubt, and which must be '' cleared up before any progress can be made in the discus- " sion ; in fact, before there can be either any disagreement 66 SUBJECT AND OBJECT. 347 ^' or any agreement between us. I shall endeavour, at the " outset, to explain what this ambiguity or inconsistency is. "In every case of cognition more is imjplied than is " expressly known. For instance, when I look at a tree, all " that I am expressly cognisant of is the tree. This at least ^' is usually the whole — the whole that is explicit. But " much more is implied. I am implied, seeing is implied, a ^' retina is implied, a hrain is implied. All these are impli- ** cated in the process. They are present and instrumental, ^^ but the tree alone is expressly known. So far, I think, " Mr. Gr. and I will agree ; so far there is no ambiguity. '' But a question here' arises. Are these implicated ele- '' ments not known at all, or are they only not known ex- ^'fressly ? In other words, may not that which is not known " expressly or explicitly be nevertheless known — known '^implicitly? "This is an important question. In reference to the " present discussion it is all-important, and it must be an- " swered unambiguously. For myself, I answer the question '- in the affirmative. I argue for implicit, as well as for " explicit cognition. And I maintain that some of the ele- " ments above referred to, as implicated in my cognition of " the tree, are known implicitly, and that others of them are ''not known at all. M' and 'seeing' are known implicitly " in and along with my explicit knowledge of the tree ; " ' retina ' and ' brain ' are not known at all. And the '^ ground of the distinction is this, that reflection enables me " to recover and render explicit ' me ' and ' seeing ' — a cir- "cumstance which to my mind proves that these Avere " already known implicitly, although overlooked at the time ; " whereas no power of reflection can reveal to me a retina or "brain as having been concerned in the operation. To dis- " cover these I must have recourse to renewed observation " and anatomy. " But what I am at a loss about is the answer which Mr. G. " gives to this important question. This is the article in "regard to which I venture to think that he is ambiguous. 348 PAPERS ON PHILOSOPHY. " From the general purport of the remarks in which he con- " troyerts my position, I would conclude that he is opposed ^' to the doctrine of ' implicit cognitions. ' But there are " expressions in his note which seem to point to the opposite " conclusion. He says that the ego ^ is understood in all " propositions, ' understood, of course, by itself and to itself ; '' that is to say, known implicitly and in the present time. " And in his last sentence he says, ' In practice men lose " sight of it (the ego) because of its universality ; but these " forgotten but distinct elements are the very matters which *^the analysing philosopher should take the most pains to " bring clearly into view. ' On this I would remark that it is '^not possible for the analysing philosopher to briug clearly " into view any element of consciousness which was not " known obscurely beforehand. Eeflection is his only instru- " ment ; and reflection cannot originate knowledge : it can " only make us know clearly and explicitly what we already " know confusedly and implicitly. " The result is, that I am in doubt as to the ground occu- " pied by Mr. G. in reference to implicit cognitions. Does "he deny them altogether? Must all cognition be either '' express or null ? In that case, he will find it very difficult, " or rather impossible, to explain how a reflective aualysis '* can go to work upon its materials, these being, on this " supposition, the absolutely unknown. On the other hand, *^ does he admit implicit cognition ? In that case, I think ^' that there cannot be any very great difference between us ; " and that, with a little explanatory coaxing, he might be " brought roimd to my side of the question : for if a man "admits any implicit cognitions, or, I should rather say, " implicit elements of cognition, he may surely accept the ego " as among the number. But until I know whether, and to " what extent, Mr. G. accepts or rejects the doctrine of im- '^ plied cognitions, I do not see how he and I can properly " join issue, either in the way of agreement or disagreement, ^ ' So much in reference to the ambiguity of which I com- " plain. SUBJECT AND OBJECT. 349 ^' For the reason given I shall not go much into argument "on the point more particularly in dispute. Let me just "say that Mr. G.'s doctrine, that we have no cognisance of ^' our present, but only of our past self, is, in my opinion, " untenable, for these among other reasons : — ''First, I cannot have any cognisance of my past self " without distinguishing myself as past from myself as pre- '' sent. But I cannot make this distinction without being " cognisant of my present self. Therefore, in being cognisant " of my past self, I must always be cognisant (implicitly it " may be) of my present self. Secondly, would the words ' I '' am' have any meaning, except in reference to a self cog- " nised in the present ? Thirdly, it would not be possible for " a man to he cognisant of his past self unless he had heen '' cognisant of his present self. What a man remembers is, " that certain sensations were his, that certain events befell " him ; that is, he remembers both himself and those events, " and the connection between him and them. If he had not been cognisant of himself in the present (which is now past), he either would remember only the events, and their " having happened to nobody, at least not to him (which is " absurd), or he would not have remembered them at all, " which is the more probable alternative, But he does re- " member them ; and he remembers, moreover, that they " happened to him, which seems to me to prove that he was " cognisant (however inexplicitly) of himself at the time. " But I have exhausted my paper, and I daresay your " patience, so I shall say no more at present, except that I "cannot think that Mr. G.'s position is not blasted, or that " mine is shaken, by anything that has been as yet advanced. '' Perhaps he thinks that a contradiction is involved in sup- " posing that the cognoscens can be in the same instant the " cognition. But that is precisely the idea and definition of "the ego, that it is at once its own subject and its own "object-— not, however, without a contrasting element, the " non-ego." 6i 6i 350 PAPERS ON PHILOSOPHY. [To this Mr. Grote rejoined.] I have read with much interest the paper of Professor Ferrier. He has handled this abstruse subject with great acuteness, and in a manner which, if it does not bring about agreement between two dissentients, enables both of them to understand better both the grounds and the measure of their dissent. The point at issue between us is brought to view more distinctly in the concluding sentence of his letter than in the preceding parts. He there says — • " Perhaps he (G.) thinks, that a contradiction is involved in supposing that the cognoscens can be in the same instant the cognitum. But that is precisely the idea and definition of the Ego — that it is at once its own subject and its own object — not however without a contrasting element, the non- Egor The question between Mr. F. and myself, as I conceive it, is, whether this " idea and definition of the Ego " be a correct one : whether there be really any such duplication or double function of the Ego, in the same instant or in the same act of present cognition. In my judgment, such dupli- cation or double function belongs, not to present cognition, but to reflex cognition only. On two points, I think, we are both agreed. First, there is in every act of cognition an essential impli- cation of Cognoscens and Cognitum — Subject and Object. Secondly, there is in every act of reflex cognition a dupli- cation of the Ego. Here it is at once Cognoscens and Cog- nitum. The case which Mr. F. states, about " seeing the tree," illustrates this perfectly ; and I quite agree with the manner in which he states it. In reflection, I disimpUcate that which in the act itself had been implicated. My reflect- ing Ego is the cognoscens : the Ego of my previous act of vision is the cognitum. On these points Mr. F. and I concur : but our difference lies in the manner of conceiving and stating the elements SUBJECT AND OBJECT. 351 really implicated in the original, present, act of cognition (or vision). He maintains that the duplication or double function of the Ego occurs in the original act of cognition as well as in the reflex act : and he argues that it could not occur in the reflex unless it had previously occurred in the original. I submit that this argument is not satisfactory. That which in the original cognition had been simply Egfo cognoscens, would present itself as Ego cognitus to the new Ego cognoscens acting in the work of reflection. It is by no means necessary to assume, that in the original act of cognition, the Ego must have been at once cognoscens and cognitus. In Mr. F.'s theory, the Ego is counted twice over in the original act of cognition — where, as I think, it really occurs only once : while no account is taken of the new Ego cognoscens which appears in the act of reflection. The inter- vention of this new Ego cognoscens makes an important difference between the act of reflection and the act of pre- sent cognition. It is an additional element, blending itself with the revived elements of the previous cognition, and generally with other cognitions brought into comparison with this latter. And it is moreover an essential condition, enabling us to disimplicate elements which had been essen- tially implicated in the act of cognition itself. ' I will not go so far as to affirm " that a contradiction is involved in supposing that the cognoscens can be in the same instant the cognituniJ' But it appears to me, that this hypothesis assumes more in the act of cognition than really belongs to it. The implication, in that act, of the cognoscens with the cognitum, is indisputable : not so, when we come to assume the triple implicate — cognoscens, cognoscens cog- nitum, and cognitum. Here we count the cognoscens twice over : not upon any evidence of direct consciousness (which is inapplicable to the case), but as an inference from what occurs in the act of reflection. The grounds upon which Mr. F. rests this inference appear to me insufficient, and it is upon this point that I join issue with him. What occurs in the act of reflection would, in my judgment, occur equally, 352 PAPERS ON PHILOSOPHY. if we admit in the primary act of cognition nothing more than an implication of the cognoscens with some oognitum — . subject ivith object. I do not use the terms Ego and Non-Ego, because they appear to me less appropriate. The last is as much positive as the first, though it is variable, while the first is constant. If I am right, this implication of subject with object is the simplest and most universal statement of what is common to all acts of cognition : whether in its ruder form, as among children and animals — or in its more complicated form, as among reflecting and analysing students. We cannot abolish either of the two without dismissing mind altogether : though we may look at cognitions from either of the two points of view, leaving out for the time the consideration of the other. In such processes of abstraction, comparison, reflection, we disimplicate the two elements of those cognitions which we compare and reflect upon. But we do not even here disimplicate the ^process of cognition: for our reflecting or comparing Ego becomes itself implicated in the act of reflexion or comparison. With reference to the reasoning in Mr. F.'s fourth page (p. 349), I would say, that ih.eioresentselfi^ present as cognizing, not as cognized : and that the words lam, though they include the present self, include a great deal more besides. Mr. F. says : " Thirdly, it would not be possible for a man to be cognizant of his jpast self, unless he had been cognizant of his present self,'' I incline to believe that the reverse of the proposition is more accurate, and that we are cognizant of our present self only through inferences from our past self. I see the books in my study now before me — I hear the noise of carriages in the street — I meditate on Mr. F.'s paper now on my table — but all this while my present self never shews himself as a part of the scene, or as an object of cognition or consciousness. In fact, it seems to me that self is a complicated word, which requires many comparisons before its meaning can be understood, and which cannot be understood except as including more than the present SUBJECT AND OBJECT. 353 moment. I cannot conceive my present self except as the continuance of an unbroken line from the past. I am con- scious of my present act of cognition : but that which is present to my consciousness is, simply the object cognized: by reflection on past acts, I know that the cognizing subject must be present and implicated— but I know it in no other way. On looking over again Mr. F.'s letter (Mr. Grote con- tinues), before sending off my reply, I perceive that I have dwelt rather too exclusively on the fourth page. I will therefore add a few words, answering more directly the question in page 2. I admit that there are implicit cognitions : that is, as I understand it, cognitions of which we have no conscious- ness distinct at the time or capable of being remembered afterwards — but which nevertheless may be proved, by evi- dence aliunde, to have been objects of consciousness and to have left their effects behind. You give in your first volume (' Senses and Intellect,' p. 390) an interesting example of this kind, in reference to the intellectual discrimination between different sensations of touch, such sensations being undistinguishable both emotionally and volitionally. But while I admit this as a fact of frequent occurrence in the human mind, and therefore as a legitimate explanation in various obscurities of mental philosophy, I must at the same time add, that the onus jprobandi lies upon him who advances the explanation. He must produce evidence to prove that these implicit cognitions have really been in the mind as cognitions. Now the evidence produced by Mr. F. does not appear to me sufficient to prove the point, in his particular case. Again, he remarks upon a phrase of mine in my first paper — " Gr. says that the Ego is understood in all propositions — understood (F. remarks) of course by itself and to itself — that is to say, known implicitly " (bottom of page 2). In regard to this, I would say, that I do not clearly remember 2 A 354 PAPERS ON PHILOSOPHY. the phrases in my first paper, but I presume that I meant understood in the sense of the Latin word suhauditum, not intelledum: as the knowing element tacitly implied, and essentially as a condition, in all present knowledge, but not knowable itself except through reflex view upon past acts of knowledge. Pray read the above remarks, and forward them to Mr. F., if you think they deserve it. I am much obliged to him for the trouble he has taken in drawing up the paper of criticism on my former remarks. I hope he will accept the present communication as a mark both of gratitude and respect. [In the months of February and March, 1871, when the fatal malady was making progress, Mr. Grote read with avidity and with much admiration the work of M. Taine, ' De rintelligence.' He still kept up undiminished his life- long interest in Logical and Psychological discussions, and could give forth his thoughts with clearness and vigour, as will be seen from the following observations, being the text of letters written on such parts of Mr. Taine's work as related to the fundamental notions and the axioms of science. These were the last rays of the setting sun.] Taine seeks to rehabilitate the Absolute, or an external self-existent, under the attenuated form of Motion reduced to its lowest terms of Order and Number, and divested of everything which distinguishes one case of Motion from another. His argument appears to me very inconclusive in these thirteen pages : for while he in several passages admits (to all appearance) the fundamental reference to ourselves and our own sensations — he in other passages professes to point out other characteristics which lie apart from this reference : the truth being, that these latter characteristics involve the same reference, just as much as the former, only ON M. TAINE ' DE L'lNTELLTGENCE.' 355 that it lies behind, and requires rather more attention to see it : which attention Taine does not bestow. Thus {e,g) look at p. 54, where he professes to discriminate the cha- racteristics relative to us from those which are absolute and have no reference to us. For example, he says : — " Le moi est un reactif entre cent millions d'autres. — A ses notations, nous substituons d'autres notations equivalentes, et nous deflnissons les proprietes des corps, non plus par nos evene- mens^ mais par certains de leurs evenemens. Au lieu de notre sensation de temperature, nous prenons pour indice Televation ou I'abaissement de I'alcohol dans le ther- mometre." Taine here overlooks the fact that the rise or fall of alcohol in the thermometre is only another variety of our sensations : an application of our sense of vision appealed to in place of our sense of temperature, and certifying comparison of temperature inferentially instead of directly. The case is the same with the other example cited by Taine — the rise or fall in one of the scales of a balance, informing us of comparative weights, much better than could be done by our own muscular sensations when we support the two bodies with our hands. Here again appeal is made to another variety of our sensations : what Taine says—" nous deflnissons les proprietes des corps, non plus par nos evene- mens, mais par leurs evenemens," — is not true. We do not, and cannot, leave out nos evenemens. It appears as if Taine thought, that whenever we had recourse to an indirect and inferential measure respecting the properties of a body, we thereby departed from the principle of E-elativity. In this I think he is quite mis- taken: and moreover inconsistent with himself. For we read, p. 57, the following passage — '* Entre les diverses classes d'evenemens par lesquels on peut definir les choses, I'homme en choisit une, y ramene la plupart des autres, suppose qu'il pourra un jour y ramener le rcste. Mais, si Ton analyse celui qu'il a choisi, on decouvre que tons les elemens originels et constitutifs de sa definition, comme de la definition de tous les autres, ne sont jamais que des 356 PAPERS ON PHILOSOPHY. sensations, ou des extraits plus ou moins elabores de sensa- tions." Surely it is impossible to declare universal Belativity — the universal implication of us the sentients, and of our sensations, in every definition — in plainer language than this. Again, I cannot but question the manner in which Taine conceives and defines Motion (p. 55) — '^ une serie de sensa- tions successives interposees entre les momens de depart et d'arrivee — une serie d'etats successifs interposes entre les momens de depart et d'arrivee." Surely Motion is con- tinuous between departure and arrival : there is no series or succession of states in Motion. There is a series or order in the lolaces through which the Motum passes — but in the fact of Motion itself, there is no series or succession. Motion is essentially continuous, from departure to stoppage : it is the very type of continuity : in order that you may have suc- cession of states, or of sensations, you must have stoppage and recommencement of motion. I consider it a contradictio in adjecio when Taine (p. 63) talks of ^* la serie continue des evenemens successifs qui constituent le mouvement d'une pierre transportee par notre main — cette serie continue de sensations museulaires successives qui constituent pour nous le mouvement de notre main." When I affirm continuity, I virtually deny succession — and vice versa. We are all moving along with the Earth in its two uniform motions of rotation and translation : but we have no consciousness of successive sensations constituting this motion. The terms senes and succession belong, not to the motion itself, but to the places through which the Motum passes, or to the collateral sensations which attach to those places respec- tively : as when we move from light to dark, from cold to hot, &c. Number and Order, to which Taine professes to reduce the fact of Motion when pared down by abstraction, do not (in my opinion) belong to Motion at all, unless you include along with it certain concomitant sensations which are not of the essence of Motion, and which may be absent as well as present. , In regard to Taine's reasoning, from p. 57 to p. 65, where ON M. TAINE 'DE L'lNTELLIGENCE.' 357 lie attempts to erect an Absolute on the back of Mill's theory and yours, I consider it altogether fallacious. I admit indeed that it holds good as an argumentum ad hominem. If I granted the absolute and independent exist- ence of minds other than my own, I should be prepared also to grant the absolute and independent existence of rocks and trees. Indeed I think the reasons for granting it in the latter case are stronger than those applying to the former. For I have no direct knowledge or commerce with another man's mind, but only with his body : before I can infer the absolute existence of his mind, I must begin by recognizing the absolute existence of his body : and when once I have done that, I cannot refuse absolute existence to rocks and trees. Taine takes for granted this recognition of absolute exist- ence of other minds, by all the followers of Berkeley. This is really his one and only argument, which he puts forward with easy confidence — " legitimement (pp. 58, 59) sur preuves valables," p. 62. He certainly is right in supposing that Berkeley recognises this doctrine, and I think (without being quite sure) that John Mill recognises it : but I dissent from it entirely. Indeed I think that the common, un- philosophical, opinion of the absolute existence of the material world generally, is more consistent and tenable than the opinion which restricts absolute existence to minds only, our own and all others besides. No one has done more than Taine to illustrate the frequent illusions of the mind in assuming, as external and independent, what is merely subjective. But in this particular case, he cannot bear to admit " une illusion de I'esprit humain " (p. 58), which he has shown to be omnipotent in so many other cases. Yet many of his sentences appear to be written as if he held the same opinion as we do. For example (p. 68) — " II essaye de considerer a part et en soi ce quelque chose independant et permanent qu'il n'a isole que par un ovhli, II cree ainsi la substance vide : sur cette entite la metaphysique tra- vaille et batit ainsi ses chateaux de cartes: pour les faire 2 B 358 PAPERS ON PHILOSOPHY. tomber, ce n'est pas trop de I'analyse la plus rigoureuse.'* This sentence expresses my opinion, and I think very well : the ovhli of which he speaks, is intended by him to express only the objective attributes from which la substance vide is detached : but I should extend the meaning so as to include also the judging and believing Subject ; which, though omni- present and inseparable, is just as much forgotten and put out of sight as if it had no existence. Taine's highly abstract attenuation of Motion is a fetch of Realism. It is on a par with la substance vide in the passage last cited. How few philosophers are there who carry out consistently the doctrine Avhich Aristotle took so much pains to inculcate — that reality is to be sought in the concrete and particular, not in the abstract and universal ! In the attempt made by Taine to bring the geometrical and arithmetical Axioms under the head of Analytic Pro- positions instead of Synthetic, he reasons in direct opposition to John Mill's argument in the second chapter of his second book: Taine adopts what Mill there calls " the ultra-Nomin- alism of Hobbes and Condillac " (p. 199) : Taine considers " that the process of arriving at new truths by reasoning consists in the mere substitution of one set of arbitrary signs for another " and a substitution, in fact, is Taine's favourite phrase for the function of general words in carrying on rea- sonino's. I do not admit the justice of Taine's reasoning (p. 341) upon the Maxim of Contradiction : he forgets that many philosophers in the time of Aristotle, together with Hegel and others in recent vears, disallowed and denied this maxim : and that they would have equally disallowed Taine's proof of it : they would not have admitted his assertion that present meant not absent — and that absent meant not present. You can only prove the maxim by uncontradicted repetition of appeals to particular facts of sense ; and if your opponent will not admit these facts of sense, you cannot prove it at all. The aggregate effect on the memory and belief of these multiplied repetitions constitutes what Taine calls (p. 342) ON M., TAINE ' DE L'lNTELLIGENCE.' 859 " Tefficacite des idees latentes " : a phrase not psychologically correct, nor at all proper for a work on reasoned truth, seeing that he puts the grounds of belief in axiomatic truths on a level with emotional fancies and prejudices. That these idees latentes (p. 342-343) do as a matter of fact very often determine our belief, he tells us very truly : but the charac- teristic feature of reasoned truth is that those secret grounds of belief shall be brouo'ht out into distinct consciousness and critically appreciated : seeing that in their latent state, they are available alike for support either of true or false belief, and carry no authority. ' In p. 344, Taine says (in proceeding to discuss the Axiom that ' the sums of equals are equal ' and the differences of equals also equal) — " Certainement, nous pouvons former ces deux propositions par I'induction ordinaire : et tres probablement, c'est de cette maniere qu'elles s'etablissent d'abord dans notre esprit.— Toutes les fois que j ai pratique dans des conditions semblables des operations semblables, j'ai verifie que Tissue etait semblable " (344, bottom). — There cannot be a clearer admission that these Axioms both may be and are of inductive origin. But in the next page, he tells us that they may also be formed ivithout induction (346-347). The very supposition that there are truths proveable by Induction, (including, as Taine justly says verification) but which are also proveable without Induction — appears to me a strange one, and most unnecessary. His attempt to shew it is by resolving Equality into Sameness, and Inequality into Difference : and by saying that two lines which are capable of exactly coinciding " ne font plus qu'une seule et memo ligne (350) — sent les memes — " while, if not so capable, they are different. It appears to me that this is a new definition of equality, which goes far to abolish it as a real attribute, and which is at the same time incorrect. Two lines capable of coinciding are equal : this is a concep- tion essentially different from, and opposed to, the concep- tion of two lines merged and confounded into one and the same line : the first of the two conceptions involves duality 360 PAPERS o:n philosophy. of the objects compared, the second abolishes it. You may say that twelve is tJie same as twelve, or as duodeeim, douze, zwolf, &c. : here is one and the same thing either described twice over by different names, or the same name repeated both in subject and predicate — a mere tautology. But you cannot with propriety say — twelve is equal to twelve, duo- deeim : here are no two objects to compare : the proposition twelve is equal to itself — is either unmeaning, or metaphorical. In framing any equation of which twelve forms one side, you must find some different number to place on the other side : 12 = ^ = ^=4x3 = 6x2=\/ 144— and so forth. Here you predicate of 12, that it is equal to the result of a certain operation performed upon some other number : that it is equal to a function of that other number, arising in a certain way. Here are always two different real terms com- pared ; and the number as well as variety of such compari- sons might be injBnitely multiplied. Taine says (p. 353) — "Sous le mot Sffal, reside le mot me7ne : voila le mot essentiel : telle est Tidee latente incluse dans I'idee d'egalite. Degagee et suivie a travers plusieurs propositions intermddiaires, elle ramene Taxiome a une pro- position analytique. Par elle nous relions Tattribut au sujet : nous la voyons presente dans les deux : mais avant de I'y voir, nous Ty pressentions : elle y etait et temoignait de sa presence par la contrainte qu'elle exer^ait sur notre affir- mation : quoique non demelee, elle faisait son office. — Nous devinions avec certitude, mais sans pouvoir preciser les choses, que dans les deux donnees et dans les deux operations, il y avait du meme: I'analyse n'a fait qu'isoler ce meme, et nous montrer a I'etat distinct la vertu qu'il y avait en nous a I'etat latent." This paragraph seems to me incorrect : Equality seems to me to exclude sameness, instead of implying it : moreover we see here what an arbitrary proceeding it is to invoke these idees latentes, and to ascribe to their influence " la contrainte exercee sur notre affirmation.^^ ON M. TAINE ' DE ^INTELLIGENCE.' 361 It is here formally announced that these axioms are no- thing more than analytical propositions. Taine ought to have tried his hand upon the Axiom — "Things which are equal to the same are equal to one another " — ^before he meddled with the more advanced pro- position — The sums of equals are equal. Suppose that a person puts before you two propositions thus framed : — 1. If there be two magnitudes A and B, both of them equal to a third magnitude 0, one of those two magnitudes will be equal to the other. 2. If there be two magnitudes A and B, both of them greater than a third magnitude C, one of those two magni- tudes will be greater than the other. On hearing these two propositions for the first time, who can tell that the first is true, and the second not true, except by trying both one and the other in application to a string of particular cases ? What idees latentes are there in each, to enable him to make this distinction? Taine's appeal (p. 347), that we should shut our eyes and reflect upon the meaning of the terms will certainly not enable us to do this, unless we employ the interval of closed eyes in imagining a variety of triplets conforming to Propositions 1 and 2, and, examining mentally what the results would be in each case. Proposition 1, though true, is not an analytic Proposition, but synthetic. Its contradictory includes no contradiction in terms. Proposition 2 is alike synthetic, and can only be shewn to be false generally, by the production of some par- ticular case in which observation attests it as false. Taine's exposition and criticism of the definition o{ parallels (355 — 363) are also unsatisfactory to me : there is the same gratuitous substitution of same distance between the parallels of equal distance. Also about straight line, (356) I agree with what he says (355) about Legendre's definition (shortest distance between two points). His own exposition however (356) implies the very same antithesis (" en reniarquant la ligne que trace le 362 PAPERS ON PHILOSOPHY. premier point lorsqu'il se meut vers le second et vers le second seulement, par opioosUion a la ligne qu'il trace lorsqu'- ayant de se moiivoir vers le second, il se meut soit vers un autre, &c."). In this exposition, tha idea of direction is assumed as already acquired and familiar. In fact, it is the idee laiente which Taine is fond of assuming arbitrarily in other cases, but which really exists in our minds in this case as the true constituent of the straight line. Taine cannot resolye direc- Hon into anything more simple and fundamental : but he ought to haye brought it out into clearer light by yaried exposition and illustration. Sameness (of direction) is here in its right place : while employed as an exponent of equality, it is quite out of place and misleading. Direction and Distance are both of them distinct aspects of the fact of motion ; but both of them are fundamental and universal ; neither of them can be resolyed into the other. Legendre's definition of the straight line (above noticed) attempts to resolve direction into distance ; and is for that reason inad- missible as a definition, though true as an affirmation. One and the same dnection is known by immediate consciousness, farther illustrated by contrast with a difi^erent immediate consciousness — varijing direction — from and tcncards. All that can be done towards defining a straight line is, to state and illustrate this consciousness and contrast in the most perspicuous manner. As to Taine's demonstration (p. 371 seq.) that several or all of the principles of mechanics are not merely truths of experience or inductiyely established, but also analytical pro- loositions, I think it quite unsatisfactory : indeed I consider it as among the worst parts of his book. The demonstration is founded upon the same abusive appeal to "Za meme^' (p. 373) which he had reasoned upon before. It is no better than the presumption of Aristotle, that the celestial bodies moved in perfect circles, because it was their nature so to move. To say that because a moving body has moved two inches in the same direction, we are entitled to presume. ON M. TATNE * DE INTELLIGENCE.' 363 and even required to believe, that it will continue to move onward in the same uniform direction and velocity, unless some disturbing cause intervene — to say that this is an axiom of which we can neither conceive nor believe the contrary (p. 386), when he had before said (p. 370) that Aristotle and the philosophers prior to Galileo all did believe the contrary — seems to me an exaggeration of bold and unwarranted assertion. It is indeed well calculated ^'to increase in an infinite measure the powers of our minds " (la portee de notre esprit s'accroit a I'infini — p. 392), and to give us knowledge not relative, but absolute, without doubts or conditions {'^ ne souffrent ni doutes, ni limites, ni conditions, ni restrictions " — p. 393). Now that, after truths have been for a long time unknown or disallowed, and only built up in the face of able opponents by laborious induction, a philosopher should come forward and say that the induction was altogether super- fluous, and that the conclusion was really contained in, and inseparable from, the premisses — appear to me assertions no less incredible than anything which we read in Aristotle ' De Coelo; In all your remarks about the Postulate of the Uniformity of Nature I perfectly concur. But we must remember that Aristotle and the Peripatetics not only did not allow this Pos- tulate, but afl&rmed another Postulate distinctly contradicting it, viz. : That there were some sequences essentially regular, others essentially irregular and unpredictable. The Postulate of Uniform Nature has been ascertained and verified by a large and ever increasing sweep of Induction, and is nov^ well entitled to overbear the counter-presumption which Aristotle in his day admitted as dividing with it the empire of phe- nomena. But it derives its certainty and authority entirely from Induction : and the last Chapter of Taine's book ap- pears to me extremely misleading, inasmuch as it is a hazy maze of words tending to make you believe that there is a distinct authority co-operating with and even superior to Induction — viz. : " la raison explicative, la soudure,'' between the separate links of the Inductive process. This extra- 364 PAPERS ON PHILOSOPHY. physical authority is alleged by Taine to do what Induction cannot do: that is, it gives us knowledge absolute and unconditional, which we can never obtain by Induction. Taine cites (with praise) Mill's Chapter on the Explanation of Laws of Nature : but he either misunderstands, or delibe- rately departs from, the main doctrines of that valuable Chapter : which presents in the clearest manner the true relation between the more comprehensive and the less comprehensive theorems in science. Taine speaks as if he thought that whenever we study one particular property of objects apart from the rest, we desert the path of Induction, and enable ourselves to discover and handle extra-physical entities such as le meme, la soudure, &c., thus putting ourselves on a platform above the inductive process. This last chapter of Taine appears to me a surrender of Mill' s Logic to the a priori of Leibnitz. It really contains some things which surprise me. " Nos yeux ne peuvent percevoir I'etendue que comme coloree : de meme, notre intelligence ne pent concevoir des faits que comme expli- cables. II n'y a de concevable pour nous que ce qui est explicable; comme il n'y a de visible pour nous que ce qui est coloree" (p. 481). He forgets that Aristotle and the Peripatetics distinctly held the contrary, and treated this position as itself incredible. The last page of Taine's book (491, 492) I do not clearly understand, but it seems to invest a priori procedure with a degree of power which enables it to dispense with experience altogether, and to determine beforehand, among the entire catalogue of possible existences, which of them (or how many among them) admit of becoming real. Taine then suggests that the enterprise of Hegel should be re-attempted with greater precautions. I can hardly think that he has studied Mill's Logic with any hear^ and serious grasp of its spirit and contents. -^- p# _ i^^4 f> ^" LONDON: PRINTED BY WILLIAM CLOWES AND SONS, STAMFORD STREET AND CHARING CROSS. ■n*-. c^ "^ V o ft- * g 1 A ■" >^ A-^ Ov- ^ s * <> > ^ ' ^Oo x^-. ^^ '' <>^^ ,'\' ^ :^' ^^ 1 Deacidified using the Bookkeepe Neutralizing agent: Magnesium ( \ -^^ \ ^ V ^^ ..•^^ O ,\- y- ueaciaiTiea usmg ine tJOOKKeeper process. (-^ Neutralizing agent: Magnesium Oxide ^ Treatment Date: add 7KO -,ies EADER IN PAPER PRESERVATION 111 Thomson Park Drive Cranberry Township, PA 1 6066 (724)779-2111 i icciuiieiii L^uic ADD 9fV19 PreservationTechnologii A WORLD LEADER IN PAPER PRESERVAT I .-^ \ 1'^ ^c" \ v^^ r O ^> o N. 1}. -S ^ ^ ; :.^:: :(].':':. ^\'y\ ■■■■''■ '" •'^:'a-4HfI*'n' LIBRARY OF CONGRESS ^Wj IIV. ,1 . ' I » . ' ' ' ' W M 1 n rt ,-u , ,.-1 -, • .. ,' ' V, ' •■-•■ •■ .•1"^-.,; . Jl,UT*r li" hid • .i.- ,•,.•!'♦* 'ft- SIS' W>*'-^ ^i.(*:uMX.- . -f ' *^ 4! I '■iV